20.07.2013 Views

Question 6 The first thing t - University of Utah

Question 6 The first thing t - University of Utah

Question 6 The first thing t - University of Utah

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

ECONOMICS 5080 QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS<br />

ALL STUDY QUESTIONS<br />

ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT, UNIVERSITY OF UTAH FALL SEMESTER 2010<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 6 is 5 in 2008fa and 6 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 6 <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> <strong>thing</strong> that Marx says about the commodity is that it presents itself to<br />

the economic agents as a <strong>thing</strong> with two different properties, use-value and exchange-value.<br />

Why does the title <strong>of</strong> the <strong>first</strong> section then say that the two factors <strong>of</strong> the commodity are<br />

use-value and value, instead <strong>of</strong> use-value and exchange-value?<br />

[1] Cougar: graded A Value or Exchange Value. A commodity is defined as “... some<strong>thing</strong><br />

produced for sale or exchange,” on page four <strong>of</strong> Hans’ annotations on Karl Marx’s<br />

Capital. Although not explicitly written by Marx, any<strong>thing</strong> “... that is produced for sale,”<br />

is considered to him a commodity. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> section describes two unrelated measures <strong>of</strong><br />

value for a commodity. “Use-Value” refers to any possible use <strong>of</strong> a commodity, from the<br />

purpose <strong>of</strong> its design to its abuse for improvised purposes. <strong>The</strong> second measure, “value” is<br />

inferred by the question to have replaced the term “exchange-value” mentioned in an earlier<br />

version <strong>of</strong> Marx’s text. As defined by Hans’ annotations on page one, “Value is that property<br />

inherent in the commodity which is responsible for its ability to be exchanged on the market.”<br />

According to Marx, “value” is purely an economic measure <strong>of</strong> a commodity. Inherent<br />

in the term “commodity” is its purpose for exchange in a marketplace, as defined by Hans.<br />

Thus the “value” <strong>of</strong> a commodity is the inherent property which provides its demand for exchange<br />

in an economic marketplace. Exchange is an intrinsic characteristic <strong>of</strong> commodity,<br />

therefore, “exchange-value” <strong>of</strong> a commodity is redundant. “Use-Value” and “value” serve<br />

merely as revised yet substantial vector coordinates <strong>of</strong> a commodity when considering the<br />

parenthetical text following the section title: “Substance <strong>of</strong> Value, Magnitude <strong>of</strong> Value.”<br />

Message [1] referenced by [3] and [2011fa:274]. Next Message by Cougar is [101].<br />

[2] KA: Exchange Value vs. Value. Marx substitutes the term exchange-value for value<br />

to emphasize the quantitative relationship between commodities. It is the “magnitude” <strong>of</strong><br />

the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities. Marx illustrates the differences in very simple terms in<br />

127:4–128:1: “Such properties come into consideration only to the extent that they make<br />

the commodities useful, i.e., turn them into use-values. But clearly, the exchange relation <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities is characterized precisely by its abstraction from their use-values.” To further<br />

elaborate on these differences, I have provided examples <strong>of</strong> each term.<br />

Use-Value: <strong>The</strong> emphasis <strong>of</strong> “use-value” is best described through the value derived by<br />

utilizing the characteristics/traits <strong>of</strong> a resource/commodity to produce another product/commodity.<br />

This will enable one to exchange one good for the consumption <strong>of</strong> another good. For example,<br />

land can best be described as a use-value by it inherent traits <strong>of</strong> what it can produce.<br />

1<br />

2 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Land can be used to produce a series <strong>of</strong> products/commodities that can eventually mature to<br />

the stage where one can barter/exchange it for another product/commodity. It is the usefulness<br />

<strong>of</strong> the land that makes it a use-value, either through the potential economic gains that<br />

can be realized after production or its immediate consumption.<br />

Exchange-value: Exchange-value was replaced with the term “value” to express a level <strong>of</strong><br />

barter. In order to obtain one product/commodity, an individual must give up the consumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> another product/commodity <strong>of</strong> equal value. This transaction could translate into a<br />

1:1 exchange or 1:2 exchange (or higher ratio) depending on the intrinsic value one assigns<br />

to their supply goods <strong>of</strong> versus their demand for a another good. For example, your demand<br />

is for 1 commodity, say apples and your exchange supply is oranges. You are willing to give<br />

up 2 oranges for every 1 apple. This subjectively defines your exchange-value or “value” for<br />

apples. Hans highlights this on pp. 2 <strong>of</strong> the annotation by stating that “not its substance but<br />

its magnitude.” <strong>The</strong> exchange proportion <strong>of</strong> one commodity versus another is the magnitude<br />

one demands for consumption with respect to their inventory <strong>of</strong> equivalent bartering goods.<br />

Hans: Your quotes from Marx and the Annotations do not say what you think they say.<br />

You seem to think that the Marx quote says that exchange-value is some<strong>thing</strong> quantitative. But the word<br />

“quantity” does not even show up in this quote. “Abstraction from use-value” is not the same as “quantity.” <strong>The</strong><br />

Marx quote says that exchange-value cannot derive from the physical properties <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s, because these physical<br />

properties are not a constant in the exchange, they are all over the place. Admittedly, this is a difficult argument.<br />

It takes some thought to wrap one’s head around it. And if one cannot quite follow Marx’s argument it is easy to<br />

make up one’s own thoughts and think this is what Marx is saying.<br />

<strong>The</strong> quote from my Annotations is taken out <strong>of</strong> context. <strong>The</strong> phrase “not its substance but its magnitude.” can<br />

be found in my text, but the context is not that I say exchange-value depends not on the substance <strong>of</strong> the use-value<br />

but its magnitude. I was simply saying that in one part <strong>of</strong> section 1 <strong>of</strong> chapter One, Marx discusses the substance<br />

<strong>of</strong> value, and in the next part he discusses not its substance but its magnitude. You are really putting words into<br />

my mouth which I clearly did not mean to say. If that were a real debate, you would get a sharply worded rebuttal<br />

from me, questioning whether you were really interested in a debate or whether you were just using every trick in<br />

the book to push your own agenda.<br />

Message [2] referenced by [5]. Next Message by KA is [48].<br />

[3] Hans: Why value and not exchange-value? Cougar read the Annotations carefully,<br />

and he will get an A for submission [1]. But his thinking is obviously grounded in the<br />

mainstream economic framework, and he did not quite realize how different Marx’s theory is<br />

from modern mainstream economics. For instance when I write in the Annotations “Value is<br />

that property inherent in the commodity which is responsible for its ability to be exchanged<br />

on the market” Cougar thinks I am talking about that inherent property which “provides<br />

its demand for exchange in an economic marketplace.” Khub [2008fa:7] had similar ideas.<br />

Khub thought the concept <strong>of</strong> value encapsulated those aspects <strong>of</strong> use-value which everybody<br />

can agree on.<br />

Marx was thinking along completely different lines. In his theory, the <strong>thing</strong> inherent in<br />

the commodities which determines its price is not the usefulness <strong>of</strong> the commodity, but it is<br />

the labor content <strong>of</strong> the commodity. This is what Marx calls “value.”<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore value in Marx’s theory is really quite different than exchange-value. Value is<br />

labor content, i.e., it is generated in production. Exchange-value is the commodity’s ability<br />

to fetch other commodities in the market. In order to illustrate how they are related, allow<br />

me to give an example from my own life:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 3<br />

When I was in elementary school in Germany in the 1950s, the teacher once discussed<br />

the differences between men and women. I thought I knew all about it: women have breasts<br />

while men don’t, their genitals are different, and women have long hair while men have short<br />

hair. I was baffled when the teacher rejected my third criterion, in fact, I was so baffled that I<br />

still remember this today. Of course, the teacher rejected it for a good reason. <strong>The</strong> hair style<br />

is not what makes a woman a woman. <strong>The</strong> hair style is irrelevant for her ability to bear and<br />

raise children. Rather, the hair style is society’s reaction to her womanhood.<br />

Marx’s theory makes an analogous distinction between value and exchange-value. In<br />

152:1 (section 3 <strong>of</strong> chapter One) Marx writes:<br />

When at the beginning <strong>of</strong> this chapter we said, in common parlance, that a<br />

commodity is a use-value and an exchange-value, we were, strictly speaking,<br />

wrong. A commodity is a use-value or object <strong>of</strong> utility, and a “value.”<br />

It represents itself as this tw<strong>of</strong>old <strong>thing</strong>, that it is, as soon as its value assumes<br />

its own, from the bodily form <strong>of</strong> the commodity different form <strong>of</strong><br />

appearance, that <strong>of</strong> exchange-value.<br />

<strong>The</strong> inherent quality which really matters is value, i.e., the labor inside the commodity.<br />

<strong>The</strong> exchange-value is only society’s reaction to the labor inside the commodity, think <strong>of</strong> it<br />

as an echo, just as the long hair is society’s reaction to somebody being a woman (at least in<br />

1950’s Germany).<br />

It is therefore not an accident that Marx says the two factors <strong>of</strong> the commodity are usevalue<br />

and value. Value is the <strong>thing</strong> inherent in the commodity, namely the labor content.<br />

Exchange-value is society’s reaction to this inherent <strong>thing</strong>, but it is not itself an inherent<br />

<strong>thing</strong> in the commodity and can therefore not be called a factor <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Message [3] referenced by [515] and [2011fa:274]. Next Message by Hans is [5].<br />

[5] Hans: Please read the text carefully. Reading a text and getting out <strong>of</strong> it what the<br />

author intended, rather than what is floating around in your own head, is difficult. KA [2]<br />

is not reading Marx carefully enough. <strong>The</strong> reading assignments are not long, but don’t be<br />

surprised if you have to read it several times before you really get it. Marx has to be read<br />

carefully because he does not say <strong>thing</strong>s which a modern reader would expect him to say. I<br />

made some more detailed comments about [2], which you can see when you download the<br />

pdf archive<br />

or<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/halfpage/2010fa.pdf<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/screen/2010fa.pdf<br />

Next Message by Hans is [11].<br />

[420] Jon: A commodity is a product that is produced with the intent to sell or exchange.<br />

When Marx talks about the use value he refers to the person’s use <strong>of</strong> the commodity after<br />

it has been exchanged for that can differ from commodity and by person. Exchange value<br />

on the other hand is the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity that it is traded for, there is an intrinsic<br />

factor for all commodities and that is labor as has been discussed. <strong>The</strong> reason that Marx<br />

refers to Exchange value as simply “Value” is that when talking about a commodity it is<br />

4 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

redundant to place Exchange in front <strong>of</strong> that value when it is inferred that the commodity<br />

will be exchanged based on the fact that it is a commodity and made for the purpose <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange.<br />

Hans: Exchange-value and value are two different <strong>thing</strong>s, not two words for the same <strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Next Message by Jon is [421].<br />

[426] AM: A look at the definitions <strong>of</strong> the terms use-value, value, and exchange value<br />

is important for an understanding why Marx says that the two factors <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

are use-value and value rather than saying the two factors <strong>of</strong> the commodity are use-value<br />

and exchange-value. My in-class answer failed to provide definitions <strong>of</strong> the terms, which I<br />

remedy below. Use-value is defined as the different uses <strong>of</strong> any given commodity. Since usevalue<br />

is determined by the individual there is as Khub [7] says variety among use-values.<br />

Value is defined as the labor content in a commodity. It is important to note that Marx<br />

explicitly states that the labor content is inherent in a commodity. Exchange-value is “the<br />

commodity’s ability to fetch other commodities in the market.” To help clarify what this<br />

means Hans suggests that we think <strong>of</strong> exchange-value as a reaction to the inherent labor<br />

content in a commodity. <strong>The</strong>se definitions came out all wrong in my in class attempt to<br />

distinguish why Marx used the terms use-value and value. I said that “exchange-value and<br />

value share an inherent some<strong>thing</strong>; that some<strong>thing</strong> is labor.” This is wrong. Since labor<br />

is inherent in a commodity and exchange value is not, Marx would not include exchange<br />

value as a factor <strong>of</strong> a commodity. I go on to suggest that exchange-value and value can be<br />

used interchangeably and present that as the reason that Marx did not use exchange value<br />

is his title <strong>of</strong> the <strong>first</strong> section. This again is wrong (perhaps the pressure <strong>of</strong> an exam had a<br />

horrid effect on my ability to express my understanding <strong>of</strong> Marx’s basic principles, although<br />

my understanding <strong>of</strong> Marx is not as advanced as perhaps Hans would like). Instead <strong>of</strong><br />

saying that these terms are interchangeable I should have presented, as Hans does in response<br />

to Chad [13], value as an “intrinsic property <strong>of</strong> the commodities governing the exchange<br />

proportions”. This shows that value and exchange-value are different concepts rather than<br />

interchangeable ones.<br />

Next Message by AM is [430].<br />

[431] Fisher: Use value, as we are all well aware <strong>of</strong> at this point, refers to the “menu <strong>of</strong><br />

uses” for that particular commodity. Marx refers to it as the “opposite” <strong>of</strong> exchange value.<br />

Value, on the other hand, is referred to by Marx as the “property inherent in the commodity<br />

which is responsible for its ability to be exchanged on the market”. According to Marx “usevalue”<br />

has no<strong>thing</strong> in common with value, except the word. <strong>The</strong> real value <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

comes from its ability to be exchanged with other goods in the market place. Use value<br />

means simply how we use an item never alluding to its ability to be exchanged.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> definitions are correct, but this does not yet answer the question.<br />

Message [431] referenced by [515]. Next Message by Fisher is [435].<br />

[515] Milly: content A late penalty 1% In my <strong>first</strong> in class submission I believe I clearly<br />

defined the terms use-value, exchange-value and value, just like Fisher did in [431], however<br />

we really didn’t answer the question. <strong>The</strong>re is actually a reason Marx purposely starts the<br />

<strong>first</strong> section with use-value and value. Although the answer is within the difference between<br />

the definitions <strong>of</strong> value and exchange-value, the question is asking why Marx chose value. It<br />

is because value is the <strong>thing</strong> that is inherent in the commodity, where exchange-value is not.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 5<br />

Exchange-value is just the social relation or society’s reaction to the <strong>thing</strong> that is inherent. It<br />

is the labor content that is really important inside the commodity, which is value. [2010fa:3]<br />

Next Message by Milly is [517].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 9 is 2 in 1996sp, 1 in 1997WI, 1 in 1997sp, 1 in 1997ut, 1 in 1998WI, 1 in 1999SP,<br />

1 in 2002fa, 2 in 2003fa, 4 in 2004fa, 5 in 2005fa, 8 in 2007fa, 8 in 2008SP, 8 in 2008fa,<br />

8 in 2009fa, 9 in 2011fa, and 1 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 9 Can one say that happiness is the only true wealth?<br />

[4] Alex: content B+ form 90% Happiness and True Wealth. Marx states that wealth in<br />

a capitalistic production market is defined by a “heap <strong>of</strong> commodities.” Hans explains that<br />

he refers here to material objects that enhance human life. However, defining wealth as only<br />

a material asset could be a debatable topic, which could be touched on when answering this<br />

question.<br />

So, replying to this question with regards to Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> wealth, and with Hans’<br />

explanation, happiness is not the only true wealth experienced by humans because happiness<br />

is, well, not material. Happiness cannot be included in the “heap <strong>of</strong> commodities”<br />

which Marx mentioned in his excerpt because according to the annotations, “a commodity<br />

is some<strong>thing</strong> produced for sale or exchange” in which Marx refers to a “commodity is every<strong>thing</strong>,<br />

whether raw material or finished good, whether a specialized brand name article<br />

or a staple, that is produced for sale.” Can we produce and sell happiness? Not directly. We<br />

get the usefulness or value <strong>of</strong> commodities that we buy, which produce happiness, but we<br />

cannot buy happiness as a material wealth.<br />

My understanding is that Marx wants the reader to recognize that wealth is described<br />

as tangible objects, commodities, and not ideas or feelings that give us some kind <strong>of</strong> value<br />

or utility. Nevertheless, the other interpretation <strong>of</strong> wealth is that it is some<strong>thing</strong> that enhances<br />

human life and not necessary has to be material, in this case happiness, or maybe joy,<br />

or health. <strong>The</strong>se concepts surely enhance human life for many individuals, however, they<br />

would not fit under Marx’s idea, or category <strong>of</strong> wealth. From Marx’s point <strong>of</strong> view, the only<br />

“true wealth” that would accommodate his definition <strong>of</strong> wealth would be exactly the “heap<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities,” or material items that enhance human lives, such as money, properties,<br />

etc. Hence, true wealth would be experienced by having abundance <strong>of</strong> material items that<br />

enhance our lives, and no<strong>thing</strong> else aside from that.<br />

Hans: Your original answer was one long paragraph; I broke it into three. I also broke up a couple <strong>of</strong> your winding<br />

run-on sentences. Please work on this. Go back over your text and edit it so that it is easy to understand for the<br />

reader.<br />

Message [4] referenced by [12] and [147]. Next Message by Alex is [31].<br />

[6] Cmellen: graded A+ If you are speaking from the ideology <strong>of</strong> Marxism, then no, happiness<br />

is not the only true wealth. To be even more clear, happiness can never be wealth, for<br />

wealth is tangible and happiness is a feeling. “Man is a wealth-seeking animal” (Hodgkinson<br />

1982). Wealth consists <strong>of</strong> goods or commodities, (which are not free) that enhance human<br />

life. This is not only pertaining to luxury items in life, but any<strong>thing</strong> such as food, clo<strong>thing</strong>,<br />

shelter, education, etc. Wealth endows one with a supposed potential <strong>of</strong> happiness. However,<br />

if the wealth is not spread around to all, then the society cannot be happy as a whole.<br />

One may perceive that life is a cycle <strong>of</strong> wealth acquisition, consumption, and distribution.<br />

6 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

We all think we know what wealth is, and we want it because it will result in happiness.<br />

Still, happiness is a presumptive end <strong>of</strong> man; it’s a feeling that is not tangible, real, or solid.<br />

Wealth is the means to the end goal (i.e. happiness). Wealth is the material, concrete, and<br />

substantial commodities that will enable the happiness one strives for in the end.<br />

Reference 1. Hodgkinson, C., Wealth and Happiness: An Analysis and Some Implications<br />

for Education. Canadian J Education, 1982.7(1): p.1-14<br />

Hans: This article is on Jstor. If someone wanted to write a Marxist critique <strong>of</strong> it, I would accept this as a term<br />

paper (and maybe you could even publish it). Usually the connection between wealth and happiness is made only<br />

on an individual level, and I like Cmellen’s extension <strong>of</strong> this connection to society as a whole. If I remember right,<br />

this is a new thought which none <strong>of</strong> the dozens <strong>of</strong> answers to this question in the archives ever had. But it is entirely<br />

logical, because wealth can only be produced in a social context. But Cmellen should not have used the figure <strong>of</strong><br />

speech “spreading around wealth” which frames the issue in a right-wing manner: it conjures the image <strong>of</strong> wealth<br />

being created by individuals, some <strong>of</strong> whom are more industrious than others, and then those who work hardest get<br />

expropriated. If you start with the notion that the production <strong>of</strong> wealth is a social process, then the next question is<br />

whether the social distribution <strong>of</strong> wealth is fair or whether it could be improved.<br />

One last point. You are using the word “commodity” in its colloquial meaning, as synonymous to “good” or<br />

“article.” But Marx reserves the word “commodity” only for goods that are produced for sale. <strong>The</strong>refore strictly<br />

speaking, from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> this class, your use <strong>of</strong> the word “commodity” in your answer was wrong both<br />

times.<br />

Final Grading Note by Hans: Whenever you participate, you give it 150%; but your participation comes in bursts;<br />

it would have been better to have a more steady presence in class.<br />

Message [6] referenced by [10] and [28]. Next Message by Cmellen is [43].<br />

[7] Kraken: (graded A–) Happiness and wealth. According to Marx, wealth is any<strong>thing</strong><br />

that enhances human life. Included in his definition <strong>of</strong> wealth would be both physical possessions<br />

that we personally own and other <strong>thing</strong>s that we don’t own like clean air and crime<br />

free cities and beautiful public parks. So to answer the question: Can one say that happiness<br />

is the only true wealth? <strong>The</strong> answer would be no. Wealth is what makes happiness a possibility.<br />

Most people need life enhancing <strong>thing</strong>s in order to be happy. A life completely devoid<br />

<strong>of</strong> physical comforts, safety, good health and beauty (which all fall within Marx’s definition<br />

<strong>of</strong> wealth) would be unhappy indeed.<br />

Hans: You answered the question: “can one be happy without material wealth?” This is a different question than:<br />

“is happiness the only true wealth?”. But since you include ecosystem services in material wealth, it is a very timely<br />

issue. People are not aware how much they depend on the environment being just right for humans. After the full<br />

brunt <strong>of</strong> climate change can be felt, there will be a rude awakening.<br />

Message [7] referenced by [426]. Next Message by Kraken is [29].<br />

[8] Hal: graded A+ Wealth and Happiness. Wealth is not a state <strong>of</strong> mind; it is purely<br />

material. Wealth consists <strong>of</strong> the material <strong>thing</strong>s that improve our well being and enhance our<br />

lives, while happiness is the recognition <strong>of</strong> good <strong>thing</strong>s in life. <strong>The</strong>refore, as mentioned in<br />

previous answers to this question (located in the archives), wealth is an input and happiness<br />

is an output. To equate happiness with wealth is to redefine wealth and make its meaning<br />

more ambiguous – even mystical. It is a clever use <strong>of</strong> words that I believe is meant to cause<br />

people to, on some level, believe that they can achieve happiness in ways they cannot.<br />

If one claims that happiness can be achieved independently <strong>of</strong> wealth, why even suggest<br />

that it is some form <strong>of</strong> wealth? If wealth is useless, why connect it with such a wonderful<br />

emotion as happiness? It would be more direct to say that wealth is useless in obtaining<br />

happiness. Perhaps with such a direct claim, it is easier for the listener to look at his/her own<br />

life and determine that some amount <strong>of</strong> wealth is indeed necessary.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 7<br />

Even Ghandi was the beneficiary <strong>of</strong> a good education and a stable upbringing. He practiced<br />

a form <strong>of</strong> voluntary simplicity, rejecting many forms <strong>of</strong> wealth, but voluntary simplicity<br />

feels much more noble than involuntary simplicity. Our society is becoming increasingly<br />

aware that there are many expensive goods and services that will not provide us with greater<br />

happiness. However, we should not jump to the conclusion that we are giving up wealth and<br />

remaining just as happy. In actuality, we are trading certain commodities for other forms <strong>of</strong><br />

wealth, such as clean air and more leisure time. We have simply become aware that many<br />

goods and services are taking away more wealth from society (i.e. clean air) than they are<br />

providing.<br />

Hans: Excellent answer. Originally, the last sentence in your <strong>first</strong> paragraph said: “It is a clever use <strong>of</strong> words that<br />

... is meant to cause people to ... believe that they can achieve wealth in ways they cannot.” I changed “wealth” into<br />

“happiness” because I think you misspoke, you really meant happiness. Let me know if I guessed wrong.<br />

Message [8] referenced by [19]. Next Message by Hal is [233].<br />

[28] Somramthom: Happiness Improves your Health. Cmellen [6] states that happiness<br />

isn’t the only true wealth and that happiness isn’t wealth at all because it isn’t tangible.<br />

Cmellen also states that “Wealth endows one with a supposed potential <strong>of</strong> happiness.” and<br />

“Wealth is the means to the end goal (i.e. happiness).”<br />

I would have to disagree. Marx doesn’t state that all wealth is tangible, but rather refers to<br />

a type <strong>of</strong> wealth: “material” wealth. Wealth is some<strong>thing</strong> that enhances human life. Cmellen<br />

argues that these material <strong>thing</strong>s are what make us happy or rather what drives our happiness.<br />

In our modern society <strong>of</strong> consumerism, it is becoming increasingly evident that this is more<br />

a false statement than it is true.<br />

I suggest that attitude is the determining factor in obtaining and maintaining happiness.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re can be two men <strong>of</strong> equal social stature, economic status and demographic region. Yet<br />

these two men could be polar opposites by means <strong>of</strong> happiness. This would be true for two<br />

wealthy individuals with little concern for economic well being or two men in a slum. <strong>The</strong><br />

principle is the same.<br />

Also, happiness is an aspect that improves human life. According to one study, Happy<br />

people are “less likely to suffer heart attacks, strokes, and pain from conditions like rheumatoid<br />

arthritis.” (http://health.usnews.com/usnews/health/articles/061217/25happy.health.htm)<br />

Thus happiness is a type <strong>of</strong> wealth, albeit an intangible type.<br />

Wealth influences your happiness, but doesn’t directly cause it. So while happiness is not<br />

the “one true wealth” it is a type <strong>of</strong> wealth despite being intangible.<br />

Hans: Interesting thought. What do others think about this? This question is no longer assigned, but if you make an<br />

ungraded submission, i.e., if your <strong>first</strong> line is ::Q:9ug, then it will be accepted and it will count as a free discussion<br />

contribution for you.<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [156].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 10 is 3 in 1995ut, 2 in 1996ut, 2 in 1997WI, 2 in 1997sp, 3 in 2003fa, 6 in<br />

2005fa, 9 in 2008fa, and 7 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 10 Wouldn’t scarcity be a better starting point for understanding how a given<br />

society is functioning than wealth? When there is scarcity, this means there is a need to act,<br />

whereas wealth consists <strong>of</strong> dead <strong>thing</strong>s. Scarcity leads us to discover what drives society,<br />

wealth does not.<br />

8 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[9] RexManning: graded A When a society functions in scarcity, it is driven by more<br />

pure individual instincts <strong>of</strong> survival, there is not a lot <strong>of</strong> care or concern for the society as<br />

a whole, but the focus is on the individual who is merely trying to survive. Ricardo states<br />

that, “Even during a famine, corn is imported because the corn-merchant thereby makes<br />

money, and not because the nation is starving.” During these times <strong>of</strong> scarcity, people are<br />

more concerned with their own wellbeing and not the wellbeing <strong>of</strong> society, which makes it<br />

difficult to understand how a society functions. When there is wealth in society, people are<br />

more likely to operate as if there were not any outside inference. An example is that in most<br />

wealthy countries there are entire organizations devoted to the wellbeing <strong>of</strong> the environment,<br />

the less fortunate, and their communities. It is easy to see that wealthier countries function<br />

in a way that benefits society, because they have the means to do so. A society that is<br />

functioning in scarcity is going to be less concerned about society as a whole.<br />

Message [9] referenced by [288], [295], [337], and [734]. Next Message by RexManning is [161].<br />

[288] Somramthom: graded A Scarcity vs Wealth. In my opinion, the most important<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the question to consider is the phrase, “a given society...” This question is asking about<br />

the behaviors <strong>of</strong> a society and how the society functions, not how an individual functions.<br />

RexManning [9] mentioned that societies don’t function as well in time so <strong>of</strong> scarcity as in<br />

times <strong>of</strong> prosperity and great material wealth. In scarcity the functions <strong>of</strong> the individuals<br />

focus on the individual and away from the society as a whole. This is similar as if each cell<br />

in a multicellular organism functioned to satisfy its immediate and direct needs (individual<br />

needs) rather than functioning in its specialized manner for the overall good <strong>of</strong> the organism<br />

(societal needs). It is easy to see in this circumstance the organism would not flourish, but<br />

die. Thus it is difficult to understand the behaviors <strong>of</strong> an organism (society) when it is<br />

struggling to survive. It cannot do its simple actions because each cell (individual) is not<br />

doing its part in the complex multicellular organism.<br />

If the individuals do not do their part, then the wealth cannot enhance human life to the<br />

extent it could in a society where the means exist to reach out to the less fortunate.<br />

Hans: Most <strong>of</strong> those people whom you call “less fortunate” are in Marx’s view systematically robbed <strong>of</strong> the fruits<br />

<strong>of</strong> their labor. It is not an accident that there are so many poor people in capitalism. Capitalism creates wealth for a<br />

few and poverty for the majority.<br />

Message [288] referenced by [295] and [734]. Next Message by Somramthom is [346].<br />

[295] Hans: Oops, this question will not be in the exam. Answer [9] got an A because<br />

it has interesting fresh thinking. It makes one big mistake which I should have caught but<br />

didn’t. When Marx uses the word “wealth” he does not mean “abundance.” Any use-value,<br />

even if it is Kool-Aid, is part <strong>of</strong> society’s “wealth” as Marx uses the word. Because <strong>of</strong> this<br />

oversight I pulled the question from the exam, it will not be in the exam. <strong>The</strong> “right” answer,<br />

in a nutshell, is that according to Marx, the most important social relations, those which you<br />

have to understand <strong>first</strong> in order to get a grip <strong>of</strong> all the other social relations, are the relations<br />

in and with respect to production, and production produces wealth. This is why you need to<br />

study wealth, not its content (use-value), but what Marx calls its “social form.”<br />

And what about “dead”? This is a teaser I wrote into the question in order to see if you<br />

notice. We just studied the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities. I.e., in capitalism, wealth<br />

is far from dead but very much alive.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 9<br />

Somramthon’s answer [288] is also very good and worth reading. I think it’s a look ahead;<br />

we will soon experience how social relations change when people are pushed closer to their<br />

survival limit through the multitude <strong>of</strong> climate-change induced crises heading our way. I<br />

think it can already be felt and, to be honest, I think a religious community is not a bad<br />

place to be in times like these. Somramthon’s emphasis that wealth is social is very much in<br />

Marx’s sense.<br />

It you are interested to read more about the Marx answer to this question, look at my<br />

[1997sp:2] (the entire discussion in that Quarter is useful) and my [2003fa:7]. <strong>The</strong> question<br />

is still assigned so that you can get credit if you want to respond to this. But I am going to<br />

take it out <strong>of</strong> the next version <strong>of</strong> Installment 1, and it will not be on the exam.<br />

Message [295] referenced by [337], [680], and [734]. Next Message by Hans is [307].<br />

[337] RexManning: <strong>The</strong>re was no big mistake. In response to Hans [295] finding a “big<br />

mistake” in answer [9], Marx does use the word “wealth” in a very broad sense. To quote<br />

directly from the annotations “Marx uses the word ‘wealth’ not only for ABUNDANCE or<br />

EXTRAVAGANCE <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s enhancing human life; any<strong>thing</strong> which enhances human life,<br />

however modest it may be, is part <strong>of</strong> society’s wealth.” So it seems that wealth does include<br />

abundance (along with any<strong>thing</strong> else that enhances life), at least according to the annotations.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> sentence “wealth includes abundance (along with any<strong>thing</strong> else that enhances life)” is illogical because<br />

abundance is not a <strong>thing</strong>. A sentence without this logical flaw would for instance be “wealth includes private jets<br />

(along with any<strong>thing</strong> else that enhances life).”<br />

<strong>The</strong> word “abundance” refers to a situation where people have more than enough <strong>thing</strong>s to satisfy their needs.<br />

In [9] you wrote “when there is wealth in society” in the meaning “when there is abundance in society.” This was<br />

your mistake.<br />

It is not a mistake considering the modern usage <strong>of</strong> the word “wealth.” Nowadays, this word is <strong>of</strong>ten used to<br />

mean abundance. But Marx did not use the word “wealth” in this way. Even in a society where there is barely<br />

enough to keep people alive, Marx thinks the production <strong>of</strong> wealth (by which he means all use-values, from Kool-<br />

Aid to private jets) is the most important social activity to look at <strong>first</strong>.<br />

Next Message by RexManning is [455].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 11 is 3 in 1995WI, 6 in 1995ut, 6 in 1996sp, 4 in 1997sp, 3 in 1998WI,<br />

3 in 1999SP, 6 in 2004fa, 7 in 2005fa, 12 in 2007SP, 10 in 2007fa, 10 in 2008fa, 10 in<br />

2009fa, 11 in 2011fa, and 8 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 11 What is a commodity? Marx does not give the definition <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

but an analysis. How would you define the <strong>thing</strong> he analyzes? (<strong>The</strong> answer can be given in<br />

one sentence.)<br />

[296] She: graded A Concisely Defining a Commodity. A commodity is any<strong>thing</strong> that is<br />

produced for sale or exchange regardless <strong>of</strong> if it is ever actually sold or exchanged.<br />

Message [296] referenced by [303] and [307]. Next Message by She is [298].<br />

[302] KA: Definition <strong>of</strong> a commodity. Marx states, “<strong>The</strong> commodity is, <strong>first</strong> <strong>of</strong> all, an<br />

external object, a <strong>thing</strong> which through its qualities satisfies human needs <strong>of</strong> whatever kind.”<br />

Marx goes further to say that a commodity can be both raw materials or finished goods,<br />

so long as they can be exchanged or sold. He states this as, “Nor does it matter here how<br />

the <strong>thing</strong> satisfies man’s need, whether directly as a means <strong>of</strong> subsistence, i.e. an object <strong>of</strong><br />

consumption, or indirectly as a means <strong>of</strong> production.”<br />

Message [302] referenced by [303] and [307]. Next Message by KA is [304].<br />

10 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[303] Lindsey: A different definition <strong>of</strong> a commodity. I realize that this exam question<br />

has been answered by both She [296] and KA [302] but I believe I give a rather different<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> a commodity, the key difference being that a commodity must intrinsically<br />

contain abstract human labor. My definition:<br />

A commodity is a good, which has both value (created through abstract human labor)<br />

and use-value (possible uses that humans can find for the object). It may also be exchanged<br />

within a society for other such goods (Marx calls this exchange-value).<br />

Message [303] referenced by [307]. Next Message by Lindsey is [361].<br />

[307] Hans: Commodities, H2O and dead cats. She’s [296] is correct.<br />

KA [302] is wrong, despite the literal Marx quote: “<strong>The</strong> commodity is, <strong>first</strong> <strong>of</strong> all, an<br />

external object, a <strong>thing</strong> which through its qualities satisfies human needs <strong>of</strong> whatever kind.”<br />

This is not Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> a commodity but only the <strong>first</strong> step in the analysis <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity. A paraphrase might be: “<strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> <strong>thing</strong> we notice when we pick up a commodity<br />

is that it is a physical object with a use-value.” But a few sentences later Marx says it also<br />

has an exchange-value. Marx never defines the commodity; he assumes the reader knows<br />

what he is talking about when he calls a <strong>thing</strong> a commodity.<br />

Lindsey [303] gives what is sometimes called a “real” definition, she enumerates the<br />

essential qualities which make a commodity what it is. It is like defining water by saying<br />

water is H2O. At the beginning <strong>of</strong> the chapter, Marx does not yet know the essential qualities<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities, he is trying to derive them. He needs a simple definition which can be<br />

understood before we know all the ins and outs <strong>of</strong> commodities. This is She’s definition.<br />

At the end a quibble about She’s definition. If it confuses you just ignore it and stick to<br />

my earlier assertion that She’s definition is correct. She writes: “A commodity is any<strong>thing</strong><br />

that is produced for sale or exchange regardless <strong>of</strong> if it is ever actually sold or exchanged.”<br />

This is like giving as definition <strong>of</strong> a cat, saying “a cat is this and this” and then adding<br />

“regardless <strong>of</strong> if it is dead or alive.” <strong>The</strong> reader would scratch their head and think: “is there<br />

really some<strong>thing</strong> to it with the nine lives <strong>of</strong> a cat, do cats really not care whether they are<br />

dead or alive?” It would have been better to say “A commodity is any<strong>thing</strong> that is produced<br />

for sale or exchange even if it is never actually sold or exchanged”, but I think the best <strong>thing</strong><br />

is to just leave it out and simply say “A commodity is any<strong>thing</strong> that is produced for sale or<br />

exchange.” More info why the definition <strong>of</strong> a commodity seems a little awkward is in my<br />

[2005fa:582].<br />

Next Message by Hans is [309].<br />

Multiple Choice <strong>Question</strong> 22 is 14 in 1999SP, 14 in 2001fa, 14 in 2002fa, 16 in 2004fa,<br />

21 in 2007fa, and 21 in 2009fa:<br />

Multiple Choice <strong>Question</strong> 22 Which <strong>of</strong> the following paraphrases best captures the spirit<br />

<strong>of</strong> Marx’s <strong>first</strong> sentence “the wealth <strong>of</strong> those societies, in which the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production<br />

reigns, presents itself as an immense heap <strong>of</strong> commodities”?<br />

(a) In capitalism, everyone tries to accumulate <strong>thing</strong>s.<br />

(b) Nearly every<strong>thing</strong> that is produced in capitalist societies is produced for sale.<br />

(c) In capitalist societies only those are considered wealthy who own many commodities.<br />

(d) In capitalist societies only those consider themselves happy who own many commodities.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 11<br />

(e) <strong>The</strong> capitalist idea <strong>of</strong> being wealthy leads to excessive commodity consumption.<br />

(f) Marx thinks that only those who own lots <strong>of</strong> material <strong>thing</strong>s can be happy.<br />

[12] Hans: Shoot the messenger! Alex says in [4]: Marx defines wealth to be material<br />

goods, and happiness is not material, therefore it does not fall under Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong><br />

wealth.<br />

What is wrong with this? It takes the flaws <strong>of</strong> capitalism and tries to smear them over<br />

Marx the person—although Marx is not a capitalist but a scientist who is telling us about<br />

these flaws.<br />

It is odd that under capitalism wealth is reduced to a pile <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s, and Marx is aware<br />

and critical <strong>of</strong> this. In a primitive nomad society, being wealthy means to have a lot <strong>of</strong> sheep.<br />

For this you must be a good shepherd, i.e., you must have the skills to keep a big herd <strong>of</strong><br />

sheep alive. In capitalism you can be the greatest idiot and still have a lot <strong>of</strong> money in your<br />

bank account. Marx writes about this in Grundrisse p. 222.<br />

In other words: if Marx tells us that capitalist society reduces wealth to the mechanical<br />

relation <strong>of</strong> a person to a pile <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s, this does not mean Marx wants it this way. Alex’s mistake<br />

is to read Marx’s critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism as a flaw <strong>of</strong> Marx himself. Other answers in the<br />

archives make the same mistake, see for instance the <strong>first</strong> paragraph <strong>of</strong> Goran’s [2009fa:447].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 22 is not one <strong>of</strong> the assigned study questions but a multiple choice question<br />

which you might have to answer in the <strong>first</strong> midterm. I am sending my commentary about<br />

Alex [4] under this question number because Alex’s and Goran’s mistake is the wrong answer<br />

(f). <strong>The</strong> correct answer is (b).<br />

Message [12] referenced by [147]. Next Message by Hans is [18].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 40 is 21 in 1995WI, 29 in 1997WI, and 38 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 40 Take some simple object, a shoe or a rubber ball, and differentiate between its<br />

properties, its usefulness, and its use-value.<br />

[10] Spiral: <strong>The</strong> commodity is a lamp. <strong>The</strong> lamp is hard, made <strong>of</strong> brass, but also fragile<br />

where it’s made <strong>of</strong> glass. When connected to an electrical circuit the lamp emits light within<br />

the visible spectrum (and hence is dependent upon the technology to access an electrical<br />

power supply). Visible light is the only way humans can use their sense <strong>of</strong> sight, and seeing<br />

is useful as one <strong>of</strong> the five senses humans use to gather information on their environment. I<br />

enjoy having a source <strong>of</strong> visible light (the lamp) because it is easier to know features <strong>of</strong> my<br />

environment.<br />

Hans: I think you mean the right <strong>thing</strong>, but you should have made it very explicit what are the properties, what is<br />

its usefulness, and what its use-value, and why.<br />

And one more quibble: don’t call it a commodity. Whether it is produced for sale or not is completely irrelevant<br />

for what you are writing. I said some<strong>thing</strong> similar also in my notes for [6].<br />

Next Message by Spiral is [503].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 46 is 43 in 2007fa and 43 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 46 Certain use-values are produced with the purpose never to be used. For instance<br />

nuclear weapons which are developed for the sake <strong>of</strong> deterrence. It is true for these<br />

use-values too that their use-value actualizes itself only in its use?<br />

12 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[35] Proletarian: Use-value <strong>of</strong> a nuclear weapon. Marx asserts that “use-value (<strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity) actualizes itself only by use or consumption (<strong>of</strong> the commodity).” However,<br />

this assertion appears to run into a barrier when considering commodities produced without<br />

the intention <strong>of</strong> ever being used. Nuclear weapons, for example, are commodities that are<br />

developed with the intention <strong>of</strong> never being used and are instead developed for the sake <strong>of</strong><br />

deterrence. Because these nuclear weapons are never used, does this mean they do not have<br />

a use-value?<br />

What some could consider an apparent hole in Marx’s argument stems from a reading <strong>of</strong><br />

the word “use” that is too narrow. Just because a nuclear weapon is never “used” (detonated)<br />

doesn’t mean that the nuclear weapon isn’t actually used. In fact, nuclear weapons are used<br />

every day and have enormous use-value. Just because the nuclear weapon is not exploding<br />

does not mean that the nuclear weapon is not being used.<br />

<strong>The</strong> primary use <strong>of</strong> the nuclear weapon is not to cause damage but is instead to act as<br />

a deterrent against others that would make war against those who possess the commodity.<br />

Simply by possessing the nuclear weapon and having it targeted upon a potential enemy<br />

in such a way that the enemy is deterred against causing harm to the those possessing the<br />

nuclear weapon, those with the nuclear weapon are using it and are realizing use-value from<br />

the weapon <strong>The</strong> nuclear weapon has enormous use-value as deterrent.<br />

So, since the primary use <strong>of</strong> a nuclear weapon is as a deterrent, the nuclear weapon<br />

indeed does have use-value which can be actualized without detonating the device. Now, if<br />

the nuclear weapon were to simply be manufactured and stuck in a warehouse without ever<br />

being targeted at anyone and without anyone ever being told <strong>of</strong> its existence, then the nuclear<br />

weapon would not be considered a deterrent and would therefore not be considered in use<br />

and would therefore would have no use-value at that point for the owner. <strong>The</strong> use-value <strong>of</strong><br />

the weapon would not be actualized until the weapon was put to use by letting others know<br />

<strong>of</strong> it’s existence as a means <strong>of</strong> deterrence.<br />

In summary, Marx’s argument that “use-value actualizes itself only by use or consumption”<br />

indeed holds up in the case <strong>of</strong> nuclear weapons if one frames the use <strong>of</strong> the term “use”<br />

properly. If one considers that the use <strong>of</strong> a nuclear weapon is not to inflict damage but is<br />

instead to impart restraint in one’s enemies through deterrence, then a nuclear weapon is<br />

being used simply by having it targeted at the enemy and by having the enemy know <strong>of</strong> the<br />

potential for destruction that would be experienced if the nuclear weapon were launched.<br />

Next Message by Proletarian is [38].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 50 is 25 in 1995WI, 35 in 1996sp, 33 in 1996ut, 36 in 1997sp, 34 in<br />

1998WI, 38 in 1999SP, 41 in 2004fa, 42 in 2005fa, 48 in 2007SP, 47 in 2008fa, 49 in<br />

2009fa, 55 in 2011fa, and 54 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 50 What is the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity? (Give its definition, not<br />

an analysis where it comes from).<br />

[290] Alex: graded A Exchange value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is established to be a different concept<br />

from that <strong>of</strong> use value, which is how useful a commodity is. Marx introduces the idea<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchange value as “the commodity’s ability to fetch other commodities in the market.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 13<br />

In simpler terms, it is a quantitative relation among the commodities—the price that the<br />

commodity is worth. Commodities are capable <strong>of</strong> having many exchange values or prices<br />

given the situation. Reading back on the archives from earlier semesters, I found that Stuart<br />

[2007fa:15] gave the exemplary definition <strong>of</strong> exchange value, stating that it is “the social<br />

relationship that allows commodities to be traded for other commodities or money, but at<br />

the same time its value is not socially determined.” He says it’s a “social relationship” because<br />

Marx describes exchange value as relative, as in the relationship that commodities<br />

have on the market, with an expression that is intrinsic labeled by the labor content inside<br />

the commodities.<br />

Message [290] referenced by [291]. Next Message by Alex is [434].<br />

[291] Hans: Please take every word you are writing very seriously. Alex’s [290] is<br />

a very good answer. Nevertheless I’d like to plug it apart and go through it sentence by<br />

sentence so that you know how I read your stuff and what I am looking for. Here is Alex’s<br />

entire text again with my comments.<br />

Exchange value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is established to be a different concept<br />

from that <strong>of</strong> use value, which is how useful a commodity is.<br />

Good idea to give the definition not only <strong>of</strong> exchange-value but also <strong>of</strong> use-value, since<br />

they form a pair. Exchange-value is not only a different concept than use-value, but for the<br />

practical agents, commodities have two different properties—truly different in the sense that<br />

they cannot be derived from each other: use-value and exchange-value.<br />

Marx introduces the idea <strong>of</strong> exchange value as “the commodity’s ability to<br />

fetch other commodities in the market.”<br />

Right, although I would have left out “the idea <strong>of</strong>” and would simply have said “Marx<br />

introduces the exchange-value as ...”<br />

In simpler terms, it is a quantitative relation among the commodities – the<br />

price that the commodity is worth.<br />

What you just said is not a reformulation <strong>of</strong> the previous sentence in “simpler terms”<br />

but this is a deepening and elaboration <strong>of</strong> the previous sentence. Exchange-value is a social<br />

relation. If you go into a store, give the grocer $3 and say “I’d like a gallon <strong>of</strong> milk,”<br />

the grocer will not say: “what are you talking about, do I know you?” or “why would<br />

you want to do that?” but he will fetch the milk from the refrigerator and give it to you,<br />

even if you are a perfect stranger. (Assuming the milk’s price is advertised to be $3). In<br />

the Annotations I describe this situation as “exchange-value is that social relation or social<br />

custom which allows commodities to be traded for each other or for money.” More about<br />

this in [1997ut:22].<br />

Commodities are capable <strong>of</strong> having many exchange values or prices given<br />

the situation.<br />

This is a true fact, but this is not part <strong>of</strong> the definition. Marx emphasizes it because after<br />

introducing exchange-value as a second property <strong>of</strong> commodities in addition to their usevalue,<br />

Marx turns around and says: “Are you sure exchange-value has some<strong>thing</strong> to do with<br />

14 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the commodities? It looks pretty relative to me, as if it was determined by circumstances<br />

alone.” (I am paraphrasing here 126:2). I.e., here the issue is whether exchange-value is<br />

really intrinsic in the commodity like use-value. <strong>The</strong> clause in the question “don’t give an<br />

analysis where exchange-value comes from” meant that I wanted you to stay out <strong>of</strong> this can<br />

<strong>of</strong> worms.<br />

Reading back on the archives from earlier semesters, I found that Stuart<br />

[2007fa:15] gave the exemplary definition <strong>of</strong> exchange value, stating that<br />

it is “the social relationship that allows commodities to be traded for other<br />

commodities or money, but at the same time its value is not socially determined.”<br />

Stuart is wrong if the says “its value is not socially determined.” Stuart thinks if it is<br />

intrinsic in the commodity it cannot be socially determined. Marx’s “value quasi-material”<br />

by contrast is an ingredient inside the commodity which is not material but social.<br />

He says it’s a “social relationship” because Marx describes exchange value<br />

as relative, as in the relationship that commodities have on the market, with<br />

an expression that is intrinsic labeled by the labor content inside the commodities.<br />

<strong>The</strong> “with an expression” clause at the end should read: “It is a social relation which is<br />

the expression <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> intrinsic inside the commodities, their labor content.”<br />

I went through it in such detail not because you need to write all this in an exam but<br />

because after grading [230] yesterday I decided I had to go on a campaign admonishing you<br />

to take every word in your own writing very seriously—because Marx is taking every word<br />

in his writing very seriously too. Best definition <strong>of</strong> exchange-value in the archives is my<br />

[2005fa:949] before I start speaking about baby teeth.<br />

Message [291] referenced by [468]. Next Message by Hans is [295].<br />

[304] KA: Define Exchange-Value. Exchange-value is derived socially through a series <strong>of</strong><br />

commodity exchanges. An exchange only between two parties does not qualify as exchangevalue<br />

if the exchange is isolated. Furthermore, the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity lies<br />

within the commodity, not the commodity owner.<br />

Hans: Correct.<br />

Next Message by KA is [305].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 55 is 24 in 1995WI, 32 in 1995ut, 39 in 2001fa, 40 in 2002fa, 46 in<br />

2004fa, 47 in 2005fa, 52 in 2008fa, 54 in 2009fa, 60 in 2011fa, and 58 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 55 Explain in your own words what it means to say that use-values are the<br />

“material carriers” <strong>of</strong> exchange-value.<br />

[298] She: Use-values as the material carriers <strong>of</strong> exchange-values. I am having some<br />

trouble explaining this in a concise manner. I feel as though my thoughts are a little jumbled<br />

on this topic and am hoping to get some helpful feedback. Marx says on page 126 <strong>of</strong> Capital<br />

that use-values are...“conditioned by the physical properties <strong>of</strong> the commodity” and cannot<br />

exist without being physically manifested. He goes on to conclude that the actual physical<br />

body <strong>of</strong> the commodity actually IS the use-value. Exchange-values are assigned by society


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 15<br />

and are no<strong>thing</strong> more than a “mode <strong>of</strong> expression,” (127:1). Without getting too analytical,<br />

exchange-values are a sort <strong>of</strong> signal which tells economic agents how much <strong>of</strong> one usevalue<br />

is worth in comparison to other use-values. Exchange-values are assigned by potential<br />

exchangers based on use-values.<br />

I see that exchange-values are just relationships; they are not tangible. So, this would<br />

seem that we would need some<strong>thing</strong> concrete, or tangible, to base them on. Marx explains<br />

that the physical body and properties <strong>of</strong> the commodity is its use-value. Basicallly, the<br />

relationships are based upon the usefulness <strong>of</strong> a commodity which is “conditioned by the<br />

physical properties <strong>of</strong> the commodity.”<br />

Message [298] referenced by [299] and [309]. Next Message by She is [359].<br />

[299] LuBr: Use-values as the material carriers <strong>of</strong> exchange-values. In response to<br />

She [298],<br />

Marx implies by “carriers” to mean the weakest connection between use-value and exchange<br />

value. Marx says that use-values are the “material carriers” <strong>of</strong> exchange values. So<br />

<strong>first</strong>, you need use-value for the commodity to be deemed exchangeable. If the commodity<br />

loses its use-value then the exchange value is gone. However, use-value does not determine<br />

exchange value, this can be seen in some<strong>thing</strong> with high use-value, for example air, that is<br />

plentiful to everybody demanding it, therefore there is no exchange-value for air.<br />

See Hans’s comments from previous years, they really help to clarify these specific technical<br />

meanings: [2001fa:130] and [2002fa:145].<br />

Hans: Thank you for the prompt response to She’s answer.<br />

Message [299] referenced by [309] and [2012fa:19]. Next Message by LuBr is [495].<br />

[305] KA: Material Carriers <strong>of</strong> Exchange-Values. If a commodity’s use-value deteriorates,<br />

so does its exchange-value. If exchange-value is socially derived and socially there<br />

is no longer a use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity, the exchange <strong>of</strong> this commodity is de minimis.<br />

<strong>The</strong> exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is a function <strong>of</strong> the use-value given there is a demand.<br />

However, if there is an abundance <strong>of</strong> goods dispersed freely there can still be a use-value but<br />

no exchange-value. This abundance <strong>of</strong> free goods no longer presents value for its exchange<br />

since anyone can freely obtain them, but the use <strong>of</strong> these commodities remains constant.<br />

Hans: This is the utility theory <strong>of</strong> value. It is different from and incompatible with Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Next Message by KA is [306].<br />

[309] Hans: Why a carrier is necessary. In response to She [298], I think LuBr [299]<br />

answered it correctly. At least LuBr correctly summarizes what I say in the Annotations.<br />

But She’s formulation “exchange-values are just relationships; they are not tangible. So, this<br />

would seem that we would need some<strong>thing</strong> concrete, or tangible, to base them on” caused<br />

me to think about it a little more deeply. Maybe the following thought is helpful: the exchange<br />

relationship is a social relation <strong>of</strong> production which is detached from the producers.<br />

<strong>The</strong> producers do not interact with each other directly but through their commodities. <strong>The</strong><br />

commodities are the conduit for this relationship. Electrons don’t care if the conductor is<br />

copper or aluminum or gold or saltwater, all they care about is that the circuit is not interrupted.<br />

In the same way, exchange-value does not care which use-value is its carrier or<br />

conduit—but a broken use-value or no use-value at all would be like an interrupted circuit.<br />

Message [309] referenced by [2012fa:19]. Next Message by Hans is [313].<br />

16 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 58 is 33 in 1998WI, 54 in 2007fa, 55 in 2008fa, and 60 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 58 <strong>The</strong> use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is the utility one gets from using it; the exchangevalue<br />

is the utility one gets from using those <strong>thing</strong>s one can trade the commodity for. Right<br />

or wrong?<br />

[65] Tyler: Utility in use-value and exchange-value. Simply put, the use-value and the<br />

exchange-value <strong>of</strong> any given commodity do not depend on the utility one gets from using it.<br />

It is explained in the readings that a use-value is “the body <strong>of</strong> the commodity, such as iron,<br />

wheat, diamond, etc.” [126:1]. On the other hand Marx describes the exchange-value as “the<br />

quantitative relation, the proportion, in which use-values <strong>of</strong> one sort are exchanged against<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> another sort” [126:2]. Utility refers to the amount <strong>of</strong> satisfaction one might<br />

receive from a given commodity, but according to Marx this has no effect on its inherent<br />

use-value or exchange-value.<br />

Hans: Your answer is basically right, see [68], but both <strong>of</strong> your Marx quotes are taken out <strong>of</strong> context. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong><br />

quote is not a definition <strong>of</strong> use-value itself but the convention to use the word “use-value” also for commodities<br />

as material objects, because people need these material objects only because <strong>of</strong> their use-values. See 127:4–128:1<br />

about this. And the second quote is not the definition <strong>of</strong> exchange-value but only the <strong>first</strong> form in which exchangevalue<br />

presents itself.<br />

Message [65] referenced by [67], [68], and [89]. Next Message by Tyler is [89].<br />

[67] Zarathustra: I think the answer is Yes. I read Tyler [65]. It is ambiguous (because<br />

he doesn’t say a straight Yes or No) but I think his answer is No. On the contrary, I think the<br />

answer is Yes.<br />

Next Message by Zarathustra is [72].<br />

[68] Hans: Marx does not define <strong>thing</strong>s through their effects on people. Tyler [65]<br />

only got the definition <strong>of</strong> use-value wrong, every<strong>thing</strong> else was right. I like to define the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity as the menu <strong>of</strong> its possible uses. Not the utility people get from<br />

it but what can be done with it. <strong>The</strong> question text gives two examples <strong>of</strong> anthropocentric<br />

definitions. This is how modern economics likes to do <strong>thing</strong>s, but Marx tried to look at<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s directly, not through the lens <strong>of</strong> human feelings <strong>of</strong> pleasure or discomfort.<br />

<strong>The</strong> anthropocentric view prevalent in modern economics assumes that humans are in the<br />

center <strong>of</strong> the universe. Acting as if humans were in the center <strong>of</strong> the universe while they are in<br />

reality one link in an interconnected ecological web can have disastrous consequences. This<br />

is apparent in environmental economics. This wrong-headed approach to the environment<br />

causes humans to saw <strong>of</strong>f the branch on which they are sitting.<br />

Message [68] referenced by [65], [72], and [401]. Next Message by Hans is [69].<br />

[72] Zarathustra: I’m still not convinced. In response to [68], I thought (and still think)<br />

the answer is Yes. However, I think someone could legitimately object to my answer and say:<br />

if exchange-value has a contradictory character (it’s rooted in some<strong>thing</strong> unchangeable—<br />

value—and is also determined differently in different contexts), the answer cannot be Yes.<br />

So, what is the answer?<br />

Hans: You are looking at the question from a deeper level than the level at which it was posed. <strong>The</strong>re are situations<br />

when exchange-value is determined on the market and not in production—for instance when toddlers trade toys<br />

in the sandbox. (This is why the parents undo the trades again afterwards: “you can’t give away your expensive<br />

handcrafted doll for for this cheap plastic airplane!”) Even in this situation, Marx would not define exchange-value<br />

by the utility which the traders get from the <strong>thing</strong>s traded. Please look again at my [68]. I added some text since it<br />

was in the archives. Maybe this will convince you now.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 17<br />

Next Message by Zarathustra is [73].<br />

[377] Oreo: graded A <strong>The</strong> use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is the utility that one gets from using<br />

it. Marx defines use-value as a menu <strong>of</strong> possible uses <strong>of</strong> the commodity. However, exchangevalue<br />

is not the utility one gets from using those <strong>thing</strong>s that one can trade the commodity for.<br />

Exchange-value is a social relation between commodities that allow them to be exchanged<br />

with each other or money. It is a way that commodities communicate, and does not have<br />

to do with the relationships <strong>of</strong> the commodity owners. <strong>The</strong>refore, exchange-value is not the<br />

use that an individual gets from using the <strong>thing</strong>s that they can trade the commodity for.<br />

Hans: You got the main point <strong>of</strong> the answer correctly (namely, the one about exchange-value). Regarding usevalue,<br />

if one wanted to be stickly one could argue that the menu <strong>of</strong> possible uses is different from the utility one<br />

gets from the commodity—but this is a finer point, and it is a good <strong>first</strong> approximation to say that they are identical.<br />

Message [377] referenced by [498], [2012fa:7], and [2012fa:610]. Next Message by Oreo is [378].<br />

[401] SMIKEC: <strong>The</strong> use value is the menu <strong>of</strong> possibilities, as stated by Hans in [68], that<br />

one gets from using a commodity. So it’s not the utility one gets from it but more <strong>of</strong> what<br />

can you do with it. Exchange value or simply value, is a commodity that can be taken to<br />

market in order to exchange for another commodity. An exchange value is still produced,<br />

even if it is never taken to market. Exchange value is created by the market and not socially<br />

determined. This is why it makes sense for an individual who has linen to exchange that<br />

for a coat. <strong>The</strong> tailor needs the linen and can make a coat more efficiently than you. If<br />

you kept making inefficient exchanges, at some point there wouldn’t be enough hours in the<br />

day to sustain your life due to the losses you suffered by not exchanging at all, or making<br />

poor exchanges <strong>of</strong> value out <strong>of</strong> the realm that the market put in place. As stated by Hans in<br />

[68], Marx does not define <strong>thing</strong>s through their effects on people, therefore utility is not a<br />

determining factor <strong>of</strong> use value or exchange value.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong>re are other ways to organize an economy with division <strong>of</strong> labor than a market.<br />

Next Message by SMIKEC is [402].<br />

[422] JB: graded A I think that what the question says is wrong. Use-value is the physical<br />

qualities <strong>of</strong> the commodity define its possible use-values. Use-values are human needs,<br />

wants or desires which the commodity can satisfy. <strong>The</strong> exchange-value is the amount <strong>of</strong> one<br />

commodity you can obtain in exchange for a definite amount <strong>of</strong> another commodity. It has<br />

no<strong>thing</strong> to do with utility.<br />

Next Message by JB is [424].<br />

[423] Bigwhite: Marx says that the double character <strong>of</strong> the commodity is the use-value<br />

and the exchange value. <strong>The</strong> exchange value is the relationship between two commodities.<br />

It is purely relative because it can be influenced by externalities. And the use value is the<br />

utility one gets from using said commodity. So I believe that it is a correct description <strong>of</strong> the<br />

two. This is different than what i wrote at <strong>first</strong>, yet says a lot <strong>of</strong> the same.<br />

Next Message by Bigwhite is [425].<br />

[437] Deadfamous: graded A– <strong>The</strong> First part <strong>of</strong> the question is correct. <strong>The</strong> Use-value<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity is the utility on gets from using the commodity. This is correct as long as<br />

the word utility is referring to “a use-value actualizes itself only by use or consumption <strong>of</strong><br />

itself.” For example, an ax does this when it chops down trees.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Second part I thought it was important to remind you that I asked you in class what<br />

the using was referring to in part 2 “the exchange-value is the utility one gets from using<br />

those <strong>thing</strong>s one can trade the commodity for. I asked Hans if using in this context is using<br />

18 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

for trade or consuming, he stated it was for consuming. I was not sure if this was a miscommunication<br />

but now I realize it was. So since we know that exchange-value in Marx’s mind<br />

means “the commodity’s ability to fetch other commodities in the market” is only right if<br />

we realize that he was speaking <strong>of</strong> trading.<br />

Hans: You originally had “a commodity actualizes itself,” I replaced “commodity” by “use-value.”<br />

Regarding your second part, there was no miscommunication. <strong>The</strong> question asks if exchange-value is the utility<br />

from consuming the traded <strong>thing</strong>s. It assumes you don’t want to trade them again but you traded or purchased them<br />

for consumption. <strong>The</strong> answer, as you say, is “no.”<br />

Next Message by Deadfamous is [441].<br />

[438] TINDOZ: <strong>The</strong> answer to this question is wrong. <strong>The</strong> use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is<br />

what it can possibly be used for. As such, a commodity could have multiple uses depending<br />

on the circumstances. For example, a Boston Cream Pie can be used to be eaten, or a clown<br />

could use it to smash into someone’s face as part <strong>of</strong> a performing sketch. It should however<br />

be noted that use values are not intertwined with utility as the question asks. Use value is all<br />

about what a commodity is used for (even if the intended or hopeful use is to not use it at<br />

all—as is the case <strong>of</strong> a nuclear weapon being used as a deterrent to aggressors simply by its<br />

existence being known to them).<br />

Exchange-value also has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with utility—neither the utility <strong>of</strong> the exchanged<br />

commodity or the utility <strong>of</strong> the received commodity (from the exchange). Marx defines exchange<br />

value as “the commodity’s ability to fetch other commodities in the market.” So<br />

exchange-value has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with either utility or use-value. A specific aspect <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange-value is that a commodity can be exchanged for all sorts <strong>of</strong> different items, for<br />

example a pair <strong>of</strong> sunglasses could be exchanged for another item <strong>of</strong> apparel, or it could be<br />

exchanged for concert tickets, or a textbook. <strong>The</strong> exchange value has every<strong>thing</strong> to do with<br />

what the commodity can be exchanged for—not the utility one gets from using the <strong>thing</strong>s<br />

one can trade the commodity for.<br />

Next Message by TINDOZ is [450].<br />

[460] Balrog: graded A Use-value, Exchange-value and Utility. This statement is<br />

wrong. <strong>The</strong> use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity are the few or seemingly endless uses a commodity<br />

possesses. Utility is the satisfaction that a person receives from using a particular commodity.<br />

Use-value does not involve the measurement <strong>of</strong> satisfaction that a person receives and<br />

thus does not deal with utility.<br />

Exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is the ability it has to be exchanged for other commodities.<br />

Exchange value is not derived from the utility <strong>of</strong> a commodity or how much people<br />

want it but is derived from the reaction people have to the labor inherent inside <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

Utility is more commonly associated with mainstream economics and not with what<br />

we have studied thus far in our Marxian Economics class.<br />

Next Message by Balrog is [621].<br />

[468] Zohan: This is a false statement. First <strong>of</strong> all, utility is generally used to describe<br />

the level <strong>of</strong> satisfaction that an individual experiences from using a commodity. According<br />

to Marx, the utility that one gets from the commodity does not determine its use-value or<br />

exchange-value. <strong>The</strong> use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is not the utility one receives from it, but<br />

can be thought <strong>of</strong> as “the menu <strong>of</strong> all the possible uses <strong>of</strong> the commodity.” If you were to


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 19<br />

measure a commodity’s use-value by its utility, essentially you would be saying that individuals<br />

could influence a commodity’s use-value, instead <strong>of</strong> its own usefulness. In addition,<br />

Marx introduces exchange-value as “the commodity’s ability to fetch other commodities in<br />

the market,” Hans [291]. Exchange-value doesn’t come from the use-value or the utility <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity, but from a “social custom.” Society determines a commodity’s exchange-value,<br />

not its utility.<br />

Hans: As I said in my notes to [336], you are right that exchange-value is a social relation, but society does not<br />

just pluck it out <strong>of</strong> thin air; it bases it on the abstract human labor in the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Zohan is [693].<br />

[488] Hit: That statement is right. Value is the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that goes into producing<br />

a commodity. A commodity is some<strong>thing</strong> that is human made by means <strong>of</strong> labor, regardless<br />

<strong>of</strong> whether it is actually ever used or traded. Use value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is the value one<br />

gets from using a commodity, example driving a car to work. Exchange value is value <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity one can receive for trading a commodity for another commodity.<br />

Hans: Your definition <strong>of</strong> commodity is wrong. It was already wrong in [253]. And What you call “value” in<br />

sentences 4 and 5 has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with what you call “value” in sentence 2.<br />

Next Message by Hit is [489].<br />

[498] Kohhep: <strong>The</strong> statement that exchange value is the utility one gets from using those<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s one can trade the commodity for is wrong. <strong>The</strong> former half <strong>of</strong> the full statement<br />

about use value is correct however. Exchange value is a commodity’s ability to fetch other<br />

commodities on the market. Exchange value has no relationship so use value otherwise.<br />

Thus, exchange value is not determined by use value.<br />

Hans: See my comments to [377].<br />

Next Message by Kohhep is [499].<br />

[509] Phayze: content A+ late penalty 1% Right and wrong. With respect to the definition<br />

<strong>of</strong> use-value, “the utility one gets from using it” would be a correct definition. Marx<br />

states that “<strong>The</strong> usefulness <strong>of</strong> a <strong>thing</strong> makes it a use-value” (Marx, 126). <strong>The</strong> description <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange-value is entirely wrong. Exchange value is the relative value <strong>of</strong> a commodity in<br />

relation to being exchanged for other commodities. Marx states that use-value is a “carrier”<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchange value (which denotes a weak link between the two), but otherwise they are two<br />

aspects that are entirely unrelated. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a commodity, which is “congealed abstract<br />

labor”, is created during the production process and manifested in exchange relations. <strong>The</strong><br />

two-fold character <strong>of</strong> labor produces both the use-value and the value-quasi material, but it<br />

is important to note that labor is not the the only requisite for the production <strong>of</strong> use-values...<br />

“We see then, that labor is not the only source <strong>of</strong> the use-values it produces or <strong>of</strong> material<br />

wealth. As William Petty puts it: labor is its father and the earth its mother”. In other words,<br />

nature also plays an important role in the production <strong>of</strong> use-values. Exchange value however,<br />

is the quantitative aspect <strong>of</strong> a commodity that is whispered through the production process<br />

and tumultuously expressed in the surface relations.<br />

Hans: I like your whisper metaphor.<br />

Next Message by Phayze is [737].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 60 is 26 in 1995WI, 37 in 1996sp, 35 in 1996ut, 32 in 1997ut, 39 in<br />

1999SP, 42 in 2001fa, 45 in 2003fa, 49 in 2004fa, 57 in 2007SP, 57 in 2008fa, 65 in<br />

2011fa, and 63 in 2012fa:<br />

20 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 60 Which empirical evidence might lead to the conclusion that exchangevalue<br />

is not some<strong>thing</strong> inherent in the commodity?<br />

[306] KA: I read 1.1.b. [From Exchange-Value to Value] to further understand what<br />

“exchange-value is not some<strong>thing</strong> inherent in the commodity” and made the connection<br />

between time and place; two variables not “inherent” in a commodity. I may be leading this<br />

answer in the wrong direction and would appreciate any <strong>of</strong> your suggestions.<br />

Marx states “a proportion which constantly changes with time and place.” illustrates that<br />

the same commodity trades in Country X may exchange in Country Y on completely different<br />

terms. This proportion change can also exist in time as well as place. For example, Year<br />

1 may have a completely different exchange-value than in Year 2, and can be <strong>of</strong>fset or even<br />

magnified due to location. <strong>The</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> time and place is not inherently obvious in the<br />

exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the same commodity may be a little lower this year than last year due to changes in productivity<br />

(learning by doing) etc., and a commodity may have different values in different countries which use different<br />

technologies. This is not what Marx means with a proportion which constantly changes between time and place.<br />

Marx is thinking <strong>of</strong> situations where the same commodity may be available at different prices in different stores in<br />

the same city, and next week one <strong>of</strong> the stores has a “sale” and the price changes again. Marx views this not as<br />

time-dependent prices but as randomly fluctuating prices, he uses the word “accidental.”<br />

Message [306] referenced by [312]. Next Message by KA is [370].<br />

[312] Orville: graded B Outside the Box. To add to KA’s comments in [306], I believe<br />

there is another good way to show that exchange-values are outside the commodity. Take<br />

movie popcorn for example. Suppose one was able to make a batch <strong>of</strong> popcorn and split it in<br />

half. If the supplier was able to sell that popcorn inside the theater, it would clearly sell for<br />

a higher price than if one was to sell it at a weight watchers, even if it were the same person<br />

buying popcorn at the theater or the weight watchers meeting. This means that although<br />

the use-values are the same and that the commodity is the same, the exchange value has<br />

changed. In order for this property to hold true, the exchange-value should stay the same as<br />

long as the commodity stays the same.<br />

Message [312] referenced by [315]. Next Message by Orville is [391].<br />

[315] Hans: Popcorn blockers. Orville’s example [312] is not one <strong>of</strong> fluctuating prices,<br />

but <strong>of</strong> prices being determined by some<strong>thing</strong> other than labor-time. Marx would say: instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> popcorn prices being higher in movie theatres than in weightwatcher meetings, the<br />

typical outcome would be that prices are the same but more popcorn will be available at<br />

a movie theatre than at a weight watcher meeting. <strong>The</strong> law <strong>of</strong> value is a tendential law.<br />

What I just described is the equilibrium situation which the economy would tend towards<br />

spontaneously. <strong>The</strong> theatre knows this, therefore they actively block this adjustment by not<br />

allowing competing vendors in the theatre and not even allowing the customers to bring their<br />

own popcorn. You might say that the signs at the door “don’t bring food into the premises”<br />

are evidence in favor <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory.<br />

According to Orville’s theory, one should go to weightwatcher meetings if one wants<br />

cheap popcorn. But if you actually go to a weightwatcher meeting, instead <strong>of</strong> cheap popcorn<br />

you will find no popcorn for sale at all. This again is evidence in favor <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory.<br />

Message [315] referenced by [442]. Next Message by Hans is [316].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 21<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 62 is 58 in 2007fa, 59 in 2008fa, and 70 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 62 In 126:2, Marx says that certain superficial evidence seems to indicate that<br />

exchange-values are accidental and relative. How much truth is there to this? To what<br />

extent are exchange-values indeed accidental, and to what extent are they indeed relative?<br />

(This question requires familiarity with <strong>thing</strong>s Marx says later.)<br />

[24] Lindsey: Despite short-term price variations, exchange-values are inherent. Certain<br />

“superficial evidence”, such as empirical evidence from the NYSE or any other recordkeeper<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodity prices through time would likely lead to the conclusion that exchangevalue<br />

is not some<strong>thing</strong> inherent in the commodity, but rather accidental and relative. <strong>The</strong>se<br />

numbers would show that over both long and short time-periods, the market price (or exchangevalue)<br />

<strong>of</strong> a specific commodity <strong>of</strong>ten varies greatly. For example, the market price <strong>of</strong> gold<br />

may have a daily trade range <strong>of</strong> one or two dollars on any given day, meaning that at one<br />

point in the day gold was worth 1 or 2 dollars more than it was worth at another point on<br />

the same day. This great and sudden variation <strong>of</strong> price does not seem to be justified by some<br />

change in the inherent qualities <strong>of</strong> the commodity because there couldn’t possibly have been<br />

such a sudden change in the these qualities in such a short time-period, but its exchangevalue<br />

changed nonetheless.<br />

From these great variations in exchange value (especially over short time-periods) comes<br />

the theory that value is accidental and relative, not intrinsic or inherent in the commodity.<br />

Marx disagrees with this conclusion, however, because he emphasizes that “valid exchangevalues”<br />

are the only comparable values. I would think that Marx would agree that the outside<br />

circumstances that sometimes affect exchange-value are “accidental” and the changes they<br />

cause in the exchange-values are relative, but when all variables (such as time and place<br />

or other “accidental” outside factors) are held constant, exchange values are inherent in the<br />

commodity. Robert’s [14] example <strong>of</strong> the drastic change in the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a bottle <strong>of</strong><br />

water in New Orleans right after Hurricane Katrina is a great example <strong>of</strong> how the presence <strong>of</strong><br />

“accidental” outside factors usually indicates the presence <strong>of</strong> great exchange-value relativity<br />

as well. Marx would argue that it is easy to confuse these sorts <strong>of</strong> extraneous circumstances<br />

to be pro<strong>of</strong> that exchange-values are relative, but in fact, when all other factors are held<br />

constant, the exchange value is inherent in the commodity and the production built into it.<br />

Hans: Very good. <strong>The</strong> reader might also find [2007fa:155] helpful.<br />

Message [24] referenced by [342] and [412]. Next Message by Lindsey is [44].<br />

[70] JJ: I believe that there is much truth to Marx’s statement that exchange values are<br />

both accidental and relative.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y are accidental to the extent that the exchange value depends upon the time and place<br />

and circumstances <strong>of</strong> the exchange. For example, the exchange value <strong>of</strong> gold to parachutes is<br />

very variable and accidental when one finds himself on a crippled airplane that is destined to<br />

crash. Versus this same exchange value when one finds himself with his feet firmly planted<br />

on the ground.<br />

Exchange values are also relative. We see that exchange values are relative to what is<br />

being exchanged. Gold for parachutes versus gold for silver gives us two different exchange<br />

values that are relative to what is being exchanged.<br />

Message [70] referenced by [71], [73], and [1173]. Next Message by JJ is [102].<br />

22 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[71] Hans: Someone Just Volunteered as a Guinea Pig! JJ’s answer [70] could have<br />

been written by someone who has not followed Marx’s argumentation or our discussion<br />

about it such as my [54]. This means JJ would not have received a good grade (fortunately<br />

it was submitted with the ug marker, so the grade will not count). On the other hand, we can<br />

still benefit from [70] because it is informative to compare Marx with what a modern naive<br />

observer <strong>of</strong> capitalism would say.<br />

JJ does not bring evidence from market exchanges in capitalism but he is trying to tell<br />

us that anybody would be willing to voluntarily trade their parachute away while sitting in a<br />

crippled airplane that is going to crash.<br />

From this we can draw two lessons:<br />

(1) Marx does not take it for granted that goods are exchangeable—while modern young<br />

people growing up in capitalism are taught that exchange is the most natural <strong>thing</strong> in the<br />

world. <strong>The</strong> crippled airplane is only the most bizarre example showing how ingrained it<br />

is in us to think that exchanges happen always and everywhere. Another situation where<br />

there are no exchanges is inside a business, or also inside a community in which everyone<br />

works together for the common good. Say a peasant family where everyone is assigned<br />

specific chores. <strong>The</strong> son is making apple cider while his little sister is carefully collecting<br />

eggs from the chicken house. <strong>The</strong> son would never get the idea to trade a cup <strong>of</strong> cider<br />

against an egg, because he would not consider the cup <strong>of</strong> cider his private property which he<br />

had the authority to trade away or to withhold from his sister. If the sister were thirsty she<br />

would get the cider from him without trading, and in the evening everybody is sitting around<br />

the dinner table eating eggs and drinking cider. <strong>The</strong>se <strong>thing</strong>s are considered to belong to<br />

everyone and are not the private property <strong>of</strong> any one family member. (Of course the letters<br />

from his girlfriend are the son’s personal property and he is carefully guarding those and<br />

will not share them.) Very specific social structures are necessary for exchanges to happen<br />

and to become as common as in modern capitalism. Marx is looking at these structures.<br />

(2) Marx is actually looking at capitalism itself to make his inferences (although his argumentation<br />

is so abstract and sophisticated that this may not be readily apparent), while JJ’s<br />

arguments come from childish fables in introductory economics books. <strong>The</strong>se introductory<br />

books show what an ideology has to do if it wants to pose as a science. <strong>The</strong>y are written in<br />

such a way that the reader must think: yes <strong>of</strong> course, this is how it is—and they are carefully<br />

hiding the tacit assumptions necessary to make these fables plausible. <strong>The</strong> utility theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> value is only plausible to someone who has <strong>thing</strong>s but not the ability to produce these<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s (i.e., lacks access to the means <strong>of</strong> production), and the whole idea that prices ultimately<br />

derive from individual preferences overlooks that we all are embedded in a powerful<br />

social structure which has its own dynamic—which we through our individual actions are<br />

unwittingly recreating but which we have little control over.<br />

Let me repeat: don’t feel bad if I am critical <strong>of</strong> what you are saying. A Marxist would<br />

say your mistakes are not your fault. You live in a social structure which does not readily<br />

reveal its true character (we will hear more about this when we talk about the fetish-like<br />

character <strong>of</strong> commodities), and whose ruling class (yes we are a class society) subjects you,<br />

in addition, to carefully orchestrated indoctrination. It is never pleasant to become aware


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 23<br />

<strong>of</strong> this. Marx wrote Capital because he thought the victims <strong>of</strong> capitalism must understand<br />

capitalism in order to be able to overcome it.<br />

Message [71] referenced by [75] and [1173]. Next Message by Hans is [75].<br />

[73] Zarathustra: (graded A) It seems to me Marx is using his dialectical reasoning here,<br />

that is, to illustrate both sides <strong>of</strong> a <strong>thing</strong> (phenomenon, etc). Exchange-value (EV) as JJ [70]<br />

said “[is] accidental to the extent that the exchange value depends upon the time and place<br />

and circumstances <strong>of</strong> the exchange.” I cannot argue against that. I think Marx would say it<br />

is true, but it is only one side <strong>of</strong> the EV. This is the social (from outside) aspect <strong>of</strong> EV.<br />

EV also has an essential/natural (from within) aspect. EV is only a reflection <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong><br />

deeper. Let me rephrase this. It is rather a deflection <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> deeper. This deeper<br />

<strong>thing</strong> is at the core <strong>of</strong> a given human-made commodity and is totally independent to the<br />

circumstances <strong>of</strong> the circulation. It is some<strong>thing</strong> implanted in the process <strong>of</strong> production. If<br />

this reasoning is valid, I think, Marx is talking about human labor power embedded in a<br />

commodity.<br />

Hans: Very good. I made some small edits, hoping to clarify what you wanted to say.<br />

Next Message by Zarathustra is [79].<br />

[342] Cmellen: graded B– Marx believes that exchange value seems to indicate it is accidental<br />

and relative. He originally came to the conclusion that exchange value was attached<br />

to a commodity, but then later realized that it is a relation and cannot be accredited to any<br />

one commodity alone. He points out that exchange proportions are relative in the sense they<br />

are affected by external conditions. <strong>The</strong>se external conditions consist <strong>of</strong> various time and<br />

place. <strong>The</strong> very same commodity can possibly have a different exchange value at different<br />

proportions. <strong>The</strong> proportion is constantly changing due to the time and place. Marx states<br />

the exchange value SEEMS accidental; this is due to the limited viewpoint at which was<br />

obtained in his <strong>first</strong> manifestation <strong>of</strong> exchange value. (Das Kapital 1.1 Use-Value and Value<br />

pg 21-22)<br />

Hans: You are describing the superficial evidence which makes exchange-value seem accidental and relative. But<br />

you are misunderstanding Marx’s argument. Marx did not change his mind, he describes here a contradictory state<br />

<strong>of</strong> affairs. Marx’s position is that those who say that exchange-value is inherent in the commodity are at least<br />

partially right, and those who say that exchange-value is completely relative and accidental are also partially right.<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 62 wants you to identify what is right in the latter position. Lindsey [24] says that there are accidental<br />

outside factors (Katrina) which might detract exchange-value from their normal level. Another factor might be<br />

technological change. <strong>The</strong>se are the <strong>thing</strong>s you should have said in this answer. Your in-class answer describes<br />

one mechanism which makes exchange-value variable: “a commodity may lose its use-value.” You should not have<br />

dropped this but maintained it in your resubmission. Apparently when you re-read Marx’s text you forgot what the<br />

question was and simply tried to summarize Marx’s text.<br />

Next Message by Cmellen is [564].<br />

[412] Tyler: Accidental and Relative. Marx says there may be some superficial evidence<br />

which indicate exchange values are accidental and relative because prices <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

through time may change. Lindsey [24], in her post to the class uses the NYSE as an example<br />

<strong>of</strong> how the price <strong>of</strong> a commodity will change over time, which would lead some to<br />

believe the “exchange value is not some<strong>thing</strong> inherent in the commodity, but rather accidental<br />

and relative.” <strong>The</strong> fact that prices may differ depending on time and location suggests that<br />

exchange values are not inherent. As was pointed out in my original answer, circumstances<br />

such as a hurricane can affect an exchange value accidentally and the resulting price changes<br />

caused are relative. Again, I feel Lindsey [24] describes the situation best when she states,<br />

24 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

“when all other factors are held constant, the exchange value is inherent in the commodity<br />

and the production built into it.”<br />

Next Message by Tyler is [414].<br />

[451] Alex: graded A– Marx indicates that exchange values or prices are both accidental<br />

and relative, which is indicated by the superficial evidence. At <strong>first</strong>, I did not understand<br />

what he was referring to with the “superficial evidence” but Hans helped me to understand<br />

this concept by deciphering what Marx meant. Prices are accidental because in capitalism,<br />

prices <strong>of</strong> similar commodities vary throughout stores, or markets, but this variation <strong>of</strong> prices<br />

is not only ok with the consumers, but it is also beneficial for the market. One simple<br />

example that made me grasp my head around this concept more clearly was that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

milk prices being different in different stores according to Hans. He states that milk, or any<br />

commodity, has the given price according to the circumstances surrounding it. Another great<br />

example <strong>of</strong> this was made by Robert when he said that after Hurricane Katrina, bottled water<br />

would undergo a change in its price excessively because <strong>of</strong> the current circumstances. When<br />

Marx talks about relative prices <strong>of</strong> commodities, he is referring to the exchange relation<br />

between two commodities, and these exchange relations are exterior surface manifestations<br />

<strong>of</strong> intrinsic values, also as explained by Hans. Producers <strong>of</strong> the same commodities have<br />

similar production costs (the socially necessary labor time to produce the commodity), which<br />

also makes the prices relative to one another. In my conclusion, commodities can have<br />

both the accidental and relative exchange values, which is what makes them belong in a<br />

capitalistic market system (as opposed to Hans example <strong>of</strong> the socialist market where people<br />

were astonished that milk had different prices at one point back in Germany).<br />

Next Message by Alex is [524].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 64 is 61 in 2008SP and 61 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 64 Marx discusses at length the question whether value is intrinsic to the commodity<br />

or relative. What is the view <strong>of</strong> mainstream economics? Does it consider value to be<br />

intrinsic or relative?<br />

[13] Lana: Intrinsic vs. Relative Value. Marx has the theory <strong>of</strong> thought that value<br />

is relative to a commodity. “Hence exchange-value seems to be some<strong>thing</strong> accidental and<br />

purely relative. A ‘valeur intrinsèque,’ i.e. an immanent exchange-value, that resides in the<br />

commodities, seems therefore a contradiction in terms.” [126:2] According to Hans’ Annotations,<br />

a commodity’s worth is measured by its interactions with other commodities, and not<br />

intrinsically. On the opposing side, mainstream economic theory has adopted the concept<br />

that value is, in fact, quantified intrinsically. According to the “common consciousness,”<br />

the worth <strong>of</strong> the commodity is in the actual good/service/etc itself, ignoring the relationship<br />

between other commodities. Marx claims this is a mass misunderstanding and this method<br />

<strong>of</strong> thought can be attributed to peoples’ contradictory “lived experiences.”<br />

Hans: Your conclusions are wrong as I try to explain in [23]. But since you have backed up your conclusions with<br />

quotes from Marx and the Annotations, your grade is not as bad as one might guess from reading [23]. Generally,<br />

in this class, the more verbal abuse you get from me disecting your essay, the less I feel I have to signal to you<br />

through a low grade that some<strong>thing</strong> is wrong.<br />

Message [13] referenced by [20], [23], [25], [42], and [426]. Next Message by Lana is [45].<br />

[20] Zarathustra: (graded B) Intrinsic vs. Relative Value. I thought <strong>of</strong> the question 64<br />

and Lana’s note [13] helped me to understand it better. But it also made me think differently.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 25<br />

For instance, say, I am a baker and you are a shoemaker. I spend two hours in making a loaf<br />

<strong>of</strong> bread and sell it to you for $10, and you spend two hours in making a pair <strong>of</strong> shoe that<br />

I will buy for $20. Does it mean that your labor is more valuable than mine? It is true the<br />

value is relative, but doesn’t mean that considering value relative mean we will have to value<br />

people differently? Is that what Marx meant, or what capitalism is?<br />

That would be great, if Lana or anyone could answer that.<br />

Hans: You missed the mistakes in [13] and although there are a few subtle and difficult answers outstanding which<br />

cry out for feedback, you are trying to start an entirely new discussion (which seems, by the way, related to your<br />

[2009fa:96]). Zarathustra is one <strong>of</strong> my graduate student co-teachers.<br />

Next Message by Zarathustra is [21].<br />

[23] Hans: Now it’s Intrinsic, now it’s Relative. Lana [13] has <strong>thing</strong>s exactly backwards,<br />

but she supports her wrong conclusions with quotes from Marx and from my Annotations—<br />

i.e., with the highest authority in this class. This must be confusing. I imagine it must be<br />

even more confusing for you that others don’t call Lana out on her mistakes but instead, as<br />

Zarathstra [32] did, say that [13] helped him understand <strong>thing</strong>s better. <strong>The</strong>refore let’s sort<br />

out what is right and what is wrong in [13]:<br />

[13] says that in Marx’s theory value is some<strong>thing</strong> relative. Wrong. In Marx’s theory,<br />

value is intrinsic, it is based on a commodity’s labor content which is inside the commodity.<br />

(This is what “intrinsic” means.) More details in my [2008fa:46].<br />

BUT [13] brings a quote where Marx is obviously down on an intrinsic value and seems to<br />

promote that value is relative. That is exactly why I said on Friday in class that the readings<br />

assigned this weekend are so interesting. I will not go more into this at the moment, because<br />

right now I don’t want you to forget that Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> value is intrinsic, not relative.<br />

[13] also says that modern mainstream economic theory (i.e. the stuff with the utility<br />

functions and demand and supply) has an intrinsic concept <strong>of</strong> value. Wrong again. In mainstream<br />

theory, the market value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is determined by marginal utility, i.e., by<br />

how much people want this commodity. This is a relative concept: value does not lie in the<br />

commodity itself but in the people desiring the commodity. If you don’t want it its value<br />

disappears. Po<strong>of</strong>. You cannot get more relative than that.<br />

BUT [13] says that it is part <strong>of</strong> common consciousness that the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity lies<br />

in the <strong>thing</strong> itself. Well, this means that the common consciousness does not always conform<br />

with mainstream economic theory. <strong>The</strong> po<strong>of</strong>! theory <strong>of</strong> value is so absurd that people only<br />

sometimes believe it (for instance when they are in an Econ 101 exam) but <strong>of</strong>ten they don’t<br />

believe it. Not even the mainstream believes it all the time. Accountants don’t have a po<strong>of</strong>!<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> value, but they have an intrinsic theory <strong>of</strong> value. More details in [2008SP:18].<br />

Message [23] referenced by [13], [25], [33], [36], and [42]. Next Message by Hans is [26].<br />

[25] David: Relative, intrinsic? No, just dialectics. Some <strong>of</strong> the answers (and responses)<br />

given to this question, particularly [13] and [23] seem to highlight the apparent<br />

contradiction pointed out by Marx. Overcoming this confusion, and finding a possible<br />

answer to the question at hand, require a basic understanding <strong>of</strong> what Marx is doing<br />

here. He is engaging in a dialectical examination <strong>of</strong> commodities in a capitalist system.<br />

Dialectics is, as Hans points out in the Annotations, “the discovery <strong>of</strong> contradictions”<br />

as well as “their subsequent resolution.” (For a good definition <strong>of</strong> dialectics, visit<br />

26 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

http://www.philosophybasics.com/general glossary.html). <strong>The</strong> contradiction is made clear<br />

by Marx, and further highlighted by <strong>Question</strong> 64. As dialectics consists <strong>of</strong> a proposal,<br />

counter-proposal, and resolution, I would suggest that there is a dialectical resoultion harmonizing<br />

the two contradictory statements.<br />

First, in order to be as precise as possible, let us assume that when <strong>Question</strong> 64 says<br />

“value” it is actually referring to “exchange-value,” as that is the subject discussed in the<br />

preceding paragraphs and questions in the Annotations. Next, examining the proposal <strong>of</strong><br />

relative value, Marx states that the exchange value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is “the proportion, in<br />

which use-values <strong>of</strong> one sort are exchanged against use-values <strong>of</strong> another sort” – sort here<br />

meaning commodity. As this proportion is determined by its location in time and space, it<br />

can vary. Hence value is relative. This is widely acknowledged in mainstream economics<br />

by what Hans refers to as the “po<strong>of</strong>! theory <strong>of</strong> value” in [23].<br />

In apparent contrast, the intrinsic value counter-proposal suggests that because exchangevalue<br />

is “carried” by use-value in a commodity, it is inherent in the commodity. However,<br />

simply because the property <strong>of</strong> exchange-value is intrinsic, the quantity may not necessarily<br />

be (although this fact may <strong>of</strong>ten be overlooked by the “common consciousness” Lana refers<br />

to in [13]). Thus the resolution <strong>of</strong> contradictions sought after by dialectics arising is that<br />

the property <strong>of</strong> exchange-value is inherent in a commodity, assuming the use-value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity is greater than zero, i.e. it always has the potential to be exchanged, but the<br />

quantity measuring that exchange value is relative and may fluctuate by circumstance. (I<br />

think this is what Hans is stating, though in a more succinct manner, in his response to<br />

Ziggy in [2008fa:78]<br />

This fact though <strong>of</strong>ten unstated and overlooked is, I believe, intuitively understood by<br />

mainstream economists. This is especially probable given that they analyze society from<br />

a scarcity standpoint, as scarcity would tend to reduce the possiblity <strong>of</strong> commodities being<br />

viewed as having zero use-value, a logical pre-requisite to an exchange-value.<br />

As a final disclaimer, I recognize that Marx put forth intrinsic exchange-value as the<br />

initial thesis and relative exchange-value as the counter-thesis in his investigation. I have<br />

set them forth in the opposite order here for the sake <strong>of</strong> developing an easily-comprehended<br />

dialectic argument.<br />

Hans: Your Philosophy Web Site defines dialectics as: “the exchange <strong>of</strong> arguments and counter-arguments, respectively<br />

advocating propositions (theses) and counter-propositions (antitheses), in arriving at a conclusion (synthesis).”<br />

I.e., dialectics is defined here as a debate. <strong>The</strong>re is also a stronger view <strong>of</strong> dialectics, which not only says<br />

that theories <strong>of</strong> the world may be in contradiction with each other, but that the world itself may be in contradiction<br />

with each other. Marx holds this stronger view <strong>of</strong> dialectics. In this view, a contradiction is not sign <strong>of</strong> a confusion,<br />

but a real aspect <strong>of</strong> the world.<br />

You say that the exchange-proportion is “determined by its location in time and space.” Marx would disagree.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fact that you can draw a timeseries <strong>of</strong> prices does not mean that prices are determined by time. Marx holds the<br />

view that not every<strong>thing</strong> in the world is determined, but some <strong>thing</strong>s are indeterminate or “accidental.” Inventing a<br />

determination where none exists is an <strong>of</strong>ten-made error in mainstream economics, and it is a version <strong>of</strong> actualism,<br />

see [2009fa:383] about it.<br />

In Marx’s view, the fact that use-value is the carrier <strong>of</strong> exchange-value does not make exchange-value intrinsic.<br />

<strong>The</strong> word “carrier” means that a commodity must have a use-value in order to have exchange-value, but that<br />

nevertheless the use-value does not determine the exchange-value. I think this is what you mean when you say that<br />

the quantity <strong>of</strong> value is not intrinsic. I.e., that what you <strong>of</strong>fer as the reconciliation would for a Marxist be the thesis<br />

<strong>of</strong> a relative exchange-value.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 27<br />

Marx’s position is that exchange-value is intrinsic even though it does not depend on the physical properties <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity. Instead it depends on the amount <strong>of</strong> (direct and indirect) labor necessary to produce the commodity.<br />

[29] Kraken: graded B Value - intrinsic or relative? Marx believed that the value <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity was immanent or intrinsic to that commodity. While it is true that every commodity<br />

has a certain amount <strong>of</strong> built-in value due to its utility, mainstream economics does<br />

not attach value to an item by looking at its intrinsic value, but rather by looking at how<br />

much <strong>of</strong> another commodity (namely money) it can be exchanged for. This exchange rate<br />

changes over time relative to people’s demand for certain items. An example <strong>of</strong> this would<br />

be some investment property which I purchased several years ago, before our current economic<br />

recession. Before the housing market crashed, I could have easily sold the property to<br />

another investor who was hoping to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it in real estate. Now, although the property<br />

still has the same intrinsic value and still provides the same utility and shelter for those who<br />

live there, the exchange value <strong>of</strong> the property has fallen. Relative to other investments and<br />

necessities <strong>of</strong> life, the value <strong>of</strong> the property has changed regardless <strong>of</strong> its intrinsic value.<br />

Hans: You are right, in Marx’s theory commodities have intrinsic values which determine their exchange relations.<br />

But this intrinsic value has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with use-value. It comes from the direct and indirect labor content <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodities.<br />

Message [29] referenced by [33] and [41]. Next Message by Kraken is [60].<br />

[33] Babyceta: graded A+ Intrinsic v. relative: Marx and the Mainstream. <strong>The</strong> relative<br />

(subjective) theory <strong>of</strong> value, held by many mainstream economists including Bentham,<br />

Marginalists, and many Austrian school economists asserts that there is no intrinsic value<br />

contained in commodities. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a commodity, they contend, is subjectively determined<br />

by scarcity and/or the ability <strong>of</strong> a commodity to satisfy human wants (not determined<br />

by price, as Kraken contends in [29]). It is therefore subjective because individuals in the<br />

market determine the value <strong>of</strong> commodities based on the personal beliefs or needs, and do<br />

not consider the “production perspective” or the labor embodied when determining value.<br />

For example, I may value a pair <strong>of</strong> shoes more if I am shoeless than someone else in the<br />

market who dons a perfectly good pair <strong>of</strong> shoes. But not everyone is shoeless so their value<br />

cannot be determined by my unique and unfortunate situation. And price is merely the<br />

mechanism <strong>of</strong> communication between buyer and seller; it has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with value. My<br />

desire or need only gives value to the object. Price (or money) was itself a “special commodity”<br />

that was generally used as a numeraire. Marx calls this special commodity the “third<br />

<strong>thing</strong>” [Capital 127:2].<br />

Marx, however, believed commodities held intrinsic value in the form <strong>of</strong> embodied labor.<br />

“This property [use-value] <strong>of</strong> a commodity is independent <strong>of</strong> the amount <strong>of</strong> labour required<br />

to appropriate its useful qualities” [126:1]. Exchange-value, to Marx, was completely separate<br />

from use-value. Use-values differ in quality, says Marx, and are only realized in use or<br />

in consumption [126:1]. “If we disregard the use-value <strong>of</strong> commodities,” Marx says, “only<br />

one property remains, that <strong>of</strong> being products <strong>of</strong> labour” [128:2]. It is the common denominator<br />

<strong>of</strong> all commodities, whether useful or not, and since all commodities are produced for<br />

exchange, they all have intrinsic value in the form <strong>of</strong> labor and labor only.<br />

Hans explained much <strong>of</strong> this in [23], but I would like to elaborate on the social nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> embodied labor. Labor, too, like commodities, contained not only quantitative aspects,<br />

but qualitative as well. According to E.K. Hunt, Marx defined value as “a qualitative social<br />

28 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

relation with a quantitative dimension.” For example, if I consume a product your labor has<br />

produced, we are in a sense dependent on each other. However, I will, most likely, be unaware<br />

<strong>of</strong> that relationship. Although your social labor gave intrinsic value to the commodity<br />

I purchased and consumed, our connection was reduced to an abstraction. I believe Marx<br />

advances the theory <strong>of</strong> intrinsic (labor) value to set the stage for abstract labor (if commodities<br />

have certain unique characteristics then so, too, must labor) and subsequently capitalist<br />

labor relations. But I am probably getting way ahead <strong>of</strong> myself here.<br />

Message [33] referenced by [34], [36], [41], and [42]. Next Message by Babyceta is [55].<br />

[34] Kat: Marx considers the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity to be intrinsic because the only<br />

determinant <strong>of</strong> value is the labor necessary to produce it. Mainstream economics, on the<br />

other hand, considers the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity to rely solely on what a consumer is willing<br />

to pay for it. That is, if consumers are not willing to pay any<strong>thing</strong> for a given good, it is<br />

worthless. This school <strong>of</strong> thought would argue that the fluctuations <strong>of</strong> supply and demand<br />

determine where prices <strong>of</strong> a commodity will land and these price fluctuations would not be<br />

possible if a commodity’s value was inherent. So, the value <strong>of</strong> a good is strictly relative to<br />

the market forces surrounding it.<br />

Hans: You mis-characterize mainstream economics. As Babyceta remarked correctly in [33], mainstream economics<br />

does not say value is determined by price. This would be a circular definition. Value is determined by<br />

utility functions and production functions and endowments.<br />

You also mis-characterize Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> an inherent price. It does not mean the price is fixed according<br />

to labor input ignoring demand and supply. Marx thinks that the spontaneous play <strong>of</strong> competition in the long run<br />

drives prices to a level where they are proportional to labor inputs.<br />

Message [34] referenced by [36] and [41]. Next Message by Kat is [204].<br />

[36] Kohhep: intrinsic vs. relative. Modern economics view the value <strong>of</strong> commodities to<br />

be relative based on what society is willing to give (usually money) for the item (or service).<br />

Although mainstream economics weighs certain <strong>thing</strong>s like labor into the exchange value,<br />

but ultimately, as Hans put it in [23], the “po<strong>of</strong>! theory <strong>of</strong> value” is put in. I’m still working<br />

on getting my head around on how to absorb these ideas and such, and also how to present<br />

them. Any guidance or constructive critiquing would be very helpful!<br />

Hans: Your <strong>first</strong> sentence is very similar to the sentence “Mainstream economics, on the other hand, considers the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> a commodity to rely solely on what a consumer is willing to pay for it” in [34]. If you repeat some<strong>thing</strong><br />

just said in the discussion, you will not get credit for it. You are expected to build on the answers <strong>of</strong> others. Since<br />

Babyceta said in [33] that value is not determined by price, there would have been a great opportunity to argue that<br />

willingness to pay is not the same as price, or that Babyceta is wrong.<br />

Also please try to be precise in your formulations. What do you mean by “putting in” a theory?<br />

Message [36] referenced by [41] and [42]. Next Message by Kohhep is [61].<br />

[40] Pweber: Intrinsic Value. As others have said, Marx considers the value <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

as intrinsic: “Now we know the substance <strong>of</strong> value. It is labour. We know the measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> its magnitude. It is labor time.” Although that statement by itself does not bestow inherent<br />

intrinsic value, Marx’s argument further establishes the relationship between labor time<br />

and the value it bestows upon commodities–a diamond is very valuable relative to the same<br />

quantity <strong>of</strong> other commodities because <strong>of</strong> the labor time required to extract diamond.<br />

Modern economic thought does not address labor value directly, at least in the way Marx<br />

frames the question. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is determined through the supply <strong>of</strong> a product<br />

and its inverse relationship to the demand <strong>of</strong> the product–price is only an agreed upon<br />

valuation, not necessarily value by itself. If the equilibrium value <strong>of</strong> fire-roasted tater tots is


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 29<br />

20 bags <strong>of</strong> the stuff, then that’s its value in that market. If a market exists that is addicted<br />

to fire-roasted tater tots (it has inelastic demand), then the “value” <strong>of</strong> the tater tots is higher<br />

compared to the <strong>first</strong> market, because there is more demand for the product, the supply is<br />

higher, and the “price” is higher.<br />

I’m interested to see how Marx addresses the value <strong>of</strong> labor. In this section <strong>of</strong> reading, he<br />

says that, “<strong>The</strong> total labour-power <strong>of</strong> society, which is manifested in the values <strong>of</strong> the world<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities, counts here as one homogenous mass <strong>of</strong> human labour-power, although<br />

composed <strong>of</strong> innumerable individual units <strong>of</strong> labour-power. Each <strong>of</strong> these units is the same<br />

as any other, to the extent that it...is socially necessary.” Modern economic thought ascribes<br />

value to labor power through the same means it ascribes value to commodities–through<br />

supply and demand. It would be difficult to argue that an engineer has equal labor value to a<br />

cashier; there is a scarce supply <strong>of</strong> engineers relative to a cashier, and as such they have more<br />

value to society than a cashier does (and this is reflected not only in their product, but also<br />

their wages). It seems that Marx’s model, as it stands, runs the risk <strong>of</strong> being as marginal as<br />

he says use-value and exchange-value are, because there is no built-in method <strong>of</strong> ascribing<br />

value to labor.<br />

Hans: Very thoughtful.<br />

Message [40] referenced by [41]. Next Message by Pweber is [127].<br />

[41] Hans: How to avoid circularity in a theory <strong>of</strong> value. In quick succession, Kraken<br />

[29], Kat [34], and Kohhep [36] said that in mainstream economics value is determined by<br />

price or the “willingness to pay”—although Babyceta [33] rightly protested that this is not<br />

the case. And it is my mistake to begin my commentary to Kraken [29] with the words “you<br />

are right” and not pointing out his error.<br />

In economics, a “value theory” is a theory which shows the ultimate reasons why prices<br />

in economics are what they are. Saying prices are determined by “willingness to pay” is<br />

not satisfactory, because then you have to ask: where does this willingness to pay come<br />

from? It is certainly not in your genes or psychological makeup. Mainstream economics<br />

says that prices are determined by utility functions, production functions, and endowments.<br />

This is far enough removed from the economy that you can get a non-circular definition.<br />

<strong>The</strong> assumption there is that people’s utility functions do not depend on their incomes but<br />

only on some inborn preferences or tastes. If the utility function changed with income, then<br />

we would be back to circularity because that what supposedly determines prices depends on<br />

prices.<br />

Pweber [40] surmised that Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> value might be defective because it does not<br />

tell us what the value <strong>of</strong> labor is. But if labor is the source <strong>of</strong> value then labor cannot have<br />

value itself, otherwise we are again in a circular theory. This will be discussed in much more<br />

detail when we read chapters 6 and 19.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [42].<br />

[42] Hans: Some Practical Matters. In his answer to question 64, Kohhep [36] is having<br />

difficulties with the material and is asking how to study. Here are some hints:<br />

(1) If you have difficulties with the material then you should come to class. You can ask<br />

questions there, and I always try to explain <strong>thing</strong>s as simply as I can.<br />

30 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(2) Answer questions which are very specific about Marx’s argumentation. Alex [31]<br />

tried his / her hand on a very specific question, and got a detailed response from me in [33].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 64 is not terribly good for understanding Marx better, because it does not really<br />

talk about Marx but about mainstream economics. <strong>The</strong> best answer came from Babyceta<br />

[33], and she learned it from Kay Hunt and not in this class here.<br />

(3) Whenever you make an assertion, try to back it up as well as you can. Lana did this<br />

in her answer [13] to this question here, and she got a detailed response from me in [23].<br />

(4) Don’t try to guess what I want to hear but rely on your own thinking.<br />

(5) Carefully read all the submissions I make to the class. I try to address those issues<br />

which people seem to be struggling with.<br />

(6) Before you answer the question you selected, look at all the earlier answers this Semester<br />

and my comments to them. I make lots <strong>of</strong> comments which are never sent to class but<br />

which are in the pdf transcript <strong>of</strong> the class. Download this transcript regularly. I personally<br />

like the screen version better than the halfpage version: it is at<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/screen/2010fa.pdf<br />

(7) Submit questions with the ug marker (as I did with this one here) so that they are<br />

ungraded. You will still get comments from me and an informational grade. Alex [31] was<br />

an ungraded question. If the grade is in parentheses you know the question is ungraded.<br />

Submitting questions with the ug marker has an additional advantage: you can submit<br />

them even after the deadline, and you get credit for it as a free discussion contribution.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [50].<br />

[346] Somramthom: Exchange value. Just making sure I am getting all <strong>of</strong> this.<br />

For most <strong>of</strong> us in a capitalistic society, it is easy to see the exchange value <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

We therefore think that it is intrinsic to the commodity. While it isn’t intrinsic, the expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity’s exchange value shows the labor content <strong>of</strong> a commodity, or its value. <strong>The</strong><br />

labor content <strong>of</strong> a commodity is intrinsic to the commodity.<br />

This misunderstanding <strong>of</strong> intrinsicity seems to stem from the type <strong>of</strong> consumers most<br />

capitalistic consumers are. We are mainly consumers with little or no sense <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

It is largely unknown to us. It is therefore difficult for us to determine a commodity’s value<br />

through an assessment <strong>of</strong> labor input.<br />

We use exchange value as a medium to display and understand the commodity’s value<br />

just as an artist uses a canvas as a medium to display his artistic abilities.<br />

Message [346] referenced by [347]. Next Message by Somramthom is [458].<br />

[347] Hans: For Somramthom. If you want to make sure you are catching the meaning<br />

<strong>of</strong> Marx’s writings, you have to rid yourself <strong>of</strong> the notion that Marx’s Capital says what a<br />

commodity-producing society should look like.<br />

If I understand your [346] right, it is based on a serious misunderstanding <strong>of</strong> Marx’s<br />

theory. You are saying the true value <strong>of</strong> commodities is their labor content. We do not<br />

value <strong>thing</strong>s at their true values because we usually cannot judge how much labor some<strong>thing</strong>


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 31<br />

contains. <strong>The</strong>refore we use exchange-value which reflects not the true value <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s but<br />

which reflects our valuation <strong>of</strong> the use-values <strong>of</strong> the <strong>thing</strong>s.<br />

I am not sure if this is what you meant, but here is what Marx’s theory really says. Marx<br />

says that despite the fact that people do not know much about production and make their<br />

individual purchasing decisions based on their preferences, the market outcomes arising<br />

spontaneously behind their backs from demand and supply and the reactions <strong>of</strong> the producers<br />

to the market outcomes is that exchange value is determined by labor content.<br />

<strong>The</strong> problem with our separation from the means <strong>of</strong> production is not, as you say, that it<br />

prevents us from knowing the labor content—it is not necessary for the consumers to know<br />

the labor content—but that it makes a utility theory <strong>of</strong> value plausible which keeps supply<br />

fixed and therefore leaves out the adjustment <strong>of</strong> the producers to the market. This is what I<br />

said in [54].<br />

Next Message by Hans is [358].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 65 is 36 in 1996ut, 33 in 1997ut, 62 in 2008SP, and 73 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 65 Formulate in your own words the two contradictory statements Marx makes<br />

about the commodity when he introduces exchange-value.<br />

[353] Wolf: When Marx <strong>first</strong> introduced the commodity, he noted that it appeared as<br />

if exchange-value was inherent to the commodity, otherwise how could commodities be<br />

exchanged (because they must have some equal substance in order to be exchanged), and<br />

that, on the other hand, exchange-value appeared to be entirely relative and based on other<br />

commodities, subject to fluctuation. A commodity wouldn’t have an exchange-value if it<br />

was in isolation from every other commodity. This is the contradiction that Marx notes. He<br />

later deduced that this contradiction is merely a surface expression <strong>of</strong> the substance <strong>of</strong> value<br />

(composed <strong>of</strong> congealed abstract labor) and the magnitude <strong>of</strong> value (measured by sociallynecessary<br />

labor time).<br />

Next Message by Wolf is [354].<br />

[371] Atticus: graded A Marx forms two contradictory ideas about the concept <strong>of</strong> exchangevalue.<br />

First he claims that it is a volatile relation between all commodities and then he claims<br />

that it is fixed. He realized that an impasse had been reached and that this fact required a<br />

deeper look into the matter. <strong>The</strong> matter was then analyzed and the apparent impasse was<br />

no longer an issue. A dialectical argument was unveiled and a deeper understanding <strong>of</strong> the<br />

matter at hand resolved the dilemma.<br />

Both concepts regarding exchange-value at <strong>first</strong> seemed contradictory but it was realized<br />

that the constant fluctuations in exchange-values is caused by pr<strong>of</strong>it motives and competition.<br />

This in turn homogenizes production processes and fixes exchange-values.<br />

Next Message by Atticus is [372].<br />

[406] Baseball: Marx defines exchange-value as the social relation which allows commodities<br />

to be traded for each other for money. When Marx introduced exchange-values, he<br />

stated that it is some<strong>thing</strong> attached to a commodity’s use-value. He means that the exchangevalue<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity is intrinsic inside the commodity and is fully manifested within. But<br />

Marx contradicts himself by saying the exchange-proportions <strong>of</strong> two commodities is not, in<br />

32 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

fact, a full manifestation <strong>of</strong> their exchange-value. <strong>The</strong>re are other elements such as money<br />

which can buy every commodity and is also a manifestation <strong>of</strong> exchange-value.<br />

Next Message by Baseball is [407].<br />

[413] Long: Exchange-value is some<strong>thing</strong> that is have a quantity relations <strong>of</strong> each use<br />

value <strong>of</strong> a commodity in which it is being exchanged. This can change constantly anywhere<br />

in the market where the commodities are being exchanged. Since it is accidental and related<br />

and an intrinsic value. Exchange value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is in term <strong>of</strong> quantity like dozens <strong>of</strong><br />

eggs, pounds <strong>of</strong> wheat or acres <strong>of</strong> land etc... <strong>The</strong> relations <strong>of</strong> exchange value is accidental is<br />

the fact that when one commodity is being exchanged for another commodity given in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> how many <strong>of</strong> say pounds <strong>of</strong> wheat is equal to one ton ot iron.<br />

Next Message by Long is [601].<br />

[470] GoUtes: When Marx introduces the exchange value <strong>of</strong> a commodity he describes<br />

it as follows “the commodity’s ability to fetch other commodities in the market.” However,<br />

Marx also brings up the point that exchange value is “relative” where the value and exchange<br />

for a commodity is not determined by society as a whole but on an individual basis. <strong>The</strong><br />

exchange value could vary according to what the value <strong>of</strong> a particular commodity is to each<br />

individual consumer. Where one consumer may trade a pen for a paper clip, another may<br />

trade a pen for a notebook. <strong>The</strong> exchange value is socially determined.<br />

Hans: What you call “socially determined” Marx would call “accidental.” It seems as if the exchange-value depends<br />

entirely on the circumstances. This is in contradiction to it depending on the commodity’s ability to fetch<br />

other commodities.<br />

Next Message by GoUtes is [471].<br />

[494] Kat: In Marx’s introduction <strong>of</strong> exchange-value, he explains that a commodity has<br />

both inherent value, which is anchored to the commodity itself, and value which is associated<br />

with its relation to another commodity. In Capital, he says “exchange-value seems to be<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> accidental and purely relative....... and immanent exchange-value.... seems therefore<br />

a contradiction in terms.” Marx then suggests that this contradiction is some<strong>thing</strong> that<br />

people living within a capitalistic society live with everyday, without understanding that it is<br />

contradictory. He explains throughout his work that labor instills value into a commodity; an<br />

exchange-value it holds as a lone commodity before an exchange relation ever takes place.<br />

He then goes on to explain the variability <strong>of</strong> exchange-values in different times and places.<br />

This variability would not seem possible if the value were inherent in the commodity. So,<br />

the contradiction <strong>of</strong> exchange-value is where the value is determined by a relation <strong>of</strong> one<br />

commodity to another standing in contrast to the assumed inherent value anchored to the<br />

commodity.<br />

Next Message by Kat is [496].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 66 is 28 in 1995WI, 37 in 1996ut, 34 in 1997ut, 54 in 2004fa, 62 in<br />

2007SP, 63 in 2008fa, 76 in 2011fa, and 75 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 66 Why does Marx’s inquiry sometimes reach an impasse which can only<br />

be resolved by “considering the matter more closely”?<br />

[391] Orville: graded A Contradiction Resubmission. Throughout “Capital”, Marx contradicts<br />

himself to show that many <strong>of</strong> the assumptions citizens take for granted are actually<br />

misconceptions. He uses logic to lead the reader down a path that seems like a fairly obvious<br />

one then Marx pulls the reader back and lets them wake up and smell the roses. Marx does


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 33<br />

this do demonstrate what he sees as the contradictions capitalism hides. <strong>The</strong> dialectical way<br />

that Marx chooses to write in “Capital” allows him to “consider the matter more closely.”<br />

This is to take a deeper look at what exactly capitalism is and what it means to live in a<br />

capitalistic society. I believe he doesn’t give the answer right away because his conclusions<br />

might not make sense if he did it that way. <strong>The</strong> conclusions drawn in this book might not<br />

make sense if they were stated without some prior knowledge. Marx contradicts himself in<br />

order to keep the reader engaged to the point where it is more obvious how his theories and<br />

ideas make much more logical sense.<br />

Hans: In your in-class answer you wrote: “Marx wants to show that the easy answers are rarely right.” I see it<br />

differently. Marx or Engels said somewhere that the secret <strong>of</strong> dialectics is that you can do your thinking one step at<br />

a time, you don’t have to come up with the correct answer all at once. I.e., the easy answers already have enough<br />

truth in them that they can be the starting point for a fertile dialectical development.<br />

I think there is also the idea in the background that you cannot jump over the negation to arrive at the negation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the negation.<br />

Next Message by Orville is [392].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 67 is 63 in 2007fa, 64 in 2008SP, 64 in 2008fa, 66 in 2009fa, 61 in 2012fa, and<br />

67 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 67 <strong>The</strong> French economist Le Trosne wrote that the value <strong>of</strong> a <strong>thing</strong> consists in<br />

its exchange-proportions with other <strong>thing</strong>s. Does Marx agree with this, or how would he<br />

re-formulate this proposition to make it correct?<br />

[16] Bigwhite: Exchange proportions. Le Trosne states that the value <strong>of</strong> a <strong>thing</strong> consists<br />

<strong>of</strong> its exchange-proportions with other <strong>thing</strong>s. Marx says that he thinks that this is only<br />

one part that goes into figuring out the value <strong>of</strong> a certain commodity. He agrees that the<br />

exchange-proportion is important but that it is also replaceable. Replaceable meaning that<br />

for instance wheat could be exchanged for gold, silk, or iron—not just one commodity but<br />

many. Marx would say that you also have to consider the producer or the production <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity as well before you can get a complete value for the commodity. Because with<br />

the exchange-proportion that can be affected by relationships between the two producers<br />

being it that they are friends or that they have a certain interest in a commodity more so than<br />

another consumer.<br />

So any given commodity can fetch numerous other commodities in exchange but it is not<br />

solely based on the exchange proportions you also have to figure in the intrinsic substance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the given commodity that is not entirely clear yet but it does hold value as well and needs<br />

to be considered when talking about the value <strong>of</strong> a given commodity.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> text <strong>of</strong> the question should have clarified what I belatedly did in [26] and [30], that the <strong>thing</strong> which Le<br />

Trosne calls “value” is the same <strong>thing</strong> which Marx calls “exchange-value.”<br />

I.e., at this point we are not yet investigating the link between value and exchange-value, but we are only looking<br />

at exchange-value.<br />

Is Le Trosne saying some<strong>thing</strong> wrong about exchange-value? Yes he is. I just wrote [30] to explain what it is.<br />

Le Trosne defines exchange-value as a relation only between two commodities, which leaves out the important fact<br />

that a given commodity can be exchanged against all other commodities.<br />

You are saying this too, which is good, but you are calling it replaceability, which is confusing because replaceability<br />

is already the next step. Replaceability means that all these exchange relations are equivalent, one is as<br />

good as the other. This is additional info about the exchange relations. To stay with the polygamy metaphor from<br />

[30], polygamous marriage relations are not replaceable but on the contrary there is a strict and contested hierarchy<br />

among the wives, as the movie series “Big Love” shows. But exchange-relations are replaceable, and from this<br />

34 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

replaceability Marx concludes that all exchange-values <strong>of</strong> the wheat say some<strong>thing</strong> about the wheat alone. I.e.,<br />

replaceability is the bridge between (1) and (2) in [30]. Your second paragraph goes a little bit in the direction <strong>of</strong><br />

saying this.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore there is good thinking in your answer. Most <strong>of</strong> the <strong>thing</strong>s that are wrong are my fault and not yours,<br />

because I did not clarify that Le Trosne’s value is the same as Marx’s exchange-value, and because I think now I<br />

made mistakes in the archive answers to this question. My Annotations benefit from this class exactly because the<br />

answers <strong>of</strong> attentive students like yourself show me where the Annotations are deficient.<br />

Message [16] referenced by [22]. Next Message by Bigwhite is [103].<br />

[22] Goldtone: graded A <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a <strong>thing</strong> is just as much as it will bring. Marx<br />

agrees, to an extent, with the statement Le Trosne makes about exchange-value and it being<br />

only equal to what an item / commodity can be bargained / traded / exchanged for in return.<br />

This agreement by Marx is obvious with his quote: “Exchange-value appears <strong>first</strong> <strong>of</strong> all<br />

as the quantitative relation, the proportion, in which use-value <strong>of</strong> one kind exchange for<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> another kind.” Where Marx would reformulate Le Trosne is in his stopping at<br />

just that. Instead, Marx would continue to argue that two different <strong>thing</strong>s being exchanged<br />

have some “element <strong>of</strong> identical magnitude” already within them. In turn, this identical<br />

magnitude makes their exchange-values reducible to a third <strong>thing</strong>. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> idea that came<br />

into my head for this “third <strong>thing</strong>” was cash / money. Marx, if I remember correctly, is<br />

thinking more along the lines <strong>of</strong> human labor.<br />

Hans: Your subject line is not from Le Trosne but from Butler in a different footnote. Other than this, I think you<br />

would benefit from reading my comments to [16].<br />

Next Message by Goldtone is [74].<br />

[26] Hans: Le Trosne—did I get it finally right? In 126:2, Marx writes:<br />

“Exchange-value manifests itself at <strong>first</strong> as the quantitative relation, the proportion,<br />

in which use-values <strong>of</strong> one sort are exchanged against use-values<br />

<strong>of</strong> another sort ...”<br />

and in the footnote Marx quotes Le Trosne:<br />

“<strong>The</strong> value consists in the exchange proportion between one <strong>thing</strong> and another,<br />

between this amount <strong>of</strong> one product and that <strong>of</strong> another.”<br />

Since these two sentences sound so similar, question 67 asks whether Marx quotes Le<br />

Trosne because he agrees with him?<br />

So far this message is identical to [2008SP:20]. But from now on it is different since my<br />

own understanding has evolved:<br />

<strong>The</strong> answer is no. Marx is critical <strong>of</strong> Le Trosne. He uses Le Trosne as witness for one<br />

half <strong>of</strong> the issue, but at the same time as an example for an analysis <strong>of</strong> exchange-value which<br />

only sees half <strong>of</strong> the issue.<br />

Before I continue, two clarifications:<br />

(1) <strong>The</strong> discrepancy between Marx and Le Trosne is not that Marx is talking about<br />

exchange-value and Le Trosne about value. Marx’s word “exchange-value” and Le Trosne’s<br />

word “value” mean the same <strong>thing</strong>. In this class we are using Marx’s terminology, not Le<br />

Trosne’s, therefore let’s pretend from now on that Le Trosne had written:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 35<br />

“<strong>The</strong> exchange-value consists in the exchange proportion between one <strong>thing</strong><br />

and another, between this amount <strong>of</strong> one product and that <strong>of</strong> another.”<br />

(2) In Capital, Marx <strong>of</strong>ten proceeds in a way that is so unfamiliar to modern readers that<br />

it is easy for them to miss how Marx argues—simply because a modern reader does not<br />

expect Marx to argue this way. Here is a summary <strong>of</strong> the steps in Marx’s argument at the<br />

very beginning <strong>of</strong> chapter One.<br />

(a) After spending a couple <strong>of</strong> paragraphs on use-value, Marx introduces exchange-value<br />

as an additional property which commodities have besides use-value. I.e., he introduces<br />

exchange value as some<strong>thing</strong> intrinsic to the commodity.<br />

(b) But when he gets to investigate this exchange-value, his <strong>first</strong> observation is that<br />

exchange-value manifests itself in a very relative way, through exchange-relations between<br />

commodities. This is where he brings the Le Trosne quote.<br />

(c) Marx says there is a contradiction between value being intrinsic and this relative manifestation<br />

<strong>of</strong> value.<br />

(d) Now comes a kind <strong>of</strong> argument modern readers are no longer used to. If a modern<br />

scientist runs into a contradiction, they will usually take this as a sign that their theory is<br />

wrong, and they try to find a theory without contradictions. Not Marx. Marx cherishes<br />

contradictions. Following Hegel, Marx thinks the world itself is full <strong>of</strong> contradictions, and<br />

someone who wants to understand how the world ticks must identify and explore those<br />

contradictions.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Annotations explain how Marx explores contradictions, and how the contradictions<br />

allow Marx to see <strong>thing</strong>s which would otherwise be invisible. I will not go into the details,<br />

because I have already said enough to show how Marx differs from Le Trosne. While Marx<br />

thinks that exchange-value is a contradictory phenomenon which is in a weird way intrinsic<br />

and relative at the same time, Le Trosne only sees one leg <strong>of</strong> the contradiction—the relative<br />

leg—and loudly declares that exchange-value is relative and not intrinsic. Marx would say<br />

that Le Trosne’s undialectical view <strong>of</strong> exchange-value makes it impossible for Le Trosne to<br />

see where exchange-value comes from.<br />

Message [26] referenced by [16] and [30]. Next Message by Hans is [30].<br />

[30] Hans: Third time is a charm. Here is another version <strong>of</strong> [26], which itself is a<br />

derivative <strong>of</strong> [2008SP:20]. It comes at the issue from a slightly different angle. In order to<br />

move unimportant issues <strong>of</strong> terminology out <strong>of</strong> the way, I silently replaced the word “value”<br />

in the Le Trosne quote with “exchange-value”:<br />

In 126:2, Marx writes:<br />

“Exchange-value manifests itself at <strong>first</strong> as the quantitative relation, the proportion,<br />

in which use-values <strong>of</strong> one sort are exchanged against use-values<br />

<strong>of</strong> another sort ...”<br />

and in the footnote Marx quotes Le Trosne:<br />

“<strong>The</strong> exchange-value consists in the exchange proportion between one <strong>thing</strong><br />

and another, between this amount <strong>of</strong> one product and that <strong>of</strong> another.”<br />

36 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Since these two sentences sound so similar, question 67 asks whether Marx quotes Le<br />

Trosne because he agrees with him? <strong>The</strong> answer is no. Marx does not agree with Le Trosne.<br />

In a debate, Marx would say the following to Le Trosne:<br />

(1) By defining exchange-value as a relationship between two commodities only, you are<br />

leaving out an important aspect <strong>of</strong> exchange-value, namely, that it encompasses all commodities.<br />

Just as it makes a big difference whether a man is married to one woman or to<br />

several women, so it also makes a big difference whether the wheat can be exchanged for<br />

iron only, or whether wheat can be exchanged for iron, silk, gold, shoe-polish, or any other<br />

commodity.<br />

(2) If exchange-value is indeed, as you say, a completely relative matter, a symmetric<br />

relation between two commodities, can you explain why it is not perceived as some<strong>thing</strong><br />

relative? Why do people speak for instance <strong>of</strong> the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> wheat, as if exchangevalue<br />

was intrinsic in one <strong>of</strong> the two commodities?<br />

Does Marx have a better theory <strong>of</strong> exchange-value which is immune to these objections?<br />

Yes, he does. In Marx’s theory, exchange-value is relative too—it is the relationship which<br />

commodities have on the maket—but this relationship is the expression <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> intrinsic,<br />

namely, <strong>of</strong> the labor content inside the commodities.<br />

Since all products contain labor this explains (1), the universality <strong>of</strong> exchange-value, and<br />

since people know from their life-long experience in capitalism that the exchange relation<br />

between commodities is really a statement about the commodities involved, this explains<br />

why they have no problem considering the exchange relations as some<strong>thing</strong> inherent in the<br />

commodities.<br />

Message [30] referenced by [Answer:11] and [16]. Next Message by Hans is [32].<br />

[409] Kraken: graded A Marx does not agree with Le Trosne’s statement. Marx believes<br />

that what Le Trosne is describing is “exchange-value”, which is actually just a surface expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> the inherent value <strong>of</strong> a commodity. Marx looks deeper to discover the source <strong>of</strong><br />

a commodity’s value. Marx believes that a commodity has value due to the social labor-time<br />

which is expended in order to produce the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Kraken is [410].<br />

[439] Kaush: Resubmission. Marx does not agree with the French economist Le Trosne.<br />

Marx’s reformulation would be that the exchange-value itself is not inherent in the commodities,<br />

but the exchange-value is the surface expression <strong>of</strong> the social labor-time amassed<br />

in the production <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Le Trosne does not see the commodity’s labor content<br />

<strong>of</strong> which the surface relation is the reflection.<br />

Next Message by Kaush is [527].<br />

[495] LuBr: By “value” Le Trosne is referring to “exchange-value,” so in answering this<br />

questions we are to analyze whether Marx and his definition <strong>of</strong> exchange-value would agree<br />

with Le Trosne’s concept <strong>of</strong> exchange-value. From Le Trosne’s description <strong>of</strong> exchangevalue<br />

it is clear that Marx would not agree with his conception <strong>of</strong> exchange-value. This is<br />

because Le Trosne believes that value is produced on the market through exchange while<br />

Marx thinks that value is created in the production process. Because the starting point <strong>of</strong><br />

value is different for Le Trosne than it is for Marx, Le Trosne then goes on to imply that<br />

the definition <strong>of</strong> exchange-value is a relation between two commodities being exchanged


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 37<br />

on the market. Marx would disagree and say that one must see the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

as congealed abstract labor contained within the commodity. So in contrast to Le Trosne,<br />

a commodity’s value is intrinsic, and although the exchange value is not intrinsic within a<br />

commodity, it is a reflection <strong>of</strong> the congealed abstract labor within the commodity, which<br />

is inherent. Le Trosne’s version <strong>of</strong> exchange value on the other hand only sees the relative<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> exchange-values, which exist only on the surface <strong>of</strong> market exchange.<br />

Next Message by LuBr is [500].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 68 is 65 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 68 <strong>The</strong> English economist Barbon wrote that no<strong>thing</strong> can have an intrinsic exchangevalue.<br />

Does Marx agree with this, or how would he re-formulate this proposition to make it<br />

correct?<br />

[17] Kleenex: <strong>The</strong> paradox <strong>of</strong> exchange-value. Marx would agree with Barbon’s statement<br />

that no<strong>thing</strong> can have an intrinsic exchange-value, to an extent. Marx writes <strong>of</strong> a<br />

“common some<strong>thing</strong>” that exists within and inside a commodity even before it has been<br />

exchanged. He clarifies what he means by “common some<strong>thing</strong>” with his metaphor <strong>of</strong> polygons<br />

and triangles: in order to find this “common some<strong>thing</strong>,” each commodity to be exchanged<br />

“must therefore be reducible.” At the core <strong>of</strong> each commodity is a shared value.<br />

This common substance is not unique or specific to only two commodities being exchanged:<br />

it exists in many different commodities, as wheat can be traded for silk, shoe polish, gold,<br />

as well as iron.<br />

However, because exchange-value is a social relation as well, it “constantly changes with<br />

time and place” and is dependent on external circumstances. It follows that “exchangevalue<br />

seems to be some<strong>thing</strong> accidental and purely relative,” hence my earlier hypothesis<br />

that Marx agrees with Barbon to an extent. Robert’s example in [14] <strong>of</strong> a bottle <strong>of</strong> water<br />

having a different exchange-value during normal times and after the devastation <strong>of</strong> a hurricane<br />

illustrates this point. In addition, why would an exchange-value have such a name<br />

if an exchange was not going to happen? Exchange-value is also described in the text as a<br />

“mere mode <strong>of</strong> expression” that is “remotely controlled,” or distant from the deeper layers <strong>of</strong><br />

Barbon’s so-called intrinsic exchange-value. Exchange-value is only a superficial or surface<br />

manifestation <strong>of</strong> the many social relations linked to the commodity.<br />

To conclude, Marx agrees, and disagrees with the English economist. In one sense,<br />

exchange-value is somewhat natural and intrinsic in that a commodity contains in itself a<br />

substance that has value. In another sense, Marx sees that social relations between commodities<br />

drive exchange-values.<br />

Hans: You are right, Marx agrees and disagrees. But the disagreement is stronger than the agreement. Let me<br />

explain.<br />

Exchange value itself is not intrinsic but relative, it is a social relation between commodities indicating that and<br />

at what exchange ratios they are exchangeable on the market. To that extent Marx agrees with Barbon.<br />

But exchange-value is the surface expression <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> that is intrinsic in the commodity. This intrinsic<br />

common substance in the commodities, which Marx calls “value,” comes from the labor necessary to produce the<br />

commodities. <strong>The</strong> exchange-value which we see on the market is therefore driven by some<strong>thing</strong> that happened in<br />

production. To say it again, the exchange-value itself is not intrinsic but it is driven by some<strong>thing</strong> that is intrinsic.<br />

This is a big point <strong>of</strong> disagreement between Marx and Barbon. Barbon says exchange-value is created on the market<br />

place, and Marx says that exchange-value is created in production.<br />

38 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Kleenex is [83].<br />

[37] She: (graded A+) Intrinsic Exchange value? When deciding whether or not Marx<br />

would agree with Barbon’s statement that ‘no<strong>thing</strong> can have an intrinsic exchange value’ we<br />

must <strong>first</strong> decide if Marx and Barbon even agree what an exchange-value is.<br />

On the <strong>first</strong> page <strong>of</strong> chapter one, Barbon says value comes from “supplying the wants<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mind” or fueling desire. If value is created this way, in the mind <strong>of</strong> the desirer, it<br />

would obviously be subjective and relative, and assigned when it comes to the marketplace<br />

not some<strong>thing</strong> that is embodied in the commodity during production.<br />

Marx says the exchange-value APPEARS as the quantitative relation—he does not say<br />

it IS the quantitative relation. <strong>The</strong> quantitative relation, which Marx does NOT believe<br />

exchange-value is, changes constantly with time and place. This in turn gives exchangevalue<br />

the appearance <strong>of</strong> being “accidental” and “purely relative.” If we are led to believe that<br />

the exchange-value is simply the quantitative relation that appears on the surface, the concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> intrinsic value will seem a contradiction and an impossibility, as it does to Barbon.<br />

Marx illustrates an example on page 127 <strong>of</strong> the many exchange-values that a single commodity<br />

can have. He deduces from this observation that these different exchange-values, if<br />

valid (See submission [14] by Robert for definition), would be “mutually replaceable or <strong>of</strong><br />

identical magnitude.” He goes on to conclude that, “. . . exchange-value cannot be any<strong>thing</strong><br />

other than the mode <strong>of</strong> expression. . . <strong>of</strong> a content distinguishable from it.”<br />

Marx believes the fact that exchange <strong>of</strong> different commodities can and does occur illustrates<br />

that there must be a common element <strong>of</strong> identical magnitude that exists between them.<br />

Every<strong>thing</strong> that has an exchange-value must therefore be reducible to this common element.<br />

To define this common element, Marx breaks away from seeing commodities as their<br />

physical manifestations but views them as products <strong>of</strong> labor; he even breaks them down into<br />

being products <strong>of</strong> the same measurement <strong>of</strong> labor—so they are equally comparable. <strong>The</strong> labor<br />

that has been used in production <strong>of</strong> these <strong>thing</strong>s is now embodied and intrinsic in them.<br />

<strong>The</strong> homogenous labor he tediously defines becomes the atom <strong>of</strong> the molecule, the “crystals<br />

<strong>of</strong> this social substance [commodity value].” This homogenous labor is the commonality<br />

earlier discussed by Marx, which allows the exchange-values to serve as the mode <strong>of</strong> expression;<br />

expressing, as he says, some<strong>thing</strong> equal, the labor intrinsic in the commodity. Marx<br />

believes the exchange-value is no<strong>thing</strong> more than “the necessary mode <strong>of</strong> expression” while<br />

Barbon appears to believe it is the actual value <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Marx says on page 130 that, “As exchange values, all commodities are merely definite<br />

quantities <strong>of</strong> congealed labor-time.” This means the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity would remain<br />

constant and would not be the quantitative relation that it initially appears to be and that<br />

Barbon believes it is. Barbon’s position is seen by Marx as not differentiating value from<br />

exchange-value.<br />

In order for Marx to reformulate Barbon’s proposition, they would <strong>first</strong> need to agree on<br />

the definition <strong>of</strong> value. Barbon believes it is a subjective judgment based on individual desire<br />

for the object and Marx believes it is derived from the labor that produced it and is therefore<br />

intrinsic to it.<br />

Next Message by She is [88].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 39<br />

[442] Rmc: graded C+ Marx would agree with Barbon that no commodity can have intrinsic<br />

exchange value. Intrinsic means automatic, or “belonging to naturally, essential”<br />

according to Apple’s Mac dictionary. Marx argued in Das Kapital that exchange-value is determined<br />

by broad social factors, preventing commodities to have intrinsic exchange-value,<br />

or even use-value. He also states that exchange-value for one and the same commodity may<br />

change over time and/or space. He would point out that exchange-value reflects use-value<br />

and that whether a commodity has use-value to begin with depends on the market—again,<br />

which changes over space and time.<br />

For example, parkas or wool coats are commodities that would be use-values in places<br />

such as Alaska, Russia, or Canada, where winter is very cold, but they would not be usevalues<br />

in places like the Bahamas or Singapore whose climates are the opposite, year-round.<br />

Parkas are designed to be used in cold climates, so people living in very hot areas would<br />

not identify parkas as use-values. In other words, these commodities are use-values in some<br />

places but not others, therefore, their exchange-values have changed (along with use-value<br />

status) across space.<br />

If use-value changes (or disappears), so does its exchange-value. This disproves that<br />

exchange-value is intrinsic in the commodity.<br />

Hans: Saying that “exchange-value reflects use-value” is an unacceptable misunderstanding <strong>of</strong> Marx which at this<br />

point will automatically lead to a bad grade. Your example <strong>of</strong> parkas in the Bahamas is similar to Orville’s argument<br />

that popcorn is more expensive in movie theatres than in a weight watcher meeting. Read my response [315].<br />

By an “intrinsic” exchange-value Marx means an exchange-value anchored in the body <strong>of</strong> the commodity itself.<br />

Its opposite would be an exchange-value depending on the circumstances <strong>of</strong> the exchange. With this definition,<br />

the fact that the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity disappears when its use-value is destroyed is evidence in favor <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange-value being intrinsic.<br />

Message [442] referenced by [443]. Next Message by Rmc is [443].<br />

[461] Somramthom: graded A Marx vs Barbon—<strong>The</strong> ultimate showdown! Marx<br />

would agree on some terms with Barbon, namely that exchange values are not inherent<br />

and that exchange values determine market exchange ratios.<br />

However, Marx does not agree on Barbon’s idea that exchange value is derived from the<br />

market. Instead, Marx says exchange value is derived from the production <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Since Exchange value is a social reflection <strong>of</strong> the inherent value <strong>of</strong> the commodity (i.e. the<br />

labor input) exchange value itself is not an inherent quality, but it reflects value, which is an<br />

inherent quality <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [462].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 70 is 47 in 2001fa, 48 in 2002fa, 50 in 2003fa, 55 in 2004fa, 55 in 2005fa, 66<br />

in 2007SP, 66 in 2007fa, 67 in 2008fa, 69 in 2009fa, and 77 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 70 Why does Marx write in 127:1 “the valid exchange-values,” instead <strong>of</strong> simply<br />

“the exchange-values”?<br />

[14] Robert: graded A+ Valid exchange-value. Clair in [2009fa:14] quotes from Webster,<br />

defining the word “valid” as that having legal efficacy or force, well-grounded or justifiable,<br />

logically correct, or appropriate to the end in view. Used as a qualifying adjective<br />

to exchange-values in Marx’s phrase the word valid takes on the meaning <strong>of</strong> well-grounded,<br />

40 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

logically correct, and appropriate (legal efficacy does not seem to be the concern <strong>of</strong> his arguments).<br />

By carefully inserting this word Marx implies that a distinction exist between<br />

some instances <strong>of</strong> exchange-value, i.e., some are valid and some are not. Marx in 129:2,<br />

in a different context (i.e., describing the labor-time required to produce a commodity) introduces<br />

the phrase “under the prevailing socially normal conditions.” By the phrase “valid<br />

exchange-value” Marx seems to be referring to an exchange-value determined using wellgrounded,<br />

logical and appropriate considerations in the instances he later identifies as “under<br />

the prevailing socially normal conditions.” Instances wherein exchange-value is subjected to<br />

abnormal external factors wherein grounding, logic, and appropriateness may not be the<br />

primary considerations in its determination (i.e., conditions different from those <strong>of</strong> the prevailing<br />

socially normal conditions) may result in an invalid exchange-value.<br />

For example, the news <strong>of</strong> the day reminds us <strong>of</strong> the circumstance in which the residents <strong>of</strong><br />

New Orleans found themselves in the aftermath <strong>of</strong> Hurricane Katrina five years ago. Under<br />

the duress <strong>of</strong> such a disaster a commodity, such as a bottle <strong>of</strong> water, may have a different<br />

exchange-value than it would when New Orleans was under normal conditions. A valid<br />

exchange-value for a bottle <strong>of</strong> water in New Orleans would best be determined when bottles<br />

<strong>of</strong> water are present in the usual, prevailing socially normal conditions <strong>of</strong> New Orleans.<br />

Another example <strong>of</strong> an invalid exchange-value is provided by Clair in [2009fa:14] <strong>of</strong> a gold<br />

ingot having the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a rock to smash open clams on a deserted island, a<br />

situation outside the prevailing socially normal conditions in which a gold ingot would have<br />

a different, valid exchange-value.<br />

Marx carefully identifies the exchange-values he uses in his discussion as those that are<br />

valid (ordinary under normal conditions), and not invalid (extraordinary under unusual conditions).<br />

Marx is obviously aware that the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> commodities may fluctuate<br />

when conditions are other than normal, but for the purposes <strong>of</strong> this discussion, he chooses<br />

to eliminate this variability in exchange-values by dealing only with valid exchange-values.<br />

Message [14] referenced by [17], [19], [24], [37], [39], [51], [52], and [459]. Next Message by Robert is [52].<br />

[19] Hans: Grothendieck Answers. Grothendieck is a French mathematician. In the<br />

math pr<strong>of</strong>ession in Germany in the 1960s, the saying used to be “where Grothendieck was<br />

once sitting, no grass grows any more” (Wo Grothendieck sich hingesetzt hat, da wächst<br />

kein Gras mehr). In other words, if Grothendieck has written a paper about some<strong>thing</strong> then<br />

this <strong>thing</strong> is over and done with—because Grothendieck has already said every<strong>thing</strong> about it<br />

that can be said.<br />

In the homework discussions we also sometimes get Grothendieck answers, i.e., answers<br />

that are so correct and comprehensive that they stop the conversation—because it would be<br />

difficult to add to them. We already had two Grothendieck answers this Semester, Robert’s<br />

[14] in the present homework period, and Hal’s [8] in the last period.<br />

To ordinary mortals I can only say: don’t be intimidated by this. In some Semesters the<br />

discussion is much more pr<strong>of</strong>ound than in others. Fall 2003 was an exceptionally productive<br />

class, and Fall 2008 was another one. <strong>The</strong> few days <strong>of</strong> discussion so far hold the promise<br />

that this class will be a high level class too. For the grades this means that you all benefit.<br />

Everybody’s grades will be higher on the assumption that you learn more sitting through a<br />

class with exciting high-level discussions than sitting through a lame class.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 41<br />

But some classes started out on a high and promising level and then the level <strong>of</strong> the<br />

discussion fell <strong>of</strong>f—presumably because others were thinking “I can’t play in the same orchestra<br />

with these virtuosos” and gave up. Please don’t give up. Except for the geniuses,<br />

people will need to be a little hard-nosed in this class because you will probably get a lot <strong>of</strong><br />

criticism from me, at least at the beginning. Please stick it out. I expect that at the end you<br />

will be glad you did because you will learn a lot, and you will learn <strong>thing</strong>s which no other<br />

class on campus has to <strong>of</strong>fer.<br />

But for those who signed up for this class because they expected an easy A, I recommend<br />

that you drop the class again on or before Wednesday, September 1. Come back later when<br />

you have more time for it. Even if you drop the class, you are not required to unsub from<br />

the mailing list, if you still want to listen in.<br />

Message [19] referenced by [77], [2011fa:265], and [2012fa:131]. Next Message by Hans is [23].<br />

[31] Alex: (graded A–) Valid Exchange Value. We have established that exchange value<br />

“is the commodity’s ability to fetch other commodities in the market” according to Hans.<br />

In 127:1, Marx is describing the exchange value using the examples <strong>of</strong> one quarter <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity wheat being exchangeable for different amounts <strong>of</strong> silk, shoe polish, or gold, and<br />

in accordance with the definition. But instead <strong>of</strong> describing wheat as having an exchange<br />

value, Marx refers to it as having a valid exchange value instead <strong>of</strong> simply an exchange value.<br />

When I <strong>first</strong> read this question, I understood it to be that the exchange value <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

is relative to not only time and place, but also to the amount that is exchangeable. For<br />

example, one pound <strong>of</strong> wheat might be exchangeable for x amounts <strong>of</strong> silk, y amounts <strong>of</strong><br />

polish, and z amounts <strong>of</strong> gold, therefore, 2 pounds <strong>of</strong> wheat could be exchangeable for more<br />

silk, or more polish, or more gold. In other words, 2 pounds <strong>of</strong> wheat have more exchange<br />

value than one pound. When Marx refers to valid exchange value, it would mean that the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the two items being exchanged is equal. An invalid exchange value would be for<br />

example, on pound <strong>of</strong> wheat for 2x <strong>of</strong> silk, or 3 pounds <strong>of</strong> wheat for x silk, according to<br />

Marx’s original example. Marx would not write simply exchange values, in my opinion,<br />

because there are instances where the exchange values <strong>of</strong> commodities might not be valid,<br />

as in the examples <strong>of</strong> Hans’ annotations <strong>of</strong> “trader having to make a fire sale or being misinformed<br />

about the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> his or her product.” This is because the value given<br />

for one item is more, or less, than the value <strong>of</strong> the other item, which creates a discrepancy.<br />

Message [31] referenced by [32], [42], and [147]. Next Message by Alex is [80].<br />

[32] Hans: How does Marx arrive at his qualification <strong>of</strong> “valid” exchange-values?<br />

Here is the beginning <strong>of</strong> Alex’s [31] again, with some small edits <strong>of</strong> mine and my comments:<br />

We have established that exchange value “is the commodity’s ability to<br />

fetch other commodities in the market” according to Hans.<br />

Yes that’s the definition <strong>of</strong> the word “exchange-value”<br />

In 127:1, Marx is describing the exchange value using the examples <strong>of</strong> one<br />

pound <strong>of</strong> the commodity wheat being exchangeable for different amounts<br />

<strong>of</strong> silk, shoe polish, or gold, and in accordance with the definition.<br />

Marx focuses here on a fact which we all know, but which is by no means trivial (as<br />

we shall see): Wheat can be exchanged on the market not only with one but with many<br />

42 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

different commodities, even such an oddball <strong>of</strong> a commodity as shoe-polish. (And wheat is<br />

no exception here, every other commodity is equally broadly exchangeable.)<br />

Just to illustrate why it matters whether every commodity is broadly exchangeable or<br />

not, think <strong>of</strong> the marriage relation. It matters a lot for the character <strong>of</strong> this relation whether<br />

you live in a monogamous or polygamous society. Marx is basically saying here, regarding<br />

exchanges, commodities are polygamous.<br />

But instead <strong>of</strong> describing wheat as having an exchange value, Marx refers<br />

to it as having a valid exchange value instead <strong>of</strong> simply an exchange value.<br />

You just made a fast forward through Marx’s argumentation, folding three steps into one.<br />

No wonder you are puzzled that Marx suddenly pulled the concept <strong>of</strong> “valid” exchangevalues<br />

out <strong>of</strong> his hat. In the rest <strong>of</strong> your essay you are then guessing what Marx might<br />

have meant with “valid”. Your guess that Marx calls an exchange-value “valid” only if it<br />

conforms with the labor content is especially bad – because labor content is not some<strong>thing</strong><br />

imposed by Marx on the exchange process, but (in Marx’s theory) a spontaneous outcome<br />

generated by market competition.<br />

If we follow in detail how Marx argues, we will get a better idea what Marx probably<br />

meant.<br />

(1) Marx’s next step is that all the different exchange-values <strong>of</strong> the wheat are replaceable.<br />

This means the following. If the market allows wheat producer A to exchange a pound <strong>of</strong><br />

wheat with with y amount <strong>of</strong> silk, then the market also allows wheat producer B to exchange<br />

a pound <strong>of</strong> wheat with y amount <strong>of</strong> silk. You don’t need a special relation with the silk<br />

producer to be able to make this exchange. Whoever you are, if you bring a pound <strong>of</strong> wheat<br />

you get the deal.<br />

(2) From this Marx concludes that each exchange-value is as good as any other. Getting<br />

z gold is not a better deal than getting y tea, because if it was, then those who traded their<br />

wheat for tea would have traded it for gold instead.<br />

Note that replaceability is necessary for this step. To come back to our polygamy example,<br />

the wives <strong>of</strong> the same polygamous husband are not equal to each other but on the<br />

contrary, as the movie Big Love shows, there is a contested hierarchy among them.<br />

(3) <strong>The</strong> next step is difficult but important: all exchange-relations say the same <strong>thing</strong><br />

about the wheat. Since they are equal among each other, the only <strong>thing</strong> they depend on is the<br />

wheat, they are different reflections (or, in Marx’s terminology, expressions) <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong><br />

that has to do with the wheat alone.<br />

In future steps Marx will argue that they are not a reflection <strong>of</strong> any<strong>thing</strong> that has to do<br />

with the use-value <strong>of</strong> the wheat, but instead a reflection <strong>of</strong> the labor content <strong>of</strong> the wheat. I<br />

will not get into this, I will stop my enumeration <strong>of</strong> Marx’s steps here, because this last step<br />

is where Marx throws in the qualification <strong>of</strong> “valid” exchange proportions. Only the valid<br />

exchange proportions are a reflection <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> about the wheat.<br />

This validity requirement seems to have fallen from the sky, but if you have followed<br />

the argument so far you know that “valid” is simply a different word for “replaceable.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 43<br />

Only the replaceable exchange values, i.e., the exchange-values open to all, the competitive<br />

exchange-values, are an expression <strong>of</strong> the wheat. <strong>The</strong> others are, well, an expression <strong>of</strong> the<br />

circumstances which make then unique and not replaceable.<br />

Message [32] referenced by [23]. Next Message by Hans is [41].<br />

[51] Hans: Exchange-Values can be valid without trading equal values. It is impossible<br />

for me to respond and correct every error made in every submission sent to the class.<br />

And sometimes I also overlook errors; sometimes I simply don’t “get” what you mean and<br />

just assume that you mean the same <strong>thing</strong> I have in my head. (So I am making the same<br />

mistake with respect to you which some <strong>of</strong> you are making with respect to Marx.)<br />

For instance I realize now, prompted by your responses to Robert, that I did not read<br />

critically enough the last sentence in Robert’s [14]:<br />

Marx is obviously aware that the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> commodities may fluctuate<br />

when conditions are other than normal, but for the purposes <strong>of</strong> this<br />

discussion, he chooses to eliminate this variability in exchange-values by<br />

dealing only with valid exchange-values.<br />

Robert means here that only those exchange-values are valid where equal value is traded<br />

for equal value; every<strong>thing</strong> else is invalid. I didn’t get it at <strong>first</strong> that this is what he meant,<br />

therefore I must say now belatedly: No, Robert, this is not the right definition <strong>of</strong> “valid.”<br />

Your definition <strong>of</strong> “valid” is is like running a regression and then throwing out all data<br />

points which do not lie on the true regression line. This is <strong>of</strong> course impossible (how can you<br />

tell) and would be infeasible even if it were possible (because the probability <strong>of</strong> a data point<br />

lying on the true regression line is zero), and Marx also does not mean this. He knows that<br />

actual exchange proportions always have noise in them: they are either higher or lower than<br />

the value proportions. This does not make them invalid. No, the invalid exchange-values are<br />

only the ouliers, they are those data points where some special circumstance was overriding<br />

the <strong>thing</strong> measured by the regression line. In a statistical analysis it is legitimate to eliminate<br />

those outliers where you can tell, by investigating the specific case, that some<strong>thing</strong> special<br />

was going on—perhaps a transcription error, a malfunctioning instrument, a thunderstorm,<br />

or whatever. But those outliers where you cannot find such irregularities should not be<br />

eliminated. <strong>The</strong>y may be the most informative data points <strong>of</strong> the data set.<br />

Message [51] referenced by [39], [52], and [361]. Next Message by Hans is [54].<br />

[52] Robert: Corrected exchange-value. Hans [51] correctly pointed out some sloppiness<br />

in my wording in [14] regarding the explanation <strong>of</strong> “valid” exchange value. I understand<br />

that Marx did not intend for valid exchange-values to be held constant (as my statement implies)<br />

across all situations. Marx intended, I believe, as Hans points out, only to eliminate<br />

the extreme cases such as those I cited (stranded on a deserted island, New Orleans after<br />

Katrina) from the definition <strong>of</strong> exchange-values. <strong>The</strong>refore, I believe valid-exchange value<br />

are those various exchange-value that occur under prevailing normal social conditions and<br />

exclude those “outliers” (as Hans defines) <strong>of</strong> exchange-values that occur under extraordinary<br />

and non-normal social conditions.<br />

Next Message by Robert is [76].<br />

[343] Goldtone: graded A Marx writes “the valid exchange-values” instead <strong>of</strong> “the exchangevalues”<br />

because he wants to distinguish socially normal conditions leading to exchange <strong>of</strong> an<br />

44 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

item from abnormal conditions. Exchange-values vary considerably across time and place<br />

due to different conditions. For example, water is worth more to someone who has just been<br />

through an earthquake and no longer has direct access to it. This would be an abnormal condition<br />

for residents <strong>of</strong> most developed countries, due to the fact that, under socially normal<br />

conditions, clean water is easy to come by. Hans notes in the annotations that this distinction<br />

is important “because only those exchange-values are replaceable with each other which<br />

have general validity”, which acts to eliminate in-valid (abnormal) exchanges.<br />

Next Message by Goldtone is [344].<br />

[361] Lindsey: Valid exchange is comparable exchange. Marx writes about “valid<br />

exchange-values” because under different circumstances, the socially perceived value (exchange<br />

value) can change. An example <strong>of</strong> this that was used in class discussion was that bottled<br />

water would be more expensive in Louisiana during/right after Hurricane Katrina than at another<br />

time. <strong>The</strong> price <strong>of</strong> bottled water after Hurricane Katrina would not be comparable with<br />

the price <strong>of</strong> bottled water in the same location just before anyone was aware <strong>of</strong> the storm<br />

coming. A “valid exchange-value” is an exchange-value where all variables (such as time<br />

and place or other “accidental” outside factors) are held constant. Valid exchange-values are<br />

the only comparable values.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> accidental factors do not have to be held constant. In terms <strong>of</strong> [51], a valid exchange is a data point with<br />

an ordinary error term, not an outlier. Katrina produces outliers. Marx would say the price <strong>of</strong> bottled water during<br />

the hurricane is not an expression <strong>of</strong> the production cost <strong>of</strong> water but an expression <strong>of</strong> the hurricane emergency. But<br />

don’t throw the accidental element out altogether!<br />

Next Message by Lindsey is [363].<br />

[469] Hal: graded A+ <strong>The</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> “valid exchange-values” is synonymous with replaceable<br />

exchange-values. Valid exchange-values are those exchange-values that prevail under<br />

normal social conditions because those are the exchange-values that are replaceable. Invalid<br />

exchange-values prevail under special circumstances, and are therefore not replaceable. For<br />

example, invalid exchange-values could occur when commodities are traded between two<br />

merchants that are family members. Invalid exchange-values could also occur with certain<br />

high-need commodities during times <strong>of</strong> crisis. Marx illustrates that the exchange-value between<br />

commodities A and B and the exchange-value between commodities A and C are both<br />

determined by certain characteristics inherent to commodity A alone. That is only the case<br />

when the two exchange-values are replaceable.<br />

Next Message by Hal is [472].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 72 is 277 in 1996sp, 56 in 2005fa, 67 in 2007fa, 68 in 2008SP, 68 in 2008fa,<br />

and 71 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 72 First give Marx’s arguments how one can come to the conclusion that exchangevalue<br />

is not some<strong>thing</strong> inherent in the commodity. <strong>The</strong>n reproduce, in your own words,<br />

Marx’s rebuttal that, despite these arguments, exchange-value seems to be some<strong>thing</strong> inherent<br />

to the commodity after all.<br />

[39] Wolf: Relative exchange-value and Marx. Marx says that exchange-values “appear”<br />

to be “accidental and purely relative” because they change from time to place (126:2).<br />

While there may be many more reasons for the fluctuation in exchange-value, Marx didn’t<br />

address these for the reason that these fluctuations are beyond our control (pg 23-24 in<br />

the annotations). Marx specifically focuses on normal social circumstances. Robert [14]


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 45<br />

explained this quite well where he clarifies the distinction between socially normal “valid<br />

exchange-value” and mere “exchange-value”.<br />

However, Marx refutes this notion with two examples. In his <strong>first</strong> example (127:1), Marx<br />

shows that a given commodity can have many exchange-values. This broader picture obscures<br />

the assumption that they are purely relative and accidental because the commodities<br />

which have an exchange-value with the given commodity can be exchanged with each other,<br />

rather than the given commodity, for an equal magnitude as that between the given commodity<br />

and the other commodities. Had we chosen an example where we lookod only at the<br />

relationship between two traders, we may find otherwise. When you step back and look at<br />

the broader structure, this makes more sense. As shown by Marx’s second example (127:2),<br />

where he shows that two commodities exchange-value is equal, alludes to a further underlying<br />

social relation, one in which exchange-value is merely an expression <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

Hans: Careful reading and nice enumeration <strong>of</strong> Marx’s steps, but there are still a few mistakes.<br />

Regarding your <strong>first</strong> paragraph, please see my [50] and [51].<br />

Regarding the <strong>first</strong> example, which I call in the Annotations the <strong>first</strong> thought experiment: Marx’s point with<br />

replaceability is not that they can be exchanged for each other, but that neither is a better deal than the other for the<br />

owner <strong>of</strong> the wheat.<br />

Regarding the second example, the end <strong>of</strong> your submission was originally the malformed expression ”one in<br />

which exchange-value is merely an expression <strong>of</strong> it,” and I changed it into what I think you mean.<br />

I am not happy with it that you are only describing Marx’s steps, you are not presenting them in enough detail<br />

that the reader could make a judgment whether Marx’s argument is sound or not. But I think this has to do with<br />

it that you have your own reservations about the validity <strong>of</strong> Marx’s steps. You are probably not alone with this,<br />

therefore I wrote [50] and [51] to clarify <strong>thing</strong>s.<br />

Message [39] referenced by [46] and [50]. Next Message by Wolf is [110].<br />

[46] Zarathustra: (graded A) Relative exchange-value and Marx. I read Wolf’s answer<br />

[39] but its sophistication didn’t allow me to understand it. <strong>The</strong> following is what I think<br />

about Q: 72.<br />

Exchange-value (EV) is not inherent because it’s some<strong>thing</strong> socially determined. If it<br />

was inherent it should have been the same for a given commodity in every place and time.<br />

In this sense, it is similar to use-value (UV) because it is also determined differently in<br />

different contexts, say, I sometimes use my pen to write a paper and other times as a tool to<br />

play with my cat. Both EV and UV are accidental and relational. But if EV is some<strong>thing</strong><br />

immanent and only “carried” by the commodity why should it vary in different contexts?<br />

Hans says “People have contradictory notions in their heads because their lived experience<br />

is contradictory”( 50.) For Marxists and philosophers contradiction is a blessing, that is, it<br />

is sign that shows the researcher has discovered two dissimilar aspects <strong>of</strong> one phenomenon.<br />

I think one possible answer to this contradiction is that EX is (i) social and rooted in<br />

(ii) value which is a qualitative matter; however, in reality (marketplace) it is quantitatively<br />

defined in terms <strong>of</strong> UV <strong>of</strong> another commodity which its consumption (usefulness) is desired<br />

individually. This type <strong>of</strong> measuring qualitative and social aspects <strong>of</strong> commodity through<br />

quantitative and individual criteria might be where we should look for the root <strong>of</strong> this contradiction.<br />

Next Message by Zarathustra is [67].<br />

46 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[50] Hans: Instead <strong>of</strong> Predicting, Understand Persistent Forces and Tendencies. Wolf<br />

[39] takes issue with Marx calling the fluctuations in exchange-values “accidental.” If I understand<br />

Wolf right, he thinks that there are reasons for these fluctuations, and Marx should<br />

not have thrown up his hands and called them “accidental” but he should have built models<br />

which incorporate these reasons and are precise enough to predict the fluctuations.<br />

If this is Wolf’s argument (and I am not clear if it is, I am guessing here), then my response<br />

is:<br />

(1) Marx would probably say it is not possible to predict such fluctuations, and modern<br />

science agrees with him here. Due to the “butterfly effect,” it is not possible to make weather<br />

forecasts for more than a week in advance, and energy prices depend on the weather: therefore<br />

it is impossible to predict every up and down in energy prices. Only their general trend<br />

can be predicted from economic mechanisms. Another example would be that everybody<br />

knows oil prices are likely to go up if there is a hurricane in the Gulf <strong>of</strong> Mexico, but it is<br />

impossible to predict how fast and how far and for how long.<br />

(2) More importantly, Marx would say, and again he is backed up by modern philosophy<br />

<strong>of</strong> science, it is not the purpose <strong>of</strong> science to predict. Events are the intersection <strong>of</strong> many<br />

different forces, and as scientists we study the forces one at a time, not the events themselves.<br />

Marx is studying the economic mechanisms.<br />

Message [50] referenced by [39]. Next Message by Hans is [51].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 74 is 59 in 2005fa, 71 in 2008fa, and 82 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 74 Comment about the following critique <strong>of</strong> Marx: When Marx asks what is<br />

the meaning <strong>of</strong> the exchange relation between two commodities, he commits the error <strong>of</strong><br />

treating the economy like a literary text. <strong>The</strong> actions <strong>of</strong> the economic agents must be causally<br />

explained, but any reflection about their “meaning” is an interpretation which does not help<br />

us understand what is really going on.<br />

[27] PLG: graded A– Economy as a Literary Text. <strong>The</strong> critique in question 74 refers to<br />

Marx’s methodology in looking for an exchange relation between two commodities. Rather<br />

than looking for a quantitative comparison between goods, Marx begins by deducing the<br />

“meaning” <strong>of</strong> the exchange relation between two goods. This is what is meant by treating<br />

the economy as a “literary text”. Marx’s methodology is a crucial step on the path to understanding<br />

the exchange value <strong>of</strong> commodities. Marx’s literary style is what leads him to<br />

a deep understanding <strong>of</strong> the social relationship between commodities, and more specifically<br />

to the social relationship <strong>of</strong> a commodity’s production.<br />

Marx’s <strong>first</strong> thought experiment describes how a commodity can be exchanged for many<br />

different commodities, making a good’s exchange value less relative, and more intrinsic.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second thought experiment looks at an underlying equalization <strong>of</strong> goods. Although a<br />

commodity may be intrinsic on its surface value, there is an underlying equalization <strong>of</strong> these<br />

goods before they enter the “second act” <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange. Marx treats the economy<br />

like a literary text in his methodology <strong>of</strong> understanding commodity exchange in order to dig<br />

deeper into a more human element <strong>of</strong> a commodity’s production.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 47<br />

His equalization <strong>of</strong> wheat and iron (pg. 27) seems to be a step back from his prior intrinsic<br />

value conclusion <strong>of</strong> a good. Instead it is a step forward to equating the social implications<br />

<strong>of</strong> the production <strong>of</strong> one good, to the social implications <strong>of</strong> the production <strong>of</strong> another good.<br />

In this “literary” process Marx is thinking through the different layers <strong>of</strong> a good’s value;<br />

surface expression, use value, and finally the underlying substance. As he digs deeper, he<br />

finds that the surface value “speaks” to the production <strong>of</strong> a good, bringing greater meaning to<br />

a commodity’s production (pg. 28). <strong>The</strong> private producers <strong>of</strong> a good then receive a message<br />

from the exchange market.<br />

<strong>The</strong> social ties to commodities, and the social relationship to the production <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

are crucial for Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> exchange value. His “literary” technique is valuable<br />

for gaining an understanding <strong>of</strong> the social context <strong>of</strong> commodities, rather than a quantitative<br />

context.<br />

Hans: What you call Marx’s “literary style” is presumably his attention to qualitative issues and contradictions<br />

etc., instead <strong>of</strong> just quantitative issues. This looks so unusual because modern science has almost entirely come<br />

away from looking at the quality <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s. Nowadays people even think: if it is not quantitative, it is not scientific.<br />

Modern mainstream economics tries to take advantage <strong>of</strong> this prejudice: it formulates highly quantitative theories<br />

in the hope that people will take this as pro<strong>of</strong> that mainstream economics is a science. (Marxists say that modern<br />

mainstream economics is an ideology posing as a science.)<br />

But this is a little bit <strong>of</strong> a tangent <strong>of</strong>f the question, because the question wondered whether it makes sense to<br />

look at what the surface relations “say”, see 127:2 (this is a simpler and better translation than talking about the<br />

“meaning” <strong>of</strong> the surface relations). <strong>The</strong> answer is in your essay: what the surface relations “say” is <strong>of</strong> interest<br />

because it characterizes the flow <strong>of</strong> information which the producers receive from observing the market outcomes.<br />

Next Message by PLG is [113].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 77 is 31 in 1995WI, 40 in 1996ut, 38 in 1997ut, 55 in 2002fa, 57 in 2003fa, 62<br />

in 2005fa, 73 in 2007SP, 73 in 2007fa, 74 in 2008fa, and 90 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 77 Marx argues that commodities are exchangeable only because they contain<br />

some common substance. Bailey denies this. He compares the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

with the distance between points, which is not based on a commonality between the two<br />

points but is purely relative: “As we cannot speak <strong>of</strong> the distance <strong>of</strong> any object without<br />

implying some other object between which and the former this relation exists, so we cannot<br />

speak <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity but in reference to another commodity compared with it.<br />

A <strong>thing</strong> cannot be valuable in itself without reference to another <strong>thing</strong> any more than a <strong>thing</strong><br />

can be distant in itself without reference to another <strong>thing</strong>.” . Comment.<br />

[38] Proletarian: graded A Marx vs Bailey and the fallacy <strong>of</strong> the “distance” metaphor.<br />

Perhaps I have always viewed the world, in some ways at least, in a Marxist manner. I have<br />

always viewed money, value, and price as some sort <strong>of</strong> measurement <strong>of</strong> work. Because I’ve<br />

always looked at the world this way, it did not seem strange or new to me when I read Marx’s<br />

assertions that commodities have an intrinsic exchange value and that commodities are only<br />

exchangeable because they contain some common substance, which is to say the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

labor it took to produce the commodity.<br />

Bailey, however, takes exception to this view. Bailey asserts that a commodity only has<br />

exchange value in relation to other commodities. He claims that the exchange value is not<br />

some inherent property in a commodity, but that the exchange value is purely relative and<br />

cannot be determined without some<strong>thing</strong> for which to exchange the commodity. In making<br />

48 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

his argument, Bailey compares exchange to distance, and claims that the distance <strong>of</strong> an<br />

object cannot be determined without some other object to reference.<br />

I disagree with Bailey’s argument, and believe that the comparison <strong>of</strong> exchange value to<br />

distance is a fallacy. While it may seem like a nice metaphor, distance and value are two<br />

entirely different <strong>thing</strong>s. A commodity still contains within itself some intrinsic value based<br />

on the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that went into creating that commodity.<br />

For example, let’s say that one puts 10 hours <strong>of</strong> labor into a field <strong>of</strong> wheat and at the<br />

end <strong>of</strong> those 10 hours has created a commodity: 1 ton <strong>of</strong> harvested wheat. Let’s say that<br />

at the same time another worker puts 10 hours <strong>of</strong> labor into a piece <strong>of</strong> stone and ends up<br />

creating 10 hammers. Would one say that the resulting commodities from these two workers<br />

have no exchange value if these commodities are never traded? Of course not. <strong>The</strong>se two<br />

commodities have some intrinsic value, and that value is best defined by the amount <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

put into the creation <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

For example, if the worker who harvested the 1 ton <strong>of</strong> wheat needed a hammer, he would<br />

be unlikely to trade his whole 1 ton <strong>of</strong> wheat for 1 hammer. In the amount <strong>of</strong> time it took him<br />

to harvest that 1 ton <strong>of</strong> wheat (10 hours) he could have made 10 hammers if he put his labor<br />

into making hammers. Instead, one could logically deduce that the worker who harvested<br />

the wheat would be willing to trade 1/10 <strong>of</strong> a ton <strong>of</strong> wheat for the hammer. Essentially, the<br />

opportunity cost for the worker who harvested the ton <strong>of</strong> wheat is 10 hammers (in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

hammers).<br />

However, the only reason the number is 10 hammers is because that is what the worker<br />

could have done with his 10 hours <strong>of</strong> labor instead <strong>of</strong> harvesting wheat. <strong>The</strong> opportunity<br />

cost could have easily been 2 shirts (at 5 hours a shirt), 5 yards <strong>of</strong> rope (at 2 hours per yard),<br />

or 1 ton <strong>of</strong> oats (at 10 hours per ton). What holds true across all the different measures <strong>of</strong><br />

opportunity cost is one underlying unit <strong>of</strong> value: labor. <strong>The</strong>refore, one can easily calculate<br />

the intrinsic exchange value <strong>of</strong> a commodity based upon how much labor went into the<br />

production <strong>of</strong> that commodity.<br />

Now, if one must use Bailey’s poor comparison <strong>of</strong> value and distance, there is a better<br />

way <strong>of</strong> looking at it. Instead <strong>of</strong> saying that exchange value is only relative as distance is<br />

since one “cannot speak <strong>of</strong> the distance <strong>of</strong> any object without implying some other object<br />

between which and the former this relation exists,” consider the metaphor differently. If<br />

one object starts at one point and moves in some direction, despite not having a destination,<br />

or even another object to relate to, did that object not move? Of course the object moved.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is some real distance that object has gone, even if there is no<strong>thing</strong> to relate to. In the<br />

same way, a commodity has some intrinsic exchange value because <strong>of</strong> the labor put into its<br />

creation, even if there is no other commodity for which to exchange.<br />

One who labors for 10 hours on some<strong>thing</strong> is not going to say it has no value. If you<br />

were to go to the worker who harvested the 1 ton <strong>of</strong> wheat and ask to take it for no<strong>thing</strong> in<br />

exchange, even if the worker is not going to use the wheat himself, he is not going to simply<br />

give you the wheat for no<strong>thing</strong>. This is because he knows that the wheat he has produced has<br />

some intrinsic value because he is the one that put the work into making it. He knows there<br />

is some underlying value in the labor he put into the wheat, and he is not going to part with


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 49<br />

that wheat unless he receives some<strong>thing</strong> in exchange that is equal in the amount <strong>of</strong> work<br />

involved in its creation to the amount <strong>of</strong> labor he put into creating his ton <strong>of</strong> wheat.<br />

When thought <strong>of</strong> in this manner, Marx’s position on the intrinsic exchange value <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity not only makes more sense, it seems naturally true.<br />

Hans: This may seem natural as long as they consider themselves independent self-interested strangers, rather than<br />

partners working together for the goal <strong>of</strong> providing for everyone.<br />

Message [38] referenced by [54]. Next Message by Proletarian is [239].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 79 is 93 in 2011fa and 91 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 79 In 127:4–128:1, Marx says that the exchange relation is characterized by an<br />

abstraction from use-values. What does this mean? Explain it in such a way that your<br />

12-year old would understand.<br />

[43] Cmellen: graded C Marx says that the exchange relation is characterized by an abstraction<br />

from use-values. This means the utility <strong>of</strong> a <strong>thing</strong> makes it a use value. To explain<br />

in layman terms we can take for example the Discovery TV show, <strong>The</strong> Colony. If you watch<br />

this show you see that in different circumstances some items are more vitally needed for<br />

their utility than they would be to someone else not in that circumstance.<br />

This is seen when they are trading the scarce items they already have (and they have<br />

scavenged for), in exchange for other goods that normally wouldn’t seem that valuable (i.e.<br />

a jar <strong>of</strong> homemade alcohol and a lb <strong>of</strong> rice was traded for a generator with less than a gallon<br />

<strong>of</strong> gas left in it). To one individual, the homemade alcohol and lb rice isn’t <strong>of</strong> much value if<br />

you have an entire kitchen stocked <strong>of</strong> food and beverage, but to someone who hasn’t eaten<br />

much in the past 10 days, yet already has electricity at their disposal, the rice and alcohol<br />

is worth much more than a generator. <strong>The</strong>refore use values become a reality only by use or<br />

consumption.<br />

Hans: Do you know the difference between use-value and exchange-value?<br />

Cmellen: I think I do. Use-value is how you can use the item, not the worth <strong>of</strong> what its made <strong>of</strong>, but what you<br />

can actually do with it. Exchange value is the quantity in which you can exchange one item for another item. Am I<br />

correct?<br />

Hans: Yes, this is correct enough for our purposes (although Marx would say that exchange-value is much more<br />

than just the quantitative exchange proportion). But why did you then insert in both <strong>of</strong> your submissions, in [43]<br />

and in [49], the sentence “This means the utility <strong>of</strong> a <strong>thing</strong> makes it a use value” after the sentence “Marx says that<br />

the exchange relation is characterized by an abstraction from use-values,” and then you argue that exchange-value<br />

is determined by use-value?<br />

Cmellen: I didn’t realize my error in understanding until after I had submitted my questions. I really appreciate<br />

your response to others’ questions as well. It helps me to grasp concepts (sometimes a bit too late).<br />

Message [43] referenced by [43], [47], [49], [54], [63], [179], and [2012fa:30]. Next Message by Cmellen is [49].<br />

[47] Lindsey: Clarifying my thoughts. This is in response to Cmellen’s [43] answer to<br />

question 79. It turns out that even Marx’s basic points can be very hard to understand so I<br />

just want to clarify my own understanding because I understood some<strong>thing</strong> different from<br />

the reading than Cmellen did.<br />

I thought that Marx’s point in this section was to talk about how exchange relations are<br />

NOT directly related to use-values (“characterized by an abstraction from use-values”—or<br />

in other words a movement away from use values).<br />

50 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Cmellen seems to focus on the different perspectives <strong>of</strong> different consumers while I don’t<br />

remember Marx saying any<strong>thing</strong> about individual consumers’ perspectives or demands affecting<br />

exchange-values (at least not yet). Marx only talks about how the use-value <strong>of</strong> different<br />

commodities can be converted into one common unit: exchange-values. In this way<br />

different <strong>thing</strong>s can be traded: “For, if considered according to its exchange-value, one commodity<br />

is just as good as any other, as long as it is present in the right proportion”<br />

I did like Cmellen’s example <strong>of</strong> rice and jam being a fair trade for a generator because<br />

it seems to me like a good illustration <strong>of</strong> how completely different <strong>thing</strong>s may be traded. It<br />

also is an interesting example because it illustrates how quantity is important: the exchangevalue<br />

<strong>of</strong> 1 lb <strong>of</strong> rice was not equal to the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> the generator, so jam was added<br />

to the rice side <strong>of</strong> the exchange.<br />

How did everyone else see this part <strong>of</strong> Marx’s argument?<br />

Next Message by Lindsey is [123].<br />

[54] Hans: Barters in a survival game do not follow the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value. Imagine<br />

an economy (an ongoing economy with production, not a group <strong>of</strong> people stranded on an<br />

island) in which, to take Cmellen’s example from [43], a jar <strong>of</strong> alcohol and a pound <strong>of</strong> rice<br />

was traded consistently on the market for an electric generator. Nobody would be producing<br />

generators and everybody would rush into producing alcohol and rice, because it takes so<br />

much more labor and resources to produce a generator than to produce alcohol and rice, see<br />

Proletarian’s careful explanation in [38]. Quickly, a shortage <strong>of</strong> generators and a surplus <strong>of</strong><br />

alcohol and rice would appear on the market. <strong>The</strong> price <strong>of</strong> generators would rise and that<br />

<strong>of</strong> rice fall. This adjustment would go on until prices would be in line with labor content.<br />

In the Colony, such an adjustment cannot take place because there is no production. <strong>The</strong><br />

Colony is an example <strong>of</strong> an economy where the neoclassical utility theory <strong>of</strong> value is correct<br />

at least for those <strong>thing</strong>s which cannot be produced in the Colony. (I don’t watch TV, I’m just<br />

guessing, please correct me if I am guessing wrong.)<br />

But <strong>of</strong> course we consumers in capitalism are carefully taught not to think <strong>of</strong> the production<br />

side <strong>of</strong> it. This may seem strange because we are the producers, or at least those <strong>of</strong> us<br />

who are working class are the producers. But the trick in capitalism is that the producers do<br />

not have control over the means <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong> capitalists have monopolized the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production, that’s why they are so rich. And economics is taught in such a way as <strong>of</strong><br />

production did not exist, so that we don’t get the idea the working class should have a say<br />

about production.<br />

Message [54] referenced by [58], [59], [71], and [347]. Next Message by Hans is [58].<br />

[57] KA: Abstraction <strong>of</strong> Use Values. Individuals can only infer that the relationship embodied<br />

in the exchange is the ultimate value <strong>of</strong> its exchange in terms <strong>of</strong> use. Individuals are<br />

only exchanging the use <strong>of</strong> a commodity for another, given that the exchange is in proportion<br />

to each other. Marx isolates this argument to an abstraction <strong>of</strong> use-values since the general<br />

characteristics <strong>of</strong> the exchange are displaced from its actual instances. <strong>The</strong> argument that<br />

one proposes is that exchange-value is established based on use-value, since the exchange is<br />

dependent on one’s use. <strong>The</strong>refore, Marx argues that “exchange-values is characterized by<br />

an abstraction from use-values.” Commodities can only be exchanged based on their quantitative<br />

differences and cannot be derived based on qualitative differences.


Explaining this to a 12-year old would be as such:<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 51<br />

Marx explains to us that an exchange-value is an abstraction <strong>of</strong> use-value because <strong>of</strong> how<br />

an individual expects the exchange <strong>of</strong> a product to be useful to us when we give up another<br />

product. A book that I read a few years back discussed the origins <strong>of</strong> wealth, and how it<br />

was created. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> chapter <strong>of</strong> the book talks about how wealth in primitive times was<br />

measured by how many heads <strong>of</strong> cattle you had. This measurement enables individuals to<br />

transact in a very simple market place. If you wanted to obtain some grains or wheat you<br />

would simply transfer the amount <strong>of</strong> cattle for a certain amount <strong>of</strong> grains or wheat. <strong>The</strong><br />

usefulness <strong>of</strong> the cattle became an exchange-value for grains and wheat, but the inverse<br />

cannot be true. Your cattle cannot be an exchange-value determined on the use-value. <strong>The</strong><br />

very simplest explanation <strong>of</strong> exchange-value is that its abstraction is based <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> the social<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> the product (cattle).<br />

Hans: Keep on trying. It is difficult to think on such an abstract level, but it takes practice.<br />

Next Message by KA is [171].<br />

[63] Hans: Do Exchange Relations Abstract from Use-Values? This is a difficult<br />

question. Before actually answering it, let’s look at its context. Marx does not believe that<br />

exchange-relations are determined by use-values. <strong>The</strong>refore Cmellen’s answer [43] is not<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> he ever would have written, whether in connection with his assertion that the<br />

exchange-relations abstract from use-values or not.<br />

On the other hand, Marx just went through a painstaking argument that exchange-value<br />

is immanent, i.e., it depends on some<strong>thing</strong> inside the commodities. This seems to lead him<br />

back to use-values. But here he protests (I paraphrase him <strong>of</strong> course): No, no, it’s not usevalue!<br />

Can’t you see, it’s obvious if you just open your eyes, that the exchange relation<br />

abstracts from use-value and therefore cannot be determined by use-value?<br />

He does use the word “augenscheinlich,” which means “in plain view, not hidden.” That<br />

is why I formulated question 78. If Marx says it’s obvious and we readers don’t see it, how<br />

can we follow his other arguments which are no longer obvious?<br />

For you, on the other hand, this makes this question doubly difficult, because you have<br />

been taught in mainstream economics that exchange-value is determined by use-values. This<br />

question asks you to find obvious evidence before your eyes that your beliefs are wrong.<br />

Here is another stumbling block which makes this question difficult: if an individual<br />

makes an exchange (or a purchase), it is certainly not true that they abstract from the usevalues.<br />

To modern consumers it is very important which use-values they get. Every nuance<br />

counts. Shopping is a national pastime. Doesn’t this contradict Marx’s claim that exchange<br />

relations abstract from use-values?<br />

Interestingly, the reverse holds. Individuals can only choose so freely whichever usevalues<br />

they like best because exchange-relations abstract from use-values or, as Marx elaborates,<br />

“one use-value is just as good as another, as long as it is present in the proper quantity.”<br />

So if you wanted a gold-plated urinal, the market will not say “urinals should not be goldplated”<br />

but the market will give you a gold-plated urinal if you have enough money to pay<br />

for it. Lenin once remarked “capitalists will sell you the rope by which you are going to<br />

52 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

hang them.” If the exchange-relations are so indifferent towards the use-values then, Marx<br />

argues, use-values cannot be what determines exchange-relations.<br />

Message [63] referenced by [2011fa:22], [2012fa:30], and [2012fa:68]. Next Message by Hans is [64].<br />

[399] PLG: graded A– Use values are the physical properties <strong>of</strong> goods that provide the<br />

owner with utility. <strong>The</strong> exchange value is the market value <strong>of</strong> a good. Use-values provide<br />

the motivation for consumers to obtain goods, but they do not determine the market value<br />

<strong>of</strong> a good. Thus a use-value must be “prepared” for the market before an exchange can take<br />

place.<br />

This market preparation takes place by an abstraction <strong>of</strong> a use-value into its “common<br />

substance”. For example, a baseball is great for hitting, throwing and catching. This is its<br />

use value. But if the baseball wants to be traded for a basketball the market must disregard<br />

the use-values, and consider the congealed abstract labor within each good, or the “common<br />

substance”. <strong>The</strong>re is an abstraction <strong>of</strong> the commodities’ value that has taken place in this<br />

exchange.<br />

Marx uses the term “common substance” to describe the exchange value within the commodity.<br />

<strong>The</strong> “common substance” is the congealed abstract labor in the good. When a usevalue<br />

is abstracted into its common substance, it is empowered for exchange on the market.<br />

This is what Marx means by the exchange relation being characterized by an abstraction.<br />

Hans: Your in-class answer was quite different and it was more on target given the question. <strong>The</strong> resubmission<br />

mixes in elements <strong>of</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> value which have no<strong>thing</strong> to do with the question.<br />

Next Message by PLG is [429].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 80 is 63 in 2005fa, 75 in 2007SP, 76 in 2008fa, 94 in 2011fa, and 92 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 80 Marx says that the exchange-relations are characterized by an abstraction<br />

from use-values. But use-values do affect the exchange proportions. If a use-value is in high<br />

demand compared to supply, then it commands a higher exchange-value. If a competitor<br />

brings out a better product, the firm’s own product may not sell any more. Can this be<br />

reconciled with the claim <strong>of</strong> abstraction from use-value?<br />

[49] Cmellen: graded C Marx says that the exchange relation is characterized by an abstraction<br />

from use-values. This means the utility <strong>of</strong> a <strong>thing</strong> makes use-value. However<br />

use-values do affect the exchange proportions. If a use-value is in high demand in comparison<br />

to scarce supply, then it commands a higher exchange proportion to be equal to one<br />

unit <strong>of</strong> the high demand item. If a competitor brings out a better product, the firm’s own<br />

product may not sell anymore. To examine this one would look at the use-value <strong>of</strong> the two<br />

competitive items. Does the new product have a greater use-value, so great that it makes the<br />

previous use-value obsolete and unwanted? Is that what makes it a “better product”? If so,<br />

then individuals would trade for the better use-value, making the original product obsolete.<br />

Hans: You are still making the same mistake as in [43].<br />

Message [49] referenced by [43] and [179]. Next Message by Cmellen is [121].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 85 is 44 in 1996ut, 67 in 2004fa, 79 in 2007SP, 81 in 2008SP, 80 in 2008fa, 97<br />

in 2011fa, and 95 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 85 Why did Ricardo’s discovery <strong>of</strong> the determination <strong>of</strong> value by labor attract<br />

the following critique: “Mr. Ricardo’s system is one <strong>of</strong> discords . . . its whole tends to the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 53<br />

production <strong>of</strong> hostility among classes and nations . . . His book is the true manual <strong>of</strong> the<br />

demagogue, who seeks power by means <strong>of</strong> agrarianism, war and plunder.”<br />

[55] Babyceta: graded A– Marx’s Critique <strong>of</strong> Ricardo. In order to better understand<br />

Marx’s critique <strong>of</strong> Ricardo, it will be beneficial to provide some historical context. Ricardo<br />

<strong>first</strong> published <strong>The</strong> Principles <strong>of</strong> Political Economy and Taxation 1817 and at that time Ricardo<br />

was more interested in establishing a correlation between the price <strong>of</strong> agricultural<br />

goods through “relative time” and their direct effect on the price <strong>of</strong> manufactured goods. Ricardo<br />

believed that an increase in the price <strong>of</strong> agricultural products would have to be <strong>of</strong>fset<br />

by a decrease in the prices <strong>of</strong> at least some manufactured goods. Remember, one <strong>of</strong> Ricardo’s<br />

main contributions was to show how as soil quality diminished labor would be less<br />

productive, and rent would squeeze out pr<strong>of</strong>it. (He unconditionally accepted Malthus’ theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> population which surmised that as pr<strong>of</strong>its and wages increased, so, too, would the birth<br />

rate. More people translated to increased demand for agricultural products, resulting in the<br />

need to cultivate more land. Since the most fertile soil had already been employed, land <strong>of</strong><br />

inferior quality would have to be developed. Less fertile land meant less productive labor.)<br />

Ricardo believed this applied, too, to the manufacturing sector since there was, he supposed,<br />

an inverse relationship between manufactured goods and agricultural goods. If less food was<br />

being produced as population increased, food prices would rise. Scarcity increases demand<br />

and factory workers would have to provide more labor in order to subsist. Providing more<br />

labor in the factory would mean increased productivity and more manufactured goods. An<br />

increase in supply usually translates to lower prices.<br />

What does all <strong>of</strong> this have to do with the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value and Marx’s critique?<br />

Well, Marx refers to Ricardo’s Principles as a “manual <strong>of</strong> the demagogue”; a demagogue<br />

being (roughly) someone who champions the cause <strong>of</strong> common people to gain power or<br />

favor. Next, Marx accuses Ricardo <strong>of</strong> agrarianism which, in eighteenth and nineteenth century<br />

England meant any land reform movement that sought to redistribute cultivated lands<br />

equally. So, if labor becomes less productive over time as population increases and less productive<br />

land must be employed because all <strong>of</strong> the good soil is already in production, then the<br />

commodities themselves will essentially be worth less because the labor embodied in them<br />

is less productive labor. If one hour <strong>of</strong> labor used to produce 10 bushels <strong>of</strong> wheat and now<br />

one hour only produces 5 bushels <strong>of</strong> wheat, then there that wheat contains less value in the<br />

form <strong>of</strong> embodied labor. If a nation runs out <strong>of</strong> productive soil to cultivate (and remember<br />

there’s a relationship with manufacturing) then that nation will have to go to other nations to<br />

get more land and resources.<br />

Marx, I believe, was critical <strong>of</strong> Ricardo (and this is where the “war and plunder” comes<br />

in) because Marx believed Ricardo was attempting to generate public support for policies<br />

that encouraged colonization and mercantilism. And since people in most countries will not<br />

generally give up their land and resources without a fight, Marx believed that Ricardo’s labor<br />

theory was essentially a veiled attempt at advancing a political agenda; mainly agrarianism,<br />

war and plunder.<br />

54 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

One final note on the “hostility among classes” Marx referred to. Ricardo was a staunch<br />

defender to the capitalist class (he was very wealthy and made a fortune in the stock exchange<br />

before migration to England from Holland). Marx, obviously, championed the working<br />

class (having witnessed the deplorable conditions facilitated by the industrial revolution).<br />

Malthus, not surprisingly, defended the rights <strong>of</strong> property owners (landlords). Wages, rent<br />

and pr<strong>of</strong>it are all prominently represented by the three men, and any rhetoric engineered to<br />

improve the advantage <strong>of</strong> one over another would certainly be viewed as an attempt to provoke<br />

class hostility. It is not surprising that Marx was contemptuous; he saw Ricardo’s book<br />

as an overpopulation scare tactic geared at generating capitalist opportunities packaged as a<br />

thesis on political economy.<br />

Source: E.K. Hunt, History <strong>of</strong> Economic Thought: A Critical Perspective, M.E. Sharp,<br />

New York, 2002.<br />

Message [55] referenced by [56] and [64]. Next Message by Babyceta is [56].<br />

[56] Babyceta: Some thoughts from another source. A brief explanation. Some <strong>of</strong><br />

you may have noticed that [55] is my second straight submission where I have referenced E.<br />

K. Hunt, a former economics pr<strong>of</strong>essor here at the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong>. I believe Dr. Hunt’s<br />

book “History <strong>of</strong> Economic Thought”, along with Hans’s annotations, can provided students<br />

with a more comprehensive understanding <strong>of</strong> how the theories and ideas in Marx’s “Capital”<br />

differ from other classical and neo-classical economists. I’m sure Hans would agree that K.<br />

(as he was known to friends and students who were fortunate enough to get to know him) was<br />

a true economic visionary and thinker, and had a knack for articulating complex material into<br />

language that even the most uninitiated econ student could get their hands around. I believe<br />

there are inexpensive copies <strong>of</strong> his book still available in the bookstore.<br />

Next Message by Babyceta is [66].<br />

[64] Hans: <strong>The</strong> Critique Did Not Come from Marx. <strong>The</strong> subject line in [55] already<br />

exhibits the main weakness in Babyceta’s answer: <strong>The</strong> quote did not come from Marx but<br />

from an American businessman who in his later life turned into an economist. Marx himself<br />

liked Ricardo a lot. Look at my relatively short answers [2008fa:100] and [2008SP:33] why<br />

the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value is feared by the capitalists.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [68].<br />

[66] Babyceta: An Apology. Wow. I feel like an complete idiot. I totally misread the<br />

question and assumed the quotation was from Marx. I read more into the quote than was<br />

intended and provided a long-winded response based more on the terms “demagogue” and<br />

“agrarianism” than on labor theory <strong>of</strong> value. I apologize.<br />

Hans: I slightly edited your answer (as I usually do): I struck out the “very” in “very long-winded.” Deadwood<br />

modifier.<br />

Message [66] referenced by [69]. Next Message by Babyceta is [108].<br />

[69] Hans: No apology needed. Babyceta [66], no need to feel bad. Your definitions<br />

<strong>of</strong> agrarianism and demagogy were useful. And your error regarding the Marx-Ricardo<br />

relation tells me I should have made it clear in the question that the critique did not come<br />

from Marx—on the contrary, Ricardo’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value was similar to Marx’s, and<br />

the critique applies to both Ricardo and Marx. Marx said that he learned philosophy from<br />

the Germans (Hegel), political economy from the English (Ricardo), and socialism from the<br />

French (Proudhon). He was critical <strong>of</strong> all three <strong>of</strong> them, but he studied them carefully.


Next Message by Hans is [71].<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 55<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 86 is 100 in 2011fa and 98 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 86 Take two very different kinds <strong>of</strong> labor, such as teaching and construction work,<br />

and discuss in what respect they are equal.<br />

[44] Lindsey: Comparing Different Types <strong>of</strong> Labor. <strong>The</strong> labor <strong>of</strong> a Chef and a Computer<br />

Programmer are very different, however they have many basic similarities as well:<br />

• Both types <strong>of</strong> labor require specialized knowledge which they use to create a product.<br />

(mental labor)<br />

• Both types <strong>of</strong> labor combine individual <strong>thing</strong>s and convert them into a whole → Both<br />

types <strong>of</strong> labor aim to produce some<strong>thing</strong> (for example: a chef takes chicken, cheese, ham,<br />

and breading and converts them into Chicken Cordon Blue; a computer programmer takes<br />

binary numbers and codes and converts them into a game or s<strong>of</strong>tware.)<br />

• Both types <strong>of</strong> labor require time<br />

• Both types <strong>of</strong> labor require at least some bodily movement (the chef has to stir and the<br />

programmer has to type)<br />

• Both types <strong>of</strong> labor may be performed in steps (as they could be written in an instructional<br />

booklet like a cookbook or “Programming for Dummies”)<br />

• Both types <strong>of</strong> labor require tools (a stove/oven/pans; a computer/keyboard/CD)<br />

Hans: Computer programmers do not convert binary numbers into code. <strong>The</strong>y usually improve pre-existing code<br />

or build applications on top <strong>of</strong> it. <strong>The</strong> compiler converts their code into binary numbers which a given hardware<br />

can understand. Only in rare cases do the programmers have to look at the binary numbers themselves.<br />

Not all production processes are hacked into discrete steps. Some <strong>of</strong> the more advanced production processes<br />

are continuous (and then startup and shutdown becomes a big issue).<br />

Message [44] referenced by [48] and [59]. Next Message by Lindsey is [47].<br />

[45] Lana: Labor comparisons. <strong>The</strong> labor <strong>of</strong> a pr<strong>of</strong>essional surfer and a successful<br />

drug dealer are very different. One is praised by society as an amazing athlete, the other is<br />

generally looked down upon as a plague in the system. However, these two pr<strong>of</strong>essions have<br />

numerous labor requirements in which they are equal.<br />

• To be a pr<strong>of</strong>essional surfer one must be able to surf incredibly well (i.e. dropping in,<br />

riding the waves, doing tricks/maneuvers, etc). To be a drug dealer one must know how to<br />

be successful (i.e. “flying under the radar,” having limited clients, etc).<br />

• Surfers must understand and accept the risk <strong>of</strong> serious injury or death involved in their<br />

occupation. Drug dealers must understand and accept the risk <strong>of</strong> becoming imprisoned or<br />

facing severe harm to themselves and others.<br />

• Surfers must know how to read tide/swell charts in order to predict the surfing conditions.<br />

Drug dealers need to be able to easily determine drug quality in order to predict its<br />

market value<br />

• Pr<strong>of</strong>essional surfers should be able to market their surfing abilities in order to obtain<br />

quality company endorsements. Drug dealers know how to market their product to gain<br />

more important clients.<br />

56 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

• Surfers must be able to put themselves in the right position to catch the wave. Dealers<br />

need to locate themselves in a place that’s drug market is without their product, therefore<br />

filling the void.<br />

• Pr<strong>of</strong>essional surfers must know and follow the rules <strong>of</strong> surfing competitions. Dealers<br />

must know the rules and protocol for dealing within the industry.<br />

• Pr<strong>of</strong>essional surfers use their acquired funds to purchase newer gear and take more surf<br />

trips in order to improve surfing skills and reputation. Drug dealers use their acquired funds<br />

to obtain better quality drugs and entire higher industry circle, raising their position in drug<br />

cartel hierarchy.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> points with marketing and reinvesting are not general characteristics <strong>of</strong> production processes but specific<br />

to capitalist relations <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Message [45] referenced by [48] and [59]. Next Message by Lana is [109].<br />

[48] KA: Lindsey [44] and Lana [45] each provide an interesting observation to how two<br />

very different kinds <strong>of</strong> labor have very similar qualities. Marx asserts that the common<br />

element <strong>of</strong> labor is not only the productive nature to make <strong>thing</strong>s useful, but also what<br />

separates one labor from another. <strong>The</strong> comparison <strong>of</strong> a surfer and drug dealer is interesting<br />

since both labor units enable a product to be useful, either by a form <strong>of</strong> entertainment or<br />

consumption. <strong>The</strong> differentiation <strong>of</strong> the labor units is the common element, the extraction <strong>of</strong><br />

human labor. Marx states, “<strong>The</strong>y no longer differ from each other, but are altogether reduced<br />

to equal human labor, human labor in the abstract.”<br />

Next Message by KA is [57].<br />

[59] Hans: Commonalities in labor. I posed this question because I wanted to know<br />

what different labor processes have in common besides being the expenditure <strong>of</strong> human<br />

labor-power.<br />

Evaluating [44] and [45] I am getting the following:<br />

All labor processes are the expenditure <strong>of</strong> human labor-power. <strong>The</strong> skill levels needed<br />

for different labor processes are different, but every labor process needs some level <strong>of</strong> competence.<br />

All labor processes need means <strong>of</strong> production produced by different labor processes. To<br />

continue harping on the same subject as in [54] and [58], this aspect is de-emphasized in<br />

your education so that you don’t notice how crippling the capitalist control over the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production is for the working class. What counts as “primitive” in a “reality” show is a<br />

state very similar to capitalism, where people are deprived <strong>of</strong> access to means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

so that they can never be independent. Are there any reality shows where people have access<br />

to arable fields and well equipped handicraft workshops able to produce every<strong>thing</strong> they need<br />

to survive? I have the hunch that there are some computer games going in this direction but<br />

no reality shows. But I am neither a gamer nor a TV watcher, and I am looking forward to<br />

your input about this.<br />

All labor processes need some material to work on. This too is de-emphasized in your<br />

education. <strong>The</strong> Solow growth model only has labor and capital as factors <strong>of</strong> production. It<br />

omits the earth. Herman Daly took issue with Solow about this. If you have a finite earth and<br />

limited substitutability between natural resources and capital, then the infinite exponential


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 57<br />

growth <strong>of</strong> the Solow growth model is an illusion. Stephen Hawking’s warning that we should<br />

not seek out but rather try to stay away from extraterrestial intelligent beings seems has to do<br />

with this: “We only have to look at ourselves to see how intelligent life might develop into<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> we wouldn’t want to meet. I imagine they might exist in massive ships, having<br />

used up all the resources from their home planet. Such advanced aliens would perhaps<br />

become nomads, looking to conquer and colonise whatever planets they can reach.” This is<br />

from http://www.timesonline.co.uk/tol/news/science/space/article7107207.ece.<br />

All labor processes are social processes. Even if you are producing alone, you could not<br />

have done it without others in society doing complementary <strong>thing</strong>s enabling you to do what<br />

you are doing.<br />

All labor processes have an element <strong>of</strong> risk.<br />

All labor processes take time.<br />

Neither <strong>of</strong> the two submissions said this, but all labor processes also need energy.<br />

Message [59] referenced by [2011fa:17] and [2012fa:33]. Next Message by Hans is [62].<br />

[60] Kraken: (graded A) Landscaper vs. Brain Surgeon. By comparing the labor <strong>of</strong> a<br />

landscaper and a brain surgeon one can see many similarities. Both require physical effort.<br />

Both require the mental capacity to understand the task at hand. Manual dexterity is required<br />

to accomplish the task correctly. Both require a degree <strong>of</strong> training and familiarly with the<br />

tools <strong>of</strong> the trade. Observation and problem solving skills are necessary in both occupations.<br />

Communication skills are required to both give and receive instruction and information from<br />

fellow co-workers. Decisions must be made as to what to cut, what to keep and what to<br />

discard.<br />

If we look at it abstractly enough, the labor <strong>of</strong> a landscaper and the labor <strong>of</strong> a brain surgeon<br />

are equal, being reduced to just “equal human labor”. But in reality, the differences are<br />

greater than the similarities. Can all labor really be “reduced to equal human labor, human<br />

labor in the abstract”? I’m sure as the class progresses, the reasoning behind this mental<br />

exercise will become clear, but for all practical purposes it seems ridiculously abstract and<br />

inapplicable to any<strong>thing</strong> in the real world. In real life, differences in human labor do matter.<br />

I wouldn’t want a landscaper attempting to remove a brain tumor. <strong>The</strong>re is a qualitative<br />

difference in the labor <strong>of</strong> a landscaper and a brain surgeon that makes them different types<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

<strong>The</strong> element <strong>of</strong> water can be thought <strong>of</strong> in the abstract, but once again the differences in<br />

quality are so pr<strong>of</strong>ound that they are for all intents and purposes different <strong>thing</strong>s. Drinking<br />

water from a pure crystal spring will refresh you and sustain your life, whereas drinking<br />

water from a sewer system will make you extremely ill or kill you.<br />

Hans: You are asking some good questions.<br />

Message [60] referenced by [61] and [62]. Next Message by Kraken is [78].<br />

[61] Kohhep: comparing labor. Comparing a school teacher to a construction worker,<br />

it’s easy to see what similarities they do possess, along with what they also do not share.<br />

both <strong>of</strong> these pr<strong>of</strong>essions require training and understanding in their required tasks. both<br />

require energy, time, patience, understanding <strong>of</strong> jargon in the workfield, and also know how<br />

to navigate their work environments. however, i do not see how you could fairly measure the<br />

58 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

labor <strong>of</strong> these two pr<strong>of</strong>essions. when a construction worker completes their task, there is a<br />

newly erected school building. you could measure the time, materials, or even quality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

structure to determine the labor inside this commodity. the school teacher, on the other hand,<br />

has no physically measurable outcome at the end <strong>of</strong> their job. you could use the time the<br />

teacher spent in the classroom while teaching the kids, ask the teacher how they are doing to<br />

determine the energy spent, but ultimately, a teacher’s job is to educate their students. how<br />

can this kind <strong>of</strong> labor possibly be measured accurately? you could use standardized tests to<br />

determine if the students learned the material, but these arguably are not accurate enough<br />

since they do not account for many other variables like language barriers, handicaps, and<br />

poor personal environments.<br />

How could many <strong>of</strong> today’s pr<strong>of</strong>essions and commodities be weighed against each other?<br />

to say that a lawyer’s single hour is equivalent to a secretary’s hour just because they shuffled<br />

the same amount <strong>of</strong> papers just does not seem correct. i don’t want to sound like an echo <strong>of</strong><br />

Kraken [60] but how can you measure the value, or labor, <strong>of</strong> a product that doesn’t physically<br />

exist? i hope i just missed some<strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Hans: Try this, not for capitalism but for socialism, assuming law schools have free tuition: A lawyer’s hour is<br />

equivalent to a secretary’s hour because both kinds <strong>of</strong> labor are necessary, one cannot be done without the other,<br />

secretary and lawyer are working equally hard, and both are equal as human beings.<br />

Message [61] referenced by [75], [81], and [86]. Next Message by Kohhep is [498].<br />

[62] Hans: Is the Abstraction <strong>of</strong> Labor Relevant? According to Kraken [60], the<br />

reduction <strong>of</strong> labor to what is common in all labor processes “seems ridiculously abstract and<br />

inapplicable to any<strong>thing</strong> in the real world. In real life, differences in human labor do matter.”<br />

What do others think about this?<br />

Next Message by Hans is [63].<br />

[130] SMIKEC: Taking two very different fields <strong>of</strong> labor in the world and comparing them<br />

can be done very easily. Taking the example <strong>of</strong> a brain surgeon and replacing the landscaper<br />

with a construction worker you can find comparisons. Again as previously stated throughout<br />

the thread <strong>of</strong> these discussions each unit <strong>of</strong> labor has a value add. Each individual has a share<br />

in the market place to help make the world “go around”. <strong>The</strong>y each take energy, expertise<br />

and a formed skill set in order to achieve a task that is above standard and acceptable to the<br />

consumer. One could argue that a construction worker does not have to go to school to learn<br />

how to hammer nails, where the doctor spends many years <strong>of</strong> his/her life getting schooled on<br />

techniques and procedure in order to be able to do his/her job down the road. I would argue<br />

that the construction worker does go through school via on the job training/ apprenticeship<br />

versus a sit down in class setting such as the doctor experiences. What the Doctor and the<br />

Construction worker do commonly share is that they rely on each other, inadvertently. If it<br />

wasn’t for the construction worker, the doctor would be stitching you up in his back yard<br />

and if it wasn’t for the doctor, the construction worker would still have a broken leg after<br />

falling <strong>of</strong>f the ladder that’s was leaning against the in progress medical building! At the end<br />

<strong>of</strong> the day the commonality is effort. <strong>The</strong> effort put forth is another dollar earned, building<br />

erected or broken leg fixed.<br />

Next Message by SMIKEC is [293].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 90 is 46 in 1996ut, 45 in 1997ut, 83 in 2007SP, 84 in 2008fa, and 105 in 2011fa:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 59<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 90 Does Marx’s “value quasi-material” (Wertgegenständlichkeit) have properties<br />

similar to physical matter?<br />

[53] Trap: Yes “value quasi material” does have some similarities to physical matter.<br />

When Marx is discussing “value quasi material” he is considering the labor-power that has<br />

been put in, which is <strong>of</strong> course different from him simply saying labor, and it is a “material<br />

object without being a material object.” Labor power, as I understand it, is basically the<br />

potential <strong>of</strong> the workers to create an end product. Marx is saying that “value quasi material”<br />

is indeed a product, but more than that, he is looking into what else is in that product, the<br />

labor power <strong>of</strong> the worker. So while physical matter, is similar in that they both create a<br />

product that needs to be sold for money, or as he states it the quasi material is reincarnated<br />

in money. I found this extremely interesting, I believe he is saying that in every product,<br />

quasi or physical, there is much more in it than is tangible. While he is considering “value<br />

quasi material” as some<strong>thing</strong> more abstract than an actual physical object, it ends up being<br />

very similar, especially when you consider that every<strong>thing</strong> made has the same labor-power<br />

as all other objects.<br />

Hans: You originally said “Labor power, as I understand it, is basically the potential <strong>of</strong> the workers to create an<br />

end product, but capitalism <strong>of</strong>ten decreases that potential.” I deleted the clause about capitalism, because this is not<br />

relevant right now, and I don’t want to confuse future readers. Other than that, your thoughts are going in the right<br />

direction. <strong>The</strong> <strong>thing</strong> is: potential labor does not produce any<strong>thing</strong>, only actual labor does. Why does society then<br />

keep track <strong>of</strong> the potential labor as potential labor, although this potential labor was then turned into actual labor<br />

which was then turned into the product? Why is it not enough just to have the product? Because this potential<br />

labor could have been used to produce some<strong>thing</strong> else. If P amount <strong>of</strong> product A is exchanged against Q amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> product B, the reason is that the labor needed to produce P amount <strong>of</strong> product A could also have been used to<br />

produce Q amount <strong>of</strong> product B. That is why the owners <strong>of</strong> the products consider this an equal exchange. Because it<br />

could have been used differently, this potential labor measures how much <strong>of</strong> the other product I can get in exchange.<br />

I am still groping for words to communicate these abstract connections in such a way that they become palatable.<br />

Other attempts are in [2008fa:107] and the earlier messages linked from there.<br />

Message [53] referenced by [432]. Next Message by Trap is [105].<br />

[381] Utefan: Marx’s quasi material value does have physical properties similar to physical<br />

matter. We use the example <strong>of</strong> linen to show how 1 hr. <strong>of</strong> labor produces 20 yards and<br />

is exchangeable with other products that have taken similar labor hours. <strong>The</strong> quality <strong>of</strong> the<br />

product also described in question 176 <strong>of</strong> this exam shows that linen or any commodity has<br />

to be produced well enough to meet exchangeable standards. <strong>The</strong> standards are the physical<br />

like properties <strong>of</strong> the product. Marx explains that it is abstract material <strong>of</strong> labor, a <strong>thing</strong><br />

made <strong>of</strong> thought, those ideas suit fine to describe materiality; the coat exchanged for linen,<br />

linen has a material physical like property that the coat maker desires and couldn’t achieve<br />

with an exchange <strong>of</strong> corn, or wheat.<br />

Hans: You think value quasi-material is a specific use-value (linen as opposed to corn or wheat).<br />

Please re-read choice (b) <strong>of</strong> the multiple choice question 176:<br />

(b) by their decisions what to exchange for what the producers signal to the market not only the quantity <strong>of</strong><br />

value, i.e., the labor content <strong>of</strong> their products, but also the quality <strong>of</strong> the value quasi-material in their products,<br />

namely, they signal that value is a uniform substance different from use-value.<br />

I.e., by <strong>of</strong>fering coats for money, the coat maker says that coats, as value, consist <strong>of</strong> the same social substance<br />

as every other commodity, namely congealed abstract labor. <strong>The</strong> question asks: why does Marx call congealed<br />

abstract labor a “quasi-material”? In what ways is it similar to physical matter? See [2008fa:107].<br />

Utefan: No, I do not think they are use-values. I nowhere in my answer say they are use-values. You are reading<br />

it wrong. I am saying that linen is linen and no<strong>thing</strong> else can be linen. That has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with use-values.<br />

Next Message by Utefan is [385].<br />

60 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[432] JSmits: graded A I think that Marx’s “value quasi-material” does have properties<br />

similar to physical matter because that potential labor or past labor was eventually turned<br />

into the post labor product so part <strong>of</strong> the potential labor has properties similar to physical<br />

matter. After reading [53] and Hans’s response my understanding is “value quasi-material”<br />

is a product but within that product there is also the labor power <strong>of</strong> the worker.<br />

Both physical matter and “value quasi-material” have physical characteristics in the production<br />

process. One is the job <strong>of</strong> the laborer or his skill set (brick layer) and the other is<br />

that he will get tired while working (abstract labor). Value itself is not some<strong>thing</strong> that has<br />

physical properties but through its social relation the production <strong>of</strong> value has that physical<br />

component which is the expenditure <strong>of</strong> labor-power.<br />

Next Message by JSmits is [433].<br />

[491] Intaglio: Value Quasi-Material. Value quasi-material is mistakenly thought <strong>of</strong> as<br />

being a physical property <strong>of</strong> matter, when it is actually abstracted human labor. Human labor<br />

is a social process and does not have properties similar to physical matter. Nevertheless,<br />

people in capitalist economies still treat value quasi-material as physical matter. So, to them<br />

it does have properties similar to physical matter even though this is a false assumption<br />

Hans: It is not a false assumption but it is a social relation which takes the form <strong>of</strong> a quasi-physical ingredient <strong>of</strong> a<br />

<strong>thing</strong> (the commodity). If this is a false assumption then the respect which most US Americans have for the flag is<br />

a false assumption too, because a flag is just a piece <strong>of</strong> cloth. Marx thinks that people should not have this respect<br />

but they should consider themselves as proletarian internationalists, and he also thinks social relations should not<br />

go through <strong>thing</strong>s. But as society exists right now, people do have this respect and social relations do go through<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s. This is a fact about our society, it is not a false assumption.<br />

Next Message by Intaglio is [906].<br />

[530] Hans: <strong>The</strong> Answer. <strong>The</strong> <strong>thing</strong> which Marx calls “Wertgegenstaendlichkeit,” translated<br />

in my Annotations as “value quasi-material,” is a social relation which has properties<br />

resembling the properties <strong>of</strong> a physical substance. This is certainly some<strong>thing</strong> to scratch<br />

your head about. I tried to make it more palatable in [2007SP:38]. Here is the the relevant<br />

passage:<br />

We must make ourselves aware that there are different kinds <strong>of</strong> social relations.<br />

Many social relations take the form <strong>of</strong> a relationship between different<br />

individuals. Such social relations are <strong>of</strong>ten called “interpersonal” relations.<br />

But this is not the only kind <strong>of</strong> social relation. <strong>The</strong> language which<br />

we all speak is also a social relation, so are manners or traffic laws. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

are not interpersonal relations, but they still constitute a social backdrop for<br />

our individual activity.<br />

Another example which I did not bring but could have brought is private property. This is<br />

also a social relation, again not taking the form <strong>of</strong> a direct interaction <strong>of</strong> people, but people<br />

have to respect the <strong>thing</strong>s I own as my private property. People are not allowed to use my<br />

car even if it is parked right there on the street and I am obviously not using it myself right<br />

now. Here is the continuation <strong>of</strong> [2007SP:38]:<br />

An interpersonal relation represents the social command or expectation or<br />

permission to behave in certain ways towards other people, otherwise there<br />

will be consequences. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is the social compulsion


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 61<br />

to treat each commodity in such a way as if the labor needed to produce this<br />

commodity was still present as a non-physical substance inside this <strong>thing</strong>.<br />

One must be very rich before one no longer has to make this calculation<br />

with every<strong>thing</strong> one does.<br />

If you want to read more about this, you may also want to look at [2007SP:313].<br />

OK, after all this language attempting to remove the objection from <strong>of</strong> your minds that<br />

a social relation cannot possibly have properties resembling physical matter, let’s see concretely<br />

if we can find properties <strong>of</strong> value quasi-material where it does visibly resemble physical<br />

matter. I can think <strong>of</strong> three.<br />

(a) If your watch falls on the floor and gets smashed, then the value quasi-material inside<br />

it disappears as well. I.e., a physical act can destroy a social relation as if this relation was<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> physical.<br />

(b) In our society, many people die because they cannot afford medical care although the<br />

doctors and hospitals are there and have empty beds etc available. It is as if these hospitals<br />

were fenced in so that people cannot enter them. <strong>The</strong> value quasi-material can act like a<br />

fence or a brick wall barring people from access to available resources. Well, price stickers<br />

do not look any<strong>thing</strong> like a wall, so how about this analogy: Value quasi-material is like rat’s<br />

poison or bug repellent sprinkled over our hospitals and many other beautiful use-values<br />

out there (Snowbird), preventing a large part <strong>of</strong> our population from using them. (In this<br />

analogy, the poor are our rats or bugs.)<br />

(c) Just like physical use-values, value quasi-material is produced during an actual production<br />

process. Even if the quasi-material itself is not physical, the process producing it is<br />

physical. This last point is elaborated in [2007SP:27].<br />

Message [530] referenced by [2011fa:21]. Next Message by Hans is [534].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 93 is 38 in 1995WI, 47 in 1995ut, 49 in 1996sp, 47 in 1996ut, 46 in<br />

1997ut, 58 in 1999SP, 60 in 2001fa, 73 in 2004fa, 72 in 2005fa, 85 in 2007SP, 85 in<br />

2007fa, 86 in 2008fa, 110 in 2011fa, and 108 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 93 What is value (according to Marx)?<br />

[310] School: Can we Measure Value? Marx doesn’t say that commodities have value,<br />

but they are values “as crystals <strong>of</strong> abstract human labor”. He later compares that a “value”<br />

is a social relation, meaning you can have two commodities and depending on what those<br />

commodities are and who is trading, they will determine the value <strong>of</strong> those commodities.<br />

Message [310] referenced by [313]. Next Message by School is [396].<br />

[313] Hans: Two individuals don’t make a society. School’s definition <strong>of</strong> social relation<br />

in [310] is wrong but I am glad he spelled it out explicitly because others probably have the<br />

same misconception:<br />

A “value” is a social relation, meaning you can have two commodities and<br />

depending on what those commodities are and who is trading, they will<br />

determine the value <strong>of</strong> those commodities.<br />

62 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

This is wrong. Values as Marx understands the word cannot be set by two people in<br />

an exchange. Values are determined by much broader forces, the competition <strong>of</strong> millions<br />

<strong>of</strong> people on the market and the reactions <strong>of</strong> the producers to the market outcomes which<br />

result in an equalization <strong>of</strong> their labors. If value is a social relation this means for Marx<br />

basically that individuals are price takers. Also look at the famous letter by Engels about the<br />

parallelogram <strong>of</strong> forces in the Annotations pp. 97/98.<br />

Also, values are created in production, not on the market, by the socially necessary labor<br />

time in the product. (I know, right now I am reducing value to its quantitative dimension,<br />

which is a no-no for Marx. Marx insists that value also has a quality. But right now I am<br />

stressing the fact that value is social—and this is perhaps easier to see if we only look at the<br />

quantity.)<br />

Next Message by Hans is [314].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 96 is 55 in 1997sp, 49 in 1997ut, 65 in 2002fa, 67 in 2003fa, 77 in 2004fa, 76<br />

in 2005fa, 89 in 2007SP, 89 in 2007fa, 89 in 2008fa, 92 in 2009fa, 115 in 2011fa, and<br />

113 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 96 Why is labor measured here by labor-time, and not by counting how many<br />

movements were made, or by the drops <strong>of</strong> sweat <strong>of</strong> the laborer, or by the discomfort <strong>of</strong> the<br />

laborer?<br />

[75] Hans: If it’s equal you must be able to measure it, don’t you? Kohhep submitted a<br />

forward-looking answer [61] because, although it was written in the last homework period,<br />

it addresses the central issue in the readings assigned right now over the Labor Day weekend<br />

and in the next homework period after this. If, as Marx says, all these different labors are<br />

equal, then it must be possible to measure them against each other, and Kohhep is asking<br />

how this can be done.<br />

Since Kohhep discusses some<strong>thing</strong> before we get to it in the readings, I can do the same<br />

<strong>thing</strong> I did in [71], namely, compare how someone living today addresses this question with<br />

how Marx addresses it.<br />

Kohhep takes it as given that the labor must be measured by its output, but he shows that<br />

this is impossible. Kohhep brings two different arguments:<br />

(1) <strong>The</strong> output <strong>of</strong> a construction worker can be measured precisely, but that <strong>of</strong> a teacher<br />

cannot.<br />

(2) <strong>The</strong>n he compares a lawyer with a secretary. Physically they produce similar <strong>thing</strong>s:<br />

memos, letters, emails. But what matters is the immaterial content <strong>of</strong> these communications.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y are so different that Kohhep is reluctant to give the physical aspect <strong>of</strong> their labor equal<br />

weight. In his own words: “to say that a lawyer’s single hour is equivalent to a secretary’s<br />

hour just because they shuffled the same amount <strong>of</strong> papers just does not seem correct.” But<br />

then he adds “I hope I am missing some<strong>thing</strong>.”<br />

Marx starts out with a much simpler solution. If all labors are equal, then you measure<br />

them by time because this is how labor is measured. See 129:1 in the presently assigned<br />

readings. But this leads him to the lazy worker paradox. <strong>The</strong> resolution <strong>of</strong> this paradox is<br />

not to use the actual time but the “socially necessary” time, as explained by Goldtone in


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 63<br />

[74]. Here Marx tacitly assumes all output can be measured. Complications such as the<br />

difficulties in measuring the output <strong>of</strong> a teacher are ignored.<br />

<strong>The</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> socially necessary labor-time allows to account for differences between<br />

workers producing the same <strong>thing</strong>. How about workers producing different <strong>thing</strong>s? Here<br />

Marx says there may be quantitative differences. A lawyer’s hour produces maybe twice the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> a secretary’s hour because for each year practising law the lawyer had to go to a<br />

year <strong>of</strong> extra schooling, and this schooling time counts as well.<br />

Kohhep and Marx differ less than it might <strong>first</strong> seem. Marx starts with a straighforward<br />

logical derivation which leads him directly into the fangs <strong>of</strong> an impasse, and then he resolves<br />

this impasse. Kohhep by contrast tries to avoid the impasse. That is why he measures labor<br />

time by output. This is a direct way <strong>of</strong> measuring socially necessary labor time instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> actual labor time. But then he forgets that he is looking at output only as a means to<br />

measure labor time, and his argument crashes when he tries to compare outputs <strong>of</strong> different<br />

production processes. This cannot be done because these outputs are qualitatively different.<br />

What he overlooks is that in order to compare the abstract labor <strong>of</strong> lawyer and secretary it is<br />

not necessary to compare their outputs. All you have to do is look at their training, and this<br />

can be compared quantitatively.<br />

Message [75] referenced by [287]. Next Message by Hans is [77].<br />

[80] Alex: graded A– Labor Time. It would seem to me rather peculiar that labor involved<br />

in producing tangible commodities would be measured in labor time instead <strong>of</strong> movements<br />

made, or drops <strong>of</strong> sweat by a laborer. This type <strong>of</strong> labor measurement would be normally<br />

considered for a service performed, such as the time it took for a cab driver to drive a passenger,<br />

or one <strong>of</strong> the simplest forms, how many hours <strong>of</strong> babysitting a nanny performed.<br />

Especially in the case where Marx introduced the concept <strong>of</strong> the lazy laborer, whose labor<br />

is more valuable because <strong>of</strong> the more effort put into it. This would instead lead me to believe<br />

that labor should be measured by quantity and quality produced, as in how many <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodities produced per shift, and how well manufactured they were by a particular<br />

individual. If a lazy laborer is indeed present, his/her work should not be any more valuable<br />

than the other non-lazy coworkers since it took them both the same amount <strong>of</strong> effort to<br />

manufacture a certain commodity. I say this because since their labor is counted by time,<br />

the non-lazy worker manufactured more goods than the lazy worker in a day, or say an hour,<br />

and also because they do not have the same amount <strong>of</strong> willingness to perform such job (I<br />

contrast laziness to willingness). <strong>The</strong>refore, the person who is not lazy should be essentially<br />

paid more or have more value because he is willing to perform the job more, and probably<br />

would do a better quality <strong>of</strong> the job than the other lazy worker, which is my opinion.<br />

This is not what Marx says, however, because he states in 129:2 that “the more lazy and<br />

inept the laborer, the more valuable his commodity would be, because more time would<br />

be required in its production.” Since I see a contradiction <strong>of</strong> my thoughts with what Marx<br />

wrote, I read further to find the reason why he measures labor in labor-time and not by<br />

movements made as stated in the question. <strong>The</strong> conclusion I came up with was that Marx<br />

measures the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity with labor-time spent in the making <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

However, since the commodities are found in a society, the labor-time is an average <strong>of</strong> all<br />

the laborers’ labor times found in that society. As stated by Marx, “<strong>The</strong> total labor-power<br />

64 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> society, which represented in the values <strong>of</strong> the commodities produced by that society,<br />

counts here one and the same human labor-power, though it is composed <strong>of</strong> innumerable<br />

individual labor-powers.” Hans explains as well how then the labor <strong>of</strong> the lazy worker is<br />

measured with the labor <strong>of</strong> the non-lazy individual and taken into account as the same when<br />

incorporated in the glob <strong>of</strong> human labor power. He does so by describing that “the labors are<br />

equal to each other because they are expenditures <strong>of</strong> one and the same human labor-power.<br />

Being expenditures <strong>of</strong> one and the same human labor-power explains why they are equal to<br />

each other—and now we no longer have to deal with the social relation <strong>of</strong> equality but with<br />

the glob <strong>of</strong> human labor-power from which these labors are derived.” So in conclusion, I<br />

suppose Marx would describe the measurement <strong>of</strong> labor in time instead <strong>of</strong> effort because it<br />

is an “average labor power <strong>of</strong> society,” (even though as Hans stated, it doesn’t necessarily<br />

mean arithmetic average), he is counting labor as an accumulation <strong>of</strong> the society’s labor<br />

rather than labor done individually by each member <strong>of</strong> the public.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> output <strong>of</strong> a taxi driver can be measured by distance, and I understand that normally taxis do charge by<br />

distance. Time kicks in only if it takes exceptionally long for the distance driven, i.e., traffic is so slow that distance<br />

is meaningless, or if the cab has to wait for you. <strong>The</strong>n they charge for extra time on top <strong>of</strong> the distance.<br />

Please look at the Marx quote with the lazy or inept laborer again. Marx does not say they produce more value.<br />

He says it might seem that they produce more value, but really they don’t.<br />

Message [80] referenced by [81] and [82]. Next Message by Alex is [147].<br />

[82] Frida: graded A How should we measure labor? It seems to me that labor is<br />

measured by time simply because there is no other means <strong>of</strong> doing it that works for all<br />

types <strong>of</strong> labor. Measuring labor by movements made seems like it would be the best way to<br />

measure certain types <strong>of</strong> labor, maybe number <strong>of</strong> stitches made by a tailor, but this definition<br />

would become meaningless for, say, a teacher. Similarly, there are many jobs that don’t<br />

entail sweating or discomfort.<br />

If we are to define the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity by the “congealed labor” we are going<br />

to need a way to measure labor that is useful for all types <strong>of</strong> laborers. Alex [80] mentioned<br />

quality and quantity <strong>of</strong> products produced as a possible measurement <strong>of</strong> labor power. Quality<br />

obviously won’t work here. In our capitalist system, as long as commodities meet certain<br />

“standards” supervisors don’t care about the quality <strong>of</strong> the products. Any laborer who can’t<br />

meet these standards is simply fired, and anyone who tries to make higher quality products<br />

is simply wasting their effort. In actuality anyone who puts extra effort into what they<br />

are making is probably penalized for taking too much time and wasting the boss’s money.<br />

Quantity also won’t work, since we are looking for a way to define the congealed labor in<br />

commodities. So the amount <strong>of</strong> labor to make a shoe would be defined as “the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

labor to make one shoe” and this is circular.<br />

<strong>The</strong> only other <strong>thing</strong> I can think <strong>of</strong> that is common to all types <strong>of</strong> labor is this elusive<br />

quality, “effort”. <strong>The</strong> foremost problem with measuring labor this way is that it is impossible<br />

to come up with a standard for measuring this quality since it is hopelessly subjective. Also,<br />

as we mentioned above, capitalists don’t reward extra effort or care so this doesn’t seem like<br />

it will work as a measurement <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Message [82] referenced by [87]. Next Message by Frida is [146].<br />

[88] She: graded A Labor is measured by labor-time and not by any other metric because<br />

it is the only <strong>thing</strong> that is required in the production <strong>of</strong> every type <strong>of</strong> commodity. You


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 65<br />

cannot count the movements required because different commodities require different movements.<br />

How can you compare the labor <strong>of</strong> a novelist to that <strong>of</strong> a house framer? How many<br />

keystrokes equal a swing <strong>of</strong> a hammer? Measuring the drops <strong>of</strong> sweat is even more impractical.<br />

Does a novelist even sweat while writing? Does a framer in Arizona sweat more than<br />

one in Alaska? <strong>The</strong> discomfort <strong>of</strong> the worker cannot be reduced into a meaningful metric<br />

as it is far too subjective. Movements, drops <strong>of</strong> sweat, and discomfort all have too many<br />

qualitative variables to be reduced to a quantitative value.<br />

Marx explains that in order to measure the quantity or magnitude <strong>of</strong> value embodied in a<br />

commodity we must breakdown the labor into identical units <strong>of</strong> human labor-power which<br />

are the same across a society. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> step in accomplishing this is to break away from<br />

seeing commodities as different products <strong>of</strong> specialized, concrete labor and to view them as<br />

simply materializations <strong>of</strong> abstract human labor.<br />

All the abstract human labor is pooled together into “. . . one homogenous mass <strong>of</strong> human<br />

labor-power,” [129:2]. This homogenous mass is broken down into equal units that are<br />

measured in socially necessary labor-time. Marx has thus created a common denominator <strong>of</strong><br />

comparison and exchange present in all commodities, regardless <strong>of</strong> the concrete labor form<br />

used to create them.<br />

Message [88] referenced by [91] and [97]. Next Message by She is [218].<br />

[91] Hans: How to Measure Abstract Labor. I submitted [81] because every single<br />

one <strong>of</strong> you rejected the solution proposed by Marx. Marx says that time is the only way to<br />

measure labor, while you all said unanimously: no no, you can’t use time. I really didn’t<br />

know why Marx’s reasoning was so uniformly rejected, therefore I asked at the end <strong>of</strong> [81]:<br />

“Why does the idea <strong>of</strong> measuring labor by time meet so much resistance?”<br />

I think in the meanwhile I figured out the answer. Using Marx’s terminology, the disagreement<br />

comes from the fact that your submissions were discussing how to measure concrete<br />

labor, while Marx is discussing how to measure abstract labor. Just as I was composing<br />

this answer, messages [87] and [88] came through which did in fact discuss abstract labor<br />

and which said <strong>thing</strong>s similar to what I am going to say. <strong>The</strong>y made the present message a<br />

little outdated. Please understand that this is a response to the earlier messages, and that I<br />

am in agreement with [87] and [88].<br />

I will say in a minute what the concepts “concrete” and “abstract” mean, for now let’s just<br />

say that concrete labor is labor as one usually thinks <strong>of</strong> it, and abstract labor needs a little<br />

bit <strong>of</strong> explanation. If one wants to measure concrete labor, then you all agreed (and I agree<br />

too) that the best way to measure it is by measuring its product (assuming the labor leaves a<br />

measurable product).<br />

Now what is abstract labor as opposed to concrete labor? For this let’s look at the context<br />

in which Marx asked the question how to measure labor. From observing the exchange<br />

process in a commodity society Marx concluded that exchange proportions are proportional<br />

to labor input. But this statement only makes sense if you can measure labor input, this is<br />

why Marx is asking how to measure labor input.<br />

66 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Measuring by the product does not work here because Marx needs to compare different<br />

kinds <strong>of</strong> labor, and the products <strong>of</strong> different kinds <strong>of</strong> labor are qualitatively different and<br />

cannot be compared.<br />

So how should labor be measured instead? For this we need to understand a little better<br />

the reasoning behind the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value. Here is one way to think <strong>of</strong> it. Society has<br />

only a limited pool <strong>of</strong> labor-power available, and the value <strong>of</strong> a product is determined by<br />

how much <strong>of</strong> this pool was used to produce this product. If 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen have a value<br />

equal to 1 coat, this means that they absorbed equal amounts <strong>of</strong> that pool, i.e., the laborpower<br />

needed to produce 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen could also have been used to produce 1 coat.<br />

This does not necessarily mean the linen weaver is also skilled to produce coats, it may<br />

require retraining etc., but society’s pool <strong>of</strong> labor-power is flexible enough that it can be put<br />

to different uses.<br />

This pool <strong>of</strong> labor-power consists <strong>of</strong> living human beings who are able to do various<br />

different kinds <strong>of</strong> labor. But each <strong>of</strong> them only has a limited number <strong>of</strong> hours available<br />

every day, they cannot work 24 hours but also need to rest and eat and sleep. If Marx<br />

talks about the abstract labor represented by a product, he means exactly this: how much <strong>of</strong><br />

society’s pool <strong>of</strong> available labor was occupied to produce this product. If you want to put a<br />

number on this, labor-time is a good method. If we know the production time under average<br />

conditions, we know how much <strong>of</strong> a bite the production <strong>of</strong> a product took out <strong>of</strong> a worker’s<br />

daily capacity to work, time which could also have been used to produce some<strong>thing</strong> else.<br />

She: Hans concludes this comment by stating that the time used in the production <strong>of</strong> a commodity could have been<br />

used to produce some<strong>thing</strong> else. This is opportunity cost. I find it helpful to pick out pieces <strong>of</strong> Marx that are focused<br />

on basic economic principles that are easily understood. It makes understanding the larger concepts much easier<br />

and facilitates further exploration into the underlying minutiae.<br />

Message [91] referenced by [112] and [287]. Next Message by Hans is [92].<br />

[97] Zarathustra: (graded A+) For She. <strong>The</strong> following quotes are from She [88].<br />

Your <strong>first</strong> sentence: “Labor is measured by labor-time and not by any other metric because<br />

it is the only <strong>thing</strong> that is required in the production <strong>of</strong> every type <strong>of</strong> commodity.” I cannot<br />

agree with you. Is really time “the only <strong>thing</strong> that is required in the production”? What<br />

would time do without human labor?<br />

Your second sentence: “You cannot count the movements required because different commodities<br />

require different movements. How can you compare the labor <strong>of</strong> a novelist to that <strong>of</strong><br />

a house framer?” True, I agree, but what about the next sentence which is your conclusion?<br />

Your last sentence: “Marx has thus created a common denominator <strong>of</strong> comparison and<br />

exchange present in all commodities, regardless <strong>of</strong> the concrete labor form used to create<br />

them.” Is the concept <strong>of</strong> time “created” by Marx or by capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production? I think<br />

Marx is here explaining capitalism and not creating any<strong>thing</strong>. I might be wrong, but if I’m<br />

right, I think, if Marx was free to “create” a standard, he would not come up with ‘time.’ I<br />

think Marx would take individuals/ ability and need as the standards. He would talk about<br />

social potential <strong>of</strong> individuals, and not time.<br />

I might be wrong though—I would like to hear what you think.<br />

Hans: I like your precision. What you say about Marx not creating any<strong>thing</strong> was spot on. That is what earned you<br />

the A+


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 67<br />

Your <strong>first</strong> paragraph is overstated. She did not mean time itself but the labor performed during this time. You<br />

might have said: “I know you mean the right <strong>thing</strong> but your formulation is unfortunate.”<br />

In your second paragraph you indicate you disagree with some<strong>thing</strong> but you are not telling us what you disagree<br />

with or why.<br />

She: My <strong>first</strong> sentence is perhaps poorly written or organized. <strong>The</strong> emphasis I intended was not on the word<br />

“only” but on the words “every type.” Perhaps my thoughts would have been better articulated had I added the<br />

word “common” after only. I meant abstract labor is the only common contributor to all forms <strong>of</strong> commodities;<br />

certainly time cannot spontaneously produce commodities. I think it is important to think <strong>of</strong> labor-time as not being<br />

time, but being the unit <strong>of</strong> measurement for abstract labor as deduced by Marx in the reading for this section.<br />

Again, in my conclusion, I could have been more articulate and made my ideas more presentable. I did not<br />

intend to give the representation that Marx created “time.” He created, or formulated, a way to 1) Find abstract<br />

labor 2) Measure it in universal units to facilitate comparison and exchange. I don’t think Marx really considers<br />

individuals much in his labor theory <strong>of</strong> value as he breaks down labor into “social” terms. He views labor in<br />

the aggregate. He makes clear the abstraction <strong>of</strong> use-value also takes away any individual contribution to the<br />

commodity. <strong>The</strong> concrete forms <strong>of</strong> labor (specialized labor <strong>of</strong> an individual) are stripped away in the <strong>first</strong> step <strong>of</strong><br />

measuring the magnitude <strong>of</strong> value. Most importantly, what Marx created is a formula <strong>of</strong> finding value-he did not<br />

create time. He simply uses labor-time, as he defines it, to be the metric to allow comparison between two products<br />

<strong>of</strong> different kinds <strong>of</strong> specialized labor.<br />

Message [97] referenced by [147]. Next Message by Zarathustra is [100].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 97 is 57 in 1997WI, 57 in 1997sp, 63 in 1999SP, 65 in 2001fa, 66 in 2002fa, 68<br />

in 2003fa, 78 in 2004fa, 77 in 2005fa, 90 in 2007SP, 90 in 2007fa, 92 in 2008SP, 90 in<br />

2008fa, 93 in 2009fa, and 117 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 97 Is it a character flaw to be lazy in an exploitive system?<br />

[76] Robert: graded A+ What is lazy and is it bad? Interestingly much <strong>of</strong> our language<br />

is loaded with emotional meaning, which leads to different understanding <strong>of</strong> the same word<br />

by different people. For example, George Lak<strong>of</strong>f has written a book entitled “<strong>The</strong> Political<br />

Mind” in which he describes how politicians can use short emotionally charged phrases<br />

such as “cut and run” to appeal to the irrational impulses <strong>of</strong> their constituents. This method<br />

is particularly effective when critical thought may lead to conclusions outside <strong>of</strong> the political<br />

motives <strong>of</strong> the speaker.<br />

For me at least, this question employs two words that evoke an emotional response. <strong>The</strong><br />

<strong>first</strong> is the word lazy. Since the context <strong>of</strong> the question is an exploitive system such as the<br />

capitalistic system in which most <strong>of</strong> us reading this question find ourselves, I suggest that the<br />

emotion invoked in most <strong>of</strong> us by the word lazy is greatly affected by the our culturization in<br />

modern capitalism. Protestantism adapted rapidly to capitalism (or capitalism appropriated<br />

religion in general and Protestantism in particular to further its exploitation <strong>of</strong> the workers)<br />

and the Protestant work ethic is systemic in our capitalistic society. <strong>The</strong>refore, hard work<br />

is a positive, godly trait and laziness is “the devils workshop.” (<strong>The</strong> fact that hard work by<br />

workers increases the pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>of</strong> the owners <strong>of</strong> production is not much discussed in western<br />

religions.) <strong>The</strong>refore, almost immediately upon reading this question we all emotionally<br />

react to a “lazy” as a negative <strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Furthermore, “character” is also full <strong>of</strong> societal meanings. In our society the definition <strong>of</strong><br />

character may include such ideas as industriousness but almost assuredly in includes such<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s as honesty. <strong>The</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> an “honest day’s work for an honest day’s pay” in our society<br />

68 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

seems to apply much more to the work side <strong>of</strong> the equation than to the pay side <strong>of</strong> the<br />

equation.<br />

Our question, in exposed emotional language, then becomes some<strong>thing</strong> like: is it honest<br />

for a worker to act negatively by performing less work than his exploitive employer thinks<br />

he should. Hans in [2009fa:93] outlined four reasons why the worker may do less work<br />

and be labeled “lazy.” Hans takes the emotion or, at least, the judgment out <strong>of</strong> the analysis,<br />

(although it appears laziness if still viewed negatively, although possibly justifiable, in his<br />

examples) which is very instructive in understanding the question. With this answer I hope<br />

to add the explicit understanding that most <strong>of</strong> us cannot help but respond emotionally to the<br />

fact that laziness is negative and a character flaw as defined in the eyes <strong>of</strong> capitalism. Hans<br />

helps us understand that there are other eyes with which to view the situation.<br />

I would also like to suggest a fifth reason or motivation for why the worker may appear<br />

to be lazy. <strong>The</strong> worker may be a very present, mindful, and aware individual, whose concern<br />

is not in pleasing his employer but in performing his work in a matter that is fulfilling to<br />

himself. He may find self-actualization in carefully and beautifully placing the bolts into the<br />

product <strong>of</strong> an assembly line. <strong>The</strong> employer may not care at all about how beautifully the<br />

bolts are placed, just that so many are placed by the employee in a certain amount <strong>of</strong> time so<br />

that he can exchange the product as quickly as possible for the greatest pr<strong>of</strong>it margin. <strong>The</strong><br />

employee in this example is likely to be labeled as lazy, with all <strong>of</strong> its negative conations<br />

in our society, and coerced by his employer, fellow employees and, possibly, his clergy to<br />

produce more (and disregard his own psycho-spiritual development).<br />

In my view, the individual I describe does not have a character flaw, but possibly has the<br />

highest possible character trait: honesty to oneself. Conversely, I would argue that many<br />

workers who are hard working might do so as a way to avoid confronting their own psychospiritual<br />

development. While society may pat these individuals on the back (i.e., owners <strong>of</strong><br />

production, who pr<strong>of</strong>it by their hard work, may hold them up as exemplary) they may suffer<br />

from the great character flaw <strong>of</strong> not being true to themselves.<br />

Next Message by Robert is [153].<br />

[753] Bigwhite: Just enough. Im intrigued by the argument that labor is under paid<br />

and justifiable so, yet on the other side <strong>of</strong> the coin there is the worker that is reaping all<br />

the spoils while being lazy and taking full advantage <strong>of</strong> the technological advances that are<br />

afforded to him. Everyone is arguing that anyone that is on a salary wage is being vastly<br />

underpaid for their excessive hours worked. I’d like to be a cynic and say that a lot <strong>of</strong><br />

workers milk the system and do just enough to get by and keep their jobs. Which seems like<br />

a valid <strong>thing</strong> to do since their being underpaid anyway, why not work half ass if you’re being<br />

exploited. I feel like this is the case in almost every business there will always be the worker<br />

or workers that do not produce what they are being paid. So does that hurt the other laborers<br />

in the capitalistic dynamic, by making them work harder to cover what the other workers are<br />

slacking on?<br />

Message [753] referenced by [755] and [756]. Next Message by Bigwhite is [771].<br />

[756] Frida: Stereotype <strong>of</strong> the lazy worker. Your argument in [753] seems to imply<br />

that only the fastidious workers are underpaid while the lazy ones are overpaid and that the<br />

capitalist is just paying out a just average between the two. <strong>The</strong> fact is that even the laziest


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 69<br />

minimum wage worker is producing a lot more value with her labor than the capitalist is<br />

paying her.<br />

Another point, I don’t know what your job experience has been, but the only workers<br />

I have ever seen get away with excessive laziness are people with managerial and similar<br />

positions. Especially in this job market, it is easy to replace unskilled workers. (Not that<br />

Manager is really that skilled <strong>of</strong> a job, the main purpose a manager serves in capitalism is<br />

to keep workers in their place. Barbara Ehrenreich in her book Nickel and Dimed states<br />

numerous examples <strong>of</strong> times when managers could have helped their workes but didn’t, and<br />

that she never came up with a purpose they could serve other than keeping workers in line.<br />

Managers usually don’t know as much about the work as the workers do. <strong>The</strong>re are, <strong>of</strong><br />

course, many many exceptions to this rule and I have known a ton <strong>of</strong> managers that have<br />

been helpful and kind and useful, but it is usually when they are fulfilling a role that is not<br />

managerial) This image <strong>of</strong> the lazy worker that will only do the minimum to survive is, in<br />

my opinion, a myth mostly propagated by people who stand to benefit from it. It is a classic<br />

stereotype that was born during the capitalists struggles against unionization more than a<br />

century ago.<br />

Next Message by Frida is [800].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 99 is 70 in 2003fa, 92 in 2007SP, 92 in 2008fa, 95 in 2009fa, 118 in 2011fa,<br />

and 117 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 99 Regarding the question how to measure the quantity <strong>of</strong> value, Marx <strong>first</strong> gives<br />

a wrong answer, which is based on an oversight, and then corrects it. Why doesn’t he give<br />

the right answer right away?<br />

[101] Cougar: graded A– First a wrong and then a Right? I was hoping others would<br />

attempt this question. Hans’ comments [2007SP:65] in Spring <strong>of</strong> 2007 were most helpful in<br />

addressing Marx’s methodology:<br />

“...Marx is trying to give a critical analysis <strong>of</strong> capitalism as it existed during his time,<br />

and as it still exists today. His critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism has two prongs. On the one hand,<br />

Marx establishes that the market value <strong>of</strong> commodities is determined by labor-time. In other<br />

words, only the workers, not the capitalists or managers or banks create this value.”<br />

Marx begins by introducing actual labor time as a quantity measure <strong>of</strong> value. He is<br />

building a foundation to critique the Capitalist ideology. According to Hans’ annotations,<br />

the universal characteristic <strong>of</strong> value, that allows for the exchange <strong>of</strong> all commodities with<br />

one another, is human labor. As Marx points out, human labor cannot be quantified and<br />

measured as a common denominator among all commodities unless it is indeed equal among<br />

all human inputs. <strong>The</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> the “lazy” or “inept worker” introduces the social aspect<br />

<strong>of</strong> abstract human labor. In essence, two workers may not produce the same amount <strong>of</strong> given<br />

commodity in the same amount <strong>of</strong> labor hours due to varying levels <strong>of</strong> efficiency. <strong>The</strong>refore,<br />

Marx does not believe that the “capitalist” quantification <strong>of</strong> value (actual labor hours) is an<br />

accurate representation <strong>of</strong> labor input. As Khub [2008fa:138] refers to in the fall <strong>of</strong> 2008<br />

archive, Marx uses a “lazy” method <strong>of</strong> response to critique the initially proposed “capitalist”<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> value. This “lazy” method effectively emphasizes the conundrum posed by the<br />

<strong>first</strong> or “incorrect” method <strong>of</strong> quantifying value and provides a valid critique.<br />

70 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Your long quote from [2007SP:65] is <strong>of</strong>f the subject: it is not an answer to the question itself but my<br />

response to the misconception by those who tried to answer this question that Marx was designing a blueprint for a<br />

better society.<br />

In your last paragraph, you originally had “<strong>The</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> the ‘lazy’ or ‘inept worker’ introduces the social<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> human labor.” I clarified this by adding the word “abstract.” This is the invisible social element I am<br />

talking about in [112].<br />

Message [101] referenced by [112]. Next Message by Cougar is [227].<br />

[112] Hans: One can’t be faulted for overlooking some<strong>thing</strong> that is invisible. Cougar<br />

[101] picked a difficult question. His answer collects some interesting tidbits from the Annotations<br />

and the archives about it, but they don’t make a coherent answer. I have been<br />

puzzling over this question myself, that’s why I asked it. Here is how I am thinking about it<br />

right now.<br />

Marx is at an impasse again, similar to the impasse at the beginning <strong>of</strong> the discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange-value, when he had to say in 126:2: “Let us consider the matter more closely.”<br />

But the way how this impasse arose is different. In the earlier impasse, Marx noticed that<br />

exchange-value sometimes manifests itself as some<strong>thing</strong> intrinsic to the commodity, and<br />

sometimes as some<strong>thing</strong> relative. Both <strong>of</strong> these manifestations were right, it is not that Marx<br />

did not see <strong>thing</strong>s right. <strong>The</strong> contradiction was not his fault but it was the exchange-value’s<br />

fault. <strong>The</strong>refore Marx asked why exchange-value manifests itself in such a contradictory<br />

fashion.<br />

<strong>The</strong> impasse with the paradox <strong>of</strong> the lazy worker arose in a different way. Marx is arguing<br />

in his careful step-by-step manner how to measure abstract labor. He arrives at the<br />

conclusion that it should be measured by time. I tried to explain in [91] how he arrives at<br />

this. In short, he has to use time because abstract labor is the opportunity cost <strong>of</strong> the time<br />

used to produce the product. <strong>The</strong>re is no<strong>thing</strong> wrong with his reasoning, so it seems. Yet<br />

if he tries to apply this reasoning to the real world, he realizes that he would get an absurd<br />

result. If he measures abstract labor by time then a product produced by a lazy person is<br />

worth more than the same product produced by a competent laborer.<br />

But then he says he overlooked some<strong>thing</strong> (that abstract labor is “equal” human labor),<br />

and when this <strong>thing</strong> that he overlooked is considered (by taking averages to eliminate individual<br />

differences), then the impasse is overcome. This is why I’d like to ask Marx: when it<br />

was your fault that you got into the contradiction (because you overlooked some<strong>thing</strong>), why<br />

didn’t you present the whole issue from the beginnning without this oversight?<br />

In order to answer this, we must understand better what this oversight consisted in. <strong>The</strong><br />

next two paragraphs explain this; they are literally from the Annotations.<br />

Let us recapitulate where we are in the overall argument. We observed that commodities,<br />

on the market, were treated as equals. Since they are not equal as physical objects, their only<br />

commonality being that they are products <strong>of</strong> labor, this equality must be the surface echo<br />

<strong>of</strong> the fact that in production, the labors producing these commodities count as equal. Of<br />

course, the producers can only then successfully and enduringly treat the different labors as<br />

equal if there is some<strong>thing</strong> actually equal in them. We found such a <strong>thing</strong>: the actual equality<br />

<strong>of</strong> all labor processes consists in all labor being the expenditure <strong>of</strong> human labor-power.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 71<br />

But when we tried to use this insight to determine the quantity <strong>of</strong> value, we ran into the<br />

paradox <strong>of</strong> the lazy or incompetent laborer. What did we overlook? Our mistake was that<br />

we tried to explain a social relation by a physiological fact, i.e., we committed the error <strong>of</strong><br />

reductionism. <strong>The</strong> physiological equality <strong>of</strong> all labor is the material basis, the condition for<br />

the social relation <strong>of</strong> abstract labor, but it is not that social relation itself. In other words,<br />

the fact that all labors are the expenditure <strong>of</strong> human labor makes it possible for society to<br />

treat all labors as equal, but is by itself not yet this equal treatment. This equal treatment<br />

is a social act. Until now, human labor in the abstract had been introduced simply as the<br />

expenditure <strong>of</strong> human labor-power, without a social element. <strong>The</strong> lazy worker reminds us<br />

that abstract labor is indeed social.<br />

<strong>The</strong> question is therefore: why didn’t Marx introduce this social dimension from the<br />

beginning and in this way avoid the paradox <strong>of</strong> the lazy worker? <strong>The</strong> Annotations try several<br />

explanations, but the one I like best is simply: because these social relations are invisible.<br />

<strong>The</strong> commodity producers themselves do not know either how much value their commodity<br />

has, all they know is how much time their concrete labor takes. Due to this invisibility,<br />

the paradox <strong>of</strong> the lazy worker signals a real contradiction—that individual labor processes,<br />

necessarily different from each other, come together to produce the socially uniform “value<br />

quasi-material”—and not a flaw in Marx’s argument.<br />

Message [112] referenced by [101]. Next Message by Hans is [117].<br />

[386] Trap: In Capital, Marx is trying to decipher capitalism and starts by breaking<br />

down the important elements, that are necessary to understand in order to see the big picture<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalism. In chapter 1, entitled “Commodity” he tries to understand the commodity,<br />

and the <strong>thing</strong> inherent in it, the value. He specifically spends time trying to discover a<br />

way to measure the quantity <strong>of</strong> value. In his <strong>first</strong> attempt he decides to measure it based<br />

on the amount <strong>of</strong> time spent producing each commodity, meaning values <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

would vary greatly from producer to producer, since value is created by abstract labor. He<br />

overlooks the lazy and inept laborers who would benefit from this, because they take so<br />

much longer to create the commodity, therefore making more <strong>of</strong> a pr<strong>of</strong>it than a laborer who<br />

takes half the time. So Marx revises his measure <strong>of</strong> the quantity <strong>of</strong> value to make the value<br />

based on the average time spent, thus enabling productive workers to receive the same as<br />

unproductive workers, who could spend twice as long on creating the commodity. This<br />

creates an equality among workers. According to Marx this is the only way to estimate the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> commodities, the only commonality among all commodities is labor. Hans says in<br />

the 2009 annotations that “abstract labor is the opportunity cost <strong>of</strong> the time used to produce<br />

the product.”<br />

Marx doesn’t give the correct answer right away because it is not a simple idea, and it is<br />

necessary to elaborate and develop the idea, in order to come to the correction. He says that<br />

social relations are invisible, making it hard to recognize right away, which is why it takes<br />

some time to understand it.<br />

Hans: Your wording that Marx “decides” to measure abstract labor by time is a little ambiguous. It is not Marx’s<br />

decision since, as you also say, this is the only way to measure abstract labor. See also my [364] about this.<br />

Next Message by Trap is [388].<br />

[473] Guh: According to Hans, “Marx did not begin with the right answer because the<br />

right answer is not a fixed and finished <strong>thing</strong> that can be delivered to your door step. <strong>The</strong><br />

72 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> the subject, here capitalist society, is necessarily a process, a development,<br />

and Marx takes his time elaborating each stage <strong>of</strong> the development before moving on.” Moreover,<br />

Marx gives the wrong answer at <strong>first</strong>, because Marx is trying to give a critical analysis<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalism as it existed during his time, and as it still exist today, as Hans states. Furthermore,<br />

Marx then gives the examples and critiques capitalism. First, he talks about the<br />

market value <strong>of</strong> commodities as it is determined by labor-time. Secondly, Marx explains that<br />

the wages <strong>of</strong> the workers are far below the value they create.<br />

Next Message by Guh is [474].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 100 is 68 in 2002fa, 72 in 2003fa, 82 in 2004fa, 80 in 2005fa, 93 in 2007SP, 95<br />

in 2008SP, 93 in 2008fa, and 118 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 100 Imagine you were studying Marxism together with a friend, and the friend<br />

said to you: Doesn’t the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value imply that, the more lazy and inept the laborer,<br />

the more valuable his commodity would be? How would you answer your friend?<br />

[74] Goldtone: graded A Dear misguided friend, At <strong>first</strong> glance, and without further<br />

understanding, my friend seems to have a valid argument. Marx seems to make a huge<br />

mistake in attaching value to its duration or labor-time. He personally brings the immediate<br />

and logical counter argument involving the lazy worker (lazy labor-power), and how it seems<br />

that the more lazy the worker, the more valuable his or her commodity.<br />

This would be true, if Marx didn’t also later in his argument say: “Each <strong>of</strong> these individual<br />

labor-powers is the same human labor-power as any other, to the extent that it has<br />

the character <strong>of</strong> the average labor-power <strong>of</strong> society and takes effect as such, and therefore<br />

requires, for producing a commodity, no more than is socially necessary.” (My own emphasis).<br />

<strong>The</strong> phrase “average labor-power <strong>of</strong> society” is critical here. This essentially means that<br />

one can average out all the individual workers’ labor-powers into one big “glob <strong>of</strong> human<br />

labor-power”, as Hans puts it. Personally, I thought <strong>of</strong> the normal curve, and how 95% <strong>of</strong> its<br />

mass (or labor-power in this case) is within one standard deviation on either side away from<br />

the mean. This 95% would be the “average labor-power <strong>of</strong> society” that Marx is talking<br />

about, and would serve as the standard measuring device for value and its link to labor-time.<br />

In more concrete terms, as Hans points out, “the reduction <strong>of</strong> a given labor-power to this<br />

average labor-power is made by the speed <strong>of</strong> the output (i.e., a labor-power that produces<br />

twice as fast as the average also produces twice the value).” Those workers that work twice<br />

as fast will be rewarded by producing twice the value that the slower workers would. This is<br />

why the lazy worker counter argument, although initially seemingly valid, actually falls flat<br />

on its face.<br />

Message [74] referenced by [75], [81], [87], and [477]. Next Message by Goldtone is [154].<br />

[78] Kraken: (graded C weight 50%) Lazy and inept laborers. I would tell my friend<br />

that just because a lazy or inept worker took twice as long to make a product, that doesn’t<br />

make the product twice as valuable. Marx placed value on a product by looking at what was<br />

the average labor power required to produce that product. So although the lazy/inept worker<br />

took twice as long to do his job, once you averaged him in with the rest <strong>of</strong> society, his effect<br />

on value would be virtually imperceptible. In order for Mr. Lazy to really increase the value


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 73<br />

<strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong>, he would have to convince a large segment <strong>of</strong> the workforce to slow down and<br />

quit being so productive and recalculate the average.<br />

Hans: Marx’s Capital is not a proposal how products should be valued. It is not Marx placing value on a product<br />

but Marx analyzing how market values are determined in capitalism. From investigating capitalism, Marx came to<br />

the conclusion that prices are determined by labor content. This does not mean workers in capitalism get paid a full<br />

equivalent <strong>of</strong> the value they produce. We will get to this later.<br />

Message [78] referenced by [79], [81], [92], and [147]. Next Message by Kraken is [99].<br />

[79] Zarathustra: Workers <strong>of</strong> the World Unite. Kraken [78] made me think <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong><br />

totally unrelated. But I think I should say that. Kraken said “[Mr. Lazy worker] would<br />

have to convince a large segment <strong>of</strong> the workforce ...” I think this suggestion is the core <strong>of</strong><br />

Marx’s work, that is, in order to do some<strong>thing</strong> and being effective people must collate, group<br />

up, and launch a movement. But with the current mode <strong>of</strong> globalization and international<br />

trade the coalition must be global. I think this is why Marx said workers <strong>of</strong> ‘the world’ unite.<br />

Lastly, workers don’t need to be less productive. <strong>The</strong>y could be hourly as productive as<br />

before and demand the same weekly wage for less hours, say, 25 hours, per week. In the<br />

new situation the output <strong>of</strong> the given business will decrease, but it doesn’t mean that workers<br />

are slacking; rather it means they are having a better life (without being lazy) in a more just<br />

system.<br />

Hans: Yes, Marx certainly thinks so. Capitalism is not just the fault <strong>of</strong> some greedy individuals, but it is a defective<br />

social relation. Individuals cannot change social relations. <strong>The</strong>y have to organize to become a social force.<br />

Message [79] referenced by [81]. Next Message by Zarathustra is [86].<br />

[81] Hans: How naive, measuring labor by time, tsk tsk. <strong>The</strong> answers submitted so<br />

far have an emotional undercurrent which I am trying to understand better. Goldtone [74]<br />

implies that Marx would have made a huge mistake had he measured labor by time, but<br />

fortunately he came to his senses and is measuring by average time. Kraken [78] mistrusts<br />

the average measure too since it can be gamed if all workers agree to work slowly. Kohhep<br />

[61] says: “to say that a lawyer’s single hour is equivalent to a secretary’s hour ... just does<br />

not seem correct.” And Alex [80] says that maybe services should be measured by time, but<br />

not labor producing tangible products.<br />

Here Kohhep might say I am misrepresenting him by leaving out part <strong>of</strong> the sentence,<br />

but I think the omission reveals the underlying argument. And Kranen did not say that<br />

he mistrusts the concept, he only said that it can be gamed and let the reader draw the<br />

conclusion.<br />

Zarathustra [79] does not join in the mudslinging againt labor time. This does not weaken<br />

my argument because Zarathustra rarely follows the general consensus anyway.<br />

All this is in stark contrast to Marx who acts as if labor time was the only way to measure<br />

labor. I want to clarify that Marx is not discussing how labor should be measured, but Marx<br />

says this is how markets spontaneously measure and compare labor—by time. But I think<br />

your objections are not that Marx’s theory is wrong but that labor shouldn’t be measured by<br />

time. Why does the idea <strong>of</strong> measuring labor by time meet so much resistance? Shouldn’t we<br />

be glad that markets come to such a fair and equitable outcome?<br />

Message [81] referenced by [86] and [91]. Next Message by Hans is [91].<br />

[83] Kleenex: the lazy farmer is not better <strong>of</strong>f. I would tell my friend that he is wrong:<br />

Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value does not at all imply that the lazy or inept worker produces<br />

74 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

commodities with higher value, just because more labor-time was spent during the production<br />

process. Marx writes, “the individual commodity counts here generally as an average<br />

sample <strong>of</strong> its kind.” When a consumer looks at a commodity, he or she does not see how<br />

much labor-time was put into producing the commodity. <strong>The</strong> consumer will rather consider<br />

the commodity’s use-value and the “average labor power” found in it. <strong>The</strong> consumer won’t<br />

know that it took 10 minutes for a farmer to harvest one bunch <strong>of</strong> grapes, or that it took the<br />

next farmer only 2 minutes to harvest the same <strong>thing</strong>. All the consumer sees is the use-value.<br />

He or she will pay the same price for either <strong>of</strong> the bundle <strong>of</strong> grapes.<br />

To illustrate and continue on my discussion <strong>of</strong> grapes, let’s suppose that on average, it<br />

takes 2 minutes <strong>of</strong> labor-time to harvest one bunch <strong>of</strong> grapes. Let’s also suppose that a lazy<br />

farmer wants to take 10 minutes to do the job, if he is truly lazy, and not just deliberately<br />

taking extra time to produce a better product. (Longer time in production does not always<br />

imply laziness.) His output is not 5 times more valuable than the grapes that took 2 minutes<br />

to harvest by the average farmer because he took 5 times the average labor-time. Also,<br />

this lazy farmer could not reasonably expect to trade his grapes with another commodity<br />

that on average, requires 10 minutes <strong>of</strong> expenditure <strong>of</strong> human labor-power to produce. In<br />

conclusion, the lazy farmer does not benefit with a higher-value commodity in the end,<br />

rebutting my friend’s statement.<br />

Hans: You are coming to an interesting and, in the scenario you describe, also correct conclusion. <strong>The</strong> lazy worker<br />

does not benefit. This raises the question: why is he then lazy? According to your argument, the lazy worker also<br />

does not harm others, he only harms himself if he wastes his own time. Again: why is there then such a strong<br />

negative sentiment against lazy workers? All this has to do with it that you are talking about independent producers<br />

selling their own product, while our usual experience with lazy workers comes from capitalist wage labor.<br />

Message [83] referenced by [398]. Next Message by Kleenex is [289].<br />

[86] Zarathustra: (graded A) In Capitalism, Labors are Not Equal. It seems when<br />

we juxtapose different occupations (e.g. a lawyer vs a secretary, a surgeon vs gardener,<br />

etc.) some <strong>of</strong> us are inclined to value the more sophisticated job better, and then come up<br />

with various solutions, such as asking workers to slack. As far as we are talking about how<br />

capitalism works, these answers (e.g. Kohhep [61] says: “to say that a lawyer’s single hour<br />

is equivalent to a secretary’s hour ... just does not seem correct”) are right. By that I mean,<br />

if I were Kohhep, I would rephrase my statement and then state: based on the criteria <strong>of</strong> our<br />

capitalist society one hour <strong>of</strong> a lawyer’s time is more precious than one hour <strong>of</strong> a secretary’s<br />

time.<br />

But if we change our paradigm (getting out <strong>of</strong> this capitalist societal system)—change our<br />

yardstick—the above answers, I think, are not right. If instead <strong>of</strong> juxtaposing occupations<br />

we put a lawyer next to a secretary as two human beings, their times and life (abstract and<br />

equal human labor power) are equal. Hans asked at the end <strong>of</strong> [81]: “Shouldn’t we be glad<br />

that markets come to such a fair and equitable outcome?” As far as one hour <strong>of</strong> my life (my<br />

labor power) as a farmer is equal to all other farmers, it is fair. But since the value <strong>of</strong> one<br />

hour <strong>of</strong> my life is not equal to that <strong>of</strong> a businessman, I think the market is unfair.<br />

(I am not quite confident now, however. Because Hans said Zarathustra “rarely follows<br />

the general consensus anyway” my emphasis.) I am not the guy who just disagrees with<br />

every<strong>thing</strong>. I don’t want to play the devil’s advocate. I would like to hear from you guys,<br />

particularly Hans, Goldtone, Kraken, Kohhep, Alex.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 75<br />

Hans: I did not mean to portray you as a guy who disagrees with every<strong>thing</strong>, but as someone who is following his<br />

own thinking more than the average person. This is a good <strong>thing</strong>, especially at a time when humankind seems to<br />

go over the climate-cliff like lemmings. Most people have their antennae trained on what others are doing and use<br />

that as guidance for themselves. A minority <strong>of</strong> people are less concerned about what others are thinking but follow<br />

their own compass. You are one <strong>of</strong> this minority. I am one too. When I see people in this class submitting answers<br />

which carefully go with the flow <strong>of</strong> what everybody else is saying, I am always amazed. I would never be inclined<br />

to do this. I can’t even follow a textbook written by someone else when I teach, I have to write my own.<br />

Next Message by Zarathustra is [95].<br />

[87] ANK: But what about pottery? I would explain to my friend that the labor theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> value is based on the socially necessary, or average, labor time needed to produce a given<br />

commodity. If a lazy and inept laborer takes twice as much time to complete the labor<br />

process, their commodity has not doubled in value. Value is determined by how much social<br />

labor went into the commodity, not the labor <strong>of</strong> a lazy worker. Lazy workers do not change<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity. My friend may continue to argue that the more time and labor put<br />

into the labor process will increase the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity, using pottery as an example.<br />

Consider two individuals (A and B) who are both equally skilled in pottery. If individual A<br />

spends 12 hours on a pot and individual B spends 6 hours on a pot, then individual A’s pot<br />

will have less flaws and more detail when compared to individual B’s pot.<br />

I would argue this example by introducing the difference between concrete and abstract<br />

labor. Concrete labor is the measure <strong>of</strong> an individual’s labor. <strong>The</strong> labor <strong>of</strong> the lazy worker<br />

or worker who spends twice the time to make a pot falls under concrete labor. Hans states<br />

in the Annotations, “Commodity producers themselves do not know either how much value<br />

their commodity has, all they know is how much time their concrete labor takes” (pg 47-48).<br />

Abstract labor is based on the average worker in normal working conditions producing any<br />

given commodity. <strong>The</strong> labor theory <strong>of</strong> value is based on this abstract labor. I would continue<br />

to explain to my friend that the value <strong>of</strong> pottery is determined by the average or socially<br />

necessary amount <strong>of</strong> labor to produce a pot, and not on the labor time <strong>of</strong> a detailed or lazy<br />

worker. I agree with Goldtone [74] when the reference to the normal curve was made and<br />

when it is stated how “95% <strong>of</strong> its mass (or labor-power in this case) is within one standard<br />

deviation on either side away from the mean. This 95% would be the ‘average labor-power<br />

<strong>of</strong> society’ that Marx is talking about, and would serve as the standard measuring device<br />

for value and its link to labor-time.” I believe the lazy worker and detailed pottery worker<br />

are represented in the 5% that fall outside <strong>of</strong> the mean and standard deviation. <strong>The</strong>refore,<br />

I would once again remind my friend that the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is determined by how<br />

much socially necessary labor went into producing it.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong>re is a little more going on than you see. A market system does not reward special efforts by individual<br />

workers. Frida mentioned this in [82]: “In our capitalist system, as long as commodities meet certain ‘standards’<br />

supervisors don’t care about the quality <strong>of</strong> the products.” High quality pottery is not a good example for this because<br />

you can actually sell it at decent prices to the millionaires in Park City, but the occasional worker in an ordinary<br />

industry who puts extra care into her product does not get rewarded for her extra labor. Teachers and nurses are<br />

underpaid because many <strong>of</strong> them feel compelled by the nature <strong>of</strong> their work to put in extra effort. <strong>The</strong> capitalists<br />

says: if you want to work extra hard, be my guest, but don’t expect me to pay you for it. (Strictly speaking we are<br />

not talking here <strong>of</strong> wages but <strong>of</strong> value created, but the hard-nosed attitude <strong>of</strong> the capitalists comes from the fact that<br />

this extra labor—not <strong>of</strong> a lazy but <strong>of</strong> an exceptionally committed worker—does not translate into higher market<br />

values.)<br />

Message [87] referenced by [91]. Next Message by ANK is [231].<br />

76 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[90] Utefan: Re: How should we measure labor? Marx made the comment that anyone<br />

that wanted to help the value <strong>of</strong> a certain commodity grow they would use the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

labor time to increase such value. <strong>The</strong> idea is that the more time taken to produce said<br />

commodity would therefore raise the value because a lazy or less capable worker would take<br />

more labor hours to make a commodity.<br />

Two aspects <strong>of</strong> said idea create flaws and therefore constituent only a comment. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong><br />

is the overwhelming societal propensity to already have an average <strong>of</strong> what any commodity<br />

should take to produce and for that reason already has a value assigned to it. <strong>The</strong> only <strong>thing</strong><br />

that seems to be true historically is that value will decrease as technology advances or where<br />

someone lives—a PS3 costs $3000 pesos in Argentina, that is $1000 dollars, and only $300<br />

dollars here in the states. Being able find better ways to make commodities only make values<br />

decrease.<br />

Second, is the ability to make a new commodity and therefore set the value from how<br />

much labor is involved to produce it. Now the flaw is that when others through open market<br />

capabilities are allowed to produce the same commodity the average hours to produce level<br />

out and the value goes down. Such commodities already exist and would not make it easy<br />

for anyone to make a new value.<br />

Value will only fluctuate according to the ability to make said commodity more valuable<br />

through more quality or scarcity.<br />

Hans: In Marx’s theory, quality and scarcity are poster children for what does not determine value. If you missed<br />

this, then you have not followed the discussion. <strong>The</strong> price distribution <strong>of</strong> a PS3 over the different markets is a<br />

matter <strong>of</strong> corporate strategy. Presumably prices are low in the US because the manufacturer has to sell enough <strong>of</strong><br />

them to recoup the high development cost and to motivate s<strong>of</strong>tware manufacturers to write s<strong>of</strong>tware for it. <strong>The</strong>n<br />

in Argentina they can charge monopoly prices. In the manuscript “Results <strong>of</strong> the Immediate Production Process”<br />

included in the Vintage edition <strong>of</strong> Capital, Marx addresses this. <strong>The</strong> law <strong>of</strong> value applies not for each individual<br />

product but for the firm’s output in its entirety. If most <strong>of</strong> the output is sold at high prices, and a small excess portion<br />

is dumped at low sales prices, this is pr<strong>of</strong>itable for the firm, even if the few individual consumers snatching up the<br />

products on sale pay less than value.<br />

Message [90] referenced by [216]. Next Message by Utefan is [131].<br />

[103] Bigwhite: I would tell my friend that according to Marx and his ideology that the<br />

lazier worker’s commodity would not garner more exchange value than that <strong>of</strong> a worker that<br />

finished his product in a more timely manner. Marx follows the writing <strong>of</strong> Hegel and that<br />

is that people want to do <strong>thing</strong>s to benefit the community as a whole; they aren’t caught up<br />

in self-interests. By this logic Marx may assume that all workers are going to do their jobs<br />

efficiently, why would someone want to spend more time on some<strong>thing</strong> that is necessary?<br />

That would be selfish and not be benefiting the society as a whole. Another <strong>thing</strong> is when<br />

you go to exchange a commodity people don’t know how long it took you to produce it, they<br />

figure if it took them 2 hours to make their commodity it probably took you about the same<br />

time to make yours. Labor is looked at as equal. One man’s labor is not valued more than<br />

the next man’s. Quantity is quantity.<br />

Hans: This is <strong>of</strong> course all wrong. Capital is not based on Marx’s ideology <strong>of</strong> altruism but it is a critique <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalist relations <strong>of</strong> production. See [2007SP:65].<br />

Message [103] referenced by [122]. Next Message by Bigwhite is [133].<br />

[359] She: graded A Marx’s Labor <strong>The</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> Value does not imply that the more lazy and<br />

inept the laborer, the more valuable the commodity will be. Marx realized this assumption


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 77<br />

would be naturally made when he declared that, “[<strong>The</strong> ‘value-forming substance (labor)’] is<br />

measured by its duration,” (Capital, 129:1). This is why he immediately refutes this in the<br />

next paragraph. Marx elaborates upon his previous statement and says that for the kind <strong>of</strong><br />

labor he is talking about, every unit is equal; so, although the lazy or inept laborer requires<br />

more time, he does not actually use more units and therefore, there is no additional value<br />

added to the commodity. It seems unnatural and somewhat illogical to assume that all labor<br />

is equal so Marx further elucidates with a thorough explanation <strong>of</strong> how to arrive at this<br />

conclusion.<br />

To grasp this concept, we need to remember that Marx has already defined the value <strong>of</strong><br />

labor in commodities to be the magnitude <strong>of</strong> abstract human labor and we are no longer<br />

entertaining the notion <strong>of</strong> concrete labor (128:3). Marx explains that the total labor-power,<br />

or potential to do work, <strong>of</strong> society is, “. . . one homogeneous mass,” which is divided into<br />

equal-sized units [129:2]. <strong>The</strong>se identical units are “socially-average” and to produce any<br />

given commodity, a society will expect that only the amount <strong>of</strong> labor required to produce it<br />

is the “socially necessary labor-time,” [129:2]. <strong>The</strong> socially necessary labor-time is determined<br />

and enforced through competition on the market; it is some<strong>thing</strong> beyond the control<br />

<strong>of</strong> the individual producer. A single-producer’s commodity will not be valued above another<br />

identical commodity simply because it took longer to produce. <strong>The</strong> value, or the socially<br />

necessary labor required, is beyond his/her control. A laborer who takes twice as long to<br />

produce a commodity will still have the socially necessary labor-time standard applied as<br />

the value-measure to that commodity. <strong>The</strong>refore, the lazy or inept laborer does not create<br />

more value, just spends more time creating the same quantity <strong>of</strong> value. This does not result<br />

in increased price, just reduced pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Next Message by She is [393].<br />

[366] Giant: graded C+ I would explain to my friend that there are two big problems with<br />

that assumption. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> one is that Marx does not believe in the ability <strong>of</strong> the individual<br />

worker to influence the market, so one slow or lazy worker is not going to be able to change<br />

the market value <strong>of</strong> a product. <strong>The</strong> second problem with her assumption is that the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity is not based solely on the time and effort put into the product but on the<br />

use-value the consumer will get from that commodity.<br />

I would educate my friend that Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value is based on the social value <strong>of</strong><br />

a product in the market, not the individual laborer’s efforts <strong>of</strong> producing a product. <strong>The</strong> social<br />

value <strong>of</strong> producing a product is determined by the producers <strong>of</strong> the product. <strong>The</strong> producers<br />

go out into the market and observe what resources are needed to produce the product and<br />

then reflect the costs <strong>of</strong> the resources through the prices on the production market, see Hans<br />

[2009fa:266]. This is why individual labor does not affect value because no one wants the<br />

same product to be valued individually (since labor-time is just one <strong>of</strong> many resources being<br />

imputed) when the same basic resources are being imputed into the same product. This is<br />

why the social medium is used to base a product’s value, see Winn [2009fa:266].<br />

Hans: You are misunderstanding the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value in two ways:<br />

(a) You write “the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is not based solely on the time and effort put into the product but on<br />

the use-value the consumer will get from that commodity.” This is not true for “value” as Marx defines it. What is<br />

called “value” by Marx depends on labor input only.<br />

78 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(b) You write “no one wants the same product to be valued individually (since labor-time is just one <strong>of</strong> many<br />

resources being imputed).” <strong>The</strong> labor theory <strong>of</strong> value converts all inputs into labor time, i.e., it uses all direct and<br />

indirect labor content. It does not leave out any inputs (but it reduced them all to labor).<br />

And please look again what the producers do according to my note to [2009fa:266]. It is not what you say they<br />

do.<br />

<strong>The</strong> dictionary definition <strong>of</strong> “impute” is “attribute or credit to.” Did you really mean “impute” or did you mean<br />

“input”?<br />

Next Message by Giant is [367].<br />

[369] Frida: graded A I would tell my friend that she had not read enough <strong>of</strong> Marx’s text<br />

and had based her implication on an underdeveloped labor theory <strong>of</strong> value. If one claimed<br />

that the value <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> was defined by how much individual labor went into it this would<br />

be the implication, but this is not Marx’s developed theory <strong>of</strong> value. Marx says that the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> is determined by the socially necessary labor time. This will be the same for<br />

the coat made by a lazy tailor as the coat made by the skilled and industrious one. It is<br />

defined to be the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that is necessary on average to produce a coat.<br />

Hans: It is not just the issue <strong>of</strong> not reading enough Marx. Labor-time, the only <strong>thing</strong> which the commodities have<br />

in common, resists measurement. This is a real contradiction.<br />

Next Message by Frida is [390].<br />

[394] Kobe: “<strong>The</strong> theory’s basic claim is simple: the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity can be objectively<br />

measured by the average number <strong>of</strong> labor hours required to produce that commodity”<br />

(1). According to this quote, the value would not be determined by the production <strong>of</strong> a single<br />

worker. <strong>The</strong> labor theory <strong>of</strong> value, according to Marx, could explain the value <strong>of</strong> all commodities<br />

in an economy. This theory is based upon the hourly average <strong>of</strong> society it takes to<br />

produce a particular commodity. Marx believes “the value <strong>of</strong> a product is determined more<br />

by societal standards than by individual conditions,” according to Wikipedia. This quote<br />

would validate that “my friend” is wrong when saying “the more lazy and inept the laborer<br />

the more valuable his commodity would be.” <strong>The</strong>refore it is not only how lazy or inept a<br />

laborer is at producing a commodity but it is a combination <strong>of</strong> the labor forces’ production<br />

in that particular commodity and the “socially necessary” labor required for the goods value<br />

to be determined.<br />

1. http://www.econlib.org/library/Enc/Marxism.html<br />

2. Wikipedia<br />

Next Message by Kobe is [452].<br />

[398] ANK: I would tell my friend that he is wrong and the reason that the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity produced by the lazy worker is not greater than an efficient worker is because<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is determined by the socially necessary or average labor time <strong>of</strong><br />

all producers <strong>of</strong> the given commodity. If the lazy worker takes twice the time to produce a<br />

given commodity the pr<strong>of</strong>it they receive is actually less than the efficient worker because the<br />

efficient worker was able to produce two commodities in the same time period it took the lazy<br />

worker to produce one commodity. Because the value <strong>of</strong> this given commodity is determined<br />

by the socially necessary labor time, whether produced by the lazy or efficient worker it has<br />

the same value. <strong>The</strong>refore, the efficient worker has two commodities to exchange in the<br />

market whereas the lazy worker has only one commodity for exchange. As Hans states<br />

in the comments <strong>of</strong> message [83] “the lazy worker does not harm others, he only harms<br />

himself”. I would tell my friend that he is wrong and re-emphasize that the value <strong>of</strong> a


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 79<br />

commodity is determined by the socially necessary or average labor time <strong>of</strong> all producers <strong>of</strong><br />

that commodity.<br />

Hans: I wish you would not just tell him that he is wrong but explain how to get from his wrong answer to the<br />

right answer.<br />

Next Message by ANK is [400].<br />

[419] Sly: Technically No. First I would explain to my friend that the labor theory <strong>of</strong><br />

value, tries to find commonalities <strong>of</strong> the substance or use <strong>of</strong> a commodity to determine the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> said commodity. Different labor times don’t up the price <strong>of</strong> a commodity because<br />

that isn’t some<strong>thing</strong> that is a commonality. I would go even further by referencing to the<br />

fact that the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is determined by socially necessary labor, which can be<br />

defined simply as the amount <strong>of</strong> time it takes to produce a good, service, etc. in the most<br />

efficient manner possible because that is what laborers and consumers have agreed on as<br />

being fair. I then would solidify my answer by giving a concrete example such as this: If I<br />

was looking to buy a laptop computer and went to the electronics store and the laptop that<br />

was made by the slow or inept worker cost $900 and the exact same laptop made by the<br />

more efficient or skillful worker cost $600, why would I buy the exact same laptop for $900.<br />

Simply put I wouldn’t because it makes absolutely no sense to pay more for the same item.<br />

Hans: Socially necessary labor is <strong>of</strong>ten not the most efficient production process.<br />

Next Message by Sly is [572].<br />

[440] Smartergirl: <strong>The</strong> more lazy and inept worker’s commodity is not more valuable.<br />

Marx states that value is comprised <strong>of</strong> the glob <strong>of</strong> human labor power. It is the total labor<br />

power <strong>of</strong> society that determines the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity. One lazy worker does not drive<br />

up the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity because he does not represent the labor power in its entirety.<br />

Marx theorizes that by grouping unskilled workers with advanced workers the labor will<br />

create an average for that particular society. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is then based on<br />

that average. <strong>The</strong> means to determine the average is unknown and causes some concern for<br />

how effective this calculation would be but combining workers and grouping them by skill<br />

level is a strong means to get an average which can then be used to determine value.<br />

Hans: Grouping novice workers with advanced workers so that the novices can learn from the advanced workers<br />

would be a rational way <strong>of</strong> handling the inevitable skill differences among workers. But Marx’s book is not about<br />

how <strong>thing</strong>s should be done in some rational society but about how <strong>thing</strong>s are done in capitalism. You don’t seem<br />

to be clear about this, especially also as you worded your in-class exam. You also gave a wrong answer to multiple<br />

choice question 56. Marx thinks exchange-value is determined by labor content, not by use-value.<br />

Capitalist are interested in promoting team work and interaction and learning among their workers. Some<br />

modern researchers (not Marx) conjecture this is the reason why all workers usually get the same pay. If pay were<br />

differentiated by individual productivity, then workers would not work with each other but against each other.<br />

Next Message by Smartergirl is [446].<br />

[444] Husani: I would explain to my friend that the lazy worker could get away with<br />

this but only if the society in which he lived had very few people producing the same good<br />

as the one the lazy worker produces. In a large economy many different people produce<br />

any one good so this makes it extremely difficult for the lazy work to fetch a price higher<br />

than what the market is <strong>of</strong>fering. <strong>The</strong> market will push the price down to what people are<br />

<strong>of</strong>fering because there is no<strong>thing</strong> special about the lazy worker’s product. It is the same good<br />

as every other good <strong>of</strong> the same type so no one will consiously buy what the lazy worker<br />

made because there are many cheap goods for sales using the average labor time necessary<br />

to produce the product.<br />

80 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> lazy worker may use more labor hours to produce his product making it more difficult,<br />

but the value comes from the labor time necessary to produce the good. A lazy worker<br />

uses more time but it is unnecessary time. This means that every extra minute <strong>of</strong> labor time<br />

that is more than the average is worthless and will not increase the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Husani is [454].<br />

[455] RexManning: graded A In the situation <strong>of</strong> the lazy laborer, a case is made that<br />

the commodity produced by that laborer would be worth more because <strong>of</strong> the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

labor, measured in time, required to produce the commodity. This logic, although wrong,<br />

does present a valid point. If Marx measures value by the amount <strong>of</strong> labor time to produce<br />

a commodity, wouldn’t a lazy worker produce a more valuable commodity? Marx does<br />

address this problem specifically and clears up any confusion. In order for commodities to<br />

be exchanged on the market, they must be equal, not equal in a physical sense, but equal<br />

in labor. Without this equality, a producer would not exchange his/her commodity for one<br />

<strong>of</strong> lesser value. According to Marx, and Hans, the substance <strong>of</strong> value is equal human labor.<br />

Human labor is the expenditure <strong>of</strong> all human labor-power. In order for this equality to exist,<br />

there must be a social context to it. This social aspect <strong>of</strong> labor is the combination <strong>of</strong> all<br />

individual labors. Since labor is a combination <strong>of</strong> what is socially necessary to produce a<br />

commodity, the case <strong>of</strong> the lazy laborer does not hold.<br />

Next Message by RexManning is [463].<br />

[477] Rico: As I mentioned in my initial response – it would be difficult not to laugh at<br />

my friend’s response. As a response to my friend, I would try to explain the significance <strong>of</strong><br />

the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value and the average labor-power <strong>of</strong> society.<br />

According to the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value, the more time invested in a commodity, the more<br />

valuable the commodity becomes. But this does not indicate that one can be lazy in their<br />

labor. Goldtone gives a quote directly from Marx in [74], which says, “Each <strong>of</strong> these individual<br />

labor-powers is the same human labor-power as any other, to the extent that it has<br />

the character <strong>of</strong> the average labor-power <strong>of</strong> society and takes effect as such, and therefore<br />

requires, for producing a commodity, no more than is socially necessary.” Goldtone uses this<br />

quote to show that Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value is measured by time and by the “average<br />

labor-power <strong>of</strong> society.” Average labor-power takes the average <strong>of</strong> all the potential labors<br />

that individual workers are capable <strong>of</strong> having. This average is used as a “standard measuring<br />

device for value and its link to labor-time,” as Goldtone explains.<br />

As a society, we have adopted a measurement <strong>of</strong> labor using time as our units. By calculating<br />

time in the average labor-power <strong>of</strong> society, we can calculate the quantitative and<br />

qualitative value <strong>of</strong> our production. In the diamond industry, diamonds are monetarily expensive<br />

due to the labor time involved in discovering the precious mineral. <strong>The</strong> average<br />

labor-power is calculated and a monetary price for diamonds is determined. If a person is<br />

twice as fast at finding diamonds as the average worker, they will be rewarded with twice<br />

the value due to their increased aptitude in finding diamonds. <strong>The</strong> same rule would apply to<br />

lazy workers, only their outcome would be less rewarding than the average worker.<br />

Hans: I liked the following sentence in your in-class answer, and regret that you didn’t take it over into the resubmission:<br />

“<strong>The</strong> labor theory <strong>of</strong> value measures the labor not only in quantitative measures but also qualitative<br />

measures.” This is a nutshell explanation why the lazy worker produces less value per hour.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 81<br />

<strong>The</strong> outcome you describe in your last paragraph holds only if the worker sells the diamonds he or she produces.<br />

If a worker working for a capitalist were to produce half <strong>of</strong> what others produce, the coworkers would be disenchanted<br />

because they would have make up for this, and eventually the slow worker would get fired or reassigned.<br />

Regarding workers who work faster than others, look at the discussion thread starting with [2005fa:1416].<br />

Next Message by Rico is [478].<br />

[512] JJ: Laziness does not build value. At <strong>first</strong> glance, the inexperienced reader (my<br />

friend) could easily make this mistake when interpreting the labor-theory <strong>of</strong> value. Marx<br />

himself comes upon this contradiction in his dialectic concerning the labor-theory <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

He resolves this contradiction by clarifying that the value added to a commodity by a laborer<br />

is not determined on a case by case basis for every item which any particular laborer produces.<br />

This might make two products seem <strong>of</strong> different value that are equal in every physical<br />

way in their final product form, except for the amount <strong>of</strong> labor time that was put into them.<br />

One product was worked on slowly by the lazy worker and the other quickly by the efficient<br />

worker. Does this really make one product more valuable than the other? Marx shows us<br />

that this contradiction is only valid when we mistakenly try and apply the labor-theory <strong>of</strong><br />

value on such a micro scale.<br />

Marx clarifies by defining value as the quasi-material intrinsic in a commodity, which<br />

is the amount <strong>of</strong> congealed and abstract human labor that has gone into it. Yet, he defines<br />

this amount <strong>of</strong> human labor as the “socially necessary” amount <strong>of</strong> human labor. Marx says,<br />

“Each <strong>of</strong> these individual labor-powers is the same human labor-power as any other, to the<br />

extent that it has the character <strong>of</strong> the average labor-power <strong>of</strong> society and takes effect as such,<br />

and therefore requires, for producing a commodity, no more than is socially necessary.” By<br />

doing this Marx refutes the misunderstanding <strong>of</strong> my friend that laziness could somehow add<br />

value to a commodity in the labor-theory <strong>of</strong> value. He also shows us that the labor-theory <strong>of</strong><br />

value can work when considered in context <strong>of</strong> the average labor-power <strong>of</strong> society.<br />

Next Message by JJ is [513].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 103 is 83 in 2005fa, 96 in 2007SP, 98 in 2008SP, and 96 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 103 <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the product is determined by the socially necessary labor-time.<br />

What are the implications <strong>of</strong> this for a capitalist supervising his employees?<br />

[89] Tyler: Capitalist Supervisors. According to Marx, the value <strong>of</strong> a product is directly<br />

associated with the “socially necessary labor-time” required in its production. However, this<br />

is drastically different in a capitalist society. In a capitalist society the value <strong>of</strong> a product<br />

is determined not from the labor-time in its production, but in its demand. A supervisor in<br />

a capitalist society does not concern him/herself with an average time frame <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

rather their goal is to increase output to its maximum rate.<br />

In the readings it is noted that “the capitalist sees to it that he (the worker)...only uses as<br />

much labor-time is necessary in the average for the production <strong>of</strong> the product” (annotations<br />

pg. 52). Further, it is pointed out that “a worker who is slower than the others will not<br />

find a job in capitalism” (annotations pg. 52). <strong>The</strong>refore, the implications <strong>of</strong> value being<br />

determined by the socially necessary labor-time are decreased production and pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Hans: What you say in the <strong>first</strong> paragraph contradicts what you say in the second. I am getting the impression<br />

that you are bringing the numerous quotes from Marx and the Annotations both in [65] and in this message here in<br />

order to cover up for it that you are not working through the assigned readings.<br />

82 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Message [89] referenced by [92]. Next Message by Tyler is [243].<br />

[92] Hans: Marx’s Capital is not a Blueprint for a Better Society. Tyler’s [89] needs<br />

an immediate response and clarification. Tyler writes: “In a capitalist society the value <strong>of</strong><br />

a product is determined not from the labor-time in its production, but in its demand.” Marx<br />

does not think so. If Marx were alive today he would think that even in today’s capitalism,<br />

value is determined by labor-time and not by demand. You are free to disagree with Marx<br />

and argue why he is wrong, but for this you must understand what Marx intended to do<br />

in his book. If you think Marx was drawing out the blueprint for a more just society, you<br />

are misunderstanding him on a very basic level. Kraken [78] got a bad grade for the same<br />

misunderstanding. Don’t expect a good grade if you have it in your head that Marx is talking<br />

about socialism or some<strong>thing</strong>. <strong>The</strong> book is called Capital and it is Marx’s attempt to analyze<br />

and understand capitalism.<br />

<strong>The</strong> idea that value comes from labor does not rule out exploitation <strong>of</strong> the workers but,<br />

on the contrary, allows us to understand how exploitation works in capitalism. Marx has not<br />

yet discussed wages, but when he does, you will see that the workers, although their labor<br />

produces all value, are paid wages that are much lower than the value they produce. <strong>The</strong><br />

difference flows into the pockets <strong>of</strong> the capitalists as pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Message [92] referenced by [122], [239], [245], and [2011fa:675]. Next Message by Hans is [94].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 104 is 42 in 1995WI, 51 in 1995ut, 53 in 1996sp, 51 in 1996ut, 60 in<br />

1998WI, 66 in 1999SP, 70 in 2001fa, 84 in 2005fa, 97 in 2007SP, 97 in 2008fa, 100 in<br />

2009fa, and 123 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 104 <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a commodity does not increase if it is made by a slow or<br />

inept laborer. Explain carefully why not. Whose decision is it to keep the value <strong>of</strong> the output<br />

<strong>of</strong> a slow worker below the time actually used for its production? How is it enforced?<br />

[364] Hans: You should know this answer even though it is not terribly simple. This<br />

has been an exam question only since Fall 2008. Earlier it was one <strong>of</strong> the ordinary homework<br />

questions. I changed it into an exam question not because it is too easy for a homework<br />

question, but because it addresses some basic concepts you all should be aware <strong>of</strong>.<br />

This question has three parts, I will answer them one by one.<br />

(a) Why does the labor <strong>of</strong> an exceptionally slow worker not create as much value per hour<br />

than that <strong>of</strong> a worker working with normal skill and intensity? One possible answer would be<br />

“because the products are indistinguishable on the market and therefore have equal values.”<br />

Marx does not give this answer! Marx’s answer is “because the labor <strong>of</strong> the slow worker is<br />

not at par with the labor <strong>of</strong> others and therefore counts as less labor.” For Marx, the basic<br />

<strong>thing</strong> one needs to know about relations <strong>of</strong> production in capitalism is that society considers<br />

all labors as one homogeneous mass; there are no qualitative differences, only quantitative<br />

differences.<br />

Now let me answer the third part <strong>of</strong> the question before the second part.<br />

(c) How is it enforced? Now Marx brings in the market, he would say “because the<br />

products are indistinguishable on the market and therefore have to be sold at equal prices.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 83<br />

An identical commodity sold at a higher price is not able to compete. But Marx stresses that<br />

competition is only the enforcer, it is not the place where economic laws are born.<br />

(b) Whose decision is it? This question goes beyond Marx’s text, I am not aware <strong>of</strong><br />

any<strong>thing</strong> Marx wrote which would directly address this. One might perhaps answer: it is<br />

nobody’s decision, it is a spontaneous outcome. I think this answer lets us all <strong>of</strong>f the hook<br />

too easily. An answer which puts more responsibility on the individuals would be: the<br />

individuals in capitalism are collectively making this decision because they are ok with it<br />

that their social relations go through <strong>thing</strong>s. Here is a third alternative answer which pushes<br />

this point even further: It is one <strong>of</strong> the major attractions <strong>of</strong> our alienated state (in which<br />

the producers do not deal directly with each other and the consumers but only through the<br />

market) that this takes care <strong>of</strong> those who do not pull their full weight. We do not have to<br />

confront them “hey, you are part <strong>of</strong> this society, but you are not contributing enough.” We just<br />

let the market do its <strong>thing</strong>. Unfortunately, the market’s “<strong>thing</strong>” goes far beyond this. Besides<br />

this one relatively fair outcome the market generates plenty <strong>of</strong> very unfair outcomes—and<br />

since about 20 years we know that the market is even about to render the planet uninhabitable<br />

for humans. Maybe it is time to re-think whether we want to stay in our alienated state.<br />

Hans: Also look at Quake [1999SP:22] including my brief comment, which is elaborated more in [1998WI:75].<br />

Message [364] referenced by [386] and [2011fa:301]. Next Message by Hans is [376].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 112 is 45 in 1995WI, 54 in 1995ut, 56 in 1996sp, 60 in 1997WI, 63 in 1997sp, 59<br />

in 1997ut, 79 in 2002fa, 81 in 2003fa, 90 in 2005fa, 104 in 2007SP, 107 in 2008SP, 105<br />

in 2008fa, and 131 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 112 How is the value <strong>of</strong> raw materials determined in Marx’s theory? How does<br />

the scarcity <strong>of</strong> these materials influence their value? Is Marx’s argument still valid in the<br />

case <strong>of</strong> an exhaustible resource, which is present only in finite supply?<br />

[84] Max: graded A <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> raw material according to Marx, is measured by the<br />

same means as other commodities are measured; by congealed labor time. Marx almost<br />

explicitly states this when he discusses diamonds in 130:1/o: “Diamonds are <strong>of</strong> very rare<br />

occurrence on the earth’s surface, and hence their discovery requires on an average a great<br />

deal <strong>of</strong> labor time. Consequently they represent much labor in a small volume.” So, like any<br />

resource, the more congealed labor time required to extract (which, in capitalism, equates<br />

with produce) a resource corresponds to the exchange-value (price).<br />

In capitalism, the scarcity <strong>of</strong> the material being mined does not influence its value relative<br />

to their congealed labor time. Yes, when resources become depleted they require more<br />

drastic means <strong>of</strong> extraction which usually equates to more labor and a higher price. However,<br />

the fact that the resource is limited does not affect the value outside <strong>of</strong> labor costs. In other<br />

words, there is no extra value placed on a scarce resource just because it will be gone in the<br />

future. Modern economics do not take into account the externalities that are associated with<br />

extractive industries.<br />

How can you put exchange-value on clean air or clean water, which extractive industries<br />

so <strong>of</strong>ten tend to disregard? (Marx does mention they do have use-value “...without being a<br />

value.”) This is some<strong>thing</strong> BP is trying to do right now in the Gulf coast. BP is trying to figure<br />

out what a healthy functioning ecosystem was worth to the tourist industry and fishermen <strong>of</strong><br />

84 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the area, but they can’t do it. People who are receiving checks from the corporation know it<br />

isn’t enough - especially when taking into account that their industries may be crippled for<br />

years, if not forever. Is it even possible to value the services provided by our earth?<br />

Hopefully I didn’t deviate from the original question too far. What I am trying to say is<br />

that Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> value based on congealed labor somewhat suffices as an appropriate<br />

means <strong>of</strong> valuing extractive industries. However, a whole other side <strong>of</strong> these industries is<br />

left out <strong>of</strong> the picture. This is a massive problem with accounting only for exchange-value<br />

(which, correct me if I am wrong, capitalism seems to do). And it is blatantly apparent today<br />

because <strong>of</strong> the environmental movement, global warming, etc.<br />

Message [84] referenced by [93] and [94]. Next Message by Max is [169].<br />

[85] Ferox: (graded B–) Value <strong>of</strong> Raw Materials. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> raw materials is determined<br />

by Marx as the labor time necessary to extract and process the materials into a usable<br />

form. For example, a heap <strong>of</strong> rocks containing iron ore must <strong>first</strong> be smelted to produce pig<br />

iron, limited value on the market due to its limited use-value. This pig iron can then be made<br />

into a usable form <strong>of</strong> iron by removing carbon impurities or into steel by even further processing.<br />

Both <strong>of</strong> these processes demand more labor time and therefore increase the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> this commodity. <strong>The</strong> end product, iron or steel in this example, are both valuable in part<br />

because <strong>of</strong> the labor time needed for manufacturing these commodities, but this value due to<br />

productive power <strong>of</strong> labor as Marx elaborates in [130:1/o]. <strong>The</strong> technology involved - how<br />

powerful the furnace is or whether the ore was mined by hand or machinery - is a factor<br />

that can be historically traced to affect the value <strong>of</strong> iron commodity in society (though this<br />

begins to veer <strong>of</strong>f topic).<br />

Additionally the scarcity <strong>of</strong> a raw material affects its value. While iron is an abundant<br />

resource on our ferrous Earth, iridium is quite rare. From a Marxian perspective, the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> iridium when compared to iron lies in the extensive use <strong>of</strong> labor power needed to locate,<br />

refine, and process iridium into a useful form. Exhaustible resources also gain value from<br />

the scarcity <strong>of</strong> the resource, but a Marxist would add that the finite supply <strong>of</strong> a resource is<br />

another productive power <strong>of</strong> labor variable.<br />

Hans: You are mixing Marxian and mainstream theories. <strong>The</strong>y cannot be mixed because they contradict each<br />

other. In Marx’s theory, pig iron has a limited value on the market not because <strong>of</strong> its limited use-value, but because<br />

not much labor is materialized in it. In Marx’s theory, scarcity <strong>of</strong> a raw material does not affect its value. According<br />

to Marx, only the labor content determines the value <strong>of</strong> a product. <strong>The</strong> powerful technology <strong>of</strong> the furnace does<br />

not add to the value <strong>of</strong> the product either. You are misreading the Marx quote which you are referring to. It does<br />

not say the productive power <strong>of</strong> labor adds value, but it says the value changes with every change in the productive<br />

power <strong>of</strong> labor. This change goes in the opposite direction than you think: an increase in productive power <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

does not add to but reduces the value <strong>of</strong> the product, because after this increase in productivity it takes less labor to<br />

produce the product.<br />

Message [85] referenced by [93]. Next Message by Ferox is [196].<br />

[93] Atticus: graded B+ According to Marx’s theory the value <strong>of</strong> raw materials is determined<br />

by the labor-time required to abstract these raw materials from the earth. <strong>The</strong> value<br />

<strong>of</strong> raw materials is determined by the amount <strong>of</strong> a common substance between all raw materials.<br />

Marx calls this common substance “congealed labor time” (annotations pp. 54). Value<br />

determined by congealed labor-time remains constant as long as the “productive power <strong>of</strong> labor”<br />

remains constant (annotations pp. 54). This last statement basically states that as more<br />

commodities can be made with increased technological innovations in the same amount <strong>of</strong>


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 85<br />

labor-time, the less value each commodity holds in terms <strong>of</strong> congealed labor-time. <strong>The</strong> same<br />

holds true with exhaustible resources. <strong>The</strong> scarcer a commodity is the more difficult it becomes<br />

to obtain. More labor-time would be required to extract scarce raw materials, thereby,<br />

increasing their value.<br />

For example, a pearl diver who abstracts pearls from a body <strong>of</strong> water with an abundant<br />

supply <strong>of</strong> oysters will obtain many pearls in x amount <strong>of</strong> labor-time. Another pearl diver<br />

with comparable skills will abstract fewer pearls in a body <strong>of</strong> water with a scarcer supply<br />

<strong>of</strong> oysters with same amount <strong>of</strong> labor-time as the more fortunate pearl diver. Each pearl<br />

obtained by the less fortunate diver has a greater amount <strong>of</strong> congealed labor-time. <strong>The</strong>refore,<br />

the less fortunate diver actually has commodities that are more valuable than the more<br />

fortunate diver.<br />

Hans: Every<strong>thing</strong> you say in the <strong>first</strong> paragraph is right, but it is no longer new. At this point in the discussion you<br />

should have addressed the mistakes <strong>of</strong> Ferox [85] instead <strong>of</strong> repeating what Max already said in [84]. Your example<br />

in the second paragraph is wrong for the reasons pointed out by Zarathustra [95].<br />

Message [93] referenced by [95]. Next Message by Atticus is [134].<br />

[94] Hans: <strong>The</strong> Fatal One-Dimensionality <strong>of</strong> Markets. Max says in the last paragraph<br />

<strong>of</strong> [84] that “Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> value based on congealed labor” leaves out “a whole other<br />

side <strong>of</strong> these industries.” Max means the extractive industries, but every<strong>thing</strong> we do has to<br />

do with natural resources. Max should therefore have said: an economy which bases value<br />

only on labor disregards an important factor <strong>of</strong> production, namely the natural resources.<br />

If Marx’s theory is right that capitalist market prices are based on labor content, then this<br />

statement has to be amended one more time: not only Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> value but the entire<br />

capitalist market economy leaves natural resources out <strong>of</strong> the picture.<br />

Let me recapitulate how this omission comes about. In a nutshell, Marx’s argument<br />

leading him to the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value says: If markets are measuring every<strong>thing</strong> with a<br />

one-dimensional yardstick, namely money, this can only work if production is also in some<br />

sense one-dimensional—since markets are the institution guiding production. And indeed<br />

Marx found some<strong>thing</strong> one-dimensional in production, namely, human labor. Basically, all<br />

capitalists are doing is to decide how to allocate human labor to the different spheres <strong>of</strong><br />

production, and the markets help them with this.<br />

Natural resources are left out <strong>of</strong> the picture, and in the past this was not a problem because<br />

they were plentiful. If you needed more you simply allocated more labor to their extraction.<br />

Due to this one-dimensionality, the economy exclusively concentrated on productivity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

labor process, and it worked wonders in increasing this productivity.<br />

But today <strong>thing</strong>s have changed. <strong>The</strong> binding constraint on production is no longer the<br />

productivity <strong>of</strong> labor but the availability <strong>of</strong> natural resources and the planet’s ability to absorb<br />

our waste products. But since we still measure every<strong>thing</strong> in money, the markets still only<br />

tell the capitalists how to allocate labor, not how to use natural resources sparingly or how<br />

to preserve our environment. <strong>The</strong> economy as a system is blind to this.<br />

Imagine you are hiking in the wilderness and some radioactive debris is hidden in the<br />

bushes. (I leave it up to your imagination how it got there; maybe someone tried to smuggle<br />

it in from Russia, but their plane was detected and they found it wise to dump it). Since<br />

humans have no sense organs which can sense radioactivity, you will probably not do the<br />

86 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

right <strong>thing</strong> avoiding the danger, and when you notice some<strong>thing</strong> is wrong it is already too<br />

late. This is the case with our market system. It does not have the sense organs to see and<br />

wisely deal with environmental constraints.<br />

If Marx’s explanation is correct why and how markets work, then we have to get rid <strong>of</strong><br />

markets in order to avoid environmental catastrophe.<br />

Message [94] referenced by [99], [102], [106], [123], [158], [195], [198], and [1072]. Next Message by Hans is<br />

[106].<br />

[95] Zarathustra: (graded A+) For Atticus. You said in [93]: “<strong>The</strong> scarcer a commodity<br />

is, the more difficult it becomes to obtain. More labor-time would be required to extract<br />

scarce raw materials, thereby, increasing their value.” So far I agree with you. <strong>The</strong>n you<br />

proceed by saying:<br />

“Each pearl obtained by the less fortunate diver has a greater amount <strong>of</strong> congealed labor<br />

time. <strong>The</strong>refore, the less fortunate diver actually has commodities that are more valuable<br />

than the more fortunate diver.” I cannot agree with your conclusion because you are now<br />

comparing individual workers. I think, by doing that you are taking the labor-time socially<br />

necessary out <strong>of</strong> the equation.<br />

Marx says in 129:3/o: “That which determines the magnitude <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> any article<br />

is therefore only the amount <strong>of</strong> socially necessary labor, the labor-time socially necessary<br />

for its production” (my emphasis.)<br />

Also Marx says in 130:1/o: “<strong>The</strong> same quantity <strong>of</strong> labor provides more in rich mines than<br />

in poor. Diamonds are <strong>of</strong> very rare occurrence on the surface, and hence their discovery<br />

requires an average a great deal <strong>of</strong> labor-time. Consequently they represent much labor in<br />

a small volume.” On the contrary to what you said (“the less fortunate diver actually has<br />

commodities that are more valuable than the more fortunate diver”) Marx doesn’t say the<br />

diamond extracted from a richer mine is less valuable, I think, because he is also thinking <strong>of</strong><br />

the socially necessary labor time (an average).<br />

Hans: Good and valid critique <strong>of</strong> [93], delivered in a non-<strong>of</strong>fensive tone.<br />

Message [95] referenced by [93]. Next Message by Zarathustra is [97].<br />

[108] Babyceta: (graded A–) Scarcity <strong>of</strong> Resources. If I understand Marx correctly, he<br />

considered labor power itself a commodity whose value could be determined in much the<br />

same way that the value <strong>of</strong> other commodities is determined. If we take our labor to the<br />

market with the sole intention <strong>of</strong> creating exchange (and not use value), then even in the<br />

abstract labor is a commodity with physical characteristics. What happens in a society in<br />

which labor itself becomes a scarce resource that must be extracted by applying more labor<br />

to secure labor? What if, for example, labor to harvest my crop <strong>of</strong> strawberries becomes<br />

scarce and I must entertain the notion <strong>of</strong> extracting labor from other markets or industries<br />

which would require more labor on my part)?<br />

Hans: Capitalism shields itself against the scarcity <strong>of</strong> labor by alway producing unemployment. This will be<br />

discussed in chapter 25.<br />

Hans discusses a total “pool” <strong>of</strong> available labor, and that commodities essentially have<br />

value in the abstract by the percentage <strong>of</strong> that labor pool contained in their production. If<br />

the “pool” <strong>of</strong> labor is depleted (or at least diminished) then commodities would contain a<br />

larger percentage <strong>of</strong> that total pool. Would it mean that they are more valuable because <strong>of</strong> a


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 87<br />

scarcity <strong>of</strong> labor? I believe that it does. In a market where labor power is a scarce resource,<br />

commodities contain greater exchange value and therefore command a greater price.<br />

Hans: When I said “portion <strong>of</strong> this pool” I did not mean percentage, but an absolute measure: how much labor was<br />

absorbed to product a given commodity.<br />

And, finally, what about improvements in technology? <strong>The</strong>y would certainly make labor<br />

more productive. If I’m an Alaskan halibut fisherman who has a sonar device on my boat, I<br />

will catch more halibut than the captain <strong>of</strong> a boat without sonar. Technology, in many ways,<br />

is our answer for the issue <strong>of</strong> scarcity. How does this notion fit into Marx’s views? Any<br />

thoughts?<br />

Hans: You can catch halibut only if there are halibut in the water. Modern fishing technology, especially the<br />

location <strong>of</strong> schools <strong>of</strong> fish by satellite, have led to overfishing and the extinction <strong>of</strong> the last fish without the price<br />

even going up—because the last fish were as easy to catch as the <strong>first</strong>. <strong>The</strong> labor needed to catch fish is therefore<br />

not a good criterion for mining fish.<br />

Message [108] referenced by [122]. Next Message by Babyceta is [162].<br />

[122] Hans: We are not yet discussing wages! Babyceta [108] is right, Marx considered<br />

labor-power to be a commodity too, but this has different implications than Babyceta thinks.<br />

It will all be explained in chapter Six.<br />

Right now Marx acts as if capital did not exist and labor-power was not a commodity and<br />

commodities were produced by individual producers (peasants and artisans) owning their<br />

own means <strong>of</strong> production. Marx does this because he wants to know: which features <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism do not come from the existence <strong>of</strong> capitalists but from the fact that capitalism<br />

is a commodity-producing society? And his result will be that you cannot truly abolish<br />

capitalism without abolishing commodity production.<br />

But this method <strong>of</strong> <strong>first</strong> looking at commodity production in abstraction from capitalism<br />

makes it difficult to see that Marx is criticizing capitalism, because the economic laws <strong>of</strong><br />

commodity production seem deceptively fair. Bigwhite [103] is an example for a wrong<br />

reading <strong>of</strong> Marx. Look at [92] and [2007SP:65].<br />

Message [122] referenced by [239] and [245]. Next Message by Hans is [125].<br />

[384] Max: graded A Value <strong>of</strong> scarce resources. In Marx’s theory, the value <strong>of</strong> raw<br />

materials is determined by the amount <strong>of</strong> labor required to extract the materials. <strong>The</strong> value<br />

<strong>of</strong> these materials remains constant “as long as the labor-time required for its production<br />

also remains constant.” However, when the material becomes scarce, the value is affected.<br />

Value “changes with every variation in the productive power <strong>of</strong> labor.” This means that the<br />

more labor required to find and extract a raw or scarce material, the higher the value <strong>of</strong><br />

the resource will be. Other factors besides scarcity affect the value or raw materials. For<br />

instance, the “workers’ average degree <strong>of</strong> skill, the level <strong>of</strong> development <strong>of</strong> science and its<br />

technological applicability, the social organization <strong>of</strong> the production process, the extent and<br />

effectiveness <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production, the conditions found in the natural environment,<br />

and others.” <strong>The</strong>se factors all affect the value <strong>of</strong> any resource because <strong>of</strong> the change <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

time required for extraction.<br />

Hans: Good summary <strong>of</strong> all the factors affecting the value <strong>of</strong> every commodity (including natural resources). For<br />

those who are still new to Marx note that wages are not among those factors. Wages tell me how much <strong>of</strong> the newly<br />

created value is reimbursed to the worker, it does not tell me how much value was created in the <strong>first</strong> place.<br />

In your in-class answer you had the added sentence “<strong>The</strong> problem with this method <strong>of</strong> value is that it doesn’t<br />

take into account the resource for future generations.”<br />

88 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Max is [387].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 122 is 112 in 2008fa, 118 in 2009fa, 142 in 2011fa, and 141 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 122 If the product is useless, can the labor producing it still be considered useful<br />

labor?<br />

[104] Orville: graded A– Useful Uselessness? In the annotations, Hans states that “the<br />

term ‘useful labor’ does not involve a judgment about the use-value <strong>of</strong> the product.” After<br />

reading this it becomes apparent that the use-value and the useful labor put into the item<br />

work independently <strong>of</strong> each other. <strong>The</strong> product can have useful labor as long as the product<br />

does what it was intended to do (Hans’ note to [2008fa:228]). <strong>The</strong> product has use-value as<br />

long as someone can use the item in any way they choose. <strong>The</strong>refore the question becomes:<br />

What if you produce a product that has no use value but does exactly what you intended it<br />

to do?<br />

<strong>The</strong> question becomes harder if you try to think <strong>of</strong> an example. Personally I can’t think<br />

<strong>of</strong> an item which anyone could produce with which no one could find a use for. Use-value<br />

seems like such a fluid term that there has to be a use-value for any<strong>thing</strong> and every<strong>thing</strong><br />

produced no matter how small that use-value may be. As Marx says in 132:2 and Hans<br />

notes in the following paragraph, the use-value is some<strong>thing</strong> that is contained inside the<br />

“physical quality <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s”. <strong>The</strong>refore, no matter what you produce, there will always be a<br />

use-value or usefulness to an item assuming it is some<strong>thing</strong> which can be used in the making<br />

<strong>of</strong> another product.<br />

Message [104] referenced by [117]. Next Message by Orville is [145].<br />

[105] Trap: Useful labor vs. use value. When Marx uses the term “useful labor” this<br />

does not take into consideration the use-value <strong>of</strong> the product. If a product is completely<br />

useless to the consumer, it will still have involved useful labor. Useful labor is understood to<br />

be the labor that goes into the finished product, so as long as the product has been completed,<br />

regardless <strong>of</strong> whether or not it is useless, in terms <strong>of</strong> use value, it has useful labor. By saying<br />

an object is useless, you cannot assume that it has not use-value, because use-value is a<br />

society driven concept, and not some<strong>thing</strong> that is intrinsic within the item. <strong>The</strong>refore, it is<br />

unreasonable and incorrect, to make an assumption about the useful labor <strong>of</strong> a commodity,<br />

if all you know is that it is a useless item, for as long as the commodity was finished, it had<br />

to have involved useful labor.<br />

Message [105] referenced by [117]. Next Message by Trap is [229].<br />

[115] Baseball: <strong>The</strong>re are two different ways to view this question. If a product is considered<br />

useless, meaning it has no use-value or demand in the market, the labor producing<br />

“said product” would not be considered useful as well. Labor is only valuable or beneficial<br />

to society and the economy if it produces goods which help circulate and keep the economy<br />

steady. If a company produces a commodity which no consumer would purchase that labor<br />

and time used to produce that commodity is wasted. It is in people’s best interest to make<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s which will be employed to their maximum value. It benefits nobody if labor is wasted<br />

producing goods which will not sell. As stated in the textbook “labor is useful if it produces<br />

a product that has any use-value <strong>of</strong> whatever kind,” and “Labor is useful to the extent that its<br />

product is useful.” On the other hand, Marx says “or in fact that its product is a use-value,”<br />

regarding the question <strong>of</strong> whether labor producing a unusable product is considered useful


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 89<br />

labor. I think that Marx means to raise the question “what if the product itself is a use-value,”<br />

which throws a wrench into our thinking. If the product itself is a use-value then that would<br />

mean the labor used to produce said product is justified. Also, “the term useful labor does<br />

not involve a judgment about the use-value <strong>of</strong> the product.” When <strong>first</strong> thinking <strong>of</strong> this question<br />

we tend to assume that useful labor means producing a product which can be sold for<br />

great pr<strong>of</strong>it. But in fact, “even if the end product is useless, or even destructive, the labor<br />

producing it is called “useful labor” as long as it manages to produce this end product.”<br />

Message [115] referenced by [117] and [138]. Next Message by Baseball is [284].<br />

[116] Kraken: graded B+ Useful or Useless? <strong>The</strong> book states that: “<strong>The</strong> term ‘useful<br />

labor’ does not involve a judgment about the use-value <strong>of</strong> the product. Even if the end<br />

product is useless or even destructive, the labor producing it is called ‘useful labor’ as long<br />

as it manages to produce this end product.” Using this definition as our guide, the answer<br />

to the question would be – yes, it would still be considered useful labor. One can’t say that<br />

a product is useless because that would be a judgment call. What is useless to one person<br />

may have great value to another. <strong>The</strong> example <strong>of</strong> the nuclear weapon is a good one. You and<br />

your friends may find it useless to have a nuclear bomb, but a group <strong>of</strong> terrorists may find a<br />

nuclear bomb to be very useful and consider it extremely valuable. As long as the product<br />

functions as intended, the labor used to produce it is considered to be useful labor.<br />

Message [116] referenced by [117]. Next Message by Kraken is [120].<br />

[117] Hans: How useful is this <strong>thing</strong> really? A big body <strong>of</strong> scientific literature has<br />

found out that the microwave radiation used for cell phones and wi-fi is damaging to your<br />

health and brain functions, especially for children. <strong>The</strong> ancient US safety standards are long<br />

overdue for a revision in light <strong>of</strong> this research. <strong>The</strong>y need to be considerably tightened. This<br />

issue is hotly debated in Europe, but the public in the USA and Canada is, unsurprisingly,<br />

kept entirely in the dark. See e.g. www.thecanadiancharger.com/page.php?id=5&a=563<br />

In other words, your convenient wi-fi access point or cell phone may not really be a<br />

use-value but it undermines your health and especially the health <strong>of</strong> your children.<br />

Does this mean that the labor producing this access point or cell phone does not count<br />

as useful labor? Unfortunately not. <strong>The</strong> market cannot tell whether a product is ultimately<br />

useful or not. As long as the product can be sold to unsuspecting consumers, the labor counts<br />

as “useful” labor. Kraken [116] came up with an even more memorable example: the labor<br />

producing nuclear weapons is useful because terrorists are eager to get these weapons on the<br />

black market.<br />

Let’s stay with the example <strong>of</strong> a wi-fi access point or a dsl modem or cable modem. <strong>The</strong><br />

consumer versions <strong>of</strong> these devices have limited lifetimes. Geeks have a jokular expression<br />

for this: they say after some time these devices turn into “bricks.” This means you still can<br />

use them for some<strong>thing</strong>, as a door stopper or a paperweight, but no longer as a modem. (<strong>The</strong><br />

web also has instructions how to “un-brick” certain devices.) Assuming your workforce<br />

turns out modems which turn into bricks already after two weeks <strong>of</strong> use. You cannot argue<br />

that this is useful labor because it produced cute paperweights with ears. Here even the<br />

market notices that this is not useful labor.<br />

In the <strong>first</strong> paragraph <strong>of</strong> [104], Orville says some right <strong>thing</strong>s, but he makes the rift between<br />

usefulness <strong>of</strong> the product and the useful character <strong>of</strong> labor too deep. This error leads<br />

90 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

him then in the second paragraph to dig himself into the hole even deeper, saying that usevalue<br />

does not really matter because if you have a material <strong>thing</strong> you can always find some<br />

use for it. Trap [105] sharpens the message in Orville [104]. Trap leaves out every<strong>thing</strong><br />

that is correct in Orville and goes straight to what is wrong in it. Trap seems to revel in<br />

absurd conclusions—but after all, we are here in a class about Marxism aren’t we? Baseball<br />

[115] goes back to Orville’s original misunderstandings. Too much text exegesis and too<br />

little thinking. Kraken [116] is shorter but he seems to have thought a little more. He brings<br />

the nuclear example but does not argue it out properly. <strong>The</strong> question is not whether you<br />

or I think nuclear weapons are useful but whether they are useful for humanity. I think a<br />

world socialist system would come to the conclusion that neither nuclear weapons nor nuclear<br />

power are useful, and the technology <strong>of</strong> enriching uranium or thorium would simply<br />

not be used. But this is a controversial issue, therefore I replaced this example in today’s<br />

message with the modem example, hoping it is a clearer illustration <strong>of</strong> the issues at hand.<br />

Message [117] referenced by [138]. Next Message by Hans is [119].<br />

[138] Hans: Bullet point fight. In the Annotations, the two bullet points<br />

• labor is useful if it produces a product that has any use-value <strong>of</strong> whatever kind,<br />

• labor is useful to the extent that its product is useful (meaning, beneficial for its consumers<br />

and/or society.)<br />

are alternatives: they say different <strong>thing</strong>s, therefore the question arises which <strong>of</strong> the two<br />

interpretations captures better the meaning <strong>of</strong> Marx’s term “useful labor” (answer being: the<br />

<strong>first</strong>).<br />

Baseball [115] does not treat them as alternatives but lists them side by side, as if reinforcing<br />

each other. Which led me to wonder if Baseball knows how to read, he is certainly<br />

not thinking through my argument, he is just picking out sentences not worrying how they<br />

fit together. That’s why my [117] said about Baseball [115]: “too much text exegesis and<br />

too little thinking.”<br />

I think I understand now better why Baseball overlooked how I was arguing, this is why<br />

I am writing this message here. In Baseball’s mind the two bullet points follow from each<br />

other. Baseball argues: if a product is useful in the <strong>first</strong> sense, that it finds a buyer, then it is<br />

also useful in the second sense, it helps the overall economy, because it “keeps the economy<br />

steady.” Producing a saleable product, making a great pr<strong>of</strong>it, and helping society are in his<br />

mind more or less the same. Some version <strong>of</strong> the invisible hand, and an interesting insight<br />

into the capitalist mindset.<br />

In my mind, producing a product that can find a buyer, and producing a product that<br />

is good for society, or even good for its buyer, are two different <strong>thing</strong>s. <strong>The</strong> illegal drug<br />

trade is not the only example. Plasma TVs have great use value for the viewer but they<br />

are energy hogs. <strong>The</strong>y cause the construction <strong>of</strong> coal-fired power plants, which dooms the<br />

planet. Nuclear weapons, cellphones which lead to brain tumors are different examples.<br />

We live in the 21st century. <strong>The</strong> possibilities <strong>of</strong> what we can produce are almost endless.<br />

Whether it is in our interest to produce all the <strong>thing</strong>s we can produce is another question.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [142].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 91<br />

[202] Jon: What is so useful about a useless product? For my free discussion I choose<br />

to direct my thoughts to what Marx describes as useful labor. He further states that useful<br />

labor is used even in producing a useless product as long as there is a finished product at<br />

labor’s end. This has been a hard <strong>thing</strong> for me to accept knowing that labor is best used or<br />

most useful when it is creating some<strong>thing</strong> that is useful. In my mind the opposite should be<br />

true as well that a product with no use value then labor must have been wasted or at the least<br />

not useful.<br />

Use-value <strong>of</strong> a product is somewhat a judgment call knowing that I have a different<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> what is useful from others even in this class. <strong>The</strong> <strong>thing</strong> that changed in my<br />

mind to help me agree with Marx is the idea that no<strong>thing</strong> is wasted or that there is a lesson to<br />

be learned even in failure. A person may spend the whole day laboring over a product that<br />

has no use-value. <strong>The</strong> truth is that the person has learned some<strong>thing</strong> in the very least that the<br />

product is not useful, and therefore will not waste their time and labor to produce it again.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is also the fact that the person has spent the day practicing skills that would have a use<br />

in the production process <strong>of</strong> other commodities. Even though the product is useless to the<br />

rest <strong>of</strong> the world the experience that is gained by the laborer is what in my mind makes that<br />

labor useful labor.<br />

Message [202] referenced by [1110]. Next Message by Jon is [250].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 126 is 51 in 1995WI, 61 in 1995ut, 63 in 1996ut, 71 in 1997sp, 66 in<br />

1997ut, 92 in 2003fa, 103 in 2004fa, 118 in 2007fa, 118 in 2008fa, 146 in 2011fa, and<br />

145 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 126 (a) Why is it necessary for the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities that they<br />

contain qualitatively different kinds <strong>of</strong> useful labor?<br />

(b) Can commodity production exist without division <strong>of</strong> labor?<br />

(c) Can division <strong>of</strong> labor exist without commodity production?<br />

(d) How does commodity production influence the division <strong>of</strong> labor?<br />

[289] Kleenex: division <strong>of</strong> labor. <strong>Question</strong> 126 asks if division <strong>of</strong> labor can exist without<br />

commodity production. Though I know that the Marx answer would be yes, according to<br />

the Annotations, I’m having a hard time understanding and relating this to real life. What<br />

are some modern examples or applications <strong>of</strong> production where division <strong>of</strong> labor exists,<br />

but commodities are not being produced? I’m guessing if division <strong>of</strong> labor exists, then<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> is being produced...but what? Any ideas would be appreciated.<br />

Message [289] referenced by [339]. Next Message by Kleenex is [292].<br />

[339] Hans: Simple answers which you should know. This question may seem intimidating,<br />

but the answers are not rocket science. I classified it as exam question because<br />

everybody should know the answers.<br />

(a) in order to be exchanged, commodities must have different use-values, therefore different<br />

labors.<br />

(b) Division <strong>of</strong> labor, i.e., different workers specializing on different products, is necessary<br />

for commodity production. Why would the linen weaver exchange linen for coat if she<br />

could produce coats as efficiently as the tailor? She would make her own coats.<br />

92 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(c) Division <strong>of</strong> labor can exist without commodity production. This would be any system<br />

which produces products not as private production with distribution through a market. <strong>The</strong><br />

Soviet Union produced based on a plan, i.e., the products were not commodities, but there<br />

was division <strong>of</strong> labor. I hope this answers [289] (sorry for the delay).<br />

(d) Commodity production deepens the division <strong>of</strong> labor. <strong>The</strong>re is an incentive to do<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s differently in order to fetch market share away from the rest.<br />

Message [339] referenced by [734], [829], and [2012fa:323.1]. Next Message by Hans is [347].<br />

[631] Hans: What is wrong with this answer? One class participant wondered why<br />

they did not get an A with the following in-exam answer. Perhaps others can explain what<br />

is wrong with this answer? I made question 162 part <strong>of</strong> the current homework assignment<br />

so that you will get homework credit if you respond. Aklthough it says “ungraded exam<br />

question” you will get a real grade for it. Here is the answer <strong>of</strong> your peer, typed in by me:<br />

(a) As described by Marx, use-values are the “carriers” <strong>of</strong> exchange values in commoditie.<br />

Commodities must have use to be exchanged. For example the linen weaver is willing to<br />

trade “x” <strong>of</strong> her linen for a coat because she is in need <strong>of</strong> a coat, which she has none <strong>of</strong>, and<br />

she has plenty <strong>of</strong> linen to trade, which she has no need <strong>of</strong>.<br />

(b) Yes, due to the homogeneous nature <strong>of</strong> the societal pool <strong>of</strong> labor-power, (within reason)<br />

any laborer can produce any given commodity with proper training, facilities, etc.<br />

(c) In this case, no! Without commodity production, there would be no need for specialization<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor, or even labor-power for that matter.<br />

(d) Commodity production allows for specialization or division because <strong>of</strong> the exchangeability<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities. Since all commodities are composed <strong>of</strong> a labor input, they can be<br />

exchanged with others <strong>of</strong> equal value. Labor can be divided to maximize and increase the<br />

efficiency <strong>of</strong> production where finished products can be traded away for other commodities<br />

<strong>of</strong> required use-values.<br />

Message [631] referenced by [634], [636], and [734]. Next Message by Hans is [635].<br />

[634] Proletarian: graded A+ What was wrong with that answer. In message [631]<br />

Hans asks why the individual who gave the answer to question 126 on the exam did not get<br />

the A they were expecting (the individual’s answer is reproduced in Hans’ post). While this<br />

is not meant to be rude or mean, the reason that the individual who penned the answer to this<br />

question did not receive an A is because, bluntly, the answer is almost completely incorrect.<br />

While the answer suggests that the respondent read the material, it shows that he or she<br />

either did not read the material closely enough or that he or she did not fully understand the<br />

material (and probably should have asked more questions in class or in the open discussion).<br />

I do not purport to be an expert on Marx; after all, I took this class to learn more about<br />

his thoughts and writing. <strong>The</strong> material is at points quite challenging and is a big departure<br />

from the kind <strong>of</strong> economic thinking that most <strong>of</strong> us have been exposed to in our lives. Still,<br />

I believe that I can explain why the respondent to this question did not receive the A that he<br />

or she was expecting.<br />

126 (a): Why is it necessary for the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities that they contain qualitatively<br />

different kinds <strong>of</strong> useful labor?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 93<br />

<strong>The</strong> respondent answered: “As described by Marx, use-values are the ‘carriers’ <strong>of</strong> exchange<br />

values in commodities. Commodities must have use to be exchanged. For example<br />

the linen weaver is willing to trade ‘x’ <strong>of</strong> her linen for a coat because she is in need <strong>of</strong> a coat,<br />

which she has none <strong>of</strong>, and she has plenty <strong>of</strong> linen to trade, which she has no need <strong>of</strong>.”<br />

First <strong>of</strong> all, use-values are not “carriers” <strong>of</strong> exchange-values in commodities. Use-values<br />

are the benefits that consumers <strong>of</strong> commodities experience from the use <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

For example, a coat has a use-value to someone if it keeps them warm in the winter and they<br />

need to be kept warm. A use-value is not quantifiable and is a strictly individual valuation<br />

(as opposed to a social valuation). A commodity only has a use-value to a person if they will<br />

experience a benefit from the use or consumption <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Now, that being said, the answer given isn’t 100% wrong, and the respondent starts to<br />

head in the right direction. First <strong>of</strong> all, he or she (I will just use he from this point to avoid<br />

the tedium <strong>of</strong> using ‘he or she’) is correct in the statement that commodities must have usevalue<br />

in order to be exchanged, though the more correct formulation <strong>of</strong> this statement is that,<br />

in the simple model <strong>of</strong> exchange, the commodities which each party receives in the exchange<br />

must have a use-values to them. This makes logical sense because nobody would enter into<br />

an exchange for some<strong>thing</strong> for which they have no use.<br />

<strong>The</strong> respondent comes even closer to being right when he says “for example the linen<br />

weaver is willing to trade ‘x’ <strong>of</strong> her linen for a coat because she is in need <strong>of</strong> a coat, which<br />

she has none <strong>of</strong>, and she has plenty <strong>of</strong> linen to trade, which she has no need <strong>of</strong>.” Still, the<br />

respondent falls short <strong>of</strong> correctly expressing the right answer. What he says is indeed true:<br />

the weaver would be willing to trade her linen for a coat because she needs a coat and has<br />

no need for linen. Still, the respondent falls just short <strong>of</strong> providing a concise and correct<br />

answer.<br />

What the respondent could have said is: commodities must contain qualitatively different<br />

kinds <strong>of</strong> useful labor because if they didn’t contain different kinds <strong>of</strong> useful labor, every<br />

producer <strong>of</strong> commodities could simply produce what they need for their own personal consumption<br />

and would have no need to enter into exchange. If all useful labor was the exact<br />

same, the linen weaver would not devote his entire life to weaving linen but would instead<br />

weave the linen he needs, harvest the wheat he needs, etc. However, since commodities<br />

contain different kinds <strong>of</strong> useful labor, this leads to specialization. Tailors make clothes,<br />

weavers weave cloth, farmers harvest crops, and so forth. Because <strong>of</strong> these different kinds<br />

<strong>of</strong> useful labor and labor specialization, different commodities with different use-values are<br />

produced and are brought to market. Because these commodities have different use-values,<br />

people are willing to exchange the products <strong>of</strong> their labor for them.<br />

This is where the respondent comes closest in his answer. People would not enter into<br />

exchange for identical use values because if they have 1 unit <strong>of</strong> use-value A, they have no<br />

reason to exchange that unit for a different, but quantitatively and qualitatively identical,<br />

commodity with the same use-value. This is obvious—after all, why exchange 1kg <strong>of</strong> potatoes<br />

for 1kg <strong>of</strong> potatoes? One would not engage in this trade because one could simply avoid<br />

the hassle <strong>of</strong> going to market and keep the 1kg <strong>of</strong> potatoes one already owns and end up with<br />

the same use-value.<br />

94 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

126 (b): Can commodity production exist without division <strong>of</strong> labor?<br />

<strong>The</strong> respondent answered: “Yes, due to the homogeneous nature <strong>of</strong> the societal pool<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor-power, (within reason) any laborer can produce any given commodity with proper<br />

training, facilities, etc.”<br />

From this response it seems like the respondent is trying to get at the idea that sociallyvalid<br />

labor is valued equally and is the source <strong>of</strong> value in commodities. He is, unfortunately,<br />

missing the point <strong>of</strong> the question and is answering incorrectly.<br />

<strong>The</strong> correct answer is no, commodity production cannot exist without the division <strong>of</strong><br />

labor. Division <strong>of</strong> labor means that different people perform different kinds <strong>of</strong> labor and<br />

produce different items, i.e. the tailor makes clothes, the farmer harvests crops, and so forth.<br />

Without the division <strong>of</strong> labor, everyone would be producing for themselves the items that<br />

they need to consume, and since everyone would be producing only for themselves, there<br />

would be no exchange. While consumable items would still be produced, they would not be<br />

commodities since commodities, by definition, are produced to be exchanged. <strong>The</strong> division<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor allows people to produce only one or a few items which they intend to take to<br />

market and exchange for other items. Since the items produced are taken to market to be<br />

exchanged they are, by definition, commodities. This taking to market for exchange would<br />

not occur without division <strong>of</strong> labor, and therefore without the division <strong>of</strong> labor, commodities,<br />

and thereby commodity production, would not exist.<br />

126 (c): Can division <strong>of</strong> labor exist without commodity production?<br />

<strong>The</strong> respondent answered: “In this case, no! Without commodity production, there would<br />

be no need for specialization <strong>of</strong> labor, or even labor-power for that matter.”<br />

This is simply incorrect. First <strong>of</strong> all, this answer seems to contradict the answer the respondent<br />

gave to part (b) <strong>of</strong> this question. In part (b) the respondent asserted that commodity<br />

production can exist without the division <strong>of</strong> labor, but here in his answer to part (c), he seems<br />

to argue that commodity production requires the division <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Second, this is incorrect because the the respondent asserts that there is no need for the<br />

specialization <strong>of</strong> labor (division <strong>of</strong> labor) without commodity production. This is an empirically<br />

inaccurate statement. When the respondent provides this answer he is only considering<br />

societies that recognize individual ownership. While capitalist societies operate under<br />

a concept <strong>of</strong> individual ownership, there are plenty <strong>of</strong> other societies that view ownership<br />

differently.<br />

For example, there are tribal societies where ownership is communal but division <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

still exists. Division <strong>of</strong> labor in these societies may lead to some individuals being responsible<br />

for hunting for meat, while others may be responsible for gathering vegetables, and still<br />

others may be responsible for weaving clo<strong>thing</strong>. In this example it is obvious that division <strong>of</strong><br />

labor is still present, but since ownership is communal there is no exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

since the individuals don’t individually own the product <strong>of</strong> their labor but rather are producing<br />

for the common good. If the hunter were to come back from the hunt unsuccessful, he is<br />

not going to be denied a share <strong>of</strong> the harvested crops or a piece <strong>of</strong> clo<strong>thing</strong>. However, if the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 95<br />

hunter was hunting in a capitalist society that subscribes to the concept <strong>of</strong> individual ownership<br />

and he returned home from the hunt unsuccessful, he would have no<strong>thing</strong> to exchange<br />

and would therefore be unable to legally receive harvested food or tailored clo<strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Finally, the mention <strong>of</strong> labor-power seems entirely out-<strong>of</strong>-place in this answer. Laborpower<br />

is the potential for productive labor. Labor can be specialized, but labor-power cannot<br />

be. While the eventual products <strong>of</strong> labor-power may be different and may be products <strong>of</strong><br />

laborers who engage in the division (specialization) <strong>of</strong> labor, the labor-power, the unrealized<br />

(to be expended) labor, is not specialized.<br />

126 (d): How does commodity production influence the division <strong>of</strong> labor?<br />

<strong>The</strong> respondent answered: “Commodity production allows for specialization or division<br />

because <strong>of</strong> the exchangeability <strong>of</strong> commodities. Since all commodities are composed <strong>of</strong><br />

a labor input, they can be exchanged with others <strong>of</strong> equal value. Labor can be divided to<br />

maximize and increase the efficiency <strong>of</strong> production where finished products can be traded<br />

away for other commodities <strong>of</strong> required use-values.”<br />

As with his answers to the previous three parts <strong>of</strong> this question, the respondent’s answer<br />

has some aspects that are correct, or nearly correct, but his answer still falls short. <strong>The</strong> exchangeability<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities is not what “allows” for the division <strong>of</strong> labor. As demonstrated<br />

above (in my response to part (c)), division <strong>of</strong> labor empirically occurs without commodity<br />

production. However, the inverse <strong>of</strong> the respondent’s assertion is true, commodity production<br />

cannot occur without the division <strong>of</strong> labor (as explained in my response to part (b)).<br />

<strong>The</strong> second sentence <strong>of</strong> the respondent’s answer to part (d) is also partially correct, though<br />

it is a simplistic and lacking explanation <strong>of</strong> how/why commodities are exchanged. All commodities<br />

do contain some amount <strong>of</strong> socially valid labor and are therefore exchangeable<br />

with other commodities containing the same amount <strong>of</strong> socially valid labor. I believe this is<br />

what the respondent means when he states that “Since all commodities are composed <strong>of</strong> a<br />

labor input, they can be exchanged with others <strong>of</strong> equal value.” If so, he is correct, though he<br />

is not expressing his thoughts as clearly as he could. Since congealed socially valid labortime<br />

is the source <strong>of</strong> value in a commodity, quantities <strong>of</strong> commodities containing an equal<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> congealed human labor are directly exchangeable (i.e. 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen containing<br />

X amount <strong>of</strong> congealed human labor are exchangeable for 1 coat if it contains the same<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> congealed human labor (at socially accepted levels)).<br />

<strong>The</strong> final sentence <strong>of</strong> the respondent’s answer to part (d) <strong>of</strong> this question is among the<br />

most correct <strong>of</strong> his entire response to question 126. <strong>The</strong> respondent says: “Labor can be<br />

divided to maximize and increase the efficiency <strong>of</strong> production where finished products can<br />

be traded away for other commodities <strong>of</strong> required use-values.” For the most part this is<br />

accurate, though it could have been explained much more clearly. A clearer response would<br />

have been:<br />

Commodity production influences the division <strong>of</strong> labor because <strong>of</strong> the production efficiencies<br />

realized in the division <strong>of</strong> labor. For example, a person who commits 100% <strong>of</strong> his<br />

time to what he is best at, for example the production <strong>of</strong> linen, will be able to produce more<br />

linen with his labor than he would be able to without the division <strong>of</strong> labor. If division <strong>of</strong><br />

labor were not undertaken he would not have the opportunity to hone his skills and become<br />

96 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

as efficient a linen producer as possible because he would have to spread his time around<br />

sewing clothes, harvesting food, etc. Because <strong>of</strong> the division <strong>of</strong> labor, production becomes<br />

more efficient and more units <strong>of</strong> each commodity is produced, increasing the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities and potential use values available in the aggregate.<br />

For example, without division <strong>of</strong> labor, each person may be able to produce one shirt, one<br />

pound <strong>of</strong> food, and one pair <strong>of</strong> shoes. However, with the division <strong>of</strong> labor and the production<br />

efficiencies realized from said division <strong>of</strong> labor (with one person specializing in production<br />

<strong>of</strong> shirts, the other in shoes, and the other in food), a total <strong>of</strong> six shirts, six pounds <strong>of</strong> food,<br />

and six pairs <strong>of</strong> shoes could be produced. Thanks to division <strong>of</strong> labor, everyone in this simple<br />

example, after participating in exchange, could potentially have two shirts, two pounds <strong>of</strong><br />

food, and two pairs <strong>of</strong> shoes each (as opposed to one unit <strong>of</strong> each commodity per person<br />

without the division <strong>of</strong> labor).<br />

Since the division <strong>of</strong> labor increases the amount <strong>of</strong> total output in the economy it allows<br />

everyone to get more use-values than they would have without the division <strong>of</strong> labor. In the<br />

above example everyone expends the same amount <strong>of</strong> labor in the production <strong>of</strong> consumable<br />

items, but thanks to the division <strong>of</strong> labor, after exchange, everyone will have twice as many<br />

goods as they would have without the division <strong>of</strong> labor. <strong>The</strong>refore commodity production<br />

influences the division <strong>of</strong> labor by encouraging division <strong>of</strong> labor because the division <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

leads to greater overall output (more units <strong>of</strong> production per unit <strong>of</strong> human labor) which<br />

increases the amount <strong>of</strong> use-value afforded to participants in the market after exchange.<br />

Message [634] referenced by [635] and [636]. Next Message by Proletarian is [636].<br />

[635] Hans: Quick remarks about point (d) and about politeness. Commodity production<br />

encourages and deepens division <strong>of</strong> labor, not only because <strong>of</strong> the productivity gains,<br />

but also because it encourages “product differentiation,” i.e., the development <strong>of</strong> different<br />

and more specialized use-values. If you have a different use-value than others, you may be<br />

able to sell it more easily and at a higher price than if you have the same use-value as the<br />

other suppliers. Product differentiation is also a way to get away with price discrimination.<br />

You make small variations <strong>of</strong> your product which appeal to the richer customers, and you<br />

charge an arm and a leg for this small difference.<br />

Otherwise [634] is an excellent answer although it is in fact a little rude. You are allowed<br />

to say that the answer is incorrect, but needling the author by saying that he or she “either did<br />

not read the material closely enough or that he or she did not fully understand the material”<br />

and that the author “should have asked more questions” was not necessary. On the contrary,<br />

these remarks make it harder for the author to read the rest <strong>of</strong> your answer. I used to do<br />

this as a little kid with my older sister. I criticized her, but I intentionally formulated my<br />

criticism in such <strong>of</strong>fensive ways that she could not learn from it—because I wanted to keep<br />

criticizing her.<br />

You are not in an adversarial relation with your peers. Or maybe I should say: you are<br />

in fact in an adversarial relation with your peers because you compete with your peers for<br />

grades, therefore it is in fact advantageous to beat down others rather than building them<br />

up—but this class has the declared aim to overcome this competition.<br />

Message [635] referenced by [636] and [2012fa:323.1]. Next Message by Hans is [637].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 97<br />

[636] Proletarian: An apology to the author <strong>of</strong> the answer to 126. Hans points out<br />

in [635] that my comments in [634] are “a little rude.” I want to sincerely apologize to the<br />

original author whose response to exam question 126 has been the subject <strong>of</strong> [631], [634],<br />

and [635]. After a revisitation to the request for input in message [631] I realize that what<br />

was really being sought was simply an explanation <strong>of</strong> what was incorrect in the answer<br />

reproduced in [631] and not an explanation <strong>of</strong> how the original author arrived at his or her<br />

answer.<br />

It is not my position as a fellow student to evaluate how or why one arrived at a particular<br />

answer. As I said in [634], I’m no expert on Marx’s writings, and I’m learning new <strong>thing</strong>s<br />

every day about the subject mater, both from Hans and his notations, as well as from the<br />

responses from other class members submitted to the email list. I know that this class is<br />

not a zero-sum game, and in my response to [631] I was simply trying to enhance the class<br />

discussion and help clarify the topics brought up in question [126]. In a course such as this<br />

we all learn together or not at all, and I wanted to make a contribution which I felt would<br />

enhance everyone’s understanding <strong>of</strong> the course material. It was not my intention to “beat<br />

down” on a fellow classmate, though I can clearly see how my response could have come<br />

across that way.<br />

Again, I want to apologize to the original author whose answer was reproduced in [631].<br />

My response certainly came across as rude, and that was not my intention. In my response,<br />

which itself was imperfect as explained in [635], I simply tried to clarify topics from the<br />

course and enhance the understanding <strong>of</strong> the material for everyone enrolled in the course.<br />

I stand by the content <strong>of</strong> my response, but I certainly could have composed it in a more<br />

constructive manner.<br />

Best regards to everyone, and especially to the author <strong>of</strong> the answer reproduced in [631],<br />

Proletarian<br />

Next Message by Proletarian is [903].<br />

[732] Cougar: You call this reconsidering an exam? I had no idea that after I asked<br />

Hans to reconsider a question on my <strong>first</strong> exam that my submission would be plastered<br />

on the mailing list for the class to see. I think it’s hilarious that Proletarian, with Hans<br />

blessing, went home immediately and began researching the question so he could “school”<br />

me. What a cowardly gesture. That is exactly the kind <strong>of</strong> arrogant, vitriolic, self-serving,<br />

phony-aristocratic behavior that gives academia a bad “vibe.” I’m sure it took a lot <strong>of</strong> brains<br />

to research the question after-the-fact and belittle me. I guess the pseudonym system grants<br />

some with a boost <strong>of</strong> courage. I do, however, accept your apology, but please realize this is<br />

the <strong>first</strong> class on Marxian thought many <strong>of</strong> us have ever taken.<br />

I would now like to take this second opportunity to defend my answer. I may not have<br />

answered the question how Proletarian thought I should (a bit wordy though, not my style),<br />

or even how Marx would have answered it but I still feel I answered with at least an understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> the material. I proposed ideas and supported them with the tools provided<br />

in the discussions and text. I appreciate Hans giving us the opportunity to question our<br />

exam grades and hope I haven’t over-stepped my bounds to defend my integrity. I feel my<br />

argument here is no more abrasive than the protest I received weeks ago. Thank you.<br />

98 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Message [732] referenced by [734]. Next Message by Cougar is [911].<br />

[734] Hans: To Cougar. Your claim that you are accepting Proletarian’s apology does<br />

not sound believable in view <strong>of</strong> all the epithets you are throwing at him in the same message<br />

[732].<br />

Yes, you did apply Marx’s categories in answer [631]. <strong>The</strong> only lapse was in point (c),<br />

where you seem to have confused “product” and “commodity.” That is why your grade was<br />

a B, i.e., I only counted point (c) as wrong and the others as right.<br />

You are not the only class participant who got question 126 wrong. I thought this question<br />

was pretty straightforward, but <strong>of</strong> the nine people who had it on the exam, a whopping four<br />

answered (b) with yes and (c) with no. When grading the exam on Tuesday evening Sep 29<br />

(right after the exam), I sent [339] to the list for the benefit <strong>of</strong> those who got it wrong during<br />

the exam. Apparently, this message didn’t reach you, since you asked me in class about this<br />

question. <strong>The</strong>refore I sent your answer to the list too. Again, this did not reach you at <strong>first</strong>,<br />

because a week later in class you asked me about this question again and you had not seen<br />

that I had responded to you on the list.<br />

This brings me to the question why there is not more privacy in this class. I am giving<br />

you high-quality individualized feedback, which takes a lot <strong>of</strong> time. I say on p. 768 <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Annotations: “I can justify the large amount <strong>of</strong> time spent on this feedback because this<br />

feedback is seen by more than one student.” I know that this feedback <strong>of</strong>ten does not reach<br />

the class participants at whom it is aimed, but I trust that others can learn from it too. I.e.,<br />

there is a trade<strong>of</strong>f between privacy and the depth <strong>of</strong> feedback I can give.<br />

Knowing that this is a delicate issue, I try to protect the privacy <strong>of</strong> the class participants<br />

by the pseudonyms. And regarding your case, Cougar, I sent your exam answer to the<br />

class without revealing your pseudonym. I appreciate you coming forward and owning this<br />

answer, but this must be your decision, not mine. <strong>The</strong>refore I don’t think your integrity was<br />

at stake in a public sense. You may also have noticed that, whenever I am critical <strong>of</strong> some<br />

submission, I <strong>of</strong>ten don’t name the author. For instance in message [295] I did not mention<br />

the pseudonym <strong>of</strong> the author <strong>of</strong> [9] because I was critical <strong>of</strong> [9], but I did mention the author<br />

<strong>of</strong> [288] because I only had good <strong>thing</strong>s to say about [288].<br />

Next Message by Hans is [752].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 127 is 121 in 2008SP and 124 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 127 Marx says in 133:1 that it does not matter for the use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat<br />

whether it is worn by the tailor or by someone else. Is this correct for every use-value?<br />

If you write a computer program for yourself then you <strong>of</strong>ten obey different principles than if<br />

you write it for others to use. A program which “works for me” is <strong>of</strong>ten poorly documented<br />

and does not consider all the possible situations which different users <strong>of</strong> the program might<br />

find themselves in.<br />

[109] Lana: Of coats and surfboards... I accept the statement that “it does not matter<br />

for the use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat whether it is worn by the tailor or by someone else.” A coat is a<br />

coat and can really only be used as a coat. All people who would use the coat would use it<br />

on their body for warmth in the same fashion as any other person. This, however, is not true


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 99<br />

for every use-value. Consider a surfboard: to a person who is a pr<strong>of</strong>essional board shaper<br />

and trained surfer, the board is incredibly useful. But to someone who say, has never surfed<br />

before in their life, the surfboard has very little use to them.<br />

Final Grading Note by Hans: All your contributions are creative and interesting. If you were to combine your<br />

creativity with a careful reading <strong>of</strong> Marx it would be even better.<br />

Message [109] referenced by [142]. Next Message by Lana is [165].<br />

[142] Hans: Coats <strong>of</strong> indifference. Lana [109] says: the use-value <strong>of</strong> a surfboard is<br />

different for someone who knows how to surf than for someone who doesn’t. Agreed. But<br />

Marx does not compare expert surfers with non-surfers. He compares consumers who are<br />

life-long specialized producers <strong>of</strong> surfboards with consumers who are not. A longer explanation<br />

is needed why Marx even divides the consumers <strong>of</strong> surfboards in such an awkward<br />

way into two classes.<br />

In paragraph 133:1 Marx argues against division <strong>of</strong> labor. Although it is true that different<br />

use-values require different kinds <strong>of</strong> labor to produce them, Marx argues here that even in<br />

modern production with many specialized use-values, there is no necessity that workers have<br />

to specialize on one use-value only.<br />

Marx brings three arguments in 133:1. <strong>The</strong> one easiest to understand comes last: Coats<br />

were produced long before any one individual specialized their work-life on producing coats.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second argument digs a little deeper. Marx says that the relationship between the<br />

coat and the labor producing the coat is not affected by it that this labor belongs to a tailor.<br />

In other words, a tailor has to do exactly the same <strong>thing</strong> when producing coats as someone<br />

producing coats who is not a tailor. From the objective side, the nature <strong>of</strong> the production<br />

process gives no special advantage to tailors. Tailors may still have an advantage from the<br />

subjective side, since a life-long tailor has more opportunity to deepen his or her skills. Marx<br />

does not discuss this obvious point. Marx is asking here: does the production process, by its<br />

structure, need us to be tailors, and the answer is “no.”<br />

Since this argument is on a higher level <strong>of</strong> abstraction than most <strong>of</strong> us are used to think,<br />

Marx tries to ease the reader into this way <strong>of</strong> thinking by <strong>first</strong> saying some<strong>thing</strong> that he<br />

expects to be abundantly clear to the reader. Marx’s <strong>first</strong> argument in 133:1, which so-to<br />

say introduces his main point that tailors have to do exactly the same <strong>thing</strong> as non-tailors<br />

when producing coats, Marx says that being a tailor also does not give any advantages in the<br />

consumption <strong>of</strong> coats. <strong>The</strong> coat does not say to the tailor wearing it: “Since you produced<br />

me, I love you as if you were my father, and therefore I will stay especially wrinkle-free for<br />

you.” On the contrary, the coat relates to its own producer as an ordinary use-value, the same<br />

way as it relates to everybody else. Perhaps Marx thought that the reader would be more<br />

familiar with consumption issues than production issues, but I think Marx’s attempt to make<br />

it clearer really made the issue more difficult to understand.<br />

Not only is this <strong>first</strong> step not strictly necessary and probably confusing instead <strong>of</strong> being<br />

helpful, but question 127 wonders if this step is even correct. If I write a crude computer<br />

program for a simple task, and some<strong>thing</strong> goes wrong because there is a bug in it, I will<br />

probably know immediately why <strong>thing</strong>s went wrong and be able to fix it in minutes. If I give<br />

this same crude computer program to someone else, who does not know how it works, and<br />

that other person hits a bug, it will be much more difficult for that other person to recover<br />

100 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

from this bug. It is as if the computer program said to its producer: “Since you produced me,<br />

I love you as if you were my father, and therefore I will stay especially bug-free for you.”<br />

Next Message by Hans is [144].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 129 is 121 in 2008fa and 148 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 129 Would a society in which people tailor in the morning and philosophize in<br />

the afternoon not be filled with dilettante tailors and philosophers neither <strong>of</strong> whom has time<br />

to get to the bottom <strong>of</strong> their pr<strong>of</strong>ession?<br />

[107] Rico: Morning Tailors and Afternoon Philosophers. According to the annotations,<br />

Marx famously said, “people can be tailors in the morning and philosophers in the<br />

afternoon.” Here Marx points out that a person doesn’t necessarily need to be tied to one job<br />

in order to be effective. <strong>Question</strong> 129 asks if a society would be effectively productive if its<br />

people were tailors in the morning and philosophers in the afternoon? As I began contemplating<br />

the question, my initial thoughts were contrary to Marx’s statement, however after I<br />

thought about the statement in further detail, I found various instances were many societal<br />

institutions insist that females and males allocate their time to multiple facets <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

I cannot think <strong>of</strong> a society that does not have parents who are raising children. Parenting<br />

is an important aspect to each society because it helps produce future generations. <strong>The</strong>se<br />

future generations include young, dependent children, who depend on their parent’s ability<br />

to provide the basic necessities for them. A parent will work in their pr<strong>of</strong>ession in order to<br />

provide food, shelter, and protection for their children. <strong>The</strong> “production process” not only<br />

comes from wage producing firms, but also from other labor-intensive activities, such as<br />

being a parent.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are other examples <strong>of</strong> people allocating their time to multiple sources <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

but the main idea <strong>of</strong> my example is to point out that humans are capable <strong>of</strong> having various<br />

responsibilities and tasks, while still being able to be effective in their production. Thus, a<br />

society can have “tailors in the morning and philosophers in the afternoon” and still have<br />

time to be effective in their pr<strong>of</strong>essions.<br />

Message [107] referenced by [119] and [129]. Next Message by Rico is [235].<br />

[119] Hans: Most <strong>thing</strong>s have more than one side. I am happy to hear that Rico [107]<br />

could get himself to agree with Marx. But generally I want your essays to be a little more<br />

critical than Rico’s and also mention the downside <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s. He should not have swept<br />

under the rug the following two <strong>thing</strong>s:<br />

(1) Highly specialized labor is definitely more productive. <strong>The</strong> question is whether this<br />

increased productivity is worth it or whether we are sacrificing humans on the altar <strong>of</strong> productivity.<br />

(2) <strong>The</strong> dilettante role <strong>of</strong> parents has been criticized. Some people say you need a licence<br />

to drive a car but not a licence to raise children.<br />

Regarding (2), I think here the problem has a lot to do with two capitalist phenomena:<br />

stress and lack <strong>of</strong> time.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 101<br />

Capitalism is stressful. People are forced to perform under threat <strong>of</strong> starvation and homelessness.<br />

Unfortunately, it is in our psychic makeup to pass on the stress to others, and the<br />

dependent, vulnerable and innocent children in our midsts are irresistible targets.<br />

And capitalism, especially in the USA, places high demands on our time. Parents in the<br />

USA today usually don’t have enough free time to devote to their children.<br />

For environmental reasons we need less production, i.e., more free time. This will definitely<br />

benefit the children. For environmental reasons we also need fewer children. This,<br />

too, allows parents to devote more time to each child. I am less optimistic about stress. <strong>The</strong><br />

succession <strong>of</strong> crises heading towards us will increase our stress levels considerably. People<br />

will resort to drugs, magical thinking, they will try to find scapegoats, etc. <strong>The</strong> remedy is<br />

“mindfulness,” i.e., awareness <strong>of</strong> your feelings and your fears. If you push them out <strong>of</strong> consciousness,<br />

they will get the better <strong>of</strong> you in unexpected ways. It is better to confront them,<br />

even if it is painful.<br />

Another remedy is not to face the crises alone but band together. Children are wonderful<br />

community builders. <strong>The</strong>y start playing with your neighbor’s children in a second. This is<br />

an opportunity for you to get to know your neighbor better too. Turn your neighborhood into<br />

a mutual aid network.<br />

A third remedy is to fight back. Instead <strong>of</strong> swallowing all the damages which the corporations<br />

and the state inflict on you, stand up and fight for your rights. This will do wonders<br />

for your sanity.<br />

Message [119] referenced by [129]. Next Message by Hans is [122].<br />

[128] Pweber: Specialization Leads to Innovation. I don’t agree with Rico in this case,<br />

and Hans really hit the point I was going to make: specialized labor is more productive than<br />

labor in general. I’d much rather have a pr<strong>of</strong>essor that is very specialized in his field and actually<br />

knows what he’s talking about than some guy who waltzed into the President’s Circle<br />

looking for a job. Being good at some<strong>thing</strong> requires specialization, and so does innovation.<br />

Capitalism has one element that I believe has made it so prevalent—innovation. Capitalism’s<br />

naturally competitive nature drives people to come up with new ideas—while this<br />

leads to stress like Hans pointed out, we do get some<strong>thing</strong> in return. We wouldn’t be able<br />

to debate about a book written before our grandparents were born on a computer from the<br />

comfort <strong>of</strong> our air conditioned <strong>of</strong>fices and homes without capitalism’s inherent innovation.<br />

Innovation naturally requires specialization, especially at the level <strong>of</strong> technology and information<br />

we have in society today. <strong>The</strong> reason who know and remember people like Leonardo<br />

DiVinci, Ben Franklin, and others is that there are very few people who are good at almost<br />

every<strong>thing</strong>. Most people need to specialize in some<strong>thing</strong> to be successful at it—without<br />

division <strong>of</strong> labor, we’d all be living in mud huts.<br />

Giant: While specialization can benefit specific areas in society, it can also create more problems at the same time.<br />

If you have a door that is broken, a window, and a water pipe you will need to call three different types <strong>of</strong> specialist<br />

to fix each <strong>of</strong> these problems. While you can be reassured that they know what they are doing because they are<br />

specialists, it would be more efficient to call a general repair man to fix all these problems, even though they are<br />

not specialized in one particular field.<br />

Message [128] referenced by [129] and [132]. First Message by Pweber is [40].<br />

102 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[129] Hans: Retraction. In [119] I told you all what I think Rico should have said in<br />

[107]. I wanted Rico’s essay to be a little more like the second paragraph in [2008fa:194],<br />

which addresses exactly the point made by Pweber [128]: doesn’t scientific work require<br />

lifelong specialization?<br />

I thought about it a little more. Here is another possibility how Rico could have clarified<br />

his argument. Rico could have said: even today, in a society which pretends to value efficiency<br />

over every<strong>thing</strong>, we have situations where people do as Marx suggested. <strong>The</strong>y are not<br />

fishermen in the morning and philosophers in the afternoon, but they are perhaps accountants<br />

during the day and child educators in the evening. Rico could have used the argument<br />

in the <strong>first</strong> paragraph <strong>of</strong> [2008fa:194] saying that many people nowadays have to hold two<br />

part-time jobs because the employers have eliminated full-time jobs so that they don’t have<br />

to pay benefits. When it is done for the benefit <strong>of</strong> the corporations, nobody complains about<br />

it that this turns our nation into a nation <strong>of</strong> dilettantes. Why are we complaining about it<br />

when it is done for the benefit <strong>of</strong> the workers?<br />

Actually I find it possible now that this was Rico’s train <strong>of</strong> thought. Rico told us that he<br />

had to mull over this question for a while. Possibly he came across the kind <strong>of</strong> thoughts I<br />

just said while he was contemplating the issue. But he had to formulate it in a way that is not<br />

critical <strong>of</strong> today’s system but praises the system—because this is what we all are taught to<br />

do. In view <strong>of</strong> this possibility, I restored Rico’s grade: he is getting a full A. Quite <strong>of</strong>ten class<br />

participants submit deep and original thoughts expressed in such a way that it is a nontrivial<br />

task to recognize them. I’m trying to do my best to give credit to these hidden geniuses.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [135].<br />

[132] Utefan: I agree with Pweber [128]. <strong>The</strong> motivation to provide better solutions for<br />

life’s problems adds to the technological boom we have had. Just as recently as 200 years<br />

ago most people ate from farms that they themselves cultivated, now we have the ability to<br />

buy food that others have grown on their specialized crops. If someone is a jack <strong>of</strong> all trades<br />

then that person is a master <strong>of</strong> none <strong>of</strong> them. Without this mastery, society would never<br />

progress past the need to supply ourselves with comfort or food or shelter. However; we<br />

only benefit while maturity and integrity govern those actions.<br />

Next Message by Utefan is [214].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 130 is 79 in 1999SP, 94 in 2003fa, 105 in 2004fa, 106 in 2005fa, 119 in 2007SP,<br />

and 120 in 2007fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 130 When Marx wrote that labor is the father and natural forces are the mother<br />

<strong>of</strong> use-values, should he also have included produced means <strong>of</strong> production in addition to<br />

nature and labor?<br />

[113] PLG: graded A– <strong>The</strong> Mother and Father <strong>of</strong> Use-Values. In section 1.2a <strong>of</strong> Hans<br />

Ehrbars “Marxian Economics,” the sources <strong>of</strong> use-value are discussed. Marx breaks down<br />

the production <strong>of</strong> use-values into its most natural elements; matter, and the human modification<br />

<strong>of</strong> matter. Marx uses an analogy to describe the basic elements <strong>of</strong> use-value production:<br />

“As William Petty puts it: labor is its father and the earth it’s mother”.<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 130 asks “When Marx wrote that labor is the father and natural forces are the<br />

mother <strong>of</strong> use-values, should he (Marx) also have included produced means <strong>of</strong> production


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 103<br />

in addition to nature and labor.” In its most basic form Marx defines the production <strong>of</strong> usevalues<br />

as the modification <strong>of</strong> matter. <strong>The</strong>refore within this definition there are two elements<br />

“matter” which in the analogy comes from the mother, and “modification”, which in the<br />

analogy is from the father. To include produced means <strong>of</strong> production would be to include<br />

a repetitive step, such as: the modification <strong>of</strong> matter, which then leads to a more efficient<br />

modification <strong>of</strong> more matter. This is a redundant concept. <strong>The</strong>re was no need for Marx to<br />

include the produced means <strong>of</strong> production in the analogy.<br />

In discussing this question it is important to consider why Marx is discussing this at<br />

all. What is the true purpose <strong>of</strong> this discussion relative to Marx’s theories about capitalism?<br />

Marx leads into this topic with a discussion about the social ties <strong>of</strong> labor, and how production<br />

must be a cooperative effort. Marx is looking at how capitalism affects the human social<br />

structure, and how the social structure is tied to the production <strong>of</strong> use-values. He then takes<br />

the opportunity to discuss how production <strong>of</strong> use-values is a natural human behavior. <strong>The</strong>se<br />

two human aspects <strong>of</strong> use-value production will be crucial in Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> capitalism,<br />

and its long run survival.<br />

Message [113] referenced by [144]. Next Message by PLG is [195].<br />

[118] Jon: Mother and Father <strong>of</strong> material wealth. I don’t believe that Marx needed<br />

to add produced means to this statement. If you read footnote 13 on page 133 <strong>of</strong> Capital it<br />

says: “All the phenomena <strong>of</strong> the universe, whether produced by the hand <strong>of</strong> man or indeed<br />

by universal laws <strong>of</strong> physics, are not to be conceived <strong>of</strong> as acts <strong>of</strong> creation but solely as a<br />

reordering <strong>of</strong> matter.” When using this explanation <strong>of</strong> production it is labor that reorders<br />

the matter that is created by mother nature to produce a product with use-value. Regardless<br />

if a laborer uses some<strong>thing</strong> that was previously produced such as the linen in the making<br />

<strong>of</strong> a coat, the laborer is still simply rearranging the linen that was previously rearranged<br />

from mother nature. This means that there are steps in production but we must still see that<br />

the original means <strong>of</strong> production come from mother nature and it is through labor that it is<br />

changed from raw materials into products with value.<br />

Message [118] referenced by [144] and [1110]. Next Message by Jon is [202].<br />

[121] Cmellen: graded B No, it is not necessary for Marx to have included produced<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production to nature and labor. If you want to use the analogy <strong>of</strong> labor being the<br />

father and natural forces being mother, then production would be the <strong>of</strong>fspring, or child.<br />

Nature grants the raw materials needed; labor takes action upon those materials along with<br />

natural forces (labor is assisted by natural forces). We merely change the form <strong>of</strong> the matter<br />

created in nature with labor and natural forces. Production is the transformation <strong>of</strong> matter.<br />

Marx states labor is necessary to mediate between man and nature, (human life). Also it is<br />

pointed out that a solitary man cannot produce. “Production requires skill and the produced<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production” (annotation). <strong>The</strong>refore produced means <strong>of</strong> production is not included<br />

with nature and labor. Remember, as labor forms use-value, it is a necessary circumstance<br />

in human life.<br />

Message [121] referenced by [144]. Next Message by Cmellen is [222].<br />

[144] Hans: Producing with your bare hands. PLG [113] writes:<br />

104 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

To include produced means <strong>of</strong> production would be to include a repetitive<br />

step, such as; the modification <strong>of</strong> matter, which then leads to a more efficient<br />

modification <strong>of</strong> more matter.<br />

This evokes the idea <strong>of</strong> producer A producing means <strong>of</strong> production with his bare hands,<br />

just using labor and the earth, and then giving these means <strong>of</strong> production to producer B who<br />

uses them to make his own production process more efficient. “More efficient” than what?<br />

Producer B apparently previously was producing with his bare hands also. But this is not<br />

what is happening! You cannot find a single production process where people produce with<br />

their bare hands without produced means <strong>of</strong> production. On the contrary, the closer you are<br />

to the earth itself, the less bare-handed the production process gets. Just think about the huge<br />

trucks and sophisticated chemical facilities <strong>of</strong> Kennecott. Isn’t that a relevant enough fact<br />

about production that Marx should have mentioned it instead <strong>of</strong> ignoring it?<br />

Jon [118] uses the fact that labor does not produce some<strong>thing</strong> new but only rearranges<br />

what is already there. If you go further into an analysis what the production process actually<br />

does you will see that labor can only rearrange matter by applying matter to matter according<br />

to the laws <strong>of</strong> physics (or chemistry or biology or zoology) itself. I.e., the “bare hands”<br />

cannot do any<strong>thing</strong> as long as they are really bare. <strong>The</strong> only way we can produce some<strong>thing</strong><br />

without means <strong>of</strong> production is to use our own bodies as means <strong>of</strong> production, i.e., as physical<br />

objects acting through the laws <strong>of</strong> physics on other materials. I.e., if we don’t seem to use<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production this is only because the means <strong>of</strong> production are attached to our own<br />

bodies, they are is our fingernails or our teeth etc. I think this strenghens the case against<br />

leaving out the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Besides echoing Jon’s point, Cmellen [121] quotes the Annotations: “Production requires<br />

skill and the produced means <strong>of</strong> production.” From this Cmellen concludes that “produced<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production is not included with nature and labor.” I don’t understand the argument.<br />

If it is true that production requires skill (which is simply a produced intellectual means <strong>of</strong><br />

production) and also produced physical means <strong>of</strong> production, then it seems to me that they<br />

exactly should be included with nature and labor.<br />

Frankly I think Marx blundered here: he should have criticized Petty for not including the<br />

produced means <strong>of</strong> production into his metaphor. And none <strong>of</strong> your arguments convinced<br />

me otherwise. [2004fa:35] gives more reasons why one should not omit this fact when<br />

talking about capitalism. <strong>The</strong> capitalists’ control over the produced means <strong>of</strong> production is<br />

so crippling for the working class exactly because no production is possible just with labor<br />

and nature.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [149].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 132 is 54 in 1995WI, 63 in 1995ut, 67 in 1996sp, 71 in 1997WI, 80 in<br />

1999SP, 85 in 2000fa, 106 in 2004fa, 107 in 2005fa, 152 in 2011fa, and 151 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 132 Is labor the only source <strong>of</strong> the use-values <strong>of</strong> its products, or do other<br />

factors contribute to the use-values as well? Is labor the only source <strong>of</strong> the values <strong>of</strong> its<br />

products, or do other factors contribute to the values as well? (“Value” is here the property<br />

which makes <strong>thing</strong>s exchangeable.)


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 105<br />

[294] Goldtone: graded A+ Creating a Door Without Wood. Labor is not the only<br />

source <strong>of</strong> use-value <strong>of</strong> a product, because nature or matter is also a source. Akudiya [2004fa:205]<br />

gives a perfect example <strong>of</strong> this when she says “when someone is making a door, they craft<br />

a piece <strong>of</strong> wood. If use-value was only created by labor, then the laborer would not even<br />

need the piece <strong>of</strong> wood to make a door.” She goes on to clarify this point “the commodity<br />

is some<strong>thing</strong> that has specific characteristics inside it. Use-values are merely activated by<br />

labor, never created.” Which I think is a good answer to the <strong>first</strong> question.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second question, asking if labor is the only source <strong>of</strong> value (not use-value), is different.<br />

Akudiya does not answer this, but Hans [2004fa:207] does. Hans states that “Here<br />

the answer is just the opposite: labor is indeed the only source <strong>of</strong> the value in the commodities.<br />

Nature does not create value.” Value is a social property, and only created by workers<br />

wanting to exchange their commodities, not by nature.<br />

Hans: Excellent! I love your very last sentence. This is a fresh and insightful formulation <strong>of</strong> the same old idea,<br />

not copied from anywhere in the Annotations or the vast archives, as far as I can tell.<br />

Message [294] referenced by [2011fa:29] and [2012fa:324.1]. Next Message by Goldtone is [343].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 139 is 57 in 1995WI, 66 in 1995ut, 70 in 1996sp, 75 in 1997WI, 84 in<br />

1999SP, 89 in 2001fa, 99 in 2003fa, 159 in 2011fa, and 158 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 139 What is abstract human labor? I want you to say what it is, not what<br />

its significance is in commodity-producing society! <strong>The</strong>se are two different questions.<br />

[292] Kleenex: Is dangerous labor abstract too? It has been repeated in the Annotations/Marx’s<br />

text that at the root <strong>of</strong> value is “human labor in the abstract” in commodity<br />

production. Both the linen weaver and the coat tailor, to use examples from the text, expend<br />

human labor-power. My question is, are relatively more dangerous jobs, such as the duties<br />

<strong>of</strong> soldier or a miner, considered more “valuable” or even any different than less dangerous<br />

jobs, such as the duties <strong>of</strong> a salesman? Again, I understand that they all have congealed<br />

human labor in common, but if there is little or no differentiation by society between the<br />

soldier and the salesman, what incentive is there to have a more dangerous job?<br />

Hans: When Marx wrote that concrete labor processes are qualitatively different from each other, this is perhaps<br />

nowhere clearer than with dangerous jobs. A dangerous job is clearly qualitatively different than a non-dangerous<br />

job. A commodity economy turns these qualitative differences into quantitative differences, i.e., this labor produces<br />

more value per hour than a non-dangerous job and it pays a little higher wages too. And people adjust to it.<br />

Regarding mining jobs, I found the documentary “Bonecrusher” interesting which is available as DVD in the<br />

Marriott Library. People like the mining jobs despite the danger and despite the fact that everyone has relatives<br />

killed in the mine, because these are decent Union wages, not hunger wages (at least in the East), and the workers<br />

like the comraderie and cooperation on and <strong>of</strong>f the workplace which arises exactly because the job is so dangerous.<br />

Next Message by Kleenex is [360].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 141 is 59 in 1995WI, 68 in 1995ut, 72 in 1996sp, 71 in 1996ut, 77 in<br />

1997WI, 79 in 1997sp, 74 in 1997ut, 80 in 1998WI, 86 in 1999SP, 98 in 2002fa, 114 in<br />

2004fa, 115 in 2005fa, 128 in 2007SP, 132 in 2008fa, 161 in 2011fa, and 160 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 141 What is the difference between labor and labor-power?<br />

[111] LuBr: Distinguishing between labor and labor-power. Marx, in his labor theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> value, tries to find a common substance that would determine the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

Commodities do not have exchange value in common, for any commodity may be exchanged<br />

106 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

at varying quantitative levels for one another. It is after all just a “form <strong>of</strong> appearance.” Commodities<br />

also lack commonality in use-value, as the only reason that commodities would be<br />

exchanged is if their use-values were qualitatively different. Marx says this common substance<br />

must be some<strong>thing</strong> social and not natural.<br />

What then, does Marx conclude to be the only property left that all commodities share<br />

in common? <strong>The</strong> labor embodied within commodities. This labor can be useful labor, in<br />

other words, labor that contributes to the useful aspects <strong>of</strong> commodities. This can be seen as<br />

qualitative differences in labor expended, be it by a mason, a carpenter, or a weaver. However,<br />

the market ultimately abstracts the types and forms <strong>of</strong> labor producing use-value, and<br />

turns labor into a single mass <strong>of</strong> abstract labor in which all labor is created equal. <strong>The</strong>refore<br />

in Marx’s quest to find a common substance from which value can be derived, he must dig<br />

deeper than useful labor.<br />

This brings us to labor-power. Marx describes that all humans have within them a potential<br />

labor-power, from which all labors derive. Labor-power pays no mind to how and<br />

by what form the commodities were produced. This equalizes labor and allows Marx to<br />

determine the magnitude <strong>of</strong> a commodity’s value by measuring the amount <strong>of</strong> labor-power<br />

congealed within the commodity. Labor-power <strong>of</strong> all kinds is reduced down to the “measuring<br />

stick” <strong>of</strong> basic labor-power.<br />

Hans: In your <strong>first</strong> paragraph you say: “commodities do not have exchange-value in common.” Yes they do,<br />

all commmodities are exchangeable. This is some<strong>thing</strong> they have in common. But if someone asks: what do<br />

commodities have in common that makes them exchangeable, then the answer “they have in common that they are<br />

exchangeable” is circular. We need a different, underlying commonality.<br />

But I absolutely love what you say next: “Commodities also lack commonality in use-value, as the only reason<br />

that commodities would be exchanged is if their use-values were qualitatively different.” This is an amazingly<br />

simple interpretation <strong>of</strong> what Marx might have meant when he said “exchange relations are characterized by an<br />

abstraction from use-value.” I will take that over into my Annotations.<br />

This is an ungraded exam question because it has a simple answer which everybody needs to know in order<br />

to understand Marx properly. This answer is formulated for instance in [2004fa:184]. But you are going way<br />

beyond that, you gave an excellent summary <strong>of</strong> Marx’s entire argument that led him to introduce the condept <strong>of</strong><br />

labor-power. <strong>The</strong>refore you will get a grade for your answer.<br />

Next Message by LuBr is [170].<br />

[293] SMIKEC: Exam Extra Credit. Labor is simply the capacity to do useful work<br />

which adds value to commodities. It’s the vehicle that transforms commodities into forms<br />

that can be exchanged. Labor Power is a means for the capitalist to create a timeline for<br />

the utilization <strong>of</strong> labor. <strong>The</strong> capitalist pays the worker just enough to reproduce him/herself,<br />

food, shelter, etc, to ensure that he can show up for work the following week, along with<br />

having time to replicate the work force by raising their children. This is a carefully thought<br />

out equation to ensure the worker is in the labor force long enough to produce more value.<br />

This is where surplus value comes into play, and is the biggest distinction between labor and<br />

labor power.<br />

Hans: About your <strong>first</strong> sentence: the “capacity to do useful work” is not the definition <strong>of</strong> labor but <strong>of</strong> labor-power.<br />

Labor is the useful work itself, not just the capacity for it. What you are calling a “carefully thought out equation<br />

to ensure the worker is in the labor force long enough to produce more value” is simply labor-power becoming a<br />

commodity and falling under the laws <strong>of</strong> commodities, i.e., labor-power being paid its reproduction cost. This will<br />

be discussed in chapter Six.<br />

Next Message by SMIKEC is [401].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 107<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 147 is 76 in 1997ut, 131 in 2007SP, and 134 in 2007fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 147 Is Marx’s appeal to experience regarding the reduction <strong>of</strong> complicated to<br />

simple labor a circular argument?<br />

[182] Kaush: Marx’s appeal to experience regarding the reduction. <strong>The</strong> experience<br />

here, that markets, which pretend that all labor-powers are equal and different quantitatively,<br />

succeed despite the fact <strong>of</strong> the qualitative differences among labor-powers. Marx’s appeal<br />

to experience is a realization that there is no general law to govern this reduction from<br />

complicated to simple labor and the realization that markets survived.<br />

<strong>The</strong> argument is circular in that Marx answers the premise regarding “the reduction <strong>of</strong><br />

complicated to simple labor” by pointing to the success in the market instead <strong>of</strong> proving why<br />

the market succeeded despite the qualitative differences among labor-powers. So Marx’s<br />

argument is a circular one since it is using the conclusion (the markets survived) to answer<br />

the premise (the reduction <strong>of</strong> complicated to simple labor).<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> labor power <strong>of</strong> great artists or athletes is qualitatively different from society’s average labor power—<br />

yet their products are sold for money like everybody else’s. How much commodity-value do they create with their<br />

performances? Marx says this cannot be known because there is no systematic way to reduce their qualitatively<br />

different labor-powers to average human labor. <strong>The</strong>refore there is no competitive mechanism driving the prices at<br />

which they sell their products to some “natural” level; rather it is determined by demand and supply. This does not<br />

bring the economy down to its knees because they are a small part <strong>of</strong> the economy and we are rich enough so that<br />

we can afford it if a small part <strong>of</strong> society’s pool <strong>of</strong> abstract labor is perhap mis-allocated.<br />

I am not aware <strong>of</strong> any research asking why markets work despite not being a 100 percent accurate surface<br />

representation <strong>of</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong> the capitalist production process. It may be too difficult given the present state <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> society. Not doing this research does not mean that the argument is circular.<br />

Such discrepancies exist in engineering as well. Every internal combustion engine vibrates because the force<br />

exerted by the pistons on the crankshaft are determined by the chemistry <strong>of</strong> combustion and are only approximately<br />

what a steady turning motion needs.<br />

Next Message by Kaush is [203].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 148 is 135 in 2007fa and 144 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 148 Just as a horse has muscles and bones in it, a commodity has useful labor<br />

and abstract labor in it. Explain. Is this also true for a product which is not a commodity?<br />

[124] Husani: Useful and Abstract Labor. To thoroughly explain why a commodity<br />

has both useful labor and abstract labor we must know the difference between the two<br />

and how they contribute to the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity. First we look at what Marx says on<br />

page 132:2 about useful labor: “We use the abbreviated expression ”useful labor“ for labour<br />

whose utility is represented by the use-value <strong>of</strong> the product, or by the fact that its product is<br />

a use-value.” This tells us that every use-value is created using useful labor. We then look<br />

at page 132:3 to see why we need abstract labor: “If the use-values were not qualitatively<br />

different, hence not the products <strong>of</strong> qualitatively different forms <strong>of</strong> useful labor, they would<br />

be absolutely incapable <strong>of</strong> confronting each other as commodities.” This statement shows<br />

us that useful labor is not enough to deteremine the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity when compared<br />

with other commodities because the type <strong>of</strong> labor is fundamentally different. <strong>The</strong> labor used<br />

to create a computer program is fundamentally different from the labor needed to created a<br />

textbook. We now look at page 70 from the annotation in which Hans gives the definition <strong>of</strong><br />

108 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

abstract labor, “Equality <strong>of</strong> entirely different kinds <strong>of</strong> labor can be arrived at only by an abstraction<br />

from their real inequality, by a reduction to the characteristic they have in common,<br />

that <strong>of</strong> being human labor in the abstract.” This states that abstract labor is the reduction <strong>of</strong><br />

human labor in all forms, although they are different, to an equality that represents human<br />

brains, nerves and muscle in the form <strong>of</strong> human labor.<br />

All commodities have both useful labor and abstract labor. Useful labor is present because<br />

it is the labor that makes the commodity a use-value. Abstract labor is present because it is<br />

a way to give a commodity value when compared to other commodities that were created<br />

using a different types <strong>of</strong> labor than itself.<br />

I don’t believe this would be true for products that aren’t commodities. Marx says that a<br />

product created for personal use isn’t a commodity. So if someone created a coat to use for<br />

themselves, it would have a useful value built into because it is a use-value to its creator—but<br />

because he isn’t looking to exchange the coat it wouldn’t have abstract labor in it.<br />

Hans: Let me clarify what you say in your last paragraph. <strong>The</strong> coat made for home consumption still has the<br />

useful labor in it—not as labor, but instead the coat shows the effects <strong>of</strong> this labor by its usefulness as a coat. <strong>The</strong><br />

maker <strong>of</strong> the coat also used his brain, muscles, etc. to make the coat, but this abstract labor has been consumed<br />

and is no longer present—neither in the coat nor anywhere else. Had the coat been produced as a commodity, then<br />

this abstract labor would still linger on in the coat. It would be visible in the price <strong>of</strong> the coat, and if the tailor<br />

exchanges the coat for linen, then he has retrieved his abstract labor back out <strong>of</strong> the coat and converted it into labor<br />

that produced some<strong>thing</strong> useful for him, namely, linen.<br />

Next Message by Husani is [230].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 150 is 133 in 2007SP and 170 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 150 Since productivity is a quality <strong>of</strong> useful labor, one might not expect it to play<br />

a great role in capitalism. But it does. Why?<br />

[143] Milly: Productivity in capitalism. At <strong>first</strong> glance, one would not expect productivity<br />

to play a major role in capitalism. <strong>The</strong> more efficient a commodity can be produced,<br />

results directly in a decrease <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> that commodity because it takes less labor or<br />

effort to produce. However, even though a product is being sold for less, when companies<br />

become more efficient and technologically advanced, they are able to produce more product<br />

at a faster rate and increase pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

In [2007SP:100], Tokolosh answers this question and gives an example <strong>of</strong> Capitalist A<br />

and B. Capitalist A produces a widget faster than Capitalist B and therefore is able to lower<br />

price and produce more product. In response to Tokolosh, Hans asks “since capitalists are<br />

interested in pr<strong>of</strong>its, i.e., more surplus-value for themselves, why are they trying so hard to<br />

decrease the values <strong>of</strong> their products?”<br />

<strong>The</strong> focus <strong>of</strong> a capitalist is not to decrease the value <strong>of</strong> their product, that just happens to<br />

be the end result <strong>of</strong> increased productivity. As long as the quality <strong>of</strong> the product remains the<br />

same, higher efficiency will lead to an increase in the quantity produced, which will result in<br />

more surplus-value. This increase in production outweighs the cons <strong>of</strong> a decrease in product<br />

value.<br />

Next Message by Milly is [172].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 109<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 155 is 86 in 1998WI, 93 in 1999SP, 98 in 2000fa, 98 in 2001fa, 138 in 2007SP,<br />

141 in 2007fa, 145 in 2008SP, 143 in 2008fa, 150 in 2009fa, and 174 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 155 If the <strong>first</strong> chapter is such a systematic discussion <strong>of</strong> value, why is it then<br />

called “Commodities” and not “Value”?<br />

[156] Somramthom: graded C Value in Commodities. Commodities are tangible <strong>thing</strong>s<br />

that improve human life. Value is an intangible, yet noticeable, social relation from the use<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity. A value cannot exist without a commodity. It is difficult to understand<br />

the social effect <strong>of</strong> a commodity without understanding what the commodity is. So while<br />

value is the main subject <strong>of</strong> the <strong>first</strong> chapter, it is easier to understand the tangible aspect <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities <strong>first</strong> and then follow with the more abstract concept <strong>of</strong> Value.<br />

Feedback would be appreciated.<br />

Message [156] referenced by [157], [162], and [179]. Next Message by Somramthom is [288].<br />

[157] Hans: Quick Feedback. Somramthon [156] recognizes correctly that commodities<br />

in our society are connected with each other by an “intangible, yet noticeable, social<br />

relation”. But then he says two entirely wrong <strong>thing</strong>s about commodities:<br />

First <strong>of</strong> all, this social relation (as Marx analyzes it) does not come from the use <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity, as Somramthon says, but from the production <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Secondly, Somramthon’s definition <strong>of</strong> a commodity is wrong too. <strong>The</strong> definition is not<br />

“tangible <strong>thing</strong>s that improve human life” (that is Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> “use-value”) but products<br />

produced for sale or exchange.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se false definitions guarantee that Somramthon will not get a good grade for his answer.<br />

It is one <strong>of</strong> Marx’s basic messages that value does not come from the usefulness <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity, but from labor. As we will see, in Marx’s theory money represents labor hours,<br />

and capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its are produced by the unpaid labor <strong>of</strong> the workers.<br />

Message [157] referenced by [162] and [2012fa:130]. Next Message by Hans is [158].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 158 What is the definition <strong>of</strong> “form <strong>of</strong> value”?<br />

[404] Babyceta: graded A+ When commodities are produced for exchange, they carry<br />

with them the social relations <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong>se relations are invisible and buried deep<br />

within the commodity, and are represented as congealed, abstract human labor. This socially<br />

necessary labor, Marx calls value, cannot surface on its own but must do so in the market<br />

as exchange value. Essentially, this form <strong>of</strong> value is the means in which producers and<br />

consumers entice the value <strong>of</strong> commodities to the surface so that exchange can occur. Hans<br />

states in the Annotations [p. 93] that a form <strong>of</strong> value is a property <strong>of</strong> commodities allowing<br />

them to relate to each other as values.<br />

Marx’s objective in Section 3 (Chapter 1) is to explain the genesis <strong>of</strong> money, and he develops<br />

the simple or accidental form <strong>of</strong> value, <strong>first</strong>, to illustrate how, out <strong>of</strong> barter, money<br />

emerges. When commodities leave the sphere <strong>of</strong> production they contain not only use-value,<br />

exchange-value, and value as determined by labor content, but they also carry a price tag<br />

110 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

and the DNA <strong>of</strong> money itself. Here, the commodity indeed processes dual form (possessing<br />

use-value and exchange-value), and an asymmetric relationship develops between two<br />

commodities; one having relative (active) value, and one equivalent (passive) value.<br />

<strong>The</strong> relationship between commodities becomes more complex when the form <strong>of</strong> value<br />

expands from its simple form to include many commodities. Here, the relative value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>first</strong> commodity, produced solely for exchange to obtain other commodities with different<br />

use-values, expresses itself now in many ways since the commodity with equivalent value<br />

can be virtually any<strong>thing</strong>. However, we then lose the simplicity <strong>of</strong> the accidental exchange<br />

because the expanded form has negated the <strong>first</strong>.<br />

In an effort to negate the negation, the general form <strong>of</strong> value emerges. In the simple<br />

and expanded forms <strong>of</strong> value, commodities <strong>of</strong> relative value expressed themselves in the<br />

use-values <strong>of</strong> other equivalent commodities. However, once commodities are exchanged<br />

for a general equivalent, use-value is no longer considered; only that other commodities<br />

will express themselves in that same general equivalent. [I]n other words, says Hans, the<br />

equivalent commodity can be used to buy all other commodities. [Annotations, p. 158]<br />

Initially, Marx abstracts away money, itself a commodity, to show us why money is necessary.<br />

Not only is money a measure <strong>of</strong> value it is also a form <strong>of</strong> value (as are prices) since<br />

all other commodities can express their value in terms <strong>of</strong> price. Price, which has traveled<br />

incognito with the commodity from the sphere <strong>of</strong> production to the sphere <strong>of</strong> circulation,<br />

now presents itself as a declaration <strong>of</strong> that mysterious social information buried deep in the<br />

commodity; the value <strong>of</strong> that congealed, abstracted human labor found in all commodities.<br />

And, thus, the cycle is complete. In Marx’s words, form <strong>of</strong> value springs from the concept <strong>of</strong><br />

value, and monetized market relations are essentially socialized surface relations signaling<br />

production mandates in a capitalist economy.<br />

Next Message by Babyceta is [411].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 164 In Contribution, 270:1, Marx writes: “Although use-values serve social<br />

needs and therefore exist within a social context, they are not an expression <strong>of</strong> a social<br />

relation <strong>of</strong> production.” Is this correct? For many products, consumers need product information,<br />

instructions how to use it, assistance in setting up the product, warranty services if<br />

the product is defective, and maintenance. Are these not relations <strong>of</strong> production?<br />

[134] Atticus: (graded C) My Things are Mine and Mine Only. Marx claims that physical<br />

possession <strong>of</strong> a commodity, which has a specific use-value, is not in itself a social relation<br />

(Annotation p. 84). I believe this means that the actual physical act <strong>of</strong> possessing an object<br />

is not a social relation; the use-value that an object possesses is the actual social relation<br />

that not just the object’s owner can access. However, possessing particular objects—mainly<br />

commodities—may come with ownership rights, which is a social relation (annotations pp.<br />

84). An object is basically a component <strong>of</strong> modified materials obtained from the earth that<br />

has been modified through useful labor by the natural forces and instincts inherent in human<br />

beings.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 111<br />

I find this to be a persuasive theory and an effective way <strong>of</strong> explaining how to critically<br />

look at the seemingly natural ways that capitalism operates to shape social behavior in human<br />

beings. But I don’t believe I can say whether it’s actually correct or not. It’s definitely a<br />

unique way <strong>of</strong> looking at social behavior. I’m not pro capitalism by any means though. <strong>The</strong><br />

idea <strong>of</strong> people being able to foster their own interests and abilities to their fullest potentials<br />

without a few people exploiting the masses at the expense <strong>of</strong> the environment and human<br />

kind may be the radical change the world needs to stop self destruction.<br />

Some products have become so complex that consumers need information, assistance and<br />

instruction in order to even identify and use a product. This is part <strong>of</strong> the production process<br />

that helps the producer identify for the consumer the use-value embodied in a product. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

are commonly expensive so it’s in the producer’s best interest to provide warranty and maintenance<br />

service to satisfy the needs <strong>of</strong> the consumers and encourage repeat purchases in the<br />

future to maintain pr<strong>of</strong>it and growth. <strong>The</strong>se extra services that are provided with products<br />

are relations to production.<br />

Hans: I don’t understand why you consider use-value to be a social relation. What is social in the use-value <strong>of</strong><br />

a peach to be nutritious and tasty food? It is the relationship between the physical properties <strong>of</strong> the peach and<br />

human needs, treated as if it was some intrinsic property <strong>of</strong> the peach. It is a relationship, say better a one-on-one<br />

interaction, but not a social relation.<br />

I also don’t get what the <strong>thing</strong>s you are saying in the <strong>first</strong> paragraph have to do with the operation <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

If you would clarify this, I’d appreciate it. I sincerely have no idea what you are talking about.<br />

Atticus: In the beginning the texts were extremely difficult for me to fully absorb, digest and understand. I responded<br />

too late to your feedback and I’m not even exactly sure what I meant but what I think went wrong was my<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> the term social relation. Other terms were also difficult for me in the beginning, such as: abstract<br />

labor, use value, exchange value, etc. However, it did become easier and I enjoyed the readings.<br />

Next Message by Atticus is [140].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 166 is 127 in 2004fa, 128 in 2005fa, 151 in 2008fa, 157 in 2009fa, and 996 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 166 If a commodity is only produced because <strong>of</strong> its value, why did Marx not say<br />

that commodities come to the world in the form <strong>of</strong> values?<br />

[131] Utefan: As Marx states a commodity is only a commodity when it has a double<br />

form, a use-value and value form. <strong>The</strong> use-value is their plain form i.e. iron, linen, corn.<br />

<strong>The</strong>ir dual nature makes them a commodity. <strong>The</strong> objectivity <strong>of</strong> commodity deals mainly<br />

with human labor and their value is purely social. Commodity must react socially with other<br />

commodities to describe value. In essence gasoline wouldn’t be as valuable, as a commodity,<br />

if we didn’t have vehicles that used gasoline.<br />

<strong>The</strong> social reaction returns a value that changes within that social realm, as in the above<br />

example gas prices fluctuate and are different in other socially different climates.<br />

Message [131] referenced by [137], [154], [179], and [216]. Next Message by Utefan is [132].<br />

[137] Hans: Terminological clarifications. Utefan [131] seems to say the right <strong>thing</strong>s<br />

until he illustrates his abstract formulations as follows:<br />

In essence gasoline wouldn’t be as valuable, as a commodity, if we didn’t<br />

have vehicles that used gasoline.<br />

112 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Here the word “valuable” refers to use-value. This is not what Marx means. When he<br />

talks about “value” (without “use-” in front <strong>of</strong> it), he means the congealed abstract labor in<br />

the product, which makes <strong>thing</strong>s exchangeable on the market. Also please remember that the<br />

word “commodity” does not just denote any use-value, but the use-values produced for sale.<br />

<strong>The</strong> statement “a commodity is produced for its value” means therefore: the purpose which<br />

a commodity producer has in mind when he produces a commodity is to sell the commodity<br />

on the market, not to use it himself.<br />

Finally, people who need this clarification should not try to answer question 166. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

should <strong>first</strong> try to understand what Marx did say, before guessing why he did not say some<strong>thing</strong><br />

else.<br />

Message [137] referenced by [145], [154], and [216]. Next Message by Hans is [138].<br />

[154] Goldtone: graded A Commodities in the Form <strong>of</strong> Value. Marx did not say that<br />

commodities come to the world in the form <strong>of</strong> values because “value”, according to Marx,<br />

is only realized when the commodity is exchanged for some other use-value. Hans explains<br />

this in [149] while talking about a linen maker exchanging 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen for a coat. <strong>The</strong><br />

linen is an expression <strong>of</strong> value to the linen maker, and the coat is an expression <strong>of</strong> use-value.<br />

<strong>The</strong> opposite would be true for the coat maker making this trade.<br />

To elaborate, (and similar to what Hans wrote in pages 83-84 in the annotations), the<br />

direct benefit <strong>of</strong> use-value can come from physical possession alone, whereas value can only<br />

come from a social relation. Hence, an individual can consume / use a commodity that they<br />

have made themselves, and bypass any kind <strong>of</strong> “value” according to Marx. Hans clarifies<br />

this in his response to Utefan [131] in [137]: “<strong>The</strong> statement ‘a commodity is produced<br />

for its value’ means therefore: the purpose which a commodity producer has in mind when<br />

he produces a commodity is to sell the commodity on the market, not to use it himself.”<br />

This is not always the case, when in fact people do use commodities they have made for<br />

themselves, give commodities away to others, and have commodities stolen. In each <strong>of</strong><br />

these cases “value” is not necessarily present, because the commodity was not exchanged.<br />

Hans: It would be wonderful if a commodity’s value disappeared the minute it gets stolen. <strong>The</strong>n we all could leave<br />

our doors unlocked. (Other than this, what you say is correct.)<br />

Message [154] referenced by [2012fa:124] and [2012fa:159]. Next Message by Goldtone is [294].<br />

[297] Kaush: Commodities come to the world. A commodity is use value immediately<br />

after its birth, because that is the purpose <strong>of</strong> its production. It is value too because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

social abstract labor embedded in it. But that does not mean the commodity has an exchange<br />

value. Because <strong>of</strong> that, one cannot say that commodities come to the world in the form <strong>of</strong><br />

values.<br />

Message [297] referenced by [316] and [555]. Next Message by Kaush is [436].<br />

[316] Hans: A simple barter exchange-value is not good enough. Kaush [297] said<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s so neatly and concisely that this clears the ground for fresh perspectives. When I read<br />

it I thought: is it true that commodities don’t have an exchange-value when they come out<br />

<strong>of</strong> the production process? I confirmed this as true when Winn said it in [2009fa:276], but<br />

right now I no longer think it is true.<br />

If the linen weaver announces to others in the market: “20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is worth 1 coat”,<br />

she does not really give her linen an exchange-value. She wishes she could do this, but she<br />

does not have this much power. All she does is guess what this exchange-value is and test


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 113<br />

her guess by making an <strong>of</strong>fer based on this guess. But if she has to guess the exchange-value<br />

this means the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> the linen exists out there already.<br />

<strong>The</strong> problem is therefore not that the commodity lacks an exchange-value, but that a<br />

direct-barter exchange-value is too primitive, it is not sophisticated enough. In a developed<br />

commodity economy one will quickly discover that one cannot get far with direct barter.<br />

Money is necessary. Marx discusses this in 182:1 where he describes the historical instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> the “logical” development. <strong>The</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> money and prices is the value form which<br />

the commodies need. This value form is not automatically given with the production <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity, but the establishment <strong>of</strong> money is a social act taking place in circulation.<br />

Now after the establishment <strong>of</strong> money we must conclude, by the same argument as above,<br />

that commodities have prices already when they come out <strong>of</strong> the production process. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

truly have a double form, the physical <strong>thing</strong> on the one hand and the price tag on the other.<br />

But this second form is no longer home-grown; the entire economy takes part in its creation.<br />

This is why Marx says the production process only produces the use-value form, and the<br />

value-form comes afterwards. In 184:3/oo Marx says the money commodity gets it value in<br />

production and its specific form <strong>of</strong> value in circulation, and I think he would also say that<br />

the price forms <strong>of</strong> ordinary commodities is generated in circulation too.<br />

Message [316] referenced by [336], [375], [528], [555], and [2012fa:124]. Next Message by Hans is [318].<br />

[336] AlexDaily: graded B+ Commodities have two types <strong>of</strong> value; exchange value and<br />

use value. Commodities are made because <strong>of</strong> their exchange value. But society gives the<br />

commodities their value. <strong>The</strong>refore, Marx could not say commodities come to the world in<br />

the form <strong>of</strong> values.<br />

Hans: Value comes from labor, i.e., value is created in the production process. Value is a social relation, but<br />

society does not just pluck the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity out <strong>of</strong> thin air; it bases it on the abstract human labor in the<br />

commodity. This is why your sentence “society gives the commodities their value” is wrong. On the other hand,<br />

as I tried to explain in [316], society at large plays a much bigger role in the exchange-value. I would not go as far<br />

as saying that society gives the commodities their exchange-value, but I think one can say that exchange-value is<br />

not only generated in the production process. That is why Marx did not say commodities come to the world in the<br />

form <strong>of</strong> values.<br />

Message [336] referenced by [468]. Next Message by AlexDaily is [356].<br />

[360] Kleenex: Marx writes that commodities come into the world, not in the form <strong>of</strong><br />

values, but in the form <strong>of</strong> use-values. It is true that the commodity possesses value from the<br />

production process. It is also obvious what the use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is when you’re<br />

examining it. However, the producer does not yet know what the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

is until it “surfaces” in the market. <strong>The</strong> producer is familiar with the labor that went into<br />

creating this commodity, but does not yet know the price tag, or what another person is<br />

willing to trade for it. Once the commodity does emerge into the market, the value-form<br />

becomes evident. As Thugtorious wrote in [2005fa:748], “the commodities are not values<br />

until they are put into relations with other commodities.” Marx also uses the analogy <strong>of</strong> a<br />

newborn baby to illustrate his point. When a baby is <strong>first</strong> born, it is unaware <strong>of</strong> its social<br />

surroundings and needs, other than being fed and loved, at the most basic level. When the<br />

baby grows up, though, it develops relationships with others and learns its value and place<br />

in the world, just as a commodity finds its exchange-value once it “grows up” and emerges<br />

on the surface <strong>of</strong> the market.<br />

Next Message by Kleenex is [365].<br />

114 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[375] KA: If a commodity is only produced because <strong>of</strong> its value, why did Marx not say<br />

that commodities come to the world in the form <strong>of</strong> values?<br />

A commodity comes into the world and is produced for its use-value; the production process<br />

gives this commodity its use-value. This use-value enables the commodity owner to<br />

exchange it for another commodity that is useful to him. <strong>The</strong>refore, the use form allows the<br />

commodity owner to take advantage <strong>of</strong> its use. On the other hand, when Marx discusses<br />

“value,” this is a different concept than use-value. Value form enables the commodity owner<br />

to take advantage <strong>of</strong> what value the commodity brings to the table. While the commodity’s<br />

use-value presents an opportunity to gain “value,” the commodity has a two-fold form <strong>of</strong><br />

value, “its bodily form and its value form.” A further emphasis must be made on what commodities<br />

come into the world as. If a commodity does come into the world and undergo<br />

a form <strong>of</strong> production its value may never be derived, since “value” is determined on “congealed<br />

abstract labor.” This is why Marx did not say that commodities come into the world<br />

in the form <strong>of</strong> values; his definition <strong>of</strong> values has a two-fold explanation.<br />

Hans: If it is true that a commodity’s use-value “enables the commodity owner to exchange it for another commodity<br />

that is useful to him,” then the commodity does not need a value-form. Read my [316].<br />

Next Message by KA is [380].<br />

[415] Lana: This question can be addressed with the relationship between wood and a<br />

finished table. Man used the wood to create the table and I as a consumer, purchase the table<br />

to put in my home. <strong>The</strong>refore, the wood has value to the Man and use-value to me. <strong>The</strong> Man<br />

must create the table from the wood in order to have some<strong>thing</strong> to exchange for his desired<br />

use-values. A chunk <strong>of</strong> wood would hold no value to me because I do not possess the skills<br />

or desire to work with it and create a table. As is such, I would purchase the table, satisfying<br />

my needs/wants. Contrastingly, the finished table holds no use-value for the Man because<br />

he does not need/want the table, but he does want to exchange it. This relationship between<br />

commodities, human labor and their value, is a social interaction.<br />

Next Message by Lana is [416].<br />

[505] Tunda: Marx did not say that commodities come to the world in the form <strong>of</strong> values<br />

because he concluded that there was a double form <strong>of</strong> a commodity to have a bodily form<br />

and a value form in order for that commodity to have worth. <strong>The</strong>re is a use-value and value<br />

and in order for a commodity to enter the world it has to gain those two forms <strong>of</strong> commodity.<br />

Next Message by Tunda is [506].<br />

[510] Cougar: content A+ late penalty 1% After reviewing submissions <strong>of</strong> students and<br />

Hans’ feedback, I have come to the conclusion that it is through circulation in the market<br />

that freshly-produced commodities establish exchange-value and not through their production<br />

alone. Because <strong>of</strong> the social nature <strong>of</strong> value, commodities and more specifically their<br />

circulation through the market reveal important relationships among producers, their competitors<br />

and consumers. Taking from the example used by Hans, the linen weaver cannot<br />

adequately predict the socially accepted value <strong>of</strong> “x” yards <strong>of</strong> linen as it relates to other<br />

commodities the weaver requires. <strong>The</strong> socially accepted value <strong>of</strong> linen is established in both<br />

its market production and circulation through various social transactions. Where barter is<br />

too primitive a method to measure these relationships, limited by the highly relative nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> the expanded form <strong>of</strong> value, money provides a standardized method <strong>of</strong> measuring<br />

the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities, from production to consumption. Once socially accepted


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 115<br />

commodity values are established among producers in the market, “price” provides a bridge<br />

between the labor content <strong>of</strong> those commodities (unknown to consumers) and their associated<br />

use-values (known and desired by consumers). This delay, in which commodity values<br />

are established through circulation in the market after production, provides the perspective<br />

that value is established through social interactions and not labor content alone.<br />

Hans: Your formulation is still a little too fuzzy. According to Marx, value is established by abstract labor alone<br />

(which itself is some<strong>thing</strong> social), but it manifests itself on the market by the exchange relations.<br />

Next Message by Cougar is [573].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 174 is 86 in 1997WI, 85 in 1997ut, 92 in 1998WI, 115 in 2002fa, 118 in 2003fa,<br />

133 in 2004fa, and 134 in 2005fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 174 How does Marx’s statement in 138:2/o that a commodity’s value quasimaterial<br />

“does not contain a single atom <strong>of</strong> physical matter” relate to his other statement<br />

in 177:3–4 that “no chemist has ever discovered exchange-value in pearl or diamond.” Do<br />

they say the same <strong>thing</strong> or some<strong>thing</strong> different?<br />

[133] Bigwhite: Atoms and Chemists. I think both statements say the same <strong>thing</strong>. <strong>The</strong><br />

<strong>first</strong> statement goes along with what Marx has said previously that the value quasi material is<br />

like a human’s soul: it is there, it adds value, yet it is not physically tangible. He also refers<br />

to it as a ghost <strong>of</strong> the commodity. <strong>The</strong> value quasi material is embedded in the commodity<br />

through the production or birth <strong>of</strong> the commodity. <strong>The</strong>re is no way to measure it for each<br />

individual commodity but it’s there.<br />

Same goes with the chemist statement. <strong>The</strong>re is no physical <strong>thing</strong> in a pearl or diamond<br />

that justifies its trade value, they are valuable because people want and desire them. In reality<br />

no one needs a diamond like they need water yet water is cheap and diamonds fetch a high<br />

price. <strong>The</strong>re is no<strong>thing</strong> physically in the diamond that makes it more valuable than water yet<br />

its exchange value is higher.<br />

Final Grading Note by Hans: <strong>The</strong>re is evidence in your answers that you are doing the readings fairly carefully,<br />

but nevertheless again and again you miss some important parts <strong>of</strong> Marx’s argument. Here you are good about the<br />

subtleties <strong>of</strong> value quasi-material but you miss (or have forgotten again) that according to Marx, value comes from<br />

labor and not from people’s wants. I am puzzled by this inconsistency. Maybe JJ’s experience recounted in [1173]<br />

speaks to you.<br />

Message [133] referenced by [136], [139], and [179]. Next Message by Bigwhite is [321].<br />

[136] Hans: Desire does not create value. Bigwhite [133] says: “pearl or diamond ...<br />

are valuable because people want and desire them.” This is mainstream economics but not<br />

Marx’s theory. If Marx’s theory is right, then pearl or diamond are valuable because labor<br />

was needed for their production. <strong>The</strong> labor that produced them is still visible in their price<br />

tag. <strong>The</strong> <strong>thing</strong> that Marx calls value quasi-material is this past labor, it is what the price tag<br />

measures. It is not concrete labor but what Marx calls “abstract” labor; think <strong>of</strong> it as the<br />

opportunity cost <strong>of</strong> the labor which was used to produce pearl or diamond but which could<br />

also have produced different <strong>thing</strong>s.<br />

I hope this clarified the question. A detailed analysis how the two statements in the<br />

question are related is in my [2003fa:98].<br />

Message [136] referenced by [430]. Next Message by Hans is [137].<br />

116 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[139] Oreo: graded A Invisible exchange-value. I believe that both <strong>of</strong> these statements<br />

say the same <strong>thing</strong>. <strong>The</strong>y each illustrate exchange-value as some<strong>thing</strong> that can’t physically<br />

be found in the commodity. Marx states at the end <strong>of</strong> the chapter that it was economists,<br />

rather than chemists, who discovered exchange value. This is because chemists study the<br />

physical properties <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s, while economists are known to focus on the abstract, which in<br />

this case in the exchange-value.<br />

I understand where Bigwhite [133] is coming from when he says that commodities, such<br />

as pearls and diamonds, are valuable because people want them. According to the supply and<br />

demand models that we have become so familiar with in our basic economics classes, this<br />

is a perfectly logical conclusion. However, as Hans points out, Marx believes that value is<br />

based on the amount <strong>of</strong> labor put into a commodity, rather than the desires for it. <strong>The</strong> reason<br />

that a diamond is more valuable than water, according to Marx, is because the diamond<br />

contains a greater amount <strong>of</strong> congealed human labor within it. <strong>The</strong> miners who acquire<br />

diamonds spend an extensive amount <strong>of</strong> time seeking and obtaining them, while water is<br />

discovered and collected using much less labor time.<br />

This congealed human labor, as Marx tells us through both <strong>of</strong> the aforementioned statements,<br />

is not physically detectable in the commodity. <strong>The</strong>refore, it is impossible to determine<br />

the actual exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity just by looking at it. To determine an exchangevalue,<br />

you must know the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that went into it.<br />

While I understand Marx’s point <strong>of</strong> view, I don’t think that it is applicable in every situation.<br />

For example, a CD from a popular band is priced a lot higher than a CD from an<br />

emerging/unknown band. So even if each <strong>of</strong> the artists used the same amount <strong>of</strong> labor, the<br />

better-known artist’s CD would have a higher exchange-value than the less popular one.<br />

Another example is clo<strong>thing</strong>. Brand named jeans are much more expensive than jeans purchased<br />

at Wal-Mart, even though they likely contain the same amount <strong>of</strong> congealed human<br />

labor. Aren’t the brand-name jeans priced higher because the desire for them is greater than<br />

Wal-Mart jeans? I have trouble siding with Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> exchange-value, and am leaning<br />

more towards Bigwhite’s view <strong>of</strong> desire determining exchange-value. Any thoughts?<br />

Next Message by Oreo is [197].<br />

[159] TINDOZ: Value is not molecular. Marx’s two statements about the physical matter<br />

<strong>of</strong> an atom-less commodity’s value quasi-material and the exchange-value being undiscoverable<br />

by a chemist go hand in hand in saying basically the same <strong>thing</strong> (with each statement<br />

backing up the other). <strong>The</strong>se two statements relate to each other (in relation to commodities)<br />

from two distinct aspects, one being value and the other being exchange-value with<br />

the commonality between the two being a sense <strong>of</strong> intangibility (at least in the physical<br />

world) to these two forms <strong>of</strong> value. He speaks <strong>of</strong> atoms and references the work <strong>of</strong> chemists<br />

(who would look at an item on the molecular level) to show how physicality (no matter how<br />

minute) cannot contain the value itself and he mentions two different forms <strong>of</strong> value (both<br />

value and exchange-value) as complements to each other in the idea <strong>of</strong> physicality playing<br />

no part in the make up <strong>of</strong> the actual forms <strong>of</strong> value—for the physicality is only the vehicle<br />

(or the tangible place holder). This all implies that the value that some<strong>thing</strong> has goes beyond<br />

what it is made out <strong>of</strong>.<br />

Hans: Value and exchange-value are not two different forms <strong>of</strong> value. Rather, Marx only talks here about one form<br />

<strong>of</strong> value, what he calls “value.” Exchange-value is how this value manifests itself on the surface <strong>of</strong> the economy to


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 117<br />

the economic agents. Value and exchange-value belong together; their other is use-value (but Marx says that value<br />

and use-value have no<strong>thing</strong> in common except the word).<br />

When you say that the commonality between value and exchange-value is “a sense <strong>of</strong> intangibility,” this is pure<br />

phantasy. This is not a mis-interpretation <strong>of</strong> Marx, this is someone guessing who has read Marx only in the most<br />

superficial way if at all.<br />

She: I think those statements work nicely together. As I interpret the concept, value, being the congealed abstract<br />

labor embodied in an object, is not visible nor is exchange-value. Exchange-value is simply the social relation<br />

between commodities. It is described as a signal in the annotations. Neither one is some<strong>thing</strong> you can see, hold,<br />

or touch. We can see and touch the natural form <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong>, but Marx explains that ”commodities possess an<br />

objective character as values only in so far as they are all expressions <strong>of</strong> an identical social substance, human labour,<br />

that their objective character as values is therefore purely social.(138:2)<br />

Hans: She, <strong>first</strong> <strong>of</strong> all, please use the notes at the bottom <strong>of</strong> existing submissions only if you have to give feedback<br />

to that particular submission. Otherwise you should submit it per email. You can add ug after the question number<br />

to make it ungraded; in this case you can also answer questions which are no longer assigned. Another possibility<br />

which many class participants have done is submit it under question 888 and indicate the question number in the<br />

subject line.<br />

Secondly, exchange-value can be seen from the exchanges a commodity makes. Exchange-value is a surface<br />

category and I would consider it visible.<br />

Message [159] referenced by [162]. Next Message by TINDOZ is [395].<br />

[162] Babyceta: <strong>The</strong> Soul <strong>of</strong> Commodities. Some thoughts on what Somramthom [156]<br />

says about why the <strong>first</strong> chapter <strong>of</strong> Capital is called Commodities and the idea that commodities<br />

do not contain a single atom <strong>of</strong> physical matter addressed by Tindoz [159]. First, I believe<br />

that Marx begins with commodities because, as Hans [157] elaborates on, commodities<br />

are the pivotal element in a capitalistic society. <strong>The</strong>y indeed contain value when produced<br />

for exchange, but also embody the invisible social relations contained in their production (I<br />

may be dependent on the goods you produce and likewise you may also be dependent on<br />

whatever I am producing, and therefore we essentially need each other to exist. But we may<br />

not be aware <strong>of</strong> each other even though our existence is dependent on this relationship and<br />

our lives are interconnected).<br />

I will go on to say that I believe what Marx is saying is that the whole idea <strong>of</strong> capitalism is<br />

based on the principle <strong>of</strong> keeping us, the producers who sell our labor to exist, separated from<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production by keeping this social relationship invisible. We are kept alienated<br />

from each other and the means <strong>of</strong> production by design so that the labor and exchange value<br />

we give to commodities can be exploited. Commodities then essentially become objects<br />

that embody the souls <strong>of</strong> workers, and in a sense if we covet and become fetishistic about<br />

commodities (again, I’m probably getting ahead <strong>of</strong> myself), then our mania is utilized by<br />

the capitalist to ensure that the cycle continues and that we are in essence slaves to the<br />

commodities themselves. I believe that is why Marx begins with commodities; they are the<br />

epicenter <strong>of</strong> capitalism on many different levels, and without understanding the nature <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities, we cannot understand Marx’s critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

I believe that Tindoz [159] also fails to capture the esoteric nature <strong>of</strong> social relations <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities by focusing on the physical matter component <strong>of</strong> the question. <strong>The</strong> same ideas<br />

I mention above apply to the physicality <strong>of</strong> commodities. Personally, I don’t think Marx was<br />

as concerned about the molecular structure <strong>of</strong> commodities as he was about showing that<br />

the soul <strong>of</strong> commodities comes, once again, from the labor <strong>of</strong> workers who toil to exist in a<br />

capitalist society and never realize that commodities unwillingly capture a small portion <strong>of</strong><br />

the their existence. It’s funny but the one <strong>thing</strong> that sticks out to me from Hans’s <strong>first</strong> lecture<br />

118 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

is the analogy <strong>of</strong> approaching Marx’s ideals like scaffolding on the exterior <strong>of</strong> a building; to<br />

appreciate Das Kapital you have to see the perfection in the framework <strong>of</strong> his arguments.<br />

Marx begins with commodities to illustrate their physical nature so that he can show that it<br />

is indeed not their physical qualities that give them value or make them important. It is the<br />

unseen soul <strong>of</strong> the commodity that breathes life into capitalism.<br />

Next Message by Babyceta is [308].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 175 is 134 in 2004fa, 160 in 2008SP, and 158 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 175 Marx writes: “Society does not consist <strong>of</strong> individuals, but expresses the sum<br />

<strong>of</strong> relations in which the individuals stand.” Why did he switch from “consist” to “express,”<br />

i.e., why did he not write “society consists <strong>of</strong> the sum <strong>of</strong> relations in which the individuals<br />

stand”?<br />

[152] Giant: graded A– Consist vs. Express. Consist is defined as, “to be made up or<br />

composed. To be comprised or contained.” While express is defined as, “clearly indicated;<br />

distinctly stated. To show, manifest, or reveal.” <strong>The</strong>se two definitions have almost opposite<br />

meanings. When Marx switched consist for expressed he altered the meaning <strong>of</strong> his<br />

sentence, breaking it into two different subjects.<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> part Marx is explaining that society is not constructed by individuals. He reemphasizes<br />

this when he says, “Society is therefore not seen as a group <strong>of</strong> individuals with<br />

rubber bands between them” (pg 89). <strong>The</strong> second part in which Marx switches “consist”<br />

with “express” changes his emphasis to explain that different areas in society construct the<br />

individual.<br />

<strong>The</strong> statement, “society consists <strong>of</strong> the sum <strong>of</strong> relations in which the individuals stand”<br />

gives the impression that all individuals pooled together make up the structure <strong>of</strong> society.<br />

This is not true, which is why it was not used. As Marx explained, a person fulfills certain<br />

social roles and depending on their desires goes into that particular role. If a person loves<br />

taking care <strong>of</strong> animals, they will fill the role <strong>of</strong> vet or another job that involves animals. This<br />

role was not created by the individual but by society.<br />

Message [152] referenced by [153]. Next Message by Giant is [201].<br />

[153] Robert: (graded A) I appreciate what Giant writes in [152] in answer to this question<br />

but I personally wonder if Marx wasn’t going a little deeper with his statements.<br />

<strong>The</strong> amalgamation <strong>of</strong> people does not itself create a society, as Giant helps us see. Society<br />

exerts its influence through its historical customs, cultures, religions, language, and many<br />

other ways on the individuals who currently comprise that society. I think Giant was also<br />

making this point; however, there may be two other influences to consider. <strong>The</strong> individuals,<br />

each in her unique way, also exert an influence on society by constantly creating new history<br />

and evolving through other customs, usually incrementally but sometimes revolutionarily.<br />

Individuals also exert influences on one another. <strong>The</strong>se influences: society on individual<br />

(as Giant states), individuals on society, and individuals on individuals, are “the sum <strong>of</strong><br />

relationships in which the individuals stand” and the expression <strong>of</strong> this sum <strong>of</strong> relationships<br />

is what society is.<br />

Next Message by Robert is [164].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 119<br />

[155] Hans: From Ontology to Epistemology. This is one <strong>of</strong> the questions where I<br />

am not sure <strong>of</strong> the answer myself. My best understanding <strong>of</strong> the issue right now can be<br />

formulated in two points (a) and (b):<br />

(a) Marx switched from “consists” to “expresses” because the <strong>first</strong> half <strong>of</strong> the sentence is<br />

an ontological statement, it tells us about the nature <strong>of</strong> society, while the second half is an<br />

epistemological statement: it tells us about the meaning <strong>of</strong> the word “society.” I.e., a slightly<br />

more detailed paraphrase <strong>of</strong> Marx’s sentence would be, as I wrote in [2008SP:97]:<br />

Society does not consist <strong>of</strong> individuals, but the word “society” expresses<br />

(a more modern formulation would be: signifies) the sum <strong>of</strong> connections,<br />

relations, in which these individuals stand with respect to each other.<br />

(b) Now why did he switch from ontology to epistemology? This is difficult to know,<br />

and I’m not familiar with any<strong>thing</strong> Marx said elsewhere which would allow us to guess.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore right now I would just be content with answering this part <strong>of</strong> the question with a<br />

shrug. We don’t know why he switched. In the Spring <strong>of</strong> 2008 we had a deep discussion<br />

about these issues, starting with and triggered by the excellent [2008SP:84]. But this was all<br />

speculation on our part. It did not have much to do with reading Marx.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> reader should look at my remarks to [485] which give an important amendment to this answer.<br />

Message [155] referenced by [373] and [485]. Next Message by Hans is [157].<br />

[373] Robert: graded A Ontology and epistemology. In the <strong>first</strong> phase <strong>of</strong> this sentence,<br />

Marx is making an ontological statement. Ontology means a particular theory about the nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> being or the kinds <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s that have existence (Merriam-Webster online dictionary).<br />

He is stating what comprises a society (or does not comprise a society, in this case). Marx<br />

does not believe that a group <strong>of</strong> individuals “with rubber bands between them” (Annotations,<br />

p. 89) is what we mean when we say society. Marx is searching for the ontological unit <strong>of</strong><br />

society...what is the smallest unit into which society can be broken down and he decides it<br />

is not the individual.<br />

In the second phase <strong>of</strong> the sentence, Marx makes an epistemological statement. Epistemology<br />

means the study or a theory <strong>of</strong> the nature and grounds <strong>of</strong> knowledge especially with<br />

reference to its limits and validity (Merriam-Webster online dictionary). Marx is trying to<br />

explain how we know what a society is, or what meaning the word society conveys. He decides<br />

that “society” means (Marx uses the word expresses, Hans in [155] suggests the word<br />

“signifies”) all <strong>of</strong> the relationships between the various individual in that society.<br />

So, paraphrasing Marx: society is not just a group <strong>of</strong> people; rather, it means all <strong>of</strong> the<br />

relationships that exist between the people in society. He could not have accurately said, in<br />

the second phrase, society is all <strong>of</strong> the relationships between people because he showing that<br />

society “means” all <strong>of</strong> the relationships not that it is those relationships.<br />

Now, the tougher question is why Marx is so careful about this distinction. <strong>The</strong> insight<br />

I had briefly during the in class exam was that Marx may have been emphasizing that the<br />

proper ontological unit for economic analysis was not the individual. If we look past society<br />

to the individuals in that society, we are leaving out society, the crucial element <strong>of</strong> the political<br />

economy. If, Marx believes the correct economic ontological unit is society it is not a<br />

very helpful statement to say society consists <strong>of</strong> individuals.<br />

120 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Since society is the ontological unit, then the best approach to understand what we mean<br />

when we use the word “society” is an epistemological approach. When we undertake such<br />

an approach, we see that what we really mean when we are discussing society is the relationships<br />

between the individuals in society. This understanding is very helpful and key<br />

to subsequent discussion <strong>of</strong> such concepts as the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities and<br />

commodity fetishism.<br />

Message [373] referenced by [374]. Next Message by Robert is [374].<br />

[427] BBM: graded A– Society does not consist <strong>of</strong> individuals, but expresses the sum <strong>of</strong><br />

relations in which the individuals stand.<br />

Marx uses the word “expresses” instead <strong>of</strong> “consists” because the word “consists” implies<br />

that society is made up <strong>of</strong> a sum <strong>of</strong> individuals and their characteristics and that’s it.<br />

But when using the word “express” it implies that it consists <strong>of</strong> much more than just individuals<br />

and their characteristics, but relationships between other individuals and how they<br />

interact. “Expresses” also explains occupation, ethnicity, religion, financial status, and all<br />

these factors together is what makes up society. This is why Marx uses the word “expresses”<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> “consists.”<br />

Next Message by BBM is [428].<br />

[445] DMorris: Marx is very particular in this word choice here. Rather than using the<br />

word consist, he uses express. By using express, Marx is speaking <strong>of</strong> the disconnect between<br />

society and the individuals therein. People do not form relationships with the intent<br />

<strong>of</strong> changing or establishing a society. Rather, society forms as a secondary effect <strong>of</strong> the<br />

relationships between people. For example, consider a small classless village, wherein every<br />

individual contributes their full labor to the village. <strong>The</strong>n, assume that one individual<br />

proclaims that for whatever reason he is now the director rather than a laborer. By changing<br />

his relationships with others, he has indirectly caused a large change in society itself. By<br />

stating that “society....expresses the sum <strong>of</strong> relations in which the individual stands,” Marx<br />

is again making the point that no individual can structure society the way he or she wants it<br />

structured. In actuality, Marx is making an even more potent statement; that even the sum<br />

total <strong>of</strong> the individuals in the society can not change it; rather that in order to change society,<br />

the relationships between individuals must change. This is similar to Marx’s later statements<br />

regarding fetishism <strong>of</strong> commodities; the system was created by society, but many members<br />

<strong>of</strong> society forget that the mysterious qualities <strong>of</strong> commodities are a result <strong>of</strong> society.<br />

Hans: People in an egalitarian society cannot become directors just by declaring themselves a director. This is<br />

not how social relations change. Marx said that early societies in the Middle East were not egalitarian but despotic<br />

because the despot was responsible to keep up the irrigation system on which everybody depended. This is how<br />

Marx thinks about social relations: it is not just what people say to each other.<br />

Next Message by DMorris is [453].<br />

[447] Proletarian: graded A+ Marx says “society does not consist <strong>of</strong> individuals, but<br />

expresses the sum <strong>of</strong> relations in which the individuals stand.” Why does Marx switch from<br />

the word “consist” in the <strong>first</strong> part <strong>of</strong> the sentence to the word “express” in the second<br />

part? It’s not necessarily because the word “consist” would be wrong in the second part, but<br />

because “express” is a much clearer and more accurate word choice.<br />

Society does not consist <strong>of</strong> individuals. If there were 300 million individual people all living<br />

in the vicinity <strong>of</strong> one another, but they had no interaction, no relationships, there would


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 121<br />

be no society, just 300 million individuals that happen to live near each other, all wandering<br />

around doing their own <strong>thing</strong>. Social interaction, social relationships, are absolutely necessary<br />

for society to exist. Once these 300 million individuals start interacting and having<br />

relationships they are no longer simply 300 million people but instead a society. It is these<br />

relationships, these interactions, that make a society possible, not the individuals.<br />

So why then is it better and more accurate to say that society “expresses the sum <strong>of</strong><br />

relations” instead <strong>of</strong> society “consists <strong>of</strong> the sum” <strong>of</strong> relations? Because, society is not<br />

really the sum <strong>of</strong> these relationships, but rather a manifestation, an expression <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> the<br />

relationships. Relationships exist in all kinds <strong>of</strong> different societies; every society is capable<br />

<strong>of</strong> having mother-son relationships or tailor-farmer relationships. <strong>The</strong>se relationships are<br />

real <strong>thing</strong>s, but they are not unique to a given society. When all <strong>of</strong> these relationships are<br />

added up they are a sum <strong>of</strong> those relationships, but that is not the same as society. It would<br />

be better to call that sum some<strong>thing</strong> like “sum <strong>of</strong> relations” or “total relations.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> reason for this? Because those relationships can exist in more than one, and in<br />

more than one type, <strong>of</strong> society, and can be expressed in different ways. <strong>The</strong> relationship<br />

between a son and a mother or a tailor and a farmer can exist in many kinds <strong>of</strong> societies,<br />

but can take different forms. <strong>The</strong> form that a society takes is an expression <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> these<br />

relationships. <strong>The</strong>se relationships could express themselves in many different societal forms<br />

(western society, eastern society, etc). Since these relationships can express themselves in<br />

so many different forms, as so many different kinds <strong>of</strong> society, then it is more accurate to<br />

say that a society is the expression <strong>of</strong> the sum <strong>of</strong> all relations rather than the relationships<br />

themselves.<br />

Think about this in a similar way to how we think about exchange-value. Exchange-value<br />

is the surface manifestation <strong>of</strong> value, which is congealed human labor. In this case society<br />

is to the sum <strong>of</strong> all relations between individuals as exchange-value is to value. Exchange<br />

value is a surface manifestation, an expression, <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity. In a similar<br />

way, society is the surface manifestation, or expression, <strong>of</strong> the real relationships between<br />

individuals.<br />

Next Message by Proletarian is [448].<br />

[456] Ryan: <strong>The</strong> reason why Marx states that society does not consist <strong>of</strong> individuals but<br />

is an expression <strong>of</strong> the sum <strong>of</strong> the relations <strong>of</strong> these individuals is because Marx makes it<br />

very clear in a few examples that the individual can not set value or define the abstract value<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor but can only be a portion <strong>of</strong> the equation to define these items. Also Marx states<br />

that characters (or roles) in a society do not have to have a specific individual to fill them but<br />

only need the definition <strong>of</strong> what all <strong>of</strong> them do, examples being, fireman, police, teachers.<br />

One fireman can not impact all <strong>of</strong> society but firemen as a whole can. I think that Marx’s<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> value is the best example to express this. Marx explains that one party can<br />

not determine the value <strong>of</strong> a single item, but that their actions can contribute to the value as<br />

formulated by society. Value, according to Marx, is determined by society buying all items<br />

that are produced at the value they see fit. <strong>The</strong>n that information makes its way back to the<br />

producer, which in turn will create an equilibrium <strong>of</strong> its use <strong>of</strong> labor to maximize its efforts<br />

to produce the goods the society had purchased.<br />

122 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> value shows that one individual does not make a society but their<br />

actions can be expressed as a contribution to a whole.<br />

Next Message by Ryan is [457].<br />

[475] Jo: Marx uses the term “express” to better illustrate the expression <strong>of</strong> value in<br />

society. A capitalist society is very individualistic. Marx is trying to help us to break out<br />

<strong>of</strong> the individualist mindset and look at the output <strong>of</strong> society as a whole. Hans writes,<br />

“the declaration that ‘society does not consist <strong>of</strong> individuals’ implies that ‘the social’ is<br />

not reducible to the conscious actions and intentions <strong>of</strong> individuals” (p. 89). It is difficult<br />

for a capitalist to think <strong>of</strong> labor as a congealed mass, with contributions from people with<br />

different education levels being equally valuable. <strong>The</strong> term “express” brings us back to his<br />

previous discussions <strong>of</strong> use-value and exchange-value, and helps us consider the labor force<br />

as a whole, instead <strong>of</strong> as individual laborers whose labor is not equally valuable. Marx’s<br />

statement also emphasizes his belief that the individual does not control society, but rather<br />

that society grows, as Hans explains, “behind the backs <strong>of</strong> the individuals.” He reduces<br />

trade between commodity owners to social interaction between the commodities themselves,<br />

driving home the idea that society (or social relations involving any form <strong>of</strong> value) truly does<br />

not consist <strong>of</strong> individuals.<br />

Hans: What you say is a correct and insightful rendering <strong>of</strong> Marx’s thinking, but you are reading too much into<br />

this one sentence. When Marx switched from “consist” to “express” in the sentence “Society does not consist <strong>of</strong><br />

individuals, but expresses the sum <strong>of</strong> relations in which the individuals stand,” I am almost certain he didn’t do it<br />

for the reasons you describe, although the thoughts you describe were somewhere in his head.<br />

Next Message by Jo is [476].<br />

[485] Ferox: graded A+ Marx switches from ‘consist’ to ‘express’ in order to place emphasis<br />

on the emergent properties <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system. To say a society ‘consists <strong>of</strong>’ is to<br />

say that society is the total sum <strong>of</strong> individuals—that at the individual level <strong>of</strong> analysis capitalism<br />

can be understood. This approach is the downfall <strong>of</strong> classical bourgeois economics.<br />

Marx, however, realizes the gestalt characteristic <strong>of</strong> society—namely that the sum (<strong>of</strong> individual<br />

exchange relations) is greater than its parts (individuals). By examining the emergent<br />

behaviours <strong>of</strong> society, the interactions <strong>of</strong> individuals are understood from a more complete<br />

level <strong>of</strong> analysis.<br />

Hans: You are right! Had he said “consists” the second time, he would simply have switched from one kind<br />

<strong>of</strong> atomism to a different kind, instead <strong>of</strong> viewing society as a totality <strong>of</strong> relations. It is not only the individual<br />

relations, but the relations between the relations that matter. I knew this in [2008SP:97] but had forgotten it when I<br />

wrote this Semester’s [155].<br />

Message [485] referenced by [155]. Next Message by Ferox is [486].<br />

[503] Spiral: Marx switches from “consist” to “express” as a way to better reflect the fluid,<br />

intangible nature <strong>of</strong> social relations. Society is constantly in motion, vibrating in place, so<br />

long as individuals are engaging in numerous social relations with each other society exists.<br />

When these interactions stop individuals remain but no longer constitute a society because<br />

as defined by Marx society is more than the sum <strong>of</strong> its parts i.e. society requires not only<br />

individuals but relations between them too. It appears for Marx society is alive on a higher<br />

plane which leaves the explanation “society consists <strong>of</strong> the sum <strong>of</strong> relations in which the<br />

individuals stand” left wanting.<br />

Next Message by Spiral is [504].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 123<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 186 is 69 in 1995WI, 77 in 1995ut, 80 in 1996sp, 81 in 1996ut, 87 in 1997WI, 90<br />

in 1997sp, 86 in 1997ut, 142 in 2005fa, and 162 in 2007fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 186 What does Marx understand to be the riddle <strong>of</strong> money? And how does he<br />

solve this riddle in section 3?<br />

[527] Kaush: Riddle <strong>of</strong> money. To Marx, the riddle <strong>of</strong> money is “money can buy every<strong>thing</strong>”.<br />

He solves the riddle by reasoning that money is the commodity’s own equivalent<br />

form <strong>of</strong> value broken <strong>of</strong>f into a specialized commodity such as gold.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> riddle <strong>of</strong> money is the question why money can buy every<strong>thing</strong>. You did not answer this but you gave a<br />

beautiful one-sentence summary <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory what money is. Does Marx’s theory as you formulated it give an<br />

answer why money can buy every<strong>thing</strong>? For this you need one more step. Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> money not only says<br />

that money is a broken-<strong>of</strong>f part <strong>of</strong> every commodity, but that every commodity must become this broken-<strong>of</strong>f part<br />

in order to function as a commodity. Commodities need to get laid, I mean need to get sold. <strong>The</strong> power <strong>of</strong> money<br />

to buy every<strong>thing</strong> comes from the commodities, not from money. Commodities have to catch up with the part <strong>of</strong><br />

themselves which has broken <strong>of</strong>f.<br />

Message [527] referenced by [555]. Next Message by Kaush is [554].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 188 is 125 in 2003fa, 142 in 2004fa, 143 in 2005fa, 160 in 2007SP, 163 in<br />

2007fa, and 166 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 188 Why doesn’t Marx say that the simplest value relation is that between commodity<br />

and money?<br />

[145] Orville: graded C Monetary Woes. As anyone in our class could tell you, Marx<br />

isn’t the most traditional <strong>of</strong> people. It is no surprise therefore that he has a problem with<br />

relating commodities and their seemingly infinitely many use-values with one monetary<br />

value put on them by the market. I believe the reason he doesn’t say that there is a simple<br />

equation between commodities and money is because in his eyes, that is not possible. By<br />

proving so thoroughly that each item has a different use-value for just about any situation<br />

you can think <strong>of</strong>, it makes sense that it can’t be represented by one amount <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

As Hans says in [2008fa:267], “the place <strong>of</strong> a certain kind <strong>of</strong> use-values in an economy<br />

cannot be measured by one number.” As we’ve discussed through our posts and as Marx<br />

has said throughout Capital, you can’t simply look at an item and know what the use-value<br />

because that depends on the future use <strong>of</strong> the item. A more concrete example <strong>of</strong> this might be<br />

when someone asks you to use a word to describe your political views in a word. No matter<br />

what word you choose, you can’t possibly express all <strong>of</strong> your views because one word could<br />

never be enough. This example works much in the way that Marx believes monetary value<br />

doesn’t represent the infinitely many dimensions a commodity possesses.<br />

Hans: You are confusing use-value and value, some<strong>thing</strong> which should no longer happen at this point <strong>of</strong> the class.<br />

As I said in [137], whenever Marx uses the word “value” without “use-” in front <strong>of</strong> it, he does not mean use-value<br />

but he means value—the congealed abstract labor in the commodity which, if Marx’s theory is correct, makes<br />

commodities exchangeable. Value relations are relations between commodities where they relate to each other as<br />

globs <strong>of</strong> abstract human labor. <strong>The</strong>se relations have no<strong>thing</strong> to do with the use-values <strong>of</strong> the commodities.<br />

Message [145] referenced by [179]. Next Message by Orville is [190].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 195 <strong>The</strong> linen weaver’s willingness to trade her linen for a coat cannot be an<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the linen, due to the principle that “bygones are bygones.” <strong>The</strong><br />

labor is a <strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong> the past, it no longer concerns the weaver; all that concerns her is what<br />

124 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

exists in the present, which is the linen. <strong>The</strong> decision to trade the linen must therefore be<br />

based on the linen itself and not on the labor used in the past to produce that linen. If the<br />

linen weaver trades coat for linen, she therefore reveals her preference <strong>of</strong> the use-value <strong>of</strong><br />

the coat over that <strong>of</strong> the linen, and does not express the value <strong>of</strong> the linen. Is this a correct<br />

argument, and if not, where is the error?<br />

[140] Atticus: (graded A) Hey! I Made That. <strong>The</strong> error is in the very <strong>first</strong> sentence: “<strong>The</strong><br />

linen weaver’s willingness to trade her linen for a coat cannot be an expression <strong>of</strong> the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the linen, due to the principle that ‘bygones are bygones’” (annotations pp. 98). Hans<br />

states that the decision <strong>of</strong> the weaver to exchange her linen for the coat is an expression <strong>of</strong><br />

value (ibid pp. 97). Although she may be unconscious <strong>of</strong> the value she places on her linen,<br />

she instinctively trades her linen by personal knowledge for the amount <strong>of</strong> labor she used to<br />

create the linen. She will attempt to exchange her linen for no less than she feels that she<br />

deserves because she intuitively knows how much energy she expended to create the linen.<br />

<strong>The</strong> linen has no use-value to the weaver but the coat does. However, the linen is carrier <strong>of</strong><br />

value and that is useful to the weaver to exchange for other use-value that she may need at<br />

the time.<br />

Hans: You are re-arguing why the coat is an expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen without specifically<br />

addressing the “bygone is bygone” objection. <strong>The</strong>refore my [151] tried to clarify what was asked.<br />

Although you didn’t quite answer the question, what you did say is accurate except for one point. <strong>The</strong> linen<br />

weaver is not free to decide how much linen she wants to <strong>of</strong>fer for a coat. <strong>The</strong> exchange proportion between linen<br />

and coat are given by the market. Marx says this in 147:2, but he does not work through the implications <strong>of</strong> this.<br />

<strong>The</strong> linen weaver either has to trade linen for coat at the exchange relation given by the market, or she cannot make<br />

the trade at all. If the coat is too expensive, she may have to keep herself warm with other means. If every<strong>thing</strong> is<br />

too expensive, she may have to quit being a linen weaver and produce some<strong>thing</strong> which pays better on the market.<br />

All this changes the quantities supplied and demanded until prices are indeed proportional to labor content. See my<br />

[2007SP:586] and [2005fa:966].<br />

Next Message by Atticus is [225].<br />

[151] Hans: Paul and Karl. Paul A Samuelson has a conversation with Karl Marx in<br />

heaven. Paul says: If the linen weaver trades 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen for one coat, this is not an<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the linen, it simply means that 1 coat ranks higher in the weaver’s<br />

utility function than 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen.<br />

Marx replies: no no, you see it all wrong. <strong>The</strong> linen weaver does not look at the linen<br />

as a use-value. She does not need linen. Her dress, her bedspread, her wallpaper, her lamp<br />

shades, are made <strong>of</strong> linen. Linen is coming out <strong>of</strong> her ears. She is maxed out on linen. She<br />

does not need an ounce <strong>of</strong> extra linen. Yet she keeps producing linen, not because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> the linen for her but because the linen is a carrier <strong>of</strong> value. She is materializing<br />

her labor in linen because she is good at it, this is her specialty, and on the market she trades<br />

her labor for someone else’s labor who has specialized in producing some<strong>thing</strong> the linen<br />

weaver needs.<br />

Karl really got going now, he can’t stop here, therefore he adds: I know you neoclassicals<br />

have banished the concept <strong>of</strong> value from your thinking, but if you don’t think about it<br />

this does not mean value suddenly goes out <strong>of</strong> existence. For every commodity producer,<br />

including the linen weaver, it is important to get a fair reward for the labor they have put in.<br />

Not because <strong>of</strong> the warm and fuzzy feeling <strong>of</strong> being treated fairly, but because a coat is not<br />

the only <strong>thing</strong> the linen weaver needs. If she has to give the entire week’s linen product for


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 125<br />

the coat, while the coat took only half a week for the tailor, then she is so much behind that<br />

she won’t be able to afford the other <strong>thing</strong>s she needs.<br />

Paul ignores Karl’s tirade about value, because in this ear he is indeed a little deaf. Instead<br />

Paul says: It is irrational to go by the linen weaver’s intentions. You have to look at her<br />

choice set. <strong>The</strong> linen is already produced, she can no longer go back and use her time in a<br />

different fashion. Bygones are bygones. She must go by what she can change now. Right<br />

now she has two options. Either keep the linen, or exchange the linen for the coat. If she<br />

goes through with the exchange, this clearly means that the use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat is higher<br />

for her than the use-value <strong>of</strong> the linen.<br />

How would Karl respond to this? This is the subject <strong>of</strong> question 195.<br />

Message [151] referenced by [140], [396], and [555]. Next Message by Hans is [155].<br />

[396] School: Trading Coats for Linen. I would say that this is an incorrect argument.<br />

Just because the weaver trades a coat for linen this doesn’t show the weaver’s preference for<br />

linen. <strong>The</strong> linen weaver could have exchanged 50 coats for the same amount <strong>of</strong> linen and<br />

this still would not reflect the weaver’s preference. If we were to write an equation for this it<br />

would be 1 unit <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 unit <strong>of</strong> coat. Both the one unit <strong>of</strong> linen and the one unit <strong>of</strong> coat<br />

could have changed in this equation. Although the exchange value is determined by labor it<br />

is the linen and the coat that trade each other and not the weaver. That is why I think this is<br />

an incorrect argument. It is because the commodities strangely trade themselves.<br />

Hans: Linen and coat don’t trade themselves. Marx uses the metaphor in chapter Two that they are eager to change<br />

places with each other, because for them an exchange is the social validation <strong>of</strong> the labor inside them, but the final<br />

decision <strong>of</strong> the trade stays with the commodity owner, who not only looks at value but also use-value.<br />

What you write has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with the bygones is bygones principle. You should have carefully read [151]<br />

and continued the argument there.<br />

Next Message by School is [397].<br />

[480] Cosmopolita: When the linen weaver is willing to trade her linen for a coat, this<br />

does not only express the value <strong>of</strong> her commodity towards a coat itself but also sets a “value”<br />

<strong>of</strong> the linen itself. Now the linen has diffracted into a bewildering multitude <strong>of</strong> different<br />

expressions.<br />

Since the linen weaver might have multiple needs as well as other memebers <strong>of</strong> that<br />

society and he active members <strong>of</strong> the market <strong>of</strong> trade it gives the linen a certain magnitude<br />

for exchange purposes.<br />

Hans: This resubmission has little to do with the question. Your in-class answer was better.<br />

Next Message by Cosmopolita is [616].<br />

[482] IrvingHowe: This argument is only half correct and deserves explanation in any<br />

event. First, the labor invested by the linen weaver cannot simply dismissed as “bygones.”<br />

Rather, it is this very labor that instills the linen’s exchange value. That is, had she not<br />

invested an amount <strong>of</strong> labor similar to the amount needed for the production <strong>of</strong> the coat, she<br />

could not have made the trade.<br />

Second, it may be that in a state devoid <strong>of</strong> all possessions that the weaver may in fact<br />

prefer the use value <strong>of</strong> her linen to that <strong>of</strong> a coat. However, her circumstances do tell us that<br />

she must prefer the use value <strong>of</strong> the coat. Probably due to the fact that she has an abundance<br />

<strong>of</strong> linen.<br />

Hans: You don’t have the right answer, but nobody did this Semester, and at least you are asking the right questions.<br />

126 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [483].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 199 is 72 in 1995WI, 80 in 1995ut, 83 in 1996sp, 84 in 1996ut, 90 in<br />

1997WI, 93 in 1997sp, 88 in 1997ut, 95 in 1998WI, 112 in 2000fa, 117 in 2001fa, and 147<br />

in 2004fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 199 Explain the different parts played by coat and linen in the equation<br />

“20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat.”<br />

[319] RexManning: graded A My time to explain one equation. In the equation, 20<br />

yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat, the 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is playing an active role, where the coat is<br />

playing a passive role. <strong>The</strong> role <strong>of</strong> the linen is active because the weaver did not labor to<br />

make 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen for herself, she produced the linen in order to exchange it for her<br />

other needs, in this case a coat, and until her need is met, she will actively look for ways to<br />

meet this need. <strong>The</strong> active role <strong>of</strong> the linen can also be described as having a “relative form<br />

<strong>of</strong> value,” meaning, its value is considered in relation to some<strong>thing</strong> else, the coat. Where the<br />

coat takes on the “equivalent form <strong>of</strong> value,” because it is in need by someone, the weaver,<br />

who has a commodity that can be used to pay for the coat.<br />

Message [319] referenced by [320]. Next Message by RexManning is [337].<br />

[320] Hans: <strong>The</strong> emphasis is on “different”. RexManning’s [319] is the kind <strong>of</strong> answer<br />

I am looking for. I want you to stress the differences in the roles. <strong>The</strong> linen is the commodity<br />

which expresses its value, this is the active role. <strong>The</strong> coat serves as measure <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [323].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 247 is 103 in 1995WI, 125 in 1998WI, and 180 in 2005fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 247 Labor was not equal in Ancient Greece—how could the Greeks then exchange?<br />

[164] Robert: (graded A–) Slaves’ labor is also value. This question seems to go right<br />

to the heart <strong>of</strong> Marx’s argument. Even though owners <strong>of</strong> slaves in Ancient Greece (or early<br />

U.S.) did not pay for the labor <strong>of</strong> their slaves the commodities the slaves still imbued the<br />

commodities they produced with value. <strong>The</strong> Greeks implicitly recognized this value when<br />

they exchanged products even though they explicitly did not recognize it when it came to<br />

rewarding the slave workers for the value they created.<br />

It is not such a far step from the plight <strong>of</strong> the slave to that <strong>of</strong> the exploited worker. If a<br />

worker does not receive fair compensation for the value he creates she is exploited by the<br />

owner <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production for the labor value she creates in excess <strong>of</strong> the fairly compensated<br />

labor. She receives no more compensation for this excess labor than a slave receives<br />

for his labor. Slaves in Ancient Greece produced value that was kept by their owners or exchanged<br />

by their owners for other value which they kept. Likewise, owners <strong>of</strong> production<br />

exchange or keep the excess value created by their exploited workers for themselves.<br />

Hans: You are addressing an important issue. A worker—whether a wage worker or slave—does not create any<br />

less value because he or she is not fairly compensated for the value created. <strong>The</strong> difference between the value they<br />

create and what they get (either in wages, as the wage worker, or in food and housing, as the slave) is the pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong><br />

the slave owner or owner <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Two remarks about this:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 127<br />

(a) slave labor in antiquity was primarily used for the consumption needs <strong>of</strong> the slave owner, not for pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore your remarks are more applicable to slavery in the US than to slavery in ancient Greece.<br />

(b) <strong>Question</strong> 247 does not address the exploitation <strong>of</strong> slaves but asks a more fundamental question about Marx’s<br />

value theory. Marx is telling us that by exchanging their products, the producers acknowledge that the labor in these<br />

products are equal. Ancient Greece seems a counterexample to this: although commodities were exchanged, labor<br />

was clearly not equal. Marx himself says in 151:5/o that labor was not equal in Greece—and it does not disturb<br />

him that this seems to contradict his theory <strong>of</strong> commodity production. Should he be disturbed?<br />

Message [164] referenced by [549]. Next Message by Robert is [167].<br />

[549] Kiko: <strong>The</strong> Greeks could exchange based on the fact that even though the one<br />

particular individual (master) did not labor. He/she owned the labor produced by the slave<br />

by caring for, feeding, providing basic needs. This gave the ownership <strong>of</strong> the slave’s labor to<br />

himself. <strong>The</strong> “master” could then in turn take “his” commodities to the market for exchange.<br />

Value has no regards for who actually made the item, just the output. Example: One does<br />

not have to do any<strong>thing</strong> much to a tree for it to bear fruit, but if one owned the land that the<br />

tree is on then he can harvest the fruit and exchange it for other commodities without having<br />

to actually bear the fruit. He only has to have the capacity and the knowledge to procure the<br />

fruit and make the exchange. For the man does labor, but more so in the exchange and not<br />

the production.<br />

Hans: Regarding your last sentence: According to Marx, the labor used for the exchange process (writing the price<br />

signs and waiting for buyers on the market) does not create value. But you described part <strong>of</strong> the labor <strong>of</strong> the tree<br />

grower in the previous sentence: the necessary knowledge takes labor to acquire, then also the labor <strong>of</strong> irrigating,<br />

pest control, protecting the trees from frost and snow if necessary, harvesting, transportation and storage <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fruit. All these take economic resources which have labor embodied in them.<br />

Generally about your answer, you ignored my remark (b) in [164]. This hurt your grade (more in the resubmission<br />

than in the in-class answer).<br />

Next Message by Kiko is [1205].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 249 I just wrote: “<strong>The</strong> power <strong>of</strong> commodity B to purchase A is an expression <strong>of</strong><br />

the value <strong>of</strong> A.” Shouldn’t it rather be: “<strong>The</strong> power <strong>of</strong> commodity B to purchase A is an<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> B”?<br />

[147] Alex: graded B– A vs. B. Once again, Marx directs back to the ideas <strong>of</strong> use value<br />

and exchange value to describe some <strong>of</strong> the elements <strong>of</strong> a commodity. In this case, he<br />

talks about the value relation <strong>of</strong> a commodity, which is also the exchange relation, as being<br />

born from the production <strong>of</strong> the commodity. When Marx compares two commodities, he<br />

compares the amount <strong>of</strong> labor being put in these items. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> these items is according<br />

to Hans “the abstract human labor in equal amounts” which comes to the conclusion that the<br />

exchange relation is represented by the exchangeability <strong>of</strong> these two items in regards to<br />

the labor put into them. Marx then states that “the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is independently<br />

expressed through its representation as ‘exchange-value’,” and as Hans explains, “the power<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodity B to purchase A is an expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> A which is independent <strong>of</strong> its<br />

use value.” To answer the question in this segment, I think that Hans did not say “the power<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodity B to purchase A is an expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> B” as opposed to “the power<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodity B to purchase A is an expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> A” because here Marx is<br />

highlighting the exchange value <strong>of</strong> A, and so measures it as A’s intrinsic value, and labor it<br />

took to complete it, and how much it’s worth (I’m guessing that’s what it means when it says<br />

the “power” <strong>of</strong> the commodity). So then in my own words: the power or ability <strong>of</strong> item B to<br />

128 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

purchase item A is measured by how much A is worth, or is measured by how much labor<br />

it took to complete A, as a comparison to item B. So if A is an expensive commodity, like<br />

diamonds, the power ability <strong>of</strong> B, say pencils is very low, because the labor it took to make<br />

pencils would be insignificant compared to the labor in producing diamonds. If it would<br />

have been “the power <strong>of</strong> commodity B to purchase A is an expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> B,”<br />

this would turn out to be: the ability <strong>of</strong> B to purchase A is measured as B’s value. In the<br />

example, it would be: the power <strong>of</strong> pencils to purchase diamonds is measured on how much<br />

pencils are worth, which doesn’t make sense to me, because diamonds will always be worth<br />

more than pencils, or have a higher exchange value than pencils according to the labor it<br />

took to make them. To me, the <strong>first</strong> statement that Hans made in the annotations made sense,<br />

and I would not think the latter comparison would fit coherently as did the <strong>first</strong> comparison<br />

in the annotations.<br />

Hans: Here you are making a mistake similar to your mistake in [4] <strong>of</strong> attributing to Marx himself <strong>thing</strong>s which<br />

Marx says are done by the markets. You are writing: “When Marx compares two commodities, he compares the<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> labor being put in these items.” You should have said: “According to Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> capitalism, if the<br />

capitalist market exchanges two commodities, it makes a comparison <strong>of</strong> them—a comparison based on the amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor put in these items.”<br />

Another sentence <strong>of</strong> yours says “here Marx is highlighting the exchange value <strong>of</strong> A, and so measures it as<br />

A’s intrinsic value.” I am tempted to respond to this with a similar formulation as Zaratustra [97]: “Marx is here<br />

explaining capitalism and not highlighting any<strong>thing</strong>.” Marx is describing how the market highlights (Marx uses the<br />

word “expresses”) certain aspects <strong>of</strong> production in the sphere <strong>of</strong> circulation but he does not do his own highlighting.<br />

Kraken made the same mistake in [78]. I am a puzzled that you are reverting to an error which you made in [4]<br />

and which I thought my [12] explained in detail. In [31] you didn’t make this mistake, or did I just not notice? Did<br />

you think Marx considered only some <strong>of</strong> the exchange-values generated by the market to be valid in the sense <strong>of</strong><br />

conforming with what Marx thought exchange-values should be? If you did, then this was wrong too.<br />

Message [147] referenced by [149]. Next Message by Alex is [290].<br />

[149] Hans: Pencils Versus Diamonds, Oops Linen Versus Coats. Alex [147] picked<br />

an interesting question which goes to the heart <strong>of</strong> the subject matter <strong>of</strong> the currently assigned<br />

readings. This question can be posed in two different scenarios, with the answer being the<br />

same in both.<br />

First scenario: we are in a direct barter society without money. <strong>The</strong> linen weaver has<br />

produced linen all week long, and on Saturday she goes to market and <strong>of</strong>fers her linen for<br />

trade. She announces that she is willing to give 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen in exchange for 1 coat and<br />

asks if there are any takers. By this <strong>of</strong>fer she enables a coat (commodity B) to “purchase”<br />

20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen (commodity A). In other words, after hearing her <strong>of</strong>fer, the tailor is free to<br />

decide whether he wants to approach the linen weaver, give her 1 coat, and receive 20 yards<br />

<strong>of</strong> linen in exchange, as if he had purchased the linen with the coat. Is this an expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the linen or <strong>of</strong> the coat? From the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the linen weaver, it is<br />

an expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the linen. She knows exactly the expenses and the labor that<br />

goes into the linen, but the does not know very well the expenses and the labor going into<br />

the coat. But the knows the use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat, and she needs a new coat because winter<br />

is coming. In view <strong>of</strong> this knowledge, she is willing to give twenty yards <strong>of</strong> linen for a coat.<br />

This is an expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the linen in the use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat. It cannot be an<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the coat because the linen weaver does not even know the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the coat. But if a tailor agrees to make this trade, then for him this is an expression <strong>of</strong> the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> his coat in the use-value <strong>of</strong> the 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 129<br />

Second scenario: We are in a monetized economy, say gold is money. We are no longer<br />

privy to the knowledge or the needs <strong>of</strong> the linen weaver, instead we are observing the market.<br />

We see what people do in the market without knowing why they do it. We see the linen<br />

weaver <strong>of</strong>fering 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen for 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold. She does this because she needs a<br />

coat, and the coat is <strong>of</strong>fered elsewhere for 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold. We do not know this half <strong>of</strong> it,<br />

we only see that she is <strong>of</strong>fering 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen for 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold. Is this an expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the linen or the value <strong>of</strong> the gold? It is again an expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

linen, because it compares the linen with all the other <strong>thing</strong>s 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold can buy. It by<br />

itself is not an expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the gold. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold is expressed<br />

in all the use-values this ounce <strong>of</strong> gold could buy, not just the linen.<br />

Marx gives both these scenarios. Although Marx himself does not stress this, I think the<br />

parallelism <strong>of</strong> the linen weaver’s individual motivation with the general information exposed<br />

by the market is important. It allows the individual market participants to use the market to<br />

express the values <strong>of</strong> their goods. <strong>The</strong> expression no longer just lives in the brain <strong>of</strong> the<br />

linen weaver. Rather it sends information about the value <strong>of</strong> the linen to the other market<br />

participants, as if the other market participants were able to read her thoughts. (<strong>The</strong> same<br />

for all the other commodities.)<br />

Message [149] referenced by [154], [363], and [2012fa:478]. Next Message by Hans is [151].<br />

[363] Lindsey: Money expresses the value <strong>of</strong> other <strong>thing</strong>s. B is an expression <strong>of</strong> the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> A because it is the “equivalent form <strong>of</strong> value” <strong>of</strong> A. It represents that A has the<br />

ability to fetch other commodities. Paper money is a clearer representation <strong>of</strong> this because it<br />

represents the value <strong>of</strong> other goods but no one would actually exchange any<strong>thing</strong> for money<br />

if it did not have the socially-given power to represent the value <strong>of</strong> other goods. Money (the<br />

equivalent form <strong>of</strong> value) measures the value <strong>of</strong> other goods with a quantitative price tag,<br />

those goods that you can buy with money do not represent the value <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Hans: If I understand you right, you are saying: in a paper money regime, a price cannot be the expression <strong>of</strong> the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> money because money does itself not have value but it is just paper. But even if money is valuable gold<br />

coins, the argument can still be made that a price is not the expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money. I showed in [149]<br />

how to argue this.<br />

Next Message by Lindsey is [403].<br />

[421] Jon: <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> way that this is put is the correct way to say this sentence: “<strong>The</strong><br />

power <strong>of</strong> commodity B to purchase A is an expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> A.” <strong>The</strong> 20 yards <strong>of</strong><br />

linen (commodity A) is used in exchange for 1 coat (commodity B), the weaver knows the<br />

labor and the time and expense that went into producing the linen when they place the coat<br />

as what they wish to exchange for the tailor has an option to accept or deny that <strong>of</strong>fer. At<br />

this point <strong>of</strong> the transaction the weaver knows the use value <strong>of</strong> the coat but not the value <strong>of</strong><br />

the coat, this is how it is seen that the value <strong>of</strong> the linen or commodity A is expressed in the<br />

coat but the coat is not. One <strong>thing</strong> not to forget is that if the tailor accepts the <strong>of</strong>fer <strong>of</strong> 20<br />

yards <strong>of</strong> linen for the 1 coat then the value <strong>of</strong> the coat is now known since it must equal that<br />

<strong>of</strong> the 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen for the exchange to take place.<br />

Next Message by Jon is [661].<br />

[435] Fisher: <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> commodity A, according to Marx, is “expressed by the direct<br />

exchangeability <strong>of</strong> commodity B with A”. So, as A gets a value by being compared to commodity<br />

B in a possible exchange, B also is given a value based on its ability to be exchanged<br />

130 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

with A, or another commodity. I think what he is basically saying here is that as commodities<br />

are compared with other commodities in the market place, they qualitatively express<br />

their individual values through their ability to be exchanged with another commodity. Only<br />

through demand for one commodity can it gain value, after it is compared with another in<br />

the market. So, I think that the power <strong>of</strong> commodity B and A are equally as powerful <strong>of</strong> an<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> both <strong>of</strong> their values, since they both represent value and are exchanged.<br />

Hans: How commodities express their values is a different question than how they “gain” value.<br />

Next Message by Fisher is [585].<br />

[472] Hal: graded A+ For commodities A and B, we assume that if B is purchasing A,<br />

that means the producer <strong>of</strong> A made the initial <strong>of</strong>fer to exchange A for B. For example, the<br />

producer <strong>of</strong> A may <strong>of</strong>fer to sell 1 unit <strong>of</strong> A for 3 units <strong>of</strong> B. B purchasing A means the<br />

producer <strong>of</strong> B accepts the producer <strong>of</strong> A’s <strong>of</strong>fer and exchanges 3 units <strong>of</strong> B for 1 unit <strong>of</strong> A.<br />

<strong>The</strong> producer <strong>of</strong> A bases her exchange <strong>of</strong>fer on the value <strong>of</strong> A, which she knows intimately,<br />

and the use-value that she would receive from B. She does not base her <strong>of</strong>fer, on the value <strong>of</strong><br />

B, so the power <strong>of</strong> B to purchase A is not a reflection <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> B; it is only a reflection<br />

<strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> A and the use-value <strong>of</strong> B. As a side note, if the producer <strong>of</strong> B decides to<br />

accept the <strong>of</strong>fer, he would be basing that decision on the value <strong>of</strong> B and the use-value <strong>of</strong> A,<br />

so his decision to accept or reject the <strong>of</strong>fer is a reflection <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> B.<br />

Next Message by Hal is [633].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 261 is 216 in 2007fa, 223 in 2008SP, 221 in 2008fa, 234 in 2009fa, 225 in<br />

2011fa, and 235 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 261 How does it become plain here that it is not the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

which regulates the magnitude <strong>of</strong> their values, but rather the reverse, it is the magnitude <strong>of</strong><br />

the value <strong>of</strong> commodities which regulates the proportion in which they are exchanged?<br />

[171] KA: Magnitude <strong>of</strong> value. Marx discusses that the magnitude <strong>of</strong> which value is<br />

created in a commodity must be widely accepted as the common means <strong>of</strong> an exchange<br />

for other commodities. This magnitude is established as a common denominator when an<br />

exchange is done. This common denominator, say linen, sets the basis for the proportion in<br />

which other commodities are valued to, say coats. In his example, 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen can be<br />

exchanged for 1 coat, suggests that the common denominator is linen. <strong>The</strong> magnitude <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity’s value is 20 vs 1.<br />

<strong>The</strong> magnitude <strong>of</strong> the value in this example suggest that 1 coat has a higher valuation to<br />

the consumer than their 1 yard <strong>of</strong> linen, and, therefore, requires additional yards <strong>of</strong> linen<br />

(20) to equal (or be in proportion) to the value <strong>of</strong> 1 coat. This magnitude establishes the<br />

proportion <strong>of</strong> 20 yards for 1 coat. A common agreement must be established between both<br />

parties in order for an exchange to be made. <strong>The</strong> coat merchant established the value <strong>of</strong><br />

their coat to cover all associated costs <strong>of</strong> labor, is <strong>of</strong> a higher magnitude for its production<br />

than the labor embodied in the production <strong>of</strong> 1 yard <strong>of</strong> linen. While linen is the common<br />

denominator for an exchange (in this example), its value in comparison to a coat is in lower<br />

proportions. Marx’s example suggests that the significance <strong>of</strong> the commodities is the basis<br />

for determining in what proportion an exchange can be made.<br />

Hans: <strong>Question</strong> 261 was posed in the context <strong>of</strong> the Expanded form <strong>of</strong> value, where 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is in the<br />

relative form, and coat, tea, iron, gold etc. are in the equivalent form. <strong>The</strong> equivalent form is the denominator. I.e.,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 131<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> measuring many different commodities with one denominator, which would be the right way to do it, and<br />

which is what you have in mind, Marx arrived at one commodity measuring itself in many different denominators.<br />

Marx arrived at the wrong way <strong>of</strong> measuring value because there is a natural transition from the Simple form to<br />

the Expanded form. After hopping up to the Expanded form he must turn the Expanded form around to get to the<br />

General form which is the right way to do it.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se forms <strong>of</strong> value do not come from the “valuation to the consumers” or “significance <strong>of</strong> the commodities.”<br />

If you say that, then you are confusing use-value and exchange-value and you will get a bad grade as the others<br />

who said this.<br />

Message [171] referenced by [178], [179], [186], and [2012fa:196]. Next Message by KA is [176].<br />

[178] Kraken: (graded A) Fluctuating value? Marx believed that a commodity had value<br />

because human labor power was expended in the creation <strong>of</strong> said commodity. Please read<br />

this as a correction to [171]! If that is the case, the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity would remain<br />

constant, regardless <strong>of</strong> the proportion at which it was exchanged for other commodities. In<br />

the short term, there will always be unequal exchanges in which some<strong>thing</strong> containing a lot<br />

<strong>of</strong> human labor power is exchanged for some<strong>thing</strong> containing little human labor power. This<br />

is due to spikes in demand for certain commodities. But in the long-run, the proportion at<br />

which commodities are traded will eventually return to trades containing equal amounts <strong>of</strong><br />

human labor power. An example would be several years ago when “Tickle Me Elmo” dolls<br />

were extremely popular. Although the human labor power used in the production <strong>of</strong> the dolls<br />

did not change, the price which people were willing to pay, using their human labor power,<br />

to get the dolls continued to increase. Eventually supply met demand (and people returned<br />

to their senses) and people returned to the long run condition <strong>of</strong> exchanging equal amounts<br />

<strong>of</strong> human labor power (until the next fad came along).<br />

Hans: You write: “the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity ... remain(s) constant, regardless <strong>of</strong> the proportion at which it (is)<br />

exchanged for other commodities.” You are right, Marx differentiates between value and price. Prices can deviate<br />

from values, but values are the “center <strong>of</strong> gravity” for prices.<br />

Message [178] referenced by [179], [186], and [402]. Next Message by Kraken is [228].<br />

[179] Hans: A thank you to Kraken for setting the record straight. KA [171] and<br />

Kraken [178] discuss the mechanism through which the magnitude <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

regulates the exchange proportions. This is not exactly the same as the question, which<br />

quotes Marx 155:3/o and asks how the Expanded form <strong>of</strong> value makes it plain that the<br />

exchange proportions come from value. But it is close enough, and it is certainly an issue<br />

that needs explanation.<br />

I commend Kraken for not following KA in saying that in Marx’s theory value is assigned<br />

by consumers, just as in mainstream economics. Kraken states right at the beginning that<br />

value comes from labor. According to Marx, value is created in production, not in marketing<br />

or consumption. Kraken should have made it clearer that the price drop after the initial fad is<br />

not only due to the fad wearing <strong>of</strong>f, but also due to increasing quantities supplied. Producers<br />

allocate more production capacity, ultimately more labor, to those <strong>thing</strong>s that sell well. This<br />

reallocation <strong>of</strong> labor only stops when all labor is equally recognized by the market, i.e.,<br />

when prices are proportional to (direct and indirect) labor input. (This is the rough story, it<br />

abstracts from some finer points.)<br />

KA is not the only one who thinks that Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> value is identical to mainstream<br />

utility theory. Messages [43], [49], [131], [133], [145], and [156] made the same error. It<br />

is an issue for some, therefore Kraken’s submission was probably helpful for many class<br />

132 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

participants. I wrote in the syllabus that I want you to help others understand the material.<br />

Kraken did this, and in order to reward him for this I added a cross reference into his<br />

submission and he will get a full participation point for this cross reference.<br />

Message [179] referenced by [378]. Next Message by Hans is [184].<br />

[186] JJ: What came <strong>first</strong> the Chicken, or the commodity value? I agree with Kraken<br />

[178] in that Marx has made it very clear that value <strong>of</strong> a given commodity is determined<br />

by the amount <strong>of</strong> human labor that has gone into it. Marx elaborates on this very subject<br />

throughout this chapter. If this expression <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a commodity as a factor <strong>of</strong> the human<br />

labor that went into it has still escaped us, then we might try reading the annotations much<br />

slower on our second go around. I am finding that I must read them slowly thrice.<br />

After completing a very long and microscopic analysis <strong>of</strong> the relationship <strong>of</strong> use value,<br />

exchange value, relative value, and equivalent value, Marx very clearly states, “Our analysis<br />

has proved that the value form or the expression <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the commodity springs from<br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> the commodity value, instead <strong>of</strong> value and magnitude <strong>of</strong> value springing from<br />

their mode <strong>of</strong> expression as exchange-value.” [Capital, 152:2/o]. I believe that in this one<br />

statement he very clearly sums up his arguments thus far and at the same time provides us an<br />

answer to question 261. It is clear up to this point that he has established that the nature <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity value is the human labor that was put into making the commodity. He also<br />

clearly states that it is this human labor that determines its magnitude <strong>of</strong> value, and hence the<br />

magnitude <strong>of</strong> value that determines the proportions in which the commodity is exchanged<br />

for its equivalent value <strong>of</strong> another commodity. Thus he has finally solved the great riddle<br />

and shown that it was the chicken that came before the egg and not the other way around.<br />

Marx clearly warns <strong>of</strong> the perils <strong>of</strong> considering the expression <strong>of</strong> value as a merely quantitative<br />

relationship. Rather, he shows that we can only really begin to express relative value<br />

<strong>of</strong> one commodity by showing its equivalent form in another commodity. He further shows<br />

that we can only begin to consider the proportion in which they are exchanged, by considering<br />

the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that went into these commodities. I believe that he is setting us up<br />

to really see that the only common form <strong>of</strong> value in any commodity is human labor which<br />

will allow him to dispel our capitalist ideas about the value <strong>of</strong> money being the basis for<br />

exchange. Hans shows us in his response to [2007fa:101] that Marx indeed is preparing our<br />

minds to accept this basic barter system and show its expression <strong>of</strong> value in labor before<br />

introducing us to the more complex barter system <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Making the mistake that it is by some common agreement <strong>of</strong> the owners <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

which determines the exchange value, as in KA [171], is incorrect. This implies that it<br />

is the owner <strong>of</strong> the commodity that determines that commodity’s value, and that he might<br />

only exchange it if he gains greater utility from his exchange. This type <strong>of</strong> utility form<br />

<strong>of</strong> value makes the other mistake that Marx warns us about. That is the mistake <strong>of</strong> the<br />

neo-mercantilists <strong>of</strong> placing too much emphasis on the qualitative side <strong>of</strong> the expression <strong>of</strong><br />

value, and hence on the form <strong>of</strong> its final equivalent value, money. Determining exchange<br />

proportions or exchange rates on one’s preference ultimately discounts the true commodity<br />

form <strong>of</strong> labor. Allowing exchange proportions in this manner could lead to classism, where<br />

the human labor <strong>of</strong> one is valued over the human labor <strong>of</strong> another. In [Kraken] [178] we<br />

are given the example <strong>of</strong> the “Tickle Me Elmo” doll. I’m nearly certain that there was an


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 133<br />

Ebay market for these dolls where they were being sold at exorbitant prices. <strong>The</strong> exorbitant<br />

asking price <strong>of</strong> the seller was a qualitative assessment <strong>of</strong> the exchange proportion <strong>of</strong> Elmo<br />

dolls to money rather than an equivalent value <strong>of</strong> money to the relative value <strong>of</strong> the doll in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> labor. Thus Marx leaves no place for greed <strong>of</strong> a seller when determining exchange<br />

proportions.<br />

Although Marx clearly answers q.261 in showing us how <strong>thing</strong>s should ideally be; I don’t<br />

believe that he is saying that the reverse does not happen as stated in the question. That is<br />

to say that in some circumstances in capitalist society, I think he would agree that, we do<br />

let the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities regulate the magnitude <strong>of</strong> their values. If we only look at<br />

the quantitative side <strong>of</strong> the value expression then we have no<strong>thing</strong>. We have no value and no<br />

magnitude <strong>of</strong> value, except in the expression <strong>of</strong> value in the exchange relation. This is why<br />

we could all be millionaires now in our capitalist society, if we had only bought AIG when<br />

it was down to 50 cents a share. This is an extreme example but I think it paints the picture<br />

<strong>of</strong> how ignoring the real labor value <strong>of</strong> commodity can be dangerous.<br />

Lastly, [Kraken] [178] states that “the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity remains constant, regardless<br />

<strong>of</strong> the proportion at which it is exchanged for other commodities.” Hans agrees with this<br />

definition. I am slightly confused by this definition. I understand that the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

is independent <strong>of</strong> the proportion at which it is exchanged for other commodities, but<br />

do not see how the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity can remain constant. I refer to the examples that<br />

Marx gives in this section to the variable amount <strong>of</strong> labor that might go into the production<br />

<strong>of</strong> Linen from year to year. He gives three examples: I, II, and II; that show how poor soil<br />

for flax or better looms will change the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that went into 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen.<br />

This changes the relative value <strong>of</strong> linen to an equivalent value <strong>of</strong> some other commodity. Is<br />

this not an example <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> commodity fluctuating?<br />

Hans: You escaped the error about the origin <strong>of</strong> value only to run into the other common misunderstaning about<br />

Marx, that Marx “shows us how <strong>thing</strong>s should ideally be.” Sorry, the world is complicated.<br />

Regarding constancy <strong>of</strong> value, I don’t think Kraken [178] meant to say that value is immune to technical<br />

change—it is not. But if commodities are sold at prices above their values, this will not cause their value to<br />

change. Marx does not believe that prices can sometimes determine value. He thinks value comes from labor, and<br />

most prices are determined either directly or through a detour by values. (<strong>The</strong>re is an occasional price which is<br />

determined by extra-economic forces, such as the price <strong>of</strong> labor and the interest rate.)<br />

Next Message by JJ is [256].<br />

[378] Oreo: graded A To answer this question, we must <strong>first</strong> understand what value is.<br />

Marx describes value as the amount <strong>of</strong> abstract labor congealed within a commodity. It<br />

is intrinsic to the commodity and is generated during the commodity’s production. <strong>The</strong>refore,<br />

value does not change after production. <strong>The</strong> exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities simply cannot<br />

regulate the magnitude <strong>of</strong> the commodity’s values because the values are already predetermined.<br />

Exchange <strong>of</strong> a commodity cannot change its intrinsic value. Since the commodity<br />

has this predetermined magnitude <strong>of</strong> value in it when it enters the market, it is able to regulate<br />

the proportion in which commodities are exchanged. Quantities <strong>of</strong> the commodity to be<br />

exchanged are based on the magnitude <strong>of</strong> its value.<br />

Hans: In order to fully answer the question you should also say how the facts as you describe them “become plain”<br />

in the Expanded form <strong>of</strong> value. But as I said in [179], just describing these facts is close enough for an answer,<br />

especially in an exam.<br />

Next Message by Oreo is [606].<br />

134 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[402] SMIKEC: Value is set by society as a whole. Individuals can not come in and set<br />

their own prices, well, I guess they could but wouldn’t be very successful, unless society<br />

supported them. If the going rate on peaches is $2, you can’t come in and charge $4. As<br />

stated by Hans in response to [178] “Marx differentiates between value and price. Prices<br />

can deviate from values, but values are the ‘center <strong>of</strong> gravity’ for prices.” In today’s society<br />

people would spend $8 on an organic peach or an inflated price for a tickle me Elmo as stated<br />

by Kraken. This is created by the hype <strong>of</strong> the item or prestige <strong>of</strong> having one. It’s a keeping<br />

up with the Jones’ idea that they need one no matter what the price is. Even though prices<br />

can flucuate above the market, again, the value has not changed, because the production<br />

process has aready been completed and doesn’t change once it is put into the market. <strong>The</strong><br />

price <strong>of</strong> the commodity in the long run will come back down to its value or even drop below<br />

after the craze is over. Hence, is tickle me Elmo even still around?!<br />

Next Message by SMIKEC is [561].<br />

[424] JB: graded A <strong>The</strong> belief that exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities regulates the magnitude <strong>of</strong><br />

their values represents the orthodox view where value is determined by supply and demand.<br />

However, Marx believes that supply and demand only account for the fluctuations <strong>of</strong> price<br />

around a constant value. That constant is determined by the amount <strong>of</strong> labor embodied in a<br />

commodity.<br />

First Message by JB is [422].<br />

[459] Balrog: graded C+ Magnitude <strong>of</strong> Value Regulates Exchange. Value is the amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor used in the production <strong>of</strong> a commodity. <strong>The</strong> exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities can not<br />

regulate values because the rate <strong>of</strong> exchange fluctuates.<br />

Robert gave an effective example in [14]. He stated that during the period <strong>of</strong> Hurricane<br />

Katrina a bottle <strong>of</strong> water would have held a much higher price than normal due to the current<br />

situation. Outside conditions can cause the exchange value <strong>of</strong> a good to fluctuate whereas<br />

the magnitude <strong>of</strong> labor intrinsic in a commodity does not change.<br />

When determining the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity we determine how much value or human<br />

labor power it contains. (<strong>The</strong> magnitude <strong>of</strong> its value). This is what is used to regulate the<br />

proportion in which the commodity is exchanged.<br />

Hans: What you say in your last paragraph seems similar to [2009fa:519]. Look at the links I give there.<br />

Next Message by Balrog is [460].<br />

[466] Zohan: Value not magnitude. Marx believes that value is not determined by the<br />

price or the worth <strong>of</strong> a commodity. But, he would say that value is created in the production<br />

process by the amount <strong>of</strong> “socially necessary labor time” put into the commodity. Not all<br />

commodities have the same amount <strong>of</strong> socially necessary labor time, therefore, different<br />

commodities will have different values. In an exchange each party trades for a different<br />

commodity. But in many cases the different commodities will have different values, or in<br />

other words they have different amounts <strong>of</strong> labor time in their production. In order for an<br />

exchange to occur an equal amount <strong>of</strong> value must be exchanged. For example, if a coat<br />

has twice the value <strong>of</strong> a hat, then in order for an exchange to happen, one would need to<br />

exchange two hats to receive one coat. This indicates that it is the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity that<br />

regulates the proportions <strong>of</strong> which they are exchanged, not the other way around.<br />

Hans: I edited in the word “necessary” where you consistently used the phrase “socially labor-time.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 135<br />

You are illustrating what it means what Marx believes to be the case, but you are not giving any arguments to<br />

support or contest it.<br />

Next Message by Zohan is [468].<br />

[489] Hit: It is the magnitude <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> commodities which regulates the proportion<br />

in which they are exchanged because a car is worth a lot more than a bicycle. So when a<br />

person wants to exchange their car for a different commodity they are going to assert the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> their car <strong>first</strong> then they will look at the value <strong>of</strong> what they are trading for to make<br />

an equal trade.<br />

Hans: That a car is worth a lot more than a bicycle is not the reason why the magnitude <strong>of</strong> value regulates prices.<br />

And the next sentence is some<strong>thing</strong> from chapter Two which has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with the question.<br />

First Message by Hit is [253].<br />

[508] Phayze: graded A It is essential to <strong>first</strong> recognize that “value” according to Marx, is<br />

created within the production process through the utilization <strong>of</strong> “human labor power”. <strong>The</strong><br />

labor power expelled during the production process animates itself as “congealed abstract<br />

labor” within the commodity. This congealed labor then manifests itself as “value” <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity. So it is within the production process rather than the surface exchange relations<br />

that the regulation <strong>of</strong> the commodities’ magnitude <strong>of</strong> value is established. <strong>The</strong> magnitude<br />

<strong>of</strong> value is therefore determined by the amount <strong>of</strong> “socially necessary labor time” needed<br />

to produce a commodity. Value does however manifest itself on the surface relations in<br />

exchange value. Since it was determined that values are all qualitatively similar (derivatives<br />

<strong>of</strong> abstract labor), the only difference would be <strong>of</strong> a quantitative nature. <strong>The</strong> perpetual theme<br />

<strong>of</strong> “quantitative differences implying qualitative equality”, is then applied to abstract labor<br />

to arrive at a homogeneous “essence” equal in all labor processes. This commonality is<br />

identified as “labor power”, and the theme is again applied to it...<br />

Next Message by Phayze is [509].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 264 is 154 in 2001fa, 199 in 2004fa, 219 in 2007fa, 224 in 2008fa, and 240 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 264 Why doesn’t Marx go from the Simple form <strong>of</strong> value directly to the General<br />

form <strong>of</strong> value by letting everyone express their values in the same commodity?<br />

[170] LuBr: Homogenizing the form <strong>of</strong> value: from abstraction to social coordination.<br />

<strong>The</strong> concepts involving this question were brought up in class, and so it is my intent to utilize<br />

what Hans touched upon, as well as my own understanding from Chapter 1.3, to answer this<br />

question.<br />

Marx begins this section by trying to understand how the general public knows the<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> labor embodied in the production <strong>of</strong> commodities when these commodities are<br />

produced in a black box and then exchanged on the market. He begins by abstracting away<br />

the necessity for prices and money. <strong>The</strong>se simply (however importantly) serve as a measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. Money does not explain the form by which these commodities express their value<br />

on the market.<br />

Through abstraction, he starts by outlining his Simple form <strong>of</strong> value. On this basic level <strong>of</strong><br />

accidental exchange, 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is equivalent to 1 coat. This exchange was facilitated<br />

because the weaver <strong>of</strong> linen knows how much socially-necessary labor was embodied in the<br />

production <strong>of</strong> 20 yards or linen, and enters into the exchange seeking a commodity with the<br />

136 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> 1 coat. In this exchange, the value <strong>of</strong> the linen is reflected in the use-value <strong>of</strong><br />

the coat. While Marx comes to an form <strong>of</strong> value different from the commodity’s use-value,<br />

one runs into the situation <strong>of</strong> a highly relative form <strong>of</strong> value that would vary qualitatively for<br />

all commodities.<br />

Instead <strong>of</strong> moving from the Simple form <strong>of</strong> value to the General form, which gives rise<br />

to the introduction <strong>of</strong> money, Marx brings an intermediate step which serves to negate the<br />

negation that Marx arrived at in the Simple form <strong>of</strong> value abstraction. In the Expanded form<br />

<strong>of</strong> Value Marx develops further the idea <strong>of</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> value by introducing more use-values<br />

that the weaver <strong>of</strong> linen is going to want to exchange for her 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen. Marx admits<br />

that this is still an abstraction in the absence <strong>of</strong> money, but could potentially work in a social<br />

exchange whereby there is one dominant commodity that is used to exchange for a range <strong>of</strong><br />

other commodities (i.e cattle in an agrarian society). If we continue with linen, all use-values<br />

contained in the body <strong>of</strong> each individually equivalent commodity now reflects the value <strong>of</strong><br />

linen. Again, this is a further and more illustrative step in distancing value from use-value,<br />

because we have many different commodities with many different use values that reflect<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> linen. Also, the Expanded form <strong>of</strong> value introduces the idea that exchange<br />

is social and does not just begin and end with 1 producer meeting another in an informal<br />

market. However, the major defect is that by differentiating value from use-value to such an<br />

extent, value in this intermediate stage loses all form <strong>of</strong> 1-dimensionality. Now value is not<br />

equivalent to any value.<br />

However, the most significant reason for Marx to include this intermediary step before<br />

reaching and developing the General form <strong>of</strong> value is to illustratively inverse the expanded<br />

form <strong>of</strong> value, to arrive at the General form <strong>of</strong> value. In this way, value becomes homogenous<br />

with no qualitative differences. <strong>The</strong> Expanded form <strong>of</strong> value illustrative a case in which<br />

one form <strong>of</strong> value, that <strong>of</strong> linen, was expressed in countless use-values, and thus no one<br />

commodity could serve as the expression <strong>of</strong> value. To express value in any one commodity,<br />

means to express every other commodity relatively and equivalently.<br />

Marx uses the General form <strong>of</strong> value to do just he opposite, and homogenize value around<br />

one socially agreed to commodity. All other commodities gain an expression <strong>of</strong> their value<br />

through general convergence around this commodity. By taking us through the intermediary<br />

form <strong>of</strong> value we see clearly the General form is the best way to measure value, because it<br />

allows us to view all commodities as equivalent and directly exchangeable. This becomes a<br />

united, social expression and coordination <strong>of</strong> the world’s commodities whose exchanges on<br />

the surface represent the productive core <strong>of</strong> the economy.<br />

Message [170] referenced by [173], [497], and [2012fa:180]. Next Message by LuBr is [263].<br />

[173] Hans: Clarifications. I’m extremely pleased with LuBr [170]. Here are some<br />

clarifications, <strong>thing</strong>s I wish I had said more clearly last night in class. LuBr writes:<br />

[Marx] begins by abstracting away the necessity for prices and money.<br />

Marx does not abstract away the necessity for prices and money, he abstracts away money.<br />

He begins with a counterfactual situation without prices and money in order to derive why<br />

prices and money are necessary. Marx begins with a developed exchange economy without<br />

money—some<strong>thing</strong> he knows cannot exist, that’s why I called it a counterfactual—because


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 137<br />

he is trying to explain how money comes about. Not the historical process but the structural<br />

necessity that wherever there is commodity production there is also, by necessity, some form<br />

<strong>of</strong> money.<br />

LuBr continues:<br />

<strong>The</strong>se [prices and money] simply (however importantly) serve as a measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. Money does not explain the form by which these commodities<br />

express their value on the market.<br />

LuBr should have said: the existence <strong>of</strong> money, whose <strong>first</strong> and most important function<br />

is to serve as a measure <strong>of</strong> value, is one <strong>of</strong> the ways how the production in the black box<br />

projects information about itself on the surface <strong>of</strong> the economy or, as LuBr says, to the<br />

general public. Being money is, as Marx says, a “form <strong>of</strong> value.” Only one commodity can<br />

be in this form. Money allows all other commodities to express their values in prices. A<br />

price is also a “form <strong>of</strong> value.” All commodities (except the money commodity) can have<br />

prices.<br />

You may wonder why I am so enthusiastic about LuBr if he says exactly the opposite <strong>of</strong><br />

what I say he should have said. Answer: saying the exact opposite <strong>of</strong> the truth is sometimes<br />

infinitely closer to the truth than saying some<strong>thing</strong> unrelated to the truth—because all you<br />

need now is a mirror to invert it. (This message here tries to be this mirror.)<br />

Since we are already (implicitly) talking about negation <strong>of</strong> negation, here is another point<br />

where I’d like to clarify LuBr. LuBr says:<br />

Instead <strong>of</strong> moving from the Simple form <strong>of</strong> value to the General form,<br />

which gives rise to the introduction <strong>of</strong> money, Marx brings an intermediate<br />

step which serves to negate the negation that Marx arrived at in the Simple<br />

form <strong>of</strong> value abstraction.<br />

This is an interesting perspective on Marx’s methodology. LuBr views the abstraction<br />

(which omits money) as a negation <strong>of</strong> empirical reality and the Expanded form <strong>of</strong> value as<br />

the negation <strong>of</strong> the negation. This could be called an epistemological dialectic, the dialectic<br />

<strong>of</strong> Marx’s scientific process. This interpretation is defensible, but it is not the usual interpretation<br />

how Marx’s development in section 3 <strong>of</strong> chapter One can be viewed as a negation<br />

<strong>of</strong> a negation. <strong>The</strong> usual interpretation gives an ontological dialectic, the dialectic <strong>of</strong> reality<br />

itself: the Simple form <strong>of</strong> value is the point <strong>of</strong> departure, the Expanded form is its negation,<br />

and the General form the negation <strong>of</strong> the negation.<br />

It is not possible to go in one step from the barter <strong>of</strong> commodities to a money economy.<br />

You need two steps: you have to negate the barter, and then you have to negate the result<br />

<strong>of</strong> this negation. In some sense this second negation is a return to barter—because sale or<br />

purchase <strong>of</strong> a commodity look like a direct barter in which one <strong>of</strong> the bartered commodities is<br />

money. But in another sense the second negation preserves the gains from the <strong>first</strong> negation<br />

(the Expanded form <strong>of</strong> value)—because money is not an isolated individual commodity, but<br />

money is connected to all commodities through the prices <strong>of</strong> these commodities.<br />

Message [173] referenced by [434]. Next Message by Hans is [174].<br />

138 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[365] Kleenex: Marx takes a while in developing his argument and doesn’t jump immediately<br />

from the Simple form <strong>of</strong> value to the General form because there are many layers<br />

<strong>of</strong> analysis to peel back to get to the heart <strong>of</strong> the matter. Marx starts at the Simple form <strong>of</strong><br />

value, comparing two ordinary commodities. Marx writes in Capital 139:2 that it is obvious<br />

that “the simplest value relation is that <strong>of</strong> one commodity to a single commodity <strong>of</strong> a different<br />

kind.” He uses the example <strong>of</strong> coats and linen, that 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen can be exchanged<br />

for 1 coat. <strong>The</strong> coat serves as the embodiment <strong>of</strong> the linen’s value, or the medium through<br />

which the linen expresses its value. <strong>The</strong> coat is an “incarnation <strong>of</strong> value,” as Marx writes.<br />

He then transitions into the relative and equivalent values. Here the linen is in the relative<br />

form <strong>of</strong> value, and the coat in the equivalent form. This illustrates their relational paradox:<br />

they can’t be separated from each other, but they are totally different, yet they express the<br />

same value. We soon find out that the coat is an equivalent or “<strong>thing</strong> exchangeable” for the<br />

linen. As he writes throughout the text, “20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat,” and vice versa. Next, he<br />

writes about the expanded form <strong>of</strong> value: now the 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen not only equals 1 coat,<br />

but it can also be exchanged for 5 pounds <strong>of</strong> wheat, or 1 chicken, or 2 pieces <strong>of</strong> jewelry, just<br />

to illustrate. <strong>The</strong> linen’s exchange value is no longer expressed only in the coat, but also in<br />

many other commodities. Finally, he discusses the General form <strong>of</strong> value, in which all other<br />

commodities are expressing their values in a general equivalent, money. Here’s where the<br />

“negation <strong>of</strong> the negation” comes into play. Marx now inverses the argument and introduces<br />

money as a same equivalent. Money, in the proper quantity, (since qualitative asymmetry<br />

exists), can purchase a vast array <strong>of</strong> commodities, if not all commodities. Money, in a<br />

way, gives a standard <strong>of</strong> which the market can standardize exchange value without having to<br />

barter. So in short, Marx did not go directly from Simple to General forms <strong>of</strong> value because<br />

it would have given inadequate information and would not have done the development <strong>of</strong> his<br />

argument justice.<br />

Hans: It is impossible to jump from the original state directly to the negation <strong>of</strong> the negation; you have to go to<br />

the negation <strong>first</strong>. But this is a too general argument; I’d like to see in that particular example what is the obstacle<br />

to going directly to the negation <strong>of</strong> the negation.<br />

Next Message by Kleenex is [379].<br />

[380] KA: Simple to General Form. <strong>The</strong> Simple form expresses exchanges in “equivalent<br />

forms” <strong>of</strong> value. For example, the Simple form <strong>of</strong> value looks at the exchange value <strong>of</strong> (one)<br />

commodity A for another commodity B, in terms <strong>of</strong> commodity A. Marx did not go directly<br />

to the General form from the Simple form because there needs to be a transition phase. This<br />

transition phase is the Expanded form. <strong>The</strong> Expanded form expresses exchanges through<br />

“generally accepted social forms <strong>of</strong> value,” so long as one commodity can be exchanged for<br />

many different commodities. <strong>The</strong> Expanded form introduces the common denominator <strong>of</strong><br />

an exchange, for example cattle, for other goods. <strong>The</strong> Expanded form sets the transition to<br />

the General form, where all exchanges in society can use a common commodity (gold) as its<br />

exchange.<br />

Hans: Good enough, although I’d like to hear it argued more clearly why the Expanded form, and not the General<br />

form, is the obvious negation <strong>of</strong> the Simple form.<br />

Next Message by KA is [585].<br />

[416] Lana: In the Annotations by Hans, this section discusses the Expanded Form <strong>of</strong><br />

Value. However, Marx begins with the Simple Form <strong>of</strong> Value, 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is equivalent<br />

to 1 coat. As previously discussed, use value is not the same as value, therefore this basic


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 139<br />

exchange will not be upheld in a normal market as each individual will have different needs<br />

and wants and may not be willing or able to make that particular exchange. <strong>The</strong> expected<br />

next step would be to bring in the General form, introducing money as currency. Instead,<br />

he acquaints us with the concept <strong>of</strong> the Expanded Form <strong>of</strong> Value, giving the linen producer<br />

more use-values in the exchange in a one-commodity society.<br />

Marx includes this extra step because it is not possible to simply move from a barter<br />

economy to a money economy. <strong>The</strong> trade must be removed from the equation and then<br />

the result <strong>of</strong> this must be abated. As money is related to all commodities via prices, this<br />

somewhat return to “barterism” experiences improvement due to the Expanded Form <strong>of</strong><br />

Value.<br />

Next Message by Lana is [590].<br />

[434] Alex: graded A When reading Marx’s rationalizations about Simple and General<br />

form <strong>of</strong> value, I would have also assumed that a logical way to compare these two ideas is to<br />

jump from one straight to the other, so as to compare them side by side. I was thinking this<br />

would have been the logical way to go about, however, Hans explains it otherwise. Hans<br />

states in [173] that this was due to the fact that Marx wanted to demonstrate the necessity<br />

<strong>of</strong> money as a form <strong>of</strong> value as its most imperative quality through a negation <strong>of</strong> a negation.<br />

First <strong>of</strong> all, Marx negates the form <strong>of</strong> barter, or the Simple form <strong>of</strong> value, when he states that<br />

“since the bodily form <strong>of</strong> each individual <strong>of</strong> commodity is here one Particular equivalent<br />

form amongst innumerable other Particular equivalent forms, the only equivalent forms in<br />

existence are limited equivalent forms, each <strong>of</strong> which excludes any <strong>of</strong> the others.” This<br />

analysis explained in simpler terms by Hans because “although the Expanded form <strong>of</strong> value<br />

covers all commodity owners <strong>of</strong>fering linen, there is not one Particular equivalent which is<br />

accepted by every commodity-owner <strong>of</strong>fering linen.” This is explaining that Marx negates<br />

the simple form <strong>of</strong> value, which is barter, by stating that barter is useless and money is<br />

necessary in this case since its is “connected through all commodities through their prices.”<br />

Which then leads to the negation <strong>of</strong> this negation (the negation <strong>of</strong> the Expanded form)<br />

and it is where this agreement comes that money is what the linen holders have in common,<br />

and it is the exemplary form <strong>of</strong> exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities. This is the General form <strong>of</strong> value,<br />

which is the negation <strong>of</strong> the negation.<br />

Hans: You should pay closer attention to the transitions from the Simple to the Expanded form <strong>of</strong> value, and from<br />

the Expanded to the General form <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Next Message by Alex is [451].<br />

[497] Cougar: graded A+ It is the input <strong>of</strong> labor in all commodities that validates the<br />

simple form <strong>of</strong> value where, in the case <strong>of</strong> a linen weaver, 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is worth the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> 1 coat. Although the weaver may not fully know the socially-acceptable labor<br />

content <strong>of</strong> the coat, her evaluation <strong>of</strong> the coat’s use-value is expressed in her willingness to<br />

trade 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen, <strong>of</strong> which she fully understands the labor content. As LuBr [170]<br />

points out, the value <strong>of</strong> the linen is expressed in the use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat in this particular<br />

social exchange. In this phase <strong>of</strong> Marx’s abstraction money is still non-existent. <strong>The</strong><br />

weaver has focused her commodity production solely on linen and must utilize that linen to<br />

acquire other necessities by means <strong>of</strong> exchange. Naturally the simple form <strong>of</strong> value expands<br />

to an intermediate, where the weaver can exchange linen for other commodities justified by<br />

140 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the homogeneous input <strong>of</strong> labor in all commodities. Just as with the coat, the weaver expresses<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> her linen in terms <strong>of</strong> other use-values required. <strong>The</strong> progression <strong>of</strong> the<br />

simple form <strong>of</strong> value to this point reveals the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities. Upon<br />

exchange with other use-values, the value <strong>of</strong> linen is established in the market. Because <strong>of</strong><br />

the homogeneous nature <strong>of</strong> commodities, suddenly value becomes a very complicated characteristic.<br />

Linen could have millions <strong>of</strong> potential values based on its exchange with other<br />

commodities in the market. Taking from Hans’ comments to LuBr [170], the negation <strong>of</strong><br />

this intermediary step by Marx leads readers back to a simple form <strong>of</strong> value where the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> all commodities is expressed in only one measuring commodity: money. In this “general<br />

form <strong>of</strong> value” all commodities express their value in terms <strong>of</strong> “price,” or amount <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Like labor, price becomes a homogeneous characteristic <strong>of</strong> all commodities and provides for<br />

their direct exchange in the market. Following LuBr’s concluding remarks in [170], money<br />

coordinates the social aspects <strong>of</strong> labor in the producing realm with the use-value(s) required<br />

by consumers.<br />

Message [497] referenced by [2012fa:180]. Next Message by Cougar is [510].<br />

[506] Tunda: <strong>The</strong> reason why Marx states the forms like this is because they transition<br />

from the Simple form into a more complete form which is the General form.<br />

Next Message by Tunda is [1194].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 267 is 172 in 2002fa, 175 in 2003fa, 202 in 2004fa, 219 in 2007SP, 222 in<br />

2007fa, and 227 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 267 In 158:4, Marx writes the following about the general form <strong>of</strong> value: “Only<br />

this form, therefore, has the effect <strong>of</strong> relating the commodities with each other as values, or<br />

enables them to appear to each other as exchange-values.” Why didn’t he write: “or enables<br />

them to appear to each other as values”?<br />

[167] Robert: graded A+ Marx carefully picked his words (in this case, at least). Marx<br />

is intentionally stating that the general form <strong>of</strong> value allows two different analyses <strong>of</strong> commodities:<br />

1) “relating” values inherent in commodities and 2) observing “appearance” <strong>of</strong><br />

socially derived exchange-values between commodities.<br />

In the <strong>first</strong> analyses, the general form <strong>of</strong> value enables the congealed abstract labor <strong>of</strong> one<br />

commodity, which is inherent in the very core <strong>of</strong> that commodity, to relate to the congealed<br />

abstract labor inherent in the core <strong>of</strong> another commodity. “Relating” is a substantive, real<br />

activity that can only occur at this core level. In the second analyses, “appearance” is a<br />

social, imaginary function that occurs only at the surface. Exchange-value also occurs at<br />

the surface <strong>of</strong> the commodity, i.e., it does not go directly (only by information sent through<br />

channel (2)) to the core <strong>of</strong> a commodity’s value. <strong>The</strong>refore, the general form <strong>of</strong> value also<br />

allows a surface comparison <strong>of</strong> the surface attributes society places on commodities<br />

Marx’s sentence as written states: the general form <strong>of</strong> values allows commodities to relate<br />

at the core level <strong>of</strong> value and appear on the surface to be interchangeable. If Marx wrote<br />

“enables them to appear to each other as values” in the last clause, he would have been<br />

saying, the general form allows commodities to appear to society on the surface to have<br />

value (congealed abstract labor) at their core. This statement makes no sense because Marx<br />

arguments have shown that the socially-derived surface appearance <strong>of</strong> what the capitalist


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 141<br />

believe is the commodity’s value is different than the true value inherent in the core <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity (congealed abstract labor.)<br />

<strong>The</strong>re has been much written in the past in response to this question. <strong>The</strong> responses in<br />

[2003fa:105] and [2007SP:143] and the threads to those responses seem to provide a good<br />

answer to the question. My intent here is to consolidate and clarify the answer.<br />

Message [167] referenced by [174]. Next Message by Robert is [211].<br />

[174] Hans: My Method for writing the Annotations. <strong>The</strong> switch from “value” to<br />

“exchange-value” in the same sentence seems significant to me. If I don’t understand why<br />

Marx switched words, or if I think Marx should not have switched but should have written<br />

“value” both times, then I am likely to have missed some<strong>thing</strong> in his argument. <strong>The</strong>refore<br />

I throw this out to you, my captive audience for this Semester, as one <strong>of</strong> the homework<br />

questions. Robert [167] took it on, and I am grateful that he did it, because he is a careful<br />

reader and thorough thinker. What I will write now is in part inspired by his answer.<br />

Following Robert’s lead, I will look at the two statements one by one.<br />

(1) Only this form has the effect <strong>of</strong> relating the commodities with each other as values.<br />

Here is what I think this means. By expressing all exchange-values in in one and the same<br />

denominator, the General form <strong>of</strong> value is the <strong>first</strong> form <strong>of</strong> value that allows the producers to<br />

see which production methods have the lowest cost and which commodities are in high demand<br />

and to adjust their production schedules accordingly. This reaction by the commodity<br />

producers equalizing their labors is called here by Marx “relating the commodities with each<br />

other as values.” <strong>The</strong> relation <strong>of</strong> the commodities as values can only take place in production<br />

since value is a category <strong>of</strong> production. Marx describes here the effect which the surface<br />

relations have on production.<br />

Now the second statement:<br />

(2) Only this form enables the commodities to appear to each other as exchange-values.<br />

My interpretation: Only if the commodities are produced as values is it possible that their<br />

exchange relations are remotely controlled by their value. Presumably this is what Marx<br />

means by the formulation that only now the commodities are enabled to “appear to each<br />

other as exchange-values.” He does not say they relate to each other as exchange-value,<br />

because their real relation is their relations as values in the production process, i.e., the<br />

commonality <strong>of</strong> all commodities as blobs <strong>of</strong> abstract labor. He says “appear,” because the<br />

exchange relations on the surface are the form <strong>of</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong>, they are remotely controlled<br />

by, the value relations in production. I think Marx would not have considered it wrong to<br />

say “they appear to each other as values,” but he did not say it because on the surface their<br />

value makes itself felt indirectly, not as value (which is a category <strong>of</strong> production) but as<br />

exchangeability. This is why he says “they appear to each other as exchange-value.”<br />

You may think I am reading a lot into Marx. Indeed, if you take only this one sentence,<br />

it alone gives little basis for my interpretation. This interpretation can only then claim to<br />

be taken seriously if it fits together with interpretations <strong>of</strong> the other obscure formulations<br />

by Marx in Capital which cohere with this interpretation here. My procedure writing the<br />

Annotations is therefore not to be too shy but write down carefully what I think I see, and try<br />

142 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

out whether other <strong>thing</strong>s Marx says elsewhere can be interpreted using the same framework.<br />

And in this class I can try out whether my interpretations make sense to you, and I also<br />

benefit from the fresh eyes with which you are looking at the text.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [179].<br />

[185] Deadfamous: graded B+ <strong>The</strong> Simple form <strong>of</strong> value is derived from the commodities’<br />

use-values being exchanged, the Expanded form derives it value from exchanging several<br />

use-values <strong>of</strong> several commodities, that is the only <strong>thing</strong> being exchanged, no<strong>thing</strong> to do<br />

with materials or labor or any<strong>thing</strong>, just use values <strong>of</strong> all commodities to satisfy each other<br />

in whatever combination. However the General form <strong>of</strong> value completely changes directions<br />

and forgets about use value—and realizes that these commodities are directly exchangeable<br />

through a certain substance that all commodities can be exchanged for; this substance which<br />

is the blob <strong>of</strong> abstract human labor is important because there evolves a social connection<br />

to the production process and trade <strong>of</strong> all commodities. So to sum up, Marx did not want<br />

to write “they appear as values” since we are no longer using use-value as a derivative <strong>of</strong><br />

value but we have not named the substance in which all commodities are equal in some way;<br />

this is why he writes “they are enabled to appear as exchange values,” since we don’t really<br />

know what they are equal to yet at this point (abstract human labor).<br />

Message [185] referenced by [183] and [187]. Next Message by Deadfamous is [223].<br />

[187] Hans: Wow, now I get it! A lesson in the art <strong>of</strong> reading. 21 minutes after I submitted<br />

[184], Deadfamous submitted [185] making the same mistake again, even emphasizing<br />

that value is not derived from labor but from the exchange. Deadfamous writes<br />

the Expanded form derives it value from exchanging several use-values <strong>of</strong><br />

several commodities, that is the only <strong>thing</strong> being exchanged, no<strong>thing</strong> to do<br />

with materials or labor or any<strong>thing</strong>,<br />

But then Deadfamous says the General form is completely different – and at this point<br />

I understood where he got his misconception from. Marx and the Annotations say that the<br />

Simple and Expanded form express the value <strong>of</strong> the linen in the use-values <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

in the equivalent form. In other words, when the linen weaver decides to exchange 20 yards<br />

<strong>of</strong> linen for a coat, then she does not compare the labor which she needed to produce the<br />

linen with the labor needed to produce the coat—for two reasons. First <strong>of</strong> all, she does not<br />

know how much labor is in the coat, and secondly, because the coat labor is not relevant for<br />

her. What matters for her exchange decision is the use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat. By making this<br />

exchange she says that she finds it worth while to put her labor into 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen in order<br />

to get the use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat. Marx, with his somewhat more abstract terminology, says<br />

that she expresses the value <strong>of</strong> the linen in the use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat. I hope you understand<br />

now that this does not mean that the value <strong>of</strong> the linen is derived from the comparison <strong>of</strong> the<br />

use-values <strong>of</strong> linen and coat—the value <strong>of</strong> the linen is still derived from the labor it took to<br />

produce the linen.<br />

With the General equivalent the expression is a little different, because the usefulness<br />

<strong>of</strong> gold for filling teeth is eclipsed by its usefulness for buying every<strong>thing</strong> that is on the<br />

market—therefore it is this second usefulness, not the <strong>first</strong>, which the sellers consider when<br />

they set their prices.<br />

Lessons:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 143<br />

(1) Simple, Expanded, and General form <strong>of</strong> value are not different kinds <strong>of</strong> value, but they<br />

are only different ways to express the same old commodity value, i.e., congealed abstract<br />

labor, on the market. “Form” means here: what the <strong>thing</strong> looks like from the outside, i.e., on<br />

the surface <strong>of</strong> the economy.<br />

(2) Deadfamous read the Annotations carefully, but he had certain misconceptions in his<br />

head which caused him to interpret the <strong>thing</strong>s he read completely differently from what<br />

Marx had in mind when he wrote it. This is not just Deadfamous’s problem; this is a known<br />

problem whenever you read some<strong>thing</strong>. It is quite difficult to stay on the same wavelength<br />

as the writer <strong>of</strong> the text and not read <strong>thing</strong>s into the text which are not in the text but only in<br />

your brain. Consider this class as a lesson in the art <strong>of</strong> reading.<br />

Message [187] referenced by [183]. Next Message by Hans is [189].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 268 is 144 in 1999SP, 160 in 2001fa, 173 in 2002fa, 176 in 2003fa, 203 in<br />

2004fa, 200 in 2005fa, 220 in 2007SP, 223 in 2007fa, 228 in 2008fa, 241 in 2009fa, 234<br />

in 2011fa, and 244 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 268 Describe the joint work <strong>of</strong> all commodities which is necessary to appropriately<br />

express the value <strong>of</strong> one commodity.<br />

[172] Milly: graded B+ Joint work <strong>of</strong> all commodities. Marx states in 158:5/o, “a commodity<br />

only acquires a general expression <strong>of</strong> its value if, at the same time, all other commodities<br />

express their values in the same equivalent.”<br />

First, commodities must be able to be exchanged in different quantities <strong>of</strong> use-values,<br />

where a certain number <strong>of</strong> use-values <strong>of</strong> one kind can be exchanged for a certain number <strong>of</strong><br />

use-values <strong>of</strong> another kind. <strong>The</strong> commonality that allows this to happen is labor. Tonight<br />

in class Hans pointed out that it is impossible to compare a computer programmer to a<br />

brick layer, however the market acts as if all labor powers are equal. Value then becomes<br />

homogeneous and commodities can be traded with everyone and representation <strong>of</strong> value is<br />

in every exchange.<br />

Hans: You are bringing fragments <strong>of</strong> the theory which are right but you are not connecting them. All the <strong>thing</strong>s<br />

you are saying are pieces <strong>of</strong> one coherent theory. It is not trivial to get this coherent theory into your head, but it is<br />

also not rocket science. Keep trying.<br />

Message [172] referenced by [184] and [385]. Next Message by Milly is [224].<br />

[180] Guh: Joint work. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a commodity according to Marx in 158:5/o is<br />

“a commodity gains a general expression its value only when, at the same time, all other<br />

commodities express their values in the same equivalent.” <strong>The</strong> joint work <strong>of</strong> all commodities<br />

is needed in order to determine the value in a generic form. Moreover, after a commodity<br />

has created a general value it then be compared to other commodities. This then allows for<br />

the appropriate expression <strong>of</strong> each commodity’s value in the general equivalent, so that the<br />

value can be quantitativley compared to all other commodities (see [2008fa:497]).<br />

Message [180] referenced by [184]. Next Message by Guh is [206].<br />

[183] Fisher: Commodities working jointly. <strong>The</strong> joint work <strong>of</strong> all commodities that<br />

Marx mentions, is the act <strong>of</strong> each individual commodity having been traded for another<br />

good to gain an identity or value. A commodity can be compared to another with a similar<br />

use value and equivalents, it can gain an identity and history, which gives people assurance<br />

<strong>of</strong> its quality when trading for that commodity. Once all commodities are on record and<br />

144 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

have established an identity for their use, then open trade may take place with confidence<br />

among traders. When many commodities are traded then there is a joint work at hand. It is<br />

interesting when he mentions that it “must be supervised by the state”, which in my opinion,<br />

might have led to monetary policy.<br />

Hans: What you are writing contains the errors I discussed in [184] and [187]. But there is a big difference between<br />

your message here and [185]: I do not recognize any elements <strong>of</strong> Marx or the Annotations in your answer. Have<br />

you read the assigned readings? <strong>The</strong>re are only faint echos <strong>of</strong> [1999SP:153.1] and [2002fa:159.4] in your answer,<br />

i.e., I do not see that you could have obtained this answer from the archives <strong>of</strong> past class discussions. Do you think<br />

you know telepathically what Marx means without reading him or anyone who has read him?<br />

Next Message by Fisher is [241].<br />

[184] Hans: Joint work versus work in parallel. <strong>The</strong> presently assigned readings are<br />

not discussing how to create or determine value. We already know how value is created: by<br />

labor. <strong>The</strong> creation <strong>of</strong> value requires the work <strong>of</strong> the laborers, not work by the commodities<br />

or their handlers. Commodities already have value before they even enter the market.<br />

<strong>The</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> the present readings is the form <strong>of</strong> value, i.e., the relations between the<br />

economic agents that tell them that their commodities have value. Marx’s criterion for the<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> value is amazingly simple: he says that the forms <strong>of</strong> value must reflect on the surface<br />

<strong>of</strong> the economy as faithfully as possible the <strong>thing</strong>s which we know about value. <strong>The</strong><br />

Marx quote used by Milly [172] and Guh [180] is therefore not the definition <strong>of</strong> value and<br />

has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with how value is determined. It formulates a condition that needs to be<br />

satisfied so that the commodities reflect their values accurately on the surface: all commodities<br />

must express their values in the same commodity, called the General equivalent. (Marx<br />

is talking here not about quantitative accuracy but qualitative concordance.) A more detailed<br />

explanation what this Marx quote says is in my [2009fa:107].<br />

<strong>The</strong> most instructive example <strong>of</strong> such a surface reflection <strong>of</strong> value is money. Money is<br />

a simple homogeneous commodity (gold) which measures the values <strong>of</strong> all ordinary commodities<br />

by their prices, and into which all other commodities have to be converted in order<br />

to find the way from producer to consumer. Commodities express their values in money,<br />

i.e., they have prices (which are only capable <strong>of</strong> quantitative differences) because their value<br />

comes from the abstract human labor which produced them, which is likewise only capable<br />

<strong>of</strong> quantitative differences.<br />

Do commodities have to work in order to get prices? Guh’s answer in [180] is that<br />

expressing their values in one and the same commodity (gold) is work. This is true but it is<br />

not joint work; rather it is work which each commodity has to do separately. <strong>The</strong>y all do the<br />

same but they do not cooperate, rather they work in parallel.<br />

But there is one aspect <strong>of</strong> this which does require coordination, i.e., joint work: namely<br />

the selection <strong>of</strong> the General equivalent. All commodity owners have to agree on expressing<br />

the values <strong>of</strong> their commodities in one and the same commodity (gold). This act, Marx<br />

called it the “preparatory act <strong>of</strong> circulation,” is the only occasion where they have to perform<br />

joint work. This coordination is the reason why Marx says in 158:5/o, in the sentence before<br />

the sentence quoted by Milly and Guh, “<strong>The</strong> General form <strong>of</strong> value ... can only arise as a<br />

joint work <strong>of</strong> the whole world <strong>of</strong> commodities.”<br />

Message [184] referenced by [183], [187], and [808]. Next Message by Hans is [187].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 145<br />

[372] Atticus: graded B– <strong>The</strong> joint work <strong>of</strong> all commodities describes the relation between<br />

all commodities expressing their values in each other. Laborers use concrete labor to produce<br />

commodities that are qualitatively different from one another. Without these qualitatively<br />

different forms <strong>of</strong> labor exchanges could not be made. Use-values are exchanged for other<br />

use-values. <strong>The</strong> amalgamation <strong>of</strong> all exchanges are done through the relations between all<br />

commodities expressing their values in one another. This is done quantitatively by reducing<br />

all concrete labors to a common factor, abstract labor. Abstract labor is congealed in all usevalues<br />

and this is the common factor that all commodities can exchange themselves with one<br />

another.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> joint work is the selection <strong>of</strong> one and the same commodity in which they all express their values.<br />

Next Message by Atticus is [575].<br />

[385] Utefan: Going back to linen; 1 hr. produces 20 yards and is exchanged with other<br />

commodities that also took 1 hr. to produce, i.e. 1 coat, 1 bushel <strong>of</strong> corn, 5 c.d.’s, etc. <strong>The</strong>se<br />

other commodities that are traded help producers identify the value <strong>of</strong> linen for they know<br />

that after exchanging a coat, bushel <strong>of</strong> corn, or 5 c.d.’s they will receive 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen<br />

which also took the same amount <strong>of</strong> abstract labor to produce. We can also now understand<br />

that if 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat, and 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 5 c.d.’s; then 1 coat = 5 c.d.’s.<br />

Hans: My [2009fa:107] applies to this answer too.<br />

Utefan: If my answer is also applicable to yours then why did I get a C- for it?<br />

Utefan: Every<strong>thing</strong> I just said is the same as your answer only compact not to mention in the book with the<br />

annotations you had us buy. Read it again.<br />

Hans: In [2009fa:107] I said: “Ivan thought that a commodity gains value only through its exchange for all other<br />

commodities,” and I tried to explain the error in this. Your error is similar though not identical as Ivan’s. You are<br />

saying “these other commodities that are traded help producers identify the value <strong>of</strong> linen.” Since you don’t see<br />

how my [2009fa:107] applies to you, I will send out a message explaining in detail what in your answer is wrong.<br />

But <strong>first</strong> I have to grade the resubmissions <strong>of</strong> everyone.<br />

Utefan: No, that is not what I am saying I am saying that through the exchange one can see how commodities are<br />

exchanged. In your annotations on page 159 and 160 We are saying the same <strong>thing</strong>. Not to mention how poor the<br />

grade is in comparison. You misunderstood me with both questions.<br />

Utefan: I just read over the review you gave us and the student named Milly under post [172] received a B+ for<br />

saying the same <strong>thing</strong> I did. Why are my grades so much lower?<br />

Next Message by Utefan is [546].<br />

[428] BBM: graded A– If you take a good to a market and want to know its value you will<br />

have to speak with each merchant to find out how much <strong>of</strong> their good they will give you for<br />

yours. <strong>The</strong> number <strong>of</strong> ratios you would have to remember would be infinite. However if all<br />

commodities expressed themselves in one commodity then you would be able to figure out<br />

how much your good is worth in terms <strong>of</strong> this one commodity.<br />

First Message by BBM is [427].<br />

[457] Ryan: <strong>The</strong> joint work <strong>of</strong> all commodities needed to express the value <strong>of</strong> one commodity<br />

can be expressed as the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> each individual item, one to another. As<br />

items begin to change hands from one party to another they are given a value. First their usevalue.<br />

<strong>The</strong>ir use-value is not given by the party that owns the item but by the purchaser <strong>of</strong><br />

the item. This <strong>of</strong> course is because the purchaser places the value <strong>of</strong> the item based on need<br />

to want, the owner <strong>of</strong> the item can not affect these. Once the use-value is determined by both<br />

parties, then the exchange value can be determined, typically one item (and consumer) will<br />

take an active role as the item was produced to be sold for a needed good. <strong>The</strong> other item<br />

will take a passive role as it is what is needed and the owner must think the other item has a<br />

146 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

high enough use value to even want to trade. Once exchange-value have been determined for<br />

every commodity (that is available for exchange) will we then gain a value in which we can<br />

measure the exchange value <strong>of</strong> all items in the market. Once we introduce money into the<br />

equation then it becomes easier to value each item as they are compared to the same <strong>thing</strong>,<br />

money. Once money has been added, then all value for all commodities can be compared<br />

(one to one) without having to worry about a third or fourth. For example three items may all<br />

have a different exchange-value between them. But when all three are compared to money<br />

it is very easy to determine the value <strong>of</strong> each as it relates to the others.<br />

Hans: You are explaining how every<strong>thing</strong> gets better once money is introduced in the equation. Alas, money does<br />

not fall from the sky. <strong>The</strong> joint work <strong>of</strong> all commodities is therefore the decision which <strong>of</strong> the commodities will be<br />

the money commodity.<br />

Next Message by Ryan is [709].<br />

[471] GoUtes: In order to truly understand the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity, we need to understand<br />

the joint work <strong>of</strong> all commodities and understand how value is measured. One <strong>thing</strong><br />

that Hans mentions is “the most instructive example <strong>of</strong> value is money.” One commodity<br />

such as a pie crust can be measured by its monetary value, a pie crust alone may cost 1<br />

dollar alone but add chocolate mousse which could cost 1 dollar and some whip cream, another<br />

dollar, to create the pie with three separate elements may cost 3 dollars. If you add<br />

the elements together and factor in labor and all the commodities, its value would be more<br />

as is indicated in stores, a pie costs 8 dollars. So what may be a lesser amount as separate<br />

commodities, when joined to create a pie with all commodities joined together, the value<br />

goes up.<br />

Hans: This is not what Marx meant.<br />

Next Message by GoUtes is [704].<br />

[496] Kat: <strong>The</strong> joint work <strong>of</strong> commodities necessary to express the value <strong>of</strong> a single<br />

commodity by determining its relationship to all other commodities. As Hans says “the<br />

relations between the economic agents that tell them that their commodities have value.”<br />

A “General Equivalent” must be determined through which all commodities can express<br />

their value. <strong>The</strong> most common equivalent is money, whether it be American dollars or<br />

gold, through which commodity prices establish value. What Marx calls a “preparatory act<br />

<strong>of</strong> circulation” is the joint work commodities must go through in order to agree upon one<br />

equivalent through which to express their value.<br />

Hans: You had “necessary to establish and express.” I deleted “establish” because the value is already established<br />

in the production process. Right now the question is how to express the established value on the surface, and you<br />

answered this correctly.<br />

Next Message by Kat is [567].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 277 is 166 in 2001fa, 184 in 2003fa, 211 in 2004fa, 207 in 2005fa, 227<br />

in 2007SP, 239 in 2008SP, 250 in 2009fa, 245 in 2011fa, and 255 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 277 What is the difference between commodity fetishism and the fetish-like<br />

character <strong>of</strong> commodities?<br />

[308] Babyceta: content A+ form 90% Fetishism and Fetish-like are Opposites. Fetishism<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities is the belief that inanimate objects possess certain social determinations<br />

given to them by physical nature—and the ability to transmit these properties to individuals.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 147<br />

Like Hans’s example <strong>of</strong> his mother saying gold is valuable because it is shiny and beautiful.<br />

Or we may realize that these determinations are social, but accept them as if they were<br />

natural outcomes, believing there is no<strong>thing</strong> that can be done about the situation.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities, however, is a social structure in which the products<br />

<strong>of</strong> society are carriers <strong>of</strong> social relations resembling natural forces, and are capable <strong>of</strong><br />

behaving in humanistic ways, or <strong>of</strong> transforming physical matter. <strong>The</strong>y are essentially a<br />

conduit <strong>of</strong> social relations transmitted by physical characteristics. We may say, for example,<br />

that our money in the bank is growing because <strong>of</strong> compounding interest, or that inflation is<br />

causing the economy to behave in a certain manner. Fetish-like is a natural force based on<br />

social construction, and fetishism is a social force based on natural construction.<br />

Hans: Great thinking, but your original writing in this particular piece was terribly sloppy—so much so that it<br />

made your essay almost incomprehensible. Here are your passages which I changed:<br />

Your <strong>first</strong> sentence (the changed words in italics): Fetishism <strong>of</strong> commodities is the belief that inanimate objects<br />

process certain social determinations endowed by physical nature that enable them to transmit these properties to<br />

individuals.<br />

I reformulated your “accept them as natural outcomes” to say “accept them as if they were natural outcomes.”<br />

So far I think (hope) I did not change your intended meaning but made it clearer. If this is not the case please<br />

let me know. <strong>The</strong> next change I made is major surgery, because you made a logical error which I tried to fix. Marx<br />

believes that commodities have a fetish-like character, but this fetish-like character itself is not a belief but it is a<br />

special characteristic <strong>of</strong> the social structure. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> sentence <strong>of</strong> you last paragraph was originally<br />

<strong>The</strong> fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities, however, is the belief that the products <strong>of</strong> society are natural forces,<br />

and are capable <strong>of</strong> behaving in humanistic ways, or <strong>of</strong> transforming physical matter.<br />

Message [308] referenced by [326], [411], [443], and [1034]. Next Message by Babyceta is [404].<br />

[326] Hans: This is what dialectics looks like. In [308], Babyceta teaches us dialectical<br />

thinking. He says that there is not only a difference between the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity and commodity-fetishism, but that they are actually opposites <strong>of</strong> each other. In<br />

his words:<br />

Fetish-like is a natural force based on social construction, and fetishism is<br />

a social force based on natural construction.<br />

Marx would probably have used the formulation<br />

<strong>The</strong> fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity is the naturalization <strong>of</strong> society,<br />

and commodity fetishism is the socialization <strong>of</strong> nature<br />

“Naturalization <strong>of</strong> society” means that social relations take the form <strong>of</strong> (quasi-)natural<br />

predicates <strong>of</strong> objects, and “socialization <strong>of</strong> nature” means that nature is thought to have<br />

social powers. People live in a world in which society is naturalized, and they are confused<br />

about it, they think that nature is socialized. It is a common occurrence that some<strong>thing</strong><br />

is mistaken to be its exact opposite. And the discovery <strong>of</strong> such dialectical inversions is,<br />

according to Hegel and Marx, not just a cute-sounding aphorism but true scientific insight.<br />

<strong>The</strong> world is full <strong>of</strong> contradictions—Hegel said every<strong>thing</strong> contains its opposite in itself.<br />

Becoming aware <strong>of</strong> these contradictions gives us a deeper understanding <strong>of</strong> the world.<br />

Message [326] referenced by [329], [727], [1034], [2012fa:227], [2012fa:326.1], [2012fa:330], and [2012fa:1014].<br />

Next Message by Hans is [329].<br />

148 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 278 is 121 in 1995WI, 98 in 1995ut, 131 in 1996sp, 133 in 1996ut, 181 in<br />

2002fa, 185 in 2003fa, 212 in 2004fa, 208 in 2005fa, 228 in 2007SP, 233 in 2007fa, 238<br />

in 2008fa, 251 in 2009fa, and 247 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 278 Which evidence prompts Marx to say, at the beginning <strong>of</strong> the Commodity<br />

Fetishism section, that the commodity is “intricate” or “mysterious”?<br />

[193] School: <strong>The</strong> reason why Marx was prompted to say that the commodity is “intricate”<br />

or “mysterious” was because with any given commodity it can have many complexly<br />

arranged elements and can be judged differently based on use-value, exchange value, or<br />

many other types <strong>of</strong> values based on analytical thinking. Although there are many ways to<br />

define value to a <strong>thing</strong>, or object, Marx defines the value <strong>of</strong> a <strong>thing</strong> or object by the labor put<br />

into the creation <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

Just like Goethe [2008SP:278] states “Marx would not agree with Le Trosne when he<br />

writes that the value <strong>of</strong> a <strong>thing</strong> consists in its exchange-proportions with other <strong>thing</strong>s. Marx<br />

sees exchange value as the exterior expression <strong>of</strong> the labor used to produce the <strong>thing</strong>. Le<br />

Trosne only sees the exterior value as exchange-value; he does not see the interior value<br />

which is the labor content.”<br />

I agree with the above statement, for example if we look at colleges around the state <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Utah</strong> there are many places to obtain a degree. Whether you go to Salt Lake Community<br />

College or whether you go to <strong>Utah</strong> State <strong>University</strong> you can retain the same knowledge and<br />

degree, i.e. you can put forth the same amount <strong>of</strong> labor to get the same end results. In this<br />

case that would be to attain higher education.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> labor you are mentioning in conjunction with the commodity <strong>of</strong> a college education is the labor necessary<br />

to consume this commodity. Marx, by contrast, looks at the labor necessary to produce commodities.<br />

Message [193] referenced by [198]. Next Message by School is [262].<br />

[198] Hans: What does the mystery <strong>of</strong> the commodity mean empirically? Several<br />

times in Capital, Marx claims that empirical evidence can be misleading—or, to be more<br />

specific and blunt, that our lived experience in capitalism lies about it what the capitalist<br />

social system really is like.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> these discrepancies where <strong>thing</strong>s seem different than they really are is mentioned<br />

by Marx right at the beginning <strong>of</strong> the section about the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Marx says that the commodity seems trivial, but its scientific analysis shows that it is<br />

intricate and mysterious. Let me again be more specific and blunt: we think commodities<br />

are <strong>thing</strong>s which we use and control, but in reality commodities have an inner life and they<br />

control us.<br />

So what is Marx’s evidence on which he bases this claim? Marx tells us what this evidence<br />

is, it is the scientific analysis <strong>of</strong> the commodity. His words in 163:3/o are: “its (the<br />

commodity’s) analysis brings out that it is quite intricate...”<br />

It is no<strong>thing</strong> new in science that the results <strong>of</strong> one scientific step become the raw material<br />

for further investigation. What is the evidence for it that matter consists <strong>of</strong> atomic nuclei<br />

with clouds <strong>of</strong> electrons around them? <strong>The</strong> entire science <strong>of</strong> chemistry is this evidence.<br />

<strong>The</strong> periodic table was originally the empirical discovery that the chemical properties <strong>of</strong><br />

elements recur periodically if you sort them by weight. That was entirely unexpected—what


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 149<br />

does weight have to do with chemical properties? It demanded further scientific exploration.<br />

This new investigation then led to <strong>thing</strong>s which chemistry itself could not have predicted:<br />

nuclear power or the spectral analysis <strong>of</strong> light coming from stars showing that the universe<br />

is expanding.<br />

Now you might say: science is only useful if it explains <strong>thing</strong>s which we can experience.<br />

Which part <strong>of</strong> our experiences does Marx throw light on with his scientific discovery that<br />

the commodity is mysterious, and with his explorations <strong>of</strong> the reasons why it is mysterious?<br />

What is the analog <strong>of</strong> nuclear power and spectral analysis in our case?<br />

Here the answer is tw<strong>of</strong>old. <strong>The</strong> Annotations give a long list <strong>of</strong> economic phenomena<br />

where the economy acts as if it had a life <strong>of</strong> its own, almost like a natural force:<br />

Many economic phenomena in capitalism have an outwardly “magical” character. <strong>The</strong><br />

power <strong>of</strong> money to purchase every<strong>thing</strong>, or the power <strong>of</strong> capital to grow quasi on its own<br />

accord, sudden financial crises and breakdowns <strong>of</strong> economic growth, inflation, unemployment,<br />

stock market booms and busts, salaries which have no<strong>thing</strong> to do with the skills or<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> the recipient, the tendency <strong>of</strong> wealth to concentrate rather than dissipate—<br />

up to the mother <strong>of</strong> all economic dilemmas <strong>of</strong> the present day: why is it more important<br />

to increases corporate pr<strong>of</strong>its than preserve the livability <strong>of</strong> our planet? <strong>The</strong>se are the big<br />

and dangerous magical phenomena where the economy seems to have a separate “life” and<br />

seems quite unconcerned about individual well-being. Although the economy is the product<br />

<strong>of</strong> the economic agents, it acts as a force independent <strong>of</strong> them. On an individual level, modern<br />

consumerism, i.e., people’s over-attachment to <strong>thing</strong>s, the social status conveyed by the<br />

clothes one wears or the car one drives, or the fact that scientists (a minority in the natural<br />

sciences but a majority in the social sciences) and the majority <strong>of</strong> newspaper reporters distort<br />

the facts to suit corporate interests—this also is evidence <strong>of</strong> economic forces interfering with<br />

our lives to a degree one should not expect in a society which has as much wealth as ours.<br />

Before investigating each <strong>of</strong> those in detail, Marx tries to uncover the root cause where<br />

this magical character comes from. This, he claims, is best done if we look at this mysterious<br />

character in its nascent state, where it is barely visible that the <strong>thing</strong> is mysterious at all, and<br />

that is the commodity. This brings us to the second part <strong>of</strong> the answer: this analysis has<br />

implications for how this natural-force like behavior <strong>of</strong> the economy might be overcome.<br />

School [193] looks at the use-value and the value <strong>of</strong> commodities in turn. This is good,<br />

but he makes mistakes in both.<br />

Regarding use-values School reminds us that commodities are <strong>of</strong>ten mechanically or electronically<br />

or chemically intricate little apparatuses. Marx by contrast says in the very next<br />

sentence in 163:3/o that as use-values commodities are not mysterious. Use-values can<br />

therefore not have been Marx’s reason for calling the commodity mysterious (and question<br />

278 asks specifically for Marx’s reasons).<br />

Regarding value, School makes the mistake <strong>of</strong> thinking that valuation <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

by labor is one <strong>of</strong> many possible valuations chosen by Marx—presumably because Marx<br />

considers this a socially just valuation. This is a basic misunderstanding <strong>of</strong> the whole book.<br />

It is not the purpose <strong>of</strong> Marx’s Capital to develop how commodities should be valued. Laborbased<br />

value is how, if Marx’s theory is right, really existing capitalism in fact determines<br />

150 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

prices. This seems deceptively fair, but my [94] tried to show why this is not a good <strong>thing</strong> at<br />

all—just because <strong>of</strong> the one-dimensionality <strong>of</strong> it, without even speaking <strong>of</strong> the exploitation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the workers based on the fact that they produce all value.<br />

Message [198] referenced by [199], [203], and [323]. Next Message by Hans is [199].<br />

[203] Kaush: Intricate and mysterious. In his quest to unravel and understand the<br />

mysteries <strong>of</strong> the commodity, Marx rules out as the culprit the use-value, the content <strong>of</strong> the<br />

value, and the production process. Though the commodity seems at the outset, simple,<br />

obvious and trivial, the scientific analysis seems to beg otherwise. What seems a simple<br />

object had turned out to be some<strong>thing</strong> complicated. When Marx uncovered contradictions in<br />

the simple surface properties <strong>of</strong> the commodity which led him to probe deeper, he discovered<br />

a new world <strong>of</strong> intricate metaphysical hairsplitting and theological niceties. It is intricate<br />

because the commodity has many undeveloped determinations which can be manifested in<br />

various forms, from the simple exchangeability <strong>of</strong> two commodities to the establishment <strong>of</strong><br />

gold or money (the god <strong>of</strong> commodities) as a general equivalent <strong>of</strong> the exchange value in the<br />

relation to the rest <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Hans: Good summary <strong>of</strong> the Annotations, but have you read [198] which specifically explained and answered<br />

question 278?<br />

Next Message by Kaush is [297].<br />

[205] Sly: A deeper look at the commodity. For my free discussion post I’ve decided<br />

to inject my opinions and critiques as to why Marx believes that the commodity is “intricate”.<br />

It is already stated clearly in the text [1.4.a.] that the commodity is intricate because<br />

“it has many determinations, it has not only use-value but also value, which manifests itself<br />

in various forms—from the simple exchangeability <strong>of</strong> two commodities to the power<br />

<strong>of</strong> money to buy every<strong>thing</strong>.” [p.g. 179]. <strong>The</strong> commodity itself has evolved into some<strong>thing</strong><br />

much more complex, and convoluted because every person in the economy has a different<br />

use/need/opinion/want for a commodity. It is implied in [1.4] that people purchase certain<br />

commodities for “social status conveyed by the clothes one wears or the car one drives” [p.g.<br />

181], but I also believe that individuals are guided towards those decisions by other forces<br />

such as advertisements, and predetermined thoughts that a commodity is better/longer lasting<br />

if its a particular brand. Take for example someone electing to purchase a Toyota manufactured<br />

car instead <strong>of</strong> a Ford manufactured car because they believe that Toyota produces the<br />

superior product, whether it be due to biases or a simple recommendation. This is why I<br />

agree with Marx that commodities are “intricate”, because there are so many driving forces<br />

incorporated into the purchasing decision <strong>of</strong> a commodity that it can’t be determined as a<br />

simple piece <strong>of</strong> the pie.<br />

Next Message by Sly is [417].<br />

[218] She: (graded A+) What is so mysterious about Commodities? Marx says that<br />

commodities are mysterious due to the underlying social relations which they embody. He<br />

says that use-values and the determinants <strong>of</strong> value, quality and quantity <strong>of</strong> labor, are not<br />

mysterious; it is the “fact that the commodity reflects the social characteristics <strong>of</strong> men’s own<br />

labor as objective characteristics <strong>of</strong> the products <strong>of</strong> labor themselves,” [164:3/o].<br />

I think what Marx is saying here is that the mystery really lies in the motivations that<br />

the prospect <strong>of</strong> exchange brings about. <strong>The</strong>re is a social relationship between producers <strong>of</strong><br />

different <strong>thing</strong>s that is embodied and represented by the commodities they produce. Marx


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 151<br />

says that, “. . . as soon as men start to work for each other in any way, their labor also assumes<br />

a social form,” [164:1]. Producers are working for each other in the sense that say a baker<br />

produces bread for a carpenter who in turn produces a table for him. In this relationship,<br />

they are essentially working for each other. <strong>The</strong>y exchange commodities, with different usevalues,<br />

rather than exchanging concrete labor for a wage. Marx says later on that the social<br />

characteristics <strong>of</strong> private labor only appear within exchange [165:2/o].<br />

Marx says there is a social relation, “. . . <strong>of</strong> the producers to the sum total <strong>of</strong> labor as a<br />

social relation between objects, a relation which exists apart from and outside the producers,”<br />

[164:3/o]. In this sentence he has explained that there are properties <strong>of</strong> commodities which<br />

are outside the control <strong>of</strong> the producers; they are thus mysterious to them.<br />

Next Message by She is [296].<br />

[388] Trap: Marx wants to understand capitalism and what motivates it, and in order to<br />

do this he looks at the base <strong>of</strong> heart <strong>of</strong> capitalism, the commodity. He says that members<br />

<strong>of</strong> a capitalist society have a commodity fetishism which is a false interpretation <strong>of</strong> the social<br />

relations. He then says commodities have a fetish-like character, which is the porperty<br />

possessed in the social relations. He begins his exploration by discovering what is not mysterious<br />

about the commodity. <strong>The</strong> most obvious is its use-value, which refers to any use <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity. He then looks a the exchange-value, which at <strong>first</strong> seems contradictory, but<br />

is not mysterious. <strong>The</strong> mystery has to do with the commodity itself, when he simply looks<br />

at the commodity and tries to explain it, it creates contradictions, so it can’t be some<strong>thing</strong><br />

“obvious and trivial.” For example, looking at the use-value and exchange-value themselves<br />

lead to immediate contradiction.<br />

But the most mysterious part <strong>of</strong> the commodity is why prices <strong>of</strong> the commodity are difficult<br />

to predict? This is not from our lack <strong>of</strong> knowledge about the commodity, we <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

believe that we control the commodity and it is a part <strong>of</strong> our capitalistic society, however the<br />

commodity has intrinsic power, that in fact controls us. An excellent example <strong>of</strong> how important<br />

commodities are, is the power <strong>of</strong> money. Marx doesn’t talk in this chapter much about<br />

money and capital, but I think it is important for understanding the “magical” character <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities. <strong>The</strong>y are mysterious because <strong>of</strong> the invisible social relations. Money has the<br />

power to buy every other commodity, it is accepted for every<strong>thing</strong>, which Marx considers<br />

extremely mysterious, however he doesn’t start with this because in order to understand that<br />

power <strong>of</strong> money, it is necessary to understand the power <strong>of</strong> any commodity that stands on its<br />

own.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> mysterious part is not the commodity itself, it is the discrepancy between form and content <strong>of</strong> the value<br />

determinations.<br />

Next Message by Trap is [686].<br />

[392] Orville: graded B Fetishistic Clocks. <strong>The</strong> commodity is “mysterious” because it<br />

seems to function as a living, brea<strong>thing</strong> being. On the surface, there is little mystery behind<br />

what a clock, for instance, is. <strong>The</strong> majority are pieces <strong>of</strong> plastic with a battery that turns the<br />

hour and minute and second hand. <strong>The</strong> mystery comes in when you observe what people<br />

do as they are living around that clock. People allow the clock to determine what time<br />

they will meet, eat, sleep, wake-up, leave, congregate, and the list goes on. <strong>The</strong> clock falls<br />

under the fetishistic view <strong>of</strong> the commodity owner or observer. <strong>The</strong> clock begins to have a<br />

certain degree <strong>of</strong> power over people as if it contains some kind <strong>of</strong> knowledge that humans do<br />

152 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

not. This fetishistic view is not unique to clocks; the economy, computers, social networks,<br />

foods, money, rare gems, precious stones, phones, credit cards, among thousands <strong>of</strong> others<br />

are perceived in the same manner. This is where the “mysterious” characters come from, not<br />

the commodity but actually social relations.<br />

Hans: This is better than saying fetishism is obsession with use-values, but it is still not right, because you still tie<br />

the fetishism to the use-value <strong>of</strong> the clock or computer. You are making the same mistake as Ryoung [2008SP:255].<br />

Strangely, your in-class answer was quite different and completely correct.<br />

Next Message by Orville is [520].<br />

[397] School: Why is this Mysterious? <strong>The</strong> reason why Marx says that a commodity<br />

is “intricate” or “mysterious” is because a commodity is determined by its value. So how<br />

is value defined? This is defined by three <strong>thing</strong>s. 1st, substance such as abstract human<br />

labor, brain, muscle, and body. 2nd, quantity, such as how much labor was put forth to<br />

make the commodity. 3rd, form, this is the social relation that creates feelings by having<br />

the commodity. Marx said that if you take a closer look at them all individually (substance,<br />

quality and form) and can understand them individually. But when you put them together in<br />

one scenario they don’t make sense that is why they are “mysterious”.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> form <strong>of</strong> value is not “the social relation that creates feelings by having the commodity” but it is those<br />

surface interactions which give producers the information so that they can distinguish which is the cheapest production<br />

method etc.<br />

Marx says that the value determinations “considered for themselves” are not mysterious. By this he does not<br />

mean “considered one by one” or “considered individually,” as you write, but he means that their content, the social<br />

resources which they are before someone put the sticker “value determination” on them, are not mysterious. <strong>The</strong><br />

mystery lies in the way the social resources are regulated in a commodity society.<br />

Next Message by School is [639].<br />

[410] Kraken: graded A Marx feels that commodities are “mysterious” because the social<br />

relations encapsulated in the commodities are not visible to or controlled by the commodity<br />

owners. <strong>The</strong> commodity is “intricate” because it has different determinations; use-value and<br />

value (Annotations). Although the commodity appears to be “obvious and trivial” on the<br />

surface, a deeper examination reveals that it is more complex. Marx feels that money and<br />

capital have the most mysterious properties but maintains that the mystery begins to manifest<br />

itself in the commodity and chooses to study the origin <strong>of</strong> the mystery in this stage when it<br />

is easier to analyze.<br />

Next Message by Kraken is [502].<br />

[436] Kaush: In an attempt to undo and appreciate the interior workings <strong>of</strong> the commodity,<br />

Marx sidesteps as the culprit the use-value, the content <strong>of</strong> the value, and the production process.<br />

Though, at the outset, the commodity seems simple, obvious and trivial; the scientific<br />

analysis seems to belie that. What seemed a simple object had turned out to be some<strong>thing</strong><br />

complicated. When Marx uncovered contradictions in the simple surface properties <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity which led him to dig deeper, he discovered a new world <strong>of</strong> intricate fine details<br />

and theological subtleties. It is intricate because the commodity has many undeveloped<br />

characters which can be manifested in various forms, from the simple exchangeability <strong>of</strong> two<br />

commodities to the establishment <strong>of</strong> gold or money (the god <strong>of</strong> commodities) as a general<br />

equivalent <strong>of</strong> the exchange value in the relation to the rest <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Next Message by Kaush is [439].<br />

[474] Guh: <strong>The</strong> reason that Marx states a commodity as complicated and mysterious<br />

and simply because it is just that. Furthermore, Marx says a commodity is complicated and


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 153<br />

mysterious, but this does not refer to a lack <strong>of</strong> knowledge on the consumers behalf, but the<br />

unpredictability <strong>of</strong> its price as Scott says in [2008fa:557]. As Hans says in [2008fa:311],<br />

“I say in the annotations because this simple answer leads to contradictions. Marx himself<br />

does not give a one-sentence answer but his formulates indicate that this apparent simplicity<br />

is only a <strong>first</strong> impression, the commodity is not as simple as it might <strong>first</strong> seem” In addition<br />

Hans also said that <strong>of</strong>ten one will assume this is a result <strong>of</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> knowledge and that Marx<br />

maintains this is not the cause. Marx however, does keep his claim that to have perfect<br />

knowledge would make the price <strong>of</strong> a commodity predictable and this is not the case.<br />

Next Message by Guh is [626].<br />

[479] Cosmopolita: <strong>The</strong> evidence that prompts Marx to say that the commodity is “intricate”<br />

and mysterious is because <strong>of</strong> the social relations encapsulated in the commodities<br />

which are not visible or controlled by the commodity owners. And fetishism <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

is related to the “theoretical errors” in which the logic expectation or answer does<br />

not follow, and a deeper explanation is necessary for the behavior <strong>of</strong> people towards certain<br />

commodities.<br />

Hans: I liked your in-class answer better than the resubmission which basically copied a sentence from the Annotations.<br />

In class you stressed that the commodity has received value in production, and that this value has social<br />

effects long after production.<br />

Next Message by Cosmopolita is [480].<br />

[483] IrvingHowe: Marx believes that the commodity is “intricate” or “mysterious” because<br />

at <strong>first</strong> glance, the concepts <strong>of</strong> use-value and exchange value are in direct contradiction.<br />

Actually, Marx sees many contradictions in commodities, from the sort <strong>of</strong> paradox <strong>of</strong><br />

water which is essential to life, has an endless use value and yet its exchange value is nearly<br />

no<strong>thing</strong> to the seemingly arbitrary way in which values are assigned to certain commodities.<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [484].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 287 is 184 in 2002fa, 193 in 2003fa, 220 in 2004fa, 236 in 2007SP, 241<br />

in 2007fa, 248 in 2008SP, 246 in 2008fa, and 270 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 287 Why does Marx explore the mysterious character <strong>of</strong> the commodity,<br />

which is bland and abstract, instead <strong>of</strong> picking up one <strong>of</strong> the many striking outwardly mysterious<br />

phenomena <strong>of</strong> capitalism?<br />

[192] Scholar: Marx’s goal in exploring the mysterious character <strong>of</strong> the commodity is<br />

to reveal the social relationships <strong>of</strong> capitalism, which are concealed by externally equal and<br />

fair market exchange.<br />

During the market exchange, people feel that their destiny or life is determined by the<br />

market, or depends on whether their commodities can be traded in the market, which results<br />

in the fetish <strong>of</strong> commodity. In fact, the producers’ life depends on whether his individual<br />

labor can be transformed into social labor, that is, whether it can be accepted by the other<br />

people during market exchange.<br />

<strong>The</strong> capitalist social relationship, especially the relationship between the capitalist and<br />

the worker, are all from the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodity based on the capitalist property rights.<br />

So, it is the commodity, instead <strong>of</strong> other surprising phenomena, that is the essential element<br />

to find the mystery <strong>of</strong> capitalist society.<br />

154 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Scholar is [226].<br />

[209] Cosmopolita: Marx does this because he tries to imply subtly that there is more to<br />

it. It is not about production <strong>of</strong> the commodity itself. After use-value, exchange-value and<br />

“value” <strong>of</strong> the commodity have been discussed, Marx throws his last-ditch <strong>of</strong> the concept<br />

commodity accepting a more “intricate” significance <strong>of</strong> commodity, to make our minds think<br />

and develop a deeper idea than just social values <strong>of</strong> a commodity and the “utility” received<br />

from them. Marx acceptance <strong>of</strong> his explanation being less than satisfactory, seems to flourish<br />

ideas and concepts not fully explained yet, but “begging the question” <strong>of</strong> concepts, which is<br />

the essence <strong>of</strong> his book.<br />

Hans: I think you are saying Marx is making up a lot <strong>of</strong> stuff in order to get people’s brains going.<br />

Message [209] referenced by [236]. Next Message by Cosmopolita is [479].<br />

[301] KA: Mysterious Character <strong>of</strong> a Commodity. Marx provides an interesting concept<br />

in exploring the mysterious character <strong>of</strong> the commodity. <strong>The</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> a piece <strong>of</strong> wood<br />

spinning itself into a table magically is the mysterious character <strong>of</strong> a commodity. A table is<br />

not a commodity, but a product <strong>of</strong> a commodity, wood.<br />

Marx explores the mysterious character <strong>of</strong> the commodity to illustrate that individuals<br />

cannot look at a finished product as being an original commodity. Marx uses the example<br />

<strong>of</strong> wood being transformed into a table to explore this mysterious character. <strong>The</strong> production<br />

<strong>of</strong> this table originated from the commodity which gave it use-value. <strong>The</strong> table is not the<br />

commodity, but rather a use-value <strong>of</strong> the wood. <strong>The</strong> mysterious character that individuals<br />

place on the table is that they transform (in their mind) that the table is a commodity rather<br />

than the product <strong>of</strong> a commodity. Marx elaborates further that if the table “steps forth as<br />

a commodity” it transforms into ”some<strong>thing</strong> that has extrasensory features attached to its<br />

sensuous existence.” <strong>The</strong> table transforms on its own from a piece <strong>of</strong> wood by “turning itself<br />

on its head, and evolves out <strong>of</strong> its wooden brain grotesque ideas, far spleenier than if it<br />

suddenly were to begin dancing.”<br />

Message [301] referenced by [323]. Next Message by KA is [302].<br />

[323] Hans: It is night. Do you know what your commodities are doing right now?<br />

KA [301] is wrong because KA stays entirely on the use-value side <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s. That which<br />

Marx considers mysterious has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with the use-values <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

I answered question 287 earlier in the Semester as part <strong>of</strong> my longer [198]. Here are the<br />

two relevant paragraphs. First I give some examples <strong>of</strong> “outwardly” mysterious or magical<br />

phenomena in capitalism:<br />

<strong>The</strong> power <strong>of</strong> money to purchase every<strong>thing</strong>, or the power <strong>of</strong> capital to<br />

grow quasi on its own accord, sudden financial crises and breakdowns <strong>of</strong><br />

economic growth, inflation, unemployment, stock market booms and busts,<br />

salaries which have no<strong>thing</strong> to do with the skills or experience <strong>of</strong> the recipient,<br />

the tendency <strong>of</strong> wealth to concentrate rather than dissipate ...<br />

<strong>The</strong> next paragraph explains why Marx does not begin with those:<br />

Before investigating each <strong>of</strong> those in detail, Marx tries to uncover the root<br />

cause where this magical character comes from. This, he claims, is best


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 155<br />

done if we look at this mysterious character in its nascent state, where it is<br />

barely visible that the <strong>thing</strong> is mysterious at all, and that is the commodity.<br />

This is all you need to say in the exam. I chose the subject line because we think commodities<br />

are simple <strong>thing</strong>s which we have under control. We don’t. Perhaps your car is<br />

being abducted by a car thief right now—because <strong>of</strong> its social powers, its ability to be turned<br />

into money.<br />

Could one say the car was not abducted but it eloped? Perhaps a car wants to be sold, and<br />

it uses the car thief to get its way? This would be an explanation <strong>of</strong> car theft in terms <strong>of</strong> the<br />

self-activity <strong>of</strong> the commodity. It is probably not the right way to look at car theft, but here is<br />

a parallel where it makes sense. Cigarette vending machines used to be designed such that it<br />

is easy to steal cigarettes. <strong>The</strong> purpose was to turn underage teenagers into nicotine addicts.<br />

Cigarettes want to be sold, and they are using shoplifting teenagers as vehicles to get their<br />

way.<br />

Message [323] referenced by [2012fa:327]. Next Message by Hans is [326].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 290 is 175 in 2001fa, 190 in 2002fa, 196 in 2003fa, 223 in 2004fa, 218 in<br />

2005fa, 238 in 2007SP, 243 in 2007fa, 248 in 2008fa, 263 in 2011fa, and 275 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 290 What is an “essential” property <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong>? What can be said in support<br />

<strong>of</strong> Marx’s claim that labor is “essentially” expenditure <strong>of</strong> human brain, nerves, muscles,<br />

sense organs, etc.?<br />

[191] IrvingHowe: essential properties <strong>of</strong> labor. To say that there is an essential element<br />

to any<strong>thing</strong> is to recognize that certain parts or inputs are indispensable.<br />

When Marx claims that labor is “essentially” the expenditure <strong>of</strong> features such as brain,<br />

muscles, nerves, sensory organs and the like—one can read into that statement that there are<br />

a couple <strong>of</strong> (correct) assumptions at work. First, that every vocation requires some mix <strong>of</strong><br />

the use <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> these features, which is true. Second, that these features are not exclusively<br />

for the use <strong>of</strong> labor, also true.<br />

In as much as one could call these features ‘resources’ that allow one to maximize the<br />

life experience, using these resources for the purpose <strong>of</strong> labor as opposed to other possible<br />

(probably more rewarding) applications represents some<strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong> a choice. One cannot<br />

be consumed by both labor and leisure because <strong>of</strong> the natural constraints placed over<br />

man/woman by these features.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, labor is in its essence an expenditure <strong>of</strong> human features or resources (brain,<br />

muscles, nerves etc). <strong>The</strong> invaluable features comprised in labor cannot be simultaneously<br />

used on alternative activities <strong>of</strong> interest to the laborer. This is an inescapable characteristic<br />

<strong>of</strong> every kind <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Hans: Production is arguably the noblest application <strong>of</strong> human resources one can think <strong>of</strong>. Production uses natural<br />

forces to make the world a better place for us. That this is even possible, that we as parts <strong>of</strong> nature an actively affect<br />

nature is somewhat <strong>of</strong> a miracle. Shame on capitalism that it does not make this miraculous activity at the same<br />

time our most rewarding activity.<br />

Message [191] referenced by [215] and [216]. Next Message by IrvingHowe is [481].<br />

[206] Guh: Essential Property. According to Hans’s remark to [2005fa:736], the essential<br />

property <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> “are those properties which make the <strong>thing</strong>s what they are.”<br />

156 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong>refore when Marx is talking about the “essentially” expenditure <strong>of</strong> human brain, nerves,<br />

and muscles, Marx is talking about the human labor <strong>of</strong> these features in the body. Moreover,<br />

he means that with these elements <strong>of</strong> the body we can produce labor, and without them we<br />

would not be able to function in a way where we could perform tasks such as labor. Furthermore,<br />

if we were to remove any <strong>of</strong> these nerves, muscles or more importantly the brain, we<br />

as human would cease to be able to produce any form <strong>of</strong> labor. Thus Marx is saying that an<br />

essential part <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> cannot be taken away for that some<strong>thing</strong> to remain intact.<br />

Message [206] referenced by [214], [215], and [216]. Next Message by Guh is [473].<br />

[207] Long: Essential. An essential (As Submitted:) Essential Essentials<br />

property <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> is just the way it property <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> is just the ways that<br />

is. With the phrase “‘essentially’ the expenditure<br />

<strong>of</strong> human brains, nerves, muscles, it is. When Marx refers to “essentially” the<br />

sense, organs, etc.,” Marx is saying that ev- expenditure <strong>of</strong> human brains, nerves, musery<strong>thing</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> the human body has to be there cles, sense, organs, etc. Marx is saying that<br />

for humans to be able to function. He is also every<strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong> the human body has to be<br />

relating to human labor therefore it will not<br />

function if any <strong>of</strong> the following are miss-<br />

there for human is able to function. He is<br />

ing. Just like in a production assembly line, also relating to human labor therefore it will<br />

not function if any <strong>of</strong> the following are miss-<br />

if one <strong>of</strong> the many components or persons ing. Just like in a production assembly line,<br />

performing the task is missing; then the po- if one <strong>of</strong> any components or person performtential<br />

outcome is not there. It is essential<br />

that all <strong>thing</strong>s must be there and remain in<br />

ing the task is missing; then the potential<br />

such group. outcome is not there. it is an essential to<br />

all <strong>thing</strong>s must be there to and to remain in<br />

such group.<br />

Message [207] referenced by [215]. Next Message by Long is [208].<br />

[213] Zohan: Essential Property. To say that some<strong>thing</strong> is an essential property indicates<br />

that is a necessary part in order for some<strong>thing</strong> to function. You can’t take away an essential<br />

property if you want it to work.<br />

Marx uses this idea to point out how labor depends on the essential properties <strong>of</strong> the<br />

human body in order for labor to exist. <strong>The</strong> body needs essential parts for it to function and<br />

perform tasks. On the other hand, labor doesn’t spontaneously occur. In order for labor to<br />

exist, essential properties must be in line. Human effort is needed to produce labor. If all<br />

the bodies essential properties like the brain, nerves, muscles, ect., are in order then it can<br />

function properly and produce labor. If any <strong>of</strong> these essential properties are taken away, then<br />

the body could not function and labor would not occur. This idea shows that labor depends<br />

on the essential properties <strong>of</strong> the human body to exist.<br />

Message [213] referenced by [215] and [216]. Next Message by Zohan is [249].<br />

[214] Utefan: Essential Property. Some<strong>thing</strong> that is essential is defined as any<strong>thing</strong> basic<br />

that has to be present for that some<strong>thing</strong> to exist. Marx says that, whatever the useful kinds<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor or productive activities, it is a physiological fact that they are functions <strong>of</strong> the human<br />

organism. Guh [206] and other class members echo the illustration <strong>of</strong> movement such as an<br />

assembly line; however, at the beginning <strong>of</strong> his paragraph he is talking in reference to the<br />

mystical characteristics <strong>of</strong> commodities. It, as Marx states, does not arise from its use values


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 157<br />

and as little does it stem from the determinants <strong>of</strong> value. Sensory organs or muscles are<br />

essentially used to produce and have to be used in order to fulfill any production. However,<br />

as Marx states, that does not define the mystical state <strong>of</strong> the commodity or the value. If<br />

one continues down the paragraph, value is determined by the quantity <strong>of</strong> labor. Essentially,<br />

then, quantity <strong>of</strong> labor determines value and is essential.<br />

Hans: I had to correct two malformed sentences.<br />

Message [214] referenced by [216]. Next Message by Utefan is [221].<br />

[216] Hans: Amendment. Things are not as black and white as I said, for didactic<br />

reasons, in [215]. Zohan [213] contains the sentence “labor doesn’t spontaneously occur”<br />

which was missing in [191] and [206]. Labor channels the course <strong>of</strong> nature in a direction<br />

in which it otherwise would not go. In order to do this, we need to use the qualities which<br />

make us humans, our attentiveness, goal-directedness, self-reflection etc. This is hard work.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore it is not an accident that production is strenuous for us humans, it is an essential<br />

property <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

I discovered Utefan [214] only after submitting [215]. Utefan is an altogether different<br />

story than the one described in [215]. Utefan tries to write what I want to hear. After seeing<br />

his grades for [90] and [131] he emailed me: “I wanted to know exactly what you are looking<br />

for in order to get an A. Are you looking for a certain length in paragraphs or more detail?”<br />

Only afterwards he read my detailed responses to [90] at the bottom <strong>of</strong> his submission and<br />

to [131] in [137]. My responses show that each <strong>of</strong> his answers had missed some essential<br />

elements for the understanding <strong>of</strong> Marx. Utefan apparently decided it is not the length <strong>of</strong><br />

paragraphs I am after but evidence that he is reading the Annotations. In [215] he went to<br />

the other extreme. Instead <strong>of</strong> relying on his intelligence to answer the questions and not<br />

paying much attention to Marx or the class discussion, [215] regurgitates the Annotations<br />

and class discussion in bits and pieces but it does not make sense. I am looking forward to<br />

the negation <strong>of</strong> the negation.<br />

Message [216] referenced by [217] and [221]. Next Message by Hans is [219].<br />

[221] Utefan: In response to [216], here is my negation to the negation. I read over what<br />

the class was stating and tried to understand more in depth what the question was asking and<br />

how I could best answer. My goal was to extend the thoughts that had already been stated<br />

and help further the class. In so doing I fell short <strong>of</strong> the desired expectations <strong>of</strong> Hans and did<br />

not receive the grade desired; however, as I have submitted assignments I hope I will learn<br />

more <strong>of</strong> how to best answer in the future. Now, reading to the rest <strong>of</strong> the class a personal<br />

email I wrote directly to Hans is inappropriate. Attacking how I do my homework is also<br />

inappropriate, we will see how this pans out.<br />

Hans: If you are asking for advice how to get an A in this class, then others in class have the right to know your<br />

question and my reaction to it.<br />

Next Message by Utefan is [381].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 291 is 197 in 2003fa, 224 in 2004fa, 219 in 2005fa, 239 in 2007SP, 251 in<br />

2008SP, 249 in 2008fa, 263 in 2009fa, and 264 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 291 Do you know production processes in which humans participate without having<br />

to spend any effort?<br />

158 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[194] Intaglio: <strong>The</strong> Future <strong>of</strong> Work, Effort Free? When I <strong>first</strong> read this question I<br />

initially thought a yes answer would relate to how little effort people using machines have<br />

to do compared with previous societies that used manual labor instead. But using these<br />

machines, factories, and technology still requires some effort, even if it is as small as coming<br />

to work just to turn on and <strong>of</strong>f the machines. Even the act <strong>of</strong> gathering up other animals to<br />

do the desired production is still effort. So there is no production processes humans are<br />

involved in that require no effort.<br />

This lead me to try and imagine a future utopia where technology is so developed that<br />

there is no workers and no need for effort: All goods are produced and delivered to everyone<br />

by smart machines and artificially intelligent robots! <strong>The</strong>se robots are also capable <strong>of</strong><br />

knowing what new machines humans need and go about building new technologies without<br />

human input (effort <strong>of</strong> thinking creatively and telling the robots what to do).<br />

Could such production be considered exempt from human effort? After all, humans<br />

would no longer be making an effort to produce what they receive, they only consume.<br />

<strong>The</strong> answer is still no. Even a technologically advanced society, with work-free production,<br />

is built upon a mass <strong>of</strong> previous human efforts. All technology is the manifestation <strong>of</strong> previously<br />

exerted human labor. Without <strong>first</strong> putting effort into basic technology, [e.g. tools,<br />

machines, robots, and finally utopian self-perpetuating artificial intelligence] we can never<br />

get to a labor free world.<br />

As production went on in a work-free utopia, the most we could say is that the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

effort involved per product is shrinking: (all previous effort leading up to the implementation<br />

<strong>of</strong> self perpetuating utopia) divided by (/) (all goods ever produced). This would continually<br />

decrease the amount <strong>of</strong> (previous) efforts involved per production <strong>of</strong> new goods, but the<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> effort will never reach zero... if that makes any sense.<br />

<strong>The</strong> answer is no. Effort is involved in all human participating production processes, and<br />

hidden in all possible future utopias devoid <strong>of</strong> work.<br />

Hans: Machine operators are not needed to turn the machines on and <strong>of</strong>f. A timer could do that. Machine operators<br />

are needed so someone is there if some<strong>thing</strong> goes wrong and to take over tasks that are not mechanized.<br />

With utopias you must be careful what you wish for. Robots smart enough to not only produce and develop new<br />

methods <strong>of</strong> production will be smart enough to dominate humans. What if they treat lower life forms (which, from<br />

their perspective, would include us) the same way we do?<br />

Message [194] referenced by [201]. Next Message by Intaglio is [232].<br />

[201] Giant: Humans Cause Too Much Work. In response to Intaglio’s [194] “<strong>The</strong><br />

Future <strong>of</strong> Work, Effort Free?”<br />

I agree with Intaglio up to a certain point that the production process in general will never<br />

reach zero but will just decrease as technology increases. I do think there is a way to break<br />

the level <strong>of</strong> human production participation level down further, but <strong>first</strong> I want to address<br />

my opinion that humans cause more work than is necessary for certain productions. I do<br />

think growing food (not farming) can be produced naturally without any human production<br />

involved. Of course having humans participate in the production does make it more efficient.<br />

Along the same lines, decomposition is some<strong>thing</strong> that humans benefit from by having more<br />

fertile soil and yet it does not require human participation to function.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 159<br />

A deeper level <strong>of</strong> division that Intaglio could have dived into is that depending on a<br />

human’s place in society, impacts the level <strong>of</strong> production process they participate in with<br />

the amount <strong>of</strong> effort they put in. A lower class worker is going to put in a lot more effort<br />

into the production process (say fixing/manufacturing the machinery <strong>of</strong> the future) than the<br />

upper class business man who is only having to push a button to get the machine to work.<br />

Hans: Interesting that even in the most extreme utopian thinking, you are taking the continuation <strong>of</strong> class society<br />

as a given.<br />

Next Message by Giant is [366].<br />

[217] GoUtes: Production Process. <strong>The</strong>re is not any production process that humans<br />

participate in, that do not require at least some type <strong>of</strong> effort. In any situation where human<br />

participation is warranted, some sort <strong>of</strong> effort is always needed, whether it be physical labor,<br />

using intellect, having authority or power over others, in all occasions effort in needed by<br />

humans in the production process. If no effort were needed, than no<strong>thing</strong> would be accomplished.<br />

According to Marx effort is an essential part <strong>of</strong> the human-nature “metabolism.”<br />

Hans: You are right, Marx thinks, and a case can be made for it, that no<strong>thing</strong> can be “accomplished,” as you say,<br />

without effort. I tried to make such a case in [216], which was sent to the class 49 minutes before your answer.<br />

Next Message by GoUtes is [255].<br />

[220] Max: Invigorating and fulfilling = effortless. Herbert Marcuse is a German<br />

philosopher who wrote Eros and Civilization in 1955. <strong>The</strong> book draws on Karl Marx and<br />

Sigmund Freud to lay out a non-repressive society. He argues that the historical repressive<br />

qualities <strong>of</strong> labor in capitalism suppress our libido to the extent that all <strong>of</strong> society has been<br />

built upon restrained instincts (in so many words...). Marcuse believes that a socialist society<br />

that frees the libido, or eros, can exist without the suppression <strong>of</strong> poor laborers. In other<br />

words, work would be a joyful experience, one that involved the collaboration <strong>of</strong> community.<br />

Many people tried doing this on communes in the sixties and seventies; they tried turning<br />

work and farming into a celebration, rather than a chore. In this way, it does not take “effort”<br />

to produce commodities, instead, labor would be invigorating and fulfilling—effortless.<br />

Hans: Think <strong>of</strong> the labor <strong>of</strong> raising children. It can be very fulfilling, but it is certainly not effortless. <strong>The</strong> equation<br />

“Invigorating and fulfilling = effortless” which I put into your subject line is in my view the questionable assumption<br />

in the theory you are sketching out.<br />

<strong>The</strong> real issue as I see it is not whether labor is effortless but whether it is alienated. I tried to bring up<br />

childrearing as an example <strong>of</strong> non-alienated labor. Even childrearing can be turned into a chore and a struggle by<br />

the capitalist system. It can be an incredibly painful uphill battle to try to protect your children, those whom you<br />

love most, from the many negative social influences—which break their spirit and try to pull them under, turn them<br />

into addicts, consumerists, racists, bigots. Many working class parents think they have to go with the flow and stunt<br />

their children so that they fit better into the limited options society has ready for them. As Adorno said, you cannot<br />

have a healthy life in a sick society.<br />

Next Message by Max is [322].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 296 is 152 in 1998WI, 170 in 2000fa, 201 in 2003fa, 256 in 2008SP, and 269 in<br />

2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 296 Since use-value is not mysterious, the commodity’s mysterious character<br />

must come from value.<br />

a. Is a commodity mysterious because it takes labor, i.e., the expenditure <strong>of</strong> human brain,<br />

nerves, muscles, etc., to produce it?<br />

b. Is a commodity mysterious because the question how much time it takes to produce it is<br />

relevant for society at large?<br />

160 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

c. Is a commodity mysterious because the labors performed in a commodity-producing society<br />

are part <strong>of</strong> an overall social labor process?<br />

d. Is there another aspect <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity which was overlooked here that<br />

might be mysterious?<br />

[393] She: graded A+ Karl Marx believes that the commodity is mysterious because, to<br />

quote the Annotations, “. . . social relations encapsulated in the commodities are not visible<br />

to or controlled by the commodity owners (Ehrbar, 170). In order to deduce what in a<br />

commodity results in the seemingly contradictory surface relations we can observe, Marx<br />

disassembles the commodity and analyzes its components individually to determine which<br />

are indeed mysterious.<br />

Marx begins with the use-value and concludes that, “...there is no<strong>thing</strong> mysterious about<br />

it,” (163:4). It is completely rational and explainable for man to make <strong>thing</strong>s useful to him.<br />

He next looks at the way man transforms <strong>thing</strong>s in nature into use-values and determines<br />

there is no<strong>thing</strong> mysterious here either.<br />

<strong>The</strong> determinations <strong>of</strong> value are not mysterious either; they are simple to understand,<br />

but in a market society, they are regulated by,”. . . interactions <strong>of</strong> the commodities on the<br />

surface <strong>of</strong> the economy,” (Ehrbar, 179). <strong>The</strong>re is a mystery to the way that in a commodity<br />

economy, society allocates labor, or socially-necessary labor-time, according to competition<br />

on the market, rather than the actual labor-time used in production. This means, this is<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the control <strong>of</strong> the producers <strong>of</strong> the commodities, it is therefore, mysterious to them.<br />

When commodities are exchanged, it is a contact between them, rather than between the<br />

producers. <strong>The</strong> will <strong>of</strong> the individual producer is thwarted by the properties inherent in<br />

the commodity. Marx says, “. . . and finally the relationships between the producers, within<br />

which the social characteristics <strong>of</strong> their labors are manifested, take on the form <strong>of</strong> a social<br />

relation between the products <strong>of</strong> labor” (Marx, 164:3). So Marx believes that there are social<br />

relations between the commodities themselves as they are the embodiment and manifestation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the relationships between producers. Marx also says this, “. . . reflects the social relation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the producers to the sum total <strong>of</strong> labor” (Marx, 165:1). Both <strong>of</strong> these points emphasize<br />

Marx’s belief that the mystery in the products <strong>of</strong> labor only arises when the products become<br />

commodity-forms.<br />

Final Grading Note by Hans: You don’t leave any<strong>thing</strong> out. You collect every<strong>thing</strong> Marx says about a specific<br />

item, even if it seems contradictory or incoherent, and then you juggle all those different aspects like balls which<br />

you are not supposed to drop. While others go for one simple concept and cannot be bothered with the confusing<br />

details, you keep all the details in mind but I cannot quite see the unifying concept.<br />

Next Message by She is [614].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 298 is 131 in 1995WI, 108 in 1995ut, 141 in 1996sp, 149 in 1997WI, 154 in<br />

1997sp, 147 in 1997ut, 246 in 2007SP, and 256 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 298 Explain how value denotes a specific relation <strong>of</strong> production and not just the<br />

general relationship between a producer and his product.<br />

[285] Baseball: <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a product is based on the labor used to create that product.<br />

<strong>The</strong> time and labor used to produce a Lamborghini is much more than what it takes to<br />

produce a Corolla. Even though the parts are extremely similar (tires, windows, rims, etc.),


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 161<br />

Lamborghinis have a longer production time and waiting list which creates a socially generated<br />

view that this car is much better and worth all the money which is paid for it. Much<br />

like a quote I read in a business text “A product only fills the void that it itself has created.<br />

Many consumers are paying for a name which gives <strong>of</strong>f the impression <strong>of</strong> high social status,<br />

when in fact substitute products are a third <strong>of</strong> the price and work/look just as well.”<br />

Hans: If you think Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value holds because <strong>thing</strong>s with more hand labor are more prestigious,<br />

this is a basic misinterpretation <strong>of</strong> the theory.<br />

Next Message by Baseball is [406].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 303 is 134 in 1995WI, 111 in 1995ut, 144 in 1996sp, 146 in 1996ut, 159 in<br />

1998WI, 166 in 1999SP, 187 in 2001fa, 201 in 2002fa, 208 in 2003fa, 236 in 2004fa,<br />

231 in 2005fa, 251 in 2007SP, 256 in 2007fa, 261 in 2008fa, 275 in 2009fa, and 277 in<br />

2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 303 How does Marx’s use <strong>of</strong> the term “fetishism” compare with its modern dictionary<br />

definition?<br />

[188] Balrog: graded C+ I would dare say that one <strong>of</strong> the most common fetishes that exists<br />

amongst people today would be shoe fetishes. In this sense the word fetish is indicating that<br />

someone has an unusual desire for or attraction to shoes. Thus, the average person in today’s<br />

society would define “commodity fetishism” as an extreme desire for material goods.<br />

According to dictionary.com the definition for fetish is an object regarded with awe as<br />

being the embodiment or habitation <strong>of</strong> a potent spirit or as having magical potency. Commodities<br />

in a way are a source <strong>of</strong> power to people and establish their social dominance or<br />

inferiority. Someone with a worn down pair <strong>of</strong> converse will not be regarded as having an<br />

equal social stature as someone with the newest pair <strong>of</strong> Air Jordan’s. By having a Rolex on<br />

your wrist you tell the world that you are successful and can feel the higher social value that<br />

accessory provides.<br />

To go one step further into what I feel Marx was trying to say is that the power that<br />

commodities possess is equivalent to a drug. If not careful upon coming into contact with<br />

that power someone can become corrupted and acquire a strong appetite for more. Within<br />

reason, whatever it now takes to acquire more <strong>of</strong> that power from commodities, whether it<br />

hurts those around you or the environment will be done.<br />

Message [188] referenced by [189], [211], and [227]. Next Message by Balrog is [252].<br />

[189] Hans: Shabbiness Principle and Fantasy Answers. I agree with Balrog [188]<br />

that in modern capitalism in the US, people use their possessions to “establish their social<br />

dominance or inferiority.” “Establish” means here: demonstrate to those (usually strangers)<br />

they interact with. Balrog’s example: “Someone with a worn down pair <strong>of</strong> converse will<br />

not be regarded as having an equal social stature as someone with the newest pair <strong>of</strong> Air<br />

Jordan’s.”<br />

I can relate because I lived my entire life in opposition to this. I grew up in post-<br />

World War II Germany where clothes were plain and modest with holes carefully but visibly<br />

patched over. People wore sweaters with leather patches on the elbows, etc. My dream as a<br />

teenager was to have raggedy clothes, long hair, but the posture or demeanor <strong>of</strong> a king. My<br />

dream was to radiate so much life and energy that people respect you as a person regardless<br />

162 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> the clothes you are wearing. I fell far short (or should I say long?) but I still remember<br />

this image. My uncle, a respected lawyer, judge, and law pr<strong>of</strong>essor, privately followed the<br />

“shabbiness principle” <strong>of</strong> deliberately wearing clothes with holes—to the consternation <strong>of</strong><br />

the family, although he said he needed these clothes because he was working in the garden.<br />

In the US, I once terribly embarrassed my little son. I visited his classroom in order to<br />

talk about my job as <strong>University</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor. <strong>The</strong> classroom had a broken window. I entered<br />

the classroom dressed in such a way that everybody thought I was the window repairman.<br />

My ex used to say to my son: “do you want to become like your father? He dresses like<br />

a bum.” In a sense I did; I considered it an act <strong>of</strong> solidarity with the bums to dress like<br />

they and experience the cold sholder everybody gives to people dressed this way. This, not<br />

gardening, was my excuse for the shabbiness principle. My son is grown up now and my<br />

excuse has changed too: Now I am wearing jeans with holes because it is environmentally<br />

unsustainable to throw out your jeans just because they have holes in their knees.<br />

When Marx talked about commodity fetishism, he did not mean the signaling <strong>of</strong> social<br />

status. In 1870, working people could barely afford shoes. <strong>The</strong>refore as an interpretation <strong>of</strong><br />

Marx, [188] falls into the category <strong>of</strong> “pure phantasy.”<br />

Balrog desribes his answer as “what I (Balrog) feel Marx was trying to say.” When I read<br />

this I had the image in my mind <strong>of</strong> someone ‘reading’ the Annotations and a few <strong>of</strong> the past<br />

answers to this question without really taking in what was said—because this material is so<br />

dense that it takes a lot <strong>of</strong> time to follow the argument. <strong>The</strong> answer is then composed not<br />

as an application <strong>of</strong> the arguments made in the readings, but from the general character <strong>of</strong><br />

the discussion, the words used, etc., i.e., from <strong>thing</strong>s one can pick up if one reads over a<br />

text without taking the time and concentration necessary to get into it and understand what<br />

is said.<br />

This leads to answers about which my feedback notes say “this is pure phantasy” or “this<br />

has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with Marx.” In this class I want you to read, not ‘read’. If the text is<br />

too difficult to follow, come to the class sessions, where I usually try to give a bird’s eye<br />

view placing the detailed readings in context. Some <strong>of</strong> the class sessions are available as<br />

audios; this week’s sessions are now uploaded, and Friday’s audio is shorter but better than<br />

Tuesday’s. <strong>The</strong>re are no earlier audios this Semester, because I projected Marx’s text on the<br />

screen, which cannot be followed in pure audio. But I can recommend the audios <strong>of</strong> the past<br />

Semesters too. Here is the link to the audios:<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/2010fa/audio/index.html<br />

Message [189] referenced by [211] and [244]. Next Message by Hans is [198].<br />

[211] Robert: <strong>The</strong> modern fetish. I’ve been thinking about the posts about fetishism.<br />

Balrog [188] described what maybe called modern fetishism, not what Marx was talking<br />

about as Hans [189] pointed out. Nevertheless, not necessarily in an effort to understand<br />

Marx but in an effort to understand modern capitalism, I think Balrog makes an interesting<br />

observation about which I would like to comment.<br />

I have had the opportunity to study a little psychology. I was driven to the study to better<br />

understand the potential <strong>of</strong> human beings, what Maslow refers to as self-actualization and<br />

Jung calls individuation. In the process <strong>of</strong> trying to understand these <strong>thing</strong> I studied a little


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 163<br />

about how the human mind may function and the interrelation <strong>of</strong> psychological emotions,<br />

neuropsychology, pathologies, development, and other aspects <strong>of</strong> human beings related to<br />

psychology. I was impressed at the advances in the science (and art) <strong>of</strong> modern psychology.<br />

I thought, as I learned, how wonderful it was that our society could train people to help<br />

others psychologically. Indeed, a good many people who study psychology do try to help<br />

other; however, sadly, many trained psychologies are employed by owners <strong>of</strong> production to<br />

use the knowledge they have gained about the functioning <strong>of</strong> human psychology to create<br />

an emotional, irrational desire in humans for the commodities <strong>of</strong> their employers. <strong>The</strong> point<br />

that Balrog [188] makes that Air Jordan shoes are viewed as cooler than Converse is because<br />

<strong>of</strong> the millions <strong>of</strong> dollars spent in advertising designed by psychologists (disgracefully) to<br />

create in young people the illusion that these shoes will bring them closer to Jordanness.<br />

<strong>The</strong> psychologist employed by modern capitalist actually feed and continue the pathology<br />

endemic in western society (and quickly spreading to the rest <strong>of</strong> the world) that ownership <strong>of</strong><br />

certain commodities, which are imbued with artificial fetish qualities, will magically bring<br />

about meaningfulness and “happiness” for its purchasers. What in fact happens is that the<br />

consumer will not find any meaning and happiness in his consumption (he will wonder, for<br />

example, why he is not suddenly as good looking and desirable as the product promised).<br />

Psychologist should be required to take the Hippocratic oath as well and pledge to do no<br />

harm. In my opinion, psychologist employed in the advertising and marketing business are<br />

doing great harm.<br />

We can tie this into Marx because the reason the psychologists are able to create desire for<br />

products in the consumers begins with the fact that the consumers, who are also workers or<br />

owners <strong>of</strong> capital, are alienated. Exploiting workers is not ultimately fulfilling to the human<br />

psyche, nor is being exploited by being forced to create more value than one is compensated<br />

for. What humans are looking for is meaningful lives; capitalism leads them to believe that<br />

what they are looking for is capital accumulation or commodity consumption...neither will<br />

provide meaning.<br />

Message [211] referenced by [227] and [244]. Next Message by Robert is [259].<br />

[227] Cougar: (graded B–) Fetishism. I would also like to comment on Balrog’s post<br />

[188] concerning fetishism after today’s lecture. As already stated by Robert [211], the<br />

analysis given by Balrog was not what Marx was trying to convey in his theory. To my<br />

understanding, rather than being a “fixation” or “obsession,” the fetishism <strong>of</strong> commodities is<br />

the revelation <strong>of</strong> social relationships among people in society within those commodities. An<br />

example used in Wikipedia is that <strong>of</strong> an 100 dollar bill in a transaction. <strong>The</strong> materials and<br />

labor necessary to create the bill are not nearly worth 100 dollars, yet both parties agree that<br />

the bill represents the sufficient amount <strong>of</strong> value to be exchanged for the designated commodity(s).<br />

<strong>The</strong> transaction represents a social relationship between both parties, that each<br />

<strong>of</strong> their commodities is valued equally with the other and is therefore exchangeable. <strong>The</strong><br />

100 dollar bill has been socially agreed upon to be worth 100 dollars worth <strong>of</strong> commodity(s)<br />

although it is clearly not worth that in terms <strong>of</strong> its inputs. This “mystical” ability, as Marx<br />

considers it, <strong>of</strong> the bill to command such a value is described by fetishism, as if the value<br />

were intrinsic <strong>of</strong> the bill itself. Hopefully I’m close to what Hans shared with us in lecture<br />

and if not, I’d appreciate feedback in preparation for the exam.<br />

164 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Message [227] referenced by [240] and [244]. Next Message by Cougar is [497].<br />

[240] Hans: Beware <strong>of</strong> Wikipedia. I love Wikipedia. It is an incredible resource, but it<br />

is not reliable in its pronouncements on Marxism. Wikepedia reflects a consensus view, and<br />

there is no consensus about Marxism (other than that Marxism is all wrong). So you will get<br />

uneven results if you consult Wikipedia about Marxism.<br />

<strong>The</strong> example with the dollar bill in the Wikipedia article about Commodity Fetishism is<br />

simply bad Marxism. <strong>The</strong> fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> money is unrelated with it that a modern<br />

dollar bill costs less to produce than its face value. Even full-weighted gold coins, which<br />

cost exactly as much to produce as their face value, have a fetish-like character—because<br />

“this physical object, gold or silver in its crude state, becomes, as soon as it emerges from<br />

the bowels <strong>of</strong> the earth, the immediate incarnation <strong>of</strong> all human labor” [187:1]. A <strong>thing</strong> has<br />

social powers just because it is gold. This is what Marx found remarkable, not that gold has<br />

in the historical development been replaced by paper money—which shows its social origins<br />

much more clearly than crude gold.<br />

Cougar [227] not only picks out the one <strong>thing</strong> that is clearly wrong in the Wikipedia<br />

article, he also theorizes that paper money is able to buy <strong>thing</strong>s because everybody agrees<br />

that it is worth some<strong>thing</strong> although it really isn’t. This is not Marx’s explanation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

“riddle <strong>of</strong> money.” Marx explains money as a “form <strong>of</strong> value,” at the surface reflection <strong>of</strong> the<br />

labor in the commodities which makes them exchangeable. Didn’t Cougar realize that the<br />

long development in section 3 <strong>of</strong> chapter One, which took up two homework periods, was<br />

Marx’s response to the simple-minded social contract theory <strong>of</strong> money?<br />

Message [240] referenced by [499]. Next Message by Hans is [244].<br />

[241] Fisher: Purchasing debt. I thought it was really interesting hearing the last discussion<br />

in class how people give human like characteristics to commodities. Nowadays people<br />

are worried about objects as if they were another person. Ipods and iphones, for example,<br />

have almost become a status symbol or even way <strong>of</strong> life for people <strong>of</strong> all ages. With all<br />

the new technological advances and easy communication channels, people have found it a<br />

“need” to have their s<strong>of</strong>tware with them at all times. Never in the history <strong>of</strong> the world have<br />

people needed to have items with them at all times, that wasn’t to help procure food, water,<br />

or shelter. <strong>The</strong> world is moving faster, and it’s likely that we all really do need these items.<br />

Do we need them more than other people?<br />

Hans: What does the subject line “purchasing debt” have to do with the text <strong>of</strong> your message?<br />

Message [241] referenced by [244], [246], and [263]. Next Message by Fisher is [242].<br />

[244] Hans: Once more about the self-activity <strong>of</strong> commodities. Fisher [241] says he<br />

enjoyed “the last discussion in class how people give human like characteristics to commodities,”<br />

and then Fisher goes on to describe how people are obsessed with their ipods—<br />

although my [189], Robert’s [211], and Cougar’s [227] all said that such an obsession is not<br />

what Marx means by commodity fetishism.<br />

Two points about this.<br />

(1) If I said in class that commodities seem to have their own agency as if they were<br />

humans, then this does not imply that people give human-like characteristics to commodities.<br />

You may think: we all know that commodities are objects—therefore if someone says they<br />

have their own agency then this can only happen if people thought they had this agency and


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 165<br />

treat them as if they were animated beings. Marx would say that this objection puts too much<br />

blame on the individual and at the same time give the individual too much power.<br />

Marx himself is not blaming individuals but he is blaming social relations. He says:<br />

commodities have their own agency—not because people act as if they were animate beings,<br />

not because people treat their ipod like pets, but because commodities are the carriers <strong>of</strong><br />

social relations.<br />

Example (a): you meet a commodity which you would like to have. Say you are walking<br />

in the park and a really cool bicycle is leaning against a tree. Although this bicylce is only<br />

an object, you cannot just walk over to the tree and take it. This bicycle belongs to someone,<br />

and the police would come after you. <strong>The</strong>refore you leave the bicycle alone—not because<br />

you give it human-like characteristics but because you don’t want to end up in prison.<br />

Example (b): if you are serious that you want this bike you have to go to the store and<br />

buy it. <strong>The</strong> price is not under your control, and it is not really under the store owner’s control<br />

either. Again, this can be called “self-activity” <strong>of</strong> the commodity, but again it does not come<br />

from you treating it as if it was alive.<br />

(2) We live in a society which gives commodities powers that are not under the control <strong>of</strong><br />

the humans. Not because we have somehow the wrong attitudes but this is how our society<br />

historically evolved. Now these social relations induce fetishistic attitudes in people. <strong>The</strong>se<br />

fetishistic attitudes have many expressions. People may think that commodities have their<br />

social powers from nature instead from society, or they may think that no<strong>thing</strong> can really be<br />

done about the social structure which allows commodities to trample people’s lives, or they<br />

may think that possession <strong>of</strong> commodities transfers some <strong>of</strong> the commodities’ social powers<br />

to their owners. All these are wrong responses, they are fetishistic responses.<br />

A non-fetishistic response would be to follow Marx’s example. Marx concluded that it<br />

cannot be good if <strong>thing</strong>s have power over people or, to say it more intuitively by leaving<br />

out the objects, if people do not have insight into or control over their own social relations.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore Marx tried to find the root cause for the perversity <strong>of</strong> our social structure, and he<br />

tried to change it—because he was not only a scientist but also a political activist.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [247].<br />

[311] Rmc: Marx’s word choice. Just a thought on Marx’s word choice (or the translator’s).<br />

While I was reading the section on the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities, I looked up<br />

its definition to make sure I was understanding it in the right context. This is one entry my<br />

Mac gave me:<br />

“an inanimate object worshiped for its supposed magical powers or because it is considered<br />

to be inhabited by a spirit.” <strong>The</strong> second one was: “a course <strong>of</strong> action to which one has<br />

an excessive and irrational commitment.”<br />

I think Marx chose a very appropriate term—in societies like ours, we seem to worship<br />

objects and status; it seems that some <strong>of</strong> us come <strong>of</strong>f as excessively materialistic.<br />

Well-worded, Marx!<br />

166 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: You submitted this as a free discussion contribution and I reclassified it as question 303. Please read the<br />

answers to this question. “Commodity fetishism” for Marx did not mean the worship <strong>of</strong> objects and status or the<br />

materialistic attitude <strong>of</strong> some individuals. In response to your “Well-worded, Marx!” Marx would have the right to<br />

say “You need to improve your reading skills, Rmc!<br />

Message [311] referenced by [322]. Next Message by Rmc is [442].<br />

[322] Max: Marx’s word choice. In response to RMC [311], Marx does not define the<br />

fetish like character <strong>of</strong> commodities as simple materialism. Instead, the fetish like character<br />

refers to social interactions that treat commodities, their trade, and their value as natural or<br />

“magical.” In reality, they only exist because <strong>of</strong> the way history has unfolded. <strong>The</strong> fact that<br />

some people living in capitalistic societies obsess over material goods is merely a byproduct<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalistic forces. Marx wrote Capital a long time ago when wealth and materialism, as<br />

it exists in modern developed nations, did not exist.<br />

Next Message by Max is [384].<br />

[387] Max: graded B Fetishism or fetishism? Marx calls “the fetishism,” some<strong>thing</strong><br />

“which sticks to the products <strong>of</strong> labor as soon as they are produced as commodities, and<br />

which is therefore inseparable from the production <strong>of</strong> commodities.” <strong>The</strong> fetishism isn’t a<br />

physical property <strong>of</strong> the commodity, nor is it a “natural character stemming from the material<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> these <strong>thing</strong>s.” Instead, it is the “social” and “economic character” which is inherent<br />

within the social process <strong>of</strong> a commodity economy. In other words, people fetishize and<br />

obsess over the trade and market relationships <strong>of</strong> commodities, even though they only exist<br />

as metaphysical elements <strong>of</strong> commodity societies, notably, capitalism.<br />

In contrast, modern usage <strong>of</strong> “fetishism” usually refers to some<strong>thing</strong> that is obsessed<br />

about. In some ways this definition is similar to Marx’s, although most <strong>of</strong> its modern usage<br />

is applied to a material attachment to some<strong>thing</strong> physical. For instance, someone can have a<br />

shoe fetish, meaning they obsess over shoes. On the other hand, Marx’s use <strong>of</strong> “fetishism” is<br />

an obsession over some<strong>thing</strong> abstract that is treated as a physical property <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Hans: If you define Marx’s usage <strong>of</strong> fetishism as an obsession you are on the wrong track. Your in-class answer<br />

was better.<br />

Next Message by Max is [595].<br />

[430] AM: Definition Showdown: Modern vs. Marx. Before comparing Marx’s use<br />

<strong>of</strong> fetishism with that <strong>of</strong> modern society’s, let’s explicitly state how each defines fetishism.<br />

To Marx, fetishism is defined (on page 165) as “<strong>The</strong>re [in the religious realm] the products<br />

<strong>of</strong> the human brain seem to be independent beings endowed with a life <strong>of</strong> their own, which<br />

enter into each other and with the human race. So it is in the realm <strong>of</strong> commodities with the<br />

products <strong>of</strong> people’s hands. This I call the fetishism which sticks to the products <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

as soon as they are produced as commodities and which is therefore inseparable from the<br />

production on commodities.” <strong>The</strong> modern definition <strong>of</strong> fetishism, as taken from the Merriam<br />

Webster Dictionary, is “extravagant irrational devotion”. <strong>The</strong>se two definitions are similar<br />

in the objects (i.e. commodities) are given lives <strong>of</strong> their own. <strong>The</strong>y are “endowed” with<br />

human-like characteristics requiring “devotion” and respect. <strong>The</strong> modern definition suggests<br />

fetishism occurs after production when one has possession <strong>of</strong> the object. But, Marx makes<br />

it clear that he feels that fetishism is there at the moment <strong>of</strong> production. Once the object is<br />

produced the fetishism follows the object regardless <strong>of</strong> its popularity or branding. Another<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> fetishism according to Marx is provided in the Annotations which provides a<br />

unique insight to where modern fetishism stems from. Please note that I see today’s society


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 167<br />

to be comparable to “bourgeois political economy.” This definition <strong>of</strong> fetishism says that<br />

the objects’ social relations, created by production, are mistaken to be a natural characteristic.<br />

Hans presents this simply (in [136]) as nature that has been socialized. While modern<br />

society’s and Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> fetishism share some points, they should not be used interchangeably.<br />

Marx sees fetishism through deep analysis <strong>of</strong> market values in capitalism<br />

and the modern use <strong>of</strong> the word comes from an economy deeply rooted in one’s personal<br />

satisfaction and greed.<br />

Message [430] referenced by [1055]. Next Message by AM is [770].<br />

[517] Milly: content A late penalty 1% Fetishism. According to Webster’s Online Dictionary,<br />

fetishism is defined as an excessive devotion to one object. It then goes on to define<br />

a fetish as an object believed to have supernatural powers, or in particular a man-made object<br />

that has power over others. Essentially, fetishism is attributing some kind <strong>of</strong> inherent value<br />

or powers to an object.<br />

Marx’s definition is similar but focuses on the social connection. Marx does describe<br />

commodities to have a mysterious character. Part <strong>of</strong> this stems from the production process<br />

where the commodities transform from natural materials and seem to have an agenda <strong>of</strong> their<br />

own. In the Annotations Marx sees fetishism as a false consciousness which sticks to the<br />

commodities as soon as they are produced as commodities.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> mysterious character <strong>of</strong> the commodity does not come from the production process.<br />

Next Message by Milly is [686].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 305 is 146 in 1996sp, 258 in 2007fa, and 263 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 305 Mark Blaug writes in p. 268:2: “Commodity ‘fetishism’ refers to the tendency<br />

to reify commodities, to treat what are in fact social relations between men as if they<br />

were relations between <strong>thing</strong>s.” Right or wrong?<br />

[212] Max: (graded A+) Marx’s Meaning <strong>of</strong> Commodity Fetishism. A lot has been discussed<br />

on possible contemporary interpretations <strong>of</strong> what commodity fetishism is. However,<br />

so far there hasn’t been much dialogue about what Marx meant when he uses the term. I was<br />

hoping someone would discuss Commodity Fetishism and Hans would make the appropriate<br />

corrections on their interpretation, but seeing as nobody yet has, I thought I would take it on.<br />

Blaug means that markets have interactions which seem to be based on physical properties<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities. In other words, people may not understand the way their product will affect<br />

the market, all they know is that they can buy X commodities with their Y commodity.<br />

Producers buy and trade commodities without knowing the exact working <strong>of</strong> markets or<br />

what the social or environmental effects <strong>of</strong> their operation will be, yet they continue to buy<br />

and sell because they think the markets based on social relationships are constant and real.<br />

Commodity fetishism is a fixation on commodities, like a horse with blinders; focused on<br />

the road ahead and no<strong>thing</strong> else.<br />

People make commodities to acquire other commodities, to acquire other commodities,<br />

etc. We can see this very clearly in the example <strong>of</strong> the housing bubble: Lenders gave mortgages<br />

to people even though they knew the people couldn’t afford the mortgage. However,<br />

this was okay because they weren’t planning to collect on the mortgage, their plan was to sell<br />

the mortgages instead. <strong>The</strong>y weren’t making a pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong>f the repayment <strong>of</strong> the mortgage, but<br />

168 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the selling <strong>of</strong> the mortgage to other banks. <strong>The</strong> social relationships within the market “reified”<br />

the commodity; turned it from an abstract relationship into a physical commodity. <strong>The</strong><br />

<strong>thing</strong> is, many <strong>of</strong> the banks knew that the mortgages they were selling were no good; they<br />

knew they could sell the commodity via social relations and make a pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> no<strong>thing</strong>.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y took advantage <strong>of</strong> the system. In the same sense, I believe this goes on (though mysteriously,<br />

most <strong>of</strong>ten without people knowing or trying to take advantage) regularly through<br />

the trade <strong>of</strong> all commodities.<br />

In conclusion, Blaug is right. Marx uses the example <strong>of</strong> religion because God is abstract,<br />

though many people use their abstract beliefs <strong>of</strong> God to formulate community, religion, and<br />

other relationships with each other. Similarly, people think <strong>of</strong> abstract social relationships<br />

(the need for commodities, the buying <strong>of</strong> commodities, the loss <strong>of</strong> value within commodities,<br />

the mysteriousness <strong>of</strong> commodities etc.) as axioms to base economic choices <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong>.<br />

Message [212] referenced by [219]. Next Message by Max is [220].<br />

[219] Hans: Blaug’s Error Exemplified. <strong>The</strong>re is a big difference between Blaug and<br />

Marx. Blaug says that the social relations are relations between people, and the problem is<br />

hat people treat them as if they were relations between <strong>thing</strong>s. Marx says the social relations<br />

are between <strong>thing</strong>s, and the problem is that individuals are trying to manipulate these socially<br />

empowered <strong>thing</strong>s for their benefit. This does not work, instead it has the unintended side<br />

effect <strong>of</strong> making the individuals the servants <strong>of</strong> anonymous social forces instead <strong>of</strong> their<br />

masters.<br />

Max’s [212] was incredibly perceptive because he found a situation in society where people<br />

acted exactly as Blaug described. This situation is banks approving lyers’ loans and then<br />

selling these loans on the market for mortgage-backed securities. Here banks were aware<br />

<strong>of</strong> their social relations with the borrower: they knew the borrower had a high probability<br />

<strong>of</strong> defaulting on the loan. But they thought by turning this relation into a <strong>thing</strong>, this social<br />

reality would not matter and they would get rich. This is a rip-<strong>of</strong>f, a pyramid scheme, which<br />

may work for a while but inevitably has to blow up.<br />

Marx says that capitalists turn to speculation only when ordinary capitalist exploitation<br />

runs into obstacles. Here is what Marx means by this. An ordinary productive capitalist can<br />

earn free money just as the speculator, but this source <strong>of</strong> free money is much more secure<br />

and long-term than the speculator’s. If therefore ordinary capitalists turn into speculators en<br />

masse, this is a sign that they are somewhat desperate because their ordinary source <strong>of</strong> free<br />

money is no longer flowing.<br />

Ordinary capitalist exploitation comes from people acting according to Marx’s definition<br />

<strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities. Capitalists know they can sell products for<br />

money, and this money gives them access to all other wealth. <strong>The</strong>y are taking advantage<br />

<strong>of</strong> social relations between <strong>thing</strong>s, between money and commodities. Of course if pressed<br />

they may say that these social relations ultimately have to do with people, but when they<br />

are buying and selling, they do not think <strong>of</strong> it as social relations between people but they<br />

see pr<strong>of</strong>it opportunities in the social properties <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s. This is a big difference. <strong>The</strong><br />

bank <strong>of</strong>ficers approving lyers’ loans and then selling them were fully aware <strong>of</strong> the social<br />

relations represented by the lyers’s loans and sent boastful emails to their friends how they<br />

made a killing from the greed and stupidity <strong>of</strong> the home buyers. Productive capitalists,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 169<br />

doing meticulous research in order to find <strong>thing</strong>s which they can produce at lower costs<br />

than their market price, do not send emails around how they screwed people. <strong>The</strong>y are not<br />

even necessarily aware <strong>of</strong> it that they are screwing the workers producing those goods—after<br />

all the workers voluntarily enter employment contracts with them. Marx will explain this<br />

paradoxical situation, that in capitalism, workers clamor for being exploited, as the book<br />

goes on.<br />

As we know from experience, ordinary capitalist exploitation is a much more stable flow<br />

<strong>of</strong> free money than any pyramid scheme. But we all know that there is no free lunch—so<br />

what is the downside? For the workers the downside is that they have to produce without<br />

prospect <strong>of</strong> ever being able to get a fair share <strong>of</strong> the wealth they are producing. But for<br />

the capitalists and society as a whole the downside is that they and we do not understand<br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> the mechanism which dispenses free money to the capitalists. We as a society<br />

are doing one <strong>thing</strong> but we think we are doing some<strong>thing</strong> completely different. What we<br />

are really doing is so non-obvious that we have to read a big and complicated book, Marx’s<br />

Capital, to understand it—and <strong>first</strong> we have to overcome the opposition <strong>of</strong> the 99% <strong>of</strong> all<br />

economists who say that Capital is wrong.<br />

This would be not such a big deal if these illusions about the nature <strong>of</strong> our social relations<br />

would not go hand in hand with us not being the masters <strong>of</strong> these social relations. It was<br />

just discovered that the same apparatus which is dispensing free money to the capitalists<br />

is also driving the entire human race and countless other species over a cliff by causing<br />

catastrophic climate change. We just can watch it as if it was a horror show on TV—and so<br />

far, the horrors are for most <strong>of</strong> us on TV screens only. A thorough change in the nature <strong>of</strong><br />

our social relations would be necessary to stop this horror from unfolding and spreading to<br />

everyone’s real life. But social changes are slow and difficult, and at the moment the climate<br />

movement is far too weak to effect such pr<strong>of</strong>ound changes.<br />

Message [219] referenced by [499]. Next Message by Hans is [236].<br />

[411] Babyceta: graded A– On the surface, Blaug’s statement about commodity fetishism<br />

appears accurate. To reify an object means to turn an abstract concept into some<strong>thing</strong> concrete.<br />

Here, Blaug means the invisible social relations between people, and supposes they<br />

are expressed concretely by individuals who treat human social relationships as if they were<br />

relationships between <strong>thing</strong>s. To Blaug, we become fetishistic about commodities because<br />

we believe their ownership reifies human social interactions. I may purchase a pair <strong>of</strong> shoes<br />

not because I benefit from their use-value, but because someone I am associated with owns<br />

a pair just like them, and having a pair expresses a bond or some sort <strong>of</strong> camaraderie with<br />

that individual. Blaug’s notions <strong>of</strong> commodity fetishism are more akin to Veblen’s notions<br />

<strong>of</strong> pecuniary emulation or conspicuous consumption, and not to what Marx would consider<br />

fetishism <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

To Marx, social relationships are between <strong>thing</strong>s, and people believe they can manipulate<br />

the physical nature or properties <strong>of</strong> these <strong>thing</strong>s for their personal benefit. That is the illusive<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> capitalism: we accept unnatural, man-made occurrences to be natural outcomes,<br />

and are therefore only fooling ourselves. I wrote in an earlier submission [308] that fetishism<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities is a social force based on natural construction (Hans replied that it would be<br />

more accurate to say commodity fetishism is the socialization <strong>of</strong> nature), and I still stand by<br />

170 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

that definition. But my understanding <strong>of</strong> what Marx is trying to say, however, has evolved<br />

to include the belief that pr<strong>of</strong>it and greed are inevitable outcomes <strong>of</strong> human nature, and<br />

therefore, they justify capitalism. <strong>The</strong> belief that the material make-up or physical properties<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities somehow transmit social characteristics is the fetishistic equivalent <strong>of</strong> the<br />

proverbial pot <strong>of</strong> gold. We see this colorful rainbow and believe that the pot <strong>of</strong> gold transmits<br />

its value to society, not because <strong>of</strong> the inherent value embedded deep inside <strong>of</strong> the gold, but<br />

purely because the gold is shiny and beautiful.<br />

Hans: To reify means to treat some<strong>thing</strong> as a material object which isn’t an material object. By definition you<br />

cannot reify an object, only some<strong>thing</strong> which is not an object.<br />

We haven’t explained capitalism yet in class, but Marx does not derive capitalist behavior from greed, and he<br />

would say that the justification <strong>of</strong> capitalism by human nature is a modern form <strong>of</strong> commodity fetishism.<br />

Next Message by Babyceta is [538].<br />

[425] Bigwhite: It seems that fetishism is caused by social behavior and social relationships,<br />

sometimes making a commodity seem more desirable or valuable than it may actually<br />

be. It is true that people seem to let social relations reflect on their commodities, which to<br />

Marx seems like somewhat <strong>of</strong> a mysterious phenomenon, that he can’t explain at <strong>first</strong>. This<br />

seems to be most apparent with <strong>thing</strong>s such as gold and diamonds, people let social relations<br />

influence the price <strong>of</strong> these commodities and makes them more expensive than if they were<br />

just traded as a relation between <strong>thing</strong>s. If there wasn’t the influence <strong>of</strong> the social relation<br />

then people would certainly say that water holds more value than diamonds. Its use value<br />

far exceeds that <strong>of</strong> diamonds for the individual person, yet it seems less valuable because it<br />

is so cheaply traded.<br />

Next Message by Bigwhite is [547].<br />

[429] PLG: graded B+ Fetishism in Marx’s terms refers to a consumer’s belief that commodities<br />

carry power because <strong>of</strong> their physical makeup. This leads consumers to become<br />

enslaved to commodities. <strong>The</strong> consumers do not make the connection that the power <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity comes from the labor used to create it. Rather than being the master <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity, the commodity becomes the master <strong>of</strong> the consumer because <strong>of</strong> this “false<br />

consciousness” as it is described in Hans’ annotations.<br />

Blaug’s description <strong>of</strong> fetishism is different from Marx in a few ways. He believes that<br />

fetishism is treating social relations between men as if they were relations between <strong>thing</strong>s.<br />

This belief in turn falsely reifies commodities. In contrast Marx does not have an issue with<br />

reifying commodities. But there must be a consciousness <strong>of</strong> the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value to go<br />

along with this reification. If there is not a notion <strong>of</strong> the labor congealed in the commodity<br />

then consumers become controlled by the power <strong>of</strong> the commodity. This leads consumers to<br />

utilize commodities for pr<strong>of</strong>its on the market rather than for use or exchange. <strong>The</strong>y enter a<br />

non-stop race <strong>of</strong> obtaining commodities to gain further power. <strong>The</strong> commodities gain control<br />

over the consciousness <strong>of</strong> the consumer.<br />

Hans: Your account <strong>of</strong> Blaug’s interpretation is much closer to Marx than what you think is Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong><br />

commodity fetishism. Your account <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory is a creative adaptation <strong>of</strong> modern consumerism to elements<br />

<strong>of</strong> Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value. You seem to have read Marx, but in some passages you didn’t pay enough attention,<br />

perhaps because you thought you already knew what he was talking about.<br />

Next Message by PLG is [551].<br />

[499] Kohhep: <strong>The</strong> statement Blaug makes about commodity fetishism is correct. In<br />

commodity fetishism people view man made relations as if they were natural events. <strong>The</strong>


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 171<br />

idea that cotton parcels stained green (money) has value, or the ability to purchase any<strong>thing</strong><br />

known to man if one has enough money, is an example. Money, in reality, has no worth.<br />

Money simply represents the value (abstract labor) within a commodity.<br />

Hans: See [219] and [240].<br />

Next Message by Kohhep is [968].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 307 is 138 in 1995WI, 115 in 1995ut, 148 in 1996sp, 150 in 1996ut, 155 in<br />

1997WI, 162 in 1997sp, 155 in 1997ut, 267 in 2008SP, 265 in 2008fa, and 294 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 307 Make a thought experiment comparing market production, in which an artisan<br />

produces some<strong>thing</strong> for sale, to community production, in which the same artisan knows<br />

the people who will use the <strong>thing</strong>s he is producing, and these are the same people who<br />

are producing the <strong>thing</strong>s the artisan is consuming. If you were this artisan, would you act<br />

differently in the market situation than in the community situation? Would, over time, the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> your product and the technology <strong>of</strong> your labor evolve differently in these two<br />

situations?<br />

[200] Frida: graded A Market v.s. community production. If I were a linen weaver in a<br />

market economy the only reason I would weave linen is that I need it to to obtain use-values<br />

for myself. I would not be thinking about the Linen as a use value for others. While I am<br />

weaving my linen I am worried somewhat about the quality <strong>of</strong> the linen, if it is noticeably<br />

inferior I will have a hard time selling or exchanging it. What is probably more important in<br />

determining my actions is quantity. If I can make more linen that is reasonably exchangeable<br />

I can obtain more use values. On the other hand, if I was on a personal basis with the people<br />

I was exchanging linen with, I would be thinking about the linen’s use value as well as<br />

exchange value as I was making it. I wouldn’t be able to help thinking about others using<br />

my linen, and I would hope that they would make sure that their products were similarly<br />

high quality.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se differences in attitude would lead to a more personal evolution <strong>of</strong> the technology<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor in the community mode <strong>of</strong> production. If I am thinking about the use-value <strong>of</strong> my<br />

linen and not just the exchange value I might use slightly less efficient means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

if it will lead to a higher quality product. I hand-weave my linen partially because I know<br />

everyone that will be using it, and also because I trade it for hand-tailored clo<strong>thing</strong> that my<br />

cousin Judy makes. In the community model, everyone knows my mode <strong>of</strong> production and<br />

that will affect my choices regarding it.<br />

Next Message by Frida is [369].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 308 is 242 in 2004fa, 266 in 2008fa, and 280 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 308 One <strong>of</strong> Marx’s basic critiques <strong>of</strong> capitalism is that the surface appearances<br />

are false, they hide what is going on underneath. But in the section about the fetish-like<br />

character Marx seems to deny this critique since he says that the relations <strong>of</strong> their private<br />

labors appear to the producers as what they are. Can this be reconciled?<br />

[197] Oreo: graded A– Is Marx contradicting himself? In the previous sections <strong>of</strong><br />

chapter One, Marx is undoubtedly telling us that the external appearances <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

provide us with no insight to how much the commodity is worth. This is true for consumers<br />

172 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

who are unaware <strong>of</strong> the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that went into a product. When Marx later states<br />

that “private labors appear to the producers as what they are”, I don’t believe that he is in<br />

any way contradicting himself. I think that he is simply saying that the producer <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity knows the amount <strong>of</strong> human labor that went into the commodity, while the naive<br />

consumer does not. If I were to go into a jewelry shop and see a necklace that I wanted to<br />

purchase, I would have no idea how much the necklace costs based on its appearance alone.<br />

However, the jewelry maker would know exactly what the necklace was worth, because he<br />

was the one who produced it. He knows precisely how many labor hours went into it, and<br />

therefore the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> the necklace would appear clearly to him, allowing him to<br />

accurately price the necklace.<br />

Message [197] referenced by [199], [335], and [555]. Next Message by Oreo is [300].<br />

[199] Hans: Predicting prices is by far not the only mystery. Oreo’s answer [197] is<br />

intelligent but I want to send out a correction right away so that the discussion does not get<br />

on the wrong track.<br />

For someone selling commodities, especially new commodities, the greatest mystery is<br />

what prices they will fetch on the market and how many people will buy it. This is incredibly<br />

difficult to predict. But this is not the mystery Marx is talking about. See message [198] I<br />

just sent. To Marx, qualitative <strong>thing</strong>s are much more important than quantitative <strong>thing</strong>s, and<br />

I think he had a point.<br />

Given this too-narrow interpretation <strong>of</strong> the mystery, Oreo says that knowledge about the<br />

labor content <strong>of</strong> commodities is available on the market—if only because the same people<br />

who produce the commodities (or today the capitalists, who supervise production and have<br />

intricate knowledge about it) also sell them. In addition, jewelry seems to me a commodity<br />

where every expert with a microscope can probably determine quite well what the cost <strong>of</strong><br />

a given piece is, even if they haven’t produced it. Oreo is right, information about the<br />

underlying economy is available on the market, otherwise the economy would be rudderless<br />

and could not function. However, some <strong>of</strong> this information is terribly misleading. In section<br />

2 <strong>of</strong> chapter One, after showing how well the relative form <strong>of</strong> value represents the underlying<br />

production relations, Marx shows that the equivalent form does not do it well but reflects<br />

every<strong>thing</strong> in an upside-down manner (the three peculiarities <strong>of</strong> the equivalent form).<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 308 was posed in the context <strong>of</strong> a very specific passage in Capital and can only<br />

be answered by looking at this passage in detail.<br />

Message [199] referenced by [335]. Next Message by Hans is [210].<br />

[335] AlexDaily: graded B+ Marx makes a seemly contradiction about capitalism saying<br />

that on the surface appearances are false and then saying that the relations <strong>of</strong> their private<br />

labors appear to the producers as what they are. However, Marx can be reconciled because<br />

he is talking about two different scales <strong>of</strong> capitalism. On the smaller scale, capitalism works<br />

with Adam Smith’s invisible hand benefiting all. However, on a larger scale much is hidden<br />

and does not benefit everyone.<br />

Hans: This is a tricky question to answer in the exam because the class discussion had only one intelligent but<br />

wrong guess [197] and my correction [199] which tried to give a better explanation and motivation <strong>of</strong> the question<br />

but did not answer it. You are right to say that Marx is talking on two different levels. It is not the bigger/smaller<br />

scale <strong>of</strong> capitalism, but the surface is by definition the market, and those who see <strong>thing</strong>s as they are are the producers.<br />

Next Message by AlexDaily is [336].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 173<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 317 What is the “secret” that gives the commodities their fetish-like character?<br />

[354] Wolf: For the in-class answer, I said that the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

is based <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> the equivalent form <strong>of</strong> an exchange and that individuals reflect the value <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity they are trading for on the use-value <strong>of</strong> the equivalent which makes it seem as<br />

if the equivalent’s use-value contains this mirrored value as its nature. I realized that this is<br />

not the case.<br />

<strong>The</strong> “secret” <strong>of</strong> commodities fetish-like characteristic comes from “the special social<br />

character <strong>of</strong> labor which produces commodities, and the corresponding peculiar social relation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity producers.” (Annotations pg. 189 from Marx’s draft <strong>of</strong> 165:1 in<br />

Capital) This means that the fetish-like characteristic comes from the production process as<br />

opposed to the exchange as I thought earlier.<br />

First, let me make it clear that the fetish-like characteristic <strong>of</strong> commodities is some<strong>thing</strong><br />

(that I will make clear momentarily) inherent within commodities that makes commodities’<br />

social relationships seem as if they were natural, coming from the commodities themselves<br />

(this applies to the social relationship <strong>of</strong> commodities as well). Within the production process<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodity-exchanging societies, a dual character <strong>of</strong> labor creates this characteristic.<br />

<strong>The</strong> dual character <strong>of</strong> labor is the difference between the two opposed aspects <strong>of</strong> concrete<br />

labor and abstract labor. In order for a commodity to be exchangeable, the labor process<br />

used to make the commodity has to be different than that used in the commodity that is<br />

being exchanged for (a use-value is not exchanged for the same use-value). This implies a<br />

social division <strong>of</strong> labor. On the other hand, the labor congealed in the commodity has to be<br />

qualitatively the same as that in the commodity being exchanged for, otherwise exchange<br />

could not occur. <strong>The</strong>refore, each concrete labor is different, but at the same time equal to<br />

every other concrete labor when abstracted as abstract labor. However, it is only abstracted<br />

in the exchange. Producers’ concrete labor is planned and reflected on this abstraction in<br />

order for them to produce for exchange on the market. This entails that the labor must be a<br />

different concrete labor producing a socially necessary use-value that is qualitatively different<br />

(without this distinction and separation, exchange is not possible) while simultaneously<br />

being abstract labor equal to other congealed abstract labors. Once the market is widespread,<br />

the producer cannot afford to pay attention to this distinction, but rather must focus on and<br />

act with the market for her/his very survival. This creates competition and atomization. Because<br />

the producer is at the whim <strong>of</strong> the market, this creates the illusion that the market is not<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> that s/he contributes to, rather, some<strong>thing</strong> to be struggled against for survival (interestingly,<br />

their very participation in the market is causing the market to act against them).<br />

Because the producer is at the whim <strong>of</strong> the market, it follows that the market appears objective<br />

and natural, some<strong>thing</strong> beyond them. This is the expression <strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Next Message by Wolf is [638].<br />

[382] Long: <strong>The</strong> secret that gives the commodities their fetish-like character is the fact<br />

that they act as a mysterious <strong>thing</strong>. It is the way that a laborer changes some<strong>thing</strong> into useful<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s which make them extrasensory. Marx said “take the form <strong>of</strong> wood, for instance, is<br />

altered if a table is made out <strong>of</strong> it. Nevertheless the table continuse to be wood, an ordinary,<br />

sensuous <strong>thing</strong>. But as soon as it emerges as a commodity, it changes into a <strong>thing</strong> which<br />

174 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

transcends sensuousness.” So the wood is useless but when it become a table it turns into<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> very useful and still it is just a piece <strong>of</strong> wood. But it takes human labour to<br />

transform it into a table which in turns make it a fetishism that attaches it to the product<br />

as it is being produced as a commodity. Marx called it “inseparable from the prodution <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities.”<br />

Hans: You are the victim <strong>of</strong> a terribly misleading translation <strong>of</strong> 163:3/o in the Penguin/Vintage edition. <strong>The</strong><br />

translation “as soon as it emerges as a commodity” sounds as if the table, despite still being simple wood, obtains<br />

mystical properties as soon as it emerges from the production process as a finished product. I.e. that the fetish-like<br />

character <strong>of</strong> the commodity consists in people falling in love with the desirable use-values <strong>of</strong> their commodities.<br />

This is exactly the opposite <strong>of</strong> what Marx wanted to convey.<br />

Next Message by Long is [413].<br />

[407] Baseball: <strong>The</strong> “secret” that gives commodities their fetish like character lies within<br />

the labor which produces them. <strong>The</strong> component which gives commodities value is the abstract<br />

human labor needed to produce those commodities. Marx says that the elements<br />

which give commodities their fetish-like character are the “expressions <strong>of</strong> the inner nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> value.” By definition, value is not derived from the worth <strong>of</strong> a commodity but from the<br />

abstract human labor used to produce the commodity. Now in the real world, consumers<br />

are attracted to products because <strong>of</strong> their use-value; in other words, the way in which the<br />

product will benefit the consumer. Use-values do not magically become attached to commodities<br />

when they are placed on the store shelf. <strong>The</strong> reality is use-values are activated by<br />

the labor which is used to produce them. <strong>The</strong>refore labor is the underlying secret which<br />

gives commodities their fetish like character.<br />

Hans: One leitmotif in the entire class discussion was the fact that the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities, which<br />

Marx discusses, is exactly not the attraction or obsession <strong>of</strong> consumers with the use-values <strong>of</strong> the commodities.<br />

Next Message by Baseball is [540].<br />

[433] JSmits: graded A <strong>The</strong> “secret” that gives commodities their fetish-like character<br />

are underlying social issues. In the production process where humans are interacting with<br />

nature there are no illusions but once these goods hit the market this introduces irrealism.<br />

At this point this is where the relations <strong>of</strong> the consumer and the good should be directed<br />

toward realism but the lack <strong>of</strong> control in this stage <strong>of</strong> production is where you lose control<br />

<strong>of</strong> realism. Marx calls the commodity “magical” because <strong>of</strong> the social power that it has over<br />

us. We think that we control the commodities but they control us.<br />

Hans’s Critical Realist Arguments in Marx’s Capital, Section 3.7, “In more modern terms,<br />

the market participants live in a virtual reality, which gives them the illusion to be able to act<br />

in their interest, but which channels them towards a predetermined outcome.” This just tells<br />

me that we really don’t have any choice in what we do because our course has already been<br />

set. It shows the power that commodities have over us.<br />

Hans: To derive from an accurate description <strong>of</strong> the workings <strong>of</strong> our society that no<strong>thing</strong> can be done about it is,<br />

according to Marx, also a form <strong>of</strong> fetishism.<br />

Next Message by JSmits is [588].<br />

[453] DMorris: <strong>The</strong> secret that Marx describes as giving commodities their fetish-like<br />

character is the fact that their character was initially created by society. For example, gold<br />

is valued almost universally, and has been used to trade with for thousands <strong>of</strong> years. However,<br />

other than its use for trading, gold has very little use-value. Additionally, gold is not<br />

significantly more labor-intensive than other metals. Despite all <strong>of</strong> this, however, gold has<br />

maintained a fantastic value for years. Marx comments on how common this is; how some


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 175<br />

commodities are worth much more than their labor and natural worth. He states that despite<br />

the fact that commodities are man-made, commodities seem to posses properties that are<br />

independent <strong>of</strong> human activity. He explains that this fetish-like character denies all rational<br />

explanation.<br />

Hans: What makes you think that gold is “not significantly more labor-intensive than other metals” and that it has<br />

“very little use-value”?<br />

I am baffled by your response—not only because I thought it was common knowledge that the part <strong>of</strong> the earth<br />

crust accessible to mining contains much less gold than other metals (such as iron, copper, aluminum), and that the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> a noncorrosive metal which is at the same time an excellent conductor is very high, but also because<br />

you throw out <strong>of</strong> the window every<strong>thing</strong> I thought this class would teach you, namely: What makes you think that<br />

gold differs from other commodities by having higher use-value and/or higher value? According to Marx’s theory,<br />

under the gold standard, an exchange <strong>of</strong> a commodity against a gold coin is an equal exchange in that the gold coin<br />

contains as much (direct and indirect) labor as the ordinary commodity. What distinguishes gold is not that it has<br />

more value, but that it has a different form <strong>of</strong> value than other commodities.<br />

Next Message by DMorris is [677].<br />

[476] Jo: <strong>The</strong> secret is the double character <strong>of</strong> labor. In essence, there is a social relationship<br />

between commodities, a mysterious value that is inherent in the production <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity, yet independent from its use-value, and completely outside <strong>of</strong> the control <strong>of</strong> the<br />

producers <strong>of</strong> the commodity, yet somehow mysteriously accounted for during the production<br />

process. It is out <strong>of</strong> the producer’s control because it results from a social relation between<br />

commodities after the commodities have been produced.<br />

As Hans explains, “Labor must fit into the division <strong>of</strong> labor as concrete labor, and all<br />

labor must be equal as abstract labor.” <strong>The</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> abstract labor can be illustrated<br />

within capitalism. By comparing a table bought from Wal-Mart and a table custom-made<br />

by a local craftsman, it is <strong>first</strong> clear that the cost <strong>of</strong> the Wal-Mart table would be much<br />

lower than the price <strong>of</strong> the custom-made table. <strong>The</strong> custom-made table takes much longer<br />

to build, since it is not constructed on an assembly line in a factory, like the Wal-Mart table.<br />

Much more abstract labor would be equated to the value <strong>of</strong> the custom-made table, which in<br />

capitalism would translate to a higher price. <strong>The</strong> way that the market arrives at this price is<br />

mysterious, as it is a reflection <strong>of</strong> the concrete labor involved in production, which (referring<br />

still to concrete labor) has no way <strong>of</strong> directly influencing the value that the market arrives at<br />

after production.<br />

Next Message by Jo is [575].<br />

[486] Ferox: graded A <strong>The</strong> ‘secret’ which gives commodities a fetish-like character is the<br />

cyclical societal belief structure surrounding commodities. This arises out <strong>of</strong> the belief that<br />

commodities have real social powers, e.g. influence over social relations, ability to affect<br />

economic forces, etc. Even though this fetish like character arose out <strong>of</strong> wishful thinking on<br />

the behalf <strong>of</strong> humans, this attribute is only an emergent characteristic <strong>of</strong> social activity—and<br />

failure to acknowledge this belief destroys the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Hans: Marx would call this idealism. You cannot change society by changing the belief-systems <strong>of</strong> individuals. It<br />

is good reasoning, therefore it gets an A, but it is not Marx’s theory.<br />

Next Message by Ferox is [559].<br />

[490] Intaglio: secret <strong>of</strong> fetish-like character. My original answer was that the secret<br />

is that the actual source <strong>of</strong> value is not a physical aspect <strong>of</strong> the commodity. This is related<br />

but it is the end result <strong>of</strong> the secret, not the actual secret. <strong>The</strong> secret that gives commodities<br />

their fetish-like character is that producers don’t base the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity on the<br />

176 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

common denominator <strong>of</strong> equalized abstract labor. Instead they judge the value by how well<br />

it will perform on the market. Producers are always changing the price <strong>of</strong> their product to<br />

take advantage <strong>of</strong> certain situations and make more pr<strong>of</strong>it. This means they have to treat the<br />

congealed labor (unchanging) as a physical property <strong>of</strong> the product. <strong>The</strong> secret lies in the<br />

social relations between the producers themselves that disregard all labor as equal.<br />

Hans: In your last sentence I added “between the producers themselves.”<br />

Next Message by Intaglio is [491].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 318 is 157 in 1996sp, 163 in 1997WI, 170 in 1997sp, 172 in 1998WI, 179 in<br />

1999SP, 190 in 2000fa, 200 in 2001fa, 214 in 2002fa, 222 in 2003fa, 252 in 2004fa,<br />

267 in 2007SP, 272 in 2007fa, 278 in 2008SP, 290 in 2009fa, 296 in 2011fa, and 309 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 318 Explain Marx’s metaphor that “value does not have it written on its forehead<br />

what it is.” Later in the commodity fetishism section, Marx uses the same metaphor “written<br />

on the forehead” again in a slightly different context. Compare what he says that second<br />

time with what he says here.<br />

[229] Trap: Value is in the Labor. As I understand it, when Marx says “Value, therefore<br />

does not have it written on its forehead what it is,” through this statement he is showing<br />

that the value <strong>of</strong> commodities is not immediately obvious, he is explaining that value comes<br />

from labor. In the next sentence Marx proves that we don’t understand that labor is the true<br />

value by saying that, “value transforms every product <strong>of</strong> labor into a social hieroglyphic.” I<br />

believe he is explaining that the producers <strong>of</strong> the products that are being traded, are done so<br />

on the basis <strong>of</strong> “my product is better than yours” without looking at the labor, which gives<br />

the item its value to begin with. In the annotations Hans states, “<strong>The</strong>y use scientific tools to<br />

decipher these hieroglyphics, and they eventually succeed.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> second time Marx uses the metaphor he says, “<strong>The</strong>se forms, which have it written<br />

on their foreheads that they belong to the social formation in which the production process<br />

has the mastery over men...” <strong>The</strong> meaning <strong>of</strong> the metaphor doesn’t change all that much<br />

between the times he uses it, but there is a little distinction. I believe that in this one he<br />

is more blatantly talking about the bourgeois economists, and their failure to ask why the<br />

“production process” has so much control over the labor that goes into commodities. He is<br />

upset that people are not seeing that the value comes from labor, and that they have little<br />

control over it.<br />

In his <strong>first</strong> reference, he is speaking more about hieroglyphs, and how people have found<br />

scientific ways to decipher them, and that they just need to recognize that value is in the<br />

labor. In the second one, he is speaking in a more theoretical sense, about the mistakes <strong>of</strong><br />

the bourgeois economists to ask the correct questions about the production process.<br />

Hans: In the second quote, Marx does not criticize the bourgeois economists for “not seeing that the value comes<br />

from labor.” On the contrary, Marx writes in 173:1/oo, just before the passage you quote: “Political economy has<br />

indeed ... analyzed value and its magnitude, and has uncovered the content concealed within these forms.” <strong>The</strong><br />

content meaning that value comes from labor and the magnitude <strong>of</strong> value from socially necessary labor-time. Not<br />

seeing that value comes from labor is not his grievance with bourgeois political economy, therefore what is?<br />

In the <strong>first</strong> instance, value is the <strong>thing</strong> with the forehead, in the second, it is forms. In the <strong>first</strong> instance Marx<br />

names some<strong>thing</strong> that is not written on the forehead, in the second he names some<strong>thing</strong> that is written on the<br />

forehead. Marx is using the same memorable metaphor in two different situations—this is not an accident. By


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 177<br />

using the same metaphor Marx indicates that the two places are related. <strong>Question</strong> 318 wanted you to sort out for the<br />

reader how these two places hang together. <strong>The</strong> vague formulation “the meaning <strong>of</strong> the metaphor doesn’t change<br />

all that much between the times he uses it” is not an acceptable answer. <strong>The</strong> difference you are naming (that the<br />

second talks about bourgeois economists and the <strong>first</strong> does not) is outside the metaphor itself, i.e., in neither case is<br />

Marx speaking about the forehead <strong>of</strong> the bourgeois economists.<br />

Message [229] referenced by [2012fa:296]. Next Message by Trap is [386].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 320 is 173 in 1998WI, 180 in 1999SP, 202 in 2001fa, 216 in 2002fa, 224 in<br />

2003fa, 254 in 2004fa, 249 in 2005fa, 269 in 2007SP, 292 in 2009fa, and 298 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 320 If someone understands that value comes from society and not from<br />

nature, how can that person still have a fetishistic view <strong>of</strong> social relations under capitalism?<br />

[245] Semaj: (graded C–) Value comes from society, not from nature. Despite understanding<br />

where true value comes from, I believe that people will continue to have a fetishistic<br />

view <strong>of</strong> social relations based on physical properties <strong>of</strong> commodity and what value the social<br />

system believes the commodity takes. Like Marx says towards the end <strong>of</strong> paragraph,“<strong>The</strong><br />

disadvantages <strong>of</strong> capitalism are believed to be anchored in human nature, instead <strong>of</strong> people<br />

recognizing that they are brought about by a very special social form <strong>of</strong> organizing production.”<br />

It’s human nature to be ignorant to the facts <strong>of</strong> the actual social relations in a capitalist<br />

mindset. I feel like even though we understand what kind <strong>of</strong> production and labor has gone<br />

into a commodity, we will still look for the physical appearances and what others say before<br />

we are fully convinced on it’s actual use-value. To truly understand what the social relations<br />

are, you would have learn how to determine alternate facts <strong>of</strong> an actual commodity and use<br />

them as your guide to value, instead <strong>of</strong> following into the highly favored fetishistic outlook<br />

on commodities.<br />

Hans: Marx’s Capital is not about some “true” value which commodities should have but according to the labor<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> value, actually existing capitalism commodity prices are indeed regulated by labor content. Compare<br />

[92], [122], and the links from there.<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 321 is 217 in 2002fa, 225 in 2003fa, 255 in 2004fa, 250 in 2005fa, 270 in<br />

2007SP, 275 in 2007fa, 281 in 2008SP, 299 in 2011fa, and 312 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 321 Marx criticizes in 166:2/o that even after the discovery <strong>of</strong> labor as the the<br />

substance <strong>of</strong> value, this was generally considered an “immutable fact.” What else should<br />

people have thought and done?<br />

[670] RexManning: This is from earlier in the book, but I still wanted to add my two<br />

cents. It is from question 321, which asks: Marx criticizes in 166:2/o that even after the<br />

discovery <strong>of</strong> labor as the substance <strong>of</strong> value, this was generally considered an “immutable<br />

fact.” What else should people have though and done?<br />

<strong>The</strong> natural sciences consist <strong>of</strong> many different laws, and theories, that we as humans tend<br />

to accept without questioning or even understanding. <strong>The</strong> social sciences, that rule human<br />

behavior and interaction are <strong>of</strong>ten lumped in the same realm <strong>of</strong> immutable facts that we<br />

blindly accept. Even after the discovery that value is based on labor, the fetishistic view did<br />

not change, because <strong>of</strong> the blind acceptance <strong>of</strong> these social “laws.” Instead <strong>of</strong> continuing<br />

to accept these immutable social facts, people should have considered the labor value <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities. Marx then says that even after such a discovery has been made, a society<br />

178 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

“can neither clear by bold leaps, nor remove by decree, the successive phases <strong>of</strong> its natural<br />

development. But it can shorten and lessen the birth-pangs.” <strong>The</strong> understanding <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

as the measure <strong>of</strong> value should have spread, and not been disregarded for a relationship <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism and human psychology.<br />

Next Message by RexManning is [801].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 323 is 160 in 1996sp, 173 in 1997sp, 165 in 1997ut, 194 in 2000fa, 205 in<br />

2001fa, 219 in 2002fa, 227 in 2003fa, 257 in 2004fa, 252 in 2005fa, 272 in 2007SP, 277<br />

in 2007fa, 283 in 2008SP, 281 in 2008fa, 302 in 2011fa, and 315 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 323 Commodity producers do not exchange their products because they consider<br />

the labor in these products to be equal and therefore believe the fruits <strong>of</strong> the labor should<br />

be distributed on an equal basis. Marx claims that, on the contrary, the market interactions<br />

induce them to unknowingly equalize their labors. Describe the process by which they<br />

equalize their labors, and the goals which they pursue in this process.<br />

[1209] Hans: Grades force you to flatten your thinking. Marx says that all labor processes<br />

in capitalism are thoroughly homogenized and alienated by the fact that the products<br />

are produced for the market. Since human labor in the abstract is the ingredient that creates<br />

value, labor becomes indeed abstract drudgery.<br />

When reviewing your contributions over the entire Semester for the final grades, I noticed<br />

a similarly detrimental influence <strong>of</strong> the market on your homework answers. <strong>The</strong> market<br />

affects the homework answers because you need to get a good grade so that your laborpower<br />

is marketable. This causes some <strong>of</strong> you to stop thinking on your own and instead<br />

sifting through the archives or the Annotations in search for the “right” answer.<br />

For instance, [243] basically says (I am caricaturing to make my point):<br />

Initially I thought output would be a better way to measure labor than time,<br />

because different workers may have quite different outputs in the same<br />

time, but then I read that it must be time because Marx measures abstract<br />

labor, therefore my answer is: time.<br />

<strong>The</strong> author discards his own thinking because it does not lead him to the “right” answer—<br />

although his thinking is valid! Marx himself said (again I am paraphrasing):<br />

I am measuring abstract labor, therefore it must be time, but this leads me<br />

to the paradox <strong>of</strong> the lazy worker. <strong>The</strong>refore I realize that abstract labor<br />

has a social dimension. This means I cannot measure labor by actual time<br />

spent but must use the socially average time necessary to produce the same<br />

output.<br />

Marx did not have any qualms to run into contradictions (I call them impasses), because<br />

if this happens, he digs himself out <strong>of</strong> the contradiction again by a negation <strong>of</strong> the negation<br />

which preserves what is good in both contradictory aspects. For instance, one might say his<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> socially necessary labor-time is a way to measure time by output, i.e., it combines<br />

the advantages <strong>of</strong> both.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 179<br />

But you don’t have the luxury <strong>of</strong> being part <strong>of</strong> a dialogue which develops the answer like<br />

Marx did. You cannot be the one speaking up for the impasse, because this is the wrong<br />

answer. For the sake <strong>of</strong> your grade you have to try to jump immediately to the negation <strong>of</strong><br />

the negation. This means you are forced to leave out the mediating steps, i.e., you are no<br />

longer allowed to think <strong>thing</strong>s through but you must simply memorize what the right answer<br />

is.<br />

I am exaggerating. Some <strong>of</strong> you can act like Marx and do their own thinking, because they<br />

are so smart that they know they can produce valid ideas which will get good grades even<br />

if they are not saying every<strong>thing</strong> that can be said about the subject. But others, who are not<br />

exceptionally smart, get beaten down every time they try to think independently—until they<br />

give up and just memorize what they are supposed to say. To add insult to injury, they think<br />

they get beaten down because they are not as smart as the others. It is extremely difficult<br />

for them to realize that the system is deliberately preventing them from developing their full<br />

potential—for instance, by being miserly with money for schools, as I argue in [2005fa:116],<br />

[2003fa:681], and [2002fa:12] because it needs cannon fodder for the assembly lines. This<br />

creates a stratification along with the homogenization; some children are robust and smart<br />

enough to get through school unharmed, they will take the management position, but the<br />

majority is beaten down because the system needs lots <strong>of</strong> people who are convinced they are<br />

stupid and therefore willing to work hard for a low wage.<br />

First Message by Hans is [3].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 325 is 177 in 1998WI, 196 in 2000fa, 221 in 2002fa, 229 in 2003fa, 259 in<br />

2004fa, 254 in 2005fa, 274 in 2007SP, 279 in 2007fa, 285 in 2008SP, 283 in 2008fa, 297<br />

in 2009fa, 304 in 2011fa, and 304 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 325 Isn’t there an inconsistency in Marx’s text? At the beginning <strong>of</strong> paragraph<br />

167:1/o, the fixity <strong>of</strong> commodity prices is stressed, while towards the end <strong>of</strong> the same paragraph<br />

167:1/o, Marx emphasizes that they fluctuate continually.<br />

[225] Atticus: graded A+ Fixed Volatility. Although there appears to be an inconsistency<br />

in Marx’s explanation on the nature <strong>of</strong> prices, there are actually distinctive social relations<br />

that are, at the same time, exclusive from and related to each other. <strong>The</strong> fixity <strong>of</strong> prices, as<br />

does the volatility <strong>of</strong> prices, stems from the social relations involved in the production process.<br />

Owners <strong>of</strong> capital continuously compete with another and try to make their production<br />

processes more efficient to remain pr<strong>of</strong>itable in the market. This in turn homogenizes the<br />

labor processes in production between identical commodities. <strong>The</strong> labor-time required to<br />

produce commodities becomes homogenous, inadvertently, in all industries to remain relevant<br />

in a capitalist society. Although this phenomenon is purely a social relation controlled<br />

by humans, it asserts itself as a natural force in capitalism like the law <strong>of</strong> gravity is immutable<br />

in physics [167:1/o]. Value is relatively fixed in a commodity producing society<br />

due to the social relations in the production process. However, this mostly depends on the<br />

general ignorance and conformity <strong>of</strong> the majority <strong>of</strong> the laborers.<br />

<strong>The</strong> other social relation that Marx discusses seems like, on the surface, a contradiction to<br />

what was just previously discussed. However, a deeper look into Marx’s take on capitalism<br />

180 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

clarifies this apparent contradiction is like explaining the differences between microeconomics<br />

and macroeconomics. Labor processes continuously change among producers to get<br />

ahead <strong>of</strong> their competition. <strong>The</strong> productivity in tailoring coats may increase by tenfold by an<br />

individual producer. <strong>The</strong> real price <strong>of</strong> the coats produced by this specific tailor drops. This<br />

change in the process <strong>of</strong> labor by this particular tailor to produce a coat is a phenomenon<br />

that is inherent in among all commodity producers in a capitalist society. This constant modification<br />

in labor processes make prices and exchange proportions volatile on an individual<br />

level among producers.<br />

A commodity producer whose labor productivity increases significantly may experience<br />

a substantial drop in the price per unit relative to other commodity producers. Prices and<br />

exchange proportions at this point seem volatile. <strong>The</strong> other commodity producers manufacturing<br />

identical commodities will either improve their productivity resulting in staying in the<br />

game, gaining an edge over their competitors or failing. A sort <strong>of</strong> equilibrium occurs in that<br />

particular commodity’s industry which leads to fixity in pricing. Think <strong>of</strong> a graph with multiple,<br />

non-linear data points and a line <strong>of</strong> regression showing the relationship <strong>of</strong> the multiple<br />

data points. <strong>The</strong> vertical axis represents prices. <strong>The</strong> horizontal axis represents time. <strong>The</strong><br />

data points are the values <strong>of</strong> the commodities produced individual firms whose labor process<br />

creates varying levels <strong>of</strong> productivity (remember that value is based on labor-time). <strong>The</strong> line<br />

<strong>of</strong> regression represents the fixity <strong>of</strong> pricing <strong>of</strong> a particular commodity in a given industry.<br />

Hans: You are right to approach this as a dialectical contradiction. Dialectics is not easy, and since this is a class<br />

about Marxism, any respectable attempt to think dialectically can expect a good grade.<br />

Message [225] referenced by [400]. Next Message by Atticus is [371].<br />

[400] ANK: “<strong>The</strong> fixity <strong>of</strong> prices, as well as the volatility <strong>of</strong> prices, stems from the social<br />

relations involved in the production process” [225]. When Marx starts out by saying that<br />

commodity prices are fixed, he is referring to the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Because the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> commodities is determined by the labor required to produce them, the price <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity should be fixed because every commodity is <strong>of</strong> equal value regardless <strong>of</strong> who<br />

produced it. <strong>The</strong>n Marx switches to say that prices fluctuate continually. This fluctuation is<br />

not due to the value, but the exchange value. For example, in the summer, 20 yard <strong>of</strong> linen<br />

may be exchanged for 1 coat, whereas in the winter 50 yards <strong>of</strong> linen may be exchanged<br />

for 1 coat. This example demonstrates that exchange-values change or prices change as the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity such as a coat increases during cold winter months. Prices <strong>of</strong><br />

a given commodity should remain fixed between all the producers <strong>of</strong> that commodity. As<br />

the demand for the given commodity changes, such as an increase in demand for a coat<br />

in the winter, the price <strong>of</strong> the commodity may fluctuate equally for every producer <strong>of</strong> that<br />

commodity. <strong>The</strong>refore, there is no inconsistency in Marx’s statements because the value and<br />

exchange value relate to different aspects <strong>of</strong> the price determination <strong>of</strong> a given commodity.<br />

Hans: Marx would say that prices do not depend on the use-value <strong>of</strong> a product. If fewer coats are needed in<br />

summer then fewer coats are produced. Otherwise not bad.<br />

Next Message by ANK is [571].<br />

[452] Kobe: Marx says “A commodity is therefore a mysterious <strong>thing</strong>, simply because in it<br />

the social character <strong>of</strong> men’s labour appears to them as an objective character stamped upon<br />

the product <strong>of</strong> that labour; because the relation <strong>of</strong> the producers to the sum total <strong>of</strong> their own<br />

labour is presented to them as a social relation, existing not between themselves, but between<br />

the products <strong>of</strong> their labour.” This passage is the basis <strong>of</strong> how Marx <strong>first</strong> emphasizes that the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 181<br />

price <strong>of</strong> a commodity is fixed and then later in the paragraph he says the commodity price<br />

fluctuates. <strong>The</strong> social relation Marx talks <strong>of</strong> plays a role in the price <strong>of</strong> the commodity; this<br />

is true because society influences the prices <strong>of</strong> a particular commodity. Another contributing<br />

factor in commodity pricing going from fixed to later in its existence fluctuating is the need<br />

for that commodity, a type <strong>of</strong> technology that can produce the technology and human beings<br />

being able to produce the commodity at a greater rate. All <strong>of</strong> these factors would cause a<br />

change in commodity pricing. Just as we see today with an item such as an IPod, when<br />

it is <strong>first</strong> introduced the price is fixed at a higher level and through its existence the price<br />

then fluctuates with the supply and demand and production <strong>of</strong> the commodity. All this being<br />

said, I don’t believe there is an inconsistency in his writing, the reader must read through the<br />

paragraph to understand what he is telling the reader.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> passage in 167:1/o where Marx stresses the fixity <strong>of</strong> commodity prices reads: “As soon as these proportions<br />

have attained a certain customary fixity, they seem to spring from the nature <strong>of</strong> the products.” Marx is clearly<br />

not talking about the high introductory price <strong>of</strong> a new commodity, but about a commodity which has been around<br />

for a long time and whose price is generally known. Think <strong>of</strong> loaf <strong>of</strong> bread rather than ipods.<br />

Next Message by Kobe is [627].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 327 is 179 in 1998WI, 198 in 2000fa, 209 in 2001fa, 224 in 2002fa, 232 in<br />

2003fa, 262 in 2004fa, 257 in 2005fa, 277 in 2007SP, 282 in 2007fa, 285 in 2008fa, 299<br />

in 2009fa, and 306 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 327 Where else should one start science if not with data? How did Marx himself<br />

come to his findings?<br />

[231] ANK: Science begins with questions and observations. Science does not begin<br />

with data, it begins with a question or observation. As with physics, the gravitational constant<br />

was not known when determining the laws <strong>of</strong> projectile motion. When Isaac Newton<br />

observed gravity, he had no data to work with but rather he made an observation and began<br />

a quest to understand natural laws.<br />

Likewise, Marx observed flaws in the thinking <strong>of</strong> bourgeois economics and began to<br />

assemble ideas that better explain how <strong>thing</strong>s work or should work. Only after years <strong>of</strong><br />

study and critique are the initial observations accepted as facts and science. As data and<br />

previous science come together, laws <strong>of</strong> nature or economics are developed.<br />

During Marx’s time, he knew <strong>of</strong> the failures and contradictions in capitalism and had<br />

developed his own ideas and socialist models to be a replacement and improvement <strong>of</strong> capitalist<br />

theories. <strong>The</strong> process <strong>of</strong> converting his observations and theories to science lacked the<br />

generations <strong>of</strong> critique and testing at that time.<br />

Science is built upon data and years <strong>of</strong> experimentation and it all begins with questions<br />

and observations.<br />

Hans: Just FYI, Marx deliberately refrained from developing socialist models. He said he did not want to write<br />

recipes for the kitchens <strong>of</strong> the future.<br />

Message [231] referenced by [235], [257], and [260]. Next Message by ANK is [251].<br />

[235] Rico: Science Begins with Data. I agree with ANK’s argument in [231], that<br />

science begins with the observation <strong>of</strong> a phenomena. However, I disagree with the argument<br />

that science begins with a question. One must make an observation before a question can be<br />

formulated. In the case <strong>of</strong> Sir Isaac Newton, he observed the apple falling from the tree, then<br />

182 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

he formulated his question. So I agree that science begins with observations, but not with<br />

the argument that it also begins with questions. <strong>Question</strong>s are simply the ensuing byproduct<br />

<strong>of</strong> an observation.<br />

After further examining question 327 and ANK’s response [231], I discovered that the<br />

process <strong>of</strong> making observations is simply the process <strong>of</strong> collecting data. By making observations,<br />

one carefully processes the observed actions <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> in order to gain information.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se facts and statistics are collected together, which constitute the collection <strong>of</strong> data.<br />

By making observations, one is simply collecting data. <strong>The</strong>refore I agree with Marx, that<br />

one should start science with collecting data.<br />

Message [235] referenced by [257] and [260]. Next Message by Rico is [477].<br />

[257] Hans: Prior science, the overlooked ingredient in every scientific process. ANK<br />

[231] and Rico [235] agree that science starts with data (in Newton’s case the apple falling<br />

from a tree). And this seems the only possiblity: science is about this world, therefore you<br />

have to start with data from this world. Marx, by contrast, repeatedly thunders about it how<br />

misleading data are. For instance, an important empirical fact about capitalism is that it is a<br />

monetized economy. But Marx says it is wrong to begin the analysis <strong>of</strong> capitalism with the<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> money. In paragraph 168:1/o, which is the context to question 327, he says that<br />

money<br />

conceals the social character <strong>of</strong> private labor ... behind quasi-physical properties<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s, instead <strong>of</strong> revealing these relations plainly.<br />

And in the <strong>first</strong> sentence <strong>of</strong> the same paragraph Marx says that beginning with money is<br />

too late because you are beginning<br />

‘after the feast’ with the completed results <strong>of</strong> the development process.<br />

Despite Rico [235], Marx does not say that “one should start science with collecting<br />

data.” Marx himself did not collect data besides his lived experience as participant in and<br />

organizer/fighter against capitalism. Most <strong>of</strong> the time he was sitting in the British Museum<br />

and reading stuff. When ANK says “Marx observed flaws in the thinking <strong>of</strong> bourgeois<br />

economics” then this is a different kind <strong>of</strong> observation than seeing an apple fall from a tree.<br />

I would even say it is not an observation at all but this is the missing ingredient, prior science.<br />

It is essential in all scientific activity, but people <strong>of</strong>ten do not notice this. Newton could get<br />

his inspiration from the apple only because he was mulling the problematics in his head<br />

already. Prior science is the reason why you need a <strong>University</strong> education if you want to be a<br />

scientist instead <strong>of</strong> just a pair <strong>of</strong> binoculars (for observing—just kidding).<br />

This is the answer I am expecting from question 327. Of course you need data, but you<br />

also need prior science. This answer is a little simple-minded, it leaves out a lot <strong>of</strong> detail<br />

about Marx’s method, but it is some<strong>thing</strong> valid about all science which people are <strong>of</strong>ten not<br />

aware <strong>of</strong>. Prior science is as essential for science as produced means <strong>of</strong> production are for<br />

production.<br />

Message [257] referenced by [260]. Next Message by Hans is [258].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 183<br />

[260] Robert: Marx the Bee. Hans’s [257] in response to ANK [231] and Rico [235]<br />

reminds me <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> Sir Francis Bacon once wrote on the subject. He described a spectrum<br />

<strong>of</strong> the relationship between data gathering and theory making in a scientific method.<br />

He <strong>first</strong> describes an ant who gathers data and amasses it. In the end the ant has a mass<br />

<strong>of</strong> data. This process Bacon compares to a purely empirical method.<br />

<strong>The</strong>n he describes a spider who spins a web out <strong>of</strong> no<strong>thing</strong>. This process he describes a<br />

purely deductive method, creating a theory out <strong>of</strong> no<strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Finally, Bacon describes the bee who creates a framework <strong>of</strong> beeswax and gathers nectar<br />

at the same time. <strong>The</strong> need for framework is influenced by the nectar gathered and vice-aversa.<br />

He concludes that a bee is an analogy for how we out to view data gather: we need a<br />

framework or theory for the empirical data we gather. <strong>The</strong> theoretical framework should be<br />

informed and adjusted as the empirical data and the data we search should be informed by<br />

the theories as they evolve..this method he called pragmatism.<br />

Marx seems to be a bee. He carefully observes capitalism and creates a complex theoretical<br />

framework and looks for empirical evidence, adjusts his theory and looks for evidence<br />

and so forth until he is confident his theory and the empirical facts match up.<br />

Hans: Interesting and instructive story. But no<strong>thing</strong> about pre-existing science in there.<br />

Next Message by Robert is [373].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 330 is 157 in 1995WI, 134 in 1995ut, 167 in 1996sp, 227 in 2002fa, 235 in<br />

2003fa, 260 in 2005fa, 280 in 2007SP, 285 in 2007fa, 290 in 2008SP, 302 in 2009fa, and<br />

309 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 330 Why does Marx call Ricardo’s exchange between primitive fisherman and<br />

primitive hunter a “Robinson Crusoe story”?<br />

[252] Balrog: graded B Marx claimed that the time spent making a commodity or in this<br />

case acquiring it is what gives that commodity its value. Robinson Crusoe while alone on<br />

his island learnt very quickly that he had to apportion his time strategically. He even kept<br />

track <strong>of</strong> the material and labor necessary to create commodities that provided utility to him.<br />

<strong>The</strong> tasks with which Crusoe filled his day were those that would better his current situation.<br />

When a primitive fisherman and a primitive hunter exchange their goods they are only<br />

looking to improve their current situation and are not preoccupied with the utility that the<br />

other will receive. <strong>The</strong>y will place a value on their product using the three determinations <strong>of</strong><br />

value and make an exchange that would provide them with the highest utility possible.<br />

Message [252] referenced by [256]. Next Message by Balrog is [459].<br />

[256] JJ: Fishing vs. Hunting. Marx relates the exchange <strong>of</strong> the fisherman and the hunter,<br />

as described by Ricardo, to that <strong>of</strong> the Robinson Crusoe analogies that are all too common<br />

with political economists. Marx gives this relation because Ricardo has portrayed the hunter<br />

and fishermen as two individuals that are living separately and looking out for their own<br />

good in the exchange. Almost as if they were two Crusoes that lived in isolated islands<br />

and only came out to exchange their fish for bear skin rugs on Saturdays. Ricardo implies<br />

that fisherman and hunter are making this exchange on a proportion equal to the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

184 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

labor put into them. According to Marx’s summary <strong>of</strong> the Crusoe story, a “Crusoe figure”<br />

would have some pen and paper saved from the ship and like a “good Englishman” would<br />

quickly take log <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> his doing including the amounts <strong>of</strong> labor that he put toward certain<br />

functions <strong>of</strong> his daily life.<br />

Marx dispels us from Ricardo’s understanding <strong>of</strong> this “exchange” and show us that it is<br />

not even an exchange. He shows us that the hunter and fisherman will not even consider<br />

the labor they put into their “commodity”. Commodity is a poor choice because they may<br />

not even see the fish or bearskin as their personal property. Rather, they would be part <strong>of</strong> a<br />

social group or tribe that supported one another. If my neighbor needed a fish and I am the<br />

fisherman then I will give him one. If I need a bear skin coat then I will go to the hunter and<br />

he will give me one. Marx shows that in this social structure that the fisherman and hunter<br />

might see these <strong>thing</strong>s as common property and freely give them to one another. <strong>The</strong>y only<br />

hold this “exchange” because on <strong>of</strong> them needed the <strong>thing</strong> that the other had.<br />

Hans: Were you too polite not to mention [252] or did you not read [252]?<br />

JJ: Honestly, I was not able to read [252] before submitting. I had thought that I was the only student in this<br />

semester to attempt this question at the time that I submitted. (I <strong>of</strong>ten work from the download <strong>of</strong> the 2010fa<br />

archive and not from the live emails.) Now that I have read it, I believe that I might have made some comment that<br />

it was a mistake to try and interlace utility theory into this type <strong>of</strong> social/tribal exchange. I also think that [252]<br />

fails to make a strong comparison <strong>of</strong> Marx’s refutations <strong>of</strong> Ricardo’s explanations.<br />

Next Message by JJ is [512].<br />

[344] Goldtone: graded A With a lot <strong>of</strong> help from Ivan [2009fa:220], I was able to better<br />

answer this question. An exchange between a primitive fisherman and hunter is like the<br />

“Robinson Crusoe story” because Ricardo portrayed them (like Crusoe) as individuals producing<br />

their own commodities to be exchanged for their own good and not for the good <strong>of</strong> a<br />

social group. Marx talks about social groups needing the same simple exchanges to benefit<br />

their group.<br />

In this light, the fisherman and hunter do not necessarily have to exchange fish and meat<br />

for their own good alone (like Ricardo says), but also to help out their fellow members <strong>of</strong> a<br />

close-knit community. If the fisherman is sick <strong>of</strong> fish and wants to try meat, then he can ask<br />

the hunter. <strong>The</strong> hunter would like to help out his community by giving the fisherman some<br />

meat if he asks. This will benefit the hunter too, if his good grace in giving away his meat<br />

is repeated by others to help him out when he gets sick <strong>of</strong> meat. <strong>The</strong> whole community will<br />

benefit from exchanges like this going on inside <strong>of</strong> it because the members will not have to<br />

rely on themselves alone for every<strong>thing</strong> they need, but will have help from others in their<br />

community.<br />

Hans: You are describing a gift society. It may also be the case that fisher and hunter do not consider their catch as<br />

their private property at all. <strong>The</strong>y have access to <strong>thing</strong>s produced by others in the tribe, and in turn they share their<br />

product with everybody. Perhaps they have the right to say who gets what, but they don’t have the right to take it<br />

all for themselves or to give it only to those who give some<strong>thing</strong> back.<br />

Next Message by Goldtone is [552].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 335 is 180 in 1997WI, 187 in 1997sp, 232 in 2002fa, 240 in 2003fa, 290 in<br />

2007fa, 295 in 2008SP, and 307 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 335 Explain Marx’s statement in 170:1 that labor in medieval society did not take<br />

a social form different from its natural form.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 185<br />

[226] Scholar: If it is very clear that someone in a society appropriates others’ labor<br />

without any compensation, then Marx calls this the natural form <strong>of</strong> a social form. If this<br />

exploitive social relationship is covered up by some<strong>thing</strong> else, so that the participant can not<br />

be aware <strong>of</strong> it, this social form is no longer a natural form. In medieval society, the landlords<br />

exploit the peasants. This is known by both <strong>of</strong> them, so there is no mystery about the social<br />

relationship. This relationship kept its natural form. In capitalist society, the fact is that the<br />

capitalist appropriates the surplus labor from the worker. But it is carried out by the form <strong>of</strong><br />

a market exchange, so the unequal relationship behind the commodity is covered up by the<br />

equal exchange relationship. So, the social form is different from its natural form.<br />

Message [226] referenced by [236]. Next Message by Scholar is [237].<br />

[236] Hans: ”Natural form” is not the same as ”obvious form.” Scholar’s [226] is<br />

an intelligent guess. It correctly reflects Marx’s general thinking, but it misinterprets the<br />

particular passage <strong>of</strong> Capital referred to by question 335. Here is Marx’s entire sentence:<br />

“<strong>The</strong> natural form <strong>of</strong> labor, its particularity—and not, as in a society based<br />

on commodity production, its generality—is here its immediate social form.”<br />

What does this mean? Let’s go back to our lazy worker. If a handicraft worker working<br />

for the market is lazy and takes longer than the normal time for his work, then this is his own<br />

business. Nobody comes knocking at his door saying: “hey, you are not working hard and<br />

efficiently enough.” But when he sells his products, then he will get less money per labor<br />

hour performed than his competitors because he has fewer products to sell per labor hour<br />

performed.<br />

All this is obvious and it seems fair, therefore we usually don’t think much about it.<br />

Marx thought more about it, and his explanation is: the lazy handicraft worker gets less<br />

compensation per hour worked because society does not reward the particularity <strong>of</strong> his labor.<br />

Instead, the worker <strong>first</strong> has to find a buyer for his products on the market before he can reap<br />

a reward for his labor. What counts in this sale is not the labor time he himself spent on<br />

the product but the average labor-time going into these products. Marx says that society<br />

rewards the generality <strong>of</strong> his labor—that what his labor has in common with the labor <strong>of</strong> the<br />

others—and not its particularity. If his particular labor falls short <strong>of</strong> the general norm, then<br />

the reward falls short by the same amount.<br />

Does Marx’s explanation bring true insights, or is he just trying to make every<strong>thing</strong> more<br />

complicated than it is so that he can sell his book, as Cosmopolita seems to imply in [209]?<br />

One application <strong>of</strong> this thinking might be: assume the handicraft worker is not lazy but<br />

has a handicap which does not allow him to work as quickly as the others. He should get as<br />

much pay for his hour <strong>of</strong> work as able-bodied people, but he falls under the same penalty as<br />

the lazy worker. His labor has a particularity which society should recognize but doesn’t.<br />

Now what happened in the Middle Ages? Bonded peasants had to work a set number <strong>of</strong><br />

hours on the landlord’s farm. If a peasant had an injury or so, then he would be excused or<br />

other peasants would do the work for him. But if a peasant does bad or inefficient work he<br />

would probably get a lashing. This is an example <strong>of</strong> a society in which the particularity <strong>of</strong><br />

labor counts, not the generality. <strong>The</strong> labor <strong>of</strong> the peasant did not even have a general form,<br />

i.e., there was no market for milk or potatoes—because everybody grew their own milk and<br />

186 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

potatoes. <strong>The</strong> “generalization,” i.e., the fitting <strong>of</strong> the particular labor into the social context,<br />

was done by direct coercion (the lashing and worse).<br />

BTW, I am not a medievalist. Can someone inform us what really happened to peasants<br />

who refused to work and/or peasants that were sick in the Middle Ages?<br />

Message [236] referenced by [237] and [248]. Next Message by Hans is [240].<br />

[237] Scholar: Agreed. Yes, I agree with Hans [236], and my explanation was really<br />

far from the context. It is a difference between individual labor and social labor, and this<br />

difference emerged during the production <strong>of</strong> commodity. In medieval time, the most labor<br />

is supplied for autarky, so labor was only the individual labor and there was no social form<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor, which need acceptance by the other people than producers themselves.<br />

Next Message by Scholar is [487].<br />

[441] Deadfamous: graded B+ I suspect that Marx is talking about different class distinctions<br />

that were around in the medieval era. Different classes performed different types <strong>of</strong><br />

labor. So the labor that you did each and every day would be exactly related to the social<br />

class you were in. For example if you were a serf your labor would be different from say,<br />

a craftsman, nobleman or lord. Looking specifically at the exploitation <strong>of</strong> serfs, in order to<br />

feed his family and pay the rent for his field, he has to grow a lot <strong>of</strong> food. <strong>The</strong> serf in all<br />

reality is producing not to sell but to support and feed his family. So naturally you are born<br />

into a certain class that determines different types <strong>of</strong> labor. This way you can see how labor’s<br />

social form and natural form ends up being the same exact <strong>thing</strong>. <strong>The</strong> tithe (what you call<br />

rent) was usuall paid in kind, not as money.<br />

Not sure if we need to notate but in case we do here is my source: (from [2009fa:242]<br />

Koolboarder and Hans)<br />

Hans: Yes, since you practically copied the earlier submission, you better give the source. Even better would be to<br />

reformulate it in your own words, so that I know if you understood it. You should at least have edited the sentence<br />

“what you call rent.”<br />

Next Message by Deadfamous is [677].<br />

[450] TINDOZ: graded A Medieval society was based on the caste system. When you<br />

were born, your lifestyle was more or less set out for you simply by who you were born<br />

to. If you were born to a noble family, your life, labor, social relations all took on aspects<br />

that were consigned to nobility. If you were a peasant-serf-king-etc, your life, labor, social<br />

relations were consistent with your class status. This is how society determined your labor,<br />

by determining who you were. Furthermore, there wasn’t movement among the classes. One<br />

wasn’t born a serf and grow up to be a member <strong>of</strong> the artisan class. <strong>The</strong>refore the labor that<br />

one was involved in (say a serf) was no different in its social form than it was in its natural<br />

form because the social aspect <strong>of</strong> their lives determined the natural aspect. So, if your class<br />

dictated that your labor was that <strong>of</strong> a dung shoveler, then that was that. Another aspect <strong>of</strong><br />

the social relations existing in the classes <strong>of</strong> the caste system is that classes differed in social<br />

status (a hierarchy) and therefore their labor was not considered equal because the people<br />

were not considered equal. Hans said in [2007fa:143], “In the middle ages, society regulated<br />

the individuals, while in capitalism it regulates the individuals’ labors.” So your labor was<br />

dictated to you by how society classed you as an individual.<br />

Next Message by TINDOZ is [464].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 338 is 197 in 1999SP and 310 in 2009fa:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 187<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 338 Which social forms do the three determinations <strong>of</strong> value take in Marx’s example<br />

<strong>of</strong> a socialist society?<br />

[223] Deadfamous: graded B+ According to the Annotations on page 207, they are: 3<br />

Determinations <strong>of</strong> Value<br />

(a) the equality <strong>of</strong> all human labor ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it is expenditure <strong>of</strong> human labor-power,<br />

(b) the social significance <strong>of</strong> labor-time, and<br />

(g) the existence <strong>of</strong> interactions between the producers through which their labors are<br />

integrated into the social labor process.<br />

Greg [2009fa:241] gives clear answers, but I have added to his answer in parenthesis<br />

(parenthesis are my further elaborations<br />

Marx’s socialist society is different than capitalism under a labor theory <strong>of</strong> value in that<br />

(a) the conscious approach would not assume that all labor is homogeneous, but would<br />

presumably take into account different circumstances and situations (so socialist assume<br />

equality <strong>of</strong> human labor, capitalist do not go so far as to make this assumption, they rather<br />

go by the requirement for commodities to be produced in a certain time)<br />

(b) labor-time is used for a dual purpose as Marx said, “Its apportionment in accordance<br />

with a definite social plan maintains the proper proportion between the different kinds <strong>of</strong><br />

work to be done and the various wants <strong>of</strong> the community. On the other hand, it also serves<br />

as a measure <strong>of</strong> the portion <strong>of</strong> the common labor born by each individual, and <strong>of</strong> his share in<br />

the part <strong>of</strong> the total product destined for individual consumption,” (We only know what our<br />

daily wages are in capitalism, we don’t have to account each day for your labor input and<br />

what should be your share)<br />

(c) producers would have to plan together in this conscious approach, not only labor and<br />

its products but distributions <strong>of</strong> the goods needed and wanted by the community.<br />

Hans: Regarding to your parenthetical addition to (a): Marx says that in capitalism labor is equalized too, but not<br />

consciously as in socialism, but as a side-effect <strong>of</strong> competition.<br />

Regarding point (b), people in socialism will get wages for their work, similar to capitalism. <strong>The</strong> difference<br />

to capitalism is that wages are the only source <strong>of</strong> income, there is no property income. Firms are not allowed to<br />

keep their pr<strong>of</strong>its if they make them, and they are not forced to shut down if they make no pr<strong>of</strong>its. <strong>The</strong> medical<br />

sector would probably only charge nominal fees, etc. Prices will probably be determined by labor content. <strong>The</strong><br />

economy’s most important decision is the investment decision. This is decided democratically instead <strong>of</strong> behind<br />

closed corporate boardrooms.<br />

Considering wages a cost <strong>of</strong> production is a too tight coupling between efficiency and distributional considerations.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re will be efficiency in production, i.e., labor time will play a role in production, but if a firm does not<br />

increase the efficiency <strong>of</strong> the production process and instead pays the workers less, this should not result in higher<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its for them as it does in capitalism. <strong>The</strong> two roles <strong>of</strong> labor time, for measuring efficiency in production and for<br />

measuring how much the workers should receive, must be separated.<br />

Message [223] referenced by [2011fa:697]. Next Message by Deadfamous is [437].<br />

[341] Cmellen: graded C+ <strong>The</strong>re are three determining social forms <strong>of</strong> value in Marx’s<br />

socialist society. First, it is understood by reading Marx that the substance <strong>of</strong> value is in the<br />

abstract <strong>of</strong> human labor, being the expenditure <strong>of</strong> human labor-power. Human labor power<br />

is the potential and/or ability <strong>of</strong> the human to do the specified labor.<br />

188 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Second is the quantity <strong>of</strong> value. This is in the form <strong>of</strong> the “socially necessary labor-time”<br />

to produce the item. <strong>The</strong> labor-time is what measures the magnitude <strong>of</strong> value; the time and<br />

duration <strong>of</strong> expending the labor.<br />

Finally, third, being the exchange value. Exchange value is a social relation on the exterior<br />

shell <strong>of</strong> an economy. This takes place in an interaction between laborers with their<br />

produced commodities being able to fetch other commodities. (Das Kapital 1.4, Fetish-Like<br />

Character and its Secret)<br />

Hans: You are describing the three determinations <strong>of</strong> value and their social forms in capitalism, not socialism.<br />

Next Message by Cmellen is [342].<br />

[414] Tyler: <strong>The</strong> social forms that Marx’s determinations <strong>of</strong> value are:<br />

1) Substance<br />

2) Form<br />

3) Quantity<br />

Substance according to the annotations examines “the equality <strong>of</strong> all human labor ins<strong>of</strong>ar<br />

as it is expenditure <strong>of</strong> human labor-power.” Hans points out that this refers directly to the<br />

expenditure <strong>of</strong> brains, nerves, muscles, etc. Form “the existence <strong>of</strong> interactions between the<br />

producers through which their labors are integrated into the social labor process.” This looks<br />

at the social relations people have on the surface to coordinate production and consumption.<br />

Quantity is “the social significance <strong>of</strong> labor time.” This determination is the one which<br />

everyone must pay some attention to in order to compete.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong>re is one paragraph in chapter One where Marx discusses a socialist society. You seem to think the<br />

entire book is about socialism.<br />

Next Message by Tyler is [667].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 339 is 164 in 1995WI, 141 in 1995ut, 174 in 1996sp, 183 in 1997WI, 182 in<br />

1997ut, 235 in 2002fa, 244 in 2003fa, 274 in 2004fa, 269 in 2005fa, 289 in 2007SP, 299<br />

in 2008SP, 297 in 2008fa, 311 in 2009fa, 318 in 2011fa, and 332 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 339 In what ways can Christianity and the commodity relation be considered<br />

similar?<br />

[228] Kraken: (graded A–) Christianity and Capitalism. If I understand Marx correctly<br />

(and chances are I don’t), he’s saying: <strong>The</strong> similarity between capitalism and Christianity is<br />

the abstraction <strong>of</strong> the human being. With capitalism, Marx abstracts the labor <strong>of</strong> individuals<br />

into some<strong>thing</strong> he calls “homogenous human labor”. I believe he is trying to apply the same<br />

sort <strong>of</strong> abstraction process to Christianity. I think he is viewing Christians as an abstract<br />

group <strong>of</strong> people who have given up their individuality and joined together in some sort <strong>of</strong><br />

herd-like mentality in order to gain salvation. Other comparisons can be drawn. Some may<br />

say that Christians see Christianity as a type <strong>of</strong> fetish with magical powers that they believe<br />

can make them better and happier. Capitalists (most <strong>of</strong> us) see commodities as having a<br />

similar type <strong>of</strong> power. We believe that if we can purchase items such as boats, large homes,<br />

expensive automobiles, impressive titles, and designer clothes that we will be better and<br />

happier people (at least better and happier than you).<br />

Hans: Marx criticizes Christianity for the belief that humans cannot be good unless they purify themselves, unless<br />

they abstract from some natural aspects <strong>of</strong> human existence—just as a commodity has to shed its colorful earthly


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 189<br />

existence in order to become pure money. This criticism <strong>of</strong> Christianity is deeper and more abstract than Marx’s<br />

jocular remark in 143:2 about the sheep-like nature <strong>of</strong> Christians.<br />

Message [228] referenced by [251] and [259]. Next Message by Kraken is [409].<br />

[251] ANK: Comparing Christianity and Capitalism. In response to Kraken [228], I<br />

think Marx is saying some<strong>thing</strong> different about the comparison between Christianity and<br />

Capitalism. Marx is saying that the focus <strong>of</strong> Christianity is on teaching individuals that they<br />

are sinners and that they must work towards living a pure life. <strong>The</strong> goal <strong>of</strong> Christianity<br />

is to urge individuals to reach their full potential. Capitalism does the same <strong>thing</strong> with<br />

commodities and tries to get the highest price for each commodity. In this sense, each<br />

commodity is working to reach its full potential just as Christians are taught. Marx disagrees<br />

with this thought and believes that use-value is more important than the dollar value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity. While I agree with Kraken that Christians believe that they can find greater<br />

happiness through Christianity, I do not think that Marx was comparing that to the happiness<br />

that individuals can find through boats, houses, clothes, etc. <strong>The</strong> happiness Christians find<br />

through Christianity is from the improvement <strong>of</strong> their lives and living at or close to their full<br />

potential and Marx compares this to commodities being sold at their highest potential price.<br />

Message [251] referenced by [259]. Next Message by ANK is [398].<br />

[254] Intaglio: commoduligion. Viewing the universe in a religious sense is similar to<br />

viewing the value <strong>of</strong> commodities as surface relations. Both are abstractions from reality.<br />

Religion takes nature and mystifies it through personification, leaving people worshiping the<br />

metaphors (taking the form <strong>of</strong> deities) instead <strong>of</strong> actual nature. Likewise, producers (mistakenly)<br />

abstract the value <strong>of</strong> their commodities by viewing them by the surface relations,<br />

i.e. how well they will perform on the market instead <strong>of</strong> the underlying abstract human labor.<br />

Yet both abstractions turn the gears <strong>of</strong> the machine; Religion gets people to improve<br />

themselves and viewing commodities like Bourgeois economists succeeds in the exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong> goods, but both are an inaccurate representation <strong>of</strong> the true nature <strong>of</strong> the situation.<br />

Without these religious and commodity fetishes, people would no longer see a need for<br />

churches and capitalism.<br />

Hans: Interesting. You see the communality between religion and capitalism in them both being forms <strong>of</strong> alienation.<br />

Next Message by Intaglio is [490].<br />

[259] Robert: (graded A) Soul and CAL. I am still a little unclear about what Kraken<br />

[228] and ANK [251] are saying about comparing Christianity and capitalism so, as in an<br />

attempt to try to understand I will try to state it in my own words.<br />

Christianity, as I understand it, believes that each human being has a soul. Some mysterious<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the human being that is not readily apparent on the surface but which really<br />

represents an very real (in the Christian view) and important part <strong>of</strong> that human.<br />

A commodity in the capitalist system also has an element that is real but not readily<br />

apparent on the surface (mysterious) and that represent a very important attribute <strong>of</strong> that<br />

commodity, i.e., value, and that element is congealed abstract labor.<br />

In other words the congealed abstract labor would be the Christian soul <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

if Christians considered that <strong>thing</strong>s had souls.<br />

190 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Marx uses the word “value-soul” in exactly this meaning in 143:1. And in 176:3/o, the sentence “now listen<br />

how the economist makes himself the mouthpiece <strong>of</strong> the commodities” is in a more literal translation “now listen<br />

how the economist speaks out <strong>of</strong> the commodity soul.”<br />

This wording simply comes from the insight that humans cannot be reduced to their bodies. That what they<br />

are in excess <strong>of</strong> their bodies is called their “mind” or “soul.” This is not yet specific to religion, but some religions<br />

claim that the soul <strong>of</strong> a human existed before his or her body was born or will continue to exist after the body has<br />

died. At least this is my understanding. Am I missing some<strong>thing</strong>?<br />

Next Message by Robert is [260].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 342 is 277 in 2004fa, 272 in 2005fa, 292 in 2007SP, 297 in 2007fa, 302 in<br />

2008SP, 300 in 2008fa, and 314 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 342 Can labor be measured in other ways than in time?<br />

[224] Milly: graded A– Labor measured in time. <strong>The</strong> time spent producing a product or<br />

service is the easiest way to measure labor, but it doesn’t always seem to work that way. For<br />

example, to compare a famous talk show host to a construction worker based <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> the hours<br />

spent to do their job would be an inaccurate comparison <strong>of</strong> equal production. One spends an<br />

hour a day making thousands <strong>of</strong> dollars while the other spends countless hours a day only to<br />

make a fraction <strong>of</strong> that amount. You can easily see another problem in those who work on<br />

commission. Many can spend days working and not make any money until a sale is made,<br />

but that does not mean they didn’t labor during that time. Doesn’t that need to be measured<br />

too?<br />

We know that because we all have different jobs and abilities, labor isn’t homogenous<br />

unless broken down into abstract labor. Abstract labor is the labor that is exactly average<br />

in its value-adding abilities. Like many other students in the past, you can easily start to<br />

measure labor in other ways such as wage, production and effort. However despite the<br />

examples above, I agree with Teresa in [2008fa:365] that measuring labor by time is the<br />

best way. No matter how experienced an employee is or how much they produce, measuring<br />

labor by time is the only true way to measure labor.<br />

I did also read [2008fa:387] and was interested about Marx reducing abstract labor to<br />

social necessary labor time. However I found that his answer may have been plagiarized, so<br />

I will need to research that further for myself.<br />

Hans: Marx would say measuring labor by income is problematic because in his theory, a capitalist’s income does<br />

not come from his own labor but the labor <strong>of</strong> the working class. Celebrities (such as talk show hosts, athletes, film<br />

stars) are hired by capitalists to motivate people to attend their movie screenings, watch their TV shows, fill their<br />

sports arenas, buy their DVDs—and for this they get a part <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

A pronouncement such as “measuring labor by time is the only true way to measure labor” needs justification.<br />

Marx did not reduce abstract labor to social necessary labor time, but socially necessay labor time is how to<br />

measure the quantity <strong>of</strong> abstract labor.<br />

Message [224] referenced by [238] and [242]. Next Message by Milly is [515].<br />

[230] Husani: Labor Time. I believe that we could measure labor by the quality <strong>of</strong> each<br />

unit <strong>of</strong> labor or by the quantity produced by each unit <strong>of</strong> labor. While thinking <strong>of</strong> how one<br />

would use these to measure labor I realized that it would be much more difficult to do this<br />

effectively without time as our key measure.<br />

Quality would be a good measure <strong>of</strong> labor but it is much harder to relate these measures<br />

with other commodities. If we start with linen and try to exchange it with a coat we hit a


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 191<br />

road block. When we measure labor with time we find that each commodity has abstract<br />

human labor congealed in it, which allows us a base to judge their value. With Quality we<br />

lose this base. We can say the linen and the coat are <strong>of</strong> good quality but that doesn’t allow<br />

us to see what this quality is because linen and coats are very different commodities.<br />

We could also look at quantity produced by a laborer and this leads us to the same road<br />

block. By comparing the quantity <strong>of</strong> a commodity produced we still do not have a common<br />

substance to help bridge the gap. If a laborer weaved 20 feet <strong>of</strong> linen and a tailor made<br />

three coats in the same time span we have little to go on with the measure <strong>of</strong> time. We can’t<br />

realistically judge the value <strong>of</strong> either commodity based on quantity produced.<br />

Time as a measure <strong>of</strong> labor is the easiest and most basic way to find value between<br />

different commodities.<br />

Hans: Your writing style is pleasant but not precise enough. Regarding your <strong>first</strong> paragraph, how do you define<br />

a “unit” <strong>of</strong> labor before knowing how to measure labor? What is the “quality” <strong>of</strong> labor? Do you mean how clean<br />

people keep their workplaces? Or do you mean the quality <strong>of</strong> the product? How can one measure labor by “quality”<br />

with “time as your key measure”? If you mean measuring labor by time with a premium for quality, this is similar<br />

to what Marx calls “socially necessary labor-time.” It is not a measurement by quality but a time measurement after<br />

converting difference in quality into quantitative time differences.<br />

Message [230] referenced by [238] and [291]. Next Message by Husani is [246].<br />

[238] Rmc: graded B– Measuring labor. Milly [224] and Husani [230] both discuss<br />

other ways to measure labor than time. Milly compares the labor-time required for different<br />

jobs (talk-show host, construction worker), noting two <strong>thing</strong>s: labor-time spent to complete<br />

the job and labor-time spent at the different jobs to earn the same wages. Husani discussed<br />

measuring labor in terms <strong>of</strong> quality and quantity and how it is difficult to compare the quality<br />

<strong>of</strong> different commodities.<br />

I agree with this and would like to add that labor is always considered when setting a<br />

price. Today, a hand-made commodity is <strong>of</strong>ten viewed as more valuable than if it were made<br />

by a machine (consider a hand-embroidered gown or hand-carved piece <strong>of</strong> furniture). This<br />

is because labor-power is expended differently by hand- personally and usually much more<br />

attentively and carefully- than by a machine. Machines can mass-produce a commodity,<br />

thus robbing each <strong>of</strong> individuality, while a number <strong>of</strong> the same hand-made commodities are<br />

almost never exactly the same.<br />

I would also like to mention that labor can be measured in more abstract ways. Depending<br />

on the stressfulness <strong>of</strong> a task on a human, whether physically, emotionally, or mentally, there<br />

are always related effects that can be observed, even though they cannot be removed from<br />

time measurement. I’m speaking in terms <strong>of</strong> endurance. It can be argued that emotional<br />

labor-time (a nurse caring for many patients) is much different than unemotional labor-time<br />

(pharmacist filling many prescriptions). Workers in the healthcare industry typically burn<br />

out much sooner than workers in other industries; it is said that the emotional wear is much<br />

more taxing. Other abstract measurements <strong>of</strong> labor include sweat and blood; these are used<br />

as <strong>of</strong>ten as metaphors, but are not invalid. How many drops <strong>of</strong> blood were spilled during<br />

the industrial revolution? How much sweat did it take to build the railroad? <strong>The</strong> last measurement<br />

I’ll mention here is the number <strong>of</strong> money-units spent in response to these effects<br />

(whether they are measured over a given amount <strong>of</strong> time or per occurrence).<br />

192 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Different types <strong>of</strong> effort related to different types <strong>of</strong> jobs test workers’ endurance and how<br />

long they can expend labor-power (over the course <strong>of</strong> their lives, maybe) before they can’t<br />

go anymore. Measurements like these vary worker to worker (even industry to industry) and<br />

product to product also.<br />

It is not possible to eliminate time from the argument, since these are typically used with<br />

a phrase like “long-term” or “short-term,” but they are measurements that can be understood.<br />

Hans: I like your distinction between emotional and unemotional labor-time; Marx calls these considerations<br />

“intensity <strong>of</strong> labor.” But if the labor process is too unemotional, it may get boring which is also a real constraint.<br />

Your reasoning why labor content affects prices is an unacceptable misunderstanding <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory which<br />

automatically depresses your grade. Look at [2007SP:586] how competition leads to prices proportional to labor<br />

input.<br />

Message [238] referenced by [242]. Next Message by Rmc is [311].<br />

[242] Fisher: Knowledge vs. time in labor. Milly [224] and Rmc [238] both touched on<br />

how labor is measured. I wanted to add yet another angle to it. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a commodity,<br />

according to Marx is the time spent used to make that commodity. I think there is more value<br />

that can be added to labor and that is education or knowledge <strong>of</strong> that labor at hand. Many<br />

people spend years mastering their craft and soon learn little bits <strong>of</strong> information accumulated<br />

only with time on the job. That makes their experience and knowledge worth some<strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Some engineers for example, get paid hundreds <strong>of</strong> dollars per hour and exert zero energy<br />

in doing so. <strong>The</strong>ir education and the scarcity <strong>of</strong> qualified individuals in that field, or<br />

competition, engineers can charge a higher premium for their services. That sems to disagree<br />

with the Marxism approach <strong>of</strong> time spent on the commodity in giving it a value. If<br />

one hired an average engineer to build some<strong>thing</strong>, it would utimately cost the public less in<br />

buying the final product as it would if you were to choose a more expensive engineer. I think<br />

time <strong>of</strong> labor does add one element to the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity, but the knowledge <strong>of</strong> the<br />

manufacturers can be as big a part <strong>of</strong> that value, if not bigger.<br />

Hans: Marx does exactly what you say he doesn’t do: not only the actual time spent but also a share <strong>of</strong> the training<br />

time necessary to do the present job contributes to the labor time represented by the product.<br />

Next Message by Fisher is [431].<br />

[243] Tyler: Measurements <strong>of</strong> labor. Initially I thought there would be many other<br />

ways to measure labor aside from using time. For example, in [2009fa:564] it is noted that<br />

productivity might be an additional method <strong>of</strong> measuring labor. <strong>The</strong> argument presented is<br />

that although two employees may work the same eight hour shift, one employee may have<br />

been much more productive by producing twice as much output than the co-worker.<br />

However, this argument is based entirely on the type <strong>of</strong> labor being examined, abstract or<br />

concrete. Hans [2009fa:322] points out that “[Marx] measures abstract labor, not concrete<br />

labor.” Since Marx is specifically talking about abstract labor, time can be the only logical<br />

method <strong>of</strong> measuring labor.<br />

Hans: You may be surprised to hear that Marx is measuring output by “productivity” as you say exactly because<br />

he is measuring abstract labor. <strong>The</strong> quantitative dimension <strong>of</strong> abstract labor is socially necessary labor time. In<br />

your example, the worker who produces twice as much product as the other also performs twice the abstract labor<br />

as the other.<br />

Message [243] referenced by [1209]. Next Message by Tyler is [412].<br />

[248] Ryan: Labor as a unit and not time. I think there are a few ways to measure labor<br />

besides as a measurement <strong>of</strong> time. First I think that we all need to take one step back and


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 193<br />

really think about labor. Many <strong>of</strong> us assume that labor is a function <strong>of</strong> work over time, and<br />

that we get paid for our labor, which is incorrect.<br />

I feel that there is not only an additional way to measure labor but there is a better way<br />

to measure labor. That is not from the worker’s point <strong>of</strong> view but from the consumer’s point<br />

<strong>of</strong> view. I agree with Marx when he says, “... why is labor expressed in value, and why the<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> by its duration is expressed in the magnitude <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the product.” Marx<br />

clearly states that the longer the time it makes to make an object should have no impact on<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> the item. Meaning that item “X” should not change in value based on the time<br />

it takes to make but on the value <strong>of</strong> the unit itself. This in turn means that time should taken<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the equation <strong>of</strong> labor and labor should be measured by the units <strong>of</strong> output.<br />

Example: Two lawyers are asked to file a Patent “X”: Lawyer 1 can complete the job in<br />

3 hours, Lawyer 2 will take 6 hours to complete. We will assume that the consumer will pay<br />

the same amount to each lawyer, Value “Y.” We will also assume that the quality <strong>of</strong> work<br />

done will be the same.<br />

If we measure labor for the view point <strong>of</strong> the consumer then we will see the labor value<br />

is 1, 1 job requested 1 job completed. Time does not need to be factored in any way because<br />

the consumer’s needs are meet and the value <strong>of</strong> the labor was constant (“Y”).<br />

I feel that if we used a unit measurement <strong>of</strong> labor it would also fall in line with what Hans<br />

[236] was saying about the Lazy worker. Lawyer 2 takes twice as long to complete the work<br />

that it would take Lawyer 1 to complete. Seeing as the value was the same for each party we<br />

know that Lawyer 2 must charge half the hourly rate than Lawyer 1. No matter the time that<br />

is spent to complete the task at hand the time required should have no impact on the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the unit being done.<br />

This <strong>of</strong> course only makes sense as all <strong>of</strong> us buy items for the value that we feel that item<br />

has, not because <strong>of</strong> the amount <strong>of</strong> time it takes to make that item. Like Hans said if Lawyer<br />

2 is lazy and takes twice as long “that is his business”, if Layer 2 wants to account time to<br />

figure out his productivity, or his wages and chooses to have time be a factor that is fine. But<br />

the Labor should be based on unit output, 1 job requested, 1 job completed.<br />

Hans: You misunderstand Marx. You think Marx wants value to be based on labor, and you are objectiong that<br />

it would be better if value was based on the consumer’s subjective valuation <strong>of</strong> the object. But Marx says that in<br />

capitalist economies value is based on labor, not that value should be based on labor. Marx thinks that this is the<br />

long- to medium run outcome <strong>of</strong> competition. If you disagree with Marx you must show that value in capitalism is<br />

in fact not based on labor.<br />

Message [248] referenced by [250]. Next Message by Ryan is [456].<br />

[249] Zohan: Time is a constant measurement. As I <strong>first</strong> began to consider ways to<br />

measure labor, I had a few ideas come to mind aside from time: Quality <strong>of</strong> product and<br />

the Volume <strong>of</strong> Production. At <strong>first</strong> glance, both seem to correspond directly with value and<br />

labor. However, after reviewing the reading and Marx’s arguments, I would have to say that<br />

time is in fact the best way to measure labor. While the quality <strong>of</strong> a product and the amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> products produced will generally have an impact on what the item itself is worth, both<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> measurement are based on a consumer’s personal bias. For instance I may find a<br />

red t-shirt to be worth more than you, but this doesn’t mean that the labor that produced the<br />

red t-shirt is worth more than what was used to produce a black t-shirt. With products value<br />

194 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

changing on nearly a daily basis, it makes no sense to change your measurement <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

along with it. Thus, time becomes the most reliable and consistent way to measure your<br />

labor.<br />

Hans: You are right. If red t-shirts are in higher demand than black t-shirts, then industry will respond to this by<br />

producing more red t-shirts and/or fewer black t-shirts. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the t-shirts is not affected by this.<br />

Next Message by Zohan is [466].<br />

[250] Jon: How is labor best measured? While reading Marx I do understand the point<br />

<strong>of</strong> measuring labor in units <strong>of</strong> time. Most <strong>of</strong> us see this as the best way to measure labor<br />

since we have worked for wage by the hour up to this point. I have been thinking <strong>of</strong> it a little<br />

deeper and I believe that the best way to truly measure the labor we use in the production<br />

process is the same way that we give value to the product itself. <strong>The</strong> demand or use value<br />

<strong>of</strong> a product is the determining factor in the value <strong>of</strong> a product and I believe that the labor<br />

that goes into production should be measured in the same way. <strong>The</strong>re is a lot <strong>of</strong> different<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s that a person could do with a unit <strong>of</strong> time and not all labor is equal so why should it<br />

be measured the same. <strong>The</strong> real reason that I have decided to continue my education is to<br />

increase the value <strong>of</strong> my labor. <strong>The</strong> more you know or the better your skills are the more<br />

valuable the labor is. <strong>The</strong> time <strong>of</strong> a teller at a bank is much less valuable than the CEO <strong>of</strong> the<br />

same bank and the pay check shows it. Society has put value on labor based on the value <strong>of</strong><br />

the product, it has become apparent through the wage inequality that has grown. I really do<br />

see the usefulness <strong>of</strong> measuring labor in units <strong>of</strong> time but labor has become more complex<br />

and it needs to be measured more in the value <strong>of</strong> its product more than just the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

time it took.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> comments I made about [248] also apply to you.<br />

Next Message by Jon is [420].<br />

[255] GoUtes: labor time. Since a lot <strong>of</strong> our group is commenting on the issue <strong>of</strong> how<br />

labor is best measured, I would like to voice my interpretation as well. I do think that labor<br />

is best measured in time, however, there are other ways to measure labor. One would be<br />

the quality <strong>of</strong> labor, another would be the effort involved, and another measure would be<br />

labor actually accomplishing. One can participate in “labor” without really doing any<strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Say if you are a construction worker, you may go through the motions, go to work, hammer<br />

some nails, paint some walls and accomplish some <strong>thing</strong>s, but what if your full effort was<br />

not there? Or if you do your job half way? Labor is still taking place, yet is it really quality<br />

labor?<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> others have said similar <strong>thing</strong>s. You should only chime in this late in the discussion if you have<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> new to say, and if you explain how your contribution differs from the rest. Marx’s concept <strong>of</strong> socially<br />

necessary labor-time meets your <strong>first</strong> and third criterion (but not the effort criterion).<br />

Next Message by GoUtes is [470].<br />

[284] Baseball: I agree with GoUtes when they say that “one can participate in labor without<br />

really doing any<strong>thing</strong>.” In order for labor to be productive and achieve a goal, progress<br />

towards the final product must exist. If labor is to be accepted as useful then progress with a<br />

product or service must be taking place within the confines <strong>of</strong> labor. If the same construction<br />

worker which GoUtes used in the example went to work and performed the same routine every<br />

work day but the work which that worker accomplished had no amplification to the final<br />

product, that labor would not be considered quality.<br />

Next Message by Baseball is [285].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 195<br />

[287] Hans: New grading policy for not building on each other’s submissions. <strong>Question</strong><br />

342 is not in installment 1, therefore it is not assigned right now. Only the questions in Installment<br />

1 will be on the exam, and those questions are assigned during the extra-credit<br />

period which goes until 6 pm Monday.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re was a lot <strong>of</strong> overlap in the answers to question 342. <strong>The</strong>re was even more overlap<br />

if you also consider question 96, which is similar to 342. (And I recommend my [75] and<br />

[91] to those who are interested in 342.)<br />

In the future, i.e., after the exam, you will be graded as follows if there is too much<br />

overlap: if you say <strong>thing</strong>s which are right but only 25% <strong>of</strong> your submission say some<strong>thing</strong><br />

new or say it better than before, then you will get an A but your grade will only have the<br />

weight <strong>of</strong> 25% <strong>of</strong> a normal submission. This is better than what I did in the past. According<br />

to the syllabus, you should get a D for it, because numerically, a D (1.0) is 25% <strong>of</strong> an A (4.0).<br />

But this is so Drakonian that I did not apply it, I ducked people a little bit but not very much.<br />

With the new grading policy, if you have a submission with less than 100% weight then you<br />

need more than five submissions for the minimum requirement in homework submissions.<br />

This is more work, but it only affects your grade if you don’t do this extra work. <strong>The</strong><br />

new solution also gives more information. You know how much your submission would<br />

be valued had it not been an overlap, and which fraction <strong>of</strong> your submission I think was<br />

overlapping.<br />

Message [287] referenced by [358] and [540]. Next Message by Hans is [291].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 347 is 242 in 2002fa, 251 in 2003fa, 282 in 2004fa, 276 in 2005fa, 296 in<br />

2007SP, 301 in 2007fa, 319 in 2009fa, 326 in 2011fa, and 341 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 347 What is Marx’s difference between bourgeois economists and vulgar economists?<br />

[215] Hans: Prettifying imitators. Marx witnessed the descent <strong>of</strong> the mainstream economics<br />

<strong>of</strong> his time from what he called “bourgeois” or “classical” economics to what he<br />

called “vulgar” economics.<br />

<strong>The</strong> former had original thinking, and although Marx did not agree with all <strong>of</strong> it, see my<br />

[2007SP:316], he had great respect for it and learned a lot from it. <strong>The</strong> latter, the part <strong>of</strong><br />

economics which Marx called “vulgar” economics, did not really look at the economy itself<br />

but just took the existing economics as gospel and polished it up. Marx only had disdain<br />

for Say (<strong>of</strong> Say’s law fame) for trying to make Ricardo more systematic and pretty but also<br />

much shallower. This has a more recent analogy in Economics: many economists feel that<br />

Hicks’s IS/LM model tries to make Keynes’s theory more systematic and accessible, but it<br />

also removes its depth.<br />

This evening a slide from original thought to prettifying imitators is happening before<br />

our eyes with the answers to question 290. IrvingHowe [191] and Guh [206] bring original<br />

thinking to the table. Zohan [213] is a smoothed-over and more eloquent paraphrase <strong>of</strong> [206],<br />

a little bit like Say was to Ricardo, and Long [207] tried this too but he didn’t understand<br />

Guh as well as Zohan did.<br />

I couldn’t resist remarking on this, that’s why I am answering a question which will be<br />

assigned starting tomorrow. A more in-depth answer to 347 is in [2005fa:507].<br />

196 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Message [215] referenced by [216] and [918]. Next Message by Hans is [216].<br />

[374] Robert: graded A Understanding vs. Explanation. To Marx the bourgeois economists<br />

whom he also referred to as classical economist, are “all the economist who, since the time<br />

<strong>of</strong> W. Petty, have investigated the real inner structures <strong>of</strong> bourgeois relations <strong>of</strong> production”<br />

(Annotations, p. 214, referring to a quote by Marx in the afterword to the second edition <strong>of</strong><br />

Kapital). Marx respected these economists for their original thinking; however, he did take<br />

issue with them on several issues. For example, as Hans in [2007SP:316] explains, Marx<br />

thought that the classical economist did not adequately distinguish between abstract human<br />

labor and useful human labor, although they did implicitly (without really thinking about it)<br />

by switching from the qualitative to quantitative aspects <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

<strong>The</strong> vulgar economist in Marx’s view were those “who only flounder around with the<br />

apparent structure <strong>of</strong> those relations [identified by the bourgeois economist], ceaseless ruminate<br />

on the materials long since provided by scientific political economy, in order to lend<br />

plausibility to the crudest phenomena for bourgeois daily food” (Annotations, p. 214, referring<br />

to a quote by Marx in the afterword to the second edition <strong>of</strong> Kapital). He goes on, in<br />

his disdain, to say that the vulgar economist try to systematize complex economic concepts<br />

in a much simplified manner. Marx, obviously, had little regard for the vulgar economist because<br />

<strong>of</strong> their lack <strong>of</strong> original thought and their attempts to simplify what are very complex<br />

relationships in the political economy.<br />

Marx, with his careful, scientific analysis <strong>of</strong> the political economy unearthed many complexities.<br />

When he ran into an apparent impasse in an explanation he considered the matter<br />

more closely. He respected the bourgeois economist because he felt they too followed similar<br />

rigorous scientific methods even though he did not always agree with their conclusions.<br />

On the other hand, he did not like those economists who stayed on the surface <strong>of</strong> any explanation<br />

and did not dig when the inconsistencies appeared. When one understands that<br />

the real contributions <strong>of</strong> Marx came from his unwillingness to accept surface signals, one<br />

can understand why he would view those who dealt only with these surface signals to be<br />

unhelpful.<br />

Furthermore, this question reminds me <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> that Dr. E. K. Hunt tried to teach me.<br />

Citing the book, <strong>The</strong> Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Social Science: An Introduction, by Martin Hollis, Dr.<br />

Hunt taught that the approach to social science in general and economics in particular can be<br />

divided into four quadrants with explanation and understanding on one axis and holism and<br />

individualism on the other. Marx (and the bourgeois economists) sought an understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> the economic system, not just an explanation <strong>of</strong> the system such as that sought by the<br />

vulgar economist. (Not relevant to this question but relevant to my [373], Marx was also<br />

more concerned about a holist view rather than an individualistic one.)<br />

Next Message by Robert is [389].<br />

[448] Proletarian: graded A Marx felt that bourgeois economists were real scientists with<br />

the honest goal <strong>of</strong> understanding and explaining capitalism. To Marx, bourgeois economists<br />

were real scientists with original thoughts. While Marx disagrees with them in their views<br />

and their understanding <strong>of</strong> economics, he respected them and he learned from them.<br />

Vulgar economists, on the other hand, are those economists that polish and perpetuate the<br />

findings <strong>of</strong> the bourgeois economists. Vulgar economists accept the findings <strong>of</strong> bourgeois


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 197<br />

economists as gospel and truth. Vulgar economists are responsible for the continued widespread<br />

acceptance <strong>of</strong> bourgeois economic thought by the mainstream.<br />

Next Message by Proletarian is [493].<br />

[504] Spiral: Bourgeois economists i.e. classical economists used the labor theory <strong>of</strong><br />

value while assuming it was a natural end product. Marx criticized them for failing to ask<br />

why labor is expressed as value which he believed was a historical construct concealed from<br />

individuals by the money commodity. It was clear value has a societal element therefore the<br />

labor theory <strong>of</strong> value was indeed a historical construct. After this critique vulgar economists<br />

began to grab the mainstream by abandoning the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value replacing it with<br />

marginal value. Marx disliked these neo-classical economists who still viewed the system<br />

as a natural phenomena which they could describe with simpler, more mechanical versions<br />

<strong>of</strong> earlier classical economist tools.<br />

Hans: Marx’s vulgar economists such as Say are still classical economists. Marx would probably have called the<br />

emergent marginalist school vulgar too, but he was not aware <strong>of</strong> them. During his lifetime they were only a tiny<br />

minority in the economics pr<strong>of</strong>ession.<br />

Next Message by Spiral is [946].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 349 is 254 in 2003fa, 285 in 2004fa, 279 in 2005fa, 299 in 2007SP, 321 in<br />

2009fa, 328 in 2011fa, and 299 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 349 How does Marx know what commodities would say if they could speak?<br />

[253] Hit: Speaking Commodities. Marx claims that if commodities could speak they<br />

would say “our use-value may interest humans, but it does not belong to us as objects. What<br />

does belong to us as objects, however, is our value. Our own interactions as commodity<br />

objects prove it. We relate to each other only as exchange-values.” Marx know this because a<br />

commodity is a physical matter, such as food, petroleum, copper or any other good for which<br />

there is demand and is produced by human labor. Commodities are made <strong>of</strong> substances that<br />

come out <strong>of</strong> the earth. <strong>The</strong> price <strong>of</strong> a commodity is universal; the price can fluctuate daily in<br />

some cases based on global supply and demand. <strong>The</strong> use <strong>of</strong> commodities interests humans<br />

as we use many commodities in our daily lives.<br />

Hans: Wrong definition <strong>of</strong> “commodity.” Look at [2007SP:271] how this question should be answered.<br />

Message [253] referenced by [488]. Next Message by Hit is [488].<br />

[500] LuBr: If commodities could talk they would say that their use-values are what<br />

interests humans but is not what belongs to them. <strong>The</strong>ir value however does belong to<br />

them as objects. Commodities are clearly confused, and Marx points out this confusion is<br />

understandable given the disorienting nature <strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the social relations<br />

within a commodity producing society, that even confuses most humans [2005fa:523]. <strong>The</strong><br />

use-value contained within a commodity are the physical properties <strong>of</strong> the commodity that<br />

provide a range <strong>of</strong> uses for people. So in reality the commodities should associate their usevalues<br />

as that which belongs to them. However, what is disorienting for them is that their<br />

physical properties should be the bases <strong>of</strong> their relations with other commodities. However,<br />

it turns out to be their value, or the social relations, which make commodities exchangeable<br />

on the market (or the amount <strong>of</strong> socially necessary congealed abstract labor embodied within<br />

the commodity), which determines their relations with other commodities. This is why<br />

commodities are fooled into thinking that their value is what truly belongs to them.<br />

Next Message by LuBr is [568].<br />

198 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 350 is 191 in 1997WI, 245 in 2002fa, 280 in 2005fa, 308 in 2008fa, 329 in<br />

2011fa, and 344 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 350 How is it a manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism to speak <strong>of</strong> “rich” people and “valuable”<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s?<br />

[233] Hal: graded A– <strong>The</strong> Subtleties <strong>of</strong> Commodity Fetishism. In past responses, students<br />

such as Soki in [2008fa:374] seem to assume that the question above is asking about<br />

idolizing rich people and valuable <strong>thing</strong>s. However, it is not only a manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism<br />

to speak <strong>of</strong> “rich” people and “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s in positive terms. In fact, one need not feel<br />

any emotion at all regarding “rich” people and “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s for the manifestation to be<br />

apparent. It becomes apparent at an earlier, more basic level when one begins regarding a<br />

person or <strong>thing</strong>’s relative status in society as an inherent “attribute” <strong>of</strong> that person or <strong>thing</strong>.<br />

To quote Hans from [2005fa:584], “Whether a person is talented or not is a characteristic <strong>of</strong><br />

that person; but whether a person is rich or not is a characteristic <strong>of</strong> the place that person has<br />

in society, not <strong>of</strong> that person herself.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> change in point <strong>of</strong> view is so subtle that I should give some examples. Suppose a<br />

stranger in a dark parking lot suddenly opens his jacket to show you what he claims is a<br />

collection <strong>of</strong> “valuable” watches. Now, Soki and many other students would say that the<br />

manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism <strong>first</strong> becomes apparent when you believe the stranger that the<br />

watches are valuable. However it <strong>first</strong> becomes apparent when you believe the stranger that<br />

any watches (or any<strong>thing</strong>, or any person) can be inherently valuable or worthless. <strong>The</strong>refore,<br />

if you tell the stranger that his watches are actually cheap, you are still falling victim to<br />

commodity fetishism.<br />

At an even more subtle level, suppose you try a watch on and you love it. You love its<br />

function and design. If you then deem it “valuable”, fetishism still becomes apparent, even<br />

though the watch carries use-value. If you later buy a cell phone and use it to keep track <strong>of</strong><br />

time, the watch loses its use-value, yet you have already deemed it “valuable.” If we speak<br />

<strong>of</strong> “rich” people and “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s, we can easily fall into the trap <strong>of</strong> believing that the<br />

value is inherent and fixed. If Bill Gates loses all <strong>of</strong> his money, he will not be a “rich” man<br />

that happens to be down on his luck, and he will not even be a “poor” man. He will simply<br />

be a man without access to society’s wealth.<br />

Recall Hans’ analogy <strong>of</strong> a talented person. Talent is a characteristic <strong>of</strong> that person, but<br />

the manifestations <strong>of</strong> talent (i.e. excelling in sports or academia) are not characteristics <strong>of</strong><br />

that person. I believe this is what Hans meant when, in [2008fa:440], he wrote, “Marx’s<br />

own thought process was much more theoretical and almost pedantic, sticking to some basic<br />

logical principles.”<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> word “cheap” at the end <strong>of</strong> your second paragraph is in italics because you originally had “useless” and<br />

I want to say some<strong>thing</strong> about this.<br />

If you were to say the watches are not likely to function well (because you recognize them as unauthorized<br />

replica), then this is not commodity fetishism. You are talking about physical properties <strong>of</strong> the watches themselves.<br />

If you say the watches are cheap, this is commodity fetishism. Cheap or valuable is their position in the market,<br />

it is not a property <strong>of</strong> the watches as objects. That is why Marx says it is strictly speaking wrong to say a watch<br />

“is” cheap or valuable.<br />

Saying a watch is useless is a grey area (that’s why I replaced it by some<strong>thing</strong> which is more definite). If you<br />

mean by this “they only look like Rolexes but they aren’t Rolexes and don’t function like Rolexes, i.e., in terms <strong>of</strong>


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 199<br />

keeping time they are useless” then you are saying some<strong>thing</strong> about the watches themselves; this is not commodity<br />

fetishism. If you mean it in the sense “they are useless because I have a cell phone” then you are blaming the<br />

watch for it that you have a cell phone, which is not fair. You are treating a relationship between you and the watch<br />

(your not needing a watch because <strong>of</strong> your cell phone) as if it was a property <strong>of</strong> the watch. Strictly speaking this is<br />

imprecise. But we commit the same imprecision every time when we call a <strong>thing</strong> a use-value. Calling the <strong>thing</strong> a<br />

use-value is lauding the <strong>thing</strong> for a relationship between the <strong>thing</strong> and our needs. Marx allows us to do this. It is a<br />

little imprecise but it has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with commodity fetishism, because the relationship which we are projecting<br />

on the commodity is not a market relationship.<br />

It’s a little inconsistent that Marx allows us to say commodities are use-values (i.e., to pretend that the relationship<br />

between their physical characteristics and our needs are their property) but does not allow us to say<br />

commodities are valuable (i.e., to pretend that their social position within the market is their property). Your third<br />

paragraph goes back and forth between these two situations. It does not help that you are using “valuable” in the<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> “having use-value,” which is a no-no in this class and diminished your grade.<br />

<strong>The</strong> last sentence <strong>of</strong> the third paragraph was originally: “He will simply be a man that has no money.” I changed<br />

it to make it clearer that “having no money” is a position in society.<br />

Message [233] referenced by [239] and [367]. Next Message by Hal is [469].<br />

[239] Proletarian: graded C Rich People, Valuable Things, and the Manifestation <strong>of</strong><br />

Fetishism. <strong>The</strong>re have been many responses to this question in years past, and even a<br />

response this year by Hal [233]. Many <strong>of</strong> these responses seem to try to answer this question<br />

by giving examples instead <strong>of</strong> simply addressing the philosophical reasons why speaking <strong>of</strong><br />

rich people and valuable <strong>thing</strong>s is a manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism. Many <strong>of</strong> the responses briefly<br />

address the philosophical reasons or allude to them, but none that I have read (though I have<br />

yet to read all the responses from all available years) seem to fully address those reasons.<br />

I believe the reason for such confusion on this topic comes from a misunderstanding, even<br />

if it is just a slight misunderstanding in some cases, <strong>of</strong> the meaning <strong>of</strong> fetishism. From my<br />

reading <strong>of</strong> the responses given by many <strong>of</strong> those who have attempted to answer this question,<br />

it appears that many <strong>of</strong> those respondents are confusing the way Marx uses fetishism with<br />

modern usages <strong>of</strong> the word. Many respondents to this question include in their response<br />

some kind <strong>of</strong> reference to feelings <strong>of</strong> lust, desire, want, or worship <strong>of</strong> commodities. Those<br />

that make the mistake <strong>of</strong> referencing worship <strong>of</strong> commodities come closest to the way Marx<br />

is using the term fetishism, but they are still a bit <strong>of</strong>f.<br />

When Marx uses the term fetishism, he does not mean, in any way, some<strong>thing</strong> related<br />

to our modern usage <strong>of</strong> the word fetish, which implies pleasure, etc. Instead, Marx uses<br />

the word fetishism in the classical sense, the anthropological sense, which is the belief that<br />

objects (in this case commodities) have some sort <strong>of</strong> supernatural powers or some power<br />

over others (the latter part <strong>of</strong> the definition is where our modern usage as well as sexual<br />

fetishism stems from). This is why those who have responded to this question and have invoked<br />

worship <strong>of</strong> commodities in their answers come close to understanding the meaning <strong>of</strong><br />

fetishism, but miss it just barely. Now that I’ve cleared up what Marx means by “fetishism”<br />

I can demonstrate why speaking <strong>of</strong> rich people and valuable <strong>thing</strong>s are a manifestation <strong>of</strong><br />

fetishism.<br />

Marx asserts that people in the Bourgeois economic mindset view commodities in a magical<br />

or mysterious way. Those in the Bourgeois economic camp view value as some natural<br />

property <strong>of</strong> a commodity instead <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> instilled into a commodity by human labor<br />

(even if they recognize labor as the source <strong>of</strong> value). Because <strong>of</strong> this view <strong>of</strong> commodities,<br />

200 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

those with the Bourgeois economic mindset have a distorted view <strong>of</strong> value and wealth. Because<br />

<strong>of</strong> this mindset, the value <strong>of</strong> one person’s labor can be distorted to be more valuable<br />

than the labor <strong>of</strong> others (hence a rich person) and the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity can be distorted<br />

to be more valuable than another, even if they contain the same about <strong>of</strong> congealed human<br />

labor.<br />

In the Marxian mindset these distortions are not possible. All commodities are equally<br />

valuable as long as the labor power that went into the manufacture <strong>of</strong> the commodities is<br />

equal (1 coat that takes 20 hours <strong>of</strong> labor to produce has the same value as 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen<br />

if those 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen take 20 hours to produce). However, in the Bourgeois mindset, even<br />

if two commodities both contain 20 hours <strong>of</strong> congealed labor, they can be valued differently.<br />

<strong>The</strong> same distortion applies to wealth. In the Marxian mindset, all laborers should have<br />

roughly the same “wealth” assuming they work the same amount <strong>of</strong> time, though inefficient<br />

or lazy workers may have less wealth and very efficient workers may have more (plus<br />

there are certain exceptions for those with very unique skills). Because the given value <strong>of</strong><br />

the labor <strong>of</strong> a person can vary drastically from one person to another in the Bourgeois economic<br />

mindset, some people in that mindset have drastically more buying power than others<br />

because their labor is valued more than others.<br />

Because the concepts <strong>of</strong> a rich person or a valuable commodity can only come out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fetishism <strong>of</strong> the Bourgeois economic mindset, speaking <strong>of</strong> these conditions is inherently a<br />

manifestation <strong>of</strong> that fetishism.<br />

Hans: You write:<br />

Those in the Bourgeois economic camp view value as some natural property <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> instilled into a commodity by human labor (even if they recognize labor<br />

as the source <strong>of</strong> value).<br />

How can one recognize that labor is the source <strong>of</strong> value and at the same time view value as some natural property<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity? <strong>The</strong>se seem direct opposites to me. Please explain.<br />

You think Marx’s Capital is developing “Marxian mindset” in which the distortions <strong>of</strong> the “Bourgeois mindset”<br />

are not possible. Please read [92] and [122].<br />

Next Message by Proletarian is [447].<br />

[367] Giant: graded C+ It is a manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism to speak <strong>of</strong> “rich” people and<br />

“valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s because it makes them seem more like a law <strong>of</strong> nature and not formed out<br />

<strong>of</strong> a social institution as it would be if it was fetish like. By it being fetishism it brings commodities<br />

with use-values to become “rich” and get “value” out <strong>of</strong> the natural commodities<br />

through labor.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is not a set amount <strong>of</strong> money one needs to acquire to be considered “rich” or<br />

specific commodities that are considered “valuable” while others are not. This is because<br />

the idea behind “rich” and “valuable” is a social concept. <strong>The</strong> social concept <strong>of</strong> both is<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> most <strong>of</strong> society strive but since few achieve these goals they are admired by<br />

others in society. Because it is not set however it is up to society to establish what is rich<br />

and valuable. This concept can vary depending on location and social group. To speak <strong>of</strong><br />

“rich” or “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s is to try and conceptualize a manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism which<br />

can only be done through social agreement, and since neither <strong>of</strong> these ideas have specific<br />

requirements the best way to socially accept them is through manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism.<br />

Hans: Please re-read the <strong>first</strong> paragraph <strong>of</strong> [233]. <strong>The</strong> admiration for the rich is exactly not the issue here.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 201<br />

Next Message by Giant is [556].<br />

[390] Frida: graded A When we speak <strong>of</strong> “rich” people and “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s, we act<br />

as if these were natural properties inherent in the people and <strong>thing</strong>s. <strong>The</strong>se are not natural<br />

properties at all, they are social relations. This confusion is a manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism.<br />

Hans: Right.<br />

Message [390] referenced by [417], [443], and [463]. Next Message by Frida is [532].<br />

[417] Sly: Rich people don’t always have valuable <strong>thing</strong>s. Fetishism is a social relation<br />

that is based upon natural construction. <strong>The</strong> reason why fetishism manifests itself when<br />

speaking <strong>of</strong> “rich” people and “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s is that most individuals aren’t naturally<br />

constructed to be wealthy or haven’t reached that point yet. Those who are “rich” have more<br />

money and have easier access to “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s, than a poor or less endowed person. If<br />

I see a women that has Marc Jacobs handbag I immediately attach the label <strong>of</strong> “rich” to<br />

that particular person even though she may not be rich. <strong>The</strong> reason that I attach that label<br />

<strong>of</strong> “rich” is because a March Jacobs handbag can be anywhere from $1500–$3000 - that is<br />

what I consider “valuable”, and I just couldn’t fathom using that kind <strong>of</strong> money on such an<br />

item. What I may not be aware <strong>of</strong> is that woman could have used her entire life savings on<br />

that handbag, but I only see the handbag that is naturally constructed that way and the social<br />

relation <strong>of</strong> “rich” is immediately applied because she has such a “valuable” item.<br />

Hans: Look at [390] how to answer this question.<br />

Next Message by Sly is [419].<br />

[443] Rmc: graded B– Fetishism, as claimed by Babyceta [308], is “the belief that inanimate<br />

objects [possess] certain social determinations endowed by physical nature that enable<br />

them to transmit these properties to individuals.”.<br />

Money is the most valuable <strong>thing</strong>, typically, in a society, because it is the measure <strong>of</strong><br />

buying power (linked to the society). If an individual is rich, in a monetary sense s/he has a<br />

lot <strong>of</strong> money and is able to buy many <strong>thing</strong>s, or expensive <strong>thing</strong>s, or valuable <strong>thing</strong>s. (<strong>The</strong><br />

more valuable a commodity is to a society, the more money it typically costs; sometimes it<br />

is so in reverse- if a commodity costs a lot <strong>of</strong> money, it is assumed it is more valuable.)<br />

One example <strong>of</strong> the way fetishism is expressed is by social reactions regarding “status<br />

symbols”—it is very common for “rich” people to own “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s such as certain<br />

cars, houses that look a certain way (or are a certain size), or they wear clo<strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong> certain<br />

fashions. People with a lot <strong>of</strong> buying power are able to purchase such socially valuable<br />

commodities whereas others who have less money cannot buy them.<br />

If society regards these commodities with a great amount <strong>of</strong> value, it follows that “rich”<br />

people who have purchased these “valuable” commodities have as much social value themselves<br />

as the commodity.<br />

Hans: This time you have a different theory <strong>of</strong> exchange-value than in the resubmission <strong>of</strong> your other exam question<br />

[442]. In that earlier message you wrote that exchange-value is determined by use-value, and in the present<br />

message you write that the price is determined by how “valuable a commodity is to society.” <strong>The</strong>se are different<br />

explanations <strong>of</strong> the same <strong>thing</strong> (price is a form <strong>of</strong> exchange-value) which are incompatible with each other, and<br />

neither explanation is compatible with the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Here is a hint how to study for this class: you should read the discussion in the pdf archives (or for the exam<br />

in Installment 1 or 2)—especially when you go back to the past discussion while writing your resubmission. You<br />

quoted [308] in its original version how it was emailed, instead <strong>of</strong> the edited version in the archive. Not only is it<br />

202 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

almost impossible to stay on top <strong>of</strong> such a complex discussion if you read it one email at a time, but you are also<br />

missing a lot <strong>of</strong> feedback comments about these contributions which are never propagated by email.<br />

And after you have downloaded the pdf archive from<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/screen/2010fa.pdf<br />

Look at Frida’s resubmission [390] to see what a correct answer to this question looks like.<br />

Next Message by Rmc is [711].<br />

[446] Smartergirl: To speak <strong>of</strong> rich people and valuable <strong>thing</strong>s is a manifestation <strong>of</strong><br />

Fetishism because it is placing a value on a social attribute instead <strong>of</strong> a natural attribute. We<br />

see this all the time in modern day society with lots <strong>of</strong> commodities but let’s use handbags<br />

for example. A gucci bag or a Dooney and Burk can cost upwards <strong>of</strong> $1000.00. It is only<br />

commanding this price because <strong>of</strong> the status that society has put on these brands. We do not<br />

pay more because the leather is particularly better, the buckles are gold or the inside is lined<br />

with mink. We simply pay for the name and the social status that having one <strong>of</strong> these bags<br />

provides. It is the same situation if we buy a thrift store bag. A person is subject to fetishism<br />

if they feel that bag is less than socially acceptable. Fetishism gives a commodity a value<br />

that is not based on its physical properties but the social interpretation <strong>of</strong> that item despite<br />

the commodities lack <strong>of</strong> a physical characteristic that would warrant the increase in value.<br />

Hans: Nice text but completely wrong. If you think that value, a social relation, depends (for <strong>thing</strong>s other than<br />

gucci handbags) on the physical properties <strong>of</strong> the <strong>thing</strong>s then Marx would say this is fetishism.<br />

Next Message by Smartergirl is [900].<br />

[454] Husani: Fetishism is the idea that value is some mystical power, intrinsic to the<br />

commodity. We look at a commodity and instead <strong>of</strong> seeing the matter and labor comprised<br />

inside it, we see the commodity as an object that is useful. We believe this value is created<br />

through nature when in reality it is produced by mankind.<br />

When we speak <strong>of</strong> “rich” people or “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s we aren’t looking at the individual<br />

person or object, but the crystallized substance they are made <strong>of</strong>. “Rich” people are the<br />

same as everyone else and were created in the same way, but we seem them as having value<br />

because <strong>of</strong> what they are. <strong>The</strong>y are valuable by themselves but we feel a need to give them<br />

value through some mystical dimension that we cannot see. A rich person is still a person,<br />

just like everyone else. <strong>The</strong> only difference is that they have more money than the rest <strong>of</strong><br />

us. This can be seen with commodities as well. We rarely see a diamond as having value<br />

because <strong>of</strong> how it is made (through years rock and dirt crushing on carbon substances) or<br />

by the labor necessary to extract it from the ground. We see it as valuable because it is a<br />

DIAMOND. We believe a diamond is valuable because <strong>of</strong> its internal properties.<br />

Next Message by Husani is [550].<br />

[462] Somramthom: graded A Fetishly fetishisms. A manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism is regarding<br />

a person or <strong>thing</strong> to be <strong>of</strong> higher worth because <strong>of</strong> the person’s or <strong>thing</strong>’s social<br />

status. Thus, when we speak <strong>of</strong> “rich” people or “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s, we are really explaining<br />

the social relations <strong>of</strong> the “rich” person or the “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>. We see this manifestation as<br />

an inherent trait or characteristic <strong>of</strong> the person or <strong>thing</strong>, though it is not.<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [467].<br />

[463] RexManning: graded A– An example <strong>of</strong> fetishism can be seen in the “value” that<br />

humans place much desired objects, such as, diamonds and gold. <strong>The</strong>se objects are a manifestation<br />

<strong>of</strong> fetishism because <strong>of</strong> their socially placed value. In normal commodity exchange,<br />

an object is not more valuable because it is shiny or because the producer simply says that it


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 203<br />

is more valuable. Although value does have a social relation, it is still in relation to labor. In<br />

the case <strong>of</strong> the shiny, or highly regarded commodity, they are only able to capture a higher<br />

price because <strong>of</strong> the social stigma associated with them, such is the case with diamonds<br />

and gold. <strong>The</strong>se objects are considered valuable, not because <strong>of</strong> the properties which they<br />

possess, but because <strong>of</strong> the social value that society places on them. People can be viewed<br />

the same way. When a person is said to be talented, smart, or outgoing, these are properties/qualities<br />

which that person possesses. If a person is said to be rich, then that person<br />

is placed high in society. Like the diamonds and gold, which are considered valuable by<br />

society, so is a rich person regarded.<br />

Hans: Leave the prestige part out <strong>of</strong> the answer. Frida [390] said it best. Regarding price versus value <strong>of</strong> gold, the<br />

issue is difficult; see my [2007SP:685].<br />

Next Message by RexManning is [465].<br />

[478] Rico: As I initially answered the question, I took the approach <strong>of</strong> explaining that<br />

when speaking <strong>of</strong> “rich” people and “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s, one is showing a manifestation <strong>of</strong><br />

fetishism because they are creating a process <strong>of</strong> socializing nature. In other words, people<br />

speak <strong>of</strong> “rich” people and “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s as a mechanism <strong>of</strong> measuring a person’s societal<br />

position. Hans mentioned this “societal position” in [2008fa:440], where he explains<br />

that “. . . whether a person is rich or not is a characteristic <strong>of</strong> the place occupied by that<br />

person in society, not <strong>of</strong> the person herself. <strong>The</strong>refore calling the person herself rich treats a<br />

social position as if it was an attribute <strong>of</strong> the person. That is why this common usage <strong>of</strong> language<br />

can be considered an manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism.” In his passage, Hans explains that it<br />

is not possible to judge the character <strong>of</strong> a person by their material possessions, because material<br />

possessions are not characteristics <strong>of</strong> the person. One’s possessions are therefore used<br />

to place him or her in a societal position. Using the rhetoric <strong>of</strong> “rich” people and “valuable”<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s is a manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism.<br />

I would also like to stress how society seeks to change how use-value is derived. When<br />

speaking <strong>of</strong> “rich” people and “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s, Marx explains the social change on how<br />

society attributes the use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity. Picard explains that society attributes usevalue<br />

as a man-made product in [2005fa:522], where he states that the use <strong>of</strong> the term “rich”<br />

people is a “manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism because this term says that use-value is “an attribute<br />

<strong>of</strong> man,” meaning it is because <strong>of</strong> man that a <strong>thing</strong> has a use-value [. . .]” <strong>The</strong>n Picard explains<br />

why attributing use-value to man-made products is wrong because “use-value belongs<br />

to the commodity itself.” Use-value does not derive from man himself.<br />

It is a manifestation to speak <strong>of</strong> “rich” people and “valuable” <strong>thing</strong>s because <strong>of</strong> the way<br />

society seeks to change nature. <strong>The</strong>y use measurements <strong>of</strong> material possessions to create<br />

hierarchies, where they place individuals in societal positions based solely on the possessions<br />

owned. <strong>The</strong>y also believe that they can actually create use-value themselves.<br />

Next Message by Rico is [738].<br />

[513] JJ: Manifestations <strong>of</strong> Fetishism, Rich and Poor. Fetishism is a false interpretation<br />

<strong>of</strong> socially related qualities as being some<strong>thing</strong> inherent to the nature <strong>of</strong> that <strong>thing</strong>. We<br />

manifest this fetishism when we speak <strong>of</strong> “rich” people. In so doing we have labeled these<br />

people as “rich” and would, in turn, label others as “poor”. Yet, this socially constructed<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> “rich” tends to imply that, somehow, their richness was rooted somehow in<br />

their natural being. However, the real natural qualities <strong>of</strong> a “rich” person are just the same<br />

204 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

as all other people that walk, talk, sleep, eat, and drink. If all people had the same amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> money then we could no longer label this person as “rich” and that person as “poor”.<br />

This is because the labels would no longer hold in the social context and could no longer<br />

be mistaken as natural to their character. We would be forced to look at the true qualities<br />

<strong>of</strong> a man or woman. i.e. this man is honest, and this woman is athletic. Hans gave us such<br />

a striking example <strong>of</strong> fetishism in a story from his youth. He explains how he was learning<br />

to differentiate between a man and a woman at an early age, and how his teacher quickly<br />

corrected his socially related understanding that if an individual has long hair that they must<br />

be a woman. This is a simple example <strong>of</strong> fetishism to assume that one’s hair length is related<br />

to the sex <strong>of</strong> that individual. Of course we know that a woman can have short hair and a man<br />

long, but society relates long hair to womanhood and therefore the young mind could see<br />

long hair as a natural trait <strong>of</strong> being a woman. It is only through this understanding that we<br />

can see that speaking <strong>of</strong> “rich” people is similarly a manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism, and mistakes<br />

their wealth as some<strong>thing</strong> that is a natural part <strong>of</strong> who they are.<br />

<strong>The</strong> same manifestation <strong>of</strong> fetishism appears when we speak <strong>of</strong> a <strong>thing</strong> being “valuable”.<br />

This once again makes the same false interpretation <strong>of</strong> a socially related quality being somehow<br />

a natural quality <strong>of</strong> the <strong>thing</strong>. Labeling one commodity as “valuable” and another as<br />

“cheap” ignores the real character <strong>of</strong> the commodity’s value, which is the amount <strong>of</strong> human<br />

labor that went into producing it. This instead adjusts the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity by means <strong>of</strong><br />

the social relationship and pretends that this social relationship is part <strong>of</strong> its natural qualities.<br />

<strong>The</strong> two commodities might be exchanged at a rate <strong>of</strong> many <strong>of</strong> X for a few <strong>of</strong> Y, but this<br />

does not make X a cheap commodity or Y a valuable commodity. <strong>The</strong> real exchange ratio<br />

here should show that many <strong>of</strong> X and few <strong>of</strong> Y represented labor equivalents and therefore<br />

held equal value when considering their natural qualities. Rather it is fetishism that tries to<br />

add this socially constructed adjustment to value.<br />

Unfortunately, fetishism is hard enigma to combat and continues to make its false interpretations<br />

and adjustments to the natural and true qualities <strong>of</strong> all <strong>thing</strong>s. This is some<strong>thing</strong><br />

that we should be aware <strong>of</strong> as we attempt to catch the false interpretations that fetishism<br />

bestows to <strong>thing</strong>s as natural and inherent. Armed with a new lens to see the world through,<br />

we can attempt to avoid creating fetishes <strong>of</strong> our own when we interact with the <strong>thing</strong>s and<br />

people in our lives.<br />

Next Message by JJ is [639].<br />

[544] Kiko: Fetishism ties directly with the idea <strong>of</strong> “rich people” and valuable <strong>thing</strong>s. <strong>The</strong><br />

idea <strong>of</strong> fetishism is one that gives life to an object that has none. <strong>The</strong> object transcends its<br />

own basic makeup to give itself life, meaning and value. Also it is individuals that help these<br />

ideas take form in that ordinary metals and plastics can be transformed into say a Mercedes<br />

or an iPhone that reflects value and shows status. It is the mysterious nature <strong>of</strong> the <strong>thing</strong> that<br />

can will people to give life where there is none. When you hear people talk <strong>of</strong> lust for an<br />

object or I want to be “rich”. It is this mysterious nature that Marx is trying to find. With the<br />

social nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s and people the object is further enhanced and the kinds <strong>of</strong> labor used<br />

to produce the good.<br />

Hans: Things do have life in capitalism. According to Marx this is not due to the attitude <strong>of</strong> people towards their<br />

toys but this is a characteristic <strong>of</strong> capitalist relations <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Next Message by Kiko is [549].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 205<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 354 is 172 in 1995WI, 149 in 1995ut, 194 in 1997WI, 201 in 1997sp, 193 in<br />

1997ut, 202 in 1998WI, 312 in 2008fa, 326 in 2009fa, and 333 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 354 Why a separate chapter about the exchange process? Has the exchange not<br />

already been discussed in chapter One?<br />

[356] AlexDaily: graded A Why a separate chapter about the exchange process? In<br />

Chapter One, Marx briefly goes over the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities. However, the main purpose<br />

<strong>of</strong> the chapter is explaining the commodity and to establish that value comes from labor<br />

and not use value. Chapter Two builds on Chapter One as does each chapter in Karl Marx’s<br />

book Capital. In the <strong>first</strong> chapter, it explains in great detail the products <strong>of</strong> labor and in Chapter<br />

Two builds upon that thought by going deeply into the social relations <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Furthermore, Chapter Two explains how certain features <strong>of</strong> a commodity have social associations<br />

which are created by individual incentives. This allows social relations to be created.<br />

As Hans puts it in [2009fa:432] “because social relations can only exist if individuals act on<br />

them.” <strong>The</strong>refore, Chapter Two is necessary to explain the social bond between commodities<br />

in the exchange process and also to relate the relationship <strong>of</strong> the commodity <strong>of</strong> the proprietor<br />

in the exchange process. In the end, Marx giving the exchange process a separate chapter<br />

shows the importance <strong>of</strong> the role humans play in driving the exchange process.<br />

Message [356] referenced by [358]. Next Message by AlexDaily is [525].<br />

[358] Hans: If we were to stop exchanging, THAT would stop the capitalist system in<br />

its tracks. But we would also starve ... AlexDaily gave a good answer in [356]. Please<br />

read also my [2009fa:1106].<br />

AlexDaily’s last sentence is: “Marx giving the exchange process a separate chapter shows<br />

the importance <strong>of</strong> the role humans play in driving the exchange process.” It is a relief, after<br />

reading about the power <strong>of</strong> commodities and the lack <strong>of</strong> human control over the capitalist<br />

system, that commodities cannot even go to market if not some human carries them.<br />

Marx would say humans are driving not only the exchange process but the entire capitalist<br />

economy in the sense that our labor and our motivations are the engine, but we are not in<br />

the driver’s seat, we are not in control. Of course, if we would all stop exchanging, then<br />

commodities would lose their power instantly. But we cannot stop exchanging, we would<br />

starve if we did.<br />

This does not mean we are entirely powerless. We cannot stop going to the grocery store,<br />

but there are other decisions which we can make if we think the capitalist growth engine is<br />

spinning out <strong>of</strong> control and we need to reduce carbon emissions. We can decide no longer<br />

to fly airplanes, we can decide to have at most one child per couple, and we can decide<br />

to save more and spend less. You notice that I am not talking about changing lightbulbs.<br />

We need to change lightbulbs too (and LEDs are becoming more and more affordable, so<br />

that I would recommend to jump over CFLs and go directly to LEDs). But we need bigger<br />

decisions—and we can do bigger <strong>thing</strong>s than changing lightbulbs.<br />

If you object that saving more and spending less brings the economy down, then my answer<br />

is: an economy which destroys the livability <strong>of</strong> our planet has to be brought down. We<br />

need to transition to a steady-state economy. This is a big change. A steady-state economy is<br />

as different from our present growth economy as a helicopter is different from a fixed-wing<br />

206 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

aircraft. As the saying goes, a failed growth economy is not the same <strong>thing</strong> as a steady-state<br />

economy. But as long as the growth economy is humming along those in power will never<br />

change over to a steady-state economy.<br />

Since the exam is over now, we have a new grading policy as announced in [287]: anyone<br />

who is going to submit additional answers to 345 this Semester is expected to build on [356].<br />

You don’t have to build on this answer here, because it goes too far afield. <strong>The</strong> focus is on<br />

reading and understanding Marx, not any particular implication <strong>of</strong> his theories for today.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [364].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 358 is 173 in 1995WI, 150 in 1995ut, 183 in 1996sp, 196 in 1997WI, 203 in<br />

1997sp, 295 in 2004fa, 318 in 2008SP, 316 in 2008fa, 337 in 2011fa, and 352 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 358 Explain in your own words Marx’s phrase that the commodity owners’ will<br />

“resides” in the objects which are his property.<br />

Is this a good <strong>thing</strong> or not? Where does it have its limits in our society? Are there <strong>thing</strong>s for<br />

which it is desirable that people’s wills reside in them?<br />

[389] Robert: graded A+ Means to an end. In [2008fa:555] Hans explains how Marx<br />

(after setting Hegel’s theories straight) attempts to straighten up those <strong>of</strong> Hegel’s contemporary,<br />

Schopenhauer. Schopenhauer theorized, “People can do what they want but cannot<br />

want what they want;” therefore, they are driven by will. He generalized this concept to include<br />

all animate and inanimate objects: the universal will. Marx adapted a part <strong>of</strong> Schopenhauer’s<br />

idea that inanimate objects can have wills (he did not accept the entire concept <strong>of</strong><br />

the universal will). <strong>The</strong> inanimate objects Marx focused on are commodities. He concluded<br />

the wills <strong>of</strong> the commodities, which they exercise in their own activity, are the wills <strong>of</strong> their<br />

owners residing within the commodities.<br />

Wills, according to Marx are finite. If a commodity’s owner surrenders his will (knowingly<br />

or unknowingly) to his commodities he loses that will and he becomes a slave to the<br />

commodity who has his will residing in it.<br />

Both good and bad derive from the fact that people invest their commodities with their<br />

wills. <strong>The</strong> good is that <strong>thing</strong>s receive the necessary care and attention and aren’t wasted.<br />

In [2008SP:269] Hans gives an example <strong>of</strong> how under Soviet Union style socialism some<br />

projects would be abandoned as administrations changed and the <strong>thing</strong>s associated with<br />

those projects would just be wasted.<br />

<strong>The</strong> bad, however, in my view is worse than any benefit <strong>of</strong> the good. Capitalism creates<br />

a situation in which those whose wills reside in commodities are the private owners <strong>of</strong> those<br />

commodities. One human being’s access to another’s property is through giving up his own<br />

private property. This private ownership creates a “split will” as described in the Annotations<br />

p. 225: one has control <strong>of</strong> his privately owned property; however, “the laws <strong>of</strong> private property<br />

take precedence over any human needs.” If you need bread and have no private property<br />

<strong>of</strong> your own, you cannot just take the bread you need, as we know from Victor Hugo’s story<br />

<strong>of</strong> Jean Valjean, because the law <strong>of</strong> private property prevents such a transaction.<br />

Even in “legal” transactions, the will <strong>of</strong> the commodities involved, i.e., to realize their<br />

values, leave the owners <strong>of</strong> those commodities standing on the sidelines. <strong>The</strong>y are not two


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 207<br />

human beings coming together to help each other. <strong>The</strong> human beings are merely a means<br />

to an end, the vehicles by which the commodities accomplish their wills. From an ethical<br />

standpoint, such exchanges force its human participant to violate the Second Maxim <strong>of</strong><br />

Kant’s Categorical Imperative, i.e., to treat other human beings as an end, in and <strong>of</strong> themselves,<br />

and not as a means to an end. It cannot be psychologically healthy, whether done<br />

with thought or mindlessly out <strong>of</strong> habit, to daily treat other human beings as mere means to<br />

an end by exercise <strong>of</strong> the will we have given up to our commodities.<br />

Message [389] referenced by [519]. Next Message by Robert is [519].<br />

[395] TINDOZ: <strong>The</strong> will <strong>of</strong> Toys and Cars. I hope I’m not looking at this too simply<br />

(especially after reading Robert’s remarks) but I have little kids at home so I’m used to<br />

reducing most conversations into simple forms. As I read in the annotations about the will<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity’s owner residing in the commodity, I couldn’t help but think <strong>of</strong> the (albeit<br />

fictitious) movie Toy Story 2. For those who haven’t seen it, I’ll sum up the story to preface<br />

my point about how ‘will’ can reside in an object and therefore express the ‘will’ idea in my<br />

own words. In the film, all the toys are personified objects that can move and interact, but<br />

only when people aren’t looking at them. Early on in the film the main toy, Woody, winds<br />

up at a garage sale by mistake. When a prospective buyer asks to buy the toy (intending to<br />

add it to a rare collection) he is told that the toy isn’t for sale. Upset at not being able to<br />

buy the toy, he steals it when the “owner” (or the owner’s mother) isn’t looking - against the<br />

will <strong>of</strong> both the toy and the owner. All this happens as Woody is playing as if he is totally<br />

inanimate and as the other toys look on from the second story window. Though seeming to<br />

not have any will during the “transaction” (or theft), Woody and his onlooking toy friends<br />

are upset that he was stolen. From this point and for a considerable portion <strong>of</strong> the film,<br />

Woody attempts to get back to his true owner, Andy, whom his will is intertwined with.<br />

A reoccurring statement expressing how Woody’s will is intertwined with Andy’s is stated<br />

throughout the 3 Toy Story films when Woody <strong>of</strong>ten tells the other toys that they are there<br />

for Andy when he has need <strong>of</strong> them.<br />

This fictitious story shows (in admittedly personified, over the top fashion) how the will<br />

<strong>of</strong> an owner can reside in a commodity—to be there when they have need <strong>of</strong> them. To<br />

take the discussion out <strong>of</strong> fiction land, I have noticed that it can sometimes seem as if an<br />

object wants what its owner would want. An example from my own life is that I have<br />

owned a 1986 4Runner since 1997. Last April it was almost stolen. It’s a long story, but<br />

what prevented the thieves from taking it was that the battery mysteriously died somewhere<br />

between evening and somewhere around 2 AM. Explaining this mystery would make this a<br />

very long discussion, but I’ll just say that it was almost as if the car ‘willed’ to not be parted<br />

from me. Another story, five years ago I had a ’98 Acura Integra stolen and driven down<br />

foothill, crashed up a bunch and left in the parking lot across from the stadium. Whenever I<br />

would drive this car, we (the car and I) almost seemed to have a will to go fast and I got it<br />

to over 120 mph on more than one occasion. It’s almost as if that car had such a strong will<br />

to go fast that it would allow someone to take it for a joy ride while my 4Runner seemed to<br />

have the will to stay with me. Perhaps it’s all coincidence, but if Marx says that commodities<br />

have their owners’ will residing in them, I can easily believe that just by thinking <strong>of</strong> my cars.<br />

Is it a good <strong>thing</strong>?—In the case <strong>of</strong> my 4Runner, yes, it’s a good <strong>thing</strong> because I’m still<br />

driving it as its will (a residual <strong>of</strong> my will) could be said to have prevented the theft. However<br />

208 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

in the case <strong>of</strong> any sort <strong>of</strong> commodity that can inflict pain, violence, death, etc. it could be<br />

disastrous. If a person’s will to kill people resides in a firearm, that could be a bad <strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Noting that will residing in the object and using the object are two different <strong>thing</strong>s, for you<br />

could “use” the gun to kill someone by shooting it or by bludgeoning them with it, either<br />

way, it’s the ‘will’ <strong>of</strong> the owner that resides in the firearm that could harm society.<br />

Where does this idea <strong>of</strong> will have its limits in society? I liked Robert’s mentioning <strong>of</strong> Jean<br />

Valjean’s theft <strong>of</strong> bread. <strong>The</strong> annotations say that private property is a social relationship as<br />

the “private” aspect <strong>of</strong> the property has to be respected by society if it is to be private at<br />

all. So at this point, is it then the individual’s will that makes it his private property, or is<br />

it society’s? And if it is society’s, would society rather a man die from starvation or would<br />

society rather abdicate someones “private” bread to the man so he doesn’t die, or would<br />

society rather the law be upheld no matter what? This dilemma is where I believe will has<br />

its limits—at the point when society has two conflicting interests for a commodity and one<br />

<strong>of</strong> those conflicts with the “private” aspect <strong>of</strong> an individual’s property.<br />

Are there <strong>thing</strong>s for which it is desirable that people’s wills reside in them? <strong>The</strong>n annotations<br />

spoke <strong>of</strong> toothbrushes and I think that is an excellent example <strong>of</strong> this. I also think<br />

someone’s broken-in pair <strong>of</strong> shoes would be another. I think that in case <strong>of</strong> the shoes, as they<br />

mold to conform to their owner’s feet, it is desirable that the will <strong>of</strong> the owner should at that<br />

point reside in the shoe itself.<br />

Message [395] referenced by [408]. Next Message by TINDOZ is [438].<br />

[408] Hans: Sign <strong>of</strong> a declining empire. Sign <strong>of</strong> a declining empire: This is what I<br />

thought reading the author <strong>of</strong> [395] promoting theories which could come out <strong>of</strong> a fantasy<br />

movie script but have no<strong>thing</strong> to do with reality—with the justification “Perhaps it’s all<br />

coincidence, but if Marx says that commodities have their owners’ will residing in them, I<br />

can easily believe that just by thinking <strong>of</strong> my cars.”<br />

I witnessed a similar turn to superstition shortly before the Chrysler Lynch Road Assembly<br />

plant was shut down in 1979. <strong>The</strong> air was thick with rumors about the future, say better<br />

the lack <strong>of</strong> a future, for the plant. And what was the favorite conversation subject on the final<br />

assembly line? Some book about past lives and soul migration which what the vogue at the<br />

time.<br />

Marx witnessed a similar situation, and he remarked about it in footnote 25 to 163:3/o<br />

(the paragraph about the table which, as a commodity, starts to dance). I left the footnote<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the class edition <strong>of</strong> the Annotations, because it’s a confusing tangent in an already<br />

difficult text, therefore the above link leads to the more complete edition in akmc.pdf. <strong>The</strong><br />

footnote says:<br />

One remembers that China and the tables started to dance when all the rest<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world seemed to stand still—in order to encourage the others.<br />

Spiritistic table-shifting had become fashionable during the reactionary aftermath <strong>of</strong> the<br />

1848 revolution in Germany. Marx saw the irony: while social progress was frozen, tables<br />

began to move. “China” is a pun. It refers at the same time to the porcelain dishes on the<br />

moving tables and to the Taiping-revolution in China, which, Marx hoped, would encourage<br />

others to follow suit.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 209<br />

Just this year, 2010, a strong working class movement has been gaining momentum in<br />

China. Marx would certainly endorse again today that we should take China as example.<br />

Message [408] referenced by [877]. Next Message by Hans is [501].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 359 is 175 in 1995WI, 151 in 1995ut, 184 in 1996sp, 186 in 1996ut, 205 in<br />

1998WI, 211 in 1999SP, 222 in 2000fa, and 235 in 2001fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 359 Is there any<strong>thing</strong> wrong with private property?<br />

[403] Lindsey: Private property is more important than my life? Hans says on p.225 <strong>of</strong><br />

the annotations, “they [commodity owners] must subordinate their wills to a legal framework<br />

which forces them to put the respect <strong>of</strong> private property above every<strong>thing</strong> else, even above<br />

their own lives.”<br />

I see that it is true that we have a very strong legal framework. If someone takes your<br />

private property without you agreeing to it (say your car), you would call the police, they<br />

would try to find the person, and he would be tried in court and likely serve some time in jail<br />

or pay a large fine or some other punishment. This encourages people to respect the social<br />

rules private property.<br />

However, I do not see how respect <strong>of</strong> private property is put above human lives. <strong>The</strong> guy<br />

who stole your car will not get the death sentence, and I do not think that you can legally<br />

shoot a trespasser on your land if they pose no threat to you—you would be punished for<br />

homicide.<br />

Perhaps I am reading this sentence incorrectly, but it caught my eye and I do not understand<br />

how it is true <strong>of</strong> the capitalist society we live in.<br />

Next Message by Lindsey is [405].<br />

[405] Lindsey: reading further. I think by reading further I have clarified my own<br />

confusion. Further on in the text there is an example that helped me to better understand<br />

the argument that private property is valued over one’s life—if you do not have money to<br />

buy food, you will starve. I agree that this is a major flaw <strong>of</strong> capitalism. We have created<br />

institutions to try to solve this problem, but they do not solve it well.<br />

I am still reading this section and will probably clarify this even more—I’ll make sure to<br />

read further before I post next time.<br />

Next Message by Lindsey is [597].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 368 is 226 in 2000fa, 239 in 2001fa, 340 in 2009fa, and 347 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 368 Are commodities selfish?<br />

[825] IrvingHowe: Are commodities selfish? No. At least not inherently. Division <strong>of</strong><br />

labor was not invented by Adam Smith. Division <strong>of</strong> labor always and everywhere results in<br />

commodity production. That is, in fact, the purpose <strong>of</strong> dividing labor in a society/economy.<br />

It is known to have existed in the earliest records we have in work and the ancient Babylonians<br />

actually produced quite a few records showing the division <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

So, why begin to answer a question <strong>of</strong> commodities with a statement on the division <strong>of</strong><br />

labor?<br />

210 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Because, to me, one must <strong>first</strong> understand the division <strong>of</strong> labor in order to understand<br />

why commodities are not selfish. Babylonia was far from an advanced capitalistic society<br />

and yet the Babylonians division <strong>of</strong> work can tells us that there is some<strong>thing</strong> that works and<br />

is therefore some<strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong> a natural phenomenon once exchange begins. Because <strong>of</strong> natural<br />

talents, physical traits and the amount <strong>of</strong> time involved, even the smallest <strong>of</strong> tribes will find<br />

it necessary to divide tasks among workmen just to survive.<br />

A commodity, being defined as a good having use-value that is produced for exchange, is<br />

a feature <strong>of</strong> even hunter/gatherer societies where selfishness certainly exists but cannot exist<br />

in amounts greater than the level <strong>of</strong> co-operation. Any tribe with a prevailing selfishness<br />

among its population would invariably perish in this setting and yet even in this primitive<br />

setting, we can see commodity production and observe trade.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, while a commodity can certainly symbolize selfishness (take a private jet or<br />

platinum as an example) it is not a permanent trait <strong>of</strong> every commodity.<br />

Message [825] referenced by [829]. Next Message by IrvingHowe is [1008].<br />

[829] Hans: Division <strong>of</strong> Labor IS Possible Without Commodity Production. This<br />

question will not be on the exam, and IrvingHowe’s [825] will not get a grade. Only those<br />

questions which were previously discussed and need further clarification are eligible for the<br />

extra credit. I just instructed my computer only to let those questions through which are in<br />

Installment 2.<br />

Let yourself not be confused by IrvingHowe’s confident assertion that “division <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

always and everywhere results in commodity production.” It does not. <strong>The</strong> ancient Incas and<br />

modern Cuba are societies with division <strong>of</strong> labor but no or very little commodity production.<br />

See [339].<br />

IrvingHowe did not answer the question whether commodities are selfish, but whether<br />

commodity production induces selfishness in people. <strong>Question</strong> 368 comes from the beginning<br />

<strong>of</strong> chapter 2, where Marx depicts commodities as beings with their own will. If you are<br />

curious about an answer in this context, go to [2009fa:442] and the links from there.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [831].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 371 is 321 in 2007SP, 329 in 2008fa, and 371 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 371 Is is a good characterization <strong>of</strong> the exchange process to say: <strong>The</strong> commodity<br />

owner throws his commodity on the market and tries to get as much use-value as he can for<br />

it?<br />

[379] Kleenex: One-sided characterization <strong>of</strong> the exchange process. No, this is not<br />

an accurate characterization <strong>of</strong> the Marxian viewpoint. Marx writes that the commodity<br />

has a will <strong>of</strong> its own, and at the instinctive level, wants to realize its value. Marx uses a<br />

sexual analogy here <strong>of</strong> the commodity giving its body and soul for another commodity. It<br />

is willing to exchange itself with any other commodity that has the same value, so here,<br />

use-value becomes irrelevant. Saying that the commodity owner throws his commodity<br />

onto the market to try to get as much use-value as he can for it, therefore, is inaccurate.<br />

<strong>The</strong> commodity owner tries to kill two birds with one stone, so to speak, when he puts his<br />

commodity on the market. He seeks to realize the value <strong>of</strong> his commodity (in the social


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 211<br />

dimension), but also desires to have his use-value maximized in the new commodity he has<br />

obtained from the exchange. This presents us with contradictory objectives. (Later, Marx<br />

discusses the private dimension <strong>of</strong> exchange in which the commodity owner seeks the reward<br />

for the labor he expended in the production <strong>of</strong> this commodity). <strong>The</strong> hypothetical statement<br />

in this question condenses and incorrectly simplifies his two goals into one and only depicts<br />

one side <strong>of</strong> the story <strong>of</strong> an exchange transaction from a Marxian perspective.<br />

Message [379] referenced by [383]. Next Message by Kleenex is [602].<br />

[383] Hans: Marx replies to a consumer who only cares about use-value. Consumer: I<br />

have done the readings, Mr. Marx, and I know that you would not characterize the exchange<br />

process this way. Kleenex says this too in [379]. Fine. But I don’t care about value. I am<br />

a consumer interested in use-values. If I have a commodity to exchange, my goal is to get<br />

those commodities which give me the highest possible use-value.<br />

Marx: even if you are only interested in use-value, the contradiction described in chapter<br />

Two still applies. This contradiction makes direct barter impossible, because direct barter<br />

tries to achieve two conflicting goals in one transaction. Chapter Two also explains how this<br />

contradiction leads to the development <strong>of</strong> money. <strong>The</strong> implications <strong>of</strong> this for your situation<br />

will then be described in section 2 <strong>of</strong> chapter Three: instead <strong>of</strong> making one or a series <strong>of</strong><br />

direct barters, you have to satisfy the conflicting goals sequentially. You <strong>first</strong> have to sell<br />

your commodity, which takes care <strong>of</strong> realizing the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity you bring to the<br />

market, and then you can use this money to buy that commodity bundle which gives you<br />

highest utility. <strong>The</strong> error in the formulation <strong>of</strong> <strong>Question</strong> 371 is that it collapses these two<br />

separate acts into one. This is impossible.<br />

Let me give you a different example <strong>of</strong> two separate acts which cannot be collapsed into<br />

one. In order to make bread, you have to proceed in two stages as well. First you mix the<br />

ingredients to make dough—you may even have to knead the dough and/or let it sit for a<br />

while. This is the <strong>first</strong> stage. <strong>The</strong>n you have to bake the dough. This is the second stage.<br />

You cannot make bread without going through these two stages. In the same way you cannot<br />

make an exchange without going through two stages: <strong>first</strong> realize in money the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity you bring to the market, and then spend this money to buy the use-values you<br />

desire. Direct barter is only feasible in very primitive situations, not in a modern economy<br />

with millions <strong>of</strong> use-values to choose from.<br />

Mainstream economics tells you how to do this second stage: if the money received from<br />

selling your commodity is M, you have to maximize your utility function subject to the<br />

budget constraint that the total price <strong>of</strong> the commodity bundle you are buying must be less<br />

than or equal to M. Mainstream economics only talks about use-value, not value. But they<br />

are making the assumption that money exists and every commodity has a price. In this way<br />

they smuggle in the value concept through the back door. <strong>The</strong>y won’t let value in through<br />

the front door because they don’t want the workers to know that their labor is the only source<br />

<strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Message [383] referenced by [Answer:8]. Next Message by Hans is [408].<br />

[830] Kaimani: On <strong>The</strong> Fly Commodities... Yes sellers are trying to get as much use<br />

value out <strong>of</strong> their commodities because they know that if they can fill the needs <strong>of</strong> others then<br />

they can create a excess and by doing so obtain commodities that have use-value that they are<br />

212 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

in search <strong>of</strong>. Marx says that the commodity doesn’t have immediate use value to the owner<br />

that is why the owner is selling the commodity or exchanging it in order to find a commodity<br />

that produces use-value for the owner. Marx explains that the owner uses his commodity as<br />

a carrier <strong>of</strong> exchange which turns into a form <strong>of</strong> exchange. For example a shirt produced by<br />

a tailor doesn’t serve the immediate needs <strong>of</strong> the tailor and thereby is sold/exchanged on the<br />

market so that by doing this the tailor can in the future find commodities that have use-value<br />

to him.<br />

Message [830] referenced by [831]. Next Message by Kaimani is [832].<br />

[831] Hans: First you have to sell your commodity. Every sentence in Kaimani [830]<br />

speaks about use-value only, except the one sentence<br />

Marx explains that the owner uses his commodity as a carrier <strong>of</strong> exchange<br />

which turns into a form <strong>of</strong> exchange.<br />

This is an important sentence. Before the owner can get the use-values he desires he must<br />

use his own commodity as a carrier <strong>of</strong> exchange-value and turn it into a form in which this<br />

exchange-value can do its <strong>thing</strong>. This form is the money form. I.e., the owner must sell his<br />

commodity. <strong>The</strong> price at which he can sell it is, according to Marx, not a reflection <strong>of</strong> the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity but <strong>of</strong> the exchange-value.<br />

Marx would say the characterization in question 371 is not a good characterization because<br />

this <strong>first</strong> act, in which the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is in the foreground, not<br />

the use-value, is left out.<br />

Message [831] referenced by [920]. Next Message by Hans is [833].<br />

[857] Wolf: Yes, however I feel that this statement is too vulgar. This may be how the<br />

commodity owner views the market or how she interacts with the surface expressions, but<br />

it doesn’t characterize very important aspects <strong>of</strong> the exchange process. For one, as I read<br />

[2008fa:616], I realized that this question left out the two-fold nature <strong>of</strong> commodity production<br />

and exchange entirely. Also, certain factors such as whether or not the commodity<br />

owner produces a socially-recognized value, if the magnitude <strong>of</strong> her commodity correctly<br />

reflects the socially-average labor time, the totality <strong>of</strong> exchanges eventually creating a general<br />

equivalent, etc. are very important characterizations <strong>of</strong> the exchange process which are<br />

left unsaid by the statement, “the commodity owner throws his commodity on the market<br />

and tries to get as much use-value as he can for it”.<br />

Next Message by Wolf is [1062].<br />

[865] PLG: graded A This is not a good characterization <strong>of</strong> the exchange process. <strong>The</strong><br />

scenario posed in the question collapses two characteristics <strong>of</strong> the exchange process into one.<br />

In my in-class submission I did not clearly make the distinction between the two dimensions<br />

<strong>of</strong> market exchange. I have explained it better in the following paragraphs.<br />

A commodity carries only exchange value on the market. Generally the value is realized<br />

by the amount <strong>of</strong> money the commodity can be exchanged for. Once this <strong>first</strong> exchange<br />

takes place the owner can then try to make an exchange for a use value. <strong>The</strong>se steps cannot<br />

be skipped. Even in direct exchange it is the congealed labor that is being traded, not the use<br />

values.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 213<br />

Marx describes this two-dimensional exchange as having a social dimension and a private<br />

dimension. <strong>The</strong> private dimension is the commodity owner’s desire for a use-value. <strong>The</strong><br />

commodity owner is driven by this desire to make an exchange. <strong>The</strong> social dimension is the<br />

realization <strong>of</strong> the commodity’s value on the market. <strong>The</strong> value is determined by the abstract<br />

labor within the commodity. <strong>The</strong> commodity is driven to be exchanged for some<strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

equal value. <strong>The</strong> commodity and the commodity owner are in conflict with their respective<br />

goals on the market.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore the exchange process is tw<strong>of</strong>old. <strong>The</strong> question does not make this distinction.<br />

If the commodity owner simply throws a commodity onto the market and sees what he can<br />

get for it, a step is removed from the exchange process. This is not how the exchange process<br />

works.<br />

Next Message by PLG is [866].<br />

[875] Oreo: graded A No, it is not a good characterization <strong>of</strong> the exchange process to<br />

say that the commodity owner throws his commodity on the market and tries to get as much<br />

use-value as he can from it. Since the commodity owner has thrown his comodity on the<br />

market, he is not receiving that commodity’s use-value. <strong>The</strong> use-value will be obtained by<br />

the purchaser <strong>of</strong> the commodity. <strong>The</strong> phrase “get as much use-value as he can” is misleading.<br />

As stated by Hans in [2008fa:616], the purchaser has two contradictory goals: 1) Realizing<br />

the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity that he has thrown on the market, and 2) Selecting the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> his or her choice. <strong>The</strong> seller <strong>of</strong> the product wants to get as much exchange-value<br />

from the product at possible, in order to purchase other commodities from which he recieves<br />

greater or equal use-value from than he did from the commodity that he threw on the market.<br />

Next Message by Oreo is [876].<br />

[912] JJ: No, this is not a good characterization <strong>of</strong> the exchange process. This type<br />

<strong>of</strong> characterization makes the mistake <strong>of</strong> trying to lump together the two distinct parts <strong>of</strong><br />

the exchange process. Namely the sale and the purchase are the two separate acts that the<br />

question mistakenly characterizes as one single act.<br />

Rather than seeking use values directly, the owner must <strong>first</strong> seek to realize the value <strong>of</strong><br />

his commodities. He realizes this value through the sale <strong>of</strong> his good for a sum <strong>of</strong> money<br />

(exchange value). This is the <strong>first</strong> and distinct part <strong>of</strong> the exchange process that the question<br />

fails to highlight. It is only after the sale <strong>of</strong> his commodity and after he receives the money<br />

from this sale that he can then put this money to use and attempt to acquire the many usevalues<br />

that he is seeking. This is the second part <strong>of</strong> this exchange process, the purchase. <strong>The</strong><br />

question implies that the sale and purchase are one transaction and all happen at once as if<br />

all exchange processes were direct barter situations.<br />

This is impossible. It is important to recognize the unique parts <strong>of</strong> the whole exchange<br />

process to satisfy the contradiction <strong>of</strong> use-values and exchange-values, and to develop and<br />

further the discussion on capitalism. <strong>The</strong>refore, the characterization <strong>of</strong>fered in question 371<br />

is a poor one. It focuses on the use-values too much, and fails to highlight the different parts<br />

<strong>of</strong> the exchange process.<br />

Next Message by JJ is [913].<br />

[920] Kaimani: <strong>The</strong> commodity owner throws his commodity on the market to try and<br />

receive as much use-value as he can because he knows by this he can attract more customers,<br />

214 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

who in turn will buy more products from him. But in order to do this Hans explains in [831]<br />

“the price at which he can sell it is, according to Marx, not a reflection <strong>of</strong> use-value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity but <strong>of</strong> the exchange-value.”<br />

Hans goes on to say that Marx would “disagree because this <strong>first</strong> act, in which the exchange<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is in the foreground and not the use-value, is left out.”<br />

Hans: Your <strong>first</strong> sentence is your in-class answer. Attracting more customers so that they will buy more products<br />

from you is a different motivation than “trying to receive as much use-value as one can,” it should rather be called<br />

“trying to receive as much sales as one can.” It is the motivation <strong>of</strong> a capitalist doing M-C-M to get his M back with<br />

as much surplus-value as possible. This question here is in the context <strong>of</strong> chapter Three, i.e., we are talking about<br />

C-M-C.<br />

In your second quote from [831] the words “this <strong>first</strong> act, in which” were left out, which left the sentence<br />

malformed. I inserted them for the archive copy, but this hurt your grade.<br />

First Message by Kaimani is [575].<br />

[957] Husani: I think it is a bad characterization in the sense <strong>of</strong> throwing it on the market,<br />

but the aspect <strong>of</strong> getting the most use-value out <strong>of</strong> his commodity is accurate. <strong>The</strong> commodity<br />

wants to be exchanged for some<strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong> equal value to itself while the owner wants to<br />

get the most use-value he can. Marx says “his commodity possesses no immediate use-value<br />

. . . It has use-values for others . . . He wants to relinquish it, in exchange for commodities<br />

whose use-values are <strong>of</strong> service to him.” I think the owner puts more thought into the exchange<br />

than just throwing it at the market and he tries to get the most use-value he can out<br />

<strong>of</strong> his commodity. He will use his prior knowledge <strong>of</strong> his exchanges to try and get the most<br />

use-value he can in exchange for his commodity.<br />

Hans: You cannot throw some<strong>thing</strong> on the market to get use-value — whether or not it is a thoughtful throwing<br />

on the market. If you want to get exactly the use-value you want, you have to try to negotiate with the few sellers<br />

who have exactly this use-value, and if you don’t have money but a commodity you would have to convince them<br />

to accept your commodity. <strong>The</strong> above story is a bad characterization because it thinks the <strong>first</strong> act, the sale <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity, is about use-value. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> act is about value.<br />

Next Message by Husani is [958].<br />

[959] Frida: graded A Flattening the contradition. No. As was stated in the class<br />

discussion this oversimplifies the situation and blurs the two stages <strong>of</strong> the exchange process.<br />

First the commodity owner must realize the value <strong>of</strong> her commodity, try to get as much<br />

money (or value, in a direct barter) as she can for it. She then must find a use value to suit<br />

her needs for her price. <strong>The</strong>se two goals contradict each other, the oversimplification does<br />

not address this issue.<br />

Next Message by Frida is [960].<br />

[978] Kobe: In my in class submission I wrote that it is true that commodity owners<br />

put their commodities onto the market to get as much use value as they can, this is untrue<br />

characterization according to Marx. He would say that the characterization described in the<br />

question is not an accurate characterization because the exchange value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is<br />

in the foreground not the use value. <strong>The</strong> owner uses his commodity as a carrier <strong>of</strong> exchange<br />

which in turn turns into a form <strong>of</strong> exchange. This being said, before an owner can get the<br />

use value he desires he must use his own commodity as a carrier <strong>of</strong> exchange value to be<br />

exchanged for a commodity that gives the owner his desired use value. In this example<br />

the commodity has a will <strong>of</strong> its own, at the instinctive level, wants to realize its value. As<br />

the owner puts his commodity onto the market he is seeking to realize the value <strong>of</strong> his


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 215<br />

commodity in the social dimension, while also wanting to realize the highest use value <strong>of</strong><br />

the new commodity in which he gets during the exchange.<br />

Next Message by Kobe is [979].<br />

[993] GoUtes: I do not think that this example accurately captures the essence <strong>of</strong> the<br />

exchange process. It is true that the owner <strong>of</strong> the commodity wants to maximize their pr<strong>of</strong>it,<br />

but, at owner <strong>of</strong> the commodity would want to study the market and see when selling would<br />

bring the greatest pr<strong>of</strong>it. <strong>The</strong> commodity owner would wait and study out the market and<br />

patterns and then strategically place their produce when pr<strong>of</strong>it potential is at its highest.<br />

Hans: Use-value is not the same as pr<strong>of</strong>it, and according to Marx’s theory pr<strong>of</strong>its are not made on the market but<br />

in production.<br />

Next Message by GoUtes is [994].<br />

[1080] Trap: Marx would say this is an incorrect representation <strong>of</strong> the exchange process, it<br />

is not that simple or 1-dimensional, in fact it is a 2-dimensional process. When a commodity<br />

owner goes to the market to sell his product he wants two <strong>thing</strong>s from the exchange. Firstly,<br />

he would like to exchange his commodity for another one with equal or more value than his<br />

own, and secondly as stated in the question he would like to select a commodity with the<br />

most appropriate use-value. <strong>The</strong> exchange will not be the greatest benefit <strong>of</strong> the producer if<br />

he fails to exchange his commodity for another with greater or equal use value, therefore he<br />

is not simply trying to get the most use value in the marketplace.<br />

Next Message by Trap is [1081].<br />

Multiple Choice <strong>Question</strong> 377 is 349 in 2009fa:<br />

Multiple Choice <strong>Question</strong> 377 All except one <strong>of</strong> the following inversions come from Marx,<br />

and one from Trotsky. Which one comes from Trotsky? (<strong>The</strong> Trotsky quote is some<strong>thing</strong> Marx<br />

would agree with, but Marx would never have formulated it in this way.)<br />

(a) “All commodities are non-use-values for their owners, and use-values for their nonowners.”<br />

179:1.<br />

(b) <strong>The</strong> commodity forms “have it written on their foreheads that they belong to a social<br />

formation in which the production process has the mastery over men, and man does not yet<br />

master the production process.” 173:1/oo.<br />

(c) “<strong>The</strong> difficulty lies not in comprehending that money is a commodity, but in discovering<br />

how, why and through what a commodity is money.” 186:1.<br />

(d) “You may not be interested in the dialectic, but the dialectic is interested in you.” (Trotsky)<br />

(e) “<strong>The</strong> ideas <strong>of</strong> the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas.” (German Ideology)<br />

(f) “<strong>The</strong> laws <strong>of</strong> the commodity nature come to fruition in the natural instinct <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

owners.” 180:3–181:1.<br />

(g) While capitalism uses co-operative labor processes to increase pr<strong>of</strong>its, history uses capitalism<br />

to introduce co-operative labor processes. 453:2/o.<br />

(h) Earlier we investigated how surplus-value arises from capital; now we have to see how<br />

capital arises from surplus-value. 725:1.<br />

[329] Hans: Marx loves inversions. To follow up on [326], here is a collection <strong>of</strong><br />

inversions. <strong>The</strong> one from Trotsky is (d). (If you read this in the archives, I added the<br />

references right into the question. If you get this multiple choice question on the exam, these<br />

216 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

references will <strong>of</strong> course not be there.) You can simply tell the Trotsky quote by its style.<br />

Marx 103:2 says it in much more bombastic ways: Capitalist crisis will “drum dialectics<br />

even into the heads <strong>of</strong>” (then Marx gives a biting characterization <strong>of</strong> the fools in charge <strong>of</strong><br />

the newly emerging German empire during his time).<br />

You may wonder why (f) is in there. It is not an inversion but a play on the word “nature.”<br />

I am not sure myself if it belongs or not.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [334].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 381 is 180 in 1995WI, 191 in 1996sp, 204 in 1997WI, 211 in 1997sp, 203<br />

in 1997ut, 221 in 1999SP, 231 in 2000fa, 279 in 2003fa, 313 in 2004fa, 328 in 2007SP,<br />

338 in 2008SP, 352 in 2009fa, 363 in 2011fa, 377 in 2012fa, and 191 in Answer:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 381 Which “deed” is Marx referring to in the following passage: “In their<br />

dilemma our commodity-owners think like Faust: ‘In the beginning was the deed.’ <strong>The</strong>y have<br />

therefore already acted before thinking.”<br />

[808] PLG: graded A In [2009fa:931] Hans says that the answer to this questions is a one<br />

liner:<br />

“<strong>The</strong> deed is the selection <strong>of</strong> a specific commodity as general equivalent.”<br />

This one-liner should suffice, but here is my more in depth interpretation <strong>of</strong> the answer.<br />

In reference to Goethe’s drama Faust, society creates a social relationship to commodities<br />

by “the deed”. Society, rather than individuals give commodities social form by giving them<br />

a general equivalent. Society acts before it thinks, whereas humans think, then act. <strong>The</strong>refore<br />

society is responsible for this deed that has given commodities a social form.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> “deed” is exactly the same <strong>thing</strong> as the “joint work” <strong>of</strong> all commodities in question 268. See [184],<br />

especially the last paragraph. <strong>The</strong> “deed” is not giving commodities a general equivalent. <strong>The</strong> social “deed” is<br />

only the selection <strong>of</strong> a commodity which the individual commodity producers will from now on use as general<br />

equivalent. This is an act in which all members <strong>of</strong> society have to act in unison. Imagine each member <strong>of</strong> society<br />

filling out a ballot which says:<br />

I want the general equivalent to be (check one): gold, silver, copper, beef, seashells, millstones.<br />

This vote would be the “deed.”<br />

Message [808] referenced by [848] and [2012fa:504]. Next Message by PLG is [865].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 391 is 185 in 1995WI, 163 in 1995ut, 197 in 1996sp, 199 in 1996ut, 218 in<br />

1997sp, 210 in 1997ut, and 229 in 1999SP:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 391 Why does a general equivalent become necessary as the number and differentiation<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities increases?<br />

[1043] Kleenex: A general equivalent becomes necessary because the Simple form <strong>of</strong><br />

value is insufficient in the exchange process <strong>of</strong> a wide variety <strong>of</strong> commodities. In the exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong> linen for a Bible, for example, the expression <strong>of</strong> the linen’s value in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

the Bible’s use-value, only one specific exchange relation is created. We don’t know how<br />

linen compares to copper, or milk, or any other commodity. We don’t know it’s “qualitative<br />

equality” nor do we know its “quantitative proportionality” with other commodities, as<br />

Marx writes in the text. If we’re supposing that the linen becomes the General equivalent,<br />

then this means that the linen now has an exchange relation with all sorts <strong>of</strong> commodities, in


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 217<br />

fact, every commodity that exists. Every commodity out there expresses its value in linen,<br />

the General equivalent <strong>of</strong> our argument. This means that it is directly exchangeable for any<strong>thing</strong><br />

else, and that it contains many many expressions <strong>of</strong> value, found in each social and<br />

exchange relation with all the different commodities. Having a General equivalent makes<br />

the exchange process smoother and steers us away from a pure bartering system.<br />

Next Message by Kleenex is [1044].<br />

[1061] KA: Society assists in the development <strong>of</strong> a variety <strong>of</strong> commodities, with each<br />

variety increasing in availability. As production <strong>of</strong> commodities increases along with the<br />

variety, so does the complexity to derive both the “commodity representing use-value and<br />

the money commodity representing the value.” Marx states that an external representation<br />

must exist that generates an independent form <strong>of</strong> value. Without this independent form<br />

<strong>of</strong> value, General Equivalent, the exchange process between all commodities will become<br />

inefficient. As society produces more commodities <strong>of</strong> different use-values, the complexity<br />

to trade will increase as well if a General Equivalent does not exist as a means <strong>of</strong> exchange.<br />

<strong>The</strong> establishment <strong>of</strong> a General Equivalent enables commodities <strong>of</strong> different use-values to<br />

be traded in the exchange place with little or no friction between parties. Society derives<br />

the General Equivalent, not the individual, therefore making the process <strong>of</strong> exchange more<br />

fluid.<br />

Next Message by KA is [1067].<br />

[1083] Kraken: graded A In a primitive society where the numbers <strong>of</strong> commodities are<br />

few, the probability <strong>of</strong> finding someone to engage in direct exchange with is relatively good.<br />

With a limited number <strong>of</strong> commodities, chances are fairly good that there will be several<br />

people who have the commodity that you want and at least a few <strong>of</strong> them will also want<br />

the commodity which you have to exchange. When the wants <strong>of</strong> people coincide in such a<br />

way that each person wants what the other person has at the same time, direct exchange is<br />

possible. As the number and differentiation <strong>of</strong> commodities increases, the variety <strong>of</strong> wants<br />

also increases. As the variety <strong>of</strong> wants increases, the probability <strong>of</strong> finding someone who<br />

has what you want and wants what you have at the same time decrease drastically and may<br />

even go to zero. An example might be: if you’re a potato farmer and you want a new wrist<br />

watch, you may never find someone who wants to directly exchange their wrist watch for<br />

your potatoes. However, you can exchange your potatoes with someone who doesn’t have<br />

a wrist watch but is willing to give you money/general equivalent. You can then exchange<br />

your money with someone who has a wrist watch who doesn’t need your potatoes.<br />

Next Message by Kraken is [1084].<br />

[1103] Lindsey: A general equivalent becomes necessary as the number and differentiation<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities increases because it is no longer easy for people to find someone who<br />

can trade with them and give them the commodity they want for the one they have and wish<br />

to get rid <strong>of</strong>. If someone wishes to sell a green ipod shuffle and wants to buy a certain kind<br />

<strong>of</strong> shoe, it would be hard to find someone who both wants to buy the ipod shuffle and has<br />

a pair <strong>of</strong> size 8, brown puma shoes that he wants to sell. Because <strong>of</strong> this problem, society<br />

chooses one specific commodity (sometimes more than one) to act as the general equivalent.<br />

This means that the commodity is accepted as money and can be exchanged for any other<br />

commodity in the correct quantity. <strong>The</strong> general equivalent makes exchange more convenient<br />

and useful because people do not have to make a 2-way trade, instead they can sell their<br />

218 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

good to one person in exchange for the general equivalent and then buy the good they want<br />

from another person using the general equivalent.<br />

Next Message by Lindsey is [1104].<br />

[1122] Fisher: General equivalent. <strong>The</strong> general equivalent is the 3rd commodity in a<br />

“polar relationship” with 2 other commodities. Eventually innovation is encouraged because<br />

<strong>of</strong> one being excluded. As more commodities are exchanged and become general equivalents<br />

which excludes them and forces them to innovate and become better so that they can enter<br />

the market as a valued commodity. <strong>The</strong> valued commodities become “money”, according to<br />

Marx and can then be compared to other commodities that have value and quality. General<br />

equivalents show that others are trying to enter the market and that future capitalists will<br />

flow into the market.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> General equivalent allows commodity owners the express the values <strong>of</strong> their commodities, not the usevalues.<br />

Innovation is not driven by the existence <strong>of</strong> a general equivalent, but by the need <strong>of</strong> the commodity producer<br />

to produce some<strong>thing</strong> for which there is a market.<br />

Next Message by Fisher is [1123].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 401 is 191 in 1995WI, 202 in 1996sp, 217 in 1997WI, 216 in 1997ut, 226<br />

in 1998WI, 236 in 1999SP, 280 in 2002fa, 294 in 2003fa, 331 in 2004fa, 346 in 2007SP,<br />

356 in 2008SP, 371 in 2009fa, 383 in 2011fa, and 397 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 401 Marx writes: “<strong>The</strong> exchange process gives the commodity which it<br />

has designated as money not its value, but its specific form <strong>of</strong> value.” Which form <strong>of</strong> value<br />

does Marx mean here? Why does Marx call this form the specific form <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the money<br />

commodity? (Assume we are under the gold standard.)<br />

[847] RexManning: graded A– Marx states that gold, silver and money are commodities,<br />

and like every commodity, must have a use value. Commodities are only able to express their<br />

value by some<strong>thing</strong> that has value itself. We could use gold, silver or money as the “<strong>thing</strong>”<br />

to which a commodity is being weighed (not literally). In this exchange <strong>of</strong> one commodity<br />

for another commodity (gold, silver, or money), one <strong>of</strong> the commodities in the exchange<br />

must be selected as the general equivalent. What will be accepted as the general equivalent<br />

will be either gold, silver or money, as they also have use value and can be used again on<br />

the market for exchange in a broader sense than the other commodity, as deemed by society.<br />

Being assigned a general equivalent, the commodity is given a specific form <strong>of</strong> value, which<br />

is associated with that commodity’s use value. This form <strong>of</strong> value is called the specific form<br />

<strong>of</strong> value, because it is only associated with the use value <strong>of</strong> that commodity (the general<br />

equivalent).<br />

Message [847] referenced by [848]. Next Message by RexManning is [998].<br />

[848] Hans: And who are YOU, Mr. Money? This question assumes the gold standard,<br />

i.e., gold is money, therefore the trio “gold, silver, and money” in RexManning [847] has<br />

shrunk to two, gold and silver. Let’s also assume, to simplify matters, that there is no<br />

bimetallism or similar, i.e., silver is just an ordinary commodity. We can send it home<br />

too, and are left with just one commodity, gold. This is the commodity which society has<br />

designated as money. If this is the case, then there is no need to select gold as general<br />

equivalent; if gold is money this means it is always and everywhere general equivalent.<br />

Indeed, this is part <strong>of</strong> the answer: general equivalent is the form <strong>of</strong> value which gold gets<br />

from the exchange process (while it gets its value from the process <strong>of</strong> mining gold).


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 219<br />

Now let’s look at this form <strong>of</strong> value in more detail. RexManning writes (I paraphrase):<br />

“Gold will be accepted as the general equivalent as it also has use value and can be used<br />

again on the market for exchange in a broader sense than the other commodities.” No, that<br />

is not the right explanation. Gold is accepted as general equivalent not because its use-value<br />

is so special.<br />

Let me tell you why gold is accepted as general equivalent. First <strong>of</strong> all, a general equivalent<br />

is necessary, commodity exchange cries out for a general equivalent, and various commodities<br />

take this form according to the circumstances. Until at some point society says:<br />

“Basta, we need only one general equivalent (that’s where the word ‘specific’ comes in),<br />

one commodity which is always and everywhere general equivalent, and that commodity is,<br />

drum roll, GOLD.” Applause, because we have just witnessed the famous Deed, see [808],<br />

<strong>of</strong> selecting one commodity to be always the general equivalent. This selection is not done<br />

in the production process, but this is the joint work <strong>of</strong> all the participants in the exchange<br />

process.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [858].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 403 is 169 in 1995ut, 238 in 1999SP, 348 in 2007SP, and 358 in 2008SP:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 403 How, why, and through what is a commodity already money, as Marx says in<br />

186:1?<br />

[370] KA: Commodity form <strong>of</strong> money. <strong>The</strong> formation <strong>of</strong> a commodity becoming money,<br />

or as Marx states “crystallized into the money-form,” is when all commodities establish<br />

their value in this particular commodity as money. While each commodity may express<br />

their exchange value in terms <strong>of</strong> this commodity, it is not considered money unless this<br />

commodity is considered as such. For example, I may express the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodity<br />

X in terms <strong>of</strong> commodity Z, and you express your commodity Y in terms <strong>of</strong> commodity Z<br />

as well, but unless there is a universal acceptance that commodity Z is a form <strong>of</strong> money and<br />

not just another commodity, it is will not be considered money.<br />

Gold and Silver took on the concept <strong>of</strong> money, because individuals valued goods in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> this commodity as money. <strong>The</strong>se commodities became money through a “social agreement”<br />

that all other commodities will express their values in it.<br />

Hans: You are describing the process how the money commodity becomes money, and you are saying correct<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s about the transition from the General form <strong>of</strong> money to the Money form. But this was not the question here,<br />

see [376].<br />

Message [370] referenced by [376]. Next Message by KA is [375].<br />

[376] Hans: Clarification. <strong>The</strong> Marx quote “How, why, and through what is a commodity<br />

already money?” does not refer to the process how a money commodity is selected and<br />

becomes money, as KA reads it in [370]. Instead, Marx claims that in some respects every<br />

ordinary commodity is already money. <strong>Question</strong> 403 wants you to explain “how, why, and<br />

through what” every ordinary commodity has money-like features.<br />

Message [376] referenced by [370]. Next Message by Hans is [383].<br />

[893] Robert: graded A A commodity is already money because it contains congealed<br />

abstract labor, which gives the commodity its value. <strong>The</strong> value is not given to it by money;<br />

money is passive and simply reflects the value that is already in the commodity. As Hans<br />

220 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

says in [518], it is not money that drives the economy; it is the value in the commodities<br />

themselves that are the engine.<br />

As I mentioned in my in class exam, this situation is similar to a human looking outside<br />

herself to find god (value); only to discover that in reality, god (value) is already within her.<br />

We may believe that congealed abstract labor is just a concept. In fact, it is a real attribute,<br />

which gives commodities value...just as it gives money value.<br />

<strong>The</strong> “why” a commodity is already money is because it has value because <strong>of</strong> the congealed<br />

abstract labor within it.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y “how” a commodity is already money is because others recognize that the commodity<br />

has value embedded in it.<br />

<strong>The</strong> “through what” a commodity is already money is the exchange process.<br />

<strong>The</strong> commodity contains congealed abstract labor (why), which others recognize as value<br />

(how) and they are willing to trade commodities that they believe contain equal value (through<br />

what) for that commodity. Thus a commodity has many <strong>of</strong> the same features <strong>of</strong> money, it<br />

contains value itself and it reflects the value <strong>of</strong> other commodities and it can be exchanged<br />

directly for other commodities. In these ways a commodity is already money.<br />

Next Message by Robert is [894].<br />

[898] Kat: A commodity is already money because it is able to be exchanged for money in<br />

the market. <strong>The</strong> ‘how’ a commodity is money lies in the fact that commodities are produced<br />

for sale or exchange. Money facilitates one form <strong>of</strong> exchange.<br />

<strong>The</strong> ‘why’ a commodity is already money is because money has been selected as the<br />

general equivalent. Money, then, is the social expression <strong>of</strong> value in an exchange.<br />

‘Through what’ a commodity is money is the relationship between exchange value and<br />

the power <strong>of</strong> money. Exchange value gives money its increased power the same way an<br />

actual exchange gives commodities exchange value.<br />

Hans: When Marx writes this, money does not yet exist. Marx is talking about the development <strong>of</strong> money out <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Kat is [899].<br />

[906] Intaglio: A commodity is already money because it can be exchanged on the market<br />

for other commodities. Commodities can only be exchanged because they have value, which<br />

comes from the congealed labor within them.<br />

Hans: This is not completely false but much more can be said about it. You already know Marxism, and by<br />

selecting the more philosophical questions and not going into the details <strong>of</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong> capitalist society as<br />

Marx lays is out in Capital you missed your chance <strong>of</strong> learning some<strong>thing</strong> new.<br />

Next Message by Intaglio is [907].<br />

[921] Lana: A commodity is money because <strong>of</strong> its value. To the seller, it has an exchange<br />

value (i.e. he knows what a buyer is willing to pay for it). To the buyer, the commodity has<br />

use-value (i.e. she knows what consumption void it will fill). Through this value relation,<br />

the commodity holds the power to motivate both buyer and seller into action. If looking at<br />

a direct barter, there is no money involved in the equivalents’ transaction. This is how the<br />

money commodity becomes money.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 221<br />

According to Fowkes, commodities do not become money, they simply are money. He<br />

states that “since a commodity does not need an (external) means to become money, but<br />

it has inner money traits.” Commodities are money because <strong>of</strong> what they represent; trade.<br />

In Hans’ Annotations, the process that this question refers to can be answered in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

the universal equivalent form and the natural form <strong>of</strong> a commodity become identified and<br />

then “crystallized into the money form.” Marx recognizes the relationship <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

being expressed as money via other commodities, but “it seems, on the contrary, that all<br />

other commodities universally express their values in a particular commodity because it is<br />

money.” <strong>The</strong> process disappears and the commodities find their own form <strong>of</strong> value “in the<br />

body <strong>of</strong> a commodity existing outside and alongside them,” taking on mysterious fetish-like<br />

characteristics.<br />

Next Message by Lana is [922].<br />

[927] Ryan: When Marx is talking about how a commodity is really already money,<br />

Marx is talking in regards to C-M-C. This Marx says in not the transition in which three<br />

commodities are traded but is the three commodities changing to a different form. Each one<br />

having a needed purpose through out the process. If you have an item that has no use value<br />

to you and you wish to complete the C-M to allow you to buy an item that does have use,<br />

you must change the form <strong>of</strong> your item to money. <strong>The</strong> reason why the commodity is already<br />

money is because the item has the value <strong>of</strong> money and the exchange just allows the form <strong>of</strong><br />

the item to change. Which is to say that you just replace the item for money and never truly<br />

change the value that you had in your hands to begin with. In the second part <strong>of</strong> the C-M-C<br />

the M-C must be occur to complete the final form change. In which money now changes to<br />

a commodity that has use value.<br />

In conclusion the three part exchange is talking an item that has no use value and changing<br />

it to an item that does have use value by using two form changes to complete. <strong>The</strong> reason<br />

how and why the commodity is already money is because each exchange is the just the<br />

realization <strong>of</strong> that money as it goes through out the C-M-C process.<br />

Hans: Marx’s aphorism was written in chapter 2, long before he discussed C-M-C. So he did not mean what you<br />

are saying. But what you are saying does make sense.<br />

Next Message by Ryan is [928].<br />

[982] JSmits: graded A In [2008SP:216] Hans has the example that people think that<br />

god is some<strong>thing</strong> that is outside them when in reality they are the gods. People think that<br />

if they have god in their lives that will make them a good person but god is an expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> the good already in them. It is the same way with a commodity in that a naïve observer<br />

would think that money is what gives value to the commodities but in reality money is the<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> value already inside <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

So how, why and through what a commodity is already money is because the trade relationships<br />

that develop from money are already found in the relationships <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Next Message by JSmits is [1119].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 412 is 234 in 1997sp, 226 in 1997ut, 236 in 1998WI, 291 in 2002fa, 305 in<br />

2003fa, 336 in 2005fa, 367 in 2008fa, 382 in 2009fa, 398 in 2011fa, and 413 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 412 Why this detour over gold, why not measure value directly by labor-time?<br />

222 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[502] Kraken: graded A– Gold not a detour—it’s a necessity. <strong>The</strong> practice <strong>of</strong> measuring<br />

value in “gold” is some<strong>thing</strong> most <strong>of</strong> us are very familiar with because we’ve grown<br />

up in a society that practices capitalism. We understand that when we go to the checkout<br />

counter to pay for our purchases, we will need to hand over money in order to get the items<br />

we want. <strong>The</strong> cashier will not accept a certificate stating we have worked “X” number <strong>of</strong><br />

hours in exchange for the products we want. Exchanging labor-time for commodities may<br />

work under some form <strong>of</strong> socialism, communism, etc. but it is incompatible with capitalism.<br />

Under capitalism, production <strong>of</strong> commodities is a private enterprise where value is measured<br />

in gold/money. It is not measured in socially necessary labor time.<br />

Hans: You are right, if you wanted to regulate the transfer <strong>of</strong> commodities between members <strong>of</strong> society strictly<br />

by labor content, you cannot maintain private decisionmaking regarding production and investment, but there must<br />

be some other arrangement so that the producers know what to produce—it could be socialism, communism, but it<br />

could also be a system as in World War II where government inspectors went into the private firms, looked around<br />

if there was unused capacity, and ordered the firms what to produce. In a capitalist system, the differences between<br />

value and prices are necessary signals to the producers to adjust their production. I tried to say the same <strong>thing</strong> in<br />

[511].<br />

Message [502] referenced by [518]. Next Message by Kraken is [541].<br />

[518] Hans: Inner measure and surface measure. Kraken [502] says “Under capitalism,<br />

value is measured in money. It is not measured in socially necessary labor time.” This is not<br />

an either/or. One might say, the inner measure <strong>of</strong> value is labor time, and the surface measure<br />

is money. Marx says this in 188:3:<br />

Money as a measure <strong>of</strong> value is the necessary form <strong>of</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immanent measure <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the commodities, namely labor-time.<br />

Message [518] referenced by [893] and [2012fa:1340]. Next Message by Hans is [521].<br />

[923] Long: We cannot measure the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity by labor time because it is not<br />

in a way a form <strong>of</strong> a payment. <strong>The</strong> labor time is measured and has to be measured as a wage<br />

or by using the gold standard. For instance, when I work 40 hours a week at XYZ company.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y don’t give me a voucher or certificate to go to the store and buy my needs. I cannot<br />

give the cashier a pieve <strong>of</strong> paper that says I worked for 3 hours and so therefore my labor<br />

time is worth say 5 gallons <strong>of</strong> milk. What would the store do with my 3 hours <strong>of</strong> labor time,<br />

it’s not a commodity to them. However, if I get paid in a form <strong>of</strong> a wage say like money or<br />

gold and then go to the store to buy 3 gallons <strong>of</strong> milk for a certain amount <strong>of</strong> money, then<br />

it is more feasible for the store. <strong>The</strong>y can use my money to purchase other goods that they<br />

need.<br />

Next Message by Long is [924].<br />

[930] Bigwhite: Because you need gold aka money to be able to put every commodity on<br />

the same scale, to be able to establish a worth for all commodities. Labor cannot be sufficiently<br />

measured and varies. Gold stays constant and is the easiest way to keep every<strong>thing</strong><br />

in line and is the easiest <strong>thing</strong> to use to help keep the markets flowing smoothly.<br />

Hans: This is not an explanation. Why is it easiest?<br />

Next Message by Bigwhite is [941].<br />

[981] Baseball: Earlier in Capital, Marx explains why we cannot use labor time as the<br />

universal measure <strong>of</strong> value. <strong>The</strong> reason he gives is because consumers cannot see how much<br />

labor time was used to produce a certain commodity. This would complicate the exchange<br />

process in markets because the values <strong>of</strong> products will vary tremendously and prices (if


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 223<br />

valued by labor time) would be high. It would be too difficult to represent a commodities<br />

value via labor time because, as stated before, consumers will not know the amount <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

time which was expended to produce such a commodity. Marx then restates that in his time<br />

gold represented money which was a simpler way to value a commodity. <strong>The</strong> abstract way<br />

to value a commodity is through the use values or its labor time. It is much easier to price a<br />

commodity by money (gold) because everyone uses this as a general equivalent for exchange<br />

in the market.<br />

Hans: Basic misunderstanding <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory. Prices would not be higher if valued according to labor-time.<br />

Marx says that in capitalism, the prices which you see are based on labor-time.<br />

Next Message by Baseball is [1066].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 414 is 235 in 1997sp, 237 in 1998WI, 247 in 1999SP, 270 in 2001fa, 307<br />

in 2003fa, 344 in 2004fa, 338 in 2005fa, 359 in 2007SP, 369 in 2008fa, 400 in 2011fa,<br />

and 415 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 414 What is the price <strong>of</strong> a commodity? Say how it is defined, and say as<br />

much as you can about it without going into Marx’s theory how its magnitude is determined.<br />

[815] Kat: Price is just one type <strong>of</strong> exchange-value. Exchange-value is the ability <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity to be exchanged for another commodity. So price represents the exchange <strong>of</strong><br />

a commodity for money. As we have discussed in the past, the price is the most definitive<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> value because it has been designated as the market equivalent. So the price<br />

represents not only what one commodity can be exchanged for money, but also its relation,<br />

through money, to all other commodities.<br />

Hans: Very good answer.<br />

Message [815] referenced by [2012fa:596]. Next Message by Kat is [821].<br />

[824] Somramthom: graded B <strong>The</strong> great equalizer. Imagine a mathematician, a doctor<br />

and a lawyer walk into a bar. <strong>The</strong>y spot a man passed out on the floor. <strong>The</strong>y ask the<br />

barkeep what happened to the man. “Guy drank so much he passed out,” replies the barkeep.<br />

<strong>The</strong> mathematician immediately asks how much the man drunk, measures his height and<br />

estimates his weight and says, “All I see here is a man who can’t hold his booze.” <strong>The</strong> doctor<br />

examines the man, and declares, “I see a man who is depressed, undervalued at his job and<br />

a potential liver transplant recipient.” <strong>The</strong> lawyer sees the man clutching his keys and says,<br />

“I see a pr<strong>of</strong>itable law-suit.” <strong>The</strong> barkeep quietly responds with, “I see a loyal customer and<br />

a way to pay <strong>of</strong>f my new TV.”<br />

This example may have several holes in it (and it may be boring to read) but the point<br />

<strong>of</strong> the story is each person saw different <strong>thing</strong>s in the same man. This is a problem in<br />

exchanging commodities. <strong>The</strong> use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is dependent upon the use-value <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity for which it will be exchanged for. This use-value will vary from consumer<br />

to consumer. What is needed is a standard; Money.<br />

Price is a specific type <strong>of</strong> exchange value, only it is an outward expression <strong>of</strong> a commodity’s<br />

value in terms <strong>of</strong> money (gold, tender, etc.) instead the use-value <strong>of</strong> another commodity.<br />

<strong>The</strong> power in this exchange allows for greater exchange options i.e. you are no longer limited<br />

to expressions <strong>of</strong> value for specific commodities but can exchange for any commodity<br />

since all commodities are now measured on the same standard.<br />

224 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Your fable shows how different use-values can be. A Marxist would say it it not possible to equalize these<br />

use-values by just slapping a price sign on them. <strong>The</strong>y are still as different as before. Price signs only make sense if<br />

the commodities are really in some way homogeneous. I.e., prices represent the labor content, not the use-values.<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [977].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 420 is 343 in 2005fa, 364 in 2007SP, 370 in 2007fa, and 390 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 420 Why do the commodity owners write the price on their price signs and not<br />

the labor-content <strong>of</strong> the commodity they are producing?<br />

[487] Scholar: Firstly, the commodity owners don’t know the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value,<br />

and they only do exchange according to the social custom; Secondy, commodity value is<br />

determined not by the individual labor time used to produce the commodity, but by the social<br />

estimate <strong>of</strong> labor time, called socially necessary labor time by Marx. Thirdly, money is not<br />

only a commodity, but also the general equivalent accepted by all commodity owners as the<br />

exchange intermediary, and they think the value <strong>of</strong> money can be used as the measurement<br />

<strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> all other kinds <strong>of</strong> commodities. So, as the monetary representation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity value, price is an objective sign that can reflect the social value <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Message [487] referenced by [501]. Next Message by Scholar is [581].<br />

[501] Hans: Status <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory in this question. I had to chuckle when reading<br />

Scholar’s answer in [487] “because they don’t know the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value.” This is a<br />

much more pleasant feeling than my exasperation last year when I had to read [2009fa:1078].<br />

If I wanted to be pedantic, I should formulate question 420 as follows:<br />

“If Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value is correct, then one might be tempted to<br />

think that commodity owners should write the labor content <strong>of</strong> their commodities<br />

on their price signs instead <strong>of</strong> a price. Why isn’t it socially customary<br />

to do this (please give an answer assuming the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value<br />

is indeed correct).”<br />

<strong>The</strong> above question text is an abbreviation <strong>of</strong> these two long sentences. And what Scholar<br />

writes under “secondly” and “thirdly” is a correct answer to this pedantic version <strong>of</strong> question<br />

420. But it is too abstract. Imagine what would happen if people did write the labor content<br />

on their price signs.<br />

Message [501] referenced by [511] and [565]. Next Message by Hans is [507].<br />

[1020] Alex: graded A– Commodity owners chose to not write the labor-content <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity in its price tag but chose to write the price instead for various reasons. <strong>The</strong><br />

main reason for this is pr<strong>of</strong>it. Capitalists will always receive pr<strong>of</strong>its even if they sold their<br />

commodities for the same price <strong>of</strong> the labor content, however, if they charged more than it<br />

cost them to produce the commodities, then their pr<strong>of</strong>it margins would be higher. Another<br />

reason for this choice is that the laborer would realize that he/she is being paid less than<br />

he/she should be paid, because his/her labor is worth more an hour than what the capitalists<br />

is <strong>of</strong>fering. Having said this, there would be an objection coming from the laborers where<br />

they would disagree with the discrepancy in their remuneration. Lastly, the labor content in<br />

some commodities might be different for different manufacturers. If one capitalist’s labor<br />

content for a commodity was much easier to manufacture than for another capitalist for the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 225<br />

same commodity, then he would have to charge the same price as the capitalist with the<br />

harder labor content because he then would be losing pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Hans: You are describing it as a choice; you are saying the sellers could do it but prefer not to for various reasons.<br />

Marx’s answer is different. He would say they don’t even have the option; the market system would not function if<br />

they did.<br />

Next Message by Alex is [1023].<br />

[1037] Guh: Pricing Wars. <strong>The</strong> reason why the owners <strong>of</strong> commodity write the price<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> the labor content is very simple. First <strong>of</strong>f Jimmie in [2005fa:1682] explained it<br />

very simply and said some<strong>thing</strong> along the lines that there really is no reason for the owner<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity to write the labor content down. After all the commodity owner is just<br />

selling the item in exchange for some<strong>thing</strong> else <strong>of</strong> equivalent, and the price is illustrating<br />

the terms <strong>of</strong> the exchange between the two individuals. This is one hundred percent true<br />

and I agree completely with his explanation. Moreover, it is also obvious that the individual<br />

purchasing the commodity is not worried about the labor content <strong>of</strong> the commodities being<br />

sold, rather the buyer wants to know the price <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Guh is [1088].<br />

[1078] Goldtone: graded A+ Commodity owners write the price on their price signs instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor-content, because in capitalism, money and price are understood better and<br />

are therefore more practical. Also, and more importantly, price allows commodities to fluctuate<br />

according to supply and demand. For example, if there is more demand, then prices<br />

can rise and more should be produced. This flexibility <strong>of</strong> price would not be possible if<br />

labor-content was used, and the producers would not be able to change price (labor-content<br />

here) according to supply and demand. <strong>The</strong> consequence <strong>of</strong> this could be overproduction<br />

and underproduction <strong>of</strong> certain commodities.<br />

Message [1078] referenced by [1145]. Next Message by Goldtone is [1079].<br />

[1127] RexManning: graded B– Commodity owners write the price on their price signs<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> the labor content <strong>of</strong> the commodity because price shows the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

in relation to money, and money in turn can express the value <strong>of</strong> not only that commodity,<br />

but its value compared to all other commodities. This value as presented by the price <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity is due to the social relations <strong>of</strong> a general equivalent, such as gold. In a capitalist<br />

society, the price shows the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity through the general equivalent, even<br />

though the purchasers <strong>of</strong> the commodity do not trade for actual gold. Gold does not even<br />

need to be present, but some<strong>thing</strong> that represents gold and has a society placed value that<br />

allows it to be exchanged for commodities, for example, money. <strong>The</strong> value comes from<br />

society, where it has an exchange relationship with gold. <strong>The</strong> price tags tell the potential<br />

purchasers what the commodity is worth, as deemed by society. Because <strong>of</strong> the societal<br />

placed value <strong>of</strong> money, price is expressed in money, and not labor content because money,<br />

in a capitalist society is “directly exchangeable” for all commodities.<br />

Hans: According to Marx’s theory, a commodity’s worth “as deemed by society” is its labor content. Assuming<br />

this is true, why use money prices instead <strong>of</strong> directly using labor content? Or is the use <strong>of</strong> money pro<strong>of</strong> that Marx’s<br />

theory is wrong?<br />

Next Message by RexManning is [1129].<br />

[1136] Cougar: graded B– In our economy, price is the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

the general equivalent: money. Money is the general equivalent because it can be exchanged<br />

for any other commodity. In addition to fulfilling the role <strong>of</strong> general measure <strong>of</strong> value,<br />

money is also a means <strong>of</strong> circulation, transferring wealth among producers and consumers.<br />

226 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Although labor-content is a common factor <strong>of</strong> all produced commodities, it is contingent<br />

upon the commodity or use-value it is being exchanged for. Because money fulfills both<br />

the role <strong>of</strong> value and role <strong>of</strong> circulation it becomes a universal means <strong>of</strong> trade in the economy,<br />

where all <strong>thing</strong>s can be exchanged for varying amounts <strong>of</strong> money. In this way money<br />

becomes the valuation <strong>of</strong> labor-content and all <strong>thing</strong>s can be measured and exchanged for<br />

money. Producers are, therefore, motivated to list the value <strong>of</strong> their products in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

money rather than hours <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Hans: A means <strong>of</strong> circulation does not transfer wealth. A commodity sold has the same value as the money for<br />

which it is sold.<br />

You seem to be saying (and this is clearer in your in-class answer) the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity in the market is<br />

its monetary value, not its labor content. This is not the same as Marx, who says that market values are indeed<br />

governed by labor content. Assuming Marx is right, would that not require that commodities be priced by labor<br />

content rather than money?<br />

Final Grading Note by Hans: You are an engaging personality, you interact well with others, here in the class<br />

discussion and also personally. It seems that the foundation from which you can be so outgoing is the certainly that<br />

the society we have is basically ok. Marx wants you to consider alternatives, but you try not to see these alternatives<br />

but to subsume what Marx says into the status quo. I hope this class has shaken this foundation a little bit. People<br />

<strong>of</strong> your social skills can make a big difference in building a better society.<br />

Next Message by Cougar is [1137].<br />

[1145] Cougar: graded A I finally see the light! Whether our society has consciously<br />

decided upon or not, money is accepted as the general equivalent. It is how we understand<br />

value and how we choose to acquire the <strong>thing</strong>s we need and the <strong>thing</strong>s we want. As children<br />

we grow up in the Capitalist society and, as products <strong>of</strong> such upbringing understand that<br />

money can be used to acquire any<strong>thing</strong> in the economy. Producers are inclined to value their<br />

products in terms we as a society can relate with. Goldtone [1078] makes a valid point that<br />

in addition to money literally being the general equivalent, it allows fluctuation in the market<br />

which may work in or against the capitalist’s favor. Increased demand calls for an increase<br />

in production and higher prices while falling demand may call for limited production and<br />

sales or clearances. Production can follow trends that dictate equilibrium rather than over or<br />

under-production. Labor content cannot fluctuate with trends like money can, but is bound<br />

to each commodity in consideration.<br />

Next Message by Cougar is [1149].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 430 is 417 in 2011fa and 435 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 430 Why is it not a defect but a sign that the price form is “admirably” adapted to<br />

commodity production, as the Moore-Aveling translation says, that prices can deviate from<br />

values due to demand and supply?<br />

[511] Hans: Impossibility <strong>of</strong> labor prices. In [501] I wrote: “Imagine what would happen<br />

if people did write the labor content on their price signs.” Please look at [1998WI:227]<br />

as a help to your imagination. <strong>The</strong> reason why people don’t write the labor content on<br />

their prices is that prices must necessarily differ from labor content, in order to motivate the<br />

producers to adjust their production to demand.<br />

Message [511] referenced by [502], [2012fa:1189], and [2012fa:1340]. Next Message by Hans is [514].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 431 is 322 in 2003fa, 360 in 2004fa, 353 in 2005fa, 375 in 2007SP, 386<br />

in 2008fa, 418 in 2011fa, and 436 in 2012fa:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 227<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 431 Which two aspects <strong>of</strong> the function <strong>of</strong> money as a measure <strong>of</strong> value <strong>first</strong><br />

look like flaws but on a closer look turn out to be necessary?<br />

[817] Husani: <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> flaw is that commodities are judged by money as their measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> value but prices can deviate from these values. This can happen if the demand for the<br />

commodity increases and the supply <strong>of</strong> it can’t match it, increasing the price.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second flaw is that gold will devalue over time with new technologies that make it<br />

easier and more efficient to mine it from the ground.<br />

Hans: Yes these are the two flaws. Would be nice to also explain why they are necessary, but in the exam the above<br />

answer gets full points.<br />

Message [817] referenced by [2012fa:1108]. Next Message by Husani is [818].<br />

Multiple Choice <strong>Question</strong> 438 Which argument does Marx apply at the end <strong>of</strong> chapter<br />

Three, section One, to make the transition from measure <strong>of</strong> value to means <strong>of</strong> circulation.<br />

Check one point:<br />

• (a) <strong>The</strong> price sign indicates that the commodity can be bought with a certain amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> money. I.e., it gives the money owner the right to receive the commodity if the<br />

stipulated price is paid. But the price does not give the commodity owner the right<br />

to receive the amount <strong>of</strong> money listed on the price sign. In order to take advantage<br />

<strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity, the commodity owner must therefore <strong>first</strong> sell the<br />

commodity for money.<br />

• (b) <strong>The</strong> price form gives the commodity an imagined parallel existence: now it<br />

exists not only as material commodity but also as the imagined amount <strong>of</strong> money<br />

listed on the price sign. This imagined parallel existence cannot be actualized without<br />

giving up the commodity’s material existence. <strong>The</strong>refore Marx looks now how<br />

the commodity can be turned into actual money. I.e., Marx goes from a imagined<br />

simultaneous double existence to an actual temporal succession.<br />

• (c) If it is possible to exchange the commodity for money then it also becomes<br />

necessary, because after money has become available as general equivalent, other<br />

commodities will no longer be accepted as equivalents. In the next step <strong>of</strong> his analysis,<br />

Marx looks therefore how this possibility and necessity becomes a reality.<br />

• (d) Gold can only become measure <strong>of</strong> value because gold is exchanged on the market<br />

for other commodities.<br />

• (e) All <strong>of</strong> the above.<br />

[859] Hans: Read them carefully: they all come from Marx. <strong>The</strong> correct answer is (e).<br />

This refers to a passage in Marx which people usually don’t read very carefully. A faithful<br />

reader <strong>of</strong> Capital is probably familiar with the aphorism in 198:1: “In the notional measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> values lurks therefore hard cash,” but if you press them about it what Marx meant by this<br />

few will be able to give a good answer. This aphorism was Marx’s summary <strong>of</strong> the points<br />

(a) through (d) he made at the end <strong>of</strong> section 1 <strong>of</strong> chapter Three. Purpose <strong>of</strong> the question is<br />

really only to get you to read these points carefully, because Marx makes all <strong>of</strong> them (i.e.,<br />

here I did not try to trick you).<br />

Next Message by Hans is [871].<br />

228 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 439 is 367 in 2004fa, 394 in 2008fa, and 426 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 439 Describe the relationship between the function <strong>of</strong> money as measure <strong>of</strong> value<br />

and as means <strong>of</strong> circulation in Marx’s theory and in modern mainstream monetary theories.<br />

[481] IrvingHowe: Marxist and contemporary monetary theory. Today, we are four<br />

decades into a totally free floating currency. That is to say that we no longer have a commodity<br />

backing our money in the United States. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> dollars today is a function <strong>of</strong><br />

demand and market confidence in the Treasury, f(D,C).<br />

First, because treasury notes are a debt issued by the United States Treasury, a potential<br />

consumer must <strong>first</strong> have confidence that the government can make good on that debt. After<br />

meeting that threshold, the value <strong>of</strong> money is set entirely by the sum <strong>of</strong> demand for dollars<br />

relative to the supply.<br />

<strong>The</strong> above could be described as a contemporary (and pretty mainstream) theory <strong>of</strong> the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Marx on the other hand believed that money is “a measure <strong>of</strong> the <strong>of</strong> value is the necessary<br />

form <strong>of</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> the measure <strong>of</strong> value which is immanent in commodities, namely,<br />

labor-time.”<br />

Marx goes on to say that the value <strong>of</strong> commodities is inherent in them already and money<br />

is essentially an expression <strong>of</strong> equality <strong>of</strong> one commodity to the other ie: corn, iron, wheat...<br />

to gold (coins).<br />

Message [481] referenced by [514] and [2011fa:503]. Next Message by IrvingHowe is [482].<br />

[514] Hans: Relation to Marx’s <strong>The</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> Money. IrvingHowe [481] brings a modern<br />

formula for the value <strong>of</strong> money<br />

f(D,C)<br />

where D is demand and C is market confidence in the Treasury. Money demand is the<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> cash the public wants to hold, for transactions and as precautionary reserves.<br />

This refers to Marx’s role <strong>of</strong> money as means <strong>of</strong> circulation in section 2 <strong>of</strong> chapter Three,<br />

and maybe also money as “hoard” in section 3.<br />

Sovereign states cannot go bankrupt, they will simply print more money. <strong>The</strong>refore C is<br />

not the confidence in government paying back the debt at all, but confidence in government<br />

paying back the debt in a currency that is not devalued. In Marx this is section 1, money as<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [518].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 442 is 448 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 442 If physics yields such good examples for dialectics, why are modern physicists<br />

not using dialectics?<br />

[559] Ferox: graded A <strong>The</strong> Scientific Dialectic. Modern physics deals with phenomena<br />

that classical Newtonian physics cannot explain. <strong>The</strong> example given by Marx is an example<br />

<strong>of</strong> classical mechanics—inertia versus gravity in celestial bodies. Modern physics is<br />

concerned with conditions well beyond the experience <strong>of</strong> humans, such as the interactions


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 229<br />

between sub atomic particles (quantum phenomena) or the formation <strong>of</strong> the universe (relativistic<br />

phenomena). Since Marxist materialist dialectics are concerned with the real world<br />

interactions on the human scale—the tangible human experience and not the idealized (such<br />

as Hegel)—there is little incentive for modern physicists to adopt this method <strong>of</strong> inquiry.<br />

This is not to say that dialectics are not used in science. Peer reviewed science uses<br />

the dialectic (and <strong>of</strong>ten the debate) process <strong>of</strong> argument in determining empirical truths.<br />

When two opposing observations regarding a phenomena are observed, all hypotheses are<br />

considered valid truths. Hypotheses are tested, data is gathered and analyzed, the results are<br />

published for a dialogue within the scientific community. <strong>The</strong> process <strong>of</strong> peer review tests<br />

empirically derived, <strong>of</strong>ten contradictory results, in order to tease out the underlying truth.<br />

<strong>The</strong> resulting synthesis gives humans a greater understanding <strong>of</strong> the interactions around<br />

them.<br />

Hans: You are only looking at the dialectic as a method <strong>of</strong> inquiry. Marx thinks that not only our thinking about<br />

the world but the world itself is dialectical.<br />

On the other hand, I agree with you that modern science flees into the extreme small or large scales and overlooks<br />

the richness <strong>of</strong> possible interactions on the intermediate scale. <strong>The</strong>se intermediate phenomena are dialectical,<br />

but modern science, because <strong>of</strong> its blindness toward dialectids, does not prepare us for this. This is a form <strong>of</strong> reductionism.<br />

Similar thought are expressed in the book Growth and Development: Ecosystems Phenomenology by<br />

Robert E Ulanowicz, Springer 1986. Look on p. 1 <strong>of</strong> that book.<br />

Message [559] referenced by [2012fa:829]. Next Message by Ferox is [646].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 443 is 363 in 2005fa, 385 in 2007SP, 397 in 2008fa, 412 in 2009fa, 431 in<br />

2011fa, 449 in 2012fa, and 363 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 443 What does Marx mean when he says in 198:3/o: one must look at the circulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities from its form side?<br />

[522] Somramthom: graded A– Commodities and molecules. <strong>The</strong> form side <strong>of</strong> circulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities is a way <strong>of</strong> viewing the exchange process. One forgets the material<br />

transfer <strong>of</strong> the physical commodity and instead focuses on the form <strong>of</strong> the commodity originally<br />

produced as it changes from a form <strong>of</strong> value, to a form <strong>of</strong> use-value the producer<br />

doesn’t want or need, to another form <strong>of</strong> value, to yet another form <strong>of</strong> use-value the producer<br />

does want or need, etc.<br />

Thinking about this question made me think <strong>of</strong> physical phase changes <strong>of</strong> matter. When<br />

water is boiled, the molecular composition does not change. It is H2O throughout the phase<br />

change. <strong>The</strong> change that takes place is a change in the matter’s form; from liquid to gas. the<br />

form side <strong>of</strong> circulation views the exchange process similarly. <strong>The</strong> commodity itself doesn’t<br />

change, rather the form the commodity takes changes, as described above.<br />

Message [522] referenced by [524], [528], [529], and [540]. Next Message by Somramthom is [523].<br />

[523] Somramthom: Shelf-life <strong>of</strong> commodities and the form side. When viewing the<br />

exchange process in the form side, does a commodity’s value or use-value ever dissipate<br />

entirely? It would seem that it would diminish with each exchange and form change. But<br />

since the material exchange is not considered, one could argue that the value or use-value is<br />

renewed with each exchange cycle, being detached from the physicality <strong>of</strong> decay.<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [759].<br />

230 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[524] Alex: graded A– Form side analysis recapitulation. In order to understand what<br />

Marx meant with the “circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities from the form side,” we must understand<br />

that this concept explains the social relations <strong>of</strong> the economy, which keeps this social metabolism<br />

in gear. Social metabolism is the term that Marx uses to describe the goods migrating<br />

from producers to consumers, where they are taken out <strong>of</strong> circulation and consumed, as Hans<br />

explained in [2005fa:996]. To look at transactions involving the circulation <strong>of</strong> money from<br />

the form side, it is a matter <strong>of</strong> going further than the social metabolism or simple exchange,<br />

and looking from the producer’s approach in a sense that is deeper than a simple exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity for money. As seen from the form side, when the producer sells his or her<br />

commodity for money, he/she still has that same commodity but with a different form. Hans<br />

states that the commodities go from being in their use-value form (in which the consumer<br />

does not wish to consume) to being in their value form which the seller does want. <strong>The</strong><br />

money commodity goes through a transformation that Marx calls a form change in 198:3/o.<br />

<strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is preserved, though the exchange <strong>of</strong> the commodity is physical.<br />

A good analysis <strong>of</strong> this is from DarkKnight [2005fa:1397] when he says the value <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity remains with the producer throughout the exchanges that takes place, it only<br />

changes its form. I also liked Somramthom’s water molecule analogy in [522], which seems<br />

very relevant to this case.<br />

Message [524] referenced by [529] and [540]. Next Message by Alex is [600].<br />

[528] Hans: Butterfly Commodities. Somramthom [522] describes the metamorphosis<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity as follows:<br />

it changes from a form <strong>of</strong> value, to a form <strong>of</strong> use-value the producer doesn’t<br />

want or need, to another form <strong>of</strong> value, to yet another form <strong>of</strong> use-value the<br />

producer does want or need, etc.<br />

This chain is too long on both ends:<br />

(a) <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> form is not a value form but a use-value form. Remember question 166,<br />

which emphasized that the commodity does not come into this world in the form <strong>of</strong> value?<br />

My answer [316] may be useful here.<br />

(b) <strong>The</strong>re is no etc. at the end. Once the commodity is in the form <strong>of</strong> a use-value which<br />

the producer needs, then Marx says in 198:3/o that it “falls out <strong>of</strong> the sphere <strong>of</strong> exchange.”<br />

I.e., now the producer consumes it, and at this stage <strong>of</strong> its life the commodity is a simple usevalue<br />

and no<strong>thing</strong> else. (Although some commodities re-emerge later again as commodities<br />

in a garage sale or in the market for used cars or houses.)<br />

<strong>The</strong> metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> the commodity therefore consists <strong>of</strong> exactly 3 phases:<br />

(1) form <strong>of</strong> use-value the producer doesn’t want or need<br />

(2) form <strong>of</strong> value, namely, money<br />

(3) again a form <strong>of</strong> use-value, but this time a use-value the producer does want or need.<br />

Marx himself does not compare it with the phase transitions <strong>of</strong> a water but with the three<br />

stages <strong>of</strong> the metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> a butterfly:<br />

(1) caterpillar


(2) chrysalis<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 231<br />

(3) (adult) butterfly<br />

Message [528] referenced by [540] and [2012fa:831]. Next Message by Hans is [529].<br />

[529] Hans: For someone who is not a capitalist, money is only a transitional phase.<br />

While Somramthom [522] made the metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> the commodity too long, Alex [524]<br />

made it too short. Alex distinguishes only two forms:<br />

(1) use-value form (<strong>of</strong> a use-value which the consumer does not wish to consume)<br />

(2) their value form which the seller does want (namely the money received from the sale<br />

<strong>of</strong> the original use-value).<br />

Alex emphasizes correctly that the money which the seller gets for his commodity should<br />

be considered just another form <strong>of</strong> the original commodity. For a capitalist, this money form<br />

is the backflow <strong>of</strong> his capital with pr<strong>of</strong>it, therefore it is indeed what the seller does want.<br />

For ordinary wage laborers, who cannot sell any<strong>thing</strong> they have produced but must sell their<br />

labor-power, the wage money they receive is only an intermediate phase: most if not all <strong>of</strong><br />

this money will be spent for use-values they need. Marx would say that this act <strong>of</strong> spending<br />

the money is again merely a form change <strong>of</strong> still the original commodity which was sold (for<br />

most <strong>of</strong> us: our labor-power). <strong>The</strong>refore<br />

(1) We <strong>first</strong> sell our labor-power and show up for work. <strong>The</strong> reason for us selling it is not<br />

exactly that we do not wish to consume the use-value <strong>of</strong> our labor-power ourselves. I bet<br />

most <strong>of</strong> us would love to work under our own command or in a worker-management situation<br />

together with their co-workers. But we do not have access to the means or production. <strong>The</strong><br />

means <strong>of</strong> production which we need in order to benefit from our labor-power are the private<br />

property <strong>of</strong> the capitalists. That is why we have to sell our labor-power to the capitalists.<br />

(2) <strong>The</strong> wage or salary we receive is the “value form” <strong>of</strong> the commodity labor-power we<br />

have sold.<br />

(3) <strong>The</strong> groceries etc we buy for this money is then the third form <strong>of</strong> our labor-power, it is<br />

the use-value which we desire, instead <strong>of</strong> the original use-value <strong>of</strong> our labor-power (which<br />

we had to sell because we are barred from taking advantage <strong>of</strong> it directly).<br />

Message [529] referenced by [540]. Next Message by Hans is [530].<br />

[540] Baseball: Marx describes the process <strong>of</strong> selling and buying (exchange) as a metamorphosis<br />

or form change. When a commodity is exchanged from one user to the other it<br />

enters the process <strong>of</strong> social metabolism, and Marx states that only the “form side” <strong>of</strong> the<br />

process is important. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> form is the stage a product is in when it is not needed or being<br />

used, it is a use-value but its use-value is not being expended. By Marx implementing the<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> metamorphosis, when a commodity is sold for money it transforms into its value<br />

form. <strong>The</strong> last form is the end process from the use-value not being expended to where it<br />

will best be used, or rather it transforms to a use-value form where it will be implemented.<br />

As Marx clearly states “it falls out <strong>of</strong> the sphere <strong>of</strong> exchange into that <strong>of</strong> consumption,” the<br />

commodity which has transformed into a use-value form is no longer up for barter, it is now<br />

simply a use-value.<br />

Hans: Your formulation “the process <strong>of</strong> selling and buying (exchange)” suggests that selling and buying and exchange<br />

are the same <strong>thing</strong>. You repeat this suggestion when you write at the end that the commodity in the hands<br />

232 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> its final consumer “is no longer up for barter” (my emphasis). Barter is not the same as buying and selling, and<br />

looking at the process <strong>of</strong> buying and selling from its form side exactly means not to mistake if for a barter. Marx<br />

emphasizes this in 199:1.<br />

<strong>The</strong> content, i.e., the social metabolism itself, is more important than the form. <strong>The</strong> form is only the specific<br />

manner in which capitalism achieves the content. Marx looks only at the form not because it is more important but<br />

because he wants to understand capitalism.<br />

I changed “it is a use-value but its value is not being expended” into “it is a use-value but its use-value is not<br />

being expended” (because this is what you say two sentences later), and I changed “it transforms into a form-value”<br />

into “it transforms into its value form.” If I misread what you wanted to say, please let me know.<br />

Those <strong>thing</strong>s which were correct in your answer were already said in [522] and [524], [528], and [529]. If you<br />

come so late in the discussion it is inexcusable that you don’t reference any <strong>of</strong> the former contributions. Your grade<br />

for this question is governed by the grading policy which announced in [287].<br />

Next Message by Baseball is [557].<br />

[560] Bigwhite: Women <strong>of</strong> the Old School. If you look at the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

from the form side then there seems to be no real need for the word or commodity that is<br />

money. It seems that one never really has money, like in the form that is not a commodity<br />

they simply use this money in other exchanges for goods that they seek use value in. Like<br />

in the story <strong>of</strong> the linen weaver which she takes her goods to the market and then exchanges<br />

it for 2 euro, which she then in turn uses to buy a bible in which she will use at home with<br />

her family. So this money is no<strong>thing</strong> more than a commodity in which she saw the use value<br />

in. Her linen only served the purpose <strong>of</strong> getting the money she wanted so it could be used<br />

to buy the bible. So in real terms it was a sale <strong>of</strong> her commodity linen then the purchase <strong>of</strong><br />

another commodity the bible with the money. But looking at it from the form side it was<br />

simply two exchanges <strong>of</strong> three goods.<br />

Message [560] referenced by [561], [563], and [569]. Next Message by Bigwhite is [569].<br />

[561] SMIKEC: I agree with Bigwhite [560], money is really worth no<strong>thing</strong> unless you<br />

buy some<strong>thing</strong> with it. In essence you could take a commodity such as shoes. As long as<br />

someone has a need for your shoes, it’s no different than money. <strong>The</strong>re’s the saying that<br />

there is always a buyer for your goods, it’s just finding them. Hopefully one finds their<br />

buyer before their value <strong>of</strong> e.g. shoes goes down because they have to have a fire sale in<br />

order to eat or put a ro<strong>of</strong> over their head, therefore diminishing their value for not having<br />

perfect timing <strong>of</strong> their “trade” or sale.<br />

Message [561] referenced by [563]. Next Message by SMIKEC is [684].<br />

[563] Hans: Money in C-M-C. Bigwhite [560] says:<br />

“If you look at the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities from the form side then ... it<br />

seems that one never really has money.”<br />

Right, in C-M-C one has money only for a little while, then it is paid out again. Money<br />

is only an intermediary between the good one sells and the good one buys.<br />

Instead <strong>of</strong> saying one never really has money, Marx says the money is still the commodity<br />

which one has produced, only in a different form. As soon as the commodity is produced, it<br />

is invisibly already money (because it has value, i.e., labor)—and the sale simply makes this<br />

invisible aspect visible. When SMIKEC [561] writes “shoes are no different than money”<br />

this also means: shoes are already value. Money makes the value <strong>of</strong> the shoes visible but<br />

money does not give the shoes value.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 233<br />

But this is only true as long as money is busy in circulation. When money is taken out<br />

<strong>of</strong> circulation and saved, then, Marx says, money act “as money” rather than as as a short<br />

interlude between sale and purchase. This is the content <strong>of</strong> section 3 <strong>of</strong> chapter Three,<br />

assigned Tuesday until Thursday.<br />

Later in his submission Bigwhite writes: “So in real terms it was a sale <strong>of</strong> her commodity<br />

linen then the purchase <strong>of</strong> another commodity the bible with the money. But looking at it<br />

form a form side it was simply two exchanges <strong>of</strong> three goods.” No, this is the mistake Kaush<br />

and I were discussing in [554] and [555] just before Bigwhite made his submission. Marx<br />

wants you not to look at it as an exchange. <strong>The</strong> best way to think about it (according to<br />

Marx) is to say that you still have the same commodity, but in a different form. <strong>The</strong> linen is<br />

the caterpillar, the money the chrysalis, and the coat is the adult butterfly.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [565].<br />

[569] Bigwhite: Clarity. After I read Hans’ comment on my submission [560] I now<br />

realize that my answer was wrong. I should have stated that the exchange from linen to<br />

money to bible is not simply two exchanges <strong>of</strong> three goods but rather a transformation from<br />

linen to money to bible which is all really one commodity going through a transformation<br />

according to the form side. Showing the different forms and ways a commodity can be seen<br />

and used.<br />

Next Message by Bigwhite is [678].<br />

[602] Kleenex: CMC and capitalism. I was thinking about C-M-C and how it cannot<br />

be considered simply as an exchange <strong>of</strong> a commodity with money, or vice versa, but that<br />

the commodities actually change form. <strong>The</strong> commodity takes its own monetary shape when<br />

put up against money in a sale. Also when a transaction is about to occur, exchange value<br />

faces use-value. Though I have not included here by any means the entire explanation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

C-M-C process, it is very interesting to me to see a simple act done on a daily basis by many<br />

broken down in such minute detail. Has capitalism altered the way we view this process?<br />

Would it be true that in a capitalist society, money is treated as a commodity, or maybe even<br />

as a more “valuable” commodity than other commodities (linen, whiskey), as it can be used<br />

to purchase those other commodities? Of course, from a Marxian perspective, it all boils<br />

down to human labor in the abstract, but we don’t seem to think much about the true value<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity in present-day society. I’m having a hard time understanding how capitalism<br />

has distorted the purity <strong>of</strong> the exchange and sale process, if at all. Any input? Thanks.<br />

Next Message by Kleenex is [937].<br />

[903] Proletarian: graded A+ When Marx says that one must look at the circulation <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities from the form side he means that to truly understand the nature <strong>of</strong> circulation,<br />

and what happens to value during circulation, examining from the form side is the only way<br />

to truly see the underlying processes instead <strong>of</strong> just surface relations. By looking at the form<br />

side we see more than simply trading money for a commodity, but instead see the value in a<br />

commodity transform.<br />

Say the producer <strong>of</strong> commodity A exchanges his commodity for money. If you look only<br />

at surface interactions you only see the exchange. However, by looking at <strong>thing</strong>s from the<br />

form side one sees that the commodity transforms into money, or rather, that the commodity<br />

A form <strong>of</strong> the value contained in the commodity transforms into the money form. After the<br />

transaction the producer <strong>of</strong> commodity A still holds the same value as he did prior to the<br />

234 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

transaction, just in a different form. <strong>The</strong>n, when the producer <strong>of</strong> commodity A exchanges<br />

that money for commodity B (which has a use value that the producer <strong>of</strong> commodity A<br />

needs) the value again changes form and morphs into commodity B. <strong>The</strong> producer always<br />

held the same value, but just in different forms (<strong>first</strong> commodity form A, then money, the<br />

commodity form B).<br />

Two excellent metaphors were given during the email discussions and were contained<br />

in Installment Two. One <strong>of</strong> the metaphors was <strong>of</strong> the butterfly, the other <strong>of</strong> water. In the<br />

butterfly metaphor, one sees that the caterpillar changes form from caterpillar to chrysalis<br />

to butterfly. <strong>The</strong> same creature takes on different forms just as the value in the commodity<br />

takes on several forms. In the water metaphor, the same chemical takes a solid, liquid, or<br />

gaseous form, but in all three forms it is still the same molecule. <strong>The</strong> same water molecule<br />

takes on different forms just as the value in the commodity takes on several forms.<br />

Next Message by Proletarian is [904].<br />

[931] LuBr: When one looks at the circulation <strong>of</strong> a commodity from the form side, C-M-<br />

C, versus as an exchange <strong>of</strong> one commodity for another, one can see an important distinction.<br />

Looking from the form side one can see that the same original commodity changes forms<br />

three times in a process that can be compared to a metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> a butterfly. <strong>The</strong> form<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity changes form in three stages:<br />

1) form <strong>of</strong> use-value that the owner <strong>of</strong> the commodity doesn’t want<br />

2) money as form <strong>of</strong> value<br />

3) form <strong>of</strong> use-value that the owner does want<br />

It is important to look at the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities from the form side because one<br />

is able to see that the original value <strong>of</strong> the commodity remains intact and with the owner,<br />

but the form <strong>of</strong> the use-value is all that has changed. Thus, from the form side we can see<br />

that the circulation process does not create any new value, a misconception that can happen<br />

if one looks at the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> exchange.<br />

Next Message by LuBr is [932].<br />

[968] Kohhep: <strong>The</strong> form side <strong>of</strong> an exchange, as described by Marx, is essentially the<br />

transformation, or metamorphosis, <strong>of</strong> a commodity during exchange. C-M-C is the formula<br />

that Marx describes where a commodity goes from 1) a commodity without use value for the<br />

producer <strong>of</strong> the commodity, where it is exchanged, or metamorphosized to 2) money, which<br />

represents the surface value <strong>of</strong> the labor value within the commodity. Finally, the money is<br />

exchanged, or better yet, transformed to 3) commodity with use value for the producer <strong>of</strong><br />

the original commodity. This cycle is continuous and sweats money from every pore. This<br />

is a three step process in which the labor value within the commodity can manifest itself as<br />

money for the producer <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Kohhep is [973].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 444 is 330 in 2003fa, 370 in 2004fa, 364 in 2005fa, 386 in 2007SP, 397 in<br />

2008SP, 398 in 2008fa, 413 in 2009fa, and 453 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 444 <strong>The</strong> empirical appearance <strong>of</strong> the processes <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase encourages<br />

a naive mistake, which makes it difficult to understand the metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Which mistake?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 235<br />

[554] Kaush: <strong>The</strong> mistake. <strong>The</strong> mistake is that we may consider the process <strong>of</strong> selling and<br />

buying <strong>of</strong> commodities as exchanges instead <strong>of</strong> metamorphoses during which commodities<br />

undergo form changes. In a barter between two commodities there is an exchange; whereas,<br />

in a sale or a purchase, the commodity that is sold or purchased changes its form from a<br />

commodity form to a “money” form.<br />

Message [554] referenced by [555], [562], [563], and [568]. Next Message by Kaush is [703].<br />

[555] Hans: Why is this a mistake? Kaush has a reputation for neat and compact answers.<br />

His [297] condenses the answer to such a degree that this condensation itself brings<br />

new insights—more in my response [316]. His [527] gives an original and refreshingly brief<br />

one-sentence characterization <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> money—which itself does not quite answer<br />

the question asked but which can be amended (I supply this amendment in my comment<br />

in the archives).<br />

Kaush’s [554] is entirely correct but I think only a minority <strong>of</strong> participants in this class<br />

will fully grasp what it means. If considered as practical acts, selling and buying are exchanges<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s, why is it so wrong to conceptualize them as exchanges? Marx’s own<br />

formulation is even more opaque than Kaush’s; Marx says in 199:1:<br />

We do not see that gold, as a mere commodity, is not money, and that the<br />

other commodities, through their prices, relate themselves to gold as their<br />

own monetary shape.<br />

Kaush unpacks this obscure formulation in part, he lays out clearly how Marx wants us<br />

to look at sale and purchase and how Marx does not want us to look at it, but it is not clear<br />

from Kaush’s formulation why the method not favored by Marx is wrong.<br />

Note that I am not amending [554] here, I am not telling you what else needs to be said<br />

in addition to [554] to make it a complete answer—given an audience which probably isn’t<br />

terribly sure what it means to look at an act <strong>of</strong> circulation “from the form side.” This message<br />

here only tries to clarify the question, in the expectation that others will give a more complete<br />

answer now that the question is better defined.<br />

I tried a similar intervention in [151]. Nobody followed up on it before the <strong>first</strong> exam.<br />

Also my [197] indicated in its very last paragraph that the question was not yet correctly<br />

answered, and again nobody followed up on it before the <strong>first</strong> exam. A number <strong>of</strong> graduate<br />

students are enrolled in this class. Three <strong>of</strong> them have made outstanding contributions to the<br />

discussion: Babyceta, LuBr, and Robert. Maybe some <strong>of</strong> the others would like to make sure<br />

that our discussion won’t have such loose ends lying around in the future?<br />

Message [555] referenced by [562], [563], and [565]. Next Message by Hans is [563].<br />

[562] TINDOZ: Why a mistake? <strong>Question</strong> 444 asks which mistake is encouraged<br />

through the sale and purchase process that makes it difficult to understand the metamorphosis<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity. As Kaush said [554] (and Hans affirmed [555]) it is to look at the<br />

process as an exchange instead <strong>of</strong> a metamorphosis. To look at it in a similar form as how<br />

you would look at bartering and ignoring the ‘money form’ - this is my sum up <strong>of</strong> Kaush’s<br />

already concise answer.<br />

Hans replied and clarified the question asking why is this a mistake, so I’ll take a crack<br />

at that aspect <strong>of</strong> the question. From the readings I think Hans sets the stage for the ‘why’ in<br />

236 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the annotations near the top <strong>of</strong> page 281. He says, “People’s thought processes and decision<br />

criteria are different when they make a sale or purchase than when they barter two commodities<br />

against each other”. <strong>The</strong> reason why it is a “naive mistake” to look at the process<br />

as an exchange instead <strong>of</strong> as the metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> the commodity into its money form is<br />

because converting a commodity into money is clearly not the same <strong>thing</strong> as exchanging one<br />

commodity for another in direct exchange - nor do we go about it psychologically the same<br />

way as Hans infers in the above quote.<br />

If you have ever heard the expression, the answer’s in the question, and then notice that<br />

this question has the word “naive” in it, the answer to “why” becomes apparent. A definition<br />

for naive is more or less looking at some<strong>thing</strong> with too much simplicity. Looking at the<br />

process <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase as merely exchange is much too simple <strong>of</strong> a way to look at it as<br />

it eliminates the form change into money - in other words, it skips past that whole extremely<br />

important step. Leaving out this money form is a mistake because it vastly neglects to<br />

recognize what is actually going on, ie, a commodity is changing form into money not<br />

simply exchanging itself. Making this mistake also ignores the psychology <strong>of</strong> what is behind<br />

the motivation for the transaction process which is an important aspect in that the “thought<br />

processes and decision making criteria” are different when dealing with the money form<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity than they are in bartering. To sum it up, looking at the process simply as<br />

“exchanging” only looks at the beginning and the end: you have commodity A, then you no<br />

longer have it but now you have commodity B. In the barter world, looking at the process as<br />

an exchange is fine, but in the sale/purchase world leaving out the important middle step <strong>of</strong><br />

metamorphosis into a commodity’s money form is a mistake as you are overlooking what is<br />

really going on and referring to it the same way you would to the bartering process.<br />

Message [562] referenced by [565] and [568]. Next Message by TINDOZ is [651].<br />

[568] LuBr: <strong>The</strong> Naive Mistake. I would agree with Hans that <strong>Question</strong> 444 has not yet<br />

been answered correctly and completely, I would also agree with Hans that as Masters students<br />

we should feel an added responsibility for tying up loose ends in our class discussions.<br />

I hope that my understanding <strong>of</strong> “circulation from the form side” in a commodity producing<br />

society serves to answer the question.<br />

<strong>The</strong> naive mistake is that we interpret the process <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase as an exchange between<br />

different commodities. In this respect, I would agree with Kaush [554] and TINDOZ<br />

[562]. However, they fail to discuss the market from the form side appropriately to answer<br />

this question, and thus fail to understand how the process <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase is not only<br />

not an exchange but is what allows the contradictory aspect <strong>of</strong> the simple barter to seek a<br />

resolution <strong>of</strong> sorts.<br />

When one does not look the market from the form side, the process <strong>of</strong> C-M and then M-C<br />

looks like two sets <strong>of</strong> exchanges between two commodities, an easy mistake to make. Or<br />

as Marx would say, a naive mistake. Naive because it can be interpreted on a very surface<br />

level as a physical exchange, that is the “physical” exchange <strong>of</strong> commodity x for the money<br />

commodity and the money commodity then for the commodity y. However, when looked at<br />

from the form side, it is not a simple act <strong>of</strong> exchange but rather a form change <strong>of</strong> commodity<br />

x. From the form side, the seller <strong>of</strong> the commodity x does not exchange her commodity, the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> her commodity morphs to the commodity gold which becomes the material form


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 237<br />

<strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> commodity x, only to change shape again in the form <strong>of</strong> commodity y, which<br />

is the realization <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> commodity x. From the form side we are able to see that<br />

C-M-C has no concern for the use-value <strong>of</strong> commodity y, it only tracks the metamorphosis<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodity x from C-M-C only to end up with the same commodity (the reincarnation <strong>of</strong><br />

commodity x’s value) but with a more desired use-value (commodity y).<br />

With the process <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase made possible by money separating the barter, it<br />

becomes possible to mitigate the contradictions that arise between the individual and social<br />

dynamics <strong>of</strong> direct exchange that we read about in section 2.2c. Now, instead <strong>of</strong> the<br />

individual striving to make his commodity the General Equivalent <strong>of</strong> all commodities with<br />

use-values <strong>of</strong> his particular interest, money now plays the role as the General Equivalent.<br />

And instead <strong>of</strong> dealing with the social problem <strong>of</strong> the individual getting credit in the form<br />

<strong>of</strong> any use-value according to his commodity’s value (which would mean that society would<br />

have to accept any use-value without discrimination if the values were equivalent), money<br />

now acts as the intermediate form change which reincarnates itself into another use-value <strong>of</strong><br />

identical value.<br />

In this way, sale and purchase is a form which allows the contradictory elements <strong>of</strong> the<br />

barter to coexist, however, as Marx says, the contradiction is still there and does not eliminate<br />

the possibility <strong>of</strong> crisis.<br />

Hans: Just one quibble: Instead <strong>of</strong> saying commodity y is the realization <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> commodity x, I would say<br />

that already the money is the realization <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> commodity x, and commodity y is then the realization <strong>of</strong><br />

the use-value <strong>of</strong> this money.<br />

Message [568] referenced by [574]. Next Message by LuBr is [604].<br />

[574] Cmellen: graded A <strong>The</strong> Mistake. LuBr [568] beat me to it. I had to wait 24 hours<br />

before posting again. However, I agree that the mistake is to interpret the process <strong>of</strong> sale<br />

and purchase as an exchange. It is not an exchange but a metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> commodity. It<br />

started out as a commodity with no use-value (to the seller); it morphed into money, and then<br />

became a commodity <strong>of</strong> use-value (to the buyer). As Hans said before, “the money does<br />

not count as a separate commodity, but is a different form <strong>of</strong> the commodity sold.” Marx<br />

suggests the buying or selling process does not exchange, but evokes a “metamorphosis” <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity. That is where the mistake is made, it should not be thought <strong>of</strong> as exchange<br />

or barter.<br />

Hans: Good and concise formulation <strong>of</strong> the main argument.<br />

Message [574] referenced by [1085]. Next Message by Cmellen is [575].<br />

[1085] Jon: <strong>The</strong> empirical appearance <strong>of</strong> the sale <strong>of</strong> one item and purchasing another is<br />

a simple exchange <strong>of</strong> one commodity for another. This however is a great mistake. In the<br />

annotations page 281 Hans stresses that there is a very different character between sale and<br />

purchase and a barter between 2 commodities. As Cmellen says in e-mail [574] “It is not an<br />

exchange but a metamorphsis. It starts as a commodity with no use value (to the seller); it<br />

morphed into money, and then became a comodity <strong>of</strong> use-value (to the buyer).” I agree with<br />

Cmellen that what is missed is the “M” part <strong>of</strong> the C-M-C that is the mistake. <strong>The</strong> form<br />

change from commodity to money is a very important change that must not be forgotten in<br />

the purchase and sale <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Next Message by Jon is [1110].<br />

238 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 447 is 291 in 2001fa, 365 in 2005fa, 387 in 2007SP, 414 in 2009fa, and 458 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 447 Why is the commodity not bruised, and why is the commodity owner “bruised,”<br />

if the commodity’s salto mortale fails?<br />

[525] AlexDaily: graded A When a laborer produces a product and does not get full<br />

return for his labor, then his labor is “bruised”. Sunflower gives an example in [2009fa:611]<br />

<strong>of</strong> how this process takes place. “In a capitalist society, producers try to manipulate the<br />

social relations in the market created by commodity production in order to maximize the<br />

value in their own commodities by trying to get more value from the market than the actual<br />

homogeneous labor expended in production produced.” “Bruising” happens when no one<br />

purchases the commodity, because the commodity owner is not getting fair payment for<br />

his labor. However, the use-value still exists in the commodity so the actual commodity is<br />

not “bruised”, simply the commodities’ owner is “bruised.” For example, if a commodity<br />

is produced and not ever sold, it holds the same use-value as the same commodity that is<br />

produced and sold. <strong>The</strong> commodity owner, on the other hand, produced two commodities<br />

but only received compensation for one.<br />

Message [525] referenced by [526], [567], [954], and [2012fa:827]. Next Message by AlexDaily is [537].<br />

[526] Hans: You may get bruised even if you are not trying to outwit the market.<br />

By quoting a specific passage from Sunflower, AlexDaily [525] seems to say that market<br />

participants get “bruised” because they or others try to outwit the market. No disagreement<br />

here, but I don’t think this is the main reason commodity sellers sometimes get bruised.<br />

Even those who are not trying to be extra smart may get bruised if they are caught up in a<br />

discrepancy between demand and supply.<br />

I am writing here “caught up” because it need not be their fault at all. Whenever there<br />

is a discrepancy between demand and supply, individual commodity producers gain (if they<br />

happen to sell some<strong>thing</strong> in excess demand) or lose (if they happen to sell some<strong>thing</strong> in<br />

excess supply). Some sellers are better than others to judge what the public wants, but the<br />

relevant question here is not whether someone deserves it when they get extra income or<br />

when they get bruised. A social concern, adjustment <strong>of</strong> supply to demand, has become an<br />

individual interest, and the relevant question (as I see it) is how well it works. Actually, this<br />

one works pretty well. Capitalism is flexible and effective in adjusting supply to demand.<br />

Other social concerns, such as full employment, are less well met through their translation<br />

into individual interests, and still others, such as sustainability and global warming, resist<br />

translation into individual interests but require social solutions.<br />

Message [526] referenced by [546], [550], [954], [996], and [2012fa:803]. Next Message by Hans is [528].<br />

[942] Balrog: graded A Why Does He Get Bruised? When an owner tries to sell a<br />

commodity and is unsuccessful the commodity is not bruised. It is happy because it still<br />

maintains its use-value. <strong>The</strong> owner on the other hand is bruised because he produced a<br />

commodity for which he did not receive a fair payment. He placed a congealed amount <strong>of</strong><br />

his labor into the commodity with hopes that it would be purchased and transformed into<br />

an equal amount <strong>of</strong> gold. With that gold he could purchase a commodity with a use-value<br />

he needs. When markets fluctuate and competition is tense producers will <strong>of</strong>ten come out<br />

bruised.<br />

Hans: At the moment when he placed the labor into the commodity the labor was not yet congealed.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 239<br />

Next Message by Balrog is [943].<br />

[954] TINDOZ: When a commodity is created by a laborer (its owner) and is taken to<br />

market for sale by its owner, two <strong>thing</strong>s can happen: it can get sold, or it doesn’t. <strong>The</strong>refore,<br />

what happens with that commodity (and as Hans points out in [526]) has a lot to do with the<br />

ratio <strong>of</strong> supply and demand for that commodity. When the commodity is brought to market,<br />

it is supplied. This now leaves the question <strong>of</strong> whether there is demand for the commodity<br />

(i.e. will it be sold) or will it not be sold and go home with the (bruised) owner who created<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> whose demand wasn’t such to get it to sell. As AlexDaily said in [525], the<br />

laborer produced a product but “does not get full return for his labor”. In the scenario where<br />

a commodity is supplied but the demand isn’t there for it to be sold, the commodities owner<br />

is bruised (he put labor into some<strong>thing</strong> and got no return) and not the commodity itself (as<br />

its use-value is still intact).<br />

For example, if a watch maker makes two watches, takes them to market, and the market<br />

demand results in only one <strong>of</strong> those watches selling, then the owner is “bruised” as the other<br />

watch’s salto mortale fails. <strong>The</strong> other watch still has the same use-value as the watch that<br />

sold and therefore the watch (or the commodity) itself does not get bruised. <strong>The</strong> bruising<br />

comes because the owner unfortunately misjudged the demand for watches and supplied<br />

more than the demand and therefore got bruised.<br />

Next Message by TINDOZ is [956].<br />

[965] SMIKEC: <strong>The</strong> commodity is not bruised because it is already made. <strong>The</strong> owner<br />

is bruised because she has the commodity and isn’t getting “X” dollars worth <strong>of</strong> labor that<br />

she put into it. I think this is a typical supply and demand situation <strong>of</strong> where you’re caught<br />

holding the commodity. If its on the demand side you will be rewarded, while if it is on the<br />

supply side with an over abundance <strong>of</strong> that commodity, that’s when you will see the most<br />

bruising. This de-values the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that the worker put forth for the capitalist. In<br />

a surplus setting the commodity holder will take the hit, causing the bruising, mostly based<br />

on being in the wrong place at the wrong time holding the commodity <strong>of</strong> lesser demand than<br />

intended.<br />

Next Message by SMIKEC is [1028].<br />

[966] Atticus: graded B+ Only the commodity owner is “bruised” because the commodity’s<br />

value and use-value remains intact while the owner gets “bruised” because his time and<br />

effort have been wasted. He will not get to purchase what he may need and he still owns a<br />

commodity that has no use-value for himself. <strong>The</strong> commodity still has value which is congealed<br />

in the form <strong>of</strong> abstract labor. Its value is expended by consumption. Its form <strong>of</strong> value<br />

changes into the money form in circulation.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> value is not intact, only the use-value is intact. Value is not just physical labor, but it is a social relation.<br />

If the commodity is produced in excess <strong>of</strong> what is needed, then the labor in the commodity does not count as<br />

socially necessary labor.<br />

Next Message by Atticus is [969].<br />

[977] Somramthom: graded B– Bruised Owners. When a commodity is produced, its<br />

value is derived from the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that was expended in its production. Since this<br />

value is inherent, it will continue on with the commodity and the commodity itself will not be<br />

bruised. <strong>The</strong> commodity owner, however, is bruised since he either produced or exchanged<br />

for the commodity and won’t be able to exchange it for some<strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong> equal value. <strong>The</strong><br />

commodity from his view point may be worthless but only the use-value is affected. This<br />

240 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

lack <strong>of</strong> use-value doesn’t negate the commodity’s inherent value. It limits what the owner<br />

can do with the commodity. <strong>The</strong>refore, the commodity owner is bruised, and the commodity<br />

itself is not.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> value is diminished. What remains intact is only the use-value.<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [992].<br />

[996] Rico: Supply and demand have become a driving force in mainstream economics<br />

today. People believe that by obeying the supply and demand <strong>of</strong> a given commodity<br />

market, they can be sufficiently informed to make decisions that will not be economically<br />

detrimental to themselves. This is not the case however. Although supply and demand help<br />

demonstrate equilibriums in the marketplace, certain discrepancies can arise. Hans explains<br />

in [2010fa:526] the possible implications that follow discrepancies between supply and demand.<br />

“Whenever there is a discrepancy between demand and supply, individual commodity<br />

producers gain (if they happen to sell some<strong>thing</strong> in excess demand) or lose (if they happen<br />

to sell some<strong>thing</strong> in excess supply).” This quote explains why the commodity owner gets<br />

bruised when the supply and demand fail to function properly. Both sellers and buyers<br />

can be positively impacted or negatively impacted by excess demand or excess supply in<br />

a commodity market. DarkKnight explains why the commodity itself is not bruised when<br />

discrepancies arise between supply and demand in [2005fa:962]. “<strong>The</strong> commodity, on the<br />

other hand, still retains all <strong>of</strong> its use-value and exchange value. . .hence the commodity itself<br />

is not bruised, it remains whole regardless <strong>of</strong> what is received in exchange.” This is well<br />

stated. <strong>The</strong> commodity’s use-value is not contingent upon the market value. <strong>The</strong> commodity<br />

retains its use-value and is therefore not bruised.<br />

Hans: But note that the value is not preserved but lost.<br />

Next Message by Rico is [1005].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 448 is 460 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 448 Usually, Marx says that the strength <strong>of</strong> the proletariat comes from its numbers;<br />

but in 200:4/o, Marx says that is is unluckily for the weaver that there are many<br />

weavers in the world. How can he come to such conflicting pronouncements?<br />

[541] Kraken: graded A– Your weaving is killing me! Marx makes two statements<br />

which are absolutely true, even though they seem to contradict each other. First, the strength<br />

<strong>of</strong> the proletariat does lie in its numbers. Individuals have little chance in rising up and<br />

changing the prevailing economic system by themselves.<br />

Secondly, and equally true is Marx’s statement: “Unluckily for the weaver, people <strong>of</strong> her<br />

kind are in plentiful supply.” <strong>The</strong> reason the weaver is unlucky to be surrounded by fellow<br />

weavers is that in the system they are bound to labor under requires them to engage in a<br />

never ending battle against one another. <strong>The</strong> more weavers there are in the world, the more<br />

likely their standard <strong>of</strong> living will decrease and they will be forced to make subsistence-level<br />

wages, if they can remain pr<strong>of</strong>itable at all. Each weaver will attempt to gain market share and<br />

steal pr<strong>of</strong>its away from their fellow weavers. <strong>The</strong>y will try to find cheaper and more efficient<br />

ways to bring their goods to the market. Many will employ technology and automation in<br />

the production process. As productivity goes up, they begin to flood the market with cheaply<br />

made goods which drives prices down for all the weavers.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 241<br />

Most wage earners are so busy in the day-to-day battle to make ends meet that they have<br />

precious little time to come together and organize themselves for the purpose <strong>of</strong> changing the<br />

system which keeps them bound to the daily struggle. It’s ironic that even though workers<br />

may despise the economic system which they labor under, it’s their continued labor that<br />

gives the system life and ensures its continuation.<br />

Message [541] referenced by [545], [546], [551], [2012fa:820], and [2012fa:842]. Next Message by Kraken is<br />

[566].<br />

[545] Hans: Why aren’t the workers rich and powerful? Kraken [541] is absolutely<br />

right: “Individuals have little chance in rising up and changing the prevailing economic system<br />

by themselves.” You cannot change society by writing essays on facebook. If you want<br />

to change society, you have to organize, work together with and get to know real individuals,<br />

get to know the strengths and weaknesses <strong>of</strong> specific people in your workplace or neighborhood,<br />

build skills and networks, become an organization which the public recognizes and<br />

learns to trust.<br />

But this is not the only <strong>thing</strong> Marx meant. According to Marx, the only strength <strong>of</strong> the<br />

working class is their numbers, but numbers are a considerable factor because the large<br />

majority <strong>of</strong> modern capitalist societies are workers. If this majority effectively organizes<br />

then they will have a lot <strong>of</strong> power.<br />

<strong>The</strong> other <strong>thing</strong>, <strong>of</strong> course, to be considered in conjuction with this is: according to Marx,<br />

only labor creates value. Machines do not create value. Pr<strong>of</strong>its are a transfer <strong>of</strong> value from its<br />

original producers, the workers, to the capitalists. Even the capital whose ownership gives<br />

the capitalists so much wealth and power is the product <strong>of</strong> the workers. Kraken alludes to<br />

this in his last sentence: “It is their continued labor that gives the system life and ensures its<br />

continuation.”<br />

If the workers are so numerous and if they produce all value, why aren’t they rich and<br />

powerful? Several reasons.<br />

One aspect here is the linen weaver aspect <strong>of</strong> the question: because capitalism is based<br />

on competition. If workers succeed in gaining higher wages then their employer may lose<br />

in competition with other employers whose workers are still on the low wage. And workers<br />

may try to secure their jobs by being loyal to the capitalist.<br />

Another aspect <strong>of</strong> capitalism keeping workers wages down is also the fact that the owners<br />

<strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production can and periodically do introduce technical innovations which<br />

replace workers. We will discuss this in chapter 25, and Kraken alludes to this too.<br />

A third aspect is the opaqueness <strong>of</strong> capitalist social relations. It is not apparent to the<br />

workers that they produce all wealth, that their pay is much lower than the value they produce<br />

for the capitalist. Part <strong>of</strong> this was discussed in the section about the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity, and more will be said in chapter 19.<br />

If Marx’s theory is right, then the working class is a huge sleeping giant. <strong>The</strong>y could be<br />

rich and powerful if only they get their act together and flex their collective muscle. And the<br />

capitalists are terribly afraid that at some time this will happen, and they do every<strong>thing</strong> they<br />

can to prolong the working class’s snooze.<br />

Message [545] referenced by [547]. Next Message by Hans is [553].<br />

242 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[546] Utefan: <strong>The</strong> Proletariat Can’t Have their Cake and Eat it Too. Both statements<br />

made by Marx are absolutely true. Kraken [541] dove in extensively on the latter part <strong>of</strong><br />

the question referring to the weavers being unlucky having many other weavers in the same<br />

field. <strong>The</strong> more weavers make competition more extensive for each individual and thus<br />

leaves less sales. Hans [526] also comments that the socially accepted labor time can hurt<br />

each individual. If the market cannot stomach the whole quantity <strong>of</strong> linen made at its normal<br />

price then too great a portion <strong>of</strong> social labor time has been expended in the form <strong>of</strong> weaving,<br />

and the effect is the same as if each weaver had used more time on his or her particular<br />

product.<br />

Now for the former part <strong>of</strong> the question; strength does lie in the number <strong>of</strong> the proletariat,<br />

the working wage class, because individuals, as Kraken also stated, have a hard time beginning<br />

any sort <strong>of</strong> revolution by themselves. Modern day examples also suggest the same.<br />

Workers can unionize and also demand as a group better pay or benefits—teachers strikes<br />

and writers strikes are the most common I could think <strong>of</strong> that illustrate this. Also groups<br />

can share in the monopoly that is their job, socially they get stronger. Anywhere from pr<strong>of</strong>essional<br />

sport players unions to the umpires who keep the rules flowing have groups that<br />

require basic membership. <strong>The</strong>se examples show the former part <strong>of</strong> the question as a strength<br />

and can get many <strong>thing</strong>s accomplished.<br />

Now the conflict comes from them both arguments, both hold some validity but as a<br />

saying illustrates that the proletariat “can’t have their cake and eat it too.” One is not without<br />

the other and that is where the conflict arises.<br />

Message [546] referenced by [548]. Next Message by Utefan is [548].<br />

[547] Bigwhite: Ahh the 80’s. Hans [545] brings to light an important dynamic <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist system hat sometimes seems to be overlooked, workers power in the economy. It<br />

seems since the 80’s that workers steadily lose how much clout they have in the economy.<br />

Unions have been banned, wages have been lowered, etc. A lot <strong>of</strong> this is due to Ronald<br />

Reagan and Margaret Thatcher; former prime minister <strong>of</strong> England. <strong>The</strong>y both had the view<br />

<strong>of</strong> supply side economics—a classical approach that had been secondary to Keynes’s views<br />

up until that time. <strong>The</strong>y made it apparent that unions and workers were going to be taken<br />

down a peg. Which is what happened. Many people lost their jobs, benefits, and wages.<br />

This did seem to spark some economic growth but was the beginning <strong>of</strong> workers losing their<br />

power in the economy. <strong>The</strong>y no longer could be protected by the union or helped in wage<br />

and labor arguments. So it is hard to say that the workers should band together and have an<br />

uprising when there are so any obstacles standing in their way.<br />

Message [547] referenced by [553]. Next Message by Bigwhite is [560].<br />

[548] Utefan: Your weaving is killing me! My [546] came after Hans’s answer [548] to<br />

what Kraken had said and almost echoed his thoughts, and since he said them <strong>first</strong> I would<br />

like to add a little more to the end <strong>of</strong> the conflicting part <strong>of</strong> the question.<br />

Hans makes us aware that capitalists try to keep wage workers down in most <strong>of</strong> their<br />

actions. <strong>The</strong>y produce all the wealth that they are so little compensated for. Now the wage<br />

worker can unionize and become stronger and demand better pay and benefits. Often this<br />

is the case and until there is a resolution consumers and the like miss out. However, due to<br />

climates <strong>of</strong> the economy and other factors, some workers don’t have all they need to demand


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 243<br />

resolution, which is power. I alluded to the saying that one can’t have their cake and eat it<br />

too. <strong>The</strong> reason being is that in most cases there will always be someone else who without<br />

employment is happy to take low wages to have a job, thus putting the original workers out<br />

<strong>of</strong> employment. My own company did the same <strong>thing</strong> with me and it resulted in a second<br />

deduction <strong>of</strong> pay and my hours went up as well. I have now double the amount <strong>of</strong> loss when<br />

adding the pay deduction and the hours at work together. I have no power and thus have<br />

to bite the bullet and accept my plight. This is that conflict. It will rage on forever in the<br />

capitalist society, only few titles have the luxury <strong>of</strong> being able to get results—sports athletes<br />

come to mind because <strong>of</strong> the highly specialized craft they pursue—and one result is because<br />

<strong>of</strong> the high numbers <strong>of</strong> multiple people doing the same job, someone else can simply take<br />

my place. <strong>The</strong>y go hand in hand.<br />

Message [548] referenced by [548] and [553]. Next Message by Utefan is [577].<br />

[551] PLG: Plan before you weave. Marx says in 200:4/o: “Moreover, although our<br />

weaver’s labor may be a recognized branch <strong>of</strong> the social division <strong>of</strong> labor, yet that fact is by<br />

no means sufficient to guarantee the utility <strong>of</strong> her 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen.”<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 448 can be answered by differentiating what Marx means when discussing the<br />

strength <strong>of</strong> the proletariat, and the number <strong>of</strong> weavers in the world. <strong>The</strong> strength <strong>of</strong> the<br />

proletariat increases with its size because it expands the capabilities <strong>of</strong> the market based on<br />

the division <strong>of</strong> labor. However, without the division <strong>of</strong> labor size can be detrimental.<br />

Marx uses the example <strong>of</strong> the weaver to make this point. If there are more weavers than<br />

needed, the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> their product decreases. <strong>The</strong>y lose purchasing power on the<br />

market due to a surplus. An increased labor size increases the power <strong>of</strong> the proletariat only<br />

if it is organized and planned. If too many laborers are assigned to the same task then the<br />

efficiency <strong>of</strong> the market will decrease.<br />

Kraken [541] says about the weavers, “many will employ new technology and automation<br />

in the production process.” One point that Kraken fails to make is that without the division<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor productivity will not go up. <strong>The</strong> division <strong>of</strong> labor is what sparks innovation, thus<br />

new technologies will not have been created. Instead labor will remain repetitive. In this<br />

case it is not an increase in productivity that will drive down prices, but a repetition <strong>of</strong> the<br />

same task which leads to a surplus. Marx is not contradicting himself. He is saying that the<br />

strength <strong>of</strong> the proletariat increases with its size, but only if it is organized and planned.<br />

Message [551] referenced by [2012fa:820] and [2012fa:842]. Next Message by PLG is [599].<br />

[553] Hans: Capitalists have their cake and eat it too. Capitalists have their wealth and<br />

can pass it on to their heirs, and in addition, this wealth increases. It almost seems to them<br />

that it increases automatically, but according to Marx’s theory it increases due to the labor<br />

<strong>of</strong> the workers.<br />

Now Utefan says in [547] and repeats in [548] that workers can’t have their cake and<br />

eat it too. I don’t think Utefan means with this that the workers can’t be capitalists. He<br />

simply means workers can’t have a job and enjoy high wages at the same time, because <strong>of</strong><br />

competition. But having a job cannot be compared to having a cake in the refrigerator. If<br />

you have a job you must show up at work every day and work. <strong>The</strong>refore a decent wage<br />

should be a natural outcome <strong>of</strong> every job.<br />

244 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> capitalists really have quite a system: not only do they benefit from the labor <strong>of</strong><br />

others, but workers count themselves happy when they have found a capitalist to exploit<br />

them. Marx’s Capital tries to unravel in detail how all this works. Next week we will finally<br />

read not about commodities and money but about capital. Here the book is no longer so<br />

abstract and more obviously relevant to our lives. Stay tuned.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [555].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 451 is 367 in 2005fa and 389 in 2007SP:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 451 Marx says that the independence <strong>of</strong> the individuals from each other is supplemented<br />

by a system <strong>of</strong> all-round material dependence. Explain what this means.<br />

[532] Frida: graded A Capitalist Communities. Marx’s text is full <strong>of</strong> the exploration <strong>of</strong><br />

contradictions, and here is another prime example. Division <strong>of</strong> labor leads simultaneously to<br />

the independence and dependence <strong>of</strong> the commodity producers. <strong>The</strong> commodity producers<br />

are independent <strong>of</strong> one another as private producers. I can decide to dedicate my time how<br />

I see fit; I can make linen, bibles, or whiskey if I so choose. But a person cannot live on<br />

whiskey alone, so if I dedicate all my time to making that commodity, I am dependent on<br />

the market for all <strong>of</strong> my other needs. On one level I am dependent on the farmer, the linen<br />

weaver, the book binder, etc., but on a deeper level I am dependent on the social structure<br />

itself, the relations that supervene on the individuals. Without them I wouldn’t survive.<br />

This is in contrast with, say, the independent frontier farmer. He and his family will have<br />

to spend their time making their own food, clo<strong>thing</strong>, etc. <strong>The</strong>y are not dependent on the<br />

market for survival. <strong>The</strong>y are also not free to spend their time book binding.<br />

Message [532] referenced by [556]. Next Message by Frida is [596].<br />

[550] Husani: <strong>The</strong> overall material dependence Marx speaks <strong>of</strong> here is the fact that we<br />

as producers don’t produce what we need. We produce commodities for the simple fact that<br />

we can take them to market and sell them to someone else. We do not have a use-value for<br />

the commodities we produce so we sell them to someone who does, in exchange for some<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

We have independence in what we produce from everyone else involved in the market.<br />

We choose to produce what we are best at and what will get us the most money in return for<br />

our hard worked labor. <strong>The</strong> market gives us independence on what we produce but at the<br />

same time we are dependent on the market for the commodities we buy to fulfill our needs.<br />

We depend on the market to get the commodities we can’t produce because we are too busy<br />

producing our specialized goods.<br />

<strong>The</strong> market supplements this material dependence because the market is a place where we<br />

can get specialized products produced by people that are highly skilled in producing them.<br />

We are much better at producing one good well and taking that good to the market in order<br />

to sell it and buy other well produced goods than attempting to produce all the commodities<br />

we need poorly.<br />

In short, we are given freedom by the market to produce what we are most skilled at<br />

producing. This also gives us the freedom to the products <strong>of</strong> our labor to the market to sell<br />

and, in turn, buy specialized products from other individuals. Although we are independent


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 245<br />

<strong>of</strong> the market we rely on it to get the products we need and to give us a place to sell our<br />

products.<br />

Hans: In your last sentence you say: “we rely on the market to give us a place to sell our products.” This is the<br />

hitch. What if the market has no room for our products? As I said in [526], this may not be our fault. Yet we have<br />

no recourse. Marx stresses that, although we depend on the market, the market is independent <strong>of</strong> us.<br />

Message [550] referenced by [557]. Next Message by Husani is [575].<br />

[556] Giant: Capitalist Communities. I agree with Frida’s examples in [532] <strong>of</strong> how<br />

division <strong>of</strong> labor leads to simultaneous independence and dependence <strong>of</strong> labor because a<br />

producer can only produce so much with their given time restriction. However I think stating<br />

that the farmer has independence because they produce their own food and clo<strong>thing</strong> fails to<br />

observe that even though the farmer does produce most <strong>of</strong> their own materials they can not<br />

produce all <strong>of</strong> them. A farmer sewing their own clothes generally has not produced their own<br />

needle or thread, but is depending on others to produce that and bought this from them. A<br />

farmer needs parts for his farming equipment that he may not have, thus depending on others<br />

for the parts. So while the farmer is more independent than other producers, the farmer is<br />

still dependent on other producers.<br />

Message [556] referenced by [567]. Next Message by Giant is [643].<br />

[557] Baseball: Husani made very good points but one point I Marx states that the usevalue<br />

seen in commodities is what attracts consumers so barter. Each producer involved in<br />

the marketplace in society has a specific skill set. As Husani said in [550] “We choose to<br />

produce what we are best at and what will get us the most money in return for our hard<br />

worked labor.” This is supported in Marx 165:2/o “commodities are the products <strong>of</strong> private<br />

labors which are conducted independently <strong>of</strong> each other.” But money is not the only<br />

incentive which attracts consumers to buy or barter. <strong>The</strong> use-values seen by consumers in<br />

other commodities is what Marx says attracts them to exchange. <strong>The</strong>refore producers generate<br />

products for the possibility <strong>of</strong> exchanging for other products, made by other producers,<br />

which use-values they will be able to employ. I understand that in today’s society not many<br />

people exchange commodities for commodities but for money. But in Marx’s eyes the main<br />

attraction to exchange for commodities is its use-value.<br />

Next Message by Baseball is [666].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 455 is 264 in 1999SP, 295 in 2001fa, and 392 in 2007SP:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 455 Metamorphosis is only a different word for form change. In C−M−C describe<br />

the form <strong>of</strong> a commodity before its <strong>first</strong> metamorphosis, after its <strong>first</strong> metamorphosis,<br />

and after the second metamorphosis.<br />

[1090] Tyler: Aux states, “the process <strong>of</strong> C-M-C is made possible by the separation <strong>of</strong><br />

the world <strong>of</strong> commodities into ordinary commodities and money” [2007SP:865]. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong><br />

form <strong>of</strong> the commodity is the commodity itself. In this stage the commodity has its value<br />

derived from the social relation which allows it to be traded for money, its exchange value.<br />

Here the commodity experiences its <strong>first</strong> metamorphosis as it is exchanged for money or<br />

the general equivalent. This money as general equivalent is used to fetch a new commodity<br />

which satisfies a particular use-value desired by the commodity owner. Following the second<br />

metamorphosis the “commodity has arrived at a place where it can serve as use-value, it falls<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the sphere <strong>of</strong> exchange into that <strong>of</strong> consumption” [2007SP:865].<br />

Next Message by Tyler is [1091].<br />

246 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 457 is 255 in 1998WI, 265 in 1999SP, 321 in 2002fa, 336 in 2003fa, 376 in<br />

2004fa, and 422 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 457 What is the deeper reason that reciprocity agreements, i.e., agreements <strong>of</strong> the<br />

form: “I buy this from you if you buy that from me” are illegal in the U.S.?<br />

[542] Robert: graded A+ Why barter is illegal in the U.S. This question implies that<br />

there exists more than one reason reciprocity agreements are illegal in the U.S and that at<br />

some <strong>of</strong> these reasons appear on the surface and other reasons are deeper.<br />

Let’s <strong>first</strong> look at what reasons may be considered the surface reasons. Reciprocal dealing<br />

possibly constitutes a violation <strong>of</strong> section 1 <strong>of</strong> the Sherman Act because it is a restraint <strong>of</strong><br />

trade analogous to unlawful tying. It could be a violation <strong>of</strong> section 2 <strong>of</strong> the Sherman Act<br />

because it is an unlawful monopolization and attempted monopolization. Furthermore, under<br />

section 7 <strong>of</strong> the Clayton Act it could be unlawful as an attempt to decrease competition.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, on the surface <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s it appears as though laws making it illegal to engage in<br />

reciprocal dealing in the U.S. protect trade from restraints, monopolies, and decreases in<br />

competition.<br />

However, if we take a Marxian closer look, we uncover a few less noble reasons that the<br />

U.S. government, as a tool <strong>of</strong> capitalism, may find reciprocal trading not desirable. One <strong>of</strong><br />

the reasons may be that it is difficult to track and tax transactions that are C-C; whereas, C-<br />

M-C transactions “leave a money trail.” <strong>The</strong> government knows the value <strong>of</strong> the commodities<br />

sold and the U.S. system taxes sales and pr<strong>of</strong>its from sales. <strong>The</strong> measurement <strong>of</strong> how much<br />

tax the government levies is also evident in the quantity <strong>of</strong> money exchanged. It is more<br />

difficult to ascertain how much tax to levy when commodities are directly exchanged (even<br />

if the transaction were reported to or discovered by the government) since the values are not<br />

as readily apparent.<br />

Furthermore, the government is the entity that prints and regulates money in the U.S.<br />

economy. It can exert certain influence and control on the economy with its monetary policy,<br />

i.e., changing the supply <strong>of</strong> money and the interest rate. In an exchange system that requires<br />

money for every transaction, such policies have effect; in a C-C or reciprocity economy<br />

money supply and cost has no effect.<br />

In a C-C transaction, both commodities drop out <strong>of</strong> circulation and the circulation process<br />

dies down. However, in transaction where commodities are sold for money Marx points<br />

out in 208:1 that even “when the money finally drops out <strong>of</strong> the series <strong>of</strong> metamorphoses<br />

undergone by a commodity, this does not mean that it vanishes.” <strong>The</strong> money “sticks to the<br />

hands <strong>of</strong> some third person” who is now ready to use it to purchase some other commodity.<br />

In this way “circulation sweats money from every pore” and there is always money to fuel<br />

the acquisition and accumulation <strong>of</strong> more commodities. Since capitalism is based on the<br />

accumulation <strong>of</strong> commodities, money circulation facilitates that accumulation. Since the<br />

U.S. government exists to support and expand capitalism it prefers that money be used in<br />

circulation so that the third persons to whose hands the money sticks can be used repeatedly<br />

to acquire more commodities.<br />

Finally, and most sadly in my view, money in circulation creates isolation for each consumer/producer.<br />

She does not meet nor control to whom her products are ultimately sold,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 247<br />

nor is she restrained in from whom and what she can buy. Goshen in [2004fa:244] calls<br />

this isolation “increased privacy” and uses the example that someone may sell bibles to buy<br />

brandy...a transaction that may not work as well in a direct exchange. In my view, this<br />

isolation <strong>of</strong> people from each other deprives them <strong>of</strong> the rich experience <strong>of</strong> interaction. A<br />

cashier or waitress becomes someone who just takes money and delivers commodities; they<br />

are merely a means through which our economic transactions occur.<br />

<strong>The</strong> U.S. government may prefer an isolated citizenry. It is beneficial to the continuation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalistic system that consumers feel isolated. Isolated individuals are psychologically<br />

more needy and more susceptible to ideas that accumulation <strong>of</strong> commodities will lead<br />

to fulfillment. Additionally, isolated individuals are more passive and do not seek to discover<br />

that they are in fact the creators <strong>of</strong> the value accumulating in the hands <strong>of</strong> the owners <strong>of</strong> the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production; therefore, they are easier to govern and exploit.<br />

Next Message by Robert is [582].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 458 is 266 in 1999SP, 283 in 2000fa, and 394 in 2007SP:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 458 How does the result <strong>of</strong> the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities differ from the result <strong>of</strong><br />

the direct exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities?<br />

[565] Hans: C-M-C versus C-C (and attention graduate students). Marx mentions<br />

several differences between C-M-C and the direct barter C-C, i.e., between the transaction<br />

in which the linen weaver exchanges linen for a bible, and the pair <strong>of</strong> transactions in which<br />

the linen weaver <strong>first</strong> sells her linen and then buys the bible for the money received for the<br />

linen.<br />

(a) <strong>The</strong> linen weaver gets bible for linen, but the seller <strong>of</strong> the bible does not get linen for<br />

his bible. He buys some<strong>thing</strong> different with his money, in Marx’s example it is brandy.<br />

(b) <strong>The</strong> buyer <strong>of</strong> the linen must have money, and at the end, the bible seller has the money,<br />

ready to do the second half <strong>of</strong> his transaction. I.e., different transactions are interlinked. This<br />

is not so with a direct barter. Nobody needs money to initiate barter, and barter doesn’t leave<br />

anybody with money at the end to do a second barter.<br />

(c) Sale and purchase do not have to take place at the same location or at the same time.<br />

I am telling you all this because this is an important issue, but it is not the same issue as<br />

Marx’s warning addressed in question 444. Tindoz [562] falsely assumes that Marx warns<br />

against considering C-M-C as C-C. In 199:1, Marx clearly says that one should not consider<br />

C-M as an exchange <strong>of</strong> commodity with money, and M-C as an exchange <strong>of</strong> money with<br />

commodity. Viewed as a practical act, it is an exchange between commodity and money,<br />

but Marx says in its essence it is quite different than an exchange between two ordinary<br />

commodities, and it should not be confused with it.<br />

Why is this so? What is it that makes it so different? Here is a hint: in a sense exchanging<br />

commodities with money is simpler than exchanging two ordinary commodities. But I am<br />

still looking for an answer which explains this really well. <strong>Question</strong> 444 therefore still needs<br />

an answer. I extended the time for question 444: it is assigned in the present homework<br />

period as well. I also discovered another loose end. As per [501], question 420 is not<br />

248 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

yet properly answered either. <strong>The</strong>refore I also re-assigned question 420 for the present<br />

homework period until Thursday.<br />

To echo some<strong>thing</strong> which I said in [555], eight participants are enrolled to get graduate<br />

credit for this class. Three <strong>of</strong> them have made outstanding contributions. <strong>The</strong> others should<br />

consider themselves as janitors: make sure that all questions which were begun this Semester<br />

have been properly answered, and if there is a gap, submit their own answers either to close<br />

the gap or somehow to push the discussion forward so that the gap can be closed.<br />

Message [565] referenced by [915], [970], and [991]. Next Message by Hans is [589].<br />

[879] Babyceta: graded A Direct barter, or C-C, differs greatly from C-M-C, where one<br />

<strong>first</strong> becomes a seller and then a buyer. First, the direct barter <strong>of</strong> commodities is essentially<br />

more difficult since I must <strong>first</strong> locate someone who not only has a commodity whose usevale<br />

I need, but also has a need for the use-value <strong>of</strong> the product I am trading. Marx says<br />

that direct barter only works in the most primitive <strong>of</strong> societies and is basically impossible<br />

today because, in Hans’s words, “it collapses the two independent and even contradictory<br />

goals <strong>of</strong> the exchanger into one.” <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> goal is to realize the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity I<br />

possess, value being the stored abstract labor mysteriously buried in my commodity (the<br />

price at which I sell my commodity merely a surface reflection <strong>of</strong> that value). <strong>The</strong> second<br />

goal is taking the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity I sold, now in the form <strong>of</strong> money but still the same<br />

value and essentially the same commodity nonetheless, and selecting a different commodity<br />

which contains the use-value I need. Direct barter cannot be easily accomplished today<br />

because there are literally millions <strong>of</strong> use-values and matching up with someone for a C-C<br />

exchange would be similar to finding a needle in the proverbial haystack. <strong>The</strong> insanity <strong>of</strong><br />

trying to accomplish these two separate goals at the same time is the contradiction Marx is<br />

referring to in Chapter Two.<br />

Next Message by Babyceta is [881].<br />

[901] Utefan: C–M–C uses a commonality in money so that the consumer can exchange<br />

the <strong>first</strong> commodity and then buy a new one. <strong>The</strong> money acts as a mediator so that no<br />

outside obstacles get in the way <strong>of</strong> going from one commodity and reaching the next; this<br />

commonality is set by the social structure and is mutually agreed upon.<br />

However for C–C many different aspects have to be taken into account such as use-values.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is no common mediator and it is therefore much more difficult to accomplish. C–C<br />

also doesn’t benefit from prices that the mediator money can take advantage <strong>of</strong>. As Hans<br />

describes C–M is asymmetric and C–C is symmetric.<br />

Next Message by Utefan is [902].<br />

[908] DMorris: C-M-C differs from C-C because it has a middle stage, changing the<br />

normal C-C barrier into a 3-person transaction. Now, instead <strong>of</strong> directly acquiring the commodity<br />

he desires, the individual must <strong>first</strong> trade his commodity for money. This is C-M, and<br />

it is as known as the selling. <strong>The</strong> individual trades a commodity for its equivalent price in<br />

money. This is the M-C phase, and it is known as buying. In this way, a market has been established,<br />

eliminating the bartering system. By having a mediating commodity (money), the<br />

direct exchange value <strong>of</strong> two commodities is masked, and no longer has to be determined.<br />

Next Message by DMorris is [909].<br />

[915] Ferox: graded A <strong>The</strong> C-M-C for <strong>of</strong> exchange, selling then buying, differs from the<br />

C-C form <strong>of</strong> exchange, direct commodity barter, in that C-M-C goes through the exchange


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 249<br />

<strong>of</strong> money as an intermediate. Money—the form <strong>of</strong> value designated by society as the general<br />

equivalent and therefore the commodity by which all other commodities can relate a respective<br />

value towards—allows the seller to exchange her commodity for a universal value form<br />

which can be exchanged for other commodities. In barter, two commodity producers must<br />

agree upon the magnitude <strong>of</strong> each commodity to be exchanged for the other. With money,<br />

the magnitude <strong>of</strong> value can be determined by price and not by the use or exchange values<br />

considered in direct barter.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong>re was a technical error. I meant to ask how the result <strong>of</strong> C-M-C differs from the direct barter, see [565].<br />

But since the exam version <strong>of</strong> the question did not say “result,” your answer is acceptable.<br />

Next Message by Ferox is [916].<br />

[934] ANK: C-M-C differs from C-C in a few ways:<br />

1. C-M-C does not happen simultaneously. <strong>The</strong> sale <strong>of</strong> the commodity takes place and<br />

the seller receives money from the exchange. Next, the individual purchases a commodity,<br />

different from the commodity that would have been used in a C-C barter, with use-value<br />

to them with the money from the purchase. C-C occurs simultaneously and money is not<br />

exchanged.<br />

2. In a C-M-C exchange, the seller works to get the most value for their commodity.<br />

With the money from that exchange, the individual purchases a commodity with use-value<br />

that they need. In C-C, there is no possible way to get the most value for your commodity<br />

and also get the commodity with use-value that you need. This is a contradiction.<br />

3. Because C-C happens simultaneously, both parties must be present for the barter. In<br />

C-M-C, the purchaser and seller do not need to be present at the same location because the<br />

exchange involves money.<br />

Next Message by ANK is [936].<br />

[948] She: graded A C-M-C differs markedly from a direct barter, or C-C exchange.<br />

According to the Annotations, Marx says that a sale or purchase is different because it has<br />

a different character than the direct barter exchange. Marx stresses that there is a difference<br />

in thought processes and decision criteria (281:3). Further in the Annotations, we read that,<br />

“In C-M-C, the sale is exclusively devoted to the realization <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

sold, without interference <strong>of</strong> the use-value which one intends to purchase afterwards, and<br />

the purchase is not burdened with the use-value which is sold to get the money,” (282:2).<br />

Marx also argues that C-C does not “recreate the conditions for the renewal <strong>of</strong> the process,”<br />

(287:1). Marx explains in great detail why and how society gradually becomes dependent<br />

and in constant need <strong>of</strong> a general equivalent. He then breaks down the C-M-C process into<br />

its separate steps to explain why it is different from C-C. In C-M-C, each step only requires<br />

one commodity. <strong>The</strong> commodity is only being used to realize its own value in money. Marx<br />

describes this as an asymmetric relation; whereas C-C is considered a symmetric relationship<br />

between two commodities. <strong>The</strong> commodities in C-M-C interact through an intermediary,<br />

which prevents them from actually interacting with each other. In direct barter, there is no<br />

such intermediary.<br />

Next Message by She is [949].<br />

[970] Deadfamous: graded A In [565] Hans points out some key difference <strong>of</strong> C-M-C<br />

and C-C, he stays away from talking about the consequences <strong>of</strong> the differences. This about<br />

sums up all the important differences right here I would say.<br />

250 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

In C-M-C<br />

1 <strong>The</strong> linen weaver gets koran for linen, but the seller <strong>of</strong> the koran does not get linen for<br />

his koran. He buys some<strong>thing</strong> different with his money most likely.<br />

2 <strong>The</strong> buyer <strong>of</strong> the linen must have money, and at the end, the bible seller has the money,<br />

ready to do the second half <strong>of</strong> his transaction. I.e., different transactions are interlinked.<br />

Bartering doesn’t leave anybody with money at the end to do a second barter as apposed to<br />

C-M-C which does.<br />

3 Sale and purchase do not have to take place at the same location or at the same time, as<br />

opposed to C-C<br />

Next Message by Deadfamous is [971].<br />

[990] School: c–m–c is when you have a farm and you are selling potatoes as a farmer<br />

you will take those commodities that have been produced and sell them for money, in turn to<br />

buy other commodities. c–c is considered direct bartering, where you remove money from<br />

the equation. <strong>The</strong> tricky <strong>thing</strong> about c–c is that the situation <strong>of</strong> crises is impossible because<br />

you remove money from the equation. Money has many different abilities to exchange itself<br />

for other commodities, but money itself also has value which can create a problem through<br />

money hoarding. By not completing the cycle <strong>of</strong> c–m–c this can create a crisis.<br />

Next Message by School is [1009].<br />

[991] Zohan: Should I Sell or Barter? <strong>The</strong>re are many ways in which C-M-C differs<br />

from the direct barter <strong>of</strong> commodities C-C.<br />

First, in the direct barter <strong>of</strong> commodities no money is needed. But, in this system <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange if a person wants a certain commodity they must <strong>first</strong> find a producer <strong>of</strong> that<br />

commodity who finds use value in what they have. For example if I produce cheese, but<br />

want a chicken, I must find someone with a chicken that finds enough use value in my<br />

cheese to trade me for a chicken. This type <strong>of</strong> system would be very difficult in today’s<br />

capitalist society. Whereas, in a C-M-C system I could <strong>first</strong> sell my cheese to someone for<br />

money and then use that money to buy a chicken.<br />

Second, in a C-C system once the trade has taken place, the commodities fall out <strong>of</strong><br />

circulation. Each party uses the commodity and doesn’t plan to resell it. On the other hand,<br />

in a C-M-C system money remains in circulation. I sell my cheese and receive money for it.<br />

I use the money that I receive to purchase a chicken, and the seller <strong>of</strong> the chicken uses the<br />

money they receive to purchase some<strong>thing</strong> else and so on and so on.<br />

Finally, in the discussions Hans [565] points out that the “sale and the purchase do not<br />

have to take place at the same location or at the same time.” On the other hand, in the C-C<br />

system the trade must take place at the same place and time.<br />

Next Message by Zohan is [1093].<br />

[1001] Spiral: C-C and C-M-C both result in equivalent exchanges <strong>of</strong> commodities but<br />

in the C-M-C this exchange is mediated by money. It appears ironic that a person would<br />

choose the longer C-M-C route for the same equivalent result. C-M-C opens up the door<br />

to transform buyers and sellers into debtors and creditors. Practical differences emerge to<br />

support this transformation such as the actual sale happening at a separate time and place<br />

from the exchange <strong>of</strong> the commodity unlike simple direct barter. <strong>The</strong> money commodity is


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 251<br />

imbued with mystical qualities under capitalism, i.e. becomes fetish-like, obscuring social<br />

relations between people and the labor-power used to create the commodity. Thinking <strong>of</strong><br />

one’s commodity in terms <strong>of</strong> the value it has in exchange for another commodity has a<br />

social connection between two persons. Multiple other connections are made when a person<br />

switches gear by thinking <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> their commodity in relation to numerous other<br />

commodities which can be purchased through the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities C-M-C.<br />

Next Message by Spiral is [1002].<br />

[1206] Kiko: C-M-C: You must <strong>first</strong> put your commodity on the market for sale, then<br />

you must actually have a “fair” price that has a willing taker and also the commodity must<br />

have a use value in relative terms to the price and for the taker. You must then exchange the<br />

commodity for money which in turn you take your $ to the market to find some<strong>thing</strong> that has<br />

use value for yourself and then again settle on a fair price and take your commodity home.<br />

C-C: is just as stated you directly barter your commodity against another commodity<br />

for some<strong>thing</strong> you feel has the same value as your own commodity. In this case there is<br />

no market just the consensus between two sellers about what their commodities are worth<br />

in direct relation. Furthermore there is no monetary exchange in this transaction just the<br />

agreement to exchange this and that.<br />

Hans: Even when it is a direct barter Marx always assumes the exchange proportions are given by the market, they<br />

are not decided by the traders.<br />

First Message by Kiko is [544].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 460 is 339 in 2003fa, 379 in 2004fa, 396 in 2007SP, and 478 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 460 Formulate Say’s Law. How is it proved? Which arguments does Marx bring<br />

to show that the pro<strong>of</strong> is invalid?<br />

[537] AlexDaily: graded A Say’s Law. Say’s law is an economic theory named after the<br />

French economist Jean Baptiste Say. <strong>The</strong> law states that there is never a deficit <strong>of</strong> demand.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, the way to increase purchasing power is to increase production. Furthermore,<br />

demand is created by supply and products are paid for by products. According to Marx the so<br />

called pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> Say’s law is “because every sale is a purchase and every purchase a sale. <strong>The</strong><br />

circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities necessarily implies equilibrium between sales and purchases”.<br />

Marx, however, thinks <strong>of</strong> this as silly dogma. Marx then goes on to show the pro<strong>of</strong> is<br />

invalid by saying “No one can sell unless someone else purchases. But no one is forwith<br />

bound to purchase, because he has just sold”. This makes Say’s law invalid because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

factor <strong>of</strong> personal choice. <strong>The</strong>re is no<strong>thing</strong> forcing anyone to purchase instantly because<br />

as the annotation states “even after many years the same money will still be able to make<br />

purchases.”<br />

Message [537] referenced by [538], [539], and [2012fa:819]. Next Message by AlexDaily is [558].<br />

[538] Babyceta: graded A+ Pouring Salt onto Say’s Wounds. Say’s Law asserts that<br />

demand in the marketplace is predicated upon supply, or that supply creates its own demand.<br />

Simply stated, this means that markets will always gravitate toward equilibrium, Say (and<br />

others) believe, since people inherently produce, not for the sake <strong>of</strong> production, but for the<br />

sake <strong>of</strong> consumption. <strong>The</strong>refore, gluts or crises were not possible in the long-run because<br />

the market will always self-correct. If goods are available, and since we are all mindless<br />

consumers attempting to maximize our utility, we will continue to consume whatever is<br />

252 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

supplied, regardless <strong>of</strong> money supply, inflation or economic shock. Supply is therefore<br />

inextricably linked to demand since, when goods are exchanged in the market, one cannot<br />

occur without the other. Essentially, people will only produce to exchange for the production<br />

<strong>of</strong> others. And since this is true for the individual, it must be true for the economy as a<br />

whole; aggregate supply must equal aggregate demand. Say’s Law has even been adopted<br />

by would-be presidential candidates. Most <strong>of</strong> us have heard <strong>of</strong> Ronald Reagan’s “supplyside”<br />

economics. In 1980, this platform secured him a landslide victory over Jimmy Carter.<br />

Although Say’s Law has been widely embraced as gospel by most neo-classical and mainstream<br />

economists, it has also, however, had its share <strong>of</strong> critics. Keynes, in General <strong>The</strong>ory<br />

(1937), disputes Say based upon his observation <strong>of</strong> business cycles and the effects <strong>of</strong> <strong>The</strong><br />

Great Depression (at the time, it was widely believed that over-production was the primary<br />

cause <strong>of</strong> the Depression). For Say’s Law to hold, Keynes observed, the demand for labor<br />

should also be derived from supply. But clearly, with unemployment over 20%, this was<br />

not the case. Additionally, Keynes believed that the breakdown in Say’s Law came about<br />

because <strong>of</strong> the disequilibrium between planned savings and planned investment. Savings<br />

was a function <strong>of</strong> current investment, while investment was a function <strong>of</strong> a number <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s,<br />

including the “animal spirits” <strong>of</strong> investors (Anderson, 2001).<br />

I believe AlexDaily [537] was accurate when he/she stated that the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> Say’s Law,<br />

for Marx, was the observation that “every sale is a purchase, and every purchase is a sale, the<br />

circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities necessarily implies an equilibrium between sales and purchases”<br />

(C-M is also M-C). But I also believe that Marx’s ridicule <strong>of</strong> Say has deeper inplications.<br />

Marx goes on to assert that this “tautology” is “foolish” because not “every seller brings his<br />

own buyer to the market with him.” To Marx, these are two separate acts, “<strong>of</strong> polar and opposite<br />

character,” and sellers do not necessarily bring their products to the market because their<br />

goal is to immediately obtain other commodities. I agree with Josh’s supplement to Deni<br />

[2007SP:600] where he writes that sellers take their commodities to the market because the<br />

commodity they wish to sell holds the incorrect use-value for their purposes. <strong>The</strong>refore,<br />

the “seller will bring his/her commodities to the market regardless <strong>of</strong> his/her desire to obtain<br />

some other commodity.” Anyone who has ever been to a garage sale understands this<br />

implicitly.<br />

I illustrate Keynes’ objection with Say’s Law not to add “fluff” to my response, but to<br />

show how it differs from Marx’s. I believe this is important to understanding Marx, and his<br />

use <strong>of</strong> dialectal reasoning, which Hans elaborates extensively on [2007SP:860]. Most refutations<br />

to Say are based on simple reasoning; if our society doubled its supply (production)<br />

<strong>of</strong> salt, for example, there would not necessarily be a doubling in the demand for salt; there<br />

would most likely be a surplus or glut <strong>of</strong> salt (how much salt do we really need?). Marx,<br />

I believe, doesn’t object to Say based on overproduction, or unemployment, or investment<br />

equaling savings, or any such nonsense. Well, at least not initially. He states at the end <strong>of</strong> the<br />

passage that the possibility <strong>of</strong> crises does exist, but their actuality does not yet exist “from<br />

the standpoint <strong>of</strong> the simple circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities.”<br />

Marx takes two pages to invalidate Say to establish a progression <strong>of</strong> dialectical reasoning<br />

because, as Hegel says and Hans reminds us periodically, every<strong>thing</strong> that exists has its opposite<br />

in itself. If, as Marx says, sale and purchase are indeed “separate acts, <strong>of</strong> polar and


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 253<br />

opposite character,” and we know from the previous section that this is true (“from hands in<br />

which they are non-use-values to hands in which they are use-values, it is a process <strong>of</strong> social<br />

metabolism”) and commodities indeed incur a “metamorphosis,” then to group sale and<br />

purchase as Siamese twins invalidates the whole idea <strong>of</strong> separation (or dialectics). I contend<br />

that the most important and relevant passage in the section is 208:2/o: ”<strong>The</strong>re is an antithesis,<br />

immanent in the commodity, between use-value and value, between private labour which<br />

must manifest itself as directly social labour, and a particular concrete kind <strong>of</strong> labour which<br />

counts as merely abstract universal labour, between the conversion <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s into persons<br />

and the conversion <strong>of</strong> persons into <strong>thing</strong>s; the antithetical phases <strong>of</strong> the metamorphosis <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity are developed forms <strong>of</strong> motion <strong>of</strong> this immanent contradiction.” Marx invalidates<br />

Say’s Law to emphasize that his critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism to this point has been a careful<br />

dialectical dissection: exchange-value and use-value, and the dual nature <strong>of</strong> commodities;<br />

<strong>of</strong> socially necessary labor and congealed abstract labor, and how value is determined; <strong>of</strong><br />

fetishism <strong>of</strong> commodities and the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities, or <strong>of</strong> the personification<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s and the reification <strong>of</strong> persons; and finally <strong>of</strong> the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities,<br />

and the genesis <strong>of</strong> money. In the introduction, I stated that Say (and others) proclaim that<br />

people produce for the sake <strong>of</strong> consumption, and in the simple exchange societies Marx’s<br />

pro<strong>of</strong> would tend to validate this claim. But in a complex capitalist system, I believe Marx<br />

would say that people may produce to consume, but since workers do not control the social<br />

relations <strong>of</strong> commodity production, the capitalist produces for the sake <strong>of</strong> production, pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

and exploitation. And that is the difference.<br />

Message [538] referenced by [539] and [2012fa:819]. Next Message by Babyceta is [539].<br />

[539] Babyceta: Beating Me to the Punch. I believe my answer [538] to Q:460 actually<br />

overflows into Q:461. I apologize for this. However, AlexDaily’s submission [537] to Q:460<br />

popped up as I was halfway through my answer, so I felt compelled to elaborate. I am curious<br />

if anyone else dreads getting another students submission, in the middle <strong>of</strong> writing theirs,<br />

which totally “beats them to the punch” and renders their response unnecessary? I hope I’m<br />

not the only one.<br />

Next Message by Babyceta is [583].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 462 is 376 in 2005fa, 398 in 2007SP, 411 in 2008SP, 412 in 2008fa, 427<br />

in 2009fa, 459 in 2011fa, and 480 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 462 How does Marx define a crisis?<br />

[521] Hans: Humans as Stewarts <strong>of</strong> the Earth. <strong>The</strong> present readings give a glimpse into<br />

Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> crisis. This is an exam question, i.e., I find this important enough that I<br />

want everyone in class to learn Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> crisis. Right now I will not speak about<br />

Marx’s definition but about modern counterparts <strong>of</strong> Marx’s crisis theory.<br />

Marx was really an optimist; he thought every crisis is a healing process. Today we are no<br />

longer so sure. On the one hand, the is the theoretical framework <strong>of</strong> the Resilience Alliance<br />

http://www.resalliance.org/<br />

can be considered a modern crisis theory. And James Lovelock has written about crisis<br />

too, please see [2007SP:611]. Here is Lovelock’s crisis theory. In a disease, i.e., when a host<br />

is attacked by disease organism, Lovelock says, there are four possible outcomes:<br />

254 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(1) destruction <strong>of</strong> the invading disease organisms;<br />

(2) chronic infection;<br />

(3) destruction <strong>of</strong> the host;<br />

(4) symbiosis – a lasting relationship <strong>of</strong> mutual benefit to the host and the invader.<br />

Outcome (4) is <strong>of</strong>ten overlooked, but modern molecular biology knows that many features<br />

<strong>of</strong> our bodies such as the bacterial fauna <strong>of</strong> our intestines which helps us digest, was<br />

originally invading hostile organisms which were reined in into a symbiotic relationship. In<br />

his 2006 book Revenge <strong>of</strong> Gaia Lovelock argued against humans trying to be stewards <strong>of</strong> the<br />

earth. Similar to Frida [166] Lovelock said that it would be much better if humans learned<br />

to live within the boundaries <strong>of</strong> the earth without damaging it. But his arguments had a<br />

different shade than Frida’s, they were a little more hard-nosed. He said: even if human<br />

succeed in managing the earth and consciously controlling those many mechanisms which<br />

right now are being done automatically, this will be incredibly expensive, and we would be<br />

much better <strong>of</strong>f not to tamper with the system at all and get all the ecosystem services for<br />

free.<br />

In his later book Vanishing Gaia Lovelock’s thinking has evolved. Here he says catastrophe<br />

will come. Humans will try geoengineering and probably miserably fail at <strong>first</strong>, but the<br />

pristine planet which we are presently watching disappear beneath our feet will never come<br />

back. Climate catastrophe is our expulsion from the paradise. We will inherit a damaged<br />

planet, and we will try to manage and fix it as best as possible. Over many generations humans<br />

will learn to do this. In the future humans will become intelligent stewards <strong>of</strong> the earth<br />

and will learn to do <strong>thing</strong>s better than the pristine planet did by itself; we may be able to recover<br />

better from big meteorites, and we will be better able to deal with the gradual heating<br />

<strong>of</strong> the sun. In this way the planet with human stewards will remain livable for a longer time<br />

than a planet without humans. Here he is talking in timespans <strong>of</strong> billions <strong>of</strong> years, so this is<br />

to be taken with a grain <strong>of</strong> salt.<br />

In terms <strong>of</strong> his crisis patterns, he is saying that the planet is going through (2), then almost<br />

(1), and then in the very long run (4) in turn:<br />

(2) a low-level chronic disease <strong>of</strong> the planet due to human activity from overhunting to<br />

agriculture has been going on for a long time now.<br />

(1) In the coming climate crisis the invading organism (humans) will almost go extinct—<br />

while the majority <strong>of</strong> other species will in fact go extinct.<br />

(4) but over the very long run there will be symbiosis.<br />

As boundary conditions he assumes: life itself is so resilient that it will never disappear<br />

due to human activity, and humans in turn are too smart they will never be entirely extinguished<br />

either (at least not until the sun becomes too hot in a few billion years).<br />

Message [521] referenced by [591]. Next Message by Hans is [526].<br />

Term Paper 468 is 802 in 2004fa, 403 in 2007SP, and 417 in 2008fa:<br />

Term Paper 468 Essay about Chapter Three, Section 2.b: <strong>The</strong> Flow <strong>of</strong> Money


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 255<br />

[575] Atticus, Cmellen, Husani, Jo, and Kaimani: graded A Marx explains the flow <strong>of</strong><br />

money as Commodity–Money–Commodity (C-M-C). In this process, the original commodity<br />

is not the same as the ending commodity. <strong>The</strong> seller does not have a use-value for the<br />

commodity he owns, he therefore sells it in exchange for money. To complete the cycle, he<br />

should then in turn buy a commodity with the money that has a use-value for him. Gaining<br />

use-value is the purpose <strong>of</strong> the C-M-C flow cycle.<br />

Money, in this circumstance, lends way to the transaction as a unit <strong>of</strong> exchange (instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity for a commodity). When a transaction is made, there is always two steps<br />

taking place simultaneously; money (M) is simultaneously commodity for money (C-M) for<br />

the seller, and money for commodity (M-C) for the buyer. This demonstrates that the flow<br />

<strong>of</strong> money is a one-sided progression, while the progression <strong>of</strong> the commodity is two-sided.<br />

This is due to the fact that any particular piece <strong>of</strong> money does not transition through these<br />

two explained stages (as every given commodity does). Money portrays the function <strong>of</strong><br />

circulation only for the reason that value <strong>of</strong> commodities has taken on an independent shape<br />

in the form <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re must be two complete metamorphosis stages to the circulation process. First, metamorphosis<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity is evident “not only as money movement, but also that <strong>of</strong> commodity<br />

itself” (Das Kapital pg 112). If the seller at this point holds the money and does not<br />

use it to obtain a commodity with use-value to him, it will remain in the <strong>first</strong> metamorphic<br />

stage. <strong>The</strong> second metamorphosis, however, is only seen as the movement <strong>of</strong> money.To<br />

complete the flow cycle, the “commodity must return to the same point in the shape <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity” (Das Kapital pg 112). Once the cycle <strong>of</strong> selling the commodity (with no usevalue<br />

to the current owner) enables the possessor to buy another commodity (with use-value)<br />

is complete, the money again leaves the hands <strong>of</strong> its possessor; hence, C-M-C. However, the<br />

C-M-C cycle is affected directly and indirectly by the actual flow or “Velocity” at which the<br />

money hits the market. Hans, stated “the velocity <strong>of</strong> money does not depend on the quantity<br />

<strong>of</strong> money in circulation. <strong>The</strong> causality goes in the other direction, the quantity <strong>of</strong> money in<br />

circulation depends on the velocity.” (Hans’ note in [2008fa:657])<br />

Velocity <strong>of</strong> Money<br />

How rapidly these metamorphoses occur in a society is the velocity <strong>of</strong> money. If commodities<br />

become infrequently transformed into money; or as Marx would put it, the dissolution<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities “into the mere equivalent form <strong>of</strong> the commodity” makes this happen<br />

infrequently, then the velocity <strong>of</strong> money is low. (Das Kapital pg 207.) <strong>The</strong> “mere equivalent<br />

form” or aliquot substance that makes the exchange between money and commodities possible<br />

is the value congealed in all commodities by labor. When the velocity <strong>of</strong> money in a<br />

capitalistic society is low- people begin to hold on to their money and fewer transactions are<br />

made. <strong>The</strong>n, the overall circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities is becomes low. This can cause great<br />

disruptions in the lives <strong>of</strong> an affected population. Some <strong>of</strong> the various causes <strong>of</strong> these disruptions<br />

are: crises, economic bubbles, expectations, high price levels relative to the supply<br />

<strong>of</strong> money, etc.<br />

Money, the representation <strong>of</strong> value, is circulated by the removal <strong>of</strong> commodities from the<br />

exchange processes. This removal <strong>of</strong> commodities from the circulation by buyers for their<br />

256 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

use-values is called consumption. (Das Kapital pg 211.) A steadily growing velocity <strong>of</strong><br />

money is necessary for a capitalistic economy with a growing population to sustain itself.<br />

Without a radical and revolutionizing change in the cultural mindset, social relations and<br />

modes <strong>of</strong> subsistence a baker cannot buy fuel to heat his home unless the coat tailor purchases<br />

his bread; a tailor cannot buy bread unless the weaver purchases his coat; a weaver<br />

cannot purchase a coat unless the seamstress purchases linen; and so on. This is a simplified<br />

version <strong>of</strong> a seemingly, complex web <strong>of</strong> transactions.<br />

This constant circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities would not be possible without some form <strong>of</strong><br />

money. Trade could still exist but, there would be many more limitations and the massive<br />

circulation <strong>of</strong> money and goods; characteristic <strong>of</strong> capitalism would be non-existent. <strong>The</strong>re<br />

would be fewer social divisions <strong>of</strong> labor and they would be far less complex. People would<br />

be, to a greater degree than in a capitalistic society, more self-sufficient. However, disparities<br />

in the distribution <strong>of</strong> wealth among members <strong>of</strong> a society exist in many other forms <strong>of</strong><br />

economies.<br />

Money Supply<br />

<strong>The</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> money this circulation requires is “determined beforehand by the sum<br />

<strong>of</strong> the prices <strong>of</strong> all these commodities” (Das Kapital pg 213). However, this determined<br />

quantity <strong>of</strong> money can vary, due to either a change in demand, a new source <strong>of</strong> gold or other<br />

valuable metal is discovered; a change in customs in how money is exchanged or a number <strong>of</strong><br />

other <strong>thing</strong>s. A change in the money supply while circulation remains relatively unchanged<br />

only determines the imaginary nominal prices <strong>of</strong> commodities, not their real value. Increases<br />

in the money supply while productivity remains unchanged only leads to inflation.<br />

Changes in the socially determined amount <strong>of</strong> necessary labor time in private production<br />

lead to changes in the value <strong>of</strong> commodities. Subsequently, this is unconsciously realized on<br />

the surface in the exchange-values <strong>of</strong> commodities. Decreasing real value <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

translates into increasing subversion <strong>of</strong> the commodity producing community. Increased<br />

output, or demand, leads to a greater demand <strong>of</strong> money. <strong>The</strong> velocity <strong>of</strong> this circulation<br />

increases regardless <strong>of</strong> money supply and creates immense pressure on the environment<br />

which is is ultimately unsustainable.<br />

Firms compete with one another by increasing productivity but only end up homogenizing<br />

labor processes and prices. This constant competition among firms with one another<br />

leads to an increased number <strong>of</strong> social divisions in labor. This makes the people increasingly<br />

dependent on a variety <strong>of</strong> producers to meet their basic subsistence needs because they<br />

are only skilled at a specialized task and become incapable <strong>of</strong> taking care <strong>of</strong> themselves.<br />

Subordination <strong>of</strong> the people by an elite minority becomes inevitable.<br />

Quantity <strong>of</strong> Money and Price<br />

Marx rejects the Capitalist “illusion” that the quantity <strong>of</strong> money affects prices. He explains<br />

that there are two other factors that have direct effects on the movements <strong>of</strong> the price<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities. <strong>The</strong>se two effects are: <strong>first</strong>, changes in the quantities <strong>of</strong> commodities in<br />

the market and second, changes in the velocity <strong>of</strong> circulation <strong>of</strong> money. Marx states this law<br />

as follows, “given the sum <strong>of</strong> the values <strong>of</strong> commodities, and the average rapidity <strong>of</strong> their


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 257<br />

metamorphoses, the quantity <strong>of</strong> money or <strong>of</strong> the material <strong>of</strong> money in circulation depends<br />

on its own value.” (Das Kapital pg 219)<br />

Marx gives a few examples to show us how these factors affect each other. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong><br />

example, shows that assuming that prices remain constant, the circulating medium may increase<br />

as a result <strong>of</strong> an increase in the quantity <strong>of</strong> commodities or a decrease in the velocity<br />

<strong>of</strong> circulation <strong>of</strong> money, or both. In the inverse <strong>of</strong> this equation, also keeping prices constant,<br />

a decrease in the circulating medium would result from a decrease in the quantity <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities or an increase in the velocity <strong>of</strong> circulation <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Assuming that the number <strong>of</strong> commodities in circulation remains constant; if prices <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities increase, the quantity <strong>of</strong> circulating medium will also remain constant as long<br />

as the number <strong>of</strong> commodities decreases in direct proportion to the increase <strong>of</strong> the prices OR<br />

if the velocity <strong>of</strong> monetary circulation increases at the same rate as the prices rise.<br />

<strong>The</strong> idea that quantity <strong>of</strong> money effects prices is based on the Capitalist notion that commodities<br />

enter the exchange process without a price. Or, that they don’t have value until one<br />

is assigned to them by the market. It also relies on the assumption that money enters the<br />

exchange process without a value. Both concepts are rejected by Marx.<br />

Conclusion<br />

<strong>The</strong> flow <strong>of</strong> money is a passive reflection <strong>of</strong> the active metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> commodity<br />

to commodity. Commodities are continually converted to use-values; while money is continually<br />

used in the exchange process. In contrast, to the Capitalist view that quantity <strong>of</strong><br />

currency will change prices <strong>of</strong> commodities, Marx maintains that the opposite is true. That<br />

the quantity <strong>of</strong> currency in circulation is determined by the sum <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

in circulation, and by the average velocity <strong>of</strong> the circulation <strong>of</strong> money. (Das Kapital pg.<br />

219.)<br />

Cmellen: Cmellen response to feedback [620]<br />

I made an error in writing the <strong>first</strong> paragraph <strong>of</strong> my group, Priceless’ term paper. I should have written about<br />

the Flow <strong>of</strong> Money:<br />

Marx explains <strong>The</strong> flow <strong>of</strong> money is a “constant removal from its starting-point” (Das Kapital p111). Commodities<br />

move in a circular motion, from one owner’s hands to another, yet money is not included in this circular<br />

movement. Its ceaseless undertaking to move further away from its original source.<br />

Also, it was never my intention to lead the reader to think that “C-M-C is not a circle.” For, in fact, to complete<br />

the cycle, the “commodity must return to the same point in the shape <strong>of</strong> a commodity” (Das Kapital pg 112). Once<br />

the CYCLE <strong>of</strong> selling the commodity (with no use-value to the current owner) enables the possessor to buy another<br />

commodity (with use-value) is complete, the money again leaves the hands <strong>of</strong> its possessor; hence, C-M-C Circle.<br />

Thank you for your input Hans.<br />

Message [575] referenced by [589] and [620]. Next Message by Atticus is [629], Next Message by Cmellen is<br />

[580], Next Message by Husani is [576], Next Message by Jo is [705], and Next Message by Kaimani is [625].<br />

[620] Hans: Termpaper Discussion. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> sentence <strong>of</strong> term paper [575] says: “Marx<br />

explains the flow <strong>of</strong> money as Commodity–Money–Commodity (C-M-C).” No he doesn’t<br />

and it isn’t. A careless reader might get this impression because the <strong>first</strong> sentence <strong>of</strong> subsection<br />

2b in 210:1 indeed talks about C-M-C. But for Marx this C-M-C is only the jumping-<strong>of</strong>f<br />

point for his discussion <strong>of</strong> the flow <strong>of</strong> money. Marx enters the discussion <strong>of</strong> the flow <strong>of</strong><br />

money with the observation that C-M-C is a circle but money keeps getting dislodged and<br />

258 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

does not go in a circle—that’s why section 2b is not called “circuit <strong>of</strong> money” but “flow <strong>of</strong><br />

money.”<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is another little quirk. <strong>The</strong> term paper says that C-M-C is not a circle—because<br />

the forms <strong>of</strong> the <strong>first</strong> and second C have, as Marx says in 207:1, “opposite” determinations:<br />

the beginning C is a non-use-value for its owner, and the C at the end is a use-value for its<br />

owner. Despite this, Marx says very clearly in both places, 207:1 and 210:1, that C-M-C is<br />

a circle.<br />

Marx does not contradict himself here. <strong>The</strong> entire movement being a circle does not<br />

exclude but even requires that whatever goes through this circle has opposite determinations<br />

at the beginning and at the end: for instance a train going in a circle at the beginning is<br />

driving out <strong>of</strong> the station while at the end it is driving into the station.<br />

I made this mistake myself. <strong>The</strong> Annotations, not in the version we are using for this<br />

class, but in a more recent version which can be downloaded from the class home page,<br />

contained the sentence: “It is not quite a circuit, because the form <strong>of</strong> the <strong>first</strong> C is not exactly<br />

equal to the form <strong>of</strong> the second C.” I have changed this now, so the next version will no<br />

longer have this mistake.<br />

So I have to thank the term paper group with the wonderful name “Priceless” that their<br />

term paper caused me to discover this error. I am acting here like a capitalist. I am benefiting<br />

from our co-operation without paying you for your share in it (except this thank you). In<br />

chapter Thirteen, 447:1, Marx calls this the “social productive powers <strong>of</strong> labor.” A team <strong>of</strong><br />

workers co-operating can accomplish <strong>thing</strong>s which none <strong>of</strong> them could have done individually.<br />

Who gets the benefits <strong>of</strong> this co-operation? <strong>The</strong> capitalist. See my [2005fa:1402]. <strong>The</strong><br />

worker, by contrast, is harmed by it. Marx writes in 798:4/o:<br />

We saw in Part IV, when analyzing the production <strong>of</strong> relative surplus-value,<br />

that within the capitalist system all methods for raising the social productive<br />

powers <strong>of</strong> labor are put into effect at the expense <strong>of</strong> the individual<br />

worker; that all means for the development <strong>of</strong> production undergo a dialectical<br />

inversion so that they become means <strong>of</strong> domination and exploitation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the producers; they distort the worker into a fragment <strong>of</strong> a man, they<br />

degrade him to the level <strong>of</strong> an appendage <strong>of</strong> a machine, they destroy the<br />

actual content <strong>of</strong> his labor by turning it into a torment; they alienate from<br />

him the intellectual potentialities <strong>of</strong> the labor process in the same proportion<br />

as science is incorporated in it as an independent power; they deform<br />

the conditions under which he works, subject him during the labor process<br />

to a despotism the more hateful for its meanness; they transform his lifetime<br />

into working-time, and drag his wife and child beneath the wheels <strong>of</strong><br />

the juggernaut <strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

If you write a term paper, please read the text carefully. I cannot expect you to “get” all<br />

the implications <strong>of</strong> Marx’s text, but if you write some<strong>thing</strong> which could have been corrected<br />

by just looking at the same paragraph more closely, this counts against you.<br />

Message [620] referenced by [575]. Next Message by Hans is [623].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 259<br />

Multiple Choice <strong>Question</strong> 469 <strong>The</strong> discovery <strong>of</strong> new gold mines making gold more abundant<br />

and easier accessible than before triggers two <strong>of</strong> the following causal mechanisms,<br />

according to Marx’s theory. One other <strong>of</strong> the causal mechanisms listed below is an indirect<br />

effect due to the combination <strong>of</strong> the two basic mechanisms, and the other three mechanisms<br />

have the causality reversed. Check the two basic effects.<br />

• (a) the amount <strong>of</strong> money circulating increases because the value <strong>of</strong> money decreases.<br />

• (b) the amount <strong>of</strong> money circulating increases because prices rise.<br />

• (c) prices rise because the value <strong>of</strong> money decreases.<br />

• (d) prices rise because the amount <strong>of</strong> money circulating increases.<br />

• (e) the value <strong>of</strong> money decreases because the amount <strong>of</strong> money circulating increases.<br />

• (f) the value <strong>of</strong> money decreases because prices rise.<br />

[997] Hans: Marx did not believe in the quantity theory <strong>of</strong> money. This was one <strong>of</strong> the<br />

questions on yesterday’s exam.<br />

<strong>The</strong> causal sequence as Marx sees it is that <strong>first</strong> (c) happens, and because <strong>of</strong> (c), then (b)<br />

happens. In other words, new discoveries <strong>of</strong> gold cause the value <strong>of</strong> gold to fall, therefore<br />

prices rise, and the higher prices require more money in circulation.<br />

(a) has therefore the causality in the right order but it is an indirect effect: more money<br />

in circulation does not come directly from a lower value <strong>of</strong> gold, but it comes from higer<br />

prices, and the higher prices come from a lower value <strong>of</strong> gold.<br />

(d) is the quantity theory <strong>of</strong> money, which says that the value <strong>of</strong> money depends on its<br />

quantity. Marx was not a quantity theorist. According to Marx, the quantity theory has the<br />

causality reversed. Prices rise because the value <strong>of</strong> money decreases. <strong>The</strong>se higher prices<br />

then have the consequence that the amount <strong>of</strong> money circulating increases.<br />

(e) is a demand and supply theory, value decreasing because supply increases. Marx<br />

keeps saying that demand and supply do not determine value.<br />

(f) is a theory in which values are determined by prices, i.e., value is determined in circulation.<br />

Marx keeps emphasizing that value is determined in production.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [1076].<br />

Term Paper 470 is 903 in 2000fa, 903 in 2001fa, and 418 in 2008fa:<br />

Term Paper 470 Essay about Chapter Three, Section 2.c: Coins and Symbols <strong>of</strong> Value<br />

[585] Fisher and KA: In section (c) “Coin. <strong>The</strong> Symbol <strong>of</strong> Value” in Chapter 3, Marx<br />

illustrates how coins become a circulation medium <strong>of</strong> money. <strong>The</strong> physical nature <strong>of</strong> coins<br />

<strong>of</strong> being a gold or silver composition reveals the “money-names” <strong>of</strong> this commodity only<br />

through circulation. Without the means <strong>of</strong> circulation, gold and silver is merely a commodity<br />

that can be exchanged for another commodity <strong>of</strong> equal value. <strong>The</strong> circulation nature <strong>of</strong><br />

money enables gold and silver to act as this medium <strong>of</strong> exchange. In 221:1/o Marx mentions<br />

that when these gold or silver coins are worn on uniforms, this illustrates the different state<br />

<strong>of</strong> value these coins have; the value <strong>of</strong> its decorative form. However, when these coins are<br />

removed from the uniform they are held in a different context in the world market, as money.<br />

260 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Marx goes further to illustrate the physical differences between coins and bullions as<br />

being one in the same if its function is <strong>of</strong> a transaction base. Coins and bullions act as<br />

a medium <strong>of</strong> exchange with the only difference being in their production state. A coin is<br />

passed through the production state <strong>of</strong> minting to transform into circulation tool. As coins<br />

move throughout circulation they become worn down with the nominal and real content<br />

being <strong>of</strong> different states. <strong>The</strong> circulation <strong>of</strong> coins decreases the weight <strong>of</strong> the coin and<br />

therefore its value, since its value is dependent on its weight. While the real nature <strong>of</strong> this<br />

commodity transformed into a common medium <strong>of</strong> exchange is physically diminished, its<br />

symbolic value maintains. <strong>The</strong> symbolic value is inherent in the commodity being a coin or<br />

circulation tool.<br />

It is further discussed that even though the circulation <strong>of</strong> this coin disjoints the real and<br />

nominal content, it is the symbolic nature <strong>of</strong> the coin that maintains the value. <strong>The</strong> replacing<br />

<strong>of</strong> the coin with some other metallic form could also serve as a medium <strong>of</strong> exchange so long<br />

as the symbolic nature maintains while the physical nature diminishes. <strong>The</strong> example Marx<br />

uses is by incorporating smaller quantities <strong>of</strong> silver and gold into the minting <strong>of</strong> the coin<br />

and substituting copper for silver and silver for gold. <strong>The</strong> symbolic nature maintains <strong>of</strong> the<br />

coin in regions <strong>of</strong> more frequent circulation. <strong>The</strong> circulation <strong>of</strong> this modified coin must still<br />

maintain some portion <strong>of</strong> gold and silver in order to render the capitalization <strong>of</strong> the lower<br />

valued metal from taking over the physical and symbolic nature <strong>of</strong> the coin.<br />

<strong>The</strong> physical nature <strong>of</strong> the modified coin is not <strong>of</strong> the same physical strength <strong>of</strong> a pure gold<br />

coin, and therefore deteriorates more rapidly as it passes through circulation. <strong>The</strong> physical<br />

weight <strong>of</strong> this modified coin no longer determines the value <strong>of</strong> the coin, as the value is<br />

independent <strong>of</strong> its physical property; the symbolic nature is the determinant <strong>of</strong> its value. At<br />

this point, the property <strong>of</strong> gold in a coin is independent in its valuation. <strong>The</strong> valuation is<br />

strictly symbolic with the medium <strong>of</strong> exchange. <strong>The</strong> transformation <strong>of</strong> gold to coins and<br />

then finally to paper money (notes) is the life cycle <strong>of</strong> the circulation <strong>of</strong> money, with the<br />

common denominator being its symbolic nature.<br />

Marx begins this next section by pointing out that the state creates paper money with<br />

different symbols to represent different values <strong>of</strong> gold that would be circulating otherwise.<br />

<strong>The</strong> examples that Marx uses, “£1, £5, etc.” are printed and represent a gold value that would<br />

be used in the place <strong>of</strong> the paper money in making market exchanges or transactions. Marx<br />

also mentions that there is indeed a law that states that paper money should not be made or<br />

put into circulation above the amount <strong>of</strong> gold or silver that would be used if had not been<br />

replaced by the symbols. If the paper money did not represent a real value <strong>of</strong> gold then the<br />

money would cease to have exchange value or circulate as a medium <strong>of</strong> exchange.<br />

Once a country keeps enough gold on hand to support the paper money in circulation, the<br />

gold will undergo changes <strong>of</strong> its constituent parts. This will not change the amount or, as<br />

Marx put it, “the continuity <strong>of</strong> its circulation”. If more paper money is in circulation than<br />

there is gold to back it, then “there is a danger <strong>of</strong> falling into disrepute”. <strong>The</strong> only way to<br />

keep paper money in circulation is to have enough gold on hand to back it. Too much paper<br />

money would then cause the value <strong>of</strong> gold to go down. Marx gives an example <strong>of</strong> how one<br />

paper symbol representing 1/4 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold would change and possibly represent 1/8 ounce<br />

<strong>of</strong> gold instead.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 261<br />

Money, according to Marx, is a representation <strong>of</strong> the symbol <strong>of</strong> value for gold or silver.<br />

Only if paper represents gold, does money have a value. Paper money and coins are just a<br />

circulating medium and no<strong>thing</strong> else. Coins and paper money can only act as a medium for<br />

exchange if they are circulating, and there is gold to support them.<br />

<strong>The</strong> action <strong>of</strong> the state or country in which a currency exists, must be “within that inner<br />

sphere <strong>of</strong> circulation which is coterminous with the territories <strong>of</strong> the community”, which<br />

implies that the people surrounding the economic region accept the paper money or coins as<br />

a symbol <strong>of</strong> exchange. If people do not accept paper money or coins as a representation <strong>of</strong><br />

gold or silver, then people would ultimately trade commodity for commodity or use gold as<br />

the standard.<br />

Hans: You had consistently (4 times) written “median” <strong>of</strong> circulation (should have been “medium”). I changed it<br />

into “means” because this is a simpler word for the same <strong>thing</strong>.<br />

In addition to [623], I’d like to point out another misreading. Your third sentence says<br />

<strong>The</strong> physical nature <strong>of</strong> coins <strong>of</strong> being a gold or silver composition reveals the “money-names”<br />

<strong>of</strong> this commodity only through circulation. Without the means <strong>of</strong> circulation, gold and silver<br />

is merely a commodity that can be exchanged for another commodity <strong>of</strong> equal value.<br />

<strong>The</strong> original in 221:1/o says:<br />

An amount <strong>of</strong> gold, whose weight is referred to by the prices or money-names <strong>of</strong> the commodities,<br />

must confront these commodities, within circulation, as coins or pieces <strong>of</strong> gold <strong>of</strong><br />

the same denomination.<br />

Marx describes here how the function <strong>of</strong> gold as measure <strong>of</strong> value and means <strong>of</strong> circulation leads to the minting<br />

<strong>of</strong> gold coins. “Measure <strong>of</strong> value” means that all prices are denominated in gold. <strong>The</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> gold which is<br />

indicated in these prices is therefore necessary to circulate the commodity. <strong>The</strong>refore gold must be available in<br />

pieces which make it easy to count out exactly as much gold as indicated by the prices. Marx calls the prices<br />

“money names” because they are not denominated in ounces <strong>of</strong> gold but in a different denomination.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is also a misreading in your last paragraph. “Coterminous” means that the neighboring countries do not<br />

accept your national currency as money.<br />

Message [585] referenced by [589], [611], and [623]. Next Message by Fisher is [837] and Next Message by KA<br />

is [1060].<br />

[611] Robert: Coins: Blinding Symbols <strong>of</strong> Value. Notwithstanding Hans admonition to<br />

not “send fluff just to help your peers” I think that Fisher and KA [585] did a great job on<br />

their analysis <strong>of</strong> what Marx wrote in Section 2.c <strong>of</strong> Chapter 3.<br />

Nevertheless, I was thinking over the weekend why it would be so important to Marx to<br />

go into this careful explanation about the minting <strong>of</strong> coins or the creation <strong>of</strong> paper money. At<br />

the same time I was thinking about Babyceta’s [583] thoughts regarding our fetish for money.<br />

I wonder if there is not some “intent” in the powers that be, i.e., the capitalist who use the<br />

power <strong>of</strong> the state as their tool, to emboss coins and paper money with symbols <strong>of</strong> power.<br />

<strong>The</strong> features <strong>of</strong> Caesars, Kings, Presidents and other powerful historic people or symbols <strong>of</strong><br />

liberty (like Lady Liberty), Justice (blind justice holding the scales) and Freedom (the Eagle)<br />

or great monuments, buildings and other seats <strong>of</strong> power typically adorn our money.<br />

<strong>The</strong> symbolic implication <strong>of</strong> holding or getting money then is one <strong>of</strong> getting or holding<br />

power. We may seek to turn our labor (via commodity production) into money because we<br />

believe having money not only allows us to acquire use-values we need but we may believe<br />

it give us the power <strong>of</strong> the symbols it bears.<br />

262 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans [610] points out that Marx taught us that money is blinding. It blinds us to the<br />

fetish character <strong>of</strong> commodities. Capitalist make pr<strong>of</strong>its by selling commodities (including<br />

the commodity <strong>of</strong> labor-power). To the extent money blinds us as to the real nature <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities, the social arrangements <strong>of</strong> exploited labor imbued in each commodity, then<br />

capitalist can proceed with their exploitation unhampered by social outcry or indignation.<br />

If money can be made even more dazzling by becoming symbols not only <strong>of</strong> value but <strong>of</strong><br />

power then all the better for the continued deception.<br />

Hans: This is not a discussion <strong>of</strong> Fisher and KA’s termpaper but these are your own musings about Section 2.c <strong>of</strong><br />

Chapter 3 in connection with the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Next Message by Robert is [675].<br />

[623] Hans: Bizarre Example <strong>of</strong> Misreading. In 221:1/o, Marx writes:<br />

In the different national uniforms worn at home by gold and silver as coins,<br />

but taken <strong>of</strong>f again when they circulate on the world market, the separation<br />

between the internal or national spheres <strong>of</strong> commodity circulation and its<br />

universal sphere, the world market, manifests itself.<br />

In order to understand Marx’s uniform metaphor, you need some facts <strong>of</strong> life at Marx’s<br />

time. <strong>The</strong>n, just as now, world wide commodity circulation was separated into two spheres,<br />

domestic and international trade. At Marx’s time, within every nation on the gold standard<br />

(such as England), gold coins served as means <strong>of</strong> circulation based on their face values. This<br />

is what Marx calls the “national uniforms” <strong>of</strong> gold. But in order to pay for international<br />

transactions, gold coins had to be melted down and shipped as gold bullion, which had no<br />

face values but were measured by their weights. This melting-down is depicted in Marx’s<br />

metaphor as the gold coins “taking <strong>of</strong>f” their national uniforms and travelling naked. <strong>The</strong><br />

separation <strong>of</strong> the two spheres <strong>of</strong> circulation finds therefore its echo in the double role <strong>of</strong> gold<br />

coins—on the one hand in domestic circulation as minted coins, on the other internationally<br />

as the ingredients <strong>of</strong> gold bullion. This is what Marx says in the above sentence.<br />

Term paper [585] gives the following paraphrase <strong>of</strong> Marx’s above sentence, which is<br />

completely wrong—and which shows again how difficult it is to read a text in such a way<br />

that you hear what the author is trying to tell you:<br />

When these gold or silver coins are worn on uniforms, this illustrates the<br />

different state <strong>of</strong> value these coins have; the value <strong>of</strong> its decorative form.<br />

However, when these coins are removed from the uniform they are held in<br />

a different context in the world market, as money.<br />

Forget this last paragraph again if you have read this far.<br />

Message [623] referenced by [585]. Next Message by Hans is [631].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 471 is 400 in 2004fa, 379 in 2005fa, 408 in 2007SP, 419 in 2008fa, 472 in<br />

2011fa, and 493 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 471 Marx defines money as the commodity which at the same time functions as<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> value and means <strong>of</strong> circulation. How does he justify this definition <strong>of</strong> money? Is<br />

there a commodity today which has these two functions? Is there money today?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 263<br />

[564] Cmellen: graded A Money is defined as value, only as the realization <strong>of</strong> socially<br />

necessary labor. It measures value as commodities exchange with each other in measurement<br />

to the extent <strong>of</strong> labor they contain.<br />

Money is a channel or go-between from commodity to commodity. Marx describes the<br />

cycle <strong>of</strong> C-M-C. In this, a commodity is exchanged for commodity, with the instrument <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange being money, but the cycle is not complete until the money is again traded for<br />

commodity (only this time it has use value for the individual, unlike the commodity they<br />

had originally and sold).<br />

Money can take any form <strong>of</strong> any given commodity as a universal medium <strong>of</strong> exchange;<br />

one customary commodity used (as universal medium <strong>of</strong> exchange) throughout history has<br />

been precious metals. Precious metals are themselves the product <strong>of</strong> socially necessary<br />

labor, as it takes skill and labor for mining.<br />

In perspective <strong>of</strong> current times, it is difficult to think <strong>of</strong> one universally accepted commodity<br />

used as a means <strong>of</strong> circulation as well as a measure <strong>of</strong> value. However if you think<br />

outside <strong>of</strong> the box, you can still consider credit and debit cards as the new “form <strong>of</strong> money”.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y are used as a means to transfer “money” from one person to another in exchange for a<br />

commodity. Although it is temporarily intangible, it still facilitates the exchange <strong>of</strong> tangible<br />

commodity for tangible commodity. This has evolved to intangible form <strong>of</strong> commodity for<br />

efficiency and security <strong>of</strong> transporting it on your person. It has been demonstrated through<br />

history that it is difficult to carry money with you if it is in the form <strong>of</strong> cattle, gold, seeds,<br />

etc. This change in form is as a result <strong>of</strong> problems like: you can easily drop it if you carry<br />

too many; it can be too heavy to carry large quantities, or you could have it stolen from you.<br />

Hans: Credit and debit cards are not themselves money but they are, as you say yourself (but with quote signs<br />

around ‘money’) “a means to transfer money from one person to another in exchange for a commodity.” This is<br />

exactly Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> the functions <strong>of</strong> money as means <strong>of</strong> payment: In 233:2/o Marx says that it is not<br />

money itself, but the promise to pay money which causes the commodities to change hands. But this money still<br />

has to be paid afterwards.<br />

Message [564] referenced by [573] and [2012fa:851]. Next Message by Cmellen is [574].<br />

[573] Cougar: graded A– <strong>The</strong>re’s money, and then there’s money... Avatar’s parallel in<br />

[2005fa:992], concerning cigarettes in the prison system, was most beneficial in formulating<br />

my response. For those unfamiliar with Avatar’s post, cigarettes take on the form <strong>of</strong> money<br />

in the prison system subculture (key word). Due to the limited spectrum <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

within prison walls, cigarettes serve as a universal measure <strong>of</strong> value for other use values as<br />

represented in the exchange <strong>of</strong>, let’s say, 9 cigarettes for a dirty magazine as Avatar uses. <strong>The</strong><br />

exchange value <strong>of</strong> the magazine is expressed in the use value <strong>of</strong> the quantity <strong>of</strong> cigarettes,<br />

acting as money. As cigarettes circulate throughout the prison, such as in the transaction<br />

just mentioned, those who have no interest in smoking may acquire cigarettes solely for<br />

the purchase <strong>of</strong> other use values. This circumstance satisfies Marx’s claim in 358:1/o that,<br />

“...Thus the slave <strong>of</strong> commerce has become its master...” Cigarettes have now evolved into a<br />

form irrelevant <strong>of</strong> their use value and only meant to satisfy the exchange <strong>of</strong> prison wealth as<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> value and means <strong>of</strong> exchange. Cigarettes therefore become money.<br />

Unfortunately the question in that term did not address Marx’s justification for the duality<br />

<strong>of</strong> “money.” Before I attempt this justification, I wish to extend gratitude for Avatar’s insight.<br />

264 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

I had hoped Cmellen’s current response [564] would have insight in this area but unfortunately<br />

I saw no response to this portion <strong>of</strong> the question. In [2008fa:963], Hans explains how<br />

gold served as money in Marx’s time and culture. Gold served as both a measure <strong>of</strong> value<br />

for commodities produced and exchanged and as a mode <strong>of</strong> circulation in transactions, usually<br />

in the form <strong>of</strong> certificates that represented a certain amount <strong>of</strong> tangible gold. Although<br />

not from Marx’s own mouth, I feel this example given by Hans adequately supports Marx’s<br />

definition. In addition to Hans input, I would like to add an unrelated source from Marx’s<br />

text 227:2 in support.<br />

“But as soon as the series <strong>of</strong> metamorphoses is interrupted, as soon as sales<br />

are not supplemented by subsequent purchases, money is immobilized. In<br />

other words, it is transformed, as Boisguillebert says, from ‘meuble’ into<br />

‘immeuble’, from coin into money.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> term “metamorphoses” brings me back to the prison setting proposed by Avatar. It<br />

is clear cigarettes undergo a similar metamorphic process: primarily an inexpensive carcinogenic<br />

release, cigarettes evolve into a measure <strong>of</strong> exchange value <strong>of</strong> the <strong>thing</strong>s found<br />

in prison and eventually a means for obtaining these <strong>thing</strong>s. To take Avatar’s example in<br />

a new direction, let’s say one inmate decides to stash or “hoard” his acquired cigarettes.<br />

Rather than quickly tossing his cigarettes back into the prison-market, his decision to hoard<br />

re-emphasizes the duality <strong>of</strong> money. Where the continual circulation <strong>of</strong> money seems to<br />

perpetuate its uncontrollable fetishism, the immobilization <strong>of</strong> money reaffirms its ability, in<br />

addition to circulation, to measure value and potentially acquire other use values. Like the<br />

picture <strong>of</strong> a busy city bridge taken with an exposed lens overnight, the “measure <strong>of</strong> value”<br />

criterion <strong>of</strong> money becomes blurred in circulation until it comes to a halt. In this case the<br />

inmate begins to establish wealth, the embodiment <strong>of</strong> the natural capitalist, with the power<br />

to both measure use values and acquire them. As stated by Hans in [2007SP:682], this is<br />

my interpretation <strong>of</strong> how hoarding acts as one <strong>of</strong> three examples Marx uses to justify the<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Now concerning money in its Marxian form today, U.S. dollars have certainly become a<br />

universal means <strong>of</strong> circulation in America and nations abroad. Although dollars do not represent<br />

actual gold stock as they once did, they are supported by factors including the stability<br />

<strong>of</strong> U.S. treasury bonds, fiscal and monetary policy as filtered through the Fed and Congress<br />

respectively (Cmellen deserves credit for this observation), and the might <strong>of</strong> the U.S. military.<br />

Factors like those just mentioned provide U.S. currency with the “authority” to measure<br />

value <strong>of</strong> commodities both foreign and domestic, satisfying the role <strong>of</strong> money as a measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. This value as represented by actual U.S. notes and coins also serves to facilitate<br />

the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities in the market fulfilling the second role <strong>of</strong> money: circulation.<br />

Cmellen’s comment concerning the metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> precious metal(s) into paper money<br />

used today serves here as an appropriate conclusion: Over time money has evolved into a<br />

form completely void <strong>of</strong> use value and into a “...servant, <strong>of</strong> commodities.” In summation<br />

<strong>of</strong> Hans annotations, rather than degrade to mere use values as other commodities, money<br />

provides its holder(s) with wealth where wealth is king in capitalism.<br />

Hans: Originally you had “<strong>The</strong> use value <strong>of</strong> the magazine is expressed in the value <strong>of</strong> the quantity <strong>of</strong> cigarettes,<br />

acting as money.” In this archive copy here I switched ‘use value’ and ‘value’ around, because this is how Marx and


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 265<br />

also Avatar say it, and in addition I replaced ‘value’ by ‘exchange value’ because the items circulating in prison are<br />

not produced in prison. One can argue that the cigarette values <strong>of</strong> prison items are indeed established in circulation<br />

and not in production, therefore it does not make sense to distinguish between exchange value and value. Also in<br />

your passage “cigarettes evolve into a measure <strong>of</strong> use values found in prison” I replaced ‘use value’ by ‘exchange<br />

values’. You still have ‘use value’ and ‘exchange value’ too intermingled in your thinking; they have to be kept<br />

apart.<br />

Next Message by Cougar is [592].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 472 is 272 in 1997sp, 272 in 1998WI, 282 in 1999SP, 299 in 2000fa, 318 in<br />

2001fa, 345 in 2002fa, 360 in 2003fa, 401 in 2004fa, 420 in 2008fa, 473 in 2011fa, and<br />

494 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 472 When does gold function as money as distinct from its function as measure <strong>of</strong><br />

value or means <strong>of</strong> circulation?<br />

[572] Sly: It may look complicated at <strong>first</strong>. In order to understand when gold functions<br />

as money, we must <strong>first</strong> understand when money functions as money. In the Annotations,<br />

Marx gives the criteria for a commodity to be money as follows – if it is not notional (as<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> value) and not capable <strong>of</strong> representation (as in means <strong>of</strong> circulation) then it’s<br />

money. (Pg 310) By reading the text it is simple to derive that in order for gold to function<br />

as money it must simultaneously embody a measure <strong>of</strong> value and a means <strong>of</strong> circulation.<br />

This is the point in which it is hard to define gold as money – because as stated in the<br />

Annotations: “<strong>of</strong>ten it only functions as measure <strong>of</strong> value or means <strong>of</strong> circulation.” This<br />

statement is made in reference to gold. (Pg 309) Marx <strong>of</strong>fers the definition that gold becomes<br />

a measure <strong>of</strong> value because it provides the world <strong>of</strong> commodities with the material in which<br />

their values can be expressed, i.e., the Gold Standard – this standard is given to gold by other<br />

commodities’ relative form <strong>of</strong> value. Since gold is now a commodity that simultaneously<br />

embodies a measure <strong>of</strong> value and a means <strong>of</strong> circulation, it has now become money. Gold<br />

loses its function as money when it doesn’t embody the two criteria, and separates itself – for<br />

example, when gold become jewelry. It is now easy to see that in order for gold to function<br />

as money it must, as the Annotations stated: “appear in person as gold” and gold becomes a<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> value when it appears as jewelry, or any other commodity constructed from gold.<br />

Hans: Money functions as measure <strong>of</strong> value because all other commodities designate their prices in money. For<br />

this money must have a stable value itself. Under the gold standard the value <strong>of</strong> money was determined by the<br />

production cost <strong>of</strong> gold, nowadays the value <strong>of</strong> the dollar is determined by trust in a non-inflationary monetary<br />

theory plus the military might <strong>of</strong> the US. It has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with jewelry.<br />

Message [572] referenced by [2011fa:1042]. Next Message by Sly is [612].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 473 is 402 in 2004fa, 410 in 2007SP, 413 in 2007fa, 419 in 2008SP, 421 in<br />

2008fa, 437 in 2009fa, 475 in 2011fa, and 496 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 473 Explain the individual motivation for hoarding money. Do these hoards have<br />

a function for the economy as a whole or only for the individual?<br />

[578] Kraken: graded A– Hoarding—OK gimme a case! Individuals hoard money<br />

because money is so extremely useful in allowing us to satisfy our wants. With a large sum<br />

<strong>of</strong> money, a person can quickly obtain most, if not all <strong>of</strong> their earthly needs and desires.<br />

<strong>The</strong> motivation to hoard money is rooted in the idea that with enough money a person could<br />

spend their entire lifetime using that money to meet their needs and wants, and never have to<br />

266 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

feel the pain <strong>of</strong> going without necessities or the “good <strong>thing</strong>s in life.” Our current recession<br />

has caused many <strong>of</strong> us to change our spending habits. We are less likely to spend money we<br />

don’t have. We are spending less and hoarding more. Marx believed that hoarding had the<br />

societal benefit <strong>of</strong> allowing the money stock room to fluctuate. Hoarding does however have<br />

a negative impact on our poor suffering retailers and reflects badly in our GDP numbers,<br />

but I believe GDP is a fairy-tale number anyway and doesn’t accurately reflect the health <strong>of</strong><br />

our economy. Consumer spending makes up such a large portion <strong>of</strong> GDP that recent history<br />

should teach us that a rising GDP simply means we have returned to our unsustainable<br />

lifestyles and are continuing to live beyond our means.<br />

Message [578] referenced by [582], [583], and [610]. Next Message by Kraken is [677].<br />

[582] Robert: (graded A) Ascetic Compulsion to Save. I have been thinking about this<br />

question for a couple <strong>of</strong> days. As it turns out one <strong>of</strong> the disadvantages <strong>of</strong> being a slow thinker<br />

is that Kraken [578] beat me to it. Nevertheless, maybe I still have some<strong>thing</strong> I can add to<br />

our thinking about this question.<br />

I think Kraken points out one <strong>of</strong> the reasons an individual hoards money: “because money<br />

is so extremely useful in allowing us to satisfy our wants.” Money is useful to us because<br />

we can buy any<strong>thing</strong> we want with money. Hans in [2009fa:634] helps us understand that<br />

this attribute <strong>of</strong> money is its qualitative aspect. However, since it is so qualitatively useful<br />

an individual soon realizes that it can be quickly and easily all used up. <strong>The</strong>refore, Hans<br />

tells us, that it “is build into concept <strong>of</strong> money itself” that an individual is going to want to<br />

amass more and more money (a quantity <strong>of</strong> money to go along with its qualitative aspect).<br />

To amass more and more money, with the motivation <strong>of</strong> amassing wealth, the miser must<br />

consume little.<br />

<strong>The</strong> impact on the economy as a whole <strong>of</strong> such hording is to reduce liquidity in the market<br />

place, which, in Marx’s time <strong>of</strong> a gold standard currency, could limit the fluidity <strong>of</strong> exchange<br />

because there would be insufficient money available to allow C-M or M-C transactions.<br />

Now, none <strong>of</strong> that took too much thinking, I’ll admit. However, what I was thinking<br />

about is Hans’s statement in [2009fa:634] that “ideas do not generate social relations but<br />

they arise afterwards, they are a reflection <strong>of</strong> social relations.” Marx is difficult for many <strong>of</strong><br />

us to understand because we are used to looking at surface data and finding an explanation<br />

for that data. We are not accustomed to trying to understand why some<strong>thing</strong> is really the<br />

way it is. With Marx’s approach in mind, I tried to look at what social relation exists that<br />

would create the idea in an individual that he should save his money.<br />

Whenever I try to think about underlying social relations in our capitalistic society I find<br />

my thinking is influenced by Max Weber’s book, <strong>The</strong> Protestant Ethic and the Spirit <strong>of</strong><br />

Capitalism. Weber explains the religious source for the idea <strong>of</strong> the “ascetic compulsion to<br />

save.” Protestantism has a complex tension in that it “not only saw in the striving for wealth<br />

as a goal the ultimate in what is reprehensible; it also regarded wealth achieved as the fruit<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor in a calling as a blessing from God” (p. 116). In order to show the world that she is<br />

blessed <strong>of</strong> God, an individual could amass wealth by being very frugal in her consumption<br />

and hording money.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 267<br />

We know that we will soon read that wealth can be amassed more quickly by using<br />

money as capital, i.e., buying commodities (including labor-power as a commodity) and<br />

selling them for more money than they cost to buy. Weber has more to say about Protestant<br />

influence on this process: how God’s blessings can be increased by becoming a capitalist.<br />

Message [582] referenced by [583]. Next Message by Robert is [591].<br />

[583] Babyceta: A riddle: what do “hoarding” and “money trees” have in common?<br />

After reading several responses to question 473 (the individual motivation for hoarding<br />

money), mainly Robert’s [582] and Kraken’s [578], I cannot help but to wonder whether<br />

or not we’re overlooking some<strong>thing</strong> about the nature <strong>of</strong> hoarding. This notion <strong>of</strong> hoarding<br />

takes me back to the whole fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities issue, and I mention the<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> hoarding as an intentional pun because fetish-like character, you will recall, means<br />

treating products <strong>of</strong> society as if they were natural forces (while fetishism is more about the<br />

socialization <strong>of</strong> nature, ie. we like gold because it is shiny and beautiful). If money is itself<br />

a commodity, then there would be the potential to assign fetish-like characteristics.<br />

I’ll give you an example. Have you ever heard the saying “money doesn’t grow on trees?”<br />

That implies the nature (there I go again with the puns!) <strong>of</strong> money supply is indeed finite and<br />

therefore must be conserved or hoarded. Sometimes as a society we treat money as a natural<br />

force, believing it possesses the ability to move mountains or even people. Money can get<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s done when no<strong>thing</strong> else can (bribery, anyone?). I should also say that if Hegel is<br />

correct and every<strong>thing</strong> contains its opposite in itself, then money too may have a dual nature<br />

(okay, I’ll stop). We may also become fetishistic about money because, honestly, no<strong>thing</strong><br />

looks prettier in my wallet than crisp new $100 bills!<br />

I agree with Kraken about money “satisfying wants.” And I’m not quite sure about “<strong>The</strong><br />

Protestant Ethic,” but Robert makes an interesting point. I do believe we haven’t yet uncovered<br />

just how deep the roots <strong>of</strong> money have entrenched themselves into our society. We may<br />

never fully understand.<br />

Message [583] referenced by [610] and [611]. Next Message by Babyceta is [624].<br />

[610] Hans: Money Fetish only Tip <strong>of</strong> Iceberg. Babyceta [583] is wondering whether<br />

our discussion isn’t overlooking the connection between money and the fetish-like character<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities. Of course, there is a deep connection. If Marx says that commodities have<br />

a fetish-like character in that act in our society as if they were alive, then money is <strong>of</strong> course<br />

the most alive commodity <strong>of</strong> them all. But in 139:1 and 187:1, Marx warns us that money<br />

is “blinding.” In money, the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity has become so brightly<br />

visible that it detracts our gaze from the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the other commodities, which<br />

may be not so clearly visible yet even more insidious.<br />

Instead <strong>of</strong> using the theory <strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities to understand<br />

money better, I think a better approach is to use our intuition about money to better understand<br />

the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities. Our relationship with commodities is not<br />

much different than our relationship with money.<br />

Commodities are use-values and values, and we fall in love with both. If we fall in love<br />

with their values, we become misers or capitalists, and if we fall in love with their use-values,<br />

we become spendthrifts or consumerists. Both miser and spendthrift are contradictory: one<br />

lives poorly in order to become rich, the other lives opulently and in this way empoverishes<br />

268 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

himself. Kraken [578] talks about this contradiction without being aware <strong>of</strong> it when he says<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s like: “individuals hoard money because money is so extremely useful.” Yeah right, if<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> is extremely useful then the obvious <strong>thing</strong> to do with it is not to use it but hide it<br />

under your mattress.<br />

Only the capitalist manages to get both—at the expense <strong>of</strong> the workers. I.e., he manages<br />

to externalize the contradiction and put himself on the receiving pole.<br />

Here is another insidious aspect <strong>of</strong> commodities, not money: commodities must be sold.<br />

Most <strong>of</strong> us are sellers <strong>of</strong> a commodity, i.e., labor-power. We need jobs. <strong>The</strong>refore we agree<br />

if government does not make the necessary renewable energy investments—because this<br />

would be a “drain on the economy” which is “weak” right now anyway. Of course, it would<br />

not tank the economy, it would only decrease capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its a little. We cannot have that!<br />

We rather have our children and grandchildren live in stress and misery on a dramatically<br />

changed planet.<br />

We need a deeper understanding <strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity. People’s<br />

fascination with money is only the tip <strong>of</strong> the iceberg which is about to ram our civilization.<br />

Message [610] referenced by [611]. Next Message by Hans is [620].<br />

[1042] AM: <strong>The</strong> individual motivation for hoarding money is rooted in the individual’s<br />

belief that a certain sum <strong>of</strong> money can be used over their lifetime to purchase necessary<br />

commodities. Hoarding occurs when the individual sells a commodity for the sole purpose<br />

to keep (i.e. hoard) the money received in exchange for the commodity. <strong>The</strong> money, if<br />

not used to buy another commodity, is in essence taken out <strong>of</strong> circulation. For this reason<br />

I see hoarding as a function only for the individual. However, I get lost in determining<br />

if hoarding has any function in the economy as a whole. I suppose if the individual uses<br />

the money hoarded at a later date to purchase a commodity his hoarding has changed to a<br />

function for the whole economy. This indicates that the individual’s hoarding is dependent<br />

on the confidence he has in the economy at a given time. <strong>The</strong> money supply in circulation is<br />

growing and falling due to the individuals’ own perception <strong>of</strong> how business is doing.<br />

Hans: If you “get lost,” why not look up what Marx said about these <strong>thing</strong>s?<br />

Next Message by AM is [1047].<br />

[1094] Kaush: <strong>The</strong>re are as many reasons for hoarding as there are hoarders. An individual<br />

may seek to hoard to save for a future event such as buying a house, a car, starting a<br />

family, etc., or hang on tightly to money in times <strong>of</strong> recession. Others do so because every<br />

time they attain a level <strong>of</strong> wealth, they feel the urge to break into the next level <strong>of</strong> wealth.<br />

Yet others’ hoarding is a function <strong>of</strong> fascination, prestige and social power. It elevates the<br />

individual to join those residing in the upper strata. <strong>The</strong>re comes a time when hoarders start<br />

to spend and by so doing, they stimulate the economy for the good <strong>of</strong> society.<br />

Next Message by Kaush is [1095].<br />

[1116] Milly: graded A Hoarding Money. When individuals hoard they are taking money<br />

out <strong>of</strong> circulation by deciding not to buy after selling. Individuals hoard money for many<br />

different reasons. For some it is about wealth, luxury, greed or power and for others they feel<br />

the need to save for emergencies or buy some<strong>thing</strong> large in the future. Marx says that there<br />

are times when circulation must be interrupted for economic reasons but for the most part it<br />

is due to the individual’s fascination with money. Hoarding can be hurtful to the economy


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 269<br />

as a whole when those who are wealthy hoard and only continue to focus on accumulating<br />

more.<br />

Message [1116] referenced by [2012fa:866]. Next Message by Milly is [1117].<br />

[1128] Smartergirl: <strong>The</strong> individual’s motivation for hoarding money is for three reasons.<br />

Primarily to purchase more valuable commodities. Secondly hoarding can be a means <strong>of</strong><br />

safety while the individual is producing his own commodity he may have a lapse in time<br />

between sales and need to rely on his money to sustain him through this time. <strong>The</strong> more<br />

hoarding the longer they can sustain themselves during production. Lastly the mere appearance<br />

<strong>of</strong> wealth is a desire and hoarding can result in an appearance <strong>of</strong> wealth.<br />

<strong>The</strong> function <strong>of</strong> hoarding can benefit both the economy as a whole as well as the individual.<br />

It functions for the individual by providing safety, allowing them to buy commodities<br />

with a higher value and sustaining themselves during the time between selling their own<br />

commodity. For the economy as a whole it is a double edged sword. I agree that it is a<br />

double edged sword however my reasoning differs a bit. Initially I said that hoarding moves<br />

commodities and keeps companies in business. This is not the correct reason that it helps<br />

the economy as a whole. It helps the economy by interupting the constant changing and<br />

evolving commodities and helps to balance the economy as a whole by interrupting the flow<br />

<strong>of</strong> increased value by investors.<br />

Hans: I was puzzled why you say that interrupting the flow <strong>of</strong> investments helps the economy, until I read your<br />

in-class answer where you say that hoarding “can harm the economy by increasing surplus-value.” Marx does not<br />

think hoarding creates surplus-value, and Marx does not think an increase in surplus-value harms the economy. On<br />

the contrary, Marx considers the capitalist economy as a huge mechanism designed to increase existing values by<br />

adding surplus-value and to concentrate more and more value in fewer and fewer hands.<br />

Next Message by Smartergirl is [1148].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 474 is 422 in 2008fa, 438 in 2009fa, 476 in 2011fa, and 497 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 474 Give an example <strong>of</strong> a transaction between P and Q in which P sells to<br />

Q but Q does not purchase from P.<br />

[580] Cmellen: Sales without Purchase. I’m going to try to take a stab at examples <strong>of</strong> a<br />

transaction between P and Q in which P sells to Q but Q does not purchase from P. In past<br />

discussions they have relied on the only 2 examples that were given by Hans.<br />

Money hoarding is quite common in a capitalist economy, so there are lots <strong>of</strong> examples<br />

to choose from. One would be when the railroads were being built. “In the case <strong>of</strong> a long<br />

working period (such as the construction <strong>of</strong> a railway, etc.) there are purchases without<br />

sales” [Insert published with Marx-Lexikon Zur Politischen Ökonomie vol. 6, July 1972].<br />

Another example would be to accumulate funds (selling commodities and not buying other<br />

commodities) for the purchase <strong>of</strong> a large costly item, such as a factory machine.<br />

[hans - are these correct examples?]<br />

Message [580] referenced by [605]. Next Message by Cmellen is [587].<br />

[605] ANK: What about food stamps or WIC? In previous semesters, Hans has given<br />

examples such as the United States purchasing oil from Saudi Arabia with newly printed<br />

money to demonstrate a transaction between P and Q in which P sells to Q but Q does not<br />

purchase from P. Marx uses the example <strong>of</strong> a merchant selling to a gold digger in exchange<br />

for gold as a function <strong>of</strong> money. To the merchant it was a sale, but to the gold digger it was<br />

270 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

not a purchase because the gold was found in the ground by the gold digger in exchange for<br />

a commodity with use-value.<br />

As I thought about these examples, I thought <strong>of</strong> a few present day examples that may<br />

fit this scenario. <strong>The</strong>se examples are food stamps and WIC (Women, Infant, Children) certificates.<br />

For individuals and families who fit a certain poverty criteria, the United States<br />

government issues food stamps and WIC certificates for use at grocery stores. At the time<br />

<strong>of</strong> transaction, the grocery store sells food items in exchange for food stamps and WIC certificates<br />

which are later exchanged for money with the government. To the individual facing<br />

poverty, it is not a purchase because the food stamps and WIC certificate were given to them<br />

just for satisfying certain poverty criteria. <strong>The</strong> groceries are exchanged and the individuals<br />

and families facing poverty gain commodities with use-value without purchasing them.<br />

I disagree with the railroad example in [580] because although it may have taken a long<br />

time for the railroad supplies to be paid for, they eventually were and the transaction took<br />

place with the expectation <strong>of</strong> a future payment. <strong>The</strong> railroad example is simply a deferred<br />

payment whereas in the examples above the grocery stores and Saudi Arabia are satisfied at<br />

the time <strong>of</strong> exchange and view the sale as complete and paid for.<br />

Message [605] referenced by [608] and [656]. Next Message by ANK is [673].<br />

[608] IrvingHowe: Thoughts about food stamps or WIC. ANK [605] uses food stamps<br />

and WIC as an example <strong>of</strong> a transaction that is not truly a purchase because the purchase <strong>of</strong><br />

the food is not really made by the holder <strong>of</strong> the voucher.<br />

This example is wrong for two reasons. First, those vouchers have very real exchange<br />

values for whomever holds them and the act <strong>of</strong> exchanging some<strong>thing</strong> that has an exchange<br />

value for some<strong>thing</strong> that has use-value is invariably a purchase, regardless <strong>of</strong> whether or not<br />

our exchange value holder looks like currency or not.<br />

Second, the purchase does in fact take place in any event. <strong>The</strong> government purchases the<br />

goods on behalf <strong>of</strong> the recipient <strong>of</strong> the vouchers who also acts as an intermediary in what is<br />

an exchange between the government and the grocery store. I am reminded <strong>of</strong> when I would<br />

go to a hardware store for my old company and purchase <strong>thing</strong>s on the line <strong>of</strong> credit they<br />

had with the store. Just because the actual purchaser was not present when I took possession<br />

<strong>of</strong> the goods and no currency was exchanged does not change the nature <strong>of</strong> the transaction<br />

which is as plain as any other.<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [647].<br />

[656] Cmellen: WIC vs Railroad. ANK [605] disagreed with my railroad example <strong>of</strong><br />

a transaction between P and Q in which P sells to Q but Q does not purchase from P. I<br />

thought more about it and I agree that the railroad example is, as ANK put it, a deferment<br />

<strong>of</strong> payment. But I get confused then; I thought thats basically what hoarding is for, means<br />

<strong>of</strong> payment later? <strong>The</strong>y werent buying the railroad materials on credit and paying or it later.<br />

<strong>The</strong> rich wealthy men that hoard money financed the railroad.<br />

I found Kuruma to explain it in a way that I THINK I understand. “<strong>The</strong> issue <strong>of</strong> money<br />

hoard; (i.e., C-M that is not complemented by M-C). is the resulting split between sale and<br />

purchase that takes on content-determination via the circulation process. “In the case <strong>of</strong> a<br />

long working period (such as the construction <strong>of</strong> a railway) there are purchases without sales


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 271<br />

and demand without supply”; this causes the problem <strong>of</strong> the split between sale and purchase<br />

(hoarding). Because the long working period itself stems from the material aspects <strong>of</strong> the<br />

production process.” [Samezo Kuruma, July 1972;]<br />

However, I believe ANK’s example <strong>of</strong> WIC to be a much simpler way to understand it.<br />

WIC and Food stamps (in my view) are definitely a sell without a purchase.<br />

Message [656] referenced by [657]. Next Message by Cmellen is [1011].<br />

[657] IrvingHowe: RE: WIC vs Railroad. Cmellon [656] states that the WIC program<br />

is a commodity exchange without purchase.<br />

While it is indeed a perfect case <strong>of</strong> disconnected incentives that indeed represent a majority<br />

<strong>of</strong> what the public sector does, it is not as ANK and Cmellon say an exchange without<br />

payment.<br />

<strong>The</strong> disconnected <strong>of</strong> incentives occurs because the end user is not in fact the purchaser.<br />

<strong>The</strong> purchaser still exists and payment still occurs though. <strong>The</strong> government is the purchaser<br />

and this example is little more than an expanded version <strong>of</strong> a child’s mom sending them<br />

to the store with a check written on her account for the purchase <strong>of</strong> candy intended for the<br />

child.<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [699].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 486 is 433 in 2008fa and 449 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 486 Explain how the function <strong>of</strong> money as means <strong>of</strong> payment contains an unmediated<br />

contradiction. What does the word “unmediated” mean here?<br />

[581] Scholar: Market exchange is virtually the exchange between the different human<br />

individual labors, which are converted into the exchange between money and commodity<br />

after money emerged. When money functions as means <strong>of</strong> circulation during the exchange,<br />

there must be enough amount <strong>of</strong> money which is equivalent to the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

exchanged so that purchase and sale <strong>of</strong> the commodity are taking place simultaneously.<br />

If the money functions as means <strong>of</strong> payment during the market exchange, it means that<br />

purchase and sale <strong>of</strong> the commodity are not simultaneous, which implies that though the<br />

owner <strong>of</strong> the commodity sells the amount <strong>of</strong> the commodity, these commodities have not yet<br />

found their genuine buyer who needs and affords them in fact. So, because <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong><br />

payment <strong>of</strong> money, the balance <strong>of</strong> supply and demand <strong>of</strong> the commodity have been broken<br />

completely, and when you sell your commodity, it doesn’t mean that your individual labor<br />

has been accepted by others in society. If the buyer still has no money to pay when it<br />

is time to liquidate, the seller <strong>of</strong> the commodity would face trouble: he would find that<br />

his commodity has not been sold out, while, he has likely produced more amount <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity for misleading by an account sale, which maybe make him bankrupt.<br />

<strong>The</strong> contradiction between individual labor and social labor which exists in the production<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodity has been intensified when the money functions as means <strong>of</strong> payment, which<br />

are shown as imbalance between supply and demand <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

If the money functions as means <strong>of</strong> circulation, the amount <strong>of</strong> money indicates the certain<br />

purchasing power for the commodity, so by the medium <strong>of</strong> the money, the supply <strong>of</strong><br />

commodity would match the demand to a certain extent, though there is not perfect match<br />

272 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

between them. But when the money functions as means <strong>of</strong> payment, there are no more<br />

medium to comfort the contradiction during market exchange, and the contradiction would<br />

be crazy.<br />

Next Message by Scholar is [628].<br />

[910] Giant: graded B– <strong>The</strong> word, “unmediated” in this sentence is being used as a contradiction<br />

because money does not have any use value other than what a society puts on it.<br />

So if a farmer exchanges an apple for three dollars he is not really getting any<strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong> use<br />

value unless the society he is living in says that dollars are able to be exchanged for use-value<br />

goods.<br />

This is also a contradiction because money can be used as a means <strong>of</strong> exchange goods as<br />

well as being a good itself, when for example people exchange different currencies, money<br />

is the means <strong>of</strong> payment as well as a good.<br />

Hans: “Means <strong>of</strong> payment” is a very specific function <strong>of</strong> money in the “modified sale” when money changes hands<br />

after the goods have changed hands. For a correct answer see [2008fa:717].<br />

Next Message by Giant is [914].<br />

[1025] Jo: Unmediated means that there is no alternative available should the flow <strong>of</strong><br />

money be interrupted. Both buyer and seller are dependent on each other for money. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

need money to sustain themselves in a capitalist economy. So if the flow <strong>of</strong> money stops, a<br />

crisis ensues.<br />

Marx explains that as long as payments balance each other, money is just used as a measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> value however “if actual payments have to be made, money does not come onto the<br />

scene as a means <strong>of</strong> circulation, as a merely transient and intermediary form <strong>of</strong> the social<br />

metabolism, but as the individual incarnation <strong>of</strong> social labor, the independent existence <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange-value, the absolute commodity” (Annotations, p. 328) <strong>The</strong>re is no regulation on<br />

the exchange <strong>of</strong> money that keeps balance <strong>of</strong> payments equal, so it is easy for hoarding and<br />

other disruptions in the flow <strong>of</strong> money to occur, which could potentially result in crisis.<br />

Hans: You do not seem aware that Marx is talking about a very specific transaction, what he calls the “modified<br />

sale.”<br />

Next Message by Jo is [1026].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 488 is 283 in 1998WI, 294 in 1999SP, 312 in 2000fa, 360 in 2002fa, 375 in<br />

2003fa, 417 in 2004fa, 426 in 2007fa, and 433 in 2008SP:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 488 Why is means <strong>of</strong> payment, and not means <strong>of</strong> purchase, the predominant function<br />

<strong>of</strong> international money?<br />

[571] ANK: Thank you Paypal. Means <strong>of</strong> payment is the predominant function <strong>of</strong> international<br />

money, rather than the means <strong>of</strong> purchase. <strong>The</strong> reason that money is not used as a<br />

means <strong>of</strong> purchase in international trade is the difficult logistics <strong>of</strong> an “in person” exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong> money and commodity at the same time. Means <strong>of</strong> payment is used in international trade<br />

because without traveling overseas, the buyer can either send the money <strong>first</strong>, or the seller<br />

can ship the commodity <strong>first</strong> when making the exchange. Because <strong>of</strong> the risk <strong>of</strong> the seller<br />

just keeping the money and never sending the commodity, most <strong>of</strong> the time the commodity<br />

is sent <strong>first</strong> and then the buyer will send the payment. When eBay <strong>first</strong> started, my friend<br />

bought a $2000 video camera he planned to use for his highlight film business. He won<br />

the auction and sent his payment overseas. He waited and waited for his new video camera


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 273<br />

and never received it. <strong>The</strong> seller took my friend’s money and never shipped a video camera.<br />

This seller may have never had a video camera and this could have been a scam from the<br />

beginning. Now, third party companies such as paypal secure a payment from the buyer and<br />

wait for confirmation from the buyer that the commodity has been received from the seller<br />

before transferring the money to the seller. Third party companies like paypal allow means<br />

<strong>of</strong> payment to be the predominant function <strong>of</strong> money in international trade by reducing the<br />

risk involved in the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodity and money when it is not logistically possible<br />

to make an exchange in person.<br />

Next Message by ANK is [605].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 490 is 296 in 1999SP, 419 in 2004fa, 396 in 2005fa, 425 in 2007SP, 437<br />

in 2008fa, 453 in 2009fa, 496 in 2011fa, and 518 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 490 Bring two examples <strong>of</strong> situations where money functions as money and<br />

not merely as measure <strong>of</strong> value or means <strong>of</strong> circulation.<br />

[587] Cmellen: Money functions as money. I would like to openly discuss exam question<br />

490: Examples <strong>of</strong> situations where money functions as MONEY and not merely as measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> value or means <strong>of</strong> circulation. Looking back thru past discussions, I see that this question<br />

is easily answered by section 3.3a-c.<br />

(a) Hoarding: Once the cycle <strong>of</strong> metamorphoses has been interrupted, the coins in circulation<br />

become [transform] into money. (Das Kapital 227:2). This is due to the fact that<br />

the coin is held for a period <strong>of</strong> time instead <strong>of</strong> immediately leaving the hands for another<br />

use-value commodity. At this point the coin seems tangible.<br />

(b) Means <strong>of</strong> Payment: Money can also take the form <strong>of</strong> actual money even while still<br />

in circulation. this is when money is advanced as “capital” or investment assets. In these<br />

situations, the role <strong>of</strong> creditor and debtor are brought into play as a result <strong>of</strong> the circulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities. Along with these roles is attached the social and economic characterization<br />

associated with debtor and creditor. Marx describes this to be a more rigid and less pleasant<br />

relationship.<br />

(c) World Money: Locally, money is the general comparable for abstract human labor; it<br />

assumes to be the same in international trading. However, in international trade, money takes<br />

on the general equivalent prior to the labors themselves have been equalized (Das Kapital<br />

p329). This all-purpose equivalent causes the bonding <strong>of</strong> domestic labors into one universal<br />

abstract human labor.<br />

Message [587] referenced by [590], [592], [828], and [2012fa:1091]. Next Message by Cmellen is [656].<br />

[590] Lana: Discussion on money and power. I would have to agree with Cmellen [587]<br />

in that the roots <strong>of</strong> money in our society go much deeper than we originally see. <strong>The</strong> part <strong>of</strong><br />

Cmellen’s [587] discussion that struck out to me was the sentence, “Sometimes as a society<br />

we treat money as a natural force, believing it possesses the ability to move mountains or<br />

even people. Money can get <strong>thing</strong>s done when no<strong>thing</strong> else can (bribery, anyone?).”<br />

With that, I believe that money is our form <strong>of</strong> communication. Above a means <strong>of</strong> trading,<br />

valuation, and labor, it is how our society speaks to each other. <strong>The</strong> language <strong>of</strong> the Almighty<br />

Dollar, so to speak. Regardless <strong>of</strong> what currency, money will nearly always speak “louder<br />

274 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

than words,” excuse me for the pun. Money has been used to alter the course <strong>of</strong> history via<br />

political influence, foreign aid, etc.<br />

Money definitely experiences fetish-like characteristics—power.<br />

Message [590] referenced by [606]. Next Message by Lana is [613].<br />

[592] Cougar: Money is Magic! I would also like to comment on Cmellen’s post [587],<br />

expounding on Lana’s observation <strong>of</strong> the “mysticism” <strong>of</strong> money in the market. Since my teen<br />

years, I have kept myself aware <strong>of</strong> the economic climate on a regular basis. Before studying<br />

economics in college, i was fascinated by the power money commanded. One day interest<br />

rates were up, the next down, and the next day up again. <strong>The</strong> stock market was spiraling out<br />

<strong>of</strong> control making people filthy rich, then it was a disaster and suddenly people were losing<br />

their inheritance. Even in history courses, I thought it absurd that the Great Depression<br />

claimed the welfare <strong>of</strong> millions <strong>of</strong> this country. How can money just do this? Of course<br />

with age comes study and understanding, but to refer back to Lana’s comment, I still cannot<br />

shake the feeling the money commands a powerful influence, or as Marx calls it, a fetishism.<br />

Who is guiding the flow <strong>of</strong> money and for what cause? In the financial meltdown now recent<br />

history, only a few cautious words over national news networks brought thousands to the<br />

market shedding their share holdings like a truck load on anthrax-contaminated letters. For<br />

these reasons, I can’t help but think that the role <strong>of</strong> money played most frequently is that <strong>of</strong><br />

a valuing stick. Where I’d like to veer from the paved path is that I feel money measures<br />

more in our society than commodities but a benchmark for the entire economic system.<br />

People seem to portray their fetishes onto money to the point that their well-being depends<br />

on the flow and health <strong>of</strong> the dollar. Businesses seem to hold on to any and every economic<br />

forecast by any pundit, in the know or not. In this sense I believe money is also an excellent<br />

indicator <strong>of</strong> fetish-like character, how people dictate their interactions by the circulation. I<br />

guess now i’m getting to the point where both roles <strong>of</strong> money, now including circulation, are<br />

frequently employed. I guess my overall point is geared towards the “mysticism” <strong>of</strong> money<br />

and hopefully Lana was getting at a similar point. I’m not here to preach against material<br />

wealth nor do I feel Marx was trying to indoctrinate people, but I do feel that money can<br />

hypnotize those who do not understand the financial system.<br />

Message [592] referenced by [606]. Next Message by Cougar is [699].<br />

[606] Oreo: Money controls us. I agree with Lana [590] that money is our form <strong>of</strong><br />

communication. I especially like the line about power being a fetish-like characteristic <strong>of</strong><br />

money. It has the power to influence individuals’ emotions, determine their decisions, and<br />

even divide them into classes. It seems like society views money as so much more than<br />

a tool <strong>of</strong> exchange. As Cougar [592] mentions in his discussion, people believe that their<br />

well-being depends on the dollar. Before taking this class, I never really thought about the<br />

effect that money has on our lives. It is so natural for us to place money the pedestal that<br />

it’s on and subconsciously accept the fact that it has control over us. When I do think about<br />

it, it seems absurd that we practically worship some<strong>thing</strong> so inanimate as paper bills. We<br />

go to great lengths to acquire them, such as giving away our leisure time by devoting our<br />

lives to labor for someone else, despite our enjoyment and fulfillment from it. <strong>The</strong>se bills<br />

can make people do <strong>thing</strong>s that they wouldn’t normally do, such as act immorally or risk<br />

their lives. However, as ridiculous as it seems that these bills have such colossal control<br />

over us, it is completely true. Without money, we wouldn’t eat. We wouldn’t have shelter


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 275<br />

to provide for our family, or any <strong>of</strong> the comforts that come with a house. We wouldn’t be<br />

viewed as competent in our society and therefore pitied and looked down on. We wouldn’t<br />

have the security that money gives us. Because <strong>of</strong> these <strong>thing</strong>s, we would starve or freeze<br />

to death without the necessities to keep us warm. <strong>The</strong>refore, money is necessary for our<br />

very survival. <strong>The</strong> saying “money can’t buy happiness” seems foolish to me. I would be<br />

much happier having money than starving on the streets. <strong>The</strong> acquisition <strong>of</strong> these bills is<br />

mandatory in our society. Our lives depend on money, therefore causing it to be extremely<br />

powerful.<br />

Next Message by Oreo is [650].<br />

[821] Kat: <strong>The</strong>re are a couple instances that I’ve seen reference to in many places in past<br />

discussions where money acts only as money.<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> is world money. Where countries trade with one another not for goods, but<br />

strictly for the trade <strong>of</strong> currency.<br />

Another example is the act <strong>of</strong> hoarding. When an individual begins to hoard money, it is<br />

no longer in circulation. This effectively strips it <strong>of</strong> its primary function representing value<br />

over long periods <strong>of</strong> time.<br />

Finally, another example is an exchange taking place, but with delayed payment. Settling<br />

a debt in this way makes using money an independent act. By separating the exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity and the payment <strong>of</strong> money, money at that later date is not just means <strong>of</strong><br />

circulation but money.<br />

Hans: At the very end, you had “money at that later date is not just money.” I corrected it, hoping that you meant<br />

“not just means <strong>of</strong> circulation.”<br />

Message [821] referenced by [828]. Next Message by Kat is [898].<br />

[828] Hans: Money as money. Kat’s answer [821] is correct. <strong>The</strong> three classic examples<br />

where money serves as money coincide with the three subsections in Capital, chapter Three,<br />

section 3: hoard, means <strong>of</strong> payment, and world money.<br />

This is enough if you are asked this question on the exam, but let’s look into it how<br />

one can tell whether money is used as money. Ask yourself: is the money used as means<br />

<strong>of</strong> circulation, or is the money used in order to transfer wealth (either from one person to<br />

another, or for the same person from one time point to another)? In the latter case, money is<br />

used as money.<br />

Hoarding is clearly money according to this criterion. How about means <strong>of</strong> payment,<br />

i.e., making a deferred payment to conclude a purchase, for instance when you paying your<br />

credit card bill? At this point, money is no longer means <strong>of</strong> purchase. <strong>The</strong> good you are<br />

purchasing has already been transferred into your ownership. Your promise to pay was the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> purchase. But now you have to make good on your promise by transferring wealth<br />

to the seller. This is the reasoning why money as means <strong>of</strong> payment functions as money.<br />

If you pay taxes or a traffic ticket, you are also transferring wealth. In this case your<br />

liability was not generated by a purchase, but you have a liability, and when you pay this<br />

liability your money functions as money.<br />

This function <strong>of</strong> means <strong>of</strong> payment is not the same as an investment. Cmellen [587] got<br />

this wrong. <strong>The</strong> function <strong>of</strong> money as a means <strong>of</strong> payment grows out <strong>of</strong> simple circulation.<br />

276 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

If you lend money to someone or take your money to the bank, then the money also<br />

functions as money. If you buy securities, I would consider this a function <strong>of</strong> money as a<br />

means <strong>of</strong> purchase and not money as money, since you have to have the money on your<br />

brokerage account before you can place the order. If a capitalist buys means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

then money functions as means <strong>of</strong> purchase (i.e., not as money) if it is a cash purchase, or<br />

means <strong>of</strong> payment (i.e., money) in the more usual case that it is a deferred payment. In other<br />

words, money that performs M-C-M does not automatically function as money because <strong>of</strong><br />

this.<br />

How about world money? Neither Kat nor Cmellen got it completely right why money in<br />

its function as world money functions as money. Marx had in mind bilateral trade arrangements<br />

under the gold standard: usually imports and exports between two countries cancelled<br />

each other out, i.e., imports were paid with the receipts from the exports. I.e., usually no<br />

money entered circulation at all. Only when there is an imbalance at the end, then money<br />

has to be shipped in the form <strong>of</strong> gold bars from one country to the other. This money on<br />

the gold ships functioned as money. It was a minute fraction <strong>of</strong> the overall trade, but understanding<br />

the international gold movements from the gold mines to the country treasuries is<br />

an important part <strong>of</strong> understanding the gold standard.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [829].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 493 is 423 in 2004fa, 438 in 2008SP, and 456 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 493 In 247:4/o, Marx makes three statements about money engaged in M−C−<br />

M: (1) this money converts itself into capital, (2) this money becomes capital, and (3) according<br />

to its determination, this money already is capital. What is the difference between<br />

these three statements? Why does Marx not say that this money is capital?<br />

[594] Goldtone: graded A A Necessary 3 Step Process. At <strong>first</strong> look, Marx appears to<br />

be making an unnecessary three step process for what could be a more efficient one step<br />

process. That is “(1) this money converts itself into capital, (2) this money becomes capital,<br />

and (3) according to its determination, this money already is capital”, could be more simply<br />

stated as “money is capital”.<br />

<strong>The</strong> problem with this simplification is that it is incorrect (money is not capital), and<br />

Marx is not trying to make <strong>thing</strong>s overly complex, but instead is trying to summarize the<br />

transition from money to capital.<br />

<strong>The</strong> distinction between money and capital is found in its “different forms <strong>of</strong> circulation”<br />

as Marx describes in 247:4/o. This leads Marx to explore the link between circulation and<br />

capital more closely, which is point 3 in the annotations on page 338.<br />

C-M-C was the initial form <strong>of</strong> circulation discussed and gutted in chapter 2 and 3. This is<br />

not the link between circulation and capital. <strong>The</strong> link is found in a new form <strong>of</strong> circulation<br />

depicted by M-C-M, or “buying in order to sell” as Marx says in 247:4/o.<br />

M-C-M is the conversion <strong>of</strong> money into capital that we see in point (1) in question 493.<br />

(2) is the fact that “money itself becomes capital if it goes through this form <strong>of</strong> circulation”.<br />

<strong>The</strong> last step in the process, (3), is more <strong>of</strong> a realization that the development <strong>of</strong> money<br />

into capital is an ontological transition whose development is only observed by a scientist /


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 277<br />

researcher, but does not need this observation because the truth is that it happens frequently<br />

in real life.<br />

<strong>The</strong> reasoning <strong>of</strong> (3) is similar to one who knows that even though a tree that falls in the<br />

forest is not observed by someone does not mean that the tree did not fall, and the truth is<br />

that trees fall all <strong>of</strong> the time without someone watching. <strong>The</strong> tree falling is comparable to<br />

the development <strong>of</strong> money into capital.<br />

Hans: Good guess, but I think better guesses are in my [640].<br />

Next Message by Goldtone is [873].<br />

[617] Cosmopolita: Marx’s three statements about money engaged in M-C-M. (1)<br />

this money converts itself into capital. Money as capital distinguishes itself <strong>first</strong> by its different<br />

form <strong>of</strong> circulation. Money is used as measure <strong>of</strong> value, as a way <strong>of</strong> circulation <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities weights.<br />

(2) this money becomes capital, because in this step the measure <strong>of</strong> value is set between<br />

commodities and there is now a pattern for next commodities to buy. I.e. if you can get 20<br />

linens <strong>of</strong> silk with one coin, or 1 coat with one coin. i.e II. If you can get a 2003 honda civic<br />

for $6000 or a 1997 mercedes benz for the same amount. the measure <strong>of</strong> value can differ in<br />

many different ways depending on social values and in the activities and motivations <strong>of</strong> the<br />

person performing these circulation acts.<br />

(3) according to its determination, this money already is capital ... the difference between<br />

all these statements is the phase <strong>of</strong> the whole process. if is either M - C, or C - M to get they<br />

money back, to hoard capital.<br />

Hans: It <strong>of</strong>ten happens that class participants who can barely hold themselves above water in terms <strong>of</strong> understanding<br />

the basic lines <strong>of</strong> Marx’s argument try to answer the most difficult and subtle questions. <strong>The</strong>y simply don’t see<br />

the subtleties.<br />

Message [617] referenced by [654]. Next Message by Cosmopolita is [652].<br />

[640] Hans: <strong>The</strong> Birth <strong>of</strong> Capital. Here is an educated guess what Marx might have<br />

meant with this formulation. Let’s start from the end.<br />

(4) At the beginning <strong>of</strong> chapter Four, Marx does not say yet that money is capital because<br />

capital cannot exist without wage-labor, i.e., without labor-power as a commodity. Does this<br />

mean usury capital and merchant capital was not really capital? Yes, in 266:2 Marx calls<br />

them “antediluvian forms,” meaning “forms before the deluge.” <strong>The</strong> deluge in this metaphor<br />

is presumably the process <strong>of</strong> “original accumulation” which pried the workers from the land<br />

and set them free as wage-laborers. In 247:1 Marx says that the “modern life-history <strong>of</strong><br />

capital” begins in the 16th century—which is the time the enclosure movement in England<br />

took <strong>of</strong>f at home and the New World was plundered overseas.<br />

(3) It already is capital “according to its determination.” Here I would think the word<br />

“determination” is taken in the meaning <strong>of</strong> “purpose,” namely the purpose <strong>of</strong> the person<br />

doing M-C-M. M-C-M only makes sense if the second M is bigger than the <strong>first</strong>, i.e., if it is<br />

M-C-M’. And the development in chapters 5 and the beginning pages <strong>of</strong> chapter Six show<br />

that the only way to do M-C-M’ which is consistent with the laws <strong>of</strong> commodity production<br />

is to buy labor-power. I.e., any individual who is looking for ways to do M-C-M’ is looking,<br />

without knowing it, for the commodity labor-power.<br />

278 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(2) Becoming, according to Hegel, is the unity <strong>of</strong> being and non-being. <strong>The</strong> process M-<br />

C-M is on the one hand capital, but without labor-power backing it up it is not yet capital<br />

but only the embryo <strong>of</strong> capital. An embryo is a human in the state <strong>of</strong> becoming, it is both a<br />

human and not a human at the same time—which leads to endless debates about abortion.<br />

Marx uses the concept <strong>of</strong> “becoming” also in chapter Three where he describes in detail how<br />

gold becomes money.<br />

(1) Marx uses the same word “convert” (verwandelt) in 227:2, where he says that money,<br />

when it falls out <strong>of</strong> circulation, is converted from money as means <strong>of</strong> circulation into money<br />

as money. What he says here in chapter Four is the negation <strong>of</strong> the negation: if money<br />

re-enters circulation in the form M-C-M then it goes through a second form change, it is<br />

converted into capital.<br />

Message [640] referenced by [594]. Next Message by Hans is [644].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 494 is 439 in 2008SP and 524 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 494 At the beginning <strong>of</strong> 248:2 Marx says that M−C−M in which the second M<br />

is intended to be equal to the <strong>first</strong> is “absurd” and “devoid <strong>of</strong> content.” Nevertheless, later<br />

in the same paragraph he says that the quantitative differences should be disregarded, and<br />

proceeds to investigate M−C−M. Why does he insist on investigating a possibility which<br />

he just called “absurd” and “devoid <strong>of</strong> content”?<br />

[599] PLG: graded A M-M-M ??????? Gaining an understanding <strong>of</strong> the form M-C-<br />

M requires an understanding <strong>of</strong> the intentions <strong>of</strong> the merchant. If the merchant intends to<br />

exchange M for an equal M, then as Marx notes, his intentions are absurd. However, this<br />

is never the intention <strong>of</strong> a merchant engaged in an M-C-M circulation. <strong>The</strong> intention is to<br />

obtain a larger M. <strong>The</strong> point that Marx makes at the end <strong>of</strong> the same paragraph 248:2 is that<br />

regardless <strong>of</strong> the quantity <strong>of</strong> the final M, money is the end goal. In the case <strong>of</strong> C-M-C a car<br />

buyer may end up with a lemon as the final C. Nevertheless, the relationship in this trade<br />

is still based on obtaining a new commodity. Marx aims to get the reader to understand the<br />

qualitative relationship to money, which is a defining factor <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

Spawnblade [2008SP:444] discusses stocks as a way to grow money. He discusses the<br />

risk obtained in trading stocks and that one may choose to break even if their situation<br />

becomes too risky. “For this reason a person may deem it necessary to cut their losses by<br />

selling at an equal or lesser value than that which they <strong>first</strong> bought it. It was not their intent,<br />

but it was some<strong>thing</strong> they had to consider when making a risky purchase.” However, Marx<br />

calls M-C-M absurd if the original intention is to break even. In Spawnblade’s example the<br />

stockholder’s intention is not to break even, it is to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it. Resorting to breaking<br />

even under risky circumstances is much different from intending to break even. Spawnblade<br />

confuses these situations. “I believe it is for this reason that Marx decides to investigate this<br />

‘absurd’ possibility, and not for the reason that it ‘never happens’.”<br />

Marx would probably think that M-C-M is absurd any way you look at it because <strong>of</strong> its<br />

capitalistic character. Yet in the context <strong>of</strong> the discussion he would not think that Spawnblade’s<br />

example <strong>of</strong> the stock holder reducing losses is absurd. Rather the stockholder serves<br />

as a good example <strong>of</strong> having a qualitative connection to money.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 279<br />

<strong>The</strong> M-C-M form makes me think <strong>of</strong> currency trading. Many people today try to pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

from exchanging foreign currencies for home currency. <strong>The</strong>y buy a foreign currency, and<br />

then try to sell it when its value appreciates. This would likely fascinate Marx if he were<br />

around today. This exchange would contain no qualitative value whatsoever. I wonder<br />

if Marx would view this exchange as M-M-M, or still as M-C-M considering capitalism<br />

commoditizes money? What do others in the class think?<br />

Hans: Your lemon example is splendid: it shows that not only M-C-M’ but also C-M-C can sometimes be unsuccessful.<br />

Regarding M-M-M, Marx calls it M-M’ and says it is the most fetishized form <strong>of</strong> the circulation <strong>of</strong> capital, in<br />

which the mediating element has completely dropped out <strong>of</strong> sight.<br />

Message [599] referenced by [649] and [2012fa:872]. Next Message by PLG is [659].<br />

[614] She: graded A That’s absurd! Let’s talk about it! It is important to understand<br />

that Marx is doing here what he always does, analyzing the phenomena by breaking it down<br />

into its microcosms. He says it is “evident” that the process would be absurd for anyone to<br />

go through the trouble <strong>of</strong> exchanging money for some arbitrary commodity only to exchange<br />

it for the same amount <strong>of</strong> money again. He is not trying to prove any<strong>thing</strong> here, just stating<br />

the obvious surface phenomenon that it is “evident.” Marx is trying to explain what makes<br />

this type <strong>of</strong> exchange so special and why it is unique.<br />

Marx says that the M-C-M exchange involves money being on a “different path <strong>of</strong> simple<br />

circulation,” [248:2]. Marx believes that the possibility <strong>of</strong> the second M being greater quantitatively<br />

is the motive for the agents participating, but it is not what makes this exchange<br />

special. He believes what makes this exchange so special and important to understanding<br />

capital and thus capitalism is the way money is used. Money is used in the M-C-M exchange<br />

to get money again in the future-money is not, “. . . spent, it is merely advanced,” [249:2].<br />

Marx recognizes that this advancement does not always create a surplus value, but that it<br />

is the only way to create a surplus value. Surplus values convert to capital which creates<br />

and fosters capitalism. Marx believes that buying in order to sell, or M-C-M creates an<br />

endless movement because you do not consume the final product as in C-M-C. It is therefore<br />

the prospects and motivations <strong>of</strong> the economic agents which Marx believes warrant an<br />

investigation, regardless <strong>of</strong> if the two values <strong>of</strong> M are quantitatively different.<br />

Hans: I would be curious to hear your reactions after reading my [649].<br />

Message [614] referenced by [649]. Next Message by She is [615].<br />

[649] Hans: Actions Matter, Intentions Don’t. PLG [599] and She [614] say Marx ignores<br />

the quantitative aspect because the intentions <strong>of</strong> the agents were to make more money.<br />

Marx himself argues a little differently. He says: whether the second M is bigger or smaller<br />

than the <strong>first</strong>, it is the same “characteristic and original path” [248:2] which begins with<br />

money and ends with money. Here are some clarifications which Marx does not bring but<br />

which I think are in his spirit. If most people would lose money, i.e., if society did not make<br />

labor-power a commodity and in this way provide the possibility to go through a pr<strong>of</strong>itable<br />

M-C-M’, then M-C-M’ would not be the social pastime which it is and the book Capital<br />

would not have to be written. But it is possible and lots <strong>of</strong> people do it. Those who lose<br />

money quickly drop out but obviously the aggregate gains outpace the aggregate losses.<br />

That’s why Marx is trying to understand how they all do it. Whether one individual capitalist<br />

is successful or not is irrelevant here as long as we know that on average it can be<br />

done.<br />

280 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Intentions don’t play much <strong>of</strong> a role in this argument. I think Marx is aware <strong>of</strong> two <strong>thing</strong>s:<br />

(1) Intentions are not exogenous, but they are created by the social structure. People<br />

would not try so hard to become filthy rich if they didn’t see by example that it was possible<br />

to become filthy rich in this society.<br />

(2) Social relations are not established by the intentions <strong>of</strong> the individuals, but by their<br />

actions. Intentions alone don’t make <strong>thing</strong>s happen. In chapter Seven, 298:2/oo Marx says:<br />

“the way to Hell is paved with good intentions.”<br />

Despite these reservations, chapter Four pays more attention to intentions than the rest <strong>of</strong><br />

the book. I think Marx does this for two reasons:<br />

(a) if we know the intentions <strong>of</strong> the commodity traders we can better predict what they<br />

do, and what they do does matter, social relations are established by the actions <strong>of</strong> the individuals.<br />

(b) Regarding capitalism, there is a rare coincidence between intentions <strong>of</strong> the individual<br />

capitalists and the social driving forces: society is geared for making money, and the<br />

capitalists are motivated to make money.<br />

Message [649] referenced by [614] and [2012fa:872]. Next Message by Hans is [654].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 496 is 197 in 1995WI, 176 in 1995ut, 210 in 1996sp, 227 in 1997WI, 280<br />

in 1997ut, 299 in 1999SP, 317 in 2000fa, 336 in 2001fa, 380 in 2003fa, 425 in 2004fa,<br />

432 in 2007SP, 443 in 2008fa, 459 in 2009fa, 506 in 2011fa, and 528 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 496 Give examples for “advancing” and “expending” money.<br />

[600] Alex: MCM/CMC Exam question. Advancing money and expending money is<br />

defined in Marxian terms as M-C-M and C-M-C respectively, where M-C-M is purchasing<br />

commodities for the purpose <strong>of</strong> making money (advancing in personal wealth, the way I<br />

see it) and C-M-C is spending (expending) the money to purchase a commodity for its consumption<br />

(for the commodity to be used up by the purchaser, such as food, or meals at a<br />

restaurant). What came to my mind when I figured out this definition <strong>of</strong> advancing money<br />

was the example <strong>of</strong> people who purchase items in foreign countries and sell them in their<br />

own countries for a pr<strong>of</strong>it in a short period <strong>of</strong> time (or vice-versa). For example, back in my<br />

home country, when people came to the United States, they would purchase various amounts<br />

<strong>of</strong> perfume bottles (not necessarily expensive brands) and would sell them back home upon<br />

their return, for twice or even sometimes three times their value. What I noticed, however,<br />

was that these perfumes remained with the seller for a short period <strong>of</strong> time before their value<br />

went down. Does time have any<strong>thing</strong> to do with value lost in the M-C-M/advancing money<br />

example?<br />

Message [600] referenced by [603] and [604]. Next Message by Alex is [655].<br />

[836] Baseball: When speaking <strong>of</strong> advancing and expending money Marx puts it into the<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> M-C-M (Money-Commodity-Money)and C-M-C (Commodity-Money-Commodity).<br />

In the case <strong>of</strong> M-C-M the buyer purchases a commodity in order to make pr<strong>of</strong>it it in the<br />

end. By making a purchase, the buyer transforms his money into the form <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

(the commodity’s inner value is labor-power but on the surface it is money), thus throwing


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 281<br />

money into circulation. <strong>The</strong> money in this case is not spent but simply “advanced.” In order<br />

to recover and get the form <strong>of</strong> money back, the buyer must sell the commodity and this<br />

transaction “advances” his wealth. C-M-C is a little different in the fact that the commodity<br />

(C) lies at the end <strong>of</strong> the chain and means that the money has been spent and “expended” into<br />

circulation. <strong>The</strong> money is no longer with the seller but instead he has a commodity which<br />

best fits his use value void. <strong>The</strong> seller realizes the value <strong>of</strong> his commodity which converts it<br />

to money and at the end <strong>of</strong> the cycle he has successfully converted that transmuted money<br />

into a commodity which serves as a use value which better fits his needs.<br />

Hans: This is not exactly a collection <strong>of</strong> examples but it is a good explanation.<br />

Next Message by Baseball is [862].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 497 is 211 in 1996sp, 211 in 1996ut, 288 in 1998WI, 300 in 1999SP, 337 in<br />

2001fa, 366 in 2002fa, 381 in 2003fa, 426 in 2004fa, 401 in 2005fa, 433 in 2007SP, 436<br />

in 2007fa, 442 in 2008SP, 460 in 2009fa, 530 in 2012fa, and 497 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 497 If someone <strong>first</strong> buys a car, and after two years trades it in for a new car, is<br />

that C−M−C or M−C−M?<br />

If someone <strong>first</strong> buys a house, then after ten years decides to move and sells his house for a<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it, is this C−M−C or M−C−M?<br />

If a farmer raises wheat, then at the end <strong>of</strong> the year sells his crop and with the proceeds buys<br />

the materials to raise next year’s wheat, is that C−M−C or M−C−M?<br />

[596] Frida: (graded A–) C-M-C or M-C-M. If someone buys a car and then trades it in<br />

for a new car, then this is C-M-C. Say our linen weaver wants to buy a car. She <strong>first</strong> sells<br />

her linen, uses that money to buy a car, then later sells the car and buys a new one. We have<br />

C(linen)-M-C(older car)-M-C(newer car). <strong>The</strong> important value in these transactions is (for<br />

our linen weaver) the use values. She engages in these exchanges because she needs a car.<br />

Indeed, cars depreciate over time so if the goal was to increase the quantity <strong>of</strong> money our<br />

linen weaver would have bought some<strong>thing</strong> other than a car. <strong>The</strong>re might be some confusion<br />

because the term “trade” is used as a label for the process, but in any actual situation in<br />

which someone is trading in their car for a new one, this is separated into the C-M and the<br />

M-C portions. First the dealership will tell you what they will give you for your car, and this<br />

counts towards the price <strong>of</strong> the new one.<br />

<strong>The</strong> situation where someone (let’s say our linen weaver) buys a house and then later sells<br />

it for a pr<strong>of</strong>it is best described as M-C-M. To fully describe this situation (assuming that she<br />

originally had no plans to later sell the house), I think there is also a C-M-C transaction at<br />

the beginning. We have C(linen)-M-C(house)-M’. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> transaction (the C-M-C) looks<br />

similar to our car transaction, it is essentially an exchange <strong>of</strong> use-values. It is only later that<br />

the exchange <strong>of</strong> money for a house becomes part <strong>of</strong> a M-C-M type transaction. <strong>The</strong> M-C-M’<br />

transaction does lead to an increase in the quantity <strong>of</strong> money for the linen weaver, which is<br />

the essential characteristic <strong>of</strong> the M-C-M transaction.<br />

<strong>The</strong> situation where a farmer sells his wheat and uses that money to buy next year’s wheat<br />

is C-M-C. We have C(wheat)-M-C(seeds). It is an exchange <strong>of</strong> use-values for the farmer.<br />

He doesn’t need wheat, but he needs the materials to grow wheat.<br />

Hans: If he doesn’t need more wheat than he already has for his own needs, then he also does not need the material<br />

to grow wheat for his own needs. He is doing M-C-M, not C-M-C.<br />

282 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Message [596] referenced by [597]. Next Message by Frida is [639].<br />

[597] Lindsey: Money to Money, Commodity to Commodity. Marx defines 2 forms<br />

<strong>of</strong> circulation in chapter 4: C-M-C (the immediate form <strong>of</strong> circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities) and<br />

M-C-M (the form <strong>of</strong> circulation <strong>of</strong> capital).<br />

C-M-C is the conversion <strong>of</strong> a commodity into money and then that money into a different<br />

commodity. In this process, the person is selling one commodity in order to buy (spend the<br />

money received on) another. Examples <strong>of</strong> this include part 1 and 3 <strong>of</strong> question 497. In part<br />

1, the person buys a car (C) and then trades it in (quick conversion in and out <strong>of</strong> M) for a new<br />

car (C). In part 3, a farmer grows wheat (C), then sells the harvest (M) and buys materials<br />

(C) to raise the next year’s wheat.<br />

M-C-M is the conversion <strong>of</strong> money into a commodity and then back into money. In this<br />

process, the person is buying a commodity in order to sell it (ultimately with the intention<br />

<strong>of</strong> getting more money—a pr<strong>of</strong>it—though this is not always the end result). Here the money<br />

is advanced (M to M); the person always intends to get it back. An example <strong>of</strong> this is part 2<br />

<strong>of</strong> question 497 where a person buys (with M) a home (C) and then sells it for pr<strong>of</strong>it (M).<br />

Hans: You are saying the same <strong>thing</strong> as [596], with the same mistake, only packaged differently. I tried to compile<br />

a comprehensive answer which combines the best insights from the archives in [Answer:1].<br />

Next Message by Lindsey is [742].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 499 In 208:1, Marx says that the circulation process C−M−C “sweats money<br />

from every pore.” Would he say the same <strong>thing</strong> about M−C−M, or would he characterize<br />

the flow <strong>of</strong> money generated by M−C−M in a different way?<br />

[588] JSmits: graded A C-M-C vs. M-C-M. In 208:1, Marx says that the circulation<br />

process C-M-C “sweats money from every pore”. Marx would characterize the flow <strong>of</strong><br />

money generated by M-C-M in a different way than he would with C-M-C. <strong>The</strong> flow <strong>of</strong><br />

money generated by M-C-M as Hans says, “Like a yo-yo, the money keeps returning to the<br />

same person again and again.” This money is not spent, it is just advanced. In M-C-M the<br />

<strong>first</strong> step, M-C, is the purchase part <strong>of</strong> the process, where the money will be changed into a<br />

commodity. During the second step, C-M is the sale, where the commodity is changed into<br />

money. <strong>The</strong>se two processes turn into one fluent step where money is exchanged for money.<br />

If I was to buy 100 pounds <strong>of</strong> linen for $20, and resold the 100 pounds <strong>of</strong> linen for $25, all<br />

I have really done is a money for money exchange which was $20 for $25. Marx infers the<br />

purpose <strong>of</strong> M-C-M by comparing the <strong>first</strong> point with the end point. <strong>The</strong>refore its purpose is<br />

exchange-value.<br />

In the form C-M-C the process is much different. <strong>The</strong> money “sweats out”, it is not a<br />

circular pattern it is a “flow”, as Marx says. Looking at the purpose <strong>of</strong> C-M-C you can tell it<br />

begins with a commodity and ends with a commodity so its purpose is use-value.<br />

With all this said, Marx would say the flow <strong>of</strong> money generated by M-C-M is different<br />

because when he spends money on a commodity, he intends to get that money back again.<br />

Where in C-M-C the circulation process completely comes to an end when the money that<br />

comes in from the purchase <strong>of</strong> a commodity is abstracted by the purchase <strong>of</strong> another commodity.<br />

Next Message by JSmits is [677].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 283<br />

[595] Max: graded A– Working out. Marx says that circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities through<br />

the process C-M-C “sweats money from every pore.” <strong>The</strong> “sweat” represents a byproduct <strong>of</strong><br />

the exchange—money in the hands <strong>of</strong> any particular trader (independent <strong>of</strong> the value representing<br />

labor). Essentially this means that the people involved in the change <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

are doing society a service by keeping the exchange <strong>of</strong> money flowing, so that at any time<br />

somebody will have money suitable for further exchange.<br />

In contrast, M-C-M doesn’t provide the same type <strong>of</strong> social service that C-M-C does. On<br />

its face value, it may seem that the capitalist (the initiator <strong>of</strong> said M-C-M process) is doing<br />

society a favor by purchasing a commodity, thus pumping money into the economy. However,<br />

because he proceeds to sell his acquired commodity for a larger sum than purchased<br />

for, he is in fact diminishing the money flow in a given society. Thus, less money is available<br />

for C-M-C processes and commodity flow diminishes. (Correct me if I am wrong, but this<br />

seems to imply a hindrance to innovation and development.)<br />

In summary, C-M-C “sweats money from every pore” because they are working out,<br />

sweating money into the economy, and living a healthy lifestyle. In contrast, M-C-M sits<br />

around on the couch, never sweats money, and lives a dull sedentary life watching daytime<br />

TV.<br />

Hans: M-C-M’ only then depletes the money stock if you are assuming the capitalists are not spending their pr<strong>of</strong>its<br />

or all <strong>of</strong> their pr<strong>of</strong>its. If capitalists invest part <strong>of</strong> their pr<strong>of</strong>its and consume the rest <strong>of</strong> it, then there is no such problem.<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>thing</strong> is, as a capitalist you can watch daytime TV and still become rich at the same time.<br />

Next Message by Max is [676].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 500 is 435 in 2007SP and 444 in 2008SP:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 500 Why does Marx place so much emphasis on the “reflux” <strong>of</strong> money implied in<br />

the form M−C−M?<br />

[601] Long: Money Flows Back to Begin (As Submitted:) w9 <strong>The</strong> “reflux” <strong>of</strong><br />

the Circuit Again. <strong>The</strong> “reflux” <strong>of</strong> money money implied in the form <strong>of</strong> M-C-M in<br />

implied in the form <strong>of</strong> M-C-M, which Marx which Marx put more emphasis on is the<br />

puts so much emphasis on, is the fact that fact that money is the starting point and the<br />

money is the starting point and the end- ending point. It is different then the C-Ming<br />

point. It is different than the C-M-C C part where money is the beginning and<br />

part where the commodity is the beginning<br />

and the end point. <strong>The</strong> circulation <strong>of</strong> com-<br />

the end product. It is the circulation <strong>of</strong><br />

modities results in a tw<strong>of</strong>old movement <strong>of</strong> the a commodities in a tw<strong>of</strong>old <strong>of</strong> the same<br />

the same money which transfers the money money that in which it is transfer from one<br />

from one hand to another. With the exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong> one commodity, the tw<strong>of</strong>old displacement<br />

is making the money flow back hand to another. With the exchanged <strong>of</strong><br />

to its original place. This backflow plays one commodity, the tw<strong>of</strong>old displacement<br />

an important role due to the fact that money is making money flow back to its original<br />

is back in the orignal place where it came place. It is in a form in which plays an<br />

from. However, Marx does not care how important role due to that fact that money<br />

much money is being made after the commodity<br />

is sold but only argues that money is back in its place <strong>of</strong> the orignal <strong>of</strong> where<br />

284 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

is back to the original owner from where it<br />

came. it came from. However, Marx does not<br />

care how much money is being made after<br />

the commodity is sold but only argues that<br />

money is back the the original state <strong>of</strong> where<br />

it came from.<br />

Hans: Your writing style is unacceptable. Here is your original submission and my tentative translation side by<br />

side.<br />

Next Message by Long is [603].<br />

[612] Sly: <strong>The</strong> ideal situation. <strong>The</strong> reason that Marx places so much emphasis on the<br />

“reflux” <strong>of</strong> money is because the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> reflux is really the secret behind capitalism.<br />

In the Annotations it’s stated that: “<strong>The</strong> agent who (initially) engaged in M-C-M never really<br />

gives up the money (originally used); like a yo-yo, the money keeps returning to the same<br />

person again and again.“(Annotations, pg. 346) To put it simply the capitalist makes and<br />

initial investment, and lets the do money multiplying automatically – with the initial money<br />

spent eventually returning back to capitalist, thus money is never really spent. In the Annotations,<br />

there is an aphorism given that “capitalist get what they spend, and workers spend<br />

what they get.” (Annotations, pg. 346), furthermore the Annotations also state that: “the very<br />

manner in which money is expended relies on its reflux. Without this reflux, the operation<br />

fails, or the process is interrupted and incomplete, since its complementary final phase, the<br />

sale, is missing.” (Annotations, pg. 347) Given this information we can derive that M-C-M is<br />

the resale <strong>of</strong> commodities, consequently the ‘manner’ in which a capitalist expends is purely<br />

for reflux, instead <strong>of</strong> use-value because the use-value is trivial to the capitalist. Capitalists<br />

are after money for money’s sake, and workers are after commodities – hence the aphorism.<br />

After taking this all into account, the secret is clear, and easily definable. One <strong>of</strong> the main<br />

building blocks <strong>of</strong> capitalism is reflux, and reflux is more or less the return <strong>of</strong> money to the<br />

capitalists in a quantity that differs from the amount that was initially invested – if we as<br />

individuals understand this we are able to see how capitalists are able to accumulate wealth,<br />

whilst investing little <strong>of</strong> any labor time. Without reflux, M-C-M (re-sale) isn’t possible, and<br />

capitalism isn’t possible because without reflux the only returns attainable through money<br />

would be in the form <strong>of</strong> use values – and not money for money’s sake, and the only means<br />

<strong>of</strong> manipulating the amount <strong>of</strong> universal value an one has (i.e. gold or money), would occur<br />

through the exchange <strong>of</strong> labor – thus eliminating the separation <strong>of</strong> workers and capitalists.<br />

So reflux enables capitalists to be exactly that – and put forth far less effort and time.<br />

Message [612] referenced by [987]. Next Message by Sly is [669].<br />

[860] AlexDaily: graded A Reflux is what makes it possible for the capitalist to remain,<br />

because M-C-M is a continuous process and doesn’t simply end at the second M. Marx says<br />

it this way “the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> reflux itself takes place as soon as the purchase commodity<br />

is resold i.e., as soon as the cycle M-C-M has been traversed in its entirety. This is therefore,<br />

a palpable difference between the circulation <strong>of</strong> money as capital, and its circulation as mere<br />

money.” This cycle <strong>of</strong> money circulating as mere money adds no value to society but simply<br />

takes the value the laborer created and gives it to the capitalist to sell. You have to understand<br />

this to understand why it is important to have C-M rather than M-C. That is why Marx places<br />

so much emphasis on reflux <strong>of</strong> money implied in the form M-C-M.<br />

Next Message by AlexDaily is [861].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 285<br />

[962] Rmc: graded B+ According to Marx, the “reflux” <strong>of</strong> money in the form M-C-M is<br />

money’s return to its original holder after he has traded it. <strong>The</strong> cycle begins with someone<br />

who has money ready to spend. This person spends the money on a commodity with the<br />

intention <strong>of</strong> selling the commodity for money. To illustrate this pattern, someone could<br />

spend £100 on a product—say a rocking chair—and then sell it for £110. Once he has sold<br />

the rocking chair for £110, he has basically just exchanged £100 for £110 and earned a pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

It is relevant to note that the buyer will trade money for a commodity and then resell it<br />

for a pr<strong>of</strong>it; as Marx says in 248:2, it would be easier for the miser to keep his £100 without<br />

exposing it to the “dangers <strong>of</strong> circulation”—there is always a chance he will not be able to<br />

resell the commodity for a pr<strong>of</strong>it, the same amount he spent on it, or at all.<br />

Marx explains that the money “refluxed” in this form is advanced, as opposed to spent on<br />

a product that is consumed (C-M-C). In this case, the money has been spent and the original<br />

holder cannot continue the M-C-M process. When the original money holder can resell a<br />

commodity for a pr<strong>of</strong>it, extra money has come back to him and he can now continue M-C-M;<br />

he essentially trades £100 for £110, then the £110 for maybe £130, and the £130 for £150,<br />

and so on.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> “law <strong>of</strong> reflux” are the macroeconomic conditions for it that the capitalist can do M-C-M’.<br />

Next Message by Rmc is [963].<br />

[987] Sly: To better understand the reflux <strong>of</strong> money in the form M - C - M, I believe that<br />

you must dumb it down to simpler terms.<br />

Essentially I look at it as M (Money) → C (Capital) → M (Money). How this makes<br />

sense to me is <strong>first</strong> the capitalist takes M (money), and invests it into means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

and labor-power for the production <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s in order to receive pr<strong>of</strong>it. Out come C (Capital),<br />

and when C (Capital) is purchased by a consumer they use M (money) to purchase the <strong>thing</strong><br />

that is produced. This is also known as the resale <strong>of</strong> commodities, and what happens is the<br />

M (money) that is returned to the capitalist is also larger than the amount <strong>of</strong> M (Money) that<br />

was invested.<br />

I had answered this question previously in a closer observation in [2010fa:612], and found<br />

that - “Capitalists are after money for money’s sake, and workers are after commodities”<br />

and “without reflux the only returns attainable through money would be in the form <strong>of</strong> use<br />

values – and not money for money’s sake, and the only means <strong>of</strong> manipulating the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

universal value an one has (i.e. gold or money), would occur through the exchange <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

–thus eliminating the separation <strong>of</strong> workers and capitalists.” - I would also like to add that<br />

laborers can’t employ the power <strong>of</strong> reflux to their own advantage because they don’t have<br />

access to the means <strong>of</strong> production - and thus can’t employ their own labor-power or for a<br />

matter <strong>of</strong> fact the labor-power <strong>of</strong> others.<br />

Reflux is the secret to capitalism and its what allow capitalist to be capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Sly is [1004].<br />

Multiple Choice <strong>Question</strong> 501 is 464 in 2009fa:<br />

Multiple Choice <strong>Question</strong> 501 When comparing C−M−C with M−C−M, Marx stresses<br />

the following points. One <strong>of</strong> the following is not what Marx says; check it. Extra credit if<br />

you point out where it is wrong and how it should be corrected.<br />

286 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

• (a) C−M−C is mediated by money, M−C−M is mediated by the commodity.<br />

• (b) <strong>The</strong> sale C−M has a different character when it is part <strong>of</strong> C−M−C than when<br />

it is part <strong>of</strong> M−C−M.<br />

• (c) C−M− C is a circular movement for the commodity, but not for the money,<br />

while in M−C−M, money returns to its beginning point (reflux).<br />

• (d) C−M−C does not repeat itself, it must always be re-started from the outside,<br />

while M−C−M automatically leads to its repetition.<br />

[858] Hans: In case you were wondering what the right answer is. Some <strong>of</strong> my<br />

multiple-choice questions are mean, but this is probably me meanest one I have have come<br />

up with (so far): if you do a close reading <strong>of</strong> the passage in chapter Four where Marx<br />

compares M-C-M with C-M-C, you will see that Marx makes exactly the four points given in<br />

this question—until you realize that his distinction between advancing and spending money<br />

is M-C while the question says C-M. I.e., the right answer is (b). Happy Thanksgiving to the<br />

many class participants who took the exam today on time! If you have an idea for an even<br />

meaner multiple choice question, let me know.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [859].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 507 is 422 in 2004fa, 398 in 2005fa, 430 in 2007SP, 431 in 2007fa, and 470 in<br />

2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 507 Is it right to say that M−C−M is incomplete because it ends with money,<br />

and the money is no<strong>thing</strong> by itself but must be spent?<br />

[586] AlexDaily: graded A M-C-M is incomplete. M-C-M is incomplete, however not for<br />

the reason that it ends with money which is “no<strong>thing</strong> by itself but must be spent.” Hans explains<br />

in [2005fa:1044] why it is incomplete: “because the M’ has exactly the same form as<br />

the original M. <strong>The</strong> same reasons which drive M to go through M-C-M’ will therefore drive<br />

M’ to through M’-C’-M”.” For example, the capitalist turns his money into commodities<br />

and then turns those commodities into money. However, this does not end the cycle because<br />

the capitalist is by no means finished. He will simply start the cycle once again, therefore,<br />

making it a continuous process and also making the statement M-C-M incomplete.<br />

Next Message by AlexDaily is [619].<br />

[1098] Max: graded A Ending the Process. M-C-M is incomplete because it ends with<br />

the same <strong>thing</strong> that it starts with: money. <strong>The</strong> whole point <strong>of</strong> capitalizing <strong>of</strong>f the original<br />

amount M, is to amass more wealth. Why would anybody stop the cycle if their goal is to<br />

amass more and more money? M and M’ are, according to Hegel’s definition <strong>of</strong> a quantitative<br />

argument, essentially the same <strong>thing</strong> because there is no way to distinguish between<br />

the two. Capitalists will keep this endless cycle going because <strong>of</strong> the curse <strong>of</strong> money; they<br />

always want more. In this way M-C-M is incomplete. A more accurate way to right MCM<br />

would be M-C-M’-C-M”-C-M(n), where n is infinite unless there is a market crash or some<br />

other disruption in the economy that would make it advantageous for the capitalist not to<br />

invest. In contrast, C-M-C is a complete transaction because the second commodity “falls<br />

out <strong>of</strong> circulation.” It becomes a use value for someone and the process is complete.<br />

Next Message by Max is [1101].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 287<br />

[1113] Hal: graded A <strong>The</strong> Insatiable Capitalist. <strong>The</strong> M-C-M process is incomplete,<br />

but not because money must be spent for use-values. At the very beginning, the capitalist<br />

may have use-values as an end goal, but that goal quickly becomes overshadowed when<br />

he/she sees that money can be used to make more money. <strong>The</strong>n the capitalist’s desire for<br />

money becomes insatiable, and M-C-M is doomed to remain incomplete. <strong>The</strong> capitalist<br />

seeks money itself, so it is constantly reinvested to ensure maximum gains. No money falls<br />

out <strong>of</strong> circulation and the M-C-M process is endlessly repeated.<br />

Next Message by Hal is [1114].<br />

[1133] IrvingHowe: Upon further investigation, I now realize that M-C-M is in fact<br />

incomplete. To see why it is incomplete really takes only a bit <strong>of</strong> critical thinking. If one<br />

starts with M, we know that one really has no<strong>thing</strong> more than a commodity representative<br />

<strong>of</strong> a certain amount <strong>of</strong> labor. It has no use value and therefore must be spent in order to<br />

realize its own worth. So, in spending it, we now have purchased a good for which the<br />

value presumably either meets or exceeds the amount <strong>of</strong> labor represented in our money. In<br />

moving again to M, we know that we have now sold this commodity that was purchased<br />

earlier for an amount greater than we paid and thus greater than the original amount <strong>of</strong> M.<br />

M-C-M’<br />

So it will continue as we have now moved into a cycle that repeats itself if only for the<br />

purpose <strong>of</strong> achieving greater amounts <strong>of</strong> M.<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [1134].<br />

[1157] Orville: content B+ late penalty 1% No, that is not correct. Many people in this<br />

world do exactly that M-C-M and keep the money for long periods <strong>of</strong> time. Hoarders get<br />

and keep money money without using its value for long periods <strong>of</strong> time. Marx uses hoarders<br />

in several examples when describing money out <strong>of</strong> circulation.<br />

Hans: This is right but it is only half <strong>of</strong> the answer.<br />

Next Message by Orville is [1158].<br />

[1194] Tunda: M-C-M’ is insatiable and Marx explains that there is a slight difference in<br />

both M-C-M and M-C-M’. <strong>The</strong>y are both the same quality which is money. Because it ends<br />

in money the money always returns back so it is safe to say that it is complete.<br />

Next Message by Tunda is [1195].<br />

[1198] Cosmopolita: M-C-M is not necessarily wrong because it ends with M. Money<br />

not being a commodity, does give access to all use values. Qualitatively is universal. Not<br />

everybody necessarily needs to consume the commodity available in the present. <strong>The</strong> person<br />

might choose to hoard money instead and use this “money” for other purposes for later on<br />

in time. <strong>The</strong> ending <strong>of</strong> money opens a Pandora box in which the options are infinite due to<br />

money’s quantitative boundedness, which goes in contradiction with its quality.<br />

Hans: You are right, Marx would disagree with the statement that money is no<strong>thing</strong> by itself. But despite this<br />

Marx would still say M-C-M is incomplete, because the pr<strong>of</strong>it motive is not a one-time <strong>thing</strong> but capitalists want an<br />

ongoing stream <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

First Message by Cosmopolita is [209].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 516 is 310 in 1999SP, 391 in 2003fa, 457 in 2008SP, and 551 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 516 Can a situation which gives you subjective satisfaction be a situation <strong>of</strong> “enslavement”?<br />

Are there other examples for this than the capitalist?<br />

288 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[593] Utefan: It’s just an illusion. Any<strong>thing</strong> (As Submitted:) It’s just an illusion<br />

that gives subjective satisfaction can, in the<br />

worst case, become an enslavement <strong>of</strong> a person,<br />

people, or organization. Without mod-<br />

Any<strong>thing</strong> that has a subjective satisfaction<br />

eration one is susceptible to becoming over- can, in the worst case, become an enslaveenthused<br />

with what one generally uses for ment <strong>of</strong> a person, people, or organization.<br />

Without moderation one is susceptible to becoming<br />

over enthused with what they generally<br />

use for satisfaction. Under post 447 pri-<br />

satisfaction. PrivateProperty [2008SP:447] vate property uses the example <strong>of</strong> the Matrix<br />

uses the example <strong>of</strong> the Matrix to illustrate to illustrate the enslavement <strong>of</strong> the capitalist<br />

system over the people - in the matrix people<br />

were given experiences through a com-<br />

the enslavement <strong>of</strong> the people by the capitalputer mapping <strong>of</strong> their lives, it wasn’t unist<br />

system. In the Matrix people were given til they were unhooked from the computer<br />

experiences through a computer mapping<br />

<strong>of</strong> their lives. It wasn’t until they were un-<br />

that they could see the truth. Two <strong>thing</strong>s I<br />

hooked from the computer that they could would like to point out: <strong>first</strong> that after being<br />

unhooked the world they lived in was hor-<br />

see the truth. Two <strong>thing</strong>s I would like to rible and not at all what one would expect,<br />

thus perpetuating to the capitalist that with-<br />

point out: <strong>first</strong> that after being unhooked the out there system the civilized world would<br />

world they lived in was horrible and not at collapse; second that in the matrix they were<br />

given a choice <strong>of</strong> whether to remain in dark-<br />

all what they expected, thus perpetuating to<br />

the capitalist that without their system the<br />

civilized world would collapse; second that<br />

in the Matrix they were given the choice<br />

whether to remain in darkness or withdraw<br />

to reality.<br />

<strong>The</strong> question <strong>of</strong> enslavement takes away<br />

ness or withdraw to reality.<br />

<strong>The</strong> question <strong>of</strong> enslavement takes away<br />

the choice <strong>of</strong> one being able to choose what<br />

the choice <strong>of</strong> one being able to choose what<br />

one would rather do. As in the capitalist sys-<br />

they would rather do. As is the capitalist<br />

tem in which we live one has little choice<br />

if one has already reached that point <strong>of</strong> en-<br />

system <strong>of</strong> which we live one has little choice<br />

slavement. An example could be any that<br />

have been already used like sex, drugs, gam-<br />

if they have already reached that point <strong>of</strong><br />

bling, many <strong>of</strong> which are common. I would<br />

like to point out social standing or popular-<br />

enslavement. An example could be any<br />

ity. People have literally killed themselves that have been already used like sex, drugs,<br />

trying to fit in and thus have become a slave gambling many <strong>of</strong> which that are common.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 289<br />

to perceptions. Another example less commonly<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> is food. Overweight people<br />

would most likely agree that they can’t I would like to point out social standing<br />

control their physical need to gorge themselves.<br />

or popularity. People have literally killed<br />

themselves trying to fit in and thus have become<br />

a slave to perceptions. Another example<br />

are less commonly thought <strong>of</strong> like food,<br />

overweight people would most likely agree<br />

that they can’t control their physical need to<br />

gorge themselves.<br />

All <strong>of</strong> these points are showing the illusion<br />

<strong>of</strong> choice when there is none. Capitalist<br />

society’s motto is that anyone can be a<br />

All <strong>of</strong> these points are showing the illusion<br />

<strong>of</strong> choice when there is none. Capital-<br />

ist society’s motto is that anyone can be a capitalist (in essence rich) but as we can see<br />

not everyone can be. <strong>The</strong> capitalist is enslaved<br />

to accumulation and thus exploits the<br />

capitalist (in essence be rich) but as we can worker who is also enslaved to the system.<br />

see not everyone can be. <strong>The</strong> capitalist is<br />

enslaved by accumulation and thus exploits<br />

the worker who is also enslaved by the system.<br />

Hans: I made so many editorial changes that I thought it would be interesting for you all to see the Utefan’s original<br />

submission and my corrections side by side.<br />

Next Message by Utefan is [642].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 517 is 448 in 2007SP, 458 in 2008SP, 461 in 2008fa, and 480 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 517 Can one say that the capitalists are addicted to making money?<br />

[607] IrvingHowe: Addiction to money. <strong>The</strong> question being: Can one say that the<br />

capitalists are addicted to making money? <strong>The</strong> answer is a resounding yes.<br />

Dr. Drew Pinsky, a prominent modern addiction specialist is known for saying that addiction<br />

is defined by its consequences, not by frequency. <strong>The</strong>re is I believe, a lot <strong>of</strong> evidence<br />

to support this as a good working definition that most <strong>of</strong> us follow already. For instance, no<br />

one accuses Italy or Germany with being overrun with addicts despite the fact that in many<br />

parts <strong>of</strong> these countries alcohol consumption is a near daily part <strong>of</strong> life. This is because the<br />

consequences many <strong>of</strong> us associate with high levels <strong>of</strong> alcohol intake just don’t appear in the<br />

way that they do in the US.<br />

That said, the modern capitalist has by and large painted themselves into a corner that<br />

simply cannot be escaped. Even if you reject global warming as a fact, you cannot deny that<br />

the capitalist is tying his/her own noose every day. As econ majors we all understand how<br />

interdependent each section <strong>of</strong> the economy is and how negative shocks feed on themselves<br />

to become much larger than the initial blow.<br />

290 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

So the question is, what happens when the capitalist runs out <strong>of</strong> resources to exploit? I<br />

do not even necessarily mean oil or energy resources. Iron ore to make steel, copper for<br />

electrical production, cement for building construction– all <strong>of</strong> these <strong>thing</strong>s are necessary for<br />

the capitalist and yet he knowingly pillages the finite supplies <strong>of</strong> these essential commodities<br />

without regard to the economic sustainability <strong>of</strong> his business.<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>it is <strong>of</strong> course the driver for this unsustainable production. It can be said that pr<strong>of</strong>it is<br />

both the motivation and the cause <strong>of</strong> death for the capitalist for even without environmental<br />

cost accounting, capitalism as we know it simply cannot be sustained and many capitalist’s<br />

know that to be the case. <strong>The</strong> capitalist can try to reason that business will lead the way to<br />

a new method <strong>of</strong> production, a new material for use and continued prosperity but this view<br />

is fatally flawed. It ignores that capitalism is already failing to find other materials for use,<br />

even when the the price <strong>of</strong> gold, ore, cement and copper skyrocket. <strong>The</strong> capitalist who takes<br />

this view also would do so by ignoring the fact that capitalism as its known today is not a<br />

tried and true, time tested survivor but rather a blip in the economic history <strong>of</strong> the world that<br />

looks wholly untested when put into historical context.<br />

Despite this, the capitalists’ addiction keeps him going.<br />

Hans: Iron and cement are not scarce, but there are many scarce minerals; lithium and rare earths were inthe news<br />

lately.<br />

Message [607] referenced by [654]. Next Message by IrvingHowe is [608].<br />

[613] Lana: <strong>The</strong> vicious cycle. Are capitalists addicted to money? <strong>The</strong> answer is quite<br />

obviously yes. As both an economics and environmental studies student, I find the fundamentals<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalism to be horribly inefficient and detrimental to the environment and<br />

species <strong>of</strong> the world. Capitalists are so motivated by the prospect <strong>of</strong> squeezing another dollar<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the resources (be it oil, child labor, forests, or themselves) that they do not care<br />

that they are essentially setting themselves up for future collapse.<br />

Capitalism is an unsustainable business that has the players enslaved. In the American<br />

society today, much <strong>of</strong> what we equate as success has to do with the possessions we can<br />

acquire. We believe that a bigger television, a second home on the beach, and that new<br />

designer handbag will bring us happiness and boost our social stature. This may in fact be<br />

true, but as a nation we work longer hours with less vacation time that most other developed<br />

countries. We are constantly trying to keep up with the “Jones’” and it’s left us in a vicious<br />

cycle <strong>of</strong> making lots <strong>of</strong> money but no time to actually enjoy it. We are enslaved by the idea<br />

<strong>of</strong> money and what it can bring us.<br />

Hans: Being addicted to money means being preoccupied with building up your net worth. This is not quite the<br />

same as wanting to have a second home on the beach.<br />

Next Message by Lana is [691].<br />

[654] Hans: Individual Habits and Social Commandments. In past semesters I tried to<br />

argue that the paradigm <strong>of</strong> addictions is not the right way to look at it. <strong>The</strong> need to accumulate<br />

more and more money does not originate in capitalist greed but is deeply embedded in<br />

the entire fabric <strong>of</strong> capitalist society. But the notion that capitalists are addicted is very appealing.<br />

IrvingHowe [607] says “a resounding yes” and Lana [617] echoes “quite obviously<br />

yes.” Also in earlier semesters, class participants were adamant that capitalists are addicted,<br />

although I tried to argue against it.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 291<br />

Why is my argument, which you can read for instance in [2007SP:601], not convincing<br />

to you? Is it wrong? Lana supplies a hint how to solve this riddle. She switches, apparently<br />

without giving it much thought, from the capitalists’ addiction to money to consumers’ addiction<br />

to consumer goods.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is a difference between Dagobert Duck sitting in his basement counting coins and<br />

him sitting on the deck <strong>of</strong> his vacation home enjoying the sunset. It is not only a difference<br />

but a contradiction. In 740:1/o, Marx brings the Faust quote “two souls, alas, do dwell within<br />

his breast,” and in the same paragraph Marx hints at it that luxury consumption is a rebellion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalist as individual against his social function to oversee accumulation. See my<br />

comments to [2008SP:712]. Apparently, the late Larry Miller was not rebellious enough in<br />

this respect; one <strong>of</strong> the complaints <strong>of</strong> his family has been that he was so unavailable because<br />

he was always busy making money.<br />

<strong>The</strong> rich are not the only ones guilty here. When I was working on the line, I knew workers,<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten in the skilled trades, who always worked, benefiting from good UAW overtime<br />

premiums. This allowed them to provide for the family and avoid the “bitch at home” at the<br />

same time.<br />

Ok, here is the solution <strong>of</strong> the riddle. <strong>The</strong> social need to accumulate more and more<br />

money is not only reflected in the greed <strong>of</strong> the capitalists, but also in the habits <strong>of</strong> many other<br />

members <strong>of</strong> capitalist society which could be viewed as addictions. See also [Answer:512].<br />

Regarding this last cross reference: I am in the process <strong>of</strong> compiling definite answers to<br />

some <strong>of</strong> the questions. Download it as<br />

or<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/halfpage/Answer.pdf<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/screen/Answer.pdf<br />

Hans.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [662].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 525 is 562 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 525 Why does Marx say that the surplus-value has the same age than the capital<br />

from which it springs?<br />

[598] Proletarian: graded A Surplus-Value, Capital, and the Holy Trinity. <strong>The</strong> reason<br />

for Marx’s statement that surplus-value has the same age as the capital from which it sprung<br />

can be drawn from Marx’s comparison <strong>of</strong> capital and surplus-value to a religious concept:<br />

that God and his son, Christ, are one being.<br />

In some Christian religions (most notably Catholicism and other orthodox religions), God<br />

the Father and the God the Son are considered to be one being <strong>of</strong> the same substance. Even<br />

though they may appear differentiated at <strong>first</strong> glance while reading scripture, such as in John<br />

3:16 “For God so loved the world, that he gave his only begotten Son...”, practitioners <strong>of</strong> the<br />

faith believe that the Father and the Son are one being. This was decided upon at the First<br />

Council <strong>of</strong> Nicaea, and since that point, orthodox religions have maintained that God the<br />

292 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Father, God the Son, and God the Holy Spirit are three “persons” <strong>of</strong> the same “substance”<br />

and are <strong>of</strong> the same age and form and in actuality one being.<br />

Think <strong>of</strong> this seemingly strange conceptualization <strong>of</strong> the “Holy Trinity” using the clover<br />

metaphor and it makes a bit more sense. God the Father, God the Son, and God the Holy<br />

Spirit are all leaves on a clover, but they are are together a clover (Godhead). <strong>The</strong>y are all<br />

components or sides <strong>of</strong> the same <strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Marx asserts that surplus-value and the capital from which it sprung have a similar relationship.<br />

At the end <strong>of</strong> an M-C-M’ cycle it is easy to say that £100 capital is different than<br />

the £10 <strong>of</strong> surplus value, at least at <strong>first</strong> glance. After all, they seem distinct, and until the<br />

£10 <strong>of</strong> surplus-value comes in, the £100 is not capital, and the £10 surplus value would not<br />

be brought to the capitalist without the £100 capital.<br />

However, at the end <strong>of</strong> the M-C-M’ string <strong>of</strong> transactions, when the capitalist receives his<br />

£110, the distinction between the capital and the surplus value disappears and the capitalist<br />

is left with £110. While conceptually surplus-value and capital can be discussed as separate,<br />

they are in actuality indistinguishable, two parts <strong>of</strong> the same substance and <strong>of</strong> the same age<br />

and form, and together they make up one “being”: M’.<br />

<strong>The</strong> clover metaphor can be applied here, too (though it’s a two-leaf clover). <strong>The</strong> £100<br />

capital and the £10 surplus-value are both leafs on the same clover, the clover being M’. As<br />

M’, the surplus-value and capital are <strong>of</strong> the same substance and are indistinguishable.<br />

Hans: “<strong>The</strong> same age” can be explained just by a simple father-son metaphor without the trinity metaphor: the<br />

moment when it gives birth to surplus-value is the moment when the originally advanced sum <strong>of</strong> money becomes<br />

capital. My son’s fifth birthday is the fifth anniversary <strong>of</strong> me being father. It is a little a stretch to call the length<br />

<strong>of</strong> the father’s role as father his “age,” and this is what you should have explained. If this can be justified then it<br />

follows that the age <strong>of</strong> the father is the same as the age <strong>of</strong> the son.<br />

Next Message by Proletarian is [618].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 528 is 459 in 2007SP, 472 in 2008fa, and 544 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 528 In what respects does M− C−M “contradict all the previously developed<br />

laws bearing on the nature <strong>of</strong> commodities, value, money, and <strong>of</strong> circulation itself”?<br />

[638] Wolf: Contradictions <strong>of</strong> M-C-M’. In regards to the nature <strong>of</strong> commodities: One<br />

may obtain more desired use-values in circulation or in exchange but this does not affect<br />

nor represent the value <strong>of</strong> commodities as both sides benefit (Capital 260-261). In M-C-M’,<br />

additional value appears to be created out <strong>of</strong> thin air through mere inversion <strong>of</strong> simple commodity<br />

circulation. This cannot be possible, because value is determined from the abstract<br />

labor within commodities.<br />

In regards to value: M-C-M’ appears to magically create additional value solely from<br />

circulation. When you look at the totality <strong>of</strong> circulation, how can it be possible to increase<br />

value from circulation alone if no new values are actually being created? If prices would increase<br />

to result in surplus-value, prices would subsequently be raised throughout the totality<br />

in order to represent values.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 293<br />

In regards to money: If money represents value, how is it possible to increase money<br />

without increasing value? Sure the seller can inflate prices but generally, buyers will gravitate<br />

back towards the better represented value in price form. This is directly linked to the<br />

above contradiction in regards to value.<br />

In regards to circulation: Circulation cannot create additional value because it is not producing<br />

or creating any use-value. On the other hand, how can a simple switch in form<br />

from C-M-C and M-C-M result in M-C-M’? Additionally, if the exchanges between M-C<br />

and C-M are contained in C-M-C and M-C-M (besides this making the general formula for<br />

capital merely simple commodity circulation, resulting in deligitimizing the distinction <strong>of</strong><br />

M-C-M’), wouldn’t the producers tend to find other producers and exchange at better representations<br />

<strong>of</strong> value (Capital 258-259)? Maybe in a particular instance can the capitalist<br />

swindle and make M-C-M’ occur, but this doesn’t seem to be too possible, especially to a<br />

point today with such extreme disparities in wealth distribution. It would have to be the<br />

biggest swindle that happened by chance in history (even though capitalism is the biggest<br />

swindle, I wouldn’t say it was by chance). Also, as stated throughout chapter five, circulation<br />

cannot create surplus-value while simultaneously supposed to run on the exchange <strong>of</strong> equivalents<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. This ties in to the above 3 contradictions with the nature <strong>of</strong> commodities,<br />

value, and money.<br />

From my limited understanding, is this where the purchasing <strong>of</strong> labor-power fits in, waged<br />

labor, and expropriated surplus-value stems from, forced by primitive accumulation?<br />

Hans: Exactly. This is the resolution in chapter Six <strong>of</strong> the puzzle how M-C-M’ is possible.<br />

Next Message by Wolf is [685].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 529 is 306 in 1998WI, 340 in 2000fa, 402 in 2003fa, 451 in 2004fa, 463 in<br />

2007fa, 470 in 2008SP, 545 in 2011fa, 569 in 2012fa, and 529 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 529 Does Marx argue in 258:2/o that capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its are middleman’s pr<strong>of</strong>its,<br />

and if buyer and seller sold directly to each other, there would be no pr<strong>of</strong>it?<br />

[627] Kobe: In this paragraph Marx is arguing that capitalists pr<strong>of</strong>its and middleman’s<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its don’t differ greatly. Instead, Marx talks <strong>of</strong> the capitalist who would switch from M-<br />

C-M to a C-M-C. A C-M-C metabolism sells goods when they need to be sold otherwise<br />

for example the good would sit in the warehouse and not be consumed. Switching from<br />

the <strong>first</strong> option <strong>of</strong> M-C-M, which is static to the later <strong>of</strong> C-M-C would now make this an<br />

emotional decision. By doing so the selling and purchasing time, starting with the selling<br />

<strong>of</strong> a good to B which would lead to a purchase <strong>of</strong> goods from A. This example does not rid<br />

capitalists from circulation, this example is one way a middleman can turn a pr<strong>of</strong>it. If buyer<br />

and seller were to sell directly to each other, pr<strong>of</strong>its would still be made but would shrink the<br />

transactions into a one-sided phase <strong>of</strong> ordinary circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Hans: You didn’t get Marx’s joke. See [Answer:3].<br />

Next Message by Kobe is [660].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 532 is 430 in 2005fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 532 How does the abstraction Marx makes in the <strong>first</strong> sentence <strong>of</strong> 260:2/o differ<br />

from the ceteris paribus assumptions <strong>of</strong> modern economics?<br />

294 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[624] Babyceta: graded A Birth weights, left-hand turns, and the difference between<br />

abstraction and ceteris paribus. <strong>The</strong> ceteris paribus assumption in economics allows us<br />

to observe outcomes between two variables by limiting or omitting the impact or influence <strong>of</strong><br />

other variables. It literally means “with other <strong>thing</strong>s the same” and it affords us a “snapshot”<br />

(Hans, [2005fa:1064]) for a brief moment when other <strong>thing</strong>s can be rendered unimportant.<br />

How realistic is this? Not very, but the “dismal science” is full <strong>of</strong> such suppositions. If we<br />

are looking at the birth weight <strong>of</strong> infants, for example, we may consider the mother’s weight<br />

and chose to hold constant her education level, her income, and even her marital status.<br />

Certainly, these <strong>thing</strong>s matter, but economics is a “s<strong>of</strong>t” science and we can do that with our<br />

models. (Ever consider the assumption <strong>of</strong> full employment in neoclassical models?) Our<br />

regression will give us the average birth weight as influenced by the mother’s weight, but<br />

it would not provide insight into the social and physical forces that define a healthy child.<br />

Hans says “this is like trying to understand how a car drives by turning the left wheel and<br />

holding every<strong>thing</strong> else constant.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> abstraction Marx makes in the last sentence <strong>of</strong> 260:2/o is not an attempt to hold<br />

all other variables constant. I believe that would be an absurd notion to Marx because his<br />

critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism is not about isolating moments or “snapshots;” it is an archaeological<br />

expedition to unearth the hidden forces present in the capitalist system. (Perhaps removing<br />

our glasses any polishing them with his handkerchief might be a better analogy?) He does<br />

this by building a framework or scaffolding that allows us to remain on the outside <strong>of</strong> the<br />

building so that we can get an unobstructed view <strong>of</strong> its foundations (most <strong>of</strong> us are indeed<br />

outsiders, but few realize this). Hans refers to these as “layers <strong>of</strong> forces” (the economy being<br />

one force, and weather, perhaps, being another), and says that “the <strong>thing</strong>s that are abstracted<br />

from are the extraneous forces which may interfere but do not contribute to the inner working<br />

<strong>of</strong> the system under scrutiny.” [2005fa:1064] For example, a snowstorm may interfere with<br />

the transportation <strong>of</strong> goods to the market, but it essentially has no bearing on the structure or<br />

operation <strong>of</strong> markets themselves.<br />

Marx, however, is not looking at birth weights. He is abstracting “all that happens in<br />

exchange” (leaving aside the replacing <strong>of</strong> one use-value by another) so that we can get an<br />

unobstructed view <strong>of</strong> the metamorphosis that occurs when commodities change form. Remember,<br />

we are talking here about turning a quarter into five nickles. I think it is important<br />

to understand what the “this” means in the statement “if we consider this in the abstract.”<br />

Here, Marx is talking about exchange-value and that fact that exchange-value does not increase<br />

in the exchange process. Marx says “the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is expressed in its<br />

price before it enters circulation, and it is therefore a pre-condition <strong>of</strong> circulation, not its<br />

result.” [260:1] <strong>The</strong> fact that value is a pre-condition means it can easily be abstracted away<br />

without affecting the manner in which we observe commodities change form.<br />

Next Message by Babyceta is [879].<br />

[628] Scholar: Marx’s abstraction means that there are no exceptions during the exchange,<br />

that is to say, all the exchanges take place according to the law <strong>of</strong> exchange that identified<br />

with by all the traders, such as the principle <strong>of</strong> equivalence and equity, exchange with free<br />

will etc. Only if these principles are followed, the market exchange could go on wheels,<br />

which has been proved by the market practice in a long history. So, Marx’s abstraction


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 295<br />

is based on the economic facts, and in order to find the essential, it gets rid <strong>of</strong> some factors<br />

that will destroy market exchange for violating the law <strong>of</strong> exchange, which happened<br />

occasionally, but not the mainstream <strong>of</strong> development <strong>of</strong> the market economy.<br />

Ceteris paribus assumptions <strong>of</strong> modern economics are not based on the facts or realities,<br />

they are prone to subjective assumptions only for the convenience <strong>of</strong> constructing their<br />

model. So, these assumptions are usually far from the practice <strong>of</strong> the economy, and so the<br />

conclusion from these assumptions is just a castle in the air and is meaningless.<br />

Next Message by Scholar is [672].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 537 is 309 in 1998WI, 343 in 2000fa, 362 in 2001fa, 408 in 2003fa, 458 in<br />

2004fa, and 435 in 2005fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 537 How does Marx rebut the argument that exchange should be considered an<br />

act <strong>of</strong> production because the same products in the hands <strong>of</strong> consumers are worth more than<br />

in the hands <strong>of</strong> producers?<br />

[629] Atticus: graded B Refutation <strong>of</strong> Newman. Marx refutes Newman’s theory that<br />

“Commerce...adds value to products, for the same products in the hands <strong>of</strong> consumers are<br />

worth more than in the hands <strong>of</strong> producers, and it may strictly be considered an act <strong>of</strong><br />

production” by stating that if this were the case, then the producer may as well directly<br />

convert the commodities into money and skip the exchange process altogether (annotations<br />

pp. 378-379). Buying and selling are not forms <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Hans makes the error in Newman’s theory clearer by stating that a “Marxist would answer:<br />

you are trying to charge me twice for the same commodity” (ibid 378). If Newman’s<br />

theory was correct then people would purchase commodities directly from the producer and<br />

skip the middleman altogether. Large retail stores like Target or Walmart would not exist<br />

unless they produced all <strong>of</strong> their own commodities.<br />

Hans: I think your <strong>first</strong> paragraph draws on the following sentence in 261:1/o: “We might ... say that the buyer<br />

performs what is ‘strictly’ an ‘act <strong>of</strong> production’ by converting stockings, for example, into money.” By this, Marx<br />

does not mean skipping the middle man, but he mimics the seller’s argument from the buyer’s side. If the seller<br />

argues that he benefits the buyer by converting the seller’s money into stockings, the buyer can argue that he benefits<br />

the seller by converting the seller’s stockings into money. With the same justification with which the buyer asks for<br />

more money for his stockings, the seller can ask for more stockings for his money. Sellers and buyers can come up<br />

with all kinds <strong>of</strong> stories trying to convince the other party to agree to a deal more favorable to them. What counts<br />

is not these stories, but what sets the long run price is the competition between the sellers. What matters for this<br />

competition is the market price compared to the labor input. If a seller can fetch a good market price compared to<br />

the labor input, he will produce more. In the long run, this will tend to make prices proportional to labor input. <strong>The</strong><br />

fact that the buyer gains use-value is not reflected in the long-run price <strong>of</strong> the commodity. This is what Marx means<br />

when he says the buyer has to pay only for the value, not for the use-value.<br />

Next Message by Atticus is [630].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 538 If you exchange risky assets with complementary pr<strong>of</strong>iles, so that both parties<br />

have the same expected value but lower variance after the exchange, is this an example <strong>of</strong><br />

value created from exchange?<br />

[618] Proletarian: graded A No Creation <strong>of</strong> Value From Exchanging Assets to Minimize<br />

Variance. No, exchanging risky assets with complementary pr<strong>of</strong>iles so that both<br />

296 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

parties have the same expected value but with lower variance is not an example <strong>of</strong> creation<br />

<strong>of</strong> value from exchange.<br />

For example, say that person A has two units <strong>of</strong> asset 1 and person B has two units <strong>of</strong><br />

asset 2. <strong>The</strong> expected value <strong>of</strong> asset 1 and asset 2 are both $100, meaning that before the<br />

exchanging <strong>of</strong> any assets both person A and person B hold assets with a total expected value<br />

<strong>of</strong> $200.<br />

Now, say that the variability for the expected value <strong>of</strong> asset 1 is very high such that it<br />

could end up with a value <strong>of</strong> $0-$200, though its expected value is still $100. On the other<br />

hand, say that the variability <strong>of</strong> asset 2 is very low such that it could end up with a value <strong>of</strong><br />

$90-$110, though its expected value is still $100.<br />

If person A should desire to exchange one unit <strong>of</strong> asset 1 for a unit <strong>of</strong> asset 2 to decrease<br />

his variability (risk) in his bundle <strong>of</strong> assets so that his outcome could be between $90-$310<br />

as opposed to $0-$400, he is doing so only to reduce his exposure to risk. <strong>The</strong> expected<br />

value <strong>of</strong> his bundle would remain at $200.<br />

Similarly, if person B should desire to exchange one unit <strong>of</strong> asset 2 for a unit <strong>of</strong> asset 1 to<br />

increase his variability (risk) in his bundle so that his outcome could potentially be as high<br />

as $310 as opposed to only $220 if he maintains his possession <strong>of</strong> both units <strong>of</strong> asset 2, he<br />

does so only to increase his potential outcome (though he may also potentially have a worse<br />

outcome by opening his bundle up to more variability).<br />

Whether or not person A and person B decide to exchange their assets does not have<br />

any effect on the total value <strong>of</strong> the assets they both started out with, no matter who ends up<br />

holding them. <strong>The</strong> two units <strong>of</strong> asset 1 and two units <strong>of</strong> asset 2 all together have an expected<br />

value <strong>of</strong> $400, and that expected value stays the same no matter who holds them.<br />

Even if the expected values do not turn out to be the actual values and the actual values<br />

end up being different than the expected values, whoever holds which assets does not affect<br />

the final valuation <strong>of</strong> said assets. Say for example that the actual value <strong>of</strong> asset 1 turns out to<br />

be $50 instead <strong>of</strong> the expected $100, and that the actual value <strong>of</strong> asset 2 turns out to be $110<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> the expected $100. If that scenario plays out, then the total value <strong>of</strong> the assets will<br />

be $320. <strong>The</strong> total value <strong>of</strong> all the assets will still be $320 no matter who holds which asset<br />

in the end. By exchanging assets it is possible that either person A or person B could end up<br />

in a better situation than he or she would have been without the exchange, but even then, his<br />

or her improved outcome is not the result <strong>of</strong> the creation <strong>of</strong> value, but rather the result <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fortuitous outcome <strong>of</strong> the exchange (which was equally unfortunate for the other person in<br />

the exchange). Put simply, if from the exchange someone benefits while the other doesn’t,<br />

it is not from the creation <strong>of</strong> value from the exchange but rather from the shifting <strong>of</strong> value<br />

from one person to the other during the exchange.<br />

Marx asserts that the creation <strong>of</strong> value cannot come from mere exchange. Value is only<br />

created by the addition <strong>of</strong> labor, and as we will be demonstrated and discussed in chapters<br />

six and seven, surplus-value can be created by capitalists performing M-C-M’ through the<br />

purchase and use <strong>of</strong> the commodity <strong>of</strong> labor-power.<br />

Hans: You are right, the expected values <strong>of</strong> the assets will not increase by the exchanges. But you ignore that the<br />

standard deviations are affected. If you are risk averse, it is better not to put all your eggs into one basket.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 297<br />

To make my point by a numerical example, I have to assume that the variability does not differ quite as much<br />

as in your example. Assume each unit <strong>of</strong> asset 1 has standard deviation <strong>of</strong> 3, and asset 2 a standard deviation <strong>of</strong><br />

4. Also assume that both units <strong>of</strong> each asset always give the same outcome, say asset 1 is a share in corporation<br />

A and asset 2 in corporation B. But assume assets 1 are probabilistically independent <strong>of</strong> assets 2. <strong>The</strong>n before the<br />

exchange, A has a standard deviation <strong>of</strong> 6, and B a standard deviation <strong>of</strong> 8. After the exchange, each A and B has<br />

a standard deviation <strong>of</strong> 5. (Extra credit if someone can do the math.) Also assume A and B are both risk averse.<br />

This means they both gained in the exchange, although B gained more than A. How is this compatible with Marx’s<br />

thesis that with respect to value, exchanges are a zero-sum game?<br />

Next Message by Proletarian is [622].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 540 is 473 in 2007fa, 503 in 2009fa, and 556 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 540 Ramsay asks: “who are the consumers?” This is a rhetorical question, obviously<br />

he had an answer in mind. Which answer?<br />

[625] Kaimani: Who is the Consumer? I think that the answer to this question, and<br />

the one that Ramsay is looking for, is that he recognizes that there is a class <strong>of</strong> people who<br />

only consume and do not produce. In reality, it is the seller who is the consumer, the seller<br />

increases their prices to make pr<strong>of</strong>it. This exceeds the actual price or value <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

and the consumer buys it because <strong>of</strong> their individual need or want but doesn’t necessarily<br />

need to use it as a tool to create more surplus for the consumer or anyone else for that matter.<br />

This pr<strong>of</strong>it allows the seller to go and seek out more commodities to sell in the market place.<br />

<strong>The</strong> cycle goes back to the seller because it is up to the seller to create or find a commodity<br />

that is wanted in the market place and the seller needs to be able to sell the commodity for<br />

money and a pr<strong>of</strong>it so that the seller can go and purchase or consume other items that will<br />

increase the sellers pr<strong>of</strong>it and living. <strong>The</strong> seller is the ultimate consumer, without the seller,<br />

trade would cease to happen and needed commodities would remain idle and therefore, the<br />

access to an array <strong>of</strong> needed commodities in the market place would be virtually impossible.<br />

Message [625] referenced by [630]. Next Message by Kaimani is [796].<br />

[630] Atticus: (graded A+) <strong>The</strong> consumers are everyone. Kaimani’s answer to this<br />

question in [625] incorrect. He/she claims that the seller is the ultimate consumer. It has<br />

already been noted that everyone in a capitalistic economy are both sellers and buyers. It<br />

seems as though Kaimani may have misunderstood the readings by his/her statement that<br />

the “seller increases their prices to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it”. <strong>The</strong> origins <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it, or surplus-value,<br />

have not yet been explained. Marx’s statement 264:2 debunks [625]: “Those who most<br />

consistently uphold the illusion that surplus-value has its origin in a nominal rise <strong>of</strong> prices,<br />

or in the privilege which the seller has <strong>of</strong> selling too dear, assume therefore that there exists a<br />

class <strong>of</strong> buyers who do not sell, i.e. a class <strong>of</strong> consumers who do not produce.” If a seller sells<br />

her commodity at ten percent above cost then she, in turn, will purchase other commodities<br />

at ten percent above their cost.<br />

To answer Ramsay’s question: the consumers are everyone.<br />

Next Message by Atticus is [716].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 546 is 313 in 1998WI, 398 in 2002fa, 413 in 2003fa, 463 in 2004fa, 440 in<br />

2005fa, 472 in 2007SP, 478 in 2007fa, 509 in 2009fa, and 562 in 2011fa:<br />

298 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 546 What is the difference between a shoemaker, who adds to the value <strong>of</strong> his<br />

leather by turning the leather into shoes, and a capitalist, who adds to the value <strong>of</strong> his<br />

money by investing it?<br />

[619] AlexDaily: graded A <strong>The</strong> Shoemaker vs. the Capitalist. <strong>The</strong> Shoemaker differs<br />

from the Capitalist in their relationship to the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity. <strong>The</strong> Shoemaker adds<br />

to the value <strong>of</strong> the shoe by turning the leather into a shoe, or in simpler terms, by adding<br />

his labor, whereas the Capitalist seeks an increase in the value without adding labor <strong>of</strong> his<br />

own. <strong>The</strong> Capitalist, therefore, needs to find a different source <strong>of</strong> labor. <strong>The</strong> producer fills<br />

this void because they need capital to start producing. Wherefore, the capitalist can invest<br />

and receive as Ada puts it in [2009fa:660] “virtually free labor (an increase in value for<br />

which he/she only pays for in time).” Furthermore, the Capitalist is looking for a return on<br />

his investment. <strong>The</strong>refore, the Capitalist needs to simply separate the producer from the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production. Hans explains in [2009fa:660] that “Today’s capitalists do not have<br />

to separate the producers from the means <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong>y benefit from the separation<br />

which society has done for them in the past.” Because <strong>of</strong> this separation, the Capitalist can<br />

pay the laborer less than he is worth and gain a return on his investment. Hans put it this way<br />

in [2003fa:361] “In a capitalist society, money increases by itself not because the investors<br />

are so smart, but because those who create all value, the workers, are cut <strong>of</strong>f from the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production and therefore get wages that are far below the value they produce.”<br />

Message [619] referenced by [633]. Next Message by AlexDaily is [653].<br />

[633] Hal: <strong>The</strong> Capitalist’s Shoe Collection. I agree with AlexDaily [619], but I have<br />

more to add.<br />

Essentially, the shoemaker adds value to the world, while the capitalist does not. Instead,<br />

the capitalist attempts to make citizens totally dependent on him to fulfill their needs, thereby<br />

allowing him to extort money from producers. If the shoemaker adds 10 beautifully handcrafted<br />

shoes to the world, the capitalist would figure out a way to extort one pair to add to<br />

his collection. In a new turn <strong>of</strong> events, the producers would then read about the capitalist’s<br />

beautiful shoe collection.<br />

Next Message by Hal is [1006].<br />

[1079] Goldtone: graded A A shoemaker is different from a capitalist in her ability to<br />

add value to leather in order to produce shoes, because she uses her own labor to produce<br />

this value. A capitalist on the other hand invests his money in order to get more money.<br />

This process does not add value to any<strong>thing</strong>, but rather is only trading money for more<br />

money. <strong>The</strong> capitalist takes the value <strong>of</strong> the laborer through his monopoly <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production. Hans notes this in [2003fa:361]:<br />

In a capitalist society, money increases by itself not because the investors are so smart,<br />

but because those who create all value, the workers, are cut <strong>of</strong>f from the means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

and therefore get wages that are far below the value they produce.<br />

Next Message by Goldtone is [1087].<br />

[1095] Kaush: <strong>The</strong> difference is that the shoemaker creates value by his/her own labor<br />

and can increase value by adding new labor. <strong>The</strong>re is more value to the shoes than the leather<br />

because the shoes contain more quantity <strong>of</strong> labor. <strong>The</strong> shoemaker employs (C-M-C). <strong>The</strong><br />

investor invests money in a commodity to make money (M-C-M). <strong>The</strong>refore the investor is


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 299<br />

not increasing the value <strong>of</strong> investment; instead, the investor is making use <strong>of</strong> the prevailing<br />

social relations that produce value from workers’ unpaid labor.<br />

First Message by Kaush is [182].<br />

[1126] Smartergirl: <strong>The</strong> difference between the shoe maker and investor is substantial.<br />

<strong>The</strong> shoe maker adds value to his leather by making shoes because he increases his own<br />

labor to create the shoe. By increasing his labor the shoe has resulted in more value. <strong>The</strong><br />

capitalist does not add additional labor to produce his pr<strong>of</strong>its, instead he uses abstinence.<br />

He abstains from using a portion <strong>of</strong> his pr<strong>of</strong>its and because he has used them productively<br />

he is rewarded with more money and pr<strong>of</strong>its. His money has increased therefore increasing<br />

value without having to labor for the value. My initial answer was on the right track but<br />

a bit unclear and skewed. I said that because there was no commodity exchanged from the<br />

investor that the value was distorted. <strong>The</strong> value is distorted but not solely because there is not<br />

an exchange but because the labor has not increased. It is increased labor that creates value<br />

in Marxs view. However the investor does not increase or use any labor but has manipulated<br />

the system to create value without increasing labor.<br />

Hans: Marx does not believe that abstinence creates value. Marx would say it is not possible to create value<br />

without labor. <strong>The</strong>refore if an investor gets value without labor, someone else in society must be working without<br />

getting the value he or she has produced. Marx also emphasizes that this can happen without value being distorted,<br />

i.e., it can happen in a situation in which every commodity is bought and sold exactly at their values.<br />

Next Message by Smartergirl is [1128].<br />

[1129] RexManning: graded A <strong>The</strong> difference between a shoe maker and a capitalist is<br />

that a shoe maker adds their labor to the leather to create shoes. By using his labor to make<br />

boots the shoe maker has created value with his labor. <strong>The</strong> boots now have more value than<br />

the leather because <strong>of</strong> the added labor. <strong>The</strong> capitalist wants an increase in value without<br />

actually adding his labor. Which is why he exploits the producer, so that they create the<br />

value with their labor, while the capitalist underpays them and keeps them separated from<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong> wages that the capitalist pays the laborer are far below the<br />

value they produce, and so the capitalist can continue to increase his value without actually<br />

having to input his labor. <strong>The</strong> capitalist is virtually doing no<strong>thing</strong> but keeping the producer<br />

from the means <strong>of</strong> production in order to increase his value.<br />

Next Message by RexManning is [1186].<br />

[1196] Guh: <strong>The</strong> Shoemaker. <strong>The</strong>re is a clear difference between a shoemaker and a<br />

capitalist when it comes to their value and labor. A shoemaker who makes his own shoe is<br />

creating value through his labor. He creates more value as he makes shoes with the leather,<br />

and is doing this solely on his own. Now, as for a capitalist, who uses laborers to create<br />

value for him, which he then invests. Furthermore, the capitalist will add value to his money<br />

by investing it and getting a return on his investment. <strong>The</strong>refore the difference in the two is<br />

that with a capitalist his investment does not add value to his money, but the producer does.<br />

Hans: Marx would say that the value is added not by the capitalist by investing but by the laborers by working for<br />

a lower wage than the product <strong>of</strong> their labor.<br />

First Message by Guh is [168].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 569 is 281 in 1996sp, 328 in 1998WI, 419 in 2002fa, 435 in 2003fa, 485 in<br />

2004fa, 462 in 2005fa, 494 in 2007SP, 499 in 2007fa, 506 in 2008SP, 509 in 2008fa, 532<br />

in 2009fa, and 611 in 2012fa:<br />

300 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 569 Which two sets <strong>of</strong> conditions must be satisfied for labor-power to be a commodity?<br />

[827] Kaush: Labor-power to be a commodity. <strong>The</strong> two sets <strong>of</strong> conditions that must be<br />

satisfied for labor-power to be a commodity are:<br />

1. <strong>The</strong> laborer must have full freedom to sell his/her labor-power, must be the sole free<br />

owner and seller <strong>of</strong> his/her labor ability and sold for a finite period <strong>of</strong> time.<br />

2. <strong>The</strong> laborer must have freedom from the means <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong>refore the laborer<br />

must sell his/her labor-power but not the products <strong>of</strong> his/her labor. In the case <strong>of</strong> selling<br />

the product <strong>of</strong> their labor, there is no need to sell their labor-power since selling a finished<br />

product is more pr<strong>of</strong>itable.<br />

Hans: This is the right answer.<br />

Message [827] referenced by [2012fa:1201]. Next Message by Kaush is [835].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 580 Describe the differences and similarities between the commodity labor-power<br />

and the commodities discussed in chapter One.<br />

[960] Frida: graded A Labor Power as a Commodity. Labor-Power is similar in that it<br />

meets the prerequisites for being a commodity. It has value, labor went into producing it.<br />

It has use-value, the details <strong>of</strong> this will be explained below. And, somewhat disturbingly,<br />

it is produced for sale. By this I mean that capitalists are always making sure there will be<br />

enough labor power on the market.<br />

<strong>The</strong> main difference that sets labor power apart is that during the consumption <strong>of</strong> its use<br />

value it creates value. This difference is crucial because it forms the foundation for the entire<br />

capitalist system. Capitalists pay workers for the exchange value <strong>of</strong> their labor power, which<br />

turns out to be much less than the value produced by their labor, which enters the equation<br />

as a use-value<br />

Hans: As I see it, it is not produced for sale, this is the main difference, but it still must be sold because it is not a<br />

use-value in the hands <strong>of</strong> its owner because the owner is cut <strong>of</strong>f from the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

First Message by Frida is [82].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 589 is 269 in 1997WI and 481 in 2005fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 589 Marx says elsewhere that labor unions are necessary for workers to be able<br />

to receive a wage which corresponds to the value <strong>of</strong> their labor-power and is not below it.<br />

Can you bring arguments from chapter Six to support this?<br />

[644] Hans: <strong>Utah</strong> Labor Law about Breaks. After reading School’s [641] I wondered<br />

whether employers weren’t obligated to give bathroom breaks to their employees. This<br />

differs from State to State, and <strong>Utah</strong> laws only regulate the breaks for minors but not for<br />

adult workers. This is reminiscent <strong>of</strong> the legislation about the length <strong>of</strong> the working-day in<br />

the mid-nineteenth century discussed by Marx in chapter Ten: initially, only the workingdays<br />

<strong>of</strong> female workers and child workers was regulated, not that <strong>of</strong> adult male workers.<br />

Right now a unionization drive at call centers is under way in <strong>Utah</strong>. It is done by the<br />

IBEW, one <strong>of</strong> the best Unions. <strong>The</strong>y are especially targeting two big ACS call centers, but<br />

they would love to make it a state wide campaign at every call center. Here is their web site:


http://CallCenterUnion.org<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 301<br />

I’d like to thank Willie, the taller guy in the video, for looking up the <strong>Utah</strong> labor laws for<br />

us. He is a U <strong>of</strong> U graduate.<br />

Cmellen: I don’t think unions is the answer for all call centers. I worked in management at a predominant call<br />

center internationally, and the centers that had unionized were not always happier employees. Is the grass greener?<br />

Hans: I think you are right Cmellen. I hear that the Verizon call centers in town are unionized, but conditions there<br />

are not much better than in the non-union shops, because the Union has given too many concessions. <strong>The</strong> Union<br />

justifies these concessions by the fact that call centers can easily be moved. Marx says about this: even though<br />

the workers are economically weaker than the capitalists and will lose many labor struggles, they should organize<br />

anyway. <strong>The</strong> main result <strong>of</strong> this organization will be that the workers overcome their isolation and confront the<br />

class enemy together. I.e., Union activity is the prelude to the working class assuming power.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [649].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 591 is 271 in 1997WI, 346 in 1999SP, 382 in 2000fa, 439 in 2002fa, 455 in<br />

2003fa, 506 in 2004fa, 483 in 2005fa, 531 in 2008fa, 554 in 2009fa, 609 in 2011fa, and<br />

635 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 591 Argue why the commodity the worker sells is labor-power, and not labor.<br />

[621] Balrog: graded A Workers do have Power, i.e. Labor Power. Many <strong>of</strong> us, just as<br />

most in a capitalistic society, come to the realization that in order to survive in this world<br />

we must work for those who hold the means <strong>of</strong> production. (Unless we are somehow able<br />

to break the mold and find a factory, machine or both in our possession). In fall 2003<br />

Hans [2003fa:400] stated that “‘Labor’ is the miraculous activity by which humans affect<br />

nature according to their designs.” <strong>The</strong> worker knows that what he is providing his capitalist<br />

employer is his potential labor or labor-power. He would only be able to consider the work he<br />

sells as labor if he were in control <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production. In this manner the capitalist<br />

maintains control and continues to pay meager wages to his workers in exchange for the<br />

labor-power necessary for his production.<br />

Message [621] referenced by [622]. Next Message by Balrog is [664].<br />

[622] Proletarian: Labor-power is a commodity, labor is not. I think that Balrog comes<br />

close to the correct answer in his response [621], but I believe he missed one crucial point:<br />

labor cannot be sold since it is not a commodity. <strong>The</strong> products <strong>of</strong> labor, commodities, can be<br />

sold because they have value, which is measured by the amount <strong>of</strong> congealed human labor<br />

in the commodity, but again, the labor is not what’s being sold, the product <strong>of</strong> labor, the<br />

commodity, is what’s being sold.<br />

Balrog writes “He would only be able to consider the work he sells as labor if he were<br />

in control <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production.” This is not right, or at least not phrased correctly.<br />

<strong>The</strong> worker would not consider himself selling labor or labor-power at all if he owned the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production. If the worker owned the means <strong>of</strong> production, he would consider the<br />

labor that he expended on the production <strong>of</strong> the commodities differently. He would not see<br />

that he was selling any labor at all, instead he would see that he was working to produce<br />

commodities which contain his labor which he could then take to market.<br />

302 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

It’s important to distinguish between the commodity <strong>of</strong> labor-power and the use <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

in production <strong>of</strong> commodities. In the simple model that Marx spent so much time developing,<br />

humans work to produce commodities with their labor, commodities which can be exchanged<br />

for other commodities with different use-values. However, as Marx demonstrated<br />

in his discussion on labor-power as a commodity, workers do not have access to means <strong>of</strong><br />

production, but they have needs that must be met. Even if they could somehow come to own<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production, they would still have to wait for the production and exchange <strong>of</strong><br />

their commodities before they could receive other commodities with use-values they need,<br />

such as food, clo<strong>thing</strong>, shelter, etc. Because the worker cannot wait the amount <strong>of</strong> time it<br />

would take to procure the means <strong>of</strong> production, start producing commodities, and sell those<br />

commodities (since the worker would need to consume commodities before he would be<br />

able to exchange the commodities he produces), the worker turns to the capitalist and sells<br />

the one commodity he does own: his potential for labor, or his labor-power.<br />

<strong>The</strong> reason the worker sells labor-power and not labor is because he is selling the potential<br />

for productive work. <strong>The</strong> capitalist that purchases the worker’s labor power is the<br />

one who determines how to use this labor in the production <strong>of</strong> commodities. <strong>The</strong> worker is<br />

simply selling his potential to perform the work the capitalist needs done, and the capitalist<br />

is the one who sells the commodities that contain the congealed human labor <strong>of</strong> the worker.<br />

Again, the worker who sells his labor-power does not consider that he is working to produce<br />

commodities he can take to market, instead he sees that the time he spends working is the<br />

commodity that he is exchanging (selling to the capitalist) for wages. <strong>The</strong> worker does not<br />

care about what that labor-power is used for, all he cares about is receiving in exchange for<br />

his commodity <strong>of</strong> labor-power another commodity that he can use, in this case his wages.<br />

Next Message by Proletarian is [634].<br />

[632] Kat: Labor vs labor power. <strong>The</strong>re is an inherent difference between labor and<br />

labor-power. <strong>The</strong> worker cannot sell his or her labor, but rather sells his or her labor power.<br />

To understand the difference, it is necessary to consider how Marx understands labor. Labor<br />

is the link between a commodity and its exchange value. Labor is the difference between<br />

pieces <strong>of</strong> linen and a coat. Though, a worker cannot spontaneously create a coat out <strong>of</strong> linen.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y must enlist the help <strong>of</strong> necessary production tools. So labor comes from the partnership<br />

<strong>of</strong> a worker’s labor-power and certain means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Labor-power represents the capacity to perform labor that each worker possesses. This<br />

may differ from worker to worker and is a reflection <strong>of</strong> subsistence. Wages will range depending<br />

on what a worker requires to survive and complete their respective jobs. Thus,<br />

labor-power and its worth is tied to what is considered fair and necessary.<br />

So, in all, labor-power represents worth in the form <strong>of</strong> subsistence wages and the capacity<br />

to perform labor. It alone cannot produce commodities, but a worker will sell this power to<br />

the owners <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production in order to complete the necessary steps to production.<br />

Hans: Two remarks about your example “Labor is the difference between pieces <strong>of</strong> linen and a coat.”<br />

(1) In a commodity society, labor not only creates use-values (coats out <strong>of</strong> cloth and thread), but it also creates<br />

value. Your previous sentence was “Labor is the link between a commodity and its exchange value.” It is this link<br />

not because <strong>of</strong> the use-value it creates, but because <strong>of</strong> the value it creates.<br />

(2) With his examples “20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat” Marx did not imply that the coats were made <strong>of</strong> linen. He<br />

was thinking <strong>of</strong> woolen coats.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 303<br />

Next Message by Kat is [679].<br />

[835] Kaush: Labor-power, and not labor. In a capitalist system, where the value <strong>of</strong><br />

labor-power is determined by market forces and favorable to the capitalist, the capitalist is<br />

after the laborer’s potential but not his labor. <strong>The</strong> capitalist is in the market to engage the<br />

laborer’s future potential with the means <strong>of</strong> production owned by the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> laborer<br />

can only sell labor-power, part <strong>of</strong> the production process that he owns.<br />

If a laborer owned the means <strong>of</strong> production, he/she would be selling commodities but not<br />

his or her labor-power.<br />

Message [835] referenced by [841]. Next Message by Kaush is [938].<br />

[841] Hans: How can you tell the worker is selling labor-power, not labor? Kaush<br />

[835] writes: “the capitalist is after the laborer’s potential but not his labor.” This is half<br />

wrong and half right. It is wrong because the capitalist DOES want the laborer to work for<br />

him. This work adds value to the product. Strutting about and showing <strong>of</strong>f your muscles<br />

(your labor-power) does not create value, only the USE <strong>of</strong> this labor-power for the production<br />

<strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong>, i.e., labor, creates value. In this sense, the capitalist IS after the worker’s<br />

labor.<br />

But the statement is half right because the capitalist does not want to and does not have to<br />

PURCHASE the labor from the laborer. <strong>The</strong> laborer cannot SELL his labor to the capitalist<br />

because he cannot make use <strong>of</strong> his own labor-power to perform labor, because he is missing<br />

an important ingredient <strong>of</strong> the labor process, the means <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong> separation from<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production prevents the worker from selling his labor to anybody and even<br />

from using it himself. He has no other choice but to sell his labor-POWER which is much<br />

cheaper than the labor itself. <strong>The</strong> consumption by the capitalist <strong>of</strong> the commodity laborpower<br />

which he has bought is the production process in which the laborer performs labor<br />

for the capitalist.<br />

One can also argue that the labor which the laborer performs does not BELONG to the<br />

laborer and therefore cannot be sold by the laborer. Since the laborer has already sold his<br />

labor-power, all the labor which the laborer performs during the time for which this laborpower<br />

is sold belongs to the capitalist. This can also be seen by the fact that the capitalist<br />

gives the laborer orders what to do.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se are the best arguments I can come up with to show that the laborer is selling laborpower<br />

and not labor. Can you think <strong>of</strong> any other arguments?<br />

Message [841] referenced by [844] and [2012fa:909]. Next Message by Hans is [845].<br />

[844] Ryan: RE: How can you tell the worker is selling labor-power, not labor? <strong>The</strong><br />

best argument that I can think <strong>of</strong> is asking a group <strong>of</strong> people to build you a home.<br />

Let’s say you find ten men that have the skills to build you a home i.e. they can perform<br />

the labor. You would never ask them to just show up to your piece <strong>of</strong> land and start building<br />

without supplying them with the needed materials (wood, nails, ro<strong>of</strong>ing). Meaning that you<br />

can’t be just purchasing skills.<br />

You would <strong>of</strong> course supply them with all that is needed to perform the task and then ask<br />

them to build you a home.<br />

You would never pay them just because they have the skills to perform the labor.<br />

304 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

You would pay them to build you a home, that is, you would pay for their labor-power.<br />

Which we know is the means <strong>of</strong> production. To build on what Hans [841] said; Hans states<br />

that labor can not be sold without the means <strong>of</strong> production. This is a great example because<br />

no one would pay you just because you can do some<strong>thing</strong>, they pay you to do some<strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Hans also states that labor does not have value even to the laborer. This can be seen by<br />

thinking about the men that know how to build homes. <strong>The</strong>y would never become rich just<br />

because the know how to do it or can do it, they need someone to purchase that ability, which<br />

is to purchase their labor-power.<br />

If you were paid for your labor, you technically would not have to work. You would just<br />

have to have the ability to perform the task. Clearly no one is going to pay you to do no<strong>thing</strong><br />

so you must be selling your Labor-power. Which is to say that you are not selling the ability<br />

to build a home, but the ability plus the means <strong>of</strong> production to produce a useful good, to<br />

actually build the home.<br />

Message [844] referenced by [845]. Next Message by Ryan is [927].<br />

[845] Hans: Building a House Together with your Friends. Ryan [844] brings an<br />

excellent example, building a house, but sometimes he seems confused by the word “laborpower”.<br />

He thinks labor-power is the labor <strong>of</strong> the workers empowered by the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production. I.e., he thinks labor-power is more than labor, but in Marx’s terminology laborpower<br />

is less than labor. Marx uses the word “labor-power” for the ability to do the work,<br />

which is necessary to do the work but which alone is not enough to do the work. And Marx<br />

uses the word “labor” for the process itself, which can only take place if labor-power is<br />

combined with the other means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Let me try to re-tell Ryan’s example using these concepts:<br />

Let’s say you find ten men that have the skills to build you a home i.e. they have the<br />

required labor-power. If you just ask them to show up to your piece <strong>of</strong> land, this labor-power<br />

will not be very useful to you. <strong>The</strong>y can’t build any<strong>thing</strong> without tools and the needed<br />

materials (wood, nails, ro<strong>of</strong>ing). You have to supply all this and make sure they don’t run<br />

out <strong>of</strong> supplies before the job is finished. But this impotence <strong>of</strong> mere labor-power without<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production also works in your favor. If they were able to use their labor-power<br />

themselves then you would have to pay them the full value which their labor creates. But<br />

their own labor-power is useless for them. <strong>The</strong>y will never become rich just because they<br />

know how to build houses or can build houses. In order to turn their labor-power into actual<br />

labor they need someone to supply them with materials and tools and a piece <strong>of</strong> land and<br />

who knows how to find a buyer. <strong>The</strong>refore you don’t have to pay them the full value created<br />

by their labor but you can just pay them a normal wage that allows them to pay their bills.<br />

In other words, if the market value <strong>of</strong> the house is $150,000 and the materials cost $50,000,<br />

then you don’t have to pay them the full $100,000 which their labor adds to the materials<br />

but only the $50,000 which they would get if they work overtime on their normal jobs.<br />

Message [845] referenced by [2012fa:649]. Next Message by Hans is [846].<br />

[1011] Cmellen: graded A <strong>The</strong> laborer does not have the means to production himself,<br />

so he must instead sell his labor-power, which is only the potential for labor. <strong>The</strong> laborer<br />

would only be able to consider the work he sells as labor if he were in control <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong>


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 305<br />

production, unfortunately the laborer does not have the means to production (such as factory,<br />

capital assets, etc).<br />

Next Message by Cmellen is [1139].<br />

[1044] Kleenex: <strong>The</strong> worker sells his labor-power to the capitalist. He does not sell his<br />

labor because he does not own the means <strong>of</strong> production. He sells his ability to do work,<br />

which is labor-power. <strong>The</strong> worker basically enters into an agreement with the capitalist to<br />

give his labor-power for a set wage, usually lower than the true value <strong>of</strong> his work. <strong>The</strong><br />

laborer does this because he has no choice: he cannot realize the full value <strong>of</strong> his labor and<br />

the commodity that comes out <strong>of</strong> it because he doesn’t own the factory, the production line,<br />

the machines to produce it. <strong>The</strong> capitalist will hopefully pay him enough in wages so that<br />

he can survive, but the capitalist has and will never pay the worker what his work is actually<br />

worth. This is what fuels the M-C-M process. <strong>The</strong>rein lies the root <strong>of</strong> the existence <strong>of</strong><br />

relative surplus-value. It is a manifestation <strong>of</strong> the growing gap between the laborer and the<br />

capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Kleenex is [1093].<br />

[1060] KA: In a capitalist society, laborers must work for those that hold the means to<br />

production in order to survive (earn wages). In most cases, if not all, the worker does not<br />

have the means <strong>of</strong> production needed to produce the commodities on their own. For this<br />

reason, workers sell their labor-power to the capitalists in order to produce the commodity<br />

and be able to earn a wage needed to survive. In turn, the capitalists pay the worker wages<br />

that are due for the amount <strong>of</strong> time spent producing the commodity. <strong>The</strong> wages paid to the<br />

worker are less than the prices charged to consume the commodity, therefore providing the<br />

capitalists with a pr<strong>of</strong>it. <strong>The</strong> price <strong>of</strong> the labor-power must be lower than the price <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity, in order to produce the commodity and employ the worker. <strong>The</strong> worker is not<br />

in the position to charge a higher price for their labor; it is the capitalists who make this<br />

determination.<br />

Hans: You are saying the capitalists can decide what to pay in wages. Marx does not think so. Wages are determined<br />

like the value <strong>of</strong> any other commodity by the labor-time it takes to reproduce the commodity labor-power.<br />

Next Message by KA is [1061].<br />

[1100] Fisher: labor power vs. labor. A capitalist will seek to hire a laborer to help<br />

create a commodity. <strong>The</strong> value that his labor creates in the form <strong>of</strong> a commodity for the<br />

capitalist, is sold by the laborer to the capitalist in the form <strong>of</strong> labor power. <strong>The</strong> exchange<br />

is labor power from the laborer for money or means to stay alive from the capitalist. <strong>The</strong><br />

capitalist then receives his completed commodity ready for sale or exchange on the market.<br />

<strong>The</strong> capitalist is looking for gains, only after the laborer is compensated for his labor power<br />

which he sold the capitalist. Before he can do so, he has had to purchase resources to create<br />

the commodity. One <strong>of</strong> these is labor power, he agrees to pay a predetermined price with<br />

the laborer who is selling labor power. <strong>The</strong> laborer has labor power which has a value less<br />

than the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity which it creates, but has the upper hand in negotiating with<br />

capitalist for this reason.<br />

Hans: As Marx sees the transaction, the laborer does not sell his product to the capitalist because the laborer never<br />

owns the product. Marx also thinks the laborer does not have the upper hand in this transaction, on the contrary, the<br />

playing field is tilted against the laborer.<br />

Next Message by Fisher is [1122].<br />

306 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1104] Lindsey: <strong>The</strong> worker sells his labor-power to the capitalist, not his labor. We<br />

know this because <strong>first</strong>ly, the sale <strong>of</strong> labor-power requires the worker to be present while the<br />

capitalist consumes it. We can see that this is in fact the case in real life because a worker<br />

must actually go to work (to the capitalist’s place) during certain hours in order to get paid<br />

(or in other words to sell his labor-power). Secondly, if the worker sold his labor, he would<br />

get paid for the amount <strong>of</strong> value which he created (the value <strong>of</strong> the commodities). We know<br />

that this is not what he is paid because the capitalists obtain a surplus-value (or pr<strong>of</strong>it). <strong>The</strong><br />

fact that the worker sells his labor-power (and doesn’t know it) allows the capitalist to exploit<br />

the worker. On the surface, it appears that the worker is selling his labor, so he thinks that<br />

he is getting paid for all the labor he does and he does not object, but in reality, part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

time he works is unpaid.<br />

Next Message by Lindsey is [1115].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 592 When Marx wrote Capital, Social Security or any other tax-financed retirement<br />

plans did not yet exist. But capitalism itself generated such plans. How do they fit into<br />

Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> the commodity labor-power and its value?<br />

[933] ANK: Social Security. This last week I was watching the national news. One <strong>of</strong><br />

the top stories was a proposed idea to raise the retirement age from 66 to 69 because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

upcoming social security funding crisis. Over 700 billion dollars has been paid out from<br />

social security since its inception by FDR in 1935. With 70 billion baby boomers headed<br />

towards retirement, the program will not be able to pay out to everyone and will run out <strong>of</strong><br />

funds in 27 years. Many ideas have been proposed to fix this problem, and this idea may<br />

exploit workers more than any other. While watching this news story, I immediately thought<br />

about what Marx would say to this proposal. Social programs arise because <strong>of</strong> the problems<br />

with capitalism and the exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers. Making workers work three extra years<br />

to be able to retire and receive social security furthers the exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers and is a<br />

continued example <strong>of</strong> the failures <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

Message [933] referenced by [945] and [955]. Next Message by ANK is [934].<br />

[937] Kleenex: more on Social Security. Also, on social security, following ANK’s<br />

thought, productivity would only decrease if the worker had to wait an additional three years<br />

until retirement. In general, as in a longer work day, motivation fades and intensity <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

wanes. In my workplace, there are some employees who are quite “old,” and just riding out<br />

their time until they reach their retirement. For civilian government work, that means thirty<br />

years <strong>of</strong> service. Once you hit the thirty-year mark, you would be entitled to 30% <strong>of</strong> your<br />

pay, but would not be able to receive these benefits until a certain age. Anyway, though these<br />

employees are very knowledgeable and experienced, it appears that they lack innovation and<br />

flexibility, which are vital in an ever-changing work environment. <strong>The</strong> mere fact that they<br />

are old in age is not the problem. <strong>The</strong> problem is that as new computer systems and new,<br />

efficient practices become introduced, their desire to adapt and be productive is lessened, in<br />

my experience. I believe that Marx would say that decreasing the eligibility age for Social<br />

Security would be a good <strong>thing</strong>, and the above example would support the argument.<br />

To comment on ANK’s submission though, is the Social Security problem attributed to a<br />

“failure <strong>of</strong> capitalism,” or more <strong>of</strong> a failure <strong>of</strong> the Social Security system itself? I do not quite


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 307<br />

see the connection between the social security issue and exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers. Simply, the<br />

Social Security program is out <strong>of</strong> balance. More money is going out than coming in.<br />

Message [937] referenced by [945], [955], and [1064]. Next Message by Kleenex is [1019].<br />

[945] Smartergirl: Social Security. It is interesting to me that they are considering<br />

increasing the retirement age by 3 years, see [933]. It definitely exploits the worker and how<br />

truly productive does the capitalist think that the worker will be in their seventies? Don’t<br />

misunderstand I’m not saying that a worker in their seventies is not productive but there is a<br />

significant difference in a 70 year old that is working because <strong>of</strong> a passion or desire to stay<br />

busy versus a person having to work to collect a retirement or for survival. Some people<br />

enjoy working for the satisfaction, so to avoid confusion I’m not speaking <strong>of</strong> them but <strong>of</strong> the<br />

people that have to work to retire. Kleenex [937] brings up a great point about the workers’<br />

ability to be flexible and learn new skills in a changing industry, as well as the lessened<br />

motivation. I agree and see the changes in myself. As a young 20 year old in the work force<br />

I was out to make a name for myself and conquer corporate America or start a company <strong>of</strong><br />

my own. I was on a quest for money. In my thirties I take flexibility in schedule, benefits<br />

and stability over a higher pay. Who knows what I will want in my 40’s, 50’s etc. I know<br />

one <strong>thing</strong> and that’s that I wont want to get up to go to work at 69. By the time I’m there<br />

they may raise it to 75.<br />

My point is don’t buy into this ridiculous idea that raising the age <strong>of</strong> retirement by 3<br />

years will benefit social security benefits. <strong>The</strong>re are articles everywhere discussing how this<br />

generation may be the <strong>first</strong> to have their parents outlive them. With the increase in heart<br />

disease due to obesity, poor nutrition and lack <strong>of</strong> exercise, which I believe people would<br />

do more <strong>of</strong> if not for the leaps in technology and desire to be one <strong>of</strong> the fastest moving<br />

economies, we don’t need to worry about the majority reaching 69.<br />

If heart disease the number 1 killer in America doesn’t weed some <strong>of</strong> the working class<br />

out, cancer which is also rapidly developing and evolving will. It is horribly sad but a reality<br />

that the capitalist medical and insurance companies are aware <strong>of</strong>. Create ridiculous plans<br />

that make it undesirable to get preventable care and by the time people get to a doctor it’s<br />

a terminal disease. Marx would have seen this. He would know that insurance companies<br />

being privately owned and allowed to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong>f health care is the worst form <strong>of</strong><br />

Capitalism also referred to as usury.<br />

If a person can work, survive every pitfall that may come their way (there are many in<br />

this country) and live to see 66 then by all means pay them their dang retirement!<br />

Message [945] referenced by [955] and [1064]. Next Message by Smartergirl is [1093].<br />

[955] Hans: Capitalists trying to own our entire lives. ANK [933] is asking “what<br />

would Marx say to this proposal” (to raise the retirement age)? Here is my attempt to answer<br />

this. If the workers live longer and are able to work longer, then <strong>of</strong> course the capitalists think<br />

they, and not the workers, own this extra time. Robert writes in [894]:<br />

Since the capitalist controls the means <strong>of</strong> production and the laborer has<br />

no way to convert his labor-power into value to sustain himself or herself<br />

without such means <strong>of</strong> production, the non-surface, real relationship between<br />

the worker and capitalist, can be described as follows:<br />

308 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> capitalist allows the laborer access to the capitalist’s mean <strong>of</strong> production<br />

under two conditions: 1) that the laborer cedes control over all <strong>of</strong> his<br />

labor-power to the capitalist; and 2) the capitalist will pay the laborer a<br />

wage which will allow the laborer to survive and to reproduce his or her<br />

labor-power.<br />

“<strong>The</strong> labor cedes control over all <strong>of</strong> his labor-power” means: all your life! Only if you are<br />

too old to work do you deserve time for yourself (as the capitalist sees it). When Kleenex<br />

[937] and Smartergirl [945] argue that after 66 the worker is indeed too old to work, then they<br />

have already ceded too much ground because they have accepted this claim <strong>of</strong> the capitalist<br />

that any productive time <strong>of</strong> the workers belongs to them. A Marxist response to the raising<br />

<strong>of</strong> the retirement age would be to say: we are not your slaves. If modern technology allows<br />

us to live longer, then the capitalists have no right to steal this time from us too.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [997].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 601 is 642 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 601 Is is true that that the labor process changes nature? It certainly changes<br />

natural <strong>thing</strong>s into other natural <strong>thing</strong>s, but it only uses the forces <strong>of</strong> nature to do this.<br />

Which arguments can be given to support Marx’s claim that it changes nature itself?<br />

[652] Cosmopolita: Labor changes nature itself. Labor is <strong>first</strong> a process between a man<br />

and nature. A human being uses its hands and thoughts to create final products. I.e., in the<br />

production process to create a table or chair, wood is needed, time and “labor.” Labor is<br />

required as well as tools to create the final product.<br />

A human tends to change his own nature, and natural state to choose and decide what to<br />

do with his time. Human beings differ from animals in this matter. Humans decide by choice,<br />

don’t go to work because they have to. <strong>The</strong>y could decide not to and create the necessary<br />

commodities for their own satisfaction. <strong>The</strong>refore labor power is an exclusively human<br />

characteristic. Humans decide to sell their labor power to get the “medium <strong>of</strong> exchange” to<br />

buy their necessary and preferable commodities that suits best their needs. Don’t create all<br />

the commodities themselves for a big market, but instead sell their “labor power” by choice<br />

to get a value on a “medium <strong>of</strong> exchange” commodity.<br />

Also, buyers <strong>of</strong> labor power consume the “commodity” <strong>of</strong> “labor power” by setting the<br />

seller <strong>of</strong> labor power to work. Workers are hired then to produce commodities (i.e. chair,<br />

table) which contain value.<br />

A human being then changes therefore his original nature, by subordinating the play <strong>of</strong><br />

its powers to his command to satisfy his specific needs. In this case, we can differentiate<br />

two types <strong>of</strong> human beings. One that values the “commodity <strong>of</strong> labor power” and one that<br />

values more the “commodity with exchange value”<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, humans being part <strong>of</strong> nature themselves are changed, (using their brains,<br />

breath, hands, body, time, etc.) for them, then change the nature into commodities with<br />

‘value’ itself, selling their labor power to the buyers <strong>of</strong> this commodity.<br />

Hans: (1) Humans cannot produce their necessities as solitary beings; production is necessarily a social process.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 309<br />

(2) Acording to Marx, the class division between workers and capitalists does not come from some liking<br />

labor-power better and some liking money better.<br />

(3) You are describing how human beings are changed, not how (or whether) nature itself is changed.<br />

Message [652] referenced by [2012fa:930]. Next Message by Cosmopolita is [712].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 603 is 618 in 2011fa and 644 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 603 What distinguishes human labor from the labor <strong>of</strong> an animal or a machine?<br />

[641] School: Our purpose makes us different. On a natural level humans and animals<br />

share instinctive forms <strong>of</strong> labor. This is where we take our surroundings which is nature and<br />

effect the change <strong>of</strong> nature. For example when a groundhog burrows its nest into the ground,<br />

the animal is taking nature and changing nature into a home. Also, another great example<br />

would be the bald eagle. This bird takes surrounding tree limbs, grass, and other forms <strong>of</strong><br />

nature to create the nest where the eagle will perch. Both the groundhog and the eagle took<br />

nature and with their labor created a home which satisfies the most basic instinctive need<br />

to exist. Humans also share these basic instinctive needs. Which leads us to the question<br />

what makes our labor different than the labor <strong>of</strong> animals? <strong>The</strong> answer to this would be that<br />

humans realize their “purpose” in the natural realm. If we were to write an equation for this<br />

it would be, Production + Human Action = Purpose. Production is governed by purpose<br />

and that is the reason why our actions are a reflection <strong>of</strong> our purpose. At times humans will<br />

willfully ignore the most basic needs for their purpose. <strong>The</strong> most prevalent example <strong>of</strong> this<br />

that I can relate to would be at my current job. I work at a call center, and it is my purpose<br />

to answer phones. <strong>The</strong>re are times when I will ignore the need to simply go the bathroom<br />

because I have to wait for my break time. I will ignore my basic needs for my purpose. This<br />

is the reason why humans differ from animals.<br />

Message [641] referenced by [642] and [644]. Next Message by School is [989].<br />

[642] Utefan: brain conception. School [641] writes about the commonality between<br />

humans and animals. He/she uses the making <strong>of</strong> a home out <strong>of</strong> natural building blocks to<br />

show what makes us similar. In the last paragraph School proclaims that humans realize<br />

their purpose in the natural realm and that is what distinguishes us from animals. Now the<br />

difference is in that animals fulfill a purpose while humans realize theirs—though many<br />

hate spiders and prefer their destruction, they perform many functions like keeping the bug<br />

population under control and fulfill a purpose.<br />

Marx plainly says that the difference is that we conceive what we do prior to fulfilling<br />

our labour. It exists ideally before ever being molded into fruition. Once again it is our brain<br />

intellect and knowledge that separates us. Animals fulfill many purposes but never come to<br />

fully realize them. <strong>The</strong>y toil and breed and eat without a major purpose other than to survive<br />

while humans grow in population, stature, knowledge, and advancement.<br />

Further, one’s enjoyment and the amount said person is attracted to the nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

work determines whether his attention is forced or not. That person allows for growth and<br />

production that can’t be matched on the animal level. Animals proceed in life to overcome<br />

obstacles but never come to their own realization or part as it were to the grand scheme <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>thing</strong>s. Humans on the other hand proceed to realize not just fulfill purpose.<br />

310 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: It is true that humans are the most advanced living beings on planet earth. But this does not mean that the<br />

planet was created for them. You will experience in your lifetime how the planet is trying to get rid <strong>of</strong> humans,<br />

trying to fight them <strong>of</strong>f like a disease organism.<br />

Next Message by Utefan is [901].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 605 is 620 in 2011fa and 646 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 605 What distinguishes human labor from play?<br />

[650] Oreo: graded A– Labor vs. Play. I think that purpose distinguishes human labor<br />

from play. When we work, we are working towards a purpose—which is to produce a<br />

product or service. When we play, we are doing so without a purpose. We aren’t meaning to<br />

do any<strong>thing</strong> more than to entertain our own wills. As mentioned in the text, we are primarily<br />

fulfilling a purpose during production—meaning the effects <strong>of</strong> our activities (the product)<br />

matter more than our will to produce them. <strong>The</strong> opposite is true in the Hegelian paradigm,<br />

where human will comes <strong>first</strong>, as it does during play. While I believe that I understand<br />

the difference between these two, I wondered if it is possible to simultaneously play and<br />

perform labor. If an individual freely pursues his will and chooses to purposelessly weave<br />

baskets because it’s what he loves to do, without intending to earn money, then hasn’t he also<br />

performed human labor? Marx states that the 3 moments <strong>of</strong> the labor process are purposeful<br />

activity, the object on which the work is performed and the instruments <strong>of</strong> that work. <strong>The</strong><br />

basket weaver’s activity only encompasses 2 <strong>of</strong> these 3 characteristics, excluding purposeful<br />

activity. <strong>The</strong>refore, the free willed basket weaver is not performing human labor since he is<br />

not primarily intending to produce these products for sale, he is simply playing.<br />

Hans: I think there is an entire spectrum between work and play. After you learn some<strong>thing</strong> really well then it<br />

becomes more like play. It has no<strong>thing</strong> to do with selling the product. It is possible to do serious work even if the<br />

final purpose is not a sale.<br />

Message [650] referenced by [2011fa:618] and [2012fa:928]. Next Message by Oreo is [875].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 607 Is it correct to say that nature is the ultimate producer, and man only manipulates<br />

nature for his own benefit? Compare this with the parallel statement: the worker is<br />

the ultimate producer, and the capitalist only manipulates the worker to take advantage <strong>of</strong><br />

him.<br />

[651] TINDOZ: Who is the puppet? Is it correct to say that nature is the ultimate producer,<br />

and man only manipulates nature for his own benefit? After reading the annotations<br />

in this chapter I reluctantly answer this question with a no; nature is not the ultimate producer<br />

and man is. <strong>The</strong> reading speaks <strong>of</strong> the object <strong>of</strong> labor and the instrument <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

as being two <strong>thing</strong>s that interact with each other whereas the laborer is at the other end <strong>of</strong><br />

this object, instrument, producer relationship. So, as for my thoughts today, I think that<br />

nature is most <strong>of</strong>ten the object <strong>of</strong> labor (though as the reading says it is also the instrument<br />

as the “original tool shed”) and that man is the producer. I make this claim because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

second half <strong>of</strong> the 607 question which asks for a comparison between the aforementioned<br />

question and the worker/capitalist (who is the master and who is the puppet) relationship.<br />

When originally scanning the chapter and questions before reading, I thought I’d say that<br />

the worker is the ultimate producer and that the capitalist is a lazy good-for-no<strong>thing</strong> won’t<br />

get his hands dirty task master who doesn’t do any<strong>thing</strong> grunt-work enough to entitle him to<br />

the term “producer”. I initially took this stand because I’ve had bosses that take credit for


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 311<br />

every<strong>thing</strong> that I did when they did no<strong>thing</strong>. However, after reading, I see that it’s not so cut<br />

and dry (good guy/bad guy) and that the capitalist is actually the producer and the worker is<br />

in fact the instrument <strong>of</strong> labor (and though I can reconcile that that was probably true with<br />

my work history - that I was an instrument to my ‘producer’ boss, it doesn’t make me like<br />

my old boss any more).<br />

So, when transferring my reluctant realization from the worker/capitalist relationship <strong>of</strong><br />

who is actually producing and what instruments they use on their object <strong>of</strong> labor, it seems to<br />

me that in that respect man is the producer and nature is the object <strong>of</strong> labor (though it also<br />

provides the instruments in some cases). Nature is the object because man (the producer)<br />

uses tools (like how the capitalist uses the worker) on the nature (for example a back hoe<br />

being used as a tool on the object <strong>of</strong> labor, ie the ground). This is my thought today, but<br />

I might sway with my other opinion tomorrow that nature is the ultimate producer. Why,<br />

because nature is in fact the only one actually “producing” some<strong>thing</strong> and it uses itself as it’s<br />

own instrument <strong>of</strong> labor (much like the example in the text <strong>of</strong> the fruit pickers’ arms actually<br />

being the instrument). Nature uses the perfect combination <strong>of</strong> moisture, sun, pressure, etc<br />

to create sandstone in Central <strong>Utah</strong> and other combinations to create Granite in the Wasatch<br />

Range. By this way <strong>of</strong> looking at it, nature is the ultimate producer and Man just comes<br />

along and manipulates nature (sandstone, granite) for his own benefit. I’m so conflicted here<br />

because both answers seem right to me at some level, but I’m going to go with my <strong>first</strong><br />

answer because I think it better coincides with the worker/capitalist relationship.<br />

Hans: What makes you think that both parallel questions should get the same answer? I think your original<br />

intuitions are correct that humans are producers in their relation with nature, but capitalists aren’t in their relations<br />

with their workers.<br />

Message [651] referenced by [666]. Next Message by TINDOZ is [710].<br />

[666] Baseball: Re: Who is the puppet? Before reading Marx’s earlier writings about the<br />

relationship between nature and human labor-power, I believed that nature was the “ultimate<br />

producer.” <strong>The</strong> thought that nature provides an abundance <strong>of</strong> raw materials which are, after<br />

being manipulated by humans and machines, transformed into useful products which can<br />

be sold on the market was all I knew <strong>of</strong>. But in the earlier readings, Marx states that the<br />

raw materials provided by nature have no use-values as they are. I did not understand this<br />

at <strong>first</strong> because materials such as wood water are useful in their natural states. But I was<br />

wrong. Marx then says that it is the human labor power which extracts the use-values out<br />

<strong>of</strong> the raw materials, making them products which can be sold on the market. So, before<br />

when I believed that wood and water had use values in their natural state, I didn’t take into<br />

consideration the labor used to chop the wood, or shape it into a chair or a door or even just<br />

a 2 by 4. This is all labor power which takes a raw material and creates a product with a use<br />

value. With the water, it needs to be cleaned and purified, which is labor power. So although<br />

nature provides us with materials which we create products from, it is not the “ultimate<br />

producer.” It takes human labor power to extract the use-values out <strong>of</strong> those materials and<br />

create the products we use in everyday life.<br />

Hans: Your original intuition was better than the “insights” you gained from your misunderstanings <strong>of</strong> Marx and<br />

<strong>of</strong> the word “ultimate.”<br />

(1) Marx said that natural resources don’t have value because they don’t contain human labor. He does say that<br />

they have use-value. Think <strong>of</strong> the air we breathe, <strong>of</strong> sunlight, or <strong>of</strong> water. Most water occurring in nature is clean.<br />

It is the humans who pollute it.<br />

312 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(2) Humans purifying the water are not the “ultimate” producers <strong>of</strong> this water. <strong>The</strong> antithesis <strong>of</strong> “ultimate” is<br />

“subsidiary.” Cleaning is a subsidiary process.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore nature is clearly the ultimate producer <strong>of</strong> natural resources. What about human-made consumption<br />

goods such as a cell phone. Is nature also the ultimate producer <strong>of</strong> it? Here the issue is not so clear-cut, see [651]<br />

and my note to it.<br />

Next Message by Baseball is [751].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 621 is 665 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 621 What is the difference between the purchase <strong>of</strong> a service and the purchase <strong>of</strong><br />

labor-power?<br />

[643] Giant: graded B– Variance <strong>of</strong> purchases. Labor power is when human labor is<br />

used to create some<strong>thing</strong> that can be exchanged for money. When purchasing a service it is<br />

more focused on the use-value <strong>of</strong> the service.<br />

Even though both labor power and service can be purchased, the end results are different.<br />

With labor power the laborer sells their labor power to someone and loses control <strong>of</strong> their<br />

service because it is being sold to someone else. Similar to a farmer selling an apple then<br />

claiming that the apple is still his. This type <strong>of</strong> purchase is focused more on financial surplus<br />

so it can be invested elsewhere.<br />

Purchase <strong>of</strong> a service is focused on a more equal exchange, as Marx phrased it,“value for<br />

value”. For example if cheese was made and it costs the maker $2.00, then they would sell<br />

it for $2.00 because that was the labor cost <strong>of</strong> the cheese.<br />

Hans: Your second paragraph puzzles me. Cheese is not a service. $2 is not a labor cost (labor costs are measured<br />

in hours <strong>of</strong> labor). <strong>The</strong> “cost” <strong>of</strong> the products to the capitalist are usually less than their values (because the capitalist<br />

don’t pay the workers an equivalent <strong>of</strong> the value they create). Can you explain?<br />

Next Message by Giant is [687].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 627 is 415 in 2001fa, 449 in 2002fa, 465 in 2003fa, 516 in 2004fa, 490 in<br />

2005fa, 644 in 2011fa, 673 in 2012fa, and 627 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 627 Why is the day taken as unit <strong>of</strong> labor-power, instead <strong>of</strong> hour or week?<br />

[667] Tyler: Daily measurement. A day is taken as the unit for labor-power because<br />

for “labor-power, the smallest unit <strong>of</strong> measurement is the day” (Annotations pg. 470). Marx<br />

shows that the day is the ideal unit <strong>of</strong> measurement because it is divided into two distinct<br />

parts. First, the necessary labor, is the time required for the worker to “produce an equivalent<br />

<strong>of</strong> his or her daily wage” (Annotations pg. 469). <strong>The</strong> second part, surplus labor, is the extra<br />

time worked where the capitalist makes his or her pr<strong>of</strong>it. <strong>The</strong>refore, the day is the best<br />

option as the unit <strong>of</strong> measurement for labor-power. Pisciphiliac also notes that the week<br />

would not work since its not possible for workers to work such a shift and the hour would<br />

be too difficult to monitor [2005fa:1139].<br />

Message [667] referenced by [693]. Next Message by Tyler is [694].<br />

[669] Sly: Breaking it down is the key to understanding. In order to understand why a<br />

day is taken as the (measurement) unit <strong>of</strong> labor-power, rather than an hour or a week, we must<br />

<strong>first</strong> understand the definition <strong>of</strong> working-day. In the Annotations Marx defines a workingday<br />

by <strong>first</strong> dividing it into two parts: Necessary Labor and Surplus Labor. Marx defines<br />

necessary labor time as: “the length <strong>of</strong> time needed by the worker every day to produce an


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 313<br />

equivalent to his or her daily wage.” (Annotations, pg. 469) and then Marx defines surplus<br />

labor as: “the additional time during which the worker produces value appropriated without<br />

equivalent by the capitalist.” (Annotations, pg. 496)<br />

<strong>The</strong> necessary labor can simply be viewed as portion that is mandated by economic law,<br />

Marx defines this economic law as the: “productivity <strong>of</strong> the kind <strong>of</strong> labor performed”, and<br />

this the half <strong>of</strong> the working-day in which the laborer “reproduce(s) the value he received<br />

when he (or she) sold it.” [340:1].<br />

<strong>The</strong> best definition <strong>of</strong> surplus is given by Tres in [2002fa:226]: he stated that: “<strong>The</strong><br />

surplus part is where the pr<strong>of</strong>its are derived and its variable.” – and I would add that this is<br />

the portion that allows capitalist to be exactly that, and this is where pr<strong>of</strong>its are made since<br />

the wages have already been accounted for in necessary labor.<br />

Marx states that the wage is the: “reimbursement for the costs <strong>of</strong> reproducing the laborpower”<br />

and that “For labor-power, the smallest unit <strong>of</strong> measurement is the day.” (Annotations,<br />

pg. 470) This gives day a value, and this value is the daily wage – Marx states that<br />

the daily wage is determined by: “the value <strong>of</strong> the ‘average daily means <strong>of</strong> subsistence’ <strong>of</strong><br />

the laborer.” (Annotations, pg. 471) <strong>The</strong> reason why this all makes sense is because Marx<br />

had previous made light that: “<strong>The</strong> reproduction costs <strong>of</strong> labor-power can be computed as<br />

the daily costs for food, rent, clo<strong>thing</strong> utilities, transportation, etc.” (Annotations, pg. 470) –<br />

those are an individual’s means <strong>of</strong> “daily subsistence”.<br />

<strong>The</strong> reason that the measurements <strong>of</strong> labor-power are done in days is that the other possible<br />

measurements <strong>of</strong> an hour or a week would be complicated if not impossible. First a<br />

<strong>of</strong>f as stated in many <strong>of</strong> the archive its makes no sense to work weeklong shifts, the laborers<br />

would never go home and the capitalists would have to pay even more money. Secondly, if<br />

labor-power were measured by the hour – tracking wages would become difficult, as Tres<br />

pointed out in [2002fa:226]: “Workers would be clocking in and out every hour.” – I would<br />

also add that this measurement would cost the capitalist more money because <strong>of</strong> the additional<br />

methods employed to keep track <strong>of</strong> such a situation. In many <strong>of</strong> the examples give a<br />

working day can range anywhere from 8, 10, 12, or 14 hours – this value is determined by<br />

an agreement between the laborer and the capitalist, but this is essentially a consolidation <strong>of</strong><br />

multiple hours. Simply put a day is the easiest, and most sensible form <strong>of</strong> measurement for<br />

labor-power.<br />

Hans: This is a careful analysis, but I think I have a better answer in [Answer:4].<br />

Message [669] referenced by [986] and [1004]. Next Message by Sly is [733].<br />

[693] Zohan: A few thoughts on Tyler’s answer. I believe that the annotations from<br />

page 469, Marx’s explanation <strong>of</strong> how the working day can be divided into necessary labor<br />

and surplus labor is helpful to understand why the day is taken as the unit <strong>of</strong> labor-power. I<br />

agree with what Tyler [667] wrote here. But, that alone doesn’t give a sufficient explanation.<br />

I think an important part to understanding the question is stated in the second paragraph<br />

in the annotations on page 470. Tyler quoted “for labor-power, the smallest unit <strong>of</strong> measurement<br />

is the day.” <strong>The</strong> next sentence, which was not included, states, “<strong>The</strong> reproduction costs<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor-power can be computed as the daily costs for food, rent clo<strong>thing</strong>, utilities, transportation,<br />

etc.” Trying to measure each <strong>of</strong> this cost on an hourly level could be very difficult.<br />

This sentence suggests that it is much more feasible to measure these cost on a daily level.<br />

314 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Also workers do not work weekly shifts, so it would not be an efficient measurement to try<br />

and measure unit <strong>of</strong> labor-power as a weekly unit. This notion further helps explain why the<br />

day was taken as the unit <strong>of</strong> labor power instead <strong>of</strong> the hour or week.<br />

Next Message by Zohan is [725].<br />

[702] Hans: Difficult <strong>Question</strong>. This question has more substance than it seems. Laborpower<br />

cannot be measured in hours because the worker is selling his entire capacity to work<br />

to the capitalist, not just an hour here or there. <strong>The</strong>refore wages must cover his total survival<br />

needs. <strong>The</strong> day is the shortest period for which it makes sense to compute this.<br />

I am compiling a list <strong>of</strong> final answers to some <strong>of</strong> the questions. You can download it from<br />

or<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/halfpage/Answer.pdf<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/screen/Answer.pdf<br />

This pdf contains a more detailed answer in [Answer:4].<br />

Message [702] referenced by [750] and [956]. Next Message by Hans is [728].<br />

[894] Robert: graded A Hans provides a very complete answer to this question in [Answer:4].<br />

I derive most <strong>of</strong> the following answer (as well as what I wrote in the in class exam)<br />

from his answer.<br />

Since the capitalist controls the means <strong>of</strong> production and the laborer has no way to convert<br />

his labor-power into value to sustain himself or herself without such means <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

the non-surface, real relationship between the worker and capitalist, can be described as<br />

follows:<br />

<strong>The</strong> capitalist allows the laborer access to the capitalist’s mean <strong>of</strong> production under two<br />

conditions: 1) that the laborer cedes control over all <strong>of</strong> his labor-power to the capitalist; and<br />

2) the capitalist will pay the laborer a wage which will allow the laborer to survive and to<br />

reproduce his or her labor-power.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se two conditions give rise to subsidiary issues. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> is how much wage does the<br />

laborer need to survive and the second, since we are dealing in a “free” society that does not<br />

permit slavery, regards the limits <strong>of</strong> the capitalist’s consumption <strong>of</strong> the laborer’s labor-power.<br />

Social forces answer the <strong>first</strong> question; a wage is a socially normal amount <strong>of</strong> compensation<br />

that allows subsistence and reproduction <strong>of</strong> the laborer. Nevertheless, the question still<br />

remains for what period <strong>of</strong> time does the wage allow the laborer to subside and reproduce?<br />

<strong>The</strong> laborer has ceded control over all <strong>of</strong> his labor-power to the capitalist: all <strong>of</strong> his<br />

power to work, every day, including weekends and holidays. <strong>The</strong> capitalist cannot require<br />

the laborer to work all <strong>of</strong> the time for two physical reasons: the laborer will die if he cannot<br />

rest and the capitalist may eventually run out <strong>of</strong> workers from whom to exploit value if the<br />

laborer cannot reproduce himself or herself. <strong>The</strong>re is also a moral reason: the capitalist<br />

should allow the labor some time to enjoy the life <strong>of</strong> a human being.<br />

One could compute the wage for a day, a week, a year, or a lifetime. If the period<br />

were longer than a day then weekends, holidays, etc. would have to all be agreed and the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 315<br />

computation becomes more complex. It is also not practical to compute the subsistence <strong>of</strong> a<br />

human being for less than a day. A day is a natural cycle <strong>of</strong> eating and sleeping that repeats<br />

consistently. One hour during a day has different subsistence requirements (lunch hour, for<br />

example) that another hour (9-10 in the morning, for example).<br />

Furthermore, a laborer goes to work in daily increments. He arrives at work sometime<br />

during the day and departs for home at some time during the day. It is unusual that a worker<br />

would report to work and remain there for a week or a month at a time.<br />

All <strong>of</strong> these factors argue that a day is the shortest, most logical, timeframe for the computation<br />

<strong>of</strong> a unit <strong>of</strong> labor-power.<br />

Message [894] referenced by [955]. Next Message by Robert is [1014].<br />

[899] Kat: Labor-power is measured in units <strong>of</strong> days because it is possible to know definitively<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> daily labor. <strong>The</strong> worker must work long enough in a day to reproduce his<br />

wages. He/she must work long enough to survive; the unit wages <strong>of</strong> a day is a representation<br />

<strong>of</strong> what is necessary for him to survive that given day.<br />

It is possible to extend the unit <strong>of</strong> labor-power and measure it longer terms, but the day is<br />

the shortest possible and easiest to comprehend. Labor-power cannot, though, be measured<br />

in hours because it is a derived quantity [Answer:4]. It is figured using the daily unit <strong>of</strong><br />

labor-power.<br />

Next Message by Kat is [1092].<br />

[907] Intaglio: <strong>The</strong> day is taken as a unit <strong>of</strong> labor power because it is the most logical for<br />

both the capitalist and worker. An hour’s wage is far too small to meet the worker’s means<br />

<strong>of</strong> subsistence. <strong>The</strong> worker will have to work several hours per day to meet their survival<br />

needs, so it is redundant to pay by the hour. Instead, paying by the smallest block <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

that keeps the worker alive is the most natural. A week is far too long because a definite<br />

break in labor takes place once the worker necessarily returns home to regain strength, eat,<br />

and sleep before the next day’s work.<br />

Next Message by Intaglio is [1062].<br />

[928] Ryan: <strong>The</strong> day is taken as a measure <strong>of</strong> labor-power for four reasons:<br />

First, because labor power is sold by a quantity that must be measured as a value to sustain<br />

life. Using any value other then a day would not make sense as you would never work just<br />

to live for an hour.<br />

Second, Labor-power is measured by the amount <strong>of</strong> the labor one can do in a day. Laborpower,<br />

which is sold to the capitalist is a measure <strong>of</strong> the amount that one needs to also live<br />

in the form <strong>of</strong> a wage. Labor-power must be sold for a finite time, and must be a function <strong>of</strong><br />

a daily wage.<br />

Third, Labor-value is a function <strong>of</strong> labor-power and is used to calculate the contributions<br />

in a period <strong>of</strong> time. Using an hour would be too small and using a week would not work<br />

as most people do not work everyday in a week. Also Marx likes to compare the work <strong>of</strong><br />

different laborers and their values, he likes to compare them in a way to say that the value <strong>of</strong><br />

one workers labor could be worth 2 or 3 days worth <strong>of</strong> the others.<br />

316 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Fourth, Labor-power to be a commodity must be able to be sold freely. You can not<br />

measure it longer than 24 hours as that would be slavery, and it must be free to sell every<br />

day, or it would not be labor-power.<br />

In conclusion, we use the day because 24 hours is the max time that could be used, and<br />

labor-power is the work that can be done in a day. Labor-power is the work that can be sold<br />

in a day. And using any<strong>thing</strong> smaller then a day would not factor the basic needs to live <strong>of</strong><br />

the seller <strong>of</strong> the labor-power.<br />

Next Message by Ryan is [975].<br />

[956] TINDOZ: <strong>The</strong> day is taken as the unit <strong>of</strong> labor power because it is the smallest unit<br />

<strong>of</strong> measure in which a laborer can earn an hourly wage that’s necessary-labor-time/surpluslabor-time<br />

ratio exceeds the amount <strong>of</strong> money needed to keep the worker alive for the whole<br />

day. As Hans said [702] this question is about labor-power and as such it “cannot be measured<br />

in hours because the worker is selling his entire capacity to work to the capitalist, not<br />

just an hour here or there”. As the worker is selling his entire capacity to work, measuring<br />

his labor by the hour doesn’t make sense. Furthermore we also know the value <strong>of</strong> daily<br />

labor-power to be the daily wage which is “the value <strong>of</strong> the ‘average daily means <strong>of</strong> subsistence’<br />

<strong>of</strong> the laborer.” (Annotations pg 471). So because we know the value <strong>of</strong> daily labor<br />

power, we can subdivide it into an hourly wage and we can then use that hourly wage when<br />

figureing the necessary-labor-time/surplus-labor-time ratio. <strong>The</strong> day is the shortest measure<br />

we can do this in. If we were to attempt this with the week, the precision <strong>of</strong> the measure <strong>of</strong><br />

labor-power would not be as accurate as by doing it by the day.<br />

Next Message by TINDOZ is [1052].<br />

[976] JSmits: graded A <strong>The</strong> day is taken as unit <strong>of</strong> labor-power instead <strong>of</strong> hour or week<br />

because it is the most accurate and easiest way <strong>of</strong> measuring labor-power. Measuring an<br />

hour <strong>of</strong> work is not realistic because as Hans says in [2005fa:1216], “the <strong>thing</strong> we are trying<br />

to measure is labor-power, not labor.” Measuring a week <strong>of</strong> labor-power is possible and so is<br />

a year or lifetime but in hours you can’t compute this because we know the daily value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

labor-power and not the hourly-value. This makes the day the shortest possible measuring<br />

unit for labor-power.<br />

Next Message by JSmits is [982].<br />

[986] Sly: In my paper submission, I failed to mention the division <strong>of</strong> the day as Marx<br />

defines it. And seeing as how I have previously answered this question ([2010fa:669]) I<br />

should have included that information, but I digress.<br />

A day is divided into two portions the necessary labor time, and the surplus labor. Necessary<br />

labor time as Marx defines it is: “the length <strong>of</strong> time needed by the worker every<br />

day to produce an equivalent to his or her daily wage.” (Annotations, pg. 469) and then<br />

Marx defines surplus labor as: “the additional time during which the worker produces value<br />

appropriated without equivalent by the capitalist.” (Annotations, pg. 496).<br />

<strong>The</strong> necessary labor time in its simplest form can be viewed as the half <strong>of</strong> the day where<br />

the laborer reproduces his or her compensation (wage) - this particular portion <strong>of</strong> the day is<br />

mandated by economic law, and the surplus <strong>of</strong> labor can simply be view defined as put Tres<br />

stated in [2002fa:226]: “<strong>The</strong> surplus part is where the pr<strong>of</strong>its are derived and it is variable.”<br />

- In my previous submission I added this is the portion in which capitalist are capitalist. I


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 317<br />

stand by that point, but I also realize now that every day, hour, minute, or second contains<br />

surplus <strong>of</strong> labor. This is the portion <strong>of</strong> the day where capitalists make the purest pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

I cited in [2010fa:669] that the wage as Marx defines it is the: “reimbursement for the<br />

costs <strong>of</strong> reproducing the labor-power” and that “For labor-power, the smallest unit <strong>of</strong> measurement<br />

is the day.” (Annotations, pg. 470) By taking these definitions into account, the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> a day is established, and that is by daily wage. Marx states that the daily wage<br />

is determined by: “the value <strong>of</strong> the ‘average daily means <strong>of</strong> subsistence’ <strong>of</strong> the laborer.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> average daily means <strong>of</strong> subsistence being - the cost <strong>of</strong> living in the form <strong>of</strong> food, rent,<br />

clo<strong>thing</strong> utilities, transportation, etc.<br />

With all <strong>of</strong> this information taken into account let’s examine why labor time is not measured<br />

in a week: If labor time were to be measured in a week, it is physically impossible for<br />

a laborer to work for an entire week with rest, food, etc., and capitalists want the most pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

- if a week long shift did exist the capitalist would have to pay the laborer while the laborer<br />

isn’t working. So not only is it physically impossible, it is also financially impossible. If a<br />

laborer were to be paid by the hour, they consequently would have to clock in an out every<br />

hour - thus detracting from their time spent working. Furthermore the capitalist would have<br />

to invest more pr<strong>of</strong>it into a tracking method such a case, which also decrease pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Finally we have come the the measurement in terms <strong>of</strong> a day. With the previous points I<br />

have made you may think that a day is 24 hours and you already stated that a person can’t<br />

possibly work such a long period without food, rest, etc. Well a working day and an actual<br />

day are much different. A day in terms <strong>of</strong> labor-power is defined in a worker’s contract,<br />

agreement...what have you. It can range anywhere from 8, 10, 12, and even 14 hours. <strong>The</strong>re<br />

are minimal and maximal bounds in a working day, and the maximal bounds are set forth in<br />

the agreement between the capitalist and the worker. This makes the day the most logical<br />

choice, it is physically possible to work between 8 and 14 hours, and a capitalist gets the<br />

most for his money.<br />

Hans: Weeks or months are possible as you say in your in-class answer, but days are the shortest possible time. If<br />

workers work week-long shifts (such as on fishing boats) then the week is the shortest possible time.<br />

Next Message by Sly is [987].<br />

[995] Rico: Although this question appears to be simple, it contains a dense substance that<br />

is difficult to grasp. I think it is important to understand what labor-power is before diving<br />

into any reasons why it can’t be measured on an hourly basis. In [2003fa:398], Rostenbach<br />

provides us with many helpful insights, which I will use to help explain my answer. Rostenbach<br />

states that “the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power, like that <strong>of</strong> any other commodity, is determined by<br />

the labor-time necessary for its production.” <strong>The</strong> labor-time necessary for production is too<br />

complex to be measured in small increments broken down by hours. If we were to attempt<br />

to do such a <strong>thing</strong>, it would become too confusing and cumbersome. Deriving the laborer’s<br />

daily wage is another important concept in explaining why the day is taken as unit <strong>of</strong> laborpower.<br />

<strong>The</strong> day is used as unit <strong>of</strong> labor-power because the laborer delivers labor-power in<br />

daily increments and not in hourly increments. From this, Rostenback states that “the laborer’s<br />

daily wage is determined by the value <strong>of</strong> the average daily means <strong>of</strong> subsistence.”<br />

This is important because the laborer can derive his daily labor by the daily wage he earns.<br />

<strong>The</strong> minimum unit <strong>of</strong> labor-power is measured by days.<br />

Next Message by Rico is [996].<br />

318 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 635 is 452 in 2002fa, 468 in 2003fa, 519 in 2004fa, 493 in 2005fa, 535 in<br />

2007SP, 542 in 2008SP, 572 in 2009fa, 653 in 2011fa, 682 in 2012fa, and 653 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 635 Explain Marx’s sentence: “<strong>The</strong> working-day is determinable but in and for<br />

itself indeterminate.”<br />

[659] PLG: graded A Is this question determinable? <strong>The</strong> following paragraph must be<br />

closely analyzed in order to answer <strong>Question</strong> 635<br />

“Although one <strong>of</strong> its parts is determined by the working time required for the reproduction<br />

<strong>of</strong> the labor power <strong>of</strong> the laborer himself, its total length varies with the duration <strong>of</strong> the<br />

surplus-labor. <strong>The</strong> working day is, therefore, determinable, but in and for itself indeterminate.”<br />

Marx Pg. 472, Annotations<br />

First <strong>of</strong>f, Marx uses the word “determined” in the <strong>first</strong> sentence. Marx makes it clear that<br />

the necessary-labor time in the working day can be determined, but that the surplus-labor in<br />

the working day is variable.<br />

Is this what he is referring to when he states in the next sentence, “ <strong>The</strong> working day is,<br />

therefore, determinable..”?<br />

I suspect that Marx is in fact making a reference to the necessary-labor time in the last<br />

sentence when he uses the word determinable. Marx is thus breaking up the definition <strong>of</strong> the<br />

working-day. He is giving two different meanings to “working-day” in a similar way to how<br />

he gives different meanings to the word “value”. Marx is stating that there is a “workingday”<br />

and a “working-day in and for itself”. <strong>The</strong> former is referencing the necessary-labor<br />

time, and the latter is referencing the working-day in a capitalist society.<br />

This perspective differs from the interpretation Hans provides on page 473. Hans believes<br />

that Marx is referring to extra-economic forces and their ability to determine a working<br />

day. This is a highly plausible interpretation, but I’m suspicious about Marx’ use <strong>of</strong> the<br />

words determinable and determined in such close proximity to each other, while referring to<br />

different <strong>thing</strong>s.<br />

Nono [2009fa:696] also refers to legalities in making a work day determinable. However,<br />

Nono believes that extra-economic forces do not determine a work-day, rather they leave the<br />

work-day “in and for itself indeterminate.” I would side with Hans’ perspective that extraeconomic<br />

forces do determine a work-day in a capitalist society.<br />

When Marx says “in and for itself”, he is personifying the working day. I interpret this as<br />

Marx making a reference to capitalism and the social identity that the working day has taken<br />

on because <strong>of</strong> capitalism. We would not have a “working-day” if all we had to fulfill was<br />

the necessary-labor time. Some occupations would potentially take 8 hours a day, or some<br />

would only take a few hours a day, but there would be no common “working-day”. This<br />

personified working day is what Marx refers to as indeterminate. If the surplus labor was<br />

removed, a true working day could be derived. Such a working day would exist in a Marxian<br />

society. Thus he is stating that the necessary-labor is determinable, but the working-day as<br />

it relates to capitalism is indeterminate.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 319<br />

Hans: That’s a long and thoughtful submission, and I didn’t have time during the Semester to do justice to it. If<br />

you are reading this in the archives and find it interesting enough to respond to it, I would be happy to give you<br />

credit for it.<br />

Next Message by PLG is [776].<br />

[668] RexManning: graded A– weight 50% so, is it? or isn’t it?? Looking at the work<br />

day in Marx line examples <strong>of</strong> A—-B+B—C, we can see that there are two separate parts<br />

that make up the total work day. For argument’s sake, I will assume that the laborer in this<br />

example needs to work 5 hours as part <strong>of</strong> the necessary work day, the amount to produce<br />

his daily labor-power. This amount is fixed, which leaves B—-C to vary in length (hours<br />

worked). If we add A—-B+B–C, we get A——C, or the total work day. What eludes us,<br />

is how A—–C is determinable, when what exists in the middle is able to vary. Since Marx<br />

seems to leave us guessing as to what he means, after he goes through all <strong>of</strong> the trouble<br />

explaining why the work day is indeterminate, and then says that it is determinable, it only<br />

seems fair to throw out some possibilities and see where they take us. Could Marx be<br />

referring to the determinable part <strong>of</strong> the work day as the fixed portion <strong>of</strong> A—B? and the<br />

indeterminable portion as A—-C because the varying hours that can exist between B—C?<br />

Since he refers to the work day as A—B+B—C, I do not think that he means to separate<br />

the two lines into determinable and indeterminable. I can only think <strong>of</strong> one other option;<br />

and what I think he means is that the work day is indeterminable due to the variance from<br />

B—C, but due to economic laws that must fix the work day to a non-varying and easily<br />

identifiable number, in order for this to be advantageous in a capitalist society, it is therefore,<br />

also determinable.<br />

Hans: You must distinguish between “determinate” and “determinable.” “Determinate” means: it is determined<br />

by the laws <strong>of</strong> economics. “Determinable” means: it can be determined. Marx says the length <strong>of</strong> the working<br />

day is indeterminate (negation) but it can be determined, i.e., the indeterminacy can be overcome (negation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

negation).<br />

Next Message by RexManning is [670].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 640 is 396 in 2000fa, 421 in 2001fa, 455 in 2002fa, 471 in 2003fa, 523 in<br />

2004fa, 497 in 2005fa, 539 in 2007SP, 538 in 2007fa, 660 in 2011fa, and 689 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 640 How long is the working-day from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the capitalist?<br />

[653] AlexDaily: graded A <strong>The</strong> length <strong>of</strong> the working-day. <strong>The</strong> length <strong>of</strong> the workingday,<br />

from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the capitalist, is getting the most time out <strong>of</strong> their labor force<br />

as possible with having their labor force at full capacity. <strong>The</strong> capitalist feels the labor is a<br />

commodity he has purchased. <strong>The</strong>refore, in Marx’s words, the capitalist “seeks to get the<br />

greatest possible benefit out <strong>of</strong> the use-value <strong>of</strong> his commodity.” Monkeys states it this way<br />

in [2002fa:333.4]: “however long it takes to, with a fixed amount <strong>of</strong> expended capital, extract<br />

the greatest possible ‘quantity <strong>of</strong> labor’ from the workers.” <strong>The</strong> capitalist does this to<br />

make the largest pr<strong>of</strong>it possible. Felix explains how this allows the capitalist to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

in [2000fa:146]: “the capitalist’s goal is to acquire as much surplus labor as possible, or in<br />

other words he would like the working day to have as many surplus-hours as possible. <strong>The</strong><br />

more surplus hours that the capitalist can buy, the more money she will make.” <strong>The</strong>refore,<br />

the determining factors for what composes a work day in the eyes <strong>of</strong> the capitalist are physiological<br />

limits; a person can only work so many hours a day at full capacity, and the social/<br />

cultural limits. Although the social/cultural limits are easy discarded by the capitalist, in<br />

320 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[2000fa:153] Hans explains why “the capitalist knows that he must respect the physiological<br />

limits <strong>of</strong> the working day, but whenever the worker takes a break or uses his time for his<br />

family or his social needs, the capitalist always watches him with jealousy and suspicion.<br />

He considers the time he gives the worker for this as a concession, and if there is competitive<br />

pressure on the business he is quick to say that he can no longer afford these concessions.”<br />

Next Message by AlexDaily is [860].<br />

[1091] Tyler: Jakeman gave a good definition <strong>of</strong> the length <strong>of</strong> the working day by saying,<br />

“the working day for the capitalist is as long as he can possibly make it while enabling<br />

the worker to be able to work the next day” [2007SP:752]. This definition reinforces the<br />

notion that there is no minimum bound for the working day because the capitalist has no<br />

minimum amount <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it. However, the maximum length <strong>of</strong> the working day is 24 hours,<br />

but the capitalist must take certain physiological and social factors into consideration. <strong>The</strong><br />

physiological bound for the work day implies that the worker must be allowed time to rest<br />

in order to remain productive. <strong>The</strong> social factor refers to the need <strong>of</strong> the worker to have<br />

personal time to reflect and interact so as to maintain their sanity.<br />

Next Message by Tyler is [1140].<br />

[1114] Hal: graded A Just enough energy for tomorrow. <strong>The</strong> capitalist wishes to maximize<br />

the length <strong>of</strong> the working day subject to one constraint: He must keep the day short<br />

enough so that he can continually retain and renew his supply <strong>of</strong> exploited workers. In other<br />

words, he must provide enough time for the worker to eat, sleep, and procreate. Other than<br />

that constraint, the capitalist wishes to maximize the length <strong>of</strong> the working day because that<br />

maximizes surplus value.<br />

Next Message by Hal is [1155].<br />

[1158] Orville: content A+ late penalty 1% From the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the capitalist, the<br />

minimum working day could never be less than what Marx calls the necessary labor time.<br />

In fact, for the capitalist to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it, the working day must always be longer than the<br />

necessary labor time. <strong>The</strong> maximum length <strong>of</strong> a working day musn’t be so long that the<br />

laborers can revolt against the capitalist, and the capitalist musn’t work the laborers longer<br />

than they physically can. That is, they must be able to work the next day.<br />

Hans: Good point with the revolt. <strong>The</strong> capitalists must be careful (and are careful) not to act in such a way that<br />

they spark a revolt. But see also [1135].<br />

Next Message by Orville is [1160].<br />

[1195] Tunda: In the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the Capitalist the working day is defined by the way<br />

the capitalist pays for his labor. He pays on a daily wage to the laborer and the capitalist<br />

wants to create surplus-value so the working day is determined by days instead <strong>of</strong> hours. I<br />

would imagine that the capitalist would want his workers to work for the maximum amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> hours in the day that they are allowed to work.<br />

First Message by Tunda is [505].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 641 is 422 in 2001fa, 456 in 2002fa, 472 in 2003fa, 524 in 2004fa, 498 in<br />

2005fa, 540 in 2007SP, and 578 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 641 Isn’t it the motive <strong>of</strong> the worker, like that <strong>of</strong> the capitalist, to get as much<br />

money as possible?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 321<br />

[655] Alex: graded A Capitalist vs Worker–getting rich (or die trying). <strong>The</strong> motive <strong>of</strong><br />

the worker is indeed to gain as much money as possible, just like the capitalist. However,<br />

this dream for the worker is not as easy to make a reality as it is for the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> way<br />

the worker goes about striving to make more money, or as much money as a capitalist, is by<br />

working overtime and as many hours as he/she possibly can for the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> capitalist<br />

on the other hand, is doing very little in order to get rich. In fact, what the capitalist does<br />

is hire these workers who are able to work for the price that he/she <strong>of</strong>fers. By doing so,<br />

these workers are exploited and work as much as they can to ultimately make the capitalist<br />

rich, with the idea that they are making themselves rich instead. <strong>The</strong>se workers do not have<br />

bargaining power, and it is very unlikely that they ever will, with the competitive market for<br />

jobs (especially nowadays) that they find themselves in. Workers are forced to take whatever<br />

wage the capitalist is <strong>of</strong>fering in order to make enough money to survive. Most <strong>of</strong> the times,<br />

these subsistence wages are higher than their current wages, or even minimum wages, if it’s<br />

what they are receiving. <strong>The</strong> worker is encouraged to make more money in order to receive<br />

more than the bare minimum, and thus works more hours because he/she (<strong>of</strong>ten) cannot<br />

receive a raise from the capitalist. This is in turn beneficial for the capitalist instead because<br />

he/she is making more money from the worker who is being employed at a very minimal<br />

cost. In the end, the worker will work itself to death (or until he/she wears out) trying to<br />

have as much or more money than his capitalist boss, while the boss sits back in the chair<br />

and watches this phenomenon happen a repeated number <strong>of</strong> times.<br />

Message [655] referenced by [673]. Next Message by Alex is [746].<br />

[673] ANK: Overtime hours or higher wages. Like the capitalist, it is the motive <strong>of</strong> the<br />

worker to get as much money as possible. Capitalists respond to the workers’ plea for more<br />

money, not by raising wages, but by <strong>of</strong>fering overtime hours. As Alex points out in [655],<br />

as workers use overtime to make as much money as possible, the capitalist is the greatest<br />

beneficiary. Capitalists have no limit to the amount <strong>of</strong> money they want to earn, because it is<br />

possible for them to continue to make more and more money as their workers increase their<br />

hours without raising wages.<br />

<strong>The</strong> primary goal <strong>of</strong> the worker is to earn enough money to provide for their family. <strong>The</strong><br />

secondary goal for workers is to gain as much money as possible even after providing for<br />

their family, because they believe they still haven’t earned enough and that it is possible that<br />

they could earn more. Because the worker lives in the capitalist society, they are hesitant<br />

to leave the possibility <strong>of</strong> making more money on the table. As workers neglect family<br />

relationships and other physiological and moral needs to work long hours, they sacrifice<br />

good health for their employer. Marx states that, “Capital therefore takes no account <strong>of</strong><br />

the health and the length <strong>of</strong> life <strong>of</strong> the worker, unless society forces it to do so.” (Capital,<br />

380:1–381:0) Society’s reaction to workers working too many hours is overtime wages.<br />

Overtime wages prevent the capitalist from working employees overtime without some form<br />

<strong>of</strong> compensation for the neglect <strong>of</strong> family relationships and personal health and require the<br />

capitalist to evaluate whether paying overtime wages to employees working overtime hours<br />

is pr<strong>of</strong>itable.<br />

Next Message by ANK is [677].<br />

[684] SMIKEC: <strong>The</strong> motive <strong>of</strong> the worker would be to make the most money as possible.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y strive to do this in order to have a fulfilling life for their family and in some instances<br />

322 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

are pressured with trying to “keep up with the Jones’.” However, the worker is content with<br />

working for the capitalist, sometimes looking around the corner for the next best <strong>thing</strong>, but<br />

not to the point <strong>of</strong> wanting to start his own business. As stated in 10.1.d, the worker would<br />

not want to be a part <strong>of</strong> the marketplace due to the lack <strong>of</strong> equality and a fair and level playing<br />

field. This is why workers stay with-in the boundaries <strong>of</strong> the capitalist due to the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

potential competition from firm to firm. This keeps the capitalist having to pay a fair price<br />

to the worker in order to keep them happy. Weighing the level <strong>of</strong> happiness changes from<br />

worker to worker. This is why capitalist try to sweeten the pot with benefits. <strong>The</strong> capitalist<br />

has to walk a fine line in this situation being pulled from one side <strong>of</strong> not “over paying” and<br />

the other side <strong>of</strong> the fence, being worker retention.<br />

Message [684] referenced by [687]. Next Message by SMIKEC is [700].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 644 is 398 in 2000fa, 458 in 2002fa, 474 in 2003fa, 527 in 2004fa, 501 in<br />

2005fa, 543 in 2007SP, 553 in 2008fa, 664 in 2011fa, and 693 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 644 Why did the worker in this whole argument never say to the capitalist “you<br />

are exploiting me”?<br />

[665] Frida: graded A+ Not people, but masks. <strong>The</strong>re is a double reason that the worker<br />

never said “you are exploiting me”. <strong>The</strong> main structural part is a basic understanding that the<br />

capitalist has the right to do with his purchased commodity as he sees fit, within the bounds<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodity exchange. Also, this is an argument against the “character mask” <strong>of</strong> capital;<br />

it is not an argument against a person.<br />

<strong>The</strong> worker (supposedly) entered the market as a free agent, as an owner <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

labor-power. When she sold her labor-power on the market, she was implicitly agreeing<br />

to the basic laws <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange. If the capitalist wants to extract surplus-labor out<br />

<strong>of</strong> the worker while using the labor power that he purchased, that is his right. (If we don’t<br />

bring any<strong>thing</strong> but the laws <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange). <strong>The</strong> worker then chooses, wisely, to<br />

argue within the bounds <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange, within which she can say no<strong>thing</strong> about<br />

exploitation.<br />

Another important point is that the capitalist doesn’t function as an individual while exploiting<br />

the worker and buying labor-power on the market. He fuctions as the character mask<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalist. <strong>The</strong> capitalist, properly understood, isn’t a person, it is a relation in society.<br />

When arguing against a mask, or a social role, one should not use points that would normally<br />

appeal to the emotions or morality <strong>of</strong> a person. “You are exploiting me” would only<br />

be a functional point when arguing against a human being. This imagery <strong>of</strong> the capitalist<br />

not being a person, but a social relation, so saying that the capitalist isn’t human has bad<br />

overtones. It helps to say that the worker is another social mask/relation. This argument<br />

between worker and capitalist is an argument between masks.<br />

Message [665] referenced by [2012fa:946]. Next Message by Frida is [688].<br />

[679] Kat: Exploited Worker. If the worker is upset being at the mercy <strong>of</strong> the capitalist,<br />

why did the worker never speak up and say “you are exploiting me”? Perhaps the biggest<br />

reason is, whether they like it or not, they must sell their labor to these capitalists in order<br />

to survive. Even if they spoke up to the capitalist, they would be forced to sell their labor


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 323<br />

to someone else who owns the means <strong>of</strong> production. So, if the worker feels his/her job is at<br />

risk, they will not speak their grievances.<br />

This is not the only reason a worker will not stand up to the capitalist, though. <strong>The</strong><br />

capitalist will likely have insulated themselves from the threat <strong>of</strong> a worker doing so. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

do this by targeting undereducated workers that may not appreciate their labor’s worth. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

may also target illegal workers who will work cheaply because they do not have the same<br />

liberties as other workers and they are threatened by deportation.<br />

To a certain extent, exploitation requires one party who is willing to be exploited. <strong>The</strong><br />

worker can save themselves from being exploited by banding together with other disgruntled<br />

workers. Unions give workers the power <strong>of</strong> voice in numbers.<br />

Hans: You are right, someone can be exploited only if they let themselves be exploited. And I also agree with<br />

you that the achilles heel <strong>of</strong> the working class is that people don’t work together. <strong>The</strong>y have to be forced to work<br />

together by the capitalists, they won’t do it voluntarily. <strong>The</strong>y also don’t want to do any<strong>thing</strong> about the environment<br />

because this would require helping each other out.<br />

Next Message by Kat is [761].<br />

[881] Babyceta: graded A <strong>The</strong> worker never says to the capitalist “you are exploiting<br />

me” for two reasons. First, the worker enters into the transaction <strong>of</strong> selling her labor-power<br />

voluntarily (although Marx would disagree with this). <strong>The</strong>re is debate concerning the “voluntary”<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> selling her labor-power because (1) she cannot obtain what she needs to<br />

subsist otherwise, and (2) she lacks the means <strong>of</strong> production necessary to use (consume) her<br />

own labor-power. Even though the capitalist realizes that consuming labor-power is the only<br />

means to increase the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity and the individual selling her labor-power may<br />

not be aware <strong>of</strong> this, he is nonetheless free to use this commodity (labor-power) in any way<br />

he chooses. He may conceal this sinister motive by extracting surplus labor value, mainly<br />

by paying a wage that reflects only the necessary labor time, but he is merely operating in a<br />

flawed system and can therefore hide behind this “mask” capitalism has created.<br />

This “mask” leads us to the second reason workers do not confront capitalist exploitation:<br />

there is no one to confront. Capitalism is a social process and not an individual. To say<br />

“you are exploiting me” to capitalism would be the equivalent <strong>of</strong> saying to racism “you are<br />

unfairly discriminating against me.”<br />

Next Message by Babyceta is [1034].<br />

[909] DMorris: Simply put, the reason the laborer does not demand to stop being exploited<br />

is that he does not know that he is being exploited. He believes that he is making<br />

a competitive daily or hourly wage, and doesn’t understand that he recoups his necessary<br />

labor (the labor that pays his wage) long before he is done working for the day.<br />

Additionally, he willingly works overtime, believing that his employer is giving him a<br />

chance to make more money as a benefit. In reality, overtime means the worker is still working<br />

at a wage less than the product <strong>of</strong> his labor. Now, however, he is voluntarily sacrificing<br />

his mental and physical health to do so. When there is a productivity increase due to some<br />

technological advance, the laborer thinks that he reaps the rewards <strong>of</strong> that, but he is still being<br />

exploited by his employer as his employer is getting the benefits <strong>of</strong> more labor without<br />

paying the full increased value <strong>of</strong> that labor. <strong>The</strong> only true winner in the system is the capitalist.<br />

However, the laborer never sees this. This inequality <strong>of</strong> information is part <strong>of</strong> Marx’s<br />

324 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

reason for writing Capital. He wants laborers to understand they are being exploited in order<br />

for them to stand up and demand their fair share <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>of</strong> their labor.<br />

Hans: Higher productivity due to technical advances creates more value only in the short run for the early adopters.<br />

Workers usually don’t get any <strong>of</strong> this.<br />

First Message by DMorris is [445].<br />

[916] Ferox: graded A Workers do not realize the exploitative process <strong>of</strong> capitalism primarily<br />

due to the belief that a worker is selling her labour, and not her labour power. If she<br />

realized that distinction and its ramifications, she would understand that her labour power is<br />

worth much more than the wage she is paid. <strong>The</strong> discrepancy in the worth <strong>of</strong> labour power<br />

and the wage paid is the surplus value generated by the expenditure <strong>of</strong> labour power for the<br />

capitalist. Additionally, due to a lack <strong>of</strong> control over the means <strong>of</strong> production, which are<br />

monopolized by the capitalist, the worker has no means <strong>of</strong> realizing the full value <strong>of</strong> her<br />

labour power for herself through production.<br />

Next Message by Ferox is [1062].<br />

[924] Long: In a way the worker would never want to say to the capitalist that “you are<br />

exploiting me.” Mainly because when a worker is out looking for a job, they <strong>of</strong>ten agree<br />

and bind themself to the contract <strong>of</strong> labor time for a wage. <strong>The</strong> workers know that they<br />

are willling to give up their time per day or per week for a wage which it is relatively low.<br />

<strong>The</strong> worker can reasonably argue with the capitalist that their labor time might be worth<br />

more wage, but as capitalist they are not willing to give a higher wage because that would<br />

not be maximizing their pr<strong>of</strong>it. Another reason would be that the capitalist would just go<br />

find someone else to hire for the same wage or even lower. In the end the capitalist always<br />

benefits because they have the power to sell the commodity whereas the workers only have<br />

one ability, to sell their power <strong>of</strong> labor as time input for a wage.<br />

Next Message by Long is [1077].<br />

[949] She: graded A– <strong>The</strong> worker does not have the power to call out the capitalist in the<br />

capitalist system. In this system, the individual laborer, no matter how frustrated and abused<br />

they may feel, is powerless to initiate change; this is deliberate and intentional. <strong>The</strong> worker<br />

is caught in a system in which they have become absolutely dependent and by default, enslaved<br />

to the capitalist because they do not have access to the means <strong>of</strong> production. Since<br />

they do not, they are trapped in a situation where they are forced to sell their labor power for<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> subsistence. Workers have the power <strong>of</strong> numbers and are physically capable <strong>of</strong><br />

gaining concessions in class-action alone. Unions are great examples <strong>of</strong> this power. Unions<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten use their collective bargaining power to stage labor strikes and force benefits and concessions.<br />

But, however, a strike is only possible if the workers have savings to live on while<br />

they are not selling their labor-power. Thus, to facilitate a strike, a capitalist owner must pay<br />

the laborers more than a subsistence wage to allow for savings. Thus, the capitalist is in a<br />

position <strong>of</strong> unchecked power in which they rule the workers. A single worker cannot step<br />

up by themselves as they are too easily replaceable.<br />

Hans: Workers have more power than you say.<br />

Next Message by She is [950].<br />

[980] Baseball: <strong>The</strong> worker has and will never say to the capitalist “you are exploiting<br />

me” because they are capitalists and because they simply realize that in order for a company<br />

to make pr<strong>of</strong>it they must receive more than they expend. This means the company’s sales<br />

must outweigh its COGS (Cost <strong>of</strong> Goods Sold)/labor. By exploiting the worker, companies


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 325<br />

are paying their workers less for the same job they have been performing. As a result the<br />

cost <strong>of</strong> labor is not higher than their sales, thus a positive pr<strong>of</strong>it. If the worker did so happen<br />

to mention that they are exploited companies would give them two options. Either stay and<br />

deal with it or go find a new job. Generally all businesses are exploiting their workers in<br />

one way or another. In capitalism the main objective is to make pr<strong>of</strong>it and by doing so some<br />

form <strong>of</strong> manipulation is present. Lastly, without exploitation in the workplace, business<br />

would either break even (make no pr<strong>of</strong>it but no loss), or go bankrupt.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> answer to the question is implicit in your description <strong>of</strong> business practices. You are describing the<br />

surface transactions, all <strong>of</strong> which seem ordinary market transactions without apparent exploitation. In capitalism,<br />

exploitation hides under a seemingly equitable surface. Exploitation is not a surface category, this is why the<br />

capitalist says to the worker: you don’t have the right to speak about it. <strong>The</strong>y deny exploitation in the same way<br />

they deny global warming.<br />

Next Message by Baseball is [981].<br />

[989] School: Fear!!! A capitalist based society is reliant on fear <strong>of</strong> the worker. Capitalists<br />

would work their workers to the maximum extent to get the surplus labor. <strong>The</strong> workers must<br />

use their labor power to provide labor value to make ends meet. Capitalist pay the workers<br />

just enough to stay with them, but not enough for the worker to have access to production or<br />

market power. By crippling the worker to not have those production or market powers fear<br />

sets in. So out <strong>of</strong> fear <strong>of</strong> losing their jobs, they were unable to stand up for themselves.<br />

Next Message by School is [990].<br />

[1002] Spiral: Workers believe they’re being paid time-wages reflecting the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

labour-power they sold to the capitalist over days or weeks. Without understanding that<br />

the capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>of</strong>f the worker’s labour-power beyond the reproduction <strong>of</strong> an equivalent<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> value the worker is unable to see the full extent <strong>of</strong> the exploitation. As a<br />

mathematical rule the rate-<strong>of</strong>-pr<strong>of</strong>it (surplus-value/constant+ variable capital) will always be<br />

less-than the rate-<strong>of</strong>-exploitation (surplus-value/variable capital). This fixed proportion will<br />

allow the capitalist to point to his small pr<strong>of</strong>its as a form <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> he isn’t exploiting workers<br />

because surely if he was his pr<strong>of</strong>its would be greater. Capitalists rob workers <strong>of</strong> their claim<br />

to the products <strong>of</strong> their labour but capitalism normalizes this theft to the point workers don’t<br />

even think to ask if they too have a right to the product.<br />

Next Message by Spiral is [1092].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 652 is 507 in 2005fa and 549 in 2007fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 652 What are the main differences distinguishing capitalism from earlier forms<br />

<strong>of</strong> exploitation?<br />

[658] Husani: <strong>The</strong> main difference Marx speaks <strong>of</strong> is the difference between slavery and<br />

capitalism. In slavery a person is forced to work while in capitalism a worker agrees to<br />

work for a capitalist. In slavery a worker is forced to work by an owner for a majority <strong>of</strong><br />

their day. This maximizes the surplus value received by the owner and in most cases limits<br />

the longevity <strong>of</strong> the slave. <strong>The</strong> owner works them to death in many cases and the slave has<br />

no recourse because if they don’t work to their full potential they won’t receive the basic<br />

necessities they need to survive, clo<strong>thing</strong>, shelter, food, etc.<br />

In capitalism the worker agrees to work for the capitalist in order to receive these basic<br />

necessities but isn’t forced to do so. <strong>The</strong> worker agrees to a certain wage but the hours he<br />

will work are yet to be determined. <strong>The</strong> capitalist, like the slave owner, wants to maximize<br />

326 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the amount <strong>of</strong> surplus value they receive from the worker but because it is an agreement<br />

between the two parties they can’t work them to death. Marx says “the laborer, free or not<br />

free, must add to the working time necessary for his own maintenance an extra working<br />

time in order to produce the means <strong>of</strong> subsistence for the owners <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

[344:2/o].” This means the worker must work in order to survive but must also put in extra<br />

work to create pr<strong>of</strong>its for his employer.<br />

She: I don’t know if Marx would say that the workers “agree” to work for the capitalists. Marx describes a situation<br />

in which the workers are forced, or coerced by biologic need, to work for the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> workers may think<br />

they are in some sort <strong>of</strong> agreement with the capitalists, but they are truly enslaved, and this thought is no<strong>thing</strong><br />

more than the product <strong>of</strong> an illusion. <strong>The</strong>y are enslaved in such a powerful institution that they do not even realize<br />

their condition. <strong>The</strong> perceptions and thoughts <strong>of</strong> a “free” worker are simply byproducts <strong>of</strong> the capitalist conditions<br />

that encapsulate society. According to Marx, the worker will be a slave until he/she has access to the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production. Any worker in a capitalist society, according to Marx’s logic, who believes himself free has not seen<br />

the “true science” <strong>of</strong> the workings <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

Next Message by Husani is [663].<br />

Term Paper 666 is 510 in 1997WI, 510 in 1997sp, 910 in 1997ut, 910 in 1998WI, 910 in<br />

1999SP, 910 in 2001fa, and 810 in 2005fa:<br />

Term Paper 666 Essay about Chapter Ten (Choose any Part <strong>of</strong> the Chapter not Covered in<br />

Class)<br />

[639] Frida, JJ, and School: <strong>The</strong> Working Day: An analysis <strong>of</strong> the effects <strong>of</strong> capititalsim<br />

on the working day in modern times. In our analysis <strong>of</strong> the effects <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

on the working day, we will attempt to not only look at Marx’s analysis, but to add our own<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> these effects to the modern working day. Marx brings many examples <strong>of</strong> the<br />

struggles <strong>of</strong> workers, the historical processes, and labor laws that went into play in determining<br />

the working day in his time. We will attempt to further his analysis <strong>of</strong> the roots <strong>of</strong> the<br />

exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers and extraction <strong>of</strong> surplus labor by providing modern day examples<br />

<strong>of</strong> this exploitation. We will look at modern day laws that are designed to limit the working<br />

day, and at how laws that attempt to classify wages by hour, salary, or commission will<br />

also effect the working day. Lastly, we will highlight some <strong>of</strong> our personal experiences <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalist exploitation. We will attempt to show this not only in our analysis <strong>of</strong> the length<br />

and make-up <strong>of</strong> the working day, but also through a study <strong>of</strong> big company policy, current<br />

wage structures, and laws designed to “help” workers. Overall, we will show how capitalistic<br />

exploitation is alive and thriving today and achieving its primary goal, to skim <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> the<br />

surplus labor <strong>of</strong> the workforce.<br />

“Capital, in turn has one single-minded life impulse, the drive to create value and surplusvalue,<br />

to make its constant portion, the means <strong>of</strong> production, absorb the greatest possible<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> surplus-labor. Capital is dead labor, that vampire-like, only lives by sucking<br />

living labor, and lives the more labor it sucks.” (341:3/o)<br />

Although men and women today are not forced to work to their physiological limits as<br />

in industrial England, modern capitalism is still able to complete its primary agenda. Even<br />

today as the laws and cultural limits to the working day have changed in favor <strong>of</strong> the worker,<br />

we will show that capitalism is still very effective in bypassing any road blocks to its goal<br />

<strong>of</strong> maximizing its extraction <strong>of</strong> surplus labor. Even when capital faces natural or market<br />

forces that cut into their pr<strong>of</strong>it rate, they can and will cut wages to create more surplus labor


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 327<br />

in the working day. In so doing, they have adjusted their rate <strong>of</strong> exploitation in order to<br />

maintain their pr<strong>of</strong>it rate. Although the times, context, and conditions have changed for this<br />

exploitation, we will show that exploitation is as relevant today as it was in Marx’s time.<br />

Capitalism, by its very nature, leads to a hunger for surplus-value and therefore surpluslabor.<br />

This “hunger for surplus-labor” (353:1) leads to the extension <strong>of</strong> the working-day<br />

for a few reasons. <strong>The</strong> means <strong>of</strong> production only exist to absorb labor and surplus labor<br />

(367:1/o). Any time that the means <strong>of</strong> production are not used is time that could be spent<br />

extracting surplus-labor, which is time wasted. Even when viewed without the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production, time not spent in the production <strong>of</strong> surplus-value is wasted time to the capitalist.<br />

In addition to prolongation <strong>of</strong> the working-day, capitalism leads inevitably to exploitation <strong>of</strong><br />

workers. Capitalists will always try to get more value out <strong>of</strong> the labor <strong>of</strong> their workers, while<br />

paying them less.<br />

<strong>The</strong> main focus <strong>of</strong> chapter ten is the extension <strong>of</strong> the working-day. For capital, any time<br />

not being used to produce surplus-value is wasted time. In certain branches <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

the owners <strong>of</strong> the machines are very concerned about wasted fuel, ink, paper, etc. Wasted<br />

human life does not concern them, since the humans are not owned by the capitalists. If a<br />

laborer dies or is injured, he is easily replaced, it does not represent any loss to the capitalist.<br />

“Moreover, the consumption <strong>of</strong> labor-power by capital is so rapid that the worker has already<br />

more or less completely lived himself out when he is only half-way through his life.” (795:1)<br />

Once again, this loss <strong>of</strong> life is <strong>of</strong> no concern to the capitalist.<br />

Yet, if child labor laws or other restrictions are put in effect, the capitalist claims to be<br />

concerned that she will lose too much <strong>of</strong> her reserve labor force. This reveals a contradiction.<br />

If they can afford to kill <strong>of</strong>f their workers, then we must assume that they can afford to<br />

lose their six-year-old workers. This leads us to wonder why the capitalists really cannot do<br />

without the labor <strong>of</strong> children. <strong>The</strong> real reason that the capitalists cannot stand to lose child<br />

labor is that it is cheaper than adult labor. If you have work that a child can do just as well as<br />

an adult, so that the products <strong>of</strong> the labor will have just as much value, the inevitable logic<br />

is that you should hire the child laborer. You can pay her less and thereby suck even more<br />

surplus labor from her. This same logic leads to the hiring <strong>of</strong> many groups that are discriminated<br />

against; children, women, and immigrants are three <strong>of</strong> the most common examples <strong>of</strong><br />

groups that suffer from this type <strong>of</strong> exploitation. In some instances the capitalist prefers to<br />

replace their workers with workers from these groups. (788:4) Marx identifies these groups<br />

later in Das Kapital as part <strong>of</strong> the “stagnant surplus population” that fills the ranks <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist’s industrial reserve army. (797:2)<br />

<strong>The</strong> most rampant example <strong>of</strong> the exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers occurring in the U.S. today<br />

is the exploitation <strong>of</strong> illegal immigrants. <strong>The</strong> employers take advantage <strong>of</strong> the fact that the<br />

laborers are in the country illegally and are afraid <strong>of</strong> getting deported. If there is little chance<br />

<strong>of</strong> your workers reporting you to the government, why not break labor laws? In factories<br />

where illegal immigrants are employed, minors have been found working 102 hours a week<br />

(Preston). This is occurring among generally bad working conditions.<br />

Another way that the capitalist attempts to get more value out <strong>of</strong> a laborer than he paid for<br />

is a simple reduction <strong>of</strong> wages. <strong>The</strong> shortening <strong>of</strong> the working-day to 10 hours in nineteenth<br />

328 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

century London resulted in a reduction <strong>of</strong> wages <strong>of</strong> at least 25% (396:1/o). This is always<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> that the Capitalist claims is inevitable, that they are forced to reduce wages because<br />

<strong>of</strong> the horrible impositions <strong>of</strong> the government. This is false; we have seen pro<strong>of</strong> that<br />

the pr<strong>of</strong>it margins can survive normal working days and normal wages. <strong>The</strong> true reason for<br />

this reduction <strong>of</strong> wages is the desire to maintain the level <strong>of</strong> surplus labor received despite<br />

government regulations to limit the working day.<br />

Forcing workers to work for no wages is the ideal situation for the Capitalist. By increasing<br />

the portion <strong>of</strong> unpaid labor he is getting additional surplus-labor for free. <strong>The</strong>re are two<br />

species <strong>of</strong> this unpaid labor. <strong>The</strong>se are: organizing the break schedule such that the worker<br />

cannot leave during breaks, and pure unpaid labor. After the 10 hours act, the manufacturers<br />

were paying 10 hours wages for “15 hours lordship over labor-power” (403:1/o) <strong>The</strong>re<br />

were also instances <strong>of</strong> children having to sleep at the factories in which they work (369:3/o).<br />

Not being able to leave your place <strong>of</strong> employment is tantamount to slavery. <strong>The</strong>re are also<br />

instances <strong>of</strong> pure unpaid labor, both in the nineteenth century and in the modern day. Journeyman<br />

bakers in the nineteenth century were forced to work overtime without being paid<br />

(361:1). Despite modern labor laws, this exact type <strong>of</strong> labor exploitation continues to this<br />

day. Wal-mart has been sued in four states for unpaid overtime; the employees claim that<br />

they were pressured to work overtime and then the overtime was deleted from their records<br />

(Ehrenreich 183).<br />

<strong>The</strong>se issues reveal the power struggle between the capitalist and the laborer. <strong>The</strong> laborer<br />

is relatively powerless against employers because he is dependent <strong>of</strong> them for survival. This<br />

is especially true in times <strong>of</strong> high unemployment. Workers will put up with bad working<br />

conditions and long hours if they feel as though their only alternative is unemployment and<br />

falling (even deeper) into poverty. Yet, even in abundant times <strong>of</strong> lower unemployment, the<br />

individual worker is kept at a disadvantage in this power struggle by capital’s maintenance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the “industrial reserve army” (784:1/o) <strong>of</strong> the unemployed. It is this unbalanced power<br />

struggle that leads to the need for intervention on behalf <strong>of</strong> workers by institutions and<br />

groups such as unions and government. Only when government intercedes on behalf <strong>of</strong><br />

workers or when workers bind themselves together to gain collective bargaining power, can<br />

the balance <strong>of</strong> power adjust. Even then, we will see that capitalism has alternative methods<br />

to sidestep government and collective bargaining power.<br />

Das Kapital “<strong>The</strong> Working Day” discusses the cruelty and disgusting nature <strong>of</strong> legal<br />

human slavery, where capitalism is the product <strong>of</strong> the most devious and degrading part <strong>of</strong><br />

labor. Which raises the question, has government been able to improve the living standards<br />

<strong>of</strong> all? Or do capitalistS find methods <strong>of</strong> tainting the good intentions <strong>of</strong> law makers? “It is<br />

the boundless excesses <strong>of</strong> the werewolf’s hunger for surplus labor, not this hunger itself that<br />

triggered the legal regulation.” (353:2/o) In order to protect the workers there must be some<br />

form <strong>of</strong> regulation to keep the capitalist from creating exorbitant surplus labor through the<br />

worker’s efforts.<br />

Child labor in London around the late Nineteenth Century was very prevalent and useful<br />

to capitalists to create surplus labor. Children <strong>of</strong>ten worked 15-18 hour days with work<br />

available occasionally at night with the same amount <strong>of</strong> pay. Today we have modern laws to<br />

regulate such <strong>of</strong>fenses; one law in particular is called the Fair Labor Standards Act (FLSA).


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 329<br />

This regulates the hours a child can work, and how hazardous to the health <strong>of</strong> the child the<br />

working conditions will be. If a person be under the age <strong>of</strong> fourteen this person should not<br />

be allowed to work. If you take a close look there still are jobs available for children under<br />

the age <strong>of</strong> fourteen even though the law mandates they shouldn’t work. Paper routes, mowing<br />

lawns, farm jobs etc. This is a way that capitalism creates surplus labor with working<br />

government laws still in place. (www.dol.gov)<br />

Early nineteenth century journeymen bakers were <strong>of</strong>ten overworked, putting in long<br />

hours. “<strong>The</strong> unpaid labor <strong>of</strong> the men was made the source whereby the competition was<br />

carried on.” (361:1) In the mid eighteen hundreds journeymen bakers organized meetings to<br />

ban Sunday and night work, but due to the tremendous amount <strong>of</strong> competition for bakers it<br />

was necessary for bakers to ignore laws that were passed to improve living standards. With<br />

fear <strong>of</strong> losing their livelihood, baker’s worked Sundays and nights. Loss <strong>of</strong> employment is<br />

very real today, especially with the current economic issues at hand. <strong>The</strong>re exists today an<br />

unemployment insurance benefit to eligible workers who are unemployed through no fault<br />

<strong>of</strong> their own, and meet other eligibility requirements <strong>of</strong> state law. If an employer terminates<br />

a person’s job for any other reason besides poor job performance then the person will qualify<br />

for this Unemployment Insurance. (www.dol.gov)<br />

Wallpaper factories in London in the early eighteen hundreds would pay overtime for<br />

any amount <strong>of</strong> hours worked over ten hours. We currently have jobs where capitalism creates<br />

an immense amount <strong>of</strong> surplus labor, while enticing workers with overtime pay. <strong>The</strong>re<br />

are different types <strong>of</strong> jobs today with different types <strong>of</strong> compensation associated with them.<br />

Three <strong>of</strong> these are: hourly, salary, and commission. Initially these were established to fairly<br />

compensate those working, but with ill intentions through a capitalist society became misconstrued<br />

and twisted to benefit the capitalist. Hourly workers work excessive amount <strong>of</strong><br />

hours to eventually receive overtime pay. Salary based workers are given a guaranteed yearly<br />

amount paid to them. Under this contract, they will not receive any overtime pay, but will<br />

be required to give the time necessary to complete the job. Lastly there is commission based<br />

pay were it is in the best interest <strong>of</strong> the worker to work as much as possible to not miss or<br />

lose a potential sale. All three types <strong>of</strong> jobs have compensation plans established to extend<br />

the working day and create surplus labor. (www.dol.gov)<br />

<strong>The</strong>se same issues have arisen in the personal experience and lives <strong>of</strong> our group members<br />

as well. Specifically, I want to highlight an example from my work experience that<br />

shows, despite the modern laws and wage structures, that companies (the capitalists) have<br />

found ways to avert minimum wage laws, and have found a new treasure trove <strong>of</strong> surpluslabor<br />

in the company benefits and perks that have thus far not been relatively discussed as<br />

a part <strong>of</strong> wages. <strong>The</strong> perks and benefits packages that a company <strong>of</strong>fers are an integral but<br />

non-monetary part <strong>of</strong> the wage, and are therefore a source <strong>of</strong> increasing or decreasing the<br />

necessary labor time and hence decreasing or increasing relatively the surplus labor time<br />

in the working day. Elimination <strong>of</strong> benefits obviously having the effect <strong>of</strong> decreasing the<br />

real wage, decreasing the necessary labor time, and increasing the amount <strong>of</strong> surplus labor<br />

available to the capitalist. This is all accomplished within the confines <strong>of</strong> modern labor laws<br />

that regulate the working day and minimum hourly wage.<br />

330 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Capitalistic exploitation is alive and kicking in today’s markets. Despite the fact that we<br />

don’t have an 18 hour working day, and we seem to have a number <strong>of</strong> modern laws that will<br />

keep us from the deplorable conditions <strong>of</strong> industrial England, we have shown that capitalism<br />

has been crafty enough to still find a way and a means to absorb the greatest amount <strong>of</strong><br />

surplus labor that it can, and effectively extend the working day <strong>of</strong> the laborer in 2010.<br />

“..capital usually knows how to transfer these (expenses <strong>of</strong> laws) from its own shoulders to<br />

those <strong>of</strong> the working class and the petty bourgeoisie.”<br />

We have shown this in modern examples, in some futile modern labor protection laws,<br />

and through our personal experiences <strong>of</strong> the capitalistic free market bid process.<br />

WORKS CITED:<br />

Preston, Julia. “After Iowa Raid, Immigrants Fuel Labor Inquiries.” New York Times 27<br />

July 2008, Print.<br />

Ehrenreich, Barbara. Nickel and Dimed. New York, NY: Holt Paperbacks, 2008. 183.<br />

Print.<br />

www.dol.gov (2010). Retrieved on October 22, 2010 from: http://workforcesecurity.doleta.g<br />

www.dol.gov (2010). Retrieved on October 22, 2010 from: http://www.dol.gov/compliance/<br />

flsa.htm<br />

www.dol.gov (2010). Retrieved on October 22, 2010 from: http://www.dol.gov/dol/topic/wa<br />

Next Message by Frida is [665], Next Message by JJ is [682], and Next Message by School is [641].<br />

Term Paper 667 is 810 in 2002fa, 810 in 2003fa, 810 in 2004fa, 568 in 2007SP, 572 in<br />

2008SP, 576 in 2008fa, 604 in 2009fa, 687 in 2011fa, and 716 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 667 Children and the Struggle around the Working Day<br />

[677] ANK, DMorris, Deadfamous, JSmits, and Kraken: Children and the Working<br />

Day. One <strong>of</strong> the principles upon which all capitalist markets operate on is the fact that all<br />

firms are pr<strong>of</strong>it maximizing. Pr<strong>of</strong>it maximization, combined with competition, establishes<br />

an environment in which capitalist firms must employ any means necessary to increase pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

This means that in capitalist markets, firms want to employ labor at as inexpensive a<br />

cost as possible. While in most modern industrialized nations this merely means that firms<br />

put themselves in opposition to labor reform movements, in many modern under-developed<br />

nations this unfortunate combination results in the exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers. Children are<br />

unfortunately some <strong>of</strong> the easiest workers to manipulate and exploit. <strong>The</strong>y generally have<br />

no legal representation, and the fact that that they are required to work generally means<br />

that their parents cannot make a living wage on their own, leaving them at the mercy <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist firm. During the Industrial Revolution in the early 1800’s, as capitalists began to<br />

realize that labor was a major expense in the production <strong>of</strong> cheap factory-made products,<br />

child labor became more prominent. Bertrand Russell, 1950 Nobel Prize winner for his human<br />

rights literature, wrote concerning the Industrial Revolution; “children worked from 12<br />

to 16 hours a day; they <strong>of</strong>ten began working at the age <strong>of</strong> six or seven. Children had to be<br />

beaten to keep them from falling asleep while at work; in spite <strong>of</strong> this, many failed to keep


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 331<br />

awake and were mutilated or killed. Parents had to submit to the infliction <strong>of</strong> these atrocities<br />

upon their children, because they themselves were in a desperate plight.”(1)<br />

For centuries, capitalists have been extending the working-day to its natural maximum<br />

limit, and then beyond this limit to a natural day <strong>of</strong> 12 hours. <strong>The</strong>n followed the birth <strong>of</strong><br />

machinism and modern industry in the last third <strong>of</strong> the 18th century and this broke every<br />

moral boundary there was. All bounds <strong>of</strong> morals and nature, age and sex, day and night,<br />

were broken down. As machinery dispenses with muscular power, it becomes a means <strong>of</strong><br />

employing laborers <strong>of</strong> little muscular strength, whose development is not yet complete, and<br />

whose limbs are suppler for the job. <strong>The</strong> labor <strong>of</strong> children was therefore the <strong>first</strong> <strong>thing</strong> that<br />

capitalists who used machinery sought after. This changed the layout <strong>of</strong> the working place<br />

because they were no longer looking for labor and laborers, they were finding a means to<br />

increase the number <strong>of</strong> wage-laborers by enrolling every member <strong>of</strong> a working man’s family<br />

with no distinction <strong>of</strong> age or sex.(2)<br />

<strong>The</strong> capitalist market does not self-regulate in terms <strong>of</strong> who is hired and at what wages<br />

they are hired at. In circumstances where the capitalist firm is given a choice between two<br />

workers who can produce the same number <strong>of</strong> products an hour, that firm will, according to<br />

the previously established tenet <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it maximization, choose the least expensive worker.<br />

Assuming both workers are applying for this position out <strong>of</strong> their own personal choice, this<br />

provides no moral dilemma. Even when assuming that these workers are selling their labor<br />

in order to pay bills or feed their families, society can assuage its moral fears by reminding<br />

itself that while the system is certainly broken, these workers are <strong>of</strong>fering their labor <strong>of</strong> their<br />

own volition. However, once children enter into the arrangement, and society sees that they<br />

are being forced into labor, their perspectives change, and society demands change in the<br />

system.<br />

Capital exploitation, which is based on commodity exchange, places no limits on the<br />

working day or on surplus labor. A force outside <strong>of</strong> the capitalist and laborer was necessary<br />

to regulate working conditions, and after years <strong>of</strong> petitioning, governments slowly started<br />

extending labor protections, despite the cries and protests <strong>of</strong> the factory owners that restricting<br />

labor would lead to a downfall <strong>of</strong> the entire market. <strong>The</strong> poor treatment <strong>of</strong> children in<br />

England brought about the Factory Act <strong>of</strong> 1833 which regulated the working day for children.<br />

<strong>The</strong> provisions <strong>of</strong> the act were:(3)<br />

1. Children (ages 14–18) must not work more than 12 hours a day with an hour lunch<br />

break.<br />

2. Children (ages 9–13) must not work more than 8 hours with an hour lunch break.<br />

3. Children (ages 9–13) must have two hours <strong>of</strong> education per day.<br />

4. Outlawed the employment <strong>of</strong> children under 9 in the textile industry.<br />

5. Children under 18 must not work at night.<br />

During the Industrial Revolution, the working class was forced to take a political stand<br />

against the capitalist factory owners on a variety <strong>of</strong> issues. Child labor was the <strong>first</strong> major<br />

issue that the working class stood up for. This political action, or extra-economic force, was<br />

required to set maximum working limits for children <strong>first</strong>, and eventually for all laborers.<br />

332 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Marx discusses the factors that determine the maximum limits <strong>of</strong> the working day in chapter<br />

10 by saying, “. . . the working-day has a maximum bound. It cannot be prolonged beyond<br />

a certain point. This maximum bound is determined in two different ways. First, by the<br />

physiological bounds <strong>of</strong> labor-power. Within the 24 hours <strong>of</strong> the natural day a man can<br />

expend only a definite quantity <strong>of</strong> his vital force. Just as a horse can only work, from day to<br />

day, 8 hours. During part <strong>of</strong> the day this force must rest, sleep; during another part the man<br />

has to satisfy other physiological needs, to feed, wash, and clothe himself. Besides these<br />

purely physiological limits, the extension <strong>of</strong> the working-day encounters moral ones. <strong>The</strong><br />

laborer needs time to satisfy his intellectual and social wants, the extent and number which<br />

are conditioned by the general state <strong>of</strong> social advancement.”(4)<br />

<strong>The</strong> exploitation <strong>of</strong> children in the labor-force violates the physiological and moral bounds<br />

<strong>of</strong> the working day. By requiring children to work long hours in poor conditions, the capitalist<br />

is violating the physiological bound. <strong>The</strong> moral bound is broken by keeping children<br />

from school and the social needs <strong>of</strong> a being a child. <strong>The</strong>se bounds as defined by Marx are<br />

addressed in the Factory Act <strong>of</strong> 1833 and its amendments. Because the goal <strong>of</strong> a capitalist is<br />

to maximize pr<strong>of</strong>its, capitalists have found ways around legislation to mistreat and employ<br />

children beyond the legal limits. Marx discusses the pr<strong>of</strong>it maximizing behavior <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

by saying that, “Capital therefore takes no account <strong>of</strong> the health and the length <strong>of</strong> life <strong>of</strong><br />

the worker, unless society forces it to do so.”(5) Marx believed that under capitalism workers<br />

were forced to work excessively long hours in order to meet the capitalist’s insatiable need<br />

for greater pr<strong>of</strong>its. Marx noted that as laborers worked longer days, their health would begin<br />

to fail and their lives were subsequently shortened. Just as tragic as a life shortened by overwork<br />

is the degradation <strong>of</strong> the quality <strong>of</strong> life due to excessive work. As the working class<br />

pressured society for a maximum length <strong>of</strong> a work day, workers were acting in society’s<br />

best interest and their own according to Marx. Hans states that “the state found itself in the<br />

contradictory situation <strong>of</strong> giving in to the demands <strong>of</strong> the working class in order to heed the<br />

long-term interests <strong>of</strong> capital.”(6)<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is a direct negative impact to society when child labor is employed. Children are<br />

unable to attend school, which decreases the literacy rate and overall level <strong>of</strong> education<br />

in society. By being forced to do manual labor for a paltry sum, children develop health<br />

problems much younger than they would had they not been forced to work. Society realized<br />

that preventing child labor was in its best interest. Hans points out the contradictory nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> this statement, but many <strong>thing</strong>s that are in society’s best interests tend to be contradictory:<br />

in order to get the most value out <strong>of</strong> the soil, the farmer must leave a plot fallow for a season.<br />

Even the capitalist must occasionally invest some <strong>of</strong> his pr<strong>of</strong>its into more infrastructure in<br />

order to increase production in the long term. In the factory act <strong>of</strong> 1833, England realized<br />

that the best way to secure its future was to prevent capitalists from stripping the youth <strong>of</strong><br />

their chances to learn, study, and develop into healthy working adults.<br />

Today in the United States, child labor is heavily regulated and looked down upon. In<br />

response to legislation in the United States against child labor, capitalists have moved production<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities to countries without legislation or under-developed countries such<br />

as China, India and Bangladesh, where children work to supplement parental income. <strong>The</strong><br />

International Labor Organization (ILO) estimates that 250 million children (between the age


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 333<br />

<strong>of</strong> 5 and 14) work in under-developed countries and that 120 million <strong>of</strong> those work full time<br />

hours.(7) In the United States, the more common problem concerning children and the struggle<br />

around the working day is the forced separation <strong>of</strong> parents and children as parents work<br />

long hours and multiple jobs to provide for their families. This situation violates the bounds<br />

<strong>of</strong> the working day as set forth by Marx even though the children are not laborers. <strong>The</strong> moral<br />

bound is violated because the child is deprived <strong>of</strong> the nurturing and moral needs that only a<br />

parent can provide as well as the physical care-taking or physiological bound that children<br />

do not receive from a parent who works multiple jobs and longs hours. <strong>The</strong>se bounds are<br />

not broken as a result <strong>of</strong> the child working, but because the parent overworks.<br />

Parents overworking, and having less time to spend with their children, takes a similar<br />

toll on society as does child labor. In many homes in the US, both parents work outside<br />

<strong>of</strong> the home, being forced to neglect parental responsibilities in order to meet the financial<br />

requirements placed on them by the capitalist market. One <strong>of</strong> the big issues with children<br />

and manufacturing was their physical deterioration. <strong>The</strong>re was an enormous mortality rate<br />

during the <strong>first</strong> few years <strong>of</strong> their lives for children whose parents where operators. <strong>The</strong> high<br />

death rates were principally due to the employment <strong>of</strong> the mothers away from their homes<br />

and to the neglect and maltreatment <strong>of</strong> her children because <strong>of</strong> her absence. Other causes<br />

were malnourishment and unsuitable food. This estrangement that families experience from<br />

working all the time creates an unhealthy environment for a mother and her children. <strong>The</strong><br />

chronic separation <strong>of</strong> parent and child not only saddens a parent, it also has a negative effect<br />

upon children. Children are left at daycare centers where they receive inferior care; and<br />

nationwide, children come home to an empty house, leaving them without supervision. Lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> proper parenting as a result <strong>of</strong> financial necessity leads to gang activity, drug abuse, and a<br />

substandard education.<br />

If left unchecked, capitalism’s insatiable need to maximize pr<strong>of</strong>its by employing child<br />

labor and working men and women beyond their natural limits will result in the decimation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the very workforce upon which they rely. Ironically, in order for capitalism to survive,<br />

measures are required to protect it from its own avarice by insuring that men, women and<br />

children are treated fairly and not required to labor under a system that unjustly enriches the<br />

lives <strong>of</strong> some while destroying the lives <strong>of</strong> others.<br />

References:<br />

1. Bertrand Russell, THE IMPACT <strong>of</strong> SCIENCE on SOCIETY, p.31.<br />

2. Capital,Volume 1 1887, 304:3-305:1<br />

3. 1833 Factory Act, http://www.nationalarchives.gov.uk/education/lesson13.htm<br />

4. Capital, 341:2<br />

5. Capital, 380:1-381:0<br />

6. Annotations, Chapter 10.2, pg 486<br />

7. http://info.worldbank.org/etools/docs/library/237384/toolkitfr/pdf/facts.pdf<br />

Hans: Very good. I like your comparison with today where small children do not have to work but are deprived <strong>of</strong><br />

their parents because the working-time for the parents is too long.<br />

334 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by ANK is [740], Next Message by DMorris is [908], Next Message by Deadfamous is [724], Next<br />

Message by JSmits is [715], and Next Message by Kraken is [719].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 669 is 483 in 2002fa, 522 in 2005fa, 571 in 2007SP, 606 in 2009fa, 689 in<br />

2011fa, and 718 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 669 Explain how an excessive lengthening <strong>of</strong> the work day decreases the rate <strong>of</strong><br />

surplus-value.<br />

[660] Kobe: Lengthening <strong>of</strong> the work day. <strong>The</strong> extension and lengthening <strong>of</strong> the workday<br />

caused by capitalist production will eventually lead to the destruction <strong>of</strong> the labor-power<br />

which sustains capital. Extension <strong>of</strong> the workday cripples human labor-power as well as<br />

causing an early ending <strong>of</strong> this labor-power itself. This is caused by a lack <strong>of</strong> physical conditions<br />

such as sleep and nutrition as well as what may be morally accepted. This not only<br />

holds true for human labor but as well as machinery, land, etc. Capitalist production therefore<br />

gets the most out <strong>of</strong> a laborer in a certain period <strong>of</strong> time but shortens the laborer’s life<br />

time <strong>of</strong> work. As this happens the rate <strong>of</strong> reproduction <strong>of</strong> labor power will steadily increase,<br />

resulting in the long term <strong>of</strong> creating greater expenses. By shortening the laborer’s working<br />

lifetime it may lead to a short term increase in production but over the length <strong>of</strong> the laborer’s<br />

working time, also the long term, it is a financially costly mistake. This example must also<br />

take into account that human laborers as well as machinery may decline in production at<br />

different times, in which the capitalist has no exact way <strong>of</strong> knowing when the production<br />

will slow. Due to this disproportionality the overuse <strong>of</strong> labor-power decreases the rate <strong>of</strong><br />

surplus-value.<br />

Message [660] referenced by [661]. Next Message by Kobe is [722].<br />

[661] Jon: Do longer days really mean more surplus? When <strong>first</strong> looking at this question<br />

one would think that if the capitalist receives the surplus labor then the best <strong>thing</strong> to<br />

do would be to extend the work day to absorb more labor. Upon a deeper look into this it<br />

becomes clear that this is not the case. From time to time it would be very possible to work<br />

what we call overtime to get the surplus labor during peak days <strong>of</strong> business or harvest. <strong>The</strong><br />

problem however comes up when the extended hours becomes a regular <strong>thing</strong>. Footnote 73<br />

on page 376:1/o <strong>of</strong> Capital says that “over-hours ... certainly tend prematurely to exhaust<br />

the working power <strong>of</strong> the men.” In the end the capitalist extends the worker’s production<br />

time within a period <strong>of</strong> time but at the expense <strong>of</strong> shortening his life, therefore decreasing<br />

the overall surplus <strong>of</strong> labor or value in the long run.<br />

Hans: In substance you are covering only a subset <strong>of</strong> what Kobe [660] covered, but you are setting up your<br />

argument differently and you are formulating it much better.<br />

Message [661] referenced by [663]. Next Message by Jon is [699].<br />

[663] Husani: I agree with Jon in [661] that the lifespan and overall productivity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

individual worker would diminish significantly over a long period if required to be overworked<br />

on a regular basis. But while reading this a thought came to mind. <strong>The</strong> passage<br />

I found interesting was what Marx says about what the slave owner does if he uses his<br />

slave/capital to its maximum. Marx says that “the slave-owner buys his laborer as he buys<br />

his horse. If he loses his slave, he loses his capital that can only be restored by new outlay in<br />

the slave-mart.” Although we aren’t necessarily talking about slave labor we can reference<br />

this to the capitalist who agrees to employ free workers. If we look at the Midwestern


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 335<br />

United States over the past 50 years we realize that farmers are leaving these rural areas to<br />

find jobs in urban areas. If a capitalist were allowed to work his capital to its full extent and<br />

diminish its lifespan to gain its surplus value in a shorter span, then the worker could utilize<br />

the newcomers to the area. Many <strong>thing</strong>s would have to fall in place for this to be achieved<br />

but I found it to be an interesting idea.<br />

Message [663] referenced by [683]. Next Message by Husani is [681].<br />

[672] Scholar: An excessive lengthening <strong>of</strong> the workday decreases the rate <strong>of</strong> surplusvalue<br />

because the value <strong>of</strong> labor power, which is also the variable costs that capitalists have to<br />

pay out, include not only necessity <strong>of</strong> workers themselves, but also the costs <strong>of</strong> reproduction<br />

<strong>of</strong> the labor force.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is a limitation <strong>of</strong> the human biology, if workers be forced to work excessively,<br />

the labor force <strong>of</strong> them will be exhausted much sooner, and so it will need their <strong>of</strong>fspring<br />

growing sooner to replace them. That means more costs would be needed to afford the<br />

sustaining <strong>of</strong> the supply <strong>of</strong> labor force, because the same production need more generations<br />

to participate. If so, the variable costs <strong>of</strong> the capitalist will rise much more than the surplus<br />

value that produced during the excessive lengthening time <strong>of</strong> workers, so the rate surplusvalue<br />

will decrease.<br />

Hans: I like your formulation “the same production need more generations to participate.” US Americans avoid<br />

talking about death directly, and this is a good way to phrase the issue.<br />

Next Message by Scholar is [717].<br />

[683] Hans: Workplace Health and Retirement Costs. All answers are correct as far as<br />

Marx goes, but you are not fully aware <strong>of</strong> the differences between Marx’s time and today.<br />

At Marx’s time, factories were murderous. Life expectancy <strong>of</strong> factory workers was 35 years.<br />

People worked until they died. Increasing their lifetime was in the long-term interest <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist class, because it decreased the reproduction cost <strong>of</strong> the laborer. Today most people<br />

work until retirement. Unhealthy work conditions do therefore not create a labor shortage,<br />

and increasing their lifetimes beyond retirement age is not in the interest <strong>of</strong> the capitalists.<br />

See [2008fa:1072]. (Perhaps it’s not an accident that today’s work conditions are just healthy<br />

enough that people can survive until 65 but not longer.)<br />

Also at Marx’s time, mechanization <strong>of</strong> agriculture and the elimination <strong>of</strong> small farms<br />

was in full swing. This created a big influx <strong>of</strong> labor-seeking farmers into the cities. This is<br />

why the capitalists could set up their factories as slaughterhouses without creating a labor<br />

shortage. Although the exodus from the farms is still continuing, so few farms are left that<br />

in relation to the labor market it is a trickle. This is my response to [663].<br />

Message [683] referenced by [1041]. Next Message by Hans is [690].<br />

[1023] Alex: graded A An excessive increment <strong>of</strong> the work day returns unfavorable for<br />

the capitalists for many reasons. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> reason is that lengthening the work day would<br />

cause the worker to work at a slower pace since he/she becomes more tired after the normal<br />

hours worked, and thus making him/her less efficient in production. In the long-term, if<br />

this was regularly implemented, the workers would become more worn out and will die<br />

faster. Increasing the work time would also cause the capitalists to pay more wages to the<br />

worker (extra hours, even if it’s at the same rate), while the worker is less productive. All<br />

these events cause the surplus-value to decrease for the capitalists. If the capitalist wants a<br />

surplus-value increase then the smart option would be to increase the labor <strong>of</strong> the worker<br />

336 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

throughout the day, that way the laborer would be working harder for the same amount <strong>of</strong><br />

pay.<br />

Hans: Doesn’t your argument that the worker gets tired apply to more intense labor too?<br />

Message [1023] referenced by [1149] and [2012fa:1007]. Next Message by Alex is [1053].<br />

[1041] AM: <strong>The</strong> excessive lengthening <strong>of</strong> the work day decreases the rate <strong>of</strong> surplus-value<br />

because at a certain point in the work day the laborer is no longer productive. If the work<br />

day is increased excessively the laborer loses his ability to work (i.e. succumbing to lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> sleep and hunger). <strong>The</strong> capitalist cannot provide the means for the laborers to replenish<br />

their reserves. It makes sense then, as Hans writes in [683] it is in the long term interest <strong>of</strong><br />

the capitalist to keep the work day length reasonable. In doing so the capitalist can keep the<br />

same laborers for a greater overall length <strong>of</strong> time; as the cost <strong>of</strong> replacing the laborer would<br />

be higher. Besides, the laborer has no obligation to work himself to death to satisfy any one<br />

else’s needs; though I am sure that the capitalist would love it if this were true. Most laborers<br />

(as I do) probably fantasize about how they will use what energy they have left after work<br />

(i.e. hobbies, sports, etc. . . ).<br />

Message [1041] referenced by [1149]. Next Message by AM is [1042].<br />

[1117] Milly: graded A Lengthening the work day means decrease in surplus-value.<br />

Marx discusses that workers need rest to regain health and strength away from work each<br />

day. <strong>The</strong> answer to this question can be found in Capital on page 376:1/o “Capitalist production,<br />

which is essentially the production <strong>of</strong> surplus-value, produces thus, with the extension<br />

<strong>of</strong> the working-day, not only the stunting <strong>of</strong> human labor-power by robbing it <strong>of</strong> its normal<br />

and physical conditions <strong>of</strong> development and function. It produces also the premature<br />

exhaustion and destruction <strong>of</strong> this labor-power itself. It extends the laborer’s time <strong>of</strong> production<br />

during a given period by shortening his overall life-time.” Because <strong>of</strong> human limitations<br />

surplus-value would decrease with excessive lengthening <strong>of</strong> the work day.<br />

First Message by Milly is [143].<br />

[1125] Guh: Labor Surplus. In the reading Marx talks about how in capitalism, the<br />

individuals doing the work/labor have a production that is owned by the capitalist. By this,<br />

the individuals doing the work, (the workers) are now treated as if they are machines that<br />

produce pr<strong>of</strong>its for the capitalist. Furthermore, the workers now have a correlation with<br />

machines, in the example from Zone [2005fa:1144] “<strong>The</strong> human machine requires food and<br />

rest instead <strong>of</strong> oil and grease for maintenance. Unlike machines the worker deteriorates at a<br />

different level than machines. Marx states in Value, Price, and Pr<strong>of</strong>it, ‘Man on the contrary<br />

decays in a greater ratio than would visible from the mere numerical addition <strong>of</strong> work.’”<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, by using this example, and what Marx states, the workers are treated unfairly and<br />

thus do not have the time to rest between work days and results in a worker’s surplus labor<br />

decreases, which is not in the best interest for the capitalist. Another great example <strong>of</strong> this is<br />

from Pele [2007SP:763] “Basically, by extending the worker’s work day, they are not only<br />

less efficient, but the long term use (exploitation) <strong>of</strong> the worker is shortened. Having an<br />

individual work 120 hour work weeks for a decade to die at 30 will result in less labor power<br />

and capital production than a worker who is exploited for 60 years on a 40 hour work week.<br />

Thus the lengthening <strong>of</strong> the work-day costs the capitalist a large amount <strong>of</strong> surplus value, by<br />

making the worker less efficient, and wearing out the human machine in production.”<br />

Next Message by Guh is [1196].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 337<br />

[1137] Cougar: graded C To begin, surplus value is the value created by laborers after the<br />

socially necessary labor time has been fulfilled in producing a commodity. This additional<br />

labor or added value is not accounted for when laborers are compensated. In a shorter work<br />

day, a laborer will be less fatigued at its conclusion. He or she is then theoretically able<br />

to work more efficiently during the next day, producing more in less time. <strong>The</strong>refore, it<br />

is possible to achieve greater output in a shorter overall workday. On the contrary, longer<br />

work days cause increased fatigue <strong>of</strong> laborers resulting in diminished productivity. For this<br />

reason more time may be required to produce the desired outcome <strong>of</strong> the capitalist, possibly<br />

affecting the socially necessary labor time <strong>of</strong> that commodity. In the case that the socially<br />

necessary labor time is increased for a commodity due to fatigue and diminished productivity<br />

<strong>of</strong> longer work days, the capitalist is actually losing surplus value. If workers are able<br />

to work more efficiently and undercut the socially necessary labor time, the capitalist is<br />

then able to take advantage <strong>of</strong> surplus labor value above and beyond socially acceptable<br />

requirements. It is in the best interest <strong>of</strong> the capitalist to promote more efficient labor through<br />

shorter work days and therefore increase his surplus labor value, which results in increased<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its only.<br />

Hans: What Marx calls necessary labor in chapter Ten is not the same as his concept <strong>of</strong> socially necessary labor<br />

in chapter One. You explain pr<strong>of</strong>it by production at a rate that is faster than the socially necessary labor-time.<br />

Marx has a different explanation <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its, which at <strong>first</strong> may seem unintuitive. On the one hand, producing more<br />

products more efficiently does not produce more value. Secondly, even if every single producer uses exactly the<br />

socially necessary labor time, Marx says that there is still pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Next Message by Cougar is [1145].<br />

[1149] Cougar: graded B Let me omit what is wrong and focus on what is right. As<br />

has been touched on by many intelligent responses to this question, workers cannot work<br />

indefinitely: <strong>The</strong>y require rest and rejuvenation. Of course it makes sense to shorten the<br />

work day. Not only will workers be thrilled to have more hours <strong>of</strong> the day to themselves, but<br />

they will have more energy reserved for the next day’s efforts. After reading Alex [1023]<br />

and AM’s [1041] responses this semester, I finally understand that the long term effects are<br />

just as pertinent as the short. Re-hiring and training new labor is expensive and less efficient<br />

as new labor must learn and develop on a curve. It is in the capitalist’s interest to keep the<br />

laborers he already has strong and healthy if he is concerned with his long-term success. In<br />

addition, longer days costs the capitalist more in wages but after a certain time, the labor<br />

falls in productivity due to fatigue: more money spent for less output! Again, the capitalist<br />

needs efficient and loyal labor that he can depend on for the future rather than spending<br />

funds on hiring and training. By pushing his laborers to work harder in shorter days, he<br />

receives more productive labor in lest time which means less wages and higher pr<strong>of</strong>its. If I<br />

understand correctly, it is this formula that leads the capitalist to surplus labor.<br />

Hans: You still don’t understand right. <strong>The</strong> formula for surplus-labor is paying a wage which is far less than the<br />

value created by the workers.<br />

First Message by Cougar is [1].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 677 is 506 in 2002fa, 524 in 2003fa, 577 in 2004fa, 529 in 2005fa, 578 in<br />

2007SP, 573 in 2007fa, 581 in 2008SP, 585 in 2008fa, 614 in 2009fa, 697 in 2011fa, and<br />

726 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 677 According to Marx, the only way to increase pr<strong>of</strong>its is to shorten the portion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the day during which the workers produce an equivalent <strong>of</strong> their wage, and to extend<br />

338 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

that portion <strong>of</strong> the day when they create unreimbursed new value for the capitalist. Are the<br />

capitalists aware <strong>of</strong> it that all their cost cutting measures, if successful, go at the expense <strong>of</strong><br />

their workers?<br />

[694] Tyler: Cost cutting for laborers. In considering a response to this question I read<br />

the response <strong>of</strong> Steveeggett [2008fa:994] which clarifies the issue. Similar to Steveeggett,<br />

I too originally thought capitalists must know that all their cost cutting measures occur at<br />

the expense <strong>of</strong> their workers, but realize many capitalists are unaware <strong>of</strong> the effects <strong>of</strong> their<br />

cost cutting measures. Hans [2009fa:729] discusses one scenario where new technology,<br />

such as a machine, will have its value determined ultimately by the worker. Capitalists in<br />

this example may erroneously believe that they are not impacting their employees through<br />

the purchase <strong>of</strong> new machinery, but it is always the worker who in the end must operate<br />

the machinery. <strong>The</strong> laborer will always absorb the effects <strong>of</strong> the capitalists’ cost cutting<br />

techniques.<br />

Next Message by Tyler is [917].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 679 is 580 in 2007SP, 575 in 2007fa, 587 in 2008fa, 616 in 2009fa, 699 in<br />

2011fa, and 728 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 679 Turgot wrote: “In every kind <strong>of</strong> labor, it must happen, and it does in fact happen,<br />

that the wage <strong>of</strong> the worker is limited to what he needs to secure his own subsistence.”<br />

Why is this so? Is this still valid today?<br />

[691] Lana: <strong>The</strong> unfortunate laughability <strong>of</strong> minimum wage. <strong>The</strong> capitalist does not<br />

wish to pay the worker any more than what is absolutely necessary and what is mandated<br />

by law. <strong>The</strong> capitalist may try to portray himself with humane characteristics but really, he<br />

is completely motivated by accumulation and has no urge to pay the worker any more than<br />

the bare minimum for his survival. His motivation is pr<strong>of</strong>it for his interests (personal gain,<br />

investors, etc), not the betterment <strong>of</strong> his employees.<br />

This is where I feel minimum wage comes into play. <strong>The</strong> minimum wage is the lowest<br />

wage that an employer is permitted to pay by law or union contract. Some have argued that it<br />

decreases poverty while the opposition claims that it increases unemployment. Regardless,<br />

the minimum wage is going against Turgot’s model. It does not sustain life for the normal<br />

person. I am from the Big Island <strong>of</strong> Hawaii and I can say <strong>first</strong> hand, that the minimum<br />

wage <strong>of</strong> $7.25 an hour is a cruel joke. <strong>The</strong> cost <strong>of</strong> living in the state is one <strong>of</strong> the highest in<br />

the country, with a gallon <strong>of</strong> milk reaching $9, a studio apartment being rented for around<br />

$1000 a month plus exorbinant utilities, and $5 a gallon <strong>of</strong> gasoline. One cannot subsist on<br />

the minimum wage in Hawaii.<br />

So how do people do it? I know families who rent out a three-bedroom home and fit<br />

fifteen family members in it. <strong>The</strong>y work two to three jobs and do not have the extra funds or<br />

free time to take care <strong>of</strong> their mental and physical health. Enrollment in unemployment and<br />

welfare programs are some <strong>of</strong> the highest in the country, credit card debt is accumulated to<br />

simply buy groceries, and there is extensive “brain drain” in the communities.<br />

<strong>The</strong> concept that the capitalist is paying the worker enough to subsist is not valid.<br />

Hans: Eloquent and moving, but how does Marx explain this outrage? Why are wages so low if the workers are<br />

the creators <strong>of</strong> all value and there is so much wealth in society?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 339<br />

Message [691] referenced by [704] and [2012fa:1003]. Next Message by Lana is [921].<br />

[704] GoUtes: Response to Lana. I agree that as Lana [691] stated, the Capitalist wants<br />

to pay the least amount possible to the laborer, he is interested in what he can do to get the<br />

most amount <strong>of</strong> work out <strong>of</strong> a laborer for the least possible cost. So I do agree with the<br />

idea that the capitalist will do what they can to keep wages as low as possible. Answering<br />

the question whether the concept is valid today, I think that most people have a different<br />

view on the amount <strong>of</strong> money they need to live and the amount <strong>of</strong> money they need to live<br />

comfortably. <strong>The</strong>se are two different issues.<br />

Next Message by GoUtes is [726].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 683 is 203 in 1995WI, 210 in 1995ut, 232 in 1996sp, 232 in 1996ut, 285 in<br />

1997WI, 350 in 1997sp, 349 in 1997ut, 359 in 1998WI, 360 in 1999SP, 472 in 2001fa, 511<br />

in 2002fa, 529 in 2003fa, 582 in 2004fa, 535 in 2005fa, 584 in 2007SP, 591 in 2008fa,<br />

703 in 2011fa, 732 in 2012fa, and 683 in Answer:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 683 What is relative surplus-value? Which mechanisms, that were so far<br />

taken as given, affect the magnitude <strong>of</strong> relative surplus-value?<br />

[687] Giant: (graded B) Is surplus value worth it? Relative surplus-value according<br />

to Marx does not have to do with the lengthening <strong>of</strong> workers’ hours to increase capitalist<br />

surplus value. <strong>The</strong> surplus-value comes from increasing the productivity level <strong>of</strong> workers<br />

by shortening the amount <strong>of</strong> work time to create a product (the overall workday hours stay<br />

the same). If a worker normally makes one chair an hour, they could now (with the help <strong>of</strong><br />

machinery) make two chairs an hour. In my example the surplus-value impact would vary<br />

depending on whether one company has machines to help lower their costs <strong>of</strong> production, or<br />

if the entire chair industry used machinery power to produce chairs (lowering the cost <strong>of</strong> the<br />

product overall—not giving any one company an advantage to create surplus pr<strong>of</strong>its).<br />

<strong>The</strong> other condition for surplus-value would depend on whether there was enough demand<br />

for the product to create surplus pr<strong>of</strong>its. If there is not enough demand when just one<br />

company has machines they could lose money by having to invest in machines and not be<br />

able to sell enough <strong>of</strong> the product to cover the cost. If the entire industry has machines, then<br />

when demand is down, companies will leave the chair market either to shut down or go into<br />

some other industry. This will make prices higher until there is enough pr<strong>of</strong>it incentive to<br />

make companies stay in the chair market.<br />

Hans: Please look at [Answer:4] and [684].<br />

Message [687] referenced by [Answer:5] and [698]. Next Message by Giant is [695].<br />

[712] Cosmopolita: Relative surplus value is a kind <strong>of</strong> surplus value which is an increase<br />

in the gap between capitalist and laborer. Specifically, in the lengthening <strong>of</strong> the working day,<br />

which is absolute surplus value. <strong>The</strong>re is a corresponding alteration in the respective length<br />

<strong>of</strong> the two components <strong>of</strong> the working day. We can assume a given working day with a given<br />

length and division AC, but the whole line is represented by A——–B—-C, where AB are<br />

10 hours necessary labor, and BC 2 hours <strong>of</strong> surplus labor. A capitalist will wonder how to<br />

increase pr<strong>of</strong>its without the prolongation <strong>of</strong> the line AC; which could be done by prolonging<br />

C to the right but we cannot increase the hours <strong>of</strong> the day, then the capitalist will push back<br />

point B more to the left, to create more surplus labor. But also here there is a limitation.<br />

But then this prolongation would be accompanied by an equal shortening <strong>of</strong> necessary labor,<br />

340 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

because Surplus Value can only increase if necessary labor becomes shorter. But to produce<br />

the same output we need productive workers so the overall equation works.<br />

Mechanisms that were taken as given were the constant working day hours and the<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> labor input, which affected relative surplus value. But then productivity concept<br />

came in effect to come up with following conclusions. As said in [2008fa:790]: Marx<br />

defines it, productivity as the volume <strong>of</strong> use values produced per total labor input. Using<br />

the word productivity for low wages is a commonly used euphemism; Marx would call this<br />

“exploitation”. Also as Hans said in [2008fa:790], the workday is extended, then higher<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its can go along with higher daily wages for workers, which benefits the capitalists and<br />

the labor power.<br />

Hans: Please work on your writing style.<br />

Next Message by Cosmopolita is [739].<br />

Multiple Choice <strong>Question</strong> 684 is 583 in 2004fa:<br />

Multiple Choice <strong>Question</strong> 684 Only one <strong>of</strong> the answers below is fully correct, all other<br />

answers are either wrong or imprecise or not specific to relative surplus-value. Mark the<br />

one which is correct. In a nutshell, relative surplus-value can be characterized as<br />

• (a) Increase in surplus-value because production increases but the number <strong>of</strong> workers<br />

and wages stay the same.<br />

• (b) Increase in surplus-value because production stays the same but wages decrease.<br />

• (c) Increase in surplus-value because higher technology lowers the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

worker’s consumption goods, so that the portion <strong>of</strong> the day the worker works for<br />

himself or herself is shortened.<br />

• (d) Increase in surplus-value because machines take over part <strong>of</strong> the labor.<br />

• (e) A widening <strong>of</strong> the gap between workers and capitalists.<br />

[698] Hans: Relative Surplus-Value. <strong>The</strong> right answer is (c). Here are comments about<br />

the other answers:<br />

(a) If more is produced with the same labor input, then the total value produced remains<br />

the same. At the beginning, the innovating capitalist may be able to charge higher prices<br />

for the more efficiently produced goods. This is called “extra surplus-value.” But over time<br />

prices will fall. <strong>The</strong>refore this alone is not the explanation <strong>of</strong> relative surplus-value. On the<br />

exam this answer will get a C.<br />

(b) This answer is almost correct. But it depends on the reason why wages fall whether<br />

this is relative surplus-value or not. This answer will get a B.<br />

(c) This is the right answer. <strong>The</strong> lowering <strong>of</strong> the values <strong>of</strong> the consumption goods may be<br />

masked by the effect that prices stay the same despite lower values, but the labor content <strong>of</strong><br />

one dollar decreases. This answer will get an A.<br />

(d) In Marx’s theory, machines do not create value or pr<strong>of</strong>its. This answer gets a D.<br />

(e) This is an effect <strong>of</strong> relative surplus-value, but relative surplus-value is not the only<br />

factor widening this gap. This answer gets a C+


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 341<br />

I am sending this because answer [687] to <strong>Question</strong> 683 says some<strong>thing</strong> similar to (a),<br />

i.e., it is wrong.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [701].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 686 is 235 in 1996ut, 361 in 1998WI, 362 in 1999SP, 585 in 2004fa, 538 in<br />

2005fa, and 623 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 686 What does Marx mean by the statement: “<strong>The</strong> general and necessary tendencies<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital must be distinguished from their forms <strong>of</strong> appearance”? Give examples<br />

<strong>of</strong> “general and necessary tendencies <strong>of</strong> capital” and <strong>of</strong> “forms <strong>of</strong> appearance” <strong>of</strong> such<br />

tendencies.<br />

[685] Wolf: I take this statement to mean that in order to better understand the subject<br />

at hand one must look at the deeper structures that express the surface appearance. This is<br />

done all the time in science (e.g. chemistry). It’s too easy to accept reality at face-value and<br />

it does disservice to one’s critical thinking.<br />

Within the context <strong>of</strong> the current readings, “general and necessary tendencies <strong>of</strong> capital”<br />

describes lowering the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power in order to increase surplus-value while the<br />

working day remains constant (a result <strong>of</strong> chapter 10). However, it appears confusing that<br />

a capitalist would lower the price <strong>of</strong> their products in order to lessen the value <strong>of</strong> laborpower<br />

(the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power is “...formed by the value <strong>of</strong> the commodities which have<br />

to be supplied every day to the bearer <strong>of</strong> labor-power, to the human so that he can renew his<br />

life-process” in Capital pg. 276:3/o) because they should not expect every other capitalist to<br />

simultaneously do this same process in order to collectively gain additional surplus-value.<br />

Nevertheless, this is what ultimately must happen in order for the capitalist to remain a<br />

capitalist.<br />

<strong>The</strong> “form <strong>of</strong> appearance” on the other hand is the intention <strong>of</strong> the capitalist to gain<br />

additional surplus-value. When the capitalist potentiates the labor-process with increased<br />

productivity (increased productivity decreases the value <strong>of</strong> the products. <strong>The</strong>re is limited<br />

value and this is spread out amongst the entirety <strong>of</strong> the products. As it increases, the value is<br />

spread thinner and thinner, lessening the overall value <strong>of</strong> the products), s/he does so to gain<br />

extra surplus-value. If you step back and look at all the capitalists attempting to achieve extra<br />

surplus-value, the totality <strong>of</strong> this process is the lessening <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power because<br />

the reproduction <strong>of</strong> labor-power is now cheaper (due to the decreased value <strong>of</strong> necessities).<br />

Marx summed this up as, “He does individually what capital itself does as a whole when<br />

producing relative surplus-value” (Capital pg. 435:1/o). Thus it may appear that the capitalist<br />

is just trying to get ahead <strong>of</strong> the game, but s/he is actually a part <strong>of</strong> a larger process that must<br />

lower the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power generally to increase the relative surplus-value.<br />

Next Message by Wolf is [856].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 688 is 237 in 1996sp, 289 in 1997WI, 354 in 1997sp, 515 in 2002fa, 535 in<br />

2003fa, 588 in 2004fa, 541 in 2005fa, 584 in 2007fa, 592 in 2008SP, 596 in 2008fa, 625<br />

in 2009fa, 708 in 2011fa, and 737 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 688 Why can we gain a scientific understanding <strong>of</strong> “the sphere <strong>of</strong> competition”<br />

only after having grasped the inner nature <strong>of</strong> capital?<br />

342 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[708] Orville: graded A Double or No<strong>thing</strong>. Marx says that we <strong>first</strong> have to understand<br />

capital before we can understand “the sphere <strong>of</strong> competition.” This is simply because you<br />

have to have competition in order for capitalism to work at all. Hans says on page 510<br />

“the competitive motivation <strong>of</strong> the capitalist is not really his own motivation, but this is how<br />

he experiences his subjugation to the laws <strong>of</strong> capital.” This is saying that capitalists don’t<br />

make the rules, they are following them the only way that they can: by being competitive.<br />

Competition drives growth which is the basic doctrine <strong>of</strong> capitalism. While on the surface, it<br />

may seem that only competition is making the people act in the way that they do, capitalism<br />

forces people to become greedy and self-centered in order to be capitalists. It is integral to<br />

understand that the sphere <strong>of</strong> competition is a mask and a driver for the capitalist system. It<br />

is so important that not only is capitalism completely dependent on competition but, as JRH<br />

says in [2002fa:245], “...competition is based on capitalism.”<br />

Next Message by Orville is [730].<br />

[710] TINDOZ: pre-requisite. <strong>The</strong> reason that we can only understand “the sphere <strong>of</strong><br />

competition” after grasping the inner nature <strong>of</strong> capital is because the inner nature <strong>of</strong> capital<br />

is more or less a pre-requisite (to use a term students are all to familiar with) to fully<br />

understanding what the ins and outs <strong>of</strong> competition are and understanding what drives this<br />

competition. <strong>The</strong> question posed uses the term “scientific understanding” which means that<br />

we are not just talking about a surface understanding. In order to have a scientific understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> any<strong>thing</strong>, one must certainly have a strong understanding <strong>of</strong> all pre-requisites.<br />

I’m struggling to find an analogy, but I can’t imagine anyone trying to write a book about<br />

a specific drug’s reaction to the body without <strong>first</strong> having an understanding <strong>of</strong> the human<br />

body, pharmaceuticals, and chemistry. I particularly liked the conceptual similarities that<br />

Marx drew between understanding competition (with needing the pre-requisite <strong>of</strong> an understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> the inner nature <strong>of</strong> capital) and understanding the planets (with the pre-requisites<br />

being an understanding <strong>of</strong> their movements). Marx points out that the movements <strong>of</strong> the<br />

planets aren’t perceivable by our senses, this is also true when trying to understand competition.<br />

Just because you live in a society where capitalism abounds and where firms are<br />

engaging in competition with one another does not mean you will understand it. Merely<br />

being near competition can no more endow you with a scientific understanding <strong>of</strong> it than can<br />

looking up at the night sky and thinking that you can properly perceive all that is going on<br />

just by what your naked eyes see. Indeed, attempting to formulate a “scientific understanding”<br />

<strong>of</strong> the planets without a knowledge <strong>of</strong> their motions brought many (in past centuries) to<br />

think that the earth was the center <strong>of</strong> the universe and was also flat - the same mistakes can<br />

be made when trying to formulate a scientific understanding <strong>of</strong> the sphere <strong>of</strong> competition<br />

without understanding the inner nature <strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

Next Message by TINDOZ is [739].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 690 is 205 in 1995WI, 238 in 1996sp, 237 in 1996ut, 290 in 1997WI, 355 in<br />

1997sp, 354 in 1997ut, 363 in 1998WI, 364 in 1999SP, 477 in 2001fa, 516 in 2002fa, 536<br />

in 2003fa, 590 in 2004fa, 543 in 2005fa, 596 in 2007SP, 586 in 2007fa, 598 in 2008fa,<br />

627 in 2009fa, 710 in 2011fa, 739 in 2012fa, and 690 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 690 Do the workers after introduction <strong>of</strong> new machinery produce more value per<br />

hour?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 343<br />

[681] Husani: After the introduction <strong>of</strong> machinery or a technology that helps to increase<br />

efficiency, the worker will produce the same value. I will <strong>first</strong> create a situation similar<br />

to what Marx brought up in the chapter. We have a factory that employs individuals who<br />

produce twelve shirts in a working day which happens to be twelve hours. One shirt per hour<br />

happens to be the socially necessary time to produce a shirt. Let’s assume that the worker is<br />

paid $1 per day and the means <strong>of</strong> production cost $1 as well. This means that on the open<br />

market one shirt will cost $2 because that is the total value that has gone into its production.<br />

Now let’s assume that the owner <strong>of</strong> the factory discovers a new technology that allows his<br />

workers to produce shirts in half the time. <strong>The</strong> workers can now make 24 shirts instead <strong>of</strong><br />

12 with one day <strong>of</strong> labor so half <strong>of</strong> one hours wage will go into the production <strong>of</strong> each shirt,<br />

$.50, but the means <strong>of</strong> production remains at $1 per shirt so the value <strong>of</strong> the shirt will actually<br />

decrease to $1.50 from $2. But if the factory owner can somehow keep this technology a<br />

secret, he will be able to utilize the market price to obtain surplus value from the sale <strong>of</strong><br />

his shirts. Every other producer <strong>of</strong> shirts still sells them for $2, but because he is producing<br />

twice as many shirts as before he must increase demand for his shirts. What this means is<br />

that he will sell them for a lower price. He will find a point between $1.50 and $2 so people<br />

will buy from him and not his competitors but he will still gain more surplus value from this<br />

because the actual value <strong>of</strong> his shirts is now $1.50.<br />

With an increase in efficiency that allows the worker to produce more shirts in one hour,<br />

the overall value <strong>of</strong> his work will remain the same. We remember that each shirt requires<br />

$1 <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production, no matter how many shirts he makes in one hour; they still<br />

each require this amount. <strong>The</strong> only change is in relation to how his labor is spread about<br />

the different shirts. <strong>The</strong> more he produces, the more the money is spread out to different<br />

products. In this example, one shirt holds $1 <strong>of</strong> labor before the technology is applied and it<br />

holds $.50 after. But in the entire hour, two shirts hold $1 <strong>of</strong> labor. This would continue for<br />

every increase in efficiency. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> his labor will always be $1 in an hour, no matter<br />

how many shirts he produces.<br />

Hans: Your calculation assumes that the value created by labor is the same as the wage cost. This is a mistake<br />

which should no longer happen at this stage <strong>of</strong> the class. It is a centerpiece <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory that workers produce<br />

more value than they get reimbursed as wages. This is why capitalists can sell their products at a price which is<br />

higher than their cost and get a pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Message [681] referenced by [692] and [695]. Next Message by Husani is [720].<br />

[692] Guh: Value Per Hour. In the readings, Marx talks about how the creation and<br />

introduction <strong>of</strong> a new machine, and how it does not create more value per hour. Moreover,<br />

according Casio [2004fa:557.15] “<strong>The</strong>re will be initial gains in the early stages <strong>of</strong> adapting<br />

the technology due to the rise in productivity but those gains will be competed away once<br />

the new technology becomes standard.” Hans also clarifies this in [2001fa:320] “Value is<br />

a social relation which ties people’s labor processes together, therefore only people can<br />

produce value, machines can’t.” So thus even in the beginning stages and use <strong>of</strong> the machine,<br />

the surplus value that is created from the machine, will have been derived from the labour <strong>of</strong><br />

the worker, and not the machine itself.<br />

Hans: Very good. I tried to explain every<strong>thing</strong> in detail in [Answer:6]. My only quibble: you should have said<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> about Husani’s previous answer [681]. This answer made a basic mistake which should have been<br />

corrected immediately.<br />

Next Message by Guh is [699].<br />

344 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[695] Giant: I agree with Husani’s assessment in [681] that the workers’ value does not<br />

increase (in your example). I do believe that there is another possibility for this situation.<br />

Since a company hires as few workers as possible to complete the product, work can only be<br />

spread out so far in a company and not all that work can be done by machines. If a machine<br />

can replace one or two workers, then the workers that are left do have increased value since<br />

they can do what the machines can’t (like fix machines that are broken).<br />

Hans: Yes, speedup is another implication <strong>of</strong> new technology, see [701]. But you referred to Husani without<br />

catching an important error he committed.<br />

Next Message by Giant is [763].<br />

[700] SMIKEC: Given the social relation <strong>of</strong> value, a worker could not produce more per<br />

hour just because <strong>of</strong> a new piece <strong>of</strong> equipment. <strong>The</strong> new piece <strong>of</strong> machinery would not<br />

change the worker’s schedule <strong>of</strong> labor (hours worked), therefore value could not change.<br />

<strong>The</strong>n you ask why would the capitalist even buy new equipment for her company? <strong>The</strong><br />

capitalist has to be leading edge to see any gains from it, be the <strong>first</strong> one on the street<br />

who has the new equipment in the market. For this short time until everyone else has the<br />

technology, she has a leading edge advantage in regards to technology and efficiencies. This<br />

upside potential is generally short lived, because competing companies catch on quick that<br />

in order to sustain against the leading technology based capitalist, they need the same tools<br />

to have a level playing field, hence where the new equipment comes into play.<br />

Next Message by SMIKEC is [713].<br />

[703] Kaush: Workers and machinery. No, workers do not produce more value per hour<br />

after the introduction <strong>of</strong> new machinery. What happens when a new method <strong>of</strong> production is<br />

introduced, the total value <strong>of</strong> production stays the same while the value per unit decreases.<br />

This outcome contradicts the capitalist’s intention <strong>of</strong> producing more surplus-value, where<br />

he instead ends up creating more products and wealth.<br />

Hans: You are repeating one <strong>of</strong> the <strong>thing</strong>s already said in the discussion, but the previous discussion touched on<br />

several other aspects, which you simply ignored. I tried to summarize it all in [Answer:6].<br />

Next Message by Kaush is [731].<br />

[832] Kaimani: Machinery doesn’t equal more value. No, the workers don’t produce<br />

more value after the introduction <strong>of</strong> new machinery. Productivity has increased but manual<br />

labor stays the same and in some causes even drops because the machines are able to do most<br />

<strong>of</strong> the load to produce the commodity. With that being said Marx states the value produced<br />

in the production doesn’t increase.<br />

Commodities are valued and measured by the social value that it creates. Machinery<br />

allows the capitalist to expand his market on a broader scale and thereby create more surplusvalue<br />

or wealth. Entering the bigger market the capitialist must double the demand and the<br />

production to meet the needs <strong>of</strong> the new market and to <strong>of</strong>fset the cost <strong>of</strong> production for one<br />

working day.<br />

By demand <strong>of</strong> the market the capitalist will become an “innovator” and lower the “price”<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity in order to “squeeze” out the remaining pr<strong>of</strong>it from the commmodity. <strong>The</strong><br />

reason for this is that the capitalist wants to make as much gain as he can and keep whatever<br />

excess that he can. This helps wilth the increased output <strong>of</strong> the product.<br />

Message [832] referenced by [834]. Next Message by Kaimani is [854].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 345<br />

[834] Hans: A sheep trying on wolf’s clothes: quickly found out. Reading Kaimani’s<br />

[832] I almost feel I am cheating because Marxism has such a simple explanation. Marx<br />

simply declares categorically that only labor creates value. Labor using machines does not<br />

create any more value per hour than labor not using machines. So the answer is simply “no.”<br />

Kaimani’s <strong>first</strong> paragraph stays in Marx’s paradigm. But then it seems as if buyer’s remorse<br />

set in. Kaimani does not quite know if he can trust the Marxists. Maybe he should<br />

better slip in the adjective “social”? Can’t hurt, can it, after all Marx keeps stressing that<br />

value is a social relation. Kaimani writes:<br />

Commodities are valued and measured by the social value that it creates.<br />

This is an awkward sentence. Maybe he meant<br />

Labor is valued and measured by the social value that it creates.<br />

But this is no longer Marx. In Marx’s theory, labor is not valued by some<strong>thing</strong> outside<br />

labor, some<strong>thing</strong> called “social value,” but labor itself is the measuring stick.<br />

Next, Karmani eases us from the concept <strong>of</strong> “social value” to “wealth”. And the word<br />

“surplus” sounds like abundance. <strong>The</strong>refore he writes:<br />

Machinary allows the capitalist to expand his market on a more broader<br />

scale and thereby create more surplus-value or wealth.<br />

Aha, the capitalist creates surplus-value with his machines. Now we can sleep well again,<br />

no fear that the angry proletarians will come after the capitalists. And the word “surplusvalue”<br />

makes sure that Marx is satisfied as well.<br />

A Marxist would say here: wealth is use-value, and more use-value does not always mean<br />

more value. This is one <strong>of</strong> the deep contradictions <strong>of</strong> the value concept.<br />

I’ll stop here. <strong>The</strong> lesson is that Marxian and neoclassical theories are very different.<br />

Trying to reformulate Marx until your neoclassical inner voice is satisfied is not a good idea.<br />

Tell that neoclassical voice to shut up, otherwise you will jeoparize your exam grade.<br />

Message [834] referenced by [919]. Next Message by Hans is [841].<br />

[856] Wolf: Workers do not create more value per hour with new machinery unless it takes<br />

more intense labor to produce with the new machinery. If the same amount <strong>of</strong> expended labor<br />

is used to make the products, then no additional value is being created because machines do<br />

not and cannot create value. If there is increased productivity, the value would be spread<br />

thinner among the products resulting in extra surplus-value immediately and cheaper laborpower<br />

generally as this productivity change happens throughout the entirety <strong>of</strong> the market<br />

over time.<br />

Hans: Your resubmission had: “unless it takes more labor to create the products than before,” I replaced this with<br />

your in-class formulation mentioning intense labor. Of course, I understand why you changed it. You can have<br />

more intense labor and still less labor if the intense labor is for a shorter duration. Still I wanted to make the point<br />

that machinery can get higher value out <strong>of</strong> the worker due to higher intensity, but not due to a more efficiently<br />

produced output.<br />

Next Message by Wolf is [857].<br />

346 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[866] PLG: graded A Initially the introduction <strong>of</strong> new machinery will bring a firm extra<br />

surplus-value in production. <strong>The</strong> laborer will produce more value per hour initially while<br />

the economy is in disequilibrium, and the company has a relative advantage over other companies.<br />

However, this will become relative surplus-value once other companies adopt the<br />

new technology. Output will increase, but the workers are not creating more value per hour.<br />

Value is determined socially. Thus it is a qualitative factor in which the value can only increase<br />

if a worker is producing more, relative to other workers. Machines never create value.<br />

Value is always labor derived.<br />

As Hans states in [2007fa:402] “value is a society wide cost category. I.e., <strong>thing</strong>s have<br />

high value if their cost to society is high, and <strong>thing</strong>s have low value if it is low.” If everyone<br />

adopts the same technology then there is no increase in labor value per hour. Thus the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> production is separate from total output. An increase in output does not mean an increase<br />

in labor value per hour.<br />

Hans: You haven’t explained how it becomes relative surplus-value (but on the other hand the question has also<br />

not asked you to explain this).<br />

Next Message by PLG is [867].<br />

[876] Oreo: graded A– Workers, after the introduction <strong>of</strong> new machinery, do not produce<br />

more value per hour. New machinery will speed up the process <strong>of</strong> production and cause<br />

commodities to be produced with less human labor time. <strong>The</strong>y will therefore contain a<br />

smaller about <strong>of</strong> congealed human labor than they did prior to the new machinery. So instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> making 5 products an hour at $100 each, laborers are now able to produce 10 products in<br />

an hour. However, the product’s decreased labor time may cause the product to now only be<br />

worth $50. <strong>The</strong>refore, each labor hour still produces $500 <strong>of</strong> value. <strong>The</strong> value per hour has<br />

not changed. In summary, while the commodity’s value has gone down, the value per hour<br />

will not increase or decrease, it will remain the same.<br />

Hans: A full answer to this question must also discuss extra surplus-value.<br />

Next Message by Oreo is [951].<br />

[904] Proletarian: graded A No, workers do not produce more value per hour after the<br />

introduction <strong>of</strong> machinery. While they may produce more commodities per hour, the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> the commodities is lower, though the overall value produced is unchanged.<br />

By definition, machines do not create value. Value comes only from congealed human<br />

labor. So, say it takes one hour for a worker to make one shirt. That shirt contains one hour<br />

<strong>of</strong> congealed human labor and one unit <strong>of</strong> value. If a machine is introduced that allows the<br />

worker to make two shirts per hour, then each shirt has 1/2 hour congealed labor therein and<br />

hence has only half the value as it would have prior to the introduction <strong>of</strong> machinery into the<br />

production process.<br />

<strong>The</strong> capitalist may be able to extract some benefit from the improved efficiency afforded<br />

them by the machine. Since they are able to produce shirts more efficiently than their competitors<br />

because they have a machine that their competitors don’t, the capitalist with the<br />

machine can produce shirts with less labor than socially necessary. However, the technology<br />

<strong>of</strong> the machinery (or some other technology that will allow production at the rate <strong>of</strong> the <strong>first</strong><br />

capitalist) will make its way to the other shirt makers, and the socially required labor time<br />

required for the manufacture <strong>of</strong> a shirt will equal the amount <strong>of</strong> labor required to manufacture<br />

a shirt using the machinery. <strong>The</strong>refore, while the capitalist may have a short-term gain


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 347<br />

from the machine, it is only temporary. <strong>The</strong> reason that the gain is temporary is because the<br />

machine does not produce value, only human labor produces value.<br />

Next Message by Proletarian is [1074].<br />

[913] JJ: No. Value is a social relation and is determined by the amount <strong>of</strong> sociallynecessary<br />

labor that goes into a commodity. Assuming that machine production is more<br />

efficient and more productive per worker does not change the amount <strong>of</strong> value that a worker<br />

can produce per hour. Rather, it will change the number <strong>of</strong> good X that is produced per<br />

hour. <strong>The</strong> price <strong>of</strong> good X, that can now be produced with less labor time, will drop. This<br />

price shows up as a reflection <strong>of</strong> the value, or labor time that went into producing that good.<br />

This drop in price will show us that although the worker may produce quantitatively more<br />

goods per hour with a machine, he ultimately will not produce any more value per hour with<br />

a machine.<br />

This concept can easily be confusing. Initially, after the introduction <strong>of</strong> new machinery,<br />

the workers that operate these machines do produce more value per hour, but this is only true<br />

in the short run. Only temporarily, before other capitalists have purchased similar machinery,<br />

and before market forces have adjusted the price to the influx <strong>of</strong> this new commodity that is<br />

now produced with less labor time, can the machine operators produce more value per hour.<br />

Because value is socially determined, the machine operators are temporarily producing more<br />

value per hour than the rest <strong>of</strong> society. <strong>The</strong> rest <strong>of</strong> society is still producing good X the old<br />

fashioned way and therefore the socially necessary labor time in this good has not changed<br />

much yet on average.<br />

Value, however, is a social relation and cannot be changed by inanimate machines. This<br />

social value <strong>of</strong> the good shows up in its price. If a good can be produced more efficiently,<br />

then this implies that it is produced with less labor time. Competition among the different<br />

factories will cause new machinery to also be introduced across the market and this good<br />

produced will be produced with less labor time even at the overall social level. In turn, the<br />

smaller amount <strong>of</strong> socially necessary labor will show up as the lower price <strong>of</strong> that commodity.<br />

This will then adjust the amount <strong>of</strong> value per hour produced by a machine operator back<br />

down to the value per hour that he produced before introduction <strong>of</strong> the machinery. <strong>The</strong>refore,<br />

the answer to question 690 is: No, workers ultimately do not produce any more value<br />

per hour with a machine.<br />

Next Message by JJ is [1173].<br />

[919] Kaimani: <strong>The</strong> simple answer to this question is No. As Hans described in the email<br />

forum in response to Kaimani [834] Hans tells Kaimani to keep away from the neoclassical<br />

and that Marx is very different from Kaimani’s explanation.<br />

Hans: Your in-class answer still gave an explanation based on demand and supply (machines increase suppply<br />

therefore the price drops). This is still not the same as Marx’s explanation, sorry.<br />

Next Message by Kaimani is [920].<br />

[932] LuBr: At the start, when new machinery or technology is introduced in a factory,<br />

the workers are producing more value per hour, because <strong>of</strong> the new machines, than any <strong>of</strong><br />

the other workers in the other factories, the workers that do not have the new machinery.<br />

This is due to an increase in labor productivity. But, after all <strong>of</strong> the other factories take on<br />

the new technology, eventually all workers would produce the same value per hour as the<br />

original factory.<br />

348 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Given value is a social relation, created by the labor-power <strong>of</strong> laborers, the introduction<br />

<strong>of</strong> new machines does not create more value. <strong>The</strong> new machines are simply transferring past<br />

congealed labor-power to the production process creating more value. Labor is still the only<br />

source <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Next Message by LuBr is [951].<br />

[958] Husani: With the introduction <strong>of</strong> new machinery the worker will produce the same<br />

value has he did before. He will produce more commodities but the total value <strong>of</strong> the commodities<br />

produced will equal the value before the introduction <strong>of</strong> the new machinery. Let’s<br />

say that a worker can produce 10 shirts in an hour and the value <strong>of</strong> these 10 shirts is $100.<br />

Each shirt is worth $10. If the new machinery allows the worker to produce 20 shirts in an<br />

hour then the total value <strong>of</strong> these 20 shirts remains $100. This reduces the individual value to<br />

$5 per shirt. Marx says “Even though the productivity <strong>of</strong> labor has doubled, the day’s labor<br />

creates no more value than before.” <strong>The</strong> value remains the same as before because the labor<br />

used in their production remains the same which is where the commodity gets its value. We<br />

are simply dispersing the value between more commodities than we were before.<br />

Next Message by Husani is [1187].<br />

[973] Kohhep: Yes, but only for the capitalists. <strong>The</strong> best analogy I know is the analogy<br />

that Hans made during lecture that machinery is like a gun during a bank robbery. <strong>The</strong> gun,<br />

or machine, does not create value, but strips it from another source. <strong>The</strong> robber is simply the<br />

capitalist, the gun the machine, and the laborer the bank. Machinery is able to simply strip<br />

away the value that is otherwise entitled to the laborer, but instead is immediately routed to<br />

the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Kohhep is [1074].<br />

[979] Kobe: <strong>The</strong> simple answer to this question is no. Marx declares categorically that<br />

only labor creates value. With this being said labor completed using machines would not<br />

increase the value per hour.“Value is a social relation which ties people’s labor processes<br />

together, therefore only people can produce value, machines can’t” In the introductory stages<br />

<strong>of</strong> machinery there will be an increase in surplus value, which is created by the machine, but<br />

this is derived from the laborer himself not the machine.<br />

Next Message by Kobe is [1022].<br />

[1026] Jo: Workers do not produce more value per hour with the introduction <strong>of</strong> new<br />

machinery. Productivity increases, however the same amount <strong>of</strong> labor is being performed,<br />

so value does not increase. More pieces are produced, but each piece has less value than<br />

before the machinery was introduced. Value is a product <strong>of</strong> labor, not technology.<br />

Hans: Your in-class answer was more complete because you also talked about the <strong>first</strong> adopters <strong>of</strong> the machine.<br />

Next Message by Jo is [1027].<br />

[1081] Trap: Throughout Capital Marx is extremely adamant about the fact that machines<br />

do not create more value per hour when <strong>first</strong> introduced. What does produce more value per<br />

hour is the workers who use the machines. When the capitalist <strong>first</strong> introduces a machine<br />

into their production, it increases the efficiency and productivity <strong>of</strong> the workers. It is possible<br />

for the workers using a new machine to create more value for the capitalist, but only if other<br />

capitalists aren’t using the machine as well. <strong>The</strong> workers create extra surplus value, which<br />

creates more value for the capitalist until their competitors have the same advancements as<br />

well, because the original capitalist loses his competitive edge. Once the other capitalists


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 349<br />

have access to the new machinery it ceases to be extra surplus-value and becomes relative<br />

surplus value. <strong>The</strong>refore, only workers produce value, not machines.<br />

Hans: It is not the productivity which allows them to create more value, but the fact that, as long as they are<br />

the early adopters, their labor is qualitatively different than the labor <strong>of</strong> the other workers with the older type <strong>of</strong><br />

machines.<br />

Next Message by Trap is [1170].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 698 is 547 in 2005fa, 606 in 2008fa, 635 in 2009fa, and 747 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 698 Relative surplus-value requires the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power to fall. Does this<br />

mean that in today’s world with sticky wages and union contracts, relative surplus-value is<br />

impossible?<br />

[705] Jo: Sticky wages and relative surplus-value. No, relative surplus-value is not<br />

impossible in today’s world. Wages can still fall, and do for various reasons. However,<br />

wages do not have to fall for the value <strong>of</strong> labor power to fall. Workers can be made more<br />

productive through the implementation <strong>of</strong> technology. This means that a worker will produce<br />

more in a work day than before. <strong>The</strong> worker will work the same number <strong>of</strong> hours and<br />

receive the same wage, yet produce more articles. As Hans mentioned in his notes at the<br />

end <strong>of</strong> [2009fa:748], “the labor content <strong>of</strong> one dollar’s worth <strong>of</strong> goods is over time slowly<br />

declining. Even if 8 hours produce as much value as before, the dollar amount representing<br />

this value increases.” This means that productivity is increasing, yet the value <strong>of</strong> the dollar<br />

is being held relatively constant, and so the labor content <strong>of</strong> that dollar is declining. Since<br />

the worker’s wage is not increasing to compensate for the change in labor content, they are<br />

essentially receiving a lower wage.<br />

Hans also says in his notes to [2008fa:828] that “Workers get lower wages, but since the<br />

labor content <strong>of</strong> their means <strong>of</strong> consumption is lower too, their standard <strong>of</strong> living remains<br />

unchanged.” How is this possible? <strong>The</strong> workers are essentially receiving lower wages, yet<br />

their standard <strong>of</strong> living does not change. This is possible because the labor content <strong>of</strong> one<br />

dollar’s worth <strong>of</strong> goods has also declined. <strong>The</strong> worker will save money by having access<br />

to cheaper goods (or “those commodities that contribute towards the necessary means <strong>of</strong><br />

subsistence” Annotations, p. 517), so even though his wage is lower, he will still be able to<br />

afford the same standard <strong>of</strong> living. <strong>The</strong> capitalist, on the other hand, will be able to enjoy<br />

the relative surplus-value owing to the increased productivity <strong>of</strong> the worker.<br />

Message [705] referenced by [2012fa:997]. Next Message by Jo is [1025].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 699 is 212 in 1995WI, 243 in 1996ut, 297 in 1997WI, 368 in 1998WI, 369 in<br />

1999SP, 457 in 2000fa, 484 in 2001fa, 597 in 2004fa, 550 in 2005fa, and 719 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 699 Does the continual striving by the capitalists to lower the value <strong>of</strong> their products<br />

contradict the basic tenet <strong>of</strong> the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value that they are only interested in<br />

value, not use-value?<br />

[711] Rmc: graded C Capitalists and value vs. use-value. Capitalists must be interested<br />

in use-value while choosing a product to exchange on the market because use-value to a<br />

buyer is exchange-value to the seller. If the producers choose to sell a commodity that has<br />

no use-value to any customers, or to too few, they risk not making a pr<strong>of</strong>it or even losing<br />

350 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

money. <strong>The</strong>y are secondarily interested in value when it comes to producing the product<br />

because <strong>of</strong> its relationship to the product’s (exchange-value’s) price.<br />

By reducing the labor-time spent on a product, which lowers the labor-time value attached<br />

to it, more products can be made for the same amount <strong>of</strong> money as before, allowing the<br />

capitalist to make a greater pr<strong>of</strong>it. This is because customers are more likely to exchange for<br />

a lower price, attracting greater demand, and allowing the seller to sell more <strong>of</strong> his products.<br />

While the value <strong>of</strong> a product may be the capitalists’ main concern for generating pr<strong>of</strong>it,<br />

they must always be aware <strong>of</strong> the commodity’s use-value. When a commodity loses its status<br />

as a use-value, it loses its exchange-value as well, and no pr<strong>of</strong>it is generated.<br />

Hans: You equate more product with more pr<strong>of</strong>it, even if the increase in output is not accompanied by an increase<br />

in labor-value. Since in Marx’s theory labor-values determine prices, you fail to explain where this higher pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

should come from.<br />

Message [711] referenced by [728]. Next Message by Rmc is [758].<br />

[728] Hans: Use-value—exchange-value chicken and egg problem. Rmc argues in<br />

[711] that the capitalists must be interested in use-value, since they cannot sell any<strong>thing</strong> if it<br />

does not have use-value for the buyers. Rmc goes as far as saying that capitalists are only<br />

“secondarily interested in value.”<br />

Marx by contrast declares categorically in 254:1 that “use-values must never be treated<br />

as the immediate aim <strong>of</strong> the capitalist.” He is not alone saying this, other economists <strong>of</strong> his<br />

time said this too.<br />

In order to decide which point <strong>of</strong> view is right, I propose to look at the use-values that are<br />

produced in capitalism. <strong>The</strong>y are usable but they have the capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>it motive stamped<br />

all over them. From excessive and deceptive packaging to planned obsolescence to lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> modularity and standardization (which makes them irrepairable so that they have to be<br />

dumped and replaced when some<strong>thing</strong> goes wrong). Don’t get me started. <strong>The</strong> failure <strong>of</strong> the<br />

US to join the rest <strong>of</strong> the world on the metric system is another one. It is clear that use-values<br />

are designed for the capitalist, not for the consumer.<br />

This is especially galling because it is an entirely unnecessary waste <strong>of</strong> our natural resources.<br />

One should expect regulation to require minimum quality and longevity standards.<br />

This is no<strong>thing</strong> new; military suppliers have had to meet such regulation for a long time.<br />

Not a peep from our esteemed legislators, although everybody knows that we are reaching<br />

or have already overshot the limits <strong>of</strong> our planet’s natural resources.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [734].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 700 is 370 in 1999SP, 544 in 2003fa, 551 in 2005fa, and 596 in 2007fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 700 Marx says that an increase in productivity will increase surplus-value not<br />

only through the cheapening <strong>of</strong> the workers’ means <strong>of</strong> subsistence, but through other avenues<br />

as well. Describe some <strong>of</strong> these other avenues.<br />

[696] Long: One <strong>of</strong> the avenues Marx describes is that with the new method <strong>of</strong> production<br />

the capitalist is now producing his commodity under their social value. This is in turn acting<br />

as a law <strong>of</strong> competition since it forces the competitor to adopt new or different methods <strong>of</strong><br />

production. Not only that, it also reduces the workers’ hours <strong>of</strong> labor. Marx gave an example<br />

<strong>of</strong> working 12 hours and producing 120 but an increase in productivity would increace it to


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 351<br />

1200 articles. Marx also describes that not only we owe debt <strong>of</strong> gratitude to such productivity<br />

because the necessary labor is shortened, but now we must work more in the future for more<br />

hours instead which in term he/she is working for no<strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Hans: You say that the innovation “reduces the workers’ hours <strong>of</strong> labor.” This is not true. Often the hours are even<br />

lengthened because the capitalist does not want the expensive machine stand idle.<br />

Message [696] referenced by [701]. Next Message by Long is [743].<br />

[701] Hans: Speedups. Besides relative surplus-value, Long [696] says correctly that extra<br />

surplus-value is another way how productivity increases pr<strong>of</strong>its. <strong>The</strong>re is a third important<br />

way, which is an issue for almost everyone who has a job these days: speedup. Machines<br />

make the work easier, more regular, and machines can be used to control and supervise the<br />

worker.<br />

This speedup will not be implemented right at the beginning when the new technology is<br />

introduced. Whenever there is new technology, the capitalists have to go easy because they<br />

want to lure the workers into learning this new technology. At the beginning they also don’t<br />

have enough experience to know how fast they can drive the workers etc. But in times <strong>of</strong><br />

economic recession, such as the last two years, when workers are afraid to lose their jobs,<br />

these stops are pulled out and speedups are implemented mercilessly.<br />

It is the workers’ right not to be completely exhausted after work. People are so busy and<br />

tired with their lives that they can no longer attend to their families. One <strong>of</strong> the reasons Marx<br />

wrote the long chapter Ten about the working day was his hope that, after the shortening <strong>of</strong><br />

the workday, workers would have more time and energy to organize to bring the capitalist<br />

system down. This didn’t happen. Right now the stakes are even higher. We should be out<br />

on the barricades to protest against our government’s suicidal neglect <strong>of</strong> global warming.<br />

But we are too overworked and exhausted, we can be glad if we get enough sleep as it is.<br />

Message [701] referenced by [695]. Next Message by Hans is [702].<br />

[709] Ryan: When Marx talks about the (As Submitted:) Q700 When Marx<br />

increase <strong>of</strong> productivity and mentions that talks about the increase <strong>of</strong> produtivity and<br />

menstions that there are other factors to consider<br />

when calculating the total Surplus-<br />

there are other factors to consider when calvalue besides the cheaping <strong>of</strong> “workers<br />

culating the total surplus-value besides the<br />

cheapening <strong>of</strong> “workers means <strong>of</strong> subsistence”<br />

he is referring to:<br />

Surplus Labor: This is the additional free<br />

labor that the worker does once the new pro-<br />

means <strong>of</strong> subsistince” he is refering to:<br />

Surplus Labor: This is the additional free<br />

labor that the worker does once the new productive<br />

messaures are in place. For example<br />

ductive measures are in place. For example<br />

a worker is paid 50 dollars a day and ex-<br />

a wprk is paid 50 dollars a day and expected<br />

pected to make 5 dolls. 10 dollars a doll. to make 5 dolls. 10 dollars a doll. Now<br />

Now with the new machine a worker can<br />

make ten dolls. <strong>The</strong>y are still paid 50 dol-<br />

with the new machine a worker can make<br />

lars a day and expected to make ten dolls. ten dolls. <strong>The</strong>y are still paid 50 dollars a<br />

352 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Now 5 dollars a doll. This additional labor day and expected to make ten dolls. Now 5<br />

is not being paid for as there has been no<br />

change to wages. dollars a doll. This additional labor is not<br />

being paid for as there has been no change<br />

to wages.<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>it from additional items made: Same<br />

worker that was making 5 dolls now makes<br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>it from additional items made: Same<br />

worker that was making 5 dolls now makes 10 dolls. Dolls sell for 20 dollars. 5X20 0<br />

minus 50 dollars in wages 10X20 0 minus<br />

10 dolls. Dolls sell for 20 dollars. 5×20=100 50 dollars for wages<br />

minus 50 dollars in wages = 50 dollars<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it. Now 10×20=200 minus 50 dollars<br />

for wages = 150 in pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Hans: Your second paragraph talks about speedup—assuming work with the new machine is more strenuous than<br />

before. If it isn’t, then Marx would argue the work performed is the same.<br />

Your third paragraph talks about extra surplus-value. But this will be competed away.<br />

Both <strong>of</strong> these <strong>thing</strong>s were mentioned earlier and discussed better.<br />

Form and writing style <strong>of</strong> your answer are unacceptable.<br />

Next Message by Ryan is [844].<br />

Term Paper 701 is 638 in 2009fa and 721 in 2011fa:<br />

Term Paper 701 Essay about the General Connection between Exploitation and Surplus-<br />

Value.<br />

[735] Robert: graded A+ In this essay, I present the connection between the Marxian<br />

concepts <strong>of</strong> surplus-value and exploitation. I <strong>first</strong> examine Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> surplus-value<br />

and describe his analysis <strong>of</strong> the source <strong>of</strong> surplus-value in a capitalist economy. I proceed<br />

to explore the definition <strong>of</strong> exploitation and what Marx means by the term. <strong>The</strong>n, I bring<br />

together the two concepts and present the connection between them. Additionally, I explore<br />

Marx’s derivatives <strong>of</strong> surplus-value, i.e., absolute surplus-value, relative surplus-value, and<br />

extra surplus value.<br />

Marx defines surplus-value <strong>first</strong> in reference to his exploration <strong>of</strong> M-C-M’. He states, in<br />

250:4/oo that M’=M +ΔM and that ΔM, the “increment or excess over the original value I<br />

call—surplus-value.”<br />

Marx then goes into a detailed analysis to discover the source <strong>of</strong> surplus-value. He <strong>first</strong><br />

examines circulation to determine if surplus-value originates there. He looks at the exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong> equivalents and concludes, “the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is expressed in its price before it<br />

enters into circulation, and is therefore a precondition <strong>of</strong> circulation, not its result” [260:1].<br />

<strong>The</strong>n Marx examines the exchange <strong>of</strong> non-equivalents and ends his search with the words,<br />

“One does not throw any light on the origin <strong>of</strong> surplus-value if one says that the owner <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodities sells them at more than their value, under the designation <strong>of</strong> producer, and<br />

pays too much for them, under the designation <strong>of</strong> consumer” [264:1b]. He finally looks at<br />

transactions between classes <strong>of</strong> individuals and individuals themselves and concludes that


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 353<br />

although such transactions may redistribute value, such redistribution is a zero sum game<br />

(Annotations, p. 385).<br />

Marx concludes his search for the source <strong>of</strong> surplus-value in circulation by stating, “However<br />

much we twist and turn, the final conclusion remains the same. If equivalents are exchanged,<br />

no surplus-value results, and if non-equivalents are exchanged, we still have no<br />

surplus-value. Circulation, or the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities creates no value” [266:1]. Circulation,<br />

by itself, is not the source <strong>of</strong> surplus-value.<br />

Marx then looks at production to see if that is the source <strong>of</strong> surplus-value. He examines<br />

a boot and decides, “ It has not valorized itself, it has not annexed surplus-value during<br />

the making <strong>of</strong> the boots. It is therefore impossible that, outside the sphere <strong>of</strong> circulation, a<br />

producer <strong>of</strong> commodities can, without coming into contact with other commodity-owners,<br />

valorize value” [268:1] and thereby create surplus-value.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, in typical Marxian fashion, when it seems there is no explanation as to the<br />

source <strong>of</strong> surplus-value, Marx digs deeper. He states in 268:2 that surplus-value “must have<br />

its origin both in circulation and not in circulation.” He then goes on to explain this “double<br />

result” [268:3] is only possible because, as I describe below, in capitalism labor-power is a<br />

commodity. <strong>The</strong> capitalist only pays for the necessary labor (the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power) and<br />

realizes for himself the value <strong>of</strong> the surplus labor.<br />

To understand surplus-value as defined by Marx we must explore this related concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> necessary labor. Marx [324:1/o] defines necessary labor: “That portion <strong>of</strong> the working<br />

day [during which the laborer produces the value <strong>of</strong> his labor-power] takes place, I call<br />

‘necessary’ labor-time, and the labor expended during that time I call ‘necessary’ labor.”<br />

This concept <strong>of</strong> necessary labor is different from Marx’s concept <strong>of</strong> the socially necessary<br />

labor to produce a commodity, which refers to the most socially common methods utilizing<br />

the socially average amount <strong>of</strong> labor time to produce such a commodity.<br />

Labor power is the capacity to work or potential labor. <strong>The</strong> laborer in a capitalist society<br />

must sell his labor-power as a commodity. Like any other commodity, the value <strong>of</strong><br />

labor-power is equal to the labor-time necessary to produce it. In reference to human brains,<br />

nerves, and muscles the amount <strong>of</strong> labor-time necessary to produce labor power is its maintenance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the human individual and her replacement, when the individual wears out. <strong>The</strong><br />

laborer must be able to sustain herself and to reproduce her own replacements (i.e., have<br />

and raise children to be future laborers). This effort is the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity laborpower<br />

that she sells to the owners <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production for a wage. <strong>The</strong> wage, which<br />

equals only the necessary labor, as defined above, only pays for a portion <strong>of</strong> the labor-time<br />

expended by the laborer. In a few hours time <strong>of</strong> expenditure <strong>of</strong> labor-power each day, the<br />

worker creates enough value to allow sustenance <strong>of</strong> herself and her replacements; this labor<br />

is necessary labor (Hunt, 1992, pp. 268-270).<br />

However, the worker has the capacity to work more hours and the workday in capitalism<br />

always extends beyond these few hours <strong>of</strong> necessary labor-time. <strong>The</strong> labor-power expended<br />

during the time difference between the actual length <strong>of</strong> the working day and the necessary<br />

labor-time is surplus labor. In capitalism, the owner <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production owns the<br />

commodity that results from production. Imbedded in that commodity is value equal to a<br />

354 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

full days labor expended in its production. That imbedded value exceeds what the owner has<br />

paid for it by an amount exactly equal to the surplus labor, for which he has not and will not<br />

pay the laborer. <strong>The</strong>refore, surplus-value equals the value created by surplus labor.<br />

To understand the connection between surplus-value and exploitation it is helpful to look<br />

at Marx’s concept <strong>of</strong> rate <strong>of</strong> surplus-value. To develop this concept, Marx [320:2] explains<br />

surplus-value in terms <strong>of</strong> capital. He describes that capital, which he labeled C, has two<br />

parts: constant capital and variable capital. Constant capital, which Marx symbolizes with<br />

c, is “the sum <strong>of</strong> money laid out upon the means <strong>of</strong> production” and variable capital, v, is the<br />

amount “expended upon labor-power.” At the beginning <strong>of</strong> production C=c+v and at the end<br />

<strong>of</strong> production C’=c+v+s, where s is the surplus-value. Marx uses these symbols to define<br />

the rate <strong>of</strong> surplus-value, s/v, which equals the surplus-value divided by wages paid, or, in<br />

the terms defined above, the value <strong>of</strong> surplus labor divided by value <strong>of</strong> necessary labor.<br />

<strong>The</strong> connection between surplus-value and exploitation is made by Marx when he states:<br />

“<strong>The</strong> rate <strong>of</strong> surplus-value is therefore an exact expression for the degree <strong>of</strong> exploitation <strong>of</strong><br />

labor by capital, or <strong>of</strong> the laborer by the capitalist” [326:2]. For every hour the laborer works<br />

for himself (i.e., earning a wage to subsist and reproduce) he works s/v hours producing<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its for the capitalist.<br />

More generally, Marx defined exploitation as the transfer <strong>of</strong> a product from those who<br />

produce that product by the expenditure <strong>of</strong> their labor power to other social classes because<br />

<strong>of</strong> their control <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Ernest Mandel (1990) writes: “Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> surplus-value is basically a deduction<br />

(or residual) theory <strong>of</strong> the ruling classes’ income . . . [which income] can always be reduced<br />

in the final analysis to the product <strong>of</strong> unpaid labour: that is the heart <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong><br />

exploitation.” By only paying the laborer for her necessary labor the capitalist, who owns<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production, exploits the worker for her surplus labor, which, because he claims<br />

ownership <strong>of</strong> the products, produces surplus value for him.<br />

<strong>The</strong> word exploitation invokes emotional responses that affect our understanding <strong>of</strong> what<br />

the word means. Jonathan Wolff’s (1999) article “Marx and Exploitation” carefully and rationally<br />

develops a definition <strong>of</strong> the word and analyzes whether there is some<strong>thing</strong> morally<br />

wrong with exploitation from Kantian, Rawlsian, and Aristotelian views <strong>of</strong> ethics. He concludes,<br />

given Marx’s understanding <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> capitalism, “then fairness demands<br />

that those who find themselves holding private property [i.e., means <strong>of</strong> production]<br />

have no right to benefit from it. Consequently, contracts <strong>of</strong> employment in which surplus<br />

labour is required or at least expected violate norms <strong>of</strong> fairness, and this is enough to make<br />

the contracts exploitative. <strong>The</strong> fact that, in Marx’s view, the labour is alienated and involves<br />

great suffering compounds the case, to make exploitation under capitalism particularly<br />

deep.” (my parenthetical comment, p. 119).<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, we can conclude that surplus-value equals the amount <strong>of</strong> value that owners<br />

<strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production expropriate from laborers employed by them and that such expropriation<br />

violates the norms <strong>of</strong> fairness. Such expropriation is exploitive, and therefore,<br />

ethically wrong. <strong>The</strong> fact that such exploitation causes alienation and suffering intensifies<br />

the wrong. In this way, surplus-value and exploitation are generally connected.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 355<br />

It is interesting to note here that a capitalistic society promotes the idea that the laborer is<br />

not selling labor-power but is selling labor. <strong>The</strong> laborer believes he is selling a day’s labor<br />

when he is paid his wage. He does not realize that he is being exploited, that he is not<br />

receiving compensation for the value he creates. He believes the capitalist concept that since<br />

he has been paid for his labor by the capitalist the capitalist owns the product the laborer<br />

produced.<br />

Similarly, the individual capitalist may not realize, because <strong>of</strong> his socialization in capitalism,<br />

that he, in fact, is exploiting his laborers. Furthermore, in a capitalist society the<br />

capitalist believes that he deserves a return on his capital and that he is compensating the<br />

laborer fairly. He believes his capital is the source <strong>of</strong> his pr<strong>of</strong>its. <strong>The</strong> fact that the laborer<br />

does not even know he is being exploited and the capitalist believes a self-serving cover-up<br />

explanation <strong>of</strong> his exploitation <strong>of</strong> the laborer seems to render the exploitation in capitalism<br />

all the more insidious.<br />

Having made the connection between surplus-value and exploitation, Marx introduced<br />

three new terms to illustrate the extent <strong>of</strong> exploitation propagated by the capitalist: absolute<br />

surplus-value, relative surplus-value and extra surplus-value.<br />

Absolute surplus-value involves attempts by capitalist to lengthen the working day so that<br />

more surplus labor-time is rendered and thereby more surplus-value created. Chapter 10 <strong>of</strong><br />

Capital relates much <strong>of</strong> the history and several instances <strong>of</strong> the struggle by capitalists to<br />

require workers to work longer hours. <strong>The</strong>re is a point <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns when the days<br />

are so long that the workers wear out and are unable to replace themselves, either in the next<br />

day’s work or by creating new laborers.<br />

Relative surplus-value involves decreasing the portion <strong>of</strong> the day required for necessary<br />

labor-time, which, as defined above, is the labor-time necessary to reproduce the worker’s<br />

wages. By a method Hans refers to as the backdoor effect [2008fa:943], capitalist can effectively<br />

decease necessary labor-time by improving productivity and thereby making the<br />

commodities required for sustenance and replacement less costly. Labor-power is a commodity<br />

in capitalism and its value is measured, as described above, by its sustenance and<br />

replacement cost. If such costs decrease, the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power decreases therefore necessary<br />

labor-time drops. By increasing efficiency capitalist have effectively lowered necessary<br />

labor time and, if the workday remains unchanged, thereby increased surplus labor time and<br />

surplus-value.<br />

Extra surplus-value occurs when, because <strong>of</strong> innovation, laborers are able to provide<br />

qualitatively different labor, which produces a product whose individual value is below the<br />

market value <strong>of</strong> that product. Extra surplus-value exist only temporarily, as others employ<br />

the innovation then the extra surplus-value <strong>of</strong> the early adopter <strong>of</strong> the innovation becomes<br />

the general relative surplus-value, described above.<br />

Capitalist, motivated by a societal necessity <strong>of</strong> accumulation <strong>of</strong> more capital, try to maximize<br />

their pr<strong>of</strong>its, which derive directly from surplus-value, the value created by labor-time<br />

expended each day in addition to necessary labor-time. <strong>The</strong>y attempt to do so by increasing<br />

356 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

either absolute or relative surplus-value or by gaining the brief advantage <strong>of</strong> extra surplusvalue.<br />

Surplus-value results directly from exploitation <strong>of</strong> labor by capitalists who expropriate<br />

the products <strong>of</strong> the labors’ surplus-labor because the capitalist controls the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production. <strong>The</strong>refore, capitalism incentivizes the class that owns the means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

to maximize their exploitation <strong>of</strong> laborers.<br />

Works Cited (in addition to Ehrbar, H. (2010). Annotations to Karl Marx’s ‘Capital.’<br />

Class Edition.)<br />

Hunt, E. (1992). History <strong>of</strong> economic thought: A critical perspective. NY: HarperCollins.<br />

Mandel, E. (1990). Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> surplus value. Retrieved October 14, 2010, from<br />

http://www.marxists.org/archive/mandel/19xx/marx/ch07.htm<br />

Wolf, J. (1999). Marx and exploitation. <strong>The</strong> Journal <strong>of</strong> Ethics. 3:2 pp.105-120. Netherlands:<br />

Kluwer Academic Publishers.<br />

Message [735] referenced by [755] and [2011fa:1132]. Next Message by Robert is [747].<br />

Term Paper 702 is 608 in 2007SP, 722 in 2011fa, and 752 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 702 Essay about Chapter Eleven: Rate and Mass <strong>of</strong> Surplus Value<br />

[739] Cosmopolita and TINDOZ: Chapter 11 in Marx’s Capital examines the trade <strong>of</strong>fs<br />

between several factors that capitalists attempt to manipulate in order to meet their goals <strong>of</strong><br />

obtaining the highest rate <strong>of</strong> surplus value from their employees. We will concentrate on this<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> the chapter, seeking to better understand what tools the capitalist uses to influence<br />

the rate and the mass <strong>of</strong> the surplus value. This examination takes place through a close look<br />

at the relationships between the following factors: surplus, value <strong>of</strong> average labor power, the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> laborers, and the total labor hours needed to meet desired goals. To begin this<br />

examination, Marx begins the chapter by setting up the mathematical relationship between<br />

all the factors involved and uses an example to explore this relationship. For us to properly<br />

examine this chapter, we will <strong>first</strong> need to do just as Marx did and define the mathematical<br />

relationships and we will also use Marx’s example.<br />

We will start by looking at the rate <strong>of</strong> surplus value which is understood as a1/a2 (or<br />

s/v). <strong>The</strong> example that Marx gives as a rate <strong>of</strong> surplus value is that if (in the example) the<br />

“necessary labor” amounts to 6 hours <strong>of</strong> labor a day, and that that is further expressed in<br />

gold as 3 shillings, then if a laborer works for only 6 hours in one day, his ratio 6/6, or 3<br />

shillings/3 shillings or 100%. This ratio can be tinkered with by (in his example Marx fixes<br />

the necessary labor at 6 hours) increasing the amount <strong>of</strong> hours worked in order to create a<br />

different percentage <strong>of</strong> surplus. For example if the worker worked for 12 hours (so 6 above<br />

the necessary labor amount) the gold ratio would be 6/3 being further expressed as the rate<br />

<strong>of</strong> surplus value being 200%.<br />

Hans: What is this “gold ratio”? Marx does not use this. He uses the rate <strong>of</strong> surplus-value, which would be 0 in a<br />

six-hour work day, and 100% in a 12 hour work day.<br />

<strong>The</strong> equation for the mass <strong>of</strong> surplus value (S) can be expressed as: S = P×(a1/a2)×n.<br />

So the mass <strong>of</strong> surplus value equals P (value <strong>of</strong> labor-power) times a1/a2 (the rate <strong>of</strong> surplus<br />

value we just discussed) times n (which represents the number <strong>of</strong> workers employed by the<br />

capitalist). In this equation, P is a fixed value as the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power does not change


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 357<br />

from day to day. This labor power value is figured by the socially necessary labor time to<br />

create the commodity in question.<br />

Hans: Wrong definition <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> labor-power.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, as this equation relies on 3 separate parts to give a specific surplus value (P,<br />

(a1/a2), and n); and one <strong>of</strong> those values (P) is constant, any manipulating <strong>of</strong> the function<br />

must be done on the other two variables. Manipulating these variable can be done by either<br />

modifying the number <strong>of</strong> workers, or modifying the number <strong>of</strong> hours worked. This surplus<br />

value equation shows that the only way that a capitalist can modify the surplus value result is<br />

by changing the values that they have control over (namely number <strong>of</strong> workers and the length<br />

<strong>of</strong> the day those laborers work). <strong>The</strong>refore if the number <strong>of</strong> workers drops, we can conclude<br />

then that a decrease in this variable may be compensated for by a lengthening <strong>of</strong> the work<br />

day for those laborers who remain. Furthermore, if a capitalist wishes to increase the mass<br />

<strong>of</strong> surplus value, then they can either lengthen the work day or employ more workers.<br />

With this equation there are limits that are set that prohibit the movement <strong>of</strong> these variables<br />

to certain degrees. For example the absolute limit for a worker to work is 24 hours per<br />

day. We say absolute limit because that is the number <strong>of</strong> hours in a day and it is impossible to<br />

increase this beyond 24. However, if a capitalist exploits his labor to working them 24 hours<br />

a day, they would be working them to death for no person could keep up with that schedule.<br />

If the health and well-being <strong>of</strong> the worker are taken into account (especially noting that if<br />

they are healthy, they are better producers) then this limits the number <strong>of</strong> hours the laborer<br />

can work even further (possibly somewhere between 8 hours and 18 hours). So let’s say that<br />

a capitalist has a number <strong>of</strong> workers who are working 18 hour days and are producing a surplus<br />

mass <strong>of</strong> X. <strong>The</strong>n the workers get fed up with working themselves to death for the benefit<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalist (because their necessary labor hours are 6) and unionize and get their work<br />

day dropped down to 12 hours a day. If this happened, the only way that the capitalist could<br />

retain the surplus <strong>of</strong> X would be to increase the number <strong>of</strong> workers he had at a proportional<br />

rate to compensate for the dropping <strong>of</strong> daily hours worked by his workforce. This limitation<br />

(<strong>of</strong> the working hours) is one that vexes capitalists as they are always trying to get the most<br />

surplus value that they can by employing the fewest people they can.<br />

Hans: Your <strong>first</strong> sentence does not summarize well what Marx does. <strong>The</strong> capitalist is interested in surplus-value<br />

itself, not the rate <strong>of</strong> surplus-value. <strong>The</strong> rate <strong>of</strong> surplus-value is only one factor in the formula which tells you the<br />

amount, the “mass,” <strong>of</strong> surplus-value. Other factors are length <strong>of</strong> the workday and number <strong>of</strong> workers<br />

Otherwise, this term paper suffers because you seem to be unclear about some <strong>of</strong> the basic concepts <strong>of</strong> Marx:<br />

necessary labor, value <strong>of</strong> labor-power, and rate <strong>of</strong> surplus-value..<br />

Message [739] referenced by [747], [755], and [772]. Next Message by Cosmopolita is [807] and Next Message<br />

by TINDOZ is [954].<br />

[747] Robert: graded A Socially Necessary Labor Time and Necessary Labor. I think<br />

Cosmopolita and TINDOZ [739] did a good job on their essay about Chapter Eleven: Rate<br />

and Mass <strong>of</strong> Surplus Value. <strong>The</strong>re is one point, that I think Marx himself is not too clear<br />

about, that I think perhaps they could have clarified a bit more for us.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second paragraph <strong>of</strong> the essay refers to “necessary labor amounts” in reference to<br />

examples provided by Marx, without a definition <strong>of</strong> what Marx meant by the term. I think the<br />

labeling is accurate and reflects Marx’s meaning <strong>of</strong> necessary labor in this context. <strong>The</strong> next<br />

paragraph <strong>of</strong> the essay states: “This labor power value is figured by the socially necessary<br />

358 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

labor time to create the commodity in question.” Again, if I understand correctly, I think<br />

the sentence correctly states the concept and Marx’s view <strong>of</strong> it. However, the use <strong>of</strong> phrase<br />

“necessary labor” in two adjacent paragraphs, in both instances referring to value and time,<br />

with two different meanings may be worth clarifying.<br />

I am suggesting an explanation some<strong>thing</strong> like: Marx uses “necessary labor” in reference<br />

to two related but different concepts. In Chapter 1, he introduces the concept <strong>of</strong> socially<br />

necessary labor time with the paradox <strong>of</strong> the lazy worker and ultimately identifies the “substance<br />

<strong>of</strong> value is equal human labor, expenditure <strong>of</strong> the same human power” that “has the<br />

character <strong>of</strong> the average labor-power <strong>of</strong> society...for producing a commodity” (129:2). This<br />

concept, from Chapter 1 is the concept referenced in the third paragraph <strong>of</strong> the essay. In<br />

Chapter 10 Marx introduces the subject <strong>of</strong> “necessary labor” by which he means the portion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the day that a laborer must work to create value equal to value <strong>of</strong> the commodity he has<br />

sold, i.e., his labor-power.<br />

<strong>The</strong> concepts are related: the worker is expected to be able to produce the product in<br />

the time allotted by the Chapter 1 definition <strong>of</strong> necessary labor. Working at this Chapter 1<br />

rate the worker will produce a value per unit <strong>of</strong> time (say hours), that value divided into the<br />

socially determined cost <strong>of</strong> maintaining and reproducing the laborer equals the necessary<br />

labor portion (in hours) <strong>of</strong> the work day.<br />

In fairness to Cosmopolita and TINDOZ the essay refers to the Chapter 1 use <strong>of</strong> “necessary<br />

labor” with the adjective “socially,” and did not apply the adjective to their reference<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Chapter 10 use <strong>of</strong> “necessary labor” (although, interestingly, it is also socially determined).<br />

Again, I don’t believe there are any errors in their references, I found I was a little<br />

confused and had to pause and realize that “necessary labor” in Marx’s world has these two<br />

different, although related, meanings.<br />

Next Message by Robert is [893].<br />

[772] Husani: Feedback for Term Paper. I think that what Cosmopolita and TINDOZ<br />

[739] said about their assessment <strong>of</strong> chapter 11 is correct. <strong>The</strong>y left out the second part <strong>of</strong><br />

the chapter and I believe this part has some significance.<br />

Marx refers to three laws which were touched on by Cosmopolita and TINCOZ but I<br />

will go more in depth on them. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> <strong>of</strong> these laws says that the mass <strong>of</strong> surplus value<br />

produced is equal to the amount <strong>of</strong> variable capital advanced multiplied by the rate <strong>of</strong> surplus<br />

value. This is a very simple equation which means that the total surplus value (S) produced<br />

can be found by multiplying the total amount <strong>of</strong> labor power purchased at its going rate (V)<br />

by the rate <strong>of</strong> surplus value (a1/a2 or s/v). This law can also be stated as the mass <strong>of</strong> surplus<br />

value is equal to the product <strong>of</strong> the number <strong>of</strong> labor simultaneously exploited by the same<br />

capitalist and the degree <strong>of</strong> exploitation <strong>of</strong> each individual labor power.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second law states that the absolute limit <strong>of</strong> the working day must be below 24 hours.<br />

Cosmopolita and TINDOZ say that if the worker labors for the capitalist all 24 hours <strong>of</strong> each<br />

day then he will die. This is true and to add to it, the worker must be given some time for the<br />

maintenance <strong>of</strong> the worker or in other words the worker needs time <strong>of</strong>f to satisfy his needs<br />

<strong>of</strong> eating, sleeping, etc.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 359<br />

<strong>The</strong> third law says that if the rate <strong>of</strong> surplus value and the amount <strong>of</strong> necessary labor-time<br />

are given or constant then the greater the variable capital advanced, the greater the mass <strong>of</strong><br />

value produced and <strong>of</strong> the surplus-value. What this third law means is that if the rate <strong>of</strong><br />

surplus value is constant and the amount <strong>of</strong> necessary-labor time is also constant, then an<br />

increase in the variable capital advanced will increase the mass <strong>of</strong> surplus-value and value<br />

will increase as well. Let’s assume that the rate <strong>of</strong> surplus value is 100% and the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

necessary labor time is 6 hours at $5. If a capitalist employs 10 workers then he will generate<br />

$50 in surplus value (100% x $5 x 10). If the capitalist doubles the capital he advances to<br />

workers he must employ five more workers and will double his surplus value to $100.<br />

One last interesting point I found in this chapter is towards the end and is in relation<br />

to how the capitalist system began. Marx says “Capital developed within the production<br />

process until it acquired command over labor, i.e. over self-activating labor-power, in other<br />

words the worker himself (424).” I believe this means that capital developed as the production<br />

<strong>of</strong> many commodities grew. As cities grew and fewer people produced all <strong>of</strong> their<br />

necessities, capital arose to fill the gaps. As this system grew the capitalists slowly began to<br />

provide for their workers and in return these workers do more work than is required. This<br />

relationship creates a cohesive bond between the worker and the capitalist which keeps the<br />

Capitalist system intact and working today. This is a short synopsis <strong>of</strong> how the system we<br />

currently use came to be.<br />

Next Message by Husani is [817].<br />

Term Paper 703 is 913 in 1999SP, 913 in 2000fa, 913 in 2001fa, 813 in 2002fa, 813 in<br />

2003fa, 813 in 2005fa, 620 in 2007SP, 611 in 2008fa, and 753 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 703 Essay about Chapter Thirteen: Co-operation<br />

[699] Cougar, Guh, IrvingHowe, Jon, and Orville: Throughout Capital, Marx has<br />

systematically analyzed capitalism by breaking the system down in every case to its lowest<br />

common denominator. In Chapter 13 <strong>of</strong> Capital, Marx has sought to explain the element <strong>of</strong><br />

production that allows a given number <strong>of</strong> workers to turn raw materials into finished goods.<br />

This element, co-operation, is defined by Marx in 443:10 as “when numerous workers work<br />

together side by side in accordance with a plan, whether in the same process or in different<br />

by connected processes, this form <strong>of</strong> labour is called co-operation.” Framed with Marx’s<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> co-operation, this paper is our attempt to understand both the nature <strong>of</strong> cooperation<br />

and its implications. In describing the nature <strong>of</strong> co-operation Marx 447:1/o0 notes<br />

in a way that is almost euphoric: “When the worker co-operates in a planned way with others,<br />

he strips <strong>of</strong>f the fetters <strong>of</strong> his individuality, and develops the capabilities <strong>of</strong> his species.” Of<br />

course, there is hardly a wasted sentence in Capital but this sentence impresses upon the<br />

reader just how important and far reaching the power <strong>of</strong> co-operation can be.<br />

Hans: I agree that there is hardly a wasted sentence in Capital and my Annotations try to show this, but the<br />

consensus view even among Marxists seems to be that Marx is rather repetitious in Capital.<br />

On the implications <strong>of</strong> co-operation, more specifically large-scale co-operation, Marx issues<br />

what at <strong>first</strong> glance appears to be merely a fairly obvious insight saying “As the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> workers increases, so too does their resistance to the domination <strong>of</strong> capital, and, necessarily,<br />

the pressure put on by capital to overcome this resistance.” However, given the<br />

historical lens that we have the pleasure <strong>of</strong> viewing Capital through, this statement becomes<br />

360 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

eerily prophetic in its implicit assurance that struggle is the inevitable by-product <strong>of</strong> the<br />

co-operation <strong>of</strong> men for the purpose <strong>of</strong> capitalistic production.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> capitalist system has the “feature” that the capitalists unwittingly organize their own grave diggers, the<br />

workers. This is by no means a trivial contradiction for the capitalists. <strong>The</strong> capitalists themselves did not think <strong>of</strong><br />

it when Ford built the River Rouge plant in Detroit. This vertically integrated auto plant gave the workers so much<br />

power that future auto plants were deliberately spread out to make it more difficult for the workers to organize.<br />

(Also your discussion at the end <strong>of</strong> the term paper is not placing enough emphasis on this contradiction. “Start<br />

seeing contradictions” is one <strong>of</strong> Marx’s bumper stickers, see [2007SP:387].)<br />

This paper is an attempt to understand co-operation and will explain what we see as three<br />

concepts from the chapter central to understanding Marx’s commentary on the subject in<br />

a more holistic manner. We see these concepts as being economies <strong>of</strong> scale, the need for<br />

supervisors and what Marx called “the animal spirits.”<br />

Economies <strong>of</strong> Scale-<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> sentence <strong>of</strong> chapter 13 says: “Capitalist production only really begins, as we<br />

have already seen, when each individual capital simultaneously employs a comparatively<br />

large number <strong>of</strong> workers, and when, as a result, the labor process is carried on an extensive<br />

scale, and yields relatively large quantities <strong>of</strong> products.” From this perspective on capitalist<br />

production it is clear that capital is not found on a small family farm where everyone puts<br />

in the work to help the family unit. Equally important is that a capitalist is not made when<br />

a person hires a few workers to help out but, only when one capitalist has command <strong>of</strong> a<br />

large number <strong>of</strong> workers who are working in a common place and time in order to produce<br />

a commodity under the command direction or supervision <strong>of</strong> that capitalist.<br />

At <strong>first</strong> sight the differences are purely quantitative. Take for example the work that one<br />

man can do in 12 days working 12 hours for X amount <strong>of</strong> dollars per day. At the end <strong>of</strong> the<br />

12 days he will have worked for 144 hours total and made 12X amount <strong>of</strong> dollars. On the<br />

other hand if 12 men were to work 12 hours but for only 1 day collectively they will have<br />

worked 144 hours and made a total <strong>of</strong> 12X dollars. In both cases the capitalist who buys the<br />

labor <strong>of</strong> the men has gotten the same amount <strong>of</strong> work done and has paid the same amount for<br />

that work to be done. <strong>The</strong> question then arises then, what is the importance in the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> workers who work for a capitalist?<br />

Economies <strong>of</strong> scale show the importance in the number <strong>of</strong> workers and the capital used<br />

to supply the workers with the necessities <strong>of</strong> production. Marx uses the example <strong>of</strong> weavers<br />

to illustrate this. If one capitalist were to employ 20 weavers then he must have a workshop<br />

sufficiently large enough for all <strong>of</strong> them to work. However, if the 20 weavers were split up<br />

into 10 pairs under 10 different capitalists then they would need more room and 10 separate<br />

workshops. <strong>The</strong> ten capitalists would need to build 10 smaller workshops and then still pay<br />

the weavers their wage. In this circumstance we see that the capitalist who runs the shop <strong>of</strong><br />

20 weavers has the larger surplus <strong>of</strong> labor because <strong>of</strong> the money he saves making one larger<br />

workshop but still receives the surplus labor <strong>of</strong> 20 weavers.<br />

Marx also shares an example in agriculture <strong>of</strong> the need for the capitalist to use an economy<br />

<strong>of</strong> scale to complete his purposes. Now that there is no need for the capitalist to build a<br />

workshop for his workers considering they are working in a field, there is no capital lost in<br />

that. If the capitalist has a 100 acre farm and 1 man can harvest 1 acre per day it would take


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 361<br />

the worker 100 days to harvest the whole field. However, if the capitalist has 20 workers<br />

who work at the same rate they can collectively harvest the whole field in only 5 days. <strong>The</strong><br />

capitalist with the 20 workers once again has the larger advantage over that <strong>of</strong> only 1 or even<br />

5 workers, due to the matter <strong>of</strong> time efficiency. In the harvest there is a time limit to when<br />

the field can be harvested. If there is, for instance, only a 5 day window and the goods are<br />

not harvested within that window, they will spoil. In the case <strong>of</strong> the capitalist employing<br />

only one laborer, he would have the misfortune <strong>of</strong> losing 95 acres <strong>of</strong> harvest.<br />

Hans: You are re-telling here Marx’s examples but you are not paying enough attention to the points which Marx<br />

tries to make with these examples. <strong>The</strong>se points are (a) the labor process is super-additive, i.e., 20 workers can do<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> which 1 or 5 workers cannot do (for instance harvest a 100 acre farm in the harvest window). Scale not<br />

only gives economies but allows new <strong>thing</strong>s to happen which could not happen otherwise. On the other hand, (b)<br />

wages are only additive, not super-additive. I.e., the capitalist reaps the benefits <strong>of</strong> the co-operation without having<br />

the pay the workers for it. He has assembled a powerful organism, but he has to pay the workers only individually,<br />

as if they were working alone. So the capitalist is getting some<strong>thing</strong> for free. Of course, this power <strong>of</strong> co-operation<br />

can also turn against the capitalist. Alone, the workers are powerless against the capitalist, but if they organize, they<br />

have much more power than they usually think.<br />

Animal Spirits-<br />

Throughout Capital, Marx has taken a scientific approach to understanding economics,<br />

capitalism, and people themselves. As we’ve seen, human interaction with commodities<br />

and their properties have been one <strong>of</strong> the focuses <strong>of</strong> Capital. But the bigger picture here is<br />

much more than people and property. It is about people’s interactions with other people. In<br />

Chapter 13: Co-operation, Marx discusses the idea <strong>of</strong> “animal spirits” when explaining why<br />

he believes groups <strong>of</strong> people are so much more productive per capita than a single worker<br />

toiling in solitude.<br />

Throughout the world <strong>of</strong> team sports, endless amounts <strong>of</strong> coaches seek to explain teamwork<br />

through anecdotes illustrating the power <strong>of</strong> co-operation. I was reminded while reading<br />

chapter 13, <strong>of</strong> one such story about the strength <strong>of</strong> horses. I had a coach once who would<br />

tell <strong>of</strong> an experiment that had been done where scientists has made a horse pull on a device<br />

which would measure the amount <strong>of</strong> pulling force the horse was able to exert. <strong>The</strong>y measured<br />

three individual horses in this manner and noted each animal’s strength. <strong>The</strong>y then put<br />

the horses on the same team to pull together. Alas, the horses together produced a greater<br />

force than the individual strengths put together. This coach called it synergy and Marx calls<br />

it “animal spirits.”<br />

Marx gives his own examples in 443:3/o0. This is his <strong>first</strong> mention in the chapter about<br />

these “animal spirits.” He says that man is “at all events a social animal.” This is in contrast<br />

to Aristotle’s theory that “man is by nature a political animal.” (Politics) Aristotle’s political<br />

animal theory would have one believe that man is naturally drawn to cities, government, and<br />

that man is not self-sufficient. Marx observes that humans who work together tend to act<br />

like animals in that they compete and work harder to become the most powerful. I believe<br />

this to be true and it can be seen anywhere we look. We can observe this in this report that<br />

a group <strong>of</strong> us students have written. By putting our ideas together and each trying our best,<br />

we will probably each spend less time per capita and come out with a better paper than the<br />

average student in our group would come up with themselves. Marx explained that even in<br />

362 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

small groups, the difference in labor productivity between individual laborers is overcome<br />

in a relatively short period <strong>of</strong> time.<br />

By showing the animal-like characteristics <strong>of</strong> humans, Marx is able to let the reader step<br />

back and view humankind from the outside and side-step any bias he or she may have.<br />

Animal spirits seem to be the idea <strong>of</strong> competition. Marx realizes that this is a fact that we<br />

should be aware <strong>of</strong> and use it to the people’s advantage as the capitalists have been using it<br />

to theirs.<br />

Hans in class lecture seems to contradict Marx’s insinuations that man is an inherently<br />

competitive being and that that competitive nature will naturally result in higher production.<br />

Hans spoke <strong>of</strong> seeing workers inside a Soviet factory that appeared to be moving in slow motion<br />

and <strong>of</strong> an excess amount <strong>of</strong> workers running simple grocery store checkout operations.<br />

Much <strong>of</strong> this can certainly be attributed to unique public policy. Hans theorized that it was<br />

as a result <strong>of</strong> full employment statutes that meant even if workers were fired they would have<br />

jobs somewhere else soon after. This would seem to contradict Marx’s assertions that this is<br />

a natural feature <strong>of</strong> man. Rather, it would seem that “animal spirits” are actually the product<br />

<strong>of</strong> cultural settings and legal environment. Removing unemployment as the capitalists’ tool<br />

<strong>of</strong> punishment, it would seem there is little incentive in factories to work hard or to compete<br />

against the other “social animals.”<br />

On the Need for Supervisors<br />

In chapter 13 <strong>of</strong> Capital, Co-operation, we read how a capitalist must use managers or<br />

supervisors, once the capital production extends. Marx refers briefly to the previous chapter,<br />

in order to explain the role <strong>of</strong> a small amount <strong>of</strong> capital and how it is necessary in order for<br />

the workers employed in production to create a surplus value that will allow the employer<br />

to remove himself from manual labor instead <strong>of</strong> becoming a small master. Quantitative<br />

differences alone will lead him to become a capitalist. Marx says in 448:10: “We now see<br />

that a certain minimum amount is a material condition for conversion <strong>of</strong> numerous isolated<br />

and independent processes into one combined social process.”<br />

Hans: You didn’t quite get Marx’s point here. Marx says that initially, a capitalist had to hire a large number <strong>of</strong><br />

workers because only the addition <strong>of</strong> many workers gives him enough surplus-value that he can be a capitalist and<br />

not a worker himself. I.e., the minimum requirement comes from the relations <strong>of</strong> production. But now he has to hire<br />

many workers because the technology requires many workers. I.e., the social features <strong>of</strong> capitalism are now built<br />

into the technology. This is not the only example, and it is indeed one <strong>of</strong> the more innocuous examples. Capitalism<br />

invades other social spheres as well. It is like a tree which you can no longer get rid <strong>of</strong> because it has become part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the building you live in. (This is especially a problem when the tree is sick and moribund—as is the case with<br />

capitalism in the view <strong>of</strong> today’s Marxists.)<br />

In addition, we also read how the labor <strong>of</strong> capital is a result <strong>of</strong> the worker, not the worker<br />

working for himself, but the worker working for a capitalist. Marx explains, “That a capitalist<br />

should command in the field <strong>of</strong> production is now as indispensable as that a general<br />

should command on the field <strong>of</strong> battle” (p. 448)<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, when looking at the purpose <strong>of</strong> capitalist production, we read that it is the<br />

self-valorization <strong>of</strong> capital. Thus, the greatest possible production <strong>of</strong> surplus value requires<br />

the greatest amount <strong>of</strong> exploitation <strong>of</strong> labour-power by the capitalist. For instance, when the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> workers increases, it results in their resistance to the capitalists’ control, which


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 363<br />

then increases pressure that are put on by the capitalist, to squash this resistance. This is the<br />

role <strong>of</strong> the capitalist, who use exploitation as a social labour process. We see an example<br />

<strong>of</strong> this exampled by J. Vanderlint who states, “<strong>The</strong> function <strong>of</strong> exploitation <strong>of</strong> social labour<br />

process, is consequently condition by the unavoidable antagonism between the exploiter and<br />

the raw material <strong>of</strong> his exploitation.” (p. 449). Furthermore, Marx explains “how the cooperation<br />

<strong>of</strong> wage labourers is entirely brought about by the capital that employs them” (see<br />

page 449). He goes on to say how there becomes association between the act <strong>of</strong> capital<br />

that brings the workers together, and how the connection that is created is derived form the<br />

capitalist plan to subject their activity to his purpose.<br />

As the capitalist starts to execute his plan as the master, we read that, “An industrial army<br />

<strong>of</strong> workers under the command <strong>of</strong> a capitalist requires, like a real army, <strong>of</strong>ficers (managers)<br />

and N.C.O.s (see page 450). In this, Marx explains how in the beginning, the capitalist is<br />

released from doing labor, but, this happens only when the capital itself has reached the<br />

minimum amount when the actual capitalist production begins. Once this actually happens,<br />

the capitalist can now hand over his role as supervisor or manager <strong>of</strong> the individual workers,<br />

to a direct worker who will take his position as a “special kind <strong>of</strong> wage-laborer” according to<br />

Marx (see page 450). This individual who takes the role <strong>of</strong> the supervisor, Marx says “is now<br />

in command during the labor process in the name <strong>of</strong> capital”. <strong>The</strong>refore, when the individual<br />

worker takes position as the supervisor, the supervision now becomes the worker’s exclusive<br />

function.<br />

Message [699] referenced by [755] and [1107]. Next Message by Cougar is [732], Next Message by Guh is [840],<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [825], Next Message by Jon is [718], and Next Message by Orville is [708].<br />

Term Paper 704 is 914 in 1999SP, 814 in 2002fa, 814 in 2003fa, 814 in 2005fa, 623 in<br />

2007SP, 612 in 2008fa, and 754 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 704 Essay about Chapter Fourteen: Division <strong>of</strong> Labor and Manufacture<br />

[686] Balrog, Long, Milly, She, and Trap: Section 1:<br />

Karl Marx begins his discussion on the division <strong>of</strong> labor and manufacture by asserting<br />

manufacture is the classical form <strong>of</strong> co-operation based on the division <strong>of</strong> labor (455:1).<br />

Earlier in Capital, Marx defines co-operation as, “. . . when numerous workers work together<br />

side by side in accordance with a plan, whether in the same process, or in different but<br />

connected processes,” (443:1). Marx contends that manufacture is not natural, but rather it<br />

originates or develops in a capitalist society in one <strong>of</strong> two ways.<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> form <strong>of</strong> manufacture depicted by Marx is one in which in one workshop or factory,<br />

under the control <strong>of</strong> a single capitalist, workers skilled in various trades come together<br />

to produce a single kind <strong>of</strong> use-value (455:1). Marx uses the example <strong>of</strong> a carriage to illustrate<br />

what happens in the manufacturing setting. To produce a carriage, you will need various<br />

craftsmen, such as upholsterers, fringe-makers, painters, wheelwrights, etc. <strong>The</strong> tragedy, as<br />

Marx sees it, in this setting is that these craftsmen were all, at one point in time, experts in<br />

their field and are now solely concentrated and the tasks <strong>of</strong> the trade specifically needed for<br />

carriage manufacturing. For example, the upholsterer is not allowed to practice upholstering<br />

items other than carriages and thus loses the skill to do so. This leads the craftsmen to<br />

become what Marx terms, “partial workers” (456:1).<br />

364 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> second form <strong>of</strong> manufacture is similar to the <strong>first</strong> in that it is a conglomeration <strong>of</strong><br />

craftsmen under a single capitalist, but different because the craftsmen are all skilled in the<br />

same craft. In this production scenario, the craftmen’s tasks are divided up so that none are<br />

allowed to practice their trade in full, but rather they are each responsible for a microcosm <strong>of</strong><br />

production. <strong>The</strong>ir operations are broken down into “. . . disconnected, isolated ones.” Each<br />

man is now performing “. . . one, and only one, <strong>of</strong> the constituent partial operations” (456:2).<br />

Manufacture can therefore arise, Marx asserts, from the, “combination <strong>of</strong> various independent<br />

trades, which lost that independence and become specialized. . . [and] are reduced<br />

to. . . partial operations in the production <strong>of</strong> one particular commodity,” (457:1). Manufacture<br />

can also arise, “. . . from the co-operation <strong>of</strong> craftsmen in one particular handicraft. . . [split]<br />

up. . . into various detailed operations. . . developing their mutual independence to the point<br />

where each becomes the exclusive function <strong>of</strong> a particular worker,” (457:1). Marx closes<br />

his analysis with the proclamation that regardless <strong>of</strong> the starting point manufacture manifests<br />

from, “. . . its final form is always the same—a productive mechanism whose organs are<br />

human beings.”<br />

Marx goes on to say, even though the handicraft is decomposed in this form <strong>of</strong> cooperation,<br />

it still retains the character <strong>of</strong> a handicraft and is dependent on the worker and<br />

that many advantages can come from co-operation, just not in this form (457:2).<br />

Section 2<br />

In this section Marx discusses “the specialized worker and his tools,” he is explaining<br />

the benefits and ultimately the problems that come with the division <strong>of</strong> labor. <strong>The</strong> skilled<br />

laborer is transformed into a more efficient worker through specialization and “converts his<br />

body into the automatic, one-sided implement <strong>of</strong> that operation” (458). <strong>The</strong> partial labor<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity leads to increased labor productivity, which means that more is produced<br />

in less time than an individual could produce by himself. Because <strong>of</strong> specialization, the<br />

laborers’ work becomes monotonous, and “the concentration <strong>of</strong> his attention. . . teach him<br />

by experience how to attain the desired effect with the minimum exertion” (458). Marx then<br />

goes on to say that manufacture is not conducive to the earlier ways <strong>of</strong> life, where the skilled<br />

craftsmen would pass their knowledge down to family members or apprentices.<br />

A craftsman who produces the product from beginning to end moves around his workspace,<br />

whether to get different tools or move to a new machine, this creates breaks throughout his<br />

day, these breaks are taken away with manufacture. Marx says that the “constant labor <strong>of</strong> one<br />

uniform kind disturbs the intensity and flow <strong>of</strong> a man’s vital forces, which find recreation<br />

and delight in the change <strong>of</strong> activity itself” (460).<br />

In this section Marx admits that the division <strong>of</strong> labor is more productive, in that it allows<br />

workers to produce more in a given amount <strong>of</strong> time, because people perfect their task and<br />

work as fast as possible. However, this makes laborers’ days monotonous and much less<br />

rewarding than when they were a skilled craftsman and were able to take pride in their<br />

product as a whole. Marx discusses the pros and cons <strong>of</strong> specialized labor in order to help<br />

us look at “manufacture as a whole” (461)<br />

Section 3:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 365<br />

Marx describes that there are two fundamentally different forms <strong>of</strong> manufacturing. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

each play different roles but occasionally they are intertwined. Marx gives an example <strong>of</strong><br />

the watchmaker and argues that it can be illustrated as division <strong>of</strong> labor in manufacturing. A<br />

watch is comprised <strong>of</strong> many different parts and it takes different skills from many craftsmen<br />

create the watch. Marx asserts that one skilled craftsman can produce a watch, or by a<br />

multitude <strong>of</strong> laborers, each specializing in a particular part <strong>of</strong> the manufacture; he calls this<br />

process as the heterogeneous.<br />

Secondly, the organic process is unique because it shows the step-by-step process <strong>of</strong><br />

the different phases <strong>of</strong> manufacturing. Many different specialized workers contribute to the<br />

completion <strong>of</strong> the product. Marx describes this process as everyone is cooperatively working<br />

together to shorten the production time <strong>of</strong> a given commodity, through the isolation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

different stages <strong>of</strong> production. Some products do require more time to complete than others;<br />

in this type <strong>of</strong> situation they should employ more workers. In some processes, it may take<br />

many different workers to do one task and Marx gives the example <strong>of</strong> the glass bottle making.<br />

It is so critical that it takes five different skilled workers to form the glass and if any one <strong>of</strong><br />

them is missing, it will essentially paralyze the process.<br />

Marx compared the two forms <strong>of</strong> manufacture and concluded that each degree <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

requires different level <strong>of</strong> training in which creates hierarchy <strong>of</strong> labor-power and different<br />

level <strong>of</strong> wages. However, Marx also states that every process require a simple or little manipulation<br />

that every laborer can do. But with labor manufacture, they are now being ossified<br />

into exclusive skills <strong>of</strong> a particular laborer. <strong>The</strong>se give a classification and separation <strong>of</strong><br />

skilled or unskilled labor, which demoralize the function <strong>of</strong> labor value. On the other hand<br />

this process <strong>of</strong> manufacture diminishes the apprentices and increases the surplus value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

product for the benefit <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

Section 4:<br />

In section four Marx describes the relationship between the division <strong>of</strong> labor in society<br />

and the division <strong>of</strong> labor in manufacture. <strong>The</strong> division <strong>of</strong> labor can be separated <strong>first</strong> into<br />

categories <strong>of</strong> agriculture; manufacturing and merchants. From those categories it can be<br />

further divided into different species and then divided again into specific sub-species which<br />

are the division <strong>of</strong> tasks.<br />

On one hand the division <strong>of</strong> labor in society stems from a natural division inside a family<br />

or tribe that is physiologically based, for example an individual’s age, gender or skills. <strong>The</strong>n<br />

on the other hand it arises from the exchange <strong>of</strong> products between individual tribes or communities.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se communities each have different products and ways <strong>of</strong> production within<br />

their own unique environment. Because <strong>of</strong> these differences, when they come in contact<br />

with each other they are compelled to exchange. This creates a conversion <strong>of</strong> products into<br />

commodities.<br />

<strong>The</strong> division <strong>of</strong> labor in manufacture is where numerous, detailed operations are being<br />

performed collectively. <strong>The</strong>se specific workers do not produce commodities but only part <strong>of</strong><br />

a whole product. Marx states that the division <strong>of</strong> labor in the workplace implies the undisputed<br />

authority <strong>of</strong> the capitalist over men. <strong>The</strong> division <strong>of</strong> labor within society is different<br />

where there is only one producer creating independent commodities and who acknowledges<br />

366 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

no authority other than those in competition. In order to have a division <strong>of</strong> labor in manufacture<br />

there must already be a certain degree <strong>of</strong> development in the division <strong>of</strong> labor in society.<br />

<strong>The</strong> two have an inverse relationship with each other. <strong>The</strong> less authority that presides over<br />

the division <strong>of</strong> labor in society, the more the division <strong>of</strong> labor develops in the workplace.<br />

Section 5:<br />

Division <strong>of</strong> labor is an undeniably pr<strong>of</strong>icient way to manufacture intricate commodities.<br />

A capitalist seeking to maximize his pr<strong>of</strong>its will exploit this system and use it to squeeze<br />

every penny out <strong>of</strong> his process <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> going about production<br />

in this manner are, in general one person makes a significant pr<strong>of</strong>it while the laborers degenerate<br />

due to the simplicity and monotonous nature <strong>of</strong> their singular operation. Adam Smith<br />

commented on this subject when he stated, “<strong>The</strong> man whose whole life is spent in performing<br />

a few simple operations ... has no occasion to exert his understanding ... He generally<br />

becomes as stupid and ignorant as it is possible for a human creature to become” (Mandel<br />

483).<br />

Those once skilled craftsmen are compelled to sell their labor power to capitalist because<br />

the level <strong>of</strong> competition exceeds their production capabilities. <strong>The</strong>ir area <strong>of</strong> expertise is<br />

refined and subdivided to the point that their artifice dwindles away. <strong>The</strong>y become subject<br />

to the control <strong>of</strong> the one purchasing their labor power and become part <strong>of</strong> a, “productive<br />

mechanism whose parts are human beings” (Mandel 457).<br />

Adam Smith made a call out to avoid this manufacture approach and avoid the division <strong>of</strong><br />

labor. His desire was that workers would not have their spirits taken from them and lose all<br />

ambition due to their tedious tasks. By investing more energy into education the liveliness<br />

and innovative side <strong>of</strong> a society may be preserved. D. Urquart on the subject exclaimed, “To<br />

subdivide a man is to execute him, if he deserves the sentence, to assassinate him if he does<br />

not... <strong>The</strong> subdivision <strong>of</strong> labor is the assassination <strong>of</strong> a people”(Mandel 484-485).<br />

Although it would be attractive to exist in a society in which all were equal and had the<br />

opportunity <strong>of</strong> nurturing their minds, in a capitalistic society this is near impossible. Our<br />

innate human desire will collectively be to crave the finest <strong>of</strong> products at a bargain price. In<br />

order to accomplish such a request, division <strong>of</strong> labor must exist and workers must perfect a<br />

specified simple operation.<br />

Message [686] referenced by [755]. Next Message by Balrog is [798], Next Message by Long is [696], Next<br />

Message by Milly is [925], Next Message by She is [727], and Next Message by Trap is [744].<br />

Term Paper 705 is 515 in 1997WI, 515 in 1997sp, 915 in 1997ut, 915 in 1999SP, 815 in<br />

2002fa, 815 in 2004fa, 815 in 2005fa, 589 in 2007SP, 601 in 2007fa, 609 in 2008SP, 613<br />

in 2008fa, 642 in 2009fa, 725 in 2011fa, and 755 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 705 Essay about Chapter Fifteen: Machinery and Large-Scale Industry<br />

[862] Baseball, Kobe, and Rico: <strong>The</strong> utilization <strong>of</strong> machinery in large scale industry<br />

is a used for producing surplus-value while increasing productivity. <strong>The</strong> main purpose<br />

for machinery used in manufacturing is its ability to accomplish the same task as a single<br />

human laborer at a faster rate. Incorporating new technology into the production process<br />

jump started the Industrial Revolution <strong>of</strong> the 18th century. Machinery consists <strong>of</strong> multiple


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 367<br />

parts/components and to help us understand, Marx analyzes the three essentially different<br />

parts: the motor, mechanism, the transmitting mechanism, and lastly the tool or working<br />

machine. First is the motor, which is the lone energy source <strong>of</strong> the machine. It can generate<br />

its own power or receive a driving force from a natural energy force such as water<br />

or wind. Next, the transmitting mechanism encompasses the moving parts <strong>of</strong> the machine<br />

that regulate motion (wheels, pulleys, gears, ropes, straps, etc.). Using linear, circular and<br />

other ranges <strong>of</strong> motion, the machine manipulates products and transforms it as the company<br />

desires. <strong>The</strong> machine is able to replace a worker, who would work a particular job with a<br />

single tool. With an apparatus the task can be accomplished at a faster rate and with many<br />

<strong>of</strong> the same tools. Marx believed that this last element, over the entirety <strong>of</strong> the “machine”<br />

is what sparked the industrial revolution <strong>of</strong> the 18th century. <strong>The</strong> industrial revolution was<br />

just that, a revolution <strong>of</strong> industry. Machines were created and brought into factories to produce<br />

commodities both higher in quantity and at a faster rate which would then be sold on<br />

the market. Consequently, at the same time these mechanisms benefited the circulation <strong>of</strong><br />

capital in the market economy, they replaced workers who, at that time, had only a handful<br />

<strong>of</strong> skills. <strong>The</strong> lightening <strong>of</strong> labor for the worker can turn in to an “instrument <strong>of</strong> torture,” in<br />

the words <strong>of</strong> Marx. It does not free a worker from work but rather it removes the work itself.<br />

“<strong>The</strong> machine, which is the starting-point <strong>of</strong> the industrial revolution, replaces the worker,<br />

who handles a single tool, by a mechanism operating with a number <strong>of</strong> similar tools and set<br />

in motion by a single motive power, whatever the form <strong>of</strong> that power (Capital p. 497).”<br />

To understand the difference Marx discusses between machines and tools a distinction<br />

between the two is in order. Marx critiques the definition <strong>of</strong> some people that for a tool, man<br />

is the motive power, whereas the power behind a machine is a natural force independent<br />

<strong>of</strong> man (an animal, wind, water, electricity). This would imply that a plough drawn by an<br />

ox would be a machine, and a loom creating silk at incredible speed, powered by a single<br />

worker, is a tool. On page 495 in Capital, Marx defines a machine thus, “<strong>The</strong> machine,<br />

therefore, is a mechanism that, after being set in motion, performs with its tools the same<br />

operation as the worker formerly did with similar tools. Whether the motive power is derived<br />

from man, or in turn from a machine, makes no difference.”<br />

Although machinery creates larger amounts <strong>of</strong> commodities at a faster rate, it creates no<br />

newly added value. This is some<strong>thing</strong> which only labor power can do. <strong>The</strong> machine itself<br />

does not “drive out” the tool once used by man, but rather the tool expands and multiplies.<br />

Simply, large scale industry has taken the productivity to a new level by combining new<br />

fast paced technology with the production process. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the machinery is therefore<br />

yielded into the product and remains within that product until its value has depleted.<br />

With the machine introduced into the setting <strong>of</strong> factories, the tools <strong>of</strong> the worker fade and<br />

his skills are handed <strong>of</strong>f to the machine. <strong>The</strong> division <strong>of</strong> labor is still present in the factory,<br />

but it is geared more toward capitalist production. <strong>The</strong> job <strong>of</strong> the human worker is divided<br />

into three groups created to assist the new mechanisms. <strong>The</strong> different divisions consist <strong>of</strong><br />

those workers who are employed on the machines and those who attend to the machines for<br />

maintenance.<br />

As Marx states there is a struggle between worker and machine. This struggle between<br />

capitalist and wage-labourer starts as existing capital-relation itself and continues on through<br />

the period <strong>of</strong> manufacture. <strong>The</strong> material foundation <strong>of</strong> the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production<br />

causes the laborer to revolt against this means <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong> instrument <strong>of</strong> labour, in<br />

368 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the form <strong>of</strong> a machine immediately becomes a competitor to the worker himself, this causes<br />

the use-vaue <strong>of</strong> the worker’s labor power to disappear as well as its exchange value. You<br />

can see this in some <strong>of</strong> today’s jobs as new technology is increasingly taking jobs <strong>of</strong> human<br />

laborers. This raises productivity and lowers the demand for human labor, at this time this is<br />

when humans revolt, no one likes their jobs being taken away. Not only do we see a decrease<br />

in human labor demand but this also affects wages. Machinery is the most powerful tool in<br />

lessening the chance <strong>of</strong> strikes among workers. With a decrease in human labor demand,<br />

laborers know they could not have the same bargaining power when there is machinery that<br />

can do the same jobs as they.<br />

<strong>The</strong> compensation theory, with regard to the workers displaced by machinery, discusses<br />

some important ideas. Workers, when driven out <strong>of</strong> the workshop by machinery are then<br />

thrown into the labour market. This increase in labor supply increases the labor power at<br />

the disposal <strong>of</strong> capitalist exploitation. It is a fact that machinery is not responsible for “setting<br />

free” the worker from means <strong>of</strong> subsistence, it does cheapen and increase production in<br />

the sector it is related to. Machinery may take some human laborer’s jobs in some sectors<br />

but increase the labor in other sectors as the demand rises in other industries. As the use<br />

<strong>of</strong> machinery extends in a given industry the immediate effect is to increase production in<br />

the other industries that prodvide the laborers with means <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong> immediate<br />

result <strong>of</strong> machinery is to augment surplus value. Due to machinery the increase in the productivity<br />

<strong>of</strong> large scale industry, as being more intensive and extensive exloitation <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

power in all facets <strong>of</strong> production permits a larger part <strong>of</strong> the working class to be employed<br />

unproductively.<br />

Respectful representatives <strong>of</strong> political economy agree that the introduction <strong>of</strong> new machinery<br />

has a baneful effect on the workers in old handicrafts. As long as machinery production<br />

expands in a certain branch <strong>of</strong> an industry at the expense <strong>of</strong> the human laborers, the<br />

result is increadily certain. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> period, which machinery overtakes human labor is very<br />

important, owing to the extraordinary pr<strong>of</strong>its that it helps produce. This increases a company’s<br />

accumulation and attracts a larger share <strong>of</strong> the additional social capital this is being<br />

created and seeking out new areas <strong>of</strong> investment. This is an area which is watched now by<br />

the government due to the chance <strong>of</strong> monopolies that can be created.<br />

With developments <strong>of</strong> the factory systems and the revolution <strong>of</strong> agriculture that comes<br />

along with it, production in all other areas <strong>of</strong> industry expand, this causes it to alter in<br />

character and impact domestic industries. <strong>The</strong> exploitation <strong>of</strong> cheap labor power is carried<br />

out in a more abrupt manner in modern manufacture than in the factory proper. This is<br />

caused by the substitution <strong>of</strong> machines for manpower, and as we know character <strong>of</strong> labor is<br />

entirely absent in machine manufacturing.<br />

<strong>The</strong> transition from Modern Manufacture and Domestic Industry to Large scale industry<br />

is caused from the cheapening <strong>of</strong> labor pwer. This is caused through abuse <strong>of</strong> labor from both<br />

women and children. This is done through robbery <strong>of</strong> all normal working conditions needed<br />

for working and living and through them being overworkered and forced to work during<br />

night hours. This finally comes up against certain insuperable natural obstacles. This is true<br />

for the cheapening <strong>of</strong> commodities as well as capitalist exploitation in general which are<br />

results <strong>of</strong> these foundations. One example given is the production <strong>of</strong> clo<strong>thing</strong> appareal, we


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 369<br />

see this on a massive scale through Amercican companies that own “sweat shops” overseas<br />

that abuse employees in order to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it. As stated the revolution in the social mode<br />

<strong>of</strong> production which is the necessary product <strong>of</strong> the revolution in the means <strong>of</strong> production is<br />

accomplished though varying medlies <strong>of</strong> transitional forms. <strong>The</strong>se forms vary depending on<br />

the industries that the new machinery effect. One <strong>of</strong> the essential conditions for existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the factory system, when the length <strong>of</strong> the work day is fixed, is certainty in the result,<br />

meaning the production in a given time <strong>of</strong> a given quantity <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

As we have seen, large scale industy sweeps away by technical means the division <strong>of</strong><br />

labor characteristic <strong>of</strong> manufacture, under which each man is bound for life to a specialized<br />

operation. At the same time the capitalist form <strong>of</strong> large scale industry reproduces this same<br />

divison <strong>of</strong> labor in a huge way, we see this in the factory proper as workers are converted<br />

into a living appendage <strong>of</strong> the machine in which he/she operates. In modern industry it<br />

never views the existing form <strong>of</strong> a production process as the definitive one. <strong>The</strong> basis is<br />

revolutionary allowing for adnvancement in technology and machinery, this is opposed to<br />

earlier views as modes <strong>of</strong> production were conservative.<br />

Next Message by Baseball is [980], Next Message by Kobe is [872], and Next Message by Rico is [995].<br />

Term Paper 706 is 602 in 2007fa, 614 in 2008fa, 643 in 2009fa, and 757 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 706 Essay about Chapter Sixteen: Absolute and Relative Surplus Value<br />

[926] Lana and Lindsey: Chapter 16 summary. In chapter 16 Marx defines absolute and<br />

relative surplus-value and illustrates how surplus-value comes about in capitalist production.<br />

He also gives us a historical background <strong>of</strong> capitalist exploitation and further develops the<br />

idea <strong>of</strong> productive labor introduced earlier in Capital.<br />

Marx <strong>first</strong> outlines how labor is a part <strong>of</strong> the production process. Productive capitalist<br />

labor is collective labor. <strong>The</strong> labor is divided and each laborer performs a subordinate function<br />

<strong>of</strong> the labor process. Capitalist production is both the production <strong>of</strong> commodities and<br />

the production <strong>of</strong> surplus-value. <strong>The</strong> production process is a social relation in which the<br />

productive worker produces surplus-value for the capitalist, thus “contributing to the selfvalorization<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital”. In other words, the worker helps create value using the capitalist’s<br />

original capital. This social relation benefits the capitalist but harms the worker.<br />

Marx defines absolute surplus value as the work that the worker does to produce more<br />

value in commodities than the value <strong>of</strong> his labor-power. <strong>The</strong> working day is divided into<br />

necessary labor and surplus labor, previously defined as the labor necessary for the worker’s<br />

subsistence and the extra unpaid labor the worker performs for the capitalist, respectively.<br />

<strong>The</strong> division allows the capitalist to create relative surplus-value by increasing worker productivity,<br />

thus making the amount <strong>of</strong> time to create a value equal to the worker’s wage shorter<br />

and the surplus-labor time longer.<br />

Next Marx gives a brief historical overview <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> the capitalist exploiters<br />

beginning from individual producers who are given more means <strong>of</strong> production by<br />

early capitalists and are thus turned subordinate to the capitalists. Under a capitalist system<br />

this exploitation becomes the norm and production becomes a universal method to create<br />

surplus-value. <strong>The</strong> capitalist production process continues to create relative surplus-value<br />

370 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

by converting industries one-by-one into this means <strong>of</strong> production and by revolutionizing<br />

the methods <strong>of</strong> production and creating technology to increase the relative surplus-value.<br />

In order to increase the surplus-value, the working day must be lengthened, maintaining<br />

the same necessary labor-time while increasing surplus labor-time, or the worker must be<br />

more productive (through technology or other innovations) so that more commodities are<br />

created in the same working day and the necessary labor-time shrinks while the surplus<br />

labor-time increases. If necessary labor time takes up the whole working day, capitalism<br />

cannot exist. While workers subsist on the value <strong>of</strong> their labor power over the period <strong>of</strong><br />

necessary labor time, capitalists subsist on the surplus-value created by workers.<br />

<strong>The</strong> less the worker’s necessary labor-time to produce their means <strong>of</strong> subsistence, the<br />

greater the time they can work for others and thus be exploited by capitalists. Marx gives<br />

natural endowments as an example <strong>of</strong> how one group’s necessary labor time can be inherently<br />

less than another’s and thus the <strong>first</strong> group is more useful for the valorization <strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

Social pressure coerces the worker who requires a small amount <strong>of</strong> necessary labor time to<br />

use his free time to work for others.<br />

Marx concludes his discussion with a criticism <strong>of</strong> the bourgeois economists’ interpretation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the production process and the creation <strong>of</strong> surplus-value. Mill and other bourgeois<br />

economists are mistaken by thinking that pr<strong>of</strong>it (or surplus value) is created by the longevity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the products over the time it takes to make them and it is created whether or not commodities<br />

are exchanged. Marx points out that this is impossible because commodities that<br />

last a short amount <strong>of</strong> time (such as bread) would reap no pr<strong>of</strong>it because they take longer<br />

to produce than they last, and we can plainly see that a bread maker is pr<strong>of</strong>itable despite<br />

the lack <strong>of</strong> longevity <strong>of</strong> his commodity. Mill also calculates the rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it incorrectly<br />

because he does not account for the initial capital investment. Mill believes that the worker<br />

is compensated for surplus labor-time later on while Marx points out that surplus-labor is<br />

never paid for and that it is how capitalists can make a pr<strong>of</strong>it without working.<br />

Next Message by Lana is [944] and Next Message by Lindsey is [1103].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 709 is 823 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 709 Why do machines not add new value to the product?<br />

[706] Ferox: graded B Machines—Tools <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Domination. If machines truly<br />

could create value, there would be less need for humans to remain working and life would be<br />

much more relaxed while the machines did all the labour. Far from a glorious mechanized<br />

utopia, we find ourselves becoming slaves to machines—the mere fact that work can be done<br />

more efficiently and quicker with the aid <strong>of</strong> machines ramps up the expected productivity <strong>of</strong><br />

the worker. This is why despite advances in technology since Marx’s time, the working day<br />

continues to be very long.<br />

Considering the relationship between the worker and the machine, a machine cannot act<br />

independently and with directed will. Even the most sophisticated computers in machines<br />

can only act on given instructions, e.g. a welding robot will not one day begin to start brewing<br />

beer on the assembly line, as it only has instructions for how to weld. <strong>The</strong> machine—<br />

while the product <strong>of</strong> labor and therefore an object <strong>of</strong> value—is merely a tool for directing the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 371<br />

volition and labour energies <strong>of</strong> a worker towards the production <strong>of</strong> values for the capitalist.<br />

Machines shorten the necessary labor time needed to produce a product. However, since<br />

the capitalist owns the machines, and the capitalist’s end goal is surplus value, the worker is<br />

forced to spend his work day producing much more value for the capitalist. Thus, machines<br />

in capitalism becomes implements <strong>of</strong> oppression, turning the workers into subjugates to the<br />

machines.<br />

Hans: You are discussing two issues at the same time: machines which are not robots versus machines which are<br />

robots, and machines owned by capitalists versus machines controlled by the workers themselves.<br />

On the other hand you are also answering two different question: the question whether machines create value<br />

is not the same as the question whether machines shorten the workday <strong>of</strong> the laborer.<br />

You correctly say that machines do not shorten the workday for the worker because they are owned by capitalists.<br />

But the other <strong>thing</strong> you are saying, that machines do not create value because they are not robots, is incorrect.<br />

Robots don’t create value either.<br />

Next Message by Ferox is [769].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 710 is 731 in 2011fa and 761 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 710 Both the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity and the mystification <strong>of</strong> the<br />

wage form are important pillars <strong>of</strong> capitalism. How are these two pillars related to each<br />

other?<br />

[727] She: graded A Pillars <strong>of</strong> Deception. <strong>The</strong> fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities and<br />

the mystification <strong>of</strong> wages are related to each other in the fact that in Marx’s beliefs, they are<br />

both components <strong>of</strong> the powerful veil that keep the relations out <strong>of</strong> sight and out <strong>of</strong> mind.<br />

Marx’s theory is heavily rooted in the idea that all participants in the capitalist system are<br />

blind to what is truly going on. He believes there are surface relationships and phenomena<br />

that appear at <strong>first</strong> as some<strong>thing</strong> they truly are not. He begins many <strong>of</strong> his passages and<br />

important sections <strong>of</strong> Capital with phrases like, “on the surface appears” or “at <strong>first</strong> appears”<br />

but always begins his intricate process <strong>of</strong> abstraction to show how the initial appearance is<br />

wrong. Hans explains in [326] that Marx and Hegel believed the world is full <strong>of</strong> contradictions,<br />

such as the surface appearances <strong>of</strong> commodities and wages. Marx believed that these<br />

contradictions, as well as others, form the pillars <strong>of</strong> capitalism. <strong>The</strong>y form the structure,<br />

the housing; without these misconceptions and without the confusion, capitalism would not<br />

work. Marx believes that these misleading surface interactions rooted in the mode <strong>of</strong> production<br />

(capitalism) produce ideas and consciousness in the people living in the system. <strong>The</strong><br />

people accept the mode <strong>of</strong> production, and all <strong>of</strong> its surface relations, as given. This is what<br />

Marx believes actually imprisons and enslaves the workers in the capitalist system.<br />

Message [727] referenced by [2011fa:950] and [2012fa:1014]. Next Message by She is [806].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 711 is 77 in 1996ut, 83 in 1997WI, 363 in 1997sp, 361 in 1997ut, 525 in 2002fa,<br />

545 in 2003fa, 599 in 2004fa, 552 in 2005fa, 625 in 2007SP, 605 in 2007fa, 613 in<br />

2008SP, 617 in 2008fa, 648 in 2009fa, 730 in 2011fa, 760 in 2012fa, and 711 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 711 Your employer gives you your paycheck. How do you know your pay is based<br />

on your labor and not your labor-power (and why does it matter)?<br />

[730] Orville: graded C+ I’m not Paying for That! To put it simply, you are paid for<br />

your labor because you are paid for your work, not for the full cost <strong>of</strong> producing that labor.<br />

372 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

To be paid for your labor-power, you would have to be paid for every<strong>thing</strong> in your life which<br />

it is necessary to produce that labor. That would include not only your cost to get to and<br />

from the job-site but food, rent, education, all the costs <strong>of</strong> living and reproducing. Because<br />

most wages are paid in on an hourly, yearly, or piece-meal basis, it is clear capitalists are not<br />

paying workers for their labor power but their labor. To paraphrase [2008fa:833], this has<br />

to be the case for our system <strong>of</strong> capitalism. <strong>The</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> capitalism requires this to happen<br />

to make pr<strong>of</strong>its. <strong>The</strong> capitalists aren’t held accountable for their lack <strong>of</strong> compassion for the<br />

working class. <strong>The</strong>ir only limit is the point at which workers rebel or form unions or strike.<br />

Even with these threats, the working class is massively underpaid for their labor. This just<br />

goes to show how much power the capitalist class has. <strong>The</strong>y pay workers for their labor<br />

because it is cheaper than paying workers for labor-power and they know there is little threat<br />

<strong>of</strong> a working class uprising.<br />

Message [730] referenced by [765]. Next Message by Orville is [1065].<br />

[731] Kaush: Labor and Labor-power. An employee may not know his or her pay<br />

is based on labor or labor-power because an employee’s wage is measured and based on<br />

a worker’s output or hours worked. Thus the form <strong>of</strong> payment and selling the labor by<br />

the worker gives the impression the worker is selling his labor, not his labor power. This<br />

method <strong>of</strong> paying for labor performed by a capitalist is socially acknowledged and robs <strong>of</strong>f<br />

the worker from being paid for labor-power that includes expense reimbursement for time<br />

spent getting ready to work.<br />

To know whether your pay is based on your labor or your labor-power matters because<br />

the difference between the two forms <strong>of</strong> payments represents hidden exploitation. Since the<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> exploitation is hidden, it enables capitalism to function.<br />

Message [731] referenced by [765]. Next Message by Kaush is [827].<br />

[765] Hans: Selling one’s Labor-Power is Not a Good Thing. Answers [730] and [731]<br />

say that unfortunately we are only paid for our work, and that it would be better if we were<br />

paid the full value <strong>of</strong> our labor-power because then we would get more money.<br />

Marx says exactly the opposite: that we would be better <strong>of</strong>f if we would get paid for<br />

our work (in the sense <strong>of</strong>: getting an equivalent <strong>of</strong> the value our work produces), because<br />

our labor produces many more dollars worth <strong>of</strong> goods than are necessary for a customary<br />

working-class existence. Even though our pay is based on our labor, it is not the full reimbursement<br />

<strong>of</strong> the value created by this labor, but it is just enough that our weekly pay allows<br />

us to reproduce our labor-power.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is so much discussion <strong>of</strong> this question in the archives that it becames difficult to<br />

wade through it. That is why I tried to give a basic explanation in [Answer:7].<br />

Next Message by Hans is [774].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 717 is 604 in 2004fa, 557 in 2005fa, 630 in 2007SP, 610 in 2007fa, 618 in<br />

2008SP, 737 in 2011fa, and 767 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 717 Marx says that labor cannot have value because it is the source which gives<br />

every<strong>thing</strong> its value. How can labor give some<strong>thing</strong> which it doesn’t have?<br />

[718] Jon: Labor is to Value as Sun is to Shadow. Hans uses the analogy given by<br />

a student to more helpfully understand how it is that Labor can give a commodity value


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 373<br />

but labor itself has no value. <strong>The</strong> analogy is the following: Labor is the cause <strong>of</strong> value in<br />

commodities, but cannot in itself have value; as the sun is the cause <strong>of</strong> shadows but cannot<br />

in itself have a shadow. <strong>The</strong> reason that the labor has no value is best explained in the<br />

annotations on page 529 when it says: “In order to have a value, you not only need labor but<br />

also some use-value in which this labor is materialized” This is also shown in Capital in the<br />

<strong>first</strong> footnote <strong>of</strong> chapter 19 on page 675:2 in which Mr. Ricardo explains how the value <strong>of</strong><br />

labor is estimated by the quantity <strong>of</strong> labor or in other words labor-power which is required<br />

to produce the wages the worker receives through his labor power, and not labor alone.<br />

Next Message by Jon is [1082].<br />

[738] Rico: Electricity and Light. After contemplating an argument, I thought <strong>of</strong> my<br />

lamp, which is producing light as I study. <strong>The</strong> electricity needed to produce the chemical<br />

reaction in my florescent bulb does not produce light itself, yet it simply is the source which<br />

gives the bulb its ability to produce light. This is also the case with labor and value.<br />

Marx says that labor cannot have value because its the source that gives every<strong>thing</strong> its<br />

value. Chris in [2007SP:1116] refers to an analogy from Marx, where he says, “. . . the<br />

Sun cannot have a shadow, yet is the cause for every<strong>thing</strong> else to have a shadow. This is<br />

the same way that Labor is able to give some<strong>thing</strong> which it does not have.” This is fairly<br />

straightforward, but one may still question, if labor cannot have value, then how can labor<br />

give some<strong>thing</strong> which is does not have? <strong>The</strong> answer is that labor power is used and measured<br />

to create value during production. Labor power creates marketplace value.<br />

<strong>The</strong> sun (labor) does not produce the shadow, yet it is the object (labor power) that casts<br />

the shadow (value).<br />

Next Message by Rico is [809].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 719 is 633 in 2007SP, 613 in 2007fa, 621 in 2008SP, 625 in 2008fa, 656 in<br />

2009fa, and 739 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 719 If labor cannot have value, does this mean labor is not a commodity?<br />

[715] JSmits: graded A Labor is not a commodity. After reading the annotations and<br />

looking at previous responses it seems as though the question’s answer is very “flexible” as<br />

to whether or not labor is a commodity. It can be argued both ways but I don’t think that<br />

labor is a commodity because <strong>of</strong> Marx’s statement in 675:3. Labor cannot be traded as a<br />

commodity because labor has no value and it can’t be traded on the markets according to<br />

Marx.<br />

In 675:3 Marx says, “If labor were to be sold as a commodity in the market, it would<br />

have to exist before being sold.” Hans says that this statement has a deeper reason than just<br />

labor can’t be traded on the markets. He is saying that once the laborer starts working for his<br />

employer his labor no longer belongs to him. He is excluded from the production process.<br />

So that labor never really existed because it never belonged to him. If he was independent,<br />

had access to the means <strong>of</strong> production, he would be able to sell his product and not be a<br />

laborer. But since he is not involved in the production process his labor can’t be sold as a<br />

commodity.<br />

Message [715] referenced by [723]. Next Message by JSmits is [749].<br />

374 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[716] Atticus: graded A Labor is the Use-Value <strong>of</strong> Labor-Power. Labor is not a commodity.<br />

It has no value. It can be compared with a use-value that one derives from a commodity.<br />

How much use-value a person derives from his commodity is similar to how much<br />

labor a capitalist derives from the commodity, labor-power, that she has purchased. Laborpower<br />

has value like a commodity but its use-value, labor, cannot be measured in quantifiable<br />

terms.<br />

Hans: Use-values can be measured, the problem is only that different use-values cannot be measured on the same<br />

scale.<br />

Message [716] referenced by [752]. Next Message by Atticus is [869].<br />

[717] Scholar: Yes, labor is not commodity, it’s only a process that labor power be used.<br />

Labor power is a commodity, and after the labor power has been sold out in the labor market<br />

by its owner laborer, like any other kinds <strong>of</strong> commodity, the labor power’s use value—<br />

labor—then belongs to its buyer—the capitalist. Althouth the labor itself have no value, the<br />

use <strong>of</strong> it—the labor process can create new value, which is embodied in the commodity that<br />

is produced by the labor process, and this value whenever how much, never belongs to the<br />

laborer himself, but belongs to the capitalist—owner and user <strong>of</strong> the labor power.<br />

Message [717] referenced by [752]. Next Message by Scholar is [1013].<br />

[722] Kobe: Labor is or is not a commodity. Labor is not a commodity. A commodity<br />

must be able to have an independent existence in order to become a commodity rather than<br />

labor. In order for a some<strong>thing</strong> to have value it must be expressed in the market place,<br />

this would give the commodity or service the concept <strong>of</strong> value, not just labor. One reason<br />

labor is not a commodity is because “labor” does not exist before being put on the market<br />

place in order to be sold, this fact alone is the determinant in whether labor is referred to as<br />

labor or a commodity. One circumstance that would allow the laborer to sell “labor” as a<br />

commodity is if he/she had access to the means <strong>of</strong> production, this would give the laborer<br />

the independent existence which would then place the laborer as a seller <strong>of</strong> his labor. Any<br />

way you slice it labor does not have value or an independent existence which means labor is<br />

not a commodity.<br />

Next Message by Kobe is [723].<br />

[723] Kobe: reply to Jsmits labor is not a commodity. After reading JSmits submission<br />

[715] and Jsmits saying it is very “flexible” as to whether or not labor can be a commodity<br />

I agree, somewhat. I did find the readings a little tricky in determining the exact reason as<br />

to whether labor is a commodity. <strong>The</strong> term “flexible” leaves the door open to labor being a<br />

commodity after Marx states that in order for labor to be a commodity it “must have to exist<br />

before being sold.” Marx describes this as an independent existence. Knowing this I do not<br />

believe it is “flexible” in determining if labor is a commodity. I do agree when JSmits says<br />

he doesn’t think labor is a commodity and like the quote he used by Marx when he talks<br />

about the laborer working for an employer and therefore the labor no longer belongs to him,<br />

rather the employer.<br />

Hans: To me this was a very helpful explanation how JSmits came to impression that it was “flexible” whether<br />

labor is a commodity.<br />

Next Message by Kobe is [745].<br />

[737] Phayze: graded A+ History <strong>of</strong> an identity crisis: labor is not a commodity. Labor<br />

is neither value nor a commodity. Labor has a two-fold character; to produce a use-value and<br />

the value-quasi material <strong>of</strong> a commodity. <strong>The</strong> value-quasi material is the common property


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 375<br />

or “substance” inherent within all commodities that give them value. Labor is therefore the<br />

impetus <strong>of</strong> value. <strong>The</strong> need for use-values generates labor to create commodities that fulfill<br />

a human need or want.<br />

Commodities <strong>of</strong> equal value are exchanged on the market by means <strong>of</strong> “equal exchange”<br />

through direct barter (C-C). As markets expand and trading grows there is an increase <strong>of</strong><br />

varying commodities which facilitates an acceleration in trade. To curb the complexities<br />

<strong>of</strong> trade, societies implement money as a universal equivalent with a stable value that can<br />

be traded to acquire all other commodities (C-M-C). <strong>The</strong> magical character <strong>of</strong> money to<br />

purchase any commodity along with the mandates <strong>of</strong> the circulation process, creates a desire<br />

to hoard. <strong>The</strong> temptation to sell a commodity for more than its labor value assists in the<br />

development <strong>of</strong> a merchant class. Commodities are now purchased only to be sold for more<br />

than their value (M-C-M). This denotes an unequal exchange, in which more money was<br />

acquired in the aftermath <strong>of</strong> the exchange (M-C-M’). A pr<strong>of</strong>it is generated by the merchant<br />

class, which is soon nulled by the regulation <strong>of</strong> market forces.<br />

Unless a merchant holds a monopoly <strong>of</strong> a specific commodity, the transparency <strong>of</strong> economic<br />

integration eliminates the merchant who sells the commodity for more than its value,<br />

by replacing her with producers who sell similar commodities for their labor value. <strong>The</strong><br />

desire to pr<strong>of</strong>it from inequality hails the arrival <strong>of</strong> the capitalists, who seek to pr<strong>of</strong>it from<br />

the sphere <strong>of</strong> production rather than the surface relations <strong>of</strong> exchange. <strong>The</strong> laborer sells her<br />

“labor-power”, or capacity to do work, for a wage. <strong>The</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> money paid to the laborer<br />

does not correspond with the amount <strong>of</strong> value created by her labor. If the capitalist were to<br />

pay her for the amount <strong>of</strong> value she produced, he would not accrue any pr<strong>of</strong>it, which would<br />

thus entail an equal exchange. But the conniving capitalist pursues an unequal exchange, and<br />

seeks to rob her <strong>of</strong> the value she creates by means <strong>of</strong> exploitation. As Hans notes, “If workers<br />

and capitalists think that the worker is selling labor and not labor-power, exploitation<br />

becomes invisible—because all labor appears as paid labor.” <strong>The</strong> laborer is forced to accept<br />

the unequal exchange <strong>of</strong> wage-labor because the capitalist owns the means <strong>of</strong> production, or<br />

the land, infrastructure, and tools used to accrue wealth.<br />

Labor is treated by the capitalist in a similar manner as if it were a commodity, but labor<br />

is not itself a commodity. Hans notes that Marx’s realism implies that “that which gives<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s value cannot itself have value”. This line <strong>of</strong> logic which applies to labor, is used in<br />

the same sense as the cosmological argument, in which creationists claim that God created<br />

man but God himself cannot and was not created...<br />

First Message by Phayze is [508].<br />

[752] Hans: Two elevator speeches why labor isn’t a commodity. Marx says emphatically<br />

that labor is not a commodity, and he gives so many reasons to back it up that the<br />

message itself gets a little blurred. So what is the best one-sentence explanation, the best<br />

elevator speech, why labor is not a commodity?<br />

Atticus [716] says labor is the use-value <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong> that is traded as a commodity<br />

(namely <strong>of</strong> labor-power) but is not a commodity itself. This is a convincing answer to me<br />

but let me play the devil’s advocate for a minute and ask Atticus: why does being a use-value<br />

disqualify labor from being a commodity? Don’t we buy all commodities for the sake <strong>of</strong> their<br />

use-values? Of course, Atticus could strike down my naive objection with the thunderbolt <strong>of</strong><br />

376 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

a direct Marx quote from 126:1, literally from the <strong>first</strong> page <strong>of</strong> Capital: “this usefulness does<br />

not dangle in mid-air” but one needs the body <strong>of</strong> the commodity in order to take advantage<br />

<strong>of</strong> its use-value. In the case <strong>of</strong> labor, the capitalist needs the person <strong>of</strong> the laborer in order to<br />

take advantage <strong>of</strong> the use-value <strong>of</strong> his or her labor, i.e., the capitalist has to hire the laborer—<br />

but this is the purchase <strong>of</strong> labor-power, not <strong>of</strong> labor itself. In Marx’s words “if labor were to<br />

be sold as a commodity in the market, it would have to exist before being sold” [675:3], but<br />

the labor has no existence without the laborer, and the laborer cannot extricate himself from<br />

this connection by <strong>first</strong> using his labor to produce a commodity and then sell the commodity<br />

without having to sell himself because he has no access to the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

I find Scholar’s elevator speech in [717] is equallly convincing: Scholar simply says that<br />

labor is a process. When reading this I thought: wow, this is such a simple explanation, why<br />

doesn’t Marx say this—or does he? Indeed, Marx says some<strong>thing</strong> similar in 677:3/oo: He<br />

says that labor is the function <strong>of</strong> labor-power, and that labor-power exists in the person <strong>of</strong><br />

the laborer. He does not explicitly say but it is clearly implied here that labor-power can be<br />

sold as a commodity because it has this existence in the person (i.e., in order to purchase<br />

labor-power you hire the laborer). In the same place, Marx also says that labor-power is as<br />

different from its function, namely labor, as a machine is different from its operation. <strong>The</strong><br />

words “function” and “operation” refer to processes; and the problem with processes is that<br />

you cannot just hand over a process from one person to the next, you need a <strong>thing</strong>. In this<br />

sense, Scholar’s elevator makes the same point as Atticus’s.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [755].<br />

[842] Fisher: Labor cannot have value because it is the cause <strong>of</strong> value. I like the example<br />

by a past student claiming that the sun makes shadows but cannot be a shadow itsself.<br />

Labor creates a commodity and causes it to have a value for which it can be exchanged or<br />

purchased. <strong>The</strong>refore labor does not have a value but gives us a use value out <strong>of</strong> whatever it<br />

creates. However, in some cases labor may be a commodity if it’s a specialized labor.<br />

Next Message by Fisher is [1012].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 720 is 226 in 1995ut, 250 in 1996sp, 248 in 1996ut, 301 in 1997WI, 367<br />

in 1997sp, 491 in 2001fa, 530 in 2002fa, 551 in 2003fa, 607 in 2004fa, 560 in 2005fa,<br />

634 in 2007SP, 614 in 2007fa, 626 in 2008fa, 740 in 2011fa, and 769 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 720 Why can the laborer not use her labor-power to produce commodities<br />

and sell them, instead <strong>of</strong> selling her labor-power?<br />

[864] Lindsey: Late Extra Credit: No Means. I didn’t get a chance to look over the<br />

exam questions before Thursday and submit an extra credit, but I wanted to try to answer<br />

one anyway: number 720.<br />

<strong>The</strong> reason that laborers cannot use their labor power to produce commodities on their<br />

own and sell them instead <strong>of</strong> selling their labor power is that they don’t have access to the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production. In order to make enough money for subsistence they have to sell their<br />

labor power to a capitalist who has the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Nowadays some laborers actually do use their own labor power to produce and sell commodities<br />

because they gain the means <strong>of</strong> production and start a “small business” where they<br />

are the only worker. However, <strong>of</strong>ten once this type <strong>of</strong> small business becomes successful,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 377<br />

the laborer suddenly has enough demand and means <strong>of</strong> production that they hire an employee.<br />

This converts them to a small-scale capitalist. Laborers that can use their own labor<br />

power and sell commodities are rare because they <strong>of</strong>ten cannot compete against the capitalists<br />

who can sell their items cheaper because they are exploiting workers or because this<br />

type <strong>of</strong> laborer is successful and then becomes a capitalist.<br />

Hans: This is a good answer but sorry, the extra credit time is over. You can get extra credit grades by term paper<br />

discussions and in other ways, see [755].<br />

Message [864] referenced by [871]. Next Message by Lindsey is [926].<br />

[871] Hans: Why workers usually cannot become capitalists. Lindsey [864] gives the<br />

answer which I have been emphasizing in class: the workers cannot use their own laborpower<br />

because they don’t have access to means <strong>of</strong> production. Of course, Lindsey is right,<br />

people still are trying; working-class people start their own businesses all the time. Lots<br />

<strong>of</strong> these businesses go bankrupt. But until very recently US bankruptcy courts were quite<br />

lenient, allowing the entrepreneur to shed their debts with a chapter 7 bankruptcy and then<br />

try again. I.e., the legal system is in favor <strong>of</strong> small capitalists. Still we do not see the<br />

much-touted ownership society with everybody being a capitalist, but we see very skewed<br />

in worsening income inequality.<br />

I have come up with three structural features <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system which work against<br />

new entrepreneurs:<br />

(a) <strong>The</strong> equalization <strong>of</strong> the rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it. We haven’t talked about it much in this Semester,<br />

but volume 3 <strong>of</strong> Capital caused a little sensation among Marxists. After saying in all <strong>of</strong><br />

volume 1 that prices are proportional to labor input, Marx suddenly says in volume 3 that<br />

in capitalism, prices proportional to labor input cannot be the equilibrium prices, because<br />

they lead to unequal rates <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it. <strong>The</strong> capitalists with a higher than average proportion<br />

<strong>of</strong> constant capital can charge more than labor values, and those with a lower proportion<br />

less than labor values. See [2009fa:678] and [2005fa:1298] about rates <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it. Think<br />

<strong>of</strong> it as the capitalists redistributing among themselves the booty they appropriated from<br />

the working class in proportion <strong>of</strong> how much capital each has invested. This redistribution<br />

favors those who have been at it for a long time and works against the new entrepreneur.<br />

New businesses almost always have lower than average constant capital, therefore they are<br />

not able to recover on the market the full value which their business creates, but most <strong>of</strong> it<br />

flows to the big heavily capitalized corporations.<br />

(b) If Marx’s theory is right and pr<strong>of</strong>its come from the unpaid labor <strong>of</strong> the workers, then<br />

this automatically puts a limit on the proportion <strong>of</strong> the people who can become capitalists:<br />

for each capitalist you need many wage laborers.<br />

(c) <strong>The</strong> secret <strong>of</strong> modern technology is not only machinery but also direct cooperation <strong>of</strong><br />

many people. But hiring others is very difficult for new entrepreneurs because <strong>of</strong> astronomical<br />

health insurance costs. <strong>The</strong> mis-management <strong>of</strong> the health care system in the USA is<br />

much more an obstacle for small entrepreneurs than for big corporations.<br />

On the other hand, as I mentioned, there are also instituational features in favor <strong>of</strong> new<br />

entrepreneurs. Bankruptcy laws were one <strong>of</strong> them, but they have been considerably tightened<br />

recently. Besides, due to consumerism, everybody has a credit rating. This can be helpful<br />

if you apply for a loan. Marx himself said that the workers <strong>of</strong> his time simply did not have<br />

378 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

access to credit. This has changed since Marx’s times. And just recently, with the financial<br />

sector taking a lot <strong>of</strong> the surplus-value away from the productive capitalists, this also means<br />

that there are venture capitalists on the lookout for promising new businesses.<br />

It is not surprising that one can discover features <strong>of</strong> the system which keep the system<br />

intact. We know that capitalism has been around for quite a while now, therefore it must<br />

have such mechanisms built in. But there is a big difference between saying “it must have<br />

such mechanisms because otherwise it would no longer exist” and actually identifying these<br />

mechanisms. If you see any other mechanisms which are either in favor <strong>of</strong> or against new<br />

entrepreneurs, please speak up. I have the impression that being a good member <strong>of</strong> the LDS<br />

church may also help in becoming a new capitalist. I am sure there are other <strong>thing</strong>s which<br />

I am not thinking <strong>of</strong>, pro can con. Please speak up if you know <strong>of</strong> any. In chapter 23, i.e.,<br />

in the readings assigned starting tomorrow over Thanksgiving break, Marx will will discuss<br />

exactly the topic how the capitalist system reproduces itself.<br />

Message [871] referenced by [2012fa:873]. Next Message by Hans is [877].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 722 is 465 in 2000fa, 493 in 2001fa, 532 in 2002fa, 553 in 2003fa, 609 in<br />

2004fa, 562 in 2005fa, 636 in 2007SP, 616 in 2007fa, 628 in 2008fa, 659 in 2009fa, and<br />

742 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 722 Do Marx’s arguments that labor cannot have value also imply that services<br />

(i.e., a haircut) cannot have value?<br />

[720] Husani: In the production <strong>of</strong> commodities, Marx argues that labor cannot have<br />

value but it creates value. A factory owner may borrow a laborer’s services for a time and<br />

a price in order to gain her labor-power. <strong>The</strong> factory owner isn’t buying her labor but is<br />

buying her labor-power. <strong>The</strong> difference between the two is that labor is contained in the<br />

worker and always will be, while labor-power is the temporary manifestation <strong>of</strong> labor which<br />

the individual can sell to the capitalist. If the worker were to sell her labor then the person<br />

that bought it would then own the person and the person would be required to work whenever<br />

the owner required. In our society this is not possible. <strong>The</strong> labor she puts into the product is<br />

what creates its value.<br />

<strong>The</strong> service sector <strong>of</strong> the economy is different than commodity production because it<br />

doesn’t produce any<strong>thing</strong> that can be held, haircuts and babysitters are two examples <strong>of</strong> this.<br />

Although they cannot be held or touched like a car or a pair <strong>of</strong> sunglasses, their value comes<br />

from the same place. This value comes from the labor put into the process <strong>of</strong> creating the<br />

service. <strong>The</strong> haircutter or babysitter are not selling their labor but are selling their labor<br />

power. Because they sell their labor-power and not their labor, value is created and they can<br />

sell it for a price.<br />

Message [720] referenced by [754]. Next Message by Husani is [748].<br />

[733] Sly: Haircut are useless if you don’t grow hair. Like many <strong>of</strong> the questions asked<br />

in the Annotations elaboration is needed in order to obtain complete understanding. As<br />

stated in the Annotations: “We have seen many times that Marx does not deny the existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> surface contradictions, but uses them as warning signs alerting us that hidden mechanisms<br />

are at work.” (Annotations, pg. 532) Marx argues that labor cannot have value, and a service<br />

– such as a haircut is clearly a manifestation <strong>of</strong> labor, and by being a manifestation <strong>of</strong> labor


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 379<br />

– how can a haircut possibly have value you might ask? Well <strong>first</strong> and foremost place this<br />

quote into context: “In order to represent his labor in commodities, the worker must, above<br />

all, represent it in use-values, in <strong>thing</strong>s which aid the satisfaction <strong>of</strong> needs <strong>of</strong> one kind or<br />

another.” [283:1] An individual doesn’t just get a haircut for no particular reason – they are<br />

seeking shorter hair or any hair grooming service <strong>of</strong>fered by the barber/stylist (this is the<br />

satisfaction <strong>of</strong> a need), and thus the haircut has a use-value. As a result <strong>of</strong> the inherited usevalue<br />

contained with in a haircut it transforms into a commodity, and like many <strong>of</strong> the parts<br />

<strong>of</strong> Marxism that we have learned throughout the year, commodities have value. Greg gives<br />

an excellent conclusion to this question in previous submissions, stating that: “<strong>The</strong> service<br />

itself is not what you value but the result.” [2009fa:1040] Because obviously if you will feel<br />

as though your haircut is an excellent one, it consequently will have more value to you.<br />

Message [733] referenced by [754] and [2011fa:656]. Next Message by Sly is [986].<br />

[754] ANK: Haircuts and Tips. Marx’s argument does not imply that services cannot<br />

have value. Services, unlike labor, do have value. Labor and services are two different<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s. Husani states in [720] that “labor cannot have value because labor creates value”.<br />

Services such as haircuts are commodities, in which the labor and sale <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

happen simultaneously. When getting a haircut you are paying for the finished product not<br />

a one-sided cut. Haircuts are commodities that are consumed immediately, because you<br />

cannot go get a haircut and then try to sell your haircut to someone else. In [733], Sly states<br />

that “if you feel as though your haircut is an excellent one, it consequently will have more<br />

value to you”. This is why when you are paying for your haircut, which is the finished<br />

product, you may feel inclined to leave a large tip if you feel the haircut has more value to<br />

you and your appearance. Likewise, if you are unhappy with your haircut, the commodity<br />

has less value to you and you would be likely to not tip, but since the commodity was<br />

consumed you would be responsible to still pay the bill.<br />

Next Message by ANK is [933].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 733 is 639 in 2008fa and 755 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 733 Marx says: if demand and supply coincide then they are unable to explain<br />

prices. What would a mainstream economist say about this?<br />

[724] Deadfamous: graded A– What’s more important than supply and demand?<br />

From the reading in the annotations and the previous answers from Needles [2008fa:947]<br />

and Heed [2008fa:859], it seems that while supply and demand are a big part <strong>of</strong> determining<br />

prices (mainstream economists, classical and neoclassical), they are missing some<strong>thing</strong>,<br />

they have simply assumed one <strong>of</strong> the most important parts about how a commodity arrived<br />

at its price is when supply and demand coincide. <strong>The</strong>y (mainstream economists) forget that<br />

the price is largely attached to the labor power it takes to produce some<strong>thing</strong>, and then the<br />

laws <strong>of</strong> supply and demand will have their influence.<br />

Mainstream economics would say that its all about these two laws: supply, and demand.<br />

If supply and demand are stabilized then this is what the price should be due to the producers<br />

and consumers agreeing on the prices together.<br />

Marx’s whole point is that the price comes from what it cost to produce. I am hesitant to<br />

say what how important Marx says supply and demand are, only that before these come into<br />

380 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

play that the labor put into the products would create a base price, then supply and demand<br />

would be secondary.<br />

Final Grading Note by Hans: <strong>The</strong>se last two paragraphs are one <strong>of</strong> the few times where you seem to be writing<br />

what you are thinking instead <strong>of</strong> reproducing some<strong>thing</strong> someone else wrote. You should have done more <strong>of</strong> that.<br />

You seem to use a lot <strong>of</strong> energy to find what others have written about the questions you are answering. You also<br />

spent many hours in class. If you pay attention in class and then write what you think in your answers, then you<br />

may not always be right but you will learn from my feedback. I think this would have been a better strategy.<br />

Next Message by Deadfamous is [970].<br />

[725] Zohan: Supply and Demand Explain Price? Mainstream economics would disagree<br />

with what Marx is arguing. Marx argues that price is not determined by supply and<br />

demand, “but is determined by what gives the commodity its value in the <strong>first</strong> place” (Hans<br />

comments on Heed [2008fa:859]). What gives this value is the amount <strong>of</strong> labor time put<br />

into the production. If the demand or the supply <strong>of</strong> the commodity fluctuated, it would not<br />

change the amount <strong>of</strong> labor time put into production <strong>of</strong> the commodity. <strong>The</strong>refore, it would<br />

not affect value, or the price <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

On the other hand, mainstream economics would suggest that the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

is related to its price. <strong>The</strong>y would argue that the simple supply and demand model could be<br />

used to explain prices. In the supply and demand model, the point where the supply is equal<br />

to the demand would be considered the natural price <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Any fluctuation<br />

from this equilibrium would have a direct effect on the price. If the demand was to increase<br />

and the supply remained constant, then the price would increase. On the other hand, if<br />

the demand was to decrease, and again the supply remained constant, then the price would<br />

decrease. According to mainstream economics, price is directly correlated to the demand<br />

and supply <strong>of</strong> the commodity, which is in contrast to what Marx is arguing.<br />

Hans: Marxists would ask: why should supply remain constant if demand decreases? Wouldn’t it be wiser for the<br />

capitalists to restrict supply <strong>of</strong> commodities not in demand and use the labor they hire for producing some<strong>thing</strong><br />

different?<br />

Message [725] referenced by [726]. Next Message by Zohan is [762].<br />

[726] GoUtes: In response to Zohan. I agree with Zohan [725] in identifying the Marxist<br />

view, that price <strong>of</strong> a commodity is not solely identified by supply and demand. A commodity<br />

would take just as much effort to produce whether the demand matches the supply or not.<br />

Mainstream economics generally will view the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity by the supply and<br />

demand, but is there any less effort in the production <strong>of</strong> a commodity if the demand is not as<br />

high? Of course not!<br />

Next Message by GoUtes is [775].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 740 is 653 in 2007SP, 633 in 2007fa, 645 in 2008fa, 762 in 2011fa, and 791 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 740 Would capitalism be possible if exploitation was not hidden but clearly visible<br />

to everybody involved?<br />

[713] SMIKEC: <strong>The</strong> exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers is happening on a day to day basis within<br />

companies that we buy products from, and we probably aren’t even aware <strong>of</strong> it. Basically<br />

anytime a worker is producing more than they are getting paid, they are being exploited.<br />

As a laborer you would have to sit at home and do no<strong>thing</strong> in order to not be exploited.<br />

Every business I am aware <strong>of</strong> is out to make money. Without exploitation there wouldn’t be


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 381<br />

the capitalist, because you would constantly be at a break even with no pr<strong>of</strong>its. <strong>The</strong> public<br />

doesn’t want to support exploitation, but inadvertently do, because they don’t see what goes<br />

on behind the scenes in order to produce the commodity that they are buying. <strong>The</strong> public is<br />

not willing to pay more for non-exploited goods. This is why companies like Old Navy are<br />

still around, when exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers and even children is at its worst.<br />

Message [713] referenced by [719], [721], and [2011fa:665]. Next Message by SMIKEC is [741].<br />

[719] Kraken: How inadvertent is it? I thought that SMIKEC [713] made some interesting<br />

observations in his post. I particularly enjoyed his comment: “As a laborer you<br />

would have to sit at home and do no<strong>thing</strong> in order not to be exploited”. I think his statement<br />

is funny; I also think it’s sadly true. He then makes a contradictory statement that verbalizes<br />

the contradictory behavior that most <strong>of</strong> us display each day when he says: “<strong>The</strong> public<br />

doesn’t want to support exploitation, but inadvertently do, because they don’t see what goes<br />

on behind the scenes in order to produce the commodity that they are buying. <strong>The</strong> public is<br />

not willing to pay more for non exploited goods”. I think his statement contains two truths<br />

and a lie. I agree that generally speaking, the public doesn’t want to support exploitation.<br />

I also agree that the public is not willing to pay more for non-exploited goods. <strong>The</strong> part<br />

I disagree with is the notion that our behavior is inadvertent. Do we really not know that<br />

someone is being exploited? How did you think you got those tennis shoes, clo<strong>thing</strong> items,<br />

house wares, fast-food, electronics and every<strong>thing</strong> else that came from Wal-Mart so inexpensively?<br />

I’m just using Wal-Mart as an example because they’re an easy target, but I’m<br />

pretty sure we know by now that if we are to continue to enjoy “Everyday Low Prices”,<br />

someone must continue to make “everyday low wages”. I believe we pretend to be blissfully<br />

unaware <strong>of</strong> what’s going on behind the scenes so we can continue to feed our addiction to<br />

consumerism. This helps us take advantage <strong>of</strong> some great deals (especially with Christmas<br />

coming) and thousands <strong>of</strong> exploited workers, all without changing our lifestyles or feeling<br />

guilty. Until we can acknowledge that we are an integral part <strong>of</strong> the exploitation problem,<br />

make some uncomfortable changes, and stop blaming capitalists for all <strong>of</strong> society’s ills, there<br />

is no hope for revolution.<br />

Message [719] referenced by [721]. Next Message by Kraken is [1083].<br />

[721] Frida: Definition <strong>of</strong> exploitation. One point that goes unmentioned in either<br />

SMIKEC [713], or Kraken [719] is the fact that essentially all products are a result <strong>of</strong> exploitation.<br />

Any commodity that was made by a wage worker using a means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

owned by a capitalist involved exploitation. It is almost part <strong>of</strong> the definition <strong>of</strong> mass production.<br />

Even if you make your own clo<strong>thing</strong>, the fabric was the result <strong>of</strong> exploitation. It<br />

does make a difference to what extent the workers involved in the production process, but<br />

this is a difference <strong>of</strong> gross exploitation and what we consider to be normal exploitation. It<br />

is not a difference between exploitation and exploitation-free.<br />

Message [721] referenced by [741]. Next Message by Frida is [756].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 754 is 668 in 2007SP, 646 in 2007fa, 655 in 2008SP, 659 in 2008fa, 690 in<br />

2009fa, 776 in 2011fa, and 805 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 754 Why a separate chapter about the time wage? Wasn’t the time wage already<br />

discussed in chapter Nineteen?<br />

382 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[751] Baseball: Values such as time wages and piece wages are the main shapes (subsets)<br />

<strong>of</strong> pay. In chapter nineteen Marx emphasizes his argument that labor can be traded as a commodity<br />

which has a price. Workers are paid by the hour or by his output (commission), he is<br />

not paid for his labor power but for the labor which he actually performed. <strong>The</strong> exchange between<br />

capital and labor relates exactly to the purchase and sales <strong>of</strong> other commodities. <strong>The</strong><br />

company pays the worker for labor, which represents a commodity. Since chapter nineteen<br />

explained the basic and current unit-measure <strong>of</strong> salary pay (hourly), the next couple chapters<br />

will focus on the subset ways <strong>of</strong> payment: time wages and piece wages. <strong>The</strong> time wage is<br />

a method <strong>of</strong> payment which extends the payments for labor. A normal method <strong>of</strong> payment<br />

is for a worker to be paid by the hour, but for time wages a worker can be paid by the day,<br />

week, month or even year. This system requires a generous amount <strong>of</strong> explanation due to<br />

the many questions and controversy it will raise.<br />

Hans: Since the commodity which the laborer sells to the capitalist is his labor-power and not his labor, the “normal”<br />

(as you say) way to pay for this would be to pay him the reproduction cost <strong>of</strong> his labor-power. Quantitatively,<br />

this is what the worker gets, but he gets it parcelled out hour by hour or piece by piece according to the work he is<br />

performing.<br />

Here is the division <strong>of</strong> labor between chapters 19 and 20/21: 19 establishes the connection between this<br />

parcelled-out way <strong>of</strong> paying and what is really, though barely visibly, going on, and the implications <strong>of</strong> this discrepandy<br />

between form and content. Chapters 20/21 look at the side effects <strong>of</strong> this parcelled-out way <strong>of</strong> paying<br />

itself: that it lengthens and intensifies the workday, that it gives capitalists an opportunity to steal from their workers’<br />

wages, etc.<br />

To say it again, 19 looks at the relationship between surface and the invisible (or barely visible) relations<br />

underneath, while 20/21 look at the surface itself.<br />

Perhaps the following metaphor is useful: Since the surface is not a direct but an indirect representation <strong>of</strong> what<br />

is really going on, i.e., since the rope tying the surface to the underlying relations is longer than it usually is and<br />

has some slack, this rope can get knotted up. Chapters 20/21 investigate these knots, while chapter 19 makes sure<br />

that this rope is still anchored in the basic transaction <strong>of</strong> selling labor-power (and not selling labor itself).<br />

Next Message by Baseball is [836].<br />

[839] Fisher: <strong>The</strong> reason that Marx talks about “Time wages” in two chapters so he can<br />

bring together the price <strong>of</strong> labor and the “underlying relations <strong>of</strong> production”. <strong>The</strong> price <strong>of</strong><br />

labor is measured by the value <strong>of</strong> labor power and by the length <strong>of</strong> the work day. Time wages<br />

relate to the daily, weekly etc. wages paid to laborers by capitalists.<br />

Hans: Yes, chapter 19 talks about the relationship between time wages and the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power from which it<br />

is derived, and chapter 20 talks about time wages in its own right.<br />

Next Message by Fisher is [842].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 755 is 691 in 2009fa and 806 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 755 What does one miss if one does not look at the form itself but only at that <strong>of</strong><br />

which it is the form?<br />

[745] Kobe: Looking at form. <strong>The</strong>re is a connection between form itself and that which<br />

is the form. This may seem very confusing but when you look deeper into the connection<br />

it become more clear. Take the price <strong>of</strong> labor for example, there is a connection here with<br />

the price <strong>of</strong> labor as well as the underlying relations <strong>of</strong> production. This example illustrates<br />

the worker’s wage or as some call price <strong>of</strong> labor, is the transformed form <strong>of</strong> the price <strong>of</strong><br />

labor power. With this being said we must take into account that surface forms have built in<br />

tendencies to lengthen the workday as well as intensify labor. Marx states that these surface<br />

forms do their best to be independent <strong>of</strong> the underlying mechanisms which help determine


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 383<br />

them. Wage labor, this is a form <strong>of</strong> some<strong>thing</strong>, what I would call the value <strong>of</strong> labor power.<br />

According to Marx mainstream economists only want to know what lies beneath these forms<br />

but not at that which is the form. With the above statements taken into account you can miss<br />

many underlying mechanisms if you look at that which is the form instead <strong>of</strong> looking at the<br />

form itself.<br />

Hans: What you are missing is not the underlying mechanisms but the mechanisms located on the surface itself.<br />

<strong>The</strong> tendency to lengthen the workday is a good example for this. This tendency does not come from any<strong>thing</strong><br />

people do in the production process, but this tendency comes from capitalists in their market interactions with the<br />

workers, wanting a low price <strong>of</strong> labor, and workers wanting a high daily wage. Both can be “satisfied” by making<br />

the day longer while keeping wages low. I put “satisfied” into scare quotes because the worker is the one who really<br />

pays for this by losing his free time.<br />

Next Message by Kobe is [843].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 757 is 671 in 2007SP, 662 in 2008fa, 693 in 2009fa, 779 in 2011fa, and<br />

808 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 757 Wages have two main forms: time wages and piece wages. Why does<br />

Marx discuss time wages <strong>first</strong>?<br />

[801] RexManning: graded A <strong>The</strong> chicken came before the egg. Wages, according to<br />

Marx, have two main forms. <strong>The</strong>se forms are time wages and piece wages. When discussing<br />

labor-power, which is what the laborer is selling in return for payment, in the form <strong>of</strong> wages,<br />

one must initially consider time above other factors. This is why Marx discusses time wages<br />

before he addresses piece wages. Time is crucial, not only to the capitalist system as a<br />

whole, but to the individual players in the system, both the laborer and the capitalist. When<br />

a laborer sells his labor-power in return for wages, his/her labor-power can only be sold for<br />

limited amounts <strong>of</strong> time. If there were not a limit to the time in which a laborer could sell<br />

their labor-power then the relationship between the laborer and the capitalist would turn into<br />

a relationship <strong>of</strong> slavery. This relationship <strong>of</strong> selling labor-power for specified periods <strong>of</strong><br />

time results in a daily value, or weekly value <strong>of</strong> labor-power, which is addressed as timewages.<br />

Another reason why time wages are discussed before piece wages, is that time wages<br />

are a direct measurement <strong>of</strong> the laborer’s wage-power, where piece wages are indirect. Even<br />

a piece wage earner can only work for a specified period <strong>of</strong> time or else the system would<br />

result in slavery.<br />

Message [801] referenced by [2012fa:1063]. Next Message by RexManning is [847].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 758 is 672 in 2007SP, 663 in 2008fa, 694 in 2009fa, and 780 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 758 At the beginning <strong>of</strong> the Time Wage Chapter one might expect an argument <strong>of</strong><br />

the sort: Wages are paid for labor, and labor is measured in time, therefore we will discuss<br />

time-wages <strong>first</strong>. Instead <strong>of</strong> this argument, Marx in 683:2 brings a different transition from<br />

labor-power to time wages. How does he argue, and what, if any<strong>thing</strong>, is wrong with the<br />

argument outlined here?<br />

[807] Cosmopolita: Surface forms <strong>of</strong> wages, time wage and piece wage. At the beginning<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Time Wage Chapter Marx reminds us <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> the <strong>first</strong> statements in the<br />

beginning <strong>of</strong> Capital, that one <strong>of</strong> the central commodities traded on the market, labor, is not<br />

really a commodity. This way remind us that on the “surface <strong>of</strong> the economy” the categories<br />

384 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

“price <strong>of</strong> labor” and “value <strong>of</strong> labor” need to be examined, since Marx argues that labor, the<br />

substance <strong>of</strong> all commodity-value, is itself not a commodity and cannot have a value.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore price <strong>of</strong> labor is not determined by the value <strong>of</strong> labor, is derived in a roundabout<br />

manner with the value <strong>of</strong> “Labor-power” and by the length <strong>of</strong> the workday.<br />

As stated in 683.2 mechanisms that were taken as given, affect the magnitude <strong>of</strong> Relative<br />

Surplus Value. <strong>The</strong>se mechanisms were a constant working day assumed, meaning labor<br />

wages being constant. But with the concept <strong>of</strong> Relative Surplus value, we can identify an<br />

increase in the gap between capitalist and laborer; specifically in the lengthening <strong>of</strong> the<br />

working day, which brings absolute surplus value. <strong>The</strong>refore commodity <strong>of</strong> labor-power<br />

can only be sold for periods <strong>of</strong> tine otherwise it would degenerate in slavery. Consequently<br />

whatever form <strong>of</strong> wage directly or indirectly contain a measurement <strong>of</strong> time as in hours, days,<br />

weeks, fortnights, etc. Thus, sale <strong>of</strong> labor power always takes place for specific periods <strong>of</strong><br />

time then value <strong>of</strong> labor can take different shapes.<br />

In chapter 19, a connection between labor power and wage based on labor is derived. But<br />

in Chapter 1, we know the essences behind the wage form do not fully define the shapes<br />

which this form can assume. <strong>The</strong> surface forms <strong>of</strong> wages somehow criticize mainstream<br />

economics, for not paying enough attention to surface forms.<br />

From 683 2 the gap between capitalist and laborer with the lengthening <strong>of</strong> the workday is<br />

again repeated with the surface forms <strong>of</strong> wages, time wages and piece wages, because both<br />

forms have built in tendencies to extend the length <strong>of</strong> the workday, and even more the piece<br />

wage has the tendency to intensify labor. What is wrong, is that from ordinary economic<br />

treatises, which in their crude obsession with substance neglects all kind <strong>of</strong> difference <strong>of</strong><br />

forms, but in Chapter 20 the surfaces forms are recognized derived from wages based on<br />

labor power.<br />

Hans: You are reading the right passages in Capital and the Annotations. <strong>The</strong> next step is to make a crips summary<br />

which only addresses the question asked and to leave out unrelated <strong>thing</strong>s.<br />

Next Message by Cosmopolita is [1197].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 761 is 674 in 2007SP, 652 in 2007fa, 662 in 2008SP, 666 in 2008fa, 697 in<br />

2009fa, 783 in 2011fa, and 812 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 761 How can the price <strong>of</strong> labor be reduced even without changing the weekly<br />

pay?<br />

[742] Lindsey: I get paid more money, but I make less? In chapter 20, Marx outlines<br />

how a worker’s weekly wage can increase while the price <strong>of</strong> his labor (calculated by wage<br />

divided by hours worked) decreases. Today this is easiest to understand if we look only at<br />

workers who earn salary wages.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are 3 ways a worker can make more nominally, though the price <strong>of</strong> his labor has<br />

actually remained the same or decreased. In each case, the number <strong>of</strong> hours worked rise,<br />

causing the wage per hour to remain the same or decrease. <strong>The</strong>y are working more surplus<br />

hours.<br />

In the <strong>first</strong> case, a person’s wage remains the same, but they work more, thus making less<br />

per hour. In the second case, a person’s wage rises, but they work more and this cancels


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 385<br />

out their increase in wage so that they make the same as they did before or even less than<br />

they did before as calculated hourly. In the third case, the hours worked are added up for<br />

a family. <strong>The</strong> head <strong>of</strong> the household cannot possibly work any more hours, but perhaps the<br />

family requires more income, so the income made by the head <strong>of</strong> the family is augmented<br />

by someone else in the family working too. <strong>The</strong> total number <strong>of</strong> hours worked by the family<br />

members increases, and the total <strong>of</strong> the hourly wages received remains the same or decreases.<br />

This argument made me think <strong>of</strong> an argument that was made in another economics class:<br />

capitalists can skim the top <strong>of</strong> workers’ wages in other ways too. <strong>The</strong> example used in<br />

my class was health benefits. Workers’ real wages have not increased much over the past<br />

several decades. This is because they are told that they will be given health benefits from<br />

their company, and they assume that this is extra—free <strong>of</strong> charge. What they don’t realize is<br />

that their employers are taking the money that they would have given the workers in wages<br />

and paying for employee health insurance. Essentially, they are saying “look how generous<br />

we are, we care about your health and want you to have health insurance on us”, but they are<br />

really just spending the workers’ money for them (and maybe even keeping a little more for<br />

themselves). On the surface it looks like employers are giving workers more, but really they<br />

are giving them the same or less—much like the 3 scenarios Marx outlines.<br />

Hans: Capitalist to Marxist worker: if you give up your health coverage, I will give you more money, like the<br />

<strong>University</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>essor told you. Marxist worker: What, I am supposed to believe THAT?<br />

Message [742] referenced by [758] and [833]. Next Message by Lindsey is [864].<br />

[743] Long: More hours, less pay. By extending the hours <strong>of</strong> work per day or per week,<br />

workers are losing because they have to put in more hours per day but still maintaining the<br />

same daily wage. Another scenario is when you’re working on salary wage. You might have<br />

to spend more time as it is necessary to get the job done which might require longer hours<br />

<strong>of</strong> input labor. I remember when I was working at a firm with a hourly wage for two years<br />

before I was promoted to a supervision job. My wage was $9/hour at the time before the<br />

promotion. After the promotion, I have figured that I was making about $4.25/hour because<br />

<strong>of</strong> the time I had to spend before and after everyone had gone home. I was there more<br />

than just eight hours a day. Lastly, the third one is the fact that many families now need<br />

two income earners to even keep up with the cost <strong>of</strong> daily living. In a way, each additional<br />

member <strong>of</strong> the family now has to put in time labor because <strong>of</strong> the head household hours<br />

is augmented like Hans had say in his notations. <strong>The</strong> last scenario fits my current status<br />

provided that my wife now has to work whereas she never did before 2008 financial cricis.<br />

Message [743] referenced by [758]. Next Message by Long is [923].<br />

[746] Alex: graded A Hourly vs. Salary. In this scenario, the price the capitalist pays<br />

for the labor isn’t seen by the capitalist as how many hours the laborer works, but instead<br />

as how much work or labor that worker produced for him. <strong>The</strong>refore, I think that in order<br />

to decrease the price <strong>of</strong> labor without changing the pay would be to increase the labor <strong>of</strong><br />

the worker within a working day, while he/she is being paid the same amount. I think<br />

the best example for this is the method the laborer is paid, such as salary vs. hourly pay.<br />

A person who gets paid by the hour will stall in their responsibilities by taking longer to<br />

perform a job, because the longer he/she takes to perform it, the more hours this worker gets<br />

paid ultimately. A person with a salary will get paid a certain amount regardless <strong>of</strong> how<br />

long it will take him/her to complete the job, so it is within his/her best interest to perform<br />

386 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the job in a precise and quick manner. A capitalist that wants to minimize on labor costs<br />

would increase the bulk load <strong>of</strong> other workers, for example, by laying <strong>of</strong>f one employee and<br />

distributing that person’s work responsibilities among the rest <strong>of</strong> the employees. This would<br />

mean that the capitalist is getting more labor done for him for the same amount <strong>of</strong> money<br />

paid to the worker in the long run.<br />

Message [746] referenced by [748], [758], and [2011fa:699]. Next Message by Alex is [773].<br />

[748] Husani: I believe Alex is correct in [746] in the fact that the capitalist will increase<br />

the working day to get more product out <strong>of</strong> the worker. <strong>The</strong> assessment <strong>of</strong> how people are<br />

paid by salary is also correct but I don’t believe it goes far enough. I think the workers must<br />

also be duped into thinking that they need to work longer to receive the full amount <strong>of</strong> their<br />

pay. <strong>The</strong> capitalist will pay them their means <strong>of</strong> subsistence or the amount they require to<br />

live if they meet a set criterion, such as, a minimum number <strong>of</strong> hours worked or a minimum<br />

number <strong>of</strong> products produced. Without this duping <strong>of</strong> the employees, they will work a lower<br />

amount each day and the capitalist won’t get his surplus-value out <strong>of</strong> his workers.<br />

Hans: Paying less than the value produced per hour has the effect <strong>of</strong> duping the worker, but the capitalist doers not<br />

do it in order to dupe the worker. <strong>The</strong> capitalist simply makes sure that he gets a full day’s labor out <strong>of</strong> the worker<br />

if he purchases his labor-power for a full day.<br />

Message [748] referenced by [758]. Next Message by Husani is [772].<br />

[758] Rmc: graded A+ Reduced price <strong>of</strong> labor. If the worker’s wage is measured by day,<br />

the price <strong>of</strong> labor decreases as hours are added to the work day. Marx explains that if the<br />

working day is a fixed number <strong>of</strong> hours (say, 10) and the wage ($1.44) is fixed by a (24-hour)<br />

day, the longer a worker labors past the fixed number <strong>of</strong> hours reduces the price <strong>of</strong> his labor,<br />

because he is not being paid for the extra hours worked. In other words, if the worker is paid<br />

weekly for the total <strong>of</strong> $1.44 a day for 6 days, he’ll be given $8.64. If he has labored for<br />

more than 60 work-hours and is not compensated, the price <strong>of</strong> his labor has been reduced.<br />

If wages are being determined by piece, the capitalist and worker have agreed on a specific<br />

number <strong>of</strong> items produced to count as socially necessary labor-time. Workers are still<br />

assumed to earn half the value <strong>of</strong> their piece, or work half the day for themselves and the<br />

other half for the capitalist. If, through experience and skill, the worker produces more products<br />

than average during a 12-hour working day, but is still paid the same wage as if he had<br />

only finished the normally expected quota, the price <strong>of</strong> his labor has been reduced because<br />

he has produced more pieces than the agreed-upon number for socially necessary labor-time.<br />

It seems he has benefited the capitalist more than himself.<br />

Lindsey, Long, Alex, and Husani also discuss this question. Lindsey [742] mentions a<br />

third scenario where wages are determined by a family’s labor-hours, not just an individual<br />

worker’s. Long [743] brings up an important perspective also—there is a huge difference<br />

between salary and hourly pay. In my own experience, I have realized that hourly pay can<br />

more accurately compensate a worker putting in extra hours. This difference can be drastic!<br />

I work in a warehouse that gets very busy during the Christmas season, and management<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten encourages overtime. However, my own supervisor is paid salary, so even though<br />

he puts in more hours than many <strong>of</strong> us, he is not paid overtime. (Let’s all pray he gets a<br />

huge bonus.) On the other hand, as Alex [746] points out, if a worker is paid by the hour<br />

it’s very tempting for them to “take their time” on the job so they are paid more by the<br />

time it’s finished. Husani [748] says that workers must be “duped” into thinking they must


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 387<br />

work longer than is socially necessary to have earned their salary, when in reality they must<br />

work longer so the capitalist can retain the workers’ surplus-value. I think my warehouse<br />

example illustrates this somewhat- in my experience, if there is work that needs to be done<br />

and overtime is required to finish it, salaried employees work extra but are not paid for it.<br />

Especially if there is no form <strong>of</strong> compensation, like a bonus, the worker has indeed produced<br />

extensive surplus-value for the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Rmc is [768].<br />

[771] Bigwhite: Wearing me out. Your labor price (hourly wage) can be reduced without<br />

you taking a hit on your weekly paycheck.<br />

1. you can be subject to working longer hours each day due to an increase in demand<br />

which leads to you needing to produce more for your weekly earnings.<br />

2. you could be subject to more intensive labor than you are accustomed to for your<br />

certain job, this can lead to you becoming more tired and decrease you life span or period in<br />

which the capitalist can rap the rewards <strong>of</strong> your labor power.<br />

3. you could be making the same wage for 20 years and now it just doesn’t pay the bills<br />

yet you are working more hours than you used to so your wife has to get a job to help make<br />

ends meet so now you have two people laboring to help augment the wages <strong>of</strong> the primary<br />

worker or head <strong>of</strong> household.<br />

Another valid argument could be a raise in inflation while your wages stay sticky if the<br />

price <strong>of</strong> all goods that you consume rise does that not take away from your wages? Meaning<br />

that you are working the same yet every<strong>thing</strong> around you is rising in price and a dollar today<br />

isn’t equivalent to a dollar next year.<br />

Hans: Inflation erodes your hourly and your weekly pay equally. <strong>The</strong> question was looking for way to reduce the<br />

pay received for a given amount <strong>of</strong> labor while still maintaining the weekly pay at the same level.<br />

Next Message by Bigwhite is [797].<br />

[806] She: graded A+ Too Much is Not Enough. Marx’s formula for determining the<br />

average price <strong>of</strong> labor is summarized in Hans’ Annotations on page 556. <strong>The</strong> average price<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor is found by dividing the average daily value <strong>of</strong> labor power by the average number<br />

<strong>of</strong> hours in the working days. Visually, we can imagine this as a ratio with the average daily<br />

value <strong>of</strong> labor power being given the top position, or the numerator and the average number<br />

<strong>of</strong> hours in the working day will be on the bottom or be designated as the denominator.<br />

Common knowledge <strong>of</strong> fractions dictates that the value <strong>of</strong> the fraction will decrease when<br />

there is a decrease in the value <strong>of</strong> the numerator or an increase in the value <strong>of</strong> the denominator.<br />

So, holding the numerator constant, the price <strong>of</strong> labor to the capitalist can fall if the<br />

denominator, or average number <strong>of</strong> hours, is increased.<br />

<strong>The</strong> easiest way to imagine this scenario is thinking <strong>of</strong> a salary employee in modern day.<br />

This analogy does not make sense if we think <strong>of</strong> wage work the way it now works in our<br />

society. Many <strong>of</strong> us would demand, and rightfully so, additional pay for additional hours <strong>of</strong><br />

work. Sometimes I feel it is difficult to see what Marx is saying because a lot <strong>of</strong> it doesn’t<br />

seem to fit the life we now live in our capitalist system. Many who read the chapters <strong>of</strong><br />

Capital concerning wages will fail to see the significance because they forget to consider the<br />

388 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

state <strong>of</strong> labor at the time this book was written. Workers now have more power and <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

times do not realize that their rights and powers have all been begat by the labor movement.<br />

Capital was originally published in 1867. This was before the Pullman Strike (1894),<br />

the Homestead Massacre (1892), and many other strikes that ended in violence and death.<br />

<strong>The</strong> concessions that are taken for granted now are the products <strong>of</strong> sacrifice and battle in the<br />

past. It seems absurd to us, nowadays, to think that our bosses would just tell us they are not<br />

paying us more, but we have to work more, if we don’t like it, we can just starve. This is<br />

exactly what happened to the steel workers and railway workers in the late 19th century. <strong>The</strong><br />

price <strong>of</strong> labor can be driven down if more product can be squeezed out without proportionate<br />

compensation for the workers’ toil.<br />

Next Message by She is [948].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 762 is 675 in 2007SP, 653 in 2007fa, 663 in 2008SP, 667 in 2008fa, 698 in<br />

2009fa, 784 in 2011fa, and 813 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 762 Is it true that the laborer is only interested in what he receives, i.e., the overall<br />

daily wage income, and not interested in what he gives, i.e., the overall daily labor?<br />

[762] Zohan: More than just a wage. For the most part I would say that this is a<br />

false statement. Most people find a sense <strong>of</strong> joy when they contribute to, or accomplishing<br />

some<strong>thing</strong>. <strong>The</strong>refore, I don’t think that laborers are only interested in what they receive.<br />

Many enjoy what they do, regardless <strong>of</strong> their wage. <strong>The</strong>y are driven by some<strong>thing</strong> more.<br />

Robbie [2009fa:776] quoted Hans stating, “Some jobs are so interesting and rewarding by<br />

themselves, and wages are high enough for a comfortable living already, that the workers just<br />

do the additional work out <strong>of</strong> enthusiasm and goodness <strong>of</strong> their hearts. But as the workers<br />

notice that their selfless attitude is cynically taken advantage <strong>of</strong> by the capitalist, this is likely<br />

to dampen their enthusiasm over time.”<br />

As I read this I thought <strong>of</strong> my parents. My mother is a public school teacher. She earns a<br />

salary <strong>of</strong> about $40,000 per year. She works several hours past her required time each week<br />

that she doesn’t get paid for. She obviously did not choose this field because <strong>of</strong> the level <strong>of</strong><br />

income it would bring. She chose to be a teacher simply because she loves to do what she<br />

does and finds more satisfaction in teaching young minds than the figures on her pay check.<br />

She doesn’t mind working extra hours because <strong>of</strong> enjoyment she gets out <strong>of</strong> her work.<br />

On the other hand, my father makes a significantly larger amount <strong>of</strong> money than my<br />

mother, but he doesn’t find the same level <strong>of</strong> joy with his job. His job is stressful and<br />

extremely time consuming. He also gets upset when he has to work more than his required<br />

time. Although he does find some degree <strong>of</strong> satisfaction in his work, I believe he finds more<br />

satisfaction in what the company gives him in wage, over what he gives them in labor. His<br />

wage is higher than his job satisfaction and that what has kept him there for thirty years. I<br />

am confident that if his wage was lower he would not work in the same field.<br />

Message [762] referenced by [768]. Next Message by Zohan is [985].<br />

[768] Rmc: I completely agree with Zohan [762], even if what he says seems optimistic,<br />

especially to those who don’t like their jobs or whose good hearts have been taken advantage<br />

<strong>of</strong>.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 389<br />

After I get my BA, I’ll be going <strong>first</strong> to massage, then physical therapy school. This<br />

has been a dream since some good friends <strong>of</strong> mine graduated from UCMT and became<br />

massage therapists- through their experiences, I realized PT is the perfect way for me to<br />

help people (I’ll be honest, I chose PT because that pr<strong>of</strong>ession allows more freedoms than<br />

massage therapists are allowed—diagnosis, for example). Anyway, one massage therapist<br />

friend in particular noticed right away that as soon as he told people what he did for a living,<br />

the <strong>first</strong> words out <strong>of</strong> their mouths would be some<strong>thing</strong> like “oh, I’ve had this pain in my<br />

back for soooo long. . . .” or “oh dude, my knee has been Killing me. . . ” and while he was<br />

willing to help them at <strong>first</strong> without any sort <strong>of</strong> payment—out <strong>of</strong> the goodness <strong>of</strong> his heart—<br />

it started to get very wearing before long, especially since after a while it felt like he was<br />

taken advantage <strong>of</strong> by people who weren’t willing to pay him for his help. In the end, that<br />

turned out to be many <strong>of</strong> his clients, since some <strong>of</strong> his work was outcall.<br />

I have noticed the same <strong>thing</strong> happens to me when I tell people I’ll be going to PT school,<br />

and I haven’t even been educated in it yet! Nevertheless, part <strong>of</strong> the reason I chose this<br />

path for myself was that I want to help people before I want the paycheck. I didn’t even<br />

look at average income for physical therapists when I picked this career. Maybe this will<br />

change over time, but right now my goal will be to help anybody who asks for it, as best<br />

I can, without expecting any sort <strong>of</strong> compensation at all. This attitude has been met with<br />

skepticism and doubt, but I absolutely mean it. With this particular pr<strong>of</strong>ession and set <strong>of</strong><br />

skills, I’ll be in a position to really help people—and if altruism replaces payment for some<br />

cases, that’s perfectly fine with me.<br />

Message [768] referenced by [797]. Next Message by Rmc is [962].<br />

[797] Bigwhite: Selfish. I have read others responses to this same question and have found<br />

that the majority feel that the laborer is not just working for wages but is in fact working for<br />

some sort <strong>of</strong> self satisfaction. Rmc [768] referenced a friend that does PT having to give<br />

information away for free when he could be in fact being paid for it but didn’t mind because<br />

it meant some<strong>thing</strong> to him to help others. While I find this a valid response I don’t feel<br />

that the masses really feel this way, there is only a small portion <strong>of</strong> the population that does<br />

any type <strong>of</strong> labor and doesn’t expect to be compensated for it. <strong>The</strong>se are the extremely<br />

charitable people that you read about that are working for the peace corp or are incredible<br />

philanthropists. To me this seems to be the exception and not the norm. This is coming from<br />

someone that has grown up in capitalism but I do feel people are in fact more worried about<br />

their wages than how much they put into their labor. I feel that this is a just argument from<br />

what we have learned in this class why would the laborer in a capitalistic system want to put<br />

every<strong>thing</strong> they have into a day’s work when they are just being exploited, I find there is no<br />

incentive to want to work your hardest on a day to day basis under the capitalistic system.<br />

Generally I believe that most people are self-interested and greedy only doing enough to<br />

keep their job and satisfy their management while having more value instilled into their<br />

leisure time.<br />

Message [797] referenced by [800] and [802]. Next Message by Bigwhite is [820].<br />

[800] Frida: graded A+ What is the relationship between capitalism and greed? I<br />

agree with the main conclusion <strong>of</strong> Bigwhite in [797], which is that in capitalism most people<br />

are more interested in what they get out <strong>of</strong> the system than what they put into it. Most wage<br />

workers don’t care much about the quality <strong>of</strong> what they produce.<br />

390 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

But this should lead us to wonder... Why are many people are like that? Are people inherently<br />

greedy, or is there some<strong>thing</strong> about being a wage worker, or a worker in a capitalist<br />

system that inherently leads to this? <strong>The</strong> examples that people have given in previous answer<br />

seem to point to the latter option. People who have to opportunity to have a better job,<br />

like physical therapist or teacher, do tend to care about how they benefit others. Bigwhite<br />

seems to agree that capitalism does contribute to this, but also seems to imply that it is part<br />

<strong>of</strong> human nature.<br />

Many people are not so lucky. If everyone could get an emotionally rewarding job, everyone<br />

would. <strong>The</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> this society forces many to work at low wage jobs just to<br />

survive, there is no time/money for college or other training to get a better/more fulfilling<br />

job. I work a minimum wage job, but I don’t rely on it to survive. I have been lucky enough<br />

to have parents well <strong>of</strong>f enough so that I can live at home and get partial support while I go<br />

to school. If I were relying on my minimum wage job for my survival (or an even lower<br />

wage job, or if it were supporting not just me but other members <strong>of</strong> my family), I wouldn’t<br />

care at all about the quality <strong>of</strong> my work. I don’t see how someone who is being exploited to<br />

that extent ever could.<br />

This is another instance <strong>of</strong> the social roles created by capitalism. <strong>The</strong>re is the role <strong>of</strong> the<br />

exploiting capitalist, and the role <strong>of</strong> the worker. <strong>The</strong>re are further subdivisions in the role<br />

<strong>of</strong> worker that range between the barely surviving worker and the worker who is basically<br />

happy with their job. In order for capitalism to function there have to be many many people<br />

barely surviving. Since they occupy this role in the system, it is no wonder if they don’t take<br />

joy in their work.<br />

Message [800] referenced by [802]. Next Message by Frida is [804].<br />

[802] Kat: Response on the selfish worker. In response to Bigwhite [797] and Frida<br />

[800], I’d like to speak further about the motives <strong>of</strong> the worker. It has been called to question<br />

whether whether a wage, happiness, or social concern is the main motive for working.<br />

Everyone, for the most part, considers survival to be the highest priority. Wages, then, are<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten time the biggest concern when seeking a job. Regardless <strong>of</strong> whether they are high or<br />

low, the absolute necessity <strong>of</strong> money to survive remains. So, happiness and social concern<br />

will take a backseat. Otherwise, perhaps more people would “work” as volunteers or not<br />

work at all, if that made them happy. Frida [800] questions whether this is greed or a capitalistic<br />

characteristic. I’d say it’s a bit <strong>of</strong> both. Greed has a negative connotation, but an<br />

individual’s pursuit <strong>of</strong> survival and a comfortable life is really a form <strong>of</strong> relative greed.<br />

That being said, it is also a characteristic <strong>of</strong> capitalism for individual’s to seek a higher<br />

and more satisfactory form <strong>of</strong> survival. I would say this suggests workers will take an active<br />

interest in what they are creating. Frida [800] mentions the necessary levels <strong>of</strong> social standing<br />

within the working world, ranging from the capitalist to the lowest level wage workers.<br />

Those on the lowest levels would prefer not to be there. So, they would be inclined to care<br />

about the quality <strong>of</strong> their labor and their production because that will be the greatest determinant<br />

in moving up the production ladder. Exploitation will not necessarily depress the<br />

worker’s drive to better their situation.<br />

Next Message by Kat is [815].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 391<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 764 is 677 in 2007SP, 665 in 2008SP, 669 in 2008fa, 700 in 2009fa, 786 in<br />

2011fa, 816 in 2012fa, and 764 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 764 In a system <strong>of</strong> hourly wages without a set daily minimum <strong>of</strong> hours, Marx says<br />

that “the connection between the paid and the unpaid labor is destroyed.” Explain what he<br />

means by this.<br />

[770] AM: Is my labor Paid or Unpaid? I find the issue <strong>of</strong> hourly wages and set daily<br />

minimum <strong>of</strong> hours to be extremely relevant even years after the initial downturn in the economy.<br />

Workers still face shortened work week hours because their employer simply does not<br />

have enough incoming jobs to create enough revenue to have his employees work a normal<br />

work week (say 40 hours). In addition with fewer jobs to complete there simply is not<br />

enough work to keep workers on the clock. All the while the employees’ bills have not<br />

changed, they still require the same amount each month to put food on the table, pay for<br />

gas, and keep the lights on. Important in all this is to note whether or not the worker understands<br />

how their wage is computed. More <strong>of</strong>ten than not the worker does not realise that<br />

he produces more value than what he actually gets paid. <strong>The</strong> example that Hans provides in<br />

reponse to JspendLove [2008fa:887] exemplifies how a part <strong>of</strong> a workers labor goes unpaid.<br />

If a client is billed $45 per hour and the worker is paid $15 per hour, after 20 minutes the<br />

worker has created a labor equivalent while the remaining 40 minutes goes unpaid. This is<br />

a good example <strong>of</strong> an asymmetric information problem for the worker. Workers previously<br />

were able to get paid for labor and unpaid for labor thereafter. Now the <strong>first</strong> step is missing<br />

there is rarely any paid labor left to be completed once unpaid labor is completed. Using<br />

Marxs’ connection between paid and unpaid labor I think about my own job and question<br />

which parts <strong>of</strong> my labor are being paid and which parts remain unpaid. I am admittedly<br />

unsure <strong>of</strong> this but may lead to an interesting discussion with my boss (we have a close, open<br />

relationship which allows for honest discussions).<br />

Hans: You might find [Answer:9] helpful.<br />

Message [770] referenced by [776]. Next Message by AM is [967].<br />

[776] PLG: graded A Healthcare inflation burdens you! Marx reveals a 1:1 ratio <strong>of</strong> paid<br />

to unpaid labor in a 12-hour working day. “he works only half <strong>of</strong> every hour for himself, and<br />

half for the capitalist” However, if the working day is variable relative to the daily value <strong>of</strong><br />

labor power, then the daily value <strong>of</strong> labor-power can be tampered with by the capitalist. A<br />

capitalist has the option <strong>of</strong> increasing or decreasing the working day, while the labor-power<br />

remains constant. <strong>The</strong>refore if a worker is working less than the level <strong>of</strong> subsistence that<br />

his hourly wage is based on than he is being exploited. In Marx’s example <strong>of</strong> abnormal<br />

underemployment he shows how a laborer’s earnings are truncated the less hours worked.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fewer hours he works, the further away he gets from subsistence. <strong>The</strong>refore, the 1:1<br />

paid to unpaid ratio is not constant as the hours worked decreases. <strong>The</strong>refore the relationship<br />

between unpaid and paid labor has been destroyed.<br />

A capitalist could hire a few part time employees to each work part <strong>of</strong> the day. He would<br />

maintain the same value produced, while paying less per laborer. None <strong>of</strong> which could reach<br />

a level <strong>of</strong> subsistence.<br />

392 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

AM [770] points out that living expenses remain the same, while part-time work is becoming<br />

more prominent in relation to full time work. Part-time work also allows the capitalist<br />

to avoid employee benefits, and further exploit workers. This is highly popular in today’s<br />

society, especially with healthcare inflation and the burden it puts on firms. Firms are transferring<br />

the burden <strong>of</strong> increasing healthcare costs to their employees rather than reducing the<br />

company surplus. This is a contemporary example <strong>of</strong> the destruction <strong>of</strong> the relationship between<br />

paid and unpaid labor. Capitalism is about firms, not about people or workers. As<br />

companies get richer, people get poorer.<br />

Hans: As long as there is any unpaid labor, Marx would say the worker is exploited. If the workday is so short<br />

that the worker can no longer pay his bills, then Marx would use a stronger word than exploitation; in this case<br />

the capitalist steals from the worker. Why steal? Because the capitalist buys the commodity labor-power from the<br />

worker, and just because he cannot use it all he refuses to pay for it all. Imagine you calling Amazon and saying:<br />

I haven’t been using the gadget very much which I bought from you. Please give me a partial refund. (Ignore that<br />

Amazon is set up in such a way that you cannot really call them.)<br />

Next Message by PLG is [803].<br />

[985] Zohan: Why A Connection Breakdown? In a system without a set daily minimum<br />

<strong>of</strong> hours, the capitalist is bound to pay only the wages for the number <strong>of</strong> hours that he<br />

chooses to employ the worker. He can choose to employ the workers for a shorter period<br />

<strong>of</strong> time, sending them home before they have a chance to work enough hours to maintain<br />

their standard <strong>of</strong> living. Essentially, the capitalist can try to exploit their labor. As long as<br />

the capitalist has allowed them to work enough hours to perform the necessary labor, the<br />

capitalist is able to keep the surplus value. In the annotations on page 561, Marx explains<br />

that when the hours are shortened, “the capitalist can harvest surplus labor without allowing<br />

the worker to perform his or her necessary labor.” When this occurs the connection between<br />

paid and unpaid labor is broken.<br />

Next Message by Zohan is [991].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 766 is 679 in 2007SP, 657 in 2007fa, 702 in 2009fa, 790 in 2011fa, and 820 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 766 In Chapter Twenty, Marx mentions two abuses connected with the wage<br />

which he thought would be abolished with the legal limitation <strong>of</strong> the working-day but which<br />

weren’t. Which are those?<br />

[744] Trap: hourly wages keep capitalists pr<strong>of</strong>itable. In chapter 20 Marx discusses the<br />

issues with time-wages. He specifically mentions two abuses that he was hoping would be<br />

overcome with the legal limitation <strong>of</strong> the working day. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> abuse he sees is the problem<br />

<strong>of</strong> hourly wages. He saw that capitalists were out to simply maximize pr<strong>of</strong>its, so the workers<br />

were at the mercy <strong>of</strong> the capitalists. Hans gives the example in [2009fa:782] <strong>of</strong> a capitalist<br />

only employing the worker when he needs him, for example during the Christmas season the<br />

worker will supposedly get enough hours to support himself, but once the Christmas season<br />

ends, his hours are cut once again to an unreasonably low level.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second abuse Marx sees is the erosion <strong>of</strong> the separation between normal time and<br />

overtime. In the annotations Hans says that “regular pay is depressed, so that the workers<br />

are forced to work longer because they depend on overtime pay.” <strong>The</strong> capitalist keeps the<br />

wages low, so that in order to support themselves the worker must work overtime hours,<br />

therefore it “undermines the normalization <strong>of</strong> the working-day.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 393<br />

Hans: You originally had written “the second abuse Marx sees is the separation <strong>of</strong> normal time and overtime.” I<br />

changed it because the separation itself is a good <strong>thing</strong>: it allows people to work overtime if they like, without this<br />

affecting their normal workday and their normal pay. <strong>The</strong> erosion <strong>of</strong> this separation is the abuse. Here is how this<br />

separation is eroded: overtime pay is used as an excuse for lowering the normal pay and in this way the workers are<br />

forced to work longer, i.e., in essence the normal workday has now become longer.<br />

By the way, what you call “the problem <strong>of</strong> hourly wages,” Marx 686:1 calls “the elimination <strong>of</strong> the bond between<br />

paid and unpaid labor.” Marx was a deep thinker, and you can learn a lot by paying attention to how exactly he<br />

conceptualizes <strong>thing</strong>s.<br />

Message [744] referenced by [2012fa:1030] and [2012fa:1202]. Next Message by Trap is [1035].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 767 is 680 in 2007SP, 658 in 2007fa, 668 in 2008SP, 672 in 2008fa, 703 in<br />

2009fa, 791 in 2011fa, and 821 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 767 How does Marx argue that longer hours are associated with a lower overall<br />

daily wage?<br />

[741] SMIKEC: Marx explains that wages are dependent on the amount <strong>of</strong> labor needed.<br />

If someone isn’t getting paid as much this could indicate that there is a greater amount <strong>of</strong><br />

labor, which leads to a longer work day and hence a lower wage. Depending on the economy<br />

and the situation the individual is in has a factor in that individual’s wage. If the worker is<br />

facing tough times, he might be more willing to accept an agreement which he generally<br />

wouldn’t. One <strong>of</strong> these terms could be a longer day for less pay. On the flip side <strong>of</strong> the<br />

coin, if <strong>thing</strong>s are a little brighter for you, you would most likely be a little choosier and not<br />

agree to certain terms such as a longer work day. <strong>The</strong> capitalist will do every<strong>thing</strong> in his<br />

power to get more out <strong>of</strong> you for no<strong>thing</strong>. I think this is where salaries come into play. Many<br />

managers and supervisor positions are structured like this. If you were working a 40 hour<br />

work week your pay would be great, but since they get 55 hours out <strong>of</strong> you a week, your<br />

wage is quickly diluted.<br />

Hans: Your argument is essentially correct, but keep [721] in mind: it applies not only for excessive exploitation<br />

but also for normal exploitation.<br />

Next Message by SMIKEC is [811].<br />

[750] LuBr: Lengthened workday means lower daily wage. Marx argues that longer<br />

hours in the workday are correlated with the erosion <strong>of</strong> the daily wage.<br />

<strong>The</strong> laws <strong>of</strong> capitalist production determine the hourly price <strong>of</strong> labor to be the ratio <strong>of</strong><br />

[daily value <strong>of</strong> labor power/working day <strong>of</strong> a given number <strong>of</strong> hours]. So, one would think<br />

that an increase in the working day would only serve to reduce the hourly price <strong>of</strong> labor. This<br />

does not answer the question however, in that we are trying to understand why an increase<br />

in the working day is linked to a reduction in the daily wage.<br />

<strong>The</strong> daily wage, according to capitalist production, is determined by the basic humanistic<br />

requirements <strong>of</strong> the worker to reproduce his labor-power, as Hans described to the class in<br />

[702]. Hans explains that the “day is the shortest period for which it makes sense to compute<br />

(his total survival needs).” This definition <strong>of</strong> the daily wage would mean that it would stay<br />

constant. Furthermore, in answering our question, one would not think that an extension <strong>of</strong><br />

the working day would have any<strong>thing</strong> to do with the daily wage.<br />

So how is the longer workday linked to a lower overall daily wage? One must look at<br />

the market forces that allow capitalists to take advantage <strong>of</strong> overly alienated (non-unionized)<br />

394 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

and desperate laborers. Laborers who are unable to organize or too poor to go without daily<br />

wages for the protest over a lengthened workday are those same laborers who are unable to<br />

fight a reduction <strong>of</strong> their daily wages. In the end, capitalists striving to compete on the market<br />

with low cost commodities see their ability to extract a higher surplus value by increasing<br />

the workday. If they can get away with this, a reduction <strong>of</strong> the daily wage will certainly<br />

follow.<br />

Next Message by LuBr is [764].<br />

[761] Kat: You just can’t win—Longer hours and lower wages. Marx argues that are<br />

longer hours will also mean lower wages because <strong>of</strong> the balance <strong>of</strong> power between workers<br />

and capitalists. That is, whoever had more bargaining power should be able to dictate hours<br />

and wages. If the capitalist has the power, they are able and inclined to extend hours and<br />

lower wages. Whereas, if the power shifts, the workers will be able and likewise inclined to<br />

argue for better wages and shorter hours. This is another instance where Marx would insist<br />

on the importance <strong>of</strong> workers banding together to gain power to better their situation.<br />

Hans: Your argument is neat and simple but it is too abbreviated. It sounds as if wages were only determined<br />

by the strangth <strong>of</strong> the competing parties capitalists and workers. <strong>The</strong> law <strong>of</strong> value plays a role in it too. I.e., the<br />

workers not only have to contend with the market power <strong>of</strong> the capitalists but the market as a whole works against<br />

them too.<br />

Next Message by Kat is [802].<br />

[833] Hans: Health Care and Wage <strong>The</strong>ft. Answering a different question, Lindsey<br />

[742] remarks that the cost escalation in health care has been used by the companies not to<br />

raise wages. This is true, but does this mean the workers are better <strong>of</strong>f in a job without health<br />

benefits? If you think there are anywhere in the USA really well paying jobs which have<br />

no health benefits and which pay so well because they have no health benefits, look again.<br />

Such jobs do not exist. All well-paying jobs have health benefits, only the poorly paying<br />

jobs don’t. <strong>The</strong> trade<strong>of</strong>f which you would expect does not exist. This is the same situation<br />

as with the jobs with long hours whose pay is less than the job with normal hours, not only<br />

per hour but even the takehome pay per day or week is less.<br />

<strong>The</strong> US health industry is an example for another concept which Marx uses in chapter 20,<br />

namely wage theft. <strong>The</strong> entire industry, not only the insurance companies but also the doctors’<br />

salaries, the hospitals, etc., owe their exceptional growth to wage theft: the capitalists<br />

and doctors have found a way to divert part <strong>of</strong> the wages which the workers have fought for<br />

into their pockets.<br />

What to do in such a situation? A Marxist would say: fight tooth and nail to protect<br />

and keep your company health benefits. Make it hard for the companies to just throw out<br />

their company specific health plans, until the companies themselves clamor for a universal<br />

system as every other civilized country has except the USA. Only this can stop the insurance<br />

companies and pharmaceutical companies and hospitals and doctors from drinking out <strong>of</strong><br />

the wage trough.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [834].<br />

[837] Fisher: free discussion health care. I was reading the response that Hans had for<br />

Lindsey on the health care system and a job with benefits and wanted to add to that. Another<br />

problem with the Health Care system is that too many people are not insured and eventually<br />

need medical attention. Once they make their visit or visits to the hospital, there is a huge


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 395<br />

bill that never gets paid. <strong>The</strong> hospitals and doctors make up for the “unpaid” bills by passing<br />

it on to those who pay their bill. Or, in other words, if everyone would get insured and pay<br />

their hospital bills then maybe health care prices would likely come down.<br />

Message [837] referenced by [854]. Next Message by Fisher is [839].<br />

[854] Kaimani: Can Everyone Afford Healthcare?? I was reading Fisher’s [837] response<br />

to Hans and Lindseys discussion on health care system. He recognizes that we have<br />

a lot <strong>of</strong> people who are “uninsured” and don’t have the means to afford their procedures or<br />

appointments. To make up for that the hospital either writes it <strong>of</strong>f or they “pass it on to those<br />

who pay their bill” Fisher than goes on to say that “if everyone would get insured and pay<br />

their hospital bills then maybe hospital bills would likely come down.”<br />

My issue is the assumption that everyone can pay their hospital bills. <strong>The</strong> reason that so<br />

many people are unisured is because insurance is so dang expensive. Especially if you are<br />

trying to do it privately and not with a company. Most <strong>of</strong> those who are uninsured make less<br />

than 40k a year and thats not take home. Cost <strong>of</strong> living and other life factors make it difficult<br />

for someone to afford insurance. Especially if that someone has a medium to large family.<br />

Also, a lot <strong>of</strong> people who are uninsured work at jobs that don’t carry insurance plans and if<br />

they do they don’t cover hardly any<strong>thing</strong>. And maybe the reason for companies who have<br />

limited insurance options is because it hurts their surplus value????<br />

I think that the problem is with rates at which doctors can charge per procedure. Also<br />

i think another problem is insurance, health insurance makes it nearly impossible to afford<br />

and if you can, it is eating a big whole in your pocket. To make health care more affordable<br />

i think that we need to look at the exchange process <strong>of</strong> insurance to health provider and see<br />

how we can make that more efficient. Maybe if we can fix that aspect then health care prices<br />

will go down. I don’t see really any other way. It is a hard issue to tackle.<br />

Message [854] referenced by [1063]. Next Message by Kaimani is [919].<br />

[897] Giant: graded B– Longer hours are associated with lower overall daily wage according<br />

to Marx by the workers being less productive. When the workers work longer hours<br />

they can not work as hard so their hourly productivity declines because they are tired from<br />

the long work hours.<br />

Hans: In Marx’s theory, wages do not depend on productivity.<br />

Another way wages are lowered is when workers are given a set wage. This set wage<br />

does not take into account any extra hours that the worker is working. A person could be<br />

working 40 hours a week, while another person works 50 but they both could be earning the<br />

same set wage. If this was the case then the worker who is putting in more work hours is<br />

getting paid less than the worker who is only working 40 hours.<br />

Hans: This would explain why the daily wage is the same despite longer hours, but Marx says the daily wage is<br />

lower in those industries where hours are longer.<br />

Next Message by Giant is [910].<br />

[994] GoUtes: Marx argues that longer hours are associated with lower overall daily wage<br />

by pointing out that those that work longer hours need to work greater hours to satisfy their<br />

personal cost <strong>of</strong> living. For example, an illegal immigrant working in construction will more<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten than not work longer hours on a day to day basis, they have lower wages and must<br />

work longer hours in order to cover their cost <strong>of</strong> living. Whereas with someone who has a<br />

good paying sought after job like an accountant, they will work less hours per day because<br />

396 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

they are getting paid more per hour, they don’t need to work as many hours to be able to<br />

cover their cost <strong>of</strong> living.<br />

Hans: According to Marx, accountants have higher wages than construction workers because they need an education.<br />

Marx says that for comparable skill levels, longer hours mean lower daily wage than shorter hours. You<br />

haven’t explained why.<br />

Next Message by GoUtes is [1093].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 769 is 674 in 2008fa and 793 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 769 In which <strong>of</strong> the examples in this chapter is there a tendency to increase (daily)<br />

wages while lowering the (hourly) price <strong>of</strong> labor, a possibility Marx invoked in 684:1/o?<br />

[769] Ferox: graded A– <strong>The</strong> Hidden Trap <strong>of</strong> Increasing Daily Wages. Marx uses the<br />

<strong>first</strong> example <strong>of</strong> one worker producing the equivalent <strong>of</strong> 1.5 or 2 workers — an example<br />

indicative <strong>of</strong> high wages but lower prices <strong>of</strong> labor. Because the worker is willing to work<br />

longer shifts in order to gain a larger daily wage, she is inflating the labor supply in a market.<br />

This leads to an increase in competition between potential workers due to the lowering <strong>of</strong><br />

the standard hourly price. Due to the currently high unemployment rate, potential workers<br />

are more willing to work for a low wage that provides a meager subsistence than not work<br />

at all (and be unable to meet basic needs.) By selling her labor power for less than others,<br />

the worker is competitively underpricing herself, but undermining all workers by bringing<br />

the standard wage down.<br />

Once employed by the capitalist, the worker will strive to keep her employment - “being<br />

a team player” - even if it means working longer hours. This will increase the daily wage<br />

but lower the hourly wage <strong>of</strong> the worker. <strong>The</strong> worker will receive more at the end <strong>of</strong> the pay<br />

period, but is working longer hours and at higher productivity to maintain that rate <strong>of</strong> pay —<br />

all due to the depressed price <strong>of</strong> her hourly labor.<br />

Hans: You are not saying any<strong>thing</strong> about Marx’s other examples—does this mean in those other examples there is<br />

no tendency to lower the price <strong>of</strong> labor?<br />

Regarding the example you did bring, it seem obvious that you used [2008fa:864], and you should have referenced<br />

it. That earlier message talks about one other example by Marx, and my note to that message about the third.<br />

It is ok to build on previous answers, but please improve them instead <strong>of</strong> falling behind them.<br />

Next Message by Ferox is [799].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 770 is 683 in 2007SP, 661 in 2007fa, 671 in 2008SP, 675 in 2008fa, 706<br />

in 2009fa, 789 in 2011fa, 819 in 2012fa, and 770 in Answer:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 770 What is the difference between surplus labor time and overtime?<br />

[749] JSmits: (graded A) <strong>The</strong> deception <strong>of</strong> surplus-labor time. <strong>The</strong> difference between<br />

surplus labor time and overtime is that surplus labor time is thought to be part <strong>of</strong> the normal<br />

working day where overtime is beyond the realm <strong>of</strong> the normal working day. Capitalists<br />

recognize that overtime is beyond the normal work day and that is why they pay employees<br />

more for it. Surplus labor time is some<strong>thing</strong> that does not exist so it is included in the normal<br />

working day.<br />

Surplus labor time is stated by Marx in 690:1/o0, “<strong>The</strong> category <strong>of</strong> surplus labor-time<br />

does not exist at all for him, since it is included in the normal working day, which he thinks<br />

he has paid for in the day’s wages”. Marx says that to the capitalist, surplus labor time does


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 397<br />

not exist. Whatever a worker’s wage is, it is not the same value as whatever they are making.<br />

That is where surplus labor time comes into play. It is the work that you do that you are not<br />

paid for.<br />

Employees think that all <strong>of</strong> their labor is paid for but it isn’t true. If it were true then there<br />

wouldn’t be any surplus labor or pr<strong>of</strong>its for that matter and they wouldn’t be exploited by<br />

the capitalists.<br />

Overtime is different because they will pay you more than what you would make in a<br />

normal work day. It seems like the capitalist would be losing money because they are paying<br />

employees for instance, time and a half, for their work but in reality they are still benefiting<br />

from it. It just benefits the capitalist and hurts the employee because it enables them to run<br />

the machinery 24 hours a day and make bigger pr<strong>of</strong>its while ruining the employee’s health.<br />

Capitalists will earn a little less because <strong>of</strong> the increased wages but they still pr<strong>of</strong>it. Overtime<br />

is very deceptive because it seems as though capitalists are doing you a favor by paying you<br />

more because you work longer—but they are just earning more pr<strong>of</strong>its while exploiting the<br />

employers through surplus labor.<br />

So surplus labor time is thought to be part <strong>of</strong> the normal work day, where over-time is<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> that is extra, on top <strong>of</strong> the normal working day.<br />

Message [749] referenced by [2011fa:744]. Next Message by JSmits is [757].<br />

[766] Somramthom: graded A Capitalism is exploitation. In a capitalistic society, exploitation<br />

must exist. <strong>The</strong>re must be surplus value created by the laborers for the capitalists<br />

to pr<strong>of</strong>it. But wages paid to the laborer must be high enough that the laborer can sustain<br />

himself and live to work another day. <strong>The</strong>se two ideas allow us to understand the difference<br />

between surplus labor time and overtime wages.<br />

Since there must always be surplus value, there must always be surplus labor time. <strong>The</strong><br />

term “surplus labor time” can be defined as the amount <strong>of</strong> time a laborer spends creating<br />

surplus value. This is when the value created by the laborer exceeds his wage. All value<br />

created after this point is reached is surplus value. Thus all the time spent creating value<br />

after the wage is reached is surplus labor time.<br />

Overtime wages are wages paid that are higher than the normal wage the laborer receives.<br />

This higher wage is an incentive to work longer than is contractually obligated <strong>of</strong> the laborer.<br />

When the laborer is paid overtime, he uses a greater portion <strong>of</strong> his labor time earning his<br />

wage and a lesser portion creating surplus value for the capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its. Surplus labor time<br />

still exists and while overtime pay is greater than the original wage, it cannot be greater<br />

than the total value created by the laborer. Otherwise, there would be no surplus value, no<br />

exploitation and no capitalism.<br />

Hans: A too high overtime rate would not eliminate capitalism, but it would eliminate overtime.<br />

Message [766] referenced by [823]. Next Message by Somramthom is [767].<br />

[773] Alex: Invisible vs. Visible labor. Surplus labor is the extra labor produced by<br />

the worker once he/she has produced the necessary labor. According to Marx, this labor is<br />

unpaid labor from the worker, and it is where all the pr<strong>of</strong>its are gained for the capitalists.<br />

Overtime is the extra labor from the worker that is paid by the capitalist at a higher rate.<br />

<strong>The</strong> difference between the two is that workers are always producing surplus labor when<br />

employed by the capitalist regardless <strong>of</strong> the hours worked, and it is always integrated within<br />

398 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

their jobs. Overtime is extra work from the employee, that even though it still has surplus<br />

value, it is seen as working beyond the necessary and better compensated. Although I tried<br />

to phrase these concepts in my own words, I have to applaud to Hans’ exemplary definition<br />

because it made me truly wrap my head around the concept and understand it. Hans says<br />

in [2007fa:493] “overtime labor is a surface category, while surplus labor is not,” where he<br />

goes on to explain that the worker thinks he’s getting fully compensated for his labor, when<br />

truly his labor is worth much more than what the capitalist is paying him, this is why it’s<br />

invisible. Overtime is visible because <strong>of</strong> the premiums received by the worker, because <strong>of</strong><br />

the extra hours worked above the regular hours, and it is appreciated by both the worker and<br />

the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Alex is [1015].<br />

[775] GoUtes: Surplus labor and overtime. <strong>The</strong>re is a great difference between surplus<br />

labor and overtime. Surplus labor is defined as labor exerted; after the required amount <strong>of</strong><br />

expected labor is performed, to create a certain good or a set amount <strong>of</strong> goods. Whereas,<br />

overtime is the amount <strong>of</strong> time exceeding the set goal established to create the good.<br />

A laborer could have overtime, work longer hours and not put forth a full effort to produce<br />

goods, yet still not reach the requirements to create a good. This would be one example <strong>of</strong><br />

an inept laborer who has “overtime”.<br />

However, the laborer could work harder and go the extra mile while still accomplishing<br />

their set goal within the allowed time frame, and exceed all expectations or limitations set.<br />

This would be an example <strong>of</strong> surplus labor.<br />

Hans: Wrong definition <strong>of</strong> surplus-labor. A worked-out example with numbers explaining surplus-labor is [Answer:7].<br />

It is important that you understand this; it is at the core <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Message [775] referenced by [796]. Next Message by GoUtes is [993].<br />

[796] Kaimani: Surplus Labor Vs. Overtime. Go Utes [775] defines surplus labor as<br />

“labor exerted; after the required amount <strong>of</strong> expected labor is performed, to create a certain<br />

good or a set amount <strong>of</strong> goods.” Marx 690:1/o defines overtime as “the prolongation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

working day beyond the limits corresponding to the usual price <strong>of</strong> labor.”<br />

Marx argues in 690:1/o that surplus labor doesn’t exist for the worker since it already<br />

included in the normal working day. Go Utes [775] tries to make the distinction that the<br />

worker if they “go the extra mile” can achieve surplus labor. This is not true because as I<br />

stated before Marx says that “surplus labor time doesn’t exist at all for the worker...... And<br />

all though there is a definite quantity <strong>of</strong> unpaid labor and by that there is the normal source<br />

<strong>of</strong> his pr<strong>of</strong>its” [690:1/o] <strong>The</strong> worker doesn’t get paid any more or any less for the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

work that he does during regular hours because those terms have been set and agreed by with<br />

the employer however, with overtime the worker can increase their wages with the increased<br />

production <strong>of</strong> their work. Although overtime is just a substitution for surplus labor and the<br />

worker doesn’t realize this, the worker is benefiting from overtime with an increase in wages<br />

for increased labor produced for the employer.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> Marx quote in your second paragraph is completely botched up. Marx says that surplus labor does<br />

not exist for the capitalist. By this Marx means that the capitalist does not know, and no<strong>thing</strong> in his immediate<br />

experience is telling him, that he is paying the worker only for part <strong>of</strong> the worker’s product. For the worker, surplus<br />

labor exists—the worker has to work far too long every day for far too little pay. This is certainly part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

worker’s experience.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 399<br />

Next Message by Kaimani is [812].<br />

[811] SMIKEC: extra credit. According to Marx, the capitalist exploits the worker<br />

by having surplus labor. <strong>The</strong> capitalist defines a wage that is a portion <strong>of</strong> the total value<br />

produced by that worker per day. Once you have value for a product you then minus the<br />

wage and that will give you your surplus labor. As an example if a worker is paid $10 an<br />

hour to pack boxes and produces $20 worth <strong>of</strong> value in that hour, then after 30 minutes <strong>of</strong><br />

work in that hour, the rest would be surplus which would equal 30 minutes. <strong>The</strong> latter 30<br />

minutes would be surplus labor because it is unpaid, since his wage was paid with-in the<br />

<strong>first</strong> 30 minutes. If you take that same example and put overtime into the mix you would<br />

still have surplus labor. Lets state that overtime equals 1.5 times more the wage, so now<br />

the box packer would be getting $15 an hour versus his $10 an hour before overtime. Even<br />

with overtime at $15 an hour the capitalist is still seeing surplus labor because the worker is<br />

producing $20 worth <strong>of</strong> value an hour, still creating $5 worth <strong>of</strong> surplus labor per hour.<br />

Next Message by SMIKEC is [896].<br />

[853] Kobe: In this question we are asked what’s the difference between surplus labor time<br />

and overtime. This is a comparison between two <strong>thing</strong>s that can not be validly compared.<br />

Surplus labor is the margin created from the worker’s wage and the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity,<br />

it is not some<strong>thing</strong> that we can physically see. As compared to overtime, in which it is labor<br />

in excess <strong>of</strong> the normal working day. Overtime is typically rewarded with higher pay as<br />

opposed to surplus labor time. Laborers do have surplus labor time in every minute <strong>of</strong> work<br />

as long as the wage is lower than the value produced by the laborer.<br />

Next Message by Kobe is [862].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 771 Why did some London workshops pay, for the same labor, time wages to<br />

Englishmen and piece wages to Frenchmen?<br />

[812] Kaimani: Wages. In [692:4/o] (2) Marx states that piece wages and time wages<br />

coexist in the same shop for the same labor ....Marx explains that some shops because <strong>of</strong><br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> the work or operation that had to be performed even though piece wages were<br />

usually the common form <strong>of</strong> pay...time wages were handed out.[771:(3)] <strong>The</strong> shops did this<br />

to maximize pr<strong>of</strong>itability and surplus labor time from their workers. with piece wages the<br />

shops were able to hirer and work people for a set rate and didnt have to pay overtime. It is<br />

almost like the salaried position at a corporate job. <strong>The</strong>y have to put in just as many hours<br />

as the time wage worker plus overtime and not get paid for the extra hours that they put in.<br />

<strong>The</strong> time wage workers get paid hourly plus overtime if they work overtime. This works in<br />

the favor <strong>of</strong> the company/shop because the piece wage worker/salaried worker is producing<br />

more than the time worker is producing while they are both working the same amount <strong>of</strong><br />

hours. <strong>The</strong> shop/corporation is maximizing the use <strong>of</strong> surplus labor time in both cases. it is<br />

compared to the salaried worker and the hourly worker. they both work the same 40 hours<br />

a week but the salaried worker is finishing more work in less time and has more demands.<br />

the hourly individual still works hard but is being compensated with less money and has to<br />

work overtime to make as much money as the salaried employee. In the end they exert a lot<br />

<strong>of</strong> effort to finish their work and they are compensated relatively the same amount over the<br />

same period <strong>of</strong> time.<br />

400 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> shop does this maximize surplus labor time and pr<strong>of</strong>itability for themselves this is<br />

why they pay half <strong>of</strong> their workers piece wages and the other half time wages.<br />

Message [812] referenced by [814]. Next Message by Kaimani is [830].<br />

[814] Hans: This <strong>Question</strong> will Not be on the Exam. <strong>The</strong> extra credit period is for<br />

designated exam questions, or general homework questions which were answered before<br />

and where the answers were inconclusive so that clarification is needed. <strong>The</strong> expectation<br />

is that your submissions help everybody to prepare for the exam. This is not the time to<br />

increase the workload for everyone else because you need a grade. Since question 771 was<br />

not answered before, it will not be on the exam, and message [812] will remain ungraded.<br />

By contrast, if you submit answers to designated exam questions at the present time, they<br />

will get grades even if the email says “ungraded exam question”.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [816].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 775 is 680 in 2008fa, 711 in 2009fa, and 830 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 775 Why is the form <strong>of</strong> piece wage just as irrational as that <strong>of</strong> time wages?<br />

[757] JSmits: graded A Exploitation Reigns Supreme. <strong>The</strong> form <strong>of</strong> piece wage is just as<br />

irrational as that <strong>of</strong> time wages because the capitalist still exploits the worker in both forms<br />

<strong>of</strong> wages. A piece wage is just a slightly different form <strong>of</strong> the time wage; they contain a lot<br />

<strong>of</strong> the same qualities.<br />

Marx says in 692:1, “<strong>The</strong> piece-wage is no<strong>thing</strong> but a transmuted form <strong>of</strong> the time-wage<br />

just as the time-wage is a transmuted form <strong>of</strong> the value or price <strong>of</strong> labor power.” Much <strong>of</strong><br />

the irrationality in both wages is because <strong>of</strong> the similarities between both. With piece wages<br />

your wage is based on the number <strong>of</strong> pieces <strong>of</strong> product you make. <strong>The</strong> example that Marx<br />

gives is that you make two pieces <strong>of</strong> commodity worth 12 cents but you are only paid 6<br />

cents.<br />

With time wages your wage for the day is not paid in full. For example, you work for 2<br />

hours but 1 hour you work is for the capitalist and the other hour is for yourself. Now this<br />

is where the irrationality lies. In both piece wage and time wage you are only getting paid<br />

for half a day’s work. This isn’t the case all the time but the worker is never getting paid the<br />

full value <strong>of</strong> the commodities he makes. <strong>The</strong> worker is still being exploited in both forms <strong>of</strong><br />

wage and that’s the irrationality.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> irrationality is not only the exploitation itself but the way how this exploitation is hidden: the worker<br />

gets paid according to his labor (so it seems that all his labor is paid for), but he is not getting an equivalent <strong>of</strong><br />

the value produced by his labor. Instead he is getting a different amount based on the reproduction cost <strong>of</strong> his<br />

labor-power and the length <strong>of</strong> the workday. <strong>The</strong> difference between the 6 cents which he gets for each hour and the<br />

12 cents which he produces each hour, or the difference between the wage per piece and the value which his labor<br />

has added to the piece, is what makes this form, in Marx’s terminology, an “irrational” form.<br />

Next Message by JSmits is [972].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 776 is 677 in 2008SP, 681 in 2008fa, 712 in 2009fa, and 831 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 776 Explain how piece wages can become a “most fertile source for wage theft<br />

and capitalist cheating.”<br />

[809] Rico: Wage <strong>The</strong>ft. <strong>The</strong>re is no question that piece wages have contributed to<br />

the “fruitful source <strong>of</strong> wage theft and capitalist cheating” (Annotations pg. 578). <strong>The</strong>re


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 401<br />

are many modern day examples <strong>of</strong> how capitalists use piece wages to corrupt a laborer’s<br />

compensation. Mick gave a great present-day example <strong>of</strong> how capitalists use piece wages<br />

to benefit themselves. In [2008SP:560], Mick gives the example <strong>of</strong> “quality control and the<br />

subjective nature <strong>of</strong> quality assessment,” which creates avenues, whereby capitalists take<br />

advantage <strong>of</strong> their laborer’s wages. Mick illustrates the manner in which capitalists go about<br />

doing this. He explains that the capitalist is free to set the standard <strong>of</strong> quality that is expected<br />

from each individual laborer, and at what pace it should be produced. By doing this, the<br />

capitalist “simultaneously mitigates his employees’ financial entitlements and enhances his<br />

personal bank account.”<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are more contemporary examples <strong>of</strong> how the capitalist uses piece wages as a means<br />

to rob and cheat their laborer’s wages. Some capitalists claim that cutting wages is a necessity<br />

during this economically challenging time. Yet they require the same level <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

and advise that their employees should be grateful for the wage earning opportunity<br />

(even though the compensation is decreased and the labor power required increased). <strong>The</strong><br />

capitalist designates the quantity and quality <strong>of</strong> production and the laborer complies, allowing<br />

the capitalist to practice wage theft.<br />

Next Message by Rico is [862].<br />

[1082] Jon: On page 778 <strong>of</strong> the Annotations Hans says “<strong>The</strong> most striking characteristic<br />

<strong>of</strong> piece wages is that quality control <strong>of</strong> the product is built in.” This is also reaffirmed in<br />

Capital on page 694. Marx describes why the exploitation is most fertile when he says “This<br />

is because they provide an exact measure <strong>of</strong> the intensity <strong>of</strong> labor.” In time labor the Laborer<br />

is paid according to the time spent on production, a portion <strong>of</strong> the time is spent in free<br />

labor for the capitalist but the laborer receives pay based on time. In piece wage however<br />

the quality control is solely in the hands <strong>of</strong> the capitalist for every individual product the<br />

capitalist takes his portion and the only pay the laborer gets is when the product has met<br />

the qualifications set forth by the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> control is even more in the hands <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist when piece wage is the compensation which leads to the mst fertile source <strong>of</strong> wage<br />

theft for the capitalist.<br />

Hans: Marx makes a distinction between exploitation and wage theft.<br />

Next Message by Jon is [1085].<br />

[1084] Kraken: graded A <strong>The</strong> example that Marx gives regarding piece wages and capitalist<br />

cheating is that <strong>of</strong> a factory employing both piece wage workers and time wage workers.<br />

In this scenario the piece wage workers were working an extra 1/2 hour each day in an effort<br />

to produce more a few more goods and make a little extra money. Due to the way the<br />

production process was set up, the time wage workers were required to stay and worked the<br />

extra 1/2 hour each day, even though they were not paid any<strong>thing</strong> extra for their additional<br />

labor. Considering the fact that factories employed hundreds <strong>of</strong> time wage workers who<br />

were laboring for free, the benefit to the capitalist was significant. In this manner capitalists<br />

were able to cheat the time wage workers out <strong>of</strong> wages which they should have been paid<br />

for.<br />

Under the piece wage system capitalists also have ample opportunity to cheat the piece<br />

wage worker. Under this system the capitalist only pays the worker when the worker is<br />

making a pr<strong>of</strong>it for the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> capitalist doesn’t have to pay the worker for any<br />

“down time”, which would cut into the pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> capitalist also has the<br />

402 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

privilege <strong>of</strong> determining how much he is willing to pay the worker for each piece produced.<br />

If the capitalist decides he is paying the worker too much for the goods he is producing, the<br />

capitalist can then decide to lower the price he will pay for each piece or require the worker<br />

to produce more pieces each day in order to get paid. <strong>The</strong> capitalist also sets the standard<br />

for product quality. This gives the capitalist the opportunity to set the standard for product<br />

quality so high that they can control how many pieces they have to pay for by rejecting the<br />

pieces that don’t meet their quality standards.<br />

First Message by Kraken is [7].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 777 is 689 in 2007SP, 682 in 2008fa, 713 in 2009fa, 802 in 2011fa, and 832 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 777 Time wages and piece wages have opposite effects on the competition between<br />

workers. Explain.<br />

[763] Giant: graded A Is it better to work together or alone? Time wage groups workers<br />

together. <strong>The</strong> capitalist looks at the bigger picture when estimating what workers’ labor<br />

power is worth, then he <strong>of</strong>fers the workers a hourly/daily/weekly/monthly wage based on<br />

this assessment. This wage will be just enough to give the worker incentive to sell their<br />

labor power yet leave the capitalist with some pr<strong>of</strong>it for producing the product. <strong>The</strong> amount<br />

or speed <strong>of</strong> individual laborers will not cause the wage to differentiate between workers as<br />

long as the overall production needs are met. This allows workers to work together as one,<br />

creating more <strong>of</strong> a team environment. By all individual workers working together to reach<br />

the capitalist demands more efficiently, they all reap the benefits by either getting higher<br />

wages, or having to work less hours. <strong>The</strong>re is competition but all workers benefit from the<br />

competition.<br />

Piece wage is designed for a more one-one-one basis. This form <strong>of</strong> production encourages<br />

workers to work as efficiently as possible. <strong>The</strong> key here is to outdo other workers so you<br />

reap the most benefit. <strong>The</strong> benefits here are given to only the individual worker and not the<br />

group <strong>of</strong> workers. While the work is more efficient for the capitalist, it causes the laborer to<br />

be more easily taken advantage <strong>of</strong> because they have to work harder than all other workers<br />

to reap benefits, thus separating workers instead <strong>of</strong> creating a team environment for workers<br />

like time wages does.<br />

Message [763] referenced by [813]. Next Message by Giant is [897].<br />

[813] Hans: Employee to Capitalist: You are Fired. How is your wage level determined?<br />

<strong>The</strong> following passage from [763] probably captures what an average employee<br />

may think about their wages, especially after taking a course or two in mainstream microeconomics.<br />

<strong>The</strong> wage is set by the capitalist at that level at which it<br />

will be just enough to give the worker incentive to sell their labor power yet<br />

leave the capitalist with some pr<strong>of</strong>it for producing the product.<br />

I.e., the wage is a little less than the value the worker adds to the product, but it cannot be<br />

too much less because then the worker would go elsewhere.<br />

Now let’s look how Marx think this wage is determined. Marx does not think the capitalist<br />

has to give the workers incentives to sell their labor power. <strong>The</strong> capitalist system does this for


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 403<br />

them: the workers have to survive, and since they have no access to the means <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

selling their labor-power is the only way for them to survive. <strong>The</strong> capitalist system helps the<br />

capitalists also in a different way: since unemployment is a systemic feature <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

(chapter 25 will explain why), workers have no market power but must accept the bare<br />

minimum. Ok, what is this bare minimum? Since workers are forced to work in order to<br />

survive, the bare minimum is just enough so that they can survive, i.e., can pay their bills<br />

and get a color TV for entertainment.<br />

Marx also says that this bare minimum is much much less than the value which the<br />

employee’s labor really creates. <strong>The</strong> average employee may not believe this, they may say:<br />

“if my employer pays me more he will go out <strong>of</strong> business.” Of course they will, because<br />

his competitors are still paying the low wages. But if all workers were to organize and<br />

obtain higher wages, you would be surprised how high the wage level can get without the<br />

capitalists going bankrupt. Just look around you; rich people in this society have access to a<br />

lot <strong>of</strong> wealth. Do you think this wealth fell from the sky? All this is wealth created by the<br />

workers for which the workers themselves did not receive an equivalent. This is how Marx<br />

sees the capitalist system.<br />

Message [813] referenced by [961]. Next Message by Hans is [814].<br />

[861] AlexDaily: graded A Piece-wages entice competition. Marx explains “in piecewages,<br />

although the price <strong>of</strong> the labor-time is measured by a definite quantity <strong>of</strong> product,<br />

the daily or weekly wage will vary with the individual differences between the workers,<br />

one <strong>of</strong> whom will supply, within a given period, the minimum <strong>of</strong> product only, another the<br />

average, and a third more than the average. With regard to their actual income, then, there is<br />

a variety among the individual workers, according to their different degrees <strong>of</strong> skill, strength,<br />

energy, and staying power.” Whereas with time wages, all workers receive the same pay as<br />

long as they worked the same amount <strong>of</strong> hours. Of course, when you are paid because <strong>of</strong><br />

your performance you will be more competitive with your other workers than if you are<br />

simply paid by time. However, piece-wages can be misleading because as Ashley states in<br />

[2008fa:897] “they are still being paid for the time <strong>of</strong> their expended labor power, as is the<br />

case with time wages”.<br />

Next Message by AlexDaily is [951].<br />

[922] Lana: In a time wage system, workers are generally less competitive because <strong>of</strong><br />

the “team work” mentality. <strong>The</strong> capitalist presents the workers with a set wage based on<br />

what their labor power is worth, and the workers decided whether or not to sell their labor<br />

power to the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> worker will earn enough to support and maintain himself and<br />

the capitalist will make a pr<strong>of</strong>it. <strong>The</strong> workers do not have incentive to work faster or harder<br />

than their fellow employees, creating an environment where the workers are a single unit<br />

efficiently accomplishing production goals. If and when these goals are met, the capitalist<br />

may reward the workers as a whole with a higher wage or other benefits because he is making<br />

a good pr<strong>of</strong>it. However, the capitalist does not like this arrangement as much because it gives<br />

his workers the ability to unionize, plot, and demand higher pay, benefits, etc. <strong>The</strong> capitalist<br />

has some<strong>thing</strong> to fear in a time wage system.<br />

In a piece wage system, competition is fierce because the system is viewed from an individual<br />

perspective. Workers do not feel like a team because the pay they receive depends<br />

solely on the amount <strong>of</strong> effort they personally expend. <strong>The</strong>y are trying to “outdo” each other<br />

404 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

and receive the most pay for themselves. <strong>The</strong> capitalist prefers this system because it is<br />

easier for him to take advantage <strong>of</strong> his workers, encouraging them to worker harder and for<br />

longer hours. This system allows the capitalist to manipulate his workers into a competitive<br />

environment and leaves him to not fear revolt from his employees.<br />

Next Message by Lana is [926].<br />

[943] Balrog: graded A Time Wages, Piece Wages and Competition. Under the time<br />

wage system the workers in a group all receive the same wage. <strong>The</strong>y do not compete against<br />

each other but as a team to complete the task at hand. When they work well they all receive<br />

the benefits and upon performing poorly they all suffer the consequences. In a piece wage<br />

system workers are paid according to how many commodities or pieces <strong>of</strong> commodities they<br />

produce. <strong>The</strong>ir goal is to make as much as they can as fast as they can. This places them in<br />

competition with their fellow workers and they no longer work as a team but against each<br />

other in order to produce the most and receive the highest wage.<br />

Hans: When the workers work against each other, then the capitalist has blown it. Capitalists are very careful to<br />

set <strong>thing</strong>s up in such a way that the workers won’t work against each other.<br />

Next Message by Balrog is [1029].<br />

[961] SMIKEC: Time wages create a group effort or union between the workers. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

all work together to try and achieve the end goal which is meant to be in the best interests <strong>of</strong><br />

the laborers as a whole. <strong>The</strong> capitalist makes sure that he is paying the time wage laborers<br />

just enough to ensure they sell their labor to him with enough margins left over to satisfy<br />

his pocket. With this, metrics or set expectations <strong>of</strong> production are created. As long as the<br />

production needs are met within the group, then the capitalist is happy. <strong>The</strong> team environment<br />

that the time wage concept creates is a competition that benefits everyone in the group.<br />

Greater efficiencies may equal higher wages which in turn is the effect <strong>of</strong> the group as a<br />

whole.<br />

Piece wage creates an environment where everyman is for themselves. If one worker<br />

excels, the only person it benefits is the worker and the capitalist because <strong>of</strong> a greater surplus<br />

labor, which in turn hinders the other laborers because they do not see any <strong>of</strong> the benefit from<br />

the improved efficiencies. Utilizing this type <strong>of</strong> production creates the “over achievers” <strong>of</strong><br />

the group, which typically lead to greater efficiencies, and more money for the capitalist.<br />

Hans: Regarding your sentence “<strong>The</strong> capitalist makes sure that he is paying the time wage laborers just enough to<br />

ensure they sell their labor to him with enough margins left over to satisfy his pocket,” read [813].<br />

Next Message by SMIKEC is [965].<br />

[963] Rmc: graded B+ Time wages more accurately portray the value <strong>of</strong> labor than piece<br />

wages because the worker is paid for how long he spends producing a commodity. If the<br />

finished commodity is sold for about the same amount the capitalist paid the worker to<br />

produce it (assume the price is increase a little to generate pr<strong>of</strong>it for the capitalist), the price<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity nearly reflects the value <strong>of</strong> the worker’s labor.<br />

With piece wages, usually the worker depends on selling the product to a customer to earn<br />

any income. <strong>The</strong> success <strong>of</strong> his efforts depend completely on the willingness <strong>of</strong> the customer<br />

to trade money for the product. This comes with much risk- does the product appeal to the<br />

consumer? Is the product a use-value to him? Can he afford to buy it? Especially in an<br />

economy such as ours currently, consumers are less willing to part with their money- it is<br />

more likely they will spend their money on food than “luxury” or unnecessary items. If a


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 405<br />

worker’s wage depends on getting the consumer to buy some<strong>thing</strong> they don’t need, want,<br />

or can’t afford, they will be hard-put to make a sale. An example is the movie <strong>The</strong> Pursuit<br />

<strong>of</strong> Happyness: the main character must sell a new, expensive machine that measures bone<br />

density to doctors and hospitals. <strong>The</strong> pool <strong>of</strong> customers is limited to begin with, and no one<br />

wants to buy his product; eventually, with no money, he and his son are left homeless and<br />

hungry because he cannot raise enough to pay for his means <strong>of</strong> subsistence. This type <strong>of</strong><br />

commission job leaves much to chance and the worker is more at risk than is counterpart<br />

who is paid a time-wage.<br />

Hans: You are saying there is almost no exploitation with time wages, only with piece wages. According to Marx,<br />

this is not true. Already with time wages the value produced per hour greatly exceeds the wage. Nowadays it is<br />

roughly twice the wage.<br />

Next Message by Rmc is [1063].<br />

[969] Atticus: graded A+ In a firm where only time wages exist laborers only create an<br />

average daily amount <strong>of</strong> value for the capitalists to pay the laborers a living wage and keep<br />

surplus value for themselves. Laborers have little or no incentive to create more value than<br />

what the capitalists expect from them. Laborers may in fact decrease the intensity <strong>of</strong> their<br />

work once this expected daily value becomes apparent to them. <strong>The</strong>re is little competition<br />

between laborers under these conditions. Piece wages are derived from average labor time<br />

and not the actual value that is created in each piece produced. Laborers have more incentives<br />

to intensify their work under these conditions. <strong>The</strong>y gain a greater desire to earn more<br />

wages by producing more than expected and “outdo” their co-workers. This increased sense<br />

<strong>of</strong> competition exists even in firms where the majority <strong>of</strong> laborers are paid time wages and a<br />

minority <strong>of</strong> exemplary laborers are paid in piece wages. <strong>The</strong> capitalists begin to expect more<br />

from laborers paid in time wages. <strong>The</strong>se conditions have the effect <strong>of</strong> lowering wages and<br />

increasing productivity. Capitalists gain more surplus value at the expense <strong>of</strong> the laborers<br />

when piece wages are thrown into the production process.<br />

Hans: Good description how the workers try to decrease the intensity <strong>of</strong> their labor.<br />

Message [969] referenced by [2011fa:735]. Next Message by Atticus is [1068].<br />

[992] Somramthom: graded A Piece wage induces competition. Time wage earners<br />

are compensated based on the amount <strong>of</strong> time spent working. Piece wage earners are compensated<br />

based on output. Because the output isn’t as important to time wagers as it is to<br />

piece wagers, time wagers spread the labor throughout the day. <strong>The</strong>re is no incentive to work<br />

harder since everyone gets paid equally no matter how much labor they perform. This results<br />

in little or no competition. Output matters much more to piece wagers. Competition is created<br />

between workers since everyone works the same number <strong>of</strong> hours, but higher earnings<br />

come to those with higher outputs. <strong>The</strong>re is now an incentive to produce more since harder<br />

workers get paid more.<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [1030].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 779 is 691 in 2007SP, 670 in 2007fa, 680 in 2008SP, and 834 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 779 Which advantages does the form <strong>of</strong> piece-wages have for the capitalists?<br />

What does it mean for the relation between the workers?<br />

[767] Somramthom: graded A Why I don’t want a commission based job. When laborers<br />

are paid according to piece wages, capitalists have more control over the number<br />

406 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> conditions in which laborers earn their wages along with the circumstances surrounding<br />

these conditions. <strong>The</strong>y benefit through more control on costs incurred, coercing higher<br />

production, diminishing laborer unity, etc.<br />

While working harder to produce more may allow the laborer to earn a greater take home<br />

pay, the capitalist also gains more surplus. <strong>The</strong> ratio <strong>of</strong> time spent earning a wage versus<br />

time spent producing surplus value for the capitalist is unchanged. However, it would seem<br />

there are a few laborers who earn wages closer to their produced value, i.e. laborers who<br />

produce more. <strong>The</strong>n it would also seem there is some benefit to the laborer, though it is<br />

limited quantitatively to those “harder” workers. This is not so. <strong>The</strong> capitalist sets a wage<br />

per piece produced. This wages remains the same whether a laborer produces 100 pieces in<br />

a day or 10 pieces in a day. Thus the surplus labor per unit and the value per unit is the same.<br />

Exploitation remains unchanged despite increased labor.<br />

Piece wages shifts the power balance more towards the capitalist and away from the<br />

laborer since the laborer’s power comes from numbers. Without that power in numbers,<br />

laborers can’t demand better wages or shorter working days. <strong>The</strong>se two changes would<br />

decrease the amount <strong>of</strong> exploitation <strong>of</strong> the laborers by the capitalist and thus prove to be a<br />

greater benefit to the laborers.<br />

It seems to me that piece-wages are more focused on benefiting the individual worker,<br />

while time wages benefits the group as a whole. Time wages allow for a greater average<br />

benefit for each laborer than piece wages. Since Marx emphasizes the power <strong>of</strong> the group <strong>of</strong><br />

laborers, he would be in favor <strong>of</strong> time wages and against piece wages.<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [823].<br />

[849] Balrog: graded A Piece wages, the capitalist’s choice. Piece wages are yet another<br />

method that the capitalist can use to squeeze every penny out <strong>of</strong> his workers. <strong>The</strong> capitalist<br />

motivates his workers by telling them that if they work harder, faster and produce more their<br />

wages will increase. Marx 696:1/o says that this form <strong>of</strong> production gives workers a “sense<br />

<strong>of</strong> liberty, independence and self-control”, where in reality the capitalist has received further<br />

power to manipulate. Workers are more easily persuaded to work longer days to receive a<br />

higher wage. In addition, the capitalist can set the piece wage at a rate where workers must<br />

work longer days in order to meet the level <strong>of</strong> pay at which they barely survive. If workers<br />

complain that their wages are low he can point out his most productive workers and create<br />

more drive within the less productive.<br />

Piece wages create a sense <strong>of</strong> competition among workers. <strong>The</strong>y are now no longer<br />

working as a team but are on a quest to produce and earn more than their fellow workers.<br />

This further pleases the capitalist because it prevents employees from uniting together to<br />

seek reasonable treatment.<br />

Next Message by Balrog is [940].<br />

[1101] Max: graded A <strong>The</strong> exploitative properties <strong>of</strong> piece wages. Piece wages are the<br />

most advantageous form <strong>of</strong> wages for the capitalist. With piece wages, labor doesn’t have to<br />

be supervised because if a laborer is not producing at the same speed and quality as another<br />

laborer, they will get paid less and <strong>of</strong>ten times will be replaced. Further, competition between<br />

laborers will intensify because nobody wants to get fired, so they all try to work harder than<br />

the other person. Laborers will also speed themselves up because they think the more they


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 407<br />

work, the more they get paid. This is true, but it also means that the capitalist is generating<br />

more pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Hans: It is not true in the long run that workers will get more pay if they produce more. <strong>The</strong> capitalists are only<br />

waiting for opportunities to increase the quota.<br />

Next Message by Max is [1176].<br />

[1134] IrvingHowe: When we take the perspective <strong>of</strong> capitalists as one party and workers<br />

as another—each group an independent <strong>of</strong> the other yet pure in their composition, we can<br />

analyze the situation rather easily. In taking this aggregate view, we will ignore what one<br />

worker may gain in the piece rate system when compared to a wage compensation system<br />

because the single worker who has gained under the piece rate system has necessarily <strong>of</strong>fset<br />

his own gains with the losses his overproduction has caused for another worker.<br />

Piece rate is a great advantage for the capitalist in most industries and inevitably destructive<br />

for the working class. For the capitalist, they only ever pay for actual units produced<br />

that making their labor expenses a wholly variable cost. In this situation, there is no loss for<br />

the capitalist when machinery goes down or a supply runs out. All burdens created by the<br />

ups and downs in production that come through no fault <strong>of</strong> the worker are still shouldered<br />

by the worker since his compensation ceases every time he must stop. This effect is again<br />

considered when the workers has to decide if taking a break is really worth the loss in pay<br />

that results from downtime and the possible loss <strong>of</strong> his job to workers producing more. For<br />

healthy, experienced workers laboring at a normal working speed, there is likely to be only<br />

a negligible difference in production levels between workers. <strong>The</strong>refore, in order to gain<br />

any additional compensation, the worker must produce more whether that means working<br />

longer, not taking breaks or even working at dangerous speeds.<br />

It is a fact <strong>of</strong> the piece rate system <strong>of</strong> compensation that creates competition and strife<br />

among workers as each struggles for his own survival. Its effects are multiplied as workers<br />

must constantly find ways to produce more and more, an act which in itself causes the loss<br />

<strong>of</strong> jobs. <strong>The</strong> workers cannot see themselves as partners in a larger struggle if they are at war<br />

with each other for their daily bread.<br />

All <strong>of</strong> these factors, disunity among workers, employing fewer people as a result <strong>of</strong> competition<br />

and totally variable labor costs are all advantages for the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> individual<br />

worker may gain, but only at the expense <strong>of</strong> his fellow worker. When viewed on the aggregate<br />

level, the piece-rate system has no benefit for the workers at all.<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [1135].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 781 is 694 in 2007SP, 673 in 2007fa, and 682 in 2008SP:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 781 Why is piece wage the wage form most appropriate for capitalism?<br />

[799] Ferox: graded A Piece Wage - a Perfect System for Capitalist Exploitation. <strong>The</strong><br />

piece wage is a perfect system for the capitalist for several reasons; it allows the capitalist<br />

to diminish the price paid per good, has a built in mechanism for quality control, creates a<br />

disunited working class, and masks the worker’s exploitation.<br />

Since time is no longer factored into the wage, the worker will attempt to increase productivity<br />

in a given period <strong>of</strong> time in order to increase the wage paid. This however lowers<br />

the price per piece produced — reducing the price <strong>of</strong> the worker’s labor.<br />

408 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Quality control is placed in the hands <strong>of</strong> the worker - who knows that regardless <strong>of</strong> the<br />

labor invested in the product, the capitalist may refuse to pay for a substandard item. This<br />

is in contrast to a time wage, where the worker is paid for the production time required.<br />

<strong>The</strong> worker is now wholly invested in maximizing value for the capitalist at the expense <strong>of</strong><br />

herself.<br />

<strong>The</strong> workers become disunited for two reasons. In a time wage scenario, all workers<br />

are paid the same for the same type <strong>of</strong> work and must endure the same conditions in the<br />

work environment. Thus it is in the collective interest <strong>of</strong> the workers to unite and fight for<br />

better pay/conditions/etc. This is the basic idea behind the formation <strong>of</strong> a union. However,<br />

in a piece wage situation, individual productivity differences <strong>of</strong> a worker translate to wage<br />

differences. A strong difference in wages compared against equal labor time <strong>of</strong> the workers<br />

causes dissatisfaction not towards the capitalist, but towards fellow workers and the self.<br />

<strong>The</strong> piece wage system masks the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the worker by shifting the production<br />

focus <strong>of</strong> the worker to producing for her benefit. While the capitalist will gain surplus<br />

value regardless <strong>of</strong> a worker’s productivity, the worker focuses on maximizing personal<br />

productivity in order to maximize her wage. When she is paid, she feels as though she has<br />

been rewarded for increased productivity — masking the exploitative process in a feeling <strong>of</strong><br />

personal achievement.<br />

Hans: You obviously used and improved on [2008SP:528]; you should have referenced it.<br />

Message [799] referenced by [971]. Next Message by Ferox is [915].<br />

[902] Utefan: Piece wage is most appropriate for capitalism because it is the easiest way<br />

to exploit the worker. <strong>The</strong> value per hour remains the same, say $40, however the time to<br />

complete the product is where exploitation takes place. Assume a product takes 2 hours to<br />

complete. If I were to get paid $15 per hour then the value would be $40 per hour for the<br />

capitalist and then my wage would be given according to the hours I worked and would not<br />

be affected whether I finished the product or not. Now if I got paid $15 per product then the<br />

capitalist receives $80 <strong>of</strong> value but only pays me $15 because it took 2 hours to complete<br />

the product; also in order to make the same wage I would have to work double in this case.<br />

It would be increasingly difficult if any product took more than 1 hour to complete.<br />

Hans: If it takes 2 hours to finish the product then the capitalist cannot expect you to finish it in 1 hour. <strong>The</strong>refore<br />

the capitalist would have to pay $30 for two hours <strong>of</strong> time wages, and the piece wage would have to be $30 per<br />

piece. This still gives him a surplus-value <strong>of</strong> $50 per piece. If the capitalist pays $15 per piece he pays only half<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> your labor-power.<br />

Next Message by Utefan is [1055].<br />

[929] Bigwhite: It is the best and easiest way for the capitalist to exploit their workers.<br />

Piece wages encourage workers to work even harder because they are being paid on how<br />

many articles they finish not an hour to hour wage. So there is the incentive for the worker<br />

to try and finish as much as they can in a work day. Someone who is paid a piece-wage is<br />

usually working harder and longer than someone making a time-wage yet isn’t necessarily<br />

being compensated more for the hard work. It also helps to create rivalries amongst workers,<br />

someone will want to outwork everyone else to bring home the biggest paycheck. This helps<br />

the capitalist stay in power because in this scenario the workers won’t band together and try<br />

to unionize. Piece wage workers tend to work harder and longer to make the wage that is<br />

sufficient to keep them alive and be able to come back to work and produce.<br />

Next Message by Bigwhite is [930].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 409<br />

[936] ANK: Piece wage is the most appropriate for capitalism because piece wages exploit<br />

the worker more than time wages. <strong>The</strong> capitalist has a set wage for each commodity<br />

produced regardless <strong>of</strong> whether the laborer produces 10 commodities a day or 1000 commodities<br />

a day. If a worker is motivated and wants to earn a higher wage, they will produce<br />

more surplus value for the capitalist. If a given commodity is worth $100 on the market and<br />

the piece wage is $20, then the capitalist makes $80 in surplus value per commodity produced<br />

by the worker. Capitalists make the same pr<strong>of</strong>it per commodity regardless <strong>of</strong> whether<br />

the laborer works hard and is motivated for high wages or if the laborer is lazy and only<br />

produces 10 commodities. Piece wages are the most appropriate for capitalists because they<br />

exploit workers and require workers to work harder than if they worked on time wages, thus<br />

benefiting the capitalists who reap the benefits <strong>of</strong> the surplus value.<br />

Hans: Workers do not have the option to work slowly. <strong>The</strong>y will get fired if they do.<br />

First Message by ANK is [87].<br />

[971] Deadfamous: graded A Most <strong>of</strong> my answer comes from Installment 2, Ferox’s<br />

[799] in particular, some are in qoutes, some are revisions <strong>of</strong> his words<br />

“Since time is no longer factored into the wage, the worker will attempt to increase productivity<br />

in a given period <strong>of</strong> time in order to increase the wage paid. This however lowers<br />

the price per piece produced — reducing the price <strong>of</strong> the worker’s labor.”<br />

“Quality control is placed in the hands <strong>of</strong> the worker - who knows that regardless <strong>of</strong> the<br />

labor invested in the product, the capitalist may refuse to pay for a substandard item. This<br />

is in contrast to a time wage, where the worker is paid for the production time required.<br />

<strong>The</strong> worker is now wholly invested in maximizing value for the capitalist at the expense <strong>of</strong><br />

herself.”<br />

It seems to mask the exploitative process in a feelings <strong>of</strong> the ability to make more money.<br />

<strong>The</strong> workers become disunited due to the fact that they may all not have to endure the same<br />

work conditions, that as the producers become more valuable to the capitalist their conditions<br />

may improve.<br />

Next Message by Deadfamous is [974].<br />

[1205] Kiko: <strong>The</strong> piece wage is the most advantageous to the capitalist. First it puts the<br />

laborer in direct competition with his fellow laborer. If he is making more that his coworker<br />

he reaps the rewards <strong>of</strong> harder work and longer hours and his friend suffers because his wage<br />

is low due to the fact that his output is lower. <strong>The</strong> capitalist loves this because she is getting<br />

commodities at a set price without any residual. For example the worker making $10/hr<br />

sometimes makes five widgets and maybe towards the end <strong>of</strong> the shift they slow to only four<br />

there is one more that they know to make but because they are already receiving the $10<br />

there is no real incentive to make that fifth. Whereas a piece wage you will always receive<br />

one widget for $2.50. <strong>The</strong> capitalist knows that the laborers are in direct competition for a<br />

piece <strong>of</strong> the pie and as we all know there is only so much pie. <strong>The</strong> capitalist also has self<br />

interest in that they want the most output for the least input. Whereas the hourly laborer can<br />

take his time for he knows he is going to be paid the same wage wether he makes on item or<br />

ten. (standards do apply)<br />

Next Message by Kiko is [1206].<br />

410 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 783 is 696 in 2007SP, 675 in 2007fa, 684 in 2008SP, 688 in 2008fa, 719 in<br />

2009fa, 808 in 2011fa, and 838 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 783 If the capitalists make higher pr<strong>of</strong>its due to technical innovation, should the<br />

workers get part <strong>of</strong> this?<br />

[740] ANK: Well it depends... When capitalists make higher pr<strong>of</strong>its due to technical<br />

innovations, they must decide whether to share the pr<strong>of</strong>its with their workers or keep the<br />

increased pr<strong>of</strong>it for themselves. My <strong>first</strong> instinct is to say that capitalists should absolutely<br />

not share their increased pr<strong>of</strong>its because they made the investment in the technological innovation<br />

and they deserve the higher pr<strong>of</strong>its for doing so. I am also inclined to say that the<br />

capitalist should not share pr<strong>of</strong>its because these innovations are likely to make the job easier<br />

for the workers, and that would please the workers and prevent an outcry for a share <strong>of</strong> the<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its. For example, consider assembly lines in the automobile industry. This technical<br />

innovation made building cars easier for workers and increased pr<strong>of</strong>its for capitalists. When<br />

assembly lines were introduced, I imagine workers were excited to use the new technology<br />

to make their work easier instead <strong>of</strong> using this as an opportunity to fight for a share <strong>of</strong> the<br />

increased pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

But on the other hand, there is one case where I think the worker is entitled to a share<br />

<strong>of</strong> the increased pr<strong>of</strong>its and that is when the worker is required to obtain new training and<br />

education to operate and use the technical innovations. This training and education makes<br />

the worker more valuable to the capitalist because they can now create higher pr<strong>of</strong>its with<br />

the new innovations. Whether or not workers “should” get a share <strong>of</strong> the higher pr<strong>of</strong>its from<br />

technical innovations depends on whether or not they are required to gain new training and<br />

education to perform their job.<br />

Hans: Look at my comments to [2007SP:931] and [2007fa:469].<br />

Message [740] referenced by [774] and [798]. Next Message by ANK is [754].<br />

[774] Hans: Why imagine <strong>thing</strong>s if you have Wikipedia. ANK says in [740]: “When<br />

assembly lines were introduced, I imagine workers were excited to use the new technology<br />

to make their work easier instead <strong>of</strong> using this as an opportunity to fight for a share <strong>of</strong> the<br />

increased pr<strong>of</strong>its.” Assembly line work was boring and demeaning compared with the highly<br />

skilled handicraft work which it replaced. <strong>The</strong> workers had no control over their labor, the<br />

assembly line completely controlled them. <strong>The</strong>y were not allowed to leave their station<br />

which was <strong>of</strong>ten measured in inches. It was usually very noisy, and where the noise was not<br />

overwhelming people were <strong>of</strong>ten not allowed to talk. BUT assembly line work paid very<br />

well. Henry Ford in 1913/14 paid $5 a day, and a worker could buy a model T with four<br />

months’ pay. Henry Ford deliberately let his workers have a part <strong>of</strong> the gains <strong>of</strong> productivity,<br />

with the express goal to create a bigger market which led to economies <strong>of</strong> scale, i.e., even<br />

higher productivity. Other capitalists considered Ford to be a class traitor. (All this info from<br />

the Wikipedia entry about assembly lines.)<br />

Message [774] referenced by [798]. Next Message by Hans is [777].<br />

[798] Balrog: graded A ‘Nice People’ Share. Ank in [740] did a fine job <strong>of</strong> presenting<br />

both sides <strong>of</strong> the argument. I too agree that it is the choice <strong>of</strong> the capitalist to decide whether<br />

to share the pr<strong>of</strong>its with his workers or not. If the workers must receive further training or if<br />

the level <strong>of</strong> expertise required increases they could potentially be eligible for a higher wage.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 411<br />

With this submission I hope to share some thoughts, ideas and examples that came to mind<br />

while reading your submission and Hans response.<br />

Some employers are generous and take care <strong>of</strong> their workers. Hans in [774] mentioned<br />

that assembly lines created a repetitive and demanding process for the workers but that Henry<br />

Ford compensated his workers well. Recently the appalling movie Grown-Ups was released.<br />

Despite being unoriginal and unfunny it made $270 million. Adam Sandler was the producer<br />

and being a nice boss rewarded his four co-stars with $200,000 Maserati sports cars.<br />

This is an example <strong>of</strong> a ‘nice boss’ (that all <strong>of</strong> us wish we had) but in a capitalistic society<br />

the capitalist knows that the new machine he purchased with his money does not create<br />

value. Even though he may produce more T-shirts in a day, the only value found in those<br />

t-shirts stems from the value <strong>of</strong> the labor that each worker placed inside those t-shirts. <strong>The</strong><br />

Labor-power he purchased from his workers before the technical innovation is still the same<br />

labor-power which holds the same value after the new technology is incorporated.<br />

I recently watched a documentary about the cruel working conditions <strong>of</strong> factories in<br />

Bangladesh. In one factory Disney was paying its workers on average 14 cents an hour<br />

to sew their cute little Pooh Bear shirts. <strong>The</strong>y would work 15 hour days 7 days a week and<br />

were denied maternity benefits. When workers asked for better treatment Disney pulled their<br />

work out <strong>of</strong> the factory and went elsewhere leaving that group <strong>of</strong> employees jobless.<br />

<strong>The</strong> capitalist is the one with the power and does not need to share the pr<strong>of</strong>its. In fall 2009<br />

Chris [2009fa:769] presented the idea that the technical innovation may be a flop and could<br />

create losses. Should the worker then share the financial burden that the new technology<br />

created? Most certainly not. In that case, the Capitalist does not need to share the pr<strong>of</strong>its<br />

that he gained by supplying the money and taking the risk <strong>of</strong> incorporating new technology<br />

into his production process.<br />

Message [798] referenced by [816]. Next Message by Balrog is [849].<br />

[816] Hans: How even the best arguments can be turned around. In a Groucho Marx<br />

episode, the boss says to his protesting employees (who could have been coming straight<br />

from an Econ 5080 session): “You are against wage-labor? So am I. You are fired.”<br />

This is an example <strong>of</strong> turning the arguments <strong>of</strong> the critics <strong>of</strong> capitalism against them. Two<br />

other examples <strong>of</strong> such a turning around can be seen in Balrog’s message [798].<br />

(1) Balrog says: the capitalist does not need to share the gains <strong>of</strong> the new technology with<br />

the worker because the capitalist knows that machines do not create value, only workers do.<br />

Well, if the capitalist is so principled, then he would not only have to share his extra pr<strong>of</strong>its<br />

but give all pr<strong>of</strong>its back to his laborers.<br />

(2) Balrog refers to [2009fa:769] where Chris argues that workers suffer from the capitalists’<br />

bad decisions in bad times much more than the capitalists themselves do. <strong>The</strong>refore,<br />

says Chris, they should also benefit from the extra pr<strong>of</strong>its the capitalists make in good times.<br />

Balrog agrees with Chris that workers should not suffer from the capitalists’ bad decisions in<br />

bad times. <strong>The</strong>refore, Balrog continues, they also have no right to benefit from the capitalists’<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its in good times. Balrog exploits here a weakness in Chris’s argument, namely, that<br />

Chris assumes, for his point to be valid, the continued existence <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> the bad features<br />

412 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalism. On the other hand, one could criticize Balrog for basing his arguments not on<br />

the actual facts but on how he thinks the facts should be.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are two lessons to draw from Balrog’s intelligent debate maneuvers:<br />

(a) capitalism is a well calibrated system whose parts fit together. If you criticize one part<br />

<strong>of</strong> it, an observant adversary in a debate can probably find another part which then no longer<br />

fits and try to use this against your critique. <strong>The</strong> retort is <strong>of</strong> course that the system cannot be<br />

reformed but must be replaced altogether.<br />

(b) if you are in a debate with someone who does not want to hear your arguments, don’t<br />

think you can convince them by bringing better arguments. An intelligent person can always<br />

find ways to deflect even the best argument. In such a situation I personally apply following<br />

tactic: let your conversation partner politely know that his defenses are not convincing to<br />

you even if they are convincing to him or her, but otherwise you should find a nice way<br />

to end the conversation about this topic with that person. Do it in such a way that future<br />

conversations will still be possible. You may have ten times the same kind <strong>of</strong> conversation,<br />

but the eleventh time some<strong>thing</strong> may have happened and suddenly your conversation partner<br />

may be open to listen to you. <strong>The</strong>re are lots <strong>of</strong> people who are open to a good argument<br />

right now, you should spend your time and energy with them and not with those who have<br />

their emotions invested in not hearing you.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [828].<br />

[843] Kobe: This question is dictated by the capitalist running the company. If he/she<br />

chooses to share the pr<strong>of</strong>its due to technical innovations it would have a direct effect on<br />

laborers’ moral. How long would this last? Higher wages typically make people work<br />

harder but not for increased periods <strong>of</strong> time. I do believe that if the capitalist invented or<br />

financed the technological innovation that allows laborers to be more productive should be<br />

allowed to determine if he/she wants to share the increased pr<strong>of</strong>its that come with increased<br />

productivity. If the pr<strong>of</strong>it margin for the capitalist is higher than needed/wanted then this<br />

would allow for the capitalist to compensate workers for the productivity gain. From a<br />

laborer’s point <strong>of</strong> view, if he/she went through some sort <strong>of</strong> education in order to run the<br />

machine then I would feel like the increased pr<strong>of</strong>it should be shared.<br />

Message [843] referenced by [846]. Next Message by Kobe is [853].<br />

[846] Hans: Privatization <strong>of</strong> Social Resources. No <strong>of</strong>fense, but Kobe’s [843] is the<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong> which drives a Marxist up the wall. Kobe says that a capitalist can choose<br />

to share the gains <strong>of</strong> technology with his workers, and that in some situations it is even<br />

advantageous for the capitalist to be this generous. This calm consideration <strong>of</strong> enlightened<br />

self-interest makes a Marxist’s blood boil. Kobe overlooks that technical progress is not<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> which the capitalist has brought to the table. Technological progress is a social<br />

force emerging from the cooperation <strong>of</strong> millions <strong>of</strong> people. Perhaps the greatest impetus to<br />

technological progress is the experience <strong>of</strong> the work process itself, i.e., is the labor and toil<br />

<strong>of</strong> all the workers. But the capitalist has creamed it <strong>of</strong>f (because he lives in a society which<br />

enables and encourages this creaming <strong>of</strong>f) and now he is sitting there pondering what to do<br />

with “his” wealth. He expects us to think he is really generous if he gives some crumbs back<br />

to the workers (but only if they have really earned it and if it does not slow them down in<br />

their toil). Workers <strong>of</strong> the world, unite!


Next Message by Hans is [848].<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 413<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 785 is 638 in 2004fa, 587 in 2005fa, 697 in 2007SP, 676 in 2007fa, and 720 in<br />

2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 785 Marx writes: “the labor process, in the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production, appears<br />

only as a means for the process <strong>of</strong> valorization.” Why does he use the word “appears”<br />

here, and why did he put an “only” into this sentence? Shouldn’t he have said “the labor<br />

process is means for the process <strong>of</strong> valorization”?<br />

[935] Cougar: graded A Pr<strong>of</strong>its make the world go ’round. While researching this topic<br />

in the annotations and archives, I came across Hans’ response in [2007fa:602] which shed<br />

much needed light on Marx’s statement <strong>of</strong> interest. As Hans brings into focus, many <strong>of</strong> the<br />

activities we citizens engage in are driven by motives other than those which the activity<br />

was orginally intended for. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> example used was eating, meant to nourish and give<br />

needed energy to the human body which has become more <strong>of</strong> an indulgent activity to satisfy<br />

hunger and cravings. <strong>The</strong> second example used are families, perpetuated by love and sexual<br />

appetites over a basal need to populate the earth. <strong>The</strong>se driving forces that “appear” to<br />

supercede the intended purposes <strong>of</strong> specific activities become the form, as Hans explains,<br />

that those basal need manifest themselves.<br />

Relating to the labor process in Marx’s statement, once the word “appears” is removed,<br />

it becomes obvious that the “only” purpose <strong>of</strong> the labor process is indeed money-making<br />

by the capitalist, which take on more acceptable forms like that <strong>of</strong> driving the economy or<br />

supplying the consumer with needed commodities. Reading Marx’s statement in this way<br />

also shows the deception laborers are kept under in the capitalist economy. To fortify the<br />

idea that pr<strong>of</strong>iteering is truly the “only... means,” driving the labor process, Hans illustrates<br />

how production halted during the Great Depression as soon as producers could no longer<br />

turn a pr<strong>of</strong>it. All externalities rooted in the production process (jobs, incomes, needs, etc.)<br />

were and are still dependent on one key ingredient as Hans finally shows, pr<strong>of</strong>its. In the<br />

same semester, Fred [2007fa:582] identifies the social nature <strong>of</strong> Marx’s statement: although<br />

the labor process has become a social necessity, filling a plethora <strong>of</strong> needs in the economy,<br />

it is only the capitalist that benefits from the surplus.<br />

Hans: Taking on these forms does not degrade the basic necessities, as you imply with your words “indulgent” and<br />

“cravings.” I think on the contrary, it sublimates them. As if humankind got bored with just fulfilling the biological<br />

necessities and made a celebration out <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

Next Message by Cougar is [1136].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 788 is 559 in 2002fa, 698 in 2007SP, 677 in 2007fa, 814 in 2011fa, and<br />

844 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 788 How is the capitalist motivated to see to it that the social conditions<br />

<strong>of</strong> reproduction are met?<br />

[911] Cougar: (graded A) <strong>The</strong> NeverEnding Story... <strong>of</strong> Reproduction! As every capitalist<br />

will discover at some point in time, the labor and means <strong>of</strong> production which they<br />

utilize is finite and prone to failure. It is, therefore, wise to consider a “hedge” against<br />

such unforeseen events, like even a factory losing millions in potential revenue due to faulty<br />

equipment. <strong>The</strong> means <strong>of</strong> production may not be limitless but on the contrary, “<strong>The</strong> laws <strong>of</strong><br />

414 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

capital are not fulfilled with a one-time pr<strong>of</strong>it, they require the ceaseless making <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its...”<br />

as described by Hans’ annotations, pg 594. To maintain this “ceaseless” cycle <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its,<br />

the capitalist must ensure that the social conditions <strong>of</strong> reproduction are met in addition to<br />

the production process itself. In other words, the means <strong>of</strong> production must be groomed,<br />

maintained and replenished so that the production process may continue uninhibited, yielding<br />

limitless pr<strong>of</strong>its. Why should the capitalist be concerned with the social conditions <strong>of</strong><br />

reproduction? Pele [2007SP:1113] in the spring <strong>of</strong> 2007 uses an excellent quote from Hans’<br />

annotations that answers the matter in words we all can understand, “In capitalism, a capitalist<br />

has strong motivation to see his investment projects through: if he does not succeed,<br />

he may go bankrupt.” Pele’s response also reiterates the key ingredient that separates the<br />

capitalist from the workers he employs: Capital. Without pr<strong>of</strong>its, or the means <strong>of</strong> achieving<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its (means <strong>of</strong> production) the capitalist is merely a worker himself. Not only is it in the<br />

best interest <strong>of</strong> the capitalist to ensure the social conditions <strong>of</strong> reproduction are met, it is<br />

necessary if he or she wishes to maintain his pr<strong>of</strong>its and position.<br />

If I may add an original thought <strong>of</strong> my own, it would seem that laborers are also a finite<br />

factor in commodity production. Must the capitalist incorporate, in his quest to maintain<br />

the social conditions <strong>of</strong> reproduction, the perpetuation <strong>of</strong> his human labor power? Marx has<br />

helped us see that laborers are in many cases exploited, providing capitalists with labor surplus,<br />

but workers must still be efficient to ensure maximization <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its. It is my hypothesis<br />

that the capitalist must devise incentives to disguise his exploits and maintain the efficiency<br />

<strong>of</strong> his laborers. An example <strong>of</strong> this phenomenon is one used by Hans in class concerning<br />

health benefits. Although not originally intended for the well-being <strong>of</strong> employees, the capitalist<br />

uses its incorporation to ensure loyalty from existing laborers. Unless the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production AND the means <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production are satisfied in total, the capitalist<br />

may find himself out <strong>of</strong> the game early.<br />

Message [911] referenced by [918], [939], [2012fa:1179], and [2012fa:1251]. Next Message by Cougar is [935].<br />

[918] Tyler: It’s all about the pr<strong>of</strong>its. A capitalist is motivated to see that the social<br />

conditions <strong>of</strong> reproduction are met in order to ensure the continuance <strong>of</strong> his/her pr<strong>of</strong>its. Since<br />

the capitalist must be concerned with the continued success <strong>of</strong> the business, he/she must also<br />

be concerned with the reproduction process. <strong>The</strong>re must <strong>of</strong> necessity be a way for the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production to be reproduced, and societal conditions makes sure this takes place. Hence,<br />

the business owner is <strong>of</strong> course concerned that the social conditions <strong>of</strong> reproduction are met<br />

so as to continue his/her pr<strong>of</strong>itable future.<br />

Hans: You are summarizing what is wrong in [911] and leaving out what Cougar got right, namely, that the<br />

capitalists maintain their own plants and look after their own investments and in this way, without intending to,<br />

contribute to the reproduction <strong>of</strong> the system. My [215] applies to your answer. In general, you would get better<br />

grades if you’d think <strong>thing</strong>s through a little more deeply. I have the impression you are not thinking much about it<br />

because you don’t agree with what Marx says. It is a good exercise to think through theories which you don’t agree<br />

with.<br />

Message [918] referenced by [939]. Next Message by Tyler is [1072].<br />

[939] Hans: What, me responsible for the sun rising again tomorrow? Cougar [911]<br />

and Tyler [918] argue that it is <strong>of</strong> course in the interest <strong>of</strong> every capitalist to see to it that<br />

the conditions <strong>of</strong> reproduction are met. One should think so, but what is the reality? Marx<br />

told us in chapter 10 that between 1820 and 1850 the English capitalists just about killed the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 415<br />

working class with excessively long hours. <strong>The</strong>y did not come to their senses by themselves<br />

but had to be forced by the organized resistance <strong>of</strong> the workers.<br />

We don’t have to go back 200 years to find examples. Today the capitalists kill their<br />

workers not by too long hours but by junk food. <strong>The</strong> capitalists in the USA have resisted<br />

taxes so much that bridges collapse and our infrastructure is falling apart. <strong>The</strong>y deprive a<br />

large section <strong>of</strong> the working class <strong>of</strong> medical care. Fueled by speculation, they made a large<br />

misinvestment in housing which nobody needs, and as a side effect undermined the entire<br />

monetary and credit system.<br />

<strong>The</strong> only way that they are concerned about the general conditions <strong>of</strong> reproduction is<br />

in those cases where it happens to directly affect their bottom line. <strong>The</strong>y want to remain<br />

capitalists, therefore they maintain their own factories in working order. But this is not<br />

always the case either. <strong>The</strong> US auto companies in the 1960s let their US plants decay and<br />

pumped all money into investments in Europe, Japan, later Brazil and Mexico. <strong>The</strong> railroad<br />

companies have let the US rail infrastructure, which was once the envy <strong>of</strong> the world, go<br />

to the dogs. Since I am talking about transportation infrastructure: the auto companies<br />

also systematically bought up and dismantled the trolley systems which many US cities had<br />

(that’s why Trolley Square is a shopping center now).<br />

<strong>The</strong> capitalists cannot afford doing what is good for everyone, not even what is good for<br />

their own class, because <strong>of</strong> competition. Instead <strong>of</strong> enlightened concern for the continuance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the system, they take it for granted that the system will continue, just as they take it for<br />

granted that the sun will rise again tomorrow, and ride it as hard as they can. I think Marx<br />

should have said in chapter 23 that the capitalist system can reproduce itself only if the<br />

working class is strong enough to teach the capitalists the most rudimentary table manners.<br />

Message [939] referenced by [2011fa:884] and [2011fa:919]. Next Message by Hans is [955].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 796 is 646 in 2004fa, 595 in 2005fa, 705 in 2007SP, 684 in 2007fa, 697 in<br />

2008fa, 729 in 2009fa, and 822 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 796 Does the capitalist, who started a business with his own capital, preserve this<br />

capital while consuming surplus-value, or does he consume his original capital and replace<br />

it with accumulated surplus-value?<br />

[917] Tyler: Beginnings <strong>of</strong> business. A capitalist that starts his/her own business with<br />

his/her own capital advances his money with the starting <strong>of</strong> the business, the money advanced<br />

is thus spent. At this point, the business provides the owner the benefit <strong>of</strong> surplusvalue.<br />

However, the owner does not necessarily replace his original capital with surplusvalue.<br />

Steveeggett describes this: “If the capitalist hoarded his surplus-value and did not<br />

use it for consumption in any way, in this manner he could in essence regain the equivalent<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> what he spent.” [2008fa:996] From this explanation it is seen that whether the<br />

original capital used in the start-up <strong>of</strong> the business is regained depends entirely on what the<br />

owner decides to do with the surplus-value received.<br />

Hans: You are misunderstanding Steveeggett’s answer. Steveeggett meant it rhetorically: it is not possible for the<br />

capitalist not to eat. And as soon as he eats, he is eating up the capital which he advanced. He should not fool<br />

himself that the workers, by supplying unpaid surplus-labor, did not over time become the rightful owners <strong>of</strong> his<br />

capital, because he is eating away their surplus-value and not his own capital. You make it sound as if the capitalist<br />

could decide not to eat.<br />

416 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Tyler is [918].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 800 is 569 in 2002fa, 592 in 2003fa, 650 in 2004fa, 709 in 2007SP, 697 in<br />

2008SP, 701 in 2008fa, 856 in 2012fa, and 800 in Answer:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 800 Sometimes a worker has to eat while working, like a machine which needs<br />

fuel in order to keep going. Marx comments that “this, however, appears as an abuse.” Why<br />

didn’t he write “this, however, is an abuse”?<br />

[938] Kaush: Abuse and appearance <strong>of</strong> abuse. <strong>The</strong>re are two types <strong>of</strong> different consumptions<br />

according to Marx: productive consumption and individual consumption. Productive<br />

consumption is what is needed to keep the production process going i.e. adding raw<br />

materials, whereas individual consumption is what is consumed as a finished good. Marx<br />

does not say the worker’s eating while producing is abuse because the worker is attending<br />

to one <strong>of</strong> life’s basic needs (individual consumption). <strong>The</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> abuse is that while<br />

the worker is eating, he/she is refueling his/her diminished capacity to full strength (productive<br />

consumption). <strong>The</strong> worker now is like a well-oiled machine ready to produce at a<br />

higher level. This high level <strong>of</strong> production is to the benefit and exploitation <strong>of</strong> the capitalist<br />

(abuse). <strong>The</strong> capitalist seems innocent and oblivious to the worker’s eating on the job but<br />

tacitly having a major component <strong>of</strong> the production process fueled for more work.<br />

Hans: Good try, but this is not the answer. When Marx wrote “abuse” (Missbrauch) he did not mean “exploitation.”<br />

What I consider a correct answer is in [Answer:12].<br />

Message [938] referenced by [2012fa:1239]. Next Message by Kaush is [1007].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 803 is 653 in 2004fa, 602 in 2005fa, 712 in 2007SP, 691 in 2007fa, 700 in<br />

2008SP, and 704 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 803 Explain the sentence in 717:3/o: <strong>The</strong> capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its, not only by what he<br />

receives from but also by what be gives to, the laborer.<br />

[925] Milly: graded A Benefits all around. In this statement Marx implies that capitalists<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it from laborers not only from what they receive in labor-power but also from what they<br />

give in wages. Hans reiterates Jerm’s answer in [2005fa:1510] by saying that there are three<br />

ways capitalists benefit. (1) <strong>The</strong>y directly benefit from the pr<strong>of</strong>its created by the labor-power<br />

received. (2) <strong>The</strong>y also benefit from the wages they give because the workers individual<br />

consumption goes towards necessities such as food, rent, gas and work clothes that allows<br />

them to show up fresh and ready to work the next day. <strong>The</strong> worker basically maintains the<br />

most productive machine capitalists have. Lastly (3) this instinct workers have to take care<br />

<strong>of</strong> their needs <strong>first</strong> and foremost is helpful to capitalists because it allows them to give the<br />

laborer just enough to get by which makes them dependent and ensures that they will show<br />

up the next day to work.<br />

Hans: Very good answer. But I wouldn’t call it “benefits all around” (which usually means benefits for everyone).<br />

<strong>The</strong> working class doesn’t benefit but the capitalists benefit from the actions <strong>of</strong> the working class in several different<br />

ways. You express this well. <strong>The</strong> working class learns how to take care <strong>of</strong> their needs with modest means, and who<br />

benefits? <strong>The</strong> capitalists, because they can continue to pay low wages and still have workers who are productive<br />

today and in need <strong>of</strong> a job tomorrow.<br />

Next Message by Milly is [988].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 417<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 804 is 406 in 1999SP, 530 in 2001fa, 571 in 2002fa, 595 in 2003fa, 654 in<br />

2004fa, 713 in 2007SP, and 705 in 2008fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 804 In chapter Twenty-Three, Marx argues that the workers’ individual consumption<br />

benefits the capitalist because it is the reproduction <strong>of</strong> the capitalist’s most indispensable<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production. Does the workers’ consumption also benefit the capitalist because<br />

this creates a market for the goods the capitalists have to sell?<br />

[940] Balrog: graded A Please Don’t Consume More Than is Necessary. Much <strong>of</strong><br />

chapter 23 has focused on the individual consumption <strong>of</strong> workers and how this benefits the<br />

capitalist. <strong>The</strong> capitalist wants his workers to come into work each day healthy and full <strong>of</strong><br />

sufficient energy to fulfill the day’s tasks. Any consumption beyond this is not in his best<br />

interest. In past classes and according to natural thought people have argued that workers’<br />

consumption improves the market in which the capitalist sells. In certain cases this may be<br />

true; but the real intention <strong>of</strong> the capitalist is stated on pg. 611 <strong>of</strong> the annotations where it<br />

reads, “All the capitalist cares for, is to reduce the laborer’s individual consumption as far as<br />

possible to what is strictly necessary...”<br />

<strong>The</strong> capitalist reaps the most benefit when his workers in order to survive are forced<br />

to work as much as he chooses at the meager wage that he chooses. In this vast world,<br />

containing a variety <strong>of</strong> people seeking a diverse list <strong>of</strong> goods, he will readily find other<br />

people willing to purchase the commodities he produces. Furthermore, take into account the<br />

rich person with 7 flat screen televisions in his home that will make up for 7 workers who<br />

can not afford one under the rule <strong>of</strong> their capitalist employer :).<br />

Message [940] referenced by [941] and [944]. Next Message by Balrog is [942].<br />

[941] Bigwhite: Fatties. I feel that Balrog is right in his answer [940] yet I feel it could<br />

go the other way too. How could the capitalist not benefit from his workers consuming the<br />

very goods they produced? Not only is he exploiting them through their labor but now is<br />

exploiting them by buying his goods. Even though some companies <strong>of</strong>fer discounts and<br />

deals for the products to their employees it is never at a rate where the company doesn’t<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it. I feel that this is a win win situation for the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> only downside could<br />

potentially be that the worker overconsumes and becomes obese and isn’t able to work at<br />

their previous level. This may very well be the case <strong>of</strong> a lot <strong>of</strong> workers in the U.S. now.<br />

Hans: Balrog’s (and Marx’s) reasoning are based on the fact that you cannot exploit somebody by selling them<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> at competitive prices. Such a sale is an even exchange, neither party gains value.<br />

Capitalists do not need the workers to be prosperous to buy their stuff. A less prosperous working-class requires<br />

a re-arrangement <strong>of</strong> the output <strong>of</strong> the industries, but Marx thinks such a re-arrangement is always possible.<br />

BTW, obesity is not a sign <strong>of</strong> overconsumption but a sign <strong>of</strong> poor quality food and lack <strong>of</strong> education.<br />

Message [941] referenced by [944]. Next Message by Bigwhite is [1017].<br />

[944] Lana: <strong>The</strong> capitalist needs us to consume. I going to agree with both Balrog<br />

[940] and Bigwhite [941]. We’ve read that the capitalist will pay his workers what they need<br />

to survive. His goal is to pay them as little as possible and get them to work as much as<br />

possible. In that regard, the capitalist doesn’t want to essentially feed the worker’s appetite<br />

for pricier living standards because then he must compensate him accordingly. That being<br />

said, without consumer involvement, the capitalist is producing for no one. If workers aren’t<br />

receiving the wages that allow them to afford more expensive items, they probably won’t be<br />

buying them (or at least they financially shouldn’t be). In the U.S., retail sales <strong>of</strong> consumer<br />

418 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

goods make up the biggest portion <strong>of</strong> the GDP every year. What this basically means is that<br />

our capitalists are foreign corporations and they definitely depend upon us, the consumer, to<br />

buy their products.<br />

First Message by Lana is [13].<br />

[950] She: Company Stores. Reading over the debates about how a capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its if the<br />

workers consume, it just reminds me <strong>of</strong> the stories about the Frick company stores. I think<br />

to understand the capitalist motives, we need not look further than the actions <strong>of</strong> Henry Clay<br />

Frick and Andrew Carnegie, true pr<strong>of</strong>it-maximizing capitalists. Every<strong>thing</strong> they did was to<br />

one end–their personal gain. <strong>The</strong>ir laborers lived in company towns and could only shop at<br />

the company store. <strong>The</strong> workers were intentionally never paid more than bare subsistance<br />

and the goods at the company store were always overpriced. This combination, along with<br />

poor and dangerous working conditions, prevented the laborers from growing too strong and<br />

kept pr<strong>of</strong>its at the maximum level for the capitalists at the top.<br />

Henry Ford paid his workers higher wages than other capitalists; his declared motive was<br />

so his workers can afford to buy his cars. He realized it doesn’t do you any good to produce<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> that was out <strong>of</strong> reach for the largest social class.<br />

So either by force or enticement, the owners <strong>of</strong> production want you to buy their product.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y want the money they bought the labor-power with returned.<br />

Next Message by She is [1038].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 806 is 408 in 1999SP, 503 in 2000fa, 532 in 2001fa, 573 in 2002fa, 597 in<br />

2003fa, 605 in 2005fa, 715 in 2007SP, 703 in 2008SP, and 862 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 806 Regarding the question to what extent consumption is productive, Marx says<br />

that the individual consumption <strong>of</strong> the laborer is unproductive for the laborer, but productive<br />

for the capitalist and the state. Comment on this.<br />

[946] Spiral: A double-edged sword. In response to this question I found a great one<br />

line answer in the archives by Jeremy who says in [2008SP:641] “<strong>The</strong> capitalist has used<br />

the [need] to perpetuate life as a means to gain wealth.” <strong>The</strong> laborer is satisfying some<br />

need <strong>of</strong> his existence in order to stay alive by selling his labor-power to the capitalist in<br />

return for wages. <strong>The</strong>se wages are exchanged for the necessary commodities to keep the<br />

laborer alive, at a given standard <strong>of</strong> living, after which he again returns to the capitalist to<br />

repeat the whole process. <strong>The</strong> beneficial effect for the capitalist is the continued availability<br />

<strong>of</strong> the laborer’s labor-power to create surplus-value i.e. a means to increase wealth. For the<br />

laborer his wealth is no greater at the end <strong>of</strong> one cycle therefore his individual consumption is<br />

deemed unproductive while the capitalist’s is productive. This analysis only becomes starker<br />

when taking a long-term view <strong>of</strong> the process because the inequality between the relatively<br />

stationary wealth <strong>of</strong> the laborer and the expanding wealth <strong>of</strong> the capitalist is potentially<br />

infinite.<br />

Governments today utilize the need to perpetuate life as a means to multiple ends. For<br />

example, in Brazil food subsidies are tied to pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> immunization, school attendance, clinic<br />

check ups, etc. Without fulfilling some other activity deemed a ‘vital state interest’ a parent<br />

cannot maintain themselves and so like the laborer they continue this process each week<br />

without gaining any<strong>thing</strong> in wealth. A crucial difference in this case is that the child does


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 419<br />

benefit in lieu <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> form <strong>of</strong> benefit is an increase in knowledge/education,<br />

health, quality <strong>of</strong> life, etc. and the state hopes healthier children with more resources put<br />

into brain development and education will yield higher national GDP.<br />

Next Message by Spiral is [1001].<br />

Term Paper 811 is 926 in 2000fa, 926 in 2001fa, 826 in 2002fa, 826 in 2003fa, 826 in<br />

2004fa, 826 in 2005fa, 724 in 2007SP, 700 in 2007fa, 708 in 2008SP, 744 in 2009fa, 838<br />

in 2011fa, and 868 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 811 Essay about Chapter Twenty-Six: Secret <strong>of</strong> Original Accumulation<br />

[1062] Ferox, Intaglio, and Wolf: graded A Marx begins this chapter explaining that<br />

his work thus far (chapters 1-25) explained various developments <strong>of</strong> capital, namely: how<br />

money is transformed into capital (through the buying <strong>of</strong> labor-power); how surplus-value<br />

is made through capital (through the discrepancies between the value <strong>of</strong> created products<br />

and the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power); and how more capital is made from surplus-value (through<br />

investing in greater means <strong>of</strong> production and hiring additional laborers.)<br />

This is, however, a cyclic relationship, a reflux called the self-valorization <strong>of</strong> capital. Capital’s<br />

self-valorization could not have originated out <strong>of</strong> nowhere. Marx seeks to understand<br />

where this never-beginning, never-ending complex originated. Building on Adam Smith’s<br />

“previous accumulation”, he states that it must have been from a “primitive accumulation.”<br />

This rephrasing is a pun on Adam Smith, as Marx is using a material historical analysis <strong>of</strong><br />

accumulation. In one sentence, Marx explains his logic for Part 8 <strong>of</strong> Capital. “<strong>The</strong> whole<br />

movement [the above three processes], therefore, seems to turn around in a never-ending circle,<br />

which we can only get out <strong>of</strong> by assuming a primitive accumulation. . . which precedes<br />

capitalist accumulation; an accumulation which is not the result <strong>of</strong> the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong><br />

production but its point <strong>of</strong> departure”.<br />

In a simple analogy, Marx compares how his contemporary political economists viewed<br />

the development <strong>of</strong> capitalism to a biblical story. In the beginning, a sinless world was<br />

turned sinful by the single act <strong>of</strong> Adam eating the apple leading to original sin. Bourgeois<br />

political economists didn’t consider the evolution <strong>of</strong> non-capitalism (precisely feudalism) to<br />

capitalism through primitive accumulation. Rather, they believed that there were naturally<br />

the hard workers and those who were lazy intoxicated with vice:<br />

“. . . long ago, [where] there were two sorts <strong>of</strong> people; one, the diligent,<br />

intelligent and abolve all frugal elite; the other, lazy rascals, spending their<br />

substance, and more ,in riotous living”, but rather through “. . . conquest,<br />

enslavement, robbery, murder, in short, force, place the greatest part”.<br />

This analogy was considered to be the accurate anecdote <strong>of</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

After this explanation, he contrarily describes primitive accumulation as, “. . . the poverty<br />

<strong>of</strong> the great majority who, despite all their labour, have up to now no<strong>thing</strong> to sell but themselves,<br />

and the wealth <strong>of</strong> the few that increases constantly, although they have long ceased<br />

to work.” From the disparity <strong>of</strong> wealth generated by capital come the defenders <strong>of</strong> private<br />

property and those who claim it came naturally through their hard work. This tends to be<br />

420 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the idyllic political economists as explained in the above analogy. Contrary to the typical<br />

bourgeois sugar-coating <strong>of</strong> history, Marx says it’s not accurate.<br />

Next Marx discusses how primitive accumulation takes place. <strong>The</strong> above description<br />

leaves the reader confused. How could murder, enslavement, etc. contribute to the creation<br />

<strong>of</strong> self-valorizing capital? Marx says that two conditions must be met, through two broad<br />

sets <strong>of</strong> commodity owners:<br />

(1) “. . . the owners <strong>of</strong> money, means <strong>of</strong> production, means <strong>of</strong> subsistence, who are eager<br />

to valorize the sum <strong>of</strong> values they have appropriated by buying the labour-power <strong>of</strong> others;<br />

and,<br />

(2) “. . . free workers, the sellers <strong>of</strong> their own labour-power. . . ” who are free from:<br />

a) being the means <strong>of</strong> production. This would be anyone who is treated as a machine,<br />

slave, serf, etc.; and<br />

b) owning any means <strong>of</strong> production on their own.<br />

This is essential for capitalism to take hold as workers would not willingly create their<br />

own class as “proletarians” and deprive themselves <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production, subsistence,<br />

etc. This process must be a forced separation <strong>of</strong> laborers from the means <strong>of</strong> survival (means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production, subsistence, etc.) altogether, enforced through the rights <strong>of</strong> private property.<br />

Marx says that there are two aspects to this:<br />

1) where social means <strong>of</strong> subsistence and production are turned into capital (for example,<br />

privatized); and<br />

2) where immediate producers are turned into wage-laborers (through expropriating their<br />

land and means <strong>of</strong> production).<br />

“<strong>The</strong> immediate producer, the worker, could dispose <strong>of</strong> his own person only<br />

after he ceased to be bound to the soil, and ceased to be the slave or serf <strong>of</strong><br />

another person”.<br />

Marx then draws the correlation that early capitalism evolved from late feudalism. It had<br />

to overcome two large obstacles: those being<br />

(a) freeing the worker from serfdom and the soil; and<br />

(b) freeing the worker from the “regime” <strong>of</strong> the guilds, apprenticeships, etc.<br />

<strong>The</strong> two processes above are the pleasant sounding historical processes espoused by political<br />

economists. However their perspective is from their bourgeois stance. Here Marx<br />

poetically and bluntly declares in contrast that “. . . the history <strong>of</strong> their expropriation, is written<br />

in the annals <strong>of</strong> mankind in letters <strong>of</strong> blood and fire”.<br />

Marx next explains that the rise <strong>of</strong> the industrial capitalist took place as, “. . . the fruit<br />

<strong>of</strong> a victorious struggle both against feudal power. . . and against the guilds” as well as the<br />

“. . . enslavement <strong>of</strong> the worker”. Thus the new free men are deceived as this form change<br />

(feudalism to capitalism) was merely a transformation <strong>of</strong> servitude — from a feudal master


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 421<br />

to a capitalist master. This process began around the sixteenth century, which Marx develops<br />

in the subsequent chapter, namely chapter 27.<br />

Marx does not believe that this dramatic economic shift in form happens overnight, but a<br />

slow, violent social process. <strong>The</strong>se changes occur at “. . . those moments when great masses<br />

<strong>of</strong> men are suddenly and forcibly torn from their means <strong>of</strong> subsistence, and hurled onto<br />

the labour-market as free, unprotected and rightless proletarians”. This process also does<br />

not happen simultaneously everywhere, and for this reason Marx decides in Chapter 26 to<br />

analyze England’s transition from feudalism to capitalism. This process, he believes, is<br />

indicative <strong>of</strong> primitive accumulation in its “classic form”.<br />

As a side note, in Chapter 28 Marx raises an important point regarding the power <strong>of</strong> the<br />

state in the process <strong>of</strong> primitive accumulation. Marx says “<strong>The</strong> rising bourgeoisie needs the<br />

power <strong>of</strong> the state, and uses it to regulate wages, i.e. to force them into the limits suitable for<br />

making a pr<strong>of</strong>it, to lengthen the working day, and to keep the worker himself at his normal<br />

level <strong>of</strong> dependence. This is an essential aspect <strong>of</strong> so-called primitive accumulation.” (p.<br />

899) Marx makes it clear that the State is an integral part <strong>of</strong> the creation <strong>of</strong> the working class<br />

- that the rising bourgeoisie requires the power <strong>of</strong> the state in order to force a working class<br />

into suitable limits for generating pr<strong>of</strong>it, to lengthen the working day, and to keep the worker<br />

dependent. This is an essential aspect <strong>of</strong> so-called “primitive accumulation.”<br />

Next Message by Ferox is [1143], Next Message by Intaglio is [1073], and Next Message by Wolf is [1163].<br />

[1092] Bigwhite, Kat, and Spiral: <strong>The</strong> vicious circle <strong>of</strong> accumulation. Up to this point,<br />

Marx has described in detail how capital and surplus value each have the potential to create<br />

and be created by the other. This self-perpetuating “vicious circle” Marx refers to presents a<br />

problem <strong>of</strong> which came <strong>first</strong>. <strong>The</strong> cycle essentially suggests that capitalists can accumulate<br />

because they have accumulated already. This is a conundrum because it leaves no explicit<br />

starting point <strong>of</strong> capitalistic accumulation. <strong>The</strong> explanation is found in the concept <strong>of</strong> a<br />

primitive accumulation.<br />

Back in this proto-capitalist epoch, the majority <strong>of</strong> producers were still tied to the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production. Over time, some saved and accumulated wealth, while others exchanged and<br />

spent their wealth. Just as the consequences <strong>of</strong> Eve’s original sin were compounded over<br />

time to a greater magnitude, the original inequality between these savers and free spenders<br />

was extrapolated over generations increasing the inequality within society. Eventually society<br />

internalized a new “sacred duty” in the form <strong>of</strong> protecting private property rights.<br />

Continued enforcement <strong>of</strong> this new social norm began the separation <strong>of</strong> people into two new<br />

classes.<br />

From this, capitalists and free workers emerge. <strong>The</strong> coercive separation <strong>of</strong> producers from<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production creates free workers while siphoning away their share <strong>of</strong> the value<br />

and surplus value reproduced in the production process. Free workers are neither part <strong>of</strong>, nor<br />

owner <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production, reducing these people to a naked seller <strong>of</strong> labor-power.<br />

<strong>The</strong> end <strong>of</strong> the feudal age brought about a dramatic shift <strong>of</strong> power to the proto-capitalists<br />

who saved rather than spent. Given enough time, the potentially infinite accumulation <strong>of</strong><br />

capital would yield individuals with the necessary social power to purchase or appropriate<br />

previously dominant institutional powers.<br />

422 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Before becoming free workers, producers had been constrained by social norms and institutional<br />

monopolies such as guilds, rules <strong>of</strong> apprenticeship, risk-averse political authorities,<br />

and a general conservative reaction to substantial changes in the production process. General<br />

preference for the status quo in feudal society supported an economic structure that provided<br />

a safety net through the unity <strong>of</strong> the producer and his necessary means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Marx criticizes “bourgeois historians” for describing this transition as the liberation <strong>of</strong><br />

free workers to sell his labor-power wherever it’s in demand, rather than a transition from<br />

one form <strong>of</strong> exploitation to another. Instead, this labor mobility was hailed as a win-win<br />

for the worker and society because the worker is deemed stronger because they are able to<br />

decide whom to sell his labor-power to. This would then correspond to a more resilient<br />

economic structure, able to adjust free workers to capitalist demands. This interpretation<br />

omits the sacrifice <strong>of</strong> the worker becoming entirely dependent on the owners <strong>of</strong> production<br />

to employ them and at the same time, exploit their labor. This version tends to go wholly<br />

unreported by historians. This seems an apt example <strong>of</strong> the aphorism: history is written by<br />

the winners i.e. capitalists.<br />

Patronus refers to the superior entity in a social relationship varying by time and place,<br />

ranging from a master-slave relation to a less exploitative advocate-client relation. Marx<br />

argues the emerging industrial capitalists leveraged their growing wealth to buy greater freedom<br />

from the dominant social powers in feudal society; namely, the aristocracy and guilds.<br />

<strong>The</strong> power-relation between capitalists and their particular patronus equalized over time until<br />

eventually industrial capitalists made a complete reversal <strong>of</strong> the relationship, surpassing<br />

their patroni in power. <strong>The</strong>se struggles were fought through blood, fire and attrition. Timepreference<br />

<strong>of</strong> some patroni worked against them as they saved and accumulated at a lesser<br />

rate than the capitalists leaking money. Money multiplies over time, though, via the application<br />

<strong>of</strong> interest, which acts as a catalyst in this transformational process. <strong>The</strong> greed <strong>of</strong> some<br />

men for short-term gain was exploited for long-term loss <strong>of</strong> power, and those strong enough<br />

to resist such sin were forcefully removed. In this way, feudal society was redistributed into<br />

a new economic structure, which reinforced capitalist-worker class divisions.<br />

<strong>The</strong> process was slow and not necessarily successful at each attempt as it spread in small<br />

towns. “Sporadic traces” <strong>of</strong> capitalist production were found at the fringes <strong>of</strong> fourteenth<br />

and fifteenth century communities arising independently <strong>of</strong> other populations where it was<br />

implemented. <strong>The</strong> emergence <strong>of</strong> multiple independent incidents <strong>of</strong> capitalist modes <strong>of</strong> production<br />

implies Marx is making an historical and logical argument apart from any particular<br />

human culture.<br />

Marx constructs a social Darwinism framework, which sees the wage-laborer at the mercy<br />

<strong>of</strong> market conditions. It would seem the free workers’ survival is reliant on his/her ability<br />

to adapt skills and labor-power to the changing environment <strong>of</strong> supply and demand. Gone<br />

are his feudal rights and social insurance, leaving no<strong>thing</strong> more than a fraternal, mutually<br />

destructive competition for the sale <strong>of</strong> labor-power.<br />

In conclusion, the chapter describes accumulation as a result <strong>of</strong> many years <strong>of</strong> oppression,<br />

working in a constant cycle. Once a laborer is freed from exploitation, he goes into<br />

the free market but will eventually be forced to become dependent and further exploited.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 423<br />

<strong>The</strong> capitalist would not be able to accumulate vast wealth if they were not able to exploit<br />

their workers. Laborers, on the other hand, are left nearly no choice but to comply and be<br />

exploited in order to survive. No matter the culture or geographical setting, this takes place<br />

and will always take place due to the natural human condition <strong>of</strong> being self-interested and<br />

greedy. <strong>The</strong> only way to stop the cycle would for the laborer to stop selling his labor and<br />

take every<strong>thing</strong> into his own hands: labor, production, marketing, sales, and transportation.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> story according to which “some saved and accumulated wealth, while others exchanged and spent their<br />

wealth” is not taken seriously by Marx. His own explanation is quite different. When reading your essay I was<br />

wondering: which text were you summarizing? <strong>The</strong>re is a lot <strong>of</strong> detail which is not in chapter 26 at all.<br />

Message [1092] referenced by [1166]. First Message by Bigwhite is [16], First Message by Kat is [34], First<br />

Message by Kiko is [544], and Next Message by Spiral is [1141].<br />

Term Paper 813 is 933 in 2000fa, 933 in 2001fa, 833 in 2002fa, 833 in 2003fa, 833 in<br />

2004fa, 833 in 2005fa, 730 in 2007SP, 702 in 2007fa, 710 in 2008SP, 714 in 2008fa, 746<br />

in 2009fa, 840 in 2011fa, and 870 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 813 Essay about Chapter Thirty-Three: Modern <strong>The</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> Colonization<br />

[951] AlexDaily, LuBr, and Oreo: graded A Modern <strong>The</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> Colonization. Chapter<br />

33, “Modern <strong>The</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> Colonization,” begins with an overview <strong>of</strong> the two different types<br />

<strong>of</strong> private property. <strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> kind is achieved by the producer’s own labor, associated with<br />

original accumulation. This type <strong>of</strong> private property in Marx’s time was only relevant in<br />

the colonies, given the extent <strong>of</strong> the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production in Western Europe. <strong>The</strong><br />

other type <strong>of</strong> private property is acquired through the employment <strong>of</strong> wage laborers. As will<br />

become apparent in the proceeding summary <strong>of</strong> this chapter, the two types <strong>of</strong> private property<br />

are mutually exclusive. <strong>The</strong> ability <strong>of</strong> the proletariat to gain access to frontier land would<br />

represent a labor shortage for the capitalist and the inability <strong>of</strong> the capitalist to complement<br />

his/her means <strong>of</strong> production with wage laborers to accumulate capital.<br />

Chapter 33 is the final chapter <strong>of</strong> volume I, and it is critical view about the ideas <strong>of</strong><br />

the British Political Economist E.G. Wakefield and his book about colonization. Wakefield<br />

writes about how to systematically organize the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production in the colonies,<br />

and ponders the conditions necessary for this to happen. Marx stands on the opposite moral<br />

and theoretical end <strong>of</strong> Wakefield’s prescriptions, however he does agree with Wakefield’s<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> what would be needed to plant the seeds <strong>of</strong> capitalism in the colonies. <strong>The</strong> two<br />

men agree on the social conditions necessary for capital accumulation, which creates an<br />

ironic takeaway from the chapter.<br />

In Marx’s view, Wakefield is correct to point out that capitalism is not adopted within the<br />

colonies as a means <strong>of</strong> production because immigrants are free to colonize the frontier and<br />

gain access to the means <strong>of</strong> production for little or no cost. This is a grave problem for the<br />

capitalists because it meant labor shortages on the wage labor market.<br />

To remedy this labor shortage, Wakefield recommends that there must exist a colonial<br />

<strong>of</strong>fice or governmental system that can enact a policy having the following two results: <strong>first</strong>,<br />

it must erect a barrier to the free occupancy <strong>of</strong> land, this can be done through a reserve price<br />

for land that is unaffordable to most if not all wage laborers, and second, restrict immigrants<br />

movements upon arrival so that capitalists will always have a surplus <strong>of</strong> laborers within the<br />

424 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

cities. As Wakefield put it, the “systematic colonization” is done via the “manufacture <strong>of</strong><br />

wage workers in the colonies.”<br />

Marx includes a humorous anecdotal story about Mr. Peel the capitalist, who as Wakefield<br />

“moans,” “took with him from England to Swan River, West Australia, means <strong>of</strong> subsistence<br />

and <strong>of</strong> production to the amount <strong>of</strong> £50,000.” Mr. Peel also “had the foresight to bring with<br />

him, besides, 3,000 persons <strong>of</strong> the working-class, men, women, and children.” However,<br />

once he arrived Mr. Peel was left with no<strong>thing</strong> but his means <strong>of</strong> production as all <strong>of</strong> his<br />

servants disappeared! As Wakefield remarks, Mr. Peel “provided for every<strong>thing</strong> except the<br />

export <strong>of</strong> English modes <strong>of</strong> production to Swan River!” Marx pokes fun at Wakefield and<br />

his inclusion <strong>of</strong> this story, but agrees with Wakefield on the following point. Wakefield<br />

understands that what makes someone a capitalist is not his/her ownership over the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production alone. <strong>The</strong> conditions necessary to create wage laborers must also be present<br />

to complement the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Wakefield understands that capital is no<strong>thing</strong> but a social relation among people, which is<br />

mediated by <strong>thing</strong>s. It is through Wakefield’s analysis <strong>of</strong> the colonies and his understanding<br />

about social relations governing capital accumulation that “the truth about capitalist relations<br />

in the mother country” becomes apparent. As Wakefield explains about the colonies, “the<br />

supply <strong>of</strong> labor is always, not only small, but uncertain” therefore the capitalist has nobody<br />

to exploit and complement his/her means <strong>of</strong> production. It is this <strong>first</strong> type <strong>of</strong> distribution <strong>of</strong><br />

private property that Marx writes in this chapter’s <strong>first</strong> sentence, which prevents the capitalist<br />

mode <strong>of</strong> production from gaining a foundation. As Wakefield says <strong>of</strong> the colonies, “the<br />

capitalist regime constantly comes up against the obstacles presented by the producer, who<br />

as owner <strong>of</strong> his own conditions <strong>of</strong> labor, employs that labourer to enrich himself instead <strong>of</strong><br />

the capitalist.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> irony <strong>of</strong> it all is that even though Wakefield has admitted to the truth about the brutality<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital accumulation by dispossession and its exploitative and criminal nature, he still<br />

argues that capitalist interests should be exported and advanced within the colonies. Marx is<br />

using Wakefield to exemplify a typical capitalist, who actively recognizes that the advancement<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalism depends upon the expropriation <strong>of</strong> labor though the annihilation <strong>of</strong> one<br />

type <strong>of</strong> private property for another. Capitalism requires the process <strong>of</strong> expropriation <strong>of</strong> labor,<br />

a process which keeps the majority <strong>of</strong> the population as proletariats or wage laborers.<br />

If there is any<strong>thing</strong> we should take from this chapter it is that capitalism is not eternal or<br />

fixed in its nature, it is an exploitative process that requires premeditation on the part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist class to recreate through exploitative means its survival and advancement.<br />

First Message by AlexDaily is [335], Next Message by LuBr is [1000], and Next Message by Oreo is [1045].<br />

[1006] Hal and PLG: Systematic Colonization. Throughout his book Capital, Karl<br />

Marx claims that the producer is exploited by the capitalist. By seizing ownership <strong>of</strong> the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production, the capitalist forces the producer to provide unpaid labor along with<br />

paid labor. Marx also claims that the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the producer by means <strong>of</strong> seizing the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production is a fundamental necessity to the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production. In<br />

the last chapter <strong>of</strong> Capital, which is titled “<strong>The</strong> Modern <strong>The</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> Colonisation,” Marx<br />

explains that the growth <strong>of</strong> the working class in America was not spontaneous or organic,<br />

but a calculated move by the most rich and powerful capitalists. As Marx writes, “In the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 425<br />

interest <strong>of</strong> the so-called national wealth, he seeks for artificial means to ensure the poverty<br />

<strong>of</strong> the people.” This calculated move, which Marx calls “systematic colonisation,” provides<br />

empirical evidence <strong>of</strong> the claims mentioned above.<br />

In Europe, colonization was purported to be spontaneous and unregulated. As Marx put<br />

it, it was claimed that “...the mass <strong>of</strong> mankind expropriated itself in honour <strong>of</strong> the ‘accumulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital.’” However in America, the masses were not so eager to expropriate<br />

themselves. America was still in its infancy and land was cheap. As the New World was just<br />

that (new), much <strong>of</strong> the land was not yet claimed by individual citizens, so it was owned by<br />

the government. <strong>The</strong> price <strong>of</strong> land was determined by the natural market forces <strong>of</strong> supply<br />

and demand, and it happened to be low at that time in America’s history. <strong>The</strong>refore, producers<br />

did not have to sell their labor power for long before they had enough money to own<br />

their own land and the means <strong>of</strong> providing for themselves and their families.<br />

As E.G. Wakefield pointed out, the workers in the New World were less dependent upon<br />

capitalists because the factors <strong>of</strong> production were readily available. Although a worker could<br />

choose to work for a capital owner, he/she was not locked into wage labor. This caused a<br />

decrease in the number <strong>of</strong> available workers at the capitalist’s disposal, and the few workers<br />

that were available did not stay with the capitalist long. <strong>The</strong>se factors allowed the worker to<br />

negotiate for better wages, thereby decreasing the capitalist’s pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Due to the naturally low market prices for land in America, the transition between being a<br />

wage laborer or a capitalist was fluid. One could transition between the two based on which<br />

<strong>of</strong>fered the most favorable risk/return ratio. In some cases, the capitalist’s worst nightmare<br />

was realized: workers that he paid to import to America soon became his competitors. Wakefield<br />

viewed this set <strong>of</strong> circumstances as dangerous. He knew that it is not until the factors <strong>of</strong><br />

production are owned and commoditized that capitalism can take form. Wakefield saw the<br />

fragmentation <strong>of</strong> capital ownership as a detriment to society. It reduces the supply <strong>of</strong> wage<br />

labor, and makes the production process completely inefficient. It removes the division <strong>of</strong><br />

labor, and decentralizes the production process.<br />

Again, according to Wakefield, the main culprit for America’s inefficiency was the low<br />

price <strong>of</strong> land. His solution was what Marx called “systematic colonization.” With systematic<br />

colonization, the government would raise the price <strong>of</strong> public property, forcing laborers<br />

to work for extended periods <strong>of</strong> time before ownership was possible. Ideally, the producer<br />

would be forced to work long enough for the capitalist to (a) make a pr<strong>of</strong>it beyond subsistence,<br />

and (b) import more laborers to replace them, thus assuring a steady supply <strong>of</strong><br />

wage labor. Wakefield believed that artificial price setting could be instituted at the onset <strong>of</strong><br />

colonization.<br />

In chapter 33, Marx also points out the hypocrisy <strong>of</strong> artificial price setting, considering<br />

the laws <strong>of</strong> supply and demand are seen as sacred to capitalists. One would think that a true<br />

capitalist would not even give consideration to artificial price setting. Seemingly unaware<br />

<strong>of</strong> this hypocrisy, Wakefield noted that when the price for public property is set, it must be<br />

“sufficient”. It cannot be so low as to allow workers to readily purchase private property,<br />

yet it must not be so high as to discourage people from entering the labor force to attempt to<br />

purchase the property by saving money.<br />

426 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Marx’s final claim is that the very need for systematic colonization is evidence that, in<br />

order for the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production to exist, laborers must <strong>first</strong> be made dependent<br />

on the capitalist for survival. Marx however notes that Wakefield’s prescription <strong>of</strong> systematic<br />

colonization was unnecessary in the American colonies due to the civil war. <strong>The</strong> war<br />

brought on a great amount <strong>of</strong> centralized capital in the form <strong>of</strong> railroads, mines, etc. (Marx,<br />

940). Marx believed that the northern “aristocracy” would bring about an elaborate capitalist<br />

institution. <strong>The</strong> north was sophisticated and capable <strong>of</strong> centralizing the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Chapter 33 is the last chapter in Marx’s Capital. Up to this point in the book, Marx has<br />

dissected nearly every facet <strong>of</strong> the social connection between the laborer and capital. In<br />

most situations, the laborer fares unfavorably. In order to put a final stake in the viability <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism and its benefit to society, Marx concludes the book with a final revelation about<br />

capitalism: “...the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production and accumulation, and therefore capitalist<br />

private property, have for their fundamental condition the annihilation <strong>of</strong> self-earned private<br />

property; in other words, the expropriation <strong>of</strong> the labourer.” This final revelation wraps up<br />

Marx’s Capital neatly. As Marx was also a sociologist, it seems fitting that his final remark<br />

was used to reiterate the subjugation and dehumanization <strong>of</strong> the worker in a capitalist society.<br />

A laborer in a capitalistic society is mere public property, and a factor <strong>of</strong> production no more<br />

sentient than a machine.<br />

Hans: Reading your term paper one thinks Wakefield’s policy was designed for the USA, and that Marx agrees<br />

with Wakefield’s theories. This is not quite right. Please submit a revised version.<br />

Next Message by Hal is [1016] and Next Message by PLG is [1058].<br />

[1058] Hal and PLG: graded A– Systematic Colonization. Throughout his book Capital,<br />

Karl Marx claims that the producer is exploited by the capitalist. By seizing ownership <strong>of</strong> the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production, the capitalist forces the producer to provide unpaid labor along with<br />

paid labor. Marx also claims that the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the producer is a fundamental necessity<br />

to the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production. In the last chapter <strong>of</strong> Capital, which is titled “<strong>The</strong><br />

Modern <strong>The</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> Colonization,” Marx takes a critical look at colonization. Marx discusses<br />

ways in which colonization threatens capitalism. A distinction is drawn between systematic<br />

colonization and unregulated colonization.<br />

In chapter 33 Marx seems fascinated by the development <strong>of</strong> economic institutions in<br />

the New World. He seems to support the idea <strong>of</strong> unregulated colonization as a vehicle to<br />

momentarily break free from capitalism. <strong>The</strong>refore, he utilizes E.G. Wakefield’s voice and<br />

opinions to speak against unregulated colonization, and the threat it poses to capitalism. E.g.<br />

Wakefield speaks out against unregulated colonization in chapter 33 in the following way.<br />

<strong>The</strong> colonization <strong>of</strong> America created an equalization <strong>of</strong> capital as described by E.G.<br />

Wakefield. He uses phrases such as “the Horror <strong>of</strong> horrors” to describe this phenomena.<br />

In the New World the workers were less dependent upon capitalists because the factors <strong>of</strong><br />

production were readily available. Anyone could claim land. Although a worker could<br />

choose to work for a capital owner, he/she was not locked into wage labor. This caused a<br />

decrease in the number <strong>of</strong> available workers at the capitalist’s disposal, giving the common<br />

laborer a great deal <strong>of</strong> power. <strong>The</strong>se factors allowed the worker to negotiate for better wages,<br />

thereby decreasing the capitalist’s pr<strong>of</strong>its. All men were on a level playing field in the New<br />

World.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 427<br />

Due to the naturally low market prices for land in America, the transition between being a<br />

wage laborer or a capitalist was fluid. One could transition between the two based on which<br />

<strong>of</strong>fered the most favorable risk/return ratio. In some cases, the capitalist’s worst nightmare<br />

was realized: workers that he imported to America soon became his competitors. Wakefield<br />

viewed this set <strong>of</strong> circumstances as dangerous. He knew that it was not until the factors <strong>of</strong><br />

production are owned and commoditized that capitalism could take form. Wakefield saw the<br />

fragmentation <strong>of</strong> capital ownership as a detriment to society. It reduced the supply <strong>of</strong> wage<br />

labor, and made the production process completely inefficient. It removed the division <strong>of</strong><br />

labor, and decentralized the production process.<br />

Wakefield’s solution to these issues was referred to as “systematic colonization.” With<br />

systematic colonization, the government would “artificially” raise the price <strong>of</strong> public property,<br />

forcing laborers to work for extended periods <strong>of</strong> time before ownership was possible.<br />

Ideally, the producer would be forced to work long enough for the capitalist to (a) make<br />

a pr<strong>of</strong>it beyond subsistence, and (b) import more laborers to replace them, thus assuring a<br />

steady supply <strong>of</strong> wage labor. Wakefield believed that artificial price setting could effectively<br />

be instituted at the onset <strong>of</strong> colonization.<br />

In chapter 33, Marx counters Wakefield’s ideas by pointing out the hypocrisy <strong>of</strong> artificial<br />

price setting. Considering the laws <strong>of</strong> supply and demand are seen as sacred to capitalists,<br />

artificial price setting was paradoxical. One would think that a true capitalist would not even<br />

give consideration to artificial price setting. Seemingly unaware <strong>of</strong> this hypocrisy, Wakefield<br />

noted that when the price for public property is set, it must be “sufficient”. It cannot be so<br />

low as to allow workers to readily purchase private property, yet it must not be so high as<br />

to discourage people from entering the labor force to attempt to purchase the property by<br />

saving money.<br />

Marx’s final claim is that the very need for systematic colonization is evidence that, in<br />

order for the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production to exist, laborers must <strong>first</strong> be made dependent on<br />

the capitalist for survival. Marx notes that Wakefield’s prescription <strong>of</strong> systematic colonization<br />

was unnecessary in the American colonies due to the Civil War. <strong>The</strong> war brought on a<br />

great amount <strong>of</strong> centralized capital in the form <strong>of</strong> railroads, mines, etc. (Marx, 940). Marx<br />

believed that the northern “aristocracy” would bring about an elaborate capitalist institution.<br />

<strong>The</strong> north was sophisticated and capable <strong>of</strong> centralizing the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Chapter 33 is the last chapter in Marx’s Capital. Up to this point in the book, Marx has<br />

dissected nearly every facet <strong>of</strong> the social connection between the laborer and capital. In<br />

most situations, the laborer fares unfavorably. In order to put a final stake in the viability <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism and its benefit to society, Marx concludes the book with a final revelation about<br />

capitalism: “...the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production and accumulation, and therefore capitalist<br />

private property, have for their fundamental condition the annihilation <strong>of</strong> self-earned private<br />

property; in other words, the expropriation <strong>of</strong> the labourer.” As Marx was also a sociologist,<br />

it seems fitting that his final remark was used to reiterate the subjugation and dehumanization<br />

<strong>of</strong> the worker in a capitalist society. A laborer in a capitalistic society is mere public property,<br />

and a factor <strong>of</strong> production no more sentient than a machine.<br />

Hans: Marx has said this all along that the original accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital means separating the working class<br />

from the means <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> the colonies is evidence that he was right.<br />

428 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Message [1058] referenced by [2011fa:931]. Next Message by Hal is [1086] and Next Message by PLG is [1132].<br />

Term Paper 814 is 871 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 814 Essay about Marx’s Use <strong>of</strong> the Word “Abstinence” in Chapters Twenty-<br />

Four and Thirty-Three<br />

[1087] Goldtone, Max, and RexManning: graded A <strong>The</strong> Folly <strong>of</strong> Abstinence. In order<br />

to understand how Marx uses the term “abstinence,” one <strong>first</strong> needs to have an understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital accumulation. In brief, capital accumulation is necessary for the reproduction <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism. Capital is derived from the surplus-value <strong>of</strong> labor. This capital is reinvested into<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production so that the capitalist maintains levels <strong>of</strong> production which further<br />

adds to his wealth. However, more wealth is amassed from the laborer than mere surplusvalue.<br />

Part <strong>of</strong> the laborers’ wages are returned to the capitalist (or the capitalist class) in<br />

purchasing necessary commodities to survive. Another key aspect <strong>of</strong> capital accumulation<br />

is the continuation <strong>of</strong> class differences. With this the capitalists maintain their level <strong>of</strong> capital<br />

(through exploiting the means <strong>of</strong> production) and the laborers stay in constant need <strong>of</strong><br />

employment (because wages are never high enough to end this reproductive cycle).<br />

In other words, accumulation is the desire <strong>of</strong> the capitalist to control. Capitalists need<br />

power, wealth, and capital in order to fill this desire. This power can be expressed in the<br />

form <strong>of</strong> capital accumulation. When the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital takes place, the capitalist<br />

is robbing his/her laborers <strong>of</strong> a quality life, as surplus-value generates the capital, and is a<br />

byproduct <strong>of</strong> the laborer. <strong>The</strong>refore, the capitalist will want the laborer to work more, and<br />

rob them <strong>of</strong> certain qualities that should exist in life. As Martin Luther put it, quoted in<br />

739:2/o: “<strong>The</strong> love <strong>of</strong> power is an element in the desire to get rich...Whoever eats up, robs,<br />

and steals the nourishment <strong>of</strong> another, that man commits as great a murder (as far as in him<br />

lies) as he who starves a man or utterly undoes him. Such does a userer (capitalist), and sits<br />

the while safe on his stool, when he ought rather to be hanging from the gallows.” Martin<br />

Luther compares the power hungry capitalist to a murderer, where one robs <strong>of</strong> life and the<br />

other <strong>of</strong> the quality <strong>of</strong> life.<br />

With this knowledge we can continue our exploration <strong>of</strong> “abstinence.” Marx <strong>first</strong> uses the<br />

term in 740:1/o when comparing the classical and modern economists. Classical economists<br />

see “individual [capitalist] consumption as ‘abstinence’ from accumulating, [while] the modernised<br />

capitalist is capable <strong>of</strong> looking upon accumulation as ‘abstinence’ from pleasure”.<br />

In addition to understanding the substance <strong>of</strong> this dualism is the blueprint it lays for the absurdity<br />

<strong>of</strong> using the term “abstinence” at all! We begin to see that in fact most <strong>of</strong> chapter 24<br />

is meant to explain the mechanisms <strong>of</strong> capital accumulation. Capitalists invest in the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production to employ laborers and evolve more capital, which, aside from the amount<br />

necessary for survival, will be reinvested to accumulate more capital.<br />

This is where “abstinence” really comes into play. Marx only explains this term because<br />

he wants to illustrate a faulty interpretation <strong>of</strong> capital accumulation made by the “vulgar<br />

economists.” His claim is that the vulgar economists substitute “an economic category” with<br />

a “sycophantic phrase.” This is not hard to believe if you agree with Hans’ annotations that<br />

say “the economists, who previously had taken the side <strong>of</strong> the capitalists in the conflict between<br />

capitalists and idle landowners, turn into apologists for capital” (Annotations 649).


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 429<br />

That being said, Marx introduces Nassau W. Senior, who is quoted saying proudly that “I<br />

substitute, for the word capital, considered as an instrument <strong>of</strong> production, the word abstinence”<br />

[743:1/oo]. Senior is also responsible for the “abstinence theory <strong>of</strong> interest” which<br />

basically states that abstaining from spending, by earning interest is what generates wealth.<br />

Senior is trying to glorify the efforts <strong>of</strong> the capitalist—instead <strong>of</strong> capital accumulation being<br />

treated purely as power accumulation, Senior tries to argue that the capitalist is benefiting<br />

the society by “abstaining” from his own pleasure by investing his money into the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production rather than spending it on him or herself.<br />

However, Senior’s explanation fails even to make logical sense on a basic level. Marx <strong>first</strong><br />

refutes his theory by pointing out “every human action may be viewed, as ‘abstinence’ from<br />

its opposite. Eating is abstinence from fasting, walking, abstinence from standing still...”<br />

[743:1/oo], as if giving abstinence the ability to explain any<strong>thing</strong> that one is not presently<br />

doing. Accumulating is abstinence from spending, says Senior—but then how, asks Marx,<br />

does the economy continue to reproduce itself?<br />

After pointing out the absurdity in abstinence theory, Marx continues to refute it. While<br />

Senior and other vulgar economists may think that abstaining from luxuries is a capitalists’<br />

moral struggle necessarily done to promote growth in society, Marx explains there are in<br />

fact societies which accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital does not exist yet still have “reproduction on<br />

a progressively increasing scale.” He gives the example pointed out by Richard Jones (the<br />

successor <strong>of</strong> Malthus) <strong>of</strong> the Hindu population which, though magnates collect some <strong>of</strong><br />

the surplus labor or the workers, most constitute wages for the laborers who also own their<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production. Marx ends the section with a comical remark comparing the “capitalist<br />

abstainer” to Don Quixote—struggling in vain to slay a dragon—when in fact everyone<br />

knows there is no such <strong>thing</strong> as a dragon; just a windmill—an imagined theory.<br />

Another historical example <strong>of</strong> an alternative social form <strong>of</strong> expanded reproduction outside<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalism is mentioned and explained by Marx in chapter 33. In this chapter Marx<br />

mentions the word “abstinence” when discussing and comparing the old world English and<br />

the new world American conflicting ways <strong>of</strong> life—back when America had only 13 colonies.<br />

<strong>The</strong> free American colonies were running on an economic system with almost no use <strong>of</strong><br />

capital, and based <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> individual producers working for themselves instead <strong>of</strong> for capital.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y were running a C-M-C society, and it was growing much faster than the old world’s<br />

“abstinence” and M-C-M driven economy, which was built and sustained on “abstinence”,<br />

exploitation, accumulation <strong>of</strong> wealth, and the dependence <strong>of</strong> workers on the capitalist for<br />

work.<br />

Marx asks the reader “where, among such curious characters, is the ‘field <strong>of</strong> abstinence’<br />

for the capitalists?” [934:1/o], when referring to the new world colonies. <strong>The</strong> answer is that<br />

there was no or very little “field <strong>of</strong> abstinence” at work, and the growth/employment was<br />

indeed doing superb without it. <strong>The</strong> result <strong>of</strong> this lack <strong>of</strong> abstinence also made for a society<br />

free <strong>of</strong> capitalist driven exploitation, because capitalist exploitation and “abstinence” go<br />

hand in hand.<br />

While Marx does talk about the capitalist abstaining from consuming in order to accumulate,<br />

the capitalists’ real power come from his ability to extract labor out <strong>of</strong> his laborers.<br />

430 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> way in which a capitalist is able to extract or “squeeze” labor out <strong>of</strong> others is directly<br />

proportional to the amount <strong>of</strong> capital the capitalist is able to accumulate. If successful, the<br />

capitalist will be able to consume more as his accumulation grows. It seems that the laborer<br />

is the one who is actually abstaining, abstaining from the joys <strong>of</strong> life, and that the capitalist<br />

is just using a play on words in order to appear less evil.<br />

In summary, the idea behind the “abstinence theory” is that capitalists abstain from the<br />

joys that consuming brings them in order to save/reinvest in the production process and<br />

become more competitive. This “abstinence” from consumption and enjoyment is cause for<br />

glorifying the capitalist—as if they are doing a great service to society—but by no means<br />

should this process glorify the capitalist, as they are only in the business <strong>of</strong> accumulating<br />

power and manipulating the laborer. Marx makes it clear that, unlike what Senior says,<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its don’t simply appear from the no<strong>thing</strong>ness that “abstinence” is, and many societies,<br />

like the old world America, did fine without it. Thus, “abstinence theory” is a theory that<br />

Marx has proven to be false.<br />

First Message by Goldtone is [22], Next Message by Max is [1098], and Next Message by RexManning is [1109].<br />

[1093] GoUtes, Kleenex, Smartergirl, and Zohan: Marx’s use <strong>of</strong> the word “Abstinence”.<br />

Chapter 24 begins with the discussion <strong>of</strong> the capitalist production process on an<br />

expanded scale and the inversion <strong>of</strong> property laws but, in the last two sections <strong>of</strong> the chapter,<br />

he discusses the Abstinence <strong>The</strong>ory and expands on its meaning and context. We present a<br />

summary <strong>of</strong> Ch 24 and an explanation <strong>of</strong> what Marx means by the word “Abstinence”.<br />

At the beginning <strong>of</strong> the chapter Marx discusses the capitalist production process on an<br />

expanded scale. In the <strong>first</strong> section he puts forth conditions that the economy as a whole<br />

must satisfy if extended production is to be possible.<br />

For the individual capitalist accumulation is easy, however specific social conditions are<br />

necessary. Marx points out three. First, is the decision by the capitalist to reinvest the<br />

surplus value. If accumulation is to occur, the entire surplus value can’t be consumed by<br />

the capitalist. Part <strong>of</strong> the surplus has to be applied back into production. Marx begins by<br />

examining the conversion <strong>of</strong> surplus value into capital from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> an individual<br />

capitalist. In order for a capitalist to convert his surplus value into capital he has to do the<br />

same <strong>thing</strong> with his surplus value as he did with his original capital and put that capital back<br />

into his production process. To explain this Marx point out here that there is a difference<br />

between capital value and surplus value, capital value returns to its original form which is<br />

money, while on the other hand the original form <strong>of</strong> surplus value is not money, but the<br />

surplus product. <strong>The</strong> difference applies to only the <strong>first</strong> transaction made by the surplus<br />

value, after that both capital value and surplus value are sums <strong>of</strong> money and their conversion<br />

back into capital takes place the same way.<br />

Second, accumulations require the availability <strong>of</strong> products on the market. In order for<br />

transactions to occur the overall social product must be right. Once a capitalist sells his<br />

product he needs to find ingredients for his next production process. Whether these <strong>thing</strong>s<br />

are available or not is not determined by the market, but the annual product <strong>of</strong> other capitalist.<br />

<strong>The</strong> market only acts as a transfer <strong>of</strong> annual product from one hand to another.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 431<br />

Third, there needs to be an availability <strong>of</strong> labor power on the market. Marx says that if the<br />

exploitation <strong>of</strong> laborers that are already employed does not increase, then additional labor<br />

power is required. To quote Hans’s Annotations, “To reconvert surplus value into capital,<br />

capital simply has to put the additional means <strong>of</strong> production on line and hire the workers to<br />

run them” (Annotation Page 624).<br />

Next Marx discusses the inversion by which the property laws <strong>of</strong> commodity production<br />

become laws <strong>of</strong> capitalist appropriation. To begin to explaining this Marx looks at the capitalist<br />

re-investing his surplus value and questions were does the original capital come from.<br />

He gives the example <strong>of</strong> an original capital <strong>of</strong> 10,000 pounds bringing a surplus value <strong>of</strong><br />

2,000 pounds and this new capital bringing in a surplus value <strong>of</strong> 400 pounds and so on and<br />

so on. <strong>The</strong> annotations explain that capitalist can’t convert all the surplus value into capital<br />

because they have to use some to live. Marx also points out the newly former capital and the<br />

original capital continues to reproduce themselves and produce surplus value. <strong>The</strong> original<br />

and the new capital continue to generate alongside each other.<br />

This however, doesn’t explain the question <strong>of</strong> the origin <strong>of</strong> the original capital. Political<br />

economists answer that the original capital was formed by the advance <strong>of</strong> 10,000 pounds<br />

and implying that the owner became possessed <strong>of</strong> it, “by his own labor and that <strong>of</strong> his<br />

forefathers,” [728:2]. Marx disagrees and would answer by stating that “<strong>The</strong>re is not one<br />

single atom <strong>of</strong> its value that does not owe its existence to unpaid labor.” Capitalist buying<br />

labor power and not paying the full equivalent <strong>of</strong> the labor performed. As Marx looks<br />

further into the situation he explains that the actual surplus value that is created by a worker<br />

is converted back into capital, which in turn employs the same worker. Marx goes on to<br />

explain that it is the working-class themselves that creates the surplus labor that will employ<br />

additional labor in the following year. “Labor creates capital before capital employs labor.”<br />

[728:4/o].<br />

Next Marx looks at the inversion <strong>of</strong> the property laws. “<strong>The</strong> more the capitalist has accumulated,<br />

the more he is able to accumulate.” As Marx enters the discussion <strong>of</strong> property laws<br />

and how they are inverted in a capitalist system, Marx expounds upon “creating capital out <strong>of</strong><br />

capital.” He shows that this process follows the laws <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange, but the result<br />

is different. To paint a fuller picture, the surplus-value derived from the additional capital is<br />

“the result <strong>of</strong> the purchase <strong>of</strong> labor-power with part <strong>of</strong> the original capital.” This commodity<br />

exchange process operates under the assumption that the commodity or money owner is in<br />

control <strong>of</strong> his own capacities and has the right <strong>of</strong> free disposal <strong>of</strong> such. It is also assumed<br />

that each transaction conforms to these commodity exchange laws. Marx comes to a seemingly<br />

odd conclusion though: 729:2/o “it is evident that the laws <strong>of</strong> appropriation or laws<br />

<strong>of</strong> private property, laws that are based on the production and circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities,<br />

become by their own inner and inexorable dialectic changed into their very opposite.”<br />

What we’ve previously seen as a common exchange, a purchase and sale <strong>of</strong> labor-power,<br />

is now seen only as “mere form.” What’s left <strong>of</strong> the transaction is just the “mere semblance<br />

<strong>of</strong> the exchange.” Marx sums it up well: “the capitalist <strong>first</strong> appropriates, without equivalent,<br />

a portion <strong>of</strong> the materialized labor <strong>of</strong> others, and then exchanges a part <strong>of</strong> it for a greater<br />

quantity <strong>of</strong> living labor.” This is an explanation <strong>of</strong> the capitalist M-C-M process. <strong>The</strong> word<br />

“appropriates” means to assign or to take for oneself. <strong>The</strong> capitalist takes a portion <strong>of</strong> his<br />

432 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

workers’ labor in materialized form and trades it for essentially more labor. <strong>The</strong> content<br />

exchanged in the transaction seems to disappear from sight: all we now see is the form <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange.<br />

Marx now moves more specifically and directly in the direction <strong>of</strong> the discussion on<br />

property rights. Initially, we think that property rights should be based on a man’s labor.<br />

However, Marx concludes that property rights belong to the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> laborer is not<br />

able to acquire any<strong>thing</strong> on his own, to include property rights. On the capitalist’s side, he is<br />

able to appropriate the unpaid labor <strong>of</strong> others. Here, Marx separates labor from property.<br />

He then goes on to discuss the three phases leading up to capital accumulation. First,<br />

in a standard purchase, one party sells labor-power, the other party buys it. One gains a<br />

use-value, the other leaves it. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the subject commodity includes the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production that were consumed and the equivalent <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the labor-power<br />

plus the surplus-value. This implies that there is value in having more useful, more efficient<br />

labor, and that the lazy man’s labor is not worth as much as that <strong>of</strong> the productive man’s. So<br />

far, we have still not violated any laws <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange. Again, the same example<br />

can be applied: the worker leaves his use-value as he sells his labor-power to the capitalist<br />

in exchange for a wage.<br />

Marx writes that the product, the result <strong>of</strong> the production process never belongs to the<br />

laborer: it belongs to the capitalist. In addition, surplus value created by the worker also<br />

becomes the property <strong>of</strong> the capitalist: here, the cost is fully incurred by the laborer. To add,<br />

the worker keeps his own labor-power: he can sell it to anyone who wants to buy.<br />

In his second point on the advancement <strong>of</strong> capital accumulation, Marx writes that simple<br />

reproduction allows the continual renewal <strong>of</strong> money into capital. <strong>The</strong> Annotations point out<br />

that the capitalist gets to consume for free. <strong>The</strong> third step is accumulation. This is just an<br />

extension, a magnification, <strong>of</strong> the second step <strong>of</strong> simple reproduction. <strong>The</strong> capitalist’s capital<br />

is continuously advanced, again, at no cost to the capitalist.<br />

Now a discussion on the re-allocation <strong>of</strong> surplus-value. It matters not whether worker A’s<br />

surplus value was used to pay worker B. <strong>The</strong> surplus-value belongs to the capitalist anyway.<br />

This situation doesn’t fall under the conventional laws <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange, which only<br />

deals with individuals, and exchanges between individuals: this situation would be larger in<br />

scope. Marx encourages the reader to look beyond the transaction between two individuals<br />

and take in the big picture, as he calls a “snapshot,” seeing the clashing <strong>of</strong> the capitalist class<br />

versus the working class. Setting this comparison and the comparison between different<br />

transactions side-by-side is not advisable, as they fall under different sets <strong>of</strong> rules. Each act<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchange is independent <strong>of</strong> the next one, and it certainly isn’t representative <strong>of</strong> the entire<br />

clash between social classes.<br />

Next, Marx makes a very important formulation: the laws <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange are<br />

social relations. He says that no matter how many times simple reproduction or accumulation<br />

occur, the capital retains its purity. <strong>The</strong> integrity <strong>of</strong> property rights is maintained as long<br />

as the laws <strong>of</strong> commodity production are properly observed throughout the process. <strong>The</strong><br />

advantage that the capitalist has is that he has continually increasing access to the constantly<br />

renewing unpaid labor <strong>of</strong> others.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 433<br />

This is perhaps the capstone <strong>of</strong> section 24.1c: “to the extent that commodity production,<br />

in accordance with its own inherent laws, develops further, into capitalist production, the<br />

property laws <strong>of</strong> commodity production change into the laws <strong>of</strong> capitalist appropriation.”<br />

Marx then transitions into accumulated wealth, or converted surplus-value. Regardless <strong>of</strong> the<br />

media through which capital regenerates, whether it is simple reproduction or accumulation,<br />

all capital converts into this form <strong>of</strong> accumulated wealth, though again, all we see is its form,<br />

or the mere semblance, in a transaction <strong>of</strong> exchange.<br />

Marx then begins to expound on consumption <strong>of</strong> surplus-value and accumulation. “Given<br />

the mass <strong>of</strong> surplus-value, then, the larger the one <strong>of</strong> these parts, the smaller is the other.<br />

Caeteris paribus, the ratio <strong>of</strong> these parts determines the magnitude <strong>of</strong> accumulation.” <strong>The</strong><br />

capitalist is the one who decides how much will be accumulated or consumed; it is not an<br />

economic need but an individual decision. <strong>The</strong> capitalist is presumed the one who will make<br />

the decision on surplus-value. However, as Marx delves into the discussion in greater detail<br />

he makes a point “that it is a decision made collectively by the capitalist class as a whole.”<br />

Marx goes on to talk about the capitalist and how he does not consume; instead a capitalist<br />

enriches himself by accumulating.<br />

Later in this section Marx touches on accumulation as well as competition. Marx argues<br />

that accumulation is necessary for individual capitalists because it is part <strong>of</strong> capitalism’s<br />

historical mission, accumulation is driven by competition. <strong>The</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> competition are<br />

felt by each individual capitalist. It compels the capitalist to constantly extend his own<br />

capital, but in order to really extend his capital and preserve it, the capitalist must do so by<br />

a progressive accumulation. However, in doing this the capitalist sacrifices his own human<br />

needs and has a great internal conflict. By accumulating the capitalist forfeits his own, self<br />

serving desires <strong>of</strong> consumption but at the same time is able to gain power. Marx states “To<br />

accumulate, is to conquer the world <strong>of</strong> social wealth.”<br />

Next Marx presents a quote from Martin Luther about the usurer or better known as the<br />

capitalist. Luther compares the usurer to a criminal but far worse condemns the usurer. He<br />

thinks that usurer’s are the scum <strong>of</strong> the earth. Luther says “Is there on this earth, no greater<br />

enemy <strong>of</strong> man (after the devil) than a gripe-money, and usurer, for he wants to be God over<br />

all men.”<br />

Marx goes back to talking about accumulation to state that accumulation and power are<br />

not human needs <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. He than transitions into the differences between classical<br />

and modern day capitalists and introduces “abstinence”.<br />

Marx points <strong>of</strong> that classical capitalists view individual consumption as a sin against<br />

his function and as abstinence from accumulating, where as the modern capitalist is able<br />

to look at accumulation as abstinence from pleasure. <strong>The</strong>refore classical capitalists view<br />

consumption as abstinence from accumulating, while modern capitalists view accumulation<br />

as abstinence from pleasure. <strong>The</strong>y have completely opposite points <strong>of</strong> view as it pertains to<br />

accumulating. Once again it is a capitalist’s personal decision either to accumulate or not.<br />

Marx discusses why capitalists are motivated to consume. <strong>The</strong>y consume for two primary<br />

reasons: one, for the purpose to make as much pr<strong>of</strong>it as possible and two, to have personal<br />

fulfillment and to be able to enjoy consumption. Marx shows that each individual capitalist<br />

434 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

needs to make a Faustian decision between accumulation and enjoyment. Which will have<br />

greater reward for each capitalist depends on the individual. <strong>The</strong>re is an important decision<br />

that each capitalist needs to make, do they want to follow their passion for accumulation or<br />

their desire for enjoyment.<br />

To conclude the question <strong>of</strong> how Marx uses the term Abstinence there needs to be an<br />

understanding that the economist were in conflict from their classical beliefs. Initially the<br />

classical economists supported capitalists and their pr<strong>of</strong>its but as the laborer continually<br />

gave more <strong>of</strong> their labor power to the capitalists, and the capitalist desire to accumulate<br />

became larger, there was a discrepancy and resistance resulting in what is known as the<br />

vulgar economy.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Vulgar economists distracted from the capitalists ability to make pr<strong>of</strong>its without laboring<br />

for them. Previously the terms labor and pr<strong>of</strong>it were used synonymously as in one<br />

resulted in the other. However the Capitalist defied this synopsis by doing no<strong>thing</strong> but still<br />

benefiting from the pr<strong>of</strong>it portion <strong>of</strong> the equation. To justify the capitalist’s pr<strong>of</strong>its and lavish<br />

accumulation the term abstinence was used. Capitalists now can show that they have done<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> to earn the pr<strong>of</strong>its. <strong>The</strong>y abstained from using a portion <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>its and are<br />

rewarded for using the capital in a productive way. This reward comes in the form <strong>of</strong> more<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Abstinence takes great commitment by the capitalist to refrain from consuming their capital.<br />

It is human nature to want to indulge and consume. <strong>The</strong> capitalist have to refrain.<br />

However Marx sees that reproduction would have to progressively increase. It would also<br />

have to be privately owned by the capitalist in order for the theory <strong>of</strong> abstinence to be valid.<br />

On the other hand Marx suggests that this increasing reproduction would happen successfully<br />

without capitalist intervention if a portion <strong>of</strong> their labor is given back in the form <strong>of</strong><br />

wages and luxuries while the land owner or company owner receives pr<strong>of</strong>its for their ability<br />

to assist the laborer with a place <strong>of</strong> production or their housing needs.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> great commitment to refrain from consumption was meant ironically by Marx.<br />

You should have left out those <strong>thing</strong>s from chapter 24 which have no<strong>thing</strong> to do with abstinence, and instead<br />

included what Marx says about abstinence in chapter 33.<br />

Next Message by GoUtes is [1159], Next Message by Kleenex is [1120], Next Message by Smartergirl is [1126],<br />

and Next Message by Zohan is [1130].<br />

[1182] Hans: Abstinence <strong>The</strong>ory: Why it’s wrong, how it came about, and what its<br />

kernel <strong>of</strong> truth is. <strong>The</strong> “abstinence theory” says that the capitalists create value by abstaining<br />

from consumption. Its modern version is no longer called “abstinence theory” but time<br />

preference theory <strong>of</strong> the interest rate: economic agents prefer to consume now rather than<br />

later, and in order to induce them to consume later, one has to pay them, and that price is the<br />

interest rate.<br />

Marx is a realist, and a theory that value is created by not doing some<strong>thing</strong> rubs him<br />

completely the wrong way. In his mind this is ridiculous. Value is wealth, it cannot come<br />

from no<strong>thing</strong> but must come from some<strong>thing</strong>. <strong>The</strong>refore Marx castigates the abstinence<br />

theory as one <strong>of</strong> the illogical fabrications <strong>of</strong> vulgar economists who are apologists <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist system.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 435<br />

But it is not enough to come up with pro<strong>of</strong>s in your system which show that a different<br />

theory than yours is wrong. That other theory probably has pro<strong>of</strong>s in its system which show<br />

that your theory is wrong. Your theory is only then superior to the other theory if you can<br />

also explain why the other theory comes to the results it does get right. This is the principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> immanent critique which Marx had learned from Hegel, and which he assiduously applied<br />

in his many footnotes about the theories <strong>of</strong> the economists <strong>of</strong> his time. Let’s look therefore<br />

how the abstinence theory arose.<br />

An important parameter <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system is the rate <strong>of</strong> accumulation, i.e., the portion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the surplus-value which was not consumed by the capitalists but reinvested into business.<br />

This parameter has special relevance because, if Marx’s theory is right, there is no<br />

economic law prescribing what the rate <strong>of</strong> accumulation must be. <strong>The</strong> rate <strong>of</strong> accumulation<br />

is a decision <strong>of</strong> the capitalists, not the individual capitalists but the capitalists as a class.<br />

This is a huge advantage for the capitalist system, because it prevents the capitalists from<br />

becoming dependent on the labor supply. School explains this well in [1069].<br />

In order to understand why the rate <strong>of</strong> accumulation is what it is, Marx looks at the<br />

history <strong>of</strong> the consumption habits <strong>of</strong> the capitalists. He discovers an interesting dialectical<br />

inversion. <strong>The</strong> early capitalists were very frugal or even miserly. <strong>The</strong>y used to meet in<br />

the pub on Friday nights, and when one drank more than a pint <strong>of</strong> wine others frowned on<br />

him. Capitalism was still an ascending social force, and the capitalists had to accumulate,<br />

they had to put almost every penny they earned back into the business in order to survive as<br />

capitalists. If they consumed, they were trangressing against their historical mission. Note,<br />

it was up to the capitalists to decide on the rate <strong>of</strong> accumulation, and for the early capitalists,<br />

accumulation was a duty, and consumption the violation <strong>of</strong> this duty.<br />

<strong>The</strong> later capitalists reversed this. This was a rebellion <strong>of</strong> the capitalist the consumer<br />

against the historical mission <strong>of</strong> capitalism. <strong>The</strong> later capitalists boldly declared that they had<br />

the right to eat all <strong>of</strong> the surplus-value, and if they did not eat it all, then this was an especially<br />

charitable act <strong>of</strong> them and they deserve getting paid for this. I.e., the abstinence theory<br />

reflects the development <strong>of</strong> the capitalist class. Marx must have had some sympathy for<br />

this because he was always in favor <strong>of</strong> human emancipation against unnecessary constraints.<br />

Why did the capitalists reverse the earlier duty to accumulate into a right not to accumulate?<br />

On the one hand, the rate <strong>of</strong> exploitation had become much bigger due to bigger capitals and<br />

higher technology, therefore luxury consumption was no longer incompatible with capitalist<br />

self-preservation. On the other, capitalists no longer only used their own capital but they<br />

used credit, and in order to show that they were creditworthy, they had to demonstrate their<br />

wealth by conspicuous consumption. In this way, even in this later phase consumption was<br />

still subordinated to accumulation.<br />

Marx talks about abstinence also in chapter 33. Wakefield complains that in the early<br />

1800s the conditions in the USA were unfavorable for the capitalists because workers were<br />

not dependent on jobs. <strong>The</strong>y could move to the frontier and become independent producers.<br />

For these workers, wealth did not come from abstinence, but wealth came from work. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

became wealthy because they could benefit from the fruits <strong>of</strong> their labor. This shows the truth<br />

<strong>of</strong> the abstinence theory: the wealth <strong>of</strong> the capitalists does not come from the abstinence <strong>of</strong><br />

436 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the capitalists, but from the abstinence <strong>of</strong> the workers who are deprived <strong>of</strong> the fruits <strong>of</strong> their<br />

labor.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [1189].<br />

Term Paper 815 is 842 in 2011fa and 872 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 815 Enumerate as many features <strong>of</strong> capitalism as you can find where the system<br />

hides exploitation to the people living in the system. <strong>The</strong>n try to explain why the system<br />

hides exploitation in so many different ways. <strong>The</strong>re are several possible explanations, for<br />

instance<br />

(a) capitalism happens to have several features which hide exploitation just by accident.<br />

(b) capitalism has systemic features (for instance the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity,<br />

i.e., the fact that individuals do not see nor control the true character <strong>of</strong> their own social<br />

relations) which cause it to systematically hide exploitation.<br />

(c) if capitalism would not hide exploitation so well, it could not exist. After the individuals<br />

have achieved personal freedom to the extent they did in modern times, only a system <strong>of</strong><br />

exploitation can survive which hides exploitation.<br />

(d) both exploiters and those exploited are interested in hiding exploitation to themselves<br />

and others; therefore the agents in a capitalist system do <strong>thing</strong>s deliberately which hide<br />

exploitation.<br />

Are there other explanations?<br />

[1055] AM, Somramthom, and Utefan: graded A Systemic Exploitation. Capitalism,<br />

a system <strong>of</strong> commodities, could not function without the value associated with individual<br />

commodities. Value is produced through production (i.e. the expenditure <strong>of</strong> labor power)<br />

which allows the commodity to be exchanged for another commodity <strong>of</strong> equal value. Labor<br />

power is provided by the laborer while the means <strong>of</strong> production (i.e. materials, machinery,<br />

utilities, factory, etc.) are provided by the capitalist. Marx writes in 449:1/o, “<strong>The</strong> directing<br />

motive, the end aim <strong>of</strong> the capitalist production is to extract the greatest possible about <strong>of</strong><br />

surplus value, and consequently to exploit labor power to the greatest possible extent.”<br />

Marx refers to an important influence on the capitalist system, exploitation. Hans describes<br />

exploitation as follows: “If the social control over these <strong>thing</strong>s (meaning the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production) is such that one part <strong>of</strong> the society if forced to work for another part <strong>of</strong> society,<br />

this is called ‘exploitation.’” (Ehrbar, Annotations Fa2010 pg. 9). A capitalist uses<br />

exploitation to alter the distribution <strong>of</strong> wealth; increasing own wealth by exploiting “those<br />

involved in the production <strong>of</strong> this wealth and systematically channel [the wealth] into the<br />

pocket <strong>of</strong> a small elite . . . ” [2007SP:285]<br />

In the capitalist system exploitation manifests itself in the inability <strong>of</strong> laborers to recognize<br />

their own exploitation and their failure to understand how or why they are being<br />

exploited. Capitalism thrives on a circular reshuffling <strong>of</strong> laborers. <strong>The</strong> next “generation”<br />

<strong>of</strong> laborers allow themselves to be exploited because they know not <strong>of</strong> the exploitation that<br />

preceded them. This perpetuates the exploitative cycle. Marx 784:1/o refers to this as the<br />

“disposable reserve army” that is always ready for exploitation. <strong>The</strong> accidental nature <strong>of</strong><br />

exploitation comes from the new “generation” <strong>of</strong> laborers who are blind to the implications


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 437<br />

<strong>of</strong> their employment. <strong>The</strong> new inexperienced laborers are far more concerned about receiving<br />

some means <strong>of</strong> wage than they are about being treated fairly. <strong>The</strong>y don’t see they are<br />

furthering capitalist accumulation.<br />

Another aspect <strong>of</strong> accidental exploitation can be seen in entertainment, sports, educational<br />

institutions, and religion. <strong>The</strong> acceptance <strong>of</strong> exploitation, in this case, stems from an<br />

inept need to accept what the capitalist says. Sports and universities desire for entertainment<br />

and further education, respectively, raise prices in a monopolistic way. <strong>The</strong> capitalists play<br />

on the socially accepted norms in these areas. Athletes, though overpaid in relation to many<br />

other laborers, are grossly underpaid in relation to the amount <strong>of</strong> wealth they produce for<br />

their owners (i.e. capitalists). Universities receive tuition from their enrolled students, yet<br />

these funds do not directly go to the individual pr<strong>of</strong>essors. In either case exploitation can<br />

be seen in the social need <strong>of</strong> laborers who are willing to work for low wages and consumers<br />

who pay for overpriced commodities. Both laborers and consumers are unaware <strong>of</strong> their<br />

exploitation; that is to say they seek without <strong>first</strong> questioning their motives.<br />

Culture, on the other hand, plays a systemic role in exploitation within the capitalist system.<br />

Hans writes “Many people in the US know how ugly and exploitative capitalism, is<br />

but they still don’t reject it, because on a macro scale, the selfish actions <strong>of</strong> the greedy capitalists<br />

come together in a dynamic macro system which benefits everyone” [2009fa:226].<br />

Meaning, the laborer voluntarily allows himself to be exploited for the overall betterment <strong>of</strong><br />

the capitalist society. Hans goes on to say “<strong>The</strong> inequities <strong>of</strong> capitalism are <strong>of</strong>ten deplored,<br />

but people say that eliminating the inequalities will not make the average person better <strong>of</strong>f”<br />

[2009fa:637]. It would be unrealistic to assume that a laborer would choose to be exploited<br />

so society as a whole can have more wealth. Yet average living conditions are better because<br />

<strong>of</strong> the actions <strong>of</strong> the capitalist and many people have risen from ‘rags to riches’. This ‘American<br />

Dream’ contributes to the laborers’ contentment with exploitation. But the ‘American<br />

Dream’ alone does not justify exploitation.<br />

Capitalist exploitation is also encountered in the production process. Demand for convenience<br />

in commodities calls for quick and cheap production, which pushes capitalists to<br />

reduce expenses such as wages and materials. As a result, exploitation rises since laborers<br />

are required to produce commodities for less. High demand causes a lack <strong>of</strong> discretion towards<br />

the environmental impact caused by raw material extraction. Currently, capitalist are<br />

going ‘green’ through the use <strong>of</strong> more efficient production processes which bring prestige<br />

and support from consumers. However, when customers are asked to pay more for commodities,<br />

consequently they are quick to blame the production process, failing to acknowledge<br />

their own participation in exploitation.<br />

<strong>The</strong> commodity form <strong>of</strong> the product and the money form <strong>of</strong> the commodity also veil<br />

exploitation. Surface relations distort what is actually going between capitalist, laborer, and<br />

commodity. Hans explains that “On the surface <strong>of</strong> the economy one can. . . say that labor<br />

is traded as a commodity which has a price.” (Ehrbar, Annotations Fa2010, pg. 524). <strong>The</strong><br />

value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is manifested when the commodity is produced. Wages paid to the<br />

laborer are only a fraction <strong>of</strong> the value created during production and are not actually based<br />

on labor itself. Rather, the laborer’s wages are dependent on his labor power (i.e. his ability<br />

to work). This information is not apparent to the laborer himself due to commodity form.<br />

438 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> laborer thinks that his wages come from the capitalist and believes that the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity is created when it enters the market. If the laborer actually knew the underlying<br />

reasons for his wage he would see wages and pr<strong>of</strong>its are a portion <strong>of</strong> the finished product. He<br />

would also see the capitalist’s wealth has acquired the power <strong>of</strong> reproducing itself through<br />

the labor <strong>of</strong> others. Marx 719:1 says, “From a social point <strong>of</strong> view, therefore, the workingclass,<br />

even when not directly engaged in the labour-process, is just as much an appendage <strong>of</strong><br />

capital as the ordinary instruments <strong>of</strong> labour.” That is to say, laborers will be exploited with<br />

or without their direct acknowledgement.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity also hides exploitation. Marx 164:3/o says<br />

<strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character, “<strong>The</strong>re (in religion) the products <strong>of</strong> the human brain seem to be<br />

independent beings endowed with a life <strong>of</strong> their own, which enter into relations with each<br />

other and with human race. So it is in the realm <strong>of</strong> commodities with the products <strong>of</strong> people’s<br />

hands. This I call the fetishism which sticks to the products <strong>of</strong> labor as soon as they<br />

are produced as commodities and which is therefore inseparable from the production on<br />

commodities.” Marx’s definition suggests that objects (i.e. commodities) have lives <strong>of</strong> their<br />

own. <strong>The</strong>y are “endowed” with human-like characteristics requiring “devotion” and respect.<br />

This is unlike the modern definition which suggests fetishism occurs after production when<br />

one has possession <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Marx makes it clear that fetishism is present at the<br />

moment <strong>of</strong> production. Once the commodity is produced the fetishism follows the object regardless<br />

<strong>of</strong> its popularity or branding. Another student <strong>of</strong> this class defined fetishism as “the<br />

objects’ social relations, created by production, are mistaken to be a natural characteristic.”<br />

(AM [430]). Marx sees fetishism through deep analysis <strong>of</strong> market values in capitalism. It is<br />

most important to realize that most individuals in the capitalist system are not aware <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fetish like character that the commodity takes on. That is to say that their social relations<br />

with the commodity are hidden.<br />

Wages are also an interesting factor <strong>of</strong> hidden exploitation. A laborer sells his entire<br />

capacity to work not an hour here <strong>of</strong> there. Since the laborer is selling labor-power, and<br />

not labor, time plays an important role in determining a laborer’s wages. Time wages are a<br />

direct measure <strong>of</strong> a laborers wage power, therefore the day is the shortest and easiest period<br />

in which to compute a laborers wages. <strong>The</strong> laborer sees his hourly wage as an incentive<br />

because he thinks ‘the more I work the more I will be paid’. However, surface relations mask<br />

the capitalist exploitation <strong>of</strong> the laborer. Exploitation is this case is not a direct coercion on<br />

the part <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> laborer believes that he is receiving the wages that correspond<br />

to the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity he has made. A laborer is satisfied with an hourly wage<br />

because his short-term goal is met; although, in the long run the laborer does not necessarily<br />

work more for his own good. <strong>The</strong> laborer is working longer in order to receive enough<br />

wages to pay the bills. <strong>The</strong> capitalist expects everyone to work more and will as a result<br />

lower-wages forcing the laborer to work harder to receive the same wage to live. Hans says<br />

“Capitalism needs a wage form in order to coerce the laborer to do the work, and the wage<br />

form has the additional side effect <strong>of</strong> concealing exploitation” (Ehrbar, Annotations Fa2010,<br />

pg. 546). Again, the laborer is exploited.<br />

Both accidental and systemic exploitation are necessary functions <strong>of</strong> capitalism. Exploitation<br />

takes on many forms which allow it to maintain a stronghold over all participants


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 439<br />

in the capitalist economy. <strong>The</strong> capitalist’s ability to keep exploitation hidden contributes to<br />

the overall success <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system.<br />

Next Message by AM is [1059], Next Message by Somramthom is [1056], and First Message by Utefan is [90].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 817 is 713 in 2008SP, 716 in 2008fa, 749 in 2009fa, 844 in 2011fa, and 874 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 817 Which use-values must be available on the market so that accumulation <strong>of</strong><br />

capital can take place?<br />

[1005] Rico: Necessities for Capital Accumulation. Before seriously contemplating the<br />

answer to this question, I made the assumption that capital was one <strong>of</strong> the necessary usevalues<br />

that is needed in the market before further capital can be accumulated. But I wasn’t<br />

sure what role it played as a necessary use-value. My incomprehension was clarified by<br />

Jenn in [2008SP:748], where she states that “capital is actually a money commodity, one<br />

must have money as a use-value in order to accumulate capital.” I believe this explanation<br />

satisfies why capital is one <strong>of</strong> the use-values that must be available on the market so that the<br />

accumulation <strong>of</strong> more capital can exist.<br />

Jenn gives two more use-values, the <strong>first</strong> being labor-power, and the second being the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production. Jenn states that “in order for the labor-power to be a use-value to the<br />

capitalist, the capitalist must have the means <strong>of</strong> production in which the labor-power can be<br />

applied.” So both labor-power and means <strong>of</strong> production are to be considered necessary usevalue<br />

on the market so that accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital can take place. Without these use-values,<br />

commodity production is not available.<br />

Hans: Capital is not a use-value. But an increasing money supply is needed whenever the economy grows.<br />

About your last sentence: commodity production is possible even if labor-power is not a commodity. This<br />

would be petty commodity production where the laborers owned their means <strong>of</strong> production and did not have to sell<br />

their labor-power.<br />

Clarification added later after reading [2012fa:1462]: the availability <strong>of</strong> labor-power as a commodity is not<br />

necessary for *commodity production*, but it is indeed necessary for the *accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital*, which is the<br />

topic <strong>of</strong> question 817.<br />

Message [1005] referenced by [1007] and [2012fa:1462]. Next Message by Rico is [1151].<br />

[1007] Kaush: Accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital. <strong>The</strong> use-values that must be available on the<br />

market so that accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital can take place are the means <strong>of</strong> production and laborpower.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se use-values produce surplus value that is required for the accumulation <strong>of</strong><br />

capital. Since the economy needs to reproduce and grow in capitalism, an individual capitalist<br />

starts accumulating capital acquiring machines and laborers the <strong>first</strong> year <strong>of</strong> business.<br />

<strong>The</strong> second year, the capitalist reinvests realized surplus value in additional machines and<br />

more labor power. Indeed it is a progressive process <strong>of</strong> accumulation and expansion through<br />

reinvesting <strong>of</strong> the surplus value generated year after year. Furthermore, another capitalist<br />

must be available in the market to supply more machines and keep up with the growing demand<br />

every year and the availability <strong>of</strong> additional money. It seems a seamless process and<br />

taken for granted as long as the resources are available and the economy is not faced with a<br />

crisis.<br />

Hans: Rico [1005] says that more money (which in Marx’s times meant more gold) is a necessary use-value too.<br />

You just dropped this point as if he had never said it. Is he right or not?<br />

Next Message by Kaush is [1015].<br />

440 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 820 is 716 in 2008SP, 719 in 2008fa, 752 in 2009fa, 847 in 2011fa, and 877 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 820 How can the capitalist be compared with a conqueror who buys commodities<br />

from the conquered with the money he has robbed from them?<br />

[947] SMIKEC: I will use Home Depot as an example <strong>of</strong> the conqueror. Since Home<br />

Depot is not a producer but a retailer, it has to use its vendor relationships to make any<br />

money. In order for Home Depot to take their pr<strong>of</strong>it, the vendors need to diminish their<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its drastically in order to even think about getting in the store. Home Depot provides<br />

a laundry list <strong>of</strong> expectations that you have to play by to even step foot in the store. Once<br />

you’re in the store then the vendor hopes that their product moves, otherwise Home Depot<br />

will kick you <strong>of</strong>f the shelves and get someone else in there who will make them more money.<br />

At this point companies <strong>of</strong> decent size are left out on the street with no<strong>thing</strong> to show for other<br />

than a loss in their investment, while Home Depot is still smiling because they really had<br />

no<strong>thing</strong> to lose. On the other side <strong>of</strong> the fence you have the mom and pop shops which don’t<br />

have a chance due to not having the same bargaining power <strong>of</strong> Home Depot. Home depot<br />

comes into these more rural areas, and pushes the small guys right out <strong>of</strong> business virtually<br />

overnight. I’ve personally seen it back in Minnesota where Home Depot came into Willmar,<br />

MN and virtually every small local hardware store within 30 miles had to shut down. On<br />

top <strong>of</strong> the punishment, a lot <strong>of</strong> these people then had to go work for Home Depot in order to<br />

survive. If this isn’t an example <strong>of</strong> the conqueror using the conquered, I’m not sure what is.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> former hardware store owner, who went bankrupt and now receives a paycheck from Home Depot may<br />

be inclined to think Home Depot is paying him with money it has robbed from him. But any other wage laborer is<br />

in the same situation. <strong>The</strong> capitalist just has robbed the surplus product from them, and now they are employing<br />

them for the next time period using the sales receipts <strong>of</strong> this robbed surplus-product.<br />

Next Message by SMIKEC is [961].<br />

[1016] Hal: graded A <strong>The</strong>re is an end only to the conqueror’s plundering. When the<br />

capitalist seizes the means <strong>of</strong> production, his objective is to force producers to provide free<br />

labor in order to ensure their own livelihood. <strong>The</strong> products <strong>of</strong> their labor will then be sold<br />

for money. Thus, if he is successful, the capitalist has taken by coercion money which<br />

should belong to the producers. <strong>The</strong> conqueror’s form <strong>of</strong> coercion is threat <strong>of</strong> violence,<br />

while the capitalist’s is threat <strong>of</strong> extreme poverty and its effects. Contrary to the conqueror,<br />

the capitalist has not broken any law, yet they have both taken by coercion, as opposed to<br />

free exchange.<br />

Whereas, in this example, the conqueror uses the money to purchase the products <strong>of</strong><br />

the producers’ labor, the capitalist uses the money to purchase the labor-power directly. In<br />

financial terms, the conqueror’s deed is less egregious. Assuming the conquered own their<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production, when the conqueror buys their commodities, they can attempt to charge<br />

exorbitant prices and make pr<strong>of</strong>it above subsistence. Also, the conqueror does not use his<br />

purchases to steal more from them. On the other hand, when the capitalist purchases laborpower,<br />

he carefully ensures that the producers only receive subsistence wages. Furthermore,<br />

he uses the labor-power that he has purchased to take even more from the producers in an<br />

endless cycle <strong>of</strong> deterioration. Is it any wonder that the gap between the rich and the poor<br />

grows larger every day?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 441<br />

Hans: Your <strong>first</strong> sentence, which Kobe [1022] finds so powerful, is not entirely true. I don’t think it is correct to<br />

say that the capitalists intentionally seized the means <strong>of</strong> production in order to steal from the worker. <strong>The</strong> capitalists<br />

are the drive-wheel in a system which is set up this way, but they are not the authors <strong>of</strong> the system. But this is indeed<br />

a powerful rhetorical device because it is easier to get mad at people than at a system.<br />

Regarding intentions, it seems to me nowadays it is accurate to say that the capitalists and their lackeys intentionally<br />

destroy the climate and the future <strong>of</strong> our children and grandchildren in order to continue the pr<strong>of</strong>it system<br />

a little longer. And I think there will be climate tribunals as there were Nuremberg tribunals. I am not saying one<br />

should not look at intentions and should not judge people by their intentions. But one must also distinguish between<br />

those <strong>thing</strong>s which are intentional and those which are not.<br />

Message [1016] referenced by [1022] and [2012fa:1513]. Next Message by Hal is [1039].<br />

[1022] Kobe: Conqueror vs. conquered. In response to Hal [1016] I had a few remarks.<br />

In his opening sentence “When the capitalist seizes the means <strong>of</strong> production,his objective is<br />

to force producers to provide free labor in order to ensure their own livelihood.” I find this to<br />

be a very powerful <strong>thing</strong> to say. Part <strong>of</strong> this statement I believe to be true, that the capitalist is<br />

looking to better himself in as great <strong>of</strong> way as possible but I am not sure that the capitalist is<br />

always looking for free labor from the laborer. <strong>The</strong> threat <strong>of</strong> the capitalist to determine wages<br />

and working conditions does cause the laborer to make a decision on whether or not the job<br />

is worth his livelihood. <strong>The</strong> capitalist is compared with a conqueror that buys commodities<br />

from the conquered with their money due to the nature <strong>of</strong> a capitalist to maximize his gains<br />

in labor power. <strong>The</strong> capitalist is buying labor power and not paying FULL equivalent <strong>of</strong><br />

the labor performed, using the capital he has received from the laborer himself to buy these<br />

commodities. This sentence summarizes entirely how this is an accepted comparison <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist.<br />

Message [1022] referenced by [1016]. Next Message by Kobe is [1048].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 821 is 717 in 2008SP, 720 in 2008fa, 753 in 2009fa, 848 in 2011fa, and 878 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 821 In what way must the laborer “buy back the fruits <strong>of</strong> his previous labor with<br />

more labor than they cost”?<br />

[972] JSmits: graded A Wages are too low. <strong>The</strong> laborer must “buy back the fruits <strong>of</strong> his<br />

previous labor with more labor than they cost” because he is not properly compensated for<br />

the work that he does. It stems from the capitalist exploiting the worker and robbing them<br />

with unpaid labor. <strong>The</strong> capitalist makes his pr<strong>of</strong>its through exploiting the workers.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the important points that Hans states in [2008SP:768] is that the price tag <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity is not determined by the capitalist who adds some markup to the initial cost <strong>of</strong><br />

materials to make the commodity. It is determined by the value <strong>of</strong> the commodities a worker<br />

produces in a certain time frame multiplied by amount <strong>of</strong> time a worker actually takes to<br />

produce those commodities.<br />

What this means is that say you are making toys for your job. Your time frame is one<br />

hour and you produce a value <strong>of</strong> $30 in that hour, you are getting paid $10 an hour, and you<br />

produce 1 toy in 20 minutes so 3 toys an hour. <strong>The</strong> capitalist will sell the toy for $10 which<br />

is calculated from the formula stated in the previous paragraph ($30 multiplied by 1/3 hour).<br />

Now if you went to a store and saw one <strong>of</strong> the toys you made and it was being sold for $10<br />

you would say to yourself, “It only took me 20 minutes to make that toy and it costs me 1<br />

hour pay to buy it.”<br />

442 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

This is where exploitation again is at the core <strong>of</strong> the matter. You are getting paid less than<br />

what you produce every hour. If his wage was higher it would be a different story but it’s<br />

not.<br />

Message [972] referenced by [1019] and [2012fa:1333]. Next Message by JSmits is [976].<br />

[1004] Sly: A disheartening situation. Initially I believed that I had a well-formulated<br />

answer to provide, until I looked at a previous submission in the archives that was made by<br />

Hans in [2008SP:768], which by the way should be looked at in order to fully understand<br />

my submission.<br />

<strong>The</strong> best way to understand why a laborer must buy back the fruits (product) <strong>of</strong> his previous<br />

labor is through example, but we must remember that throughout the semester it has<br />

been stressed that the laborer produces more than he/she is being compensated for by the<br />

capitalist - in order to better understand this please refer to my previous submission [669] or<br />

the definition given by Hans in [Answer:4].<br />

In my example I will attempt to use simple numerical values to make the computations<br />

easier on myself, and to any readers. <strong>The</strong> example I will use is a computer-producing factory,<br />

and in this computer-producing factory each laborer produces $100 an hour <strong>of</strong> value. <strong>The</strong><br />

capitalist pays each laborer 20 dollars an hour, as a result the capitalist is making 80 dollars<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it an hour from each laborer, and in this example it takes the laborer 30 minutes to<br />

produce a computer. For the final computations <strong>of</strong> prices in my example it is important to<br />

understand the prices, as Hans stated in [2008SP:786]: “are not determined by the capitalist<br />

who adds some “markup”, but by multiplying the half hour <strong>of</strong> labor represented” (I’m not<br />

including the prices given in the example in order to decrease confusion) – <strong>of</strong> course if the<br />

half hour mentioned is interchangeable with any amount <strong>of</strong> time used to produce the item.<br />

So the capitalist sells the computers produced for $50 because two computers are produced<br />

each hour. If a laborer wished to purchase a computer that came from the factory he/she<br />

would have to pay $50, which is the equivalent to 2.5 hours <strong>of</strong> labor. (20+20+10=50)<br />

So the laborer is working 2.5 hours in order to be able to purchase a computer that took<br />

him/her 30 minutes to produce.<br />

Message [1004] referenced by [1019]. Next Message by Sly is [1072].<br />

[1019] Kleenex: unfair wage system. At the root <strong>of</strong> this issue is the capitalist wage<br />

system. According to Marx, and even intuition ingrained in my mind from being raised in<br />

a capitalist environment, the capitalist will always make a pr<strong>of</strong>it. <strong>The</strong> capitalist owns the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production: he is in control, and the workers only enter into an agreement with the<br />

capitalist because they need a way to make a living, to pay the bills, to put food on the table.<br />

<strong>The</strong> worker will produce x amount <strong>of</strong> value in the commodities he produces in any given<br />

day, but he will only earn a fraction <strong>of</strong> that value in wages. Perhaps if he was his own boss,<br />

he would be able to keep all the pr<strong>of</strong>its and realize all <strong>of</strong> the value he created by his labor<br />

input, but many start-up businesses like that don’t get very far, because they don’t have the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production that the capitalist does.<br />

<strong>The</strong> laborer must buy back the fruits <strong>of</strong> his previous labor with more labor than they<br />

cost because <strong>of</strong> the above reason. JSmits in [972] uses the example <strong>of</strong> toys and Sly [1004]<br />

illustrates his/her point with computer production. To determine what the capitalist will<br />

sell the toy or computer for, one multiplies the value produced per hour by the required


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 443<br />

time to produce the commodity–note that the price charged to consumers isn’t arbitrarily<br />

determined, or “marked-up” as we commonly refer to it as. Let’s say $6 per hour <strong>of</strong> value<br />

is produced and it takes the worker 10 minutes to complete it. $6 multiplied by 1/6 <strong>of</strong> an<br />

hour, or 10 minutes. Though it took the worker 10 minutes to make, he will have to pay 60<br />

minutes worth <strong>of</strong> his wages, for example, if he wants to buy that commodity. This is what<br />

the capitalist will charge, and this is why the worker has to “buy back the fruits” <strong>of</strong> previous<br />

labor.<br />

Hans: You are assuming the worker’s wage is $1 per hour. Would it be $2 per hour, then he would only need 30<br />

minutes to buy back the 10 minute product.<br />

Next Message by Kleenex is [1021].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 824 Spell out explicitly the “Law <strong>of</strong> appropriation” or “law <strong>of</strong> private property”<br />

based on commodity production and circulation. In other words, explain the principle that<br />

ultimately entitles the owner <strong>of</strong> a commodity to own his or her commodity.<br />

[967] AM: What’s Yours is Mine and What’s Mine is Yours. I was intrigued by this<br />

question because it addresses an issue that we encounter from a young age: private property.<br />

Several childish phrases came to mind while thinking about this question: “Finders keepers,<br />

losers weepers,” “you snooze you lose,” “but you didn’t call your seat,” “no give backs.”<br />

While I acknowledge these are all very trivial responses to the issue <strong>of</strong> who owns what,<br />

but it gets the conversation started. Now I can address the far deeper issue at hand “law <strong>of</strong><br />

appropriation” and/or “law <strong>of</strong> private property.” A major implication <strong>of</strong> capitalism is that it<br />

requires growth, the change <strong>of</strong> commodity into capital. <strong>The</strong> “law <strong>of</strong> appropriation” manifests<br />

during the transformation from commodity to capital. This advancement <strong>of</strong> money comes<br />

from unpaid labor as a direct result <strong>of</strong> the laborer. However, it is important to note that<br />

property rights do not come from his labor alone. Marx says “Only the mutually independent<br />

buyer and seller face each other in commodity production. Relations between them cease<br />

on the day when the term stipulated in the contract they concluded expires”. <strong>The</strong> contract<br />

need not be written but can be spoken too. <strong>The</strong> most intriguing part in all <strong>of</strong> this for me is as<br />

Hans writes “Every<strong>thing</strong> strictly follows the laws <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange, yet the result is<br />

opposite to the principles governing simple commodity production and exchange.” I suppose<br />

the main message in all this is the capital is essentially being created out <strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> “law <strong>of</strong> appropriation” <strong>of</strong> commodity production is: “if you make it, you own it.” In capitalism, the<br />

principle “if you make it, you own it” no longer holds.<br />

Interestingly, this principle is also absent in your collection <strong>of</strong> nursery rhymes. <strong>The</strong> nursery rhymes say: if you<br />

are the <strong>first</strong> to claim some<strong>thing</strong>, and ready to defend your claim against others, then you own it. This is closer to<br />

the capitalist reality. In other words, ever since toddler age, we are trained to accept the capitalist outrages as the<br />

normal functioning <strong>of</strong> the world.<br />

Next Message by AM is [1041].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 825 is 757 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 825 Why mere semblance?<br />

[1009] School: Mere Semblance <strong>of</strong> what was. Marx uses the phrase “mere semblance”<br />

to describe the paradoxical from <strong>of</strong> exchange between the capitalist and the worker. In the<br />

annotations pg 629 it states that “the exchange remains because <strong>of</strong> the original operation<br />

444 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

with which we started has now become turned round in such a way that only the mere semblance<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchange remains.” As explained in the earlier parts <strong>of</strong> Capital, Marx explains that<br />

all commodities are linked together through the labor that was taken to produce each commodity.<br />

Depending on how much labor-value put into said commodity was the determining<br />

factor for the exchange <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Unfortunately it was through the capitalist that this form <strong>of</strong> exchange was warped and<br />

changed. Like Samwell [2009fa:1111] says “Following the events that led to the separation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the workers from their means <strong>of</strong> production, it became impossible for the worker to produce<br />

his own commodities as he no longer had access to the means <strong>of</strong> production. Property<br />

became the exclusive right <strong>of</strong> the capitalist class, and labor-power the worker’s only exchangeable<br />

commodity.” Without the worker having access to production or market power<br />

and only having the ability to use their labor-power the worker would only create more value<br />

to each commodity and the excess labor was unpaid labor-value produced by the workers<br />

themselves.<br />

So the phrase “mere semblance” describes that once upon a time the commodity exchangevalue<br />

was measured by the labor-value, and now in the capitalist eyes it is measured by<br />

surplus and exploitation <strong>of</strong> the workers. This change reminds me <strong>of</strong> an rubik cube, when<br />

you <strong>first</strong> buy one all six side have the same color and after tinkering with the cube for a few<br />

minutes you find that the colors are all mixed up and you have the desire to solve the cube,<br />

and put it back into its original form. You then discover that it is much harder than it appears<br />

to go back to its original form. Like the original form <strong>of</strong> exchange over time it was tinkered<br />

with and now it is a problem that is very difficult to go back to its original form.<br />

Hans: Good try, and I love your rubik cube analogy, but Marx sees the matter a little differently. He says exchange<br />

proportions are still governed by labor values, but the workers don’t benefit from being the producers <strong>of</strong> all this<br />

value because the exchange between capitalist <strong>of</strong> laborer is no longer a free exchange but an act <strong>of</strong> dispossession<br />

posing as an exchange, i.e., a “mere semblance” <strong>of</strong> an exchange.<br />

Next Message by School is [1018].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 827 is 726 in 2008fa, 759 in 2009fa, 855 in 2011fa, and 885 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 827 Why is it not admissible to seek relations between whole social classes in the<br />

laws <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange?<br />

[953] Kobe: social classes. In this case only the seller and buyer face each other in<br />

the commodity production. <strong>The</strong>y have this relation during the duration <strong>of</strong> the contract, this<br />

time can vary from a simple purchase <strong>of</strong> a hamburger or longer in the leasing <strong>of</strong> land over<br />

50 years. If this transaction is repeated it is done again as the result <strong>of</strong> a new agreement<br />

which has no relation to earlier transaction. Doing business with a repeat seller and buyer<br />

is only done so by chance. If commodity production is to be judged you must consider<br />

each exchange as a separate exchange, apart from the previous exchange as well as the<br />

later exchange. Due to sales and purchases being done solely between individuals it’s not<br />

valid to seek for relations between whole social classes. This argument argues that social<br />

relations are emergent from interpersonal relations, therefore laws <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange<br />

are interpersonal surface relations not core relations, which some believe they are.<br />

Next Message by Kobe is [978].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 445<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 828 is 760 in 2009fa, 856 in 2011fa, and 886 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 828 Describe as well as you can the social mechanism <strong>of</strong> which the capitalist is<br />

merely a drive-wheel.<br />

[1013] Scholar: This question is not easy!<br />

In the mode <strong>of</strong> capitalism, property right is private, also the means <strong>of</strong> production are<br />

owned by individuals (capitalists).<br />

Almost all production becomes commodity production, even the labor power also becomes<br />

a commodity.<br />

On this basis, social distribution is carried out through market exchange, which is ‘free’<br />

and ‘fair’. That means if you have more money, you can buy more labor power and more<br />

machine freely to produce more production, so you will get much more money.<br />

But on the other side, this ‘good’ environment also makes competition between capitalists<br />

more fierce. Stronger capitalists who have more money will afford more skilled workers and<br />

better machines, even more advanced technology, which will make his products cheaper, so<br />

the weaker capitalists who can not compete with them will be swallowed or bankrupt.<br />

It is clear, as a capitalist, if he wants to survive in the market competition, ceaseless<br />

capital accumulation is essential and necessary, that means every capitalist will do his best<br />

to accumulate, whether he wants or not.<br />

First Message by Scholar is [192].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 829 is 725 in 2008SP, 728 in 2008fa, 761 in 2009fa, and 891 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 829 What does Marx mean with the remark “but original sin is at work everywhere”<br />

in 740:1/o?<br />

[1008] IrvingHowe: Original sin. I believe Marx is referring to the triumph <strong>of</strong> human<br />

nature over the necessities <strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

More specifically, Marx says in Ch. 26 “But the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital presupposes<br />

surplus-value; surplus-value presupposes capitalistic production; capitalistic production presupposes<br />

the pre-existence <strong>of</strong> considerable masses <strong>of</strong> capital and <strong>of</strong> labour power in the<br />

hands <strong>of</strong> producers <strong>of</strong> commodities.” From this we see that capital accumulation is the cornerstone<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalist development. It is, Marx seems to say, not unlike a commandment.<br />

In Christianity, we are taught that god gave a commandment to Adam not to partake <strong>of</strong> the<br />

forbidden fruit. In a triumph <strong>of</strong> human nature over Adam’s desire to obtain god’s approval,<br />

Adam eats the fruit. This despite god’s promise <strong>of</strong> everlasting life.<br />

For a human in the role <strong>of</strong> a capitalist, capital accumulation is likened to this broken commandment.<br />

It is <strong>first</strong> in the genesis <strong>of</strong> capitalism and essential for capitalism’s continuation<br />

and yet accumulation is directly at odds with the human desires <strong>of</strong> the capitalist to consume.<br />

Nature, as it always does, wins out over nurture and the person in the role <strong>of</strong> the capitalist<br />

will indulge himself. This despite capitalism’s commandment to accumulate, accumulate,<br />

accumulate. This, Marx would say, is ‘economic original sin’ at work.<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [1097].<br />

446 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 830 is 220 in 1996ut, 301 in 1997sp, 297 in 1998WI, 712 in 2008SP, 729 in<br />

2008fa, 858 in 2011fa, and 892 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 830 Is a capitalist free to decide whether to expand his business, and how much<br />

<strong>of</strong> his pr<strong>of</strong>it to use for personal consumption? Which mechanisms, if any, constrain him or<br />

her?<br />

[988] Milly: graded A Capitalist’s Decision to Accumulate. In the annotations, the<br />

question arises who decides how much will be accumulated and how much consumed. <strong>The</strong><br />

answer is the capitalist does. It states that it is an individual decision, not an economic<br />

necessity and is an act <strong>of</strong> his will. However it goes on to say that the rate <strong>of</strong> capitalization is<br />

not exactly determined by the individual capitalist but by the capitalist class as a whole.<br />

Accumulation is necessary in the development <strong>of</strong> the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production and<br />

with competition he constantly needs to extend his capital in order to preserve it. When<br />

he decides to accept private consumption he decreases his accumulation. When he declines<br />

consumption he promotes accumulation and he gains more power.<br />

Next Message by Milly is [1116].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 831 is 763 in 2009fa and 859 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 831 How was surplus-value divided into capital and revenue in the different historical<br />

periods <strong>of</strong> capitalism?<br />

[974] Deadfamous: graded B– In the Annotations Marx speaks <strong>of</strong> 4 main Historical Periods<br />

<strong>of</strong> Manchester’s history depicted by Dr Aikin:<br />

1st step was when the working class was “obliged to work hard for their livelihood.”<br />

2nd step the working class worked just as hard as before and acquired small fortunes<br />

3rd step is when the working class was better <strong>of</strong>f due to trade, when “riders (traders)<br />

being sent into every market town in the kingdom” [luxury began].<br />

4th step is when trade was through all <strong>of</strong> Europe and the time “in which expense and<br />

luxury have made great progress” being supported by the trade through all <strong>of</strong> Europe.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se four steps speak <strong>of</strong> how surplus labor was little the laborer had to be really austere<br />

in the begining and then slowly beginning to acculate surplus over time, then if trade<br />

becomes a part <strong>of</strong> your business you can find a way to afford certain luxuries, and this path<br />

continues as trade continues.<br />

In his notes to [2009fa:763] Hans pointed out some<strong>thing</strong> key to understanding how<br />

surplus-value was divided in different time periods was mainly due to creation and availability<br />

<strong>of</strong> CREDIT. Before the credit was available, the capitalist could only reinvest for better<br />

technology with his accumulated revenue that s/he possessed. Once credit came along the<br />

rules <strong>of</strong> the game for the capitalist changed since they could invest much more quickly, once<br />

they (capitalists) qualified for credit <strong>of</strong> some kind enabling them to speed up this process.<br />

It also meant that the revenues that they had after credit came along was all theirs since,<br />

not having to worry so they could reinvest.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 447<br />

“With the development <strong>of</strong> the credit system capitalists no longer had to selffinance<br />

all expansion but could rely on credit. This meant they could use<br />

much more money for consumption. This consumption also demonstrated<br />

their wealth and therefore served as a means to get credit.”<br />

This is probably the two main historical periods <strong>of</strong> capitalism that are most important,<br />

PRE and POST CREDIT. It also seems that the demonstration <strong>of</strong> wealth helped your chances<br />

to get capital through credit in a sort <strong>of</strong> snowballing effect.<br />

Hans: You say “working class” where Marx and Aiken were talking about the capitalists. Marx did not consider<br />

the capitalists to be part <strong>of</strong> the working class.<br />

Next Message by Deadfamous is [1111].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 835 is 728 in 2008SP, 734 in 2008fa, 767 in 2009fa, 863 in 2011fa, and 897 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 835 What is the “Abstinence <strong>The</strong>ory”?<br />

[975] Ryan: According to the Abstinence <strong>The</strong>ory saving is an act <strong>of</strong> abstaining from<br />

consumption. Since to abstain is painful, it is necessary to reward people for this act. This<br />

reward is in the form <strong>of</strong> the interest paid to those who saved, rather than consumed their<br />

incomes.<br />

Marx does not like this idea at all, and for good reason. Marx feels that you should be<br />

rewarded for what you do (labor in most examples) and not for what you don’t do.<br />

Hans in [2009fa:1184] basically tells you every<strong>thing</strong> you would ever need to know about<br />

how Marx feel about the Abstinence theory. I will just highlight the stuff that made it make<br />

sense to me and add another view as well. Marx uses a quote from Cazenove that sums up<br />

every<strong>thing</strong> that is wrong with the Abstinence <strong>The</strong>ory:<br />

He who converts his revenue into capital, abstains from the enjoyment<br />

which its expenditure would afford him. ... It is not the abstinence, but<br />

the use <strong>of</strong> the capital productively, which is the cause <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

As we all know by now Marx claims that all joy and wages come from contribution<br />

(action) not abstinence. In the quote above the assumption that you must abstain from enjoyment<br />

you wish to have is to suffer seems to be a very large overstatement. Many <strong>of</strong> us<br />

that choose to invest do consider the items we could purchase instead <strong>of</strong> putting money into<br />

our 401k’s or IRA’s or into the stock market, but I never feel that I am owed some type <strong>of</strong><br />

interest (or reimbursement) back because I am now not able to buy some item. It is an investment<br />

Plan not a long term torture plan. (although over the last few years you investment<br />

portfolio may have felt like a torture plan :-) )<br />

<strong>The</strong> “real” value comes to the owner <strong>of</strong> that capital not because <strong>of</strong> the abstinence but from<br />

the use <strong>of</strong> the capital to produce more. Many people would rather invest their money than<br />

spend it on random items. I do not feel that there is any discomfort or lack <strong>of</strong> enjoyment on<br />

their part. <strong>The</strong> reason why I said earlier that quote above seems to be a large overstatement is<br />

because, consider those who have more than enough money. Do you really think that when<br />

the choose to put money into (savings) instead <strong>of</strong> spending it on commodities that they really<br />

448 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

suffer. Are they really “abstaining from enjoyment” or do they already have so much stuff<br />

that they really don’t need a fifth car or a seventh TV. <strong>The</strong> Abstinence <strong>The</strong>ory states that<br />

there must be a price (suffering) for not spending but, how many <strong>of</strong> us save just because we<br />

make more than we spend are we passively suffering, can you passively suffer?<br />

You never choose to abstain from spending, you just choose to save. You never choose to<br />

be miserable now, you choose to be happy later.<br />

Next Message by Ryan is [1074].<br />

[998] RexManning: graded A Some<strong>thing</strong> for no<strong>thing</strong>. Abstinence <strong>The</strong>ory is an idea<br />

brought on by the “vulgar economists” and presented by Nassau W. Senior when he announced<br />

his discovery “I substitute, for the word capital, considered as an instrument <strong>of</strong><br />

production, the word abstinence.” Senior is suggesting that the capitalist’s pr<strong>of</strong>its are a result<br />

<strong>of</strong> abstaining from the overwhelming desire to expend. Suggesting that pr<strong>of</strong>its come from<br />

doing no<strong>thing</strong> is in stark contrast to Marx, because value must come from some<strong>thing</strong>, some<strong>thing</strong><br />

real (like the comparison <strong>of</strong> the shoemaker and the capitalist). Although the capitalist<br />

is not pouring his labor into his investments in order to pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> the interest, he is, as<br />

Cazenove suggests, using the capital productively in order to pr<strong>of</strong>it. What Senior suggests<br />

in his abstinence theory is that because the capitalist is abstaining from expending, he is<br />

able to convert his revenue into capital. <strong>The</strong> way in which he uses the word “abstinence”<br />

makes it seem as if the capitalist is gaining by doing no<strong>thing</strong>, which is incorrect. <strong>The</strong> way<br />

in which this theory is presented is as if the “vulgar economists” suggest that the capitalist<br />

is an “abstaining saint.”<br />

Next Message by RexManning is [1087].<br />

[1014] Robert: (graded A) Capitalist-Apologetic Economic <strong>The</strong>ory. Abstinence theory<br />

is a capitalist-apologetic economic theory <strong>first</strong> presented by Nassau Senior. It states that the<br />

virtuous capitalist, by restraining from consuming his production capital, continues to be<br />

able to loan the hapless workers his means <strong>of</strong> production. For this act <strong>of</strong> self-sacrifice the<br />

capitalist is rewarded with pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

I can imagine Marx’s veins bulging as he read Senior’s theory. <strong>The</strong> idea the the capitalist<br />

“loan” their means <strong>of</strong> production to the workers brought a “(!)” from Marx. First <strong>of</strong> all,<br />

notwithstanding that capitalists are but “one <strong>of</strong> the drive wheels” <strong>of</strong> the “social mechanism”<br />

it is not appropriate to attribute virtue to him or her. <strong>The</strong> capitalist is exploiting the workers<br />

by demanding from them all <strong>of</strong> the labor power he can extract in exchange for wages which<br />

allow the laborer to exist and reproduce in exchange for access to means <strong>of</strong> production which<br />

are not rightly is but he claims to own. <strong>The</strong>re is no<strong>thing</strong> virtuous about this arrangement.<br />

Secondly, in the “real” world value does not come from no<strong>thing</strong>. Value is real and it is created<br />

by human expenditure <strong>of</strong> brains, muscle, and energy. Doing no<strong>thing</strong> cannot create any<br />

value. Abstinence is NOT doing some<strong>thing</strong>. Hans reminds us in [2009fa:1184] that Marx<br />

was a critical realist and he obviously had a concern with a theory suggesting some<strong>thing</strong><br />

coming from no<strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Thirdly, abstinence as an “activity” makes no sense at a philosophic level. Right now<br />

all <strong>of</strong> us are abstaining from doing some<strong>thing</strong>...I am abstaining from fly-fishing and from<br />

doing my job (because I’m writing this email). So, whatever we are doing we are abstaining<br />

from doing some<strong>thing</strong> else. For example, Marx writes: “eating is abstinence from fasting,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 449<br />

walking, abstinence from standing still, working, abstinence from idling...” and so on. Is<br />

the capitalists’ not consuming their means <strong>of</strong> production a special kind <strong>of</strong> non-activity? <strong>The</strong><br />

reasoning is flawed. We all are abstaining from certain activities and no one is attributing<br />

value <strong>of</strong> our abstinence.<br />

Finally, it is true capitalist generally do not consume their means <strong>of</strong> production. Marx<br />

sarcastically wonders how difficult it is for them to not eat “all these steam-engines, cotton,<br />

railways, manure, horses, and all.” Hans points out in [2009fa:1184] that the Abstinence<br />

theoreticians obviously didn’t mean the literal consumption <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production but<br />

the consumption <strong>of</strong> their value. So why do capitalist not consume their means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

or the value <strong>of</strong> their means <strong>of</strong> production? We are back to where we started this discussion:<br />

without the means <strong>of</strong> production the capitalist cannot exploit surplus-value, which he claims<br />

for himself, from those who have no access to means <strong>of</strong> production. That is why s/he doesn’t<br />

consume them.<br />

Kobe: I think that Robert’s submission concerning the Abstinence <strong>The</strong>ory is a pretty thorough one. I would like<br />

to add a few ideas that I think simplify it and put it in terms everyone could understand. In economic terms <strong>of</strong><br />

society there occurs not just simple reproduction but reproduction on a progressively, increasing scale. Meaning<br />

with more goods being produced there is more to consume which leads to larger consumption, consequently more<br />

products have to be converted into means <strong>of</strong> production. This part <strong>of</strong> the Abstinence theory I believe is a major part<br />

<strong>of</strong> Marx’s argument. Marx denied the existence <strong>of</strong> any such function while arguing that the social product must be<br />

attributed entirely to acts <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong>re is a link between the abstinence theory and expanded reproduction. In simple reproduction the capitalists<br />

consume the entire surplus-value, i.e., there is no abstention. But in expanded reproduction the capitalists do<br />

not consume all the surplus-value, and the Abstinence theory is trying to turn this into a meritorious act.<br />

Message [1014] referenced by [2012fa:1563]. First Message by Robert is [14].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 838 is 663 in 2004fa, 737 in 2008fa, 770 in 2009fa, 866 in 2011fa, and 900 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 838 If it is true that the laborers produce all the value, it is necessary to explain<br />

why they do not get it. This question becomes especially puzzling if one considers the<br />

exponential character <strong>of</strong> the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital. One should expect labor demand to<br />

eventually outrun the labor supply, so that the labor market will eventually become a seller’s<br />

market. Which mechanisms prevent this from happening?<br />

[1052] TINDOZ: Bad bosses cutting their knees out from under them. I think there<br />

are probably multiple mechanisms and though Greg’s [2009fa:1163] comment, about “(1)<br />

technological advances, (2) finding new labor pools and (3) ... recessions and depressions”<br />

was fantastic, I won’t regurgitate his answer, but take if from another angle - that <strong>of</strong> greed.<br />

<strong>The</strong> mechanism that I’ll add to this question is the mechanism <strong>of</strong> how the sheer greed<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalist can result in high turn over where new employees are just recycled after<br />

refusing to work for another greedy capitalist. Before I get into it, I recognize that this isn’t<br />

always the case, but I think in some cases this does prevent some companies from having a<br />

labor demand that is higher than the supply - and hopefully I’m not totally <strong>of</strong>f base. Years<br />

ago I worked for a local s<strong>of</strong>tware company where I learned <strong>first</strong> hand how a greedy capitalist<br />

can fall into a cycle where their demand for labor becomes a simple need to replace former<br />

laborers that refused to work for them anymore. <strong>The</strong> management would continually lie to<br />

potential clients that they had s<strong>of</strong>tware that they didn’t. On multiple occasions, they even<br />

450 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

SOLD s<strong>of</strong>tware that didn’t even exist and up to that point wasn’t even on the drawing board.<br />

After selling the phantom s<strong>of</strong>tware and having a set delivery date, they would return to the<br />

development team and demand they work around the clock (with no over-time pay) to meet<br />

their delivery date in one week. <strong>The</strong>y would attempt to make it seem like we were all in this<br />

together, working as a team - when the fact was, they wanted more pr<strong>of</strong>it so they lied and<br />

expected us to do what we had to so we wouldn’t lose our jobs. However, when the money<br />

rolled in, the pay <strong>of</strong> us laborers wasn’t increased regardless <strong>of</strong> our being a team player. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

did this over and over again. This rush resulted in multiple bugs for a basically untested<br />

product that would trickle into my position <strong>of</strong> tech support. I’d start getting calls about<br />

s<strong>of</strong>tware that I had only just barely installed on my machine an hour earlier. This resulted in<br />

multiple extremely disgruntled employees - which led to resignations. All <strong>of</strong> the sudden the<br />

demand for labor wasn’t to fuel expansion, it was for retention - and those who replaced the<br />

ones that left had similar stories from where they came from, not realizing until they were<br />

hired that they just got the same package with different wrapping paper. I observed this turn<br />

over a few times before I finally walked. This inefficiency (rapid turn over) was all fueled<br />

by the greed <strong>of</strong> the capitalists on top. It’s now been years, and their company has had very<br />

minimal growth because they keep cutting their knees out from under them by infuriating<br />

their work force. I doubt that this is an intended “mechanism” <strong>of</strong> keeping labor demand to<br />

only a few employees - it just keeps happening and it prevents any real growth. True they<br />

are <strong>of</strong>ten in demand for new labor, but the new faces that would be hired were just recycled<br />

from some other poorly managed s<strong>of</strong>tware company. So I suppose this mechanism really<br />

only affects the poorly managed companies (and it treats them as a group) because rather<br />

than growing, they just reshuffle their employees ever now and then because they are too<br />

greedy for their own good.<br />

Hans: Capitalists are not overly worried if you quit in disgust. <strong>The</strong>y may lose you, but they may be able to replace<br />

you with an excellent worker who just quit in disgust from their competitor.<br />

First Message by TINDOZ is [159].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 839 is 771 in 2009fa, 867 in 2011fa, and 901 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 839 “Value composition” and “organic composition” are two names for the same<br />

number, namely, the proportion between constant and variable capital c/v. When does Marx<br />

use the word “value composition” and when does he use “organic composition?” Why<br />

would one want to introduce two different words for the same number? Are there other<br />

examples where Marx uses two different words for the same <strong>thing</strong>?<br />

[1040] Kleenex: value and organic composition <strong>of</strong> capital. Marx uses different terms<br />

for same subject, when considered in two different situations. Value composition, defined<br />

as constant capital (materials and machines) divided by variable capital (related to laborpower),<br />

is NOT used when value composition and technical composition are causally related,<br />

meaning when technical composition comes before, or is “causally prior” to, value<br />

composition. This describes organic composition. Marx writes more precisely, “I call the<br />

value-composition <strong>of</strong> capital, in so far as it is determined by its technical composition and<br />

mirrors the changes in the latter, the organic composition <strong>of</strong> capital.” Marx uses two different<br />

terms also because two different outcomes can occur. On one hand, the composition <strong>of</strong>


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 451<br />

capital is determined by a ratio <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the production means and the value <strong>of</strong> laborpower.<br />

On the other hand, it can be understood by the physical component, consisting <strong>of</strong><br />

physical mass <strong>of</strong> employment. Also, value composition can change under different circumstances<br />

than the conditions under which organic composition would change. To illustrate,<br />

when you for example, buy a defective product from the store, is a defective part always a<br />

result <strong>of</strong> the production process? It’s quite possible. However, the defect/damage could’ve<br />

also been caused by negligence during the shipping process, or maybe how the store handled<br />

the item, or the quality <strong>of</strong> the materials used. It seems like Marx uses two different words for<br />

the same <strong>thing</strong> in his earlier chapters, when he talks about the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity rooted<br />

in labor: abstract human labor, and congealed human labor, though I may have this mixed<br />

up with other terms he uses.<br />

Next Message by Kleenex is [1043].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 842 is 319 in 1997WI, 387 in 1997sp, 384 in 1997ut, 582 in 2002fa, 606 in<br />

2003fa, 665 in 2004fa, 612 in 2005fa, 736 in 2007SP, 707 in 2007fa, 736 in 2008SP, 741<br />

in 2008fa, 774 in 2009fa, 871 in 2011fa, and 905 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 842 <strong>The</strong> capitalist depends on the worker for pr<strong>of</strong>it, and the worker depends on<br />

the capitalist for survival. Does this mean that workers and capitalists have the same interests?<br />

[1030] Somramthom: graded A <strong>The</strong> bigger picture. When I initially read this question,<br />

I thought there is one interest for the capitalist and the worker to be for or against. But the<br />

more I thought about the question, the more interests I recognized. In [2005fa:1568] SueGirl<br />

lists 8 interest for the capitalist and 8 for the worker. She shows that both the capitalist and<br />

the worker must and do have more than one interest. Yet, her list is fairly nearsighted since<br />

it doesn’t account for long run interests. <strong>The</strong> players in capitalism have many different<br />

interests and they all come into play in one way or another. So depending on which interests<br />

you look at it can seem that workers and capitalists have the same interest or completely<br />

different ones.<br />

<strong>The</strong> main goal <strong>of</strong> the capitalist is to exploit the worker by pr<strong>of</strong>iting from the “surplus”<br />

labor the worker creates. <strong>The</strong> aim <strong>of</strong> the worker is to obtain a wage and support himself. <strong>The</strong><br />

capitalist wants to drive down costs, including wages, and the worker wants an increase in<br />

wage. <strong>The</strong> worker isn’t fairly compensated for the value he creates and still allows himself<br />

to be exploited. <strong>The</strong>se interests are clearly opposing. But there are other interests they<br />

share. Hans states in [2009fa:226] “Many people in the US know how ugly and exploitative<br />

capitalism is, but they still don’t reject it, because on a macro scale, the selfish actions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

greedy capitalists come together in a dynamic macro system which benefits everyone.”<br />

Since capitalism is a social system, interaction and dependency is involved. If it wasn’t,<br />

it wouldn’t be social. For the system to survive, the capitalist must depend on the worker<br />

and the worker must depend on the capitalist. <strong>The</strong>y share the interest <strong>of</strong> continual social<br />

interaction in the capitalistic system since they both live in said system.<br />

If you look at the short-term and micro scale the capitalist and the worker have opposing<br />

interests. It’s when you look at the bigger picture that you see that their interests aren’t so<br />

far apart from each other.<br />

452 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: You are right, we all share the interest to live in a society which functions well enough that it can produce<br />

wealth for everyone. Marxists would say there is again a difference <strong>of</strong> interests, because workers play a much<br />

bigger role in the production <strong>of</strong> this wealth than the capitalists. Marxists think that workers do not really need the<br />

capitalists, they could easily take over the jobs <strong>of</strong> the capitalists, while the capitalists can do no<strong>thing</strong> without the<br />

workers.<br />

Message [1030] referenced by [2011fa:1078], [2011fa:1105], and [2012fa:1530]. Next Message by Somramthom<br />

is [1055].<br />

[1066] Baseball: <strong>The</strong> capitalist and worker have two different motives when interacting<br />

with each other in the workplace. Capitalists, by nature, exploit workers and their labor<br />

power in order to turn a pr<strong>of</strong>it and will do any<strong>thing</strong> in order to succeed, even if it means<br />

reducing the workforce at the expense <strong>of</strong> the employee. Workers, on the other hand, sacrifice<br />

their labor-power in exchange for wages which cover their cost <strong>of</strong> living/surviving. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

both are interacting with each other with the expectations <strong>of</strong> making money but money is<br />

the universal means <strong>of</strong> exchange, used to represent exchange values <strong>of</strong> commodities and<br />

services. A quote which I thought represents the relationship is, “Capital comes to control<br />

the supply <strong>of</strong> the exploitable material on which its accumulation depends.” Capital being a<br />

capitalist representative and the exploitable material being the workers. Capitalists exploit<br />

workers because if they did not, their business would not succeed aka turn pr<strong>of</strong>it. Workers<br />

realize this and accept the actuality <strong>of</strong> their exploitation. For if it was not for this, they would<br />

not have a source <strong>of</strong> income to help them survive.<br />

Hans: How did you mean this when you said capitalists ecploit workers “by nature”? A Marxist would criticize<br />

what you are saying because you sound as if capitalism was the only possible social order.<br />

First Message by Baseball is [115].<br />

[1067] KA: Incentivize the Laborer. Marx argues that Capital requires Labor in order<br />

produce a commodity, and Labor requires Capital in order to survive. If there is an increase<br />

in demand for Labor, wages will rise, which in turn will provide better working and living<br />

conditions for Labor. Marx hedges this comment in stating that Labor will only be hired<br />

if the cost <strong>of</strong> the labor-power is low enough to still assume a pr<strong>of</strong>it. Marx also states that<br />

the laborer cannot employ himself (use their own labor-power) because he does not have the<br />

means for production. Essentially stating that the laborer is reliant on Capital to survive.<br />

<strong>The</strong> laborer is further incentivized through means <strong>of</strong> employment, to increase capital for the<br />

capitalists. Marx argues, “<strong>The</strong> labor-power <strong>of</strong> the wage worker can only exchange itself for<br />

capital by increasing capital, by streng<strong>thing</strong> the power whose slave it is.” Furthermore, Hans<br />

states in the annotations “the growth <strong>of</strong> the working-class must be such that it serves the<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> capital. Such an outcome would not be possible if the growth <strong>of</strong> the working<br />

class were independent, exogenous, to capital.” In order for the working class to grow, its<br />

dependence on capital is obvious. Marx answers Q: 842 clearly by stating, “Hence, increase<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital is increase <strong>of</strong> the proletariat, that is, <strong>of</strong> the working class.”<br />

Hans: Growth <strong>of</strong> the working class means also growth <strong>of</strong> their dependence and poverty. Marx would say that<br />

growth <strong>of</strong> the working class is not in the interest <strong>of</strong> the workers. (He also says that the classless society can only be<br />

achieved through a transitional period where the working class is the ruling class—but this is different than growth<br />

<strong>of</strong> the working class in a capitalist system.)<br />

First Message by KA is [2].<br />

[1077] Long: I don’t think the laborer and the capitalists have the same interest. Mainly<br />

because I think that the capitalist uses the power that they have to hire laborers only when<br />

they deem as necessary and still able to maximize their pr<strong>of</strong>it. <strong>The</strong>y usually try to use


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 453<br />

whatever laborers they already have and try to push for more output. <strong>The</strong> capitalist mind<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking would always be minimal laborer, maximum output equals more pr<strong>of</strong>it. On<br />

the other hand, when the laborer put themself on the market for a job would most likely<br />

do it for the fact <strong>of</strong> survival. To provide for their daily needs. As Hans pointed out that<br />

“wage labor without capital is not alive, the laborer cannot use her labor-powere for herself<br />

because she is separated from the means <strong>of</strong> production.” I think that as laborer, we are bound<br />

to our contracts and always willing to work for a lower wage than the capitalist wants to pay<br />

especially in our current economic crisis. I have seen the same job opening with same duties<br />

that are paying less now than I’ve seen in the past.<br />

She: I agree that capitalists and laborers do not have the same interests. Maximization <strong>of</strong> someone else’s pr<strong>of</strong>its<br />

does not equate to the maximization <strong>of</strong> happiness or personal gain. Large corporations have seen huge growth in<br />

productivity and pr<strong>of</strong>its over the last 2 years while the average worker has been paid and employed less. <strong>The</strong> owners<br />

<strong>of</strong> the means, as Long says, are using the worried mindset <strong>of</strong> the workers to their advantage.<br />

First Message by Long is [207].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 849 is 912 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 849 In footnote to 765:1/o Marx asks: “who created the civil institutions?” He<br />

clearly had a specific answer in mind. Which answer? Full disclosure: Hans doesn’t know<br />

the answer himself. He sees three possibilities:<br />

(a) members <strong>of</strong> the ruling class<br />

(b) individuals involved in production, with an intimate knowledge <strong>of</strong> the specific needs <strong>of</strong><br />

production<br />

(c) individuals living in this society who have a general understanding <strong>of</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong><br />

society<br />

<strong>The</strong>re may be other possibilities.<br />

[1027] Jo: Who created the civil institutions? My initial thought is that Marx is referring<br />

to the members <strong>of</strong> the ruling class. He is responding to Eden’s statement: “<strong>The</strong>re are others<br />

who, though they ‘neither toil nor spin’, can yet command the produce <strong>of</strong> industry, but who<br />

owe their exemption from labor solely to civilization and order. . . ” Those who are exempt<br />

from labor due to civilization and order sound like the ruling class; many <strong>of</strong> whom have<br />

inherited their fortune, all <strong>of</strong> whom are exempt from labor.<br />

A close look at any civil institution can provide insight into who created it (or who recreated<br />

it, or is currently influencing its actions). Who is benefiting from it? Who is it<br />

serving? <strong>The</strong> U.S. Congress for example, consistently passes legislation that benefits the<br />

ruling class, whether it be in the form <strong>of</strong> tax cuts, corporate bailouts, or a pitiful minimum<br />

wage. Token concessions are made for the working class to maintain their complacency.<br />

Message [1027] referenced by [2012fa:1499]. Next Message by Jo is [1032].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 850 is 743 in 2007SP, 743 in 2008SP, 748 in 2008fa, 781 in 2009fa, 879 in<br />

2011fa, and 913 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 850 What is the “juridical illusion”?<br />

[1036] Guh: Illusion. According to Marx the juridical illusion is the concept that society<br />

influences the laws and the lawmaker then makes the actual law. Thus, the laws are essentially<br />

created and designed by the society, even though they are not the ones that are actually<br />

454 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

making the laws laws. Marx says in 765:1/o, “He does not regard the law as a product <strong>of</strong> the<br />

material relation <strong>of</strong> production, but rather the reverse: he sees the relations <strong>of</strong> production as<br />

products <strong>of</strong> the law.” Moreover, Mat says in [2009fa:1175] “<strong>The</strong> illusion Marx is referring<br />

to is that laws are created by all <strong>of</strong> us in society.” Now, I agree with part <strong>of</strong> this statement,<br />

however, like Matt says, “this is no illusion, we all know that it is not we who make the<br />

laws.” I agree with Matt and have never actually made or created a law, but I may have had<br />

influence in my role in society.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> remark to Mat’s [2009fa:1175] did not come from me but from class participant Matt. Matt commenting<br />

on Mat.<br />

Message [1036] referenced by [1057]. Next Message by Guh is [1037].<br />

[1047] AM: Illusions Illusions. I like, Shannon [2007SP:1212], went searching for information<br />

that would help me define “juridical illusion”. I found an interesting quote from<br />

Marx in Grundrisse, MEGA I/5 p. 308:<br />

“Just as the bodily weight <strong>of</strong> individuals does not depend upon their ideal<br />

will or caprice, so it does not depend on them whether they embody their<br />

will in the law”.<br />

I think this applies to the discussion <strong>of</strong> “judicial review” because it acknowledges that<br />

an individual does not have to embody their ideal. That is to say that someone in the ruling<br />

class may put on like he has society’s best interest at heart when trying to pass laws when he<br />

only has the interest <strong>of</strong> a select few at heart. Laws appear to be fair on the surface but there<br />

are underlying problems that the public does not see.<br />

Obama Care I guess could be a good current example <strong>of</strong> this. Many people believe that<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s like this go into immediate effect once law are passed, when in fact it takes time<br />

for the effects to trickle down to those who truly need the assistance. Also, many people<br />

are aware <strong>of</strong> what types <strong>of</strong> procedures and medications are covered by the new health care<br />

system. I can’t blame those who take what the media and politicians tell us at face value. It<br />

is hard not to listen to them because we hope that as elected <strong>of</strong>ficials and people with access<br />

to accurate information they will only share the truth because they have the public’s best<br />

interest at heart.<br />

Next Message by AM is [1055].<br />

[1048] Kobe: Definition. <strong>The</strong> illusion Marx talks <strong>of</strong> is that each individual in our society<br />

help in creating the laws. This is an illusion because as in today’s society the rich, high<br />

class, wealthy and politically high powered create the laws. <strong>The</strong> middle and lower class<br />

people believe that they have a say in a particular law that is or is not made, which is untrue.<br />

This is true <strong>of</strong> a capitalist society that the rich capitalists use their power and wealth to make<br />

and control laws that better themselves as opposed to the society as a whole.<br />

In today’s world we see this being done in large corporations that make their employees<br />

feel like they are a part <strong>of</strong> the team. Laborers take less money in wages because they feel like<br />

they are helping contribute to a higher cause, while CEOs are making millions <strong>of</strong> dollars.<br />

This is an illusion that is created by the capitalists to better themselves and keep the laborers<br />

happy with their wages and involvement in a particular company or industry. This is a<br />

product <strong>of</strong> the laws created by the upper class.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 455<br />

Hans: As you indicate in your very last sentence, the legal system is more than a smokescreen to appease the<br />

masses. It plays a role as a foundation.<br />

Message [1048] referenced by [2012fa:1518]. Next Message by Kobe is [1180].<br />

[1051] Fisher: juridical illusion. Juridical illusion is when people in the middle and<br />

lower classes <strong>of</strong> society think they are participating in law making but are not. Although<br />

they pay taxes and are members <strong>of</strong> a social class they are at the mercy <strong>of</strong> the rich capitalists<br />

and higher class members <strong>of</strong> society. <strong>The</strong> high class capitalists and politicians tend to control<br />

law making and even shape it to their own benefit. AM had a nice take saying “That is to say<br />

that someone in the ruling class may put on like he has society’s best interest at heart when<br />

trying to pass laws when he only has the interest <strong>of</strong> a select few at heart.” I agree. Also, I<br />

think Wall Street is a good example <strong>of</strong> this, although we are all taxpaying members <strong>of</strong> this<br />

society, it is wall street that runs this country. This will never change because capitalism<br />

depends on their success. Kobe was right on as well. Our employers may pretend to like us,<br />

but its their own self interests that they really like.<br />

Hans: You are just uncritically repeating. Your only addition is Wall Street, but I don’t see how your assertion that<br />

“Wall Street runs this country” throws light on the juridical illusion.<br />

Next Message by Fisher is [1099].<br />

[1057] Kaush: Juridical illusion. I thought to add and build on Guh’s [1036] explanation<br />

<strong>of</strong> juridical illusion and to give a direct continuous answer. Juridical illusion is viewing the<br />

social and political institutions <strong>of</strong> capitalism—wages, pr<strong>of</strong>its, etc.—as institutions naturally<br />

created and conforms to natural laws. To Marx, capitalists and laborers have equal footing<br />

from a legal perspective when they meet on the market. To him also, nature does not produce<br />

owners <strong>of</strong> money and commodities on one side and workers who possess no<strong>thing</strong> but labor<br />

power to sell. For Marx this line <strong>of</strong> thinking is fallacious because it assumes those social<br />

institutions are naturally ordained. Marx argues that people have the tendency to mistakenly<br />

reverse order <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s. Marx stresses that what is illusory about juridical thinking is that it<br />

regards society as the product <strong>of</strong> rules and laws instead <strong>of</strong> considering those rules and laws<br />

as social products serving capitalists.<br />

Hans: Thank you for putting the discussion on the right track again. <strong>The</strong> issue is not whether people make the<br />

laws, but the issue is: do laws create the social relations <strong>of</strong> production, or do social relations <strong>of</strong> production create<br />

their own systems <strong>of</strong> justice which are then codified in laws?<br />

Next Message by Kaush is [1094].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 851 is 327 in 1997WI, 395 in 1997sp, 392 in 1997ut, 589 in 2002fa, 613 in<br />

2003fa, 672 in 2004fa, 619 in 2005fa, 744 in 2007SP, 715 in 2007fa, 749 in 2008fa, 782<br />

in 2009fa, and 914 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 851 Why is it more beneficial for capital to keep the working class in a state <strong>of</strong><br />

“easy and liberal dependence” than to exert the maximum <strong>of</strong> surplus-value from them?<br />

[1035] Trap: Workers in a constant state <strong>of</strong> dependence. <strong>The</strong> most important role<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalist is to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it, generally at the exploitation <strong>of</strong> his workers. Keeping<br />

the “working class in a state <strong>of</strong> ‘easy and liberal dependence’” is an important tool for the<br />

capitalist. If the capitalist exerted the maximum surplus value from his laborers, it would<br />

reduce the productivity <strong>of</strong> the worker, both in the short and the long run. If a worker works<br />

at a factory that has two 12 hour shifts, and the worker works one <strong>of</strong> the shifts every day, he<br />

will have little time for any<strong>thing</strong> else. He will become angry and more importantly to the<br />

456 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

capitalist he won’t have time and may not have the resources necessary to raise his family,<br />

the next generation <strong>of</strong> laborers. In the long run, the worker will have built up animosity<br />

towards his capitalist boss, and create problems and may even quit, making the capitalist’s<br />

job more difficult. <strong>The</strong>refore it is important to keep the workers in a state <strong>of</strong> “easy and liberal<br />

dependence,” they may not love their job or particularly care about what they do, but they<br />

will continue to work, and the capitalists will continue to exploit them and make pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Hans: If the workers quit, this does not worry the capitalists. <strong>The</strong> system makes sure that they can always find<br />

enough workers. <strong>The</strong> <strong>thing</strong> which scares the capitalists is if the workers organize, as Intaglio says in [1073].<br />

Message [1035] referenced by [2012fa:1531]. Next Message by Trap is [1080].<br />

[1038] She: graded A+ Knowledge Enlarges and Multiplies our Desires. It is more<br />

beneficial for the capitalist to keep the working class in a state <strong>of</strong> “easy and liberal dependence”<br />

than to exert the maximum <strong>of</strong> surplus-value from them because as Megan says in<br />

[2009fa:1176] laborers do not live to only labor. <strong>The</strong>y have families and emotions, needs,<br />

wants, and dreams. <strong>The</strong>y cannot be forced to work only until they are burnt out entirely, they<br />

will not be satisfied. Unhappy workers are unproductive workers. Marx 764:1/oe quotes<br />

Bernard de Mandeville as saying, “Those that get their living by their daily labor. . . have<br />

no<strong>thing</strong> to stir them up to be serviceable but their wants which it is prudence to relieve, but<br />

only folly to cure.” What he is saying is that if you provide every<strong>thing</strong> that a worker wants,<br />

he will have no reason to continue working. Mandeville goes on to say that only moderate<br />

compensation will keep the worker productive and that, as Megan said, too little will break<br />

his spirits. He argues that keeping them ignorant to their situations will never create the desire<br />

for change. <strong>The</strong> direct Mendeville quote reads, “To make the society happy and people<br />

easier under the meanest circumstances, it is requisite that great numbers <strong>of</strong> them be ignorant<br />

as well as poor; knowledge both enlarges and multiplies our desires, and the fewer <strong>thing</strong>s<br />

a man wishes for, the more easily his necessities may be supplied.” <strong>The</strong> cheaper a worker’s<br />

necessities are, the cheaper it is for the capitalist to pay to reproduce the labor-power the<br />

worker sells. Melanie in [2007fa:662] reminds us that easy and liberal dependence is yet<br />

another method the capitalist uses to keep the exploitation <strong>of</strong> his workers secret and hidden<br />

from plain view. It is just another pillar <strong>of</strong> deception. <strong>The</strong> greatest return for capitalists<br />

from an ignorant society, is that the ignorant workers willingly reproduce and create a fully<br />

stocked army <strong>of</strong> ignorant workers ready to supply to capitalists in the next generation.<br />

So in the end, acting to not maximize surplus value actually does maximize surplus value.<br />

This is a prime example <strong>of</strong> how the neoclassical model <strong>of</strong> creating maximum value does not<br />

hold true because <strong>of</strong> the assumptions that are impossible to really occur. It is examples<br />

like this, and real life stories and situations, that are creating a need for more research in<br />

behavioral economics.<br />

Hans: You are right. Working class parents teach their children not only the required discipline and skills to keep a<br />

job, but (at least at this historical conjuncture) they also try to teach them to be content with the crumbs the system<br />

has for them and not to be rebellious.<br />

Next Message by She is [1175].<br />

[1073] Intaglio: Bling Bling. <strong>The</strong> “easy and liberally dependent” worker is a complacent<br />

one. If the workers enjoy a decent standard <strong>of</strong> living they will be completely apathetic<br />

towards the system. <strong>The</strong>y won’t organize unions or even start to think about how they could<br />

be receiving the full fruits <strong>of</strong> their labor. Furthermore, capitalist marketing can get workers<br />

to identify consuming commodities that do not improve their standard <strong>of</strong> living with “living


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 457<br />

the life.” This is a good way for capitalists to get the extra ‘complacency’ money they give<br />

to the worker back into their pockets. If workers didn’t have the extra money to afford<br />

MP3 player headphones to plug their ears, SUVs with blingin’ rims, videogames to play,<br />

snowboards to ride, and other distractions they would definitely think about the system more<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten.<br />

Keeping the workers from organizing against the capitalist system is the most important<br />

part <strong>of</strong> staying in control <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production and maintaining class society as a<br />

whole. This is why corporations are funding reactionary pro-private pr<strong>of</strong>it movements like<br />

the tea party. This is why revolutions were so popular in the 1800s, because goods were<br />

scarce, the standard <strong>of</strong> living was low, and people got angry enough to think <strong>of</strong> ways to<br />

improve their situation. It’s too bad Americans are usurping the unseen cheap labour <strong>of</strong><br />

those exploited in the third world, there would have been a revolution by now if they had to<br />

do it themselves.<br />

Message [1073] referenced by [1035], [1097], and [2012fa:1520]. Next Message by Intaglio is [1181].<br />

[1097] IrvingHowe: liberalism and puppy treats. In adding to what Intaglio [1073] said<br />

on the matter:<br />

<strong>The</strong> answer is really quite simple. As a student <strong>of</strong> econ, I see nearly every selection that<br />

anyone makes as a thoughtful choice between the selection made and other alternatives. In<br />

making this choice, theoretically, an individual has most likely conducted some<strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong> a<br />

risk/benefit analysis whether they are conscious <strong>of</strong> it happening or not. This is not to say<br />

that I believe that the world is full <strong>of</strong> 6 billion rational people or that perfect information<br />

conditions are even in existence anywhere. I only mean to say that given a set <strong>of</strong> choices and<br />

the information at hand, people are constantly weighing one option against the other.<br />

In choosing not to occupy workplaces, challenge the system <strong>of</strong> government and fire their<br />

bosses, the majority <strong>of</strong> workers have made the choice that what they stand to lose is greater<br />

than what they think they can get. This is no accident.<br />

Franklin Roosevelt, who is seemingly viewed by so many Democrats as a nearly (Japanese<br />

internment camps) flawless liberal was actually forced to run and govern much farther<br />

to the left than he intended due in large part to pressure from the left <strong>of</strong> him. Huey Long <strong>of</strong><br />

Louisiana wrote a book and ran on the slogan <strong>of</strong> “Every Man a King” and Socialist Norman<br />

Thomas won over a million votes for president in the middle <strong>of</strong> the depression. For FDR,<br />

governing as he did was a matter <strong>of</strong> survival, for capitalism and his own job.<br />

If we’re willing to look back just a bit further to what was the catalyst for so much <strong>of</strong> the<br />

pre and post-depression era liberalism, we can look at Russia. Here we had a family, the<br />

Romanov family, who had ruled as an absolute monarchy for over 400 years. <strong>The</strong>y were the<br />

last absolute monarchy in Europe and even had the Russian Orthodox Church backing up the<br />

claims <strong>of</strong> their own divine right to rule. But, the peasants and industrial workers had no<strong>thing</strong>.<br />

For a reference on how bad <strong>thing</strong>s were, remember that these situations were the types <strong>of</strong><br />

conditions that gave birth to much <strong>of</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> Marx and Engels. Russian historian James<br />

Heinzen, in commenting on the prevailing conditions for the people <strong>of</strong> Russia around 1917<br />

once said “It’s pretty hard to imagine that any<strong>thing</strong> other than a right-wing dictatorship, a<br />

military dictatorship, or a left-wing dictatorship could have emerged.”<br />

458 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

This simple notion, that the masses will put up with any<strong>thing</strong> until they’ve had enough<br />

has been parroted in a more pretentious manner for a century now. It has come from Republicans<br />

and Democrats, Tories and Liberals since 1917. In fact, not 4 months ago, President<br />

Clinton’s former Secretary <strong>of</strong> Labor recently publicly acknowledged that “It could very well<br />

happen” when asked if inequality continues to get worse whether or not people would revolt<br />

and begin taking from the rich.<br />

James Gross, a pr<strong>of</strong>essor at the Cornell school <strong>of</strong> Industrial and Labor Relations recently<br />

put it best when he told me “human resources, employee perks and this new emphasis on<br />

workplace partnerships are no<strong>thing</strong> more than the boss showing you that he thinks no<strong>thing</strong><br />

more <strong>of</strong> you than he does his dog. All he thinks he has to do is pat you on the back, rub your<br />

tummy and throw you a treat and he can get you to do any<strong>thing</strong> but more importantly, you<br />

won’t go shoving that damn union down his throat... It’s a disgrace.”<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [1133].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 853 is 398 in 1997sp, 395 in 1997ut, 675 in 2004fa, 621 in 2005fa, 746 in<br />

2007SP, 717 in 2007fa, 746 in 2008SP, 751 in 2008fa, 784 in 2009fa, 882 in 2011fa, and<br />

916 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 853 What does Marx use the metaphor <strong>of</strong> a golden chain for? Why does he say<br />

the chain has become heavier?<br />

[1039] Hal: graded A– This is one chain not worth its weight in gold. Marx uses the<br />

golden chain as a metaphor for the enslavement <strong>of</strong> the working class. Each day, producers<br />

are required to provide free labor to their capitalist employers. Producers do not wish to<br />

perform unpaid labor, yet they must in order to survive. <strong>The</strong> chain being golden, rather than<br />

iron, corresponds to the capitalists’ need to pay producers enough to buy commodities and<br />

keep the market running smoothly.<br />

As time goes on, capitalists accumulate wealth faster than the working class. Capitalists<br />

then use that wealth to take ownership <strong>of</strong> more means <strong>of</strong> production, which makes the<br />

working class even more dependent on their employers. Also, capitalists use their wealth<br />

to grow their companies and eliminate competitors, making it harder each year for someone<br />

from the working class to accumulate capital. Capitalists, with their increased power, are<br />

able to demand more free labor from the working class. <strong>The</strong> golden chain becomes heavier.<br />

In other words, the domination <strong>of</strong> the working class becomes more absolute.<br />

Hans: Oreo [1045] explains better what Marx means with “heavier.”<br />

Message [1039] referenced by [1045] and [1046]. Next Message by Hal is [1058].<br />

[1045] Oreo: Golden Chains. For my free discussion contribution, I would like to add<br />

to the submission by Hal [1039]. I agree that Marx uses the golden chain metaphor to<br />

illustrate the fact that laborers are similar to slaves for capitalists. However, laborers are<br />

not completely synonymous to slaves, seeing as they have the freedom to break free from<br />

the chains if they so desire. Marx states, “..which the wage-laborer has already forged for<br />

himself. . . ”, meaning the worker was not forced such as a slave would be, but has willingly<br />

accepted these golden chains. I believe these chains are golden because gold is the generally<br />

accepted commodity <strong>of</strong> exchange. <strong>The</strong> worker willingly subjects himself to gold in order to<br />

provide himself with commodities.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 459<br />

This chain is loosened when the capitalist provides the worker with a higher wage. More<br />

gold is added to the chain, causing it to become longer and providing the laborer more<br />

comfort and ability to move. However, the longer the chain, the heavier it becomes. <strong>The</strong><br />

laborer becomes more weighed down with chains and consequently has less hope to escape.<br />

With the wage increase, the laborer is even more imprisoned to the capitalist than he was<br />

previously. Since the laborer is making more money, he is less likely to try and break free<br />

from the chains. As Hans states in [2009fa], the increase in wage is proportional to the<br />

laborer’s dependence on the capitalist. As long as laborers continue to make money and<br />

accept their subordination to capitalism, they will never break free from the gold chains that<br />

they confined themselves in.<br />

Hans: Very good. But I never found the reference which you call [2009fa].<br />

Message [1045] referenced by [1039]. Next Message by Oreo is [1049].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 854 is 331 in 1997WI, 399 in 1997sp, 396 in 1997ut, 593 in 2002fa, 617 in<br />

2003fa, 676 in 2004fa, 622 in 2005fa, 718 in 2007fa, 785 in 2009fa, 883 in 2011fa, and<br />

917 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 854 Does it make sense for the working class to fight for higher wages if the<br />

capitalist, for economic reasons, usually maintains the upper hand in such conflicts?<br />

[1029] Balrog: graded A Fight Back or be Abused? In 1997 185,000 UPS employees<br />

went on strike after fighting for better wages and benefits for some time. This strike which<br />

lasted 15 days cost the UPS company an estimated $650 million dollars. <strong>The</strong> result was<br />

that UPS agreed to make 10,000 part time employees full time employees and overall wages<br />

increased by 40%. As references and for more information I have provided links to the<br />

following two websites.<br />

http://www.pbs.org/newshour/bb/business/july-dec97/ups 8-19a.html<br />

http://www.nathannewman.org/other/why ups strike matters.html<br />

This example clearly shows that fighting for higher wages does make sense. <strong>The</strong> capitalist<br />

is in control <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production and can manipulate his production process. His goal<br />

is to achieve the highest rate <strong>of</strong> return possible and in order to do so will cut corners and<br />

exploit his workers until they fight back.<br />

<strong>The</strong> working class must be careful in how they go about seeking higher wages. If one<br />

worker goes on strike by himself, a capitalist can bear to lose that worker and may fire him or<br />

her. In the case <strong>of</strong> UPS a union containing 185,000 people worked together and due to their<br />

numbers and organization were successful. Examples like this give hope to other workers<br />

and help them have the courage to unite and fight for better treatment.<br />

Message [1029] referenced by [2012fa:1507]. First Message by Balrog is [188].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 855 is 332 in 1997WI, 405 in 1998WI, 429 in 1999SP, 524 in 2000fa, 554 in<br />

2001fa, 594 in 2002fa, 618 in 2003fa, 677 in 2004fa, 748 in 2008SP, 786 in 2009fa, and<br />

884 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 855 Does the dependence <strong>of</strong> the workers on capital decrease when wages are<br />

high?<br />

460 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1049] Oreo: graded A Dependence on Capital. <strong>The</strong> dependence <strong>of</strong> the workers on<br />

capital, in most cases, does not decrease when wages are high. In fact, it’s just the opposite.<br />

This is apparent when you put yourself in this position. If you are working for a company,<br />

and the company increases your wage, wouldn’t you be less likely to quit your job? Your<br />

dependence on capital, therefore, increases. <strong>The</strong> relationship between wage and dependence<br />

seems to be a positive and proportional one. When a laborer’s wage is increased, their<br />

dependence to capital is increased as well. On the other hand, increased wages may decrease<br />

one’s dependence on capital if the laborer uses his money to save up and eventually purchase<br />

his own capital. As Bone [2009fa:1171] writes, “the only way for the worker to become less<br />

dependent on capital is to purchase some capital <strong>of</strong> their own so that they can start producing<br />

and selling their own commodity.” <strong>The</strong>refore, if the higher wage leads to the purchase and<br />

accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital, then the dependence on capital would in fact decrease when wages<br />

rise. However, the majority <strong>of</strong> workers don’t become capitalists, meaning that the wage raise<br />

will most <strong>of</strong>ten increase dependence on capital. As Marx mentions earlier in the chapter,<br />

laborers are enslaved by the golden chain <strong>of</strong> capitalism. <strong>The</strong> wage raise would only loosen<br />

the chains causing the worker to be more comfortable, but the weight <strong>of</strong> the chains would<br />

increase, imprisoning the worker even more and causing him to be even more dependent on<br />

capital.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> capitalist system has built-in mechanisms preventing too many workers from becoming capitalists.<br />

Message [1049] referenced by [1089]. Next Message by Oreo is [1168].<br />

[1053] Alex: (graded A–) Dependence on capital. Dependence on capital from the workers<br />

does not decrease, instead, it creates more comfort for the worker. What happens is as<br />

the worker is being paid more than he/she is used to, therefore the worker has more money to<br />

buy the <strong>thing</strong>s that he needs, and could actually afford <strong>thing</strong>s that he was not able to before<br />

this raise. Capital will always be an independent variable, as Hans explained in [2003fa:645]<br />

that the system follows a constant pattern <strong>of</strong> alienation and exploitation, and since the workers<br />

do not see a way <strong>of</strong> changing the system, they do not use that extra comfort level to<br />

attempt to do so, and therefore leave it as the status quo. <strong>The</strong> dependency <strong>of</strong> the worker<br />

for money remains the same, it is simply that he/she is now able to buy more commodities<br />

and/or services due to the increase in comfort level, which is due to a slight increase in pay.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong>ir inactivity does not come from “not see(ing) a way <strong>of</strong> changing the system.” Since they have a stake<br />

in the system they are not even looking for ways to change the system, and they have some<strong>thing</strong> to lose if they try.<br />

I.e., the slight increase in wages makes them more dependent on the system.<br />

Final Grading Note by Hans: You are a hard and conscientious worker. <strong>The</strong> reason why you didn’t get all As is<br />

because Marx requires you to throw what you know overboard and think <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s in a different way. You refuse to<br />

do this more speculative thinking, you are always very down to earth and reasonable. This is an important function,<br />

you are the reality-checker. I’d like to have you on my team. But try to think more outside the box sometimes.<br />

Message [1053] referenced by [1089]. First Message by Alex is [4].<br />

[1089] Rmc: graded A– Dependence on capital. If workers want to keep the status quo,<br />

their dependence on capital increases when wages are high.<br />

Alex’s answer [1053] describes a result <strong>of</strong> increased wages. Oreo [1049] explains why<br />

workers are more dependent on capital when wages are high, and does so in great detail.<br />

I’ll try to answer the question more concisely. It is true that, as Alex says, when wages are<br />

high, workers are less likely to quit their jobs because they want to keep the higher income.<br />

I’d like to add that the demand for workers allows them some power because they can more


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 461<br />

easily obtain a higher price for their labor. More importantly, I think, once they have found<br />

employment they depend on a strong economy—and plenty <strong>of</strong> capital—in order to keep<br />

their jobs and maintain high wages. Low wages reflect a low demand for workers, usually a<br />

result <strong>of</strong> a poor economy and lack <strong>of</strong> capital. In this case it is not a question <strong>of</strong> quitting, but<br />

<strong>of</strong> being laid <strong>of</strong>f.<br />

Alex raises a good point about dependence decreasing if the worker has been saving to<br />

purchase his own capital, and dependence decreases only “if the higher wage leads to the<br />

purchase and accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital.”<br />

Hans: You are saying it is good for the workers when there is plenty <strong>of</strong> capital. But where does the capital come<br />

from? Marx would say it comes from the unpaid labor <strong>of</strong> the workers. I.e., it is good for the workers if their own<br />

exploitation is successful.<br />

Next Message by Rmc is [1161].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 859 is 430 in 1999SP, 525 in 2000fa, 752 in 2007SP, 757 in 2008fa, and 790 in<br />

2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 859 Recapitulate the concrete reasoning which leads Marx to the conclusion that<br />

the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital is the independent, and the wage rate the dependent variable.<br />

[1069] School: Attacking the Gazelle. Marx stated: “one <strong>of</strong> the main social functions <strong>of</strong><br />

the capitalist class is to determine the rate <strong>of</strong> accumulation.” Also in the annotations it says:<br />

“it is these absolute movements <strong>of</strong> the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital which manifest themselves<br />

as relative movements <strong>of</strong> the mass <strong>of</strong> exploitable labor-power, and therefore seem produced<br />

by the latter’s own independent movement.” Through these quotes we understand that Marx<br />

had come to the conclusion that the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital is the independent and the wage<br />

rate is the dependent variable. <strong>The</strong> reasoning for this is because the capitalist can wait for<br />

the opportune moment to invest. <strong>The</strong> capitalist can wait until the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital is<br />

at the perfect amount for investment, the mere ability to choose shows that it is independent.<br />

Whereas TKaufmann states in [2009fa:1148] “the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital may slow down,<br />

causing a decrease in the demand for labor. Laborers, however, are in the unfortunate position<br />

that they have to sell their labor power in order to survive. As the demand for labor<br />

slows down, unemployment increases and the wage rate will drop” This shows us that the<br />

rate wage rate is the dependent variable. It’s as if the capitalist are lions and the worker is<br />

the gazelle. <strong>The</strong> lion will wait for the right moment to attack when the gazelle is not paying<br />

attention. <strong>The</strong> capitalist waits for the right moments to attack the unsupecting workers.<br />

Message [1069] referenced by [1182]. Next Message by School is [1106].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 861 is 334 in 1997WI, 557 in 2001fa, 754 in 2008SP, and 792 in 2009fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 861 How does the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> capital discussed in the Accumulation<br />

chapter differ from that <strong>of</strong> the commodity discussed in chapter One?<br />

[1034] Babyceta: graded A Fetish-like Character: <strong>The</strong> Sequel. In [308], I assert that<br />

the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities “is a social structure in which the products <strong>of</strong> society<br />

are carriers <strong>of</strong> social relations resembling natural forces, and are capable <strong>of</strong> behaving<br />

in humanistic ways, or <strong>of</strong> transforming physical matter.” Hans clarified my position by<br />

adding in [326] that “[t]he fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity is the naturalization <strong>of</strong> society,<br />

meaning ‘social relations take the form <strong>of</strong> quasi-natural predicates <strong>of</strong> objects’.” Others,<br />

462 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

specifically Mhurst [2009fa:1130] and Mitternacht [2008SP:784], contend that commodities<br />

possess power by dividing classes <strong>of</strong> people through their “attachment to items.” I believe<br />

this view is overly simplistic and misguided. Marx would probably say that the commodities<br />

themselves do not possess power in the literal sense; they have power only because we (the<br />

naive masses <strong>of</strong> the working class born into an exploitative system we do not clearly see or<br />

understand) all buy into this notion that social relations can travel through <strong>thing</strong>s. We give<br />

the commodity super-human strength as if they were capable <strong>of</strong> performing feats beyond<br />

even the ability <strong>of</strong> individuals, and therefore it is much more than simple obsession; it is<br />

the humble acceptance that in some ways commodities are physically superior to us, and<br />

they deserve our respect and maybe even our obedience. What’s paramount here is that this<br />

fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities lives solely in our minds; we breathe life into the idea<br />

by our blind acceptance—a natural law, if you will—and there is no<strong>thing</strong> we can do about<br />

it. It is an implied force living in our psyche—<strong>of</strong>fspring <strong>of</strong> our collective conscience.<br />

Not so, with the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> capital. <strong>The</strong> power <strong>of</strong> capital in our society is<br />

indeed real, and exists not as an internal conception lacking transparency, but as external<br />

force that physically controls us. Capital must indeed grow and expand in order for capitalism<br />

to function, and it must do so whether we believe in it or not. This growth is not<br />

contingent upon collective consciousness or psyche; it is a natural mandate <strong>of</strong> the capitalist<br />

system that requires participation <strong>of</strong> all who must toil to exist. We cannot change or control<br />

the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> capital. <strong>The</strong> decision was made for us long before, and is kept<br />

alive, as Marx says in 771:1/o, “not by the product <strong>of</strong> [our] own brain, but by the product<br />

<strong>of</strong> [our] own hand.” It is not a mental fabrication that social forces are transmitted through<br />

objects. It is a forceful social transmission facilitated by fabricating objects.<br />

Hans: Marx would say that the fetish-like character if commodities is not a mental fabrication either but also a<br />

very material force, growing out <strong>of</strong> the organization <strong>of</strong> production in a commodity society.<br />

Next Message by Babyceta is [1054].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 863 is 559 in 2001fa, 727 in 2007fa, 756 in 2008SP, 761 in 2008fa, 794 in<br />

2009fa, and 896 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 863 What is the right answer to the question: “How has the worker” (and not only<br />

the worker but mankind as a whole) “been able to pass from being the master <strong>of</strong> capital—as<br />

its creator—to being its slave?”<br />

[1046] Jo: From Master to Slave. Jojo [2009fa:1143] brings up the point that the workers<br />

are not the only ones that have become slaves to the system, but that capitalists themselves<br />

are slaves as well. <strong>The</strong> necessity <strong>of</strong> capitalism is capital accumulation, and in order<br />

to keep that up, the capitalists remain trapped within the system. Jojo says, “this ‘selfishness’<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalist is inherent within the system. This coincides with Hans’ statement<br />

in [2008SP:832]: “How did this control [over social relations] slip away from us, so that<br />

commodities make social interactions for us and our means <strong>of</strong> productions are our masters<br />

rather than our tools? If 187:1 is a guide, Marx blames individualism and atomism for it<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> greed.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> worker, on the other hand, does not control the means <strong>of</strong> production and has no<strong>thing</strong><br />

to exchange but labor. Hal points out an idea in [1039] that I had not considered: “As time<br />

goes on, capitalists accumulate wealth faster than the working class. Capitalists then use


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 463<br />

that wealth to take ownership <strong>of</strong> more means <strong>of</strong> production, which makes the working class<br />

even more dependent on their employers.” <strong>The</strong> worker is dependent on the wage received<br />

from laboring. An increase in wage, or rise in the price <strong>of</strong> labor, “comes back to them in<br />

the shape <strong>of</strong> means <strong>of</strong> payment, so that they can extend the circle <strong>of</strong> their enjoyments, make<br />

additions to their consumption fund <strong>of</strong> clothes, furniture, etc., and lay by a small reserve<br />

fund <strong>of</strong> money” (Annotations, p. 670). This all sounds ok at <strong>first</strong>, but in the next section<br />

Marx reveals the harsh reality that “this rise in the price <strong>of</strong> labor. . . no more abolishes the<br />

exploitation and dependence <strong>of</strong> the wage laborer than to better clo<strong>thing</strong>, food and treatment,<br />

and a larger peculium, abolish that <strong>of</strong> the slave” (Annotations, p. 671). Increasing the wage<br />

doesn’t make the worker any less <strong>of</strong> a slave to his wage, or any less dependent on selling his<br />

labor for survival.<br />

Marx elaborates: “Wages, as we have seen, imply by their very nature that the worker<br />

must always provide a certain quantity <strong>of</strong> unpaid labor” (Annotations, p. 672). <strong>The</strong> worker<br />

will always provide a certain amount <strong>of</strong> free labor for the benefit <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. <strong>The</strong>re is<br />

a limit to how much a worker’s situation can improve within capitalism and it will never be<br />

sufficient to deliver the worker from capitalist rule.<br />

Hans notes the following on p. 677 <strong>of</strong> the Annotations: “That the standard <strong>of</strong> living <strong>of</strong> the<br />

laborers is subordinated to the needs <strong>of</strong> capital is an expression <strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital. ‘Fetish-like character’ no longer means, as in the case <strong>of</strong> commodities, that the<br />

social relations lack transparency because they go through <strong>thing</strong>s, but that these <strong>thing</strong>s now<br />

dominate the individuals.<br />

In summary, the capitalist and the workers are slaves <strong>of</strong> capitalism: the capitalist is dominated<br />

by an obsessive goal <strong>of</strong> making more pr<strong>of</strong>it; while the worker is dominated by the<br />

goal to maintain and improve his standard <strong>of</strong> living. <strong>The</strong> harmful effects <strong>of</strong> capitalism are<br />

hidden from view by the capitalists and workers’ intense fixation on their respective goals.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y will continue to pursue them even in the face <strong>of</strong> likely disaster, as we have seen in the<br />

case <strong>of</strong> climate change.<br />

Next Message by Jo is [1071].<br />

[1068] Atticus: graded A <strong>The</strong> Nasty Side Effect <strong>of</strong> Commodity Production. <strong>The</strong> production<br />

<strong>of</strong> goods for the purpose <strong>of</strong> being sold in market exchanges rather than for directly<br />

meeting personal subsistence needs must be present in a given society in order for a capitalistic<br />

economy to exist. Before capitalism, commodities were produced, owned and sold<br />

by their producers. In the early stages <strong>of</strong> commodity production laborers owned their own<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production and received the full value <strong>of</strong> the commodities they produced when<br />

exchanged in the market for equivalents. <strong>The</strong>y had to produce and sell enough <strong>of</strong> their own<br />

commodities to acquire a combination <strong>of</strong> qualitatively different commodities to reproduce<br />

their own labor-power and means <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong> early laborer was the “master <strong>of</strong> capital”.<br />

Increases in specialization led to even more increases in specialization, increases in productivity<br />

and deeper divisions in labor. This gradual change in the structure <strong>of</strong> production<br />

processes led to changes in social relations. <strong>The</strong> social relations generated by commodity<br />

production led to the implementation <strong>of</strong> private property laws conducive to the dynamics<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalism. Technological innovations led to exponential increases in productivity and<br />

464 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

concentrated the means <strong>of</strong> production into fewer and fewer hands. <strong>The</strong> interdependency <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity producing society created by increased specialization made it necessary for the<br />

majority <strong>of</strong> people who did not own the means <strong>of</strong> production to meet their basic subsistence<br />

needs by selling their labor-power as a commodity to the small class <strong>of</strong> people who did own<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production. This small class <strong>of</strong> people, the capitalists, kept this relationship<br />

intact by paying laborers only for their labor-power and not the actual value they produce.<br />

<strong>The</strong> true relationship <strong>of</strong> this dynamic was not immediately apparent to either capitalists or<br />

laborers due to the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> capital (annotations pp. 677) <strong>The</strong> laborer is now<br />

capital’s “slave”.<br />

Next Message by Atticus is [1167].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 866 is 435 in 1999SP, 530 in 2000fa, 561 in 2001fa, 603 in 2002fa, 627 in<br />

2003fa, 761 in 2007SP, 730 in 2007fa, 759 in 2008SP, 764 in 2008fa, 797 in 2009fa, 899<br />

in 2011fa, and 929 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 866 In 773:1, Marx discusses an empirical phenomenon in which technical progress<br />

“expresses” itself. Which phenomenon is that? Why does Marx speak here <strong>of</strong> an expression?<br />

[1171] Jo: Expression. <strong>The</strong> empirical phenomenon is the social degree <strong>of</strong> productivity<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor, or “the relative extent <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> productions that one worker, during a given<br />

time, with the same intensity <strong>of</strong> exertion <strong>of</strong> his or her labor-power, turns into products.” 773:1<br />

<strong>The</strong> word expression is used because technical progress is expressed through the fact that the<br />

worker is producing more products. Technical progress does not automatically equal more<br />

products being produced in an equal amount <strong>of</strong> time. But we can see based on the fact that<br />

the worker is using the same “intensity <strong>of</strong> exertion” to produce more products, that technical<br />

progress is an underlying factor in this equation. As Hans explains in his response to Corey<br />

in [2007fa:679], “A is an expression <strong>of</strong> B if A is a visible process whose occurrence indicates<br />

that the underlying process B, which can not be directly seen, is happening.” <strong>The</strong> visible<br />

process is the production <strong>of</strong> more products, while the invisible process being expressed is<br />

the technical progress.<br />

Hans: You are right, the underlying invisible process is technical progress. One <strong>of</strong> the possible expressions <strong>of</strong> technical<br />

progress is that more products can be produced with the same aggregate labor input; another expression might<br />

be that better products or new products become available. Marx is talking about yet another expression, namely,<br />

that the technical composition <strong>of</strong> the production process increases, i.e., more means <strong>of</strong> production (machines and/or<br />

materials) per laborer. You call this “social degree <strong>of</strong> productivity <strong>of</strong> labor.” This is not quite accurate. It is not this<br />

productivity itself, but it is an expression <strong>of</strong> this productivity. Look again what Marx says in 773:1.<br />

Message [1171] referenced by [2012fa:1555]. First Message by Jo is [475].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 869 is 414 in 1998WI, 438 in 1999SP, 533 in 2000fa, 564 in 2001fa, 606 in<br />

2002fa, 630 in 2003fa, 689 in 2004fa, 636 in 2005fa, 764 in 2007SP, 767 in 2008fa, 800<br />

in 2009fa, and 932 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 869 Why can the soil <strong>of</strong> commodity production carry production on a large-scale<br />

only in capitalist form, as Marx says in 775:1/o? (Also define better the “soil” which commodity<br />

production provides for the growth <strong>of</strong> large-scale production.)<br />

[1170] Trap: Workers are the soil. In [2002fa:392] Oregonian states that “<strong>The</strong> individuality<br />

and lack <strong>of</strong> co-operation <strong>of</strong> commodity production in a non-capitalist system makes<br />

large-scale commodity production practically impossible.” He is correct in saying this, but


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 465<br />

the keyword here is “practically.” Cooperation on a large scale is only possible through cooperation<br />

and by the workers pooling their means together to complete the task. So the<br />

question remains, if this is possible, why is it not practiced? <strong>The</strong> answer is that commodity<br />

production prevents cooperation. Commodity production focuses on the individual, not cooperation,<br />

it is based on competition. If workers work by themselves they <strong>of</strong>ten believe they<br />

will gain more than by combining with other workers to take over the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Marx talks about the “soil” <strong>of</strong> production. What he means is that the workers are the soil<br />

<strong>of</strong> production that provides for the growth <strong>of</strong> large-scale production, but that is not all he is<br />

referring to. He is also referring to the capitalist system that allows large-scale production<br />

to prosper. It is important to realize that the division <strong>of</strong> labor allows capitalists to remain<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>itable, the laborers have so little option and do the same <strong>thing</strong> repetitively for years, they<br />

don’t realize there are other options. If they do realize other options could be available if<br />

they combine and work together, they are too afraid to leave their dismal, but precious jobs.<br />

Hans: You had originally written “capitalism prevents cooperation. Capitalism focuses on the individual.” This<br />

orientation was already present in pre-capitalist commodity production. <strong>The</strong>refore I replaced “capitalism” with<br />

“commodity production.”<br />

First Message by Trap is [53].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 871 is 343 in 1997WI, 440 in 1999SP, 566 in 2001fa, 608 in 2002fa, 632 in<br />

2003fa, 691 in 2004fa, 638 in 2005fa, 766 in 2007SP, 802 in 2009fa, 904 in 2011fa, and<br />

934 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 871 Accumulation increases productive powers <strong>of</strong> labor and higher productive<br />

powers <strong>of</strong> labor increase accumulation. One might think that accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital and<br />

the productive powers <strong>of</strong> labor go together really well—or is there a hair in the soup, i.e.,<br />

are there ways in which technical progress also obstructs capital accumulation?<br />

[1153] Rico: <strong>The</strong> Hair in the Soup. Yes, there is a “hair in the soup.” Hans’ response<br />

to answer [2009fa:1219] explains that “higher productivity also means higher technical and<br />

higher organic composition <strong>of</strong> capital. <strong>The</strong>refore the rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its declines at the same time<br />

as the rate <strong>of</strong> surplus-value increases.” This is the “hair in the soup.”<br />

I believe there might be another explanation, which could be another “hair in the soup.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> exponentially increasing amount <strong>of</strong> technology will lead to a deterioration in the amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> human creativity and innovation used in the production process. Because increased<br />

amounts <strong>of</strong> capital and technology lead to less worker involvement, less innovation and<br />

creativity are incorporated into the the capitalist system. Capitalism is an unbalanced system<br />

and as such, it has the need to consistently innovate in order to continue sustaining its<br />

output. I understand that it is not self-sufficient and that it will collapse, but I would argue<br />

that it is through human adaptation and creativity that the system has been able to continue<br />

functioning well beyond the estimated collapse time that Marx predicted. If technology<br />

takes the place <strong>of</strong> human creativity, then the collapse <strong>of</strong> technology will also become a “hair<br />

in the soup.”<br />

Hans: I would not say the collapse <strong>of</strong> technology, but the alienation <strong>of</strong> technology from human needs. What we<br />

can do is almost unlimited; the question is whether we should be doing it. Nuclear power comes to mind to me as<br />

a technology which we would be better <strong>of</strong>f abandoning.<br />

First Message by Rico is [107].<br />

466 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 872 is 609 in 2002fa, 633 in 2003fa, 692 in 2004fa, 767 in 2007SP, 736 in<br />

2007fa, 770 in 2008fa, and 905 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 872 Describe the mechanisms <strong>of</strong> repulsion and attraction <strong>of</strong> individual capitals<br />

in the course <strong>of</strong> accumulation.<br />

[1099] Fisher: Mechanisms. <strong>The</strong> mechanisms <strong>of</strong> repulsion and attraction in the course<br />

<strong>of</strong> accumulation are: accumulation itself, concentration, and centralization proper. First<br />

accumulation is the “transition from handicrafts to capitalist industry”, which seems to me<br />

as the <strong>first</strong> step taken from a collection <strong>of</strong> personal items crafted by an individual alone<br />

for sale in the market. Handicrafts would not be made by employees who are paid by a<br />

capitalist. <strong>The</strong> social capital <strong>of</strong> society would grow at a slow rate within the idea <strong>of</strong> original<br />

accumulation. Second, concentration is when “existing individual capitalists invest their<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its into themselves”, causing all capital to grow at the same rate. This is more productive,<br />

yet there remains room for improvement. Last centralization proper indicates a large mass<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital “in a single hand in one place”, which was lost by others in another place. I<br />

guess this might be comparable to the stock market? Obviously large amounts <strong>of</strong> capital are<br />

exchanged, lost or obtained on Wall Street leaving the possibility <strong>of</strong> one hand holding the<br />

whole deck <strong>of</strong> cards.<br />

Hans: You are confusing accumulation with original accumulation.<br />

Message [1099] referenced by [1154]. Next Message by Fisher is [1100].<br />

[1154] Spiral: Mechanisms. Yes Fisher [1099], I think the stock market is an appropriate<br />

setting for explaining the point about “a large mass <strong>of</strong> capital in a single hand in one place.”<br />

More broadly I think the financial industry is full <strong>of</strong> examples because the majority <strong>of</strong> the<br />

sector seeks to maximize pr<strong>of</strong>it working through the mechanism <strong>of</strong> competition. <strong>The</strong> recent<br />

great recession was characterized by the market realizing that investment banks, the pillars<br />

<strong>of</strong> Wall Street, had reinvested their pr<strong>of</strong>its into their competitors. This web <strong>of</strong> risk diffusion,<br />

and hence exposure, accelerated the attraction <strong>of</strong> money concentrating into a couple dozen<br />

investments banks deemed too-big-to-fail. This is a misnomer for a network that was set up<br />

to bankrupt the system.<br />

Tigerwoulds provides a standard to judge the mechanism used in the process: [2008fa:1236]<br />

“When repulsion takes place in the course <strong>of</strong> accumulation, new firms are created by breaking<br />

<strong>of</strong>f or splitting up from larger firms.” <strong>The</strong> result <strong>of</strong> the great recession has not been the<br />

emergence <strong>of</strong> new firms but further concentration. For example, Merrill Lynch and Countrywide<br />

Financial were bought by Bank <strong>of</strong> America, Washington Mutual was acquired by<br />

JPMorgan Chase, Wells Fargo purchased Wachovia, to name a few. Once the closure <strong>of</strong><br />

hedge funds, private equity firms, and other banks are included it’s clear the financial system<br />

has been left more concentrated than before; recently repulsion has been a weak mechanism<br />

in the American economy. Politicians talk <strong>of</strong> helping to create new small businesses but the<br />

bailouts reinforced and centralized the old economic structure. Accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital is<br />

potentially limitless raising the specter <strong>of</strong> all powerful monopolies vertically integrating all<br />

steps in the national or global chain <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Next Message by Spiral is [1162].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 467<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 874 is 611 in 2002fa, 635 in 2003fa, 694 in 2004fa, 641 in 2005fa, 769 in<br />

2007SP, 738 in 2007fa, 767 in 2008SP, 772 in 2008fa, 805 in 2009fa, 907 in 2011fa, and<br />

937 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 874 How do competition and credit help in the process <strong>of</strong> centralization?<br />

[1115] Lindsey: Competition and Credit Are Catalysts for Centralization. Competition<br />

helps in the process <strong>of</strong> centralization because the most successful capitalists “expropriate”<br />

other capitalists and by this mechanism, their company grows and becomes more powerful<br />

and more productive and can continue to take over smaller companies more easily. Additionally,<br />

the minimum requirements for capital input to be able to compete become greater<br />

and small firms squeeze into certain sectors where there are no big firms they have to compete<br />

against until one or a couple <strong>of</strong> the small firms conquer the others in that sector too. In<br />

this way many small firms are transformed into a few large ones.<br />

Credit helps in the process <strong>of</strong> centralization by “drawing the disposable money scattered<br />

throughout society into the hands <strong>of</strong> individual or associated capitalists”. As Hans outlines,<br />

credit becomes a weapon in the competitive battles (those who have credit can attain more<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production and workers and thus become stronger competitors) and it pools investments<br />

from many sources without the reorganization <strong>of</strong> firms (firms can increase their<br />

financial power without even taking over another firm).<br />

First Message by Lindsey is [24].<br />

[1148] Smartergirl: Competition helps to centralize by putting small capitalists directly<br />

in a fight for market share and pr<strong>of</strong>its. By fighting for market share the small capitalist has<br />

to lower prices and squeeze production to its capacity which could potentially drop below<br />

their operation cost putting small capitalist out <strong>of</strong> business leaving the large capitalist to take<br />

their market share. We witnessed this in the lending industry nearly four years ago. As the<br />

competition to lend on mortgages got fiercer between small banks and lending institutions<br />

they lowered fees, rates, and closing costs. <strong>The</strong> smaller banks took an initial loss to secure<br />

the loan in the hopes <strong>of</strong> making up for the loss in the long run through interest paid to<br />

them. When the housing market bubble popped all the smaller lenders where left more<br />

vulnerable and without the number <strong>of</strong> payments coming in that they had planned for the<br />

lending institutions went bankrupt and were forced out <strong>of</strong> business. Someone had to service<br />

the loans so the larger banks there are now five I believe bought all the loans for pennies on<br />

the dollar and collect all the interest that the smaller bank that is now out <strong>of</strong> business had<br />

anticipated. <strong>The</strong> big capitalist ultimately benefits from the smaller capitalists fight. While<br />

the smaller capitalist in lending is nearly extinct. This hugely impacted centralization <strong>of</strong> the<br />

lending industry.<br />

Credit also assists in centralization. Marx saw it as a weapon to be used in competition<br />

and it allows centralization without reorganizing firms by gathering investments from many<br />

diffrent sources.<br />

A large retailer comes to mind and how credit is used as a weapon is simple. If a retailor<br />

is advertising a commodity and you want it but cant afford it you will most likely go to the<br />

retailer that will lend you credit to have instant gratification. For example back in the 50’s<br />

Sears Robuck and company became a major retailor partly because they <strong>of</strong>fered layaway.<br />

Esentially a form <strong>of</strong> credit. People began buying commodities that they could not afford<br />

468 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

but because they had the option to put it on hold they could make payments to the retailer<br />

over a longer period <strong>of</strong> time. This deceives the consumer because remember the reason for<br />

using lay away is because they can not afford the item now. <strong>The</strong> consumer still pays the<br />

same amount plus more for any fee and possible interest but because it is in smaller chunks<br />

<strong>of</strong> money or coin they do not feel the impact <strong>of</strong> the purchase the same way. <strong>The</strong>y are still<br />

spending more that they can aford but are tricked by credit to feel as though they can afford<br />

it. When credit cards, loans, and other forms <strong>of</strong> high interest credit come into the picture we<br />

are already used to spending more that we can afford and have an addiction to consumption.<br />

We now are at the mercy <strong>of</strong> paying what we cant afford and interest on what we already dont<br />

have. This results in working more and a vicious cycle <strong>of</strong> consuming, working to pay cfor<br />

the consumption, and taking more money from what we would have been able to hoard to the<br />

capitalist collecting the interest for him to hoard and slowly the average consumer sinks into<br />

debt and owes his life to the large capitalist who gave them credit to begin with. <strong>The</strong> more<br />

the average consumer has in debt the more centralized we become. <strong>The</strong> capitalist get larger<br />

and make money <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> our labor even though he may not be our employer. We now work<br />

for the capitalist whom employs us and the one that gave us credit. Everyday we lose more<br />

and more <strong>of</strong> our personal pr<strong>of</strong>it and the capitalist grow closer and closer to centralization.<br />

Hans: Speculative bubbles not only centralize but also destroy capital.<br />

Regarding your second paragraph, I changed “and gathering” into “by gathering.”<br />

Your example <strong>of</strong> consumer credit is good for recent forms <strong>of</strong> capitalism. Marx cannot have meant it because it<br />

did not exist at his time.<br />

Next Message by Smartergirl is [1150].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 875 is 773 in 2008fa and 938 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 875 How does Marx’s concept <strong>of</strong> competition differ from the neoclassical concept<br />

and from the “better mousetrap” ideology surrounding competition in modern US society?<br />

[1107] Orville: graded A Not-so-friendly Competition. In neo-classical economics, we<br />

are taught that competition is the engine <strong>of</strong> the economy. That everyone competing against<br />

each other is the best for us because we benefit with lower-priced, more reliable, better<br />

quality, higher technology goods. <strong>The</strong> idea is that with everyone competing against each<br />

other, people who supply the goods at the low price and better quality will push those who<br />

lag behind. That is what the “better mousetrap” idea is. Using a mousetrap as an example,<br />

if there is a large number <strong>of</strong> people who want to make the best mousetrap, this leads to the<br />

best mousetrap being made and sold at the cheapest price.<br />

In our term paper [699], my group wrote about chapter 13 which is entitled “Co-Operation.”<br />

Marx, in chapter 13, talks about the “animal spirits”, which is essentially our competitive<br />

nature as humans. He wrote that when people work together, there is a sense <strong>of</strong> competition<br />

even when they are working towards the same goal.<br />

In chapter 25, however, Marx seems to be highlighting the darker side <strong>of</strong> competition.<br />

With new advances, capital takes a larger chunk <strong>of</strong> the work away from the workers and<br />

therefore, fewer workers are needed. He also shows how the smaller capitalists are made to<br />

suffer because there are more to compete against and a higher likelihood that they fail. In<br />

777:2/o Marx remarks, “It always ends in the ruin <strong>of</strong> many small capitalists, whose capitals<br />

partly pass into the hands <strong>of</strong> their conquerers, and partly vanish completely.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 469<br />

<strong>The</strong> above is in sharp contrast to those neo-classists who would say that competition<br />

makes everyone better. Marx and Hans say that is it completely wrong. <strong>The</strong> small capitalists,<br />

as Hans pg. 692 writes, “are squeezed into murderous competition amongst themselves by<br />

the rising minimum size <strong>of</strong> capital.”<br />

Next Message by Orville is [1157].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 880 is 417 in 1997sp, 646 in 2005fa, 774 in 2007SP, 743 in 2007fa, 778 in<br />

2008fa, 913 in 2011fa, and 943 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 880 Does the surplus-population arise from capital’s inability to keep pace with<br />

the growth <strong>of</strong> the population?<br />

[1140] Tyler: Surplus-population. Surplus-population does not arise from capital’s inability<br />

to keep pace with the growth <strong>of</strong> the population. Parmenio references Hans’ four main<br />

reasons for the rise in surplus-population as follows [2005fa:1867]:<br />

1. An increase in centralization leads to an increase in the scale <strong>of</strong> production and technical<br />

progress. This can occur even if capital does not experience growth.<br />

2. Technical innovation in new capital will force the old capital to introduce the new<br />

technology.<br />

3. Organic composition increases in more industries.<br />

4. Intermediate pauses become shorter.<br />

Essentially, as Parmenio puts it, with increased technology less direct-labor is required to<br />

produce a given product. This is the cause <strong>of</strong> surplus-population.<br />

First Message by Tyler is [65].<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 884 is 450 in 1999SP, 576 in 2001fa, 621 in 2002fa, 645 in 2003fa, 704<br />

in 2004fa, 815 in 2009fa, 917 in 2011fa, and 947 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong> 884 Why is the surplus-population created under capitalism called “relative”?<br />

[1106] School: Army <strong>of</strong> Workers. <strong>The</strong> surplus-population created under capitalism<br />

called “relative” because <strong>of</strong> surplus. As Hans states in [2004fa:629] “Marx does not want<br />

to imply by the word “surplus” that there are too many people in the world. <strong>The</strong>se people<br />

only constitute a surplus relative to the hiring needs <strong>of</strong> capital – although this Surplus is on<br />

the other hand very useful for the accumulation needs <strong>of</strong> capital.” <strong>The</strong> needs for Capitalist<br />

to create surplus is key for their gains. By having large amounts <strong>of</strong> surplus workers the<br />

capitalist can select and choose from an army <strong>of</strong> unemployed workers. If they didn’t have<br />

this surplus <strong>of</strong> workers and the workers had the market power then a strike or death <strong>of</strong> even<br />

one worker would be detrimental to the capitalist. To avoid that the capitalist take away<br />

that power from the worker. That is what makes it relative, due to the amount <strong>of</strong> capital<br />

that is transferred and brought back to the means <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong> fluctuation <strong>of</strong> capital<br />

accumulation is what determines the amount <strong>of</strong> surplus-population.<br />

Hans: At the very end you had “amount <strong>of</strong> surplus value in the population.” Even with my correction, your last<br />

sentence is not entirely correct.<br />

First Message by School is [193].<br />

470 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 886 is 623 in 2002fa, 647 in 2003fa, 706 in 2004fa, 652 in 2005fa, 780 in<br />

2007SP, 749 in 2007fa, 779 in 2008SP, 784 in 2008fa, and 949 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 886 Which violent means did capital use in its infancy to sweep away the bounds<br />

imposed on its accumulation by the natural limits <strong>of</strong> the exploitable working population?<br />

[1143] Ferox: graded A Violent means <strong>of</strong> capitalist accumulation. As burgeoning capitalists<br />

did not initially have a reserve army <strong>of</strong> laborers, violent means under the guise <strong>of</strong><br />

state policy were used. <strong>The</strong>se mechanisms took the form <strong>of</strong> forceful resource extraction,<br />

conquest, enslavement, genocide, etc. This is complemented by social violence furthering<br />

capitalist interests in the form <strong>of</strong> establishing private property, taxation, and the division<br />

<strong>of</strong> society into stratified classes. Marx says in Chapter 26 that there must be at least two<br />

polarized classes; those with the means <strong>of</strong> production, money, and means <strong>of</strong> subsistence<br />

(capitalists); and free laborers — who must be isolated from their own means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

and will sell the only commodity possessed, labor power. This polarization <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

market gives the primordial conditions for capitalist production. A process that clears<br />

the way for the capitalist system inherently needs to separate the laborer through means <strong>of</strong><br />

violence from the possession <strong>of</strong> their own means <strong>of</strong> production. Marx termed this initial gain<br />

by coercion or force ‘primitive accumulation’ in Chapter 26. In Chapter 27 Marx examines<br />

the development <strong>of</strong> England’s primitive accumulation through the expulsion <strong>of</strong> the populace<br />

from the lands and the rise <strong>of</strong> the industrial city center - a case study <strong>of</strong> the violent means by<br />

which capitalists usurp resources and wealth, driving men to sell their labor power.<br />

Message [1143] referenced by [1166]. Next Message by Ferox is [1165].<br />

[1166] Spiral: Violent means <strong>of</strong> capitalist accumulation. In the proto-capitalist epoch, a<br />

majority <strong>of</strong> producers controlled access to their means <strong>of</strong> production. Over time, some saved<br />

and accumulated wealth, while others exchanged and spent their wealth. <strong>The</strong> inequality may<br />

have been negligible but extrapolated over decades or centuries a marked division begins to<br />

emerge. Eventually society internalized a new “sacred duty” in the form <strong>of</strong> protecting private<br />

property rights. Continued enforcement <strong>of</strong> this new social norm began the separation <strong>of</strong><br />

people into capitalists and the working class. One explanation for this difference in behavior<br />

is the concept <strong>of</strong> time preference: how much value an individual places on enjoyment right<br />

now versus delayed enjoyment. Also called delayed gratification in psychology. It’s hard to<br />

operationalize this concept into a measurable variable but behavioral psychology does have<br />

a famous test for time preference.<br />

<strong>The</strong> marshmallow test involves a young child typically 3-5 years <strong>of</strong> age left alone in a<br />

room with one marshmallow. If the child is able to wait until the researcher returns a second<br />

marshmallow will be given as their reward, otherwise the child only gets the <strong>first</strong> marshmallow<br />

they ate too early. Tracking these same children through their secondary education<br />

researchers found that children able to restrain themselves to not eat the <strong>first</strong> marshmallow<br />

had statistically significant higher grades. <strong>The</strong>re appears to be a connection between time<br />

preference and success in American capitalist society at least in an academic sense. Researchers<br />

have to wait until their subjects age through higher education and eventually join<br />

the national workforce before broader correlations (or causation) can be assessed. A link to<br />

the original study is here:<br />

http://duende.uoregon.edu/hsu/blogfiles/Shoda,Mischel,&Peake(1990).pdf


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 471<br />

More recent data does suggest high salaries and more stable family lives for those children<br />

with greater self-control. Updated article from the New Yorker with recent analysis here:<br />

http://www.newyorker.com/reporting/2009/05/18/090518fa fact lehrer<br />

Savers vs. spenders i.e. time preference is an historical and logical argument but as a passive<br />

force it fails to explain the vast inequality <strong>of</strong> industrial society. New violent tools were<br />

necessary to move from primitive accumulation to modern industrial levels. Wren succinctly<br />

states this problem in [2008fa:1273] “Capitalism in its infancy did not have a large industrial<br />

reserve army in which it could use as leverage to maintain accumulation and growth.” Continued<br />

accumulation and movement <strong>of</strong> capital is necessary to keep a capitalist system stable<br />

so early capitalists were under pressure to expand their pool <strong>of</strong> available labour. Ferox<br />

[1143] mentions coercive taxation, colonialism, and various deadly forms <strong>of</strong> conquest to<br />

which I would like to add the creation <strong>of</strong> a legal system that recognizes the legitimate use<br />

<strong>of</strong> force by an individual only in situations <strong>of</strong> self-defense. Governmental jurisdictions have<br />

developed a monopoly on the use <strong>of</strong> force manifested as the various branches <strong>of</strong> the military<br />

plus intelligence agencies at the federal level and police departments at the state level. Capitalists<br />

created a multitude <strong>of</strong> institutions to constrain worker’s opportunities forcing them to<br />

sell their labour-power in order to survive.<br />

Hans: This is a rehash <strong>of</strong> term paper [1092]. It has little to do with Marx’s theories.<br />

First Message by Spiral is [10].<br />

887 is 887 in 2008fa, 887 in 2009fa, and 887 in 2012fa:<br />

887 Notes about Event outside Class<br />

[637] Hans: Ethics <strong>of</strong> Climate Change. I, Pr<strong>of</strong>. Hans G. Ehrbar, will facilitate a discussion<br />

about the Ethics <strong>of</strong> Climate Justice tomorrow evening, Friday Oct 29, 7-9pm in the<br />

First Unitarian Church in SLC. Address:<br />

569 S 1300 E, Salt Lake City, UT<br />

This is very close to the Stadium Trax station. You can get a map by googling “First<br />

Unitarian Church SLC.” <strong>The</strong> discussion will be in “the Haven”, a meeting room upstairs.<br />

We will use the book <strong>The</strong> Ethics <strong>of</strong> Climate Change by James Garvey, see<br />

http://www.amazon.com/Ethics-Climate-Change-Right-Warming/dp/0826497373/<br />

but the discussion will be more about the topic itself than the book, therefore you should<br />

come even if you haven’t read the book. This discussion is in preparation <strong>of</strong> the trial <strong>of</strong> Tim<br />

DeChristopher, see<br />

http://www.climatetrial.com<br />

Tim’s trial is presently scheduled for Dec 13. It will be big; the world will look at Salt<br />

Lake City. If you want to get involved in the preparations for this event, tomorrow would be a<br />

good opportunity to meet the relevant people. If you attend, you will also get 1 participation<br />

point just as for the class attendances. And if you want to send your notes about it to the<br />

class, use question number 997.<br />

Please forward this email to your friends (this is why I put my full name at the top).<br />

472 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans<br />

Next Message by Hans is [640].<br />

888 is 0 in 2005fa, 0 in 2007SP, 888 in 2007fa, 888 in 2008SP, 888 in 2008fa, 888 in<br />

2009fa, 888 in 2011fa, and 888 in 2012fa:<br />

888 Free Discussion<br />

[21] Zarathustra: Since I was super busy with all sort <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s this week, I decided to<br />

study the Annotation and Marx’s Capital this weekend to catch up with the class. I took a<br />

look at both, flipped them, read the introductions and conclusions, ... to get a feeling <strong>of</strong> how<br />

to read them. I mean when I grab a novel to read, I know how the form, genre, plot and style<br />

are. <strong>The</strong> way I read a novel is different from the way that I read newspapers.<br />

That would be great if someone could tell me how I should study Marx’s Capital (and<br />

Hans’ Annotation)? Marx’s writings are very dissimilar to other econ text-books that I have<br />

read in college. What are the form, style, genre, plot, etc.? Simply, how should I study it?<br />

Next Message by Zarathustra is [46].<br />

[168] Guh: Next Business Cycle. For my free discussion I am going to talk about the<br />

factors that were behind the run up <strong>of</strong> the housing bubble, both on the demand side as well<br />

as the supply side. When looking at this <strong>first</strong> we examine the stock market boom <strong>of</strong> the<br />

1990’s, we had a rise in the information systems and online websites being created, which<br />

in return drew investors to invest in these stocks. As the stocks continued to increase in<br />

value investors became wealthier. With the increase in personal wealth, created by the stock<br />

market boom, individuals started a consumption boom as they started to spend more and<br />

more money. As people continued to spend money, the demand for newer bigger house<br />

became very popular and people started buying up real estate. Given that information above<br />

I find my self wondering if this will repeat its self? It may be in a different industry other than<br />

real estate, but when the time comes in the next few years where we see the next economic<br />

boom, what will be the drivers and cause for an increase in quick rapid wealth, which will<br />

in return cause for the next business cycle?<br />

Message [168] referenced by [176] and [181]. Next Message by Guh is [180].<br />

[176] KA: Response to Next Business Cycle. I think your discussion [168] is interesting,<br />

but would present an alternative outlook. You say that as the stocks continue to increase,<br />

personal wealth <strong>of</strong> those investors increase as well. This is true, but let’s examine the investors<br />

that were able to purchase these stocks at the IPO. Who are these investors that had<br />

the sufficient resources/capital to invest? Were these investors pension funds, investment<br />

banks, institutions, or individuals? What influenced their decision to invest in this pre-boom<br />

era? I acknowledge the fact that those who got in at the onset took a significant risk that<br />

paid <strong>of</strong>f handsomely, but what opportunity does this present to those with little or no knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> these investment opportunities. I would also present a conflicting argument that as<br />

these investments increased in value, it presents little opportunity for smaller investors with<br />

an entry point. Smaller investors do in some degree have an opportunity to get into these<br />

investments, but only through the means <strong>of</strong> their pension/401k plan. As the information<br />

technology era enhances, smaller investors are at a disadvantage with the introduction <strong>of</strong><br />

high-frequency/program trading or dark pool trading. You position your trade (as an individual<br />

investor using your ETrade account) in a few minutes while these computer based


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 473<br />

platforms trade on the nanosecond. By the time you have considered placing your trade,<br />

your bid has already been displaced several seconds back. This may not answer your immediate<br />

question <strong>of</strong> what the next boom will be, but may shed some light as to how fast we<br />

must adapt to the ever changing environment that we attempt to compete in.<br />

Next Message by KA is [301].<br />

[181] Fisher: Adding to Guh. For free discussion i would like to add to GUH’s free<br />

discussion [168] on the real estate market boom in the United States. Many people were<br />

experiencing success either in real estate or other fields <strong>of</strong> business and became unhappy<br />

with the “average house”. <strong>The</strong>y began buying bigger homes which left many homes for<br />

sale available to lower income families. <strong>The</strong> banks wanted to lend money to a more diverse<br />

crowd and began lowering their underwriting standards to bridge the gap between the lower<br />

income homes and “normal borrowers” to keep the market moving. In time many banks<br />

followed suit, in a herd like way, and began to lend to below average credit borrowers land<br />

essened their own due diligence into who they were lending money to. After a while the<br />

wave <strong>of</strong> new buyers, wealthy and middle to lower class, began to drive up prices and give<br />

balloon values to real estate throughout the country. In my opinion it might have go on for<br />

a longer period if it had not been for gas prices going through the ro<strong>of</strong>. <strong>The</strong> combination <strong>of</strong><br />

over priced houses and extremely high gas prices was too much for the economy to sustain<br />

and small crash inevitably followed. Having worked in real estate for the last ten years it<br />

was easy to see this coming. <strong>The</strong> banks were giving large loans to just about anyone who<br />

wanted one. If i were lending my own money out, i would have to assume that eventually<br />

some is going to stiff me. Why didn’t that occur to the banks? Did they care?<br />

Message [181] referenced by [190]. Next Message by Fisher is [183].<br />

[190] Orville: Oversimplification. In response to Fish [181], I think he/she brings up a<br />

good point about the housing bubble. Having said that I also think we tend to oversimplify<br />

the problem. Yes, the housing bubble caused a large decline in the stock market but that is<br />

not the only factor that lead to our current recession. Our economy is far too complicated<br />

for one market failure to bring on a full on recession by itself. <strong>The</strong>re are many other factors<br />

that caused it which include: the rapid increase in food and oil prices among others. I think<br />

that it is important to step back and realize that every recession and/or panic that we have<br />

had or will have before markets are overcome is not due to a single market or commodity<br />

bubble. We are already taking a non-mainstream look at economics in this class, we need to<br />

open our eyes and stop following pundits who simply blame one scapegoat like big banks or<br />

the sub-prime mortgage market.<br />

Message [190] referenced by [208] and [222]. Next Message by Orville is [312].<br />

[208] Long: Oversimplification. Adding to Orville [190]: not to mention that at the<br />

time people were trying to do more than they could. People got caught up in a quick money<br />

making scheme <strong>of</strong> buying homes with low rates and thinking to quickly selling with the<br />

intention <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its. As we find out that people buying homes not being able to pay because<br />

they don’t make enough. At the same time the lenders are doing the same <strong>thing</strong> as consumers<br />

trying to pr<strong>of</strong>it. So eventually it only takes one person to cause the chain reaction that we<br />

see today. Borrowers can’t pay causing a domino effect <strong>of</strong> all the lenders in the process and<br />

causing credit so crunch up so that essentially every<strong>thing</strong> crashed. I think that we need to go<br />

back to basics and live within our means.<br />

Message [208] referenced by [222]. Next Message by Long is [382].<br />

474 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[222] Cmellen: Long [208] said, speaking in regards to the mortgage issue that caused<br />

the current economic state <strong>of</strong> our Union, “Borrowers can’t pay causing a dominoes effect<br />

<strong>of</strong> all the lenders in the process and causing credit so crunch up that essentially every<strong>thing</strong><br />

crashed. I think that we need to go back to basics and live within our means.” Long’s remark<br />

was an addition to Orville [190] who said that our market is far too complex for one market<br />

failure to bring forth recession crisis by itself.<br />

Periodic economic crises has been said to be an expected pattern or economic cycle,<br />

as Charles Sismondi pointed out in 1819. Sismondi’s theory <strong>of</strong> periodic crises developed<br />

thru economists and eventually was addressed by Karl Marx in Das Kapital (at great length<br />

discussed crises). “Periodic crises in capitalism formed the basis <strong>of</strong> the theory <strong>of</strong> Karl Marx”.<br />

He (Marx) believed an economy centered upon production <strong>of</strong> commodities to be sold in the<br />

market is essentially inclined to crisis. So why does the general public point their fingers at<br />

this market failure or that market failure, when if we follow what Marx tried to point out, it is<br />

essential to the economic pattern if your economy is based upon production <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

to be sold in the market.<br />

Hans: If you quote Wikipedia, it is not enough to put the quoted sentence into quotation marks. Please be upfront<br />

about your sources even in the free discussion.<br />

Cmellen: thank you for clarifying; I will be better at quoting my sources next time.<br />

Next Message by Cmellen is [317].<br />

[246] Husani: After reading what Fisher posted [241] I realized that many people do need<br />

these new technologies to function. I do have an ipod and a facebook account but I don’t<br />

need these to function on a day to day basis. What I have realized is that the younger people<br />

<strong>of</strong> my generation do need these technologies to function. <strong>The</strong> current upcoming generation is<br />

in constant need <strong>of</strong> what is going on in the world whether or not it is absolutley necessary to<br />

know them. I don’t consider myself old but I have realized that the people that are a few years<br />

younger than me are in constant need <strong>of</strong> knowing what is going on with their friends through<br />

facebook and other media outlets. My girlfriend and brother are constantly searching the<br />

internet for updates on meaningless <strong>thing</strong>s. I believe that as technology inproves we will<br />

become more and more obcessed with these aspects <strong>of</strong> our lives than we ever have before.<br />

Message [246] referenced by [247] and [263]. Next Message by Husani is [261].<br />

[247] Hans: You are in need <strong>of</strong> information? I agree. Responding to Husani [246]:<br />

if the younger generation is using computers because they are in such constant need to<br />

know what is going on in the world—why are so many utterly uniformed about the greatest<br />

challenge <strong>of</strong> our time or possibly <strong>of</strong> all times, the climate crisis? Excellent info about this<br />

is available on the internet. And this is pretty much the only source <strong>of</strong> information about it,<br />

since newspapers and TV are systematically downplaying or denying it.<br />

Message [247] referenced by [263]. Next Message by Hans is [257].<br />

[261] Husani: Technology. What I meant when I said that many people in the new<br />

generation use vast amounts <strong>of</strong> technology on a daily basis, wasn’t that they use this in a<br />

way in which they will become more knowledgeable about history or current events but<br />

to see what their friends and celebrities are doing. Facebook can be used to learn about<br />

what political groups are proposing the government needs to do and how they will make our<br />

country a better place but this is a very small portion <strong>of</strong> what its users look at when they<br />

logon.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 475<br />

Although we have these technologies at our fingertips we do not use them to their full<br />

potential.<br />

Next Message by Husani is [444].<br />

[263] LuBr: Fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> technology. Responding to Fisher [241], Husani<br />

[246], and Hans [247], regarding the advancement <strong>of</strong> technologies, more specifically the<br />

fetish-like properties <strong>of</strong> the internet. I would agree that the internet holds vast amounts <strong>of</strong><br />

information regarding climate change, however, given the social relations <strong>of</strong> the younger<br />

generation, this information is not sourced nearly as much as trivial “goings-on” among<br />

friends on facebook.<br />

It is an interesting discussion. When a lot <strong>of</strong> people think about the looming climate crisis<br />

and the inconceivable economic and social effects <strong>of</strong> peak oil, people act as if technology<br />

will save the day. Technology will get us out <strong>of</strong> this mess that we’ve so blindly gotten<br />

ourselves into. It is proclaimed as if technology has a life <strong>of</strong> its own and has assumed<br />

‘altruistic’ life-like characteristics.<br />

When we say technology will triumph, we forget that we all have technology as a tool<br />

at our finger tips for expanding and enlightening social relations. We all are part and parcel<br />

<strong>of</strong> social relationships that extend throughout communities and throughout the world. We<br />

forget that every one <strong>of</strong> us, as individuals, are simply reinforcing a society that elects big<br />

oil apologists into our public <strong>of</strong>fices. We fail to admit that our “small” carbon footprints<br />

aggregate to one that threatens to push Earth past unknown ecological thresholds.<br />

We forget how interconnected we are, and by connected I don’t mean to the internet. I<br />

mean to say we forget how to relate and unite as humans around morally and socially optimal<br />

causes.<br />

I think it is because we lose touch <strong>of</strong> human relationships on the community level, we forget<br />

what it means to be engaged socially. Instead <strong>of</strong> getting out in our communities, realizing<br />

what climate change means for Salt Lake, challenging local politicians for green reform, and<br />

communicating with other communities/countries about successful zero-emissions models,<br />

we turn instead to our technological commodities to reinforce digital relationships and social<br />

patterns. But in the end, technology will save us, right?<br />

Message [263] referenced by [520]. Next Message by LuBr is [299].<br />

[484] IrvingHowe: Hans and class-Marx on pr<strong>of</strong>it. A friend and I got into a discussion<br />

the other day on Marx’s views on pr<strong>of</strong>it and socially acceptable labor times. <strong>The</strong> exchange<br />

was fairly lengthy but the discussion could be broken down simply as follows:<br />

Does not a compensation system based on socially acceptable labor times provide an<br />

incentive for faster production?<br />

Doesn’t it also necessarily provide pr<strong>of</strong>it to those who can produce a commodity in less<br />

time than is socially necessary?<br />

It would seem that the next logical place to take this if indeed the above can be answered<br />

in the affirmative, is to ask: Doesn’t pr<strong>of</strong>it encourage overproduction?<br />

I feel as if I understood Marx as essentially equating pr<strong>of</strong>it with theft <strong>of</strong> the laborer’s<br />

leisure time.<br />

476 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

“<strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> mode <strong>of</strong> expressing the rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it is the only one which shows you the real<br />

ratio between paid and unpaid labour, the real degree <strong>of</strong> the exploitation (you must allow<br />

me this French word) <strong>of</strong> labour. <strong>The</strong> other mode <strong>of</strong> expression is that in common use, and<br />

is, indeed, appropriate for certain purposes. At all events, it is very useful for concealing<br />

the degree in which the capitalist extracts gratuitous labour from the workman.” Karl Marx-<br />

Value, Price and Pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [579].<br />

[520] Orville: Action-less Altruism. To add to LuBr [263], there seems to be a common<br />

theme that real change can come from a click <strong>of</strong> a button or by simply becoming a fan on<br />

facebook. <strong>The</strong> groups on facebook are a good indication <strong>of</strong> our generation’s lack <strong>of</strong> real<br />

action. When people add to their friends groups like ‘We support our troops’ or groups like<br />

that. While spreading the word about causes like that and showing your support for those<br />

causes may seem like a way to inspire real change, it rarely does. How many friends have<br />

you heard <strong>of</strong> who were inspired by a facebook page to take action or actually give money?<br />

During the Super Bowl XLII in 2010, the Red Cross raised funds by asking viewers to<br />

contribute to the cause <strong>of</strong> helping <strong>of</strong> victims <strong>of</strong> the recent devastation <strong>of</strong> the earthquake<br />

that rocked the island. By texting a certain number from their cell phones, viewers would<br />

automatically have a $10 donation added to their next months bill. This might be a good<br />

example <strong>of</strong> how technology grants people the ability to make a difference they might not<br />

otherwise make. On the other hand, there is a big difference between donating money and<br />

volunteering. By texting their contributions to the cause and not doing much else, the viewer<br />

gets the feeling <strong>of</strong> having made a difference but the Red Cross gets $10 out <strong>of</strong> that.<br />

Another factor that may have contributed to the large amount <strong>of</strong> money raised through<br />

these series <strong>of</strong> commercials and announcements is the social factors. <strong>The</strong> vast majority<br />

<strong>of</strong> fans and non-fans who watch the Super Bowl don’t watch it by themselves. Parties are<br />

usually thrown and people tend to gather together to watch the big game. When commercials<br />

like those <strong>of</strong> the Red Cross are shown people talk about them. This leads to a perception<br />

that one person is better than others or that they are wealthier or simliar thoughts. This leads<br />

us back to the philosophical discussion <strong>of</strong> whether it is better to do what is perceived as the<br />

right <strong>thing</strong> for the wrong reasons or better to do no<strong>thing</strong> at all.<br />

This is one <strong>of</strong> the big challenges for our generations faces and part <strong>of</strong> the reason that<br />

support for causes and organizations are struggling to find volunteers but many times have<br />

so little problem finding funding. By never seeing the problem and showing up for real<br />

support, our generation has made the decision that the cause is not as important as the time<br />

it takes to volunteer. We’d rather take a few seconds and text our money away. This can be<br />

called generosity but it is a far from altruism.<br />

Next Message by Orville is [689].<br />

[552] Goldtone: Pr<strong>of</strong>it in Marxian Economics. For my free discussion I wanted to ask<br />

a few fundamental questions about a hypothetical Marxian driven economic system. <strong>The</strong><br />

answers my be obvious to some, but I need help with them to better understand Marx’s<br />

position.<br />

1. Would there be any form <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it, or would the money simply be distributed to the<br />

workers involved in creating the commodity? For this question I know that the socially


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 477<br />

necessary labor time is the basis for how workers get paid, which would essentially increase<br />

blue collar income and decrease white collar income. Is this trade <strong>of</strong>f enough to take away<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it, or would the trade <strong>of</strong>f between blue / white collar income still leave room for excess<br />

money after costs are taken into account?<br />

2. Without a means to pr<strong>of</strong>it (or only a means to have greatly reduced pr<strong>of</strong>its), how would<br />

there be investments in new and improved technology? How I understand Marx is that those<br />

that work harder, have more training, and are more efficient will yield more money for their<br />

commodity than the average socially necessary labor time, and this drives them to innovate.<br />

This “better than the average” work is what creates “pr<strong>of</strong>it” and innovation in an Marxian<br />

economic system.<br />

Am I thinking about this in a warped way, or is there some validity to my thoughts?<br />

Message [552] referenced by [558] and [566]. Next Message by Goldtone is [594].<br />

[558] AlexDaily: <strong>The</strong> worker is worth his labor. In response to [552], it’s not about<br />

taking money away from white-collar workers and giving it to blue-collar workers. It is<br />

about giving more money to all workers and making their wages correct for their labor. It<br />

doesn’t matter if you are a factory worker or a doctor, you get paid less then your worth<br />

because the owner or the investor wants to pr<strong>of</strong>it from your labor without adding any labor<br />

<strong>of</strong> his own. Marx is talking about replacing those investors with money pooled from the<br />

people (government). For example, in a factory there would be no investors or owners and<br />

the pr<strong>of</strong>its would go to the workers. <strong>The</strong> incentive to be innovated would still come from the<br />

same place it does today. <strong>The</strong> difference would be that the capital, instead <strong>of</strong> coming from<br />

the private sector, would come from the government. But people with more responsibility<br />

would make more then the simple worker because his labor is worth more than the worker.<br />

However, the amount <strong>of</strong> both <strong>of</strong> their wages would go up because you are getting rid <strong>of</strong> the<br />

investor.<br />

Message [558] referenced by [566] and [567]. Next Message by AlexDaily is [570].<br />

[566] Kraken: More money for all? In AlexDaily [558] response to questions posed<br />

by Goldtone [552] he says: “it’s not about taking money away from white-collar workers<br />

and giving it to blue-collar workers. It is about giving more money to all workers and<br />

making their wages correct for their labor”. That sounds like a beautiful <strong>thing</strong>, but how do<br />

you give MORE money to ALL workers? As with all <strong>thing</strong>s which have a finite supply, it is<br />

impossible to give MORE money to ALL workers, unless you reduce the number <strong>of</strong> workers.<br />

As a side note, one <strong>of</strong> the reasons we’re faced with our current financial and environmental<br />

problems is that we behave as if there’s an infinite supply every<strong>thing</strong> and we fail to manage<br />

our finite resources responsibly.<br />

Marx did not espouse the idea <strong>of</strong> giving more money to all workers. He advocated revolution.<br />

He taught that the proletariat should rise up and seize control <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production. In other words; blue-collar workers should rise up and take what is owned by<br />

white-collar workers. That is a redistribution <strong>of</strong> wealth. So yes, in a Marxian driven economic<br />

system, Marx IS talking about taking money away from white-collar workers and<br />

giving it to blue-collar workers.<br />

Message [566] referenced by [570]. Next Message by Kraken is [578].<br />

478 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[567] Kat: Blue collar, white collar, and the concept <strong>of</strong> innovation. This is in response<br />

to several questions and ideas posed by my peers. Goldtone [525] initially posed the question<br />

concerning pr<strong>of</strong>it and the redistribution <strong>of</strong> wealth between blue and white collar workers.<br />

AlexDaily [558] answers that it is about giving more money to ALL workers, about which I<br />

would agree with Kraken [556] is not exactly the point. It is important to consider the two<br />

classes <strong>of</strong> ‘workers’ to understand the restructuring that Marx suggested. As Kraken [556]<br />

said, Marx advocated for revolution, a complete takeover <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production. If the<br />

proletariat should succeed in doing this, the so called ‘white collar workers’ would cease to<br />

exist. Taking their place would be the government to take control <strong>of</strong> production. I would<br />

argue, then, it is less a redistribution <strong>of</strong> wealth than it is a complete restructuring.<br />

AlexDaily [558] also briefly mentioned innovation in his/her answer, “.....the incentive to<br />

be innovated would still come from the same place it does today.” I wonder, though, if this is<br />

the case. Innovation comes in many forms, but if one’s innovation could potentially become<br />

property <strong>of</strong> the government (in a Marxian economy), is there incentive? If innovation comes<br />

in the form <strong>of</strong> faster or more efficient production, it can be argued costs will go down and<br />

wages will be effected. In this way, there may be some incentive, but a Marxian economy<br />

does not seem to support innovative behavior in the same way a Capitalistic economy does.<br />

I wonder if anyone has any insight on this? As far as I see it, innovation is certainly not the<br />

cornerstone <strong>of</strong> Marxian economics.<br />

Message [567] referenced by [570] and [576]. Next Message by Kat is [632].<br />

[570] AlexDaily: In continuation <strong>of</strong> the collar discussion. A white collar worker is an<br />

educated pr<strong>of</strong>essional who does no manual labor, such as a doctor, architect or engineer. In<br />

[567] Kat says “the so called ‘white collar workers’ would cease to exist. Taking their place<br />

would be the government to take control <strong>of</strong> production.” Kat seems to be suggesting that the<br />

whole population would work in some kind <strong>of</strong> manual labor position and every<strong>thing</strong> else<br />

would be done by the “government.” However, I don’t see how any<strong>thing</strong> would get done<br />

without white collar workers. You can’t build a bridge on manual labor alone, you need<br />

engineers to do the math and the design for the plans. You need foreman to manage and do<br />

the job in an orderly way. In the production process there is need for both white collar and<br />

blue collar workers. In [566] Kraken says this in response to my comment that all workers<br />

would gain an increase in wage “but how do you give MORE money to ALL workers? As<br />

with all <strong>thing</strong>s which have a finite supply.” If Kraken would have read on, he/she would have<br />

received the answer. All workers gain an increase because the investor is gone and the pr<strong>of</strong>its<br />

go back to the workers. For example, let’s look at the building <strong>of</strong> a house. A company has an<br />

investor giving the company money and allowing it to buy capital such as building supplies,<br />

work equipment and so forth. In return for the money given by the investor, the investor<br />

wants to receive a pr<strong>of</strong>it. Or in other words, they want their money to grow without doing<br />

any labor or adding to the building <strong>of</strong> the house in anyway. This company has architects<br />

(white collar) and manual labor ( blue collar) workers. Both <strong>of</strong> their wages are lessened<br />

because some <strong>of</strong> the money they have earned goes to the investor. <strong>The</strong>refore, if you get rid<br />

<strong>of</strong> the investor both white collar and blue collar workers gain an increase. And where that<br />

money comes from is the money that would have gone to the investors.<br />

Message [570] referenced by [576]. Next Message by AlexDaily is [586].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 479<br />

[576] Husani: Innovation. I agree with Alexdaily [570] in the sense that there will still<br />

be a need for “white collar” workers in any society. But I think that what Kat was talking<br />

about in [567] was that in a society in which the government takes control and everyone<br />

receives the pr<strong>of</strong>its instead <strong>of</strong> a ruling minority, everyone would reveive the same pay. <strong>The</strong>re<br />

wouldn’t be a difference between the white and blue collar workers execpt their occupation.<br />

This also brings up questions in where innovation will come from. If everyone is receiving<br />

the same pay there is little incentive to innovate and stagnation will happen.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is one question I would like to ask. Alexdaily said “If Kraken would have read on,<br />

he/she would have received the answer. All workers gain an increase because the investor is<br />

gone and the pr<strong>of</strong>its go back to the workers.” If this is true then where does the money come<br />

from to build the house? If there is no investor present to provide the company with capital<br />

to build the house and the pr<strong>of</strong>its from building the house are returned to the workers, then<br />

do these same workers forgo a portion or all <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>its to help the company build houses<br />

in the future?<br />

Next Message by Husani is [658].<br />

[577] Utefan: How Exploitation Works. I had some thoughts <strong>of</strong> exploitation that I<br />

thought I would ask the class and Hans so that I could get a better feel for how it works. I<br />

argue that our lack <strong>of</strong> knowledge leads to an accidental exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers. For example<br />

I had no idea before entering this class that what capitalism was and how it functioned. I<br />

even less understood the meaning behind my own experiences and how, as I now see them,<br />

I my self am exposed to it as well.<br />

Now the accidental nature I am referring to has to do with the inability for workers to<br />

recognize their own exploitation, like myself, and understand why or how it is happening. In<br />

later chapters one comes to learn that capitalism thrives on almost a circular reshuffling if you<br />

will <strong>of</strong> employees, the next generation comes in and allows by lack <strong>of</strong> previous knowledge<br />

to be exploited and the cycle happens all over again. Unions are made and forced out, new<br />

workers come in and fill jobs that are needed and reshuffle to prior experienced workers<br />

to the unemployment line. Strength can be found in numbers for workers but they find<br />

themselves out <strong>of</strong> a job when someone else will accept being exploited just for the sake <strong>of</strong><br />

work.<br />

<strong>The</strong> accident comes from a new generation <strong>of</strong> workers who have don’t understand the<br />

implications <strong>of</strong> their employment, and are more excited about landing some means <strong>of</strong> wage<br />

then to be concerned with whether they are treated fairly or rather just furthering capitalist<br />

accumulation.<br />

Next Message by Utefan is [593].<br />

[579] IrvingHowe: Marx and free floating currency. Upon reflecting on Tuesday’s<br />

class, I began to wonder how Marx would view the free floating currencies that dominate<br />

modern economies.<br />

In Marx’s day, all currencies had the backing <strong>of</strong> some sort <strong>of</strong> commodity. Today, they can<br />

purchase a commodity but are never actually backed by any real value (coins excepted.)<br />

Certainly Marx would think this to be the most mysterious <strong>of</strong> commodities. After all, in<br />

theory, all the holders <strong>of</strong> dollars in the world could literally remove the dollar <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> it’s<br />

480 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

value (they haven’t much in the way <strong>of</strong> use-value to begin with) simply by refusing to accept<br />

them any longer.<br />

It would seem that modern currency is a contradiction <strong>of</strong> Marx’s <strong>The</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> Use Value<br />

since they do not <strong>first</strong> have any use-value to speak <strong>of</strong> but may have very high exchange<br />

values.<br />

Is this thought misguided?<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [607].<br />

[603] Long: Free discussion. In response to Alex [600]: I don’t think that time have<br />

any<strong>thing</strong> to do with value <strong>of</strong> a product lose. I experience similar situation in my home<br />

country. Travelers would come to U.S. and buys the cheapest <strong>of</strong> product here (toothpatse,<br />

toothbrush, soap, shampoo ect..) and only to return home and sell them for, like you said,<br />

two or three times <strong>of</strong> their value. I also did this myself. I would travel home to visit my<br />

family in Vietnam and bring all different kind <strong>of</strong> goods and items that are popular. I would<br />

pay $1 for a tube <strong>of</strong> toothpaste and in return, I can get $4 out <strong>of</strong> it in Vietnam which is four<br />

times more than what I paid for. People in my home country value products which are made<br />

in the U.S that they would pay for such price <strong>of</strong> that product even though it is the cheapest<br />

<strong>of</strong> product here in the U.S. <strong>The</strong> value <strong>of</strong> M-C-M is not being lost cause I know I can hold on<br />

it this product for along period <strong>of</strong> time because the people demand and are willing to pay for<br />

such price <strong>of</strong> that product. This is speaking from my past experience.<br />

Next Message by Long is [686].<br />

[604] LuBr: Buying perfume for money advancing purposes. On Alex’s question [600]<br />

regarding time-lags and ones ability to advance money, <strong>first</strong> I dont think you can say that the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> a commodity goes down when it remains in the hands <strong>of</strong> a seller for too long. As<br />

we have learned, value is some<strong>thing</strong> intrinsic within the commodity, that being congealed<br />

abstract labor. However, it does seem that the exchange value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is effected<br />

by peoples’ perceptions <strong>of</strong> the perfume not being hot <strong>of</strong>f the market from America. If this<br />

is the case, and the price people are willing to pay for the perfume after a certain amount <strong>of</strong><br />

time is at parity or even below the amount the seller paid, then he would not be successfully<br />

advancing money, and it may seem that the money would be “irreversibly spent,” as Marx<br />

says, and the person is stuck to enjoy the perfume himself. Or it could be that instead <strong>of</strong> the<br />

advancement <strong>of</strong> money one gets M-C-M instead <strong>of</strong> M-C-M’. In this case, the quantitative<br />

difference <strong>of</strong> money from beginning to end would not be large enough to incentivize people<br />

to engage in these money advancing activities using foreign perfume in the <strong>first</strong> place.<br />

So, you could say that time in the perfume example does have a social impact on the<br />

exchange-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity such that it reduces the quantitative amount <strong>of</strong> money in<br />

circulation from the beginning to the end <strong>of</strong> M-C-M that would cause people to disengage<br />

from the act <strong>of</strong> Money-Perfume-Money. <strong>The</strong> result would be either not to buy the perfume<br />

in the <strong>first</strong> place, enjoy the perfume himself, or give them away as gifts.<br />

Next Message by LuBr is [750].<br />

[615] She: New Capital is all money...that has to converted into capital? Since this<br />

concept seems either too basic to be discussed or too confusing for me to understand I though<br />

I would try it as a free discussion.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 481<br />

Marx says that “all new capital, in the <strong>first</strong> instance, steps onto the stage in the shape <strong>of</strong><br />

money, money which has to be transformed into capital by definite process,” [247:3]. This<br />

whole sentence seems a contradiction.<br />

Is Marx saying that new capital is in the form <strong>of</strong> money at all times, even though it actually<br />

is capital, because it must go through some exchange to be converted into the specific usevalue<br />

capital an investor is seeking? If money buys capital inputs, such as machinery and<br />

technology, it has to come to the market, make a purchase <strong>of</strong> the specific capital, and then<br />

through the M-C-M exchange, become money again?<br />

Message [615] referenced by [616]. Next Message by She is [686].<br />

[616] Cosmopolita: Re: New Capital is all money...that has to converted into capital?<br />

In response to She [615]: According to Marx, money is the <strong>first</strong> form <strong>of</strong> capital. M-C-M is<br />

one form <strong>of</strong> circulation <strong>of</strong> capital. This could be seen in real life with tools or machinery for<br />

an industry to convert capital in money, or on finished products with an investor buying a<br />

product(commodity) to convert it in capital. With the finished products there is many interesting<br />

variables that can made capital multiply since many value commodities in a different<br />

way. i.e an investor buys a house in a short sale, so invests money (capital) and sells this<br />

commodity fixed up at a higher price than bought converting the commodity again in Money<br />

M (capital) for a happy customer that values finished products, as in this case a fixed up<br />

house. <strong>The</strong>re’s many examples <strong>of</strong> this form circulation <strong>of</strong> capital. with so many different<br />

commodities to enjoy in this world <strong>of</strong> consumers, the M - C <strong>first</strong> phase multiple options<br />

could be found depending on the activities and motivations <strong>of</strong> the persons performing these<br />

circulations acts and the social relatiosn which make these individual activities possible.<br />

Next Message by Cosmopolita is [617].<br />

[626] Guh: Competitive Advantage. I am taking a class called Current Economic Problems,<br />

and in class we were discussing, what the benefits are from free trade, as suggested by<br />

mainstream economist and using the notion <strong>of</strong> comparative advantages. As we got into our<br />

groups it was very interesting to see other peoples opinions and viewpoints on the matter.<br />

In my opinion, one <strong>of</strong> the main advantages <strong>of</strong> free trade that I read about in class, was the<br />

advantage that countries have over other courtliness. For example when I say this, I mean<br />

this in the extent that some countries have a competitive adantage in some sort <strong>of</strong> products,<br />

which allows certain counties to produce these products at faster rates or even allows them<br />

to produce a product that another country cannot produce. Take for instance c<strong>of</strong>fee. In<br />

South America c<strong>of</strong>fee is grown and sold to other countries, which gives them a competitive<br />

advantage vs Alaska, where they cannot grow c<strong>of</strong>fee. <strong>The</strong>refore the more closely a country<br />

conforms to its underlying pattern <strong>of</strong> competitive advantage, the more it can consume and<br />

this done by focusing and increasing its own product.<br />

Next Message by Guh is [692].<br />

[646] Ferox: Information and Open Source in a Marxist Framework. In the Friday<br />

the 29th <strong>of</strong> October class discussion Marx’s core theory <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it was discussed. A topic that<br />

was touched on several times during the class was a Marxist understanding towards digital<br />

commodities. My logic so far has yielded:<br />

M-C-M’ (the genesis <strong>of</strong> capital) exists “if there is a commodity on the market whose consumption<br />

creates more value than the commodity itself costs” [10-29-2010 Class Discussion<br />

(10:30)] and this commodity is labour power. <strong>The</strong> expenditure <strong>of</strong> labour power creates the<br />

482 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

value <strong>of</strong> commodities — as the labour theory <strong>of</strong> value states. Digital commodities, say a<br />

.mp3 file <strong>of</strong> a song or Photoshop program, have value initially because <strong>of</strong> the work that went<br />

into them whether by recording the song or coding the program. In a digital environment,<br />

information can be duplicated indefinitely and transferred between consumers quickly and<br />

cheaply (if not free) by the click <strong>of</strong> a mouse button. By these acts a single digital commodity<br />

can multiply with minimal labour input. Do all these duplicates have the same value as<br />

the initial commodities? According to my understanding <strong>of</strong> Marx the answer would be no<br />

— since the labour power involved in the duplicate commodity’s creation is very little (hitting<br />

Ctrl+C). However, the duplicate commodity is effectively identical, and has the same<br />

use-value.<br />

So how have capitalists tried to enforce on a commodity that eludes the typical M-C-<br />

M’ model <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it? One method is digital copyrighting, effectively a commodity as it is<br />

a property right allowing the consumer to be the sole recipient <strong>of</strong> the intended use-value.<br />

As Hans touched on in the Friday discussion, ‘information wants to be free’ and clever<br />

people have been able to ‘crack’ the copyright protections on digital media and programs. A<br />

successful example <strong>of</strong> these attempts at undermining the digital capitalist empire can be seen<br />

with thepiratebay.com — a community <strong>of</strong> people uploading free music, movies, programs,<br />

etc. for anyone with a torrent client to download.<br />

Additionally, the emergence <strong>of</strong> open source s<strong>of</strong>tware is digital community solution to traditional<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it based s<strong>of</strong>tware and operating systems. Looking at the variety <strong>of</strong> Linux builds,<br />

the forums devoted to improving s<strong>of</strong>tware and sharing knowledge, and released media using<br />

the several open source licensing agreements — all <strong>of</strong> which produce commodities outside<br />

<strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Labour power is a commodity every human being can exchange on the material market.<br />

It is some<strong>thing</strong> that every capitalist wants because <strong>of</strong> the M-C-M’ model, where value <strong>of</strong><br />

labour can be pr<strong>of</strong>ited upon. In a digital market, an equivalent commodity to labour power is<br />

personal information. It is some<strong>thing</strong> that every company wants - from Google to Facebook<br />

to Paypal. On one hand it provides a way <strong>of</strong> organizing humans into data and can be used to<br />

protect users from fraud or misuse. However, it makes the individual vulnerable, as that data<br />

can be exploited for pr<strong>of</strong>it (Facebook selling user data, Google targeted advertising, etc.)<br />

Just as labour power is exploited in a capitalist system, personal information is exploited in<br />

a digital system.<br />

Just some ideas I was throwing around this weekend. Comments or corrections are greatly<br />

appreciated!<br />

Message [646] referenced by [647]. Next Message by Ferox is [706].<br />

[647] IrvingHowe: Re: Information and Open Source in a Marxist Framework. Just<br />

a thought on the ‘sharing’ <strong>of</strong> commodities digitally as discussed in [646].<br />

I personally believe it to be wrong and I think Marx would also because <strong>of</strong> the creator<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity being denied control and compensation with regard to their own work.<br />

To clarify, I could care less about the companies that legally own the commodity (Adobe,<br />

Micros<strong>of</strong>t, AMC Records etc). To me, it is a sort <strong>of</strong> sweet revenge that these companies


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 483<br />

get shorted out <strong>of</strong> their money as they shorted (nearly without exception) the actual people<br />

behind the creation <strong>of</strong> the commodity being ‘shared.’<br />

However, there are a lot <strong>of</strong> hardworking (mostly underpaid) people that do deserve the<br />

fruits <strong>of</strong> their labor but are denied as much when someone downloads it for free. I think this<br />

is a large philosophical break for me from various anarcho/syndicalist inspired movements.<br />

Even for the most <strong>of</strong> pop-stars, it is wrong to take in their work without even minimal reward.<br />

Now, with that I must note that some artists have given their blessing to fans wanting to<br />

download the fruits <strong>of</strong> their labor. This is <strong>of</strong>ten a response to the lousy conditions most<br />

artists get in their recording contracts and I have absolutely no qualms with downloading it<br />

in this case– even if the artists don’t actually have the legal authority to give such permission.<br />

Although it’s hard to equate these acts with the tangible examples <strong>of</strong> theft that we think<br />

<strong>of</strong>, it is no different. <strong>The</strong> difficulty in making this distinction comes as a result <strong>of</strong> the market<br />

conditions under which these particular laborers (music artists, s<strong>of</strong>tware engineers) work.<br />

You wouldn’t try to minimize or not pay for the work <strong>of</strong> a carpenter who comes to install<br />

cabinets in your house and yet most people have no problem with downloading a song.<br />

<strong>The</strong> cabinets and the songs both represent the effort, time and skill spent on a commodity.<br />

However, since the delivery methods for the commodity are very different, it is all too easy<br />

to draw an artificial moral distinction between not paying the carpenter his wages when they<br />

are due and not paying for a song.<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [657].<br />

[662] Hans: Interview with Dr Michael Hudson. Michael Hudson has interesting theses<br />

about the international monetary system and gold. H.E.<br />

http://billtotten.blogspot.com/2010/10/interview-with-dr-michael-hudson.html<br />

by Eric Janszen<br />

Personal correspondence (October 25 2010)<br />

Eric (E): Welcome Michael Hudson to iTulip again. Thanks for joining us.<br />

Hudson (H): Thank you, Eric.<br />

E: So we’ve had discussions in the past about China’s response to America’s escalation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the currency wars. Yesterday they made a bold move, raising their interest rates and also<br />

imposing an export embargo on an important industrial commodity, rare earth metals.<br />

H: Let’s talk about the latter <strong>first</strong>. I think China finally caught on to the fact that it was<br />

pricing its rare earth minerals at the uneconomic low-cost margin <strong>of</strong> extraction, not taking<br />

into account the environmental clean up costs or the replacement costs for these basically<br />

irreplaceable rare metals. <strong>The</strong>y pointed out that these exports rightly should be priced at<br />

the high-cost margin, which <strong>of</strong> course is the basis <strong>of</strong> Ricardian rent theory. So they’re conforming<br />

to basic Western price theory and practice. America sells its military technology for<br />

what the market will bear. If the Pentagon would sell its new missile and bomb technology<br />

at the physical cost <strong>of</strong> production - CDs with the blueprints - then China would not have to<br />

pay the high price <strong>of</strong> buying this information from Israeli espionage agencies.<br />

484 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

E: That’s not likely to happen, because last time I checked, the Pentagon has China on<br />

top <strong>of</strong> their list <strong>of</strong> places to worry about.<br />

H: <strong>The</strong> thought that China would wage a war or pose any military threat to the United<br />

States is crazy. <strong>The</strong> national security approach holds that any industrial capability is potentially<br />

military, and hence is a threat. What China has reason to worry about is that there<br />

are crazy people in the Pentagon and Congress who get ill-tempered at America’s loss <strong>of</strong><br />

industrial power and “blame the foreigner”.<br />

China-bashers are encouraging the Pentagon to create problems in the China Sea. And<br />

China has every reason to fear that US military adventurism may take a violent turn or be<br />

accident-prone. That is what countries do when they blame foreigners for problems that<br />

they themselves caused. <strong>The</strong> Obama administration is mishandling the economy as badly as<br />

the Bush administration did, so you can expect the “blame the foreigner” reaction to take a<br />

military dimension. <strong>The</strong> xenophobic idea is that China is taking away American jobs, not<br />

that America’s pro-financial policies are responsible for de-industrializing the economy and<br />

shrinking domestic markets and employment here.<br />

E: Isn’t there another possible explanation more consistent with the past US policy <strong>of</strong><br />

raising the spectre <strong>of</strong> the fearsome Soviet Union’s military capacity, which really was just a<br />

way to ensure that one <strong>of</strong> our greatest exports, weapons, would continue to flow?<br />

H: That’s true. I think that just yesterday India promised a huge new fighter aircraft<br />

purchase. America has been pressuring India, saying “Look, we’re running a big trade<br />

deficit with you, so you have to balance it by buying what we can export”. Prime Minister<br />

Singh is yielding, agreeing to buy 125 fighter jets. What does India need these for?<br />

E: We just had some pretty juicy deals with the Saudis, too. I think these deals are bigger<br />

than the entire stimulus program that Obama recently discussed.<br />

H: Yes, this is bizarre, but what else can America export these days? Prices for these<br />

exports are so high that other countries are beginning to compete. Unfortunately, it’s an<br />

economically useless competition - overhead, not capital formation.<br />

E: We could speculate that one <strong>of</strong> the motivations for cutting <strong>of</strong>f rare earth metals is<br />

there’s a lot <strong>of</strong> difficulty in making a lot <strong>of</strong> these weapons without that stuff. So maybe<br />

China doesn’t want to participate.<br />

H: I was in Beijing last year and they pointed out that the United States has numerous rare<br />

earth deposits. One <strong>of</strong> the biggest is owned by Molycorp - the old Molybdenum Corporation.<br />

Another mining company sold all its equipment, lock, stock and barrel to the Chinese.<br />

So the United States is not mining many rare earth metals now, because China has undersold<br />

the market so drastically - and so uneconomically. In any case, these rare earths are available<br />

in many places, only at a higher price. <strong>The</strong> military simply will bid up prices to their<br />

replacement cost, which is what Japan is paying to buy old computers, telephones and other<br />

used equipment to refine the rare earth content from them.<br />

Suppose China charges a few thousand dollars a pound for its rare earths, instead <strong>of</strong> six<br />

or seven dollars a pound. At this price I think that the Pentagon can [be] able to get all it<br />

needs, so higher prices are not going to stop the US military threat.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 485<br />

E: That’s a good point. <strong>The</strong> price rise probably is going to spur a fair amount <strong>of</strong> speculation<br />

in US production <strong>of</strong> rare earth metals.<br />

H: It’s hard to speculate. I think the main company that was mining China’s rare earth<br />

deposits was a Hong Kong or Taiwanese company. <strong>The</strong> government should take control <strong>of</strong><br />

most such monopolies and price their output at the marginal replacement cost, as textbooks<br />

describe. China was nearly giving away these metals without taking into account either their<br />

replacement costs or environmental clean-up costs. It pointed out that these were among the<br />

dirtiest metals to mine, and local opposition has arisen to protest the environmental problems<br />

they caused.<br />

E: <strong>The</strong> second move by the Chinese was their quarter-point rate hike. This seems to be<br />

a paradoxical response to the accusation that they’re overvaluing their currency. Certainly<br />

you’d expect such a move to increase the yuan’s exchange rate.<br />

H: That’s right. I can understand why they would raise the rate in order to slow the rise in<br />

bank credit and housing prices. I would rather use a tax approach to this. Bob Stiglitz had a<br />

good report today [October 19 2010] in <strong>The</strong> Guardian on why tax policy rather than financial<br />

policy should be used. China will have to impose capital controls to prevent interest-rate<br />

arbitrage from flowing into its currency out <strong>of</strong> the dollar.<br />

E: Exactly.<br />

H: And what Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Stiglitz said on Democracy Now is even sharper:<br />

[Federal Reserve] lending is actually below what it was in 2007. In a globalized economy,<br />

the money is looking for the best place to go. And where is it finding it? In the emerging<br />

markets.<br />

So, the irony is that money that was intended to rekindle the American economy is causing<br />

havoc all over the world. Those elsewhere in the world say, what the United States is<br />

trying to do is the twenty-<strong>first</strong> century version <strong>of</strong> “beggar thy neighbor” policies that were<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the Great Depression: you strengthen yourself by hurting the others. You can’t do<br />

protectionism in the old version <strong>of</strong> raising tariffs, but what you can do is lower your exchange<br />

rate, and that’s what low interest rates are trying to do, weaken the dollar. <strong>The</strong> flood<br />

<strong>of</strong> liquidity abroad is trying to push the exchange rates abroad. And they say - they’re saying,<br />

’We can’t allow that’. 1<br />

So the important question is how China can respond except by imposing capital controls?<br />

And how can Brazil or other countries avoid such controls in the face <strong>of</strong> the Federal<br />

Reserve’s “quantitative easing” that actually is financial aggression?<br />

E: <strong>The</strong> interest-rate rise appears to be a doubling down on China’s assertion that they’re<br />

not underpricing their currency.<br />

H: What is pushing up the renminbi’s exchange rate is largely capital flight out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dollar, not trade. I don’t think they’d raise their interest rate just for public relations or<br />

psychological purposes. I think their main concern is to hold down price rises for real estate<br />

and slow the stock market. Any economy in this position would probably raise its interest<br />

rate. But given the international effects, I don’t see how China is going to withstand yet more<br />

486 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

demand for its currency as speculators and other foreigners try to buy yuan-denominated<br />

assets. <strong>The</strong>re’s going to be a lot more renminbi flowing into the Central Bank - which already<br />

got $2.6 trillion in reserves. What can China do with these reserves, when the United States<br />

is taking a nationalistic position by saying, “We’re not going to let you buy US companies.<br />

You have to let us buy your companies but we’re not going to let you buy Unocal or refineries<br />

or any<strong>thing</strong> that we consider important.” Canada now is under nationalist and even overtly<br />

racist pressure not to let the Chinese buy their Potash mining company in Saskatchewan.<br />

E: Almost every government that has allowed property prices to rise so steadily (Japan in<br />

the 1980s, the US in the early 2000s) seems to think that they can end these distortions with<br />

merely marginal measures such as rate hikes. Alan Greenspan said throughout the dotcom<br />

bubble, “Raise the rates, raise the rates”. But it takes quite a bit to finally drive speculators<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the market. This usually happens quite suddenly. That’s the lesson that was learned in<br />

1999 and 2000, and again in 2006. Do you think that the Chinese will experience a similar<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> effect?<br />

H: I think every<strong>thing</strong> happens by a phase change, not in smooth marginal movements.<br />

You go from one phase to another. Things may be marginal within each phase, but there is<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> like turning an on/<strong>of</strong>f switch from one phase to the next. That’s as true for China<br />

as it has been for any other economy. I’m sure they must realize this, but I’m not sure just<br />

what they have in mind, except maybe an attempt to show up the US in preparation for the<br />

G20 meeting in Seoul next month.<br />

E: I think that’s right. <strong>The</strong>re’s obviously a lot <strong>of</strong> pushing and shoving verbally before the<br />

IMF meeting two weekends ago, and then we’ve got the G20 coming up in November. A lot<br />

<strong>of</strong> this is probably a combination <strong>of</strong> posturing and sending messages to bolster the positions<br />

<strong>of</strong> the various players.<br />

H: My experience is that China’s position in the current situation is defensive, not <strong>of</strong>fensive.<br />

It’s trying to figure out a way to defend its stability. It’s saying: “We’re not going to<br />

destabilize our economy in order for you (Europe and the US) to take measures that you<br />

claim will stabilize your economy, but actually is making your economy worse and worse”.<br />

In other words, “we’re not going to give in to your fantasies, we’re going to live in the real<br />

world”.<br />

E: So in a way, what Chinese policy makers are doing is explaining back to the Bernanke<br />

set, “You don’t really have an inflation problem. It doesn’t make any sense with $25 silver<br />

and $1300 gold. What the United States really has is a debt-deflation problem. That’s<br />

a political problem, and you guys have got to deal with it without flooding us with your<br />

money.”<br />

H: That’s exactly correct. <strong>The</strong> US economy is all loaned up. So when the Federal Reserve<br />

provides more liquidity to the banks, they are not going to lend to real estate that already has<br />

one-third <strong>of</strong> homes in negative equity. Obviously, the only <strong>thing</strong> banks are going to do is to<br />

try to work their way out <strong>of</strong> debt is by lending abroad - by speculating in the carry trade, just<br />

as Japan’s banks did.<br />

E: Sure. And countries from Brazil to China - any economy on the receiving end <strong>of</strong> all<br />

this liquidity - will have to defend themselves against this “quantitative easing”.


H: That’s right.<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 487<br />

E: What is the end game here? On one side <strong>of</strong> the equation we have rising commodity<br />

prices, and on the other side we have falling bond yields. I think if you went to the average<br />

portfolio manager five years ago and told him, “Five years from now silver will be five times<br />

the price it is today and the yield on ten-year Treasury bonds will be around 4.5%”, they’d<br />

probably have thought you were crazy.<br />

H: <strong>The</strong>re’s no way that you can project past trends to see where the intersection point is<br />

today, because we’re in a quandary. <strong>The</strong> US economy has reached a wall <strong>of</strong> indebtedness. It<br />

can’t take on more debt. A choice has to be made: Either write down the debts to the ability<br />

to pay, or flood the market with enough credit to keep the debt bubble growing. That’s<br />

ultimately going to make it even harder for the economy as a whole to work its way out <strong>of</strong><br />

debt. So I don’t see what can happen, except more breaks in the chain <strong>of</strong> payments. We’re<br />

now living under what James Galbraith calls the “Predatory State”, a government taken over<br />

by the financial interests. <strong>The</strong>y say, “We want all the debt to be paid, regardless <strong>of</strong> the effect<br />

on the economy as a whole. And we also want all <strong>of</strong> our financial gambles and CDOs to<br />

be made whole, even if it shrinks the economy. We don’t care if you have to scale back<br />

pensions and Social Security, or reduce wages by twenty percent and lower living standards.<br />

We want to get paid.” And they’re telling politicians, “Don’t forget that we’re the guys who<br />

are paying for your Congressional and Senate campaigns. We expect you to do what we tell<br />

you to do, or else we’ll back someone else.”<br />

So basically, the financial sector is saying to the economy, “Drop dead!”<br />

E: Isn’t it even worse? Paul Krugman wrote in his New York Times op-ed yesterday<br />

[October 18 2010] comparing US deflation to that <strong>of</strong> Japan. This is one <strong>of</strong> the favorite<br />

arguments for advocates <strong>of</strong> printing more money and increasing federal deficits further. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

claim that we’re making the same mistake that Japan did, by not being “aggressive enough”<br />

with fiscal stimulus.<br />

H: On another plane we’re doing the opposite <strong>of</strong> what brought on Japan’s bubble crisis.<br />

<strong>The</strong> Basel II agreement in 1988 ruled that banks needed much higher capital reserves to<br />

bring them up to the new European standard. As a result <strong>of</strong> their weak position after World<br />

War Two, Japanese banks had been operating for half a century on much lower capital. All<br />

<strong>of</strong> the sudden, the Basel Agreement forced these banks to stop lending and rebuild their<br />

capital base. In conjunction with high interest rates (which the Americans insisted upon)<br />

and upward revaluation <strong>of</strong> the yen, this killed Japan’s economy. So Japan’s giving in to<br />

American financial demands destroyed it.<br />

By contrast today, instead <strong>of</strong> lowering bank liquidity the US Federal Reserve is pushing<br />

liquidity into the financial system. This enables banks to increase their loans, on the theory<br />

that America can borrow its way out <strong>of</strong> debt - which is crazy, <strong>of</strong> course. So Bernanke and<br />

Krugman are drawing a false parallel.<br />

E: I agree completely. <strong>The</strong> US was never slow on the gas pedal as the Bank <strong>of</strong> Japan was.<br />

We never did fall into a liquidity trap that some members <strong>of</strong> the Feds are claiming we are in<br />

today. <strong>The</strong> way I see it is that these [are] arguments for continuing to borrow - to use your<br />

488 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

phrase, to move debt from private to public accounts by the Fed’s cash-for-trash swaps and<br />

bailouts.<br />

Comparing our opportunity to Japan’s, isn’t our sovereign credit risk much higher than<br />

Japan’s in terms <strong>of</strong> per capita GDP growth, structural balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments deficit, history<br />

<strong>of</strong> default and history <strong>of</strong> inflation?<br />

H: <strong>The</strong> financial credit risk is really a political question <strong>of</strong> national policy. In the last few<br />

weeks China has negotiated currency swaps with Russia, Turkey and Brazil. <strong>The</strong> aim is to<br />

prevent losses on these swaps. <strong>The</strong>re’s a mutual guarantee that a central bank <strong>of</strong> a currency<br />

that loses value will reimburse the central bank that’s holding its currency so that the latter<br />

will not suffer a loss as denominated in its own currency.<br />

I suspect that all the United States would have to do (at least in the short run) would be to<br />

make the same deal so that foreign countries would not take a loss on their dollar holdings.<br />

Instead, America is saying bluntly: “In order for us to solve our economic problem at no<br />

cost to ourselves, you must take a loss. We are going to solve our problem at your expense.<br />

If you don’t like it, you had better arm yourselves (preferably by buying our own weapons<br />

exports) because we’re going to do <strong>thing</strong>s our way. What are you going to do about it?”<br />

E: Yes.<br />

H: Imagine what effect this is creating abroad! Other countries have gone along with<br />

US policy so far, because there was some mutual gain, at least in the US market for foreign<br />

countries’ exports. But now that US consumers have little left to spend on goods and services<br />

(because they have to spend so much on debt service and housing), America has little to <strong>of</strong>fer<br />

any more. So foreign countries are moving away. I was told two weeks before Turkey made<br />

the currency-swap agreement with China that they decided that America is going to be on<br />

the losing side, and they wanted to go with the winners - that is, with the growing economies,<br />

not those that are sinking into debt deflation.<br />

<strong>The</strong> United States is playing as if other countries are still going to automatically obey it.<br />

<strong>The</strong> only ground for believing this is that other countries are looking at the United States as<br />

a “madman”. It certainly looks as if people like Ben Bernanke are even nuttier than Alan<br />

Greenspan. <strong>The</strong>y’re disappointed with Obama, whom they see more as a continuation <strong>of</strong><br />

Dick Cheney than <strong>of</strong> George Bush. He’s turned over the shop to the Rubinomics gang <strong>of</strong><br />

financial predators.<br />

E: You’re in Germany. What’s the general feeling there about US economic policies?<br />

H: <strong>The</strong>re is resentment against Angela Merkel and her government for following American<br />

policy and not realizing that the world has changed from what it used to be. <strong>The</strong>re is<br />

still high unemployment here, almost twenty percent. <strong>The</strong> economy is not doing well, and<br />

German exports - like other European exports - are being hurt by the euro’s rise while the<br />

US Fed continues to pursue low interest rates to increase the capitalization rate <strong>of</strong> its real<br />

estate and corporate income - which has the side effect <strong>of</strong> lowering its exchange rate. So<br />

Europe is bearing the brunt <strong>of</strong> American financial aggression. <strong>The</strong>re is a feeling that Merkel<br />

is turning as much into Obama’s poodle as Blair was Bush’s poodle. And her French friend<br />

Sarkozy is not popular here either.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 489<br />

E: Regarding the currency swap agreements between China and other countries to avoid<br />

the downside <strong>of</strong> holding dollars and doing trade in them, is this a gradualist approach?<br />

H: It’s an either/or approach. Foreign central banks know that holding dollars is like<br />

buying an asset that is going down in price. Nobody wants to do that, because they will have<br />

to show a loss on their books, which are kept in their own currency. Most central bankers<br />

expect China’s currency to rise, just like the yen rose after 1985. <strong>The</strong>y naturally would rather<br />

hold a rising currency asset than a depreciating one.<br />

E: Speaking <strong>of</strong> which, one <strong>of</strong> the major changes in the global market over this year is that<br />

central banks have become net buyers <strong>of</strong> gold. Earlier this week the central bank <strong>of</strong> South<br />

Korea announced that they’re beginning to diversify out <strong>of</strong> dollars. Do you see this as part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the process that I call decommissioning the dollar as a reserve currency?<br />

H: Certainly. <strong>The</strong> United States, Germany and France hold half <strong>of</strong> their foreign reserves<br />

in gold. Korea has only 0.2% <strong>of</strong> its international reserves in gold. So it’s saying, in effect:<br />

“Wait a minute. <strong>The</strong>re’s some hypocrisy going on here. You’re telling us to hold dollars,<br />

but you’re holding gold. We’ve decided to do as you do, not as you say.” <strong>The</strong> corollary is<br />

to spell this out: “We don’t know what the future global monetary system is going to be.<br />

But it looks like the United States is expecting a gold-based system. Otherwise, let the US<br />

Treasury sell <strong>of</strong>f its gold stock.”<br />

Korea may have been discussed its gold purchase with other countries. Its act says, in<br />

effect: “We’re hosting the G20 meetings next month. Why doesn’t America hold down the<br />

price <strong>of</strong> gold by putting its money where it’s mouth is, and announce that it’s going to sell<br />

the gold in Fort Knox?” Other countries might well say, “By the way, can you give us back<br />

the gold we’re holding in the New York Federal Reserve? Now that we don’t have to worry<br />

about World War Two any more, we’d like to hold our own gold.” <strong>The</strong>re is a growing feeling<br />

that the US Government is acting on behalf <strong>of</strong> financial thieves, and that this theft is causing<br />

unemployment in Europe and other countries.<br />

E: So this leads to my final question: Clearly the world needs a new global monetary<br />

system. This has been obvious for a while. My sense is that for most governments around the<br />

world, the final straw has been the financial crisis that we’ve imposed on everybody. So the<br />

question is, in the past such agreements were reached with at least one dominant power (that<br />

would be us) holding most <strong>of</strong> the cards and dictating the arrangements. This time around,<br />

that’s not really an option any more. But it’s not clear just where the leadership is. So is there<br />

any precedent for a multilateral agreement among countries for a new international currency<br />

regime?<br />

H: I think this mischaracterizes the issue. <strong>The</strong>re never was a multilateral currency system.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re was the US dictating to the rest <strong>of</strong> the world, as you point out. It used an internationalist<br />

rhetoric for nationalistic financial and trade purposes. That’s what my Super Imperialism<br />

(2003) was all about.<br />

E: Yes, that’s what I mean. That is what we always had before.<br />

H: <strong>The</strong> United States said to other countries: “We’ll never join a multinational system in<br />

which other countries can set our policy. We insist on veto power - or the power to simply<br />

490 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

ignore your recommendations. And for your part, you must do what we say, or we’ll do to<br />

you what we did to Iraq or Afghanistan. So get out <strong>of</strong> our way!”<br />

I think that other countries have given up hope <strong>of</strong> a multi-lateral system in which the<br />

United States will cooperate. So they’re creating a parallel system, namely as the BRIC<br />

countries have done. <strong>The</strong>y’re saying, “We’re going to avoid using the dollar altogether”.<br />

And the dollar’s own financial managers are turning it into nearly a pariah currency. This is<br />

what I wrote about in the Financial Times yesterday: the US refusal to cooperate with other<br />

countries, above all its double standard insisting that other countries must turn their foreignexchange<br />

surpluses over to the US Treasury to promote US financial markets at their expense<br />

- and the demand that any country running a trade surplus with America spend the money on<br />

US arms - is so abhorrent that other countries are proceeding to create an alternative global<br />

financial system <strong>of</strong> settling trade and balance-<strong>of</strong>-payments transactions without the United<br />

States.<br />

So what will emerge is a new multi-lateral financial system after all. But there will be<br />

two financial systems: one centered on the BRIC countries with strong trade balances and<br />

currency values, another system centered on the US dollar. Europe is likely to be left out,<br />

and may become an economic backwater, because so much <strong>of</strong> its politics are run by US<br />

aficionados. So I see a dual world monetary system and a dual world trade system operating<br />

under a different set <strong>of</strong> trade and financial rules.<br />

US diplomats no doubt will call this socialism. Other countries can reply, “What we’re<br />

doing is just what the French Physiocrats, Adam Smith, John Stuart Mill and the other major<br />

classical free-marketers wanted: no free lunch. If we’re socialists, what are you guys? We’re<br />

too polite to use the word, but it was used in World War Two.”<br />

E: On that note we’ll wrap it up. We appreciate your thoughts on this. It’s certainly going<br />

to be an interesting meeting coming up next month among the G20, and we’ll see what<br />

comes out <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

H: Have a glance at the article I wrote in the Financial Times [October 19 2010].<br />

E: Will do.<br />

H: I think that spelled out a lot <strong>of</strong> the logic <strong>of</strong> what I’ve just been talking about.<br />

E: Very good. Thank you very much Michael. Appreciate your time.<br />

H: It’s always good to talk to you.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [674].<br />

[664] Balrog: Pushing Others Down. I am in favor <strong>of</strong> our capitalistic society and feel<br />

that the pros <strong>of</strong> our current economic system outweigh the bad. As I continue to study the<br />

words and theory <strong>of</strong> Marx my eyes have been opened to some obvious holes that do exist<br />

capitalism. I recently had a conversation with a friend about the <strong>thing</strong>s that capitalists do in<br />

our society today to remain in power and maximize their pr<strong>of</strong>its without consideration for<br />

the overall well-being <strong>of</strong> their workers and society as a whole. We came to the conclusion<br />

that too <strong>of</strong>ten those in charge <strong>of</strong> Fortune 500 companies and those that are considered to be<br />

the wealthiest people in the world have screwed a lot <strong>of</strong> people to get there.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 491<br />

Examples are Albert H. Wiggin the former head <strong>of</strong> Chase National Bank who invented insider<br />

trading in the 1920s and Martha Stewart who was caught more recently. Meg Whitman<br />

and other billionaires hiding money through <strong>of</strong>fshore accounting. Lee Raymond a former<br />

chairman <strong>of</strong> Exxon and his $400 million pension. Pablo Escobar a Colombian drug Lord<br />

was the 7th richest man according to Forbes’s list in 1989. Mark Zuckerberg the founder<br />

<strong>of</strong> Facebook at an estimated current net worth <strong>of</strong> 6.9 billion dollars has had a number <strong>of</strong><br />

lawsuits filed by those who accuse him <strong>of</strong> dishonest and unscrupulous business actions that<br />

have helped him create his dynasty.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are some good people out <strong>of</strong> there but I feel that too <strong>of</strong>ten those who are at the<br />

top are those who pushed down the most people along the way and continue to exploit those<br />

beneath them.<br />

Message [664] referenced by [688]. Next Message by Balrog is [686].<br />

[688] Frida: Marx, societal roles, and regulation. In response to Balrog [664]: Marx<br />

would say that it is a contradiction to be in favor <strong>of</strong> a capitalistic society and be <strong>of</strong>fended by<br />

the actions <strong>of</strong> the richest in this society. Capitalism creates the social role <strong>of</strong> the capitalist,<br />

which is always filled by someone. It is not in human nature itself to so ruthlessly exploit<br />

others. If it were, we would not see nearly so much cooperation and kindness in society. It<br />

is also not just the characteristics <strong>of</strong> these individuals. It is the power <strong>of</strong> capital itself that<br />

creates these problems. <strong>The</strong>re is much anecdotal evidence to support this claim. <strong>The</strong>re are<br />

(almost?) no successful capitalists that have not taken advantage <strong>of</strong> others to get where they<br />

are. Capitalism feeds on surplus labor, which is impossible without exploitation <strong>of</strong> laborers.<br />

Capitalism would cease to exist without the atrocities that those at the top commit.<br />

As a side note, I’m curious: what exactly are the pros <strong>of</strong> the capitalist society that are<br />

supposed to outweigh the fact that capitalism has no regard for the health <strong>of</strong> the earth or the<br />

vast majority <strong>of</strong> humankind? Any sort <strong>of</strong> environmental or labor regulations, as I understand<br />

them, stand outside capitalism as a restraint and do not form a part <strong>of</strong> the body <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

itself. Also, welfare, social security and other social programs aren’t in accord with capitalist<br />

ideals. Am I mistaken in thinking that they form a separate body? One that is supposed to<br />

keep capitalism partially in check and ends up strengthening it in the end, because capitalism,<br />

left to its own devices, would eventually self-destruct? I would appreciate other’s ideas on<br />

this issue.<br />

Message [688] referenced by [690] and [729]. Next Message by Frida is [721].<br />

[690] Hans: Welfare a necessary part <strong>of</strong> capitalism. A quick answer to Frida’s question<br />

at the end <strong>of</strong> [688]: welfare and unemployment insurance etc. are an integral part <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism. Since capitalism creates poverty it needs institutions allowing people to survive<br />

despite poverty. <strong>The</strong>se institutions are intentionally demeaning, cumbersome, and intrusive,<br />

to encourage people to re-enter the workforce.<br />

Message [690] referenced by [729] and [818]. Next Message by Hans is [698].<br />

[729] Robert: Alive, humble and ready to go back to work. I think that Frida’s question<br />

at the end <strong>of</strong> her comments [688] and Hans’s response [690] pose a very interesting question<br />

about the necessity <strong>of</strong> welfare regulation within a capitalistic society. It makes logical sense<br />

that capitalism needs: a) healthy workers from which it can exploit value and b) peaceful<br />

workers who will not revolt against the system. <strong>The</strong>refore, capitalism, as Hans suggests,<br />

492 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

must provide programs that allow workers to survive poverty (to work another day) but to<br />

keep them demeaned enough so that they do not have the self-esteem to revolt.<br />

Interestingly, Frances Fox Piven and Richard A. Cloward published a book some time ago<br />

entitled, Regulating the Poor: <strong>The</strong> Functions <strong>of</strong> Public Welfare (Updated Edition 1993, New<br />

York: Vintage). It provides convincing evidence, from the Great Depression through the<br />

Bush I years, that public relief programs in the United States are employed by the government<br />

to avert uprisings by the working class during economic recession and to put pressure<br />

on the working class to seek employment during periods <strong>of</strong> economic growth.<br />

Welfare policy generally is another example <strong>of</strong> a phenomenon in capitalism that appears<br />

different on the surface than it really is. It calls for a Marxian “a closer look.” It may appear to<br />

be motivated by humanitarian compassion but in its implementation, again as Hans suggests,<br />

it is brutal and demeaning. It says in effect, “here’s enough to keep you alive, but you must<br />

not be much <strong>of</strong> a person to need this help...surely not enough <strong>of</strong> a person to question the<br />

powers-that-be. By the way, don’t get too comfortable with your dole, because when we<br />

need your labor we’ll decrease it and put pressure on you to return to the workforce and<br />

create more value for the owners <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production.”<br />

Next Message by Robert is [735].<br />

[759] Somramthom: Re: Valued labor or upkeep? Thinking about the distinction<br />

between labor-power and actual labor, I wonder if it would be accurate to compare laborpower<br />

to a sort <strong>of</strong> potential, while labor itself is a sort <strong>of</strong> action. As a worker you would<br />

sell your potential to the capitalist. <strong>The</strong> capitalist either sees your potential and agrees on a<br />

contract <strong>of</strong> some sort, sees your potential and <strong>of</strong>fers no contract, or doesn’t see your potential<br />

at all. In the case a contract is <strong>of</strong>fered and agreed upon, then the capitalist pays you (the<br />

laborer) for your actions (the manifestation <strong>of</strong> your potential, i.e. your labor). He is no<br />

longer focused on the potential you have, rather now he focuses on the actions you perform.<br />

Looking at it this way, it is evident it would not be a sustainable route for the capitalist<br />

nor the laborer to take to pay laborers according to their potential. While some short term<br />

gain may be realized by the laborer (getting paid for work you would never do), the unpleasant<br />

ramifications <strong>of</strong> a weak system where many laborers obtain wages for no labor and<br />

the economy depends on a few overworked laborers would produce some bleak long-term<br />

losses. <strong>The</strong> society as a whole would ultimately suffer.<br />

It may seem that workers get paid according to productivity. But Hans makes it perfectly<br />

clear that they do not, since capitalism is in essence the accumulation <strong>of</strong> surplus value<br />

through exploitation <strong>of</strong> laborers by the capitalist. It would seem that it isn’t the magnitude<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor that determines pay, but the exchange value <strong>of</strong> the laborer’s labor-power. <strong>The</strong> capitalist<br />

is paying for the commodity <strong>of</strong> labor-power. Like any other commodity, say gasoline<br />

for example, the magnitude doesn’t determine the value. If I purchase one gallon <strong>of</strong> gas or<br />

25 gallons <strong>of</strong> gas, it costs the same per gallon <strong>of</strong> gas.<br />

Thus, laborers whose labor-power has a higher exchange value than others will be valued<br />

more. Since wages in capitalism cannot exceed the value <strong>of</strong> the labor performed, the<br />

labor must be more valued in order for the laborer to receive an increase in wages, always<br />

maintaining an adequate level <strong>of</strong> surplus value for the business to be pr<strong>of</strong>itable.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 493<br />

But Hans states that wages are “determined by some<strong>thing</strong> which has no<strong>thing</strong> to do whatsoever<br />

with the work they perform.” Rather it depends on the upkeep <strong>of</strong> the laborer, i.e. the<br />

reproduction costs. How do these two differences match up?<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [766].<br />

[760] Hans: Great animated video about capitalist crises. Don’t miss the animated<br />

verson <strong>of</strong> David Harvey’s Crises <strong>of</strong> Capitalism at<br />

www.youtube.com/watch?v=qOP2V np2c0<br />

Message [760] referenced by [764] and [869]. Next Message by Hans is [765].<br />

[764] LuBr: David Harvey–moving beyond capitalism. Hans [760] posted a link to<br />

David Harvey’s animated version <strong>of</strong> the Crisis <strong>of</strong> Capitalism. It is a great practical application<br />

<strong>of</strong> Marxist theory and an important reminder <strong>of</strong> how we all must see beyond the current<br />

political debate about the Great Recession or Crisis <strong>of</strong> Capitalism.<br />

Harvey says that capitalism never solves its crises, it merely moves them around geographically.<br />

He uses a quote from Marx’s Grundrisse, where Marx says “capital cannot<br />

abide a limit.” Instead it turns these limits into barriers which it can just transcend and relocate.<br />

With the decline <strong>of</strong> real wages starting in the 70’s the problem <strong>of</strong> effective demand was<br />

solved by pumping up the credit economy, which led to mounting debt in shored up housing.<br />

Harvey explains that financial ingenuity was how capitalism was able to overcome the<br />

barriers that it faced with declining effective demand. This financial ingenuity ensured that<br />

those financiers who were at the financial technological frontier would be rewarded monetarily<br />

and with ever-increasing power. To the point that in the last few years, top hedge fund<br />

managers were earning upwards <strong>of</strong> $3 billion per year. Is this a world that we want to live<br />

in?<br />

David Harvey asks the most important, yet simplest question: where is the debate and<br />

discussion about this? And I agree. I think that in the midst <strong>of</strong> a crisis <strong>of</strong> capitalism, the<br />

only debate that has made headway within the United States is that <strong>of</strong> quantitative easing.<br />

Printing dollars that will flood emerging markets while serving to devalue our currency and<br />

inflate away our massive debt. Like Harvey says, capitalism never solves its crises, it just<br />

moves them around geographically. It seems to me as if we are shifting the barriers that this<br />

crisis exposed to avoid the limits <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system yet again.<br />

If anyone has time, I greatly recommend another speech by David Harvey, it was filmed<br />

and can be seen on Youtube (http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=YYQb0fthNfI).<br />

In line with what Harvey says, we should be actively debating how we apply all <strong>of</strong> this<br />

unemployed capital and labor towards meeting the social need <strong>of</strong> today. As Harvey says, we<br />

must craft a theory <strong>of</strong> social change and re-teach ourselves about socialism and communism<br />

in a mature and de-politicized way. In this theory <strong>of</strong> social change we must reexamine society’s<br />

present day relation to nature and how environmental limits must be respected by any<br />

future mode <strong>of</strong> production. In addition we must understand how technology has advanced<br />

to reinforce the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production. In doing so, we can better understand a new<br />

technological frontier that reproduces a more just and socialist mode <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

494 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

In sum, we are unfortunately failing to address the root <strong>of</strong> the crisis, and that is the inherent<br />

instability <strong>of</strong> the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production. Instead <strong>of</strong> using this opportunity for<br />

debate and discussion and opportunity for change we are diffusing the crisis geographically<br />

once again. This is a band-aid solution. Capitalism may be able to shift its crises geographically<br />

but the ecological limits that we are bumping up against will prove to be a limit that<br />

not even capitalist innovation and technology can evade.<br />

Next Message by LuBr is [931].<br />

[818] Husani: Welfare in Capitalism. I was watching CNBC yesterday and the program<br />

that was on at the time brought up an interesting question. Should people be allowed to opt<br />

out <strong>of</strong> social security? What I found interesting about the question is that as far as I know<br />

people today are paying into the system to help the currently retired and the next generation<br />

will do the same. I find it interesting that the wealthy aren’t interested in helping the poor<br />

people in our country and would like to keep their money, made by exploiting the poor, all<br />

to themselves. Hans said in [690] “welfare and unemployment insurance etc. are an integral<br />

part <strong>of</strong> capitalism. Since capitalism creates poverty it needs institutions allowing people to<br />

survive despite poverty.” I wonder what would happen if the wealthy had their way and the<br />

poor were allowed to starve?<br />

Next Message by Husani is [868].<br />

[820] Bigwhite: Good ol Capitalism. So while i was listening to my ipod i heard a very<br />

good line from a rapper out <strong>of</strong> California, it went like this ”Capitalism is pimps and hoes<br />

i guess any<strong>thing</strong> goes. I know its maybe not quite appropriate for this class yet it did shed<br />

light on the discussions we’ve been having about labor and wages. In the system <strong>of</strong> a pimp<br />

and hoe the pimp gets most <strong>of</strong> the money while the hoe does all the work and labor and some<br />

would say is exploited to the fullest extent. I did make me feel like this is capitalism at its<br />

roots. And even though you may not be a hoe you are being exploited like one in your job.<br />

Next Message by Bigwhite is [929].<br />

[823] Somramthom: Resubmission etiquette. I am not sure if what I just submitted is<br />

allowed in the class. I answered an exam question ungraded a couple <strong>of</strong> days ago and just<br />

found out it is one <strong>of</strong> the questions we can answer for extra credit. So I resubmitted the same<br />

question only it was not tagged as ungraded and instead labeled as Extra credit. Is this okay?<br />

If not, I apologize.<br />

Hans: Your resubmission does not qualify for the extra credit because it did not clarify any<strong>thing</strong> that wasn’t there<br />

before. But I turned your earlier submission [766] into a graded submission.<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [824].<br />

[840] Guh: Economic Instability. In one <strong>of</strong> my Economic class that I am taking this<br />

semester, Current Economic Problems, the pr<strong>of</strong>essor asked us to compare and contrast free<br />

market/conservative economist and liberal economist on the their views <strong>of</strong> the source <strong>of</strong><br />

economic instability. So I gave my opinion and said that I think free market economist<br />

admits that a system driven by freely operating markets will be subject to an occasional<br />

bouts <strong>of</strong> instability. This might include bouts <strong>of</strong> inflation, unemployment and slow negative<br />

growth, as well as that the government should not intervene. Now, as for a liberal economist,<br />

who I find them to believe that through government tax and spending power, could ultimately<br />

eliminate, or at least s<strong>of</strong>ten the sharp reduction in economic activity and as a result would<br />

leave the economy in a more stable and balance place, with less instability.<br />

Message [840] referenced by [872]. Next Message by Guh is [874].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 495<br />

[869] Atticus: Ignorance and the True Origin <strong>of</strong> Value. <strong>The</strong> video Hans posted in [760]<br />

was useful in supplementing my understanding <strong>of</strong> how capitalism has inherent contradictions<br />

that ultimately lead to crises no matter what monetary <strong>of</strong> fiscal policy tweak is undertaken<br />

unless it is one that involves a total reformation <strong>of</strong> the current system. It neatly summarized<br />

some <strong>of</strong> the <strong>thing</strong>s I learned that I feel would be useful. A major flaw in modern economic<br />

practices and theories is not acknowledging that prices are determined by the labor power<br />

that is expended in creating value that is congealed in the total output by particular social<br />

relations created by capitalism. <strong>The</strong> fluctuations in prices are due to imbalances in output and<br />

demand indicate to producers that production processes need modification and the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

required labor power needs to be adjusted. However, this theory fails to explain why prices<br />

are what they are in equilibrium.<br />

<strong>The</strong> natural level <strong>of</strong> output should really be called the average natural level at which labor<br />

power is expended in the long run. <strong>The</strong> tendencies <strong>of</strong> capitalism, intensification in the<br />

divisions in labor and the private ownership <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production (or means <strong>of</strong> subsistence)<br />

creates a crisis in the class structure <strong>of</strong> modern capitalistic countries. <strong>The</strong> small<br />

capitalist class consists <strong>of</strong> a small minority <strong>of</strong> people who own the means <strong>of</strong> subsistence and<br />

become increasingly powerful by indirectly reducing the standard <strong>of</strong> living <strong>of</strong> the proletariat<br />

by increasing productivity and decreasing production costs. Capitalism creates an insatiable<br />

need to compete for an edge on competition and gain extra surplus value essentially to survive.<br />

This constant drive to gain extra surplus value eventually leads to an overall increase in<br />

relative surplus value, cheapening <strong>of</strong> commodities <strong>of</strong> labor costs, huge strains on the environment<br />

and greater class struggles. Capitalists make gains by exploiting laborers who believe<br />

that they are being paid fairly and their employers make pr<strong>of</strong>it only through markups. True<br />

markups only create price increases for everyone, including capitalists, and real pr<strong>of</strong>its are<br />

gained by paying wages not equal to the value created remains largely unknown to the proletariat<br />

class. <strong>The</strong> disparity in the distribution in wealth between capitalists and laborers is<br />

a crisis in itself. This phenomenon seemingly will not forcibly correct itself until capitalism<br />

completely collapses through either revolutionary changes or the strains on the environment<br />

caused by capitalism finally become too great and natural catastrophes force the human race<br />

to adapt to radical changes in the means <strong>of</strong> subsistence.<br />

What has caused this crisis to go on for as long as it has is due to another crisis caused by<br />

the financial system. Value and the quantity <strong>of</strong> money representing this value have drifted so<br />

far apart from one another due to the fetish-like behavior that commodity production creates<br />

in capitalistic societies. <strong>The</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> debt accrued represents an extremely high amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> value that has not yet been created by the expenditure <strong>of</strong> labor power. To temporarily<br />

ease the symptoms <strong>of</strong> the terminally ill capitalistic economy certain policy changes in the<br />

economic structured need to modified to reverse the disequilibrium and pay <strong>of</strong>f the enormous<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> debt through significantly decreased consumption and the equalization <strong>of</strong><br />

money representing value and actual value created by the expenditure <strong>of</strong> labor power. However,<br />

contradictions intrinsic in capitalism will only create future crises until an unavoidable<br />

upheaval in the system drastically changes the means <strong>of</strong> human subsistence.<br />

Next Message by Atticus is [966].<br />

[872] Kobe: response to Guh. Im writing in response to Guh [840] talking about the issue<br />

<strong>of</strong> free trade policy. Free market advocated believe the benefits <strong>of</strong> free trade are substantial.<br />

496 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Through free trade policy, a countries real income rises which allows citizens the opportunity<br />

to consumer more. Because citizens will have the opportunity to consume more they will be<br />

able to afford better health care, food etc. <strong>The</strong>se gains are based on the gains that are made<br />

form the exchange as well as from specialization. A liberal economist discussing free trade<br />

policy believes that there should be government interference through tariffs and taxes. This<br />

is the case for many poor countries because they lack the foundation to have a competitive<br />

free trade market. Poor countries that are undeveloped also lack the opportunity to collect<br />

taxes, through tariffs this would give them the best opportunity to do so. <strong>The</strong> topic <strong>of</strong> free<br />

trade policy is heavily debated and I am not sure I could pick exactly which one I think is<br />

the best, what I do know is that each case should be evaluated by the economic stability <strong>of</strong><br />

the country not by a universal yes or no to free market trade.<br />

Message [872] referenced by [2011fa:1070]. Next Message by Kobe is [952].<br />

[873] Goldtone: I have the means <strong>of</strong> production, now what? My sister bought a<br />

small business recently. This small business sells ice cream, has one location, and two<br />

employees. Due to the fact that they are small and not well known, they currently are not<br />

getting much business, and hence are essentially working for free—actually are working and<br />

yet still losing money. This is despite the fact that she has complete control over the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production.<br />

I think a big advantage <strong>of</strong> working for a large capitalist corporation that has access to the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production—like cold stone compared to my sisters shop—is the fact that, not only<br />

do you always get paid, but as a worker you do not have to worry about advertising, creating<br />

prices, management decisions, wage decisions, menu items, business financial planning, etc.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are many reasons why working for a large company in a capitalist system is better than<br />

trying to start up your own system and means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

I wanted to bring up this point because I believe that the means <strong>of</strong> production is not the<br />

only <strong>thing</strong> that drives exploitation.<br />

For fellow students that read this, I would like to ask how you think Marx would explains<br />

this phenomenon in capitalism? Are <strong>thing</strong>s like size, capital, and ability to advertise a part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production according to Marx? I do not think they are. I think they are other<br />

means used to exploit workers and small businesses.<br />

Next Message by Goldtone is [1078].<br />

[952] Kobe: where does money come from. Where does a capitalist get his original<br />

capital from? When deciding upon where capital derives from we must leave out <strong>of</strong> consideration<br />

the portion <strong>of</strong> the surplus value consumed by the capitalist as well as assuming he<br />

keeps the gains in capital rather than giving it to someone else. Capital when made continues<br />

to reproduce itself and produces surplus value. This can be explained by someone getting<br />

an inheritance then buying capital with the capital that they <strong>first</strong> had. By buying more <strong>of</strong><br />

a commodity this gives the capitalist surplus value, he now has more capital. He can then<br />

sell it for even more and the cycle is self repeating. Marx writes that “by his own labor and<br />

that <strong>of</strong> his forefathers,” he is possessed with this capital. This supposition is the only one<br />

constant with the laws <strong>of</strong> the production <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Next Message by Kobe is [953].<br />

[999] Max: <strong>The</strong> Jungle. By Upton Sinclair.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 497<br />

‘You listen to these <strong>thing</strong>s,’ the man was saying, ’and you say, “Yes, they are true, but<br />

they have been that way always.” Or you say, “Maybe it will come, but not in my time - it<br />

will not help me.” And so you return to your daily round <strong>of</strong> toil, you go back to be ground<br />

up for pr<strong>of</strong>its in the world-wide mill <strong>of</strong> economic might! To toil squalid homes, to work<br />

in dangerous and unhealthful places; to wrestle with the specters <strong>of</strong> hunger and privation,<br />

to take your chances <strong>of</strong> accident, disease, and death. And each day the struggle becomes<br />

fiercer, the pace more cruel; each day you have to toil a little harder, and feel the iron hand<br />

<strong>of</strong> circumstance close upon you a little tighter. Months pass, years maybe - and then you<br />

come again; and again I am here to plead with you, to know if want and misery have yet<br />

done their work with you, if injustice and oppression have yet opened your eyes! I shall<br />

still be waiting - there is no<strong>thing</strong> else that I can do. <strong>The</strong>re is no wilderness where I can hide<br />

from these <strong>thing</strong>s, there is no haven where I can escape them; though I travel to the ends<br />

<strong>of</strong> the earth, I find the same accursed system - I find that all the fair and noble impulses <strong>of</strong><br />

humanity, the dreams <strong>of</strong> poets and the agonies <strong>of</strong> martyrs, are shackled and bound in the<br />

service <strong>of</strong> organized and predatory Greed! And therefore I cannot rest, I cannot be silent;<br />

therefore I cast aside comfort and happiness, health and good repute - and go out into the<br />

world and cry out the pain <strong>of</strong> my spirit! <strong>The</strong>refore I am not to be silenced by poverty and<br />

sickness, not by hatred and obloquy, by threats and ridicule - not by prison and persecution,<br />

if they should come - not by any power that is upon the earth or above the earth, that was,<br />

or is, or ever can be created. If I ail tonight, I can only try tomorrow; knowing that the<br />

fault must be mine - that if once the vision <strong>of</strong> my soul were spoken upon earth, if once the<br />

anguish <strong>of</strong> its defeat were uttered in human speech, it would break the stoutest barriers <strong>of</strong><br />

prejudice, it would shake the most sluggish soul to action! it would abash the most cynical,<br />

it would terrify the most selfish; and the voice <strong>of</strong> mocker would be silenced, and fraud and<br />

falsehood would slink back into their dens, and the truth would stand forth alone! For I<br />

speak with the voice <strong>of</strong> the millions who are voiceless! Of them that are oppressed and have<br />

no comforter! Of the disinherited <strong>of</strong> life, for whom there is no respite and no deliverance, to<br />

whom the world is a prison, a dungeon <strong>of</strong> torture, a tomb! With the voice <strong>of</strong> the little child<br />

who toils tonight in a Souther cotton mill, staggering with exhaustion, numb with agony,<br />

and knowing no hope but the grave! Of the mother who sews by candlelight in her tenement<br />

garret, weary and weeping, smitten with the mortal hunger <strong>of</strong> her babes! Of the man who<br />

lies upon a bed <strong>of</strong> rags, wrestling in his last sickness and leaving his loved ones to perish!<br />

Of the young girl who, somewhere at this moment, is walking the streets <strong>of</strong> this horrible<br />

city, beaten and starving, and making her choice between the brothel and the lake! With the<br />

voice <strong>of</strong> humanity, calling for deliverance! Of the everlasting soul <strong>of</strong> man, arising from the<br />

dust; breaking its way out <strong>of</strong> its prison - rending the bands <strong>of</strong> oppression and ignorance -<br />

groping its way to the light!’... ‘ I plead with you,’ he said, ’whoever you may be, provided<br />

that you care about the truth; but most <strong>of</strong> all I plead with workingmen, with those to whom<br />

the evils I portray are not mere matters <strong>of</strong> sentiment, to be dallied and toyed with, and then<br />

perhaps put aside and forgotten - to whom they are the grim and relentless realities <strong>of</strong> the<br />

daily grind, the chains upon their limbs, the lash upon their backs, the iron in their souls. To<br />

you, workingmen! To you, the toilers, who have made this land, and have no voice in its<br />

councils! To you, whose lot it is to sow that others may reap, to labor and obey, and ask no<br />

more than the wages <strong>of</strong> a beast <strong>of</strong> burden, the food and shelter to keep you alive from day to<br />

day. It is to you that I come with my message <strong>of</strong> salvation, it is to you that I appeal. I know<br />

498 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

how much it is to ask <strong>of</strong> you - I know, for I have been in your place, I have lived your life,<br />

and there is no man before me here tonight who knows it better. I have known what it is to be<br />

a street waif, a boot-black, living upon a crust <strong>of</strong> bread and sleeping in cellar stairways and<br />

under empty wagons. I have known what it is to dare and to aspire, to dream might dreams<br />

and to see them perish - to see all the fair flowers <strong>of</strong> my spirit trampled into the mire by the<br />

wild beast powers <strong>of</strong> life. I know what is the price that a workingman pays for knowledge<br />

- I have paid for it with food and sleep, with agony <strong>of</strong> body and mind, with health, almost<br />

with life itself; and so, when I come to you with a story <strong>of</strong> hope and freedom, with the vision<br />

<strong>of</strong> a new earth to be created, <strong>of</strong> a new labor to be dared, I am not surprised that I find you<br />

sordid and material, sluggish and incredulous. That I do not despair is because I know also<br />

the forces that are driving behind you - because I know the raging lash <strong>of</strong> poverty, the sting<br />

<strong>of</strong> contempt and mastership, ‘the insolence <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>fice and the spurns.’ Because I feel sure that<br />

in the crowd that has come to me tonight, no matter how many may be dull and heedless,<br />

no matter how many may have come out <strong>of</strong> idle curiosity, or in order to ridicule - there<br />

will be some one man whom pain and suffering have made desperate, whom some chance<br />

vision <strong>of</strong> wrong and horror has startled and shocked into attention. And to him my words<br />

will come like a sudden flash <strong>of</strong> lightning to one who travels in darkness - revealing the way<br />

before him, the perils and the obstacles - solving all problems, making all difficulties clear!<br />

<strong>The</strong> scales will fall from his eyes, the shackles will be torn from his limbs - he will leap<br />

up with a cry <strong>of</strong> thankfulness, he will stride forth a free man at last! A man delivered from<br />

his self-created slavery! A man who will never more be trapped - whom no blandishments<br />

will cajole, whom no threats will frighten; who from tonight on will move forward, and not<br />

backward, who will study and understand, who will gird on his sword and take his place in<br />

the army <strong>of</strong> his comrades and brothers. Who will carry the good tidings to others, as I have<br />

carried them to him - the priceless gift <strong>of</strong> liberty and light that is neither mine nor his, but is<br />

the heritage <strong>of</strong> the soul <strong>of</strong> man! Workingmen, workingmen - comrades! open your eyes and<br />

look about you! You have lived so long in the toil and heat that your senses are dulled, your<br />

souls are numbed; but realize once in your lives this world in which you dwell - tear <strong>of</strong>f the<br />

rags <strong>of</strong> its customs and conventions - behold it as it is, in all its hideous nakedness! Realize<br />

it, realize it! Realize that out upon the plains <strong>of</strong> Manchuria tonight two hostile armies are<br />

facing each other - that now, while we are seated here, a million human beings may be hurled<br />

at each other’s throats, striving with the fury <strong>of</strong> maniacs to tear each other to pieces! And this<br />

in the twentieth century, nineteen hundred years since the Prince <strong>of</strong> Peace was born on earth!<br />

Nineteen hundred years that his words have been preached as divine, and here two armies <strong>of</strong><br />

men are rending and tearing each other like the wild beasts <strong>of</strong> the forest! Philosophers have<br />

reasoned, prophets have denounced, poets have wept and pleaded - and still this hideous<br />

Monster roams at large! We have schools and colleges, newspapers and books; we have<br />

searched the heavens and the earth, we have weighed and probed and reasoned - and all to<br />

equip men to destroy each other! We call it War, and pass it by - but do not put me <strong>of</strong>f with<br />

platitudes and conventions - come with me, come with me - realize it! See the bodies <strong>of</strong> men<br />

pierced by bullets, blown into pieces by bursting shells! Hear the crunching <strong>of</strong> the bayonet,<br />

plunged into human flesh; hear the groans and shrieks <strong>of</strong> agony, see the faces <strong>of</strong> men crazed<br />

by pain, turned into fiends by fury and hate! Put your hand upon that piece <strong>of</strong> flesh - it is hot<br />

and quivering - just now it was a part <strong>of</strong> a man! This blood is still steaming - it was driven by<br />

a human heart! Almighty God! and this goes on - it is systematic, organized, premeditated!


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 499<br />

And we know it, and read <strong>of</strong> it, and take if for granted; our papers tell <strong>of</strong> it, and the presses<br />

are not stopped - our churches know <strong>of</strong> it, and do not close their doors - the people behold<br />

it, and do not rise up in horror and revolution!<br />

’Or perhaps Manchuria is too far away for you - come home with me then, come here<br />

to Chicago. Here in this city tonight ten thousand women are shut up in foul pens, and<br />

driven by hunger to sell their bodies to live. And we know it, we make it a jest! And these<br />

women are made in the image <strong>of</strong> your mothers, they may be your sisters, your daughters;<br />

the child whom you left at home tonight, whose laughing eyes will greet you in the morning<br />

- that fate may be waiting for her! Tonight in Chicago there are ten thousand men, homeless<br />

and wretched, willing to work and begging for a chance, yet starving, and fronting in terror<br />

the awful winter cold! Tonight in Chicago there are a hundred thousand mothers who are<br />

living in misery and squalor, struggling to earn enough to feed their little ones! <strong>The</strong>re are<br />

a hundred thousand old people, cast <strong>of</strong>f and helpless, waiting for death to take them from<br />

their torments! <strong>The</strong>re are a million people, men and women and children, who share the<br />

curse <strong>of</strong> the wage-slave; who toil every hour they can stand and see, for just enough to keep<br />

them alive; who are condemned till the end <strong>of</strong> their days to monotony and weariness, to<br />

hunger and misery, to heat and cold, to dirt and disease, to ignorance and drunkenness and<br />

vice! And then turn over the page with me and gaze upon the other side <strong>of</strong> the picture.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are a thousand - ten thousand, maybe - who are the masters <strong>of</strong> these slaves, who own<br />

their toil. <strong>The</strong>y do no<strong>thing</strong> to earn what they received, they do not even have to ask for it<br />

- it comes to them <strong>of</strong> itself, their only care is to dispose <strong>of</strong> it. <strong>The</strong>y live in palaces, they<br />

riot in luxury and extravagance - such as no words can describe, as makes the imagination<br />

reel and stagger, makes the soul grow sick and faint. <strong>The</strong>y spend hundreds <strong>of</strong> dollars for<br />

a pair <strong>of</strong> shoes, a handkerchief, a garter; they spend millions for horses and automobiles<br />

and yachts, for palaces and banquets, for little shiny stones with which to deck their bodies.<br />

<strong>The</strong>ir life is a contest among themselves for supremacy in ostentation and recklessness, in<br />

the destroying <strong>of</strong> useful and necessary <strong>thing</strong>s, in the wasting <strong>of</strong> the labor and the lives <strong>of</strong><br />

their fellow creatures, the toil and anguish <strong>of</strong> the nations, the sweat and tears and blood <strong>of</strong><br />

the human race! It is all theirs - it comes to them; just as all the springs pour into streamlets,<br />

and the streamlets into rivers, and the rivers into the ocean - so, automatically and inevitably,<br />

all the wealth <strong>of</strong> society comes to them. <strong>The</strong> farmer tills the soil, the minder digs in the earth,<br />

the weaver tends the loom, the mason carves the stone; the clever man invents, the shrewd<br />

man directs, the wise man studies, the inspired man sings - and all the result, the products<br />

<strong>of</strong> the labor <strong>of</strong> brain and muscle, are gathered into one stupendous stream and puoured into<br />

their laps! <strong>The</strong> whole <strong>of</strong> society is in their grip, the whole labor <strong>of</strong> the world lies at their<br />

mercy - and like fierce wolves they rend and destroy, like ravening vultures they devour and<br />

tear! <strong>The</strong> whole power <strong>of</strong> mankind belongs to them, forever and beyond recall - do what it<br />

can, strive as it will, humanity lives for them and dies for them! <strong>The</strong>y own not merely the<br />

labor <strong>of</strong> society, they have bought the governments; and everywhere they use their raped and<br />

stolen power to intrench themselves in their privileges, to dig wider and deeper the channels<br />

through which the river <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its flows to them! - And you, workingmen, workingmen! You<br />

have been brought up to it, you plod on like beasts <strong>of</strong> burden, thinking only <strong>of</strong> the day and<br />

its pain - yet is there a man among you who can believe that such a system will continue<br />

forever - is there a man here in this audience tonight so hardened and debased that he dare<br />

500 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

rise up before me and say that he believes it can continue forever; that the product <strong>of</strong> the<br />

labor <strong>of</strong> society, the means <strong>of</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> the human race, will always belong to idlers and<br />

parasites, to be spent for the gratification <strong>of</strong> vanity and lust - to be spent for any purpose<br />

whatever, to be at the disposal <strong>of</strong> any individual will whatever - that somehow, somewhere,<br />

the labor <strong>of</strong> humanity will not belong to humanity, to be used for the purposes <strong>of</strong> humanity,<br />

to be controlled by the will <strong>of</strong> humanity? And if this is ever to be, how is it to be - what<br />

power is there that will bring it about? Will it be the task <strong>of</strong> your masters, do you think -<br />

will they write the charter <strong>of</strong> your liberties? Will they forge you the sword <strong>of</strong> deliverance,<br />

will they marshal you the army and lead it to the ray? Will their wealth be spent for the<br />

purpose - will they build colleges and churches to teach you, will they print papers to herald<br />

your progress, and organize political parties to guide and carry on the struggle? Can you<br />

not see that the task is your task - yours to dream, yours to resolve, yours to execute? That<br />

if ever it is carried out, it will be in the face <strong>of</strong> every obstacle that wealth and mastership<br />

can oppose - in the face <strong>of</strong> ridicule and slander, <strong>of</strong> hatred and persecution, <strong>of</strong> the bludgeon<br />

and the jail? That it will be by the power <strong>of</strong> your naked bosoms, opposed to the rage <strong>of</strong><br />

oppression! By the grim and bitter teaching <strong>of</strong> blind and merciless affliction! By the painful<br />

groping <strong>of</strong> the untutored mind, by the feeble stammerings <strong>of</strong> the uncultured voice! By the<br />

sad and lonely hunger <strong>of</strong> the spirit; by seeking and striving and yearning, by heartache and<br />

despairing, by agony and sweat <strong>of</strong> blood! It will be by money paid for with hunger, by<br />

knowledge stolen from sleep, by thoughts communicated under the shadow <strong>of</strong> the gallows!<br />

It will be a movement beginning in the far <strong>of</strong>f past, a <strong>thing</strong> obscure and unhonored, a <strong>thing</strong><br />

easy to ridicule, easy to despise; a <strong>thing</strong> unlovely, wearing the aspect <strong>of</strong> vengeance and hate<br />

- but to you, the workingman, the wage slave, calling with a voice insistent, imperious - with<br />

a voice that you cannot escape, wherever upon the earth you may be! With the voice <strong>of</strong> all<br />

your wrongs, with the voice <strong>of</strong> all your desires; with the voice <strong>of</strong> your duty and your hope -<br />

<strong>of</strong> every<strong>thing</strong> in the world that is worth while to you! <strong>The</strong> voice <strong>of</strong> the poor, demanding that<br />

poverty shall cease! <strong>The</strong> voice <strong>of</strong> the oppressed, pronouncing the doom <strong>of</strong> oppression! <strong>The</strong><br />

voice <strong>of</strong> power, wrought out <strong>of</strong> suffering - <strong>of</strong> resolution, crushed out <strong>of</strong> weakness - <strong>of</strong> joy<br />

and courage, born in the bottomless pit <strong>of</strong> anguish and despair! <strong>The</strong> voice <strong>of</strong> Labor, despised<br />

and outraged; a mighty giant, lying prostrate - mountainous, colossal, but blinded, bound,<br />

and ignorant <strong>of</strong> his strength. And now a dream <strong>of</strong> resistance haunts him, hope battling with<br />

fear; until suddenly he stirs and a fetter snaps - and a thrill shoots through him, to the farthest<br />

ends <strong>of</strong> his huge body, and in a flash the dream becomes an act! He starts, he lifts himself;<br />

and the bands are shattered, the burdens roll <strong>of</strong>f him; he rises - towering, gigantic; he springs<br />

to his feet, he shouts in his new-born exultation -’<br />

p. 299-303 Read this book.<br />

Message [999] referenced by [1000]. Next Message by Max is [1031].<br />

[1000] LuBr: Thank you to Max who provided the excerpt from <strong>The</strong> Jungle [999], I really<br />

enjoyed reading it, and it makes me want to go back and read the book again after having<br />

taken this course.<br />

It is scary that capitalism leaves the majority <strong>of</strong> us with no choice but to sell our laborpower<br />

for a barely sufficient wage. <strong>The</strong> fact that life in a highly capitalist society is to a large<br />

degree left up to luck. Some people have the good fortune <strong>of</strong> having money saved, but a large<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> people are working two or even three jobs, and have high expenses for their car,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 501<br />

rent, food, that leave them with little else to save. Should a string <strong>of</strong> bad luck come their<br />

way they could lose every<strong>thing</strong> they have worked for. <strong>The</strong> fact is that an unsettling amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> people in this country are not very far away from living on the streets. All it would take<br />

would be a serious injury or sickness to yourself or a family member and to not be insured, a<br />

car accident, a natural disaster, etc. <strong>The</strong>se events, which are more or less random, can mean<br />

a person could lose every<strong>thing</strong>. And this could happen even if this person was working two<br />

or three amounting to every waking hour. It is a thankless and very de-humanizing mode <strong>of</strong><br />

production for the majority <strong>of</strong> the working-class.<br />

Next Message by LuBr is [1164].<br />

[1003] Guh: Health Care. I was reading in one my classes how the neoclassical model<br />

doesn’t apply to health care markets. Furthermore, when thinking about this, I found myself<br />

thinking <strong>of</strong> what I believed to be two <strong>of</strong> the biggest problems that the US health care system<br />

has. I came to the thought that with the escalating health care cost has become unbearable<br />

and is running up our deficit drastically. How to fix this is the huge debate, and that involves<br />

talking with insurance providers, and hospitals to get a more reasonable price. <strong>The</strong> second<br />

problem, and yes I am aware there are more than two problems, but again I am just thinking<br />

what are the two biggest... Now, again the second problem that I see is in the expenditures<br />

price times quantity p*q. We as Americans consume more health care and the price <strong>of</strong> that<br />

health care is rising so we see both driving the costs up. I don’t have a fix it solution, but<br />

just wanted to express my thoughts and on the matter. <strong>The</strong> billion dollar question literally,<br />

is how to fix this.<br />

Message [1003] referenced by [1141]. Next Message by Guh is [1036].<br />

[1012] Fisher: Current recession. I was in another class where we have been talking<br />

about the current situation in our economy and it seems that the blame shouldnt go to one<br />

president, but to many presidents and their decisions. Ronald Reagan began a trend <strong>of</strong><br />

deregulation and corporate tax cuts that has carried on until our current president. Couple<br />

the lack <strong>of</strong> wall street regulation <strong>of</strong> derivatives and CMO’s with the tax cuts and we have our<br />

current situation. Once deregulation occured and Wall Street was free to sell CMO packages,<br />

moral hazard crept into the equation and the banks were <strong>of</strong>f the hook. Agree?<br />

Message [1012] referenced by [1142]. Next Message by Fisher is [1050].<br />

[1017] Bigwhite: Capitalism. Is anyone on the side <strong>of</strong> the capitalist? I’m thinking in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> them providing jobs, income, and goods for people. <strong>The</strong>re is the bad side <strong>of</strong> it<br />

all but do the cons outweigh the pros? You can also argue that they are a product <strong>of</strong> their<br />

environment—yes they are money driven but that is how they were taught/raised in a sense.<br />

I feel after reading Marx that the laborers are certainly getting the short end <strong>of</strong> the stick, but<br />

what is the alternative? Is the grass really greener on the other side? It seems that you cannot<br />

please everyone, there will be someone complaining in any economic structure.<br />

Message [1017] referenced by [1018], [1021], [1028], and [1032]. Next Message by Bigwhite is [1092].<br />

[1018] School: Can we reach an agreement? Bigwhite in [1017] brings up a valid point:<br />

no matter what type <strong>of</strong> economic structure we are in, no one can or will be 100 percent<br />

completely satisfied. As humans we are conditioned to view situations and take sides. What<br />

is right for me won’t always be right for others. In certain aspects <strong>of</strong> life we can find that<br />

in this life we have certain norms and truths. Meaning we all know it to be true that we<br />

are all people that are equal to one another. We all have needs which are food, shelter,<br />

and emotional interaction with one another. <strong>The</strong>se necessities <strong>of</strong> life are what defines us<br />

502 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

as people, and it should be that because <strong>of</strong> these basic needs this is where we should find<br />

our middle ground. Exploitation does exist but there are fantastic <strong>thing</strong>s that come from<br />

capitalism. Like for example capitalists can get tax breaks from the government if they<br />

provide to society a public service like tuition reimbursement, or charities to benefit third<br />

world countries. Those <strong>thing</strong>s wouldn’t exist if capitalists didn’t get some sort <strong>of</strong> benefit,<br />

but yet they better our society as a whole.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is good and there is bad, but also has to be middle grounds where we can coexist,<br />

because our needs are the same! It’s when we confuse our wants with our needs that define<br />

what type <strong>of</strong> person we really are.<br />

Next Message by School is [1069].<br />

[1021] Kleenex: I never thought about that before... I’d like to add to Bigwhite’s<br />

free discussion contribution [1017]. <strong>The</strong> discussion I’ve been reading in the e-mails speak<br />

more favorably upon Marxism than capitalism. I don’t think that everyone in this class is<br />

a Marxist, necessarily, but being immersed in Marx’s literature through the readings and<br />

the interpretations in the Annotations, speaking for myself, I can’t help but think about the<br />

pros <strong>of</strong> what Marx is saying. Even at the most basic level, I’ve never thought <strong>of</strong> value<br />

originating from labor: it was always “what was on the price tag” for me. Going back to<br />

the beginning <strong>of</strong> this course, congealed human labor would’ve never crossed my mind as<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> contributing to value. Though I see merits to what Marx says, especially in his<br />

discussion on the capitalist and how he exploits the worker, I see capitalism as a way to<br />

better technologies, processes, and products through free competition and laissez faire.<br />

Message [1021] referenced by [1031]. Next Message by Kleenex is [1040].<br />

[1028] SMIKEC: Capitalism. As stated by Bigwhite [1017] the capitalist does get the<br />

short end <strong>of</strong> the stick when it comes to being the bad guy. Society looks at the capitalist<br />

as being the greedy one, but if it wasn’t for the capitalist, where would all <strong>of</strong> the laborers<br />

be. <strong>The</strong> capitalist is the one who takes the up-front risk <strong>of</strong> starting a business. Whether it’s<br />

a devotion <strong>of</strong> time or financial undertaking, they are taking the chance to make a business<br />

successful and for this they should be rewarded for creating jobs and pumping more revenue<br />

into the economy. I think it’s at the point where they want more and more and are not<br />

satisfied with their original projections is where society throws the greed card in disgust,<br />

giving capitalist as a whole the bad wrap.<br />

Message [1028] referenced by [1032]. Next Message by SMIKEC is [1072].<br />

[1031] Max: I never thought about that before... I will agree with [1021]. If it weren’t<br />

for capitalism, we wouldn’t have innovative products like the iPhone! Now we can listen to<br />

music and call people at the same time! However, if all that labor power and inventiveness<br />

that it took to create the iphone went into some<strong>thing</strong> that would benefit society - say ending<br />

childhood hunger, fighting cancer, or building windmills - our society would actually be a<br />

more pleasant place to live. It is a problem that in our capitalist world, people see material<br />

items as a gauge for quality <strong>of</strong> life. What has the iphone really given us? A status symbol?<br />

Capitalism is a great social system for the production <strong>of</strong> frivolous items. I would much rather<br />

live in a society that had cured cancer than invented the iphone.<br />

Message [1031] referenced by [1050]. Next Message by Max is [1087].<br />

[1032] Jo: Re: Capitalism. I would like to contribute to the discussion on Capitalism that<br />

BigWhite [1017] started and SMIKEC [1028] has also contributed to. When I began reading


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 503<br />

Capital (I read it for the <strong>first</strong> time for this class), I found that my old ways <strong>of</strong> thinking were<br />

useless in my endeavor to understand what Marx is getting at. <strong>The</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> the capitalist<br />

providing “jobs, income, and goods for people” is a very capitalist mindset. I understand<br />

how someone would arrive at that conclusion. I think what Marx is doing is trying to get us<br />

to think about it differently.<br />

In my limited understanding, it seems that Marx is asserting that everyone is involved in<br />

innovation, production <strong>of</strong> value, and job creation. We are all connected in the process <strong>of</strong><br />

fulfilling basic human needs. Not only that, but any one person’s achievement is derived<br />

from the sum <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> the labor and achievement that came before him, therefore it is everyone’s<br />

achievement. Everyone’s contribution, from the laborer, to the teacher, to the scientist,<br />

is vital and therefore equally valuable. Every job needs to be done - some people are just<br />

better suited to certain jobs.<br />

I don’t assume that capitalists are inherently greedy - I am more concerned about the<br />

system <strong>of</strong> capitalism and its tendency to promote greed and oppression. It also does not<br />

make sense to support a system that is not sustainable. We live in a finite world, with a finite<br />

supply <strong>of</strong> resources. Capitalism operates on the principle <strong>of</strong> infinite growth, which is simply<br />

not possible in a finite world. Not only is it not possible, but it is incredibly harmful to the<br />

planet and to society.<br />

I highly recommend this recent interview with Chilean economist Manfred Max-Neef:<br />

http://www.democracynow.org/2010/9/22/chilean economist manfred max neef us<br />

Here are some main points from the interview. I found it very enlightening:<br />

<strong>The</strong> principles <strong>of</strong> an economics, how it should be, are based on five postulates and one<br />

fundamental value principle.<br />

1: <strong>The</strong> economy is to serve the people and not the people to serve the economy.<br />

2: Development is about people and not about objects.<br />

3: Growth is not the same as development, and development does not necessarily require<br />

growth.<br />

4: No economy is possible in the absence <strong>of</strong> ecosystem services.<br />

5: <strong>The</strong> economy is a subsystem <strong>of</strong> a larger finite system, the biosphere, hence permanent<br />

growth is impossible.<br />

And the fundamental value to sustain a new economy should be that no economic interest,<br />

under no circumstance, can be above the relevance <strong>of</strong> life.<br />

Message [1032] referenced by [1071]. Next Message by Jo is [1046].<br />

[1050] Fisher: adding to Max and iphone. I was reading what Max [1031] said about<br />

capitalism resulting in such technologies as the iphone etc. and tend to agree that capitalism<br />

has given us many cool <strong>thing</strong>s. However, i disagree in the sense that these technologies arent<br />

helping with important <strong>thing</strong>s as world hunger and disease. Technology has progressed<br />

to this point, giving us information about world hunger and disease with the touch <strong>of</strong> our<br />

fingers. I think we are moving in the right direction to making the world a better place and<br />

504 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

helping the less fortunate through technology. Many are able to donate money, time, and<br />

other resources much easier now with these iphones and other technologies. Many are more<br />

informed now as well. To make the world healthier information is the <strong>first</strong> step giving people<br />

information and opportunities to help with ease.<br />

Next Message by Fisher is [1051].<br />

[1054] Babyceta: Some Final Thoughts About Marx and Veblen: A Lengthy Free Discussion<br />

and Cynical Rant! A couple semesters ago, I took a Communism/Socialism class<br />

and wrote a paper comparing the critical writings <strong>of</strong> Thorstein Veblen and Karl Marx. Both<br />

men were visionary thinkers and took a historical approach to understanding the roots <strong>of</strong> capitalism;<br />

both equally critical and merciless. Both saw the debilitating effects <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

on the lives <strong>of</strong> workers; each at different periods in time where the effects <strong>of</strong> exploitation by<br />

one class over another was extremely palpable. And both men accurately predicted eminent<br />

crises and depressions inherent in the capitalist system, warning <strong>of</strong> increased social malaise<br />

and dysfunction as a byproduct <strong>of</strong> the division <strong>of</strong> labor. To say that they were contemptuous<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalism would be a huge understatement, and although there are amazing similarities<br />

in their rhetoric, there are pronounced differences as well. Here is some <strong>of</strong> what I<br />

wrote:<br />

“Veblen’s assessment <strong>of</strong> historical influences was based largely on science as well, but<br />

more on biological influences and less on the social aspects <strong>of</strong> change. Veblen was largely<br />

influenced by Darwin, and his theories are sometimes referred to as “evolutionary economics.”<br />

<strong>The</strong> villain in Veblen’s eyes was not the bourgeois class, about which Marx had written<br />

prolifically, but the nouveau-riche industrialist, known as “robber barons,” he despised. He<br />

disagreed with Marx that the driving force <strong>of</strong> capitalism was the exploitation <strong>of</strong> surplus labor.<br />

For Veblen, capitalism was fueled by the competition for status and respectability. It<br />

was not the distribution <strong>of</strong> surplus that was socially determined, as Marx believed, but “conspicuous<br />

consumption” <strong>of</strong> extravagant and meaningless junk purchased in a vulgar display<br />

<strong>of</strong> wealth that served no purpose except to show others just how wealthy you really were (or<br />

at least wanted them to believe). For Veblen, these traits were inherent manifestations <strong>of</strong> the<br />

biological nature <strong>of</strong> man, compounded by the social evolution <strong>of</strong> historical institutions <strong>of</strong><br />

early societies. In addition, Veblen introduced a direct refutation to the marginalist notions<br />

<strong>of</strong> utility. He believed that social relations did influence consumption <strong>of</strong> the working class<br />

in what he called “pecuniary emulation,” or the desire to emulate the consumptive spending<br />

habits <strong>of</strong> our immediate peers or those in the socioeconomic class directly above. But he felt<br />

this need for human beings was biologically determined. After all, that is what separated us<br />

from other animal species.<br />

Marx was also aware <strong>of</strong> the potential pitfalls <strong>of</strong> capitalist consumption and wrote extensively<br />

on the “fetishism <strong>of</strong> commodities;” where social relationships are transformed into<br />

objective relationships between the individual and commodities. Marx believed this obsession<br />

to be akin to religious mania and blamed the institution <strong>of</strong> private property for its<br />

manifestation. All societies produce goods, says Marx, but not all goods are commodities.<br />

Commodities gain their peculiar nature through their exchange in the market, and therefore<br />

the labor embodied in them essentially becomes a commodity. Its value determined not by<br />

its usefulness, but by its ability to be exchanged for other goods. <strong>The</strong> social aspect <strong>of</strong> this<br />

labor thus becomes a materialistic relationship between <strong>thing</strong>s...


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 505<br />

..Although Marx and Veblen each adopted historical approaches to understanding the<br />

origins <strong>of</strong> capitalism, their theories on class struggle vary greatly. Marx advanced theories<br />

<strong>of</strong> class oppression in <strong>The</strong> Communist Manifesto that eluded to the inevitable uprising <strong>of</strong><br />

the proletariat class (workers) against the bourgeois capitalist (owners). <strong>The</strong> workers <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world would eventually unite to overthrow their oppressors who shamelessly and greedily<br />

exploited their labor and turned the source <strong>of</strong> their prideful humanity into a commodity <strong>of</strong><br />

valueless exchange. To Veblen, the bourgeoisie were in fact a “leisure class” <strong>of</strong> predatory<br />

opportunists bent on coveting goods without the benefit <strong>of</strong> actual work. But if Marx is<br />

correct and the proletariat was contemptuous and reviled capitalists, then why would the<br />

world have to wait for the revolution to break out and for communism to take its rightful<br />

place as the economic system <strong>of</strong> choice? Veblen’s answer was in the psychological nature <strong>of</strong><br />

workers. He believed workers did not despise their oppressors; they envied them and aspired<br />

to emulate them through pecuniary habits. Veblen observed that workers viewed their labor<br />

as somehow less dignified and envied the ability <strong>of</strong> the leisure class to sit around and benefit<br />

from the efforts <strong>of</strong> others. Marx assumed that workers detested their bosses, but Veblen<br />

contented that they instead admired them. Veblen believed the goal <strong>of</strong> workers was not to<br />

displace the upper class; it was to ascend the mountain <strong>of</strong> historically determined inequality<br />

to become one <strong>of</strong> the privileged.<br />

Doubtless, both men witnessed extreme poverty and the inhumane treatment <strong>of</strong> workers.<br />

At Marx’s time, deplorable conditions existed in industrialized factories, and women and<br />

children were especially targeted. It is understandable, in retrospect, why Marx equated the<br />

exploitation <strong>of</strong> surplus labor with unpaid labor, given the length <strong>of</strong> the average workday<br />

and the demands on workers to labor for greater periods <strong>of</strong> time. Marx’s see<strong>thing</strong> contempt<br />

for the capitalist system ignited the fires <strong>of</strong> dissention and fostered a growing willingness<br />

to entertain socialist principles. His legacy cannot be overstated, even while considering<br />

that the great revolution he predicted never actually happened. Many <strong>of</strong> his ideas are as<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>ound today as when they were originally published. Ironically, Thorstein Veblen never<br />

quite received the notoriety <strong>of</strong> Karl Marx, although in some respects his analysis was decidedly<br />

superior. Veblen’s understanding <strong>of</strong> pecuniary and consumptive emulation is extremely<br />

relevant even today, given the marketing strategies <strong>of</strong> luxury goods.”<br />

I am utilizing my free discussion to illustrate a point (or go on a rant, depending on<br />

how you look at it): although my understanding <strong>of</strong> Marx has improved greatly and I would<br />

probably revise some <strong>of</strong> what I wrote a year ago, I still think Veblen’s analysis <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

was decidedly superior (sorry, Hans), and it was definitely more prophetic, especially his<br />

concepts <strong>of</strong> conspicuous consumption and pecuniary emulation. I agree with Veblen that<br />

the goal <strong>of</strong> the working class was never to overthrow the bourgeois capitalist. It was to<br />

ascend the mountain <strong>of</strong> impossibility to become one <strong>of</strong> the elite. Maybe that was the greatest<br />

deception <strong>of</strong> capitalism overall: it dangled the carrot just enough so that the workers <strong>of</strong> the<br />

world believed they could actually do that. Isn’t that the American dream? Isn’t that what<br />

they told us growing up; you could be any<strong>thing</strong> in life and have all that we desired? Marx<br />

believed we would see the illusion for what it really was: a bunch <strong>of</strong> B.S. But I think he<br />

underestimated the capitalist and overestimated the working class. Veblen didn’t. He based<br />

his assumptions on the biological nature <strong>of</strong> human beings, and realized that the tendency to<br />

follow the herd is just too deeply ingrained in our genetic code. No matter how much social<br />

506 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

institutions transform, at the end <strong>of</strong> the day we are all <strong>of</strong> us dreamers. We love a good fairy<br />

tale, especially one that involves us! Why do you think the lottery is so popular? <strong>The</strong> odds<br />

are about 80 million:one, but as long as there’s that one chance, THAT ONE CHANCE,<br />

people will line up to play. That’s what capitalism does: it convinces us to work our butts<br />

<strong>of</strong>f to buy that Wonka chocolate bar because that golden ticket may just be inside. <strong>The</strong><br />

whole time we keep working and happily buying chocolate, working and buying chocolate.<br />

And what happens? No<strong>thing</strong>. Wonka gets rich and retires to Miami Beach, and we become<br />

obese, move in with our aunt Trudy and retire to the s<strong>of</strong>a. Because once they privatize social<br />

security and the capitalists get hold <strong>of</strong> it, then Miami Beach too will be just another dream<br />

we buy into.<br />

I told you it was a rant, but, hey, it’s the end <strong>of</strong> the semester and probably no one will<br />

read this anyway.<br />

Message [1054] referenced by [1056]. Next Message by Babyceta is [1074].<br />

[1056] Somramthom: Some Final Thoughts About Marx and Veblen: A Lengthy<br />

Free Discussion and Cynical Rant! Interesting thoughts in [1054] about consumptive<br />

emulation. That is definitely existent in modern society. And it is spreading around the<br />

world. But Marx still holds clout as well. In the vast majority <strong>of</strong> business classes taught<br />

today (at least Westernized ones) you are taught about the bottom line; pr<strong>of</strong>its are assumed<br />

to be the main objective <strong>of</strong> firms. Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> where that pr<strong>of</strong>it comes from could still<br />

hold true despite your conclusion that the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital doesn’t drive capitalism.<br />

In my experience, there is virtually never a time where one variable decides an outcome.<br />

It is always several variables (nearly infinite number <strong>of</strong> variables in real life situations) that<br />

decide outcomes. Why, therefore, can’t they both be right? not completely, mind you, just<br />

bits here and there.<br />

P.S. I only read your post because I happened to see the “it’s the end <strong>of</strong> the semester and<br />

probably no one will read this anyway.” comment at the end <strong>of</strong> your post. I am strange like<br />

that.<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [1105].<br />

[1059] AM: Unemployment: to stimulate or not to stimulate. I was listening to Sean<br />

Hannity’s radio show the other day not because I necessarily agree with his point <strong>of</strong> view but<br />

rather because I enjoy hearing all sides <strong>of</strong> an argument before making my own decision. His<br />

topic was extending unemployment. Hannity’s opinion was that extending unemployment<br />

will not necessarily stimulate the economy in the way that those in government would like<br />

to see. He made the point that extending unemployment through the holiday season will not<br />

necessarily stimulate the economy immediately or for unnecessary items. <strong>The</strong> money given<br />

to those without jobs will go to purchases for <strong>thing</strong>s they desperately need (i.e. diapers,<br />

food, gas) and not to gifts and extra <strong>thing</strong>s. Also, Hannity suggested that those unemployed<br />

do not really want money to be extended to them but that they would rather be provided with<br />

opportunities to get out <strong>of</strong> unemployment. I think that there has to be some middle ground<br />

between increasing the debit this country has and decreasing the unemployment rate.<br />

But what would Marx think? Hans writes on pg. 709 <strong>of</strong> the Annotations “surpluspopulation<br />

→ sudden expansion → sudden contractions → more surplus populations.” I


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 507<br />

am not sure if I am applying this correctly but it makes me think <strong>of</strong> the current unemployment<br />

and stimulus. Surplus-population <strong>of</strong> unemployed→ sudden expansion <strong>of</strong> the economy<br />

due to stimulus→rapid contraction <strong>of</strong> the economy because it could not handle the sudden<br />

expansion→ large surplus population <strong>of</strong> unemployed. So I guess that means I am suggesting<br />

that there will be a short-term goal met (i.e. reducing unemployment) but in the long<br />

term there will end up being more unemployed people.<br />

Another interesting motive <strong>of</strong> the capitalist that Hans points out on pg. 714 in the Annotations<br />

is that “capitalists are motivated to get more out <strong>of</strong> the same number <strong>of</strong> workers<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> hiring more workers, because hiring more workers requires higher outlays in constant<br />

capital than having the same number <strong>of</strong> workers working longer hours.” I remember<br />

Sean Hannity mentioning this same idea during his radio show. Currently, the average work<br />

week is some<strong>thing</strong> like 36 hours a week. Since employers have not increased the hours <strong>of</strong><br />

the laborers they already have, it is doubtful that they are going to hire new laborers out <strong>of</strong><br />

the unemployment pool. <strong>The</strong> employers are more likely to increase establish laborers hours<br />

than they are to try and increase their capital to support new workers.<br />

Message [1059] referenced by [1065] and [1075]. Next Message by AM is [1118].<br />

[1063] Rmc: Re: Health insurance, social security. I know I’m late contributing to this<br />

conversation, but I wanted to add some thoughts to Kaimani’s post [854].<br />

Kaimani said “I think that the problem is with rates at which doctors can charge per<br />

procedure.” I agree, but it’s not just limited to doctors- everybody working in the industry,<br />

and every material used, is responsible for the cost <strong>of</strong> health care. For example, take the cost<br />

<strong>of</strong> getting an x-ray- isn’t it true that there are separate charges for each step, like the person<br />

who takes the x-ray, the cost <strong>of</strong> the film and developer (which I think has become largely<br />

obsolete with computers), maybe paying <strong>of</strong>f the cost <strong>of</strong> the machine, someone different<br />

charges to look at the x-ray, and the physician relays the results (which someone else read) to<br />

the patient. (Also, the other staff have to be included—janitors, receptionists, even cleaning<br />

supplies and electric bills, etc.) Each step costs a ton <strong>of</strong> money, and the price <strong>of</strong> each could<br />

be reduced. Doctors aren’t the only ones who charge too much. (Side note: I don’t know<br />

if this is true with many others, but my dentist said he charges much less for patients who<br />

don’t use insurance—he knows the insurance company won’t pay him the full amount, so<br />

he has to make up the difference by inflating the price for insurance carriers. He loves when<br />

people come in willing to pay out <strong>of</strong> their own pockets- they are much easier to work with<br />

than insurance companies anyway, haha.)<br />

Next Message by Rmc is [1064].<br />

[1064] Rmc: Re: social security. I know I’m late contributing to this thread also, but I<br />

would like to add anyway-<br />

Re: Kleenex [937]- While lack <strong>of</strong> innovation and flexibility is an accurate description <strong>of</strong><br />

some or many older workers, it is not necessarily applicable to all <strong>of</strong> them- it’s an insult to<br />

those who are perfectly capable <strong>of</strong> adapting to ever-changing work environments or those<br />

who still have the motivation and willingness to learn new skills, like using technology. Just<br />

saying. / Addressing another point mentioned, about the number <strong>of</strong> years <strong>of</strong> service needed<br />

to work before the employee is eligible for retirement benefits- I understand it’s becoming<br />

more and more common for companies to hire increasing numbers <strong>of</strong> temporary workers<br />

508 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

instead <strong>of</strong> permanent in order to save money on benefits. How sad is that? Many people<br />

are stuck with their “temporary” status for much longer than is fair. Even worse, other<br />

places will terminate employment on purpose before the worker has reached the years <strong>of</strong><br />

service mark. Target specifically has a disappointing reputation for letting employees go–<br />

sometimes in the form <strong>of</strong> encouraging-to-quit– after they’ve worked 10 or 15 years just so<br />

they don’t have to pay them retirement benefits. Well, once someone has put in that much<br />

time at one place, how will they work 30 or so years somewhere else?<br />

Re: Smartergirl [945]- I’d like to add another point- many older workers are forced to<br />

retire because they believe they won’t be able to find work in their field at their age, even<br />

if they are capable <strong>of</strong> working until late in life. I know someone personally who, while<br />

extremely knowledgeable and skilled in his field, and who would have been an asset to<br />

any company, couldn’t find a job in the US because he was too old to be hired- in his late<br />

50s. <strong>The</strong> trend <strong>of</strong> hiring younger people, as long as it continues, will mean older and more<br />

qualified, experienced workers will be replaced and they may not be able to work through to<br />

the retirement age. <strong>The</strong> job market pushes them out.<br />

Next Message by Rmc is [1074].<br />

[1065] Orville: How did we get here? To add to AM [1059] in another hot-button issue,<br />

the Bush era tax cuts are set to expire. It is no doubt what Sean Hannity would say on the<br />

subject because <strong>of</strong> his close work with the GOP. To relate this argument to class, Marx might<br />

look at this discussion and wonder how we got to this point. To say that the capitalists need<br />

a greater break than they already have would be one that goes against all <strong>of</strong> the cases made<br />

in Capital. Although it is clear that Marx would prefer some socio-economic system other<br />

than capitalism, Marx would have a few questions about how our tax dollars are collected<br />

and spent.<br />

A topic similar to that mentioned above was presented in another class. One student<br />

came at it with an interesting case, he said that his father had come from a poor family in<br />

southern <strong>Utah</strong> and had made it into the middle class. His ideas were that there should be<br />

no welfare system and that people could escape poverty simply by working hard. Clearly<br />

this individual has not been presented the ideas put forth in this class or in any sort <strong>of</strong> study<br />

<strong>of</strong> demographics in the United States. Marx would certainly have some<strong>thing</strong> to say to this<br />

person. After explaining his labor theory <strong>of</strong> value and the exploitation <strong>of</strong> labor, I believe he<br />

might ask a few questions at how we got to this point. How did we get to a point where there<br />

are those who make more in one year more than most will make in their entire lifetime? Our<br />

models tell us that economics allocates goods in the most efficient way; that those willing<br />

to pay more are those who will get the most use out <strong>of</strong> it. This is my main problem with<br />

capitalism. Under that same idea, if Bill Gates wants a sandwich and is willing to pay $50<br />

for it while a single mother only has $5 to spend on it, is that allocating effectively? Along<br />

with that, can we, self-interested automatons, stop the coming climate crisis as debated in<br />

the <strong>Question</strong> 935?<br />

Next Message by Orville is [1107].<br />

[1075] SMIKEC: Unemployment: to stimulate or not to stimulate. I have to agree with<br />

AM [1059] some<strong>thing</strong> has to be done but none <strong>of</strong> the answers seem to be the one that fixes<br />

all. By handing out more money, by extending the unemployment handouts, we are creating<br />

more debt for us to have to eventually deal with. If they did extend it now then would people


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 509<br />

be spending it on gifts versus the day to day necessities, ......probably. Would that be such<br />

a bad <strong>thing</strong> though, in the sense, one <strong>of</strong> the only ways more jobs are going to be created<br />

is by people spending money in the economy. By spending more, then the capitalist has a<br />

greater demand for their good and in turn a greater need for labor. However as AM [1059]<br />

said, the capitalist would probably just extend hours on current workers versus bringing on<br />

more staff, hence trying to get the most surplus labor out <strong>of</strong> them versus bringing on more<br />

overhead. Its a tough scenario which is going to take a multitude <strong>of</strong> components to make a<br />

decent fix plan.<br />

First Message by SMIKEC is [130].<br />

[1076] Hans: How the “American Century” will end. This article by historian Alfred<br />

McCoy is making the rounds in the internet today:<br />

http://www.tomdispatch.com/post/175327/<br />

Assuming some<strong>thing</strong> like this is going to happen what would be a wise strategy to prepare<br />

for it?<br />

Message [1076] referenced by [1102]. Next Message by Hans is [1102].<br />

[1086] Hal: Preparing For <strong>The</strong> Decline <strong>of</strong> America. In the article “<strong>The</strong> Decline and<br />

Fall <strong>of</strong> the American Empire,” Alfred McCoy outlines four possible future scenarios. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

are “economic decline, oil shock, military misadventure, and World War III.” Assuming at<br />

least one <strong>of</strong> these scenarios unfolds, which I think seems likely, America will hold a much<br />

different position in the world than before. We can prepare for such a future in a number <strong>of</strong><br />

ways.<br />

On a national level, we can make our nation’s decline in status more gradual by putting<br />

political pressure on government <strong>of</strong>ficials to...<br />

(1) ...avoid military misadventure. In other words, avoid war and cut military spending.<br />

(2) ...aggressively seek energy independence and renewable forms <strong>of</strong> energy.<br />

(3) ...create a better public transportation infrastructure, and provide incentives for individuals<br />

to live in cities.<br />

(4) ...create and foster international alliances (preferably with future super powers).<br />

(5) ...allocate more money (while we still have it) to education in order to train more<br />

scientists and engineers.<br />

On an individual level, we can...<br />

(6) ...make an effort to amass knowledge and skills useful for global communication and<br />

commerce. For instance, we could study languages (Chinese, Hindi, Russian, Portuguese),<br />

cultures, world history, world news, and international economics.<br />

(7) ...move into cities with better public transportation so that living without a car would<br />

be easier, thereby leaving us less dependent on oil<br />

(8) ...build more energy efficient houses, or even move to more temperate climates where<br />

heating and air conditioning will be less necessary<br />

(9) ...sell all <strong>of</strong> our stocks!<br />

510 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Message [1086] referenced by [1102], [1121], [1152], and [1155]. Next Message by Hal is [1096].<br />

[1088] Guh: I was having an interesting discussion in my current economic class about<br />

the criticisms raised against free trade by heterodox economists. Now, this is an interesting<br />

conversation, but I found my self to think about the arguments against the neo-liberal<br />

orthodoxy <strong>of</strong> free trade, and the clams <strong>of</strong> small countries being pushed into free trade too<br />

quickly by more powerful countries. Moreover, by forcing these small and weaker economic<br />

countries into free trade, results negatively for these smaller/weaker countries. What needs<br />

to happen is the smaller/weaker countries need to stabilize and straighten themselves and<br />

even their products before entering the free trade market with the other big players.<br />

Next Message by Guh is [1125].<br />

[1102] Hans: How to s<strong>of</strong>ten the landing. Hal [1086] took me up on my question: how<br />

should one prepare for the decline <strong>of</strong> the empire. I like Hal’s <strong>first</strong> point a lot. It is “avoid<br />

military misadventure.” Note that McCoy says:<br />

Counterintuitively, as their power wanes, empires <strong>of</strong>ten plunge into illadvised<br />

military misadventures. This phenomenon is known among historians<br />

<strong>of</strong> empire as “micro-militarism” and seems to involve psychologically<br />

compensatory efforts to salve the sting <strong>of</strong> retreat or defeat by occupying<br />

new territories, however briefly and catastrophically. <strong>The</strong>se operations,<br />

irrational even from an imperial point <strong>of</strong> view, <strong>of</strong>ten yield hemorrhaging<br />

expenditures or humiliating defeats that only accelerate the loss <strong>of</strong> power.<br />

Here is the link again to McCoy’s article, same as in [1076]:<br />

http://www.tomdispatch.com/post/175327/<br />

I.e., we know from history that military misadventures are a completely irrational reaction<br />

which does not support the empire but undermines it. Had the world-wide mobilization <strong>of</strong><br />

6 million people on February 15 2003 prevented the US from invading Iraq, then the US<br />

empire would be in a much better situation today than it is. I think Hal came up with a wise<br />

and achievable goal: support the peace movement. And cut military spending so that those<br />

in power are not able to play with the fire.<br />

McCoy calls this “micro-militarism” because it is not a world war. But World War III is<br />

also one <strong>of</strong> McCoy’s scenarios. If it happens, it will be a war between the US and China. <strong>The</strong><br />

ruling class has been preparing the US public for this war for a long time by its systematic<br />

demonization <strong>of</strong> China. McCoy’s own article demonizes China too, talking about China’s<br />

“rigged currency rates,” and making China the aggressor in World War III.<br />

But demonization and the creation <strong>of</strong> a “them versus us” mentality has also become much<br />

more difficult with modern information technology. Also the economic globalization has<br />

made world wars more difficult. <strong>The</strong>refore Hal’s point (7) is also a good preparation for the<br />

future: learn Chinese. <strong>The</strong> indebtedness <strong>of</strong> the US is so large that there is a good chance the<br />

company you work for will be owned by the Chinese at some point in the future.<br />

Hal’s points (2), (3), (8), (9) talk about energy independence and energy savings. Hal’s<br />

instincts are better than McCoy’s, whose report didn’t say a word about climate change and


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 511<br />

the end <strong>of</strong> world wide economic growth. (McCoy is a historian, and these issues are relatively<br />

new.) As I see it, the world-wide environmental crisis would have been an opportunity<br />

to prolong US hegemony if the US would have stepped into the void as the leader for resource<br />

conservation and renewable energy. But I guess the US body politic is too corrupt for<br />

this, also a sign <strong>of</strong> a declining empire. I like McCoy’s formulation “the American system is<br />

flooded with corporate money meant to jam up the works.”<br />

Besides his blindness on climate change, McCoy is also blind to the alternatives <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

I find it totally possible and compatible with our historical experience that the entire<br />

South American continent will go over to socialism, and that China will have another revolution<br />

and emerge as a leading socialist world power. Hal’s point (4) <strong>of</strong> better international<br />

co-operation is not possible under capitalism, it will only be possible if the nations are socialist,<br />

or if the threat <strong>of</strong> socialism is so strong that the capitalists go on their best behavior.<br />

Message [1102] referenced by [1112], [1121], and [1152]. Next Message by Hans is [1182].<br />

[1109] RexManning: Tax break here, 100% write <strong>of</strong>f there. If according to the abstinence<br />

theory, capitalists are forgoing the overwhelming desire to expend, so that they can be<br />

the saviors that society has deemed them to be, and provide us (the workers) with access to<br />

the production process so that we can be exploited and further increase their pr<strong>of</strong>its, why is it<br />

that with the tax cuts being implemented, are they able to receive 100% write <strong>of</strong>f for capital<br />

investment? Not only are the tax cuts going to be extended to everyone, the capitalists will<br />

get the chance to further widen the gap between the middle-class and upper-class by being<br />

able to invest in capital without really having to pay for it. Perhaps more funds should be<br />

directed to the people who really need it. Instead <strong>of</strong> costing the government another $200<br />

billion which it really can’t afford.<br />

Message [1109] referenced by [1162]. Next Message by RexManning is [1127].<br />

[1111] Deadfamous: What if the Rich only paid taxes? I was just wondering what<br />

Marx would think about a capitalist structure where the poor up to a certain point never had<br />

to pay taxes, and would have to start paying taxes after 40,000 or so per person, would this<br />

be in his frame <strong>of</strong> thinking? I know he is pro-unions what if all the poor people united and<br />

stated that since they don’t own the means <strong>of</strong> production, they should not have to pay taxes?<br />

Just thinking out loud?<br />

First Message by Deadfamous is [185].<br />

[1118] AM: a nice film. Not long after submitting a term paper on exploitation in capitalism<br />

I watched a documentary film called Freakonomics. I was not surprised to see yet<br />

another example where exploitation is hidden by surface relations. One <strong>of</strong> the segments<br />

during the documentary delved into the world <strong>of</strong> Sumo wrestling. Immediately I thought,<br />

‘Sumo Wrestling? Really ancient Japanese sport wrought with exploitation and deceit? No<br />

Way!’ Well, as the documentary went on to explain, Sumo wrestling is in fact a sport in<br />

which the general public is exploited by a select few. That is to say that the millions <strong>of</strong><br />

people who follow Sumo Wrestling and admire it as an ancient custom are exploited by the<br />

select few chosen to participate in and oversee the sport. Social relations (i.e. ancient rituals<br />

and reverence) hide the fact that Sumo matches are rigged. Much like it is in the best interest<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Capitalist to exploit his laborers because his main goal is to increase his capital, it<br />

is in the best interest <strong>of</strong> some Sumo wrestlers to lose and take a pay <strong>of</strong>f in order to benefit<br />

financially.<br />

512 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

After spending a month writing on exploitation in the capitalist system, this documentary<br />

brought home how many different examples <strong>of</strong> exploitation there are. I think Marx would<br />

classify the exploitation occurring in Sumo wrestling systemic because by no means is it<br />

accidental. <strong>The</strong> exploitation is occurring on a very conscious level without accident.<br />

I just needed to share how delighted I was with the film and general and specifically that<br />

I could relate it to some<strong>thing</strong> that I was learning in-class.<br />

Next Message by AM is [1138].<br />

[1121] Kleenex: How to s<strong>of</strong>ten the landing. I would like to respectfully comment as<br />

a free discussion on Hal [1086] and Hans [1102], specifically the statement, “support the<br />

peace movement. And cut military spending so that those in power are not able to play with<br />

the fire.”<br />

Though world peace is an ideal for everyone, and would be wonderful to experience,<br />

unfortunately, our adversaries are not peaceful, nor do they promote peace. Reality bites.<br />

Sure, we can be peaceful and pacifist, but I would venture to say that that would actually<br />

leave us in an even worse condition. I am glad that there is a 1% <strong>of</strong> the US population<br />

who is willing to keep us from being destroyed by those who hate the ideals we stand for<br />

(democracy, freedom), the freedom that allows us to partake in these types <strong>of</strong> discussions<br />

without persecution or government censorship.<br />

Just also wanted to note that military spending is indeed being cut. I experience this and<br />

am reminded <strong>of</strong> this everyday where I work: doing more with less resources. However,<br />

many other sectors should be experiencing budget cuts as well (Department <strong>of</strong> Education,<br />

Department <strong>of</strong> Transportation, etc), if they aren’t already doing so. Looking at our national<br />

debt, we will all just have to do “more with less,” not just the military, but everyone, to<br />

include frivolous consumption at the national, state, county, city, and even individual level.<br />

Message [1121] referenced by [1152] and [1155]. First Message by Kleenex is [17].<br />

[1123] Fisher: Palestine. <strong>The</strong> last class was interesting, particularly when Hans mentioned<br />

Palestine and Isreal as an example <strong>of</strong> how life could become. Last class was very<br />

interesting. I will definately read more into Marx and Capital.<br />

First Message by Fisher is [181].<br />

[1141] Spiral: Health Care. In response to [1003]: Classical economics doesn’t apply<br />

to the health care market in the sense that the conditions for perfect competition within the<br />

market are nonexistent. All available information is not available nor is the supply <strong>of</strong> health<br />

care perfectly elastic. <strong>The</strong> unique attribute <strong>of</strong> the health care market is that the physician<br />

controls the entire process i.e demanding and supplying health care. Here the doctor controls<br />

demand because the consumer doesn’t have the necessary knowledge to demand the specific<br />

health care they need. This is why we see a doctor. Additionally, the doctor supplies the<br />

health care he just told us to demand. This is a peculiar case where the physician control<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production (equipment and medicine) and supplies the labour-power applying<br />

health care.<br />

Message [1141] referenced by [1150]. Next Message by Spiral is [1142].<br />

[1142] Spiral: Current recession. I agree with your general supposition in [1012] that<br />

blame for the recent economic recession and the nasty aftermath we’re all dealing with is


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 513<br />

spread across a large number <strong>of</strong> actors. But I think the list is significantly longer than Presidents<br />

and investment banks aka Wall Street. I would add Alan Greenspan for his irrational<br />

exuberance keeping the discount rate and the fed funds rate at never before seen historic<br />

lows, Senator Phil Gramm for fighting to repeal the Glass-Steagall Act on behalf <strong>of</strong> investment<br />

banks who paid him millions while in <strong>of</strong>fice and more afterward. <strong>The</strong> Act kept<br />

commercial and investment banking separate since the Great Depression but after repeal exposed<br />

the financial system to unknown risks economists are still discovering. Lets not forget<br />

the rating agencies who were paid by banks to rate their investment instruments from mortgage<br />

backed securities (MBS) to exotic structured investment vehicles (SIVs). <strong>The</strong> perverse<br />

incentive <strong>of</strong> being paid to analyze and criticize the property <strong>of</strong> the entity who is paying you<br />

resulted in millions <strong>of</strong> false triple AAA ratings.<br />

<strong>The</strong> list <strong>of</strong> those who are morally blameworthy goes on to include many Presidents, public<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials, banks, regulatory agencies, CEOs etc. <strong>The</strong> point is that this great recession was a<br />

system-wide phenomenon with capitalists, public <strong>of</strong>ficials, and workers all taking part in<br />

the credit bubble’s creation. Moral hazard remains an issue after bailouts created a new<br />

tier <strong>of</strong> firms under the all-powerful title “too-big-to-fail.” An answer <strong>of</strong> how to wind down<br />

these capitalist behemoths has not been found, but some good ideas are floating around.<br />

Institutions <strong>of</strong> this size must develop a bankruptcy plan for the government or a receivership<br />

to parcel out the firm’s assets to those owed money. Greater transparency through new<br />

international accounting standards will help but cooking the books will always be a danger<br />

so more needs to be done. An intriguing idea is for moral hazard to spur the proletariat to<br />

call for accountability in the form <strong>of</strong> a plan to vest ultimate protection and authority with the<br />

people. This is a democratic idea but one which could also be the beginning <strong>of</strong> a proletarian<br />

movement awakening to their unity as a class.<br />

Next Message by Spiral is [1154].<br />

[1146] Proletarian: What’s a Marxist to do? What is the aspiring Marxist to do? I’m<br />

sure there are plenty <strong>of</strong> us in this class, and in this world for that matter, who would like to<br />

see the fall <strong>of</strong> capitalism and the rise <strong>of</strong> a social order that is more equitable, sustainable,<br />

and empowering <strong>of</strong> the masses. But what does one do in the meantime? How can we help<br />

stop the unrelenting machine <strong>of</strong> production in the name <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its?<br />

We have to deal with the fact that, for the moment, we live in a capitalist economic system,<br />

and as much as we’d like it to be the case, it’s improbable that we’ll wake up tomorrow and<br />

be living in a socialist paradise. Overcoming capitalism will take a massive social movement<br />

that will require a lot more than the actions <strong>of</strong> just an individual. However, it seems to me<br />

that there should be at least some ways that we can help ease the burdens on the proletariat<br />

and help “prime the system” for larger scale social change.<br />

One <strong>thing</strong> I’ve thought <strong>of</strong> was starting a business and organizing it as an employee owned<br />

business. While we’ve seen that capitalism keeps the working class from owning the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production, there are social and governmental programs that are designed to help smallbusinesses<br />

and entrepreneurs. While starting a business isn’t easy, it is possible, and by<br />

organizing your business to be employee owned and operated one can create a company<br />

where workers collectively own their means <strong>of</strong> production and benefit from them.<br />

514 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Another thought I had is to support organized labor. Unfortunately, the strength <strong>of</strong> unions<br />

in our county has been greatly weakened in the last thirty years, starting with Ronald Regan.<br />

However, it seems to me that the damage is not irreprerable, and that by supporting unions we<br />

can empower workers to fight for their rights and better work environments, and hopefully,<br />

have mechanisms in place that can lead to employee takeover <strong>of</strong> companies once the push<br />

for a more socially equable form <strong>of</strong> economic structure comes on a societal level.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se are just a couple <strong>of</strong> my thoughts. Any others?<br />

Message [1146] referenced by [1156] and [1165]. Next Message by Proletarian is [1147].<br />

[1147] Proletarian: What’s next? Coming into the semester I had no idea what to expect<br />

from this class. Obviously I expected to learn quite a bit about Marxism, but what I didn’t<br />

expect was the extraordinary delatil and depth <strong>of</strong> our exploration <strong>of</strong> Marx’s thoughts and the<br />

foundations <strong>of</strong> the Marxist view on the structure and function <strong>of</strong> economics. While I went<br />

into the class expecting to be somewhat accepting <strong>of</strong> Marxist thought, I had no idea how<br />

much I would agree with this view <strong>of</strong> economics. In fact, one may say that I’m coming out<br />

<strong>of</strong> this class a Marxist (or at least a Marxist-in-training).<br />

What I hope to get out <strong>of</strong> this discussion is an answer to the following: what’s next?<br />

Specifically, what’s next in two areas. First, what can those interested in learning more<br />

about Marxism do next (what should they read, where should they go, etc.)? Second, what<br />

should one who wants to cause social change and work towards the end <strong>of</strong> capitalism be<br />

doing right now?<br />

First Message by Proletarian is [35].<br />

[1150] Smartergirl: Health Care. In addition to what Spiral stated in [1141] I would<br />

like to add and go even a little deeper. Perfect competition may be seen as non existent<br />

and because doctors were not abundant in earlier times they clearly had a market advantage.<br />

As Spiral stated the physician had control <strong>of</strong> the entire process but we see centralization<br />

even in health care now. More and more small capitalist doctors are going bankrupt because<br />

they cannot afford the insurance to have a private practice. Because the doctor most likely<br />

depended on credit to get through med school they are a slave to their debt and have to pay<br />

it <strong>of</strong>f. <strong>The</strong>y need to practice medicine because it brings in a higher value. Even the doctor<br />

is enslaved to big medical companies that have investors from insurance companies on their<br />

board <strong>of</strong> directors. Doctors no longer can use the available medical treatment that they have<br />

been taught because they have to clear it with the insurance company. Is the doctor truly<br />

immune from perfect competition? I believe they are just as much a slave and victim to<br />

modern day economics as we are.<br />

Next Message by Smartergirl is [1183].<br />

[1151] Rico: Capitalism vs Leftist Governments. After the in-class discussion Tuesday<br />

night, I found it interesting that our government has <strong>of</strong>ten been opposed to leftist dictators.<br />

After briefly researching the argument, I discovered that the US government has favored<br />

right-wing dictators, while extremely opposing left-wing dictators.<br />

Has the USA ever embraced a foreign leftist government (i.e. Marxist gov’t, comunist<br />

gov’t, etc)?<br />

Next Message by Rico is [1153].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 515<br />

[1152] Zohan: Cut Spending? I would also like to comment on Hal [1086] and Hans<br />

[1102] specifically the text, “Had the world-wide mobilization <strong>of</strong> 6 million people on February<br />

15 2003 prevented the US from invading Iraq, then the US empire would be in a much<br />

better situation today than it is.....support the peace movement. And cut military spending<br />

so that those in power are not able to play with the fire.”<br />

But <strong>first</strong> I would like to thank Kleenex [1121] for your comments. I myself am a part <strong>of</strong><br />

the 1% mentioned in Kleenex [1121]. I normally am pretty reserved regarding my service in<br />

the military, but under a pseudo name I feel more comfortable to share. I spent 15 months in<br />

Iraq, surviving, fighting and sacrificing, and I did it all for my love and devotion to this great<br />

nation. I have never asked for a thank you from anyone, but it nice to know that there are<br />

civilians that appreciate those that sacrifice and what it cost to enjoy the freedoms we have.<br />

Regarding Hal’s comments. I support the peace movement, I really do. I hoped for<br />

no<strong>thing</strong> more each day I spent a world away from my family and the <strong>thing</strong>s that I love. I wish<br />

the world was a peaceful place. I wish that world leaders <strong>of</strong> nations would see eye to eye and<br />

that we could all coexist in peace. But that’s not our world and that’s the reality that we need<br />

to live in. After reading through the emails I have to ask would the US empire really be in a<br />

better situation than we are today? I don’t know, but I also asked myself, would a nation be<br />

liberated from the rule <strong>of</strong> a tyrant? Would stopping the US invasion in Iraq have prevented<br />

the economic breakdown? Is it really the governments spending on military that has led our<br />

nation down this path? And finally, should America reduce our global military campaign<br />

and invest more on our domestic interest and our own people? I mean no disrespect by my<br />

comments, or questions, and don’t claim to know all the answers, but as someone who has<br />

given much to his country I would like to think that my time spent fighting on foreign soil<br />

did not weaken the our nations empire, but helped secure our precious freedoms, ensure our<br />

way <strong>of</strong> life, and help lift a nation from under the grasp <strong>of</strong> a violent tyrant so that their nation<br />

may one day prosper as well. Maybe my time spent in the military has tainted my opinion,<br />

or maybe I am just a naive patriot who loves his nation too much, I don’t know. But I do<br />

know that if our nation is to continue as the empire we are,we must be cautious <strong>of</strong> how we<br />

chose to cut spending and how we chose to allocate our budgets. We need to learn from<br />

history and hopefully the leaders, that we as a people have chosen, make the right decisions.<br />

Just a side note, it is a result <strong>of</strong> military spending that has provide myself the opportunity<br />

to receive a higher education. With out the funds I received as a result <strong>of</strong> my service it is<br />

doubtful that I would have ever stepped foot on a college campus.<br />

Message [1152] referenced by [1155]. Next Message by Zohan is [1169].<br />

[1155] Hal: Military Misadventure. I feel the need to respond to Zohan [1152] and<br />

Kleenex [1121].<br />

In [1086], the only comment I made regarding military misadventure was the suggestion<br />

to put “political pressure on government <strong>of</strong>ficials to...avoid military misadventure. In other<br />

words, avoid war and cut military spending.” I made no comments regarding any specific<br />

wars.<br />

In general, a nation in decline should avoid war and cut military spending along with<br />

cutting other areas <strong>of</strong> government spending. Assuming that our country is in decline, we will<br />

516 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

need to step down from being the leader in policing other countries and restrict ourselves to<br />

more <strong>of</strong> a defensive role. On a smaller budget, we can still adequately defend ourselves and<br />

provide great benefits for our troops.<br />

Message [1155] referenced by [1160] and [1169]. First Message by Hal is [8].<br />

[1156] IrvingHowe: What’s a Marxist to do? Proletarian,<br />

A couple <strong>of</strong> thoughts in response to your email [1146].<br />

You’re raising a lot <strong>of</strong> big questions that cannot be properly discussed in this format but<br />

allow me to try and inject my two cents. First, there are a great many employee owned businesses<br />

and it has not brought capitalism’s demise a single day closer. Interestingly enough,<br />

the 5th largest corporation in Spain is an employee owned firm. Personally, I would say that<br />

if your end goal is a complete re-tooling <strong>of</strong> our economy, this is not the best use <strong>of</strong> your<br />

time. If you would like to inject a bit <strong>of</strong> justice and dignity into the lives <strong>of</strong> a few working<br />

people, than this may be a good route to take.<br />

Second, I believe, as you do, that the struggle has to begin with workers. Labor is some<strong>thing</strong><br />

I care deeply about and some<strong>thing</strong> that I have dedicated all <strong>of</strong> my adult life to. <strong>The</strong>re<br />

is work going on right now to re-start a student labor association at the <strong>University</strong>. I would<br />

encourage getting involved. However, I for one do not blame Reagan for labor’s ails nor do<br />

I think they began there. I have a great deal <strong>of</strong> thoughts on the matter though and again, this<br />

format is a bit limiting.<br />

Besides supporting workers struggles, I would say that the best <strong>thing</strong> you can do is network<br />

with everyone and anyone that you can. <strong>The</strong> biggest problem with the real left, as I see<br />

it, is that there are not enough bonds between the various causes and organizations that share<br />

so much in common. <strong>The</strong> big political parties have been so successful (if you can call them<br />

that) because they have tied together many different constituencies into one big force. Many<br />

<strong>of</strong> these constituencies are a natural fit but most would appear to have little to no<strong>thing</strong> to<br />

do with each other. For instance, a bible belt christian should theoretically want no<strong>thing</strong> to<br />

do with a greedy Wall Street trader but they both go in the same tent not because they share<br />

any beliefs but because the organization has championed each constituency’s most important<br />

cause, abortion and taxes. Strange bedfellows though they may be, they both can feel good<br />

about getting behind the GOP and defending one another because they know that this is the<br />

only way either one can get what they want out <strong>of</strong> the deal. <strong>The</strong> same can be said about<br />

culturally conservative black people and LGBT members <strong>of</strong> the Democratic Party.<br />

My point is, I believe the most effective use <strong>of</strong> a person’s time that shares your views is to<br />

work tirelessly to connect the various networks <strong>of</strong> concerned people into some<strong>thing</strong> that can<br />

function as a community. Even absent a political party (waste <strong>of</strong> time) a group <strong>of</strong> this kind<br />

can be a refinery for thought, a forum for thought and a support structure that can mobilize to<br />

fight the battles that need to be taken on. If one could get any<strong>thing</strong> sizable going, it is bound<br />

to produce thought that would permeate to corners <strong>of</strong> society that have been untouched by<br />

the left in 80 years.<br />

Just a thought.<br />

Message [1156] referenced by [1163]. Next Message by IrvingHowe is [1179].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 517<br />

[1159] GoUtes: I would just like to add on to the discussion <strong>of</strong> “cutting spending on war”.<br />

I agree with Zohan, I truly respect and admire those who have fought for our rights and<br />

freedoms, who put aside their families, friends, obligations at home and risk their lives for<br />

our freedom. For this Zohan I would like to thank you for your service. I adamantly believe<br />

that cutting back spending on <strong>thing</strong>s such as war would not make much <strong>of</strong> a difference in an<br />

already ever increasing national deficit.<br />

Now don’t get me wrong, we should not throw billions <strong>of</strong> dollars away just to be reckless<br />

or to a lost cause, but I personally believe that spending should not be cut, it should be<br />

increased if it gives our troops any sort <strong>of</strong> advantage in helping to liberate a country that<br />

other wise has no chance to succeed, but more than any<strong>thing</strong> else, if it helps to protect our<br />

rights and our freedoms, give our troops all that they need to defend our great nation.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong>re is no need to “adamantly believe” some<strong>thing</strong> if you can easily look up the facts on the internet.<br />

According to the Wikipedia entry for the Military budget <strong>of</strong> the United States, military spending swallows up over<br />

50% <strong>of</strong> total discretionary spending, and over 50% <strong>of</strong> tax revenues.<br />

Next Message by GoUtes is [1172].<br />

[1160] Orville: Ideas from Li. Just to add to Hal’s [1155], I agree with him. Minqi Li<br />

is a pr<strong>of</strong>essor who has come up in other discussions on this email list but allow me to throw<br />

his name out there one more time. In his class, we have learned how the failed wars are a<br />

sign that there will be a change in the hegemonic power. Like England being unable to win<br />

wars in India and other colonies, this clearly shows that a world power is slipping out <strong>of</strong> its<br />

dominant role. I agree with Hal in that we need to cut military spending and put it towards<br />

better investments, those being education, green technology, and social welfare programs.<br />

Li suggests in his book, “<strong>The</strong> Rise <strong>of</strong> China and the Demise <strong>of</strong> the Capitalist World<br />

Economy,” the war in Iraq and our inability to successfully set up a government and get<br />

our troops out <strong>of</strong> Iraq. I believe this to be true to an extent. <strong>The</strong> war in Vietnam seems to<br />

have said the same <strong>thing</strong> but we’ve been the world hegemonic power for 30+ years since<br />

then. <strong>The</strong> difference now is that there is a serious player who could take over the capitalist<br />

economy: China.<br />

I wonder what the future system will look like. Will China continue to run itself like a<br />

capitalist economy? Will India take over after China? I suppose the only <strong>thing</strong> to do now is<br />

wait.<br />

First Message by Orville is [104].<br />

[1162] Spiral: Tax break here, 100% write <strong>of</strong>f there. In response to [1109]; No doubt<br />

the current deal in Congress to extend unemployment benefits by 13 months for an extension<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Bush tax cuts for two years smacks <strong>of</strong> hypocrisy. Neither extension is paid for so the<br />

deficit will increase but just last week Congress was up in arms over recent proposals to fix<br />

our nation’s fiscal woes. <strong>The</strong> deal hasn’t been passed by both chambers <strong>of</strong> Congress yet so<br />

it remains to be seen what percentage capitalists will be able to write <strong>of</strong>f. <strong>The</strong> President<br />

has publicly shared his support for the deal should it reach his desk for signing. Marx sees<br />

capitalism as a fluid system constantly in motion and should this movement slow or stop the<br />

system careens toward collapse. This is what happened during the recent great recession;<br />

money stopped flowing through Wall Street’s wires where it was concentrated in the hands<br />

<strong>of</strong> a few precipitating the chain reaction <strong>of</strong> foreclosures and bankruptcies. Tax write <strong>of</strong>fs<br />

in this case are a means for the government to facilitate necessary fluidity <strong>of</strong> capital for<br />

518 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

growth. This system <strong>of</strong> growth creation does work for the capitalists who can guarantee<br />

public <strong>of</strong>ficials jobs and campaign donations. What can the working-class promise public<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials except their individual votes? Some politicians focus on how to maximize their<br />

vote to dollar spent ratio in the campaign for public <strong>of</strong>fice which skews attention toward<br />

capitalists with their monetary shows <strong>of</strong> support. If tax incentives for capital investment<br />

decrease it will be harder for those already in the corridors <strong>of</strong> power to remain there.<br />

Next Message by Spiral is [1166].<br />

[1163] Wolf: For Proletarian. I agree with IrvingHowe in [1156] that worker-owned<br />

cooperatives will not effectively counter capitalism. While it makes for a more pleasant<br />

work-atmosphere, it does no<strong>thing</strong> except showing a limited alternative which only can be<br />

done by those who are economically priviledged enough to start a business.<br />

As was said before, what should we do? If there were a large anti-capitalist movement capable<br />

<strong>of</strong> gaining momentum which could effectively counter the current paradigm, it would,<br />

in all likelihood, be violently supressed. This has shown true in this country’s history with<br />

the maching-gunning <strong>of</strong> strikers to COINTELPRO or assassination. Despite these odds, I<br />

feel it is imperative that we continue building an anti-capitalist movement as this would intersect<br />

most <strong>of</strong> the few social movements which currently exist, those being the labor movement,<br />

animal-rights, environmental, anti-authoritarian, and the small remnants <strong>of</strong> the dead<br />

anti-war and anti-globalization movements (besides the small Zapatista movement).<strong>The</strong>se<br />

struggles are interconnected with capital’s totality and as an anti-capitalist strategy, it makes<br />

sense to network with these movements in order to broaden anti-capitalist struggle.<br />

With this, I have lost complete hope in political parties and now view both Left and<br />

Right as strategies to better manage the effects <strong>of</strong> capital through whatever social climate it<br />

encounters. Even charity work eases the strains manifested by capital, enabling its continuation.<br />

It has taken over all life, as well as all possible avenues for escape or struggle, using<br />

them for its reproduction (think the Left, powerful labor unions, and globalization).<br />

<strong>The</strong> only possibility I see is in the beginnings <strong>of</strong> collapse. If crises develop small cracks<br />

in capitalism, it could be increasingly easier for the anti-capitalist movement to insert itself<br />

within them, widening them. Other than that, I feel as if capital has almost entirely won.<br />

On a brighter note, no system exists for ever and it seems as if capitalism is nearing a limit<br />

(environmentally) which could create new possibilities in anti-capitalist struggle. It will be<br />

very interesting to see how the world plays out in the next two decades.<br />

I’m sorry for the overall pessimism and don’t hope to disuade you from acting. It is<br />

easy to be hopeless, apathetic, and feel a sense <strong>of</strong> powerlessness. That’s what capital wants!<br />

Think <strong>of</strong> it this way: <strong>The</strong>re is much work to be done. Also, take note that my anarchist<br />

convictions change how I view our situation as I don’t feel any green government will lead<br />

us to communism, thus limiting my favorable options. I would suggest, as further reading,<br />

many <strong>of</strong> the french communists (more recent ones), some Zizek, Negri (or any Italian<br />

communists/anarchists from the 70’s), Camatte, and Chomsky (as info on US foreign policy).<br />

<strong>The</strong>se authors tend to tickle my palate. You could always check out revleft.com if you<br />

are interested in discussion amongst left and post-left radicals/revolutionaries. Find local<br />

struggles and radicals and ally with them!<br />

Message [1163] referenced by [1165]. First Message by Wolf is [39].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 519<br />

[1165] Ferox: DIY- taking down capitalism one project at a time. Proletarian [1146]<br />

has posed a question that I believe we should all be asking right now. Given the tools and<br />

knowledge we have acquired to critically analyze the capitalist structure around us, where<br />

do we as individuals and a small group begin? Personally, I agree with Wolf [1163] in that<br />

capital has almost (emphasis here) entirely won, that to look to government or action through<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficial channels for drastic and necessary change only perpetuates the capitalist system. It<br />

is a very pessimistic (albeit realistic outlook in my opinion) to have.<br />

However, I also agree with Wolf in that there is much work to be done. To buy into the<br />

feelings <strong>of</strong> hopelessness and pessimism is to acknowledge that capitalism has completely<br />

(emphasis again) won. This, I believe, is not true. Change begins with small actions and<br />

the strength <strong>of</strong> the individual. At the core <strong>of</strong> Marx’s analysis <strong>of</strong> capital is the labor theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. That is, the human sentience acting upon natural forces thereby effecting directed<br />

change is the origin <strong>of</strong> value. <strong>The</strong> will to act upon (or against) those forces (both natural and<br />

unnatural) in our lives is the genesis <strong>of</strong> meaningful and valued existence.<br />

As a suggestion to anyone looking to break away some <strong>of</strong> the shackles <strong>of</strong> the capitalist<br />

system imposed upon us - I recommend taking a DIY attitude. DIY (acronym for Do<br />

It Yourself) is the act <strong>of</strong> making, repairing, or modifying some<strong>thing</strong> without the aid <strong>of</strong> experts<br />

or pr<strong>of</strong>essionals. This has many effects. By circumventing the traditional markets and<br />

consumer culture where we are forced to rely on others to satisfy our needs, we are taking<br />

back some <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production back for ourselves. We are making a stand against<br />

capitalist monopolies on production, against consumption, and against exploitation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

laborer. Through the act <strong>of</strong> creation we are imbuing objects with value and generating skills<br />

for ourselves - even if the pair <strong>of</strong> pants you sewed are not as ‘well made’ as those produced<br />

by exploitative labour processes in Third World countries or in line with the latest fashions<br />

imposed upon us, pride can be taken in the fact that YOU made them. <strong>The</strong>y are a crystallization<br />

<strong>of</strong> YOUR labor power. YOU gave them value. YOU have prevented the system <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalist exploitation for one pair <strong>of</strong> pants.<br />

I have found this mindset has helped me in my life to appreciate what I have, do more with<br />

what others perceive as less, expand my creative horizons, share skills and learn new ones,<br />

and meet a host <strong>of</strong> people who for one reason or another have said enough to the destructive<br />

exploitation <strong>of</strong> capitalism - giving me a sense <strong>of</strong> community. As we near the twilight <strong>of</strong> a<br />

First World capitalist lifestyle, I think we can all benefit from this mindset.<br />

First Message by Ferox is [85].<br />

[1169] Zohan: One last comment. I have one last comment to make on Hal [1155]<br />

I realize that your comments were not solely directed on military spending and I thought<br />

you had some valid points. I agree that a nation that is under economic distress should<br />

rationally cut military spending to unneeded campaigns. I would also agree that America<br />

should be extremely cautious <strong>of</strong> how and when we chose to get involved with the conflicts <strong>of</strong><br />

the world. Policies to reduce unneeded spending in certain sectors should be implemented<br />

durning times <strong>of</strong> economic downturn. Unfortunately our nation is facing a economic crisis<br />

at the same time as being heavily involved in two major conflicts and reducing military<br />

spending may cause more harm than good at this point. It is a complicated situation.<br />

520 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

We invest our budget on social programs like Medicaid and unemployment but when<br />

compared to military spending what overall advantage do you gain. Military spending brings<br />

advances in technology, medicine, defence systems and energy security for our nation. <strong>The</strong>se<br />

are all areas that America must continue to develop and invest in if we want to remain as one<br />

<strong>of</strong> the great nations <strong>of</strong> the world.<br />

First Message by Zohan is [213].<br />

[1173] JJ: So now I’m a Marxist. Where do we go from here. One <strong>of</strong> the <strong>thing</strong>s that<br />

we’ve been discussing in the class sessions is where we should go from here and what we<br />

took away from the class. How can us new-born converted Marxists now go out into the<br />

world and assimilate into a purely capitalist society?<br />

At the beginning <strong>of</strong> the semester, this class had me scrambling. I found that I had to<br />

completely clear my mind <strong>of</strong> all that I had learned before and start over my learning as if I<br />

was a child. This was the only way that I found that I could start to comprehend the ideas<br />

<strong>of</strong> Marx on Capitalism, without allowing any <strong>of</strong> my preconceived notions to come into play.<br />

It’s almost as if this was the way the Marx intended it and I believe that this has much to do<br />

with the order in which he displays his different ideas. Hans wasn’t kidding in the syllabus<br />

when he discusses that the majority <strong>of</strong> the work for this class will come hard and heavy in<br />

the <strong>first</strong> few weeks. This is part <strong>of</strong> the reasoning <strong>of</strong> why we don’t have a final exam in this<br />

class. I heartily agree with Hans’ assessment <strong>of</strong> the work load and his choices on how to<br />

handle the testing. This has naught to do with any desire to get a freebie on a theoretical final<br />

exam, but every<strong>thing</strong> to do with the level <strong>of</strong> mind altering concentration this class required<br />

in the <strong>first</strong> few weeks.<br />

“Clear your mind young grasshopper and imagine a commodity and only this one commodity.<br />

. . .”<br />

By doing so, I believe that I might have actually turned some switch in my brain that<br />

I’m fearful that I won’t be able to turn <strong>of</strong>f. If only that I always thought <strong>of</strong> myself as a<br />

conservative independent, and now for the <strong>first</strong> time in my life I find myself wondering if<br />

there isn’t some<strong>thing</strong> else to all <strong>of</strong> this. Maybe, some<strong>thing</strong> inside me has been awoken to<br />

let me realize that I have some desire to be more liberal, or socialistic, or maybe I’m just a<br />

sleeping Marxist and I don’t know it yet. Long story short is that many <strong>of</strong> the ideas on the<br />

capitalistic system hit home and hit home hard. You might even say that I’m a capitalist that<br />

read Marx’s “Capital” and find myself a little bit ashamed. Am I that same capitalist that<br />

has a werewolf’s hunger for the surplus labor <strong>of</strong> my minimum wage employees? ( I work<br />

in management ) Or will I continue to convince myself that this world is a “dog eat dog”<br />

world? Will I continue with my philosophy <strong>of</strong> marginalism wherein there should only be a<br />

survival <strong>of</strong> the fittest? This works for the world <strong>of</strong> biology and for the wild animals in the<br />

Serengeti, why shouldn’t this work for us? Is the only solution to “go rogue” and quit my<br />

job before I add to the amount <strong>of</strong> exploitation? (Going Rogue is not a Sarah Palin reference,<br />

but it would be funny if it was) Do I have any free will in choosing whether I will or will not<br />

be a cog in the capitalist machine? Do I choose, as a management figure and representative<br />

<strong>of</strong> the company, to cooperate with labor unions at the risk <strong>of</strong> losing my job? I don’t have the<br />

answers to any <strong>of</strong> the above necessarily, but find myself thinking these crazy thought after<br />

completing this class.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 521<br />

I have spent some time this evening going over my old submissions and was so interested<br />

to see the difference <strong>of</strong> my <strong>first</strong> submissions. I truly believe that I was thinking differently<br />

when I made these submissions. Although I thought myself to be logical, I now look back at<br />

these same submissions and ask myself, “what was I thinking?”. Hans [71] even pointed out<br />

that my submission [70] was as good as my volunteer consent to be the class guinea pig. I’m<br />

glad that he did this to challenge me. I once again found that to even begin to comprehend so<br />

many <strong>of</strong> the ideas that I had to clear my mind and slowly build a new structure and thought<br />

process. <strong>The</strong> labor theory <strong>of</strong> value! Labor itself being embedded into a commodity!? This<br />

was crazy talk. Yet, I now find myself questioning why it can’t be true as a labor-theory <strong>of</strong><br />

value now seems all but too natural for me.<br />

Does this mean that I’m now a Marxist? I don’t think that it does, but I know for sure that<br />

I’m some<strong>thing</strong> different than what I was before.<br />

In speaking with some <strong>of</strong> you after class, I find that many <strong>of</strong> you also feel the same way.<br />

Are you also now Marxists, or have you even budged a few inches in that direction more<br />

than you did since you began this class? I guess it depends on whether you see yourself as a<br />

capitalist <strong>of</strong> a worker.<br />

Message [1173] referenced by [133] and [1176]. Next Message by JJ is [1174].<br />

[1175] She: Tax cuts...what income bracket is more likely to spend the extra cash?<br />

When an economy is down, as a true believer in demand-side economics, I believe that<br />

circulating and spending money is the only way to fix it. If our government is going to give<br />

people more money based on their income, where should these policies be concentrated to<br />

achieve the greatest effect?<br />

If we give the top 2% additional money, the Republicans are saying that they will create<br />

jobs with it. <strong>The</strong> reality is that the top 2% already have money sitting around, idle that<br />

they would use if they were going to invest, but they aren’t investing it because there is no<br />

demand for new products and services since many middle income families cannot afford to<br />

spend more money. So, if we give the top 2% more money, there is no guarantee it will get<br />

spent or circulated in any way in our economy.<br />

Study after study have shown that the lower we go on the income scale, the less money<br />

people save. This isn’t because they are bad with money, it is because they have such a small<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> it, there is never a surplus after basic goods are purchased. Tax benefits given<br />

to the lower income classes is guaranteed to be spent and begin the process <strong>of</strong> circulation<br />

through our economy, benefiting countless people along its way. Tax benefits for the middle<br />

class achieve almost the same effect.<br />

Middle class families, when given more income, tend to save only a small portion and<br />

tend to consume more goods and services when provided with the opportunity.<br />

<strong>The</strong> increased consumption <strong>of</strong> the middle and lower class will stimulate demand which<br />

will require the capitalists at the top to invest and create more jobs to keep up with the new<br />

increased demand. <strong>The</strong> demand for labor is not some<strong>thing</strong> that can be created on the supply<br />

side; it is truly demand driven.<br />

First Message by She is [37].<br />

522 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1176] Max: So now I’m a Marxist. Where do we go from here. Sweet submission<br />

[1173]. I’ve also learned a lot that has changed the way I think. In a perfect system, I think<br />

socialism would be the best option for a large population commodity producing society. In a<br />

small population, I think anarchism with strong moral upbringing is the most decentralized<br />

government. However, I think that in America today, too many people fear socialism, especially<br />

because on one end <strong>of</strong> the spectrum you have republicanism which wants to do away<br />

with big government. It is this idea that makes me a big believer in Jeffersonian Democracy;<br />

where individualism and strong moral upbringing is supported while at the same time restricting<br />

power from the wealthy. Jefferson believed we all should be self-sufficient farmers<br />

so we don’t have to succumb to the exploitative powers <strong>of</strong> corrupted businesses and financial<br />

institutions. While the self-sufficient farm movement is growing larger, Jeffersonian<br />

ideas may not be applicable to everyone. Still, I think his republican values can be a very<br />

strong uniting force in a divided America whose political parties are solely divided because<br />

<strong>of</strong> wedge issues like abortion and gay marriage. Jefferson wanted an end to big business,<br />

and I think his philosophy is a great way to incorporate anti-government Marxist sentiment<br />

without resorting to state controlled socialism.<br />

First Message by Max is [84].<br />

[1177] Cmellen: So now I’m a Marxist. Where do we go from here. Message from<br />

Purely Capitalist Society: “Resistance is futile! You will be assimilated.”<br />

Message [1177] referenced by [1178]. First Message by Cmellen is [6].<br />

[1178] Somramthom: Re: So now I’m a Marxist. Where do we go from here. In response<br />

to [1177]. Just because we learned a few <strong>thing</strong>s about how Karl Marx saw capitalism<br />

doesn’t change the fact that we were raised in a capitalistic society. My guess is most <strong>of</strong> us<br />

will continue on with little or no change in behavior.<br />

Just my guess though...<br />

Message [1178] referenced by [1179]. First Message by Somramthom is [28].<br />

[1179] IrvingHowe: So now I’m a Marxist. Where do we go from here. Just because<br />

you are raised a certain way does not mean you should continue on in such a way. Anybody<br />

else want to pick up on the racism <strong>of</strong> our parents generation??<br />

Also, you are right in [1178] that many people in the class will probably go on with their<br />

lives in the way that they were before this class. If you fit into that group, my guess is that<br />

this post was not intended for you.<br />

Final Grading Note by Hans: You are more mature, more realistic, yet more radical than most <strong>of</strong> the other<br />

participants. This is a rare combination.<br />

First Message by IrvingHowe is [150].<br />

[1180] Kobe: what we know now. I can truly say I understand both sides <strong>of</strong> the coin,<br />

capitalist ideas vs. marxist ideas, after this semester <strong>of</strong> classes. With the problems that are<br />

going on today in our government we hear many talk and radio hosts commenting that the<br />

current regime are Marxist and hate the idea <strong>of</strong> capitalism. Until taking this class I didn’t<br />

fully understand what they were talking about when they said this. This class will now allow<br />

me to see both sides <strong>of</strong> the argument and both sides <strong>of</strong> issues that are going on today, such<br />

as tax breaks. Because I was raised in a capitalist society I believe I am a capitalist but have<br />

much more respect for Marxist ideas. Through Marx writing and ideas I believe if we were<br />

to incorporate some <strong>of</strong> these ideas in our capitalist society we could see great growth in our


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 523<br />

economy. <strong>The</strong>re is my two cents, what does everyone else feel? Has this class changed your<br />

way <strong>of</strong> thinking or even made you believe you are a Marxist?<br />

First Message by Kobe is [394].<br />

[1181] Intaglio: So now I’m a Marxist. Where do we go from here. lol at all the<br />

reactionaries in this class.<br />

Where to? I’d recommend exploring the different tendencies within socialism. <strong>The</strong>re are<br />

incredibly different ideas within the left wing, especially on how to get to socialism. <strong>The</strong>re<br />

are authoritarian forms <strong>of</strong> socialism and there are libertarian/anarchist forms. Personally, I<br />

prefer socialist-anarchism. Historically marxism has been implemented from the top down,<br />

causing stagnant workers. Yes, workers are still pissed when their capitalist oppressor is replace<br />

by the state oppressor. Give them control <strong>of</strong> their labor! Some even consider “marxist”<br />

state exploitation <strong>of</strong> the worker more harsh that the capitalist pillaging. <strong>The</strong>re are also huge<br />

bureaucratic corruption problems within the state apparatuses marxists have set up. <strong>The</strong> various<br />

critiques <strong>of</strong> what happened in the Soviet Union are really important. See the anarchist<br />

and libertarian-marxist criticisms <strong>of</strong> state-socialism. <strong>The</strong> Leninists (authoritarian socialists)<br />

will defend the state no matter how obvious its troubles are, but you should probably read<br />

Lenin’s <strong>The</strong> State and Revolution regardless.<br />

But then there are marxists who see these state route as being antithetical to socialism,<br />

such as the autonomous-marxists and council communists. Also see what the Anarchist-<br />

Communists have to say and where they differ from marxists on communism. Kropotkin<br />

is a good place to start with anti-state communism. Most anarchists largely agree with<br />

marx’s critique <strong>of</strong> capital, though i would say Marx is too determinist. Or maybe you’ll like<br />

Mutualism, a socialist/anti-capitalist free market. yeah everyone that reads Marx should also<br />

read Kropotkin. <strong>The</strong> Conquest <strong>of</strong> Bread.<br />

http://libcom.org/library/the-conquest-<strong>of</strong>-bread-peter-kropotkin<br />

First Message by Intaglio is [194].<br />

[1183] Smartergirl: So now I’m a Marxist. Where do we go from here. Its interesting<br />

to me that every<strong>thing</strong> has to have a label. Socialism, anarchism, capitalism. I think its<br />

fair to say that each <strong>of</strong> them have their pros and cons. It would be great to take the best<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> these and try to incorporate them into a productive cooperative system.<br />

No labels necessary. <strong>The</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> having a label and an all or no<strong>thing</strong> perspective is why our<br />

government is stagnate and not making nearly the rapid progress that we could be. Instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> wrapping a new idea or perspective into a labeled preconcived system, present the ideas<br />

and their more likely to become a reality. Im not a firm believer in every<strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong> any<strong>thing</strong><br />

but would rather incorporate the strengths <strong>of</strong> many systems to get closer to a perfect one.<br />

First Message by Smartergirl is [440].<br />

[1186] RexManning: Marx as a person. I am curious, does anyone know what kind<br />

<strong>of</strong> background Marx came from? Was he born into a wealthy family, a poor family? This<br />

class has really gotten me interested in Marx as a person. Was there an identifiable “turning<br />

point” in his life that spurred some <strong>of</strong> his thinking? Maybe someone can recommend a good<br />

biography.<br />

First Message by RexManning is [9].<br />

524 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1187] Husani: Taxes and Unemployment Benefits. Earlier this week President Obama<br />

made a deal with Republican Congressman which would renew the Bush era tax cuts for<br />

another two years. This bill is projected to cost the Federal goverment $857.8 billion due to<br />

lost tax revenues. I guess I’m just confused by the Tea Party movement and their motives.<br />

Leading up to the election last month they were running on reducing the federal debt but<br />

when they have the opportunity to do some<strong>thing</strong> about, they decide to give money to the<br />

ubber rich instead (by providing the top 2% with a tax cut). As this was being worked out<br />

the Republicans voted down a bill that would provide First Responders <strong>of</strong> 9/11 with $4.2<br />

Billion that would go to pay their medical bills. Why are the rich more important than the<br />

people who save lives?<br />

I just wanted to get some opinions on the recent decisions made in congress. I believe<br />

that this is a sign that we need a bit more Marxism and a little less capitalism.<br />

Message [1187] referenced by [1188]. First Message by Husani is [124].<br />

[1188] JJ: Taxes and Unemployment Benefits. Many <strong>of</strong> the questions that were posed<br />

in [1187] and their varied responses can depend greatly on your perspective to the situation.<br />

Democrats are calling it a renewal <strong>of</strong> Bush era tax cuts and [1187] labelled this as a cost<br />

and loss <strong>of</strong> some 857 billion dollars in revenue to the government. Seems even Obama is<br />

making a deal with the devil.<br />

I watched the opening statements to this latest session known as the “lame duck” session.<br />

Republicans kept trying to remind everyone that in their view this was not a tax cut for the<br />

rich, but the continued denial <strong>of</strong> a tax hike. To them this is not a loss <strong>of</strong> tax revenue, but a<br />

continued savings to the American people.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fact that this vote was even brought forward by the democrats in the lame duck<br />

session proves this to be politics and not economics. In this I mean to say that even the<br />

democrats knew that they had zero chance <strong>of</strong> this passing, but brought it forward regardless<br />

to set the tone for their agenda. This failed vote is a chess move in a larger game <strong>of</strong> politics.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fact that it was even brought forward and painted in such a light is actually a win for the<br />

democrats. Republicans look exactly as [1187] described them to many in the world unless<br />

you happen to be a member <strong>of</strong> the 2% elite. This had to be what the democrats set out to do<br />

in a lame duck session. Mission accomplished! <strong>The</strong>re’s a reason its called the “Lame Duck”<br />

session. <strong>The</strong>re is a lot <strong>of</strong> shuffling and maneuvering, but no<strong>thing</strong> really gets done. I think<br />

that this is frustrating for both sides <strong>of</strong> the aisle and is most frustrating for the American<br />

public.<br />

Also, you’d think that even our congress could put aside their differences to take care<br />

<strong>of</strong> our wounded <strong>first</strong> responders from 9/11. Yet I wonder if the 4.2 Billion dollar 9/11 <strong>first</strong><br />

responder bill was as simple as that. More <strong>of</strong>ten than not, bills with that are well intended<br />

have ear marks or addendums that accomplish some other goal that is completely unrelated.<br />

I only say this so that people might dig further to ensure that their was no ulterior motives<br />

to the bill that also doomed it before it even came to a vote. In these siutations, Is this the<br />

fault <strong>of</strong> the parrty that lumped partisan agendas into a non-partisan bill? Or the fault <strong>of</strong> the<br />

party that shoots down the good willed bill in their refusal to ignore the side deals that were


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 525<br />

thrown in with it. I see this as more politics and not economics. This is a flaw in the system<br />

that both sides exploit to either send political messages or to tack on their side agendas.<br />

At the end <strong>of</strong> the post [1187] it was stated that we needed less capitalism and more<br />

Marxism. I couldn’t help but notice that the tone <strong>of</strong> the post implied that Marx would have<br />

sided in favor <strong>of</strong> democrat’s agenda. This is why politics isn’t always economics. It is hard<br />

to say whether Marx would not laugh or cry at the futility <strong>of</strong> the whole situation. Would<br />

Marx side with the republicans or with the democrats? I think with neither. What is another<br />

900 billion in the hands <strong>of</strong> the elite 2% capitalists or in the hands <strong>of</strong> the capitalist controlled<br />

government? What good would the 900 billion do for the worker and the laboring class<br />

when the money is controlled by a capitalistic republican government? What good does any<br />

<strong>of</strong> our complaining do. It will not be our government that saves us from capitalism, it can<br />

only be ourselves organized into groups. I believe that Marx might see that both sides <strong>of</strong> the<br />

aisle are in a love affair with capitalism<br />

In our last class session Hans noted some comments <strong>of</strong> Ralph Nader. <strong>The</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

course had turned to capitalism and its effects not only on the working class, but, as it so<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten does, to its negative effects on the environment. Hans reminded us that Nader had one<br />

time commented on our plight with the environment. Nader said some<strong>thing</strong> to the effect that<br />

we were in a downward spiral concerning global warming and the environment and that the<br />

only <strong>thing</strong> that might be our salvation would be inspired billionaires choosing to do the right<br />

<strong>thing</strong>.<br />

Naders comments made sense to me. What if the top 2% elite saw the light and helped us<br />

to course correct. If its true that they control our government via lobbyists then our resistance<br />

is futile in the long run. A few inspired billionaires could do some good in this world. Yet,<br />

I think we know that we can’t wait for the day that inspired billionaires save us from our<br />

plight. We also need to organize.<br />

Inspired billionaires or a revolutionary working class to slow the hunger <strong>of</strong> capitalism,<br />

either way I agree that we need some changes. Sometime’s that’s all we need is the ability<br />

to agree <strong>first</strong> on some<strong>thing</strong> and then we can build and organize from there. <strong>The</strong> antics <strong>of</strong> one<br />

session <strong>of</strong> congress will be meaningless in the long run if we are not organised.<br />

First Message by JJ is [70].<br />

890 Essay for the <strong>Utah</strong> Labor Newsletter<br />

[755] Hans: Second Exam and Check List for Getting a Good Grade. This year’s<br />

class discussion has such a high quality that I’d like to give everyone a good grade. Here is<br />

a check list, for making sure you are meeting the minimum requirements and which informs<br />

you <strong>of</strong> extra credit options:<br />

Submit at least 5 homework answers in 5 different homework periods. And be aware, if<br />

you make more than 5 regular homework submissions, then the worst grade will be dropped!<br />

Participation in both midterms (the second midterm will be THIS COMING FRIDAY,<br />

Nov 19, and Tuesday Nov 23. Those who took the <strong>first</strong> Midterm on Friday morning must<br />

take the second Midterm on Friday, otherwise there will be a 10% grade penalty for the<br />

in-class portion <strong>of</strong> the midterm.<br />

526 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Submit your term paper.<br />

Here are extra credit opportunities:<br />

<strong>The</strong> discussions in preparation <strong>of</strong> the exams are riskless extra credit. This will be possible<br />

again between this coming Tuesday until Thursday morning, Nov 16-18<br />

Also discussions <strong>of</strong> the term papers are a riskless extra credit opportunity. Right now until<br />

the end <strong>of</strong> Monday, term papers [686], [699], [739], and [735] are in the archives waiting for<br />

your input. I made lots <strong>of</strong> comments to [699] if you want to have an example.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are two additional extra credit opportunities in this Semester, they are not in the<br />

syllabus:<br />

(a) <strong>Utah</strong> Jobs with Justice is sponsoring a labor newsletter edited by <strong>Utah</strong> workers where<br />

they tell each other about the latest struggles and outrages on their jobs. If you can report<br />

about some interesting happenings in your worklife, and if you want to be published (probably<br />

anonymously) in the premier issue <strong>of</strong> this Newsletter (probably right after the holidays),<br />

please submit it under question number 890. This should not just be a collection <strong>of</strong> stories<br />

but also a discussion about what should go into such a labor newsletter. Bosses have become<br />

incredibly bold lately, this needs to be exposed, but should we also discuss the ways how<br />

workers arrange themselves with the system? I think Bigwhite [753] posed an important and<br />

by no means trivial question: what is one to think <strong>of</strong> it if a worker stops hating exploitation<br />

but finds ways to arranges himself <strong>of</strong> herself with it? If you contribute stories or thoughts<br />

to this discussion, this will give you an extra credit grade similiar to the termpaper discussions.<br />

(With this message here I am testing whether I correctly set up the computer to accept<br />

question 890.)<br />

(b) I am also looking for readers and editors <strong>of</strong> the Annotations. I am spending a lot <strong>of</strong><br />

time this year to revise the Annotations and make them clearer. If someone wants to work<br />

through a portion <strong>of</strong> the latest version <strong>of</strong> the Annotations, please contact me. I will make a<br />

printout available to you which is printed only on half <strong>of</strong> the page with the other half blank,<br />

and all I need is you carefully reading it and jotting down some notes: what you find unclear<br />

or unconvincing, what you agree with, better formulations, questions, etc.<br />

Message [755] referenced by [864]. Next Message by Hans is [760].<br />

[777] Hans: <strong>The</strong> New Faces <strong>of</strong> Labor. Here is some<strong>thing</strong> written by a socialist organizer.<br />

What do you think? Should this be included in the labor newsletter, or is it too radical? Does<br />

it need changes? Your input is appreciated. Obviously, the rest <strong>of</strong> this message is not written<br />

by me. Hans.<br />

Last year I was fired from my job <strong>of</strong> 5 years at a call center. I was not let go due to<br />

performance issues, the economic crisis nor restructuring. I was brought into the director’s<br />

<strong>of</strong>fice by the CEO <strong>of</strong> the company and told that I was being let go because <strong>of</strong> reports that<br />

I was working with the agents on the call floor to form a union. At this point, I closed my<br />

mouth and did not open it again until I was told that I had 60 seconds to get my stuff and<br />

get <strong>of</strong>f the property or they would call the police. I did not open my mouth because I did<br />

not want to say any<strong>thing</strong> that could jeopardize the union organizing movement. I was not<br />

allowed to say good bye to any <strong>of</strong> my co-workers, I was told that unions bring violence and<br />

how dare I bring this upon the company. That my actions were not in the best interest <strong>of</strong> the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 527<br />

company. What I wanted to say was how are your actions in the best interest <strong>of</strong> the workers?<br />

<strong>The</strong> people that make THIS company the money? How is it in their best interest to take<br />

away their bonuses without notice? To not <strong>of</strong>fer insurance that did not cost more than they<br />

made? How is it in their best interest that seniority not matter when it comes to pay? How<br />

is it in their best interest that you not <strong>of</strong>fer them computer monitors that show the needed<br />

materials to do their job without ruining their eyesight? How is it in their best interest to not<br />

<strong>of</strong>fer paid sick time?<br />

I had no protection when they fired me. I was not an hourly worker, but a Sr. Manager, a<br />

manager that was sick <strong>of</strong> the workers working so hard, and being last to benefit. <strong>The</strong> harder<br />

they worked the more money the company made, but that money never made its way down to<br />

benefit the very people that were making it. When some <strong>of</strong> the agents came to me to tell me<br />

how unhappy they were and that they were working on doing a walk <strong>of</strong>f or strike I realized<br />

that I had a decision to make. Being a socialist, I was perhaps a bit more informed <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ramifications that an action like walking <strong>of</strong>f or striking without union protection would only<br />

hurt the workers more. So I told them about unions and joined the union movement. I knew<br />

the second I did that there was no turning back. That in my position I would not benefit<br />

from the formation <strong>of</strong> a union, but there comes a time when you have to be willing to lose<br />

a bit personally to stand up and fight for some<strong>thing</strong> that is right and affects more then just<br />

yourself.<br />

Now I know that when you hear about unions and the working class you usually think <strong>of</strong><br />

production lines and hard helmets, but oh how times have changed. Production in the US<br />

has dwindled, due to the outsourcing <strong>of</strong> the manufacturing jobs since globalization, and with<br />

that has gone our working class consciousness. With credit the working class was made to<br />

believe that we can afford any<strong>thing</strong>, we can buy a car, a house—We are living the American<br />

dream!! We are middle class!! But last year most <strong>of</strong> the country had an awakening—Banks<br />

were failing and credit was freezing—And with that came the cold reality to most <strong>of</strong> the<br />

“Middle Class,” a reality that made us see that we are not middle class, we are working<br />

class. Job descriptions might have changed, we may be more service then production, but as<br />

we are all working for a pay check, we are all part <strong>of</strong> the working class, and that is no<strong>thing</strong><br />

to be ashamed <strong>of</strong>.<br />

This company that I worked for was not a manufacturing plant, nor a production line. It<br />

was an outsourced call center. Not the type <strong>of</strong> place you would normally think <strong>of</strong> unionizing.<br />

But times have changed. Call centers are the new sweat shops. Instead <strong>of</strong> sewing, we are<br />

stuck at our computers, taking call after call. Making sure that we are up selling each call<br />

and not letting the customer <strong>of</strong>f the phone until they have said “no” twice. We are not given<br />

time between calls to pull ourselves together to face the next customer, we are told when we<br />

can take our breaks and lunches, <strong>of</strong>ten called <strong>of</strong>f those to help answer the phones. We are<br />

sent home <strong>first</strong> if volume is slow with no pay. We have supervisors monitoring each call we<br />

take, each status we chose, how <strong>of</strong>ten we go to the bathroom, every<strong>thing</strong>. So it might not be<br />

a typical place to find a union but there is a desperate need for one.<br />

So here we are the new faces <strong>of</strong> labor. <strong>The</strong> new faces <strong>of</strong> the working class. We are the<br />

majority <strong>of</strong> what once was a great country, and what could be again. Unionizing and building<br />

solidarity with our communities is just as important as the air we breathe. Right now our<br />

528 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

communities are being picked apart separately by the system. Be it the passing <strong>of</strong> bills like<br />

SB 81, the failure <strong>of</strong> the common grounds initiative, to the continuation <strong>of</strong> environmental<br />

destruction, the recent shut out <strong>of</strong> single payer healthcare and the stalling <strong>of</strong> the Employee<br />

Free Choice Act. <strong>The</strong>se are stalling because we are, as the working class, we need to stop<br />

seeing the people standing next to us as strangers and see them as members <strong>of</strong> our working<br />

class community. It is time for us as the working class to stand up and say “Enough”<br />

WE WILL NOT GIVE MORE CONCESSIONS TO BIG BUSINESS<br />

WE WILL NOT FACE ONE MORE OUNCE OF DISCRIMINATION<br />

WE WILL NOT STAND BY AND ALLOW FAMILIES TO BE RIPPED APART BASED<br />

ON HOW SOMEONE CAME INTO THE COUNTRY THEY NOW CALL HOME<br />

WE WILL NOT ALLOW ANYONE ELSE TO TELL US WHO WE CAN OR CANNOT<br />

MARRY.<br />

WE WILL NOT PAY FOR BANKS’ BONUSES AND PARTIES WHILE SO MANY<br />

OF OUR WORKING CLASS BROTHERS AND SISTERS ARE BEING KICKED OUT<br />

OF OUR HOMES.<br />

As the new faces <strong>of</strong> labor and the newly informed members <strong>of</strong> the working class it is our<br />

DUTY to take what we have learned and join the already informed working class to continue<br />

to learn and spread our momentum and raise our voices so that no one else in our community<br />

gets discriminated against, or lost fighting on their own.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [813].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 891 is 433 in 1998WI, 583 in 2001fa, 628 in 2002fa, 652 in 2003fa, 711 in<br />

2004fa, 657 in 2005fa, 754 in 2007fa, 784 in 2008SP, 789 in 2008fa, 823 in 2009fa, and<br />

954 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 891 Why does the capitalist have the motive to get the same labor-time out <strong>of</strong> a<br />

smaller number <strong>of</strong> workers? Which economic facts did Marx refer to, and which additional<br />

economic facts go in the same direction nowadays?<br />

[1144] Somramthom: graded A Low costs and lower costs. <strong>The</strong> main reason a capitalist<br />

would want to get the same labor-time out <strong>of</strong> a smaller number <strong>of</strong> workers is to reduce costs.<br />

<strong>The</strong> fewer costs the capitalist incurs, the more surplus labor he can extract from the worker.<br />

Enticing a current worker to work more hours would result in the same amount <strong>of</strong> surplus<br />

value created as hiring another worker, only with fewer costs incurred. As Marx puts it, “If<br />

[the capitalist] has to hire more workers, the outlay <strong>of</strong> constant capital increases in proportion<br />

to the mass <strong>of</strong> labor set in motion; if he gets more labor out <strong>of</strong> the same number <strong>of</strong> workers,<br />

that increase is much smaller.”<br />

For example, say Worker A works 20 hours a week and 10 <strong>of</strong> those hours is effectively<br />

spent producing surplus labor for the capitalist. If the capitalist wants to double the output<br />

he can do one <strong>of</strong> two options. He can either hire Worker B to also work 20 hours, thus<br />

giving him 10 more hours producing surplus value. Or he could entice Worker A to work 40<br />

hours a week resulting in the same amount <strong>of</strong> surplus value created. At this point it seems<br />

irrelevant whether the capitalist chooses either option. But Worker A is already trained, has


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 529<br />

a working spot, and already has incentive to work. He also, arguably, has greater loyalty to<br />

the capitalist and is less likely to quit the job than Worker B, who would be a new employee.<br />

Hiring Worker B would require paid training time, another spot in the factory to work, more<br />

machinery if it is required to work, and he would have to develop an incentive to work. Plus<br />

Worker A would have extra incentive to work more since he would get a greater paycheck<br />

and possible benefits.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are several areas <strong>of</strong> cost that can be decreased by hiring fewer people, both fixed<br />

and variable. More workers would require more machinery and building space and utilities<br />

like electricity, water, etc. So fixed costs would increase. <strong>The</strong> more workers you hire, the<br />

more time you have to spend to train them to be efficient workers. If you have benefits,<br />

then the more workers you hire the more it will cost to insure them and more investments to<br />

match as well as more taxes to pay. Thus, variable costs also increase.<br />

Costs would increase despite the path chosen. <strong>The</strong>y would just increase less with fewer<br />

workers.<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [1178].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 893 is 787 in 2007SP and 926 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 893 Why does the link between variable capital, employment, and labor performed<br />

become weaker as accumulation proceeds?<br />

[1167] Atticus: graded A– Technology Commands the Masses. Productivity increases<br />

in production processes leads to decreases in the amount <strong>of</strong> labor-power needed to perform<br />

the labor required to produce surplus value. Capitalistic tendencies decrease the ratio <strong>of</strong><br />

variable capital to constant capital. Constant capital is accumulated at a faster rate than<br />

variable capital. As firms competitively decrease the amount <strong>of</strong> variable capital relative<br />

to constant capital required to operate and to fulfill their incessant drive to acquire more<br />

surplus value they expand the relative surplus population. At the same time this is happening<br />

the accumulation <strong>of</strong> constant capital employs more variable capital but less <strong>of</strong> this variable<br />

capital is required per unit <strong>of</strong> constant capital. <strong>The</strong> growth <strong>of</strong> the total population increases<br />

as more variable capital is employed. Absolute variable capital does indeed increase but at a<br />

slower rate than constant capital. This leads to decreases in the employment rate <strong>of</strong> a given<br />

population.<br />

Firms decrease the rate <strong>of</strong> variable capital required to operate by quantitative and qualitative<br />

means. Qualitatively firms decrease variable capital through technological improvements<br />

<strong>of</strong> machinery used by either modification, more efficient labor processes requiring<br />

less labor power and/or the complete replacement <strong>of</strong> old machinery with new and more efficient<br />

machinery. <strong>The</strong> qualitative changes <strong>of</strong> the production process leads to the quantitative<br />

decrease <strong>of</strong> variable capital employed. Earlier forms <strong>of</strong> machinery and constant capital employed<br />

a greater number laborers that were more skilled. Technological innovations leads to<br />

the displacement <strong>of</strong> skilled labor with unskilled labor to operate machinery at reduced costs<br />

to the capitalists. “Machinery controls the laborer better and organizes the labor process in<br />

such a way that it can be sped up” (annotations pp. 714).<br />

530 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital effectively “weakens the link between variable capital, employment,<br />

and labor performed”.<br />

Hans: By a “weakening link” Marx means the labor performed becomes to some extent independent <strong>of</strong> variable<br />

capital and employment, i.e., the capitalist understands to get more labor without increasing employment or even<br />

increasing variable capital. Those mechanisms are described in [2007SP:1408].<br />

First Message by Atticus is [93].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 896 Marx says twice that the (Malthusian) law <strong>of</strong> population is a “beautiful” law.<br />

Why does he use the word “beautiful” here?<br />

[1110] Jon: <strong>The</strong> “beauty” <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> population. Marx here shows his humor when<br />

he calls the law <strong>of</strong> population beautiful. When looking at the context <strong>of</strong> this abnormally long<br />

sentence it becomes clear that the law <strong>of</strong> population is nice and neat and in all ways quite<br />

beautiful, the problem arises however that this is not the way the world works. <strong>The</strong> law <strong>of</strong><br />

population describes that wages are dependent on the absolute population size. Hans says<br />

that this is a mistake and that “the law <strong>of</strong> population is utterly unable to to explain the facts<br />

which according to Marx are: capital accumulation is not subordinate to the growth <strong>of</strong> the<br />

population.” <strong>The</strong> law <strong>of</strong> population is beautiful in a sarcastic way because it is not complete.<br />

As Marx puts it in Capital it would be absurd to lay down a law that says the movement <strong>of</strong><br />

capital is dependent simply on the movement <strong>of</strong> population. <strong>The</strong>re are too many factors to<br />

simplify it all to the law <strong>of</strong> population regardless <strong>of</strong> how simple clean cut and “beautiful” as<br />

it may be.<br />

Hans: This is a good example <strong>of</strong> the kind <strong>of</strong> questions you selected throughout the Semester: they deal with a<br />

small subtlety in Marx’s formulations, and your answer does not say any<strong>thing</strong> other than the Annotations say on<br />

the same page as the question. And the question is pretty irrelevant for the understanding <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory. You<br />

addressed similar nonessential subtleties in [118] and [202].<br />

First Message by Jon is [118].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 906 is 596 in 2001fa, 641 in 2002fa, 665 in 2003fa, 724 in 2004fa, 670 in<br />

2005fa, 799 in 2007SP, 803 in 2008fa, and 939 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 906 Which parts <strong>of</strong> the surplus population do these people belong to: A housewife<br />

looking for a job, someone employed part time (or with several part time jobs) looking for a<br />

full time job with benefits, high school graduates who don’t find jobs, someone unemployed<br />

actively looking for work, someone unemployed waiting until the unemployment compensation<br />

has run out, discouraged workers on welfare, someone who has a lower-paying job<br />

because her skills are outdated.<br />

[1124] Jo: Surplus Population Classification. I classified the workers as follows:<br />

1. A housewife looking for a job: latent surplus population<br />

Hans compares the latent surplus population to “a stream <strong>of</strong> ground water: the water is<br />

not visible on the surface but it will collect as soon as one digs a ditch.” (Annotations, p 730)<br />

<strong>The</strong> housewife has the potential to work, but is currently not being utilized as part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

workforce.<br />

2. Someone employed part-time looking for a full time job with benefits: stagnant surplus<br />

population


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 531<br />

This group is “characterized by a maximum <strong>of</strong> working time and a minimum <strong>of</strong> wages.”<br />

This group may be active in the labor force, yet holds irregular employment. Explains Marx,<br />

“It <strong>of</strong>fers capital an inexhaustible reservoir <strong>of</strong> disposable labor-power.” (Annotations, p. 731)<br />

Many workers in the U.S. economy are kept at part-time so that the employer does not have<br />

to <strong>of</strong>fer benefits. This helps keep them working as much as possible, while keeping their<br />

wages as low as possible.<br />

3. high school graduates who don’t find jobs: flowing surplus population or stagnant<br />

surplus population<br />

Hans explains on page 727 that “<strong>The</strong> flowing surplus population is readily reabsorbed<br />

again.” This group will not remain out <strong>of</strong> work for long. <strong>The</strong>y generally work in largescale<br />

industries that don’t require advanced education. However Marx explains that, “It<br />

is precisely among the workers in large-scale industry that we meet with the shortest lifeexpectancy.”<br />

(Annotations, p. 729) <strong>The</strong> high school graduates could fall into that category, or<br />

they could also be part <strong>of</strong> the stagnant surplus population, which is sometimes characterized<br />

by a low skill level.<br />

4. someone unemployed actively working for work: flowing surplus population<br />

This person will probably not stay out <strong>of</strong> work for long, as they are actively seeking<br />

employment. <strong>The</strong>y will probably be happy to take the <strong>first</strong> job that comes along.<br />

5. someone unemployed waiting until the unemployment compensation has run out: latent<br />

surplus population<br />

Like the housewife, this person also has the potential to work, but is hidden or is hiding.<br />

6. discouraged workers on welfare: stagnant surplus population<br />

“It’s conditions <strong>of</strong> life sink below the average normal level <strong>of</strong> the working class, and it is<br />

precisely this which makes it a broad target for specialized branches <strong>of</strong> capitalist exploitation.”<br />

(Annotations, p. 731)<br />

7. Someone who has a lower-paying job because her skills are outdated: stagnant surplus<br />

population<br />

“It is constantly recruited from workers in large-scale industry and agriculture who have<br />

become redundant, and especially from those decaying branches <strong>of</strong> industry where handicraft<br />

is giving way to manufacture, and manufacture to machmery.” (Annotations, p. 731)<br />

Next Message by Jo is [1171].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 908 is 472 in 1999SP, 643 in 2002fa, 726 in 2004fa, 672 in 2005fa, 801 in<br />

2007SP, 800 in 2008SP, 805 in 2008fa, 838 in 2009fa, and 941 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 908 What is pauperism?<br />

What is its relationship to the relative surplus population?<br />

Discuss contemporary forms <strong>of</strong> pauperism.<br />

Which political actions can one expect from paupers and why?<br />

[1119] JSmits: graded A <strong>The</strong> Lowest <strong>of</strong> Lows. Pauperism is the deepest fallout from the<br />

relative surplus population according to Marx. In Marx’s time this cyclical unemployment is<br />

532 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

caused by the technical innovation in capitalism. In the major industries laborers are released<br />

and then brought back again when capitalists see fit. On the whole though, the number <strong>of</strong><br />

laborers being employed grows at a smaller rate than the scale <strong>of</strong> production. This creates<br />

the surplus population <strong>of</strong> laborers. Paupers are the lowest group in the surplus population.<br />

“Pauperism is the infirmary <strong>of</strong> the active labor-army and the dead weight <strong>of</strong> the industrial<br />

reserve army.” <strong>The</strong>y are formed as a result <strong>of</strong> capitalism, and capitalists need the surplus<br />

population for production.<br />

Now paupers are viewed as some<strong>thing</strong> that is part <strong>of</strong> the surplus population but not really<br />

part <strong>of</strong> it. This means that they are regarded as part <strong>of</strong> that population however they are a<br />

result <strong>of</strong> that population. <strong>The</strong>y become the surplus population and when they stay out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

work force, they lose their desire to go back and then become homeless, criminals, etc. As<br />

Hans says, “unemployment (not accumulation) turns the unemployed into paupers.”<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are many modern day paupers including some that Marx included in his text. I<br />

think the most prevalent are the children <strong>of</strong> paupers. <strong>The</strong> children <strong>of</strong> criminals, homeless,<br />

prostitutes, etc. will sometimes live their lives without their parents. Some people become<br />

homeless or prostitutes because the capitalist has discarded them and they can’t find the<br />

willpower to rise up and get back into the workforce so they live a riskier life, a more impoverished<br />

life that can sometimes lead to death and this can lead their children to becoming<br />

paupers.<br />

Paupers for the most part I would think wouldn’t have that big <strong>of</strong> an effect on political<br />

actions. <strong>The</strong>y are deemed dead weight to society so they aren’t usually looked upon to fondly<br />

and I can’t imagine their voices are dealt with high concern. I have to agree with Picard’s<br />

statement as well in [2005fa:1837] which says that the paupers wouldn’t be too involved in<br />

politics because they are just trying to survive.<br />

Hans: <strong>The</strong> potential for political action does not depend on how fondly they are looked at. Our society looks down<br />

not only on paupers but also on unskilled laborers, but employed laborers have an infinitely larger potential for<br />

political action than the unemployed.<br />

First Message by JSmits is [148].<br />

[1130] Zohan: Don’t call me a Pauper. Pauperism is the group <strong>of</strong> people in society that<br />

are the poor and destitute. <strong>The</strong>y are those that our capitalist society frowns upon. <strong>The</strong>y are<br />

the homeless, the drug dealers, the prostitutes, the criminals, etc. <strong>The</strong>se people are <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

times forced into their position by loss <strong>of</strong> employment, injury, or national economic stress.<br />

Once forced into this lower echelon the ability to rise becomes more outlined by the direction<br />

<strong>of</strong> society than one’s drive to work, or succeed. Many are born into these circumstances and<br />

are quickly placed in a position <strong>of</strong> pauperism just by simple being. <strong>The</strong> annotations on page<br />

734 describe that in many ways the key to rising out <strong>of</strong> pauperism and reaching a new layer<br />

<strong>of</strong> society is by society experiencing a crisis <strong>of</strong> trade becoming more machinery and mine<br />

driven, which places a need upon the pauper and what small labor skill they posses.<br />

Paupers are likely to commit to very little political action due to their necessity to rely<br />

so heavily on the action <strong>of</strong> others. Unlike citizens that exist in the levels <strong>of</strong> society above<br />

them, paupers are controlled by society, whereas others form and shape it. Often paupers<br />

are so overwhelmed with the actions <strong>of</strong> survival on a day to day basis, that they are likely<br />

to be found filing for unemployment, church and charity help, and many social programs


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 533<br />

designed to provide the fourth layer class with the basic supplies <strong>of</strong> survival. I would agree<br />

with Bone [2009fa:1237] that these people are looked down upon by society and even if they<br />

were to overcome all the obstacles they face, it is unlikely that their voice would have a large<br />

impact.<br />

Next Message by Zohan is [1152].<br />

[1197] Cosmopolita: Free Discussion on Pauperism. As a personal experience, I can<br />

see pauperism every time I go volunteer at the Food Banks in different cities within Salt Lake<br />

County. And I can see the displaced workers, due to lack <strong>of</strong> education or skills training, age,<br />

disability, drug addictions, etc. <strong>The</strong>re are different aspects <strong>of</strong> pauperism, and some can be<br />

corrected or be guided through the next positive step with appropriate social help. <strong>The</strong> local<br />

government and leaders can make a distinct difference with decisions that can change the<br />

local environment with a change in the local people. It is true that some have been born in<br />

this situation and did not choose their fate, but also others that decided a path in life as for<br />

example the one <strong>of</strong> drugs, and deliberately are discouraged workers, and therefore displaced<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor force. But we should take in consideration that this last class <strong>of</strong> pauperism could<br />

have been also traumatized abused children at one point, that did not receive the appropriate<br />

social help at the right moment, and the problem dragged to a further degree <strong>of</strong> social crisis.<br />

<strong>The</strong> right help at the right moment could make the difference for people in this class, and as<br />

active members <strong>of</strong> higher education and some us member <strong>of</strong> the workforce we could actively<br />

call our local government and give our opinions periodically and be active members when<br />

voting.<br />

Message [1197] referenced by [1200]. Next Message by Cosmopolita is [1198].<br />

[1200] Hans: Living in a war zone. I respect Cosmopolita’s civic mindedness and the<br />

responsibility she demonstrates as an intellectual in an underserved community, but just<br />

as food for thought I’d like to counterpose what a Marxist would think about the issues<br />

addressed in [1197].<br />

A Marxist would say, following the argument in chapter 25, that capitalism as a system<br />

creates and needs unemployment because this is its reserve army, and that pauperism is the<br />

necessary consequence <strong>of</strong> people being thrown in and out <strong>of</strong> work. Of those which the<br />

system spits out, the state apparatus tries to fix some up just enough so that they remain<br />

employable, and the rest is left dangling to deter everyone else from resisting exploitation.<br />

<strong>The</strong> paupers therefore are not only the victims <strong>of</strong> bad choices or poor upbringing, they<br />

are also the victims <strong>of</strong> class war. <strong>The</strong> state is not on their side. <strong>The</strong> state wants capitalism to<br />

work, i.e., it cares about the people only as cannon fodder for the system. A Marxist would<br />

suspect that people realize this, that’s why they don’t vote or call their local government<br />

reps. A Marxist would not discourage them from voting, but a Marxist would say this is<br />

not their only avenue for political action. <strong>The</strong>y can also join the Brown Berets or Black<br />

Panthers or similar. <strong>The</strong>re you will still find the same problems, people not trained to be<br />

disciplined and overwhelmed with problems in their families etc. But if you fix them up for<br />

class struggle instead <strong>of</strong> fixing them up to make them employable again, this will probably<br />

correspond much better with what these people really want to do. <strong>The</strong> Black Panthers were<br />

a shock for the capitalists; they didn’t think poor people could organize.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [1209].<br />

534 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>Question</strong> 909 is 473 in 1999SP, 599 in 2001fa, 644 in 2002fa, 668 in 2003fa, 727 in<br />

2004fa, 673 in 2005fa, 802 in 2007SP, 771 in 2007fa, 801 in 2008SP, 806 in 2008fa, 839<br />

in 2009fa, 942 in 2011fa, and 972 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 909 What is worse: the misery <strong>of</strong> idle impoverishment or the torture <strong>of</strong> work?<br />

[1096] Hal: graded A It doesn’t take a monk. If we compare extreme impoverishment<br />

with extreme amounts <strong>of</strong> work, the argument settles around physical well-being, rather than<br />

mental, emotional, or spiritual well-being. In both extreme cases, a person would tend to<br />

be consumed with physical survival, rather than feeling happy. It seems obvious to me that<br />

a rational person choosing between those two extremes would prefer being subjected to<br />

torturous work simply for the greater likelihood <strong>of</strong> survival. However, comparing extremes<br />

is rather uninteresting and I believe it misses the underlying question, which is focused more<br />

on non-physical aspects <strong>of</strong> well-being.<br />

I mention extreme cases <strong>first</strong> because, when we exclude those cases where fear for physical<br />

well-being comes into play, the choice becomes obvious. It simply is not the case that, in<br />

this day and age, being mildly impoverished forces us to be idle. <strong>The</strong>re are so many <strong>thing</strong>s<br />

to do that cost little to no money. For a list <strong>of</strong> 100, see the following web page:<br />

http://www.thesimpledollar.com/2008/07/17/100-<strong>thing</strong>s-to-do-during-a-moneyfree-weekend/<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s we enjoy about many jobs could be done for free. Even if a woman loves<br />

teaching her high school math class, she might find more enjoyment out <strong>of</strong> joining the Peace<br />

Corps and teaching math to children in developing nations. With a little imagination and assertiveness,<br />

free time becomes much more valuable than money earned for any<strong>thing</strong> beyond<br />

subsistence.<br />

Message [1096] referenced by [1108]. Next Message by Hal is [1112].<br />

[1105] Somramthom: graded A Circumstantial perspectives <strong>of</strong> torture. <strong>The</strong> two extremes<br />

in this question are very rarely the circumstance one can find himself in. Life rarely<br />

dwells in extremes. Rather, it bounces back and forth in between opposing extremes. How<br />

we feel about these circumstances (i.e. which is worse) depends on our perceptions <strong>of</strong> the<br />

circumstance. I will illustrate my point with my own experiences.<br />

After a particularly difficult spring semester I was happy to see an increase in my free<br />

time. I still worked full time, but didn’t have to fill my days with reading and homework<br />

and the such. However, after 2 or 3 weeks I found myself increasingly bored. I longed for<br />

my busy days and felt ready to begin school again. <strong>The</strong> feeling grew more and more as time<br />

passed slowly by until summer was over and I happily started fall semester. This happiness,<br />

like the happiness gained from the extra free time, was short lived. After 2 or 3 weeks I was<br />

ready for the semester to be over.<br />

While the change in circumstance in this story is not the same as going from impoverished<br />

to employed full-time, there are similarities. When employed we are more likely to perceive<br />

the situation as torturous and wish we had more free time. In this instance, the torture <strong>of</strong><br />

work outweighs the misery <strong>of</strong> idle impoverishment. Yet when we are impoverished we are<br />

more likely to perceive our situation as one <strong>of</strong> misery and wish we could find employment,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 535<br />

in which case we would willingly accept the tortures <strong>of</strong> labor. Thus, our perceptions <strong>of</strong> our<br />

circumstance play a vital role in answering the question, “What is worse: the misery <strong>of</strong> idle<br />

impoverishment or the torture <strong>of</strong> work?”<br />

Marx notices the amount <strong>of</strong> torture one receives from labor is inversely related to the<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> misery from impoverishment. This means the more we work the more torture we<br />

are exposed to and vice versa. Depending on where one is in between these two extremes,<br />

one will see idle impoverishment or torturous work as worse.<br />

Message [1105] referenced by [1108] and [1161]. Next Message by Somramthom is [1108].<br />

[1108] Somramthom: How extreme is our poverty? I apologize for submitting [1105]<br />

after Hal submitted [1096] this morning at 3:45am. I submitted my answer last night just<br />

before midnight but it wasn’t assigned yet.<br />

Hal [1096] also labels the two circumstances in the question as extremes as I did. He says<br />

the question is not asking about extremes since they deal with survival rather than well being.<br />

Hal says if extremes are involved, working is a better chance for survival but when extreme<br />

cases are removed the best choice is idle impoverishment since in our day impoverishment<br />

and idleness don’t necessarily go hand in hand.<br />

Although Hal has good points, he is still describing different circumstances. While his<br />

statement, “It simply is not the case that, in this day and age, being mildly impoverished<br />

forces us to be idle,” is true for the average American, many people (I would say the vast<br />

majority) are struggling to survive every day. <strong>The</strong> circumstances <strong>of</strong> these people would fit<br />

Hal’s <strong>first</strong> paragraph since survival is an everyday concern. So while Hal is attempting to<br />

avoid extremes, his main point focuses around the standard <strong>of</strong> living <strong>of</strong> the average American.<br />

In a global perspective this is an extreme. According to <strong>The</strong> World Bank in its 2007<br />

document titled “Understanding Poverty”, nearly half <strong>of</strong> the world (2.7 billion) live on less<br />

than $2 a day. This is the other extreme. And this doesn’t account for all the people between<br />

these two extremes. Again, perspective and circumstance ultimately must be decided for the<br />

answer to hold any clout.<br />

Hans: You are right, your answer was originally submitted very early, therefore you can’t have seen Hal’s answer<br />

before you submitted yours. Yet both <strong>of</strong> you speak about extremes. Thank you for pointing out the relation between<br />

your answers and your feedack to Hal. That was very helpful for flow <strong>of</strong> the discussion.<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [1144].<br />

[1161] Rmc: graded A How do you choose between extremes? I think almost always,<br />

someone experiencing one <strong>of</strong> the extremes will long for the other. If one is jobless, homeless,<br />

and has no money for any<strong>thing</strong>, I would guess they would embrace what one would call<br />

“torturous work” because the pay would enable them to eat. Somramthom [1105] says, “In<br />

this instance, the torture <strong>of</strong> work outweighs the misery <strong>of</strong> idle impoverishment.” On the other<br />

hand, someone working at a job which is physically, emotionally, and mentally too much (or<br />

perhaps too mentally uninspiring instead) for too long would probably define that job as torturous<br />

and draining. We established earlier in the semester that it is necessary for the worker<br />

to be allowed time <strong>of</strong>f to rest, eat, socialize, etc to maintain health and mental stimulation,<br />

which keeps productivity up. A torturous job such as this would probably make the worker<br />

wish for the other extreme—have no<strong>thing</strong> and do no<strong>thing</strong>, rather than have some<strong>thing</strong> but<br />

do too much. Somramthom says it exactly right: “our perceptions <strong>of</strong> our circumstances play<br />

a vital role in answering the question.”<br />

536 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Personally, I can’t say whether I would rather endure a torturous job for the paycheck<br />

and meals than no job, which comes with no guarantee <strong>of</strong> any<strong>thing</strong>. My <strong>first</strong> thought is<br />

to endure the job, but there are so many ways to define “torturous”—physically, morally,<br />

emotionally—that I’m not so sure I could choose the work after all, depending on the specific<br />

choice. I’m not saying this because <strong>of</strong> pride or any<strong>thing</strong>—what I mean is, how can we choose<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> that is so far from our experience? It may be easy to say “I’d rather starve than<br />

do that” when you know you have food in the refrigerator in the next room, but if you were<br />

really faced with that choice—in real life, not just in a homework question—would you<br />

make the same decision? Like S said, (the perceptions <strong>of</strong>) our circumstances play a vital<br />

role in answering the question. <strong>The</strong> distance <strong>of</strong> its reality plays a vital role as well. Someone<br />

who has suffered near-starvation would have a very different perspective than someone who<br />

has not.<br />

Message [1161] referenced by [1164] and [1168]. First Message by Rmc is [238].<br />

[1164] LuBr: <strong>The</strong> harsh middle ground <strong>of</strong> impoverishment AND work. In accordance<br />

with Rmc [1161], I would agree that it would be better to participate in the daily grind than<br />

to be idle and impoverished. Unless you have a supportive family, being out <strong>of</strong> work can<br />

be a very humiliating and dehumanizing experience. You would have more free time in the<br />

short-run to dedicate to hobbies or spending time with family, some<strong>thing</strong> I think everyone<br />

would enjoy, but in the medium to long term I think people lose a sense <strong>of</strong> purpose and<br />

belonging to their society. Being unemployed is so <strong>of</strong>ten associated with laziness in this<br />

society, so the stigma <strong>of</strong> being idle and impoverished can play heavily on a person’s mental<br />

state. I think that is one <strong>thing</strong> that the unemployment numbers do not show is that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

dehumanizing and desperate experience that people experience being unemployed. And the<br />

human experience will only get worse as our economy sets <strong>of</strong>f on a path <strong>of</strong> “jobless growth.”<br />

On the other hand, I think <strong>of</strong> the massive population <strong>of</strong> working poor in this country who<br />

have a “job” but that job pays minimum wage, and requires one to seek second and third<br />

jobs. In so many <strong>of</strong> these jobs you are a faceless employee who is denied the opportunity for<br />

overtime (and don’t even consider a raise), and the possibility <strong>of</strong> benefits. I would consider<br />

these people in a harsh limbo, in which they are experiencing the torture <strong>of</strong> work but also<br />

the misery <strong>of</strong> impoverishment, as even with working 50 hours a week, they struggle to make<br />

ends meet on a good day. Considering medical emergencies or their cars break down, or<br />

any<strong>thing</strong> that would require them to take time away from work, puts people in desperate<br />

situations whereby they’re at the misery <strong>of</strong> unhappy managers who keep their own jobs<br />

by preserving the bottom line. I think it would be this torturous weight on the minds <strong>of</strong><br />

these workers that they need every hour <strong>of</strong> their miserable jobs (think Walmart) and if some<br />

outside event meant they need to take time <strong>of</strong>f work, the massive reserve army <strong>of</strong> workers<br />

are waiting to replace him/her. I think it would be this middle ground whereby workers<br />

experience both the misery <strong>of</strong> impoverishment (be it not idle), and the torture <strong>of</strong> work, that<br />

is the most depressing and dehumanizing condition that exists for Americans today.<br />

Message [1164] referenced by [1168]. First Message by LuBr is [111].<br />

[1168] Oreo: Enduring the torture <strong>of</strong> work. For my free discussion, I want to add to<br />

the submissions provided by Rmc [1161] and LuBr [1164] regarding whether the misery <strong>of</strong><br />

idle impoverishment is worse than the torture <strong>of</strong> work. I agree with Rmc that an individual<br />

experiencing one <strong>of</strong> these extremes will always believe that the grass is greener on the other


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 537<br />

side, and wish for the alternative. My initial thought was, similar to Rmc, that the ‘torture’<br />

<strong>of</strong> work would definitely be preferable to the misery <strong>of</strong> idle impoverishment. Having a job is<br />

essential in society, it provides for means <strong>of</strong> survival as well as the ability to be viewed from<br />

your community as competent and accepted. When I <strong>first</strong> imagined the ‘torture <strong>of</strong> work’, I<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> being stuck in an <strong>of</strong>fice cubicle, or standing at a register at Walmart. Jobs that<br />

may not be fulfilling or enjoyable, but pay the bills nonetheless. I would easily choose jobs<br />

like these over being unemployed. However, after researching the worst jobs in America, I<br />

began to seriously question the issue.<br />

According to Forbes.com, the top ten worst jobs included ironworkers, lumberjacks and<br />

maintenance people for oil rigs and pipelines. <strong>The</strong>se physically intensive jobs required 12+<br />

hour work days, unfavorable conditions and high possibilities <strong>of</strong> injury and death. Additionally,<br />

as LuBr mentioned, these employees are experiencing a middle ground where the<br />

torture <strong>of</strong> work and the misery <strong>of</strong> impoverishment are combined. <strong>The</strong> median income <strong>of</strong><br />

an oil rig worker was just above $31,000, which still creates a struggle although it exceeds<br />

the poverty level. Emotionally draining pr<strong>of</strong>essions, such as being a lawyer, also could be<br />

torturous. While they certainly don’t experience impoverishment, they may be selling their<br />

lives to some<strong>thing</strong> that is too stressful and can cause related health issues and unhappiness<br />

if they don’t get enough time to focus on family and themselves.<br />

However, the misery <strong>of</strong> impoverishment may outweigh these jobs. I think which is worse<br />

is determined by the individual, but I believe the majority would rather undergo the torture <strong>of</strong><br />

work. That is why over 90% <strong>of</strong> Americans are employed, and the majority <strong>of</strong> the remaining<br />

population wish to be. <strong>The</strong> oil rig worker, while risking his life and living in fear, has chosen<br />

this job over no job at all. Given the expenses <strong>of</strong> living and the critical society, most <strong>of</strong> us<br />

accept the fact that we must work, and continue to endure torturous working conditions.<br />

First Message by Oreo is [139].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 913 is 475 in 1999SP, 601 in 2001fa, 729 in 2004fa, 806 in 2007SP, 775 in<br />

2007fa, 805 in 2008SP, 810 in 2008fa, and 946 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 913 Define and discuss the law <strong>of</strong> the absolute impoverishment <strong>of</strong> the working<br />

class. Does it apply today?<br />

[1120] Kleenex: impoverished/all workers deserve better. <strong>The</strong> law <strong>of</strong> absolute impoverishment<br />

says that when capital increases, laborers are worse <strong>of</strong>f than they were before. Absolute<br />

impoverishment has both financial and social aspects. On the money side, the worker<br />

is still undercompensated for his work, as he produces more value than what he earns in<br />

wages. He does the same work, produces the same commodities, but sees bigger cuts in his<br />

pay, lower workplace standards, and labor violations with extended hours. While the laborer<br />

suffers, the capitalist gains. He feels no sympathy for his workers, as these worsening work<br />

conditions result from his insatiable greed.<br />

On the social side, the laborer now has a harder time surviving and providing for his<br />

family. He still doesn’t own the means <strong>of</strong> production, and is still subject to the capitalist’s<br />

desires. He is literally impoverished: physically exhausted, mentally fatigued, and spiritually<br />

worn out. Marx paints the picture <strong>of</strong> the laborer’s world as such: production in a<br />

capitalist system “distort[s] the worker into a fragment <strong>of</strong> a man, they degrade him to the<br />

538 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

level <strong>of</strong> an appendage <strong>of</strong> a machine...they transform his life-time into working-time, and<br />

drag his wife and child beneath the wheels <strong>of</strong> the juggernaut <strong>of</strong> capital.” What a revolutionary<br />

concept it is to treat the workers like human beings! What a crazy idea it might be to put<br />

the welfare <strong>of</strong> your workers above the company’s pr<strong>of</strong>its!<br />

Absolute impoverishment still applies today. My example for this would be a facility on<br />

base where I work. This service that they provide is contracted out, meaning, the government<br />

hired someone, a company, from outside <strong>of</strong> the government to produce a service, at<br />

a lower cost. Because they are not a part <strong>of</strong> DoD and are contractors, they are not held to<br />

DoD standards: just their company’s standards, whatever those may be. It was reported that<br />

this facility had a hostile working environment: unsafe and unpleasant to work at. Most<br />

contractors in my experience are great at what they do, but in this one specific instance, several<br />

workers left that company because they didn’t feel comfortable going to work anymore.<br />

This is a result, probably, <strong>of</strong> absolute impoverishment by the capitalist owner <strong>of</strong> that company,<br />

putting the advancement and success <strong>of</strong> the firm as a higher priority over the welfare<br />

<strong>of</strong> his people. It’s bad enough that the worker has to be subject to the capitalist’s production<br />

process, selling his labor-power in exchange for a way to make a living, but it’s worse that<br />

human respect and dignity is thrown out the window for the sake <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it and advancement<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

Message [1120] referenced by [1139]. Next Message by Kleenex is [1121].<br />

[1139] Cmellen: Touching a bit more on the discussion by Kleenex [1120] – Absolute<br />

impoverishment <strong>of</strong> working class under capitalism.<br />

<strong>The</strong> social condition <strong>of</strong> the working class constantly deteriorates. A process <strong>of</strong> relative<br />

impoverishment is inherent in long-term capitalist development. In Capital Marx wrote:<br />

“<strong>The</strong> situation <strong>of</strong> the worker becomes worse, whatever his wage may be, be it high or low.”<br />

This ever increasing misery for the workers, under capitalism, is referring to absolute impoverishment.<br />

Today we can see this applied to the Palm Oil industry in Southeast Asia and Indonesia.<br />

Palm oil is common cooking oil extracted from the pulp <strong>of</strong> the fruit <strong>of</strong> the palm plant. Its<br />

increasing use internationally has been a result <strong>of</strong> its lower cost and high oxidative stability,<br />

Palm oil is a highly sought commodity, especially for Brittain to use as manufacturing<br />

lubricant as well as biodiesel.<br />

Capitalists in the Palm oil industry have been accused <strong>of</strong> many human-rights violations.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se violations include low pay and poor working conditions for the locals. Even more<br />

upsetting is theft <strong>of</strong> land and murder. <strong>The</strong> capitalists are also using whatever means to<br />

increase production <strong>of</strong> the oil by spraying harmful pesticides that is getting into the land<br />

making it too “salty” for any<strong>thing</strong> else to grow. <strong>The</strong> poison is also polluting the rivers<br />

and ground water, therefore affecting the population’s drinking water. But the Europeans,<br />

with the means to production and pressing the oil from the fruit <strong>of</strong> the palm, don’t pay any<br />

attention to the devastation they are causing the workers and their families in Indonesia.<br />

Next Message by Cmellen is [1177].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 539<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 915 is 383 in 1997WI, 648 in 2002fa, 672 in 2003fa, 731 in 2004fa, 678 in<br />

2005fa, 808 in 2007SP, 777 in 2007fa, 807 in 2008SP, 812 in 2008fa, 845 in 2009fa, and<br />

948 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 915 “<strong>The</strong> poor and idle are a necessary consequence <strong>of</strong> the rich and active.”<br />

Right or wrong?<br />

[1131] Sly: <strong>The</strong> American Dream? I think not! Initially viewing this particular question,<br />

I immediately believed the formulation to be fairly trivial – that indeed the poor and<br />

idle are a necessary consequence <strong>of</strong> the rich and active, but I quickly found my answer to be<br />

narrow minded and brash. Growing up here in America the adage <strong>of</strong> the American Dream<br />

was instilled in many, including myself. (Please pardon if I butch the definition.) <strong>The</strong> adage<br />

that I speak <strong>of</strong> is: If an individual works hard, and pays his/her dues that riches will soon<br />

follow once the perpetual ladder <strong>of</strong> wealth – as well as the lazy will never be rich because<br />

they don’t work hard, and thus are destined to be poor due to their laziness.<br />

In reading through the archives I found some very interesting points like the one made<br />

by Chris in [2007fa:702], it reads: “It’s from the poor working man that the rich accumulate<br />

all their wealth.” – in response to not only this statement, but the entire post Hans stated: “If<br />

one puts every<strong>thing</strong> you say together then the aphorism should read: the rich and idle are a<br />

necessary consequence <strong>of</strong> the poor and active. Right?” Chris then responded: “In a capitalist<br />

society that would read right. <strong>The</strong> rich are not always idle but in comparison to the wealth<br />

they amass they can be considered idle.” I would have to totally agree with that conclusion.<br />

As a result <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system there is a division <strong>of</strong> wealth, which creates the rich/elite<br />

and the poor/destitute. After coming to that conclusion, it was also necessary to dig deeper.<br />

In the Annotations Marx states in pg. 737 [798:4/o] in reference to the laborer that: “that<br />

all means <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> production undergo a dialectical inversion so that they<br />

become means <strong>of</strong> domination and exploitation <strong>of</strong> the produces; they distort the worker into a<br />

fragment <strong>of</strong> a man. . . ” – the whole subsection goes even further, but a simple interpretation<br />

is that the capitalist exploits and abuses the laborer in the name <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Thugtorious in [2005fa:1798] refers to the laborer as the proletariat, which is defined as:<br />

“a social class comprising those who do manual labor or work for wages” (http://wordnetweb.princeton<br />

and then to reiterate the conclusions that I had come to earlier Thugtorious in the same post<br />

also states: “If any<strong>thing</strong>, it should read “the poor and active are a necessary consequence <strong>of</strong><br />

the rich and idle,” or just “the poor are a necessary consequence <strong>of</strong> the rich.”” With all <strong>of</strong><br />

this in account it seems to be general consensus that the answer to this questions calls for<br />

more <strong>of</strong> a reformulation <strong>of</strong> the question, being: <strong>The</strong> poor and active are a necessary consequence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the rich and idle. I wholeheartedly agree with this, and my justifications are very<br />

similar to that <strong>of</strong> Khwai who stated in [2008fa:1295] that: “there are many idle individuals<br />

who are wealthy, such as those born into money, and many actively engaged individuals who<br />

are poor.” Adding to that I would say the question should really be looked at as the counter<br />

point to the theory <strong>of</strong> the American Dream that I had brought up earlier. Capitalism allows<br />

for these contradictions to exist, such as those who are born into wealth, and the individuals<br />

who work hard but never climb the perpetual ladder to wealth.<br />

First Message by Sly is [205].<br />

540 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1172] GoUtes: Poor and idle vs rich and active. Right, the poor and idle are a necessary<br />

consequence <strong>of</strong> the rich and the active..... Well at least one would think that. <strong>The</strong> assumption<br />

is that if you are rich you obviously were active and worked hard to obtain your riches,<br />

whereas if you’re poor, you are lazy and deserve to be poor. That is a very close minded,<br />

ignorant statement to say the least. <strong>The</strong>re are many a rich people that did no<strong>thing</strong> to deserve<br />

their good fortune and riches, and many hard working Americans that just can’t seem to<br />

excel financially.<br />

A prime example <strong>of</strong> this is Paris Hilton, she is blessed to be heir to the multi-million<br />

dollar Hilton Hotel business. What has she done to deserve such financial stability? Just<br />

milk her name sake until it is bone dry. She has made a name for herself in every<strong>thing</strong><br />

else besides being a hard worker and most <strong>of</strong> her “accomplishments” would make even the<br />

foulest <strong>of</strong> human kind cringe. However, Jose, who may have come to this country illegally<br />

for an opportunity at a better life, may put in 16 hours <strong>of</strong> work and effort every single day<br />

seven days a week and still barely make enough to support his family and be able to survive.<br />

So the real answer would be FALSE!<br />

Message [1172] referenced by [1174]. First Message by GoUtes is [217].<br />

[1174] JJ: Paris Hilton is a Rich and Active Capitalist. I wish to respond to question<br />

915 and clarify where my opinion differs from Go Utes submission [1172].<br />

I believe that the answer to this question is absolutely YES. <strong>The</strong> poor and idle are a<br />

necessary consequence <strong>of</strong> the rich and active. I believe that Marx states this plainly for us at<br />

the beginning <strong>of</strong> [784:1/o] when he says:<br />

“A surplus population <strong>of</strong> workers is a necessary product <strong>of</strong> accumulation<br />

or the development <strong>of</strong> wealth on a capitalist basis. However this surplus<br />

population also becomes, conversely, the lever <strong>of</strong> capitalist accumulation,<br />

and indeed a condition for the very existence <strong>of</strong> the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

It constitutes a disposable industrial reserve army, which belongs<br />

to capital as absolutely as if the latter had bred it at its own cost. It creates a<br />

mass <strong>of</strong> human material always ready for exploitation by capital, according<br />

to capital’s own changing valorization requirements, independently <strong>of</strong> the<br />

limits <strong>of</strong> the actual population increase.”<br />

We have thus far been shown where capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its come from. We know that this<br />

comes from the exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers by the capitalists. We saw this in the lengthening <strong>of</strong><br />

the working day and in our comparison <strong>of</strong> the necessary labor time to the surplus labor time.<br />

This analysis allowed us to build on the ideas that ultimately showed us how a capitalist<br />

could harness the surplus labor power <strong>of</strong> their workers for pr<strong>of</strong>its. I won’t bore you all with<br />

my poor version <strong>of</strong> a summary <strong>of</strong> the M-C-M’ versus C-M-C’ analysis either. But let it<br />

suffice to say that we should thus far understand that Marx is trying to show us a relationship<br />

between the rate <strong>of</strong> exploitation <strong>of</strong> the worker to the rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong> the capitalist.<br />

So. . . Capitalists need workers to exploit in order to make pr<strong>of</strong>its and get rich, right? One<br />

could argue that the capitalist is to whom question 915 refers to as the “rich and active”.<br />

Although the active part is questionable, as it seems to me that the only <strong>thing</strong> that they are<br />

actively doing is exploiting their workers. Yet the workers that we’re talking about here can’t


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 541<br />

be the “poor and idle” people as referenced in the question. <strong>The</strong>y are working hard for their<br />

subsistence wages and are probably working long hours or two jobs in order to reproduce<br />

their labor. This is not idle or even lazy. So to whom is the question referring when it asks<br />

about the “poor and idle”?<br />

When I think <strong>of</strong> the poor and idle I think <strong>of</strong> Marx’s ideas on the industrial reserve army.<br />

When I think <strong>of</strong> idle I think <strong>of</strong> unemployed. I do not think that the question intends us<br />

to define the word idle here as laziness. This is the idea that the capitalists intentionally<br />

maintain their industrial reserve army <strong>of</strong> the unemployed. It goes to say that if you are<br />

unemployed that you are most likely idle for the lack <strong>of</strong> work. It also goes to say that you<br />

are very likely poor as you are not even given the chance to be exploited and earn subsistence<br />

wages like the active army <strong>of</strong> the capitalists. So at this point let us define the “poor and idle”<br />

as the “industrial reserve army” or as the “surplus population”.<br />

Do capitalists need this surplus population to make pr<strong>of</strong>its and get rich? At <strong>first</strong> glance<br />

once might assume that they don’t need them at all, because they have all <strong>of</strong> the workers<br />

that they need to exploit to make their pr<strong>of</strong>its. Yet, if we look deeper at the purposes that<br />

the industrial reserve army serves for capitalists, we will see that the ranks <strong>of</strong> the industrial<br />

reserve army are both consequences and the design <strong>of</strong> the capitalist to allow him to maintain<br />

or increase his rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it and his capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Let me use the example <strong>of</strong> Paris Hilton, given by GoUtes in [1172]. She is the heiress<br />

<strong>of</strong> a multi-billion dollar Hilton hotel business. Whether she deserves this dynasty or not is<br />

not the question here. <strong>The</strong> fact is that her inheritance is an inheritance <strong>of</strong> dead capital. <strong>The</strong><br />

accumulated pr<strong>of</strong>its and capital <strong>of</strong> her family, when they die, will become hers. She inherits<br />

most importantly the buildings that house hotel guests. It is this definition <strong>of</strong> her property<br />

rights to these hotels which gives her exclusive access to the means <strong>of</strong> production for this<br />

industry. <strong>The</strong>refore she is rich from the years <strong>of</strong> exploitation <strong>of</strong> hotel workers, and is actively<br />

being a capitalist by spending the pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>of</strong> her family’s exploitation <strong>of</strong> these workers. (This<br />

might be a stretch to call her active).<br />

[1172] also gives us the example <strong>of</strong> imaginary but noble and hard working “Jose”. Jose<br />

works 16 hours a day for his subsistence wages that barely feeds him and his family. Could<br />

I extrapolate the example <strong>of</strong> GoUtes that its possible that Jose works as a maintenance tech<br />

at a local Hilton hotel? He works hard at the Hilton fixing leaky pipes and clogged toilets<br />

and provides for his family. In fact he’s really good at what he does and will always be<br />

needed regardless <strong>of</strong> the hotels occupancy rate. Meaning that for purposes <strong>of</strong> the example<br />

it is unlikely that he will be laid <strong>of</strong>f. Assuming this would make him part <strong>of</strong> the industrial<br />

active army.<br />

Now we can look at Jose’s sister Maria. (A new character <strong>of</strong> my own creation.) She works<br />

at the same hotel in the housekeeping department. Maria also works hard but was recently<br />

laid <strong>of</strong>f due to it being the low season for travel at the local Hilton hotel where they work.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are not enough rooms that need cleaning and the Hilton, being the smart business<br />

minded people that they are, laid her <strong>of</strong>f. She is now poor and idle and without work. She<br />

has been retired to the ranks <strong>of</strong> the industrial reserve army by the hotel to be called up at any<br />

time that the hotel needs her or when the busy season starts.<br />

542 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong>se cycles, ebbs and flows <strong>of</strong> the industrial cycle is one <strong>of</strong> the reasons that Capitalists<br />

need the poor and idle. Marx shows us this in the lower portion <strong>of</strong> 784:1/o when he says:<br />

“ <strong>The</strong> path characteristically described by modern industry, which takes the form <strong>of</strong> a<br />

decennial cycle (interrupted by smaller oscillations) <strong>of</strong> periods <strong>of</strong> average activity, production<br />

at high pressure, crisis, and stagnation, depends on the constant formation, the greater or<br />

lesser absorption and the reconstitution <strong>of</strong> the industrial reserve army or surplus population.”<br />

[784:1/o]<br />

Thus, Maria is a necessary consequence to the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production, and is part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the industrial reserve army. She is only to be called up when needed as the ebbs and flows<br />

<strong>of</strong> the hotel’s busy seasons and slow stagnation seasons come and go. She is placed in the<br />

ranks <strong>of</strong> the poor and idle industrial reserve army as a consequence <strong>of</strong> the capitalist’s need<br />

for this flexible work force.<br />

Other reasons for the capitalist’s maintenance <strong>of</strong> the industrial reserve army is to maintain<br />

lower wages. I believe that it can be simply put that when there is an excess supply <strong>of</strong><br />

laborers in the market that market forces will keep wages low. By maintaining this army <strong>of</strong><br />

the unemployed they are able to maintain their power over the regular laborer. If the market<br />

was fully employed then wages would be higher. Laborers would regain some power by<br />

being able to organize into groups and demand higher wages. If they don’t receive them<br />

then they can strike. A fully employed market means that there are not any poor and idle<br />

to fill the jobs <strong>of</strong> the organized strikers. Capitalists therefore also maintain their industrial<br />

reserve army <strong>of</strong> the unemployed as a threat to the worker that demands a higher wage. <strong>The</strong>y<br />

use the reserve army against any revolts <strong>of</strong> their active army. By the upkeep <strong>of</strong> the surplus<br />

population the capitalist can say to his worker, “What!? You say that you need a raise for<br />

your hard work? <strong>The</strong> answer is NO. <strong>The</strong>re are 50 people lining up outside my door to take<br />

your job at the same rate!”. <strong>The</strong>reby quelling any uprisings in the ranks <strong>of</strong> their core active<br />

army.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore, I believe that it is important for us to understand that the poor and idle ARE<br />

a necessary consequence <strong>of</strong> the rich and active. <strong>The</strong>y go hand in hand and the does not go<br />

without the other.<br />

Next Message by JJ is [1188].<br />

[1189] Hans: Causality between rich and poor. This quote comes from an early economist<br />

who thought that there simply was not enough wealth to go around that everybody<br />

could be rich. This economist (his name was Ortis) thought the labor which made the rich<br />

rich was not creating new wealth but was only shifting the existing wealth around. That is<br />

why the activity <strong>of</strong> the rich caused the poverty <strong>of</strong> the poor: it shifted wealth into the pockets<br />

<strong>of</strong> the rich which could therefore not go to the poor.<br />

I think Marx would turn it around and say that the rich and idle are a necessary consequence<br />

<strong>of</strong> the poor and active. It is not the rich who make the poor poor but the poor are<br />

making the rich rich. And it is not an iron law determined by limits <strong>of</strong> productivity but it<br />

is due to the capitalist relations <strong>of</strong> production, i.e., due to the ownership <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production by the rich.<br />

Message [1189] referenced by [1190]. Next Message by Hans is [1190].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 543<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 918 is 386 in 1997WI, 456 in 1998WI, 480 in 1999SP, 734 in 2004fa, 681 in<br />

2005fa, 780 in 2007fa, 810 in 2008SP, 815 in 2008fa, 848 in 2009fa, and 951 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 918 What is the General Law <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Accumulation?<br />

[1138] AM: capitalist accumulation. <strong>The</strong> General Law <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Accumulation involves<br />

the advancement <strong>of</strong> money or capital (i.e. M-C-M’). Specifically, the more capital<br />

that is accumulated the more pressure there is on the working class. <strong>The</strong> pressure stems<br />

from the “need” to accumulate more capital and is a result <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system in general.<br />

Aub in [2009fa:1210] brings my favorite subject exploitation into the picture writing<br />

“capitalists exploit their workers because <strong>of</strong> an increase in pr<strong>of</strong>its, while they pinch every<br />

last bit <strong>of</strong> value from the workers by using more and more pr<strong>of</strong>icient capital”. Even after<br />

spending a great deal <strong>of</strong> time on exploitation, I don’t think I could have said it better myself.<br />

Exploitation is a reoccurring theme in capitalism, which brings so many interesting issues to<br />

the table. It is important to note that low wages for laborers and unemployment are results<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalist accumulation. Marx says that the general law <strong>of</strong> accumulation like all other<br />

laws in modified in its workings by many circumstances. I think this means that there is a<br />

general principle, which I have described above, but the law takes shape in many different<br />

forms and with many different influences. I will not discuss all the various ways that this<br />

law takes shape as it would be too lengthy for a homework question.<br />

Hans: If the capital needs to accumulate, isn’t this a pressure on the working class which the working class should<br />

welcome and can take advantage <strong>of</strong>, by raising wages?<br />

First Message by AM is [426].<br />

[1190] Hans: <strong>The</strong> Need for Solidarity. After reading a long chapter called “the general<br />

law <strong>of</strong> capitalist accumulation,” can you tell me now what is the general law <strong>of</strong> capitalist<br />

accumulation? Just by taking a brief look into the most recent archives I discovered that<br />

there were really no clear answers to this question, therefore here I go again, on the Sunday<br />

after the end <strong>of</strong> the Semester.<br />

By “general law <strong>of</strong> accumulation” Marx means the economic law that the accumulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> wealth on the side <strong>of</strong> the capitalists is at the same time the accumulation <strong>of</strong> misery on the<br />

side <strong>of</strong> the working class.<br />

It is almost as if Ortis, the economist about whom I talked in [1189], was right. If part<br />

<strong>of</strong> society becomes wealthy, people are not terribly surprised that another part <strong>of</strong> society<br />

becomes poor: the wealth is shifted from the poor to the rich. <strong>The</strong> problem with this view<br />

is that it considers wealth creation a zero-sum game. Marx shows that the poverty <strong>of</strong> the<br />

masses and unemplyment does not come from the fact that there is not enough wealth for<br />

everybody, but that the poverty <strong>of</strong> the majority is artificially created by the system in order<br />

to force them to surrender the wealth they are producing to the rich.<br />

People <strong>of</strong>ten don’t see this. When I was working on the Assembly line for Chrylser in<br />

the 1970s, the United Farm Workers and Cesar Chavez were a big issue. <strong>The</strong>re was a grape<br />

boycott, and the UAW supported the United Farm Workers. But many rank and file workers<br />

did not support the United Farm Workers because they thought low food prices were in their<br />

best interest. <strong>The</strong>y did not see that it was in their interest to eradicate low wages everywhere<br />

because low wages are contagious: they tend to spread from one worker to the next.<br />

544 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Eventually, this short-sighted attitude caught up with them. Instead <strong>of</strong> fighting for health<br />

care for all workers, the UAW wasted its bargaining power on fighting for health care only<br />

for UAW members — which ultimately led not only to the loss <strong>of</strong> their health care but even<br />

the loss <strong>of</strong> their jobs. Most UAW plants still in existence are Canadian plants, because the<br />

Canadian system does not allow the capitalists to renege on their health care liabilities by<br />

switching to non-union factories.<br />

Today, there is another wrinkle in the situation which Marx did not foresee. If you look<br />

at the planet as a whole, Ortis was actually right. It is simply not possible that everybody<br />

on earth can live the same lifestyle as the US Americans. This would require the natural<br />

resources <strong>of</strong> five planets, but we only have one. This is a challenging situation, and if we<br />

don’t get this one right, we will not only lose healthcare and jobs, but we will lose a livable<br />

planet. Did I say “wrinkle”? This is the most fundamental issue <strong>of</strong> our time.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [1200].<br />

Term Paper 920 is 786 in 2007fa, 811 in 2008SP, 816 in 2008fa, 849 in 2009fa, 953 in<br />

2011fa, and 983 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 920 Term Paper on the Externalities <strong>of</strong> Capitalism, i.e., on the positive and<br />

negative local and global impacts <strong>of</strong> production in the name <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

[1015] Alex and Kaush: graded A Social and Environmental Externalities: For the<br />

Good and the Bad. Capitalism is a chain reaction <strong>of</strong> consequences, with each advance<br />

there are positive and negative consequences throughout. <strong>The</strong>se consequences are externalities,<br />

which in this case can be separated into social and environmental externalities. What is<br />

peculiar, however, is that these externalities contain both a negative and a positive outcome<br />

from their occurrence. Depending on every individual’s take on the matter, these externalities<br />

can have more <strong>of</strong> a detrimental, or more <strong>of</strong> a benign influence to society and the<br />

environment.<br />

It is true that capitalism cannot develop under a steady economy, and therefore it needs<br />

change and advancement in order to evolve and progress. But how much longer will it survive<br />

until it trips in its own externalities? Or are these externalities just the precise changes<br />

it needs in order to thrive?<br />

Regarding the environmental externalities <strong>first</strong>, one can truly see that the <strong>first</strong> <strong>thing</strong> in<br />

mind are the overconsumption <strong>of</strong> limited resources and the extensive pollution made by the<br />

capitalists in their adventures. This was surely in Marx’s mind when he claimed that “sooner<br />

or later, the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital must run into the limitation <strong>of</strong> population growth.”<br />

Capitalists are in these endeavors for the money, regardless <strong>of</strong> the environment’s health.<br />

<strong>The</strong> capitalist does not consider that resources are being deteriorated and will diminish in<br />

a given amount <strong>of</strong> time, and will continue to consume until such are depleted. As a pr<strong>of</strong>itmaximizer<br />

and cost-minimizer, a capitalist will use up these resources in order to prosper<br />

without thinking <strong>of</strong> the effects towards others, because they are cheap and easy to acquire.<br />

Many <strong>of</strong> the resources that capitalists use and damage are <strong>of</strong>ten the simplest elements found<br />

on Earth, such as water and air; nonetheless, they are the most necessary for the survival<br />

<strong>of</strong> humans. Concerning pollution, not only is this externality affecting the environment,<br />

it also affects human health. Only interested in increasing personal wealth and, to some


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 545<br />

extent, power, the capitalists will consume natural resources, damage what is left after their<br />

manipulation, and continue to do so until its thirst for pr<strong>of</strong>its is quenched.<br />

<strong>The</strong> above mentioned are negative outcomes <strong>of</strong> capitalism, but with every black cloud<br />

there’s a silver lining. Due to many <strong>of</strong> these ubiquitous effects from capitalistic activity,<br />

many individuals, policy-makers, and concerned citizens have become aware <strong>of</strong> the harms<br />

that all these capitalists are bringing about with their innovations. With their complaints<br />

and pressures towards these entrepreneurs for awareness <strong>of</strong> their harmful behaviors, many<br />

<strong>of</strong> these companies and company owners have opted for adopting a more environmentally<br />

friendly business procedure. Needless to say, the capitalists will not survive in a business<br />

where he is not making pr<strong>of</strong>it, which will be the case when these concerned citizens, individuals,<br />

and policy-makers boycott their products in order to get their message across.<br />

Thanks to this, the capitalist will attempt to appease their strikes and commence to employ<br />

methods that are beneficial to the environment. Programs such as “Going Green” and “Recycling<br />

Projects” have been implemented by many companies around the world in order to<br />

use the resources available in a wise manner, as well reduce pollution and properly dispose<br />

<strong>of</strong> wasteful products. With more motives such as these, to take care <strong>of</strong> this land in order<br />

to maintain its resources, more technology is being developed, more uses for materials are<br />

being found, and new sources <strong>of</strong> energy are being applied. All these positive technology<br />

advances wouldn’t have come about if individuals had not become aware <strong>of</strong> the capitalist’s<br />

negative demeanor towards this habitat.<br />

Most <strong>of</strong> the capitalistic externalities lie within the field <strong>of</strong> social changes and outcomes.<br />

Marx discusses in length the effects <strong>of</strong> capitalism in regards to labor, focusing on the control<br />

<strong>of</strong> such by the capitalist, and the power they enclose in the matter. <strong>The</strong> capitalist manipulates<br />

the control they obtain over the workers once they hire these laborers to work in their enterprises.<br />

Not being able to sell their labor individually, the worker is forced to work for the<br />

capitalist who exploits him to the fullest he can in order to gain most pr<strong>of</strong>it and benefit with<br />

the smallest cost incurred. This might <strong>of</strong>ten lead to unethical practices from the capitalist<br />

in the workplace. <strong>The</strong>se negative externalities lead to positive outcomes, such as the safety<br />

regulations and laws that have been created since the last century which protect the employees<br />

by giving these rights and benefits in the workplace, and demanding the employers to<br />

implement better working conditions and stipulations favorable to the laborers.<br />

When capital expands, it increases the demand for producers <strong>of</strong> goods. Capital growth<br />

outpaces supply <strong>of</strong> labor. This, in turn, may result in a rise <strong>of</strong> laborers’ wages. Though this<br />

may seem positive for the laborer, which in a way is a positive externality that improves a<br />

laborer’s standard <strong>of</strong> living, it does not free the laborer from exploitation which is, to Marx,<br />

better chains to exploit the laborer. A laborer to the capitalist is a tool to achieve an end, once<br />

this tool is used up, it is discarded and replaced. A laborer’s worth to the capitalist is good<br />

in proportion to the pr<strong>of</strong>its generated, and then the laborer is no longer useful once he/she<br />

ceases to produce those pr<strong>of</strong>its. As much as capitalism brings about a variety jobs available<br />

to the market, which is a positive externality, it also causes unemployment, adding also to the<br />

list <strong>of</strong> negative externalities. Again, as the goal <strong>of</strong> the capitalist is to maximize pr<strong>of</strong>its while<br />

reducing costs, it will seek the best way to do so by any possible means necessary. Such<br />

include the outsourcing <strong>of</strong> the production side to other countries, which would evidently<br />

546 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

reduce their labor costs and increase their wealth. <strong>The</strong> positive aspect <strong>of</strong> this change is<br />

increasing employment in other countries, which will help their economies as well as the<br />

well-being <strong>of</strong> these families. However, this also brings about unemployment in the home<br />

country, along with increasing unethical practices and severe exploitation in these foreign<br />

countries. Some <strong>of</strong> the practices include unsafe places to work, child labor, and long work<br />

hours for minimal pay. <strong>The</strong> question is how far and for how long a capitalist can continue<br />

to grow and cut costs in a local economy to produce pr<strong>of</strong>its before hitting a wall? It is<br />

analogous to inflating a balloon to its limit. This may explain the emergence <strong>of</strong> imperialism<br />

to sustain the capitalistic system’s need for resources and markets. Again, the capitalist mind<br />

will take advantage <strong>of</strong> the opportunities presented, not being mindful <strong>of</strong> the externalities it<br />

leaves behind.<br />

With the increase <strong>of</strong> capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>it and success, so it becomes an incentive for individuals<br />

to become <strong>of</strong> capitalistic spirit. Individuals, armed with the knowledge that the sky is<br />

the limit, will thrive in such environment to become successful entrepreneurs. Entrepreneurs<br />

will hire employees who will become productive members <strong>of</strong> society and consequently those<br />

employees can provide for their families and be part <strong>of</strong> a civil society. This increases the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> companies created and the number <strong>of</strong> capitalists who start ventures. This positive<br />

externality brings forward more positive externalities that are favorable to society. Capitalists<br />

are also competing against each other to have control <strong>of</strong> the market. This incentive alone<br />

leads to many positive outcomes. More competition entices capitalists to come up with innovative<br />

ideas that are beneficial and create great pr<strong>of</strong>it. Thus the technological advances from<br />

part <strong>of</strong> these entrepreneurs give humanity advances in many fields, such as health care, engineering,<br />

science, among many. Nonetheless, with the increase <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its, the competition<br />

among capitalists begins to exacerbate, in many cases, leading to the creation <strong>of</strong> monopolies<br />

or monopolistic enterprises or oligopolies, controlling the supply <strong>of</strong> certain commodities in<br />

the hands <strong>of</strong> a few or one producers. Presently, these phenomena are seen in local water and<br />

gas companies as oligopolies, and previously seen monopolies that emerged from excessive<br />

practice <strong>of</strong> capitalism, such as the oil and steel industries in the early 1900’s. When these<br />

types <strong>of</strong> business practices come around, consumers are out <strong>of</strong> luck having no other choice<br />

but to pay their excessively high prices.<br />

<strong>The</strong> most interesting externality that capitalism has brought about, however, is globalization.<br />

More than a need to be connected worldwide, globalization happened as a product <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism. <strong>The</strong> most reasonable example to be depicted is that <strong>of</strong> the internet. It is true that<br />

this means <strong>of</strong> communication was created with intents to be used for military purposes, however,<br />

capitalistic incentive led internet to become commercialized to the public. With this<br />

new method <strong>of</strong> effortless communication, the world can be communicated in a matter <strong>of</strong> seconds<br />

regardless <strong>of</strong> the location. Having a more globalized economy utterly aids capitalists,<br />

being able to expand to whole new markets in ways that were impossible before. Capitalists<br />

will also find new means <strong>of</strong> production, where labor is cheaper and resources easier to<br />

obtain, thus making their ultimate dream come true <strong>of</strong> minimizing costs to the fullest while<br />

their pr<strong>of</strong>its are sky high.<br />

Capitalism brings about changes to the economy, and to the world, not because it wants<br />

to, but because it has to. Without an evolving economy, capitalism will sink, making it


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 547<br />

harder to gain pr<strong>of</strong>its. <strong>The</strong>se externalities are those changes that took place, and are taking<br />

place right now in the world. <strong>The</strong> capitalist’s drive to maximize pr<strong>of</strong>its in the midst <strong>of</strong><br />

fierce competition leads to technological advances that will lead to efficiency in production,<br />

product quality, and production <strong>of</strong> commodities and services that increase the comfort level<br />

for people. Negative externalities in a capitalistic system leads to unfair distribution <strong>of</strong><br />

wealth and power, a tendency toward market monopoly, and various forms <strong>of</strong> economic and<br />

cultural exploitation, repression <strong>of</strong> workers and leads to phenomena such as social alienation,<br />

economic inequality, unemployment and economic instability. Conversely, a capitalistic<br />

system is not devoid <strong>of</strong> positive externalities, the fact that it is a dominant system throughout<br />

the world boasting some <strong>of</strong> the richest economies in the world and in the absence <strong>of</strong> a<br />

viable alternative speaks for itself. It is up to each individual and capitalist to decide which<br />

externalities are worth the effort and time on keeping and which must be demolished for<br />

everyone’s sakes.<br />

Next Message by Alex is [1020] and Next Message by Kaush is [1057].<br />

[1072] SMIKEC, Sly, and Tyler: Impacts <strong>of</strong> Capitalism. <strong>The</strong> potential effects whether<br />

positive or negative made possible through Capitalism have made it the most practiced economic<br />

and social system in the world for centuries. <strong>The</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> capitalism are widespread,<br />

with positive and negative effects on laborers and capitalists – in both in local and global<br />

economies alike. <strong>The</strong>se positive and negative effects are not only economic, but they are<br />

also social and environmental.<br />

When analyzing capitalism, a negative consequence is very prevalent both locally and<br />

globally, and this negative effect arises due to the limitations <strong>of</strong> the environment. This<br />

becomes apparent through an observation that Marx makes about the environment, stating:<br />

“sooner or later the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital must run into the limitation <strong>of</strong> population<br />

growth.” <strong>The</strong> effect that we attempting to refer to develops out <strong>of</strong> the requirement for the<br />

economy to experience a sustained, and consistent growth over time, which in the long run<br />

capitalism cannot do. Our world contains scarce and limited resources, and this challenge<br />

is only expounded upon due to the continued use <strong>of</strong> those limited resources through the<br />

production processes brought about by capitalism.<br />

This same negative effect creates separate negative effect that impacts the globe not only<br />

environmentally, but also socially. As Hans mentioned in class on Friday, the dependency<br />

<strong>of</strong> fossil fuels to assist in the capitalistic processes – by making many if not all production<br />

processes possible. <strong>The</strong> use <strong>of</strong> fossil fuels results in a negative effect that only multiplies with<br />

continued use. <strong>The</strong> negative effect is that <strong>of</strong> pollution, due to the pollution <strong>of</strong> the environment<br />

– both local and international government entities are required to enact social policies like<br />

sustainability policies (such as the “green movement”), consumption policies, and any other<br />

act that will sustain, restore, and prevent the environment from further deterioration. Due to<br />

its uses, and the negative events that it brings forth, fossil fuels will eventually result in their<br />

extinction, which is some<strong>thing</strong> that both locally and globally must take precedence – if the<br />

world is to continue to not only function, but to grow.<br />

With all <strong>of</strong> these negative effects in consideration its easy to overlook the positive effects<br />

that capitalism brings, but it is also important to acknowledge that there are positive effects <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism on the local and global – economic and social systems, as well as the environment.<br />

548 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

As Bones and Miles cited in [2009fa:1157]: “Butters, an economics pr<strong>of</strong>essor at Nebraska,<br />

who suggests that “the single greatest benefit that capitalism provides is that it enables<br />

human choice.” (p. 7).” Human choice is the single greatest impact because capitalist<br />

are empowered with the ability to choose whether or not to invest in means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

and labor-power, which in turn as allows laborers to maintain their, as Marx stated it, “daily<br />

means <strong>of</strong> subsistence”. In essence capitalist enable to laborers to live, by paying laborers<br />

wages for their labor-power, and these laborers use their wages to maintain and stimulate<br />

themselves both physically and mentally. This positive effect impacts both local and global<br />

economies.<br />

Although we pointed out that capitalists pollute the environment through means <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

conversely they also are the greatest contributors to the restoration, and preservation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the environment. Because the environment is the lifeblood to capitalism, and capitalist<br />

wouldn’t have the ability to be capitalist if the environment wasn’t able to provide the necessary<br />

resources for production. Capitalist recognize this, and push for <strong>thing</strong>s such as sustainability<br />

policies, consumption policies or any other act that will maintain their ability to<br />

be capitalist even if these acts reduce pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Of course we didn’t discuss all <strong>of</strong> the positive and negative brought effects upon by capitalism,<br />

but that would indeed take several more pages. <strong>The</strong>re are indeed many positives<br />

to capitalism, there are also many negatives to <strong>of</strong>fset these positive, but it is important to<br />

recognize them all.<br />

Hans: Your declaration that capitalists are “the greatest contributors to the restoration, and preservation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

environment” because they want capitalism to continue is wishful thinking. Capitalism is a social force which is<br />

not under the control <strong>of</strong> the capitalists. Capitalism as a system does not have the sense organs to see the limits <strong>of</strong><br />

the environment as I said in [94].<br />

Next Message by SMIKEC is [1075], Next Message by Sly is [1131], and Next Message by Tyler is [1090].<br />

[1074] Babyceta, Giant, Kohhep, Proletarian, Rmc, and Ryan: graded A+ Externalities<br />

<strong>of</strong> Capitalism. As with most other human activity, capitalism is a source <strong>of</strong> externalities<br />

affecting various aspects <strong>of</strong> nature and society. While many <strong>of</strong> these externalities are readily<br />

apparent, such as the dramatic depletion <strong>of</strong> the world’s natural resources and the pollution <strong>of</strong><br />

its ecosystems, others are less conspicuous. <strong>The</strong> externalities <strong>of</strong> capitalism affect virtually all<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> our lives, and are <strong>of</strong>ten so prevalent and common that those who live in capitalist<br />

societies <strong>of</strong>ten fail to realize that many <strong>of</strong> these externalities are externalities at all, and they<br />

simply accept the externalities as natural or inevitable occurrences. In this paper we will<br />

discuss just some <strong>of</strong> the many negative (and sometimes positive) externalities <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

Effects on the Environment:<br />

<strong>The</strong> natural environment suffers from countless negative externalities <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system.<br />

Climate change, acid rain, nutrient imbalance in soil, polluted air and water, pesticide<br />

accumulation, contamination, endangered species, disappearing rain forests, and damaged<br />

wilderness are just a few examples <strong>of</strong> the negative effects <strong>of</strong> local, national, and global<br />

economies in the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production. In this section, environmental externalities<br />

caused by the use <strong>of</strong> fossil fuels, the animal and food production industries in the United<br />

States, and the production <strong>of</strong> plastic materials, will be discussed in greater detail.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 549<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the most widely publicized and significant externalities <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system<br />

is climate change, or “global warming.” <strong>The</strong> excessive burning <strong>of</strong> fossil fuels for energy to<br />

fuel capitalist production results in the the release <strong>of</strong> greenhouse gasses which accumulate<br />

in the Earth’s atmosphere. <strong>The</strong> accumulation <strong>of</strong> these gasses has been linked to climate<br />

change (Michaels, 2005). One <strong>of</strong> the many problems associated with climate change is<br />

melting glaciers and polar ice caps, which may eventually affect ocean currents and result in<br />

changes in weather patterns, average temperatures around the globe, unprecedented floods<br />

or droughts, and the disappearance <strong>of</strong> islands and costal areas due to higher sea levels.<br />

<strong>The</strong> ever increasing demand for energy from fossil fuels will only worsen the problem.<br />

“<strong>The</strong> twentieth century witnessed historically unprecedented rates <strong>of</strong> growth in energy systems,<br />

supported by the widespread availability <strong>of</strong> fossil fuel resources” (Delgado et al, 2003).<br />

Locating, collecting, and transporting fossil fuels results in damage to the environment, including<br />

species endangerment, contamination, and habitat destruction (Energy Guy, 2003).<br />

Unfortunately, transitioning to alternative “clean” energy sources is far more expensive than<br />

continuing to use fossil fuels, so despite growing awareness <strong>of</strong> the negative externalities associated<br />

with burning fossil fuels, the implementation <strong>of</strong> alternative energy sources will be<br />

hindered by market forces, especially since the costs <strong>of</strong> the externalities <strong>of</strong> carbon emissions<br />

are not priced into the cost <strong>of</strong> energy.<br />

Food production is another area with severe negative environmental externalities. In the<br />

United States, for example, agricultural production and animal husbandry are quite detrimental<br />

to the environment. While in the past there were more livestock farms than there are<br />

today, they were smaller and more sustainable. Over time, as the population grew and the<br />

demand for meat increased substantially, the capitalists consolidated livestock production<br />

and expanded the scope <strong>of</strong> their operations exponentially. While meat production has become<br />

very efficient, the sheer size <strong>of</strong> the industry has caused great harm to the environment.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se enormous operations have led to an alarming imbalance <strong>of</strong> nutrients in the soil both<br />

on the farms themselves and on surrounding land. Farmers use, and have always used, the<br />

manure produced by their animals to replenish nutrients in the soil where they live and graze.<br />

However, since livestock production has become super-concentrated in many areas, the excessive<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> manure produced on farms has resulted in nutrient imbalance in the soil<br />

on the farms and nearby areas (due to polluted run<strong>of</strong>f water). Additionally, the staggeringly<br />

high number <strong>of</strong> animals on these farms has led to significant increases in the release <strong>of</strong> the<br />

greenhouse gas methane (a byproduct <strong>of</strong> the animals’ digestion).<br />

Another source <strong>of</strong> harmful externalities from food production has been the development<br />

<strong>of</strong> genetically modified plants. Genetically modified plants have come to dominate many<br />

parts <strong>of</strong> the agricultural industry, especially in the United States. While originally intended to<br />

help farmers grow healthier and more abundant crops, genetically modified plants have had<br />

adverse effects. Many plants have been modified to survive drought, severe temperatures,<br />

pests, pesticides, herbicides, and disease. Plants have also been modified to grow bigger and<br />

faster. One negative consequence <strong>of</strong> this genetic modification is related to pest resistance<br />

and pesticide. While the modifications to resist pests were initially successful, research has<br />

demonstrated that insects have adapted to the modified plants and the resistance effect has<br />

been negated. Farmers must now use more pesticides as a consequence, which means the<br />

550 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

final product contains multiple pesticides in larger amounts than they used to in their natural<br />

form. Aside from consumer health externalities associated with this system, the excessive<br />

pesticide applied by farmers pollutes soil and water.<br />

Plastics production in capitalism is another area that has had severe negative impacts on<br />

the environment, impacts that we are now only starting to fully grasp. Plastics have had a<br />

huge impact on modern society. Plastics are very easy to produce, are quite versatile in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> application, and are used in almost every industry to produce, contain, transport, or store<br />

millions <strong>of</strong> products. Millions <strong>of</strong> jobs have been created due to plastics production (Flores,<br />

2008). However, plastic pollution has dramatic negative impacts on the environment.<br />

Plastics are extremely difficult to recycle and reutilize, and when incinerated produce highly<br />

toxic emissions. ”<strong>The</strong> corrosive fumes released into the atmosphere from plastic combustion<br />

can also increase acidity levels <strong>of</strong> the environment. A potential effect from such emissions<br />

is the generation <strong>of</strong> acid rain” (Flores, 2008).<br />

When plastics are not recycled or incinerated, they are dumped in landfills or taken out<br />

to sea. Plastic trash dumped in the ocean is nearly impossible to clean up and poses a threat<br />

to marine life because <strong>of</strong> the risk <strong>of</strong> entanglement or ingestion. Plastics placed in landfills<br />

almost never fully biodegrade, and studies have shown that when plastics decompose,<br />

gases released from the decomposition process contain poisonous chemicals that are toxic<br />

to animals. Additionally, recent studies have shown that chemicals from discarded plastics<br />

can seep into the water table. <strong>The</strong> toxic chemicals in the water act as endocrine blockers<br />

and have severe consequences to animals and have been shown to potentially impair human<br />

development, especially in childhood.<br />

While several important legislative acts have been passed to regulate solid waste disposal,<br />

the regulations are not enough to prevent terrible externalities. <strong>The</strong> Solid Waste Disposal Act<br />

<strong>of</strong> 1965 focuses specifically on “dealing with the externalities generated by plastic materials<br />

industrial and municipal recycling” (Flores, 2008). Plastic materials make up a large portion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the solid waste produced in the United States, and every year more and more plastic makes<br />

its way into our landfills and oceans. <strong>The</strong> increasing demand for plastic materials challenge<br />

even the most progressive waste management policies, which are proving to be insufficient<br />

in addressing the problem <strong>of</strong> plastics. <strong>The</strong> thirst <strong>of</strong> capitalist production for more and more<br />

plastics is only going to make the problem worse and will lead to even greater plastic related<br />

externalities.<br />

Social Effects <strong>of</strong> Capitalism:<br />

<strong>The</strong> social externalities <strong>of</strong> living in a capitalist society are extremely broad and complex.<br />

Those living in capitalist societies may not even recognize the externalities as externalities,<br />

but instead may falsely accept that these externalities are natural occurrences, as just the way<br />

life is. What those in capitalist societies do not know is that these problems are not a natural<br />

part <strong>of</strong> life, but that these problems stem from operating under capitalism. Capitalism exists<br />

for one reason: pr<strong>of</strong>it. <strong>The</strong> quest for pr<strong>of</strong>its by the capitalists will be met at all costs, and the<br />

workers are the ones who bear the burden <strong>of</strong> this vicious cycle. <strong>The</strong> burden <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it-seeking<br />

leads to social symptoms that manifest themselves throughout our cultures, lifestyles, and<br />

mindsets.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 551<br />

<strong>The</strong> United States is the most prominent <strong>of</strong> the capitalist countries, and the social externalities<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production are easily seen throughout American society.<br />

One readily apparent symptom <strong>of</strong> capitalism in the US is the enormous amount <strong>of</strong> work<br />

hours the average American works per year compared to other industrialized nations. <strong>The</strong><br />

International Labor Organization (ILO) found that in 1997 Americans worked, on average,<br />

1,966 hours. That is four percent more hours than Americans worked in 1980 (1,883 hours).<br />

In contrast, the annual average number <strong>of</strong> hours worked in may other countries has been<br />

declining. In Japan, average hours worked declined over 10% from 1980 to 1995 (ILO,<br />

1999).<br />

In 2001 and 2002 the ILO concluded that Americans work the most hours in a year, and<br />

that their productivity has increased every year from 1995 to 2002. While Americans continue<br />

to work more and more, Canadians, Japanese, Australians, and Mexicans work 100<br />

fewer hours annually than Americans, British and Brazilians work 250 hours less, and Germans,<br />

astonishingly, work 500 hours less than their American counterparts. That works out<br />

to over 9.5 fewer hours worked in a week by German workers. Despite the huge difference<br />

in hours worked, Germany is an economic powerhouse, in part due to its workers being more<br />

efficient than American workers (CNN, 2001).<br />

Because <strong>of</strong> the high number <strong>of</strong> hours an American works every year one might assume<br />

that Americans have higher annual incomes to show for it. Unfortunately for the American<br />

worker, this is not the case. According to the United States Census Bureau, American households<br />

earn, on average, $50,233 annually (US Census, 2010) (CIA, Accessed 2010). This<br />

figure puts American household average annual income behind many countries where workers<br />

work fewer hours, such as Canada, Switzerland, and Luxembourg. American workers<br />

do not fare as well as many <strong>of</strong> their counterparts in the world despite the fact that the United<br />

states has the highest GDP in the world at $14.26 trillion and the highest market value <strong>of</strong><br />

publicly traded company shares at $11.27 trillion (CIA, Accesses 2010).<br />

Additionally, the United States is rated at only number 42 in the world on the Gini Index<br />

<strong>of</strong> family income distribution, just slightly better than Uruguay, and a little worse than<br />

Cameroon (CIA, Accessed 2010). With such a low Gini Index rating and such a high GDP,<br />

it comes as no surprise that the United States has the highest number <strong>of</strong> billionaires in the<br />

world (403) according to Forbes magazine (Forbes, 2010). So, despite America’s unprecedented<br />

wealth, only a small proportion <strong>of</strong> the population reaps the benefit. Approximately<br />

one percent <strong>of</strong> the US population controls 34.6% <strong>of</strong> all privately held wealth (42.7% in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> financial wealth) (Domh<strong>of</strong>f, 2010).<br />

Not only does a small proportion <strong>of</strong> the US population, the capitalist class, control most<br />

<strong>of</strong> the wealth, the working class has failed to realize much benefit at all from America’s<br />

recent economic success. Despite America’s GDP rising from a 1973 level <strong>of</strong> $1.37 trillion<br />

to its current level <strong>of</strong> $14.26 trillion (World Bank, 2010), the average wage <strong>of</strong> the American<br />

worker has been virtually stagnant (in real terms), according to a report by Dean Baker<br />

released in 2007 (Baker, 2007). <strong>The</strong> report shows that current American wages are barely<br />

higher than wages in 1973, which runs counter to “common wisdom” that “a rising tide lifts<br />

all boats.” <strong>The</strong> accumulation <strong>of</strong> wealth by the capitalist class on the backs <strong>of</strong> the working<br />

class is empirically demonstrated. For example, in 1972, average executive pay was around<br />

552 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

$700,000 a year, or about 25 times higher than the pay <strong>of</strong> an average worker. Executive pay<br />

in 2000 had since risen to almost $2.2 million a year, or almost 90 times higher than the<br />

average worker’s pay (Lyon, 2008), not accounting for the unprecedented bonuses paid to<br />

executives outside <strong>of</strong> their annual salary.<br />

Drawing from the aforementioned example <strong>of</strong> executive pay it is very easy to see the<br />

enormous accumulation <strong>of</strong> wealth by a very small portion <strong>of</strong> society in the United States.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se numbers are incredible to say the least, but at least the American worker is no worse<br />

for the wear, right? Unfortunately, the answer is no. While the income <strong>of</strong> the American<br />

worker has remained unchanged, other aspects <strong>of</strong> the average American’s life have been<br />

drastically affected by capitalism in the last few decades. Take, for example, the changes<br />

in American family and social life. According to Jennifer Baker <strong>of</strong> the Forest Institute <strong>of</strong><br />

Pr<strong>of</strong>essional Psychology in Springfield, Missouri, divorce rates have risen to 50% for <strong>first</strong><br />

marriages, 67% for second marriages, and an astonishing 74% <strong>of</strong> third marriages end in<br />

divorce. At the same time, almost 30% <strong>of</strong> students drop out <strong>of</strong> school before high school<br />

graduation (Alliance for Excellent Education, 2009).<br />

American health has also taken a hit in recent decades due in part to pressure from<br />

work and lower amounts <strong>of</strong> personal time. According to a study commissioned by livescience.com,<br />

the average number hours Americans committed to sleep nightly has progressively<br />

declined to barely six hours for white Americans and, shockingly, to just above five<br />

hours for black Americans (Britt, 2006). Poor eating habits, resulting in part from the pressures<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalist production, have also contributed to a decline in American health. Obesity<br />

now affects over two-thirds <strong>of</strong> the adult American population, and childhood obesity rates<br />

(obesity in those under 18 years <strong>of</strong> age) are approaching 33% (Doane, 2010).<br />

In part because <strong>of</strong> low amounts sleep and poor physical health, the use <strong>of</strong> psychiatric<br />

drugs (antidepressants) has increased dramatically. In 1996, 5.84% <strong>of</strong> Americans took antidepressants.<br />

This figure had risen to 10.12% by 2005, and the increases were seen mostly<br />

in white patients. Despite the increase in antidepressant usage, an increase in diagnosed clinical<br />

depression was not observed. Antidepressants are now the most commonly prescribed<br />

drug class in the United States (Olfson and Marcus, 2009).<br />

In addition to poor sleep habits, poor diets, and and poor mental health, the well-being<br />

<strong>of</strong> American youth has fallen victim to the capitalist system. For example, due in part to<br />

the pressures <strong>of</strong> capitalist production and the pressures that it puts on parents, over 100,000<br />

children are now locked up in juvenile detention centers across the country according to an<br />

astonishing article published by Time magazine. <strong>The</strong>se children will most likely drop out <strong>of</strong><br />

compulsory education (Time, 2005).<br />

<strong>The</strong> affects <strong>of</strong> capitalism on the rest, relaxation, and recreation <strong>of</strong> Americans can also be<br />

seen. According to recent studies, unhappy people tend to watch the most television, and<br />

Americans now watch more television than citizens <strong>of</strong> any other country on Earth (Adams,<br />

2008). Due in part to their lack <strong>of</strong> free time (which has been consumed by work), and lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> disposable income, Americans will watch, on average, the equivalent <strong>of</strong> nine years <strong>of</strong><br />

television by the time they die. That averages out to watching four hours <strong>of</strong> television (and<br />

247 commercial advertisements) per day (Herr, 2007)(Adams, 2008).


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 553<br />

In their free time many Americans tend to travel (or at least those Americans with the<br />

financial ability to travel). However, travel, especially international travel, is very limited.<br />

Only 22% <strong>of</strong> Americans have a passport, and only about 20% <strong>of</strong> those with a passport actually<br />

use it to travel internationally (<strong>The</strong> Expeditioner, 2010). Because <strong>of</strong> heavy demands at<br />

work it has become more and more difficult for Americans to break free and take vacations.<br />

According to an article by ABC News, Americans receive, on average, only 12-14 days <strong>of</strong><br />

vacation per year. Even then, much <strong>of</strong> this time is not used for holiday or relaxation; on<br />

average, Americans leave about four <strong>of</strong> their annual vacation days unused.<br />

Adding insult to injury, thanks to technology such as email, cell phones, and laptops, employers<br />

are able to keep workers working even when they’re on “vacation” (Johnson, 2006).<br />

Overworked employees are also discouraged from taking time <strong>of</strong>f, even if it is company<br />

policy to do so, out <strong>of</strong> fear that they could lose their job if they take too much time <strong>of</strong>f.<br />

Additionally, because they do not want to come back to all the work that they will have to<br />

catch up on (even though they were on leave using time allocated for leave), many workers<br />

are discouraged from taking vacations (Johnson, 2006).<br />

<strong>The</strong> fear <strong>of</strong> being fired without justification is another externality <strong>of</strong> capitalist production.<br />

Normally a company lays <strong>of</strong>f workers in times <strong>of</strong> lower pr<strong>of</strong>itability, but not anymore. Despite<br />

the healthy stock markets and record pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>of</strong> the early 21st century, corporations laid<br />

<strong>of</strong>f millions <strong>of</strong> workers, and upwards <strong>of</strong> 7.5 million jobs were lost during the “great recession”<br />

(Oak, 2010). While the unemployment rate continues to hover around 10%, stocks<br />

prices have recovered and pr<strong>of</strong>its have reached record levels (G Network, 2010). How is this<br />

possible? Because the capitalists have managed to squeeze more labor out <strong>of</strong> the workers<br />

while the working class has suffered. To maintain their lifestyle, Americans have used credit<br />

to <strong>of</strong>fset their low wages, with 43% <strong>of</strong> American families spending more each year than they<br />

earn. <strong>The</strong> average American family currently holds $8,000 in credit card debt, and personal<br />

bankruptcies have doubled in the past decade (Khan, 2010). Once again, the capitalist class<br />

has benefited while the working class has suffered.<br />

Education is yet another area where the social externalities <strong>of</strong> capitalism are manifest.<br />

Education is widely considered to be a fundamental human right. According to the Universal<br />

Declaration <strong>of</strong> Human Rights “Education shall be directed to the full development <strong>of</strong> the<br />

human personality and to the strengthening <strong>of</strong> respect for human rights and fundamental<br />

freedoms.” Education serves as an important tool in capitalism. As capitalism progresses it<br />

is essential to increase the level <strong>of</strong> education <strong>of</strong> the labor force in order to increase surplus<br />

value for the capitalists. However, with the increased demand for education, it becomes<br />

more expensive, and therefore more difficult, to obtain an education.<br />

While the competition for quality education benefits the capitalist by increasing the quality<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor, eventually allowing for greater pr<strong>of</strong>its, the working class suffers a negative<br />

externality from the competition for education. A laborer without a decent level <strong>of</strong> education<br />

has not only limited access to well-paying jobs, but also suffers from a lack <strong>of</strong> access to<br />

quality health care, healthy food, and even quality housing.<br />

To make matters worse, there is a catch-22 to the capitalist education system. If one is<br />

working at a low-paying job that requires a low level <strong>of</strong> education, how does one acquire an<br />

554 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

education to get a higher paying job? <strong>The</strong> answer, generally, is debt. This is good for the<br />

capitalist because it supplies them with a highly skilled labor force that is willing to work<br />

for lower wages in order to pay their debt obligation (the worker cannot hold out for higher<br />

wages because <strong>of</strong> their debt). This willingness to work for less impacts the entire workforce<br />

because it gives capitalists the opportunity to hire a skilled workforce at increasingly lower<br />

wages, pitting the working class against itself.<br />

However, there are positive externalities from education under capitalism. For example,<br />

the general rise in education levels resulting from capitalism has contributed to an increased<br />

standard <strong>of</strong> living for the working class (though the standard <strong>of</strong> living <strong>of</strong> the working class<br />

has not increased proportionately to the standard <strong>of</strong> living <strong>of</strong> the capitalists). Education has<br />

also led to the development <strong>of</strong> general knowledge that has benefited all classes. A century<br />

ago, when it was not common knowledge that washing your hands could prevent illness,<br />

many people got sick and even died from easily avoidable diseases. Now, thanks to scientific<br />

progress, bacterial and viral diseases are well understood, and infections are being prevented.<br />

Additionally, education gives insight into other large problems. For example, education and<br />

scientific discovery has made humanity aware <strong>of</strong> overpopulation and other major problems,<br />

and may eventually empower humanity to overcome them.<br />

Summary:<br />

Capitalism is a source <strong>of</strong> great wealth for the capitalist class, and in its wake follows many<br />

externalities. While some <strong>of</strong> these externalities have a positive effect on society, most have<br />

great negative consequences on society, the natural world, and the future <strong>of</strong> humanity. While<br />

many efforts have been undertaken by societies and governments to <strong>of</strong>fset the externalities<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production, the unrelenting influence <strong>of</strong> capital, and the overarching<br />

drive for pr<strong>of</strong>its, <strong>of</strong>ten overwhelms these efforts. Despite the best intentions <strong>of</strong> many actors,<br />

the quest for pr<strong>of</strong>its has continued to compound and complicate the externalities <strong>of</strong> the capitalist<br />

mode <strong>of</strong> production. Capitalism, especially in its current form, is unsustainable. <strong>The</strong><br />

push for ever greater pr<strong>of</strong>its inherently leads to a strain on resources, a strain which is today<br />

being realized in the exhaustion <strong>of</strong>, and destruction <strong>of</strong>, Earth’s natural resources. <strong>The</strong> only<br />

way to overcome the externalities <strong>of</strong> the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production is to overcome the<br />

capitalist system itself. If capitalism cannot be overcome, society is on a path to imminent<br />

destruction.<br />

Sources and Work Cited:<br />

• “Americans work longest hours among industrialized countries,” http://www.hartfordhwp.com/archives/26/077.html,<br />

accessed November 2010.<br />

• “Study: U.S. employees put in most hours.” http://archives.cnn.com/2001/CAREER/trends<br />

last modified August 2001.<br />

• Mark Olsen, MD, and Steven Marcus, PhD, “National Patterns in Antidepressant Medication<br />

Treatment.” General Psychiatry, 2009. Accessible at: http://archpsyc.ama-assn.org/cgi/co<br />

• Dean Baker, “<strong>The</strong> Productivity to Paycheck Gap: What the Data Show,” Center for Economic<br />

and Policy Research, 2007. Accessible at: http://www.cepr.net/documents/publications/g


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 555<br />

• Tory Johnson, “<strong>The</strong> Death <strong>of</strong> the American Vacation,” ABC News, 4 July 2006. Accessible<br />

at: http://abcnews.go.com/GMA/TakeControlOfYourLife/story?id=2151399&page=1<br />

• Shanon Lyon, “CEO Salaries: What is the Average Salary <strong>of</strong> a CEO?” Accessible at:<br />

http://blogs.payscale.com/content/2008/07/ceo-salaries–1.html<br />

• G. William Domh<strong>of</strong>f, “Power In America: Wealth, Income, and Power.” Accessible at:<br />

http://sociology.ucsc.edu/whorulesamerica/power/wealth.html<br />

• G Network. “DOW JONES – Stock Market Crash 2010” Accessed November 2010,<br />

http://gnetwork.com.au/money/dow-jones-stock-market-crash-2010/<br />

• “<strong>The</strong> basics, How Does Your Debt Compare” http://moneycentral.msn.com/content/savingandd<br />

• CIA World Fact Book, https://www.cia.gov/library/publications/the-world-factbook/2009<br />

• Patricia Michaels, “Environmental Externalities and Air Pollution.” Green Nature. 2010.<br />

30 November 2010. Accessible at http://greennature.com/article473.html<br />

556 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

• “An Introduction to Externalities.” <strong>The</strong> Energy Guy, 21 July 2003. Accessed November<br />

2010. Accessible at http://www.theenergyguy.com/externalities.html<br />

• Norman Herr, “Television and Health,” California Stat <strong>University</strong>, http://www.csun.edu/science/health/docs/tv& • Delgado, Christopher L., Ph.D., Clare A Narrod, Ph.D., and Marites M. Tiongco, Ph.D.,<br />

accessed November 2010.<br />

“Project on Livestock Industrialization, Trade and Social-Health-Environment Impacts in<br />

• Stephen Adams, “Unhappy people watch more television,” <strong>The</strong> Telegraph, 14 Novem-<br />

Developing Countries.” 24 July 2003. Agriculture and Consumer Protection. Accessed 30<br />

November 2010. Accessible at: http://www.fao.org/wairdocs/LEAD/X6170E/x6170e00.htm<br />

ber 2008. Accessible at: http://www.nowpublic.com/health/unhappy-people-watch-more-tv<br />

• Frank Baker, “Ads in a Day.” http://www.frankwbaker.com/adsinaday.htm, accessed<br />

• “Environmental externalities, market distortions and the economics <strong>of</strong> renewable energy<br />

technologies [dagger].” <strong>The</strong> Energy Journal. 1 June 2004. Accessed November 2010.<br />

November 2010.<br />

Accessible at: http://goliath.ecnext.com/coms2/gi 0199-568859/Environmental-externalities-<br />

• Jon Bruner, “World’s Richest People,” Forbes, 10 March 1010. Accessible at: http://www.forbes.com/2010/03 market-distortions-and.html.<br />

2010-richest-people interactive-map.html<br />

• Mario C. Flores. “Plastic Materials and Environmental Externalities: Structural Causes<br />

• “US Census Results.” Accessible at: http://www.census.gov/newsroom/releases/archives/incom and Corrective Policy.” Lethbridge Undergraduate Research Journal, 2008. Accessible at<br />

• <strong>The</strong> World Bank, “World Development Indicators,” http://data.worldbank.org/data-catalog/world http://www.lurj.org/article.php/vol3n2/plastic.xml<br />

development-indicators?cid=GPD WDI, accessed November 2010.<br />

First Message by Babyceta is [33], First Message by Giant is [152], First Message by Kohhep is [36], Next Message<br />

by Proletarian is [1146], Next Message by Rmc is [1089], and First Message by Ryan is [248].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 921 is 851 in 2009fa, 957 in 2011fa, and 987 in 2012fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 921 If capitalism is as bad as Marx says, why isn’t there an open rebellion against<br />

it?<br />

• “Divorce rates.” http://www.divorcerate.org/, accessed November 2010.<br />

[1135] IrvingHowe: Why not revolt? On some level, there is revolt. Every day people<br />

• Alliance for Excellent Education, Fact Sheet - High School Dropouts in America, Updated<br />

February 2009, http://www.all4ed.org/files/GraduationRates FactSheet.pdf<br />

• Robert Britt, livescience.com, “Americans Sleep Less than <strong>The</strong>y Think <strong>The</strong>y Do,”<br />

http://www.livescience.com/health/060703 sleep less.html<br />

from all kinds <strong>of</strong> backgrounds do in fact openly rebel against capitalism. <strong>The</strong> reason it goes<br />

unnoticed in the US, if I may be so brash as to say so, is that the wealthy in America have<br />

turned capitalism into an institution more sacred to the nation than any other. This condition<br />

has paved the way for an all-out, illegal and brutal assault on anyone that dare organize or<br />

speak out. No, I’m not trying to pitch some wild 1984 type Big Brother conspiracy.<br />

• Seth Doane, “Battling Obesity in America,” accessed November 2010, http://www.cbsnews.com/stories/2010/01 Anyone who openly criticizes capitalism on a serious level is likely to find themselves<br />

• Steve Liss, “Children Behind Bars,” Time Magazine. Accessed November 2010, http://www.time.com/time/photoessays/juv<br />

losing friends, being demoted/fired at work and otherwise marginalized in society. So, like<br />

a dandelion that keeps getting stepped on, it never dies because the roots are still alive, but<br />

• <strong>The</strong> Expeditioner, http://www.theexpeditioner.com/2010/02/17/how-many-americans-<br />

it is never permitted to do much.<br />

have-a-passport-2/, accessed November 20010<br />

As to why it hasn’t been successful, the wealthy and powerful have simply done an amaz-<br />

• http://www.democraticunderground.com/discuss/duboard.php?az=view all&address=132x736429<br />

ing job <strong>of</strong> convincing the masses that theirs is the best system ever devised by men and that<br />

• Robert Oak, “Unemployment 9.6% for October 2010, Accessed November 2010,<br />

the any rough times will always be followed by better years (a ridiculous notion when you<br />

put the last 140 years or so <strong>of</strong> capitalism in the context <strong>of</strong> a race that is 50,000 years old).<br />

http://www.economicpopulist.org/content/unemployment-96-october-2010<br />

State, religion and business have come together to collectively support and propagate on<br />

behalf <strong>of</strong> the status quo. And as Che Guevara noted in Guerilla Warfare ‘No revolution can<br />

be successful without the support <strong>of</strong> the people.’<br />

Although Marx was no doubt a <strong>first</strong> rate intellectual, he could not have foreseen the<br />

state <strong>of</strong> affairs that Americans know as daily life. Marx once famously wrote “Religion is<br />

the sigh <strong>of</strong> the oppressed creature, the heart <strong>of</strong> a heartless world, and the soul <strong>of</strong> soulless<br />

conditions. It is the opium <strong>of</strong> the people.” What Marx couldn’t have foreseen is a society<br />

where capitalism is the most popular religion. Certainly he noted conditions similar to what<br />

we observe today when he wrote the opening <strong>of</strong> the Communist Manifesto, “A spectre is


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 557<br />

haunting Europe — the spectre <strong>of</strong> communism. All the powers <strong>of</strong> old Europe have entered<br />

into a holy alliance to exorcise this spectre: Pope and Tsar, Metternich and Guizot, French<br />

Radicals and German police-spies.” But today the defense <strong>of</strong> capitalism has gone much<br />

further than this. Today, in every single social group, among every ethnicity, age group or<br />

any other possible demographic <strong>of</strong> Americans there is overwhelming defense <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

While volumes could certainly be written on the matter, this is in a nutshell why there<br />

isn’t open revolts on a massive level. <strong>The</strong> people have swallowed the pill that makes them<br />

ill.<br />

To convince the working masses to support policy contrary to their own interest is surely<br />

the single greatest achievement <strong>of</strong> the world’s elite.<br />

Message [1135] referenced by [1158], [2011fa:894], and [2012fa:1572]. Next Message by IrvingHowe is [1156].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 927 What does someone living today need to know about Marxism?<br />

[674] Hans: What to tell the BYU Audience. <strong>The</strong> topic <strong>of</strong> my talk tomorrow at BYU<br />

will be: what an anthropologist today should know about Marxism. Well, anthropologist or<br />

not, here are some <strong>thing</strong>s that I think one should know about Marxism today. Please help<br />

me with this; I made it belatedly one <strong>of</strong> the homework questions. Please tell me from your<br />

perspective what you find most important about Marxism.<br />

One big difference between Marxism and most modern mainstream social sciences is that<br />

Marxism does not start the understanding <strong>of</strong> society with the individual. <strong>The</strong> utility theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> mainstream economics is methodologically individualist; it derives the social relations<br />

(prices) from the preferences <strong>of</strong> individuals. By contrast, the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value is not a<br />

methodologically individualist theory but a holistic theory <strong>of</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong> society. <strong>The</strong><br />

preferences <strong>of</strong> individuals play a much smaller role in shaping our society than an economics<br />

student is inclined to think. Individuals do not create their society, but they are born into an<br />

already created social structure and they have very limited influence about the the character<br />

<strong>of</strong> this social structure. This is a big contradiction: humankind masters nature really well,<br />

but even today we still have a poor grip on our own social relations.<br />

Since Marx is not a methodological individualist, he does not explain the economic<br />

growth in our society by the greed <strong>of</strong> the capitalists and/or the high consumption demands<br />

<strong>of</strong> the consumers. Instead, growth is deeply buried in the fabric <strong>of</strong> our society. In a nutshell<br />

the Marxist explanation <strong>of</strong> the need to grow exhibited by capitalist societies is: in capitalism<br />

every<strong>thing</strong> is measured by a one-dimensional measuring stick, money, and the only <strong>thing</strong><br />

which a one-dimensional <strong>thing</strong> can do is grow.<br />

And here is a nutshell version <strong>of</strong> Marx’s derivation <strong>of</strong> the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value: In capitalism<br />

the organization <strong>of</strong> production is mediated by the market, and the market measures<br />

every<strong>thing</strong> in one dimension, namely money. This can only be successful if production itself<br />

is based on a one-dimensional factor, namely on labor. Money, therefore, in Marx’s theory,<br />

measures labor.<br />

This means all social attention is directed to one <strong>of</strong> the factors <strong>of</strong> production, to labor,<br />

and capitalism has indeed brought about incredible increases in productivity. Capitalism has<br />

become so successful that it is now an anachronism: labor is no longer the most important<br />

558 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

factor <strong>of</strong> production. What limits production today is not the availability <strong>of</strong> labor but the<br />

exhaustion <strong>of</strong> the planet’s natural resources, expecially the exhaustion <strong>of</strong> the atmosphere’s<br />

ability to absorb CO2 from fossil fuels. <strong>The</strong> capitalist system is structurally unable to be<br />

sustainable. This criticism <strong>of</strong> capitalism is extremely relevant today.<br />

Other Marxist cricticisms <strong>of</strong> capitalism are <strong>of</strong> course that it creates poverty and injustices.<br />

But one <strong>of</strong> the main strands <strong>of</strong> Marx’s criticism is that it is a social system which seems to<br />

those living in this society to be different than it really is. On the surface every<strong>thing</strong> seems<br />

egaliarian because market relations are voluntary relations. <strong>The</strong>re is one circumstance which<br />

is usually overlooked: in capitalism those who do all the work in society do not have control<br />

over the means <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong> means <strong>of</strong> production are owned by a small elite, and the<br />

most important economic decision, the investment decision, is made not according to the<br />

greatest benefit for all, but according to the greatest benefit for this small elite.<br />

<strong>The</strong> most important question for anthropologists and everyone else today is why humankind,<br />

although we know we are destroying the livability <strong>of</strong> the planet, is doing far less<br />

than we could be doing to prevent this. This is the question our grandchildren will ask us:<br />

why did you do so little while there still was time? Unfortunately, the flaws <strong>of</strong> the capitalist<br />

system which Marx has already pointed out come together and reinforce each other in<br />

devious ways:<br />

(1) Individuals who see the need for an alternative economic course, which minimizes<br />

carbon emissions and the use <strong>of</strong> natural resources rather than minimizing labor costs, have<br />

very little influence. <strong>The</strong> system is on autopilot, it chases after pr<strong>of</strong>its and growth and does<br />

not know about the environment. <strong>The</strong> one-dimensionality <strong>of</strong> markets leaves no room for the<br />

environment.<br />

(2) Commodity relations are social relations which look like natural properties <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s,<br />

namely, prices attached to commodities. This is Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity. People tend to think economic constraints are more natural than natural<br />

constraints. This is why they don’t want to disturb the economy even if protecting the<br />

economy destroys the natural basis <strong>of</strong> our existence.<br />

(3) Marxism says that we live in a class society, that the working class is deprived <strong>of</strong><br />

control over the means <strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong>y were expropriated in the past and nowadays<br />

they aren’t even aware any more that the workers should have control over the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production. What is happening right now is a second wave <strong>of</strong> expropriation where the natural<br />

environment is taken away from them as well. <strong>The</strong>y don’t get outraged enough about it<br />

because the same ideology which tells them it is ok not to have control over the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production also tells them that the natural environment is not really their birthright.<br />

Here are two <strong>of</strong> the <strong>thing</strong>s where Marx was wrong:<br />

(a) Marx did not recognize the role <strong>of</strong> cheap energy in the Industrial Revolution. He<br />

thought is was all due to productivity.<br />

(b) Since Marx was writing against Malthus in the mid 1800s, many <strong>of</strong> today’s Marxists<br />

think overpopulation is not an issue. <strong>The</strong>y argue the planet is big enough, it is only the<br />

maldistribution <strong>of</strong> income that is the problem. <strong>The</strong>y are wrong, wrong, wrong. In my mind,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 559<br />

the limitations <strong>of</strong> the environment are one <strong>of</strong> the biggest obstacles to removing the maldistribution<br />

<strong>of</strong> income. This is the single biggest issue which condemns the ecosocialist<br />

movement as it stands today to irrelevance, despite the fact that Marxism would be the right<br />

paradigm to understand and solve today’s problems.<br />

Message [674] referenced by [675]. Next Message by Hans is [680].<br />

[675] Robert: graded A Capitalism: A social structure that inhibits individual psychospiritual<br />

development. I have mused (as I am known to do) about the concept Hans<br />

[674] summarizes as: “Individuals do not create their society, but they are born into an<br />

already created social structure and they have very limited influence about the character <strong>of</strong><br />

this social structure.” I think Marx taught us, and we should listen, that capitalism promotes<br />

and fosters, at a social level to be sure, individual behavior that is harmful to the psychospiritual<br />

development <strong>of</strong> the individual.<br />

Even if one does not consciously know that she is being exploited or that she is exploiting<br />

someone, I believe that unconsciously the injustice wears on the psyche or the soul <strong>of</strong> the<br />

individual. <strong>The</strong> wealth we generate in a capitalistic society is increasingly concentrated in<br />

the hands <strong>of</strong> few. On the outside they may appear to be “happy” being rich but their souls<br />

are becoming increasingly bankrupt...possibly without them even consciously knowing it (or<br />

having enough time to care about it). <strong>The</strong> increasing population <strong>of</strong> poor feels in the essence<br />

<strong>of</strong> their beings that they are being exploited, this undoubtedly fills them with resentment and<br />

disdain, in addition to the misery and suffering they endure because they are poor.<br />

Capitalism flourishes if there are many workers who do not cause too many problems.<br />

Government in a capitalistic society is a tool <strong>of</strong> the owner <strong>of</strong> production to keep the workers<br />

pliable and to protect the means <strong>of</strong> production for those who claim ownership <strong>of</strong> them. In<br />

capitalism, the individual is lead to believe he has freedom. He feels in his soul this is not<br />

the case but he hears that it is. Even modern economic theory tells him he is free to choose<br />

his preference and maximize his utility. Ironically, capitalism, which touts freedom, is very<br />

enslaving. <strong>The</strong> soul knows it is enslaved even if the conscious brain does not.<br />

<strong>The</strong> relationship with the planet in which the individual finds himself under capitalism is<br />

also inhibits psycho-spiritual development. Mankind is meant to live in harmony with the<br />

Earth <strong>of</strong> which he is a product. It is unnatural for humans to feel that they own the Earth and<br />

that it is a <strong>thing</strong> to be used and consumed. <strong>The</strong> Earth can and will sustain humans in more<br />

ways than simply material. Capitalism does not prompt, in fact in discourages, viewing the<br />

Earth as a living entity with which we can live in harmony.<br />

Finally (this may not go over well at BYU) I believe capitalism has co-opted religion to<br />

serve its own purposes. Religion in capitalism encourages the workers to work hard for the<br />

sake <strong>of</strong> work itself and to postpone any need <strong>of</strong> gratification. Furthermore, religion teaches<br />

that those who accumulate wealth are “blessed” and deserving; therefore, if one works hard<br />

and is “good” he too may receive such blessings.<br />

Unfortunately, the very source an individual may look for help in her psycho-spiritual development,<br />

i.e., religion, in a capitalistic society is for the most part an apologist or, worse, a<br />

justification for the society’s embracement <strong>of</strong> capitalism. <strong>The</strong>refore, embracing a religion in<br />

560 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

a capitalist society may actually intensify the psycho-spiritual damage caused by capitalism<br />

by providing a divine meaning to the capitalistic processes <strong>of</strong> exploitation and accumulation.<br />

Message [675] referenced by [680]. Next Message by Robert is [729].<br />

[676] Max: graded A Contemporary Marxism. <strong>The</strong> economic downturn starting in 2008<br />

made a lot <strong>of</strong> people question the stability <strong>of</strong> the US economic system mostly relating to the<br />

legitimacy <strong>of</strong> bank lending policies. <strong>The</strong> economic repercussions we are experiencing from<br />

the meltdown <strong>of</strong> banks makes clearer the fact that banks take risks by gambling with loans<br />

and interest rates. This is a blatant illustration that the drive for capitalists is not the long term<br />

stability <strong>of</strong> the economy or the well-being <strong>of</strong> the worker, but simply providing shareholders<br />

with maximum pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Marx figures that money is how commodities are valued, and money’s value is given<br />

by the amount <strong>of</strong> labor time necessary for production. If the health and well-being <strong>of</strong> a<br />

laborer was considered, the typical work day for them would be just long enough to meet<br />

the economic demands <strong>of</strong> the company. However, capitalists take into the health <strong>of</strong> their<br />

worker only ins<strong>of</strong>ar as they are able to come back the next day and perform their job. Thus,<br />

they work laborers to the fullest socially acceptable limits. In this way, capitalists are able<br />

to take advantage <strong>of</strong> the worker and amass more wealth than they are able to simply by<br />

collecting interest <strong>of</strong>f commodities.<br />

However, if the laborers owned the means <strong>of</strong> production (the factory, the mine, etc.) then<br />

they could schedule their own amount <strong>of</strong> time working based on the collective economic<br />

necessity <strong>of</strong> the company. Furthermore, the banking sector would be run to sustain the<br />

economic stability for the borrowers and users <strong>of</strong> the bank.<br />

Not only does capitalism disregard the happiness <strong>of</strong> the worker (to the limit where the<br />

working-class’ strength ends), but it also lacks any mechanism restraining environmental<br />

degradation.<br />

Marx’s theory on capitalism clarifies the inner workings <strong>of</strong> “one-dimensional” growth. A<br />

society where money is valued higher than the quality <strong>of</strong> life for those in that society is not<br />

a happy one.<br />

Message [676] referenced by [680]. Next Message by Max is [895].<br />

[678] Bigwhite: People. I’ve been reading various people’s posts that seem to put all the<br />

ails <strong>of</strong> the world on the shoulders <strong>of</strong> capitalism, and that if the world followed the Marxist<br />

ideal that every<strong>thing</strong> would be just fine. I feel that it isn’t that simple although people may<br />

not be able to change the social structure they are born into they do have choices that they<br />

can make to help improve their own lives. It seems like an easy way out to blame every<strong>thing</strong><br />

on capitalism and not hold the individuals accountable for their actions whether they be<br />

right or wrong. I think people especially in America don’t always take full advantage <strong>of</strong> the<br />

opportunities that they have being born into this society, and when <strong>thing</strong>s don’t work either<br />

economically or environmentally they seem to blame everyone but themselves.<br />

Message [678] referenced by [680]. Next Message by Bigwhite is [753].<br />

[680] Hans: Thank you for your suggestions. In my BYU talk, I will follow Robert’s<br />

suggestion in [675] to emphasize that capitalism promotes alienated behavior which is harmful<br />

for the individual’s soul. Appealing to will power to resist the bad habits and temptations<br />

without questioning the system which promotes this behavior is inconsistent.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 561<br />

I will not say that religion has been co-opted by capitalism, for several reasons:<br />

(a) It is not my place to say this as someone outside the faith.<br />

(b) I am not sure if this irreversibly true. <strong>The</strong>re is some<strong>thing</strong> called liberation theology.<br />

(c) In the climate change emergency that is upon us, a religious community is probably<br />

not a bad place to be. I said this already in [295]. <strong>The</strong> LDS community with their traditional<br />

emphasis on resilience seems to be a good choice.<br />

(d) Some <strong>of</strong> the best people in society are religious. I think they have to be won over to<br />

socialism, not alienated. Again this general argument about religion applies very well to the<br />

LDS church because <strong>of</strong> their socialist past.<br />

Bigwhite [678] objects that by blaming the capitalist system, socialists let the individual<br />

<strong>of</strong>f the hook. <strong>The</strong> “individual flourishing” which is the declared aim <strong>of</strong> socialism does not<br />

mean that individuals are allowed to sprout like weeds. <strong>The</strong>re must be self-discipline. But<br />

this self-discipline can only evolve after the discipline imposed by the exploiter is removed.<br />

This is another example where you cannot go directly from the status quo to the negation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the negation. We cannot skip over the negation, hamely, the removal <strong>of</strong> the unnecessary<br />

restrictions on our freedom generated by capitalism.<br />

Max [676] reminds me that I should say some<strong>thing</strong> about the current economic crisis.<br />

Good suggestion, I will. Max also says that the work day is too long. Another good suggestion.<br />

A shorter work day directly benefits the laborers, and it is also socially necessary<br />

because we (at least those in the developed countries) have to switch to a non-growth economic<br />

path. <strong>The</strong> demand for a shorter work week could possibly be a demand where the<br />

labor movement and the environmental movement have joint interests.<br />

Message [680] referenced by [682]. Next Message by Hans is [683].<br />

[682] JJ: Mormon Socialists. I wanted to add a few interesting comments on Hans [680],<br />

particularly to his point (d). Hans expands the discussion by giving us this statement:<br />

“Some <strong>of</strong> the best people in society are religious. I think they have to<br />

be won over to socialism, not alienated. Again this general argument about<br />

religion applies very well to the LDS church because <strong>of</strong> their socialist past.”<br />

I don’t wish to speak specifically about the religion, but possibly how Marx felt about<br />

this type <strong>of</strong> socialism as exemplified by the early Mormon Church which I will discuss in a<br />

round about manner.<br />

I think this is a very valid point that many people <strong>of</strong>ten make in <strong>Utah</strong> when discussing<br />

how the early Mormons actually achieved Marx’s idea <strong>of</strong> socialism. In our study <strong>of</strong> Capital<br />

we <strong>of</strong>ten forget that Marx is explaining capitalism to us, so that we can understand it. He<br />

does not spend the majority <strong>of</strong> his time explaining in detail what the “classless” society will<br />

look like, or how it will function. Although we don’t get this from Das Kapital, I do believe<br />

that he had a vision <strong>of</strong> what it might be like. I would argue that in Marx’s view the early<br />

Mormon Church did not achieve this. Not that they weren’t trying, in fact he might say that<br />

their attempt was successful on a small scale, but would be futile in the bigger picture for<br />

America or the world.<br />

562 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Although I have to agree with Hans that the argument made above applies very well.<br />

Religious people can be some <strong>of</strong> the best in society and might be more predispositioned to<br />

become good socialists. Yet, I also want to reiterate his more difficult point (as I understood<br />

it) that he makes later in [680], when he refers to the self discipline that must evolve in<br />

the exploiter before we can allow individuals to flourish. This means that we must take<br />

certain steps before we can reach socialism and attain its goal <strong>of</strong> allowing the individual to<br />

flourish properly. Hans defines this step as the removal <strong>of</strong> “the unnecessary restriction on<br />

our freedom generated by capitalism.” Did the early Mormon Church achieve this? I would<br />

say yes they did, or came very close. However, I still believe that Marx would be critical <strong>of</strong><br />

their attempt.<br />

Once again the point I try to make is not about religion, but about socialism. I believe<br />

that the Mormon attempt was noble, but not the right way to bring about change at a grander<br />

level. <strong>The</strong>ir isolationist ideas allowed them to cut themselves <strong>of</strong>f from the rest <strong>of</strong> the world<br />

and achieve a form <strong>of</strong> socialism. It is exactly this isolation that made this possible. Marx<br />

was critical <strong>of</strong> other isolationist groups that tried to follow his every word to a T on a small<br />

scale. I believe that for Marx’s dream (as interpreted by me) to come true that society as a<br />

whole would need to throw <strong>of</strong>f the restrictions to our freedom that are created by capitalism.<br />

I believe that Marx might have argued that those peoples that desire the classless society<br />

should not group together and isolate, but that they should integrate in society and try to<br />

effect this change from within the ranks <strong>of</strong> that overall society.<br />

This is true as well as our planet becomes smaller and smaller and our populations bigger<br />

and bigger. <strong>The</strong>re are fewer and fewer places to isolate oneself. Marx had to <strong>of</strong> known<br />

that this process that might one day lead to a classless society would take a very long time.<br />

Hence, I believe that he might have disagreed on some points <strong>of</strong> this isolationist approach to<br />

socialism.<br />

Hans: Excellent points!<br />

Next Message by JJ is [912].<br />

[689] Orville: Religion vs Capitalism. This conversation has been so interesting because<br />

it is comparing the two subjects that most wars have been fought over: religion and power. I<br />

say power because that is what Marx has credited the capitalist system in creating at times.<br />

<strong>The</strong> powerful and the powerless. I feel like that is how religion acts in some ways. <strong>The</strong> saved<br />

and un-saved. Although neither religion nor society makes it that black and white, there is<br />

still an understanding with how conversations are formed between members in our society.<br />

To make one more comparison between the two ideas, think about missionaries. Not<br />

only in the LDS Church but Protestant, Catholic, Jehovah’s Witness, Islamic, Hindu faiths<br />

all have missionaries. <strong>The</strong>y travel to foreign lands (primarily) and try to convince the people<br />

living there that their way <strong>of</strong> living is the right way, or at least better. It seems to me that<br />

the missionaries <strong>of</strong> capitalism today are those who would go to foreign lands and try to<br />

convince those people that there is a better way <strong>of</strong> living and a means to a more stable or<br />

more productive and prosperous society. This can take place through such individuals as<br />

government <strong>of</strong>ficials, teachers, Peace Corps workers, and many others.<br />

This is not to say that this is a bad <strong>thing</strong>. Clearly there is good that missionaries can do.<br />

Exposing others to alternate views is never a bad <strong>thing</strong>. Few would argue that it would hurt


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 563<br />

anyone to convert those who would sacrifice children, like the Aztecs, as a part <strong>of</strong> their rituals<br />

to any other non-violent religion. Capitalism also has its sacrifices. Human trafficking,<br />

alternative and illegal-markets, prostitution, are all examples <strong>of</strong> the ways in which capitalism<br />

has put others in horrible situations. This comparison makes me wonder if we’ll ever find a<br />

system that works for everyone just as if the world will ever find common religious beliefs.<br />

Next Message by Orville is [699].<br />

935 is 350 in 2005fa, 350 in 2007SP, 935 in 2008SP, 935 in 2008fa, 935 in 2009fa, 350 in<br />

2011fa, and 350 in 2012fa:<br />

935 Marx and the Environment<br />

[99] Kraken: What’s the alternative. Hans [94] says that “we have to get rid <strong>of</strong> markets<br />

in order to avoid environmental catastrophe”. How is that done in a global economy? He<br />

also states that the market system “does not have the sense organs to see and wisely deal with<br />

environmental constraints”. Who or what could do a better job? I’m hoping to understand<br />

what a better alternative would be.<br />

Message [99] referenced by [100], [102], [106], and [150]. Next Message by Kraken is [116].<br />

[100] Zarathustra: To Kraken. In response to [99], Hans could be talking about energy<br />

policy, climate change, and how economic cost and benefit analysis <strong>of</strong> markets cannot be<br />

applied to a moral (e.g. do we have the right to destroy the next generation’s resources and<br />

planet? Is our life more important than that <strong>of</strong> the next generation? etc.) and environmental<br />

issues which are usually long-term plan. Note that cost and benefit analysis is usually a shortterm<br />

calculation and does not take into account the fact that sometimes less productivity is<br />

better than high productivity, particularly when it will be catastrophic in future. As the<br />

capitalist system exploits workers (i.e. the majority <strong>of</strong> the living human beings), it destroys<br />

our environment through the blind logic <strong>of</strong> the market.<br />

Next Message by Zarathustra is [126].<br />

[102] JJ: How do we get rid <strong>of</strong> markets? In this is the great conundrum. How do we<br />

get rid <strong>of</strong> markets? Kraken [99] does not take a stance as to whether he agrees or disagrees<br />

with Hans [94], which states “If Marx’s explanation is correct why and how markets work,<br />

then we have to get rid <strong>of</strong> markets in order to avoid environmental catastrophe.” Rather than<br />

disagree Kraken might be asking, if the answer is to abolish the capitalist market, then how<br />

do we accomplish this? Kraken’s statement might be misleading as a disagreement because<br />

he does not deliberate further on the leading explanation <strong>of</strong> Hans [94] or <strong>of</strong>fer an alternative<br />

solution.<br />

I see the overall connection <strong>of</strong> how a capitalist market driven by productivity and pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

will not have the foresight to account for the moral questions <strong>of</strong> their effect on the environment<br />

and future generations. Yet, I found myself asking the same question <strong>of</strong> his solution.<br />

How do we abolish markets in a capitalist society that is run by markets? This is indeed a<br />

great undertaking.<br />

I believe that any attempt to abolish markets even in very controlled circumstances can<br />

seem futile. We see this in controlled economies that have black markets spring up. We even<br />

see this in our prison systems where markets spring up as if from no where in a controlled<br />

564 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

environment that specifically bans the market. Prisoners begin trading in a ‘for pr<strong>of</strong>it’ system<br />

by trading what is available to them. i.e. cigarettes, sex, tattoos, protection, commissary.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are certain players that control the means <strong>of</strong> production and trade and these are they<br />

that ultimately benefit from the surplus <strong>of</strong> that market ultimately causing the prison population<br />

to suffer. I may have misinterpreted the prison market as a twisted form <strong>of</strong> a capitalist<br />

market. I don’t intend to go into a detailed analysis <strong>of</strong> a prison system market, but only<br />

attempt to show that markets have a tendency to pop up like weeds in the strangest <strong>of</strong> places,<br />

in the most controlled environments, and despite our best efforts to stifle them.<br />

I also will not <strong>of</strong>fer an alternative solution, but agree that getting rid <strong>of</strong> markets could help<br />

us avoid environmental catastrophe. I agree, but also find any attempt to get rid <strong>of</strong> or abolish<br />

markets as wishful thinking. I won’t attempt to suggest the solution <strong>of</strong> how to correctly and<br />

effectively get rid <strong>of</strong> markets, but I believe that this unknown solution is the “who” and the<br />

“what” that will do a better job in answer to Kraken’s [99].<br />

In fact, one might ask the rhetorical question that if is true that markets are blind and do<br />

“not have the sense organs to see and wisely deal with environmental constraints” [94], then<br />

how hard is it to find a system that does a “better job” than the current system which does<br />

no<strong>thing</strong> to account for environmental constraints? It does no<strong>thing</strong> to account for environmental<br />

constraints because these issues are not even part <strong>of</strong> the capitalist market equation.<br />

One might suggest ANY system would be better that at least takes this moral question into<br />

account.<br />

Message [102] referenced by [106]. Next Message by JJ is [186].<br />

[106] Hans: How to Respond to a TINA Argument? I say in [94] that we have to get rid<br />

<strong>of</strong> markets if we want to preserve a habitable planet for humans. Kraken’s respone [99] does<br />

not reveal whether he agrees or disagrees with this provocative thesis. Instead he asks “how<br />

is that done in a global economy?” In the <strong>first</strong> paragraph <strong>of</strong> [102], JJ reflects on this question.<br />

JJ is very perceptive and I think his conclusions entirely correct. <strong>The</strong> next paragraph here is<br />

a re-statement and sharpening <strong>of</strong> JJ’s conclusions:<br />

JJ does not say this, but to me, the phrase “in a global economy” gives Kraken away—<br />

because this is no longer a question but a counterargument. Kraken does not believe that one<br />

can get rid <strong>of</strong> markets. He wants me to give my ideas how it should be done only so that he<br />

can shoot them down. This is called a “TINA” compromise, an attitude based on the thesis<br />

that “there is no alternative.” We are stuck with capitalism like it or not, therefore no need to<br />

change any<strong>thing</strong> in our lives.<br />

TINA situations do exist. If you are trapped in a burning building or a mine you may find<br />

yourself in situation where it is simply impossible to get out and it does not really matter<br />

what you do. But we are not trapped in mines. On the contrary, the possibilities <strong>of</strong> what we<br />

can do are vast. Admittedly, the horizon <strong>of</strong> our possibilities is shrinking. We had even more<br />

options before the economic crisis hit, but we still have lots and lots <strong>of</strong> options. This is why<br />

the text-book rebuttal <strong>of</strong> someone arguing TINA is: “there is always an alternative.”<br />

While TINA says that the status quo is our only option, the present situation is arguably<br />

the exact opposite <strong>of</strong> TINA because today, continuing with the status quo, business as usual,<br />

is no longer an option. Let me explain. Those alive today find ourselves in a unique situation.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 565<br />

I always have to pinch myself that this is real and not a dream or some<strong>thing</strong> I am making up.<br />

I have lived with Marxist doomsday prophets all my life who announced the impending end<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalism. But today it is not Marxists thinking the proletariat will not bear this blatant<br />

theft and exploitation any longer, sooner or later they will rise up. Today, the best scientists<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world (natural scientists, not social scientists) predict with painstaking data analysis<br />

that due to global warming conditions for humans will steadily deteriorate. And every month<br />

events on the News which confirm the trend. If any<strong>thing</strong>, the IPCC have underestimated the<br />

danger. Scientists say that drastic changes are needed very soon.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore today’s situation is: we know for sure that the status quo is not an option.<br />

Are there feasible alternatives? Well, nobody can know for sure how much <strong>of</strong> the coming<br />

disaster can be prevented or even what should be done. <strong>The</strong> only way to find out whether<br />

alternatives exist is to try them. Be creative, think outside the box. Do some<strong>thing</strong> new<br />

and radically different. Don’t be discouraged by failure, if one <strong>thing</strong> doesn’t work, try the<br />

next. Don’t be afraid to make yourself a nuisance, maybe you can dislodge some <strong>of</strong> the<br />

conventional ways <strong>of</strong> doing <strong>thing</strong>s this way. Don’t wait for a savior but take <strong>thing</strong>s into<br />

your own hands. But don’t do <strong>thing</strong>s in isolation either. Build networks, let others know<br />

what you are doing, maybe they want to join you. Build or join organizations. If you are<br />

already involved in struggles against discrimination, for GLBT issues, for social justice, by<br />

all means continue, but look to combine them with climate issues. Social injustices are one<br />

<strong>of</strong> the reasons for society’s paralysis in climate matters.<br />

So far I have only talked about individual actions. One form <strong>of</strong> the TINA argument today<br />

is that individual actions are not sufficient but that social coordination is needed. We need<br />

laws and infrastructure investments and publicity campaigns. This is true, and clearly this is<br />

not forthcoming. Not even under Obama. But instead <strong>of</strong> giving up this means two <strong>thing</strong>s:<br />

(a) People should use the full extent <strong>of</strong> their democratic rights: write letters to the editor<br />

and to representatives, make sure they won’t get re-elected if they vote against the necessary<br />

climate legislation. Keep copies <strong>of</strong> every letter you write to representatives or newspapers<br />

and their responses. If you ever find yourself in court because <strong>of</strong> civil disobedience, pro<strong>of</strong><br />

that you tried the legal avenues <strong>first</strong> is a powerful defense.<br />

(b) On the other hand, it is an old Marxist insight that the capitalist state cannot be reformed<br />

but a new state apparatus is needed, i.e., revolution is needed. Marxism also say<br />

that the only force in society which is powerful enough to make a revolution is the working<br />

class. <strong>The</strong>refore a Marxist response to the climate crisis is to work for the merging <strong>of</strong> the<br />

environmental movement with the labor movement.<br />

TINA is wrong, lots can and needs to be done. When David Letterman had Bill McKibben<br />

on his show on Sep 1, see www.youtube.com/watch?v=0JcRj-Yokuw, Dave tried to pull<br />

a TINA on Bill. Dave was amazingly receptive to Bill’s ideas, he did not argue against<br />

global warming, but he tried to entrap Bill into saying that no<strong>thing</strong> can be done about it.<br />

Dave was more successful with it than I would have liked. And Bill said no<strong>thing</strong> about the<br />

working class. It is a critical weakness <strong>of</strong> the modern environmental movement that they<br />

have forgotten the Marxist insights.<br />

566 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: I have known TINA for a long time and I used it in [2008SP:208], [2004fa:488], [2003fa:678], [2000fa:140],<br />

[2000fa:87], and [1996ut:287]. Today’s posting is much more detailed, and I may not always have used it correctly<br />

in the past.<br />

Message [106] referenced by [120]. Next Message by Hans is [112].<br />

[110] Wolf: Annihilating Markets. “How do we get rid <strong>of</strong> markets?” This is, I believe,<br />

the hardest question in this day and age, as well as the most pertinent. I agree with Hans<br />

about a new synthesis <strong>of</strong> the working class struggles and the environmental movement. I believe<br />

that both <strong>of</strong> their struggles, if actually carried to their logical end, are anti-capitalist. I<br />

believe these also have to be revolutionary, NOT mere reformist. <strong>The</strong> “greenwashing” strategy<br />

used by co-opting liberal capitalists will not suffice. We can not buy green products to<br />

end global climate change. As well, being more energy efficient may be part <strong>of</strong> the problem<br />

(http://unews.utah.edu/p/?r=112009-1)! I am convinced that these have to be decentralized,<br />

horizontal struggles. <strong>The</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> this is too great to be risked by involving union<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials, politicians, vanguards, etc. as mediators who will probably turn their back on the<br />

struggle. As to what to do, I have no idea. <strong>The</strong> workers struggles in Greece look kind <strong>of</strong><br />

promising. <strong>The</strong> economic recession has created an opportunity for fomenting anti-capitalist<br />

sentiment in the US but it seems as if the reactionary right (tea partiers) got to it <strong>first</strong> and<br />

are using it for pro-capitalist ends. As to the environmental struggle, many radical environmentalist<br />

strategies are considered terrorist in the US. In China, there also seems to be<br />

a lot <strong>of</strong> struggling over environmental/worker issues lately. This may have some potential.<br />

One possibility I see is that as the crises deepen, these struggles will grow and resonate with<br />

others in other countries and spread. <strong>The</strong> likeliness <strong>of</strong> that is thin, however. Other than that,<br />

I think the future is going to be quite bleak. I remember hearing Slavoj Zizek talking about<br />

how China is proving to manage capitalism better than the US, especially in regards to the<br />

environmental crisis, and there is danger that the US could emulate it’s totalitarian aspects,<br />

in order to keep capitalism on life support. Thoughts?<br />

Next Message by Wolf is [353].<br />

[120] Kraken: Talkin bout a revolution. I appreciate the answer [106] that Hans gives<br />

to the <strong>first</strong> part <strong>of</strong> my question. <strong>The</strong> question being: How do we get rid <strong>of</strong> markets in a<br />

global economy? After easing into the subject with phrases like “drastic changes are needed<br />

very soon”, “the status quo is not an option” and “social coordination is needed”, he finally<br />

gets around to what it will really take to rid the world <strong>of</strong> markets; “revolution is needed”.<br />

Let me add that since much <strong>of</strong> the world has willingly embraced the free market system,<br />

this would need to be revolution on a global scale. I don’t believe Hans is framing the<br />

conflict correctly. He speaks as though the pure in heart proletariat are engaged in a noble<br />

battle against the evil capitalists to reclaim what is rightfully theirs. <strong>The</strong> problem with this<br />

argument is that it doesn’t take into account the fact that human nature is the same regardless<br />

<strong>of</strong> whether a person would be classified proletariat or capitalist. <strong>The</strong> truth is the proletarians<br />

want what the capitalists have and most would gladly trade places with the capitalists if<br />

they could. <strong>The</strong> proletariats are just as short sighted, selfish and greedy as the capitalists<br />

are. <strong>The</strong> proletariats think the same way that the capitalists do. <strong>The</strong>y just haven’t been<br />

financially successful enough to earn the title <strong>of</strong> “capitalist”. If the proletariats ever do rise<br />

up to overthrow the capitalists it will not be because they are fighting for justice and a noble<br />

cause, it will be because they want what the capitalists have and they are going to take<br />

it. I am not necessarily infatuated with capitalism, nor am I opposed to revolution, but for


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 567<br />

any solution to have a chance <strong>of</strong> succeeding it needs to be grounded in reality. <strong>The</strong> idea<br />

<strong>of</strong> urging a bunch <strong>of</strong> wanna-be capitalists to stand up and fight to rid the world <strong>of</strong> the free<br />

market system (a system they hope will one day make them rich), is like trying to convince<br />

a bunch <strong>of</strong> would be porn stars to stand up and fight to rid the world <strong>of</strong> pornography. In both<br />

cases, the idea <strong>of</strong> easy money is too alluring to ever persuade them to bite the hand that may<br />

or may not feed them.<br />

Hans: You say “the proletarians want what the capitalists have and most would gladly trade places with the capitalists<br />

if they could.” This may be due to the present legal framework. Who doesn’t like getting some<strong>thing</strong> for<br />

no<strong>thing</strong>, and modern property rights are basically a license to steal for everyone who has money. Marx will explain<br />

the mechanics <strong>of</strong> this in chapter Six, and see also the dialectical reversal <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> appropriation in chapter<br />

Twenty-Four. But conditions can change. If capitalism were ever to experience a Fallujah moment with capitalists<br />

hanging from lampposts, the wish to become a capitalist would wane quickly.<br />

Message [120] referenced by [125]. Next Message by Kraken is [178].<br />

[123] Lindsey: What’s the better alternative? In response to Hans [94] remarks and<br />

Marx’s theory... I find the thought that “we have to get rid <strong>of</strong> markets in order to avoid<br />

environmental catastrophe” very disturbing. I see how markets are one-dimensionally focused,<br />

and I agree that it is a problem that the environment is seldom taken into account<br />

since resources are scarce. However, I don’t see what the better alternative is.<br />

Other types <strong>of</strong> economic systems that the capitalist world could convert to, while they<br />

may take environmental circumstances into account, leave out other important concepts.<br />

For example, workers <strong>of</strong> an agricultural co-op may find the conditions to be unfair because<br />

everyone is rewarded the same, no matter how hard they work. This creates a shaky system<br />

as people become disenchanted and also less productive because everyone will begin to<br />

work no more than the laziest worker <strong>of</strong> the group, and soon the members <strong>of</strong> the co-op will<br />

produce little agricultural product. So the environment may not be destroyed as quickly,<br />

but people may starve to death because the co-op will not produce enough food. Thus one<br />

pathway to scarcity and destruction is traded for another.<br />

Can’t we think <strong>of</strong> a way to just edit the market system to take the environment into<br />

account? I realize that we have made some attempt at this by giving corporations incentives<br />

and putting a cap on smog etc., but can’t we do more? <strong>The</strong>re must either be a way to keep<br />

markets without destroying the environment, or an alternative to markets that doesn’t neglect<br />

another important piece to our survival and well-being.<br />

Message [123] referenced by [127], [158], [160], [195], and [300]. Next Message by Lindsey is [303].<br />

[125] Hans: How markets will be overcome. Kraken [120] is probably right. <strong>The</strong>re<br />

won’t be a successful revolution, at least not in the USA. We won’t get rid <strong>of</strong> markets. This<br />

means severe climate crisis, with perhaps half a billion people surviving at the end <strong>of</strong> the<br />

century. Most <strong>of</strong> them will live in Alaska, Siberia, Scandinavia, Greenland, North Canada,<br />

Antarctica, perhaps a few islands like England and Hawaii, because the rest <strong>of</strong> the world<br />

is too hot. Conditions are primitive, those surviving will have to work many hours just to<br />

provide food. I think it will be most difficult for those who know how <strong>thing</strong>s were previously<br />

because they have to mourn the loss, and those who have to witness the great reduction in<br />

population numbers—which will deadly for most and traumatic for the rest. Out <strong>of</strong> the 100<br />

in this class, maybe 10 will live to see this. I.e., it will be most difficult for you in the<br />

second halves <strong>of</strong> your lives and your children (if you/they survive). It will probably be one<br />

568 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> those situations where the living envy the dead. I will be dead. Those born into the new<br />

circumstances won’t suffer as much; they haven’t known otherwise.<br />

Yet the situation is not the same as in the middle ages. In the middle ages, the individual<br />

did not count much, everybody was subordinated to society. It was a sin to leave your<br />

god-given place in society. Capitalism was the reaction to this. Individuals emancipated<br />

themselves from the social fetters, and the pendulum swang into the other direction. Now<br />

everybody acted as if others were strangers, people competed against each other and tried to<br />

take advantage <strong>of</strong> each other, they did not realize how dependent they were on each other.<br />

<strong>The</strong> respect for the individual will not be forgotten, but I think in the times emerging<br />

from the climate catastrophe people will realize their interdependence as well. This is the<br />

negation <strong>of</strong> the negation in a more violent sense than Marx would ever have anticipated. With<br />

the new beginning people are forced back together into small communities. Under these<br />

circumstances everyone will have the awareness that capitalist development was a dead-end<br />

street. <strong>The</strong>y will slowly build up the technology appropriate for the new climate conditions,<br />

over many generations and centuries, slowly re-conquer wider areas <strong>of</strong> the planet again as<br />

the carbon dioxide levels <strong>of</strong> the atmosphere decline, make the best <strong>of</strong> the crippled planet<br />

they have inherited. But they will pass on from generation to generation the lesson they have<br />

learned: you don’t treat others as objects, you don’t take advantage <strong>of</strong> their misfortunes, you<br />

don’t try to advance at the expense <strong>of</strong> others. Any harm you inflict on others is ultimately<br />

harm to yourself. And they will never again allow the fate <strong>of</strong> their societies to be governed<br />

by anonymous markets.<br />

Message [125] referenced by [126], [148], [158], [196], [1071], and [2012fa:464]. Next Message by Hans is [129].<br />

[126] Zarathustra: Horrific Picture. I don’t have much to say. I just wanted to say I<br />

very much like the horrific picture that Hans portrayed in [125]. (I don’t mean I like it to<br />

happen. I like the way he described it.)<br />

Message [126] referenced by [636]. First Message by Zarathustra is [20].<br />

[127] Pweber: Externalities and Hans’ Armageddon. Lindsey [123], I think there are<br />

ways around it within modern economics and capitalism* (asterisk, because pure market<br />

capitalism does not provide a way around it). In modern economics, externalities exist that<br />

cause positive or negative benefits that aren’t corrected through supply or prices; i.e., a<br />

school brings positive externalities and pollution brings negative externalities (parties that<br />

don’t partake in the market transaction are affected by the transaction).<br />

Obviously, to correct for externalities, government has to be involved. Only governments<br />

have the power and the ability to correct for negative externalities like global warming, and<br />

yet most governments stand idly by and mumble some<strong>thing</strong> about “...maybe next year.” In<br />

developed countries, no one is doing any<strong>thing</strong> about the problem because we’ve let corporations<br />

become so large and powerful they can buy whatever they want. Politicians aren’t<br />

going to campaign about some<strong>thing</strong> that won’t get them reelected, especially when Exxon-<br />

Mobil rights them a large enough check. Like Upton Sinclair said, “It is difficult to get a<br />

man to understand some<strong>thing</strong> when his salary depends on his not understanding it.”<br />

What this country ought to be doing is a Manhattan project <strong>of</strong> energy, defining the next<br />

generation <strong>of</strong> power sources (and apparently we’ve forgotten all about nuclear energy). Instead,<br />

we won’t even do CO2 cap and trade, which is a pretty lame solution already. Anyway,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 569<br />

my point is that externalities in economics do allow the real cost <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s like pollution to<br />

be calculated and corrected for. We as a people just won’t do it.<br />

Next Message by Pweber is [128].<br />

[135] Hans: Robert Jensen: A World In Collapse? Robert Jensen interviewed by Alex<br />

Doherty<br />

(September 03 2010)<br />

New Left Project<br />

http://www.countercurrents.org/jensen030910.htm<br />

Robert Jensen is a pr<strong>of</strong>essor in the School <strong>of</strong> Journalism at the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Texas. He<br />

is the author <strong>of</strong> Getting Off: Pornography and the End <strong>of</strong> Masculinity (2007); <strong>The</strong> Heart<br />

<strong>of</strong> Whiteness: Confronting Race, Racism and White Privilege (2005); and Citizens <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Empire: <strong>The</strong> Struggle to Claim Our Humanity (2004), among other works. He spoke to New<br />

Left Project’s Alex Doherty about the threat <strong>of</strong> environmental catastrophe.<br />

Alex Doherty: You have written that: “To be fully alive today is to live with anguish,<br />

not for one’s own condition in the world but for the condition <strong>of</strong> the world, for a world that<br />

is in collapse”. Even amongst environmentalists it is rare to describe our situation in such<br />

apocalyptic terms. Why do you think it is justified to describe the world as collapsing?<br />

Robert Jensen: Take a look at any measure <strong>of</strong> the fundamental health <strong>of</strong> the planetary<br />

ecosystem on which we are dependent: topsoil loss, chemical contamination <strong>of</strong> soil and<br />

water, species extinction and reduction in biodiversity, the state <strong>of</strong> the world’s oceans, unmanageable<br />

toxic waste problems, and climate change. Take a look at the data, and the news<br />

is bad on every front. And all <strong>of</strong> this is in the context <strong>of</strong> the dramatic decline coming in<br />

the highly concentrated energy available from oil and natural gas, and the increased climate<br />

disruption that will come if we keep burning the still-abundant coal reserves. <strong>The</strong>re are no<br />

replacement fuels on the horizon that will allow a smooth transition. <strong>The</strong>se ecological realities<br />

will play out in a world structured by a system <strong>of</strong> nation-states rooted in the grotesque<br />

inequality resulting from imperialism and capitalism, all <strong>of</strong> which is eroding what is left <strong>of</strong><br />

our collective humanity. “Collapsing” seems like a reasonable description <strong>of</strong> the world.<br />

That doesn’t mean there’s a cataclysmic end point coming soon, but this is an apocalyptic<br />

moment. <strong>The</strong> word “apocalypse” does not mean “end”. It comes from a Greek word that<br />

means “uncovering” or “lifting the veil”. This is an apocalyptic moment because we need to<br />

lift the veil and have the courage to look at the world honestly.<br />

AD: Why do you think many leftists shy away from such language when discussing the<br />

environment?<br />

RJ: I think not only leftists, but people in general, avoid these realities because reality is<br />

so grim. It seems overwhelming to most people, for good reason. So, rather than confront<br />

it, people find modes <strong>of</strong> evasion. One is to deny there’s a reason to worry, which is common<br />

throughout the culture. <strong>The</strong> most common evasive strategy I hear from people on the left is<br />

“technological fundamentalism” - the idea that because we want high-energy/high-tech solutions<br />

that will allow us to live in the style to which so many <strong>of</strong> us have become accustomed,<br />

570 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

those solutions will be found. That kind <strong>of</strong> magical thinking is appealing but unrealistic, for<br />

two reasons. First, while the human discoveries <strong>of</strong> the past few centuries are impressive, they<br />

have not been on the scale required to correct the course we’re on; we’ve created problems<br />

that have grown beyond our capacity to understand and manage. Second, those discoveries<br />

were subsidized by fossil-fuel energy that won’t be around much longer, which dramatically<br />

limits what we will be able to accomplish through energy-intensive advanced technology.<br />

As many people have pointed out, technology is not energy; you don’t replace energy with<br />

technology. Technology can make some processes more energy-efficient, but it can’t create<br />

energy out <strong>of</strong> thin air.<br />

I’ve had many left colleagues tell me that they agree with some or all <strong>of</strong> my analysis, but<br />

that “people aren’t ready to hear that yet”. I translate that to mean, “I’m not ready to hear<br />

that yet”. I think a lot <strong>of</strong> leftists displace their own fear <strong>of</strong> confronting these difficult realities<br />

onto “the masses”, when in fact they can’t face it.<br />

<strong>The</strong> other factor is that truly crazy end-times talk, which comes primarily from reactionary<br />

religious sources, leads many people to reflexively dismiss any talk <strong>of</strong> collapse. So,<br />

it’s important to be clear: I’m not predicting the end <strong>of</strong> world on a specific date. I’m not<br />

predicting any<strong>thing</strong>. I’m simply describing what some <strong>of</strong> us believe to be the most likely<br />

trajectory <strong>of</strong> the high-energy/high-tech society in which we live. And I’m suggesting that<br />

we keep this trajectory in mind as we pursue left/feminist critiques <strong>of</strong> hierarchy and domination,<br />

in the hope that more egalitarian and humane models for human organization can help<br />

us deal with collapse.<br />

AD: Given the severity <strong>of</strong> the situation you are describing what are the implications for<br />

left activism? Should other forms <strong>of</strong> activism be abandoned in order to focus on the threat <strong>of</strong><br />

climate change? How realistic are proposals for alternative economic systems such as green<br />

bio-regionalism or participatory economics in the context <strong>of</strong> climate catastrophe?<br />

RJ: First, I think every political project - whether it is focused on labor organizing, resistance<br />

to white supremacy, women’s rights, anti-war activity - has to include an ecological<br />

component. That doesn’t mean everyone has to shift focus, but I think there is no meaningful<br />

politics that doesn’t recognize the fragility <strong>of</strong> our situation and the likelihood that<br />

the most vulnerable people (both in the United States and around the world) are going to<br />

bear the brunt <strong>of</strong> the ecological decline. A responsible left/feminist politics should connect<br />

the dots whenever and wherever possible. Here’s one obvious example: US imperial wars,<br />

born <strong>of</strong> a patriarchal system, are waged to support corporate interests in the most crucial<br />

energy-producing regions <strong>of</strong> the world, which are predominantly non-white. Resistance to<br />

those wars requires a critique <strong>of</strong> male dominance, white supremacy, capitalism, and the affluent<br />

First-World lifestyles that numb people to the reality that they are morally implicated<br />

in these wars. Those wars are dramatically escalating the intensity and potential destructiveness<br />

<strong>of</strong> the coming collapse. Concern for justice and ecological sustainability demands<br />

an anti-war and anti-empire politics. <strong>The</strong>re is no way to focus on one aspect <strong>of</strong> an injustice<br />

without understanding these intersections.<br />

Second, more than ever, “let a hundred flowers blossom”. When we know so little about<br />

what’s coming, it’s best if people pursue a variety <strong>of</strong> strategies that they feel drawn to. In


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 571<br />

Austin, I’m working primarily with one group that advocates for immigrant workers (Workers<br />

Defense Project) and another that helps people start worker-owned cooperative businesses<br />

(Third Coast Workers for Cooperation). Neither group is focused specifically on the<br />

ecological crises, but there’s incredible energy and ideas in these groups, and they create<br />

spaces for advancing a coordinated critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism, white supremacy, and patriarchy,<br />

all with an understanding <strong>of</strong> the ecological stakes. Maybe it’s natural for people to want to<br />

believe that they have hit on the solution to a problem, but I believe that the problems are<br />

complex beyond our understanding, and it’s not only unlikely that there’s a single solution<br />

but there may be no solutions at all - if by “solution” we mean a way to continue human<br />

existence on the planet at its current level. We need experiments on every front that help us<br />

imagine new ways <strong>of</strong> being.<br />

AD: Lately you have been writing about the way people react emotionally to the reality<br />

<strong>of</strong> climate change. Why do you believe that is an important topic? What is your emotional<br />

response to humanities [sic] current predicament? What reactions have you seen in others?<br />

RJ: It’s not just climate change, <strong>of</strong> course, but the multiple ecological crises. Anyone who<br />

is paying attention is bound to have some kind <strong>of</strong> emotional response. I think emotions are<br />

important because we are emotional animals. It really is that simple. How can we confront<br />

the end <strong>of</strong> the systems that have structured our lives and not have powerful emotional reactions?<br />

Yes, we have well-developed rational capacities, but in the end we are animals who<br />

feel as much, or more, than we think. And if thinking and feeling are not wholly separate<br />

processes but are part <strong>of</strong> the way people understand the world, it is folly not to pay attention<br />

to our emotional reactions. None <strong>of</strong> this should be confused with the apolitical therapy<br />

culture that dominates in the United States. I’m not talking about emotions separate from<br />

politics, but the emotions that flow from political engagement.<br />

To borrow a phrase from a friend, I wake up every morning in a state <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ound grief.<br />

We humans have been given a privileged place in a world that is beautiful beyond description,<br />

and we are destroying it and destroying each other. I cope with that by building temporary<br />

psychological damns and dikes to hold back that grief. But the emotion comes so powerfully<br />

from so many different directions that life feels like a process <strong>of</strong> constantly patching<br />

and moving and rebuilding those damns and dikes. Some <strong>of</strong> this is intensely personal, but for<br />

me the political work is a crucial part <strong>of</strong> that coping process. If I weren’t politically active,<br />

I would lose my mind. <strong>The</strong> only way I know how to cope is to use some <strong>of</strong> my energy in<br />

collective efforts to try to build some<strong>thing</strong> positive.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re is a lot <strong>of</strong> individual variation in the human species, which means there will be<br />

lots <strong>of</strong> different reactions as the reality <strong>of</strong> our predicament sets in. I worry that in a society<br />

like the United States, where so many have lived for so long with abundance and a sense<br />

<strong>of</strong> entitlement, people won’t be able to face up to the dramatic changes that are inevitable.<br />

That could lead people to accept greater levels <strong>of</strong> hierarchy and authority if political leaders<br />

promise to protect that affluence. In that case, people’s inability to deal with the emotions<br />

that arise out <strong>of</strong> awareness <strong>of</strong> collapse could usher in an era <strong>of</strong> even more unjust distribution<br />

<strong>of</strong> wealth and resources in an even more violent world.<br />

572 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> only way to combat that is to talk openly about what we see coming and work to<br />

create conditions that allow us to rely on the best <strong>of</strong> our nature, not the worst.<br />

AD: You dismiss the possibility <strong>of</strong> technological solutions to climate change but given the<br />

severity <strong>of</strong> the crises we are facing do we not have a duty to try every<strong>thing</strong> we can to avert<br />

disaster? Shouldn’t we be ramping up research into alternate fuels and renewable energy<br />

resources? What about geo-engineering as way to avert the worst effects <strong>of</strong> climate change?<br />

RJ: I don’t dismiss the relevance <strong>of</strong> advanced technology to sensible policy proposals. I<br />

do dismiss the claim that because we want to solve problems with technology we will invent<br />

that technology, and that it will be safe and not cause new problems. I reject that because it<br />

strikes me as a fantasy that ignores history and diverts us from the reality <strong>of</strong> the present.<br />

So, yes, we have that duty, and I support serious investment in alternative energy. My concern<br />

is that the culture’s technological fundamentalism leaves people vulnerable to scams.<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>first</strong> step is to recognize we are all going to live in a lower-energy world fairly soon,<br />

and that means a massive shift in how we live in the First World . <strong>The</strong>re is no replacement<br />

for that fossil energy, and we had better come to terms with that. When we don’t recognize<br />

that, we are more easily suckered into absurd schemes like the tar sands in Canada, which is<br />

an ecological disaster. <strong>The</strong> same for bi<strong>of</strong>uels and the absurd claim that we can sustainably<br />

replace fossil fuels with ethanol, which is also an ecological loser.<br />

Geo-engineering goes a step beyond that, into real insanity. Proposals to manipulate the<br />

planetary ecosystem through schemes like putting reflective particles into the atmosphere, or<br />

mirrors in space to deflect sunlight, or altering the clouds - all <strong>of</strong> them prove that we haven’t<br />

learned the most important lesson <strong>of</strong> the industrial era. We have not learned, as Wes Jackson<br />

puts it, that we are far more ignorant than we are knowledgeable. We have a history <strong>of</strong><br />

imagining that our knowledge is adequate to manage major interventions into the ecosystem,<br />

leaving us to face the unintended consequences <strong>of</strong> those interventions. At this point, there<br />

is no rational approach to the ecological crises that doesn’t start with this recognition: We<br />

are going to live in a low-energy world that is powered primarily by contemporary sunlight,<br />

not the ancient energy <strong>of</strong> fossil fuels. As a society we are not prepared, in terms <strong>of</strong> either<br />

physical infrastructure or cultural awareness, to deal with that. Any<strong>thing</strong> that further delays<br />

coming to terms with this reality is a threat to life on the planet, not a solution.<br />

AD: In a recent talk you said that “I am glad to see the end <strong>of</strong> most <strong>of</strong> what we have come<br />

to call ‘the good life’, for it never struck me as all that good, at least not for most people<br />

and other living <strong>thing</strong>s”. In what respects do you think contemporary capitalism has failed<br />

to meet the needs <strong>of</strong> even the most privileged sectors <strong>of</strong> western societies?<br />

RJ: Capitalism is the most wildly productive economic system in history, but the one<br />

<strong>thing</strong> it cannot produce is meaning. Even more troubling is the way, through its promotion <strong>of</strong><br />

narcissism and mindless consumption, that capitalism undermines the larger culture’s ability<br />

to create real meaning. Virtually all <strong>of</strong> what is good in society - solidarity, compassion,<br />

creativity, ethics, joy - comes from outside capitalism, giving the illusion that capitalism is<br />

a civilized system. It’s a cliche, but important enough that we sing it over and over: Money<br />

can’t buy you love. Capitalism cannot create a healthy human community, and it undermines<br />

the aspect <strong>of</strong> human nature rooted in solidarity and love.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 573<br />

<strong>The</strong> other obvious failure <strong>of</strong> capitalism is its contribution to the erosion <strong>of</strong> the health <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ecosystem. Humans have been drawing down the ecological capital <strong>of</strong> the planet since the<br />

invention <strong>of</strong> agriculture about 10,000 years ago, but that process has intensified dramatically<br />

in the capitalist/imperialist/industrial era. Our culture is filled with talk about the success <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism even though that system degrades our relationships and threatens our existence.<br />

That’s an odd definition <strong>of</strong> success.<br />

AD: Are there any writers on this topic whose work you would like to recommend?<br />

RJ: Wes Jackson is one <strong>of</strong> my most trusted sources on these issues. Wes is a scientist<br />

working in research on sustainable agriculture, but his critique encompasses politics, economics,<br />

and culture. His new book, Consulting the Genius <strong>of</strong> the Place: An Ecological<br />

Approach to a New Agriculture, is due out this fall, and I’m looking forward to reading. I<br />

think Bill McKibben’s latest book, Eaarth: Making a Life on a Tough New Planet (2010), is<br />

important, though I think his faith in the power <strong>of</strong> the internet to help us through the transition<br />

is dangerously naïve. William Catton’s books Overshoot (1980) and Bottleneck (2009)<br />

have also helped me come to terms with reality.<br />

In addition to the ecological questions, I think we also have to keep focused on the political<br />

and cultural questions, about how the existing distribution <strong>of</strong> wealth and power are serious<br />

impediments to meaningful change. That means continuing to think about the predatory<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> empire and capitalism, and the degree to which patriarchy and white supremacy<br />

structure our world and undermine our capacity to be fully human.<br />

===========<br />

Robert Jensen is a journalism pr<strong>of</strong>essor at the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Texas at Austin and board<br />

member <strong>of</strong> the Third Coast Activist Resource Center in Austin. He is the author <strong>of</strong> All My<br />

Bones Shake: Seeking a Progressive Path to the Prophetic Voice (S<strong>of</strong>t Skull Press, 2009);<br />

Getting Off: Pornography and the End <strong>of</strong> Masculinity (South End Press, 2007); <strong>The</strong> Heart <strong>of</strong><br />

Whiteness: Confronting Race, Racism and White Privilege (City Lights, 2005); Citizens <strong>of</strong><br />

the Empire: <strong>The</strong> Struggle to Claim Our Humanity (City Lights, 2004); and Writing Dissent:<br />

Taking Radical Ideas from the Margins to the Mainstream (Peter Lang, 2002). Jensen is also<br />

co-producer <strong>of</strong> the documentary film “Abe Osher<strong>of</strong>f: One Foot in the Grave, the Other Still<br />

Dancing”, which chronicles the life and philosophy <strong>of</strong> the longtime radical activist. Information<br />

about the film, distributed by the Media Education Foundation, and an extended interview<br />

Jensen conducted with Osher<strong>of</strong>f are online at http://thirdcoastactivist.org/osher<strong>of</strong>f.html<br />

.<br />

Jensen can be reached at rjensen@uts.cc.utexas.edu and his articles can be found online<br />

at http://uts.cc.utexas.edu/ rjensen/index.html . To join an email list to receive articles by<br />

Jensen, go to http://www.thirdcoastactivist.org/jensenupdates-info.html .<br />

http://www.countercurrents.org/jensen030910.htm<br />

Message [135] referenced by [196]. Next Message by Hans is [136].<br />

[146] Frida: Ecological Philosophy. One contemporary philosopher, David Abram, has<br />

said that the root <strong>of</strong> the problem with the way that humans relate to the environment is simply<br />

the way we feel about it and talk about it. <strong>The</strong> idea is that the <strong>first</strong> step towards change is to<br />

574 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

stop thinking about humans as the center <strong>of</strong> all consciousness and stop thinking <strong>of</strong> ourselves<br />

as a separate <strong>thing</strong> from the environment. Reading his book “<strong>The</strong> Spell <strong>of</strong> the Sensuous”<br />

really changed my view on the way that we should relate to nature, even though I had always<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> myself as some<strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong> an environmentalist.<br />

Reading the last few posts on this thread about ecological disaster, and thinking about<br />

some <strong>of</strong> Abram’s writings more in the context <strong>of</strong> this class has made me think that <strong>thing</strong>s<br />

are even worse that a total separation from our natural environment. People have gotten to<br />

the point that they objectify every<strong>thing</strong>, including other human beings. Without this objectification<br />

capitalism couldn’t exist. This ruthless need for commodities etc. etc. leads to a<br />

warping <strong>of</strong> the way people are supposed to relate to each other, the environment, and even<br />

their own sustenance.<br />

Message [146] referenced by [165]. Next Message by Frida is [166].<br />

[148] JSmits: Impact <strong>of</strong> Global Warming. After reading Hans [125], the reality that<br />

the world could be affected so drastically by global warming at the end <strong>of</strong> the century was<br />

very alarming. I haven’t heard any<strong>thing</strong> <strong>of</strong> that nature before I read Hans email and it really<br />

opened my eyes. Of course I knew it was and has been one <strong>of</strong> biggest issues in the last few<br />

years but to hear that my kids could be affected so greatly by this when they get older was<br />

hard to hear.<br />

Message [148] referenced by [158]. Next Message by JSmits is [432].<br />

[150] IrvingHowe: Kraken—what alternative? Kraken, in response to Hans’ comments<br />

regarding capitalism’s inability to adequately address the environmental problems,<br />

you asked in [99] “Who or what could do a better job? I’m hoping to understand what a<br />

better alternative would be.” First, allow me to say that there has been volumes written on<br />

this very subject and it would be worth looking into the subject for many obvious reasons. I<br />

think your question itself seems to concede by omission that capitalism does indeed lack the<br />

ability to tackle the crisis it has caused to our eco-system. So, what is else is there you ask.<br />

To understand the answer, it is necessary to ask what about capitalism causes such destruction.<br />

Capitalism as a economic philosophy can be summed up as a system consisting <strong>of</strong> any<br />

number <strong>of</strong> consumers and producers each when acting in their own self interest produces a<br />

most optimal mix <strong>of</strong> outcomes. <strong>The</strong> result is supposed to be, as Adam Smith said referring to<br />

the role <strong>of</strong> undertakers (producers) in promoting general welfare, “an end which was no part<br />

<strong>of</strong> his intention” namely optimal social welfare for all citizens including, for the <strong>first</strong> time in<br />

history, the working classes. <strong>The</strong> problem with that, as econ 101 tells us, is that our choices<br />

are riddled with consequences which we neither intended nor have to deal with, or externalities.<br />

It is beyond reason to believe that intelligent people living with even a minimal amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> information regarding any type <strong>of</strong> natural science could not understand pollution is in fact<br />

hurting him/herself and legions <strong>of</strong> descendent children. It is also beyond reason to believe<br />

that this action is understood to be any<strong>thing</strong> less than a moral wrong. However, because the<br />

rewards can be so great, it overwhelms whatever human element may exist in a businesses<br />

decisions. This cannot be reformed. It is in fact the foundation <strong>of</strong> capitalism that each firm<br />

and consumer act in their own interest. Since the reward is so great and the chance <strong>of</strong> having<br />

to personally reckon with the exact level <strong>of</strong> damage inflicted by their actions against the<br />

environment so small, the result will always be the same.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 575<br />

As for alternatives, I would like to be even handed about this but I honestly do not know<br />

<strong>of</strong> any real ideas for reform out <strong>of</strong> the right wing (or for that matter what is commonly considered<br />

the left) <strong>of</strong> American politics. Fortunately for this particular purpose, there is a very<br />

fractured political left each with their own platform and ideas to address the environmental<br />

crisis. <strong>The</strong> one <strong>thing</strong> that they all have in common, the most important <strong>thing</strong>, is a systematic<br />

approach to radically reforming a poor set <strong>of</strong> incentives that encourages abuse against<br />

humans and the environment alike.<br />

For one, most include high minimum wages and a maximum wage which would greatly<br />

reduce the potential reward for polluters. Also, there is a growing movement for what is<br />

known as a steady-state economy. I don’t have room to do any <strong>of</strong> these <strong>thing</strong>s justice in<br />

explanation, I apologize. As for the analogy <strong>of</strong> a black market in prison, I think it is misguided<br />

for this discussion. <strong>The</strong> large scale polluters <strong>of</strong> the world have no real way <strong>of</strong> ‘going<br />

underground.’ It is a very large investment to build, say, a steel mill on the <strong>of</strong>f chance that no<br />

one discovers the legions <strong>of</strong> workers and raw material going to said plant. To the apparent<br />

concern over some sort <strong>of</strong> central authority making decisions for environmental purposes, I<br />

would say think <strong>of</strong> it in context <strong>of</strong> the great services already provided by both the private,<br />

public and not-for-pr<strong>of</strong>it sectors. <strong>The</strong>re are wonderful <strong>thing</strong>s going on in each <strong>of</strong> these and<br />

they are all being planned by some sort <strong>of</strong> powerful central body, I will say that I personally<br />

prefer decision making to be as decentralized as is functionally feasible.<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [160].<br />

[158] Hans: Answer to a question you didn’t ask. Lindsey [123] said she found my<br />

[94] disturbing, and JSmits [148] said, in response to my “end <strong>of</strong> the world” email [125], he<br />

had not known how serious the situation was. If the situation is as serious as I say, why am<br />

I not out on the barricades, throwing if necessary my body into the machinery to stop the<br />

madness?<br />

Answer: I think I can be more effective if I push the envelope <strong>of</strong> what I am allowed to<br />

say as a teacher, than if I get myself fired because <strong>of</strong> civil disobedience. Since I am trying<br />

to teach you dialectical thinking in this class, this is a wonderful example <strong>of</strong> a contradiction.<br />

If I want to be around to tell you about climate change, I can not really act appropriately<br />

myself, i.e., I am forced to deny with my actions what my words are saying. This, <strong>of</strong> course,<br />

makes me also a lousy example to emulate. I may be wrong but I see this not as flight from<br />

responsibility but the most effective use <strong>of</strong> my place in society to combat climate change.<br />

And don’t forget that I am 65 years old. I will not live through the brunt <strong>of</strong> the climate<br />

catastrophe. <strong>The</strong> young have to be the leaders, not the old who will not be personally affected<br />

as much by climate change and whose reactions will therefore be much too mild.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [173].<br />

[160] IrvingHowe: <strong>The</strong>re are plenty <strong>of</strong> alternatives. Lindsey [123],<br />

I think that there are plenty <strong>of</strong> alternatives to the current market system, even some that<br />

are in practice today. What we have really is a matter <strong>of</strong> life or death. Never mind the<br />

decrease in production that comes from a group <strong>of</strong> unhappy co-op workers. <strong>The</strong> shifting<br />

climate patterns and soil erosion already taking place are going to kill more people than an<br />

unproductive co-op. Crop production is not possible without a resource rich earth, no matter<br />

the happiness <strong>of</strong> the workers.<br />

576 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Also, to address your metaphor more directly, I want to quickly point out a couple <strong>of</strong><br />

flaws. First, there is the almighty mistake that market-minded individuals tend to make<br />

which prematurely cuts <strong>of</strong>f debate—that is your scenario assumes that the individuals are<br />

only motivated by money. I think that the <strong>University</strong> is a pretty good place to see an example<br />

<strong>of</strong> why this isn’t true. Every day, thousands <strong>of</strong> students study to be teachers rather than<br />

accountants despite the monetary reward involved in the latter. I don’t think it’s necessary to<br />

continue with the thousands examples <strong>of</strong> non-economically motivated actions that play out<br />

every single day on our campus. My point is simply that people are indeed moved to action<br />

by a very wide variety <strong>of</strong> incentives.<br />

Second, there are also thousands <strong>of</strong> companies which are very successful in which wage<br />

rates are the same or very nearly the same for all employees. Employee owned businesses,<br />

co-ops and any number <strong>of</strong> unionized firms come to mind when thinking <strong>of</strong> successful businesses<br />

that disprove the need for wide wage disparities.<br />

Whether or not Marx was mostly right about capitalism’s self destructive tendencies is<br />

certainly worth debating, he was definitely not right on every<strong>thing</strong>. In fact, he acknowledges<br />

this repeatedly throughout Capital vol. I and Engels plainly states in vols. II and III that<br />

he is not even certain that he is properly interpreting Marx’s manuscripts. However, I feel<br />

that half <strong>of</strong> this discussion is operating under false premises—that is that even if it’s not been<br />

explicitly stated, there seems to be an underlying idea that the only alternatives are command<br />

economic models which have already failed.<br />

I for one reject that notion. <strong>The</strong>re are a lot <strong>of</strong> options out there for addressing the many<br />

crises that capitalism creates. All <strong>of</strong> the options however require a fundamental restructuring<br />

<strong>of</strong> incentives in our economy. This is an absolute necessity. All would require largely<br />

dismantling the dogmatic loyalty that Americans have to the idea that business always knows<br />

best. Some <strong>of</strong> the most productive changes we can make are as simple as ending the suburban<br />

nightmare and turning to far more dense city structures.<br />

This isn’t a matter <strong>of</strong> choice. Our lifestyles will force drastic change to our economy—5<br />

percent <strong>of</strong> the world’s population just can’t go on consuming 30 percent <strong>of</strong> its resources.<br />

She: I agree with you that the restructuring <strong>of</strong> incentives in our system is absolutely crucial to making a significant<br />

change.<br />

<strong>The</strong> entire capitalist system is based on incentives. Some individuals value money most and see it as the greatest<br />

incentive, other people have different values and see other activities or emotional fulfillment as a greater incentive.<br />

<strong>The</strong> people in the former classification don’t really exist totally, I don’t believe. This would be the ”rational man”<br />

or the ”pr<strong>of</strong>it-maximizing corporation” there are plenty <strong>of</strong> examples, as you show, that do not fit these assumptions.<br />

Yet it is assumptions like these that drive the neo-classical school <strong>of</strong> economics. People do ”irrational” <strong>thing</strong>s all<br />

the time, because it makes them happier, it provides more ”utility” as some would gesture.<br />

I think incentive changes need to happen to discourage corporations and individuals from reaping their own<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its without regard to the effects they have on others. <strong>The</strong>y need to be held accountible for the social costs that<br />

are incurred on their behalf.<br />

Next Message by IrvingHowe is [191].<br />

[161] RexManning: How did the cat get so fat? A song <strong>of</strong> the same title as the above<br />

subject line from a band called NOFX, who helped to shape who I am now, brought to light<br />

some serious problems that I had never thought <strong>of</strong> as a teenager. Now that I am much older,<br />

and possibly a bit more grown up, I can see the problems that relate to and make up the<br />

reality <strong>of</strong> the less fortunate as other scramble and trample over each other to get ahead in


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 577<br />

life. After taking Poverty and Inequality last year, I became much more aware <strong>of</strong> the over<br />

looked value <strong>of</strong> the human being. As NOFX put it “how did the cat get so fat?” How did so<br />

much power come to rest in the hands <strong>of</strong> the few, and when did those few stop caring about<br />

their neighbors? Maybe I am an idealist, but I sincerely believe in the idea <strong>of</strong> this country<br />

and the good that the majority <strong>of</strong> its people possess in their hearts.<br />

That being said, some<strong>thing</strong> must be done to make this world a better place for those that<br />

will follow us. A war for pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong> fat contracts, misled by our leaders and carried out by the<br />

brave is some<strong>thing</strong> that would surely cause our forefathers to roll over in their graves. It is<br />

true, we are the home <strong>of</strong> the free because <strong>of</strong> the brave, but these young men and women do<br />

not need to be exploited in the worst kind <strong>of</strong> way. As a veteran <strong>of</strong> the Iraq war and soonto-be<br />

veteran <strong>of</strong> the war in Afghanistan, I have seen the gruesome reality that is war, but<br />

I also rest assured knowing that there are those out there who are willing to put their lives<br />

on the line for others. Although, that may not be the basis <strong>of</strong> the war in Iraq, we are most<br />

certainly putting our lives on the line for others in Afghanistan. That is the kind <strong>of</strong> love and<br />

dedication that is needed to turn this boat around. Hans may think it is out <strong>of</strong> our hands now,<br />

but I believe in the power <strong>of</strong> the people, and look forward to a brighter tomorrow. Here are<br />

a few lines from NOFX. Enjoy!<br />

“It’s all about the money<br />

Political power is taking<br />

Protecting the rich, denying the poor<br />

Yeah, they love to watch the wars from the White House<br />

And I wonder...<br />

How can they sleep at night?<br />

How can they sleep at night?<br />

How did the cat get so fat?”<br />

Next Message by RexManning is [319].<br />

[165] Lana: Taking accountability. Frida [146] talks about how humanity’s consumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities is disconnecting us from nature and disintegrates our human-to-human<br />

relationships. While I agree with David Abram’s idea <strong>of</strong> defocusing humans’ importance,<br />

I believe to a degree that we are the caretakers <strong>of</strong> the Earth. Capitalism is not necessarily<br />

a bad <strong>thing</strong> if those operating the system are aware that there are additional goals besides<br />

making a pr<strong>of</strong>it. Commodities can be produced and consumed from the land, just as long as<br />

we take accountability for what is being depleted and replace it, or make it better.<br />

Message [165] referenced by [166] and [169]. Next Message by Lana is [415].<br />

[166] Frida: Re: Taking Accountability. In response to Lana [165]:<br />

<strong>The</strong> very idea that humans are supposed to be “the caretakers <strong>of</strong> the Earth” is in the same<br />

destructive vein as the idea that the earth is here for our benefit and use, though it seems to<br />

be the opposite idea. It still assumes that humans have a preeminent role, and objectifies the<br />

Earth itself. <strong>The</strong> Earth’s many species have evolved to weather patterns, currents, etc. for<br />

the past few billion years. To say that humans are caretakers <strong>of</strong> the Earth is preposterous; we<br />

578 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

are incapable <strong>of</strong> caring for the earth in any way, as I understand the term. <strong>The</strong> attempts <strong>of</strong><br />

some to minimize the horrible damage we have done to other species and to the environment<br />

in general are the closest example I can come up with. It reminds me <strong>of</strong> an old friend <strong>of</strong><br />

mine who once pushed me <strong>of</strong>f a porch and then caught me at the last second. He then said<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> about saving my life, obviously as a joke. We evolved as a small part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

earth’s ecosystem and have since decided that we are the most important component <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

Presumably because <strong>of</strong> our ability to do <strong>thing</strong>s like derive calculus equations and our over<br />

important view <strong>of</strong> that sort <strong>of</strong> intelligence.<br />

It is an obvious fact that humans as a species can survive without damaging the earth,<br />

as we have many examples <strong>of</strong> such cultures (but we have less and less current ones as time<br />

goes by). Since it is hard to know what works without experiential evidence I am open to<br />

ideas about what sort <strong>of</strong> social structure could lead to a less abusive relationship with the<br />

ecosystem. Still, if we are looking at capitalism, it seems an unlikely candidate. When the<br />

goal <strong>of</strong> an economic system is private gain (correct me if I am wrong on this definition <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism) it is hard to see how it could lead to a more positive relationship with the Earth.<br />

People will take advantage <strong>of</strong> short term opportunities for pr<strong>of</strong>it if given the chance and<br />

raised to believe that the economic goal <strong>of</strong> their lives should be accumulation <strong>of</strong> personal<br />

wealth. This short-sightedness will always lead to objectification <strong>of</strong> fellow humans and <strong>of</strong><br />

plant life, animals, etc.<br />

If people are aware that “there are additional goals besides making a pr<strong>of</strong>it”, then they<br />

have some motivation outside <strong>of</strong> capitalism. This awareness is somewhat antithetical to the<br />

idea <strong>of</strong> capitalism. Commodities can be produced in systems besides capitalism, we just<br />

need to find some<strong>thing</strong> that works. After being depressed over all this for the last few days,<br />

right now I’m afraid we won’t and ecological disaster will ensue. <strong>The</strong>n we will be forced, if<br />

we like it or not, into a different lifestyle.<br />

Message [166] referenced by [204], [519], and [521]. Next Message by Frida is [200].<br />

[169] Max: How to regulate corporations. In response to Lana [165]:<br />

Integrating a system that checks and balances corporate environmental degradation is a<br />

lot harder than it seems. Even if it gets passed in congress (judging by how financial reform<br />

was met) it will leave many aspects <strong>of</strong> our environment still extremely vulnerable. And it is<br />

foolish to think that corporations will make the necessary changes on their own.<br />

However, one <strong>of</strong> the only reasons we have so many archeologists is because mining companies<br />

are usually required by law to make sure they aren’t operating where valuable prehistoric<br />

remains are located, so they hire an archeologist. It may be possible to regulate<br />

corporations in this way whereas they are required to hire bipartisan scientists to study the<br />

impacts <strong>of</strong> their operations. (My friend who works for <strong>The</strong> Nature Conservancy <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> is<br />

involved in a program similar to this where they will be studying the value <strong>of</strong> the natural<br />

resources corporations are using. For instance, if a company is polluting a stream, they economically<br />

evaluate the benefits that stream makes to the company. <strong>The</strong>oretically (though not<br />

in existence yet) the company would then essentially be taxed for the services that nature<br />

provides).


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 579<br />

<strong>The</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> capitalism is to take advantage <strong>of</strong> the situation to make a larger pr<strong>of</strong>it. If<br />

regulation does get passed to mitigate corporate environmental wrongdoings, there are still<br />

other aspects <strong>of</strong> production and trade that capitalists will take advantage <strong>of</strong>. For instance, the<br />

health <strong>of</strong> workers, health <strong>of</strong> consumers, and moral aspects pertaining to unequal distribution<br />

<strong>of</strong> wealth. A revolution may be the only way, or at least a less capitalistic nation rising to<br />

greater power than the USA. (China?)<br />

Next Message by Max is [212].<br />

[195] PLG: How to Save the Environment. In agreement with Lindsey [123] who was<br />

initially commenting on Hans [94], capitalism has showed a great amount <strong>of</strong> promise in<br />

solving the environmental catastrophe. Markets may actually be the very force that pulls us<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the catastrophe. We are certainly facing a severe crisis, and face crucial decisions on<br />

how the issue can be solved. We can either delve deeper into our capitalist system, or step<br />

back and focus more on centralized planning to provide the answers.<br />

Commoditizing the health <strong>of</strong> the environment is a viable option. Environmental economists<br />

have come up with savvy ways to shift incentives in favor <strong>of</strong> the environment. <strong>The</strong> cap and<br />

trade system is a brilliant way to control for externalities. Taxing pollution is a government<br />

driven concept, but it utilizes the market system that we have in place. Similarly the pollution<br />

created by fishing vessels is rapidly destroying the world’s coral reefs. Coral reefs are<br />

on the verge <strong>of</strong> extinction. Environmental economists are currently working to figure out<br />

ways to commoditize coral reefs that would tax fishing corporations for any pollution they<br />

put into the oceans.<br />

Although Marxian thinking can <strong>of</strong>fer a bird’s eye view <strong>of</strong> the horrible situation capitalism<br />

has brought us into, there is certainly evidence that capitalism can pull us out. Capitalism<br />

can work in favor <strong>of</strong> the environment in the same way it has worked in favor <strong>of</strong> major corporations<br />

and manufacturing industries. If it costs more to reap the earth’s natural resources<br />

and pollute, people will be more careful in how they produce. Offering tax incentives for<br />

businesses that contribute to the health <strong>of</strong> the earth may even have a reversal effect. It will<br />

demand a great amount <strong>of</strong> creativity, but commoditizing the environment is a worthy concept.<br />

It may even lead to the birth <strong>of</strong> a new business cycle.<br />

Hans: Coral reefs are destroyed in part by modern destructive fishing practices with explosives, in part by dead<br />

zones coming only to a small part from the pollution put in the oceans by fishing boats but mainly from agricultural<br />

run<strong>of</strong>f, by rising sea temperatures, and by ocean acidification due to higher CO2 concentration in the atmosphere.<br />

Message [195] referenced by [204], [210], [232], and [300]. Next Message by PLG is [399].<br />

[196] Ferox: Building a new world on the ashes <strong>of</strong> the old.... Hans’ emails [125] and<br />

[135] regarding economic and ecological collapse hit on themes that have personally interested<br />

me for several years. Namely I have been fascinated with the idea <strong>of</strong> mass extinctions<br />

and the resulting bottleneck ecological growth that happens afterwards. Throughout the history<br />

<strong>of</strong> the earth there have been mass extinctions. Following such an event the fossil record<br />

shows amazing adaptation and proliferation <strong>of</strong> life as ecological niches open up. A familiar<br />

example is the End Cretaceous Extinction, which ended the dominance <strong>of</strong> the dinosaurs—<br />

after which mammals and birds flourished.<br />

<strong>The</strong> question that arises in my mind is when the next great extinction happens - which<br />

at this point looks to be man made - what will the world look like when the dust settles?<br />

580 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Armed with this in mind, what can be done to either mitigate or prepare for living in a<br />

radically different world?<br />

I have compiled a list <strong>of</strong> books, movies, and other media which have helped stimulate<br />

my mind on this topic over the last several years. Some <strong>of</strong> these resources, like Marx’s<br />

Capital, have tremendous foresight and applicability in today’s climate despite their age <strong>of</strong><br />

publication. Others are merely whimsical musings, stories warning <strong>of</strong> hubris, or practical<br />

survival manuals. I have tried to organize them by subject and media, and by author under<br />

each category. This is by no means a complete list, just what I have found and enjoyed.<br />

Any<strong>thing</strong> I missed or further input would be appreciated!<br />

—Books—<br />

Rebuilding Societies<br />

Horseclans - Robert Adams<br />

<strong>The</strong> Long Tomorrow - Leigh Brackett<br />

<strong>The</strong> World Jones Made - Philip K. Dick<br />

<strong>The</strong> Penultimate Truth - Philip K. Dick<br />

A Canticle for Leibowitz - Walter M. Miller, Jr.<br />

Earth Abides - George R. Stewart<br />

<strong>The</strong> Chrysalids - John Wyndam<br />

Misc Apocalyptic Scenarios<br />

<strong>The</strong> Survivalist series - Jerry Ahern<br />

<strong>The</strong> Postman - David Brin<br />

Children <strong>of</strong> Men - P. D. James<br />

I Am Legend - Richard Matheson<br />

Lucifer’s Hammer - Larry Niven and Jerry Pournelle<br />

<strong>The</strong> Last Man - Mary Shelley<br />

Ecological Collapse/Dying Earth/Peak Resource<br />

Hothouse - Brian Aldiss<br />

Collapse - Jared Diamond<br />

<strong>The</strong> City <strong>of</strong> Ember - Jeanne DuPrau<br />

Dark is the Sun - Phillip Jose Farmer<br />

Endgame - Derrick Jensen<br />

<strong>The</strong> Road - Cormac McCarthy<br />

Damnation Alley - Roger Zelazny<br />

Reference Manuals


<strong>The</strong> Zombie Survival Handbook - Max Brooks<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 581<br />

Back to Basics: A Complete Guide to Traditional Skills - Abigail R. Gehring<br />

How to Survive the End <strong>of</strong> the World as We Know It - James Wesley Rawles<br />

<strong>The</strong> New Self-Sufficient Gardener - John Seymour<br />

<strong>The</strong> Self-sufficient Life and How to Live It - John Seymour<br />

—Film—<br />

28 Days Later (2002)<br />

28 Weeks Later (2007)<br />

A Boy and His Dog (1975)<br />

Akira (1988)<br />

<strong>The</strong> Book <strong>of</strong> Eli (2010)<br />

Children <strong>of</strong> Men (2006)<br />

<strong>The</strong> City <strong>of</strong> Ember (2008)<br />

Delicatessen (1991)<br />

Doomsday (2008)<br />

Dr. Strangelove or: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the Bomb (1964)<br />

I Am Legend (2007)<br />

Land <strong>of</strong> the Dead (2005)<br />

<strong>The</strong> Last Man on Earth (1964)<br />

Max Max Trilogy (1979-85)<br />

<strong>The</strong> Omega Man (1971)<br />

Planet <strong>of</strong> the Apes (1963)<br />

<strong>The</strong> Postman (1997)<br />

<strong>The</strong> Road (2009)<br />

Soylent Green (1973)<br />

Stalker (1979)<br />

Star Trek - First Contact (1996)<br />

Testament (1983)<br />

Twelve Monkeys (1995)<br />

Wizards (1977)<br />

—Video Games—<br />

Fallout 3 - Bethesda Studios<br />

582 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Borderlands - 2K Games<br />

S.T.A.L.K.E.R.: Shadows <strong>of</strong> Chernobyl - GSC Game World<br />

Next Message by Ferox is [485].<br />

[204] Kat: How to Save the Environment. In response to PLG’s environmental consideration<br />

[195], I agree that capitalism is potentially capable <strong>of</strong> adjusting to the environmental<br />

situation. PLG discusses the incentives and economic policies that can be put in place to<br />

shift companies’ motives in favor <strong>of</strong> the environment. <strong>The</strong>se have to potential to make significant<br />

changes on the big picture <strong>of</strong> capitalism’s effect on the environment. <strong>The</strong>re is also<br />

an important environmental shift in the products and services for domestic use. As environmental<br />

awareness has reached the household consumers, demand has begun to shift from<br />

cheap, large quantities <strong>of</strong> basic goods to a newly created ‘green’ version <strong>of</strong> the same good;<br />

cleaning products, organic foods and other household goods can all now be eco-friendly.<br />

Because <strong>of</strong>ten consumers feel the only way for them make a difference is in the way the<br />

choose to consume. So, in this way, capitalism and reinvented itself to find pr<strong>of</strong>its in new<br />

areas and interests, in this case environmental consideration.<br />

Frida [166] believes that capitalism can in no way benefit the environment because it goes<br />

against the pr<strong>of</strong>it seeking mentality. She claims that considerations <strong>of</strong> any<strong>thing</strong> other than<br />

turning a pr<strong>of</strong>it is “somewhat antithetical to the idea <strong>of</strong> capitalism.” I disagree that capitalism<br />

cannot harbor pr<strong>of</strong>it seeking behavior and a basic consideration for the environment. Frida<br />

seems to have a very unbecoming view <strong>of</strong> the capitalist, perhaps picturing a cold, calculating<br />

person with a reckless desire to make money. While I’m sure there are such people, I think<br />

demonizing anyone involved in the capitalistic business <strong>of</strong> making money is a bit cynical.<br />

I think beyond pr<strong>of</strong>its, most people have an inherent desire to at least reasonably avoid<br />

recklessly harming the environment. So, as the public becomes increasingly concerned with<br />

the environment, capitalism and the capitalist will likely shift their actions to adhere to what<br />

is now expected <strong>of</strong> them. That, now, being environmental consideration.<br />

Message [204] referenced by [210]. Next Message by Kat is [492].<br />

[210] Hans: How to Inform Yourselves about Global Warming. PLG [195] and Kat<br />

[204] believe that capitalism can deal properly with climate change. Do you know what the<br />

actual track record is and where to get information about it? I can recommend Joe Romm’s<br />

Climate Progress web site. I visit it every day, it has several new and relevant items every<br />

day. This is a good way to get hold <strong>of</strong> the information which should be in the newspapers<br />

and on TV but isn’t, because the media are part <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system. Joe Romm is an<br />

insider; he was Acting Assistant Secretary <strong>of</strong> Energy for Energy Efficiency and Renewable<br />

Energy during the Clinton Administration. He knows what he is talking about. Here is a<br />

posting from yesterday:<br />

http://climateprogress.org/2010/09/19/climate-sensitivity-lukewarmers/<br />

Joe says there:<br />

Given that the anti-science, pro-pollution forces seem to be succeeding in<br />

their fight to keep us on our current emissions path, it’s no surprise that<br />

multiple recent analyses conclude that we face a temperature rise that is far,<br />

far beyond dangerous:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 583<br />

If you go to the web site, you will be able to follow links to specific scientific reports about<br />

what to expect by the end <strong>of</strong> this century. <strong>The</strong> authors are not weirdos predicting the end <strong>of</strong><br />

the world, but prestigious scientific centers around the world. One-sentence summaries are<br />

Hadley Center: “Catastrophic” 5-7 deg C warming by 2100 on current emissions path<br />

M.I.T. doubles its 2095 warming projection to 10 deg F—with 866 ppm and Arctic warming<br />

<strong>of</strong> 20 deg F<br />

Our hellish future: Definitive NOAA-led report on U.S. climate impacts warns <strong>of</strong> scorching<br />

9 to 11 deg F warming over most <strong>of</strong> inland U.S. by 2090 with Kansas above 90 deg F<br />

some 120 days a year—and that isn’t the worst case, it’s business as usual!<br />

“<strong>The</strong> Copenhagen Diagnosis” warns “Without significant mitigation, the report says global<br />

mean warming could reach as high as 7 degrees Celsius by 2100.”<br />

Next Message by Hans is [215].<br />

[232] Intaglio: This Gov isn’t capable <strong>of</strong> Saving the Environment. I think the most<br />

unsettling <strong>thing</strong> about the ongoing environmental destruction is that people are looking for<br />

solutions within the system that causes the problem. <strong>The</strong>y are so used to the way <strong>thing</strong>s<br />

are they refuse any alternative except the “free market” or “green Keynesianism.” If these<br />

“solutions” persists there certainly is no hope.<br />

I thoroughly disagree with PLG [195] about commoditizing the health <strong>of</strong> the environment<br />

as being the way out <strong>of</strong> environmental catastrophe. It’s way too optimistic. Market incentives,<br />

the few that come into play, won’t be nearly enough to fix the problem. It will be like<br />

trying to soak up a flood with a tiny sponge.<br />

Capitalism is a grow or die system due to its competitive nature. It isn’t sustainable on a<br />

finite planet, regardless <strong>of</strong> climate change, we are still running out <strong>of</strong> other resources. When<br />

capitalism runs out <strong>of</strong> resources to exploit it will crash.<br />

Most <strong>of</strong> the economy is driven by oil, <strong>of</strong> which we will hit the peak <strong>of</strong> production<br />

soon. Exploding populations and industrialization around the world will suffer a tremendous<br />

amount from this in the near future. <strong>The</strong> only solution i can see there is depending on<br />

capitalism or the state to invent its way out through clean energy. I think capitalism might be<br />

capable <strong>of</strong> finding new energy sources. But again, it won’t be enough. <strong>The</strong> whole “science<br />

will save us” theories are drastically irresponsible. <strong>The</strong> world uses 85 Million barrels <strong>of</strong> oil<br />

a day. Bi<strong>of</strong>uels are not going to save us.<br />

Plus we have the oil companies buying up patents to clean energy so they can hold onto<br />

the current energy model. Renewable energy isn’t as pr<strong>of</strong>itable because once it’s set up there<br />

is no more pr<strong>of</strong>it. <strong>The</strong> capitalists have incentive not to switch to clean energy.<br />

Another solution that does not work is placing power and responsibility in the hands<br />

<strong>of</strong> the politicians <strong>of</strong> leading capitalist countries. Look what happened in the Copenhagen<br />

Climate Summit. <strong>The</strong>y didn’t even go for the minimal regulations like carbon trading! <strong>The</strong>ir<br />

absolute failure to do any<strong>thing</strong> about climate change is rooted in the systemic problems <strong>of</strong><br />

our society. It makes no sense to try and fix <strong>thing</strong>s through the system that is in itself the<br />

problem.<br />

584 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>The</strong> problem with the system: In capitalist nations, control <strong>of</strong> the government is always<br />

in the hands <strong>of</strong> the upper class. <strong>The</strong> longer wealth is allowed to concentrate upwards, the<br />

less power the people have. Money is power. <strong>The</strong>re a point reached in plutocracy where the<br />

masses will not be able to affect change through the political institutions. Alternative means<br />

will become necessary. <strong>The</strong>y are already necessary in my opinion. Now if the economic elite<br />

have control over government policy, why would they let market incentives come into play<br />

when they can just as easily lobby for no regulations and make more pr<strong>of</strong>it? I’m expecting<br />

very few market incentives to be put into place because <strong>of</strong> this.<br />

I also think placing the blame solely on the Capitalist motive is an incomplete analysis;<br />

<strong>The</strong> political elite also find regulations undesirable, especially in the USA. This is due to<br />

their desire for power and control over other countries through energy sources. If they limit<br />

or regulate capitalism they are seriously hindering their ability to achieve the imperialist<br />

aims <strong>of</strong> maintaining and expanding their dominance over the world. <strong>The</strong>ir ability to do this<br />

is derived from the economic growth <strong>of</strong> capitalism. That is why our leaders in America did<br />

no<strong>thing</strong> to regulate and control the climate problems. <strong>The</strong>y depend on capitalism for their<br />

own hegemony, and the capitalists depend on imperialism to expand their market. Remember,<br />

capitalism will crash if it stays in a finite system. <strong>The</strong> state will do every<strong>thing</strong> it can to<br />

stop this crash because they will lose their power if it happens.<br />

So how about a mass movement to pressure our leaders? That could be a solution. But<br />

<strong>first</strong>, let’s consider that it is a serious problem that we have to have millions marching in the<br />

streets to get our leaders to do any<strong>thing</strong>. Even if we do get mobilized and pressure them into<br />

passing a few laws, we are still going to have to deal with their stagnant responses to our<br />

other needs. <strong>The</strong>y obviously don’t care about us, let alone our climate.<br />

But isn’t that their job? Taking care <strong>of</strong> the people? If you know the history <strong>of</strong> states you<br />

will know they arose to protect capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its and maintain class society, not to protect<br />

the people. Knowing this is essential if you are going to be looking for a solution from the<br />

Bourgeois state. <strong>The</strong>y have a track record <strong>of</strong> protecting the rich, today, the corporations<br />

pillaging the planet. All odds are against us when trying to get these corrupt politicians to<br />

do any<strong>thing</strong>.<br />

I think the much more rational solution is to overthrow the capitalist structure, which is<br />

inseparable from the current state. We need to change the system as a whole, i.e. revolution.<br />

It is just a matter <strong>of</strong> which revolutionary politics to choose from. If we don’t we will experience<br />

an intense version <strong>of</strong> fascism when capitalism runs into these ecological limits and<br />

looks to it’s nanny, the state, for rescue.<br />

Imagine the current energy wars times 10, and then stop looking for solutions within this<br />

system.<br />

Message [232] referenced by [262] and [300]. Next Message by Intaglio is [254].<br />

[262] School: How to Save the Environment—Rebuttal. Intaglio [232] provides a great<br />

argument about the free market and, the Capitalist Society that we currently live in. From<br />

my understanding Intaglio’s main points were that if the free market and capitalist societies<br />

continue, that there is no hope for the future, and that “Capitalism is a grow or die system<br />

due to its competitive nature. It isn’t sustainable on a finite planet”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 585<br />

I will agree that capitalism is a growing or dying system. That is because when one<br />

job becomes obsolete another job is created because <strong>of</strong> innovation. For example, for those<br />

people who have watched “Charley and the chocolate factory” the newest one with Jonny<br />

Depp. In this film Charley’s dad’s job was to screw on the lids on to bottles <strong>of</strong> tooth paste.<br />

During the course <strong>of</strong> the film Charley’s dad was replaced by a machine (innovation). At <strong>first</strong><br />

this was sad, but at the end <strong>of</strong> the film Charley’s dad was able to get the job <strong>of</strong> fixing the<br />

machine that replaced him. Jobs will constantly be created and destroyed.<br />

Intaglio continues to say “we have the oil companies buying up patents to clean energy so<br />

they can hold onto the current energy model. Renewable energy isn’t as pr<strong>of</strong>itable because<br />

once its set up there is no more pr<strong>of</strong>it. <strong>The</strong> capitalists have incentive not to switch to clean<br />

energy.” I will say that Intaglio is correct in the fact that Oil companies are buying these<br />

patents, for what reason I do not know. For all we know is that they could be buying these<br />

patents so they can retain their oil businesses, or they could be just adapting to what the<br />

future may bring. Right now everyone is looking for a better way to save the environment,<br />

and I think that is fantastic! We should all do our part to find better ways <strong>of</strong> saving the world<br />

around us, but how can you expect people to drastically change? If we are in a capitalist<br />

society we have to slowly introduce the idea that this is not correct. And I think that is what<br />

the Oil company is trying to do, they can’t merely change overnight. <strong>The</strong> change would be<br />

to drastic and this would destroy jobs. <strong>The</strong> change must take place gradually if one is to be<br />

made. You can’t merely change everyone’s opinion over night. You must show them why it<br />

is right, you must motivate a person to choose what is best, and then let the person make the<br />

decision for themselves.<br />

<strong>The</strong> last point that I would like to talk about that Intaglio shared was about the current<br />

government. Intaglio states: “<strong>The</strong> problem with the system: In capitalist nations, control <strong>of</strong><br />

the government is always in the hands <strong>of</strong> the upper class. <strong>The</strong> longer wealth is allowed to<br />

concentrate upwards, the less power the people have. Money is power.”<br />

Unfortunately we live in a world were money is power, and as history shows us, money<br />

can corrupt people. In this case I think we should take a moment and try to take a broader<br />

look at what is happening. It takes money to run government programs. <strong>The</strong>re are a lot<br />

<strong>of</strong> programs that benefit all, low, middle, and upper class. To say that the Upper Class<br />

controlls the goverment is pretty bold. <strong>The</strong> only reason I say that is because if you look at<br />

the Declaration <strong>of</strong> Independence it says “That whenever any Form <strong>of</strong> Government becomes<br />

destructive <strong>of</strong> these ends, it is the Right <strong>of</strong> the People to alter or to abolish it, and to institute<br />

new Government, laying its foundation on such principles and organizing its powers in such<br />

form, as to them shall seem most likely to effect their Safety and Happiness.” Our country<br />

was established that if you don’t like some<strong>thing</strong> and you think that the government “becomes<br />

destructive” it is the people’s rights to change this! It is up to ALL OF US to make a<br />

difference.<br />

Hans: You are making <strong>thing</strong>s up to feel better about the very bad situation we are in. <strong>The</strong> Oil companies are<br />

financing disinformation campaigns about the climate. By no stretch <strong>of</strong> imagination can this, or their greenwashing<br />

advertising, be construed to be a quest “for better ways to save the climate.” <strong>The</strong>y are looking for better ways to<br />

make money right now.<br />

Message [262] referenced by [300]. Next Message by School is [310].<br />

586 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[300] Oreo: Capitalism vs. the Environment. Contrary to what School [262] says, I<br />

believe the rich do have control over those who don’t have money. A perfect example, as<br />

Intaglio [232] brings up and School refers to, is that fact that oil companies are buying up<br />

patents so that clean energy does not become an option. <strong>The</strong>y are the ones with the money<br />

and therefore are able to make the decisions. Global warming and other potential effects<br />

<strong>of</strong> pollution caused by big companies are easy to ignore now because we aren’t noticing<br />

any remarkable changes that affect our day to day lives. CEOs <strong>of</strong> the oil companies are<br />

getting huge paychecks as incentives to keep pretending that they aren’t harming the planet.<br />

Capitalism keeps them rich and if they were to surrender to alternate fuel, they would no<br />

longer be able to dominate the market and make the pr<strong>of</strong>its that they are making now. I<br />

believe that clean energy will not become a reality until it’s too late. Not until the effects<br />

<strong>of</strong> the pollution overcome our planet and begin immediately affecting our lives, will big<br />

businesses such as oil companies change their ways.<br />

I agree with PLG [195] and Lindsey [123] when they say that capitalism can actually help<br />

us save the environment. Once individuals working for big business realize that their lives<br />

are at stake due the changes in our planet, there will be motivation to find alternatives. Once<br />

we begin switching to alternate forms <strong>of</strong> energy and other measure that are healthier for our<br />

environment, capitalism can help. Companies will compete with each other creating better<br />

and better clean energy at less and less costs to them and the public. Capitalism was a big<br />

factor in destroying our environment, but once the realization <strong>of</strong> the harm to our planet sets<br />

in, I believe capitalism will be able to help us save it.<br />

Next Message by Oreo is [377].<br />

[519] Robert: God help us! Two interrelated factors dim our ecological future: capitalist<br />

economics and religion. This free discussion has witnessed some interesting views about the<br />

<strong>first</strong> <strong>of</strong> these factors and Frida in [166] began a discussion about the second. I want to focus<br />

on the second.<br />

<strong>The</strong> factors are interrelated because capitalism finds support in religion. For example, the<br />

protestant work ethic, the idea that rewards for hard work and faithfulness come in the next<br />

life encourages passive acceptance <strong>of</strong> exploitation. However, you could be “blessed” to be<br />

a capitalist then you receive prosperity in this life because <strong>of</strong> your “faithfulness.” Somehow,<br />

religions that teach us about loving our neighbors also allow us in capitalism to treat others<br />

as means to an end, as I point out in [389]. Moreover, religions that preach selfless service<br />

embrace the seemingly contrary idea that if we economically pursue our own best interest it<br />

will be good for all.<br />

More destructively, in my view, than supporting a destructive economic system, however,<br />

is the fact that many modern organized religions teach that man did not come from and is not<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the Earth. <strong>The</strong>y teach that natural man is an enemy <strong>of</strong> God, that God threw mankind<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the garden, that humans have to fight with and subdue the Earth, and that humans need<br />

not worry about destroying the Earth because one day it will be magically renewed. Apart<br />

from the psycho-spiritual damage such unnatural separation from Nature causes human beings;<br />

it encourages unreasonable, unloving treatment <strong>of</strong> the Earth. Furthermore, many <strong>of</strong>


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 587<br />

these same religions contest the most basic science. <strong>The</strong>y refuse to accept the scientific evidence<br />

about the development <strong>of</strong> the planet and its species let alone accept the evidence <strong>of</strong><br />

how mankind is currently destroying it.<br />

If we all agreed today that we need to take drastic action to save the Earth we may have<br />

some chance <strong>of</strong> reducing the impact <strong>of</strong> global warming. If, on the other hand, we continue<br />

to debate whether the science is “real” and, in the face <strong>of</strong> science, to believe in magical<br />

solutions, there is little hope that we can adjust our course <strong>of</strong> destruction quickly enough to<br />

save our species and several others for whom we may well render the Earth uninhabitable.<br />

My concern, like Hans’s, is not for myself; it is for you, my younger fellow students,<br />

and for future generations. My concern is not even for the planet; in a few million years the<br />

Earth will recover from whatever damage we human have wrought upon it and will evolve<br />

another species capable <strong>of</strong> apprehending Her beauty (and hopefully capable <strong>of</strong> refraining<br />

from destroying the ability <strong>of</strong> the planet to sustain the species).<br />

Message [519] referenced by [591]. Next Message by Robert is [542].<br />

[591] Robert: I’m trying to be optimistic. My last post to this question [519] was a<br />

little bleak. Hans [521] reminded us all that Marx was optimistic about crisis resolution<br />

and gave us an example <strong>of</strong> James Lovelock’s evolving theories <strong>of</strong> crisis management in<br />

Revenge <strong>of</strong> Gaia and Vanishing Gaia. I just want to go on record that I too am an optimistic<br />

person...I delayed in posting any<strong>thing</strong> to our ecological discussion because I have a hard time<br />

restraining my advocacy. I make the strongest case I can for why we need to pay attention<br />

now.<br />

However, even as an optimist I have to wonder about Hans’s [521] description <strong>of</strong> Lovelock’s<br />

“boundary conditions [that] ... humans in turn are too smart they will never be entirely<br />

extinguished...” when I read in the New York Times, October 20, 2010 the article entitled,<br />

“Climate Change Doubt Is Tea Party Article <strong>of</strong> Faith.” <strong>The</strong> article cites Indiana Representative<br />

Baron Hill, an embattled Democratic incumbent, as saying, “Climate change is real,<br />

and man is causing it.” <strong>The</strong> article reports he was booed and a Tea Party <strong>of</strong>ficial replied,<br />

“It’s a flat out lie.” This <strong>of</strong>ficial cited the sources <strong>of</strong> Rush Limbaugh (go ahead Hans...you<br />

should dock me several points for even mentioning that name in this or any class) and the<br />

Bible. He went on to say, “I read my Bible...He made this earth for us to utilize.” Another<br />

spokesperson for the Tea Party is reported to have said,“Being a strong Christian I cannot<br />

help but believe the Lord placed a lot <strong>of</strong> minerals in our country and it’s not there to destroy<br />

us.”<br />

Fortunately (here’s the optimism) the Tea Party only represents a few people and all <strong>of</strong><br />

them are not, I am sure, as stupid as the two <strong>of</strong>ficials quoted here. However, as long as<br />

this sort <strong>of</strong> magical thinking exists I still worry about our ability to undertake the radical<br />

adjustments to our current consumption necessary to save our species and those with whom<br />

we share our beautiful planet.<br />

Next Message by Robert is [611].<br />

[867] PLG: What do you suggest we do? Recently in one <strong>of</strong> my other econ classes we<br />

engaged in a conversation about the state <strong>of</strong> the environment. Our teacher explained how a<br />

rise in global temperatures <strong>of</strong> 2 to 2.4 degrees Celsius would make the planet uninhabitable<br />

for humans. In an article on the website that Hans recommended<br />

588 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

http://climateprogress.org/2010/09/19/climate-sensitivity-lukewarmers/<br />

a catastrophic increase <strong>of</strong> 5 to 7 degrees Celsius is projected by the year 2100.<br />

<strong>The</strong> other day on NPR a woman discussed government involvement in the climate crisis<br />

versus individual action, and how capitalism is leading us to an uncontrollable doom.<br />

Her theory was that individual action was like “getting better at swimming upstream”.<br />

It’s some<strong>thing</strong> that we all need to do, but we are living in a system that is leading us in the<br />

wrong direction. Capitalism is clearly at the crux <strong>of</strong> the problem. It encourages immediate<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it based on a cost benefit analysis, and incentivizes consumption. Not only does it shift<br />

incentives away from environmental protection, but it also makes us too busy to consider<br />

long-run issues.<br />

I think if green technologies can truly be the next immerging market on the stock market<br />

than we could potentially see a cultural shift to go along with it. Every venture capitalist<br />

and entrepreneur will shift their focus and start innovating green businesses in the same<br />

way web-based technologies experienced. This is the only solution I see our current system<br />

<strong>of</strong>fering.<br />

Changing the capitalist structure seems daunting. <strong>The</strong> teacher who led us in the discussion<br />

on the environment says she plans to create new recommendations for developing<br />

countries that will consider the environment much more highly. My question for Hans is<br />

what do you think will help solve the issue <strong>of</strong> the environment. In your opinion where<br />

should the younger generations focus their energy and studies to help solve these problems?<br />

What institutions have the best chance <strong>of</strong> fostering in these changes? Does anyone else in<br />

the class have solutions to <strong>of</strong>fer?<br />

Next Message by PLG is [1006].<br />

[868] Husani: Climate Change. I don’t know what to do as far as society as a whole. I<br />

would suggest not listening to the media and searching out ways to lessen our impact on the<br />

environment. I saw earlier today that a local news station is doing a special report on how<br />

reusable bags for grocery shopping are bad for you. I believe the station was channel 2 and it<br />

airs sometime tomorrow night. <strong>The</strong> fact that a news outlet would promote the use <strong>of</strong> plastic<br />

bags over reusables is quite appaling to me, especially since the apparent problem has to do<br />

with bacteria in the bags. Call me crazy but maybe a simple solution would be for people to<br />

wash their bags after they use them.<br />

A major problem with the debate is that so many people watch the news that is funded<br />

by major corporations, which portray climate change as a myth. My personal view is that<br />

whether or not climate change is fact, we should try to make our home (earth) a more livable<br />

place. Whether or not the sulphur and other chemicals dispersed from coal power plants<br />

creates climate change I don’t want to breathe it and others shouldn’t either.<br />

Message [868] referenced by [874]. Next Message by Husani is [957].<br />

[874] Guh: Climate Change Response. In response to Husani [868] discussion regarding<br />

climate change and the role <strong>of</strong> the media I agree with you on the topic <strong>of</strong> the media, however,<br />

the conversation with climate change is debatable, and I disagree with you on that. Moreover,<br />

as far as the media goes I agree with you one hundred percent. <strong>The</strong> media is a ran and funded<br />

by corporations that feed the public fear, and information that is not entirely accurate. One


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 589<br />

<strong>thing</strong> that I found interesting about your post, was the topic <strong>of</strong> re-usable bags, and how this<br />

is bad for you in the contexts <strong>of</strong> air pollution. Well interestingly enough, last semester I was<br />

an intern in Washington D.C. and the District <strong>of</strong> Colombia passed a law when I got there,<br />

that you had to pay 10 cents per plastic bag when grocery shopping. You could re-use the<br />

bags and it was encouraged, so you wouldn’t have to spend 10 cents a bag every time you<br />

went to the grocery store. I found this <strong>of</strong> interest and think it is interesting the channel 2<br />

news is doing a report on this, when in D.C. they highly encourage costumers to re-use their<br />

plastic bags. I don’t know why channel 2 would say this other than the reason you gave, and<br />

I agree with you that people should just wash them out and re-use them.<br />

Message [874] referenced by [877]. Next Message by Guh is [1003].<br />

[877] Hans: Don’t let the climate deniers confuse you! If someone were to state in the<br />

free discussion that 2+2=5, I would feel obligated to step in, although this is not a math class.<br />

And if the author <strong>of</strong> [874] says that “climate change is debatable” and criticizes the press<br />

for “feed(ing) the public fear”, then I have to step in too. Few scientific issues are better<br />

checked and better confirmed than the disastrous consequences <strong>of</strong> our policies on climate.<br />

<strong>The</strong> scientific issue is settled, but if you listen to the press you are made to think there is<br />

a debate. <strong>The</strong> press is not feeding the public fear, on the contrary, they are complicit in<br />

keeping the truth about climate away from the American Public.<br />

I wouldn’t be surprised if the author <strong>of</strong> [874] learned these mistaken convictions about<br />

climate change during his work as an intern in Washington DC. Joe Romm’s blog published<br />

a map showing all states that have climate deniers as congressional reps, and after the recent<br />

election the answer is: almost every state. Exceptions are Maine, Vermont, Connecticut,<br />

Delaware, and Hawaii, tiny flecks compared to the rest <strong>of</strong> the US land mass. Here is the map<br />

if you are interested<br />

http://climateprogress.org/2010/11/19/the-climate-zombie-caucus-<strong>of</strong>-the-112thcongress/<br />

That our elected representatives in these trying times stick their head in the sand instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> providing leadership—this is another sign <strong>of</strong> a declining empire, see my [408]. Keep your<br />

eyes open—it is scary and will be a disaster, but it is also incredibly interesting.<br />

A big part <strong>of</strong> the responsibility for the public ignorance about climate change lies with<br />

the schools and Universities. <strong>The</strong> <strong>University</strong> should have a requirement that everybody<br />

graduating here must have taken at least one course where he or she learns the basics about<br />

climate change. President Young pretty much vetoed this one, he says there are already too<br />

many requirements. Everyone learns in school the rudiments how our bodies function, we<br />

should also learn the rudiments <strong>of</strong> how our planet functions, especially the carbon cycle and<br />

the role <strong>of</strong> fossil fuels. Such basic education would make it much more difficult for the<br />

deniers and delayers to confuse the public. For more info about how this denialism was<br />

constructed and their links to cigarette smoke denialism, read Hoggan and LittlemoreK’s<br />

book “Climate Cover-Up: <strong>The</strong> Cruisade to Deny Global Warming”<br />

http://www.amazon.com/Climate-Cover-Up-Crusade-Global-Warming/dp/1553654854/<br />

590 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

or Oreskes and Conway’s book “Merchants <strong>of</strong> Doubt: How a Handful <strong>of</strong> Scientists Obscured<br />

the Truth on Issues from Tobacco Smoke to Global Warming”<br />

http://www.amazon.com/Merchants-Doubt-Handful-Scientists-Obscured/dp/15969161<br />

or listen to a 58-minute talk by Naomi Oreskes at<br />

http://www.uctv.tv/search-details.aspx?showID=13459<br />

Next Message by Hans is [905].<br />

[895] Max: Buy local! Hans, I noticed that you posted links to Amazon.com. Aren’t<br />

the prices that Amazon sells there products much to low, thus forcing down prices <strong>of</strong> competitors?<br />

This may seem like a good <strong>thing</strong> at <strong>first</strong>, until you realize that the lower prices <strong>of</strong><br />

goods corresponds to lower wages for the producers (abroad) and less jobs for local retailers?<br />

I realize you can buy used products on Amazon but they still take a cut <strong>of</strong> the sale.<br />

It seems like we haven’t discussed much about “buying local,” in this class, but it makes<br />

sense that purchasing products from local business owners keeps wealth flowing within those<br />

communities. You may save some money buying from online warehouses because they cut<br />

out some middlemen, but in the end your money is going to someone who is already very<br />

wealthy.<br />

For example, if I’m going to buy a bicycle, I could buy it online and save some money.<br />

Or I could go to a bike shop that sponsors local bicycle clubs and events and employs people<br />

who are passionate about bikes; many <strong>of</strong> whom contribute to the local bicycle community<br />

in their own right. <strong>The</strong> same can be said about all local businesses.<br />

Anyway, what do you guys think?<br />

Message [895] referenced by [896] and [905]. Next Message by Max is [999].<br />

[896] SMIKEC: I agree with Max [895] that people should buy local. However, in this<br />

economy buying local does generally cost more which people are currently looking for the<br />

deal. I’m all about buying local and can cost justify the increased price due to maybe better<br />

quality e.g. farmers market produce versus chain grocery stores. Customer service also<br />

comes into play. Im willing to pay more for some<strong>thing</strong> if it is backed by a person that you<br />

can meet face to face with. Buying local goes with the concept <strong>of</strong> living more green, I think<br />

most people’s intentions are there, but are quickly side tracked or influenced to go another<br />

route when they find the costs are higher.<br />

Message [896] referenced by [900]. Next Message by SMIKEC is [947].<br />

[900] Smartergirl: SMIKEC [896] has a lot <strong>of</strong> valid points and I also agree that buying<br />

local is a ideal however can be costly. With the latest issues in our economy I feel people are<br />

having a stronger desire to support local businesses. We felt the effects <strong>of</strong> too many imports<br />

and an inflated market and a strong desire to go back to basics.<br />

All <strong>of</strong> a sudden there are magazines that are booming by the titles <strong>of</strong> Simple, Clean,<br />

minimalists. I think as a society we have had enough <strong>of</strong> commercials telling us what we<br />

need and to stuff our homes with as much stuff as we can afford and if we cant afford it get<br />

more credit. When the house is full get a storage unit and buy more stuff all in the sake <strong>of</strong><br />

keeping the money moving. Marx would have been appalled by this type <strong>of</strong> consumerism.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 591<br />

In his idea <strong>of</strong> value, commodity, and exchange value the very basics keep us living simply<br />

and induce a relationship with local businesses.<br />

I believe people are willing to pay a higher price for service, quality and the satisfaction <strong>of</strong><br />

saying the bought locally. Companies are fully aware <strong>of</strong> this shift in the American consumer<br />

because we all see signs everywhere stating that they are an American Company. We also<br />

see locally grown on produce, this large shift in marketing would make it pretty clear that<br />

consumers are looking for local goods.<br />

Next Message by Smartergirl is [945].<br />

[905] Hans: <strong>The</strong> world is falling apart, I better start recycling. Or putting in CFL<br />

lightbulbs, or buying local, or stop using plastic shopping bags. All these are <strong>thing</strong>s we<br />

should be doing, but this alone will not stop the climate catastrophe. Some climate activists<br />

don’t push these <strong>thing</strong>s very hard because they don’t want people to think they are solving<br />

the problem through these actions. George Marshall, in his book Carbon Detox, writes: the<br />

biggest climate denier is in ourselves. It is really difficult to admit to ourselves the gravity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the problem, especially since it does not feel like a crisis. Here are some videos featuring<br />

George Marshall<br />

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=D1EDmFglU8U<br />

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=vbGAKJTqOtE<br />

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=sn2S00 xp4M<br />

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=sGPnFiXC2Q0<br />

http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=fNH20fGCz-0<br />

BTW, George Marshall has a neat answer to Max’s [895] objection to Amazon’s low<br />

prices: he has an Amazon UK link on his web page<br />

http://www.carbondetox.org/html/buy.html<br />

with the explanation “Click on this link to buy a copy through Amazon (and a small<br />

percentage will be given to the author which will just about compensate him for the impacts<br />

<strong>of</strong> Amazon’s cost cutting on his royalty).” Here in the US the only choice is to get it through<br />

Amazon Market place (it’s certainly worth it), see<br />

http://www.amazon.com/gp/product/1856752887/<br />

Message [905] referenced by [914]. Next Message by Hans is [939].<br />

[914] Giant: Climate Change is Happening Now. <strong>The</strong> George Marshall videos in [905]<br />

demonstrate how lax the entire world is taking global warming, just waiting for another<br />

nation to make the <strong>first</strong> move before they con-seed their advantageous yet destructive method<br />

<strong>of</strong> production. <strong>The</strong> best point Marshall brought up was that the <strong>first</strong> step that needs to be<br />

taken is for people to stop making climate change and global warming a future event. I did<br />

not notice it that much before but when problems are discussed they are talked about as some<br />

far unknown future event that will happen if no<strong>thing</strong> is done now to fix it. Climate change<br />

is rarely discussed in present tense, and even less <strong>of</strong>ten is there a set number <strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s that<br />

will happen in so many years. This kind <strong>of</strong> language makes it easier to imagine that climate<br />

592 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

change and global warming is not going to happen for a long time. Instead <strong>of</strong> it staring us<br />

right in the face now while the world does very little about it because it has not brought<br />

about the apocalypse yet.<br />

Next Message by Giant is [1074].<br />

[1071] Jo: A Marvelous Victory. I have <strong>of</strong>ten thought about Hans’ message about climate<br />

change [125], since he sent it to us back in September. I never imagined before that people<br />

would survive a climate change catastrophe, so the scenario that Hans describes, while very<br />

bleak, seems kind <strong>of</strong> exciting and hopeful to me. It makes me happy to think that humans<br />

will live on. Granted, it will be horrible and tragic in the process, but within the scenario<br />

that Hans <strong>of</strong>fers is an opportunity to rebuild society in a more compassionate way, which is<br />

some<strong>thing</strong> I hadn’t considered before.<br />

While a climate catastrophe is likely if we don’t change course, I still don’t think it’s inevitable.<br />

Manfred Max-Neef, see [1032], raises some interesting points about the absurdity<br />

<strong>of</strong> shipping goods all over the world and calling it economical to do so. Reducing consumption<br />

to local economies would make a huge dent in carbon emissions. It would mean much<br />

less fuel required and less factory farming. Higher cost <strong>of</strong> goods and less variety available<br />

would mean less but more meaningful consumption. It could also mean a return to close-knit<br />

communities where many commodities can be shared. Local economies would lead to less<br />

exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers as well. As we have learned in this class, there is some<strong>thing</strong> about a<br />

huge, anonymous marketplace that encourages despicable behavior.<br />

I know that right now it seems unlikely that such a shift could occur on a large scale, but<br />

I think it is happening already. <strong>The</strong> shift is slow and gradual, but people are more conscious<br />

<strong>of</strong> what they buy and where it comes from. For example, my husband’s parents are not ready<br />

to give up eating meat in support <strong>of</strong> the environment, but they have switched to buying meat<br />

that is raised and butchered in their town and no longer support factory farming. <strong>The</strong>y aren’t<br />

the only ones that are starting to think this way. Even if this shift never reaches a magnitude<br />

that can halt climate change, it at least helps prepare communities to rely on each other in<br />

the face <strong>of</strong> disaster.<br />

I don’t think it’s cynical to believe what scientists are predicting about climate change.<br />

It doesn’t mean we should give up on life or lose faith in humanity. It also doesn’t mean<br />

we shouldn’t try to change <strong>thing</strong>s. Trying to come up with a way to change the system as<br />

a whole will get anyone down, but when I think about what I can do in my own life, or<br />

in my own sphere, I feel much more hopeful. I have an advantage over those who won’t<br />

believe it. I can build my life and my experiences around people and relationships, instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>thing</strong>s. I can live a compassionate, responsible lifestyle. I can see through the absurdity<br />

<strong>of</strong> mainstream media and the commodity craze and seek out reality as an alternative. Being<br />

able to recognize the difference means so much. My life will not be a bright, fuzzy blur, but<br />

will be filled with rapturously beautiful moments as well as painfully bleak ones, in all <strong>of</strong><br />

which I will be fully present.<br />

Here is an excerpt from <strong>The</strong> Optimism <strong>of</strong> Uncertainty by Howard Zinn. He sums up my<br />

meaning better than I can:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 593<br />

“Revolutionary change does not come as one cataclysmic moment (beware<br />

<strong>of</strong> such moments!) but as an endless succession <strong>of</strong> surprises, moving zigzag<br />

toward a more decent society. We don’t have to engage in grand, heroic<br />

actions to participate in the process <strong>of</strong> change. Small acts, when multiplied<br />

by millions <strong>of</strong> people, can transform the world. Even when we don’t ‘win’,<br />

there is fun and fulfillment in the fact that we have been involved, with<br />

other good people, in some<strong>thing</strong> worthwhile. We need hope.”<br />

“An optimist isn’t necessarily a blithe, slightly sappy whistler in the dark<br />

<strong>of</strong> our time. To be hopeful in bad times is not just foolishly romantic. It is<br />

based on the fact that human history is a history not only <strong>of</strong> cruelty but also<br />

<strong>of</strong> compassion, sacrifice, courage, kindness. What we choose to emphasize<br />

in this complex history will determine our lives. If we see only the worst,<br />

it destroys our capacity to do some<strong>thing</strong>. If we remember those times and<br />

places—and there are so many—where people have behaved magnificently,<br />

this gives us the energy to act, and at least the possibility <strong>of</strong> sending this<br />

spinning top <strong>of</strong> a world in a different direction. And if we do act, in however<br />

small a way, we don’t have to wait for some grand utopian future. <strong>The</strong><br />

future is an infinite succession <strong>of</strong> presents, and to live now as we think<br />

human beings should live, in defiance <strong>of</strong> all that is bad around us, is itself a<br />

marvelous victory.”<br />

Next Message by Jo is [1124].<br />

[1112] Hal: Climate change and staring capitalism in the face. In [1102], Hans mentions<br />

that McCoy’s “...report didn’t say a word about climate change and the end <strong>of</strong> world<br />

wide economic growth. (McCoy is a historian, and these issues are relatively new.)” It is<br />

also frustrating that even among environmentalists, scientists and economists, only a select<br />

few openly chastise capitalism as being the primary cause <strong>of</strong> the climate crisis. Capitalism is<br />

inherently dependent on growth <strong>of</strong> output, which is the underlying cause <strong>of</strong> global warming<br />

and the destruction <strong>of</strong> natural resources, and ending capitalism is absolutely necessary if we<br />

wish to avoid major environmental collapse.<br />

Minqi Li, another economics pr<strong>of</strong>essor at our university, has spent quite a bit <strong>of</strong> time researching<br />

the environmental threat posed by capitalist growth. He wrote the following article<br />

on the subject, which I believe is quite persuasive because it is readable, yet scientifically<br />

rigorous:<br />

http://www.monthlyreview.org/080721li.php<br />

Li provides ample evidence that no amount <strong>of</strong> technological innovation alone can save<br />

us from global warming disaster. Even with the most optimistic projections <strong>of</strong> increased<br />

energy efficiency and use <strong>of</strong> renewable energy courses, the economy must actually contract<br />

in order to avoid catastrophe. Yet, as Li writes, “...under a capitalist system, so long as the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production and surplus value are owned by the capitalists, there are both incentives<br />

and pressures for the capitalists to use a substantial portion <strong>of</strong> the surplus value for capital<br />

accumulation. Unless surplus value is placed under social control, there is no way for capital<br />

accumulation (and therefore economic growth) not to take place.”<br />

594 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

I think many people intuitively suspect that capitalist growth causes global warming,<br />

but most <strong>of</strong> us wish to either (a) deny that global warming exists, or (b) hold out hope for<br />

increased energy efficiency. For the most part, not even politicians or wealthy capitalists<br />

continue to deny global warming. <strong>The</strong>refore, Plan B goes into effect. We are continually<br />

reassured that technology will save us. Most <strong>of</strong> Li’s article uses scientific evidence combined<br />

with common sense to stamp out that false hope. We can make significant advances in energy<br />

efficiency, but the only long term solution is the world wide end <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

Message [1112] referenced by [1132]. Next Message by Hal is [1113].<br />

[1132] PLG: 2012 is approaching. In response to Hal [1112] Minqi Li’s article provides<br />

an informative look into the ties between capitalism and climate change. Particularly interesting<br />

is the data on large countries CO2 emissions. Minqi Li notes that Russia is the only<br />

large economy that has been able to reduce its CO2 emissions since the signing <strong>of</strong> the Kyoto<br />

protocol in 1990. Minqi Li also notes that the Kyoto protocol is set to expire in the year<br />

2012.<br />

With the year 2012 approaching it is crucial that a new international agreement is established<br />

before the Kyoto protocol expires. If this does not happen world-wide production<br />

would face very few restrictions pertaining to clean energy. International agreements on the<br />

climate crisis have been difficult to come by as the developing world blames the rich world<br />

for the majority <strong>of</strong> the pollution, while the rich world pressures the developing world to take<br />

on demanding development standards.<br />

<strong>The</strong> current financial crisis is not helping the situation as the rich world is at odds with<br />

the developing world in the financial sector. <strong>The</strong> developing world is criticizing the US<br />

and Europe for its irresponsible financial markets. Increasing capital inflows are burdening<br />

developing countries. Unfortunately the financial meltdowns could overshadow climate<br />

negotiations leaving a new international agreement on the back burner. Again this is an example<br />

<strong>of</strong> how capitalism is at odds with the environment. Financial needs must come <strong>first</strong> in<br />

capitalism, while more holistic needs are secondary.<br />

Final Grading Note by Hans: You were a serious and deep thinker from the beginning, and I think I noticed that<br />

during the class you became a little more confident <strong>of</strong> your own thinking and critical <strong>of</strong> others.<br />

First Message by PLG is [27].<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 0 is 0 in 2011fa:<br />

<strong>Question</strong> 0 Announcements<br />

[11] Hans: Careful with umail subscriptions. This message is only relevant for those<br />

who use their umail account for this class. You must subscribe that email address to the<br />

das-kapital mailing list which shows up in the From: field when you send email.<br />

Here is an example <strong>of</strong> what I mean. My uNID number is u0019795, i.e., email sent<br />

to u0019795@utah.edu will reach my umail inbox. But if I send emails from umail, the<br />

From: field <strong>of</strong> the email says ehrbar@economics.utah.edu. This may present a problem.<br />

If I subscribe u0019795@utah.edu to das-kapital, then I will get all list emails, i.e., every<strong>thing</strong><br />

seems fine until I send a submission to das-kapital. Mailman sees the email address<br />

ehrbar@economics.utah.edu and it has no way <strong>of</strong> knowing that this is the same as<br />

u0019795@utah.edu. <strong>The</strong>refore it will think this is a submission from someone who is not


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 595<br />

subscribed. It will send you a message with the subject line “Your message to Das-Kapital<br />

awaits moderator approval”, but don’t get your hopes up: this message will never be approved.<br />

I am writing this because in the last few hours at least two people subscribed themselves<br />

with their uNID numbers but their umail account identifies their outgoing emails with a<br />

different address string containing their real name. Sorry, you have to go to the subscription<br />

page<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/mailman/listinfo/das-kapital/<br />

and unsubscribe your uNID address and subscribe your real-name address. This is an<br />

issue which you will have not ony with das-kapital but with every other mailing list as well.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [12].<br />

[18] Hans: New Feature, not yet in the Syllabus. <strong>The</strong> syllabus says: when you write<br />

“ug” after the question number, then your answer will receive a grade for your information<br />

only. This grade does not enter the GPA calculation for your final class grade.<br />

This is still true, but I made two enhancements:<br />

(a) if you write “ug” after the question number, then your submission counts as one <strong>of</strong><br />

your free discussion submissions.<br />

(b) if you write “ug” after the question number, then your answer is accepted even after<br />

the deadline for the regular homework answers.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [19].<br />

[58] Hans: Beware <strong>of</strong> non-breaking spaces. At least two times in the last 12 hours<br />

someone submitted his or her answer in the correct format, it was not html but plain text,<br />

and the <strong>first</strong> line seemed to say<br />

::Q: 34<br />

where 34 was the respective question number. Yet it was rejected with the explanation<br />

that the <strong>first</strong> line <strong>of</strong> the message did not begin with a line saying ::Q: 34. <strong>The</strong> problem with<br />

these messages was that there was a “non-breaking space” either between the ::Q: and the<br />

number, or after the number. This is a non-ascii character which looks like a blank space.<br />

Some <strong>of</strong> the s<strong>of</strong>tware which you are using to compose your mail inserts those non-breaking<br />

spaces where it thinks there is the end <strong>of</strong> a sentence, so that there will be a bigger blank<br />

space when rendered in html. <strong>The</strong> safest way around this is to write the line without any<br />

spaces, as in ::Q:34, and make sure that there are also no trailing spaces at the end <strong>of</strong> the line<br />

(and <strong>of</strong> course also no commas or periods etc).<br />

I hate it when s<strong>of</strong>tware is trying to guess what you want and do <strong>thing</strong>s without telling you.<br />

That’s why I am using linux, not Windows. Computers are a powerful means <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

and Windows is very capitalistic in the way I described in [54]: it tries to take away your<br />

control over your means <strong>of</strong> production even if this means <strong>of</strong> production is sitting right in<br />

your living room.<br />

Message [58] referenced by [59]. Next Message by Hans is [59].<br />

596 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[77] Hans: How to study, no audios yet. Someone asked: “are we expected to read<br />

every email from all students?” <strong>The</strong>re are different ways to do this class. Some students<br />

study the Annotations very carefully and compose their answers from their reading <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Annotations, others rely more on the class discussion. Some students come to class every<br />

single time, others show up in class only for the one obligatory class session and the exams.<br />

You need to be self-motivated to do this class. If you don’t find the subject matter <strong>of</strong> the<br />

class interesting, this will be a serious handicap. This class teaches you new perspectives<br />

that require engagement with the material and mulling over. More study hints along these<br />

lines are also in my message [19].<br />

At the minimum you should<br />

(1) keep up with the assigned readings<br />

(2) read all the messages I send to class<br />

(3) if you are preparing an answer yourself, download the pdf archive http://marx.economics.<br />

kapital/pdf/screen/2010fa.pdf and read every<strong>thing</strong> that was said about the question you are<br />

about to answer.<br />

This past Tuesday and Friday I did not make audios <strong>of</strong> the in-class sessions because I<br />

projected Marx’s text on the screen and discussed this. I may do this more <strong>of</strong>ten because I<br />

am polishing up my Annotations in order to get them ready for publication as a book. <strong>The</strong><br />

revised Annotations, which are very similar to what I said in these classes, are available<br />

either in screen format in the zip file<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/screen/akmc.zip<br />

or in halfpage format in<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/halfpage/akmc.zip<br />

If you download these, I recommend to extract them into a different directory on your<br />

computer than the other class materials, because they contain new questions and possibly<br />

list the old questions under different numbers.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [81].<br />

[258] Hans: Installment 1 not yet ready. I couldn’t keep up with the flood <strong>of</strong> submissions<br />

last night, therefore installment 1 will not be ready before class today. I will finish it up as<br />

soon as I can this afternoon, and send out another email when it is ready.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [287].<br />

[314] Hans: Sample exam, and bring student ID! If you want to see what the exams<br />

this week are going to look like, I put a sample up at<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/print/exam.pdf<br />

Your actual exams will look exactly like this, but they will have different question numbers.<br />

You need to show your student ID during the exam!<br />

Next Message by Hans is [315].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 597<br />

[317] Cmellen: So am i to understand that the questions on the test (that we will need to<br />

do a resubmission on) could be any <strong>of</strong> the exam questions listed on Installment 1? (three to<br />

choose from will be listed on page 1 same again on page 2 - we pick ONE <strong>of</strong> those one page<br />

1 and ONE on page 2) but it won’t necessarily be the questions listed on the Exam example.<br />

So in other words.. to be prepared.. be able to answer any <strong>of</strong> the questions in the installment<br />

1 - cause we don’t know which ones will really be on the exam?<br />

Message [317] referenced by [318]. Next Message by Cmellen is [333].<br />

[318] Hans: Different status <strong>of</strong> the questions called ”Exam <strong>Question</strong>” In response<br />

to Cmellen [317]: <strong>The</strong> questions to be resubmitted are only questions in Installment 1 (or<br />

questions similar to those in Installment 1) which are not labeled “Exam <strong>Question</strong>”. <strong>The</strong><br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong>s cannot be resubmitted, and you don’t have a choice with them. <strong>The</strong>refore I<br />

would recommend that you <strong>first</strong> make sure you know all the answers to the questions labeled<br />

Exam <strong>Question</strong>. You know two <strong>of</strong> those will be on the exam, and you have to answer both<br />

in class without resubmission.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [320].<br />

[321] Bigwhite: Looking to join or start a group to write a term paper together, im in the<br />

friday class, let me know if interested or have a spot open to join group<br />

Next Message by Bigwhite is [423].<br />

[333] Cmellen: Exam question: In the instructions, we are told use self-copying “NCR”<br />

paper for the questions that are to be resubmitted. Is this self-copying paper going to be<br />

provided, or do we pick it up at the bookstore prior to the exam? I called the book store and<br />

they said it is sold $10.00 per 50 sheets (no smaller quantities available).<br />

Message [333] referenced by [334]. Next Message by Cmellen is [341].<br />

[334] Hans: In response to [333], the NCR paper will be provided. You need a pen, and<br />

your student ID, and perhaps some scratch paper. Blue books not necessary.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [339].<br />

[458] Somramthom: What the Heck! I am having a hard time resubmitting my exam<br />

questions and don’t know what I am doing wrong. Could someone please tell me what they<br />

did to resubmit their answers please?<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [461].<br />

[464] TINDOZ: How to submit. Somramthom, you’ve asked this after midnight (with it<br />

being due in less than 3 hours), so I might be the only one up reading my email help you out<br />

- and hopefully you haven’t given up before reading this.<br />

I submitted mine by just sending 2 emails (one for each question) to das-kapital@marx.econ.utah.edu<br />

- I had a subject line <strong>of</strong> Exam <strong>Question</strong> 58 Submission (on the one) and started the email <strong>of</strong>f<br />

like any other email, (ie I sent my <strong>first</strong> one by starting with ::Q:58 followed by my answer<br />

to the question). <strong>The</strong>n not too long after I sent it I got a confirm email. If that’s what you are<br />

doing and you are still having problems, try sending it with a different browser (firefox for<br />

example).<br />

Good luck, I hope that helps you as it’s getting close to zero hour.<br />

Next Message by TINDOZ is [562].<br />

[465] RexManning: Re: What the Heck! I just submitted mine and they seemed to go<br />

through. What I did was place the question number in the same format that we have always<br />

598 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

done at the beginning <strong>of</strong> the email, for example, if you were resubmitting Q 100, the <strong>first</strong><br />

line in the body <strong>of</strong> your email should be ::Q: 100<br />

Followed by a double space and then your resubmitted answer. Hope that helps.<br />

Next Message by RexManning is [668].<br />

[467] Somramthom: Fwd: What the Heck! I submitted them successfully! Thanks to<br />

everyone who emailed back to help me. I really appreciate it!<br />

Next Message by Somramthom is [522].<br />

[492] Kat: Interactive website. I’m having a issues with the interactive website. Every<br />

time I try to open it, I get only a series <strong>of</strong> HTML. Is anyone else having this problem? Or<br />

have any idea why it might be doing this? Any help would be appreciated. Thanks<br />

Message [492] referenced by [493]. Next Message by Kat is [494].<br />

[493] Proletarian: Re: Interactive website. Kat, I’m having the same issue you mentioned<br />

[492]. I’ve been getting it all day today. Just a huge page <strong>of</strong> code.<br />

I’m assuming the site may be down for maintenance or some<strong>thing</strong>...<br />

Next Message by Proletarian is [598].<br />

[507] Hans: Plone site. <strong>The</strong> plone site sometimes goes down, because it has access to<br />

your grade info, and this info is changing all the time with you making new submissions<br />

and I giving grades. <strong>The</strong> s<strong>of</strong>tware I have written for this is deliberately brittle: if there is<br />

the slightest doubt about a grade or the identity <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong> the contributors, it just tanks,<br />

forcing me to look at the issue and rectifying it. For instance once it went down because<br />

two different subscribers to das-kapital had chosen the same pseudonym. I also recently<br />

discovered someone who had mistyped their student ID in the subscription, and similar<br />

<strong>thing</strong>s. I notice this because I am running tests which give me error messages. But this<br />

takes the plone site down with itself. <strong>The</strong> problem is that I don’t <strong>of</strong>ten look at the plone site.<br />

<strong>The</strong>refore if you notice it is down, please send me an email, then I can fix it. Right now it is<br />

up again (I hope). <strong>The</strong> best email to reach me is<br />

ehrbar@lists.econ.utah.edu<br />

Hans<br />

Next Message by Hans is [511].<br />

[534] Hans: Term Papers. If you are planning to write a term paper about the topics<br />

468 Essay about Chapter Three, Section 2.b: <strong>The</strong> Flow <strong>of</strong> Money<br />

or<br />

470 Essay about Chapter Three, Section 2.c: Coins and Symbols <strong>of</strong> Value<br />

or<br />

491 Comparison <strong>of</strong> Chapter Three in Capital with Chapter Two in Marx’s 1859 Contribution<br />

to the Critique <strong>of</strong> Political Economy.<br />

then someone in your termpaper group must submit the term paper between Tuesday Oct<br />

19 and Thursday Oct 21. Submit it in the same format as an ordinary homework question,<br />

with the question number 468, 470, or 491. But you can make a presubmission already now<br />

if you want feedback from me before you submit your final paper. Your submissions will


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 2010fa 599<br />

not be forwarded to the class but will show up in the archives at the end <strong>of</strong> the submission<br />

window for that termpaper.<br />

If you don’t have a term paper group yet you need to get one. If you are not in a term paper<br />

group (or have my express permission to write your term paper alone) your submissions will<br />

not be accepted.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [545].<br />

[589] Hans: Term Papers. <strong>The</strong>re are two term papers in the archives now, messages [575]<br />

and [585]. Between now and Tuesday, term paper discussions are invited, i.e., you can give<br />

feedback about these term papers. <strong>The</strong>se term paper discussions are not group submissions<br />

but individual submissions. I will grade them strictly, so don’t send fluff just to help your<br />

peers. But your grade will only count if it improves your GPA.<br />

<strong>The</strong> next opportunity to submit a term paper is between next Tuesday and Thursday, and<br />

the questions admitted for this term paper are 599 and 600. Look at the syllabus, p. 762 and<br />

the following pages about the other term papers.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [609].<br />

[609] Hans: Multiple Choice <strong>Question</strong>s. All multiple choice questions are now available<br />

at<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/questions/<br />

<strong>The</strong> ones eligible for the second exam start at number 377.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [610].<br />

[803] PLG: Please Read! Hello<br />

I was hoping that we could get a study thread going on the exam questions, multiple<br />

choice questions, and any other info that may be pertinent to the post-midterm email discussions.<br />

It would be great to start working on this before friday for the early test takers.<br />

Hopefully we can get some feedback from Hans as well.<br />

I’m posting a couple exam questions in hopes that class members will participate by<br />

posting some more exam questions,or multiple choice questions etc.<br />

Hopefully we can crack the next exam.<br />

Thanks, PLG<br />

Next Message by PLG is [805].<br />

[804] Frida: RE: Please Read! Did I miss some<strong>thing</strong>, or isn’t the entire mailing list a<br />

study thread already? I don’t think I know what you are proposing.<br />

Message [804] referenced by [805]. Next Message by Frida is [959].<br />

[805] PLG: Please Read! In response to [804]: I was reading some <strong>of</strong> the past annotations<br />

where students had posted answers to exam questions during exam week. Hans commended<br />

them on trying to answer the questions prior to the exam, but in one instance said he wished<br />

they did it earlier in the week so he could give feedback if needed.<br />

For the last exam only a few students posted extra credit exam questions.<br />

I was just hoping to rally everyone to talk about the exam questions a bit.<br />

600 2010fa Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

So basically I’m proposing that students try to contribute some more extra credit responses<br />

to the examquestions. Make sense?<br />

Next Message by PLG is [808].<br />

Compiled by Hans G. Ehrbar 2013-07-07 04:11:38.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!