20.07.2013 Views

ECONOMICS 5080 QUESTIONS AND ... - University of Utah

ECONOMICS 5080 QUESTIONS AND ... - University of Utah

ECONOMICS 5080 QUESTIONS AND ... - University of Utah

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>ECONOMICS</strong> <strong>5080</strong> <strong>QUESTIONS</strong> <strong>AND</strong> ANSWERS<br />

INSTALLMENT 2<br />

<strong>ECONOMICS</strong> DEPARTMENT, UNIVERSITY OF UTAH FALL SEMESTER 2012<br />

Question 348 Should the relationship between individual and society be compared to the<br />

relationship between an individual bird and a flock <strong>of</strong> birds, or to the relationship between<br />

the bumble bee and the flowering plant? Give Pros and Cons for each alternative.<br />

[432] Reeree: Relationship between the individual and society. I feel that society can<br />

be compared, in many ways, to the way an individual bird might be viewed among a flock<br />

<strong>of</strong> birds. Society is full <strong>of</strong> various “cliques;” groups <strong>of</strong> individuals that share a common<br />

interests, views, or purposes. It’s interesting to watch a flock <strong>of</strong> birds. They follow each<br />

other without question. The bird in the lead changes direction and the others change as well.<br />

I believe that people want to be accepted in a group. I think that need is inherent in people.<br />

As a result, people are <strong>of</strong>ten willing to blindly change things about themselves, following the<br />

1


2 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

“lead bird,” hopefully resulting in acceptance among the group as a whole. This definitely<br />

has pros and cons. On the positive, individuals’ need for acceptance is strong. Individuals<br />

that find that feel a sense <strong>of</strong> belonging. However, it can also have a very negative effect, both<br />

on the individual who “belongs” to the group, and for the person who does not. Someone<br />

that blindly follows in order to be accepted <strong>of</strong>ten has to sacrifice their own beliefs and morals<br />

in order to “fit in.” And for the individual who is not a part <strong>of</strong> a group suffers many negative<br />

feelings <strong>of</strong> “not belonging.” Society, on the other hand, can also be compared to a bumble<br />

bee and a flowering plant. Without the work <strong>of</strong> the individual, nothing gets accomplished<br />

for the group as a whole. It’s extremely important for society to have each individual. For<br />

without the individuals, there is no society. A bumble bee works hard, on an individual<br />

level, in order to benefit the colony. This can also be seen within society; those individuals<br />

working to benefit the larger group. I believe that most people want to do good and do their<br />

part to help in society; there is a wonderful sense <strong>of</strong> accomplishment in doing this. However,<br />

people are <strong>of</strong>ten willing to sacrifice a lot in order for group acceptance.<br />

Message [432] referenced by [453]. Next Message by Reeree is [610].<br />

[433] Neela: graded A– Birds and Bees. The relationship between individual and society<br />

could be compared to both the relationship between an individual bird and a flock <strong>of</strong> birds,<br />

and the relationship between the bumble bee and the flowering plant. In Annotations it<br />

says, “Individuals must use the social relations and institutions in order to pursue their own<br />

goals” (page 221). One could compare the flock <strong>of</strong> birds to the social relations necessary<br />

to pursue the individual birds’ goals. Consecutively, one could compare the institutions,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 3<br />

needed in order for the bumble bee to pursue its own goals, to the flowering plant. However,<br />

I believe the comparison between an individual bird and flock <strong>of</strong> birds better represents the<br />

comparison between individual and society.<br />

The pro for comparing the relationship between individual and society with an individual<br />

bird and a flock <strong>of</strong> birds, is that the flock <strong>of</strong> birds can represent the social relations which<br />

provide the “character masks” they need to take on to survive. This comparison is also<br />

supported by the following statement in Annotations, “...this social framework can only<br />

persist if it enables individuals to survive and reproduce; otherwise individuals would have<br />

no choice but to act outside the social framework” (page 221). The flock <strong>of</strong> birds can enable<br />

the individual bird to survive by providing protection, power in numbers, etc. The flock<br />

<strong>of</strong> birds can also enable the individual bird to reproduce, as society enables the individual<br />

to reproduce. The con to comparing the relationship between individual and society with<br />

an individual bird and flock <strong>of</strong> birds is that the flock <strong>of</strong> birds as society will more likely<br />

determine what that individual bird will do compared to a flowering plant for a bumble bee.<br />

The pro for using the relationship between the bumble bee and the flowering plant for<br />

a comparison is that the flowering plant portrays this characteristic <strong>of</strong> society as stated in<br />

Annotations accurately, “Society does not determine what the individuals do, nor does it<br />

guarantee the individuals their survival” (page 221). The con for comparing it with a bumble<br />

bee and a flowering plant is that the flowering plant, as society, does not represent this<br />

characteristic <strong>of</strong> society as stated in Annotations, “Society does not determine what the


4 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

individuals do, nor does it guarantee the individuals their survival” (page 221). In a way, the<br />

flowering plant is needed for the bumble bee to survive, because the pollen they collect from<br />

flowers is taken back to the hive for food, especially for the young. Also, the flowering plant<br />

as society does not enable the bumble bee to reproduce, which as stated in Annotations, “...if<br />

it enables individuals to survive and reproduce...” (Page 221).<br />

Message [433] referenced by [453]. Next Message by Neela is [594].<br />

[453] Hans: I tried to be outrageous but didn’t succeed. Reeree [432] didn’t even notice<br />

that the question said “flower,” she thought it said “colony.” Another example that people<br />

read into the text what they expect to read. Neela [433] noticed the flower, but didn’t say<br />

anything about the most outrageous aspect <strong>of</strong> this comparison: while human societies consist<br />

<strong>of</strong> humans, flowers do not consist <strong>of</strong> bees. On the other hand, one <strong>of</strong> the reasons why I chose<br />

this comparison is that both flowers and society provide means for reproduction. Flowers<br />

provide means for reproduction, namely food, and society provides means for reproduction,<br />

namely the production process for which society is necessary. Neela missed that part.<br />

Flocking is not “follow the leader” behavior. It is self-organization with subtle interaction<br />

and “swarm intelligence.” See<br />

http://www.aviation-for-kids.com/Swarm-intelligence.html<br />

When people today think <strong>of</strong> society, they usually think <strong>of</strong> social fads and pressures and<br />

how to be popular and how not to <strong>of</strong>fend others (be “social”). This low view <strong>of</strong> society may


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 5<br />

be influenced by the experience <strong>of</strong> the pathological society we live in, and it also fits together<br />

with the Hollywood culture <strong>of</strong> rugged individualism. When Marx thinks about society he<br />

thinks about production and about providing the infrastructure for human flourishing. If we<br />

want to change our society for the better we have to learn to organize and work collectively.<br />

It cannot be done by even the most heroic individual.<br />

Message [453] referenced by [509], [532], [812], and [880]. Next Message by Hans is [464].<br />

[454] SLOVENEC: I think the relationship between an individual and society should be<br />

compared to a bumble bee and a flowering plant. The reason for this is because the flowering<br />

plant is dependent on the bees role and function as a pollinator. Without bees, flowers would<br />

struggle to reproduce and thrive. This is a pro <strong>of</strong> the bee analogy, the flower <strong>of</strong>fers a common<br />

good that the bees benefit from and therefore provides an incentive for them, the bees, to<br />

maintain it. Similarly, society is that <strong>of</strong> a flowering plant that desperately depends on the<br />

individual contributing, or not contributing, to it. Without individual effort and contribution,<br />

society would fail to innovate and provide those things that we, as a whole, depend on (i.e.<br />

stable economic activity, social programs for the poor, basic protective rights to its citizens,<br />

etc). The flowering plant <strong>of</strong>fers the bees pollen and nutrients they need to survive, so another<br />

pro for this analogy is that the bees have a common focus that, if properly managed, benefits<br />

everyone in the long term.<br />

That is why I feel the relationship between an individual and society is better compared<br />

to a bee among flowers instead <strong>of</strong> a bird among other birds. Although I don’t think this


6 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

is a real con <strong>of</strong> the Bee analogy, one could make the argument that if every bee does all it<br />

can to maintain the plant, they may not interact as closely as they could in the bird analogy,<br />

therefore hurting their productivity. Another con for this analogy is that bees interacting<br />

solely with the plant doesn’t leave much room for specialization. Unless the bees interact<br />

with each other and categorize certain tasks, each bee will try to manage all the jobs by<br />

itself and waste time switching from each job. That being said, I do see how both analogies<br />

effectively describe the individual/societal relationship.<br />

In the case <strong>of</strong> a bird among other birds, society is comprised <strong>of</strong> the aggregate activities<br />

<strong>of</strong> humans. The act <strong>of</strong> individuals contributing to their own respective trades automatically<br />

results in coordinated efforts among its participants. Therefore, all societal things that we<br />

enjoy, or don’t enjoy, are the result <strong>of</strong> others’ actions. Another pro to this analogy is that each<br />

bird has the freedom <strong>of</strong> choice to positively, or negatively, interact with its fellow beings.<br />

However, one con that is present with this metaphor is the failure to include common<br />

focus that binds “the birds” together in one cause. Birds just interacting with other birds<br />

are like humans interacting with other humans. Although the birds are working with each<br />

other, this doesn’t mean that they’re being productive. I submit that the remedy to this<br />

shortcoming is that the “Bee Relationship” automatically corrects the coordination issue via<br />

individual efforts to maintain the flowering plant binding everyone together for a common<br />

good. Another con <strong>of</strong> the bird analogy is that it fails to protect the bird society from a social<br />

ill believed among the majority (i.e. if the majority <strong>of</strong> birds believe eating other birds is


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 7<br />

socially acceptable). Eventually, this belief and action following will be the demise <strong>of</strong> this<br />

bird society until something changes. This con is also relevant to the Bee society in that<br />

if the majority believe it is wise to chew away the outer layer <strong>of</strong> the plant stem, the plant<br />

will eventually be starved <strong>of</strong> nutrients and wither away, thereby hurting the Bee society as a<br />

whole. However, again, I think that bees working to maintain the flowering plant will be the<br />

most likely society to avoid engaging in long term destructive behavior and is therefore the<br />

most appropriate comparison to an individual living in a society.<br />

Hans: You had this all in one paragraph. This is much too long.<br />

Next Message by SLOVENEC is [502].<br />

[509] Keeper: Relationships between individuals and society can be compared to nature<br />

in many aspects, more than just comparing an individual bird and a flock <strong>of</strong> birds. When we<br />

look into different types <strong>of</strong> societies we can compare them to different birds in nature.<br />

As an individual, say a lone hawk, your dependence relies solely on yourself. Being<br />

able to stand strong and provided for yourself and has its rewards. But it will cost you a<br />

lot with many different struggles. This could be an individual society like the USA. Many<br />

individuals with lots <strong>of</strong> struggles and a few “Lone Hawks” that have been greatly rewarded.<br />

On the other hand we can compare a selfless society like many Asian societies to a flock<br />

<strong>of</strong> geese. In this society the geese use their numbers to make workloads lighter for one<br />

another. With these large numbers avoiding predators becomes easier. In these cultures


8 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

many individuals take less risk to spread the reward over to as many as possible. Instead <strong>of</strong><br />

focusing on the good <strong>of</strong> one, the focus is on the good <strong>of</strong> all.<br />

Hans: Both the US and Japan are capitalist societies, although the cultural attitudes <strong>of</strong> the individuals living there<br />

are very different. The question was not about the cultural attitudes but about the actual relations.<br />

You missed the point <strong>of</strong> the question which I tried to clarify in [453].<br />

Originally you had “on many aspects,” I changed it to “in many aspects.” “From many aspects” would also have<br />

been possible.<br />

About your second sentence: are you comparing societies with birds or with flocks <strong>of</strong> birds?<br />

Malformed sentence “Being able to stand strong and provided for yourself and has its rewards.”<br />

Next Message by Keeper is [1438].<br />

[532] EricR: The relationship between and individual and society is best compared to the<br />

relationship between an individual bird and a flock <strong>of</strong> birds.<br />

a. The bird does not need the flock <strong>of</strong> birds to survive. However, the bird will have<br />

many great benefits being in the flock <strong>of</strong> birds compared to the bird being alone in the<br />

wilderness—much like an individual benefits greatly being part <strong>of</strong> a society, but not needed<br />

to survive. But the flock <strong>of</strong> birds is not dependent on the single bird. Much like a society is<br />

not dependent on a single individual to join. (This is debatable if the individual is playing a<br />

main part in the society, e.g. a farmer for crops in order to feed to society)<br />

b. The bumble bee and the flower plant is a totally different relationship. The bumble bee<br />

is dependent on the flowering plant to survive, however this deviates from the first example<br />

and the flower also benefits from the bumble bee. — This is similar to a society, since the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 9<br />

individual can play a part in the society which will also benefit the society. But not in a way<br />

that the individual is completely reliant on the society in order to survive.<br />

Hans: What makes you think humans can survive without society? Even if society does not feed the individual,<br />

society creates the framework in which the individual can feed himself or herself.<br />

You are flatly contradicting and ignoring things I said in [453] without any attempts to address the arguments<br />

there.<br />

Next Message by EricR is [581].<br />

[547] Speq: The Birds and the Bees. The bird would be most people’s initial reaction to<br />

this question. The bird is a single species that works together to achieve a common goal that<br />

benefits the group. Birds fly in a V formation. The bird in the front <strong>of</strong> the formation, at the<br />

point <strong>of</strong> the V, is the one that is doing the most work. The birds that fly behind benefit from<br />

updraft caused by the leader bird. The birds will switch positions during flight and take turns<br />

being the leader bird. The work load is shared amongst the birds pretty evenly. Humans can<br />

do this too, but we don’t. With a flock <strong>of</strong> birds it is much easier to catch cheaters or free<br />

riders. But, due to the immense size <strong>of</strong> our society, catching cheaters and free riders is much<br />

more difficult. So instead, we live in a society that is more bee-like.<br />

When the bumble bee wants nectar, it finds a flowering plant. On the other hand when the<br />

flowering plant wants to spread its pollen, it attracts a passing bumble bee. The two entities<br />

come together to make an exchange. It is almost as if the flower says, “I’ll trade you this<br />

nectar if you spread my pollen to the other flowering plants.” And the bee responds, “I want<br />

your nectar. So I’ll spread your pollen.” This is much more symbolic <strong>of</strong> how society works.


10 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Adam has a coat and would like some linen. Karl has some linen and would like a coat.<br />

The two form a symbiotic relationship for the duration <strong>of</strong> the exchange. The draw back <strong>of</strong><br />

the bee analogy is the perfect pairs found in nature versus a human’s ever expanding needs.<br />

There is no medium <strong>of</strong> exchange. The bee doesn’t buy his nectar with nature-dollars. And<br />

the plant doesn’t purchase the bee’s delivery service either. For this system to work, the bees<br />

must be paired perfectly to the plants and vice versa.<br />

Next Message by Speq is [679].<br />

[548] Luke: graded C Like a Bee. Comparing the relationship <strong>of</strong> a bee and a flowering<br />

plant to that <strong>of</strong> society and an individual, the bee would represent society, and the flower the<br />

individual. From the text the following list are pro’s to the scenario <strong>of</strong> the bee, I felt like it<br />

fit fairly well and I couldn’t come up with any cons.<br />

PROS Like a bee:<br />

1. The flower depends on its relationship to the bee to reproduce and the bee depends on<br />

the flower to provide the nourishment that it needs to survive.<br />

2. The labor to produce pollen by the flower can be considered homogeneous between<br />

flowers.<br />

3. The bee does not tell the flower how much pollen to make or when to make it.<br />

4. The bee doesn’t guarantee that it will collect the pollen from a particular flower and<br />

therefore does not guarantee its survival.


CONS Like a bee:<br />

I couldn’t come up with any cons.<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 11<br />

The scenario <strong>of</strong> the individual bird to the flock was also a good example, however, I was<br />

able to come up with a few cons for this one, so I feel like the example <strong>of</strong> the bee would fit<br />

a little better with Marx’s view points.<br />

PROS like a bird:<br />

1. While flying, birds in a V formation use each others labor to advance their flock and<br />

travel farther then the could individually.<br />

2. In this V formation every individual’s labor is homogeneous or considered equal to the<br />

other birds flying in the flock.<br />

CONS like a bird:<br />

1. Labor used to find nourishment is an individual effort. Birds are <strong>of</strong>ten competing<br />

against each other when it comes to finding food. It does not provide the social framework<br />

needed to enable them to survive and reproduce.<br />

2. While flying, the flock determines what each individual bird does. They cannot leave<br />

the formation and fly on their own or they will not survive.<br />

Hans: Do you still think Capital lays out Marx’s view points, i.e., he wants labor to be homogeneous? This hurt<br />

your grade, despite the creativity shown in this answer.


12 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Luke is [968].<br />

Question 356 is 174 in 1995WI, 153 in 1995ut, 186 in 1996sp, 206 in 1997sp, 207 in<br />

1998WI, 292 in 2005fa, 312 in 2007SP, 322 in 2008SP, and 320 in 2008fa:<br />

Question 356 Which social relations must exist between producers so that they exchange<br />

(or buy and sell) their products as commodities? Describe groups or societies which have<br />

social relations that preclude exchange between individual members.<br />

[423] Gladwell: graded A+ Don’t talk to strangers. In order that producers exchange<br />

their products as commodities they must have private property rights, with producers treating<br />

each other as owners <strong>of</strong> the commodities. These rights must take precedence over all other<br />

rights, as Gottlieb argues in [1996sp:282].<br />

Once these rights are in place, producers must treat each other as strangers. Ziggy<br />

[2008fa:923] argues this by pointing out that friends don’t typically sell to each other, except<br />

at a discounted price. Fenix [2007SP:462] alludes to it by saying that the sole reason<br />

people engage in business is to better their personal situation. In exchanging commodities<br />

it’s typically for personal gain, so the producers must be strangers.<br />

Since it is necessary that producers be strangers in order to exchange, the prime example<br />

<strong>of</strong> a group that precludes exchange between individual members is the family. A clear<br />

example <strong>of</strong> this happened to me yesterday. Although my dad was planning on selling a


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 13<br />

dvd player at a garage sale, he chose to give it to me for free. Why would he give it me,<br />

even though he was going to sell it to customers at a garage sale? I’m family, they’re just<br />

strangers.<br />

Hans: Good references! I like it that you cited ordinary class participants, not the Marxist Hans.<br />

Next Message by Gladwell is [463].<br />

[1249] PJM: Social Relations Necessary for Commodity Exchange. The exchange <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities requires that individuals relate to each other as private property owners who<br />

are strangers.<br />

First <strong>of</strong> all, producers must relate to each other as owners <strong>of</strong> private property. Even<br />

though it appears as a relation between the individual and his commodity, this social relation<br />

takes the form <strong>of</strong> a contract between an individual and the rest <strong>of</strong> society. That is, since<br />

commodities cannot and do not have a will <strong>of</strong> their own as inanimate objects, they must be<br />

treated as imbued with their owner’s will. In fact, Marx formulates this concept by saying<br />

that the commodity owner’s will “resides in his or her commodities”. Marx is saying that<br />

the rest <strong>of</strong> society must treat commodities as if the commodity owner intended for them<br />

not to be stolen or expropriated, but that access to such commodities is only guaranteed by<br />

exchanging them with other commodities. If this relation is to hold, commodity owners<br />

must subordinate their bodily desires to possess commodities to the private property rights<br />

protecting the individual ownership <strong>of</strong> commodities.


14 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

While the social relation <strong>of</strong> private property typical stems from government legal action,<br />

commodity exchange also depends on the largely non-legal relation whereby commodity<br />

owners relate to each other as strangers. This relationships arises out <strong>of</strong> the individuality<br />

<strong>of</strong> the producers, who engage in exchange to realize individual gains in the form <strong>of</strong> specific<br />

use-values. Often times, special social groups such as families or business partnerships<br />

can interfere with this relation necessary for commodity exchange. When we trade with our<br />

family members for example, we may not necessarily be trading based on the desire to fulfill<br />

individual needs or acting in our own interest. In such cases, our actions will not reflect the<br />

individualistic purposes that necessitate and accurately reflect commodity exchange.<br />

Next Message by PJM is [1540].<br />

[1314] Frankie: graded A Social relations and exchange. Producers must respect the<br />

property rights <strong>of</strong> others and value that right above all else, in order for the exchange <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities to exist. In [1996sp:282] there was an extreme example used that illustrates<br />

that for us. Gottlieb says “The needs <strong>of</strong> other individuals must take a back seat to the commodities’<br />

owners. The starving child in the slums must be allowed to become ill and die in<br />

order for the store owner to retain his right <strong>of</strong> ownership; even if he chooses to throw away<br />

the food the child needs so badly.” I believe that shows that property rights are extremely<br />

important in the ability to exchange commodities because something that someone will die<br />

without is not given away even if it is to be thrown away. Certain social relations exist that


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 15<br />

preclude exchange between individual members these are. Friends and family relations preclude<br />

exchange because you may want to sell at a reduced price or even give the commodity<br />

away, and this represents a problem in the exchange process.<br />

Next Message by Frankie is [1316].<br />

[1367] Agloeck: The social relations in a capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production are precisely<br />

defined. Individuals are subject to judicial law that enforces private property ownership<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodities they have, and trade their commodities under non-coercive conditions.<br />

Marx describes commodity owners in a capitalist society as “the characters who appear on<br />

the economic stage are merely personifications <strong>of</strong> economic relations, and it is the bearers <strong>of</strong><br />

these economic relations that they come into contact with each other” (pg. 178). Marx looks<br />

at the economic roles <strong>of</strong> individuals, not the individuals themselves because individuals can<br />

have multiple and contradictory roles.<br />

Commodity producers in capitalism need to be strangers when they are exchanging products<br />

because each individual is trying to maximize pr<strong>of</strong>it for himself in the exchange. This<br />

breaks down when individuals have familiar relationships prior to the exchange. For example,<br />

if I purchase a couch from my brother he is much more likely to sell it to me for less<br />

money than he would a stranger because I am family.<br />

Next Message by Agloeck is [1370].<br />

[1391] Roosty: Dad’s Car. In order for producers to be able to exchange their products as<br />

commodities, their social relations must be as strangers to one another. Because a producer


16 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

exchanges his/her commodity to achieve some sort <strong>of</strong> gain, whether it be in monetary pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

or in the use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity in which he receives in the exchange, the relationship<br />

<strong>of</strong> strangers is required to enable this personal gain. An example to illustrate this necessity <strong>of</strong><br />

selling to a stranger is demonstrated by a producer selling a commodity to family members.<br />

When my father was selling our family car, I managed to buy it from him for $600. At this<br />

price, my dad did not gain, rather lose on this transaction. Had my dad sold it to a stranger,<br />

his asking price would have been at least $2,500. This is an example that exhibits why the<br />

social relation between producers must be strangers in order to exchange their products as<br />

commodities.<br />

Next Message by Roosty is [1405].<br />

[1418] Novatore: For producers to buy and sell products, they must have an estranged<br />

social relationship. That is to say, groups such as kin groups are more likely to share products<br />

freely, but people that do not have close ties either through family or community have reason<br />

to exchange products for values they perceive as equal. For example, I work as a cook for<br />

a living; the food I make is a commodity which is exchanged for money. Though if I am at<br />

home cooking for my family, I am not going to charge them money for the food I made.<br />

Next Message by Novatore is [1419].<br />

[1425] Vini: The primary social relation that must exist between producers is the existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> personal property rights. These are fundamental for exchange because in order to buy or<br />

sell commodities the producer must first have ownership rights derived from producing the<br />

commodity. Social relations that preclude exchange between individual members would be


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 17<br />

members <strong>of</strong> the same family. For instance, a family member may feel inclined to give a<br />

commodity to a fellow members at no monetary cost versus the possibility <strong>of</strong> exchanging it<br />

with a stranger for money. Strangers try to get the better hand in exchange, not familiarity<br />

between family and friends.<br />

Next Message by Vini is [1427].<br />

Question 365 is 176 in 1995WI, 154 in 1995ut, 187 in 1996sp, 189 in 1996ut, 200 in<br />

1997WI, 207 in 1997sp, 199 in 1997ut, 208 in 1998WI, 228 in 2000fa, 241 in 2001fa, 273<br />

in 2003fa, 330 in 2008SP, 328 in 2008fa, 342 in 2009fa, and 349 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 365 In chapter Two, Marx depicts commodities as conscious beings which are<br />

eager to be exchanged, but do not care about the use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity they are exchanged<br />

for. Why are commodities, which are inanimate things, depicted here as beings with<br />

their own will which comes into conflict with the will <strong>of</strong> their owners, and why do they not<br />

care about the use-value <strong>of</strong> the other commodity?<br />

[451] AbeFroman: The Commodity Creature. In chapter two, Marx anthropomorphizes<br />

commodity-form <strong>of</strong> products in order to explore how societies (as opposed to individuals)<br />

use commodities to dictate the actions <strong>of</strong> individuals within the market. Marx describes this<br />

relationship in chapter one, section four:<br />

the commodity form <strong>of</strong> the products <strong>of</strong> labor, and the value relation in which<br />

it represents itself, have absolutely nothing to do with the physical nature


18 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> the products or with any relations they have as physical objects. It is the<br />

specific social relation <strong>of</strong> the people themselves which assumes for them .<br />

. . the form <strong>of</strong> a relation <strong>of</strong> things” (Marx, Hans annotations, pp. 180-181)<br />

So, when Marx acts as if commodities have a will <strong>of</strong> their own, he is looking at commodities,<br />

not as physical things, but as social objects. He is essentially creating a creature out <strong>of</strong><br />

the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity. This creature was created to chase money and<br />

has no interest the use-value <strong>of</strong> objects. It responds only to the value <strong>of</strong> other commodities,<br />

when this value is expressed through exchange.<br />

If one could remove the social bonds from the commodity producer (the market-process<br />

that turns useful objects into commodities), he should be able to treat the objects he and others<br />

create in a way that is based on their use-value. He would no longer be driven externally<br />

by the exchange-value others have placed on commodities.<br />

Message [451] referenced by [565]. Next Message by AbeFroman is [787].<br />

[565] Carol: The Disobedient Commodity. In Chapter Two, Marx personifies commodities<br />

by portraying them as agents disobedient to their owners. This illustration is used<br />

to clearly contrast the two goals the commodity producer pursues during the transaction.<br />

When the commodity producer takes his commodity to the marketplace, he has two objectives<br />

in mind. Driven by the personal dimension <strong>of</strong> the transaction, the commodity producer<br />

first would want to generate the use-value that best meets his needs at the time. Acting on<br />

the social dimension <strong>of</strong> the transaction, the commodity producer would like to realize his


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 19<br />

commodity’s value. The market is necessary for achieving this goal because what is important<br />

here is what the commodity will be exchanged for given the market/social relationships<br />

between the commodities in the exchange.<br />

In this sense, the owner can determine the use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity, but the market<br />

relationships <strong>of</strong> value and exchange <strong>of</strong> a commodity are social dimensions that are out <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity producer’s hand. Therefore, when commodities are being exchanged, they<br />

are not concerned about each other’s use values, but each other’s values created by abstract<br />

labor and time. The commodities themselves may have a “desire” to be exchanged because<br />

<strong>of</strong> the labor contained in them. This is why Marx depicts commodities as conscious beings<br />

that are agents independent <strong>of</strong> its owner.<br />

AbeFroman [451] notes that through the description, Marx is showing how the commodities<br />

are “created to chase money and has no interest the use-value <strong>of</strong> objects. It responds only<br />

to the value <strong>of</strong> other commodities, when this value is expressed through exchange.” I agree<br />

that the personified commodity has no interest in the use-value <strong>of</strong> other commodities; however,<br />

I think Marx at this point is not relating the exchange to monetary pr<strong>of</strong>it. Marx is<br />

demonstrating how in an exchange, the commodity itself performs in a society-wide relationship<br />

that decides if the commodity fits into the social division <strong>of</strong> labor. The exchange is<br />

representative <strong>of</strong> the socially necessary labor in the commodity.


20 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Your critique <strong>of</strong> AbeFroman is correct. They are not chasing money, which would imply that their owner<br />

wants more and more money. They are chasing other commodities, because they need pro<strong>of</strong> that the labor which<br />

they contain fits into the social division <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Next Message by Carol is [744].<br />

Question 375 is 178 in 1995WI, 156 in 1995ut, 189 in 1996sp, 202 in 1997WI, 201 in<br />

1997ut, 265 in 2002fa, 278 in 2003fa, and 337 in 2008SP:<br />

Question 375 Which contradictions do commodity owners face if they want to barter their<br />

products (as opposed to buying and selling them)? Make up imaginary dialogs on the market<br />

place in which these contradictions are expressed.<br />

[512] Skylerp: Commodity owners contradictions. Barterers are constantly facing the<br />

contradiction between the individual process and social process. In the individual process,<br />

owner A wants to exchange his commodity for another commodity that satisfy his use-value<br />

needs. Owner A does not care for the use-value owner B will receive from his commodity<br />

that he is exchanging. Owner A believes his commodidty is equal to all other commodities<br />

being traded. Marx calls this the General equivalent. There can be only one General<br />

equivalent in a market, but every owner believes their commodity is the one General equivalent.<br />

The big problem is Owner A wants credit for his commodity he is exchanging whether<br />

or not it provides use-value to owner B. This is the social process contradiciton. Without<br />

money being exchanged they can’t be exclusively individual and social. With only being<br />

able to barter one commodity for another, this would make it extremely difficult because


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 21<br />

each owner would have to produce a commodity that has equal value and use-value to that<br />

which commodity they will exchange for. Meat [1997WI:212] makes a good comparion<br />

with car production and watch production and the difficulty these two owners would have<br />

trading with one another. In today’s society it is much easier for us dealing with this contradiciton<br />

because <strong>of</strong> money. If we are looking to fulfill our use-value we can pay the full<br />

price or if we want to settle for something less that may not give us all the use-value we need<br />

we can just buy something cheaper or less valued. Just like buying school books for classes.<br />

It’s very easy to pay full price for the newest book edition for class, but its also very easy to<br />

buy an older edition for much less. The question you have to ask is: does the extra use-value<br />

you gain from the newer book edition benefit you more than buying the older edition and<br />

using the extra money left over for something else?<br />

Next Message by Skylerp is [652].<br />

[1300] JohnLennon: Commodity owners face many contradictions while using the barter<br />

system. For a barter system to work both parties engaged in trading commodities must have<br />

a need for the commodity in which they are trading for. Say one person has ten chicken and<br />

another person has ten coats. The owner <strong>of</strong> the chickens needs three coats for his family.<br />

The chicken owner may then propose to the coat maker “Six chickens for three coats?”.<br />

Depending on if the coat maker needs chickens or not he will agree or disagree. In the<br />

barter system there is no set price for chickens to coats (unless chickens became currency or<br />

money only, but that isn’t part <strong>of</strong> a true barter system). Bartering depends on the needs <strong>of</strong><br />

commodity owners or not at all. Perhaps the chicken owner gives a chicken to a relative for


22 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

nothing in return because he has an excess <strong>of</strong> chickens. This is an example <strong>of</strong> how a barter<br />

system could work if only one party needs a good and the other does not.<br />

Next Message by JohnLennon is [1301].<br />

[1373] Brie: There are two factors in the barter process; first, the individual process. In<br />

this process, individuals that make trades want to be sure that whatever they do barter for<br />

will provide an adequate use-value for themselves personally. The other aspect, the social<br />

process, reiterates that the individuals want to receive the same value in return which they<br />

are bartering with. The following situation properly demonstrates this principle.<br />

A home builder barters with a car dealership owner. In this barter, the home builder<br />

agrees to build a home for the car dealer in trade for a new Lamborghini. As the building<br />

process gets underway, the car dealer begins to ask for upgrades which were not originally<br />

agreed upon, and demands that any work be redone if it is not up to his satisfaction. At this<br />

point, the use-value <strong>of</strong> the Lamborghini becomes less to the builder than his skills and cost to<br />

create the product which the car dealer demands. The builder quickly realizes that he would<br />

have been better <strong>of</strong>f to pay cash (or the general equivalent) for the Lamborghini as the barter<br />

is now unequal and thus, there is a contradiction.<br />

Hans: Very interesting example!<br />

Next Message by Brie is [1386].<br />

[1413] Ula: Barter. In a barter situation, all parties enter the market with their own<br />

personal interests in mind, as well as the social interests <strong>of</strong> the marketplace. Just like all


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 23<br />

other owners, owner A enters the market with the goal to exchange his commodity (for<br />

which he has no use-value) with a commodity that fulfills his personal use-value. He is not<br />

interested in any other owner’s use-value. He is only interested in exchanging his commodity<br />

for a commodity that can fulfill his use-value. At the same time, he is focused on getting the<br />

most exchange-value for his commodity. This is the social aspect <strong>of</strong> the market. After all,<br />

the exchange <strong>of</strong> the commodity requires the social interaction that can only take place within<br />

the marketplace. So we see that in a barter situation, owner A must play both sides <strong>of</strong> the<br />

equation–the buyer and seller. He must buy what he needs (use-value) with his commodity<br />

that he wants to get the best value for (exchange-value).<br />

This is different from a sale because in a sale situation there is the existence <strong>of</strong> a general<br />

equivalent or money. The general equivalent allows the seller <strong>of</strong> a commodity to just focus<br />

on the exchange-value side <strong>of</strong> the equation. Also, it allows the buyer <strong>of</strong> a commodity to<br />

simply focus on the use-value side <strong>of</strong> the equation. Again, in the barter is a contradictory<br />

situation because owner A (and all other commodity owners) must be the buyer and the<br />

seller. What if owner B does not want to exchange with owner A?<br />

For instance, owner A brings his flip flops to the market to exchange for owner B’s corn.<br />

Unfortunately, owner B has no use for flip flops. owner B is in the market for other food<br />

items. Now what? Will owner A sell his flip flops at a discount to lure owner B into selling<br />

him the corn that he needs? Perhaps. Then, however, owner A is not getting the full value<br />

for his flip flops.


24 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Ula is [1416].<br />

[1438] Keeper: Commodity owners face contradictions when they are in a market place<br />

trying to barter their products instead <strong>of</strong> acting in a buying or selling position. These include<br />

the contradiction <strong>of</strong> full product value. By setting a barter they are limiting themselves to<br />

the market place by allowing a evaluation <strong>of</strong> their product to be disengaged with the market<br />

place and should remove their product altogether.<br />

::Q:719<br />

Self-interested capitalists will focus on treating their workers well because it is a incentive<br />

for the capitalists. If they can have a happy, productive, engaged workforce then the capitalist<br />

will be bale to extract as much value from the work force as possible. Adding benefits,<br />

perks, higher quality environments, only incentives the work force to preform better. Where<br />

the argument goes wrong is that the capitalist will do whatever means they have too to keep<br />

a work force happy. This is not true, the capitalist will only do as much as he can to still be<br />

as pr<strong>of</strong>itable as possible.<br />

::Q:377<br />

Marx is referring to the commodities owner equity stake or ownership displayed by the<br />

“deed” pf the commodity. Having this mind-frame that we own and must have a say in its<br />

use is a inappropriate mind set to have. This can be detrimental to the value that could be<br />

extracted form such a commodity.


::Q:596<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 25<br />

THe difference between value <strong>of</strong> labor power and value created by labor power can be<br />

determined by the labor force inputs. The value <strong>of</strong> labor can be a set or measured amount<br />

that is used to create, improve, or produce a good or service. The value created by a labor<br />

force is a investment <strong>of</strong> the labor force as a input to that good or service.<br />

Hans: In order to get credit for your answers to questions 719, 377, and 596, you have to submit them in 3 separate<br />

emails.<br />

First Message by Keeper is [479].<br />

Exam Question 377 is 180 in 1995WI, 191 in 1996sp, 204 in 1997WI, 211 in 1997sp, 203<br />

in 1997ut, 221 in 1999SP, 231 in 2000fa, 279 in 2003fa, 313 in 2004fa, 328 in 2007SP,<br />

338 in 2008SP, 352 in 2009fa, 381 in 2010fa, 363 in 2011fa, and 191 in Answer:<br />

Exam Question 377 Which “deed” is Marx referring to in the following passage: “In their<br />

dilemma our commodity-owners think like Faust: ‘In the beginning was the deed.’ They have<br />

therefore already acted before thinking.”<br />

[504] KapitalSB: (content A– form 95%) Mr. Deeds aka Money Mayweather. Like<br />

PLG said in [2010fa:808] “The deed is the selection <strong>of</strong> a specific commodity as general<br />

equivalent.” From reading 2.2 [The Deed] I would answer that the “deed” is the creation <strong>of</strong><br />

money. The definition <strong>of</strong> money is an generally accepted payment <strong>of</strong> medium <strong>of</strong> exchanges,<br />

such as good and silver. Society as a whole must accept it. For example one individual,


26 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Mr Mayweather, wants to buy flowers. He can either barter or use an medium <strong>of</strong> exchange<br />

(money) to acquire the good.<br />

Also, Neolib in [2003fa:253] used a great thing and I also feel it is important. “Marx<br />

states, ‘Through the agency <strong>of</strong> the social process it becomes the specific social function <strong>of</strong><br />

the excluded commodity to be the general equivalent. It thus becomes—money’ [180:3–<br />

181:1].”<br />

Hans: Marx differs from most modern mainstream economics in that he does not define money as medium <strong>of</strong><br />

circulation. His first function <strong>of</strong> money is measure <strong>of</strong> value, i.e., it gives the material for all commodities to have a<br />

value form, namely their price form.<br />

The phrase “an generally accepted payment <strong>of</strong> medium <strong>of</strong> exchanges” is malformed, and “Neolib ... used a<br />

great thing” is sloppy writing not appropriate for a course with which you meet the writing requirement.<br />

Next Message by KapitalSB is [656].<br />

[1184] Jason: graded A The Deed. The deed Marx is referring to is the social selection<br />

<strong>of</strong> a specific commodity as general equivalent.<br />

Next Message by Jason is [1187].<br />

[1288] Kannon: The deed is the creation <strong>of</strong> the general equivalent (and the money form).<br />

By acting as commodity producers, the act <strong>of</strong> creating a commodity (as opposed to a barter<br />

for example) necessitates a measure <strong>of</strong> value that is one-dimensional - and Marx shows this<br />

to be the general equivalent.<br />

Hans: It is not a creation but a selection or exclusion, because many commodities already act as equivalents before<br />

the deed. Now the role <strong>of</strong> “equivalent” is limited to just one commodity.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 27<br />

Next Message by Kannon is [1289].<br />

[1302] JohnLennon: The “deed” Marx is using here is to describe the thought process<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity owners. The commodity owners have “therefore already acted before<br />

thinking” when it comes to trading that commodity. The trading parties have already put a<br />

pre-determined value <strong>of</strong> the commodity they are trading for. The “deed” could be money or<br />

the equivalent or the commodity being traded. This can cause problems when determining<br />

price and what is “fair” between buyer and seller.<br />

Next Message by JohnLennon is [1303].<br />

[1349] DJB: The deed. The deed is the fact that workers think they are selling their labor<br />

but what they don’t realize is their labor power. The capitalists own the rights <strong>of</strong> production<br />

but the workers own the labor power and the workers don’t know how much power they<br />

actually have.<br />

Hans: A deed is something you do, not something you think.<br />

Next Message by DJB is [1351].<br />

[1366] Ula: The ”deed” The “deed” that Marx is referring to is when gold became the<br />

general equivalent–the one commodity that would become the measure <strong>of</strong> value and could<br />

be exchanged for all other commodities.<br />

Next Message by Ula is [1369].<br />

[1386] Brie: Marx’s referral <strong>of</strong> the “deed” pertains to the commodity owner and their<br />

thought process. The selection <strong>of</strong> a commodity as a general equivelant, or the agreement<br />

that all individuals use the same commodity to determine value is the deed.


28 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Such an agreement is not merely a thought process but indeed a “deed.”<br />

Next Message by Brie is [1389].<br />

[1435] MKW: The deed to which Marx is referring is the setting <strong>of</strong> price by the commodity<br />

owner.<br />

Hans: This is the first thing one has to do if one wants to sell a commodity, but it is not what Marx refers to with<br />

his Goethe quote.<br />

Next Message by MKW is [1436].<br />

[1445] Jess: graded B– Referenced “deed”. This “deed” Marx is referring to, is the<br />

process <strong>of</strong> handling loans. To a capitalist, a loan is both a blessing and a curse. It is a<br />

blessing, because it helps them to invest in their corporations, and allows for them to reap<br />

more pr<strong>of</strong>its. It is a curse, however, because they must pay this money back. This causes<br />

a decrease in the amount <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its a capitalist may accumulate. Loans can, and should be<br />

considered as the capitalist’s worst nightmare. They have acted (obtaining a loan) before<br />

thinking (understanding the loss <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its).<br />

Hans: Creative interpretation <strong>of</strong> a sentence whose context in Marx’s argument and whose previous answer you<br />

apparently don’t recall.<br />

Next Message by Jess is [1448].<br />

Question 378 Why can commodity owners relate their commodities to each other as commodities<br />

only if they relate them to each other as values? Also explain what it means to<br />

“relate their commodities to each other as commodities” and “relate their commodities to<br />

each other as values.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 29<br />

[478] Hans: The “Find your own Prince” Dating Agency. Commodities are the unity<br />

<strong>of</strong> value and use-value. If the linen weaver wants to give 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen for 1 coat because<br />

she needs a coat, she is trying to relate linen and coat with each other as commodities. Both<br />

value and use-value count. The role <strong>of</strong> the use-value is explicit (she knows exactly what<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> coat she wants), while the role <strong>of</strong> value is more implicit (the fact that she is able to<br />

afford a coat at the market exchange rate has to do with the values <strong>of</strong> linen and coat). Marx<br />

says that this transaction is only possible if she relates the commodities as values first, i.e.,<br />

the value aspect <strong>of</strong> the transaction must be made explicit and it is the first thing the weaver<br />

has to do. This is important. Although individuals are primarily interested in use-values,<br />

market realities force them to be interested in values. I said similar things in [144]. Using<br />

the metaphor <strong>of</strong> my message [476], the linen weaver needs the value relations as a dating<br />

agency in order to find the coat.<br />

Now you can stop reading. Only those interested in the gory details should continue,<br />

because this is my own developing thinking. It is different than what I wrote in [2010fa:149],<br />

where I treated the value relations not merely as a dating agency, but thought that at some<br />

level the weaver is actually interested in value. Right now I am trying to explain it on the<br />

premises that the linen weaver does not care about value, yet the market forces her to take<br />

value very seriously.<br />

A dating agency would go through all the tailors in their database to find someone who<br />

fits together with the weaver. The value form <strong>of</strong> the linen does it in a more elegant way. They


30 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

advertise themselves as the “find your own prince” dating agency. Like any dating agency,<br />

they send every subscriber a questionaire where the weaver for instance has to fill in how<br />

much <strong>of</strong> her linen she wants to trade for coats at the exchange rate <strong>of</strong> 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen per<br />

coat, and many other similar questions. So far nothing unusual.<br />

But what comes next is so unusual that the designers <strong>of</strong> this dating agency hope to be<br />

bought out by Google eventually. They select one <strong>of</strong> the commodities, say gold, as general<br />

equivalent. This is what Marx calls “the deed.” Then they use their proprietary computer<br />

program to distill from their database a price list with the market clearing exchange rates <strong>of</strong><br />

all commodities for gold. Then they send a copy <strong>of</strong> this price list to each subscriber, with a<br />

cover letter saying:<br />

“Produce as much as you want <strong>of</strong> the commodity you are specializing in,<br />

for instance linen or whatever you are producing, sell this commodity on<br />

the market at the price printed in our price list, and use the money to buy<br />

whatever you want at the prices in this price list. We guarantee that, as<br />

long as you adhere to our price list, you will be able to sell the amount<br />

you have chosen, and be able to buy whatever you want to buy, because<br />

our proprietory computer program has set the prices at exactly the market<br />

clearing levels.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 31<br />

This is a metaphor for what the value form <strong>of</strong> the linen does. In this metaphor, the “deed”<br />

is an easy, almost trivial step, because a centralized dating agency takes the place <strong>of</strong> the<br />

swarm behavior <strong>of</strong> all commodity traders. In reality, my [190] applies. Then the dating<br />

agency tells everyone to sell, i.e., treat their commodities as values, in order to be able to<br />

buy, i.e., to get hold <strong>of</strong> the use-values they want.<br />

Furthermore, this metaphor calls the computer program “proprietary” because Marx simply<br />

assumes at this point in Capital that market clearing prices coincide with values. How<br />

this is achieved is a different process, which Marx simply assumes to work, without going<br />

into the details how. He wanted to write an additional volume about “Competition” where<br />

this process is explored, but never did. See also [185] about this.<br />

Message [478] referenced by [476] and [1449]. Next Message by Hans is [735].<br />

[1129] Justin: Commodity owners can only relate their commodities to each other in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> value, or exchange value, because that is the form <strong>of</strong> the commodity that allows it<br />

to relate to others. Individuals are mainly interested in the use values <strong>of</strong> their commodities.<br />

Use value, however, only has meaning in terms <strong>of</strong> an individual commodity, and it means<br />

nothing to attempt to compare the use values <strong>of</strong> different commodities. Exchange value, on<br />

the other hand, is the exact property <strong>of</strong> the commodity that allows it to be compared to other<br />

commodities through their own exchange values. Without looking in terms <strong>of</strong> exchange<br />

value, it is impossible for the commodity owners to relate their commodities to each other.<br />

Hans: I corrected your second sentence in order to make your answer more coherent. This sentence was originally<br />

“If the commodities are related as commodities, this emphasizes the use value <strong>of</strong> each individual commodity.”


32 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Metaphorically, in order to get at the use-values <strong>of</strong> the other commodities, individual must pass through the<br />

value door, because the social relations between commodities go through the values only. I.e., when you write<br />

“compare,” it is not an individual looking at the commodities and comparing them with each other, but social<br />

processes, the competition between consumers and producers, compare the commodities, and the only possible<br />

socially valid basis for this comparison is the value, i.e., the abstract labor content, <strong>of</strong> these commodities.<br />

Next Message by Justin is [1130].<br />

[1200] RedRyder: Value — Third dimension. I happen to like sports a great deal, this<br />

passion <strong>of</strong> mine is most intense in regards to college football. For years I have passionately<br />

followed the sport even blogging about it in my free time and like many college football<br />

fans I have had to ask myself, how do I differentiate between the many teams who compete<br />

across the United States every season, and how can we crown one champion <strong>of</strong> them all.<br />

This is not meant to be a critique on the state <strong>of</strong> college football or the BCS but merely a<br />

metaphor. On my blog I regularly rank what I feel are the 25 best teams in the nation.<br />

Doing so presents me with several challenges, the chief most being how do I compare so<br />

many different ‘commodities’? I really am at a loss <strong>of</strong> how each team from USC to <strong>Utah</strong><br />

State and over to Alabama compare as far as commodities go without assigning some sort<br />

<strong>of</strong> value to each one. These values are dictated <strong>of</strong> course by my own feelings <strong>of</strong> what’s important<br />

to a team but nevertheless must fall in line with those values dictated by the invisible<br />

hand <strong>of</strong> sports, which tells us all what’s valuable in a team such as who did you beat, how<br />

tough was your schedule, how good did you look throughout the season, etc. Then and only<br />

then, after assigning out values to each team, can I even hope to compare so many teams


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 33<br />

who might not have even played each other, in such a way as to say who is more valuable<br />

than any other. These values allow me to take so many differing commodities and compare<br />

them against the market and see just what they exchange for. For this becomes the only way<br />

in which two seemingly disparate commodities can even be thought <strong>of</strong> as being related in<br />

any way.<br />

In the world <strong>of</strong> economics we see this very same thing, at flea markets around the world<br />

we see different sellers coming together trading various commodities in differing amounts<br />

on a daily basis. This is done thru assigning values, which is done invisibly by market<br />

forces, only then can efficient exchanges be made and disparate commodities be related.<br />

Without these values we are stuck trying to fit a square peg in a round hole, we cannot hope<br />

to compare any two commodities without bringing in a third dimension that adds depth to<br />

the market. That third dimension is value.<br />

Next Message by RedRyder is [1203].<br />

[1217] EricR: They can only relate commodities to each other as values because they are<br />

using a third commodity as the General Equivalent to determine the commodity’s value.<br />

Relating their commodities to each other as commodities: -Relating the use-value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity.<br />

Relate their commodities to each other as values: -Relating in the form as exchange-value<br />

in regards to the commodity.<br />

Hans: The General equivalent does not determine the value. Value is determined by labor content.


34 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Relating commodities to each other as commodities does not mean relating them to each other as use-values<br />

but at the unities <strong>of</strong> value and use-values, i.e., not forgetting their values.<br />

Next Message by EricR is [1218].<br />

[1224] Carol: In 180:3 – 181:1, Marx makes a distinction between the implicit and explicit<br />

attributes <strong>of</strong> a commodity and explains that the delineation between the two is made based<br />

on the instinct the commodity owners gained through their market activities. For example,<br />

a linen weaver might want to <strong>of</strong>fer 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen for a coat because winter is coming<br />

and she needs a coat to keep her warm. When the linen weaver goes to the market to make<br />

this transaction, she is relating the coat and the linens as commodities. The use-value is<br />

demonstrated explicitly here because she knows she wants a warm coat to protect her in the<br />

cold weather. But when the linen weaver is making the exchange on the market, the role <strong>of</strong><br />

value is guiding her implicitly. Giving 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen in exchange for a coat indicates that<br />

the exchange rate deals with the values <strong>of</strong> the linen and <strong>of</strong> the coat. According to Marx, the<br />

transaction is only possible if she sees the two commodities as values first explicitly. The<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> the market forces the commodity owners to relate their commodities to each other<br />

as commodities and see their values.<br />

Next Message by Carol is [1225].<br />

[1320] AJH: Relating values to values. Commodity owners can relate their commodities<br />

to one another as commodities only if they relate the commodity to another commodity as<br />

value because, when two commodities want to be compared to each other there is no way to<br />

do this without looking at the value and comparing the value <strong>of</strong> both commodities against


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 35<br />

one another. Relating commodity value to another commodity value can only happen if they<br />

compare the labor power used to produce the two commodities, and relating the commodities<br />

to their values is similar because the labor used to produce commodities give them value so<br />

you can compare the two commodities through value and the labor power used to produce<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Hans: Instead “there is no way to compare commodities without looking at value” it would have been better to say<br />

“there is no other social connection between commodities other than through their values” because they are both<br />

products <strong>of</strong> society’s limited pool <strong>of</strong> labor-power.<br />

Next Message by AJH is [1321].<br />

[1449] Jag: Commodity owners relate their commodities to each other as commodities<br />

when they want something in exchange for something else. If I want to exchange five baseballs<br />

for one basketball, then I am relating them to each other as commodities. Hans uses<br />

a similar analogy in [478] when explaining the exchange for 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen for one coat,<br />

they are being related as commodities. If I am the baseball maker, I want basketballs because<br />

I want to use them, I will get some sort <strong>of</strong> use-value out <strong>of</strong> them. Use-values play an important<br />

role in exchange because its how we determine what we want. I can only exchange<br />

baseballs for a basketball if I can afford to. If I only have three baseballs to exchange, then<br />

I can not afford a basketball because five baseballs = one basketball. Commodity owners<br />

relate commodities to each other as values and then once they determine the exchange will<br />

work according to values, they then relate them to each other as commodities.<br />

Next Message by Jag is [1452].


36 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1495] Chris: Commodity owners relate their commodities to each other as commodities<br />

only if they relate them to each other as values because otherwise there is no standard way<br />

to compare the commodities. Comparing commodities to each other as commodities does<br />

not give the owners a way to measure the value inherent in the commodity. A coat and three<br />

pounds <strong>of</strong> rice can not be compared to one another as just commodities. They have to be<br />

related to one another in terms <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> them. Then they can be properly related when<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> them is introduced because then an exchange could be made. Value allows a<br />

determination <strong>of</strong> how many pounds <strong>of</strong> rice is comparable to a coat when the amount <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

in them is compared. Relating a coat to three pounds <strong>of</strong> rice does not allow for an exchange<br />

or real measure <strong>of</strong> comparison to be made. Value must be introduced into the relation.<br />

Hans: Where you say “comparing commodities to each other as commodities,” Marx would say “comparing commodities<br />

to each other as use-values.” Use-values are important to the commodity owners but they cannot establish<br />

a social relation for the reasons you give.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [1496].<br />

Question 382 is 182 in 1995WI, 160 in 1995ut, 192 in 1996sp, 209 in 1997WI, 205 in<br />

1997ut, 214 in 1998WI, 233 in 2000fa, 312 in 2005fa, 343 in 2008SP, 343 in 2008fa, and<br />

368 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 382 Why is the occasional exchange <strong>of</strong> surplus products between tribes not an<br />

exchange <strong>of</strong> “commodities” but one <strong>of</strong> “products”?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 37<br />

[427] JEP: Purpose <strong>of</strong> Production. The reason that the occasional exchange <strong>of</strong> surplus<br />

products are referred to as an exchange <strong>of</strong> “products” rather than an exchange <strong>of</strong> “commodities”<br />

is because <strong>of</strong> the original purpose <strong>of</strong> production. The tribe had the intention <strong>of</strong> using<br />

the products for themselves throughout the production process, however, once the tribe’s<br />

needs had been satisfied they exchanged the excess products. A commodity, by definition,<br />

is anything produced for sale or exchange in the market. This purpose <strong>of</strong> use, rather than<br />

exchange, throughout the production process is the reason the tribe’s surplus products are<br />

referred to as products rather than commodities.<br />

Message [427] referenced by [513]. Next Message by JEP is [556].<br />

[513] It: Reply to JEP. i would agree completely with JEP [427] on the point that things<br />

that are made to be used and not to be exchanged, like when somebody grows their own<br />

private garden and uses the produce for themselves. This is not a commodity. It is a product,<br />

so if the owner <strong>of</strong> the garden exchanges some extra beets for his or her neighbor’s extra<br />

carrots. they are exchanging products and not commodities.<br />

Hans: Good contemporary example.<br />

Next Message by It is [559].<br />

[1271] Smalls: The occasional exchange <strong>of</strong> surplus products between tribes is not an<br />

exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities due to the initial intentions <strong>of</strong> the tribe. The tribe is not seeking<br />

to produce commodities for exchange, but rather to produce products which meet their own<br />

needs. Once their needs are met, tribes are willing to exchange any surplus with neighboring<br />

tribes. Often the products produced by the tribe are not exchanged beyond the tribe at all.


38 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

The intention <strong>of</strong> production is never to produce commodities for exchange. A commodity is<br />

always produced with the intent <strong>of</strong> exchanging it for other commodities.<br />

Next Message by Smalls is [1272].<br />

[1279] Shickadance: graded A A commodity is anything that is created with the intent<br />

<strong>of</strong> being exchanged on the market. Therefore, when a group creates something with no<br />

intention <strong>of</strong> using that particular creation other than to make it available to interested traders<br />

for barter or exchange, the good is traded as a commodity. However, when a group is satisfied<br />

by the commodities and there are “leftovers” which are not needed, these are exchanged as<br />

products. So when something is created for the specific use <strong>of</strong> the tribe who created it (the<br />

tribe has a specific use-value in mind for the creation during its construction) and then it<br />

is traded due to there being an unnecessary amount <strong>of</strong> surplus, this good is exchanged as a<br />

product rather than a commodity.<br />

Next Message by Shickadance is [1280].<br />

[1283] Littlerock: graded A Tribes Producing Commodities. A commodity is something<br />

that is produced not for the immediate consumption <strong>of</strong> the producer, but rather for<br />

exchange on the market. If something is produced for the intent <strong>of</strong> being consumed directly<br />

by the producer, then it is a product, not a commodity. Tribes produced for their own consumption,<br />

not originally for sale on the market. It is only happenstance that some <strong>of</strong> those<br />

products became surplus products and were available to be traded between tribes.<br />

Next Message by Littlerock is [1284].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 39<br />

[1376] Ruffian: An exchange within a tribe would be referred to as an exchange <strong>of</strong><br />

“products” and not an exchange <strong>of</strong> “commodities” because <strong>of</strong> the tribe’s original intended<br />

purpose <strong>of</strong> those goods. The tribe created those products only to satisfy the immediate<br />

needs <strong>of</strong> the tribe. If such a case were to arise where they had left over supplies due to<br />

overproduction and could never use said products they would then exchange the products to<br />

retain some use. Commodities by definition are created only with the intent to be traded or<br />

sold at market. However this is not the case when the produced items were strictly created<br />

for use within the tribe and not for trade. Having been created only to be consumed and not<br />

sold they cannot be considered commodities.<br />

Next Message by Ruffian is [1378].<br />

[1383] ZachS: graded B+ In order for surplus products to be exchanged as commodities<br />

they would have to be sold using money and then with that money the alternate commodity<br />

could be purchased (C-M-C). And since these are surplus products the value <strong>of</strong> the product<br />

has become less valuable.<br />

Hans: In an exchange <strong>of</strong> surplus-products between tribes, value (labor-time) is probably not very important. Value<br />

is therefore not diminished but it is not yet relevant.<br />

Next Message by ZachS is [1384].<br />

Exam Question 397 is 191 in 1995WI, 202 in 1996sp, 217 in 1997WI, 216 in 1997ut, 226<br />

in 1998WI, 236 in 1999SP, 280 in 2002fa, 294 in 2003fa, 331 in 2004fa, 346 in 2007SP,<br />

356 in 2008SP, 371 in 2009fa, 401 in 2010fa, and 383 in 2011fa:


40 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Exam Question 397 Marx writes: “The exchange process gives the commodity which it<br />

has designated as money not its value, but its specific form <strong>of</strong> value.” Which form <strong>of</strong> value<br />

does Marx mean here? Why does Marx call this form the specific form <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the money<br />

commodity? (Assume we are under the gold standard.)<br />

[1081] Shelly: graded A Specific Form <strong>of</strong> Value. The form <strong>of</strong> value Marx is referring to<br />

is form as the general equivalent. He calls it the “specific form <strong>of</strong> value” because gold is the<br />

commodity which everyone has agreed upon to be used as the general equivalent.<br />

Ula: Gold, like all other commodities in the market, has value because <strong>of</strong> the labor used to produce it. So, the<br />

exchange process does not give gold its value, value already exists because <strong>of</strong> the production process. It does,<br />

however, give gold a “specific form <strong>of</strong> value” because <strong>of</strong> its designation as the money commodity. It is the general<br />

equivalent, meaning all other commodities express their exchange-value in quantities <strong>of</strong> gold. It is universally<br />

agreed upon; it is the only commodity on the market with this “specific” designation. Every commodity can be<br />

exchanged for gold.<br />

Next Message by Shelly is [1085].<br />

[1088] Jag: The form <strong>of</strong> value. The form <strong>of</strong> value which Marx means here is money<br />

being used as the general equivalent. Assuming we are under the gold standard, Marx calls<br />

this the specific form <strong>of</strong> value because nothing else gets its value the same way that gold<br />

gets its value.<br />

Hans: Your statement “nothing else gets its value the same way that gold gets its value” is wrong. Marx would<br />

say: gold gets its value in exactly the same way as all other commodities, through labor necessary for its mining<br />

and refining. What makes gold special is not that it has value, but it is the form <strong>of</strong> value, namely, being General<br />

equivalent.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 41<br />

Next Message by Jag is [1449].<br />

[1127] Justin: With his statement Marx means the General Equivalent form <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Marx calls this the specific form <strong>of</strong> value because the money has its own value as a commodity<br />

before it becomes money, and it has presumably progressed through the simple and<br />

expanded forms <strong>of</strong> value already. So the specific form that it has now as money is the general<br />

equivalent form.<br />

Next Message by Justin is [1128].<br />

[1141] Shelly: graded A The General Equivalent. The form <strong>of</strong> value as the general<br />

equivalent. Marx calls this form the “specific form” because it is the commodity everyone<br />

had decided on as the general equivalent in which to represent value.<br />

Next Message by Shelly is [1210].<br />

[1150] Curtis: graded A– The money commodity. The exchange process gives the<br />

money commodity the general equivalent form <strong>of</strong> value, in which it can be related to the<br />

universe <strong>of</strong> commodities. This is the “specific” form <strong>of</strong> value for the money commodity because<br />

all further exchanges from the perspective <strong>of</strong> the money commodity are made treating<br />

the money commodity as the general equivalent form <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Hans: Assuming gold is the money commodity, then “general equivalent” is the specific value form <strong>of</strong> gold, because<br />

only gold is in this value form. All other commodities are in a different value, namely, the general relative<br />

value form which is also called the price form <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Curtis is [1156].


42 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1153] Diego: graded A– The exchange process designates money as the ‘general equivalent.’<br />

This is a specific form <strong>of</strong> value such that all commodities can have their value (including<br />

labor) represented in the money form, which is the price. This form is called the ‘form<br />

<strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the money commodity’ as it is a representation <strong>of</strong> the labor value inherent in all<br />

commodities.<br />

Next Message by Diego is [1154].<br />

[1192] EricR: Marx means the form <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the money commodity.<br />

Gold at this state was considered money commodity because it had two attributes.<br />

1.-It showed its basic value-form <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

2.-It goes through circulation-form <strong>of</strong> money<br />

These both make up gold as “Universal Money”<br />

Next Message by EricR is [1194].<br />

[1206] RedRyder: The exchange process gives money its specific form <strong>of</strong> value. This<br />

value is projected upon money by its universal acceptance as money. Thus, its value is<br />

derived almost entirely from its exchange. This is what Marx meant by specific form <strong>of</strong><br />

value.<br />

Hans: No, this is not what Marx meant. He had a reason for calling it “form <strong>of</strong> value” instead <strong>of</strong> “value.”<br />

Next Message by RedRyder is [1298].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 43<br />

[1226] Carol: Here Marx is talking about money as a value in itself because it represents<br />

the equivalent <strong>of</strong> the product.<br />

Next Message by Carol is [1227].<br />

[1317] AJH: Specific form <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the money commodity. Under the gold standard<br />

money represents the value <strong>of</strong> producing gold has and because the commodity is a representative<br />

<strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> gold, it is called the specific form <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the money commodity.<br />

Hans: In fact, money was either gold itself (gold coins) or it represented gold and the owner was entitled to have<br />

it exchanged for gold at a fixed rate if he or she wanted.<br />

Next Message by AJH is [1318].<br />

[1334] KapitalSB: graded B– The form value means here that without the exchange process<br />

value cannot be given money form.<br />

Hans: Marx does not talk here about ordinary commodities at all but only about the money commodity, and he<br />

distinguishes its value from its value form.<br />

Next Message by KapitalSB is [1335].<br />

[1473] Skylerp: Marx is speaking <strong>of</strong> the general equivalent when he refers to the specific<br />

form <strong>of</strong> value. He calls it the general equivalent because he is referring to gold as the standard<br />

use or form <strong>of</strong> value for the money commodity. Just like other productions, gold has to be<br />

mined and refined which creates value due to labor. This is why Marx calls it a specific form<br />

<strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Hans: “Form <strong>of</strong> value” for Marx is not one <strong>of</strong> the forms which a valuable thing can take, but it is a social relation,<br />

attached to the commodity as if it were a physical property <strong>of</strong> the commodity, in which the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

becomes visible and actionable. A better translation is “value form <strong>of</strong> the commodity.” Ordinary commodities


44 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

are in the “relative value form,” namely, their value becomes visible and actionable in their price, and the money<br />

commodity is in the “equivalent form,” its value becomes visible and actionable in its ability to purchase all other<br />

commodities.<br />

Next Message by Skylerp is [1474].<br />

[1494] Chris: Marx means money’s form <strong>of</strong> value is <strong>of</strong> exchange—gold. Money in the<br />

form <strong>of</strong> gold gives it the form <strong>of</strong> value. Money’s value is in the gold and the gold can be<br />

exchanged for other commodities.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [1495].<br />

[1502] Bear: graded C– This relates to the exchange value <strong>of</strong> gold etc. The gold itself may<br />

be used to make jewelry, conduct electricity, for use in chemical processes. These would be<br />

its use values, the “form” referred to here is the exchange value <strong>of</strong> gold. The weight <strong>of</strong> gold<br />

is translated into a monetary value as in 5 apples per 1/4 oz. <strong>of</strong> gold. The exchange rate<br />

is set not according to the use value <strong>of</strong> the gold but by what it can be traded for in specific<br />

amounts.<br />

Hans: Saying “the exchange rate <strong>of</strong> gold is set by what it can be traded for” amounts to saying “the exchange rate<br />

<strong>of</strong> gold is set by the exchange rate <strong>of</strong> gold.”<br />

Next Message by Bear is [1503].<br />

Question 413 is 234 in 1997sp, 226 in 1997ut, 236 in 1998WI, 291 in 2002fa, 305 in<br />

2003fa, 336 in 2005fa, 367 in 2008fa, 382 in 2009fa, 412 in 2010fa, and 398 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 413 Why this detour over gold, why not measure value directly by labor-time?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 45<br />

[566] JEP: Gold as Labor-time. According to Marx in 188:3, gold, or money, is the<br />

necessary form <strong>of</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> the immanent measure <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the commodities, namely<br />

labor-time. Marx states earlier in 188:3 that the commodities cannot be exchanged because<br />

they are <strong>of</strong>fered for the same amount <strong>of</strong> money, however the opposite is true. Money is a<br />

common representation <strong>of</strong> labor-time for commodities, ensuring that two commodities being<br />

<strong>of</strong>fered for the same amount <strong>of</strong> money have the same immanent value or equal amounts <strong>of</strong><br />

labor invested in them. Gold, or money, is a commodity used to provide an exterior measure<br />

that is driven by an internal force, labor-time.<br />

Hans: Your second sentence misreads what Marx says at the beginning <strong>of</strong> 188:3. “Commensurable” is not the<br />

same as “exchangeable.” Other than this, your submission reiterates that there is a detour but does not enlighten the<br />

reader why this detour is necessary.<br />

Next Message by JEP is [831].<br />

[787] AbeFroman: Why Not Measure Value Directly by Labor-Time? According to<br />

Marx, in a capitalist society, the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is equal to the amount <strong>of</strong> labor time<br />

that has been used in its production. However, Marx is not talking about concrete labor time<br />

(i.e., total man-hours), he is talking about abstract labor, the amount <strong>of</strong> socially-necessary<br />

labor embodied in the product.<br />

Marx describes this labor time as follows: “The labor-time socially necessary is that<br />

required to produce an article under the prevailing socially normal conditions <strong>of</strong> production<br />

and with the socially average degree <strong>of</strong> skill and intensity” (Hans Annotations, p. 57).


46 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Therefore, to Marx, the commodity has value because it represents some portion <strong>of</strong> society’s<br />

total pool <strong>of</strong> labor-power. Other factors besides how much <strong>of</strong> an individual’s time he<br />

has spent on production play a role in determining how much <strong>of</strong> this pool was created by<br />

the individual (e.g., labor intensity, technology, etc.). This is much more difficult to quantify<br />

than simply checking a time-card or watching somebody work. Instead value must be<br />

derived socially, through the exchange process.<br />

One can not directly measure value in the market by labor-time because the abstract<br />

labor time that makes-up a commodity’s value is only visible when compared with other<br />

commodities. Trying to measure value directly in labor would be putting the cart before the<br />

horse.<br />

Next Message by AbeFroman is [792].<br />

[1134] Snowball: graded A Gold and Labor. The question is, why gold? Why not labortime?<br />

The reason is that labor-time is subjective and removes the focus <strong>of</strong>f demand and onto<br />

the labor content <strong>of</strong> commodities. Producers would simply focus on producing products that<br />

would be considered rich in labor-time despite what the market demanded.<br />

For example, let’s suppose the creation <strong>of</strong> a marble sculpture takes significant labor time.<br />

A producer brings it to market and is paid handsomely in “labor money” which he is able<br />

to use to purchase other things he needs. Other producers will catch on, meaning less necessities<br />

will be available at the market while the market overflows with unneeded marble


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 47<br />

sculptures. This would drive people to a black market and create an incentive to only bring<br />

junk to market.<br />

Instead, we detour to gold, which has defined quantitative and qualitative work that is<br />

mutually agreed upon. Gold, then, becomes a standard <strong>of</strong> reference for value. It is the<br />

general equivalent, what Marx calls the “specific equivalent commodity.” This is why the<br />

detour to gold is essential.<br />

Next Message by Snowball is [1135].<br />

[1182] Rowlsroyce: A value would not be purely measured in labor-time because let’s<br />

say somebody takes a long time on purpose to complete a job, it would be an unjust value<br />

given to the commodity. By having the detour <strong>of</strong> gold, it gives the commodity somewhat a<br />

just value, it makes you want to make the item as efficiently as possible too make more gold.<br />

Next Message by Rowlsroyce is [1207].<br />

[1189] Neela: graded B “Since all commodities measure their exchange-values in gold, in<br />

the proportion, in which a given amount <strong>of</strong> gold and a given amount <strong>of</strong> commodity contain<br />

equal amounts <strong>of</strong> labor-time, gold becomes the measure <strong>of</strong> value.” (253-254, Annotations)<br />

Our society was built on the system described in this quote. We have structured our marketplaces<br />

to accommodate to this type <strong>of</strong> system. We use gold to provide commodities with a<br />

way in which they can express their values, and a way in which they can be equally comparable<br />

in relation to each other or on the same “scale”. Gold and money cannot represent<br />

labor-time, because the products <strong>of</strong> labor must take the form <strong>of</strong> commodities such as paper


48 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

money. In taking the form <strong>of</strong> commodities, they are distinguishing that they are commodity<br />

and that they are a money commodity as well. By distinguishing the differences <strong>of</strong> value<br />

and prices, the producers in a capitalist society can use them as determinants to adapt their<br />

production. This allows the producers to know what to produce. As Hans said in Fall 2010<br />

[2010fa:511] Hans: The reason why people don’t write the labor content on their prices is<br />

that prices must necessarily differ from labor content, in order to motivate the producers to<br />

adjust their production to demand.<br />

Hans: You seem to imply that the US is on the gold standard today, and you call paper money a “commodity.” This<br />

is wrong. Marx lived under a monetary system that was different than ours. Nevertheless, the basic principles he<br />

drew from his analysis are still valid today, even if the form it takes today is wrong.<br />

Next Message by Neela is [1250].<br />

[1196] Leont: Gold gives the means to have a universal accepted form <strong>of</strong> payment. Every<br />

commodity is produced with its respected labor-time but the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities between<br />

buyer and seller becomes complicated if the buyer doesn’t have an equal commodity<br />

to trade. Gold gives the means to set a value that can be agreed upon, then exchanged as<br />

money to increase the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities. Labor-time is also difficult to quantify if<br />

you are not familiar with its process <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Hans: According to Marx, the first function <strong>of</strong> money is not means <strong>of</strong> payment but measure <strong>of</strong> value. For you, the<br />

first function <strong>of</strong> money is means <strong>of</strong> payment, and the issue <strong>of</strong> measure <strong>of</strong> value seems irrelevant because you say<br />

that the value “can be agreed upon.”<br />

Next Message by Leont is [1197].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 49<br />

[1326] JEP: “Since all commodities measure their exchange-values in gold, in the proportion,<br />

in which a given amount <strong>of</strong> gold and a given amount <strong>of</strong> commodity contain equal<br />

amounts <strong>of</strong> labor-time, gold becomes the measure <strong>of</strong> value” (pg. 253-254). In our current<br />

marketplace, the first function <strong>of</strong> gold is to provide the world <strong>of</strong> commodities with a<br />

material for which the commodities can express their value with a common denomination,<br />

qualitatively equal and quantitatively comparable (pg. 254). Just as stated in the annotations<br />

we have created a marketplace in which we use money as a measure <strong>of</strong> value to compare<br />

commodities to one another. Due to this structure in the marketplace, gold cannot represent<br />

labor-time because the commodity produced through labor must take the form <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

such as paper money, in Marx’s time (today it represents credit). This helps to establish<br />

a difference in value and price, motivating producers in a capitalistic society to adjust their<br />

production towards the market demand.<br />

Next Message by JEP is [1328].<br />

[1340] TMM: Marx begins to take a detour over gold because gold (money) he believes<br />

that is the “general equivalent,” gold could be thought <strong>of</strong> as a form <strong>of</strong> money, or the moneyform<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. Gold or the general equivalent can be used to show a measure <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities from the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities <strong>of</strong> equal labor content. Marx believes that<br />

when two commodities are up for sale at the same amount <strong>of</strong> money, this is because they<br />

have the same amount <strong>of</strong> labor embodied these two particular commodities. This is because<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> labor value, commodities tend to become homogenous, the commodities can then<br />

be looked at by another form <strong>of</strong> measure to value the commodity, that being money. As a


50 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

side note, money in Marx’s time represented gold, however today money represents credit.<br />

Marx stated that labor embodied in the commodities is shown in the form <strong>of</strong> money or gold.<br />

As Hans says in [2010fa:518] and [2010fa:511], in a capitalist system, the differences<br />

between value and prices are necessary signals to the producers to adjust their production.<br />

So the detour over gold is needed because production is private. Chudak in [1998WI:212]<br />

explains this clearly by saying how Marx described the idea <strong>of</strong> “labor money” in a society<br />

founded on the production <strong>of</strong> commodities as “shallow utopianism.” Where we would have<br />

to be very naïve to think that we could all “just get along” where we measure values directly<br />

by labor time. Today the inevitable change and innovation in society would make it very difficult<br />

to measure values accurately. Marx believes that all commodities as values are simply<br />

“objectified human labor, and are therefore commensurable,” which means this allows their<br />

values to be measured in a standard commodity. The standard means <strong>of</strong> measurement would<br />

turn the commodity into the common measure <strong>of</strong> values, that common measure <strong>of</strong> values<br />

would be “money” (i.e. the general equivalent). In summary, essentially all commodities as<br />

values are objectified human labor. Objectified human labor can be measured by the same<br />

specific commodity, where if society choose money then (represented gold during Marx’s<br />

time) or if society chose money (where today it represents credit), they become the common<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> value and thus makes it easier to exchange these commodities with a common<br />

standard measure <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Next Message by TMM is [1341].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 51<br />

[1354] Glister: In a capitalist society Marx measures value by the amount <strong>of</strong> labor time<br />

invested in the commodity. Marx does not only talk about labor time he also talks about<br />

abstract labor which is the time embodied in the commodity. Abstract labor is very hard to<br />

measure, according to Marx “The labor-time socially necessary is that required to produce<br />

an article under the prevailing socially normal conditions <strong>of</strong> production and with the socially<br />

average degree <strong>of</strong> skill and intensity” using this method is very hard to account for all the<br />

time put into the commodity. The capitalist will put a price amount on the commodity and<br />

not relate it to labor so he can exploit his labor. That is why we use gold as a detour and not<br />

use labor time to measure value<br />

Message [1354] referenced by [1553]. Next Message by Glister is [1355].<br />

[1374] AR: graded C Why this detour over gold, why not measure value directly by<br />

labor-time? Measuring value directly by labor time would not accurately show what is<br />

put in the product. Hans tells us for simplicity reasons “gold is the money-commodity,<br />

money commodity became the measure <strong>of</strong> value.” The “measure <strong>of</strong> value” (gold) is the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> money that has equal amounts <strong>of</strong> labor value in the exchanged commodity. For<br />

Marx each must be “qualitatively equal and quantitatively comparable.” Labor time does not<br />

accurately measure value. According to Hans it is just the “driving force, generating the<br />

exterior measure, money.”<br />

Hans: Even if it were possible to accurately measure the labor-time in a product, exchange ratios cannot be exactly<br />

equal to labor-time. See [1998WI:227] why not.<br />

Next Message by AR is [1392].


52 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1463] AbeFroman: Why Not Measure Value Directly By Labor. Value cannot be<br />

directly measured in labor-time because the labor that creates value is socially-necessary<br />

abstract human labor. This is difficult, if not impossible, to measure without putting commodities<br />

in contrast with one another. It isn’t a simple analysis <strong>of</strong> how much work was done<br />

by an individual, but how much <strong>of</strong> the total labor pool was placed into the commodity. It is<br />

therefor an opportunity cost.<br />

Measuring the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity in gold also allows for a great deal <strong>of</strong> the exploitation<br />

that is inherent in capitalism to occur. It could be possible over time to closely estimate the<br />

abstract labor going into products and pay workers based on this, but that would change the<br />

relationship capitalists have with workers. For instance, it appears to workers as if they are<br />

selling labor to capitalists, but, in fact, they are selling their ability to do labor (labor-power).<br />

This is what allows capitalists to gain pr<strong>of</strong>it. A direct analysis by workers <strong>of</strong> this over time<br />

would make this relationship difficult to maintain and would most likely make capitalism<br />

unpalatable to most workers.<br />

Next Message by AbeFroman is [1464].<br />

[1553] Hans: The capitalist system confesses that it is exploiting the worker. Glister’s<br />

exam resubmission [1354] seems to define exploitation as the difference between what the<br />

worker is getting in capitalism and what he should get according to Marx’s way <strong>of</strong> measuring<br />

value. This is a misunderstanding <strong>of</strong> Marx, and I am sending my response to the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 53<br />

list because this misunderstanding is common, not only in this class but in today’s Marx<br />

reception generally.<br />

Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> capitalism is not trying to set up a parallel fairer system <strong>of</strong> measurement,<br />

but it is trying to understand the system <strong>of</strong> measurement the capitalist system itself uses.<br />

This theory has the result that by capitalism’s own standards, the worker is not getting an<br />

equivalent <strong>of</strong> the value he produces, but only the value <strong>of</strong> his labor-power. This is not the<br />

application <strong>of</strong> a parallel measuring system, but value is measured in exactly the same way<br />

the system itself measures value, by the same laws which underlie competitive marketcomes.<br />

There are good reasons to use the word “exploitation” or “unpaid labor” for the difference<br />

between the value created by the worker’s labor and the value <strong>of</strong> the worker’s labor-power.<br />

This exploitation can be defined within the capitalist system. Marx so-to-say is showing that<br />

capitalism confesses the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the worker. This exploitation is not even a violation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the laws <strong>of</strong> value guiding capitalist market interactions, but it is in full compliance with<br />

these laws.<br />

To say it again: if Marx’s theory is correct, then exploitation is an inherent feature <strong>of</strong><br />

the capitalist system itself. It can be defined inside the system, without recourse to some<br />

observer’s conception <strong>of</strong> value or fairness. The implication <strong>of</strong> this theory is therefore not<br />

that wages should be higher, but that the entire system must be abolished and replaced by<br />

a different system. Raising wages while maintaining capitalism is analogous to giving the<br />

slaves better food and more comfortable quarters while maintaining slavery.


54 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Hans is [1565].<br />

Exam Question 415 is 235 in 1997sp, 237 in 1998WI, 247 in 1999SP, 270 in 2001fa, 307<br />

in 2003fa, 344 in 2004fa, 338 in 2005fa, 359 in 2007SP, 369 in 2008fa, 414 in 2010fa,<br />

and 400 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 415 What is the price <strong>of</strong> a commodity? Say how it is defined, and say as<br />

much as you can about it without going into Marx’s theory how its magnitude is determined.<br />

[1061] Abysmal: (content B form 95%) The price <strong>of</strong> a commodity is essentially its<br />

exchange-value, given by its exchange proportions with the money commodity. Price is<br />

ultimately determined by the amount <strong>of</strong> abstract labor (value) congealed in a commodity,<br />

and is therefore determined by the socially necessary labor time it takes to produce a given<br />

commodity, in relation to the socially necessary labor time it takes to produce the money<br />

commodity.<br />

Hans: Your first sentence is an acceptable definition <strong>of</strong> price. Your second sentence does exactly what the question<br />

asked you not to do, namely, summarize Marx’s theory about the magnitude <strong>of</strong> prices. Is there anything else to say<br />

about prices than this? In [2004fa:436] I wrote:<br />

In Marx’s theory, both price and exchange-value are expressions <strong>of</strong> the value, i.e., <strong>of</strong> the labortime<br />

in the commodities. But one can say that the exchange-value is a diffuse expression, since<br />

the value is expressed in the use-values <strong>of</strong> arbitrary other commodities. The price is a much<br />

more focused expression, because every commodity expresses its value in the same equivalent.<br />

By this one equation, the value <strong>of</strong> these commodities is not only placed in relation with gold,<br />

but with all other commodities.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 55<br />

In order to get an A in the exam, you have to say at least one thing about the price other than how its magnitude is<br />

determined. This quote from 2004 is an example <strong>of</strong> what can be said about prices.<br />

Next Message by Abysmal is [1142].<br />

[1116] KATES: Price and exchange value <strong>of</strong> a commodity. The price <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

comes down to the exchange value <strong>of</strong> the commodity. The exchange value <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

is the commodity’s ability to be exchanged for another commodity and price is the ability<br />

for a commodity to be exchanged for money. Marx says “the value <strong>of</strong> these commodities is<br />

not only placed in relation with gold, but with all other commodities. Its price is its ability<br />

to be exchanged for another commodity.”<br />

Hans: The first sentence <strong>of</strong> what you present as a Marx quote is not Marx but my formulation in [2004fa:436], and<br />

the second sentence is probably not Marx either.<br />

Next Message by KATES is [1117].<br />

[1123] GMS: The price <strong>of</strong> a commodity. The price <strong>of</strong> a commodity is defined as the<br />

worth value <strong>of</strong> something in the terms <strong>of</strong> money. Money is a measurement <strong>of</strong> value that<br />

people put on a commodity. The price comes from the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that went into the<br />

commodity. Money is essential for everything that can be exchanged.<br />

Hans: Wrong definition <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Next Message by GMS is [1124].<br />

Question 418 is 309 in 2003fa, 347 in 2004fa, 362 in 2007SP, and 387 in 2009fa:<br />

Question 418 Compare the Price form with the Simple form <strong>of</strong> value.


56 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[596] SVN: Money. The simple form <strong>of</strong> value is the expression <strong>of</strong> one commodity in the<br />

form <strong>of</strong> another. It is represented by the equation x commodity A = y commodity B, or 20<br />

yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat. The simple form represents a barter system in which a commodity<br />

can be traded for an endless number <strong>of</strong> other commodities. The upside to this is that the<br />

possibilities for exchange seem endless. In this context, the equivalent form, linen could be<br />

exchanged for food, gold, c<strong>of</strong>fee etc. This can backfire if there are too many linen producers<br />

and the market becomes saturated with linen, thus reducing the need for linen and the<br />

ability to exchange linen for other goods that the linen producer needs. With time and place<br />

changing, the ability to exchange linen can fluctuate making it an unpredictable, exhaustive<br />

bartering process for exchange <strong>of</strong> goods.<br />

Hans: Do you mean commodity money can backfire because too much <strong>of</strong> thhe money commodity is produced? Or<br />

a general equivalent can backfire because it makes prices dependent on the global economy rather than on a local<br />

equilibrium? Please explain.<br />

Whereas with simple form the commodity can express its value in the form <strong>of</strong> a multitude<br />

<strong>of</strong> other commodities, the price form <strong>of</strong> a commodity can only be expressed in the form <strong>of</strong><br />

a single commodity, and that is money. Or as Kat [2010fa:815] says “Price is just one<br />

type <strong>of</strong> exchange-value. Exchange-value is the ability <strong>of</strong> a commodity to be exchanged for<br />

another commodity. So price represents the exchange <strong>of</strong> a commodity for money.” Price is<br />

the relative form <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> gold becoming the measurement <strong>of</strong> value through which all<br />

commodities can be exchanged.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 57<br />

The problem with the money form is that it conceals the labor that went into the commodity,<br />

and as Hans says p. 258 Annotations “In this sense, the value is ‘invisible’ to the<br />

surface agents.” Therefore prices can become incredibly high or low because all that has to<br />

be present is a price tag on the commodity and no gold present for the price form to have a<br />

real effect in driving market prices.<br />

Hans: Gold need not be present when prices are set, but Marx explains in chapter Three section 1 that actual gold<br />

and its labor content still play a role. You should look this up, it is an interesting story. Nowadays, monetary policy<br />

is necessary to keep the price level stable.<br />

Next Message by SVN is [865].<br />

[652] Skylerp: Price form/simple form <strong>of</strong> Value. The simple form <strong>of</strong> value is the value<br />

relaiton with one commodity to another. It’s one single equation. Exchanging one commodity<br />

for another. This simple form <strong>of</strong> value is “produced” as Marx says through society. It is<br />

society itself that creates the relation between one commodity to another commodity. Price<br />

form <strong>of</strong> a value is now the expanded form <strong>of</strong> value. It is expressing commodites under the<br />

same condition. Money can be used if accepted by society as a General equivalent. One<br />

form <strong>of</strong> value that all commodities can be exchanged for. Both forms <strong>of</strong> value show an<br />

interest in exchange. Money just adds another commodity to the simple form equation. In<br />

essence price form and simple form are very similar besides money being involved in the<br />

first. Also money allows society to not have to deal with producing equivalent commodities<br />

with one another.<br />

Hans: Wrong definition <strong>of</strong> Expanded form <strong>of</strong> value.


58 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

The main difference between Simple form and Money form is not given in your answer.<br />

Even if money “conceals the labor” as SVN says in [569], Marx still maintains that exchange ratios are determined<br />

by labor ratios.<br />

Next Message by Skylerp is [653].<br />

[697] Basil: The Evolving Forms <strong>of</strong> Value. The Price Form <strong>of</strong> Value and the Simple<br />

Form <strong>of</strong> Value are different, but related. As Marx explains in the first chapter <strong>of</strong> Capital,<br />

the expression <strong>of</strong> Value by the commodity progresses through different stages, or forms, <strong>of</strong><br />

Value. The Value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is initially expressed in the Simple Form through its interaction<br />

with just one other commodity. This expression took place through the relative form<br />

that each commodity shared, their Exchange-value. Beyond the Simple Form, we see the expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> Value in the Expanded Form through the commodity’s interaction with all other<br />

commodities. Furthermore, as market interactions progress, one commodity will evolve into<br />

the General Equivalent Form, which then expresses the Value <strong>of</strong> all commodities. And from<br />

the General Equivalent Form evolves the Money Form when one the General Equivalent<br />

Form becomes universally associated with a specific use-value. Marx uses the example <strong>of</strong><br />

gold as society’s General Equivalent, or Money Form <strong>of</strong> Value, and gold therefore becomes<br />

the measure <strong>of</strong> values for all commodities. But with a single commodity as a measure <strong>of</strong><br />

value, that in turn acts back on the relative form, or the exchange-value. With gold as the<br />

Money Form, the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> gold becomes its price.<br />

Whereas Marx’s previous analogy was to say 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat, a fitting adjustment<br />

would be to say that 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = $10 (or any arbitrary price), and that 1 coat =


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 59<br />

$10 (the same price). Therefore, the relationship that the linen or the coat has with money<br />

has become a socially valid expression <strong>of</strong> Value in the Simple Form—the Value <strong>of</strong> linen, or<br />

Value <strong>of</strong> coat, can be completely expressed through their relative value with money. This<br />

relative form, or Exchange-value, is the price. So, in comparing the Price Form <strong>of</strong> Value<br />

with the Simple Form <strong>of</strong> Value, we can say that in the Simple Form, Value is expressed<br />

relatively through Exchange-value. And for the Money Form, Value is expressed relatively<br />

through the Price. So, whereas the expression <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a single commodity in relation to<br />

money now looks like the Simple Form, the expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money with all other<br />

commodities looks like the Expanded Form. And for each expression <strong>of</strong> value, Price can be<br />

equated to the Exchange-value <strong>of</strong> commodities in relation to money as if expressed in the<br />

Simple Form.<br />

Next Message by Basil is [818].<br />

[1519] MKW: price form vs simple form. Simple form <strong>of</strong> value is the expression <strong>of</strong> one<br />

commodity in terms <strong>of</strong> another. An economy based on a barter system would employ the<br />

simple form <strong>of</strong> value. A price form <strong>of</strong> value is the expression <strong>of</strong> the commodity in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> a single commodity, in most societies the gold standard, which all other commodities<br />

can be expressed in a socially valid manner, eliminating the need to equate all the different<br />

commodities one to another. This is a great benefit to societies that employ the price value<br />

money and enables exchangeability and simplifies what could be a near inscrutably complicated<br />

barter system, eg. you instruct my <strong>of</strong>fspring in the knowledge <strong>of</strong> Marx and I will<br />

give you a mortgage. One can only imagine the social connections necessary in an economy


60 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

and society as complex as ours needed to acquire the simplest necessities <strong>of</strong> life if only the<br />

simple form <strong>of</strong> value was employed!<br />

Hans: This uniform expression <strong>of</strong> value in one commodity, gold, not only facilitates exchange but also gives<br />

producers and consumers information about what to produce and what to buy.<br />

Next Message by MKW is [1575].<br />

Question 423 is 407 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 423 Imagine you were studying Marxism together with a friend, and the friend<br />

said to you: Doesn’t the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value imply that people should write the labor<br />

content <strong>of</strong> their commodities on the price signs instead <strong>of</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> money? How would<br />

you answer your friend?<br />

[779] TMM: Friends and The LTV. If I were studying Marxism together with a friend<br />

and my friend believed that the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value implies that people should write the<br />

labor content <strong>of</strong> the commodity on their price tags or signs instead <strong>of</strong> the amount <strong>of</strong> money<br />

I would re-explain Marx’s theory to them. I would say that Marx formed the labor theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> value specifically to be able to explain the development <strong>of</strong> something (that being money)<br />

and why this developed in a society. Marx believes that on the surface <strong>of</strong> the economy,<br />

all commodities are measured by a one-dimensional measuring stick, that being money.<br />

The surface interactions can only then fit together with the relations <strong>of</strong> the producers in<br />

production if production is also governed by a one-dimensional guideline, which is abstract<br />

human labor. This is why Marx begins chapter 1 in Capital with the commodity; the analysis


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 61<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity leads us to value, where capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>it is value produced by worker from<br />

excess pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong>f their wages. A commodity is something that is produced for exchange or<br />

sale where it doesn’t require the existence <strong>of</strong> money, but Marx goes on to say that money<br />

will ultimately have to be developed in a society where many different commodities are<br />

produced. Marx explains that the use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity comes from two sources, that<br />

being not only labor but also nature. Value is what brings commodities to the market and<br />

value is ultimately created by laborl As Hans says, the labor inside the commodity is invisible<br />

and exchange allows labor to be introduced into social interactions. Hans says on page 259,<br />

“By their price tags, the commodities tell the world what they are worth (or at least what<br />

the owner thinks they are worth). This is not merely a theoretical musing but has practical<br />

implications: the price tag commits the owner to hand the commodity over to anyone who is<br />

willing to pay the market price.” Marx believes that there should be a system <strong>of</strong> exchange,<br />

and the gold does not have to necessarily be present, and in a capitalist society producers<br />

would want to exploit the excess <strong>of</strong> their own labor to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it, thus a price mark-up<br />

might be necessary to reflect what the producer thinks the good is worth and to make some<br />

capital gains <strong>of</strong> their labor. The labor theory <strong>of</strong> value simply explains how an economy<br />

system with money in it should orx will work<br />

Hans: The “should” in your last sentence is wrong. Marx’s theory is not normative, it is critical. You don’t have a<br />

specific targeted answer for your friend so you just dump the whole theory on the poor fellow.<br />

Next Message by TMM is [857].


62 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[789] RSL: If I were studying Marxism with a friend whom understood the labor theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> value and they asked if the theory implied that commodities should be labeled with labor<br />

content as opposed to price, I would disagree. Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value is specifically<br />

a theory determining the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity; it is not also determining price theory.<br />

Regardless <strong>of</strong> whether my friend and I are in agreeance <strong>of</strong> the accuracy <strong>of</strong> the labor theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> value, I would explain that this theory is stating that the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity can be<br />

related to the labor needed to produce or obtain a commodity. The theory is not extending<br />

itself to state what would also be the most accurate pricing mechanism.<br />

I would additionally point out that by putting a price tag on a commodity, the labor<br />

required for the commodity is kept anonymous. As Hans states, “In the negotiations between<br />

buyer and seller, only the properties <strong>of</strong> the product itself are discussed; the labor spent by<br />

the producer is treated as if it was a private affair <strong>of</strong> the producer (p. 258).” By remaining a<br />

private affair, the producer can determine a price that they believe the commodity is worth.<br />

If a tag <strong>of</strong> the actual labor were put on a commodity, the true value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is<br />

being stated, not the value that the commodity producer is willing to accept, as is done with<br />

a price mechanism.<br />

Hans: Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value does not say what value should be but what they are, i.e., Marx does believe<br />

that labor values guide actual prices.<br />

Next Message by RSL is [805].<br />

[799] Extraterrestrial: graded A– Price Tag Manipulation. If I was studying Marxism<br />

with a friend and they said that the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value requires the amount <strong>of</strong> labor to be


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 63<br />

put on a price tag <strong>of</strong> a certain commodity, I would first <strong>of</strong> all tell him that is not the case. DO<br />

in [2011fa:535] states that, “Though the labor theory implies the fact that the labor content<br />

<strong>of</strong> one’s commodity may determine the value <strong>of</strong> a given commodity, money is a much easier<br />

way <strong>of</strong> exchanging commodities.” I agree to a very small extent with DO but disagree for<br />

the most part. Money is not necessarily an easier way to exchange commodities. It is still<br />

difficult to value a commodity by putting a number on it.<br />

Another reason labor content is not put on the price tag is because, in capitalism, labor<br />

is exploited. If buyers knew how much labor was put into something, employers may start<br />

needing to pay their employees more. The whole idea here is that labor content itself is not<br />

written on the price tag but labor content should be included in the price. Often times the<br />

labor content is not included because that would force (in certain circumstances) a company<br />

to raise prices because labor content was included in the value. In other circumstances, if<br />

labor content was reflected in the price tag, prices would need to be dropped.<br />

After all this discussion it would be very interesting to have a world where labor content<br />

was actually put onto a price tag. It may be printed in the number <strong>of</strong> hours it took to produce<br />

that commodity or how many workers hands it passed through and how many hours<br />

each worker spent on it. The putting <strong>of</strong> labor value on a price tag is almost done in some<br />

cases. Some commodities or products have written on them, “homemade” or “handmade.”<br />

Handmade or homemade implies more labor time. “Made in China” or “Made in Singapore”<br />

reflects the fact that workers are exploited.


64 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Extraterrestrial is [912].<br />

[1407] GTIguy: There are many things wrong with the idea that a producer should write<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> their labor content on their commodities instead <strong>of</strong> the price. The greatest<br />

problem is the fact that it would devalue the producer’s labor. Why would a consumer<br />

willingly pay more for a product if they know that the labor input value is less than the<br />

sale value? The labor value <strong>of</strong> the producer is only a small portion <strong>of</strong> the overall price <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity. The greater, and arguably more important, portion <strong>of</strong> the price is the use<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the commodity to the consumer. Let’s suppose that a commodity is sold at a regular<br />

market value <strong>of</strong> $50 but only requires $10 <strong>of</strong> labor to produce. If the producer were to<br />

advertise that the labor value <strong>of</strong> the product on the price tag the consumer would see this and<br />

not be willing to pay the full asking price.<br />

Hans: If the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value does not hold, then there is <strong>of</strong> course no reason to label the commodities with<br />

their labor content.<br />

Next Message by GTIguy is [1411].<br />

[1417] Tiburon: I would tell my friend that he has a valid point because the value <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities represents the human labor used to produce the commodity. Nevertheless, this<br />

value is invisible to the economy because it is inside <strong>of</strong> the commodity. The guardian <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodities needs to use a price tag with money in it that would allow the buyer to know<br />

what the commodity is worth according to the seller.<br />

Hans: You had “inside <strong>of</strong> the economy,” I changed it into “inside <strong>of</strong> the commodity,” because I think this was a<br />

writing error. You are right that value (in Marx’s theory) is invisible and inside <strong>of</strong> the commodity. But Marx also


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 65<br />

says that the exchange relations on the market are signs pointing to these invisible values. I.e., these exchange<br />

relations do not indicate “what the commodity is worth according to the seller,” as you write, but they are, without<br />

buyer and seller necessarily being aware <strong>of</strong> it, expressions <strong>of</strong> this invisible value.<br />

Next Message by Tiburon is [1422].<br />

Question 435 is 430 in 2010fa and 417 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 435 Why is it not a defect but a sign that the price form is “admirably” adapted to<br />

commodity production, as the Moore-Aveling translation says, that prices can deviate from<br />

values due to demand and supply?<br />

[726] Reeree: Supply and Demand. Price form is admirably adapted to commodity<br />

production in that prices can deviate from values due to supply and demand. As we have<br />

learned, value is the congealed abstract labor that resides in a commodity that helps it to<br />

be exchanged in the market place, whereas price is expressed in the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> two<br />

commodities. Hans states in the annotation that “price is the exterior expression <strong>of</strong> the<br />

immanent value, and this exterior expression is open to other influences as well.” The other<br />

influence can take place by how many individuals will desire a certain commodity and if<br />

there is enough <strong>of</strong> it being produced to meet demand. The relationship <strong>of</strong> supply and demand<br />

will take effect, and price will be the determining factor over the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Hans: You are making a too big rift between value and price. In Marx’s theory, price is the expression <strong>of</strong> value, i.e.,<br />

prices are proportional to labor content. Some Marxists say that values are the “centers <strong>of</strong> gravitation” <strong>of</strong> prices, or<br />

prices “rotate around” value. I.e., there is always a discrepancy, but values are attractors <strong>of</strong> prices. There must be


66 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

this discrepancy because production is private and the deviations <strong>of</strong> prices from values motivate the producers to<br />

adjust supply to demand.<br />

Next Message by Reeree is [855].<br />

[1131] Pepe: graded A Prices can deviate from their actual values as demand grows or<br />

lessens, or likewise supply grows or lessens. Price form is adapted to commodity production<br />

because it responds accordingly to these factors. Increase in demand will drive prices up,<br />

and supply will be increased eventually to respond to demand, bringing the price factor back<br />

to what neo-classical economists would call equilibrium. This movement in price is not a<br />

defect, it is adaptable to market forces.<br />

Next Message by Pepe is [1132].<br />

[1216] Stig: The English word ‘admirable’ is synonymous with excellence; it is something<br />

<strong>of</strong> high value. But valuable for who?<br />

Marx states on p. 291 “Supply and demand regulate nothing but the temporary fluctuations<br />

<strong>of</strong> market prices. They will explain to you why the market price <strong>of</strong> a commodity rises<br />

above or sinks below its value, but they can never account for that value itself.” Marx notes<br />

that prices can be attached to almost anything, they therefore do not necessarily express the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the commodity but rather the prices facilitate a claim to its ownership or use.<br />

The variability <strong>of</strong> price due to supply and demand <strong>of</strong>ten means that the capitalist can gain<br />

even more from the sale <strong>of</strong> commodities than by exploiting the laborer alone. One example<br />

could be the purchasing <strong>of</strong> the last seat on an airline flight to Chicago from Salt Lake versus


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 67<br />

a ticket purchased several months in advance, the price is <strong>of</strong>ten two or three times more the<br />

price <strong>of</strong> purchasing a ticket with more advanced notice; yet the value <strong>of</strong> the two tickets is<br />

the same. This variability <strong>of</strong> price allows for more efficient selection <strong>of</strong> what commodities<br />

to produce. If the capitalist noticed that there was higher demand to fly to Chicago than he<br />

had supply <strong>of</strong> seats then he would add flights to Chicago. This is not reflected in value and<br />

therefore it is price which is ‘admirably’ suited to commodity production<br />

It is therefore not a defect <strong>of</strong> capitalism but shows one <strong>of</strong> its greatest strengths. And in<br />

my opinion this ability to adapt is one <strong>of</strong> the major reasons capitalism has survived so far.<br />

Next Message by Stig is [1296].<br />

[1243] KATES: There are a couple <strong>of</strong> reasons why prices deviate from values due to<br />

demand and supply. Price and value are not the same thing. Price interacts with commodities<br />

and supply and demand can be accommodated by price easier than by change in actual value.<br />

Depending on how much <strong>of</strong> a product is produced, supply and how much <strong>of</strong> a product<br />

is needed, demand these variables help to determine price. In [501] Hans discusses the<br />

impossibility <strong>of</strong> labor prices and asks us to imagine what would happen if people did write<br />

labor content on price sings. People do not disclose labor content on their price sings because<br />

prices differ from labor content and producers become motivated to adjust their production<br />

levels to meet the demand <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

Hans: Although prices cannot be identical to labor values, in Marx’s theory labor values are still the background<br />

influence determining prices. Your answer does not see this.<br />

Next Message by KATES is [1244].


68 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Exam Question 436 is 322 in 2003fa, 360 in 2004fa, 353 in 2005fa, 375 in 2007SP, 386<br />

in 2008fa, 431 in 2010fa, and 418 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 436 Which two aspects <strong>of</strong> the function <strong>of</strong> money as a measure <strong>of</strong> value first<br />

look like flaws but on a closer look turn out to be necessary?<br />

[1108] Gladwell: graded A+ Changing Prices and Gold Devaluation. The first flaw<br />

comes from the fact that prices do not always reflect the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity [2005fa:1376].<br />

Although value may be constant, prices can fluctuate depending on supply and demand.<br />

This, however, is necessary because it signals to the producers to supply more, or less.<br />

When price is greater than value, producers produce more. The opposite holds true, as well.<br />

The second flaw is that increases in technology causes gold (currency at that time) to<br />

decrease in value over time [2010fa:817]. As technology increases, more and more gold<br />

can be mined, decreasing the value <strong>of</strong> gold. This effect, however, allows prices to be more<br />

constant because technology as a whole, not just in gold, increases as well.<br />

Hans: Correct answer and good and clear explanations, but your cross references to not point to the most enlightening<br />

answers in the archives.<br />

Message [1108] referenced by [1198]. Next Message by Gladwell is [1201].<br />

[1136] Snowball: graded B– Necessary Flaws. The two aspects that appear to be flaws<br />

are the constant fluctuation <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money and the constant fluctuation <strong>of</strong> the price


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 69<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities. These flaws are necessary because they consider the lowering cost <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

For money, such as gold, this could mean more efficient mining. For commodities,<br />

it could mean technical advancement.<br />

Next Message by Snowball is [1137].<br />

[1138] Basil: Deceiving Aspects <strong>of</strong> the Function <strong>of</strong> Money. The two aspects <strong>of</strong> the<br />

function <strong>of</strong> money as a measure <strong>of</strong> value that appear flawed are variability in the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> gold, and the disparities or deviations in price from the actual value <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

These seem like they would undermine money as a measure <strong>of</strong> value, but they are actually<br />

necessary to adjust for changes in the production productivity <strong>of</strong> commodities as well as<br />

variable extraction productivity for gold. These price disparities tell producers how to adjust<br />

their production schedules to demand.<br />

Hans: The variability in the price <strong>of</strong> gold still has another advantage which you don’t mention here.<br />

Next Message by Basil is [1139].<br />

[1180] Neela: graded A The two aspects <strong>of</strong> the function <strong>of</strong> money as a measure <strong>of</strong> value<br />

that first look like flaws but on a closer look turn out to be necessary are the variability in the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> gold as money and the differences in commodities’ prices from their value.<br />

Next Message by Neela is [1181].<br />

[1198] Leont: The first flaw comes from the fact that prices do not always reflect the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Value may be constant, prices can fluctuate depending on supply<br />

and demand. This is necessary because it signals to the producers to supply more, or less.<br />

When price is greater than value, producers produce more.


70 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

The second flaw is that increases in technology causes gold to decrease in value over<br />

time. As technology increases, more and more gold can be mined, decreasing the value <strong>of</strong><br />

gold. Gladwell [1108]<br />

Hans: Is there a good side to this second flaw?<br />

Next Message by Leont is [1199].<br />

[1204] Gladwell: graded A The first aspect <strong>of</strong> the function <strong>of</strong> money is that, at the time,<br />

gold was used for money and increases in technology allowed for the mining <strong>of</strong> gold to<br />

increase, devaluing the currency. This was necessary, however, because increases in technology<br />

is widespread so that the devaluation actually makes it more stable.<br />

The second aspect is that supply and demand make prices fluctuate. This is necessary,<br />

however, because prices signal to producers to produce more or less. If the price is greater<br />

than the labor value, producers will produce more. If it is less, producers will produce less.<br />

Next Message by Gladwell is [1205].<br />

[1207] Rowlsroyce: 1. Money or cash is more valuable than having capital or a commodity.<br />

It gives you more freedom, or can give you more use-value, so you can decide what to<br />

with it.<br />

2. Money’s exchange-value can vary depending on surplus. If there is too much circulating,<br />

or in production it can lose value. But at the same time it can be a strength on the<br />

opposite spectrum and be <strong>of</strong> more value.<br />

Next Message by Rowlsroyce is [1208].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 71<br />

[1230] AndyUte: graded C Firstly, one aspect <strong>of</strong> the function <strong>of</strong> money that initially looks<br />

like a flaw is the fact that money is the measure <strong>of</strong> value rather than labor. Secondly, another<br />

necessary aspect that seems like a flaw is the fact that the general form <strong>of</strong> circulation, or the<br />

general equivalence was gold.<br />

Next Message by AndyUte is [1231].<br />

[1277] Bimmer: graded D The two aspects <strong>of</strong> the function <strong>of</strong> money as a measure <strong>of</strong><br />

value that look like flaws, are the store <strong>of</strong> value and the measure <strong>of</strong> value. One aspect if for<br />

example in today’s world we use paper and coins to buy and sell goods and services. Yet, if<br />

I find a gold coin, since that gold coin is still viewed as money since money is anything that<br />

is valued by (gold, silver, etc) what a person wants. That gold coin that I found regardless<br />

<strong>of</strong> how old it is, will still be able to be used to buy and sell. As long as the item I have is<br />

determined to have value, no matter what, it will be accepted. The second aspect, is measure<br />

that value, today we measure value based upon the value denominated on currency. If I use<br />

the gold coin, it can be weighted to determine a value in today’s world and it will ultimately<br />

be able to be used.<br />

Hans: “Store <strong>of</strong> value” and “measure <strong>of</strong> value” are not the two aspects that look like flaws.<br />

At Marx’s time, an antique gold coin could indeed have been used as money: its owner could have, if he would<br />

have been stupid enough to do so, taken it to the mint where it would have been melted down and converted into<br />

British pound coins called “guineas.” But this would have been a stupid move; almost certainly the value would<br />

have been higher had the owner sold this antique gold coin as an antique.


72 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Today we are no longer on the gold standard. The value <strong>of</strong> the dollar is no longer tied to the value <strong>of</strong> gold, and<br />

it is no longer possible to take gold to the mint and have it directly converted into money. Today you have to sell<br />

gold like any other precious metal in order to convert it into money, i.e., gold is a commodity, it is not money.<br />

If you are in the US and find an antique gold dollar, you could use it to buy and sell, but this is because these<br />

gold coins were never invalidated, it is not because gold is money now. You can even buy newly minted gold coins<br />

from the US mint as collectors items, but you have to pay far more than their nominal value for this, and only a fool<br />

would use them as money.<br />

Thirdly, the theory <strong>of</strong> money and commodities formulated here has nothing to do with Marx.<br />

Next Message by Bimmer is [1278].<br />

[1292] JEP: Two aspects <strong>of</strong> the function <strong>of</strong> money as a measure <strong>of</strong> value that at first look<br />

like flaws but on a closer look turn out to be necessary are the variation in value <strong>of</strong> gold as<br />

money and the difference between the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity and its price.<br />

Hans: You had “the differentiation in the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity and its price,” which means something different,<br />

namely that both value and price take up a whole range <strong>of</strong> values instead <strong>of</strong> only one.<br />

Next Message by JEP is [1293].<br />

[1342] TMM: The aspects are that money must be necessary and has two conditions in<br />

the market such as everyone (meaning all producers) must be strangers to one another. Marx<br />

points out that gold can be referred to as the “general equivalent.” The general equivalent<br />

being universally accepted as money where in this case gold could be seen as the general<br />

equivalent as a measure <strong>of</strong> value. The flawed outlook that turns out to be necessary is how<br />

specie money must and should exist in a market. Money comes embodied with three main<br />

functions by Marx, a measure <strong>of</strong> value, a means <strong>of</strong> circulations as well as the function <strong>of</strong>


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 73<br />

money. It seems that it is necessary to have circulation in conjunction with money, however<br />

once it hits circulation money it becomes valued less and less with more circulation that is<br />

undertaken.<br />

Next Message by TMM is [1343].<br />

[1356] Glister: Money, like gold will fluctuate in value over a period <strong>of</strong> time making it<br />

necessary. Money is a way to put a price on a commodity and not its labor time.<br />

Next Message by Glister is [1357].<br />

[1360] Nunu: Two necessary flaws in the functions <strong>of</strong> money. One flaw is that the<br />

price <strong>of</strong> the commodity does not always reflect its true value. There are outside forces which<br />

influence fluctuations in price. This ‘flaw’ however is necessary because it indicated to the<br />

producer to increase or decrease production. An increase in the price <strong>of</strong> a commodity would<br />

likely be followed by an increase in production <strong>of</strong> that commodity and vice versa. The second<br />

apparent flaw, at the time <strong>of</strong> the gold standard, is that technological advancement would<br />

increase the supply <strong>of</strong> gold which in turn would decrease its value. However, technological<br />

advancements are not limited to gold production. Technology usually advances across the<br />

board, or at lesast in many more areas than gold alone.<br />

Hans: Technical innovation decreases the value <strong>of</strong> gold because less labor is needed to produce gold. This usually<br />

leads to increases in supply <strong>of</strong> gold, but the increases in supply follow from the fall in value, they are not the reason<br />

for the fall in value.<br />

Next Message by Nunu is [1361].


74 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1404] AR: content D form 90% Which two aspects <strong>of</strong> the funtion <strong>of</strong> money as a measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> value first look like flaws but on a closer look turn out to be necessary? Two<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> the function <strong>of</strong> money as a measure <strong>of</strong> value that look like flaws but on a closer<br />

look turn out to be necessary are; first, prices that can change or money as a measure <strong>of</strong> value<br />

and second, as technology increase the value <strong>of</strong> money will also decrease. First, the price is<br />

the “form <strong>of</strong> its values” and can change. Price is just the “exterior expression” according to<br />

Marx. This change can look like a flaw but is necessary for private commodity production to<br />

satisfy high consumer demand. Marx is stated by Hans saying that “the discrepancy between<br />

value and price is not a defect but a necessity for private commodity production.” Second,<br />

as efficiency improves due to improvements in technology. One’s own personal labor value<br />

can decline looking like a flaw but production improves and hopefully making more jobs. A<br />

good example <strong>of</strong> this is the dot com boom.<br />

Hans: You are not allowed to rewrite the designated exam question. YOur grade is for the in-class answer.<br />

Next Message by AR is [1406].<br />

[1465] AbeFroman: Flaws with Money as a Measure <strong>of</strong> Value. Gold production can<br />

be affected by increases in productivity and gold will therefore become less valuable over<br />

time. However, this is true <strong>of</strong> other commodities as well and therefore helps to balance the<br />

market.<br />

Hans: It helps keeps prices stable (not by balancing the market). “Balancing the market has to do with the second<br />

“flaw” which you are not mentioning.<br />

Next Message by AbeFroman is [1466].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 75<br />

Question 445 is 389 in 2007fa, 394 in 2008SP, 410 in 2009fa, and 427 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 445 Which “contradictory and mutually exclusive relationships” 198:2 are, according<br />

to Marx’s analysis, contained in the process <strong>of</strong> exchanging commodities?<br />

[825] Skylerp: Process <strong>of</strong> Exchanging Commodities. In the process <strong>of</strong> exchanging, each<br />

barter faces a contradictory and mutually exclusive relationship. When looking to exchange<br />

one commodity for another each barter transaction wants to get the value they think their<br />

commodity holds as well as exchanging it for another commodity that will provide their<br />

desired use-value. In the same idea the barter wants to get “X” amount <strong>of</strong> value for his<br />

commodity and also receive a different commodity for a “great deal.” If every barter thinks<br />

this way, it makes it very difficult for exchanges to even occur. If the transaction is separated<br />

into two parts, sale and purchase then the contradiciton is transformed and exchanges can<br />

occur more <strong>of</strong>ten. This is also possible when money is brought into the equation. Mhurst<br />

[2009fa:607] explains very well the mutually exclusive relationship between buyer and seller<br />

views <strong>of</strong> their commodities. Marx compares this relationship with an analogy <strong>of</strong> elliptical<br />

orbit. In the analogy he explains that material body is constantly falling towards one another,<br />

but at the same time constantly flying away from it. It is the same way a seller views his/her<br />

commodity as a value and the commodity they are looking to exchange for as a use-value,<br />

but never as both.<br />

Hans: Your sentence “the barter wants to get ‘X’ amount <strong>of</strong> value for his commodity and also receive a different<br />

commodity for a ‘great deal’” addresses the value dimension twice and leaves out the use-value dimension. The


76 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

party in the barter wants a great deal and at the same time this “great deal” expressed in the use-value <strong>of</strong> his or her<br />

choice.<br />

Before deciding whether Mhurst [2009fa:607] is worth quoting approvingly, you should have looked at my<br />

response [2009fa:623].<br />

Your writing is not up to the standards <strong>of</strong> a writing requirements class. When you write “each barter transaction”<br />

you seem to really mean “each individual participating in a barter transaction.” Also the sentence “he explains that<br />

material body is constantly falling towards one another” needs some corrective surgery. There were also typos in<br />

your original submission which I corrected for the archives.<br />

Next Message by Skylerp is [947].<br />

[834] AR: graded C Marx gives a metaphor explaining the contradictory and mutually exclusive<br />

relationships contained in exchanging commodities. This metaphor is <strong>of</strong> an elliptical<br />

orbit that allows contradictions between gravity and inertia. He uses this to represent the<br />

process <strong>of</strong> exchanging commodities and how they contain contradictory and mutually exclusive<br />

relationships. Direct barter is one relationship <strong>of</strong> contradiction which is the separation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world <strong>of</strong> commodities into ordinary commodities and money that allows the barter to<br />

split the sale and purchase. Marx does not believe that “real” contradictions disappear, in<br />

fact it is practically impossible to entirely resolve contradictions. They just seem to manifest<br />

themselves in different forms for contradictions. Going back to the elliptical orbit metaphor<br />

tells us “the contradiction that a material body constantly falls toward another but at the same<br />

time constantly flies away from it.” This is saying that as a contradiction in the process <strong>of</strong><br />

exchanging commodities is never completely resolved; just as it seems to be fixed another<br />

contradiction arises.


Hans: You didn’t answer the question.<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 77<br />

Next Message by AR is [957].<br />

[848] Novatore: Marx in the beginning <strong>of</strong> chapter two tells us how this contradictory and<br />

mutually exclusive relationship <strong>of</strong> exchange exists. “All commodities are non-use values for<br />

their owners and use values for their non-owners.” A person needs their commodity to be<br />

realized as value in order to exchange it, but in order to find value in something that is a nonuse<br />

value they also need to be a non-owner <strong>of</strong> a use-value. To further elaborate, an owner<br />

must have their commodity socially validated in order for other commodities to satisfy their<br />

individual wants. Or to use Marx’s metaphor; much like in an elliptical orbit exists because<br />

<strong>of</strong> a moving towards and away from an object, an exchange exists because a commodity is<br />

both a use-value socially and a value individually.<br />

Hans: The value relation is the social relation, not the use-value relation.<br />

Next Message by Novatore is [1260].<br />

[1441] Jess: graded B+ Contradictory and mutually exclusive relationships. In Marx’s<br />

analysis, the contradictory and mutually exclusive relationships that are contained in the<br />

process <strong>of</strong> exchanging commodities, is found in an item’s use-value and its exchange value.<br />

An item’s use value is expressed through its exchange value, which means it can get skewed<br />

very easily. For example, the commodity <strong>of</strong> lumber should hypothetically have a high use<br />

value because it can be used for a variety <strong>of</strong> things. However, it does not require vast amounts<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor to extract, which is why it is exchanged at such a low cost. On the opposite end<br />

<strong>of</strong> the spectrum, one can find the commodity <strong>of</strong> diamonds. Diamonds are beautiful to look


78 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

at, but they don’t really have much use outside <strong>of</strong> jewelry and adornments. If one were<br />

to base an exchange value on commodities purely on an item’s use value, lumber would<br />

hypothetically cost more than diamonds. However, we know this is not the case, and that<br />

is because diamonds require way more labor to extract. This increase in labor requirements<br />

increases a diamond’s worth, which helps explain the difference in selling power.<br />

Hans: This is not the contradiction in the exchange process but the contradiction between real wealth and monetary<br />

wealth.<br />

Message [1441] referenced by [1448]. Next Message by Jess is [1442].<br />

Question 449 is 363 in 2005fa, 385 in 2007SP, 397 in 2008fa, 412 in 2009fa, 443 in<br />

2010fa, 431 in 2011fa, and 363 in Answer:<br />

Question 449 What does Marx mean when he says in 198:3/o: one must look at the circulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities from its form side?<br />

[802] SLOVENEC: What Marx means in his statement about the importance <strong>of</strong> looking<br />

at the form side behind the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities is that although the an exchange <strong>of</strong><br />

an item looks simple on the surface, it is in fact a process <strong>of</strong> a commodity molding itself into<br />

different forms that fulfill the need <strong>of</strong> the producer and consumer. As Marx puts it, “In so far<br />

the process <strong>of</strong> exchange transfers commodities from hands in which they are non-use-values<br />

to hands in which they are use-values, it is a process <strong>of</strong> social metabolism.” The commodity<br />

is important to the producer because <strong>of</strong> both its value and the fact that to him, it has no<br />

desired use-value, so he finds a buyer searching for that use-value and engages them into an


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 79<br />

exchange. Once the commodity passes into the buyer’s hands, it changes from having value<br />

and non-use-value and will now become one <strong>of</strong> its other forms as a needed use-value to<br />

the individual who bought it for consumption. Therefore, when envisioning the circulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities, imagine a tube where there are three holes through which the commodity<br />

must pass through. Each hole has its own shape and meaning (i.e. square stands for value,<br />

circle stands for non-use-value, and star stands for use-value). The commodity is like a ball<br />

<strong>of</strong> putty that is pushed through each hole, taking on different shapes throughout the process,<br />

but never changing what it is. Such is the process <strong>of</strong> commodity circulation. Commodities<br />

take on different forms when they are in the hands <strong>of</strong> their producers and consumers.<br />

Hans: You misunderstand the form change. Look again at Marx’s text!<br />

Next Message by SLOVENEC is [884].<br />

[817] Alee: By the statement “one must look at the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities from its<br />

form side” Marx meant that in order to understand how the process <strong>of</strong> individual selling and<br />

buying (transferring products from producer to consumer) works the whole process must<br />

be looked at from the form side. The need to only look at the form change. Which means<br />

that we are not looking at use-values but only at the values. The view <strong>of</strong> “from the form<br />

side” is instead <strong>of</strong> having the idea <strong>of</strong> a process to first sell and then buy something to have<br />

the view <strong>of</strong> “from the form side” which is a process involving three different forms <strong>of</strong> the<br />

same commodity. First use-value for others, then value unencumbered by any use-value,<br />

then third use-value for its owner.


80 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Your own description <strong>of</strong> the form changes shows that the characterization “we are not looking at use-values<br />

but only at the values” is wrong. You should have consulted [Answer:18].<br />

Message [817] referenced by [833]. Next Message by Alee is [1028].<br />

[831] JEP: Metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> Value. To look at circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities from its<br />

form side is the examining <strong>of</strong> the transformation <strong>of</strong> a commodity’s underlying value as it is<br />

produced and exchanged in the market. The specific commodity goes through a metamorphosis,<br />

form change, <strong>of</strong> value as it moves through circulation, starting with a use-value <strong>of</strong><br />

the producer for which he or she doesn’t need. This lack <strong>of</strong> necessity for the use-value <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity by the producer instigates a metamorphosis to the form value <strong>of</strong> money, or in<br />

Marx’s time gold, and the producer then exchanges the commodity for money. The producer<br />

who had recently exchanged the commodity then takes the money and exchanges it for a<br />

different commodity that is <strong>of</strong> necessity and has a use-value. Throughout circulation the<br />

original producer holds the value <strong>of</strong> the original commodity, the value just takes on different<br />

forms.<br />

This three-phase metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> value is highlighted by a great example by Hans<br />

[2010fa:528]. Hans describes the three stages <strong>of</strong> a butterfly, something many <strong>of</strong> us learn<br />

as young children, to show how something can take different forms, yet be the same creature<br />

(value in our case). In the butterfly example we can physically see the different forms the<br />

butterfly takes on throughout its life, providing a concrete example to learn from. Although<br />

the value form <strong>of</strong> a commodity may not be as clear as the life cycle <strong>of</strong> a butterfly, the concept


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 81<br />

is the same, value can take different forms throughout circulation but remain the same as the<br />

original value.<br />

Next Message by JEP is [967].<br />

[833] AR: This is a response to [817]. Marx states that one must look at circulation<br />

from its form side saying that the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities has different use-values for<br />

different people in the circulation <strong>of</strong> the commodities process. Alee [817] does give some<br />

good reasons why circulation needs to looked at from the form side but lacks an in-depth<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> the circulation itself.<br />

Marx talks <strong>of</strong> “social metabolism <strong>of</strong> use-values” which explains how products through<br />

the division <strong>of</strong> labor change hands after they are produced. “People do not consume their<br />

own products but the products <strong>of</strong> others.” Form comes into play when the exchanges <strong>of</strong> these<br />

use-values are processed. This all takes place in the activities in the market. “Commodity<br />

forms are socially induced properties <strong>of</strong> the commodities.” Marx states that the circulation<br />

changes these properties. He uses an example <strong>of</strong> the linen weaver and how the commodity<br />

in hand is a use-value to others but not the producer. This is more or less how form and<br />

circulation connect; “first use-value for others, then value unencumbered by any use-value,<br />

then use-value for its owner.”<br />

Next Message by AR is [834].<br />

[1210] Shelly: graded A The Form Side. To look at commodity circulation from its form<br />

side is to view the process as a metamorphosis. This shows that the commodity owner is


82 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

still in possession <strong>of</strong> the value produced, it has simply changed form: the commodity transforms<br />

from a use-value not needed by the commodity owner, to its independent value form<br />

(money), to a commodity with use-value the owner needs/desires. Marx uses the analogy<br />

<strong>of</strong> metamorphosis to view one side <strong>of</strong> commodity circulation, rather than looking at the<br />

interaction <strong>of</strong> two separate commodities. This form is represented by C-M-C.<br />

Hans: I changed “form <strong>of</strong> value” to “its (i.e., the value’s) independent value form.”<br />

Next Message by Shelly is [1211].<br />

[1474] Skylerp: Marx is pointing out that each commodity can have a different form<br />

side in the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities. The circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities must be looked at<br />

from its form side because each commodity has its own value and is produced with different<br />

materials.<br />

Next Message by Skylerp is [1475].<br />

Question 453 is 330 in 2003fa, 370 in 2004fa, 364 in 2005fa, 386 in 2007SP, 397 in<br />

2008SP, 398 in 2008fa, 413 in 2009fa, and 444 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 453 The empirical appearance <strong>of</strong> the processes <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase encourages<br />

a naive mistake, which makes it difficult to understand the metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Which mistake?<br />

[818] Basil: The Elusive Qualities <strong>of</strong> Sale and Exchange. The mistake <strong>of</strong>ten made<br />

when examining the process <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase occurs when individuals perceive the sale


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 83<br />

and purchase process as one <strong>of</strong> barter and exchange rather than one <strong>of</strong> metamorphosis <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity. This mistake can further be described as confusing each sale or purchase<br />

as a transaction involving two different commodities, when in reality it is a transaction that<br />

involves the evolving use-value and value forms <strong>of</strong> one commodity.<br />

For example, an individual may perceive the transaction <strong>of</strong> 20 yards linen for $5 as the<br />

exchange or barter <strong>of</strong> the use-value linen for its equivalent in the use-value gold. However,<br />

this perception does not identify that $5 does not represent the use-value gold, but it represents<br />

the Money Form <strong>of</strong> the General Equivalent form <strong>of</strong> Value for linen. As Hans describes<br />

in Annotations [p. 283], $5 “is the money shape <strong>of</strong> the commodity 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen.” Therefore,<br />

a sale and purchase transaction does not result in the exchange <strong>of</strong> two use-values, nor<br />

is the intent <strong>of</strong> the commodity owners to attain another use-value. A sale and purchase depicts<br />

the metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> the commodity “from the form side” as a process involving two<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> the same commodity: “first use-value for others, then value unencumbered by any<br />

use-value.” And when the money received for the linen is then used to purchase another<br />

commodity, the form becomes a “use-value for its owner” [p. 282]. They key distinction is<br />

that money is not viewed as a separate commodity as in a barter transaction, but it is viewed<br />

as the representation <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity linen.<br />

Hans: Your second sentence was originally:<br />

This mistake can further be described as confusing sale and purchase as a transaction involving<br />

two different use-values, when in reality it is a transaction that involves the evolving form <strong>of</strong><br />

value <strong>of</strong> the commodity.


84 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

I changed it because even if you look at it from the form side (as you should), you see two different use-values—<br />

they are two different use-value forms <strong>of</strong> the same commodity. Looking at it from the form side does not only mean<br />

value forms but includes the use-value forms as well.<br />

Next Message by Basil is [887].<br />

[840] Glister: process <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase. After reading this section several times, I<br />

think I finally understand what Marx is trying to explain when he talks about the processes<br />

<strong>of</strong> a sale and purchases. While reading Marx, he explains that it is difficult to see that a<br />

barter transaction is very different than barter between two normal goods without money<br />

(exchange) is very different. Every form change <strong>of</strong> a commodity has two things, ordinary<br />

commodity and money commodity. Barter has two main parts giving something away for<br />

something to be received. Marx explains that in a sale you only need to worry about the<br />

giving or sale that’s why Marx says that the sale <strong>of</strong> a good is a form change and not a barter<br />

between two commodities selling. The main mistake that I found is that barter is <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

looking at and conceived as exchanging money for a common good. The “process <strong>of</strong> sale<br />

and purchase”. For example if I go out and buy a new pen to write with and pay for it with<br />

a 10-dollar bill. That is not barter, it is simply a sale and purchase transaction. The reason<br />

for this is due to the paper itself not having use value this is why the metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity is hard to understand.<br />

Glister: I sent an email that had the wrong content, if there is any way to discard that email that would be great.<br />

The email content was somebody else’s 888 submission, the subject was process <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase. I meant to<br />

send my homework assignment but copied the wrong material.<br />

Hans: The definition <strong>of</strong> “barter” is: exchange <strong>of</strong> two commodities neither <strong>of</strong> which is money.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 85<br />

I made it an ungraded submission but didn’t want to delete it because it seems whoever wrote it was trying<br />

to understand the text. Keep on trying. It is difficult to know what to pay attention to in reading such a text, this<br />

requires a lot <strong>of</strong> practice.<br />

Next Message by Glister is [1000].<br />

Question 468 is 397 in 2007fa, 403 in 2008fa, and 418 in 2009fa:<br />

Question 468 What does Marx mean with the aphorism: “Money may be dirt, although dirt<br />

is not money.”<br />

[810] Neela: graded B+ Money in the bank... What Marx means by the aphorism:<br />

“Money may be dirt, although dirt is not money” can be broken down by piece. The first half<br />

that says, “Money may be dirt” means that one gained their money through selling something.<br />

On page 301 in Annotations it states, “In order to have this money, one must have<br />

made a sale”. The sale can be the sale <strong>of</strong> anything, and including dirt. In other words, they<br />

could have sold dirt for money, therefore ‘money is the value form <strong>of</strong> the dirt’. The second<br />

half that says, “...dirt is not money” means that although you may sell dirt for money, you<br />

cannot purchase items with dirt. The dirt is not valuable to the possessor until it is turned<br />

into money.<br />

Message [810] referenced by [816], [832], and [849]. Next Message by Neela is [883].<br />

[816] Hans: Think “copper” instead <strong>of</strong> dirt. The following proposition is also true, let’s<br />

first discuss it, and then see where question 468 differs:


86 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

“Money may be copper, although copper is not money.”<br />

Neela’s answer [810] can be adapted for copper almost entirely. As Neela did, I will split<br />

the answer into two halves.<br />

The first half “money may be copper” means that the owner <strong>of</strong> money may have obtained<br />

this money through selling anything, and this anything may have been copper.<br />

The second half “...copper is not money” means that although people can sell copper for<br />

money, they cannot purchase items with copper.<br />

Why not? Now Neela’s answer gets wrong. Neela says: “The copper is not valuable to<br />

the possessor until it is turned into money.” This is wrong for the following reason:<br />

(1) “Valuable” in this context cannot mean use-value. The question whether copper has<br />

use-value for its owner or not is not what determines what can be done with it on the market.<br />

(2) Therefore let’s look at the value <strong>of</strong> copper, meaning the congealed abstract labor in<br />

the copper, and let’s assume we live under the gold standard. If someone sells copper on<br />

the market for money, then the value <strong>of</strong> the copper sold is exactly equal to the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

money (gold) received. Therefore the reason why one cannot use copper to buy things is not<br />

that it is not valuable enough. It is not the quantity <strong>of</strong> value that distinguishes money from<br />

copper but its form <strong>of</strong> value. If there is a general equivalent (money) then people will not<br />

accept other commodities in direct barter but they will insist on receiving money.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 87<br />

The problem with dirt is that the word “dirt” does not indicate whether it is a valuable<br />

commodity (potting soil) or a value-less byproduct <strong>of</strong> some other activity. The kind <strong>of</strong> dirt<br />

which can be sold for money is a valuable commodity, and if we are talking about valuable<br />

commodities, the reasoning is exactly the same as with copper.<br />

Message [816] referenced by [832], [849], and [1330]. Next Message by Hans is [822].<br />

[832] AndyUte: graded D Money for Dirt. It is quite clear from Marx’s aphorism:<br />

“Money may be dirt, although dirt is not money”, that he is alluding to money’s ability to be<br />

exchanged for any commodity and dirt’s lack <strong>of</strong> ability to be exchanged for any commodity.<br />

It is simple to understand the part “Money may be dirt....” when we read Hans’ response<br />

to [2007fa:302]. He states that “money can be transformed into any use value”. Similarly,<br />

on page 302 in Annotations it reads that “Money is the absolutely alienable commodity, because<br />

it is the disembodied shape <strong>of</strong> all other commodities.” Money is universal, it can be<br />

exchanged for dirt and all other commodities. Dirt, however, cannot be exchanged for any<br />

commodity. I agree with Neela [2012fa:810] when she says, “The dirt is not valuable to the<br />

possessor until it is turned into money.” Unlike the universal exchangeability <strong>of</strong> money, dirt<br />

is not going to get you very much.<br />

Hans: You are repeating exactly the errors which I tried to correct in [816]. To say it again, Marx is not talking<br />

about dirt that is a valueless byproduct <strong>of</strong> construction or mining, but compost or potting soil or similar, which is a<br />

commodity just like copper.<br />

Next Message by AndyUte is [1006].


88 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[843] KATES: Money and Dirt. Marx regards money as a possible exchange for commodities,<br />

he assumes that it alienates both the input labor and the laborer himself. Marx sees<br />

every economic relation as a social relation. The exchange value <strong>of</strong> money can dangerously<br />

fluctuate, and is based on the trust people have in its value. Recognizing that the exchangevalue<br />

<strong>of</strong> money is a construction <strong>of</strong> limited relevance to economic domains we can gain a<br />

better understanding <strong>of</strong> the ways in which money is imagined, transformed or ignored.<br />

In order to have money you need to have made a sale to gain money. When you sell<br />

something someone else purchases an item which makes it a sell. A sell can be anything as<br />

long as it is a commodity that someone is willingly to buy such as dirt or anything else. If<br />

someone wants dirt then someone can sell dirt for money which makes money a value form<br />

<strong>of</strong> dirt if dirt is desired. Dirt is not money though because dirt is not valued in the same way<br />

as money. Dirt has value if people are willingly to pay for it with money. Because people are<br />

willingly to accept money for dirt and money for other commodities then money becomes<br />

what people expect to receive for commodities. But dirt is not money because when trading<br />

commodities people will expect to receive money and not dirt. You can sell dirt for money<br />

but you can’t purchase another commodity for dirt.<br />

Hans: How is your first paragraph relevant for the question asked?<br />

Next Message by KATES is [1018].<br />

[849] JohnLennon: Dirt is not money. I’ve found this question quite interesting. Many<br />

have broken up the question into two parts and many have mostly focused on the first part


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 89<br />

unless there is some stuff I’ve missed in the archives. For the sake <strong>of</strong> this question I will<br />

break into the two traditional parts as well.<br />

The first part. As referenced by Neela [810], “Money may be dirt” means that one gained<br />

their money through selling something/commodity or in this instance dirt. We see this part <strong>of</strong><br />

the answer to be correct in many instances when this question is asked for the course. To be<br />

even more plain here is another example from MikeyMoz [2008fa:1065] “A person wishing<br />

to buy something with their dirt needs to exchange their dirt for gold, this is done through<br />

the process <strong>of</strong> selling. This newly transformed dirt can now be used to buy anything.” The<br />

phrase “newly transformed dirt” is referencing gold or money.<br />

Now let’s look at the second half. “Dirt is not money” In a capitalist society dirt is not<br />

money. Money is money. I like the phrase in annotations that states “But the purchaser<br />

is in a different position than you. He needs money to make the purchase, while you do<br />

not need money for making the sale”. I had never considered the idea that money is not<br />

a requirement for selling an item. Money is only needed to purchase. It’s kind <strong>of</strong> funny to<br />

think that the phrase “it takes money to make money” is so far from the truth in this scenario.<br />

It takes a commodity to make money. So why would anybody want to trade one commodity<br />

for another at equal value (assuming there was a way to determine equal value), when they<br />

could trade the commodity for money which can be used to purchase whatever they want.<br />

Nobody wants to be tied down to the barter system, because nobody can ever get what they<br />

truly want through trade. Just as Hans stated this semester [816] “It is not the quantity <strong>of</strong>


90 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

value that distinguishes money from copper/dirt but its form <strong>of</strong> value”. I don’t know if I can<br />

bold and underline the word “form”, but it definitely should be. The form <strong>of</strong> money gives us<br />

purchasing power not selling power, therefore dirt/commodity is not money.<br />

Next Message by JohnLennon is [1003].<br />

[1193] Elias: graded B Too Much Face Value. Perhaps I was looking into Marx’s aphorism<br />

too much at face value. I took the quote as meaning that money is a creation that takes<br />

the form <strong>of</strong> a good that is regarded as “money.” That the idea <strong>of</strong> money could be applied to<br />

anything that is tangible to humans, even dirt. This is based on the understanding that money<br />

is created as a way to exchange for goods, yet it has to be a good itself that has a perceived<br />

value by society. Therefore, if we lived in a world that had high esteem for dirt, there is a<br />

possibility that it could be used as money. Thus, “dirt can be money”.<br />

However, it would not be as effective as gold, because it is in great abundance and not<br />

scarce like gold and other precious metals that were used as currency in Marx’s time. Thus,<br />

“dirt is not money”.<br />

Yet from the looks <strong>of</strong> understanding from others that the quote is understood as saying<br />

that dirt may have been sold for money, that doesn’t mean that dirt can be considered money<br />

in a different transaction. Which would tie a little into what I was stating that dirt is too<br />

abundant and doesn’t have enough value to be able to be used effectively as a currency.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 91<br />

Hans: The reason why dirt cannot be used as money is not that dirt lacks value. The dirt which you can buy does<br />

have value. Even if your example uses a valuable commodity, such as copper, you cannot buy things with copper<br />

either. Dirt and copper are lacking the proper value form to serve as money.<br />

Next Message by Elias is [1195].<br />

[1233] Alee: “Money may be dirt although dirt is not money” can as well be looked at as<br />

“Money may be copper although copper is not money.” The first part “Money may be dirt”<br />

or “Money may be copper” means that the owner may have earned this money by selling<br />

something and that something may have been copper. And the second part “although dirt is<br />

not money” or “copper is not money” means that although you can sell copper for money<br />

you cannot buy items with copper.<br />

Next Message by Alee is [1234].<br />

[1330] Gunther: graded A I’d first like to start my response by replacing dirt with copper.<br />

If an individual obtains wealth it may be that they did so by selling their copper to obtain<br />

it. But that individual can’t go out and purchase other commodities with that copper. Hans<br />

said in [816], “If there is a general equivalent (money) then people will not accept other<br />

commodities in direct barter but they will insist on receiving money [instead].” Therefore,<br />

money may be dirt but dirt is not money.<br />

Next Message by Gunther is [1331].<br />

[1372] Amcelhiney: Dirt can have use-value while money is only exchangeable for the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> dirt as a commodity. Dirt can be used as money; exchangeable for other commodities<br />

but cannot hold a use-value. Value in money can be gained from selling dirt.


92 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Dirt can have use-value but dirt cannot hold a use-value? Value can be gained by selling dirt?<br />

Next Message by Amcelhiney is [1380].<br />

Exam Question 480 is 376 in 2005fa, 398 in 2007SP, 411 in 2008SP, 412 in 2008fa, 427<br />

in 2009fa, 462 in 2010fa, and 459 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 480 How does Marx define a crisis?<br />

[1097] PJM: How Marx Defines a Crisis. In general, Marx defines a crisis as a violent<br />

force that results from the external separation <strong>of</strong> two objects that are intrinsically related.<br />

The objects can only evolve independently so far until their independent evolution comes<br />

to an end due to the inner unity, which violently asserts itself. Marx discusses crisis in<br />

relation to the commodity circulation, which, by separating purchase and sale which are<br />

both related as parts <strong>of</strong> the exchange process, gives rise to the possibility <strong>of</strong> crises. An<br />

important example <strong>of</strong> such a crisis was the 2008 recession. The crisis was caused by the<br />

ability to take out mortgages which effectively displaced the buying and selling <strong>of</strong> houses<br />

through time. However, over that time when people were buying their houses, the housing<br />

bubble burst, causing a rapid devaluation <strong>of</strong> assets. However, mortgage payments stayed the<br />

same or even increased, causing a crisis. If the purchase and sale <strong>of</strong> houses would not have<br />

been so separated in time and place, the crisis could have arguably been avoided.<br />

Hans: Your definition <strong>of</strong> crises is good, but it is incomplete. Crisis can also be the forcible separation <strong>of</strong> two things<br />

which should be intrinsically separate but which were externally combined.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 93<br />

Your characterization <strong>of</strong> the substandard mortgage bubble does not seem convincing to me, but it is a good idea<br />

to look whether it fits into Marx’s framework. I think it is a crisis <strong>of</strong> the second kind: instead <strong>of</strong> paying for the<br />

houses with the equity they have due to their income, people tried to pay for their houses with the equity which they<br />

acquired when buying the house. But intrinsically you cannot pay something with its own value, you must have<br />

something different that is valuable to pay for it. For a while it worked because it was a bubble, but then it crashed<br />

as it had to.<br />

Next Message by PJM is [1103].<br />

[1109] AndyUte: graded A CRISIS. Marx defines a crisis in two different ways. First,<br />

a crisis is the forcible separation <strong>of</strong> things that are internally separate but that are bound<br />

together by an external bond. Secondly a crisis can be the forcible unification <strong>of</strong> things that<br />

internally belong together but that have an externally separate existence.<br />

Hans: This is the right definition, sufficient for a designated exam question, although it cries out for elaboration<br />

and examples.<br />

Only one quibble: look at it not statically but as a process <strong>of</strong> motion. Instead <strong>of</strong> your “forcible unification <strong>of</strong><br />

things that internally belong together but that have an externally separate existence” I would prefer the formulation<br />

“forcible unification <strong>of</strong> things that internally belong together but that externally have moved too far apart.” Read<br />

[2011fa:757]. But these are details, for an exam the above answer is entirely satisfactory.<br />

Next Message by AndyUte is [1228].<br />

Question 495 is 474 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 495 Interruptions in the circulation <strong>of</strong> money are very mundane practical facts.<br />

How can they have enough influence to initiate an entirely new social function <strong>of</strong> money,<br />

namely money as a hoard?


94 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[854] Villa: graded A Going back a step. When a coin is interrupted it is turned into<br />

money, the metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> commodities has stopped. This is the start <strong>of</strong> a new social<br />

relation that is classified as hoarding - the word is meant to have the negative connotation<br />

removed and to be thought as formation <strong>of</strong> treasure as Hans explained in the annotations - it<br />

has its place in society as means to prepare for emergencies or living expenses. It is a practical<br />

fact as the question suggests because it happens all the time in society. Bigger purchases<br />

require selling more commodities and not immediately exchanging them for something <strong>of</strong><br />

equal value. This can be thought <strong>of</strong> as the positive side <strong>of</strong> hoarding, one saves to buy a vehicle,<br />

a downpayment for a house, college tuition, etc. We can see the usefulness <strong>of</strong> money<br />

as exchange value because producer A may not be in need <strong>of</strong> producer B’s commodity and<br />

it might result in ridiculous amounts <strong>of</strong> one commodity; I imagine exchanging 2,000 pairs<br />

<strong>of</strong> shoes for a vehicle would not be reasonable. However, the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> gold<br />

that supposedly holds power would play to the greed <strong>of</strong> a consumer in that he/she would<br />

more than plainly want, but enjoy hoarding more and more gold as possible. This is that step<br />

back we must take in order to understand better why a person continues to hoard gold further.<br />

Its fetish like power is alluring, for if a person hoarded money only for the purpose <strong>of</strong><br />

emergency or commodities with higher exchange values, such as vehicles, a certain amount<br />

could be set and reached. However, as workers are exploited in capitalism and higher pr<strong>of</strong>its<br />

gained we can see that this is certainly not the case, more is always wanted. Perhaps this is<br />

why hoarding has a negative connotation to begin with in the English language.<br />

Message [854] referenced by [860]. Next Message by Villa is [873].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 95<br />

[860] Nunu: Significance <strong>of</strong> money as a hoard. Interruptions in the circulation <strong>of</strong><br />

money have enough influence to initiate money as a hoard because everybody wants money,<br />

everybody can make use <strong>of</strong> money. However, Hans points out that Marx is not referring<br />

to hoarding as the selfish acquiring <strong>of</strong> a thing but rather for the usefulness <strong>of</strong> the thing, its<br />

treasure-like quality. Villa [854] and Skiingforlunch [2011fa:561] also mention this point in<br />

their submissions. As the circulation <strong>of</strong> money increased so did its social power and so did<br />

its demand and the need and passion to hang on to it. What was once only material wealth<br />

turned into social wealth. Money holds potential to be exchanged for many things (nearly<br />

everything) and people recognize it as such. When money is immobilized its potential is<br />

recognized, it is not merely the transfer between two commodities that comes and goes.<br />

At the point when money stops circulating dynamics change. Money as a hoard is seen<br />

as a treasure that “has its place in society as means to prepare for emergencies or living<br />

expenses [including those unexpected]” Villa, [854]. Society gave money power when it<br />

was recognized, like Marx says, as the “absolute and ever ready social form <strong>of</strong> wealth.” The<br />

social significance that money has been given by society makes it desirable. When money is<br />

not being spent after having been exchanged for a commodity, it can be considered surplus<br />

money, it helps people be prepared for necessities and it can also show society that the<br />

individual has plentiful <strong>of</strong> all necessities and wants, so much that the individual can hold onto<br />

the money and not spend. However this is not entirely always the case, people also choose<br />

to hold on to money for the power that it brings, in the correct amount it holds potential to<br />

acquire any other commodity, Skiiingforlunch [2011fa:561] also makes this point.


96 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Message [860] referenced by [1358]. Next Message by Nunu is [888].<br />

[1358] Nunu: A social function <strong>of</strong> money: hoarding. Marx says that money is the<br />

“absolute and ever ready form <strong>of</strong> social wealth”. Nunu [2012fa:860] mentions: “As the circulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> money increased so did its social power,...its demand and the need and passion to<br />

hang on to it”. Furthermore, people understand the power <strong>of</strong> money and that it can be used as<br />

means <strong>of</strong> exchange for nearly everything whether it is in the present or for future necessities<br />

or emergencies. Furthermore, money is hoarded because <strong>of</strong> its treasure-like quality, not in a<br />

selfish sense where people want to keep as much as they can so that nobody else can have it,<br />

but in the sense that people can always make use <strong>of</strong> it even when it is out <strong>of</strong> circulation and<br />

not being used at the present moment.<br />

Hans: What people appreciate so much about money is that it is both a social relation and a thing. It is a social<br />

relation which you can stick into your pocket. It is not surprising that the thing-like aspect <strong>of</strong> money acts back and<br />

modifies the social relations in which money is involved.<br />

Next Message by Nunu is [1359].<br />

Question 496 is 402 in 2004fa, 410 in 2007SP, 413 in 2007fa, 419 in 2008SP, 421 in<br />

2008fa, 437 in 2009fa, 473 in 2010fa, and 475 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 496 Explain the individual motivation for hoarding money. Do these hoards have<br />

a function for the economy as a whole or only for the individual?<br />

[857] TMM: Individual Motivation For Hoarding Money. The individual motivation<br />

for hoarding money is derived from the fact that money is representative <strong>of</strong> many use-values


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 97<br />

you can apply it to. Individuals in society may hoard money in order to realize social power.<br />

It is necessary to hoard money in an economy, however it is mostly due to individual activity<br />

and people’s fascination with money. Hans states in [2008SP:435] that in Marx’s time,<br />

the money that was not needed for circulation was not returned to the banking system, it<br />

was in fact horded by gold hoarders and kept private. This proved to be beneficial for the<br />

economy because it was also in the form where the reserves <strong>of</strong> the gold hoards could then<br />

be used for international transactions. It is the individual’s passion for money and the obsession<br />

to abstain from the circulation process and accumulate more reserves. The hoarders (as<br />

stated by Marx Student in [2011fa:1209] have a function in the economy where they act as<br />

a buffer when the process <strong>of</strong> selling commodities (C-M) has not been <strong>of</strong>fset the commodity<br />

purchases (M-C). This means that when the difference between the purchasing and selling <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities is too great, money would then be released from the hoarders into the system<br />

to allow proper circulation and satisfy the imbalance. Hans writes in [2008SP:435] that the<br />

economic functions <strong>of</strong> modern consumer debt are quite different where one <strong>of</strong> the biggest<br />

contradictions in capitalism is overproduction, where so much is produced and not enough<br />

can be sold because very little wages are paid, thus leaving an escape route through debt.<br />

This means that capitalists in a modern society can continue selling products without raising<br />

wages, accumulate capital from debt service payments leaving the consumers in debt as a<br />

way out <strong>of</strong> mountains <strong>of</strong> debt that is no longer able to be repaid. Marx writes that together<br />

with circulation “necessity and passion” is created to keep money out <strong>of</strong> circulation and to


98 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

hoard it instead. Money was originally created in order to aid to the process <strong>of</strong> circulation,<br />

commodities are sold not in order to buy commodities, but in order to replace their<br />

commodity form with their money form where the change in form becomes an end in itself.<br />

Hans: You had originally: “very little wages are paid because not enough can be sold.” Marx thinks the causality<br />

goes the opposite direction, therefore I changed it into “not enough can be sold because very little wages are paid.”<br />

Next Message by TMM is [898].<br />

[863] IrwinFletcher: graded B+ This is a question that I believe to have many layers and<br />

complexities. The more pensive I am about the pr<strong>of</strong>oundness <strong>of</strong> this question the more I<br />

believe that the function <strong>of</strong> hoarding money is unlike any other form or function <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

There are a handful <strong>of</strong> motives for which someone would want to hoard money. The first<br />

motive is the desire to accumulate as much money as possible. Many people look to money<br />

as a social status symbol. The other reason is more practical and that is hoarding money<br />

would be useful in a trade deficit. For example I use the fable <strong>of</strong> the ant and the grasshopper.<br />

The fable concerns a grasshopper that has spent the warm months singing and lounging<br />

while the ant worked hard to hoard and keep the grains <strong>of</strong> wheat she had worked so hard to<br />

gather. Once winter hit the grasshopper had no food to eat because he had hoarded nothing.<br />

Being faced with a trade deficit the ant chose not to be a positive function for society. For<br />

her personally she had options to eat the wheat that she gathered or use it to gain other<br />

necessities. When faced with the perils <strong>of</strong> improvidence it is wise to hoard.<br />

Hans: When you say “the ant chose not to be a positive function for society” you mean it would have been a<br />

positive function for society if the ant had worked less and consumed everything she produced? Please explain how


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 99<br />

you mean this. There is no money in Aesop’s fable, the fable is about hoarding food for the winter, not hoarding<br />

money.<br />

Next Message by IrwinFletcher is [902].<br />

[866] Gunther: content C form 90% Hoarding Money. There can be a number <strong>of</strong><br />

reasons why individuals hoard money. Sometimes it can be for reasons <strong>of</strong> greed or power,<br />

and to increase their social status by collecting money being considered wealthy. Other<br />

times it can be that the individual feels the need to save for an emergency, or buy something<br />

expensive. When people hoard money they literally take it out <strong>of</strong> the circulation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

economy and like Milly says in [2010fa:1116] “deciding not to buy after selling.” Hoarding<br />

can hurt the economy as whole when those that are wealthy are amassing money and proceed<br />

to accumulate even more wealth. Marx says that sometimes circulation must be interrupted<br />

for economic reasons but for the most part it is the individuals following the lure <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Hans: You had “sometimes circulation must be interjected for economic reasoning.” I think you mean “interrupted”<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> “interjected,” and “economic reasons” instead <strong>of</strong> “economic reasoning.” Only after I made these changes<br />

I realized that this makes it identical to Milly’s formulation, but if you paraphrase you should at least paraphrase in<br />

a way that makes sense.<br />

If you want to substitute “lure” for “fascination” you have to change the grammar <strong>of</strong> the sentence too: you had<br />

“the individual’s lure with money” and I changed it into “the individuals following the lure <strong>of</strong> money.”<br />

Next Message by Gunther is [990].<br />

[880] Hans: Hoarding: Good or Bad? Just to clarify two points:


100 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(1) if people hoard money in order to get social status, Marx would call this an individual<br />

motivation, although modern language usage might consider it a “social” motivation. Marx<br />

did not use the word “social” in this way. I alluded to this also in [453].<br />

(2) Don’t see it as an either-or situation. Don’t think: either people hoard for selfish<br />

reasons, or they hoard for the sake <strong>of</strong> the economy as a whole. People usually hoard because<br />

it benefits them personally. The question asked: under what circumstances does it also<br />

benefit the economy as a whole?<br />

Next Message by Hans is [890].<br />

[1393] IrwinFletcher: graded A– There are a few reasons for hoarding money. One <strong>of</strong><br />

those reasons is for a symbol <strong>of</strong> status. I agree with Marx and his thinking when he says<br />

that money doesn’t determine value, it only determines price. It’s for that reason that an<br />

individual should not hoard money with the intent to “save it for a rainy day”. If that day<br />

should come there is a chance that his money will be utterly useless. Hoarding money does<br />

indirectly and directly have a function on the economy. it serves a circulation function.<br />

Hans: Marx is critical <strong>of</strong> the miser, who hoards money in order to enrich himself. He is not critical <strong>of</strong> hoarding<br />

money for a rainy day, on the contrary, he considers this a legitimate reason for hoarding money.<br />

Next Message by IrwinFletcher is [1394].<br />

[1395] SLOVENEC: An individual’s motivation for hoarding money comes from an individual’s<br />

unquenchable want for commodities and more money. Although money itself<br />

cannot feed us or keep us warm, we as humans, view it as a means <strong>of</strong> accessing commodities<br />

for both consumption and advancement <strong>of</strong> money i.e. creating more money. Because


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 101<br />

<strong>of</strong> money’s measure <strong>of</strong> value, each person seeks to obtain as much as possible while also<br />

limiting how much is spent for other goods. As to whether hoarding has a function for the<br />

economy, it serves as the backbone <strong>of</strong> the financial sector and makes available capital for<br />

banks to lend. However, hoarding <strong>of</strong> money also can lead to a liquidity crisis, in which<br />

everyone wants to sell items, but not buy anything.<br />

Hans: Hoarding, as Marx uses the word, is not the same as invesing. The assumption is that the money will not<br />

earn any returns while hoarded.<br />

An individual’s “unquenchable want for commodities” would not be the motivation <strong>of</strong> the hoarder but <strong>of</strong> the<br />

spendthrift, who is the opposite <strong>of</strong> the hoarder.<br />

All this has nothing to do with the function <strong>of</strong> money as measure <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Next Message by SLOVENEC is [1398].<br />

Exam Question 497 is 422 in 2008fa, 438 in 2009fa, 474 in 2010fa, and 476 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 497 Give an example <strong>of</strong> a transaction between P and Q in which P sells to<br />

Q but Q does not purchase from P.<br />

[1120] Shelly: graded A P-Q. Sale and Barter. An example would be a merchant walking<br />

up to a gold digger and selling his blankets for the gold just pulled from the ground. For the<br />

merchant, this transaction is a sale because he has a commodity he is willing to exchange in<br />

order to obtain money (so he can buy other commodities needed), but for the gold digger it<br />

was a barter transaction because the commodity he just “produced” is already money. There


102 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

was no need for a previous transaction to occur so that the gold digger could acquire money<br />

to buy the blankets; he simply dug it from the ground.<br />

Hans: Very good.<br />

Message [1120] referenced by [1121]. Next Message by Shelly is [1140].<br />

[1121] Brie: Sweden. In Sweden, there are fields <strong>of</strong> beautiful flowers that grow behind<br />

John’s home. Because the flowers grow on his property, he cuts them at the height <strong>of</strong> their<br />

bloom and takes them to the town market. During this time, he is approached by Leo whom<br />

wishes to trade for meat which has been prepared on his farm. The trade now provides Leo<br />

with a commodity which he can sell for cash value at the town market, and provides John<br />

with meat for his family. The flowers represent a commodity which John obtained without<br />

trade or money; they were already worth a cash value upon his act <strong>of</strong> cutting them for barter.<br />

Hans: You misunderstand the question. The right answer is [1120].<br />

Next Message by Brie is [1364].<br />

Question 498 Is the transaction by which the gold producer trades his product for the usevalues<br />

he needs a purchase or a barter?<br />

[916] Littlerock: (graded A) Sale <strong>of</strong> Gold: Barter or Purchase? I believe that the answer<br />

to this question is that it would normally be a purchase. The exception to this rule would be<br />

if the person receiving the gold wants the gold for a use-value besides that <strong>of</strong> money. If the<br />

purchaser <strong>of</strong> the gold, for example, wished to receive it in order to use it for dental fillings,<br />

then it would be a barter. Money is money when it is used as a measure <strong>of</strong> value and as


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 103<br />

means <strong>of</strong> circulation. Money as money contains the potential to be converted to any kind <strong>of</strong><br />

use-value sold on the market. If the purchaser <strong>of</strong> gold wishes to use it, as in this example, for<br />

dental fillings, then she is not planning on using it to facilitate future purchases. It will no<br />

longer be used as means <strong>of</strong> circulation and it will lose its ability to be converted to an infinite<br />

number <strong>of</strong> other use-values. It is not being used as money, it is no longer money, and the<br />

transaction is a barter. However, if the person trading for the gold plans to use it as means<br />

<strong>of</strong> circulation and as a way to be able to obtain other use-values, than the gold is being used<br />

as money, the purpose <strong>of</strong> trading for the gold was to obtain money, and the transaction is a<br />

purchase, not a barter.<br />

Hans: Your distinction makes sense, but it is the criterion whether the person trading for the gold is selling or<br />

bartering their own commodity for gold. See my [981] for this. For the gold producer, trading his gold for usevalues<br />

he needs is never a purchase, it is always a barter (Marx uses the word “direct exchange” for the same<br />

transaction which I call “barter”).<br />

Jason [923] gives textual evidence that Marx classifies it this way. To Marx, sale and then purchase are two<br />

halves <strong>of</strong> what would otherwise have been a barter. In the case <strong>of</strong> he gold producer, there is no need to split the<br />

transaction into two, it can stay un-split, therefore it is a barter and not a purchase.<br />

Message [916] referenced by [923] and [1467]. Next Message by Littlerock is [930].<br />

[923] Jason: (graded A) Gold Directly from the Producer. Reading Chapter 3, I got a<br />

different impression from the text and the annotations than Littlerock [916]. Normally, the<br />

exchange <strong>of</strong> Gold is a purchase, as the “deed” has already been done, and Gold has been<br />

selected as the general equivalent. However, this question asks about the special case <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Gold producers trading their newly-produced Gold. It seems to me as if Marx considered


104 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

this, from the perspective <strong>of</strong> the Gold-trader, a barter transaction. Marx writes “(Gold), at<br />

the sources <strong>of</strong> (its) production, however (is) directly exchanged for other commodities. Here<br />

we have sales (by the owners <strong>of</strong> commodities) without purchases (by the owners <strong>of</strong> Gold...)<br />

(akmk, pg. 228:2/oo).” I translate this as a barter transaction.<br />

From the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the Gold producer, the transaction has taken the form C-C. The<br />

Gold producer has managed to take a non-use-value, and turn it into an immediate-use-value,<br />

with no intermediate step. The fact a social act has already occurred to fuse the use-value<br />

Gold with the universal measure <strong>of</strong> value, and the means <strong>of</strong> circulation, such that the usevalue<br />

the Gold-trader exchanges can immediately be stamped with the ‘M’ monicker is not<br />

insignificant. But, to Marx, in order to be a purchase, this Gold must already be the product<br />

<strong>of</strong> a prior sale.<br />

Message [923] referenced by [916]. Next Message by Jason is [924].<br />

[981] Hans: The Answer, Briefly, Without Explanation. For the producer <strong>of</strong> gold it<br />

is a barter and not a purchase. For the other partner in this transaction it is usually a sale,<br />

assuming this other partner uses the gold to purchase other things with it. In the exceptional<br />

case that the other partner uses the gold for filling his teeth, then it is a barter for the other<br />

partner too.<br />

Message [981] referenced by [916] and [1362]. Next Message by Hans is [983].<br />

[1142] Abysmal: graded A A gold producer trading his product for use-values he needs<br />

is a barter, not a purchase. C-M-C does not occur as normal, as the producer’s end <strong>of</strong> this


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 105<br />

exchange is already in the money form, and needn’t be converted into the money commodity.<br />

In this case, the other producer conducts a sale to the gold producer, but the gold producer<br />

does not purchase. Hans used examples <strong>of</strong> the U.S. printing money to exchange for oil, and<br />

Kennecott exchanging minerals it extracts for oil, and this case is no different. This is a<br />

barter, not a purchase.<br />

Hans: The Kennecott example does not come from me, but from OBJ in [2011fa:767]. I added a remark now that<br />

such barters do not happen in practice. Under the gold standard, Kennecott could have taken the gold it produces<br />

directly to the mint and used the money it received to “buy” something. I put “buy” into scare quotes because Marx<br />

would not call it a purchase, and taking gold to the mint is not a sale, but rather related to making change, i.e.,<br />

breaking up a $100 bill into five $20 bills. I wrote about Kennecott and gold in [2011fa:770].<br />

Next Message by Abysmal is [1143].<br />

[1146] ImmanentMaterialist: Since gold represents the money form <strong>of</strong> commodities,<br />

if the gold producer were to trade some <strong>of</strong> his gold for a particular use-value it would be<br />

a purchase—not a barter. The only way in which a case such as this could be considered<br />

properly as a barter would be if the producer were to craft his gold into some sort <strong>of</strong> usevalue<br />

(say, fillings for a tooth or jewelry) and then traded the gold as that form in a manner<br />

that did not reflect the price <strong>of</strong> the commodity for which it has been exchanged.<br />

Hans: In both cases, it would be a barter for the gold producer. In the second case it would not be a sale by the<br />

other party in this transaction, the owner <strong>of</strong> the use-valued the gold producer needs, while in the first case it would<br />

be a sale for him or her.<br />

Next Message by ImmanentMaterialist is [1147].


106 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1168] SVN: Test 2 Resubmission Question 498. This transaction for the gold producer<br />

is a barter for several reasons. The gold with which the gold producer “paid” for the commodity<br />

is gold that came from the ground, not gold that came from circulation. For the<br />

producer to get this gold, it did not require a sale, or a C-M on his part. This fact allows<br />

people to accumulate hoards <strong>of</strong> gold and for the flow <strong>of</strong> money to be interrupted. The money<br />

that is taken out <strong>of</strong> circulation is replaced by the gold producers trading their gold for other<br />

commodities on the market. The gold is brought out <strong>of</strong> the ground not only as a commodity<br />

with a use value, but also as a commodity that is already in a universally recognized general<br />

equivalent form. The gold producer does not have to convert his raw material into a<br />

commodity that can be exchanged for money with which he can then purchase other commodities<br />

that he needs. The gold producer’s commodity is directly exchangeable. He is able<br />

to take his commodity straight out <strong>of</strong> the ground and simply exchange it for any commodity<br />

that his quantity <strong>of</strong> gold can afford. Unlike a baker for example, who would first have to<br />

get all <strong>of</strong> his supplies together to to bake the bread and then would have to sell his bread<br />

for gold. He could then take that gold and purchase another commodity for it which would<br />

be a C-M-C process. In some instances, but it would vary with time and place, the baker<br />

could bypass the C-M-C process and barter using his bread to directly exchange for let’s say<br />

a bible. For the gold producer the transaction will be a barter because the gold producer can<br />

always take his commodity, gold, and exchange it for a bible or bread, without having to first<br />

sell his gold. For the gold producer his transaction will be a C-C process and will thus be a<br />

bartering process.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 107<br />

Next Message by SVN is [1169].<br />

[1175] RikkiAllie: Gold is considered a value <strong>of</strong> currency. If a gold producer wants to<br />

use its use-value it would be purchasing an item, not bartering. With gold being considered<br />

money and the “market” has set prices due to a gold standard, gold is therefore set and can<br />

no longer be bartered. Barter items are if a commodity is exchanged for an equal commodity<br />

(buy/trader’s discretion). Once gold is used to purchase a commodity, then the new<br />

commodity would be available to be bartered.<br />

Hans: Your answer makes sense but this is not Marx’s use <strong>of</strong> the terms.<br />

Next Message by RikkiAllie is [1176].<br />

[1183] Villa: graded A The act in question is a barter. He is trading a product for another<br />

use-value, not utilizing the money form <strong>of</strong> gold to buy another commodity. Marx would<br />

depict this transaction as commodity-commodity or C-C. If it were a purchase it would be<br />

characterized as M-C; this is certainly not the case as gold in this scenario is a product, i.e<br />

made from some means <strong>of</strong> production such as mining. For the other producer involved it<br />

could be a sale, unless the other person were using the gold for a use-value such as gold<br />

plating for a guitar.<br />

Next Message by Villa is [1185].<br />

[1222] Reeree: The transaction that would take place by which the gold producer trades<br />

his product (meaning gold) for a use-value <strong>of</strong> his liking would not be a purchase, but a barter.<br />

This is because he has produced something that has not gone through the circulation cycle,<br />

so it has no “money” value to it.


108 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Your answer is correct but the reason you give is not quite correct. It is not true that the gold lacks “money”<br />

value, because the gold has “money” value for the other person, for whom this identical transaction would be a sale.<br />

The reason Marx nevertheless calls it a “barter” and not a “purchase,” even though money is given in exchange, is<br />

that in Marx’s terminology, a purchase is a purchase because the money given is pro<strong>of</strong> that the owner has produced<br />

something for which he or she has found a buyer. For a gold producer there is no such previous transaction, he<br />

directly uses his own private product, therefore Marx calls is a “barter.”<br />

Next Message by Reeree is [1486].<br />

[1258] Tim: graded A Barter. Since in this case the gold producer is trading his output<br />

directly for the output <strong>of</strong> another.<br />

Next Message by Tim is [1397].<br />

[1306] Extraterrestrial: graded B A barter is trading a commodity for another commodity.<br />

In this case, if gold was the general currency, it would be a purchase. Gold, here, would<br />

be considered a general equivalent. If gold was not the general currency, and not widely<br />

accepted as currency or the general equivalent it would be considered a barter.<br />

Hans: This makes sense, but interestingly, Marx uses a different criterion.<br />

Next Message by Extraterrestrial is [1307].<br />

[1362] Batgirl: The transaction by which the gold producer trades his product for the<br />

use-values he needs is a barter for him, not a purchase. However, for his transaction partner<br />

it is usually a sale unless used for fillings or other actions, Hans mentions this in [981].<br />

Next Message by Batgirl is [1363].<br />

[1467] Tony: graded B– From Hans’s response to Littlerock [916], the other partner uses<br />

gold to further buy other things for their use-values, so he doesn’t take use-values from gold,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 109<br />

because he uses gold as a medium as exchange. So whether or not a person could instantly<br />

earn value from trade depends on whether or not medium <strong>of</strong> exchange comes to play a role.<br />

It doesn’t matter whether this person is a gold producer or not. The matter thing depends on<br />

whether medium <strong>of</strong> exchange play a role or not. To get use value from trade, a person needs<br />

to barter because if he trade for medium <strong>of</strong> exchange in a purchase, he earns exchange value,<br />

not use value from it. There is no money related in this sentence. It is a C-C (commodity to<br />

commodity), not the C-M (commodity to money)<br />

Next Message by Tony is [1468].<br />

Question 505 is 278 in 1997sp, 267 in 1997ut, 274 in 1998WI, 285 in 1999SP, 321 in<br />

2001fa, 350 in 2002fa, 365 in 2003fa, 427 in 2008fa, and 443 in 2009fa:<br />

Question 505 Describe the inner contradiction <strong>of</strong> monetary abstract wealth which determine<br />

the goals <strong>of</strong> a miser, and the ridiculous contradiction <strong>of</strong> the means by which he is trying<br />

to reach this goal.<br />

[865] SVN: Miser Lifestyle. The inner contradiction <strong>of</strong> monetary abstract wealth is that<br />

qualitatively money is unlimited, but quantitatively it is limited. As Marx says, “money is<br />

unlimited: it is the universal representative <strong>of</strong> material wealth because it is directly convertible<br />

into any other commodity. But at the same time every actual sum <strong>of</strong> money is<br />

quantitatively limited, and therefore has only a limited efficacy as a means <strong>of</strong> purchase”<br />

(Annotations p. 324). This quote is representative <strong>of</strong> the curse <strong>of</strong> money, because on one


110 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

hand it can buy everything but on the other hand there is an upper limit to the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

money a person can have.<br />

This creates an incentive to produce, to sell, and to accumulate. Production becomes<br />

based solely on the drive to accumulate money instead <strong>of</strong> just producing a use-value that<br />

can be exchanged for another use-value that one needs to subsist. The ways <strong>of</strong> a miser or<br />

hoarder change society from a C-M-C to a M-C-M.<br />

The miser does not realize that he is trapped in a contradiction though, because the contradiction<br />

is inherent in the commodity production society. No matter how much money he<br />

has, there will always be more money to accumulate, there is no ceiling, it is like trying to<br />

chase the horizon. As Hans describes on page 325 <strong>of</strong> the Annotations, “But however much<br />

money he has, it is never enough.”<br />

To accumulate the money the miser must spend very little <strong>of</strong> it along the way. Marx says,<br />

“The miser therefore sacrifices the lusts <strong>of</strong> his flesh to the fetish <strong>of</strong> gold” (Annotations pg.<br />

325) He therefore lives his life centered around the accumulation <strong>of</strong> ultimately, a bunch <strong>of</strong><br />

use values, but use-values that will not be realized by him because he won’t spend. With<br />

such frugality he will not ever be able to enjoy his money for the phobia <strong>of</strong> parting with it<br />

is too great. The example <strong>of</strong> the miser, is a contradiction from numerous angles, but at its<br />

core is a wealthy member <strong>of</strong> a commodity producing/consumption based society that won’t<br />

consume.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 111<br />

Hans: A miser is not a wealthy capitalist that won’t consume, a miser is a worker who is trying to become wealthy<br />

by not consuming. Marx says this is impossible.<br />

You are confusing misers with capitalists. Your second paragraph is wrong, the reader should just disregard it.<br />

Next Message by SVN is [867].<br />

[1294] Kannon: First, when Marx discusses what a miser is he is not talking about a<br />

stingy capitalist in the way one would suspect today. Instead Marx is discussing workers<br />

who attempt to become capitalists or a at least get ahead through thrift. This is difficult for<br />

the worker because they are a paid a market wage that is equivalent to their living expenses.<br />

Even beyond their paltry level <strong>of</strong> subsistence however, Marx shows that a miser is doomed<br />

to fail in pursuing money through hoarding. The contradiction is that the miser is making<br />

himself poor to become rich; he is hoarding money because it is universal and can be used<br />

to obtain all use values. However, it is limited in a quantitative way and the miser can not<br />

actually accrue all use values.<br />

The miser is also doomed because because <strong>of</strong> the exploitative nature <strong>of</strong> the production<br />

process. This is because the laborer does not realize he is selling his labor power, not his<br />

labor as (s)he thinks. Instead, the value that this frugal worker is hidden and siphoned <strong>of</strong>f<br />

by the capitalist. The capitalist is able to do this by owning the means <strong>of</strong> production. Also<br />

if there is a technological advance it will allow the capitalist to extract higher value from<br />

the laborer’s value <strong>of</strong> labor—but it appears to the laborer as selling the same labor—even<br />

though it is not accompanied by an increase in his wage. Once this technological advance


112 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

extends to more industry (especially gold production in Marx’s time) the price <strong>of</strong> living will<br />

increase and the miser will be no better <strong>of</strong>f.<br />

Hans: This is not strictly “The right answer” but it is very thoughtful and interesting. You are describing the<br />

modern version <strong>of</strong> misers, working class people who try to get ahead by being very frugal. They are not identical to<br />

Marx’s misers, because they hope their savings will enable them to become capitalists. Marx was talking about the<br />

stylized character <strong>of</strong> a miser in pre-capitalist times who end up with lots <strong>of</strong> money which is sterile exactly because<br />

it can not be used to exploit workers and in this way increase its value by itself.<br />

I think the answer to the frugal worker is: most <strong>of</strong> those who indeed become small capitalists go bankrupt<br />

again. A better way to improve the lot <strong>of</strong> the workers used to be organizing in unions. But globalization and the<br />

competition <strong>of</strong> workers in the poor countries has eroded the bargaining power <strong>of</strong> the traditional unions. Capitalism<br />

itself is under stress because <strong>of</strong> the limits <strong>of</strong> growth and can no longer give the goodies it used to give to the working<br />

class. A frontal attack on capitalism is already necessary because capitalism destroys the environment, and also<br />

from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> workers making a better living, the goal or replacing capitalism itself becomes more and<br />

more necessary. We already witness this in Europe, I am curious to see whether it will also manifest itself in the<br />

USA.<br />

You are right, there are periods in history where the traditional value <strong>of</strong> labor was eroded because gold lost<br />

value and therefore prices rose.<br />

Next Message by Kannon is [1375].<br />

[1295] Jason: graded A The Contradictions <strong>of</strong> Abstract Wealth and the Ridiculous<br />

Miser. The inner contradiction <strong>of</strong> abstract monetary wealth is that money is qualitatively<br />

unlimited, in that it can purchase any other use-value as the general equivalent. At the same<br />

time, money is quantitatively limited - as soon as a person tries to realize the qualitatively<br />

unlimited nature <strong>of</strong> money, they find they start running out <strong>of</strong> it. The miser attempts to defeat


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 113<br />

this contradiction by trying to make money as unlimited quantitatively as it is qualitatively<br />

(Hans [2008fa:705]).<br />

The amusing this, however, is that in trying to defeat one contradiction, the miser personally<br />

plays out another. In order to become rich, the miser must make himself poor - he<br />

abstains from consumption. He ridiculously suffers poverty <strong>of</strong> use-values - real wealth - in<br />

order to grow his hoard <strong>of</strong> money - abstract wealth.<br />

Next Message by Jason is [1323].<br />

[1338] DJB: The miser. As the miser tries to accumulate wealth and hoard money there<br />

is a contradiction in what he is doing. Money is an item that in a capitalist society can be<br />

exchanged for any good and only has a use value <strong>of</strong> exchange. The miser is accumulating an<br />

item that is socially dependent on its value. Goods have a certain use-value which gives them<br />

a certain exchange value and with money it has no inner real value but only a social value<br />

that is dependent upon social attitudes. The other contradiction is the fact that the miser is<br />

living in a capitalist society and is not accumulating wealth but hoarding away money that is<br />

not worth anything when he could be spending his money and buying goods that are worth<br />

something. The miser is caught up in a social paradox where money is seen as wealth when<br />

in reality he doesn’t understand use values in actual goods.<br />

Hans: in Marx’s theory, commodities do not get exchange-value from their use-values but from labor. Marx was<br />

writing about the gold standard, when money had value.<br />

Next Message by DJB is [1348].


114 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1437] MKW: A miser, who aims to amass great wealth while spending very little contradicts<br />

himself by placing such an enormous value on money and yet does not use it for the<br />

very purpose for which it was designed, as a general equivalent for exchange. The miser<br />

chooses to ignore that fact that while money has value as a universal medium <strong>of</strong> exchange<br />

for use-values, in and <strong>of</strong> itself as a piece <strong>of</strong> paper or as an entry on a ledger. Money will<br />

do nothing for the miser but add stuffing to his mattress. He builds for himself a poor existence<br />

and forgoes the use-values that he could utilize because he places a higher value on the<br />

quantity <strong>of</strong> money he accumulates, which would be depleted if he chose to indulge, rather<br />

than the quality <strong>of</strong> the thing as a universal medium <strong>of</strong> exchange.<br />

Hans: At Marx’s time money did have value. Also, in Marx’s theory, the original purpose <strong>of</strong> money is not means<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchange but measure <strong>of</strong> value. Yet the contradiction was present also in the world seen through Marx’s eyes.<br />

Next Message by MKW is [1439].<br />

Exam Question 518 is 296 in 1999SP, 419 in 2004fa, 396 in 2005fa, 425 in 2007SP, 437<br />

in 2008fa, 453 in 2009fa, 490 in 2010fa, and 496 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 518 Bring two examples <strong>of</strong> situations where money functions as money and<br />

not merely as measure <strong>of</strong> value or means <strong>of</strong> circulation.<br />

[1091] AJH: Money as money. Marx states that money seems to have the desire and<br />

ability to move, without the apparent goal or driving force. I agreed with [2010fa:587] when<br />

Cmellen points out the three ways that Marx tells how money can function as money and not


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 115<br />

merely a measure <strong>of</strong> value or means <strong>of</strong> circulation. The three ways that Marx states money<br />

functions as money are; hoarding, means <strong>of</strong> payment, and world money.<br />

According to Marx, hording is storing up <strong>of</strong> money so that at a later time it can be used as<br />

the general incarnation <strong>of</strong> wealth and it does not have the negative meaning <strong>of</strong> unwillingness<br />

to share connected as the English hoarding does. Marx says that the circular movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> money stems from two antithetical metamorphoses between sale and purchase. Marx<br />

says that the movement <strong>of</strong> the metamorphoses can be interrupted and that as soon as the<br />

commodity owner no longer immediately supplements their sales with purchases, the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> circulation go from value to “money”.<br />

Another way that Marx states that money is money is by means <strong>of</strong> payment. Marx says<br />

that whoever holds the money and is considered the “buyer” is a mere representative <strong>of</strong><br />

money, or rather the representative <strong>of</strong> future money. The example Marx gives was renting a<br />

house when you could rent and pay the rent at the end <strong>of</strong> the month. Marx says that sellers<br />

become a creditor, and buyers become the debtor and thus because the form <strong>of</strong> value has<br />

undergone a change here, money becomes means <strong>of</strong> payment.<br />

Hans: In order to properly explain the role <strong>of</strong> money as means <strong>of</strong> payments you have to say that this is the payment<br />

<strong>of</strong> a monetary debt after the commodities already have changed hands. For instance, if a business gets merchandise<br />

delivered and then pays the invoice, this is money as means <strong>of</strong> payment. In a cash purchase, money functions as<br />

means <strong>of</strong> circulation and not as money.<br />

Next Message by AJH is [1315].


116 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1114] Neela: graded A Money, Money, Money. I agree with both [2011fa:901] Danish<br />

and [2011fa:963] Karl from Fall 2011 when citing the example <strong>of</strong> money functioning as<br />

money in the international sphere—countries paying their debts to each other, deficits in<br />

import/export markets, etc. A second example <strong>of</strong> money functioning as money and not<br />

merely as measure <strong>of</strong> value or means <strong>of</strong> circulation would be when one has to pay for their<br />

student loan or even a mortgage—the money from the loan would have already been paid<br />

to the university for the tuition and the family would already be living in the house they’re<br />

paying the mortgage for.<br />

Next Message by Neela is [1126].<br />

[1190] Elias: graded B+ Money as Money. The first example <strong>of</strong> money functioning<br />

purely as money is the buying and selling <strong>of</strong> foreign nation’s debt. This is purely a transaction<br />

<strong>of</strong> obtaining money in bonds or IOUs by purchasing that amount <strong>of</strong> debt. The second<br />

example would be student loans or a home mortgage. In that case the initial purchase <strong>of</strong> the<br />

house or education was done in advance by a financial institution. The loans itself is then a<br />

transfer <strong>of</strong> money by the borrower to the lending firm to make the debt back up.<br />

Hans: If you as a private investor use money to buy foreign government debt (or domestic government debt, or<br />

privately emitted bonds, or stocks), your money is a means <strong>of</strong> purchase, even though the commodity you are buying<br />

is an investment vehicle. This investment vehicle itself is not money.<br />

It is a different issue if a central bank does not get enough <strong>of</strong> a certain foreign currency by exports and therefore<br />

has to pay for a trade deficit so that imports from that foreign country can be continued. This money is used to<br />

transfer wealth from the domestic money form into the foreign money form. At Marx’s time it was done by shipping<br />

bullion to the foreign country.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 117<br />

In this case, the use <strong>of</strong> money as means <strong>of</strong> payments is much simpler than using money for cash purchases. Here<br />

is what would have to be done for cash purchases. In order to facilitate cash purchases in the foreign country, the<br />

central bank would have to ship some bullion from its vaults to the mint in the foreign country to have it converted<br />

into gold coin <strong>of</strong> that foreign country, then ship the gold coin back, so that domestic capitalists can make imports<br />

and pay for them by shipping the coins back to the foreign country.<br />

Shipping the same gold three times is wasteful. Instead, both imports and exports are made on credit and only<br />

if they do not balance out are shipments <strong>of</strong> gold necessary to cancel the debt. Nowadays it is rarely shipments <strong>of</strong><br />

gold, it is also not shipments <strong>of</strong> paper dollars, but foreign sales <strong>of</strong> treasury bonds to a foreign central bank which<br />

holds them as currency reserves (and may or may not issue domestic currency because it has more reserves now).<br />

Next Message by Elias is [1191].<br />

[1235] Alee: One example is paying a student loan or a house mortgage. You are living in<br />

the house already bought but you’re still paying for it. Second example is a country paying<br />

its debt for the imports/export that they have made.<br />

Next Message by Alee is [1236].<br />

[1269] Smalls: A savings account would be money as money. You are storing your money<br />

in a savings account not to measure value or for means <strong>of</strong> circulation, but just as money. A<br />

bribe would also be money as money. The person asking for the bribe wants nothing more<br />

than to receive the money.<br />

Hans: The act <strong>of</strong> depositing money into a savings account or withdrawing it from a savings account is a transaction<br />

in which money functions as money. It is the modern counterpart to using money as a hoard.<br />

In some countries with poorly developed tax collection systems, bribes are used to finance government services.<br />

The bribe necessary to get a passport, is that money as money or as means <strong>of</strong> circulation?<br />

Next Message by Smalls is [1270].


118 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1274] Shickadance: graded A One example <strong>of</strong> where money functions simply as money<br />

and not a measure <strong>of</strong> value is when the United States pays <strong>of</strong>f a debt to Germany. Another<br />

example is when Person A pays <strong>of</strong>f a loan to a bank which he had received to purchase a<br />

car. In these examples, the creditor is receiving payment on the things which the debtor is<br />

already using and enjoying. Money is not measuring value or being a means a <strong>of</strong> circulation;<br />

it is only functioning as money.<br />

Hans: Yes. Money is not measuring value because the price was agreed on when the good was ordered.<br />

Next Message by Shickadance is [1275].<br />

[1285] Littlerock: graded A+ Money as Money. Money functions as money when it is<br />

being used as a hoard. In that case, money is not being circulated, it is in its pure value form.<br />

Money is also being used as money when it is used to pay interest on a debt.<br />

Hans: Interest payment is a good example, and I don’t remember it in the archives. When money is used to pay<br />

taxes it is also used as money.<br />

Next Message by Littlerock is [1286].<br />

[1331] Gunther: graded C One <strong>of</strong> example <strong>of</strong> using money as money and not merely as a<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> value would be if I wanted to buy a new car I couldn’t trade 1,000 blankets for it<br />

even if it carried the same exchange value. Therefore, you would have to use the money in<br />

order to purchase the car and not make a trade for it. Also, there are people who buy houses<br />

under the market rates and fix them up to sell them and make a pr<strong>of</strong>it. Meanwhile, there<br />

are families in need <strong>of</strong> shelter that just buy a home to live in and keep for their own use and<br />

survival instead <strong>of</strong> the self-interested capitalist mindset <strong>of</strong> ‘getting gain.’


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 119<br />

Hans: If you were to buy the car or the house with cash, then money would not serve as money but only as means<br />

<strong>of</strong> circulation. In the more common case that you buy them on credit, money serves as measure <strong>of</strong> value at closing<br />

when you obligate yourself to the terms <strong>of</strong> the mortgage, and as money in every mortgage payment. The question<br />

whether the purchase M-C is part <strong>of</strong> C-M-C or M-C-M does not matter here.<br />

Next Message by Gunther is [1332].<br />

[1347] Speq: The first is when people hoard. Hoarders are not circulating money, but<br />

are instead, gaining utility from the use value <strong>of</strong> money. I.e. they find satisfaction in having<br />

money. The second is when money (namely gold) is melted down and converted to use<br />

value. I.e. converted into jewelry, dinner utensils, ornaments, etc.<br />

Hans: When a gold coin is melted down in order to be used for jewelry, then it is not used as money but as a<br />

natural use-value. (This is a different use-value than the use-value <strong>of</strong> knowing one can purchase anything with<br />

money, which Marx would call the “formal” use-value <strong>of</strong> money.)<br />

Next Message by Speq is [1350].<br />

[1382] Amcelhiney: 1) Monetary payment to settle a debt after the merchandise has<br />

already changed hands.<br />

2) Hoarding the money—not to increase its value over a long period <strong>of</strong> time, but simply<br />

not to use it.<br />

Hans: Penalty for editing your answer. You are required to type in your answers <strong>of</strong> the designated exam questions<br />

without editing them.<br />

You had originally “after the payment has already changed hands.” I changed it to make it correct.<br />

Next Message by Amcelhiney is [1403].


120 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1385] ZachS: graded C 1. When it’s used to purchase a commodity such as gold because<br />

gold is the measure <strong>of</strong> value outside <strong>of</strong> any currency.<br />

2. When purchasing items needed for everyday living.<br />

Hans: In both examples money does not function as money.<br />

Next Message by ZachS is [1388].<br />

Exam Question 528 is 197 in 1995WI, 176 in 1995ut, 210 in 1996sp, 227 in 1997WI, 280<br />

in 1997ut, 299 in 1999SP, 317 in 2000fa, 336 in 2001fa, 380 in 2003fa, 425 in 2004fa,<br />

432 in 2007SP, 443 in 2008fa, 459 in 2009fa, 496 in 2010fa, and 506 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 528 Give examples for “advancing” and “expending” money.<br />

[1072] Agloeck: Example <strong>of</strong> advancing and expending money. If I buy a car at what<br />

I feel is a good “deal” with the intention <strong>of</strong> selling it again quickly at a pr<strong>of</strong>it then I am<br />

advancing money. I am trying to increase my hoard through the purchase and sale <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity. On the other hand, if I purchase a car to use as my primary vehicle then I am<br />

expending money.<br />

Hans: Good example. But I would be very cautious in the judgment whether a car is really a good deal. Gas prices<br />

have to go up, and there will be other disincentives for cars with low gas mileage (such as higher registration fees).<br />

Cars which seem cheap today will turn out to be expensive in the future, the only question is whether this future is<br />

next year or five years from now.<br />

Next Message by Agloeck is [1082].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 121<br />

[1085] Shelly: graded A– M-C-M, advancing money. An example <strong>of</strong> “advancing” or<br />

“expending” money would be a capitalist purchasing the means <strong>of</strong> production and the commodity<br />

labor-power in order to produce products which will be sold for more than the capitalist<br />

pays in wages, thus realizing a pr<strong>of</strong>it. Another example would be if I purchased a pair<br />

<strong>of</strong> used shoes, polished them up, and then sold them for more than what I originally paid.<br />

Hans: Both are examples for “advancing” money. Marx reserves the word “expending” money for spending money<br />

for final consumption, where the money does not come back with a pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Next Message by Shelly is [1086].<br />

[1245] PJM: Advancing Versus Expending. Advancing money is the term used for<br />

exchanging money for a product with the intention to sell the product for more money.<br />

A classic example <strong>of</strong> advancing money is the capitalist performing M-C-M’, who throws<br />

money into exchange for labor power with the intention <strong>of</strong> getting more money M’, out <strong>of</strong><br />

the exchanging. Expending money, on the other hand, involves exchanging money in order<br />

to get a product that one intends to consume, such as buying a house in order to live in.<br />

Next Message by PJM is [1246].<br />

[1310] Frankie: graded A Advancing money is when you buy a commodity or good with<br />

the intention <strong>of</strong> selling it for a pr<strong>of</strong>it. In light <strong>of</strong> the Hostess Brand recently going bankrupt,<br />

an example would be buying a box <strong>of</strong> twinkies with the intention <strong>of</strong> selling them again at a<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it.


122 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Expending money is purchasing something for final consumption. An example that goes<br />

along with the previous example would be buying a box <strong>of</strong> twinkies and eating them for<br />

personal utility and consumption.<br />

Next Message by Frankie is [1311].<br />

[1312] Agloeck: Examples <strong>of</strong> money. I gave the following example in the mailing list<br />

and I will use it again here. If I purchase a car from my friend at below market value with the<br />

intent to sell it quickly in order to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it then I am advancing money. If I purchase the<br />

same car for my own use as my primary vehicle then I am expending money. After reading<br />

your comment I agree that I would need to take into account gas prices to evaluate whether<br />

the car is actually a “deal”.<br />

In case it is not okay to repeat myself, I have another real life example. My friend goes to<br />

baby clothing stores and buys sale items then immediately sells them on ebay for more than<br />

she paid. That is advancing money. If she was buying the clothes for her own child to wear<br />

then that would be expending money.<br />

Next Message by Agloeck is [1313].<br />

[1377] Roosty: An example <strong>of</strong> “advancing” money would be to purchase an ipod <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong><br />

Ebay for a good (relatively speaking) deal, and then to sell it for pr<strong>of</strong>it. “Expending” money<br />

would be buying the ipod <strong>of</strong>f Ebay for my own personal use.<br />

Next Message by Roosty is [1381].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 123<br />

[1398] SLOVENEC: Advancing money is the process <strong>of</strong> buying a commodity for the<br />

purpose <strong>of</strong> reselling it for a higher price. In essence, you are buying more money. An<br />

example <strong>of</strong> this is buying a house, waiting a few months, and then reselling it at a price<br />

higher than you paid. Expending money is the process <strong>of</strong> spending money for consumption.<br />

An example <strong>of</strong> this is selling a chair to earn money that will be spent to feed your family<br />

that night.<br />

Next Message by SLOVENEC is [1399].<br />

[1400] IrwinFletcher: graded A An example <strong>of</strong> advancing money would be if we were<br />

to buy motorcycles and then turn around and sell them for more money than I bought them<br />

for, in order to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it. Expending money would be if I bought a house with the sole<br />

purpose to live in it and use it the way that it should be.<br />

Next Message by IrwinFletcher is [1402].<br />

[1414] GTIguy: Advancing money is the process <strong>of</strong> spending money with the intent on<br />

realizing a return. An example <strong>of</strong> this would be buying a home in order to fix it up and sell it<br />

for a pr<strong>of</strong>it in the future. Expending money is when money is spent without ever expecting<br />

a return. A good example <strong>of</strong> expending money is purchasing food. We buy food in order to<br />

survive but it eventually gets consumed and its value is lost.<br />

Hans: You are not allowed to re-write your answers to the designated exam questions.<br />

Next Message by GTIguy is [1415].<br />

[1420] Novatore: Marx outlays advancing money as the process <strong>of</strong> M-C-M’. In this<br />

process I am advancing my money by purchasing a commodity and then selling it at a higher


124 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

value. For example, I buy ten pounds <strong>of</strong> socks for twenty-four dollars and then sell them<br />

for thirty dollars. Expending money is the process by which a commodity is purchased for<br />

its use value alone, or the M-C portion <strong>of</strong> the C-M-C process. Buying rain boots so my feet<br />

won’t get wet is an example <strong>of</strong> expending money.<br />

Next Message by Novatore is [1421].<br />

[1423] Tiburon: -Advancing money can be done by re-investing the money into commodities<br />

or activities that would lead to a future return. By advancing the money, we take it<br />

further to another plane to get a pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

- Expending money is done when money is used to buy commodities that have no useful<br />

value or pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Hans: Your definition <strong>of</strong> expending money is wrong. (And you were asked to give examples, not definitions.)<br />

Next Message by Tiburon is [1424].<br />

[1428] Vini: One example for “advancing” versus “expending” money would be when<br />

stock is purchased. You advance money when pr<strong>of</strong>it is made when stock is bought at a lower<br />

price and then sold at a higher value. Pr<strong>of</strong>it is made for the purchaser because more money<br />

went back them then what was sent out. Expending would be when the buyer sits on the<br />

stock and no immediate sale is made ie, investment.<br />

Hans: Even if the stock is sold at a loss or not immediately sold again, its purchase is still an advance <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Expending money would be for consumption.<br />

Next Message by Vini is [1429].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 125<br />

Question 540 In the exchange process, it is clearly the objective <strong>of</strong> the traders to get as<br />

much in return for their commodity as possible. Likewise, it is clearly the objective <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalists to get as much return on their capital as possible. Nevertheless Marx analyzes the<br />

exchange as an equalization and abstracts from the quantitative differences, while his analysis<br />

<strong>of</strong> the circuit <strong>of</strong> capital explicitly takes the quantitative differences into consideration.<br />

Is this unequal methodology justified, or does it bias Marx’s results?<br />

[886] Jason: graded A+ Marx is More Interested in Social Relations than Individual<br />

Motivations. The initial methodology with which Marx analyses the circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

and the circulation <strong>of</strong> capital are not unequal. He begins by looking at the practical<br />

actions (from which he makes inferences about motivations) <strong>of</strong> the agents participating in<br />

the process, and through an examination <strong>of</strong> the forms <strong>of</strong> circulation, he attempts to make<br />

inferences about the content <strong>of</strong> the social relations enabling and necessitating these actions.<br />

Marx is really interested in social processes, not individual actions, and this is clear from the<br />

beginning (he examines a capitalist society) <strong>of</strong> his investigation. His focus on social rather<br />

than individual content for his examination <strong>of</strong> circulation processes is consistent and justified.<br />

While the practical actions <strong>of</strong> both the traders and the capitalists may be similar in that<br />

both try to maximize their returns (motivations), the social content <strong>of</strong> exchange differs from<br />

the social content <strong>of</strong> capital - a discovery made from an investigation <strong>of</strong> the complete form<br />

<strong>of</strong> both commodity circulation and the circuit <strong>of</strong> capital.


126 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

The contradictions <strong>of</strong> direct barter are given room to move in the exchange process, the<br />

circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities. Individuals are looking both for social recognition <strong>of</strong> the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> their own commodity, as well as a particular use-value to satisfy their consumption needs.<br />

This contradiction breaks apart the direct barter transaction into two separate transactions,<br />

and causes a commodity to change forms as it moves through the circulation process. It<br />

moves from a non-use-value form to a value-form and finally to an immediate-use-value<br />

form. The content <strong>of</strong> this process, the social function it fulfills is “the transfer <strong>of</strong> the goods<br />

from those who produce them to those who use them (akmk, pg. 358).” These forms abstract<br />

from quantities, because quantity is not necessary to determine the form a commodity takes<br />

in this process. Marx admits there may be differences in the magnitudes <strong>of</strong> values, but (in<br />

case we had forgotten his previous developments in Chapter 1) “such differences are purely<br />

accidental (akmk, pg. 252:1).” Further, these abnormalities do not affect the content <strong>of</strong> the<br />

social relations driving the exchange. The most important thing, from the perspective <strong>of</strong><br />

social relations, is that commodities that are qualitatively different are exchanged - a process<br />

made possible by their quantitative equality that sustains the division <strong>of</strong> labor in capitalism.<br />

Accidental quantitative differences <strong>of</strong> value are irrelevant. In addition, Marx has already<br />

explained in the section on the secret <strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity that the<br />

motivations <strong>of</strong> the traders to maximize their returns only reinforce the social relation <strong>of</strong> equal<br />

value in exchange.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 127<br />

In a similar examination <strong>of</strong> the circulation <strong>of</strong> capital, Marx comes to a different conclusion.<br />

The individual agents in this case are using money to purchase a commodity, which<br />

they then use to purchase money. He first abstracts from quantities to determine the forms<br />

<strong>of</strong> the M-C-M process. But when he tries to make inferences about the social content <strong>of</strong><br />

M-C-M from its forms, it seems to be empty and meaningless. Money is replaced by money.<br />

No qualitative change occurred. But “M-C-M is too prevalent not to have a social content<br />

(akmk, pg. 358).” Marx’s original attempt to probe deeper levels <strong>of</strong> reality beyond the surface<br />

actions <strong>of</strong> the individuals was unsuccessful with an abstraction from quantities. He<br />

must swim back to the surface and acknowledge quantitative differences, for the individuals<br />

would not engage in M-C-M at all if not for the quantitative difference. This has a direct<br />

impact on the social content. Also, since the M-C-M’ process ends where it started, with<br />

money and not consumption, the process is endless. The measure <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> capital is able<br />

to, and must expand endlessly. The motivations <strong>of</strong> the capitalist become fused with the content<br />

<strong>of</strong> this circulation process. A social relation, capital, now acts through an agent, the<br />

capitalist. Marx says in the capitalist capital is “personified and endowed with a will (akmk,<br />

pg. 254:1).”<br />

Since Marx is not immediately interested in individuals and their motivations, but in the<br />

content <strong>of</strong> social relations, he must abstract from quantitative differences in value in the<br />

exchange. But the individual motivations (the valorization <strong>of</strong> capital) <strong>of</strong> the capitalist are<br />

fused with the social content <strong>of</strong> capital, making quantitative abstraction impossible.


128 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Marx loved inversions and I wonder if it tickled him the content <strong>of</strong> the process C-M-C<br />

owes its content to an exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities that is quantitatively equal but qualitatively<br />

different, while the process M-C-M owes its content to a process that is only quantitatively<br />

different at both its “M-poles.”<br />

Hans: Marx was certainly aware <strong>of</strong> this inversion: qualitative difference and quantiative equality versu quantitative<br />

difference and qualitative equality. He considered the circulation <strong>of</strong> capital to be the negation <strong>of</strong> the simple<br />

circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Next Message by Jason is [918].<br />

[1151] Diego: graded A When we review the exchange process in detail with Marx he<br />

makes it clear that we must consider the dual nature <strong>of</strong> value when we exchange goods.<br />

Parties may both gain in an exchange as they are both looking to trade to get a different<br />

use-value from what they had before the trade. In terms <strong>of</strong> use-value each party should gain<br />

more in the exchange then they started with. When we then look at a commodity’s value, it<br />

is a zero-sum game as no new value can be created in exchange, even in the case where an<br />

exchange is uneven no new value is created, but value is transferred. (Hans, [2005fa:1791].)<br />

Marx has made this clear in the study <strong>of</strong> surplus-value that value is only created via labor<br />

exploitation in the production process and not in exchange.<br />

Next Message by Diego is [1152].<br />

[1157] Curtis: graded A+ Different exchange processes. The unequal methodology is<br />

justified. In the exchange process, such as C-M-C, the end result is C-C, and it is use-value<br />

that is that is desired, and can be justified on grounds other than maximization <strong>of</strong> value. The


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 129<br />

capital circuit, M-C-M, ends in the same form, M-M, and cannot be justified unless there is<br />

a difference in the first M and the second M (so we could say M’ = M + ∆M), so quantity in<br />

M-C-M’ is an important factor, otherwise there would be no reason to participate.<br />

Next Message by Curtis is [1159].<br />

[1337] KapitalSB: graded C The method during the exchange process is getting as much<br />

as possible from their commodity. This unequal method is justified because the value one<br />

receives from one commodity is different then the value another receives. Marx analyzes<br />

the exchange as equal is different then Marx analysis <strong>of</strong> circuit <strong>of</strong> capital because <strong>of</strong> the removal<br />

<strong>of</strong> quantitative differences during the exchange. Marx is not interested in individual’s<br />

motivations but is interested in social relations.<br />

Hans: You are confusing value and use-value.<br />

Next Message by KapitalSB is [1339].<br />

[1500] Bear: graded C– The unequal methodology is justified in the sense that there<br />

are two separate objectives in mind. By analyzing the exchange process and looking at<br />

it as an equalization, Marx can look at the other factors which affect value: costs, labor<br />

requirements, and other aspects <strong>of</strong> production which give a commodity their value without<br />

regard for pr<strong>of</strong>it maximization. Although in his analysis <strong>of</strong> the circuit <strong>of</strong> capital, he examines<br />

the quantitative differences to examine motivations and methods behind pr<strong>of</strong>it maximization.<br />

The specifics remain the same but the perspective <strong>of</strong> the observation is changed.<br />

Hans: According to Marx’s theory, value is one-dimensional. It does not depend on costs and other aspects <strong>of</strong><br />

production, it only depends on the abstract labor that was used to produce the commodity.


130 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Marx would disagree with the characterization that he looks at the exchange as an equalization in order to derive<br />

what value is. He sees his analysis as the discovery <strong>of</strong> the principles underlying commodity production which has<br />

the result that the underlying driver is congealed abstract labor, the thing he calls “value.”<br />

Marx considers the personal enrichment motive <strong>of</strong> the capitalists important, but it is by no means the full<br />

explanation <strong>of</strong> capitalism. Capitalism is a social relation deeply anchored in the one-dimensional character <strong>of</strong><br />

wealth in commodity production. In order to overcome it, market relations must be replaced by other economic<br />

institutions organizing production and distribution.<br />

Next Message by Bear is [1501].<br />

Exam Question 573 is 307 in 1998WI, 341 in 2000fa, 359 in 2001fa, 391 in 2002fa, 405<br />

in 2003fa, 454 in 2004fa, 431 in 2005fa, 463 in 2007SP, 467 in 2007fa, 474 in 2008SP,<br />

477 in 2008fa, and 549 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 573 Is exchange (direct barter) a transaction in which both sides gain more<br />

than they give up?<br />

[897] Amcelhiney: If there is equality among exchange one side gains no more than the<br />

other. Only in use-value might one side gain more than the other. Any sort <strong>of</strong> advantage or<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it cannot be created with the exchange.<br />

Hans: Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> an equal exchange is not that both sides gain equally, but that neither side gains or<br />

loses, i.e. both sides come out even.<br />

In preparation <strong>of</strong> the second exam, everyone should be familiar with answer [2005fa:1791] to this question.<br />

Next Message by Amcelhiney is [959].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 131<br />

[1132] Pepe: graded B Exchange is a transaction where both sides gain more than they<br />

lose, if it wasn’t either party would not participate in the exchange. Different parties have<br />

different needs and use-values, thus exchange can be optimal for both sides.<br />

Hans: Both gain only in terms <strong>of</strong> use-value, not in terms <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Next Message by Pepe is [1133].<br />

[1145] Abysmal: graded B– Exchange is not a transaction in which both sides gain more<br />

than they give up. This is a neo-classical interpretation <strong>of</strong> trade that assumes that both<br />

sides gain more marginal utility from the transaction. However, Marx’s theory is not based<br />

around marginal utility, but rather value, and it would be impossible for both sides to gain<br />

more value from an exchange. In the Marxian conception <strong>of</strong> an exchange, participants by<br />

nature typically trade commodities <strong>of</strong> equal values (meaning that they required the same<br />

socially necessary labor time and the same amount <strong>of</strong> congealed abstract labor in order to<br />

produce). Therefore, exchanging leaves each side with the same amount <strong>of</strong> value, but in<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> use-values that are more useful to them.<br />

Hans: It is a big misunderstanding <strong>of</strong> Marx to think that people like to trade equal values, or that this is fair<br />

or “natural” to them. Values are immanent in the commodities, they are created in production, not in exchange.<br />

Therefore an exchange will not increase the values <strong>of</strong> the goods exchanged, and if one gets more value out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

exchange this is because the other gets less value.<br />

Next Message by Abysmal is [1163].<br />

[1148] ImmanentMaterialist: An exchange (also understood as a direct barter) is, by<br />

definition, a transaction in which neither party gains or loses any <strong>of</strong> the value that they


132 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

possessed before the occurrence <strong>of</strong> the exchange. So in regards to the above question, no,<br />

neither party would gain (or for that matter lose) and value in the exchange.<br />

Hans: A complete answer also looks at the use-value aspect <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

Regarding values, it is very possible that unequal values are exchanged. In this case, one person gains what the<br />

other person loses.<br />

Next Message by ImmanentMaterialist is [1149].<br />

[1164] Stig: test resubmission. Yes. Hans states that direct barter, or exchange, is a<br />

“zero sum” transaction, as far as value is concerned. However, for use value both parties are<br />

‘giving up’ a commodity for which they do not have use for one that they do. We expect that<br />

if both parties did not gain use values from the exchange that they wouldn’t do it! Therefore<br />

neither party loses (on an aggregate level) exchange value but both gain use value.<br />

Next Message by Stig is [1165].<br />

[1170] SVN: Yes. Each side is out to gain more than they gave up, otherwise a trade would<br />

not take place if each side ended up the exact way at which they started. For example, the<br />

linen weaver who has linen coming out her ears has no use value for so much linen. To her<br />

these is nothing to be gained by weaving more <strong>of</strong> what she doesn’t need, so she takes it to<br />

market to trade up for something she values more. Winter is coming and she has no coat, os<br />

she trades however much linen she has to, to gain a coat from the tailor. In the linen weaver’s<br />

eyes she has gained more than she has given up, for she badly needed the new coat, and all<br />

she had to do was give up some <strong>of</strong> her linen that does not mean much to her. The coat tailor<br />

who has been selling tons <strong>of</strong> coats for winter needs more linen to make more coats to keep up


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 133<br />

with the pace <strong>of</strong> the quickly selling coats. So in the tailor’s eyes he gained something more<br />

valuable to him because more linen signifies more coats he can make to keep his business<br />

running.<br />

Hans: But in terms <strong>of</strong> value, it is a zero sum game, i.e., what one gains the other loses.<br />

Next Message by SVN is [1171].<br />

[1177] RikkiAllie: The exchange has to be beneficial to both parties. They must both be<br />

gaining a commodity or value that they previously were not able to obtain.<br />

Hans: Yes, but terms <strong>of</strong> value, i.e., in terms <strong>of</strong> their access to society’s wealth, exchange is a zero sum game.<br />

Next Message by RikkiAllie is [1178].<br />

[1186] Villa: graded A The exchange-value <strong>of</strong> the commodities are equal otherwise they<br />

couldn’t be exchanged. However, in use-value they both, the persons making the exchange,<br />

gain from the use-values they receive.<br />

Next Message by Villa is [1188].<br />

[1213] KATES: Exchange at direct barter is a transaction where both sides gain a commodity<br />

<strong>of</strong> need to them. In an exchange one person is giving up something that does not<br />

have as much value to them as it does to the person they are exchanging with and in return<br />

they are receiving something back that has value to them.<br />

Hans: What you call “value,” Marx would call “use-value,” while “value” for Marx has an entirely different meaning.<br />

When reading Marx you must use his terminology, otherwise it gets too confusing.<br />

Next Message by KATES is [1214].


134 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1219] Reeree: Exchange is a transaction in which both sides gain more; otherwise the<br />

exchange would have no purpose. Each individual desires something that the other person<br />

has, so an exchange will take place. In the end, the individuals have the commodity they<br />

desire and have traded something else that had less value to them.<br />

Hans: In this class you shouldd not use the word “value” if you are talking about what Marx would call “use-value.”<br />

If we read Marx we must use his terminology.<br />

Next Message by Reeree is [1220].<br />

[1256] Tim: graded A Is possible in terms <strong>of</strong> use-value, being that levels <strong>of</strong> need and<br />

desire vary. This ought not be true in terms <strong>of</strong> the exchange value <strong>of</strong> the things, as the<br />

exchange is under a condition <strong>of</strong> equalization.<br />

Hans: Even if unequal values are exchanged, it is not possible for both parties to gain value, since value is neither<br />

created nor destroyed by exchange.<br />

Next Message by Tim is [1257].<br />

[1308] Extraterrestrial: graded C Direct Barter is not a transaction in which both sides<br />

gain more than they give up. Everything, at the end <strong>of</strong> the barter, should be a wash. Each<br />

party is gaining something, some kind <strong>of</strong> use value but each party is also losing something<br />

that they trade with. Both parties definitely benefit but neither party gains. They come out<br />

equal.<br />

Hans: This contradictory situation that both sides benefit but it is a wash can be sorted out if you use the right<br />

categories.<br />

Next Message by Extraterrestrial is [1309].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 135<br />

[1368] Batgirl: An exchange, or a direct barter if you will, is not a transaction in which<br />

each side gains more than they give up. A bolt <strong>of</strong> fabric is worth the same to a tailor as it<br />

is to a weaver, same with the value <strong>of</strong> a coat to a tailor and a weaver. They may barter it<br />

for something that they personally value more in their minds, however on the makrket it is<br />

worth typically what it is bartered for.<br />

Hans: You have to distinguish between use-value and exchange-value in order to give a coherent answer.<br />

Next Message by Batgirl is [1371].<br />

[1431] Tony: graded B– No, the direct barter would gain an exchange equally. There is<br />

no more or less on a direct barter. The thing is that the value or use-value are equal except<br />

for the quantity that they exchange, i.e, 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen equal a coat<br />

Hans: Instead <strong>of</strong> writig “value or use-value” you should have distinguished between value and use-value because<br />

the answer is different for value than for use-value.<br />

Next Message by Tony is [1467].<br />

[1460] Steve: Yes. All parties in an exchange supposedly have a goal to maximize their<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it, and one would assume that if one party were to incur any loss in an exchange, acting<br />

as a rational agent, they would not participate in said exchange.<br />

Hans: Wrong answer. Pr<strong>of</strong>it is defined in terms <strong>of</strong> value. Exchange does not create value. The gains <strong>of</strong> all partners<br />

in an exchange are gains in use-value, not in value.<br />

Message [1460] referenced by [1483]. Next Message by Steve is [1461].<br />

Question 591 is 415 in 2003fa, 465 in 2004fa, 443 in 2005fa, 481 in 2007fa, 491 in<br />

2008fa, and 566 in 2011fa:


136 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Question 591 Why does Marx say at the and <strong>of</strong> chapter Five: “hic Rhodus, hic salta”?<br />

[895] SVN: Exploited. The reference to the story from Aesop’s Fable is not only fitting<br />

for the conclusion <strong>of</strong> the chapter but also is a perfect cliffhanger, leaving the reader wanting<br />

more. The entire chapter Marx continues to describe situations in which surplus-value cannot<br />

be created inside or outside <strong>of</strong> circulation. Page after page the reader twists and turns<br />

the mind to come up with an explanation <strong>of</strong> how pr<strong>of</strong>it through commodity exchange can<br />

actually be created. Finally when the end <strong>of</strong> the chapter is approaching and the reader thinks<br />

that Marx will reveal the secret behind pr<strong>of</strong>it, he tells the story <strong>of</strong> the braggart, continuing<br />

the frustration.<br />

He does this because the vast majority <strong>of</strong> people are not sure how capital all around them<br />

is being created. They know it is happening, but they do not know how it is taking place<br />

because they have never seen it with their own eyes. Just like the braggart, who claimed he<br />

had made an immense jump in Rhodes and someone replied to him “hic Rhodus, hic Salta.”<br />

They were saying that “here” is no different than Rhodes and he should do the jump here<br />

in front <strong>of</strong> them. They said not because they didn’t believe he could do it, but because they<br />

wanted to see for themselves how it was actually done. The braggart performing the jump<br />

in this secret place called Rhodes is the same thing as the capitalist performing his pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

churning athletics in private, keeping everyone in the dark as to what is actually happening.<br />

The commodity producing society and the supposed egalitarian structure <strong>of</strong> it, conceal the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 137<br />

exploitation <strong>of</strong> the worker. If the worker was not being exploited, there would not be such<br />

large pr<strong>of</strong>its. The capitalist goes against nature. His sole aim is to make money, he uses<br />

money to make more money, which was not the original intent <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Steeveegett [2008fa:754] phrases nicely what I am getting at when he says<br />

“capitalism seeks to hide the process through which value is made into<br />

more value—and it does it well. It is happy to show what it produced, yet<br />

reluctant to show us how. It doesn’t want people to know that this value<br />

is created from exploitation. Nor does it want me or you to know that our<br />

labor produces an exponentially higher value than we are paid.”<br />

Next Message by SVN is [948].<br />

[1344] Speq: Marx uses the phrase “Hic Rhodes, hic salta” (“Rhodes is here, Jump here”)<br />

to show that his point is shown now. The context Marx pulled the quote from is a story <strong>of</strong><br />

a man that says he could jump to Rhodes and that he could produce witnesses. A listener<br />

to his story says “Hic Rhodes, hic salta” which implies that he does not need witnesses, as<br />

he should be able to jump to Rhodes now to prove his point. The Annotations points out<br />

many differences between this story and the points Marx is making. (1) The capitalist isn’t<br />

pretending to be able to “jump to Rhodes”. He can jump, and we know because (2) the<br />

evidence is all around us. (3) In the story Rhodes is a faraway place, whereas the capitalist<br />

is doing it before our eyes. We just don’t know how. And finally, (4) we are not asking the


138 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

capitalist to do anything differently. We are the ones that need to change the way we look at<br />

things to better understand how the world works.<br />

Next Message by Speq is [1345].<br />

Exam Question 596 is 571 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 596 What is the difference between the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power and the value<br />

created by labor-power?<br />

[1102] AndyUte: graded A Labor Power. Labor-power’s value comes from the amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor-time needed to produce and reproduce itself. Labor-power creates value if it is used<br />

to produce a use-value that can be sold. The value created by labor-power will always exceed<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power so that capitalists can continue to take advantage <strong>of</strong> laborers and<br />

make pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Hans: Very good, but keep the causality straight in your last sentence. If the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power is not smaller<br />

than the value created by this labor-power then capitalists will not hire that person.<br />

Next Message by AndyUte is [1107].<br />

[1187] Jason: graded A Value <strong>of</strong> Labor-power and Value Created by Labor-power.<br />

The value <strong>of</strong> labor-power is the value <strong>of</strong> all the commodities required to sustain a worker at<br />

a given standard <strong>of</strong> living, at a given place and at a given time. Labor-power creates value if<br />

it is used to produce a use-value that can be sold. If the value <strong>of</strong> a worker’s labor power is not<br />

less than the value created by the consumption <strong>of</strong> this worker’s labor-power, then capitalists<br />

will not hire this worker.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 139<br />

Next Message by Jason is [1295].<br />

[1289] Kannon: The value <strong>of</strong> labor power is the amount necessitated to reproduce itself<br />

(so daily amount/hour). The value created by labor power is the value created for the capitalist<br />

in excess <strong>of</strong> labor power ( the amount that does not show up on the paycheck, so to<br />

speak). This is a major part <strong>of</strong> the mystification <strong>of</strong> wages Marx discusses and a demiurge <strong>of</strong><br />

the exploitative relation between workers and capitalists.<br />

Hans: Labor-power also creates the value that does show up on the pay check. But the difference between the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> labor-power and the value created by labor does not show up on the pay check.<br />

I also don’t understand your parenthesis “daily amount/hour.”<br />

Next Message by Kannon is [1291].<br />

[1303] JohnLennon: Marx would say that there is no value in labor-power because value<br />

lies in the commodity itself. The commodity is a tangible item with value whether it be usevalue<br />

or exchange-value or both. A commodity is produced by labor-power creating value<br />

in that commodity. Labor itself is not a commodity, a commodity is a good with use-value<br />

that can be used physically by a person. Value is in the tangible item, not in the intangible<br />

labor.<br />

Hans: Labor is not a commodity, but labor-power is.<br />

Next Message by JohnLennon is [1550].<br />

[1351] DJB: How the capitalist makes its pr<strong>of</strong>it. The value <strong>of</strong> labor power is the amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor put into a commodity, to be able to re-produce that same commodity. The value


140 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

created by labor power is the amount that is able to be sold. The capitalist will always want<br />

there to be a difference so he can continue to own the rights <strong>of</strong> production and be pr<strong>of</strong>itable.<br />

Next Message by DJB is [1469].<br />

[1369] Ula: Labor-Power. The “value <strong>of</strong> labor-power” is a commodity sold by an individual<br />

to a capitalist. The “value created by labor-power” is much greater than the “value <strong>of</strong><br />

labor-power” in that it includes the surplus labor performed to produce a commodity.<br />

Next Message by Ula is [1413].<br />

[1390] Brie: The value <strong>of</strong> labor-power is determined by the amount <strong>of</strong> labor-time required<br />

to produce a commodity, whereas labor-power creates value if it produces something with a<br />

use-value which can be sold.<br />

Hans: Wrong definition <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> labor-power.<br />

Next Message by Brie is [1539].<br />

[1436] MKW: The value <strong>of</strong> labor power is the wage which a worker is paid, while the<br />

value created by labor power is the price <strong>of</strong> the final good that the capitalist captures as a<br />

result <strong>of</strong> the worker’s labor when the commodity is sold.<br />

Next Message by MKW is [1437].<br />

[1448] Jess: graded B Difference between value <strong>of</strong> labor-power and value created by<br />

labor-power. Value <strong>of</strong> labor-power is how much your labor is worth to a capitalist. If you<br />

are a more efficient worker, your labor-power is worth more. You are able to produce more<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it (commodities) for the capitalist, because you are able to shorten the amount <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

time required for producing the commodity.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 141<br />

The value created by labor-power is the amount <strong>of</strong> extra “worth” you give to a commodity<br />

by producing it. Going back to my lumber vs. diamonds example in [1441], diamonds<br />

are worth more because they require more labor power to produce. The labor-power is<br />

essentially what creates the value <strong>of</strong> diamonds.<br />

Hans: What you call “value <strong>of</strong> labor-power,” Marx would call its use-value to the capitalist. The labor-power does<br />

not have any direct use-value to the worker (other than a means <strong>of</strong> exchange) because he or she does not have access<br />

to the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Next Message by Jess is [1534].<br />

Exam Question 600 is 247 in 1997WI, 321 in 1999SP, 374 in 2001fa, 422 in 2003fa, 450<br />

in 2005fa, 482 in 2007SP, and 574 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 600 Chapter Six is not the first place where labor-power is discussed.<br />

Where was labor-power introduced first, and which role did it play then? But the discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor-power in chapter Six introduces one fundamental new aspect <strong>of</strong> it which was not<br />

discussed before. What is it?<br />

[1113] Neela: graded A Labor-Power’s Roles. Although Chapter Six discusses laborpower,<br />

it is not where it was introduced first. Labor-power was first introduced in Chapter<br />

One. It played the role <strong>of</strong> the expenditure <strong>of</strong> physical human labor-power as the value in<br />

commodity production. However, in Chapter Six it is discussed in the role <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

Message [1113] referenced by [1118]. Next Message by Neela is [1114].


142 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1128] Justin: Labor power was first introduced in Chapter One in terms <strong>of</strong> its contribution<br />

to the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity. In Chapter Six it is discussed in terms <strong>of</strong> its<br />

role as a commodity itself.<br />

Hans: Labor-power contributes to the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity, and this value is expressed in the exchange-value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity. This is a two-step process, these steps should not be collapsed.<br />

Next Message by Justin is [1129].<br />

[1140] Shelly: graded A– Labor-Power. Labor-power was first introduced in Chapter 1 as<br />

the expenditure <strong>of</strong> human labor-power and the source <strong>of</strong> all value. In Chapter 6, labor-power<br />

is now discussed as a commodity, which the capitalist buys in order to generate surplus value.<br />

Hans: Your first sentence needs reformulation, perhaps say: “Labor-power was first introduced in Chapter 1,<br />

where Marx showed that the the expenditure <strong>of</strong> human labor-power is the source <strong>of</strong> all value.” See [2005fa:1134]<br />

for another formulation I can recommend.<br />

Next Message by Shelly is [1141].<br />

[1154] Diego: graded A Labor power was first discussed early in the book in Chapter 2<br />

as Marx was discussing the commodity. As this early point labor-power was only discussed<br />

as an input to the creation <strong>of</strong> commodities, that is, the laborers used their labor-power to<br />

create labor value as a part <strong>of</strong> a commodity’s value. Chapter 6 introduced the purchase <strong>of</strong><br />

labor-power by the capitalist via payment <strong>of</strong> a wage. The purchase <strong>of</strong> labor-power by the<br />

capitalist and not labor-value is fundamental to worker exploitation.<br />

First Message by Diego is [16].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 143<br />

[1156] Curtis: graded A Labor-Power. Labor-power was first introduced in chapter one.<br />

It was introduced as the common denominator between all commodities, allowing them to be<br />

related to each other. Value in all commodities is how much congealed abstract human laborpower<br />

the commodity contains. Chapter six now introduces labor-power as a commodity<br />

itself that can also be bought or sold by workers and capitalists.<br />

Next Message by Curtis is [1157].<br />

[1194] EricR: Labor-Power was first introduced on pages 131-134, (these pages are from<br />

Vol.1, not the blue binder book in class) when labor value was introduced or talked about.<br />

Chapter 6 in the form <strong>of</strong> M-C-(M+∆M) (∆ meaning surplus value). Labor-Power made<br />

this possible.<br />

Next Message by EricR is [1217].<br />

[1227] Carol: Labor power is first introduced in Chapter Three. The role it played then<br />

was to measure the commodity’s value. The new idea introduced is that <strong>of</strong> necessary labor.<br />

Next Message by Carol is [1237].<br />

[1318] AJH: New aspect <strong>of</strong> labor power. Labor power was first discussed when Marx<br />

talked about child labor and focused effort. The fundamental new aspect here is that labor<br />

power creates value.<br />

Next Message by AJH is [1320].


144 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1335] KapitalSB: graded C In chapter 3, labor power was first introduced as the labor<br />

that the wage earner sells to the capitalist, but in chapter 6 it discuss labor power as the labor<br />

used by the capitalist.<br />

Hans: The worker does not sell his labor, he sells his labor-power.<br />

Next Message by KapitalSB is [1336].<br />

[1453] Jag: Labor power was first introduced in Chapter One. Marx did not call it “labor<br />

power,” it just played a behind the scenes role whenever commodity production is talked<br />

about. Abstract human labor in commodity production is the expenditure <strong>of</strong> human labor<br />

power. The difference in Chapter Six is that labor power itself is a commodity.<br />

Hans: When I wrote “behind the scenes” in [2005fa:1134], I did not mean to say that it was not called “laborpower.”<br />

The main category <strong>of</strong> interest in chapter One was abstract human labor, which was defines as “expenditure<br />

<strong>of</strong> human labor-power.” “Labor-power was “behind the scenes” because it was needed for the definition <strong>of</strong> abstract<br />

human labor which took center stage in the discussion.<br />

Next Message by Jag is [1539].<br />

[1472] Skylerp: Labor-power was first introduced in chapter 1. From chapter 1 labor<br />

power was related to the actual human effort put forth to produce a commodity. This explaination<br />

helped Marx relate labor-power with value <strong>of</strong> that specific commodity. In chapter<br />

six he talks about labor-power to help explain relative surplus labor and how we derive it.<br />

He also relates labor-power to necessary labor to help explain the difference between labor<br />

power and labor value.<br />

Hans: Relative surplus-labor is introduced in chapter Twelve. Chapter Six introduced labor-power as a commodity<br />

and the difference between the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power and the value created by the consumption <strong>of</strong> labor-power.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 145<br />

Next Message by Skylerp is [1473].<br />

[1493] Chris: Labor-power was first discussed in Chapter 1. There, it was discussed as<br />

labor. In Chapter 6, labor-power is introduced as a commodity.<br />

Hans: Labor-power is not labor.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [1494].<br />

[1503] Bear: graded C Labor power was introduced when referring to labor in general.<br />

We examined the aspects <strong>of</strong> labor including labor power to signify that labor power could<br />

be used to explain value in a commodity. The value transferred into a commodity by the<br />

labor to produce it. The new aspect is bargaining power or the impact <strong>of</strong> labor on capital and<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its. We are discussing the same labor power from a new angle as its effect on production.<br />

Hans: Bargaining power is only an issue if you talk about commodities. The new aspect is that labor-power is a<br />

commodity.<br />

First Message by Bear is [645].<br />

Question 611 is 281 in 1996sp, 328 in 1998WI, 419 in 2002fa, 435 in 2003fa, 485 in<br />

2004fa, 462 in 2005fa, 494 in 2007SP, 499 in 2007fa, 506 in 2008SP, 509 in 2008fa, 532<br />

in 2009fa, and 569 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 611 Which two sets <strong>of</strong> conditions must be satisfied for labor-power to be a commodity?<br />

[902] IrwinFletcher: graded A As I was kicking this idea in my head I thought that<br />

there could be several different conditions to satisfy labor power to be a commodity. But


146 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

what Marx is looking for is to boil all <strong>of</strong> it down and get down to the root <strong>of</strong> labor power, to<br />

encapsulate the very essence <strong>of</strong> labor power and commodities. I have come to the conclusion<br />

that the components to satisfy labor power into a commodity are as follows:<br />

1. The laborer must be inclined to sale his labor power and not his product from his<br />

labor power. There is a huge difference between the two things. [2009fa:671] Urka said<br />

“the laborer selling labor power must be separated from at least one portion <strong>of</strong> the labor<br />

process as well as the means <strong>of</strong> production, for if they were involved with the entirety <strong>of</strong> the<br />

production process they would be selling the commodity rather than their labor power”. I<br />

agree with this because if they sold the product <strong>of</strong> the labor power then that would eliminate<br />

the necessity <strong>of</strong> selling labor power.<br />

2. There must be no strings attached to the labor power. The laborer should be free to<br />

do as he pleases when it comes to the subject <strong>of</strong> the labor power. Setting prices, terms and<br />

conditions <strong>of</strong> contracts, duration <strong>of</strong> time etc.<br />

Next Message by IrwinFletcher is [904].<br />

[1140.1] Basil: Two Conditions for Labor-Power. The two set <strong>of</strong> conditions that must<br />

be satisfied for labor-power to be a commodity are: 1) Freedom <strong>of</strong> the laborer to sell his or<br />

her labor-power, 1a) Laborers must be the sole seller <strong>of</strong> their labor power, 1b) The laborer<br />

must have free disposal to use their labor-power, 1c) The seller and buyer <strong>of</strong> labor-power<br />

must be legally equal, 1d) The worker must sell themselves only for limited periods <strong>of</strong> time<br />

(they can’t sell themselves into slavery). 2) The laborer can only sell their labor-power but


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 147<br />

not the products <strong>of</strong> their labor, 2a) The laborer must be deprived <strong>of</strong> access to pre-existing<br />

products, 2b) The laborer must be deprived <strong>of</strong> having things to consume before producing,<br />

2c) The laborer cannot benefit from their labor-power until the product <strong>of</strong> their labor is sold<br />

(Annotations P. 410). If the above two conditions were not necessary, then laborers could<br />

produce value for themselves and reap the rightful benefits.<br />

If the question had mistakenly been read “What set <strong>of</strong> conditions must be satisfied for<br />

labor-power to become, or be turned into, a commodity?” then the following answers would<br />

be relevant: 1) Labor-power must be consumed through a means <strong>of</strong> production. 2) Laborpower<br />

must create value in the form <strong>of</strong> an exchangeable use-value. Because labor power is a<br />

commodity, it must be consumed to create value as a commodity, and this can only be done<br />

through a means <strong>of</strong> production–because the capitalists control the means <strong>of</strong> production, laborers<br />

are forced to rent their labor-power to them in order to expend it for creation <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

For labor-power to become a commodity, it must produce something that is exchangeable–if<br />

a use-value is not exchangeable, then it is not a commodity.<br />

Next Message by Basil is [1141.1].<br />

[1201] Gladwell: graded A Free To and Free From. The first condition that must be<br />

satisfied for labor-power to be a commodity is that the laborer must be free to choose whether<br />

or not to sell the labor-power. She must be the one selling her own labor, and it must be done<br />

for a finite period <strong>of</strong> time [2010fa:827].


148 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

The second condition that must be satisfied is that the laborer must be free from the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production. The laborer cannot be selling the actual product, but must instead sell<br />

her labor-power to the capitalist. If the laborer was able to sell the final product, she would<br />

earn more pr<strong>of</strong>it, and do that instead [2009fa:1067].<br />

Next Message by Gladwell is [1202].<br />

[1228] AndyUte: graded A– Firstly, the laborer must be in the business <strong>of</strong> selling his<br />

labor-power and freely choose to do so. He must not be coerced or made to do so. Secondly,<br />

the laborer must not be looking to use his labor-power to produce a commodity. He must<br />

rely and be dependent on the capitalist and his means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Hans: Marx would say: even if there is no formal coercion, the workers are coerced by their social situation. This<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory is not evident in your upbeat answer.<br />

Next Message by AndyUte is [1229].<br />

[1282] Bimmer: graded A There are two specific conditions that must be satisfied for<br />

labor-power to be a commodity. The two conditions are that the laborer must be able to sell<br />

their labor-power which is their ability to work. The second condition is that the laborer is<br />

limited in that he/she can not produce a final good to be sold in the open market.<br />

The first condition says that the laborer must be able to sell their labor-power. The amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor-power or work sold is based upon the amount that the laborer wants to sell. Furthermore,<br />

the work can not be coerced out <strong>of</strong> the laborer. The laborer must be able to sell his/her<br />

labor on their conditions. They must be able to enter into a contract and leave a contract<br />

willingly and when they decide. By this I mean at the end <strong>of</strong> his contract he can chose to


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 149<br />

continue working or not. This freedom is part <strong>of</strong> the first condition. The final last point <strong>of</strong><br />

the first condition is based on the the previous sentence. Since the laborer has the freedom<br />

to chose to enter and leave a contract, the labor sold is therefore only sold as a temporary<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> time.<br />

To continue on about the second condition is that the laborer’s labor-power is the reason<br />

why he/she can not sell a final good on the open market. The reason the laborer sells their<br />

labor-power, is for precisely this reason. The labor-power is what is added with the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production to create a final good. Since they don’t own the means <strong>of</strong> production, they can not<br />

own the final product or the commodity. Therefore labor-power is the commodity because<br />

you need labor-power along with the means <strong>of</strong> production to create a final good. Without one<br />

or the other you have a missing link. The capitalist owns the means <strong>of</strong> production; therefore,<br />

the commodity is labor-power.<br />

Next Message by Bimmer is [1324].<br />

Question 666 Explain how the transformation <strong>of</strong> money into capital at the same time does<br />

and does not take place in circulation.<br />

[918] Jason: graded A The Metamorphosis. With respect to the transformation <strong>of</strong> money<br />

into capital, Marx says “This metamorphosis, this conversion <strong>of</strong> money into capital, takes<br />

place both within the sphere <strong>of</strong> circulation and also outside it” (akmk, pg. 301:2/o). Here<br />

Marx is mostly recapitulating what was already discovered in Part II (Chapters 4-6). Marx


150 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

had already said “Capital cannot therefore arise from circulation, and it is equally impossible<br />

for it to arise apart from circulation. It must have its origin both in circulation and outside<br />

circulation” (akmk, pg. 268:2).<br />

Though the general formula <strong>of</strong> capital “immediately appears as M-C-M’ ‘’ (akmk, pg.<br />

257:1), the only way the circuit <strong>of</strong> capital can achieve self-valorization without violating<br />

the laws <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange is through the form <strong>of</strong> industrial capital - M-C...C’-M’.<br />

Capital is not only value in motion, but value attempting to expand by itself - in the process<br />

<strong>of</strong> achieving these aims, the transformation <strong>of</strong> money into capital occurs (and must occur)<br />

both within and outside <strong>of</strong> circulation.<br />

While money is the first form <strong>of</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> capital, money by itself cannot be capital.<br />

In order to be capital, value must be exposed to a process, it must be set in motion. As<br />

Marx says at the beginning <strong>of</strong> Chapter 6 “The change <strong>of</strong> value, by which money transforms<br />

itself into capital, cannot take place as long as it remains in the form <strong>of</strong> money...if it retains<br />

the form <strong>of</strong> money, it petrifies into a mass <strong>of</strong> value unchanging magnitude” (akmk, pg.<br />

270:1). So the capitalist, being the embodiment <strong>of</strong> capital, and acting on its behalf “throws”<br />

money into circulation (M-C) in the hope the money will one day return to him in a greater<br />

quantity. But, as we learned in Chapter 5, mere circulation does not create value, and the<br />

process <strong>of</strong> exchange is an exchange <strong>of</strong> equivalents. Merchant’s capital, or direct M-C-M’<br />

seems contradictory.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 151<br />

In Chapter 6, however, we learn the solution to the mystery <strong>of</strong> surplus-value rests in the<br />

purchase and consumption <strong>of</strong> a very special commodity - labor-power. While the purchase <strong>of</strong><br />

the labor-power occurs on the market, and in the sphere <strong>of</strong> circulation, in order to utilize the<br />

commodity labor-power, the capitalist must consume this commodity - they must exit to the<br />

private sphere <strong>of</strong> production, outside the realm <strong>of</strong> circulation. Industrial capital is the form<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital in which self-valorization is possible, without breaking the laws <strong>of</strong> commodity<br />

exchange. Equivalent values are always exchanged, yet the capitalist walks away with more<br />

value than the equivalent for the value advanced. This can occur because the productive<br />

consumption <strong>of</strong> labor-power, an act outside the sphere <strong>of</strong> circulation, leads to the creation <strong>of</strong><br />

a product with more value than the inputs into the production process.<br />

To continue the quote from the beginning <strong>of</strong> this essay (akmk, pg. 301:2/o), Marx says<br />

“...within the circulation, because conditioned by the purchase <strong>of</strong> the labor-power in the market...”<br />

Here, Marx means two things: (1) that labor-power becomes a commodity converted<br />

into capital, which the capitalist has advanced money in the market (the sphere <strong>of</strong> circulation)<br />

in order to acquire; and (2) the availability <strong>of</strong> wage-labor on the market is a historical<br />

necessity for the transformation <strong>of</strong> money into capital (akmk, pg. 272:3/o). Marx continues<br />

“...outside the circulation because what is done within it is only a stepping-stone to the production<br />

<strong>of</strong> surplus value, a process which is entirely confined to the sphere <strong>of</strong> production.”<br />

In other words, while the purchase <strong>of</strong> the commodity labor-power (and the means <strong>of</strong> production)<br />

starts the necessary motion needed to transform money into capital, these commodities


152 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

cannot just be resold with the expectation <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it. Instead, the capitalist must withdraw to<br />

the sphere <strong>of</strong> production to productively consume his (purchased) labor-power - a process<br />

that can yield surplus-value. The final step, not mentioned here, is a return to the sphere <strong>of</strong><br />

circulation with the output <strong>of</strong> the labor-process - capital in the form <strong>of</strong> a commodity, which<br />

contains surplus-value. After the commodity has been sold in the market, and capital has<br />

returned to the money form (now M’), the process can be repeated.<br />

It is this process, where money enters into circulation by advancing itself for the use-value<br />

labor-power (and other means <strong>of</strong> production, but especially labor-power), followed by the<br />

consumption <strong>of</strong> this labor-power in the production process, outside <strong>of</strong> circulation, and the<br />

realization <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the product <strong>of</strong> this productive consumption in the market, which is<br />

the transformation <strong>of</strong> money into capital. Three things are important to note in this process:<br />

(1) This process occurs both inside and outside circulation; (2) M-C-M’ does occur (though<br />

maybe more accurate would be M-(C+L)-C’-M’) - value is set in motion, surplus-value is<br />

created, so value has self-valorized, and money has become capital; and (3) the laws <strong>of</strong><br />

commodity exchange, i.e., equal values are exchanged for equal values, are not violated.<br />

Next Message by Jason is [922].<br />

[1370] Agloeck: Magic money. The transformation <strong>of</strong> money into capital appears as a<br />

magical process upon first glance. Marx <strong>of</strong> course delves into the process <strong>of</strong> circulation and<br />

production to see how this “magic trick” <strong>of</strong> capital is actually accomplished. He finds that it<br />

happens in and out <strong>of</strong> circulation.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 153<br />

First the capitalist has to purchase the means <strong>of</strong> production such as raw materials and<br />

machinery—which are all products <strong>of</strong> past or abstract labor. The capitalist must buy these<br />

commodities at market values which are subject to the rules <strong>of</strong> exchange—which is socially<br />

necessary labor. For example, if the capitalist was producing clothing it would not be socially<br />

necessary to purchase solid gold scissors for his workers to use when regular steel scissors<br />

would produce the same results.<br />

The next step <strong>of</strong> capital creation takes place outside <strong>of</strong> circulation in the labor process.<br />

The material and labor are purchased in the marketplace at their value but then put to work<br />

to create more value during the production process out <strong>of</strong> sight <strong>of</strong> the marketplace. The<br />

labor-power the capitalist purchased revives the “dead” means <strong>of</strong> production through the<br />

labor process and gives the commodity a new form <strong>of</strong> value. The value is not just equal to<br />

the inputs but has surplus-value.<br />

Marx outlines this process at the end <strong>of</strong> chapter 5 when he says that the money owner<br />

“must buy his commodities at their value, sell them at their value, and yet at the end <strong>of</strong> the<br />

process withdraw more value from circulation that he threw into it at the beginning” (pg.<br />

269). What appears magical in this transformation <strong>of</strong> money into capital is the congealed<br />

labor contained in the commodity produced.<br />

Hans: No, the magic lies in the fact that the consumption <strong>of</strong> labor-power produces more value than is necessary<br />

for the labor-power to reproduce itself.<br />

Next Message by Agloeck is [1471].


154 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1411] GTIguy: The transformation from money to capital depends on one’s perspective.<br />

When money is in circulation it is constantly changing hands. As it moves from one hand to<br />

the next it changes from money to capital and back again upon the next transaction.<br />

Hans: Wrong definition <strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

Next Message by GTIguy is [1414].<br />

[1427] Vini: The transformation into capital from money both does and does not take<br />

place in circulation because it all factors into how the individual will use the capital. Money<br />

can turn into the capital in the exchange process and from this point can either be sat on or<br />

stabilized for growth or investment or further purpose down the line or can be transformed<br />

back into monetary acquisition with further or more immediate exchange. One example<br />

would be the purchase <strong>of</strong> stock at one point in time (money → capital) which can then either<br />

be held on to, ending immediate circulation, or sold when stock value is higher, advancing<br />

circulation (capital → money).<br />

Hans: You are only talking about monetary values. Money is sterile; it cannot grow its value. The process when<br />

this growth actually occurs is outside circulation.<br />

Next Message by Vini is [1428].<br />

Question 683 Would Marx agree that the minimum length <strong>of</strong> the working day is the time the<br />

worker needs to earn enough money to make a living?<br />

[939] Villa: graded A– Necessary labor equals making a living. If necessary labor<br />

denotes the amount <strong>of</strong> hours a laborer must work in order to make a living then yes when


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 155<br />

setting surplus labor or b—c equal to 0 the result is a minimum length <strong>of</strong> the working day.<br />

This tends to be in only in theory. Marx knows that the capitalist system knows little if any<br />

minimums because the system is based on surplus value. The capitalist yearns to become<br />

wealthy, developing power on the backs <strong>of</strong> the laborer. Interesting to note that Marx utilizes<br />

the phrase “necessary labor” and not something like “worker’s labor”; his use <strong>of</strong> the phrase<br />

shows his view <strong>of</strong> capitalism, how the worker should be treated in his view. The formulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> this fact is the basis for which we can see that in theory surplus value or exploitation is<br />

not necessary, but that in practice it is an inevitability and otherwise capitalism would not<br />

function.<br />

Hans: Wrong definition <strong>of</strong> necessary labor, see multiple choice question 724. What is called “necessary labor”<br />

does not depend on Marx’s views how workers should be treated, but on simple economics.<br />

Using the same definition <strong>of</strong> necessary labor as Marx, you are right that capitalism can only exist if the working<br />

day is longer than the necessary labor. The bright side here is that economics does not dictate how much longer the<br />

working-day must be. If workers fight for higher wages, they make the necessary labor longer and the surplus-labor<br />

shorter. Capitalists may not like that, therefore they try to pretend the economy comes to a screetching halt if wages<br />

are raised, but this is not true.<br />

Message [939] referenced by [940] and [949]. Next Message by Villa is [961].<br />

[940] Jag: How much is needed to survive? I don’t believe that Marx would agree that<br />

the minimum length <strong>of</strong> the working day is the time the worker needs to earn enough money<br />

to make a living. Marx says nothing about the minimum amount <strong>of</strong> hours in his text. Villa’s<br />

statement about capitalists in [939] is perfect when he states that the capitalist system knows<br />

little if any minimums. In the capitalist system, workers could work all day and capitalists


156 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

would be happy because they are creating more money. The “necessary labor-time” could<br />

be confusing and some may think that it means the worker only needs the “necessary labortime”<br />

to survive, Marx means it’s the part <strong>of</strong> the working-day in which the worker produces<br />

an equivalent <strong>of</strong> his wages. I don’t think this means that the worker’s wage is necessarily the<br />

amount he needs to survive.<br />

Hans: You have the right definition <strong>of</strong> necessary labor, but you say two other things about Marx which puzzle me:<br />

(1) you say “Marx says nothing about the minimum amount <strong>of</strong> hours in his text.” Marx discusses the minimum<br />

length <strong>of</strong> the working-day in 341:2.<br />

(2) Even if you don’t think so, Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> wages is exactly that wages are determined by what the worker<br />

needs to survive at a modest standard <strong>of</strong> living. Marx thinks that wages are not determined by output.<br />

Message [940] referenced by [958]. Next Message by Jag is [1007].<br />

[949] Stig: Just enough to get by. Marx says: “. . . we have a minimum bound [to the<br />

working day], i.e., the part <strong>of</strong> the day which the laborer must necessarily work for his own<br />

maintenance.” [341:2] This is the amount <strong>of</strong> ‘time the worker needs [to work] to earn enough<br />

to make a living’, or provide for their own sustenance. So yes, Marx would agree with that<br />

statement.<br />

The workday is defined as A—-B—-C, which represents its division into two parts, A<br />

through B and B through C. A—-B is representative <strong>of</strong> the portion <strong>of</strong> the day the laborer<br />

needs to work to provide the most basic needs <strong>of</strong> survival, if his labor is less than this then<br />

he cannot survive and cannot continue working; A—-B is therefore the minimum length <strong>of</strong><br />

the working day.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 157<br />

B—-C is the remaining time worked by the laborer and the value he creates from that<br />

labor is essentially the pr<strong>of</strong>its for the capitalist who owns his means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

This is simply a longer explanation <strong>of</strong> what Villa says in [939] “. . . when setting surplus<br />

labor or b—c equal to 0 the result is a minimum length <strong>of</strong> the working day.“ Meaning that<br />

if the distance B—-C equals zero then the only part <strong>of</strong> the workday remaining is that part<br />

which provides minimum sustenance for the worker.<br />

I agree with Marx’s division <strong>of</strong> the workday, however I recognize it as a simplified form.<br />

An example I think <strong>of</strong> to complicate it is: most laborers in modern capitalist societies themselves<br />

receive a surplus from their labor. Very few laborers actually receive exactly enough<br />

to make ends meet. Although I am very aware that it <strong>of</strong>ten feels that way (like for me, now),<br />

there is usually a net gain by the worker i.e. net savings, or making payments on a house<br />

that include principal not only interest. This extra division does not help explain where capitalists’<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its come from and therefore was not necessary to include here, but I still wonder<br />

what Marx would think about it and how it would fit into his theory. Any ideas?<br />

Hans: You misunderstand what Marx says in 341:2, and Marx is not terribly clear. The time “the laborer must<br />

necessarily work for his own maintenance” is the time necessary for the worker to produce the things he or she is<br />

consuming, roughly in the USA today this is half a day, see [920] about that. It is not the time necessary to earn<br />

enough money to buy these things. Hourly wages are set up in such a way that the workers need all day to earn an<br />

equivalent <strong>of</strong> what they produce in the first half <strong>of</strong> the day.<br />

In your last paragraph you write that the worker gets ahead when they pay <strong>of</strong>f their mortgage. But they are <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

forced to take out a reverse mortgage when they retire. Counting over their whole lifetime they don’t get ahead. If


158 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

they happen to have something left over, <strong>of</strong>ten the medical bills <strong>of</strong> their last weeks use it up. Capitalism has ways<br />

to ensure that workers do not benefit from their labor.<br />

Next Message by Stig is [1164].<br />

[958] AR: Responding to [940], Marx would not agree that the minimum length <strong>of</strong> the<br />

working day is the time the worker needs to earn enough money to make a living. Jag [940]<br />

talks <strong>of</strong> necessary labor is important because it is the fixed time that needs to happen in order<br />

to get the job done. This is true but also, Marx mentions about surplus labor and how this<br />

carries day to day. Surplus labor is going to change and cannot be consistently calculated.<br />

Necessary labor and surplus labor are what make up the labor day not just the necessary<br />

labor-time.<br />

Hans: While question 683 formulates one <strong>of</strong> the usual wrong definitions <strong>of</strong> necessary labor, your answer formulates<br />

a different wrong definition. Multiple choice question 724 is an attempt to collect all these wrong definitions.<br />

Question 683 is wrong answer (b), and you are formulating a wrong answer similar to (e) which I added for future<br />

Semesters as (f). By the way, related multiple choice questions, where you can exercise this distinction more, are<br />

725 and 789.<br />

Next Message by AR is [1074].<br />

[1139.1] Pepe: graded C Marx would disagree with your assessment, because the minimum<br />

length <strong>of</strong> the working day is not the time needed for the worker to make a living, rather<br />

the time needed for the worker’s labor-value to produce enough for him to live on. The distinction<br />

is that the minimum length <strong>of</strong> the working day must take into account the worker’s<br />

labor-value, time wage, and ability to produce. Minimum work day would be incomplete<br />

without considering the value <strong>of</strong> said labor time.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 159<br />

Hans: The main difference is a different one: if a worker earns $15 per hour, then this does not mean his labor<br />

creates a value <strong>of</strong> $15 per hour. This value is usually around twice as much.<br />

Next Message by Pepe is [1162].<br />

[1143] Abysmal: graded A Marx would not agree that the minimum length <strong>of</strong> the working<br />

day is the time the worker needs to earn a living. Marx would say that the minimum length<br />

is actually the time it takes for the worker to reproduce the value <strong>of</strong> his or her labor power.<br />

Time in excess <strong>of</strong> this is that which produces surplus value for the capitalists. The minimum<br />

bound exists because, if it were not surpassed, there would not be surplus working time for<br />

the capitalists to pr<strong>of</strong>it from.<br />

Next Message by Abysmal is [1144].<br />

[1147] ImmanentMaterialist: If “the minimum length <strong>of</strong> the working day” is to be understood<br />

as necessary labor time, then no, this particular formulation is incorrect. Necessary<br />

labor time is determined by the amount <strong>of</strong> time that the worker spends producing a sum <strong>of</strong><br />

value that makes up for his or her daily wage, not by the requirements <strong>of</strong> their daily subsistence.<br />

For example, lets say a worker is paid $10 an hour and works 8 hours a day. Further,<br />

lets say that for every hour worked the laborer produces $25 in value for the capitalist. In<br />

this case, the necessary labor time would be 3 hours and 12 minutes as that would be the<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> time needed to reproduce the $80.<br />

Hans: Another difference is that between reproducing a value and earning a value.<br />

Next Message by ImmanentMaterialist is [1148].


160 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1176] RikkiAllie: A minimum working day could consist <strong>of</strong> only those hours needed<br />

for necessary labor, but the company would not be making a pr<strong>of</strong>it. Also, workers would<br />

be working less time and their wages would be lower. Marx also states that laborers should<br />

be earning and be compensated for their labor at a decent rate to not only live, but live<br />

comfortably. Marx also talks about the minimum bound. This minimum bound exists in<br />

theory but not in practice (annotations, 487). He believes that due to many factors including<br />

wages, the bounds are fluid. You cannot limit every company to a certain amount <strong>of</strong> hours<br />

that would be a beneficial minimum length.<br />

Hans: Your second sentence is wrong. The shorter the day, the higher the hourly wages, because the entire daily<br />

wage still has to feed the worker for a day.<br />

Next Message by RikkiAllie is [1177].<br />

[1214] KATES: Marx would not agree that the minimum length <strong>of</strong> the working day is<br />

the time the worker needs to earn enough money to make a living. Instead <strong>of</strong> determining<br />

the minimum bounds or length <strong>of</strong> the working day by the amount <strong>of</strong> time a worker needs<br />

to reproduce his wage Marx would instead say “in order to reproduce the value <strong>of</strong> his labor<br />

power.” If the workday is at this minimum not enough would be produced for the capitalists<br />

to skim <strong>of</strong>f their pr<strong>of</strong>it. This leads Marx to say the minimum itself is unattainable.<br />

Next Message by KATES is [1243].<br />

[1215] Stig: Marx states that ‘the minimum bound <strong>of</strong> the working day is indeterminable’<br />

[341:2]; he would agree, however, that necessary labor is the time the worker needs to earn<br />

enough money to make a living. Marx divides the working day (defined as a – b – c) into two


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 161<br />

parts: necessary labor and surplus labor. Necessary labor is given as a – b, and surplus labor<br />

as b – c. He defines a – b as the amount <strong>of</strong> time necessary to reproduce the equivalent <strong>of</strong> the<br />

laborer’s daily wage; this is the break even point for the capitalist any less and he is losing<br />

money to have the laborer work for him, anymore and he is making a pr<strong>of</strong>it. Therefore a – b<br />

is the absolute minimum workday possible.<br />

Marx, however, also notes that if the capitalist is not earning a pr<strong>of</strong>it then he will not<br />

engage in that activity when he states “On the basis <strong>of</strong> capitalist production, however, this<br />

necessary labor must always only form a part <strong>of</strong> the working-day; the working-day itself can<br />

never be reduced to this minimum.” [341:2] Therefore: in practice the working day must be<br />

to some degree greater than a – b and becomes a – b – c so that there is some (usually a lot)<br />

<strong>of</strong> surplus value (a – b – c).<br />

So, although Marx would recognize this as the theoretical minimum workday, he knows<br />

it doesn’t quite work out that way in practice but that the true minimum is larger than a – b.<br />

Hans: a – b would be the break-even point for the capitalist if he had to pay the same wage to the worker regardless<br />

<strong>of</strong> length <strong>of</strong> workday.<br />

Next Message by Stig is [1216].<br />

[1221] Reeree: Marx mentions that “a day’s labour is vague, it may be long or short.” The<br />

minimum length <strong>of</strong> the working day is the length in which the worker needs to work in order<br />

to survive. As where the maximum length is how much a worker can keep on producing<br />

without physically hurting themselves.


162 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: So would or wouldn’t Marx agree with the formulation in the question?<br />

Next Message by Reeree is [1222].<br />

[1238] Hans: Work Day Limits for Society. For an individual worker, it is true that he<br />

or she must work long enough every day to earn enough to make a living. But this criterion<br />

does not carry over to society at large.<br />

For society at large, the working day cannot be shorter than the time the worker needs to<br />

produce the value <strong>of</strong> the things he or she is consuming. As Marx sees it,<br />

(a) workers in capitalist society are only allowed to consume enough to maintain their<br />

labor-power (although the question <strong>of</strong> what counts as “enough” is not just bare survival but<br />

also depends on the outcomes <strong>of</strong> past labor struggles)<br />

(b) capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its come from surplus-labor or unpaid labor, i.e., labor which the workers<br />

performs for the capitalist without reimbursement.<br />

If the worker works only enough every day to maintain their labor-power, then the capitalists<br />

would not be able to pay the workers a wage below the value product <strong>of</strong> their labor<br />

and therefore would not be able to make pr<strong>of</strong>its (unless they want to depress the traditional<br />

standard <strong>of</strong> living <strong>of</strong> the workers, which is a change in the prevailing social structure that<br />

will probably lead to conflicts).<br />

The answer to this question is therefore: Marx would disagree with the question as formulated.<br />

The working day cannot be shorter than the time the worker needs to produce an


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 163<br />

equivalent <strong>of</strong> the things they need to maintain their labor-power. It must be longer, because<br />

this difference is the source <strong>of</strong> capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its. Only if the working-day is longer can the<br />

capitalist pay the worker a hourly wage which is less than the value the workers produce in<br />

that hour. The time the workers nees to earn a living is therefore strictly longer than the minimum<br />

length <strong>of</strong> the working day, because the worker must produce not only an equivalent <strong>of</strong><br />

his own wages but also the pr<strong>of</strong>its for the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [1241].<br />

[1307] Extraterrestrial: graded C The minimum length <strong>of</strong> the working day, according to<br />

Marx, is the amount <strong>of</strong> time necessary for a worker to work in order for a capitalist to make<br />

a pr<strong>of</strong>it. So no, Marx would not agree with this statement unless <strong>of</strong> course workers were<br />

actually paid what their labor power is worth.<br />

Hans: You are apparently talking about the break-even level. See questions 667 or 789.<br />

Next Message by Extraterrestrial is [1308].<br />

[1397] Tim: graded B– If we assume “a living” constitutes that which is required to earn<br />

enough wages to purchase the bare necessities <strong>of</strong> life; then yes, Marx would agree, since<br />

being deprived <strong>of</strong> this income level would render the worker uninterested in returning to<br />

work, or dead.<br />

Next Message by Tim is [1509].<br />

[1468] Tony: graded A Marx wouldn’t agree that the minimum length <strong>of</strong> the working day<br />

is the time the worker needs to earn enough money to make a living because the minimum<br />

length <strong>of</strong> the working day is not enough money for the worker needs to earn to make a


164 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

living. The formulation shows that in working-day, the hourly wages are the subsistence<br />

needs divided by working hours. The calculation shows that in capitalism, the workday set<br />

up first half <strong>of</strong> working day as a subsistence needs, and another half as a surplus value, but<br />

the thing is that in capitalism, they do not let the workers making enough money if they only<br />

work half <strong>of</strong> the day because the capitalist won’t be able to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Next Message by Tony is [1479].<br />

Exam Question 687 is 395 in 2000fa, 420 in 2001fa, 453 in 2002fa, 469 in 2003fa, 521<br />

in 2004fa, 495 in 2005fa, 537 in 2007SP, 536 in 2007fa, 544 in 2008SP, 575 in 2009fa,<br />

and 658 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 687 What are the minimal and maximal bounds for the length <strong>of</strong> the<br />

working-day, and how are they determined?<br />

[1083] Agloeck: minimum and maximum bounds. Marx says that the working day is<br />

not constant, but variable. Hans explains in annotations (p. 486) that variable means that<br />

there is no economic law which would force the total working-day to be a certain lengththere<br />

are just bounds for minimum and maximum length. The minimum length would be<br />

what workers need to receive in daily wages to pay for living expenses such as clothes,<br />

rent, utilities, food, etc. But the minimum is indeterminable. The maximum bound can<br />

be determined because it cannot be forced beyond a certain point. There are two ways to<br />

determine the maximum bound. First, by the physiological bounds <strong>of</strong> labor power. There is


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 165<br />

only so much labor a person can perform in a single day. The second is the cultural bound<br />

which is the time a worker needs to satisfy his intellectual and social needs.<br />

Hans: Your definition <strong>of</strong> the minimum bound is wrong. See [2011fa:752].<br />

Next Message by Agloeck is [1084].<br />

[1115] KATES: Minimal and Maximal bounds and the working day. The minimal and<br />

maximal bounds for the length <strong>of</strong> a working-day are determined by a few different factors.<br />

Minimum bounds are determined by the amount <strong>of</strong> time it takes to reproduce wages and<br />

labor power and the maximum bounds are determined by a persons need. Minimum bounds<br />

the time it takes to reproduce wages, but also the labor power according to Marx. You need<br />

to reproduce your wages in the length <strong>of</strong> a working day but if your wages are not enough<br />

for pr<strong>of</strong>it then just reproducing your wages makes the minimum unattainable and it comes<br />

down to the value <strong>of</strong> your labor power. The maximum bounds are determined by the value<br />

received from a laborer’s power, but a laborer only has so much power because they also<br />

have a need for physical and mental well being. The maximum bounds are determined by<br />

how long a laborer can work, the need for a healthy mental state, the need for food and sleep<br />

and the need for social interaction. Workers need to stay healthy mentally and physically in<br />

order for them to keep maintaining labor value for the firm. When a worker is tired and not<br />

performing as well as a healthy person their value to the firm goes down. When a worker is<br />

healthy and able to perform to their full ability they are more valuable to their firm.<br />

Hans: The maximum length is not the same as the optimum length for the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by KATES is [1116].


166 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Question 717 is 499 in 2003fa, 552 in 2004fa, 570 in 2007SP, 565 in 2007fa, and 605 in<br />

2009fa:<br />

Question 717 Is it true today that the laborer is for 24 hours a day nothing else than laborpower?<br />

[943] TMM: Working 24 Hours a Day. Yes, it is true. The laborer is for 24 hours a<br />

day nothing else other than labor-power. The working class believes that this is the case<br />

and there is no other way, the capitalists have made this the only thing they can believe<br />

by embedding it into their routines and minds. The laborer today is labor-power for 24<br />

hours because everything the worker does might be related to work even though they are<br />

not necessarily still “working.” He or she has to recover from work, prepare for work, etc.<br />

(as stated by Hans’s translation on Page 502). This can be best explained by an example <strong>of</strong><br />

a worker that works a normal work day 9:00am to 5:00pm, where the worker is constantly<br />

surrounded by the effects and the thought <strong>of</strong> work. A weekend or weeknight can be thought<br />

<strong>of</strong> a preparation for the next working day where the worker is constantly thinking about how<br />

they must get enough rest in order to be productive at work, or take it easy on the weekend<br />

because the upcoming week <strong>of</strong> work is going to be rough. A worker is continuously affected<br />

by work; it’s always in the front or back <strong>of</strong> their mind right up to the moment they go to bed.<br />

The average laborer will have to miss certain events because <strong>of</strong> work in the present moment<br />

or because they must prepare for work the next day, where the average laborer accepts work<br />

the next day as a given and the routine eventually becomes a subconscious action. In 375/o,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 167<br />

Marx says that “time for education, for intellectual development, for the fulfilling <strong>of</strong> social<br />

functions and for social intercourse, for the free-play <strong>of</strong> his bodily and mental activity, even<br />

the rest time <strong>of</strong> Sunday” must be sacrificed to the exigencies <strong>of</strong> work. The capitalist would<br />

most likely exploit the employee to the maximum with long days and treat them as a droid<br />

that continues to work a steady pace. The laborer simply needs to replenish themselves in<br />

order to prepare for the next working day, if they do not, their productivity will most likely<br />

be down, this is the only reason they get a time away from their immediate “work.” There is a<br />

continuous strain between the capitalists and the worker; this will always be ongoing because<br />

the capitalist will always continue to maximize the amount <strong>of</strong> labor from the laborer.<br />

Message [943] referenced by [950]. Next Message by TMM is [969].<br />

[948] SVN: Just Another Laborer. There are so many ways to look at the situation <strong>of</strong><br />

the present day laborer and how they fit into modern capitalist society. It is true that labor<br />

laws and conditions have vastly improved compared to the “Robber Baron” days <strong>of</strong> the late<br />

1800’s and early decades <strong>of</strong> the 1900’s, which, being generous, were a half step above full<br />

blown slavery. It is true that over the last 150 years the worker has fought back against the<br />

capitalist and made life better for themselves, these steps essentially leading to the creation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the middle-class. Because <strong>of</strong> unions, the length <strong>of</strong> the working day has been shortened,<br />

allowing the laborer some time to fulfill other physiological and social aspects <strong>of</strong> life.<br />

But this is extra free time that the laborer has garnered for himself is just the modern day<br />

equivalent <strong>of</strong> the “minimum-bound” as Marx calls it, that the overly worked laborers <strong>of</strong> the


168 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

early 1900’s were given. As technology has evolved and become more efficient, less labor<br />

time <strong>of</strong> the worker in the factory is required, so it leaves one to wonder if the unions’ success<br />

for decreased labor hours was actually a true social victory, or if it was just something<br />

the capitalists could afford to cede, because technology had evolved so much. Marx talks<br />

about how there is no sentiment in capitalism, not necessarily because the capitalist does not<br />

have a soul, but because there is so much competition that everything must evolve around<br />

maximizing labor-power and squeezing a pr<strong>of</strong>it out <strong>of</strong> every last ounce <strong>of</strong> it. Any changes<br />

in working time for the laborer are likely not be because <strong>of</strong> human sentiment, but because in<br />

the end a shortened day will still maximize pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Therefore I would argue that the modern day laborer is still nothing more than 24 hours<br />

a day nothing else than labor power. Sure there is some time to go play s<strong>of</strong>tball or hang<br />

out with some friends and family, but that is all just the modern day minimum bound. It is<br />

what the present day worker needs to be able to be fully productive at work the next day.<br />

Whatever the firm does to cater to the worker, is so that they will be fully productive the<br />

next day, everything revolves around productivity. Even in the “white collar” jobs like at<br />

corporations such as GOOGLE, where there is day care, a gourmet cafeteria, and a gym<br />

all at the <strong>of</strong>fice as well as fancy company retreats. They <strong>of</strong>fer these amenities because they<br />

don’t want the worker to leave the <strong>of</strong>fice. Offering “perks” such as that are just ways to keep<br />

the laborer working at full capacity. GOOGLE is a perfect example <strong>of</strong> the corporation has<br />

taken over the family lifestyle.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 169<br />

Capitalism still thrives on laborers, being laborers 24 hours a day, but now it just has a<br />

different mask on than it did 100 years ago.<br />

Message [948] referenced by [950]. Next Message by SVN is [1012].<br />

[950] ZachS: Re: Just Another Laborer. If I understand SVN [948] correctly you are<br />

saying that every hour <strong>of</strong> the day is being used up as labor power because that is what<br />

satisfies the ‘minimum-bound’? If labor-power is a commodity, and what you say is true,<br />

wouldn’t every hour <strong>of</strong> the day have to be spent with the focus <strong>of</strong> producing more commodities?<br />

Obviously the laborer eats and sleeps and has time spent not working to fulfill his/her<br />

minimum-bound, but there comes a point where someone can have too much free time especially<br />

if the work day continues to decrease in length. I think the laborer has the potential to<br />

use all <strong>of</strong> his/her time wisely under the banner <strong>of</strong> labor-power, but I don’t think it’s realistic<br />

with our society today. Some people like to unplug and get away from work and not think<br />

about it at all.<br />

Hans: You seem to be saying that the worker can get a lot <strong>of</strong> free time if they use their time wisely, and that “too<br />

much free time” is not good for them anyway. If I understand you right (and I am not sure if I do), your little essay<br />

confirms that “the working class believes there is no other way” as TMM said in [943].<br />

Next Message by ZachS is [1383].<br />

[973] Hans: Called in without pay. Below I am including a true story from Brian<br />

McKenna, Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> Anthropology at the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Michigan, Dearborn. It shows that<br />

the capitalists still today think they own their workers 24 hours a day. Brian’s story brought<br />

memories back to me about my first three months at Chrysler’s Lynch Road Assembly Plant


170 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

in Detroit in 1972. I took this job because I wanted to organize workers for the Communist<br />

Labor Party. Several times I was told to show up for work during Summer Changeover time,<br />

only to sent back home again. The UAW had a “call-in pay” in their contract, which says:<br />

if they call you in for work, they have to pay you at least for 4 hours. I never got my callin<br />

pay. I don’t know why, perhaps there was some fine print saying employees still under<br />

“probation” don’t get call-in pay, perhaps the foreman never told management that he called<br />

me in and then sent me home again. I didn’t ask questions because I didn’t want to make<br />

waves because I was still under probation and they could fire me any time. Plus I had not<br />

told them about my Ph D in Math from Germany, I told them that I had worked in a bakery<br />

in Germany, and lying on your application was cause for dismissal in the first 3 years. This<br />

was my own story, from here on it is Brian speaking. I think his story is more outrageous<br />

than mine:<br />

I tell [my students] that I have had several fast food jobs, and I tell them about my first<br />

one, at 19, when I flipped burgers at Gino’s (a competitor <strong>of</strong> McDonald’s) in 1975 in the<br />

suburbs <strong>of</strong> Philadelphia. I was earning money for college. Ginos advertised “flexible hours”<br />

to cater to college student’s busy needs. I signed on at $1.90 an hour, plus one free hamburger<br />

per shift.<br />

“One day I was called in at the last minute for an evening shift <strong>of</strong> four hours. Not owning<br />

a car, I took public transportation to the place, about 4 miles away, for the 4:00 shift. It


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 171<br />

started to rain. When I arrived, soaking wet at 4:00, I was told, ‘we don’t need you anymore<br />

tonight, Brian.”<br />

“But it took an hour to get here and I want to work. Please let me do something.”<br />

“Can’t you see?” the manager pointed out the window, “it’s raining out, hard, and no one<br />

is coming into Ginos. We don’t need you. Can you work a shift on Saturday at 11:00 to<br />

2:00?”<br />

“Can I at least have my hamburger?”<br />

“But you didn’t work!” he said.<br />

I got home around 6 PM. Total time spent from home to home again: 3 hours. Total<br />

wages earned: $0.00.<br />

“This was an education for me,” I tell students. “I thought, why aren’t we paid for the<br />

time we travel to work, and for the time getting ready for work? Why do we have no real<br />

power at work? And how did they decide on the $1.90 price per hour in the first place?” This<br />

led to a series <strong>of</strong> many more critical questions, over time, about commodity production and<br />

the reproduction <strong>of</strong> the laborer, about pr<strong>of</strong>its and people, about how we can and must resist.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [980].<br />

Question 719 is 484 in 2002fa, 555 in 2004fa, and 579 in 2008fa:


172 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Question 719 What is wrong with the argument that the economic self-interest <strong>of</strong> the capitalists<br />

themselves will see to it that they treat their workers well?<br />

[945] Jason: graded A+ Count Capital the Bloodsucker. Capitalists increase their<br />

wealth and social power through the use <strong>of</strong> capital, especially capital in the form <strong>of</strong> laborpower.<br />

One might therefore expect the capitalist class, acting in its own self-interest, to<br />

“guard and cherish this treasure,” i.e. look out for the health and well-being <strong>of</strong> the working<br />

class, so they could have sustainable access to this resource. But Marx explains production<br />

where the exchange-value or the production <strong>of</strong> surplus-value predominates, combined with<br />

the social content <strong>of</strong> capital, is unable to regulate itself in this way. Further, Marx shows historical<br />

developments that promote the tendencies <strong>of</strong> boundless expansion by capital. Marx<br />

therefore concludes that capital will overreach its moral and even physiological bounds despite<br />

the self-interest <strong>of</strong> capitalists, and a class-struggle where the working class asserts its<br />

own rights is necessary in order to mediate and sustain the long-run interests <strong>of</strong> capital (and<br />

capitalists).<br />

From Marx’s first examination <strong>of</strong> the circuit <strong>of</strong> capital in chapter 4, we learn the movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital, and the quest for surplus-value is insatiable. In chapter 10, Marx draws<br />

an analogy between capital and a vampire. Capital is an insatiable monster, whose goal is<br />

to suck the lifeblood out <strong>of</strong> living labor for the purpose <strong>of</strong> its own expansion - it is value<br />

run amok. Marx says “Capital cares nothing for the length <strong>of</strong> life <strong>of</strong> labor-power. All that


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 173<br />

concerns it is simply and solely the maximum <strong>of</strong> labor-power, that can be rendered fluent<br />

in one working-day.” The capitalist acts as the living embodiment <strong>of</strong> capital, his or her own<br />

will intertwined with the social content <strong>of</strong> capital. Therefore, as capital cares nothing for<br />

the length <strong>of</strong> life <strong>of</strong> labor-power, the capitalist cares nothing for the well-being <strong>of</strong> his or her<br />

workers. Marx demonstrates the attitude <strong>of</strong> the capitalists with respect to the mistreatment,<br />

degradation, even torture <strong>of</strong> the workers with the quote “Ought these to trouble us since they<br />

increase our pr<strong>of</strong>its?”<br />

But the social relations surrounding capital represent only tendential (and historically<br />

conditioned) laws - there must be an enforcer <strong>of</strong> these laws. In capitalism, the sheriff,<br />

deputy, judge, jury, and executioner are all one...market competition. Marx shows how<br />

certain historical developments within competition have led to the mistreatment <strong>of</strong> workers<br />

in the consumption <strong>of</strong> labor-power, enabling and necessitating capital’s drive for selfvalorization.<br />

Historically, in capitalist societies, there has existed a “rural-overpopulation.”<br />

To show how this supply <strong>of</strong> replaceable labor can affect the well-being <strong>of</strong> workers, Marx<br />

gives a historical account <strong>of</strong> slavery in Georgia and Mississippi. Given a situation with a vast<br />

supply <strong>of</strong> slaves, he says “when his place can at once be supplied from foreign preserves, the<br />

duration <strong>of</strong> his life becomes a matter <strong>of</strong> less moment than its productiveness while it lasts.”<br />

The capitalists experienced the same ability to overwork their own employees in the pursuit<br />

<strong>of</strong> surplus-value, because workers could easily be replaced from the rural population. The


174 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

capitalist wouldn’t even have to worry about additional outlays for slave-capital. Competition<br />

enforced the social relations <strong>of</strong> capital, and helped transform the ability to overwork<br />

and mistreat workers into a necessity. Any kind capitalist interested in the well-being <strong>of</strong><br />

their employees would be overrun by the more brutal capitalists, who managed to extract the<br />

most value and social power from their workers. This leads to a kind <strong>of</strong> social Darwinism,<br />

as Bobby [2008fa:786] recognizes. Capital will, over time and with help from competition,<br />

find the vectors, the capitalists, who are as interested in surplus-value as capital is.<br />

Because capitalists are slaves to the social relations <strong>of</strong> capital, and these social relations<br />

call for maximum exploitation <strong>of</strong> labor-power, even at the expense <strong>of</strong> worker’s health, the<br />

capitalist class cannot move to treat their workers well. This requires class struggle, a declaration<br />

<strong>of</strong> the rights <strong>of</strong> the working class by the working class, and an insistence on a normal<br />

working day, which doesn’t overstep moral or physiological boundaries. It is this class struggle<br />

that can help mediate the expansion <strong>of</strong> capital, and keep it in check (though this class<br />

struggle cannot eliminate the internal contradictions <strong>of</strong> capitalism). Thus, in asserting their<br />

own rights, the working class helps the capitalist class to follow its own self-interest, or at<br />

least enables a certain level <strong>of</strong> sustainability. But this cannot stem from the social relations <strong>of</strong><br />

capital, or the self-interest <strong>of</strong> the class which enacts its will - it must come from an external<br />

force.<br />

Here, Marx is very critical <strong>of</strong> Classical Political Economy’s concept <strong>of</strong> the invisible hand.<br />

The idea is that individuals acting in their own self-interest, whatever that may be (selfish,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 175<br />

selfless, etc., doesn’t matter), will benefit society. However, the social content <strong>of</strong> capital and<br />

the social relations surrounding the production <strong>of</strong> surplus-value are so strong they will not<br />

only enable certain actions by individuals, but necessitate these actions, such that the intent<br />

<strong>of</strong> these individuals becomes subsumed into social roles. As slaves to these social relations,<br />

capitalists, acting on the behalf <strong>of</strong> capital, do not benefit society. Quite the opposite, if left<br />

unchecked they are capable <strong>of</strong> destroying it.<br />

Message [945] referenced by [956]. Next Message by Jason is [1184].<br />

[1291] Kannon: Many <strong>of</strong> the submissions this semester (and previous semesters) assume<br />

that capitalists care about the workers’ well being—that the altruism is an extension <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

seeking behavior. This is false. The working day and its length (and treatments <strong>of</strong> workers)<br />

is determined by the minimum bound (where labor power reproduces itself in value) and is<br />

an unattainable limit because pr<strong>of</strong>it would be zero. The maximum limit is the amount the<br />

worker can work while still meeting his or her physical and social needs. This is a constant<br />

contention between worker and capitalist—and capitalist <strong>of</strong>ten use outright exploitation (in<br />

addition to hidden exploitation <strong>of</strong> value produced) to quell workers’ rights. An example in<br />

the archive was capitalists who hire undocumented workers and then claim they are treated<br />

well because they keep showing up for work [2011fa:745]. But if they didn’t they would<br />

be fired and deported. There are also current events that confirm this, like the recent Papa<br />

Johns healthcare debacle where the CEO threatened to fire workers because his company<br />

could not afford healthcare for its workers, even though this would be only the equivalent<br />

<strong>of</strong> 10 cents extra per pizza sold. These examples are clear indications that Marx was right.


176 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Capitalists have diametrically opposed reasons in commodity production than their workers.<br />

Instead the inherently exploitative relationship is driven between the maximum and<br />

minimum mentioned, in the capitalists’ drive for surplus value. This is why capitalism is<br />

an inherently dehumanizing system, and the capitalists don’t care about their workers’ well<br />

being for altruistic reasons.<br />

Next Message by Kannon is [1294].<br />

[1301] JohnLennon: There are a few reasons supporting an argument against the concept<br />

that “the economic self-interest <strong>of</strong> the capitalists will see to it that they treat their workers<br />

well”. The first argument against this could be that overpaying your workers can cause<br />

laziness and less incentive to do a job well. If the worker is making just enough to get by<br />

that worker will have a smaller chance <strong>of</strong> calling in sick and slacking <strong>of</strong> on the the job. If<br />

the worker believes that he/she needs this job to survive and that there isn’t a better job out<br />

there for them they will do whatever is necessary to maintain that that job.<br />

However if someone is overpaid and has plenty <strong>of</strong> extra money they may be more apt to<br />

take the day <strong>of</strong>f if they are sick or tired, knowing that they have plenty <strong>of</strong> money to make<br />

ends meet. For a capitalist to get the most out <strong>of</strong> their workers they have to create a strong<br />

need for their workers to labor most effectively.<br />

Next Message by JohnLennon is [1302].<br />

[1348] DJB: Capitalist is king. The capitalist is dependent upon capital and the creation<br />

<strong>of</strong> it. With labor being one <strong>of</strong> the key sources <strong>of</strong> capital the capitalist must find a way to


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 177<br />

always keep re-supplying his means <strong>of</strong> production. As such the capitalist will want the<br />

worker only taken care <strong>of</strong> in as much to give him their labor. If he does this that means he<br />

will always have a source <strong>of</strong> labor in which to create and make his goods, giving him the<br />

control over the rights <strong>of</strong> production. Marx is able to show this in chapter 14 when he is able<br />

to conclude that capitalism is focused on expanding and drawing out as much labor power<br />

that is available in a worker’s day. So the capitalist really doesn’t care about the worker but<br />

the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that they can put out and supply to him. The social consequences <strong>of</strong><br />

capital being created is drawing from another source <strong>of</strong> power, so when a capitalist does this<br />

he does not care about the workers health, life, wants, or needs—he cares about his own<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Hans: I think you mean chapter 10 instead <strong>of</strong> 14.<br />

Next Message by DJB is [1349].<br />

[1389] Brie: In order for the capitalist to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it, they must insure that the cost<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor is lower than the pr<strong>of</strong>it made from from the commodities produced. If this means<br />

exploiting their laborers, the capitalist will do so. As the need for jobs is typically great,<br />

the capitalist gets away with treating their workers to their advantage, and forcing them to<br />

create as much product as possible. If such a worker becomes ineffective in the future, the<br />

capitalist can simply obtain a new one. Accordingly, the capitalist’s interests lie in whatever<br />

benefits them the most, rather than insuring that working conditions are favorable or that<br />

their employees are paid well.<br />

Next Message by Brie is [1390].


178 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1416] Ula: Self-Interest and Exploitation. The whole capitalist system–including the<br />

labor laws–is setup to benefit the capitalist. In this system, the laborer is not a person with<br />

feelings and interests, but a commodity to be exploited. After all, it is in the production<br />

process which includes the individual’s labor-power where the value is derived and, in turn,<br />

where the capitalist realizes his surplus-value. It’s in the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the labor-power<br />

(worker) that the capitalist makes his money and gains his wealth. His, the capitalist, selfinterest<br />

comes at a detriment to the laborer. The laborer is unaware <strong>of</strong> how much value she<br />

has created. It’s a secret kept from her and all other workers. It may be true that she knows<br />

or has some idea that she is being exploited, but she has no idea to what degree she is being<br />

exploited. She has no idea <strong>of</strong> her true worth to the capitalist. Therefore, she cannot truly<br />

know how “well” she should be treated. Unfortunately, she fits right into the system and<br />

plays her role in the system. Her role is simply to be the labor-power and to make a living<br />

wage.<br />

First Message by Ula is [700].<br />

[1439] MKW: The argument that it is in the self interest <strong>of</strong> the capitalist to treat his<br />

workers well does not have a vast amount <strong>of</strong> evidence to fall back on. The overarching<br />

goal <strong>of</strong> the capitalist is to maximize pr<strong>of</strong>it. Therefore the capitalist will pay the worker the<br />

lowest possible wage and still remain competitive and keep them coming back. He becomes<br />

a master at reducing the cost <strong>of</strong> labor power by lowering wages, extending the workday<br />

and/or subcontracting work and doing so in a manner that disguises his real intentions <strong>of</strong><br />

increasing his surplus value. Once all the use-value <strong>of</strong> a worker has been exhausted through


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 179<br />

this exploitation, there’s always another desperate fellow eager to take his place so there’s<br />

hardly any incentive for the capitalist to improve conditions.<br />

Next Message by MKW is [1512].<br />

[1442] Jess: graded A– Capitalists treating workers well? The argument that economic<br />

self-interests <strong>of</strong> capitalists will see to it that they (the capitalists) will treat workers well, is<br />

extremely flawed. This is because it fails to realize that a capitalist’s main goal, is simply<br />

to accumulate pr<strong>of</strong>its. In order to reach this end, a capitalist will exploit the hours a laborer<br />

works for as long as is legally and physically possible. If a capitalist cared for the wellbeing<br />

<strong>of</strong> its workers, they would either cut back the amount <strong>of</strong> surplus labor hours they<br />

allocate in a day, or they would increase labor wages. However, when have we ever seen<br />

this happen within a capitalist society? The answer to that question is: you don’t. This is<br />

why in capitalistic societies, you see generations <strong>of</strong> families forced to live in poverty or even<br />

fluctuations <strong>of</strong> welfare recipients. If capitalists cared for their workers, they would make<br />

sure they receive a fair wage that allows for them to afford the basic needs that our society<br />

deems as “socially necessary” for living.<br />

Hans: Are you seriously thinking there were never raises in wages and a shortening <strong>of</strong> labor hours in capitalism?<br />

Next Message by Jess is [1445].<br />

Question 723 Why were some capitalists themselves in favor <strong>of</strong> shortening the work day?


180 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[963] AbeFroman: Individual Capitalists in Favor <strong>of</strong> Shortening the Work Day. Althoug<br />

capitalists function in the market as the personification <strong>of</strong> capital (Hans’s annotations, p.<br />

490), with a “were-wolf’s hunger for surplus labour” (Hans’s annotations, p. 503), this isn’t<br />

due to some sort <strong>of</strong> inherent malevolence within the individuals. It’s competition between<br />

capitalists that drives this behavior. Individual capitalists essentially cannot afford to let<br />

their sense <strong>of</strong> what is good for their workers interfere with their pursuit <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its. If they<br />

decide that their moral values outweigh the drive for surplus-value, they will be crushed in<br />

the market by those with less scruples.<br />

Despite this dynamic, however, unethical practices can still be exorcised from the market,<br />

but this can’t happen without an outside influence that is able to force the uniform application<br />

<strong>of</strong> rules and regulations. An individual capitalist may personally support shortening the<br />

work day, believing that granting workers more personal time is ethically-speaking the right<br />

thing to do, and as an individual, he may welcome a new regulation enforcing this practice.<br />

However, he will also not willingly shorten the work day <strong>of</strong> his workers, without everybody<br />

else also being forced into the same position.<br />

Hans: I changed “drive for value” into “drive for surplus-value.”<br />

You stress the moral sentiments <strong>of</strong> the capitalists. There are also economic reasons. With a shorter workday,<br />

labor can be intensified. Capitalists who introduced more modern and efficient production methods did not want to<br />

be undercut by ruthless competitors working their workers excessive hours.<br />

Next Message by AbeFroman is [1352].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 181<br />

[977] Diego: Capitalists need intervention to collude! I found this to be an interesting<br />

question and one worth discussion though past the period already. When looking at why<br />

capitalists would actually be in favor <strong>of</strong> shortening the working day or (by extention) not<br />

allowing child labor we find only a faint hint <strong>of</strong> morality.<br />

Capitalists are in direct competition with each other - all the bakers for example are<br />

competing for morning customers. In the capitalists mind they are forced to have laborers<br />

working all night and long hours to beat the competition. The capitalists interest is to make<br />

the same pr<strong>of</strong>it without having laborers work overnight. This could be due to faint morality<br />

as it is not nice to have the poor hours for their laborers or, to be more pessimistic, due to<br />

the fact that it is not convenient for them to monitor or manage at all hours <strong>of</strong> the night. In<br />

any case, these capitalists would like to make the same pr<strong>of</strong>it without the long hours.<br />

The capitalists could accomplish this by collusion - by discussing with all other bakers<br />

that no one is to sell fresh bread prior to 3pm allowing all parties to hire laborers for day<br />

work only and not have to compete for a delivery time. For many reasons, collusion is<br />

extermely difficult and basically impossible in a commodity market with many bakers - as<br />

someone would surely cheat to win pr<strong>of</strong>its! Therefore, by going to the state seeking ‘hours<br />

regulations’ the capitalist can reach the same goal as collusion but with the state involved<br />

in monitoring. In this way the state regulation works to the benefit <strong>of</strong> the capitalist by<br />

effectively helping them collude.


182 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

This is why you see some capitalist interested in shortening <strong>of</strong> the working day.<br />

Message [977] referenced by [980] and [1152]. Next Message by Diego is [982].<br />

[1130] Justin: Some capitalists might be in favor <strong>of</strong> shortening the work day for either<br />

moral or economic reasons. The moral reason, which is less likely to be the true reason,<br />

is that they legitimately care about their workers’ health and happiness more than they care<br />

about making a pr<strong>of</strong>it. It is possible that some capitalists would feel this way, but a much<br />

more likely reason is economics. If the work day is shortened, the capitalist is able to<br />

increase the intensity <strong>of</strong> labor performed to a degree that he otherwise could not, allowing<br />

him to extract more surplus value from the laborers. Treating his workers better could also<br />

give consumers a more favorable opinion <strong>of</strong> his company and encourage them to buy more<br />

from him, which would also help increase his economic standing.<br />

Hans: Concern for the workers also has an economic component: they don’t want to have to compete with other<br />

capitalists who get an unfair advantage by abusing their workers.<br />

Next Message by Justin is [1327].<br />

[1152] Diego: graded A The lengthening <strong>of</strong> the working day - looking at bakeries for<br />

example - made it very difficult for capitalists to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it without lengthening the day<br />

for their workers. Bakeries were competing for bread purchases in the morning and so had to<br />

have hot bread early ensuring their employees had to work through the night. A baker who<br />

wanted to shorten this or change hours would be disadvantaged due to late bread availability<br />

in the morning. The bakers could form a sort <strong>of</strong> cartel and agree that no one produces bread<br />

for sale prior to 10 am but this would be impossible to enforce. Shortening, legally, the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 183<br />

working day would be the equivalent <strong>of</strong> an enforcing mechanism and so some capitalists<br />

saw this as an opportunity to balance competition. In this case the state regulation works to<br />

the benefit <strong>of</strong> the capitalist by helping them to collude (Diego, [2012fa:977]).<br />

Next Message by Diego is [1153].<br />

[1218] EricR: Below is a few reasons why capitalists where in favor for shorting the work<br />

day.<br />

-Keep up the overall health <strong>of</strong> the laborer, too long <strong>of</strong> work days would end the laborer’s<br />

life sooner. (Marx gives this example <strong>of</strong> the German versus the French Army. The French<br />

were malnourished and could barely bear a gun.)<br />

-Have the Laborers actually have a chance buy the product the capitalist were producing,<br />

with some time while they are not at work.<br />

-Marx states that capitalists are “destroying the source <strong>of</strong> value and wealth.” And they are<br />

doing this if they are overworking the laborer’s and they do not have a surplus <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Hans: There is a difference between the why a too long work day is bad for society, and the reasons why capitalists<br />

are interested in shorter work days.<br />

Next Message by EricR is [1223].<br />

[1225] Carol: Hans mentioned in his annotations that “Capital’s only standard is pr<strong>of</strong>itability”<br />

(p. 510). In an unregulated scenario, it is extremely difficult for the capitalist to<br />

consider the conditions <strong>of</strong> the worker unless he is forced to do so by the struggles <strong>of</strong> the


184 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

working class represented as “society”. It is then that some capitalist are in favor <strong>of</strong> shortening<br />

the working day due to long term interests. Although some moral sentiments may apply<br />

when the capitalists wish to shorten the workday, there are also overwhelming amounts <strong>of</strong><br />

economic reasons in play. Labor can be intensified in a shorter workday. This means that<br />

usually more workload will be placed on each individual worker, and thus increasing the<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> surplus value generated for each paid working hour. Intensified labor also means<br />

shorter rest periods for the worker and an increase in the overall effort required by the worker<br />

in a given shift. Shortening the hours in this way would ensure that capitalists with more<br />

advanced methods <strong>of</strong> production are not challenged by other ruthless capitalists who are<br />

making their workers work excessive hours. Simultaneously, shortening the working day<br />

does not stop the capitalists from pr<strong>of</strong>iting from the laborer. For example, if a worker’s<br />

hourly wage is $10 and produced a value <strong>of</strong> $20 per hour, the capitalist makes an 100%<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong> $10 an hour out <strong>of</strong> the worker. If the labor is intensified, the worker may even<br />

produce more surplus value with added pressure. In addition, even if the laborer’s working<br />

hours are reduced from 8 hours a day to 4 hours, the worker still generates the surplus value<br />

per hour. This means that the pr<strong>of</strong>it the capitalist receives remains the same.<br />

Hans: In Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> wages, hourly wages are the daily reproduction cost <strong>of</strong> the labor-power divided by the<br />

normal number <strong>of</strong> hours worked. I.e., shorter hours will not decrease the wages the workers get per day.<br />

Next Message by Carol is [1226].<br />

[1501] Bear: graded C The short answer is that the capitalist is interested in maximizing<br />

productivity as well as efficiency. A rested worker will do a better job than an overworked


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 185<br />

one. A happy worker will have less turn-over which saves on training new employees and<br />

increases job satisfaction. Many capitalist opted for a long work day to squeeze every bit<br />

<strong>of</strong> productivity from a worker with no thought <strong>of</strong> tomorrow or the well-being <strong>of</strong> the worker.<br />

The shorter work day is still a selfish endeavor but a more long-term approach to pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

maximizing.<br />

Hans: This sounds like a reasonable explanation, but it is not Marx’s explanation. Marx argues that the capitalists<br />

are too greedy for their own good. They are not able to switch to an enlightened long-term view in which the pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

motive takes second place to social peace.<br />

Only after some industries were forced by the resistance <strong>of</strong> the working class to shorten the day, and after it had<br />

become clear that the extremly long workdays would not come back, did some other capitalists ask for a general<br />

legislation forcing a uniform length <strong>of</strong> the work day on all capitalists in order to eliminate unfair competitive<br />

advantages.<br />

Next Message by Bear is [1502].<br />

Exam Question 732 is 203 in 1995WI, 210 in 1995ut, 232 in 1996sp, 232 in 1996ut, 285 in<br />

1997WI, 350 in 1997sp, 349 in 1997ut, 359 in 1998WI, 360 in 1999SP, 472 in 2001fa, 511<br />

in 2002fa, 529 in 2003fa, 582 in 2004fa, 535 in 2005fa, 584 in 2007SP, 591 in 2008fa,<br />

683 in 2010fa, 703 in 2011fa, and 683 in Answer:<br />

Exam Question 732 What is relative surplus-value? Which mechanisms, that were so far<br />

taken as given, affect the magnitude <strong>of</strong> relative surplus-value?


186 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1080] Shelly: graded A Relative Surplus Value. Relative Surplus Value is the surplus<br />

value derived from a decrease in necessary labor time (labor time necessary to reproduce the<br />

workers wages), which stems from an increase in technology/production.<br />

The productivity <strong>of</strong> labor is the factor which has been considered constant up until this<br />

point.<br />

Next Message by Shelly is [1081].<br />

[1084] Agloeck: relative surplus-value. Marx defines relative surplus-value as “surplusvalue<br />

which arises from the curtailment <strong>of</strong> the necessary labor-time, and from the corresponding<br />

alteration in the respective lengths <strong>of</strong> the two components <strong>of</strong> the working day.”<br />

To “curtail” necessary labor the capitalists can reduce wages below labor-power value<br />

to increase the surplus-value; but this is not a long run solution because it “undermines<br />

the development <strong>of</strong> the working-class” (Annotations, pg. 518). Therefore the only way<br />

to reduce necessary working time is to increase productivity. Marx states the results <strong>of</strong><br />

continually increasing productivity: “Capital therefore has an immanent drive and constant<br />

tendency, towards increasing the productivity <strong>of</strong> labor, in order to cheapen commodities and,<br />

by cheapening commodities, to cheapen the worker himself” (pg. 437)<br />

Hans: Yes, this is right.<br />

Next Message by Agloeck is [1312].<br />

[1137] Snowball: graded C Relative Surplus Value. Relative surplus value is the surplus<br />

value attained when there is a technical advancement that leads to a shorter amount


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 187<br />

<strong>of</strong> time required to produce a commodity. Relative surplus value is temporary, however,<br />

as other firms will catch on and implement the same changes, bringing all firms back into<br />

equilibrium.<br />

Hans: What you describe is extra surplus-value, not relative surplus-value.<br />

Next Message by Snowball is [1514].<br />

[1139] Basil: Relative Surplus Value. Relative Surplus Value is increases in surplus value<br />

that result from production increases as a result <strong>of</strong> technical innovation. Simply put, when<br />

productivity increases, a worker can produce the same amount <strong>of</strong> necessary value in less<br />

time, but because the time in the workday does not decrease, the worker simply produces<br />

more relative surplus value. Any given hour <strong>of</strong> work now produces the same necessary<br />

value, and more relative surplus value, which translates to more pr<strong>of</strong>it for the capitalist. The<br />

mechanism previously held constant is productivity.<br />

Hans: What is “necessary value”? Marx does not use this concept.<br />

Originally you hade “productive capacity” in your last sentence, which is not the same as “productivity,” although<br />

I assume you meant “productivity.”<br />

Next Message by Basil is [1140.1].<br />

[1181] Neela: graded C Relative surplus-value is the distribution <strong>of</strong> extra surplus-value<br />

amongst the laborers. The two mechanisms that, were so far taken as given, affect the<br />

magnitude <strong>of</strong> relative surplus-value are the social conditions <strong>of</strong> wages and the labor process.<br />

Hans: This is not the definition <strong>of</strong> relative surplus-value. It might be helpful for you to go through the answers <strong>of</strong><br />

multiple choice question 733.<br />

Next Message by Neela is [1189].


188 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1199] Leont: Relative surplus-value appears when the shortening <strong>of</strong> the necessary labortime,<br />

and from the corresponding change in the respective lengths <strong>of</strong> two components <strong>of</strong> the<br />

working day. Productivity <strong>of</strong> labor is the mechanism that is a given affecting relative surplusvalue.<br />

When the productivity <strong>of</strong> labor increases so does the relative surplus-value. On the<br />

other hand when there is a decrease in the productivity <strong>of</strong> labor, the relative surplus-value<br />

decreases as well. [2008fa:797]<br />

Hans: You are required to copy your answers <strong>of</strong> the designated exam questions without change.<br />

When copying your source you introduced inconsistent grammar. Is this your idea <strong>of</strong> using your own words?<br />

Next Message by Leont is [1515].<br />

[1205] Gladwell: graded B Relative surplus value is when extra surplus value, which is<br />

temporary, spreads to all producers. Gains due to increases in technology/production lead<br />

to extra surplus value. When competing firms adopt the new technology or productionincreases,<br />

extra surplus value becomes relative surplus value. Technology and productionincreases<br />

affect the magnitude <strong>of</strong> relative surplus value.<br />

Next Message by Gladwell is [1481].<br />

[1209] Rowlsroyce: Relative surplus-value is basically even though labor-time was into a<br />

commodity that was produced to the point <strong>of</strong> surplus, it still has value even though it loses<br />

value or its value is changed because <strong>of</strong> the surplus. One <strong>of</strong> the mechanisms that affect the<br />

magnitude is the labor-value. It has to fall for relative surplus-value to exist.<br />

Next Message by Rowlsroyce is [1456].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 189<br />

[1231] AndyUte: graded A Relative surplus-value involves the capitalist shortening the<br />

necessary labor time <strong>of</strong> his workers which would, in effect, increase his pr<strong>of</strong>its. Technological<br />

innovations and advancements are one way through which capitalists are able to decrease<br />

the necessary labor time.<br />

Next Message by AndyUte is [1254].<br />

[1278] Bimmer: graded A Relative surplus value is the decrease in the necessary labor<br />

time. Ultimately by decreasing the necessary labor time, you can decrease wages and effectively<br />

make the workers more productive. That is really what relative surplus value is<br />

about, it is about increasing productivity through technical innovation. Better machinery<br />

and means <strong>of</strong> production will allow more productive workers which in turn cuts down the<br />

necessary labor time.<br />

Next Message by Bimmer is [1282].<br />

[1293] JEP: Relative surplus value is the extra value created by reducing the labor time<br />

in production. This can be done through advancements in the labor process while keeping<br />

wages constant.<br />

Hans: Since value is measured by labor time, a reduction <strong>of</strong> labor time in production does not create extra value<br />

but creates less value.<br />

Next Message by JEP is [1326].<br />

[1343] TMM: The relative surplus value requires the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power to fall. If<br />

we can assume the capitalists cannot increase surplus value by making the workers work<br />

longer hours, in order to increase or decrease the surplus-labor this would depend on the


190 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

difference between the value produced and the value <strong>of</strong> the labor power. However, capitalism<br />

cannot still function with shorter or longer surplus hours, but the surplus value cannot be<br />

necessarily determined by economic laws. Mechanisms taken as a given that affect the<br />

magnitude <strong>of</strong> relative surplus value are that the capitalists cannot increase their surplus value<br />

if they can’t make the worker work longer hours. Essentially, the capitalist’s subjective<br />

purpose in pursuing M-C-M’ is valorization <strong>of</strong> value and the objective content in M-C-M.<br />

For example, assume the wage is $10 per hour and the worker works an 8 hour day, the<br />

worker also produces $32 <strong>of</strong> value per day. If we take a look, this means the worker’s daily<br />

wage is $10 × 8 hrs = $80 per day, where at a produced value <strong>of</strong> $32 per day this means that<br />

the worker really only needs to work 2 hours and 30 minutes in order to produce the daily<br />

value <strong>of</strong> $32 per day. The rest <strong>of</strong> the day (the other 6 1/2 hours) the worker is simply being<br />

exploited by the capitalist to gain a larger surplus <strong>of</strong>f the worker.<br />

Hans: I cannot follow your math. If the worker produces a value <strong>of</strong> $32 per day and gets a value <strong>of</strong> $80 per day,<br />

then he gets more value than he produces, there is no exploitation.<br />

First Message by TMM is [172].<br />

[1357] Glister: Relative surplus value is the change in labor, for example, if labor became<br />

more efficient then one would produce a commodity faster creating relative surplus value.<br />

The laborer will increase his labor power but will not receive labor value in his paycheck.<br />

Money is something that affects the magnitude and surplus labor time<br />

Hans: More efficient labor increases the use-value produced per hour but not the value produced per hour.<br />

Next Message by Glister is [1574].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 191<br />

[1361] Nunu: Relative surplus-value, technology and constant production. Relative<br />

surplus-value has to do with greater value <strong>of</strong> a commodity or greater pr<strong>of</strong>its due to decreasing<br />

value <strong>of</strong> labor-power that is brought on by technological advancement. Better technology<br />

allows for greater, easier production <strong>of</strong> commodities. Constant production was taken as a<br />

given but with better technology more and more can be produced.<br />

Hans: Technical progress leads to higher pr<strong>of</strong>its but not to more value produced per hour.<br />

Next Message by Nunu is [1412].<br />

[1406] AR: content C form 90% According to Marx relative surplus-value is “surplusvalue<br />

which arises from the shortening <strong>of</strong> the necessary labor-time.” Necessary labor-time<br />

is what is used to produce worker’s wages. The productivity <strong>of</strong> labor is the mechanism<br />

that affects most <strong>of</strong> relative surplus-value. Relative surplus-value increases as technology/production<br />

and labor increases.<br />

Hans: You are not allowed to rewrite the answers <strong>of</strong> the designated exam questions. Your grade is for your in-class<br />

answer.<br />

Next Message by AR is [1586].<br />

[1466] AbeFroman: Relative Surplus-Value. Relative surplus value is value capitalists<br />

gain by increasing the productivity <strong>of</strong> workers. This can be done in many ways (e.g. benefits<br />

from group work, introduction <strong>of</strong> technology). It is relative because workers aren’t, in fact,<br />

producing more value (the same abstract labor is placed in the commodities), but they are<br />

lowering the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power by making it easier for workers to subsist on lower total<br />

value.


192 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by AbeFroman is [1510].<br />

Question 739 is 205 in 1995WI, 238 in 1996sp, 237 in 1996ut, 290 in 1997WI, 355 in<br />

1997sp, 354 in 1997ut, 363 in 1998WI, 364 in 1999SP, 477 in 2001fa, 516 in 2002fa, 536<br />

in 2003fa, 590 in 2004fa, 543 in 2005fa, 596 in 2007SP, 586 in 2007fa, 598 in 2008fa,<br />

627 in 2009fa, 690 in 2010fa, 710 in 2011fa, and 690 in Answer:<br />

Question 739 Do the workers after introduction <strong>of</strong> new machinery produce more value per<br />

hour?<br />

[978] Brie: Machinery in Value. “New machinery does not increase value, it only<br />

produces more <strong>of</strong> the product being produced.” Marx continually states that labor is the epicenter<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. Thus, the increase in production may produce more commodities, however<br />

does not increase the value <strong>of</strong> the commodities themselves. As value is a social relationship,<br />

I believe it is important to recognize that the laborers play an important role. When a<br />

machine is introduced, the commodity is no longer produced by a living, breathing human<br />

being. With this decrease in interaction, a decrease in value as a social representation is seen.<br />

Although an increase in product will be seen, the value <strong>of</strong> the product will not increase by<br />

hour; the laborer’s efforts do not increase with the machines, they are still the same for each<br />

hour and each working day.<br />

Message [978] referenced by [992]. Next Message by Brie is [1062].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 193<br />

[992] Neela: graded A– Machinery to Value. After reading Annotations and the response<br />

from Brie [978] I would thoroughly agree with her and Marx that the labor is the epicenter<br />

<strong>of</strong> value and that “new machinery does not increase the value, it only produces more <strong>of</strong> the<br />

product being produced”. I would stress the fact that yes, there may be higher productivity<br />

and an increase in the production output with the introduction <strong>of</strong> machinery. However, the<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> labor exerted is the same as prior to the introduction <strong>of</strong> machinery- thus, this new<br />

process <strong>of</strong> producing does not increase the value produced.<br />

It helps to apply it to a modern day product, for example, let’s assume I work a 1 hour<br />

shift packaging iPods at the Apple factory every day. One day, they bring in a machine that<br />

tapes the boxes shut for me. This decreases the amount <strong>of</strong> time I spent taping each box,<br />

therefore shipping more boxes per shift than before. I’ve increased my output for my shift,<br />

however I am still working 1 hour and the value produced does not increase with my output.<br />

Marx also mentions “individual value <strong>of</strong> the commodity”. As stated in Annotations, “The<br />

value calculation which Marx just made will eventually be relevant for all capitalists, when<br />

all producers have introduced the new production method; but right now it is only correct<br />

for the innovator’s individual value.”<br />

Next Message by Neela is [1021].<br />

[1195] Elias: graded C+ Is Time/Effort Saved Valuable? When new machinery is introduced,<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> work produced by the laborer increases. Generally new machinery<br />

means that there has been a technological advancement or old, broken machinery has been


194 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

replaced. In the first case, that would mean a more productive or efficient unit, therefore the<br />

laborer would be able to produce more product in an hour than before. In the second case it<br />

would mean that a laborer would produce more than before as well, because they are using<br />

machinery that is now more functional than before.<br />

However, I get the feeling that my reasoning for this is not necessarily in the laborer’s<br />

favor, but the capitalist. Because <strong>of</strong> the increased productivity <strong>of</strong> the machinery and the less<br />

input necessary from the laborer, the value <strong>of</strong> that product in terms <strong>of</strong> the labor-input would<br />

actually be decreased from before. This would mean that the laborer has less value placed<br />

in to the product, than the work <strong>of</strong> the machine which could be exploited by the capitalist in<br />

greater pr<strong>of</strong>its for them, and stagnant or decreasing wages for the laborer.<br />

Hans: In Marx’s theory, machines produce no value. What the capitalist exploits is not the value produced by the<br />

machines, but the value produced by the laborers. New machines will not change that value.<br />

Next Message by Elias is [1253].<br />

[1234] Alee: Workers after introduction <strong>of</strong> new machinery do not produce more value<br />

per hour. As Marx said “New machinery does not increase value, it only produces more <strong>of</strong><br />

the product being produced.” He continually states that labor is the epicenter <strong>of</strong> value. The<br />

machines may increase the production and more products may be produced but it does not<br />

increase their value.<br />

Next Message by Alee is [1235].<br />

[1284] Littlerock: graded A Whether Machines Facilitate Producing More Value. Only<br />

if the new technology has not been generalized, or in other words, if other firms have not


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 195<br />

either already adopted that new technology or developed other, equally productive means <strong>of</strong><br />

production, can the workers create more value per hour than normal. The reason that the<br />

workers can produce more value per hour immediately after the introduction <strong>of</strong> new machinery<br />

is because the average time necessary to produce that commodity has not changed.<br />

The other firms have not adopted the new machinery yet, so the workers at the firm that has<br />

implemented the new machinery are producing more rapidly than the average worker. As<br />

soon as the new machinery is generalized among firms, however, the socially average time<br />

required to produce that commodity decreases, and thus, all workers create the same value<br />

again.<br />

Next Message by Littlerock is [1285].<br />

[1329] Gunther: graded C When a worker is introduced to new machinery on the job<br />

they do not produce more value per hour. They are able to become more efficient with their<br />

task at hand and can essentially produce more <strong>of</strong> the product being produced per hour, but<br />

this does not increase the product’s value. The amount <strong>of</strong> labor exerted by the worker stays<br />

the same. For example; If I have been packaging golf clubs at the Callaway golf factory by<br />

hand and suddenly acquire a tape gun my efficiency level rises with the surplus <strong>of</strong> output.<br />

Therefore, being introduced to new machinery does not increase the value per hour, while<br />

the output production surplus does rise.<br />

Hans: If they produce more products per hour and the value <strong>of</strong> the product stays the same, then they produce more<br />

value per hour. Marx would agree with this only in the short run. In the long run, the value <strong>of</strong> each piece <strong>of</strong> the<br />

product falls.


196 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Gunther is [1330].<br />

[1345] Speq: Marx would say that yes, the workers do produce more value per hour when<br />

new machinery is used. This implies that the additional value is generated by the worker<br />

and the additional pr<strong>of</strong>its generated are part <strong>of</strong> the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the worker. I disagree with<br />

Marx on this point. I would argue that, even though more value is being added to the product,<br />

the individual worker is not the one adding it. The new machine is adding the value. The<br />

value that the machine adds is due to the value added to the machine during the labor process<br />

that created the machine or the natural value that resides from coming from the Earth. I.e.<br />

to create the machine, labor power was used (or found naturally). The value created by that<br />

labor power (or from nature) is realized when used by the worker. This value is added to the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the worker’s labor power to create the final value <strong>of</strong> the completed product. This<br />

would instead imply that the value created by the new machines does in fact belong to the<br />

capitalist, being the one that paid for the value on the open market, and not an exploitation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the worker’s labor power.<br />

Hans: Marx thinks that only in the short term, while the machine is new and not generally used, workers using this<br />

machine will create more value per hour. After this initial period, they create the same value as other comparable<br />

labor.<br />

According to Marx, commodity production does not have a direct way to value material resources.<br />

Marx agrees with you that machines transfer the value which they received from the labor <strong>of</strong> those producing<br />

them. But Marx emphasizes that other than this transfer, machines do not add new value to the product.<br />

Next Message by Speq is [1346].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 197<br />

[1384] ZachS: graded B Yes, the workers using the new machinery, as long as the new<br />

machine has exceptional productivity making the task much less labor intensive, do produce<br />

more value per hour than those with similar skills and productivity, but are still using old<br />

machinery.<br />

Hans: This is only half the story. In the long run, the value produced per hour remains exactly the same.<br />

Next Message by ZachS is [1385].<br />

Exam Question 741 is 218 in 1995ut, 242 in 1996sp, 293 in 1997WI, 365 in 1998WI, 366<br />

in 1999SP, 453 in 2000fa, 479 in 2001fa, 518 in 2002fa, 538 in 2003fa, 592 in 2004fa,<br />

545 in 2005fa, 598 in 2007SP, 588 in 2007fa, 596 in 2008SP, 600 in 2008fa, and 712 in<br />

2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 741 What is extra surplus-value? How is it related to relative surplusvalue?<br />

[999] Reginald: Extra Surplus Value. Extra surplus value is taken by individual capitalists<br />

from their enterprises by reducing the individual value <strong>of</strong> the commodity. The higher<br />

productivity <strong>of</strong> the labor <strong>of</strong> workers in the technologically more advanced enterprises, in<br />

comparison to the average level <strong>of</strong> productivity for a particular sector. Extra surplus value is<br />

temporary, because when new techniques and technology spread to other business in a similar<br />

sector, the social value <strong>of</strong> the commodities declines, and the disparities between their<br />

individual and social value disappears. Although extra surplus value is temporary, it doesn’t


198 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

disappear entirely but shifts from some capitalists to others. The extra surplus value consist<br />

<strong>of</strong> multiple surplus values. This is how they work together.<br />

Next Message by Reginald is [1266].<br />

Question 747 is 547 in 2005fa, 606 in 2008fa, 635 in 2009fa, and 698 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 747 Relative surplus-value requires the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power to fall. Does this<br />

mean that in today’s world with sticky wages and union contracts, relative surplus-value is<br />

impossible?<br />

[997] Curtis: (graded A) Sticky wages and surplus value. On pg. 533 <strong>of</strong> the Annotations,<br />

Hans presents scenarios in which the surplus-value remains constant even when the<br />

required value <strong>of</strong> labor power remains constant. Each <strong>of</strong> these scenarios involves both prices<br />

and wages falling. In today’s world, union contracts typically prevent falling wages; however,<br />

both wages and prices fell in the scenarios Hans presented. Capitalists accommodate<br />

for their inability to decrease wages by not dropping prices. Thus, the error in thinking<br />

that union contracts and sticky wages prevent relative surplus-value from being accrued is<br />

thinking in nominal, rather than real, terms. In real terms, the value represented by the<br />

worker’s wages is falling as a result <strong>of</strong> technological progress, but the worker neither has his<br />

work-day reduced nor his wages increased. Technological progress creates surplus-value<br />

for the capitalist, which is cleverly disguised in unchanged wages and prices. As Jo said in<br />

[2010fa:705], “Since the worker’s wage is not increasing to compensate for the change in


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 199<br />

labor content, they are essentially receiving a lower wage.” Marx also points to the role <strong>of</strong><br />

technological progress in the creation <strong>of</strong> surplus value in 435:1/o; to paraphrase, the capitalist<br />

pays the same wage as before, even though the required time to reproduce value has<br />

dropped, and the capitalist’s surplus-value grows.<br />

Hans: Re-reading this later in the Semester I realize that I need to explain something which is only implicit in this<br />

answer. Monetary policy keeping the purchasing power <strong>of</strong> money constant is not analogous to keeping the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> gold constant, but to the technical progress in the production <strong>of</strong> gold being the same as the technical progress in<br />

the production <strong>of</strong> everything else. If this is the case, technical progress does not decrease prices, but it increases the<br />

dollar amount <strong>of</strong> value created per hour.<br />

Message [997] referenced by [1359]. Next Message by Curtis is [998].<br />

[1359] Nunu: Relative surplus value and consistent wages. Relative surplus-value is<br />

still possible even in today’s world with sticky wages and union contracts because <strong>of</strong> technological<br />

innovation. The advancement <strong>of</strong> technology allows for the value <strong>of</strong> the product to<br />

be greater than the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power because more is being produced in the same amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> time as before the new and improved technology came into place. So, even when wages<br />

remain constant, production can keep increasing with technological advancement therefore<br />

driving greater returns and relative surplus-value. Even as wages remain the same because<br />

<strong>of</strong> sticky wages or union contracts, the capitalist still has the option to not drop prices or<br />

even increase prices (Curtis [997]).<br />

Next Message by Nunu is [1360].


200 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1392] AR: graded C+ Relative surplus-value requires the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power to fall.<br />

Does this mean that in today’s world relative surplus-value is impossible? Even in<br />

today’s world relative surplus-value is possible. ZuluBaba [2009fa:732] brings up a good<br />

example <strong>of</strong> how some employees in some companies took pay cuts in order to save other<br />

co-workers from being laid <strong>of</strong>f during the recent recession. On the contrary, sticky wages<br />

and union contracts bring down relative surplus-value and make wages closer to necessary<br />

labor-time. This will never make it impossible in the capitalist system. Hans shows on<br />

page 533 in the text, “how the individual capitalist are motivated to produce relative surplus<br />

value.” The reason is competition. Competition is why prices are lowered. Competition is<br />

what turns extra surplus-value into relative surplus-value.<br />

Hans: “Sticky wages” means that workers resist a lowering <strong>of</strong> their nominal wages, and unions help them in this<br />

resistance. This does not matter because technological progress not only lowers the value <strong>of</strong> the worker’s means or<br />

consumption but it also lowers the value <strong>of</strong> gold, therefore it does not lead to lower prices.<br />

Next Message by AR is [1404].<br />

Exam Question 760 is 77 in 1996ut, 83 in 1997WI, 363 in 1997sp, 361 in 1997ut, 525<br />

in 2002fa, 545 in 2003fa, 599 in 2004fa, 552 in 2005fa, 625 in 2007SP, 605 in 2007fa,<br />

613 in 2008SP, 617 in 2008fa, 648 in 2009fa, 711 in 2010fa, 730 in 2011fa, and 711 in<br />

Answer:<br />

Exam Question 760 Your employer gives you your paycheck. How can you tell whether<br />

your pay is based on your labor or not? According to Marx, the simple practical detail that


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 201<br />

the pay <strong>of</strong> most people is based on their labor has strategic importance for the functioning<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalist system. What is this importance?<br />

[1086] Shelly: graded A Labor is the work performed. Labor-power is the human<br />

expenditure. If my paycheck states how many hours I worked, then my pay is based on<br />

my labor, aka the work performed. However, my paycheck does not show how much value<br />

I truly produced; it hides the exploitation <strong>of</strong> my labor-power. For instance, suppose I am<br />

paid $300 for the week. My paycheck will in fact reflect this figure, but it will not show<br />

that the capitalist actually sold the commodity for $600, which is the total value I produced.<br />

The $300 reflects my labor and the amount required for subsistence. The $600 reflects the<br />

value I produced with my labor-power. So, why do I sell my labor-power for less than its<br />

true value? Because I do not own the means <strong>of</strong> production, the capitalist does.<br />

Hans: Your subject line is not quite right. Labor-power is the human ability to work. Selling one’s labor-power<br />

means to rent oneself out and allow the capitalist to use one’s ability to work for his purposes.<br />

In Marx’s view, the fact that the paycheck hides exploitation has strategic importance.<br />

Next Message by Shelly is [1087].<br />

[1117] KATES: Paychecks and Labor. Marx states that your hourly wages are determined<br />

by dividing your average weekly reproduction cost by the normal number <strong>of</strong> hours<br />

you work every week. If a paycheck shows how many hours you worked or how much <strong>of</strong><br />

something you produced during your work time then you can see from your paycheck that


202 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

your pay is based on the labor you performed at your job. This calculated form <strong>of</strong> payment<br />

hides the exploitation <strong>of</strong> labor or else capitalism would not survive.<br />

Next Message by KATES is [1118].<br />

Question 761 is 710 in 2010fa and 731 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 761 Both the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity and the mystification <strong>of</strong> the<br />

wage form are important pillars <strong>of</strong> capitalism. How are these two pillars related to each<br />

other?<br />

[1006] AndyUte: graded B The Mystification <strong>of</strong> Capitalism. On page 675 in Capital,<br />

Marx states regarding the mystification <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the wage form that “In order to be sold as a<br />

commodity in the market, labour must at all events exist before it is sold. But if the worker<br />

were able to endow it with an independent existence, he would be selling a commodity, and<br />

not labour.” Similarly, Marx introduces us to the fog <strong>of</strong> the ‘fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity’<br />

on page 164 stating “A commodity appears at first sight an extremely obvious, trivial<br />

thing. But its analysis brings out that it is a very strange thing, abounding in metaphysical<br />

subtleties and theological niceties.”<br />

Marx, no doubt, considers both the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity and the mystification<br />

<strong>of</strong> the wage form, as important pillars to capitalism, to be controversial and extremely<br />

troublesome to understand. Because most <strong>of</strong> the partakers <strong>of</strong> capitalism are senseless to how


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 203<br />

the system works, pillars such as the wage form and the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

will continue to cloak Capitalism and limit its ‘bottom feeders’. Just as it is difficult for<br />

a blind man to remove himself out <strong>of</strong> a maze it is difficult for a worker to escape the bonds<br />

<strong>of</strong> Capitalism, especially when he does not know he is bound.<br />

Hans: Do you consider workers to be the “bottom-feeders” <strong>of</strong> capitalism?<br />

Your answer was originally submitted under question number 783, but it does not say anything about this<br />

question. So I assume that you meant it as an answer to question 761.<br />

Next Message by AndyUte is [1095].<br />

[1014] Curtis: graded A+ Mystification <strong>of</strong> Wages and the Commodity’s Fetish-Like<br />

Character. Both the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity and the mystification <strong>of</strong> wages<br />

are illusions that, on the surface, appear to be reality.<br />

The fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity gives the commodity “magical” properties<br />

that it does not truly have. Producers make commodities in order to exchange them for other<br />

use-values, and because the commodity is the avenue through which the rest <strong>of</strong> society is<br />

accessed, the commodity develops a fetish-like character, even though a commodity is still<br />

made <strong>of</strong> the same matter everything else is.<br />

Wages are mystified by appering to be derived from labor when they are really derived<br />

from labor-power. The capitalist has not bought the worker’s labor, meaning the work performed,<br />

but labor-power, the ability to do work. A helpful analogy I can think <strong>of</strong> to further


204 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

describe the difference between labor and labor-power is to think <strong>of</strong> labor-power as raw marble,<br />

and labor as the sculpture formed from the marble; the capitalist purchases the marble,<br />

not the sculpture, but also creates a sculpture from the marble.<br />

Both the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities and the mystification <strong>of</strong> wages are based on<br />

contradictions between the internal character and the external appearance. [2010fa:727] and<br />

[2010fa:326] draw on the importance <strong>of</strong> internal contradictions in producing surface appearances<br />

that hide a deeper functioning and reality. For the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities,<br />

the contradiction lies between the specific use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity and its existence as unchanging<br />

matter, and the power <strong>of</strong> the commodity to connect the commodity owner with the<br />

rest <strong>of</strong> his society. The mystification <strong>of</strong> wages is also based on a contradiction, namely the<br />

contradiction between labor and labor-power, the former representing a specific act and the<br />

latter representing the general ability to work.<br />

Second, both <strong>of</strong> these pillars <strong>of</strong> capitalism are necessary to uphold the capitalist system.<br />

[2010fa:727] said,<br />

They form the structure, the housing; without these misconceptions and<br />

without the confusion, capitalism would not work. Marx believes that these<br />

misleading surface interactions rooted in the mode <strong>of</strong> production (capitalism)<br />

produce ideas and consciousness in the people living in the system.<br />

The people accept the mode <strong>of</strong> production, and all <strong>of</strong> its surface relations,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 205<br />

as given. This is what Marx believes actually imprisons and enslaves the<br />

workers in the capitalist system.<br />

Why is it that capitalism “would not work” without the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

and the mystification <strong>of</strong> wages? Without the commodity’s fetish-like character, commodities<br />

would not be traded; the appearance <strong>of</strong> the commodity as the channel through<br />

which the rest <strong>of</strong> society’s productive power is accessed, commodities would not be produced.<br />

Producers would say, “Why should we produce commodities? I’d rather produce<br />

what I will consume.” The capitalist system would reach a grinding halt. Without the mystification<br />

<strong>of</strong> wages, workers would be less willing to sell their labor power. They would<br />

ask, “Why should I sell my labor-power when I could consume it myself and produce commodities<br />

and sell them myself?” One might even suggest that the mystification <strong>of</strong> wages<br />

is a special case <strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity, where labor-power is the<br />

commodity.<br />

Hans: Your essay is very good but the last paragraph is wrong. Production for home use without division <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

is far less effective than modern mass production. People simply do not have the option to do this. And they cannot<br />

use their labor-power themselves because they don’t have access to modern factories and warehouses.<br />

Next Message by Curtis is [1068].<br />

[1016] SLOVENEC: The fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity and the mystification <strong>of</strong><br />

the wage form are related to each other due to the clouding effect they cause on the minds<br />

<strong>of</strong> those participating in a capitalist society. For instance, the fetish-like charactor <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity creates a misconception among the workers due to the transformation <strong>of</strong> human


206 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

relations from the subjective, perceivable, aspects <strong>of</strong> a commodity to objective, socially<br />

determined, aspects <strong>of</strong> the commodity. By doing this, workers no longer see the full value<br />

behind each product and consequently, are ignorant to the full use-value they create. This<br />

allows the capitalists to only pay them a portion <strong>of</strong> what, in reality, they truly create. And in<br />

the case <strong>of</strong> the mystification <strong>of</strong> the wage form, the labour time required by each worker in<br />

a given day becomes necessary labor, labor that the worker is actually paid for, and surplus<br />

labor, labor that the worker is not paid for but transfers those earnings into pr<strong>of</strong>its for the<br />

capitalists. Both <strong>of</strong> these processes cloud and distort workers so that they are numb to the<br />

fact that they are being taken advantage <strong>of</strong>. In order to earn pr<strong>of</strong>its, a company must restrict<br />

wages so as to allow room for surplus labor, and the system <strong>of</strong> earning pr<strong>of</strong>its is capitalism.<br />

Without these two mechanisms, capitalism would not exist because workers would only<br />

work until they create the equivalent value for which they are paid.<br />

Next Message by SLOVENEC is [1126].<br />

[1401] SLOVENEC: The fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities and the mystification <strong>of</strong> the<br />

wage form provide the pillars on which capitalism can stand and are related to each other<br />

because they both cloud out the reality <strong>of</strong> what’s going on. The mystification <strong>of</strong> the wage<br />

form creates confusion, as the laborer is not able to see that the value he is producing is more<br />

than his wage. The fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodities allows people to sell as much as<br />

they can and hoard money. These two mechanisms maintain the disorientation <strong>of</strong> the public<br />

and numbs them to the reality that they are being exploited.<br />

Hans: Wrong definition <strong>of</strong> fetish-like character.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 207<br />

Next Message by SLOVENEC is [1526].<br />

[1405] Roosty: The mystification <strong>of</strong> wage for and the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

are both pillars <strong>of</strong> capitalism because they hide the realities <strong>of</strong> exchange in capitalism<br />

from consumers and laborers. The mystification <strong>of</strong> wage form is a pillar <strong>of</strong> capitalism because<br />

it enables the capitalist to exploit his laborer by paying for labor as opposed to laborpower.<br />

The fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity is a pillar <strong>of</strong> capitalism because it give<br />

properties to the commodity that do not truly exist, and thus, gives the ability to produce<br />

and sell the commodity based on these manifested properties. These deceptions enable the<br />

capitalist to increase their surplus-value without the consumer’s knowledge.<br />

Hans: Wrong characterization <strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Also your other two contributions<br />

about this subject, [298] and [767], show that you did not understand Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> commodity fetishism but<br />

instead knitted together your own theory.<br />

Next Message by Roosty is [1524].<br />

Exam Question 769 is 226 in 1995ut, 250 in 1996sp, 248 in 1996ut, 301 in 1997WI, 367<br />

in 1997sp, 491 in 2001fa, 530 in 2002fa, 551 in 2003fa, 607 in 2004fa, 560 in 2005fa,<br />

634 in 2007SP, 614 in 2007fa, 626 in 2008fa, 720 in 2010fa, and 740 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 769 Why can the laborer not use her labor-power to produce commodities<br />

and sell them, instead <strong>of</strong> selling her labor-power?<br />

[1087] Shelly: graded A Silly rabbit, the capitalist owns the means to production! The<br />

workers sell their labor power rather than using it to produce and sell their own commodities


208 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

because the capitalist owns the means to production. Since the capitalist is the one who<br />

owns the factories, the cloth, the machines, etc the worker has no other choice than to sell<br />

his labor-power to the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Shelly is [1120].<br />

[1107] AndyUte: graded A McDonalds. Our laborer has no choice but to sell her laborpower<br />

because she does not have the necessary production methods as our capitalist does.<br />

For example, a hamburger flipper at McDonalds chooses to sell her labor-power to McDonalds<br />

rather than start her own restaurant where she could sell her own hamburgers because<br />

the necessary costs to own her own restaurant greatly exceeds her own assets.<br />

Hans: This is the right answer, and a good example.<br />

Message [1107] referenced by [1286]. Next Message by AndyUte is [1109].<br />

[1191] Elias: graded A The Capitalist Owns Your Means. The laborer is unable to use<br />

her labor-power to produce commodities because the capitalist owns the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

The capitalist owns the raw materials, machinery, and the factory space to produce<br />

those goods, not the laborer. However, she does own the labor-power that is required to<br />

operate and make the factory actually work. Therefore, she has to sell her labor-power to<br />

the capitalist in order to receive a wage, and the capitalist buys this so that they may obtain<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it. If the laborer owned the means <strong>of</strong> production, she would not have to sell her<br />

labor-power to anyone!<br />

Next Message by Elias is [1193].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 209<br />

[1236] Alee: The laborer can not use her labor-power to produce commodities and sell<br />

them because the labor power can only be sold.<br />

Next Message by Alee is [1240].<br />

[1270] Smalls: She does not have access to the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Next Message by Smalls is [1271].<br />

[1275] Shickadance: graded A If the laborer controlled the means <strong>of</strong> production, she<br />

would be willing and able to use her labor power to produce and sell commodities. The problem<br />

she runs into is having the necessary means <strong>of</strong> production. The cost <strong>of</strong> those means <strong>of</strong><br />

production would put her in a hole, so she has to resort to an hourly wage from a productionmeans-owning<br />

capitalist. Someone who works at Taco Bell can make a tasty taco, and might<br />

be successful on their own. But this laborer doesn’t control means <strong>of</strong> production, and has to<br />

make tacos for a capitalist where resources are available.<br />

Next Message by Shickadance is [1279].<br />

[1286] Littlerock: graded A Laborer Doesn’t Own the Means <strong>of</strong> Production. The<br />

laborer does not own the means <strong>of</strong> production. The capitalists monopolize the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

As AndyUte explained in [1107], a hamburger flipper at Mcdonalds cannot produce<br />

his own hamburgers because he does not have the necessary assets to buy a restaurant.<br />

Next Message by Littlerock is [1536].<br />

[1332] Gunther: graded A This question only requires a simple response. The capitalists<br />

monopolize the means <strong>of</strong> production. The worker doesn’t have the necessary capital or


210 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

assets to rent a business building, provide machinery, tools, computers, etc. Therefore he or<br />

she is forced by the capitalist society into selling her labor power to the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Gunther is [1482].<br />

[1346] Speq: The laborer cannot use her labor power to produce commodities because<br />

she has no means <strong>of</strong> production. I.e. she does not possess the tools and supplies needed to go<br />

into production herself. Making the problem worse is her need to sustain herself. She cannot<br />

live <strong>of</strong>f nothing during the production process and cannot wait for the sale <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

to buy her subsistence.<br />

Next Message by Speq is [1347].<br />

[1378] Ruffian: The laborer cannot use their labor power to produce commodities because<br />

they do not control the full means <strong>of</strong> production, only their own labor and time. The Capitalist<br />

provides the necessary means to create a commodity, such as the buyers and suppliers<br />

as well as the ability to sell to others, but never the workers. If the laborer supplied these<br />

they would immediately change roles.<br />

Next Message by Ruffian is [1379].<br />

[1388] ZachS: graded C Labor-power is part <strong>of</strong> what gives a commodity its value, so<br />

labor-power must be sold by the worker to give the commodity value. If the worker wants,<br />

it can use its labor to produce commodities, but not labor-power because <strong>of</strong> how the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity is defined.<br />

Next Message by ZachS is [1476].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 211<br />

[1403] Amcelhiney: Workers have no control over the means <strong>of</strong> production. The laborer<br />

must make enough money to survive and the only opportunity they have to make money is<br />

to sell their labor power to the capitalist.<br />

Hans: You are not allowed to re-write the designated exam questions. The grade is for your in-class answer, with<br />

a penalty.<br />

First Message by Amcelhiney is [677].<br />

Question 783 is 754 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 783 What are the contradictions <strong>of</strong> the concept “value <strong>of</strong> labor”?<br />

[1005] Frankie: graded B+ Absolutely Contradictory. The contradiction <strong>of</strong> the concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> “value <strong>of</strong> labor” is expressly stated in the terminology “value <strong>of</strong> labor” by implying that<br />

in fact labor has value. This is stated by Alex [2011fa:677] “According to Marx, the term<br />

‘value <strong>of</strong> labor’ is in itself one giant contradiction, as it implies that labor has value. Marx<br />

makes clear that labor cannot have value itself. As such, any use <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> labor term<br />

is essentially a figurative expression.” In the Annotations it is stated how this contradiction<br />

was originally formed saying “Classical economists did not see the logical impossibility that<br />

labor, the source <strong>of</strong> value, cannot have value itself.”<br />

Hans: Look what I said in [2011fa:690] about Alex [2011fa:677].<br />

Next Message by Frankie is [1024].


212 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Exam Question 787 is 221 in 1995WI, 258 in 1996sp, 257 in 1996ut, 373 in 1997ut, 544<br />

in 2002fa, 621 in 2004fa, 573 in 2005fa, 630 in 2007fa, 642 in 2008fa, 673 in 2009fa,<br />

and 758 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 787 How is the “value <strong>of</strong> labor” derived from the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power?<br />

Compare the “value <strong>of</strong> labor” thus obtained with the value <strong>of</strong> the product <strong>of</strong> the labor.<br />

[1099] Gladwell: graded A Capitalist Pr<strong>of</strong>it. To find the value <strong>of</strong> labor you must divide<br />

the daily value <strong>of</strong> labor-power by the daily number <strong>of</strong> hours worked [2005fa:1349]. The<br />

value <strong>of</strong> labor is the wage the worker must be paid to work, which is also equal to her cost<br />

<strong>of</strong> living. The capitalist will always ensure that the value <strong>of</strong> labor is less than the value <strong>of</strong><br />

the product <strong>of</strong> the labor, for this is how the capitalist obtains pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Message [1099] referenced by [1118]. Next Message by Gladwell is [1108].<br />

[1118] KATES: Value <strong>of</strong> labor and value <strong>of</strong> labor power. The value <strong>of</strong> labor is a derivative<br />

<strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> labor power. The value gained from the product <strong>of</strong> labor then becomes<br />

a reflection <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> labor power. In a commodity, labor is reflected by production.<br />

Labor is not able to be priced because it is an action that has not happened and the labor is<br />

not produced. The value <strong>of</strong> labor comes from the actual production. As [1113] Neela stated,<br />

Chapter 6 is where Marx first discusses labor power as a commodity.<br />

Hans: This answer is too vague, and in an exam you should not open the can <strong>of</strong> worms why labor has no value<br />

if it is not necessary. In an exam it would be totally sufficient to say: “the word ‘value <strong>of</strong> labor’ in the question<br />

is in scare quotes because labor does not really have a value.” Gladwell [1099] gave a good answer which does<br />

everything an exam answer would require.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 213<br />

Next Message by KATES is [1155].<br />

[1122] GMS: Value <strong>of</strong> labor-power. Marx explains the labor <strong>of</strong> value as labor-power<br />

as the tool to create value, and this is the only way to produce value. Therefore whenever<br />

someone produces something it creates value. The value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is derived from<br />

the labor <strong>of</strong> the workers and nothing else. The workers are not receiving the value they are<br />

producing, the workers only get the wage.<br />

Hans: You are not answering the question.<br />

Next Message by GMS is [1123].<br />

[1246] PJM: Value <strong>of</strong> Labor. The value <strong>of</strong> labor is essentially the value <strong>of</strong> a day’s labor<br />

power divided by the number <strong>of</strong> labor hours actually worked. Since the value <strong>of</strong> labor is<br />

merely a derivative <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> labor power, it is always less than the value created by<br />

labor. This difference in the value <strong>of</strong> labor or value <strong>of</strong> labor power and the value created by<br />

labor is the reason for the capitalist’s pr<strong>of</strong>it in performing M-C-M’.<br />

Next Message by PJM is [1249].<br />

[1311] Frankie: graded D The value <strong>of</strong> labor is derived by taking overall value produced<br />

during the day and dividing it by the amount <strong>of</strong> hours worked. The value <strong>of</strong> labor is always<br />

lower than the value <strong>of</strong> the product <strong>of</strong> the labor (or capitalism would no longer exist). The<br />

value <strong>of</strong> labor is lower than the value <strong>of</strong> the product <strong>of</strong> the labor and this excess is the pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

gained by the capitalist through the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the worker.<br />

Hans: What you have to start with is not the value produced during the day but the daily value <strong>of</strong> labor-power.<br />

This difference is a central point in Marx’s theory.


214 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Frankie is [1314].<br />

[1313] Agloeck: value <strong>of</strong> labor vs. labor-power. The “value <strong>of</strong> labor” is derived by<br />

taking the daily value <strong>of</strong> labor-power and dividing it by the number <strong>of</strong> hours worked in a<br />

day. The value <strong>of</strong> the product <strong>of</strong> labor is always greater than the value <strong>of</strong> labor because the<br />

capitalist controls the means <strong>of</strong> production and can exploit the worker; paying the worker<br />

for his labor-power not for the value he creates with his labor.<br />

Hans: In your first sentence you had “taking the daily value <strong>of</strong> labor,” I corrected it, but a full answer would also<br />

have to say how the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power is determined.<br />

Next Message by Agloeck is [1367].<br />

[1381] Roosty: The “value <strong>of</strong> labor” is the portion <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power that the<br />

laborer is compensated for. The “value <strong>of</strong> labor” will be less than the value <strong>of</strong> the product <strong>of</strong><br />

labor, as this is how the capitalist exploits his worker to gain pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Next Message by Roosty is [1391].<br />

[1399] SLOVENEC: The “value <strong>of</strong> labor” is derived from the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power as<br />

workers are paid for the value <strong>of</strong> their labor power, but in actuality create more value in the<br />

commodity they produce. Therefore, once the labor power is hired and employed, this leads<br />

to the value <strong>of</strong> labor i.e. the value that can be extracted from the workforce, and ultimately<br />

ends once a commodity is produced containing a higher value than what the workers were<br />

paid for. This leads to pr<strong>of</strong>its for capitalists, and exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers. This is possible<br />

because the capitalist owns the means <strong>of</strong> production and the workers don’t<br />

Next Message by SLOVENEC is [1401].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 215<br />

[1402] IrwinFletcher: graded C Value <strong>of</strong> labor is derived from the value <strong>of</strong> labor power<br />

because value <strong>of</strong> labor is what the laborer gets paid for, or the amount that he sells his labor<br />

to the capitalist for. The value <strong>of</strong> the labor power is the value <strong>of</strong> the product <strong>of</strong> what the<br />

laborer is making. The capitalist always wants the value <strong>of</strong> the power to be greater than the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> labor because that ensures that the capitalist earns a pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Hans: Wrong definition <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> labor-power.<br />

Next Message by IrwinFletcher is [1454].<br />

[1415] GTIguy: In order to derive the value <strong>of</strong> labor from the value <strong>of</strong> labor power<br />

you must divide the value <strong>of</strong> labor power by the number <strong>of</strong> hours worked each day. The<br />

difference between what the commodity sold for and the wages paid for labor is the value<br />

generated by the laborer and the pr<strong>of</strong>it margin for the capitalist.<br />

Hans: Your grade is for your in-class answer, with a penalty because you are not allowed to re-write the answers<br />

<strong>of</strong> the designated exam questions.<br />

Next Message by GTIguy is [1458].<br />

[1421] Novatore: Value <strong>of</strong> labor is derived from vale <strong>of</strong> labor-power by dividing the daily<br />

wage by the daily hours worked. Once obtained, this value, compared to the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

product <strong>of</strong> labor, can indicate how much surplus value was extracted from the laborer’s labor<br />

process.<br />

Next Message by Novatore is [1480].<br />

[1424] Tiburon: The value <strong>of</strong> labor is derived from the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power, and it<br />

can be explained as the capacity <strong>of</strong> the laborer to perform a certain task. The capitalist


216 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

buys the labor-power, but in the capitalist reality, it compensates the worker for the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor performed. When this happens, is like buying wine and only compensating the<br />

seller according to the degree to which you get drunk with his/her wine. This is incorrect,<br />

nevertheless this happens daily in the capitalist society to hide exploitation, and thus the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> labor could be compared with the value <strong>of</strong> the product <strong>of</strong> the labor.<br />

Hans: The capitalist does not “compensate the worker for the value <strong>of</strong> labor performed.” The worker gets the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> his labor-power, no more.<br />

Next Message by Tiburon is [1561].<br />

[1429] Vini: The value <strong>of</strong> the labor includes the alternate forms <strong>of</strong> labor that went into<br />

making the final product that is not always considered in the final purchase price. The<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the final product <strong>of</strong> labor is what others are willing to part with or pay to obtain<br />

the product, and <strong>of</strong>ten times what the potential buyer is willing to pay does not include the<br />

sweat, blood, tears and muscle power that went into the production process, just what the<br />

buyer is willing to concede. This is the difference between the value <strong>of</strong> labor and the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the product <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Hans: Wrong definitions and wrong theory <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its, as far as Marx is concerned.<br />

Next Message by Vini is [1455].<br />

Question 791 is 653 in 2007SP, 633 in 2007fa, 645 in 2008fa, 740 in 2010fa, and 762 in<br />

2011fa:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 217<br />

Question 791 Would capitalism be possible if exploitation was not hidden but clearly visible<br />

to everybody involved?<br />

[1013] Curtis: (graded A) How Exploitation Can Exist. After reading through many <strong>of</strong><br />

the answers to this question in the archives, I noticed many attempted to answer this question<br />

based upon the conscience <strong>of</strong> consumers and capitalists. I don’t feel this is the most insightful<br />

way to approach this question. Consumers purchasing superficially cheap commodities<br />

and capitalists exploiting their workers are not surprising facts, and even with awareness,<br />

it’s possible nothing would change on a large scale in their behavior. Whatsmore, examining<br />

the conscience <strong>of</strong> consumers and capitalists in the process and at the end <strong>of</strong> the creation <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities does not answer how those commodities could possibly be created to begin<br />

with; why is it that the workers who are being exploited continue to sell their labor power?<br />

Capitalist and consumer conscience, admittedly, could help stop exploitation, but does not<br />

explain how the exploitative relationship emerged to begin with, and in that investigation, the<br />

worker, who willingly accepts the exploitative relationship (albeit sometimes begrudgingly)<br />

must come first.<br />

After reading this, you would be correct in assuming that I do not believe that capitalism<br />

could exist if exploitation were clearly visible. I recall Hans’ comment in the Annotations<br />

that there is no whistle in the workday signalling the end <strong>of</strong> necessary value-reproducing<br />

labor and the beginning <strong>of</strong> surplus labor. Imagine, for a second, that such a whistle did exist.


218 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

What would happen after the whistle blows? What would the workers do? Would they work<br />

with equal diligence? It’s only by the compulsion <strong>of</strong> the capitalist and her threat to fire her<br />

workers that they even stay. And what if that whistle blew later in the day for some capitalists<br />

and earlier in the day for others? Who would the workers be more willing to work for? The<br />

mill where the whistle blows earlier would struggle finding labor. It’s simply hard to imagine<br />

capitalism functioning effectively and the workers placatedly accepting their wage-slavery<br />

if they were aware they were being exploited. It’s necessary for capitalism to maintain the<br />

illusion <strong>of</strong> fairness in order to keep the working class complacent and willing to accept their<br />

exploitation and continue to sell their labor-power, rather than rejecting the capitalist class<br />

and producing on their own, with only enough surplus value to maintain investment.<br />

Next Message by Curtis is [1014].<br />

[1023] Basil: There May be No End to Exploitation. When Marx uses the term “exploitation”<br />

he is referring to whenever laborers receive wages for less than the value <strong>of</strong> their<br />

labor production. The surplus value that the laborers create, in turn, becomes pr<strong>of</strong>it for<br />

the capitalist. From this, we can deduce that the term “exploitation” is essentially synonymous<br />

with the term “pr<strong>of</strong>it” because in a capitalist economy, the way the capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its is<br />

charging more for a product than it costs to produce, thereby accumulating the surplus value<br />

from their laborers. This question asks, “Would capitalism be possible if exploitation was<br />

not hidden?” I would argue yes: I do not think that capitalism is possible without exploitation<br />

(that would mean no pr<strong>of</strong>its), but I do think capitalism can occur with visibly exposed<br />

exploitation.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 219<br />

Right now, exploitation is hidden because people do not think in terms <strong>of</strong> the labor theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. We do not think about the fact that when we produce something that someone else<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its from, we are being exploited, and we do not think about how when we buy goods that<br />

someone else pr<strong>of</strong>its from, we are contributing to the exploitation <strong>of</strong> other workers. If the<br />

mindset <strong>of</strong> people changed to the point where we did think in these terms, however, I still do<br />

not believe it would change the phenomenon <strong>of</strong> exploitation itself, at least not significantly.<br />

This response had to parts, the first is to the question whether people would stop exploiting<br />

others if they realized they were doing it, the second is whether people would try to put<br />

a stop to it if they realized they were being exploited. To the first part <strong>of</strong> the question, I feel<br />

like the simple answer is no. Because <strong>of</strong> the capitalist attitude people inherit that the world<br />

is a zero-sum “me against you” game, it is easy to rationalize the exploitation <strong>of</strong> others. In<br />

the most extreme and egregious cases, like forcing children to work in dangerous conditions,<br />

and sweat shops paying people just pennies per day, people <strong>of</strong>ten seem to be well aware <strong>of</strong><br />

these issues, but it does not stop them from buying products produced made in China and<br />

East Asia in this manner just described.<br />

To the second part <strong>of</strong> the question, <strong>of</strong> whether people would put an end to exploitation if<br />

they realized the capitalist was exploiting their productive power, I still think no. It seems<br />

that to this end, there may be more resistance by people who feel unfairly exploited, but<br />

overall the system would not change. It is true today that people do feel exploited, not in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> their labor-power like Marx describes, but in terms <strong>of</strong> their purchasing power. I


220 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

think many people do realize that their purchasing power is intentionally limited in favor <strong>of</strong><br />

the capitalist who own the means <strong>of</strong> production, and that their real income is not sufficient<br />

relative to market prices. Because <strong>of</strong> this, we occasionally see labor strikes, or movements<br />

like Occupy Wall Street, but they are not enough to incite change. However, maybe, as the<br />

question states, if exploitation became visible to all people, we would see movements and<br />

opposition on a large enough scale to change the status quo.<br />

The only way I could see visibly exposed exploitation putting an end to the capitalist<br />

system is first, as I stated above, that people realized on a very large scale that they are being<br />

exploited, but second, that people choose to stop exploiting others when they realize they are<br />

doing it. To me the first is more achievable, but the latter will be very difficult. And as long<br />

as there is one person doing the exploiting, there will be another who is exploited. Therefore,<br />

I do believe capitalism would be possible if exploitation was not hidden but clearly visible<br />

to everybody involved.<br />

Next Message by Basil is [1054].<br />

[1026] Glister: hidden exploitation. In order to determine if capitalism would be possible<br />

if exploitation was not hidden, it is important to determine what Marx’s view <strong>of</strong> exploitation<br />

is. From the readings, exploitation is the benefit to one person without the other person<br />

gaining benefit. In addition, it is unfair that one person or party gains the benefit without<br />

any benefit going to the other person or party. If I understand it correctly, the capitalist is<br />

exploiting the laborer if and only if the capitalist benefits, without the capitalist benefiting


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 221<br />

the laborer in return . So we can see that this is simply unjust. I feel Marx believed that<br />

capitalism went hand in hand with exploitation because he believed it was unjust and not<br />

fair to the worker that did not get paid for their works, which were a product <strong>of</strong> his labor.<br />

Regarding the questions <strong>of</strong> whether or not capitalism is possible if exploitation was not<br />

hidden but clearly visible to everybody involved, initially the issue seemed simple but after<br />

some thought it became very complex and I began to think <strong>of</strong> many answers. I would like to<br />

start out by saying that I think that most people feel that they are being exploited in the labor<br />

market but don’t know to what extent they are being exploited at. For example, if we take an<br />

assembly job worker in an auto manufacturing plant, how is that worker going to know how<br />

much labor they contributed to the whole car manufacturing processes and the total value <strong>of</strong><br />

that car . I feel it all relates back to the industrial revolution when the worker was forced to<br />

perform repetition labor, unlike before when it was more <strong>of</strong> a craft and the labors work was<br />

more meaningful to him- or her-self.<br />

We also have to consider what Hans said in the annotations about there being no whistles<br />

when the surplus labor starts every day. So the question still remains, how can capitalism<br />

still be possible in this situation. I go to work because it’s the only way I can survive in this<br />

economy; in reality I don’t have much <strong>of</strong> a choice. I can either become an exploiter myself or<br />

join a union but that will still not fix the problem completely. I think that if exploitation was<br />

not hidden but clearly visible it would only change some people’s minds due to the worker<br />

only wanting the amount from the employer that would be sufficient for his or her needs.


222 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

But if we look at human nature, sufficient is never enough which leads me to believe that<br />

capitalization would not last if exploitation were not hidden and if at the same time we can<br />

keep one variable static. The variable would be the desire to become an exploiter himself.<br />

Hans: Marx uses the word “exploitation” for social relations between classes, not for individual interactions. See<br />

multiple choice question 612. Marx is critical <strong>of</strong> societies in which the transfer <strong>of</strong> wealth from certain classes to<br />

other classes is part <strong>of</strong> the social structure. Marx thinks if the means <strong>of</strong> production are controlled by the workers<br />

themselves, then people can still abuse each other and take advantage <strong>of</strong> each other individually, but you will not<br />

have idle rich people drawing property income while workers work all their lives and do not get ahead financially.<br />

Next Message by Glister is [1126].<br />

[1027] Amcelhiney: Visible exploitation. Exploitation is a necessity for the capitalist.<br />

Working class people (the majority) grow up understanding that they must work harder and<br />

produce more to progress, but they do not earn the pr<strong>of</strong>it increases that the capitalist takes.<br />

The worker sees and experiences the exploitation, but believe that they have little power to<br />

alter their situation. It is possible that many people are simply sheep that follow the herd and<br />

obey the shepherd (Capitalist). Exploited workers cannot beg to change their situation while<br />

supporting the same people that encourage the corruption.<br />

Hans: You say that exploitation is visible. My response here is: society is sending mixed signals. Sometimes<br />

exploitation is obvious, but in other situations there can be doubt. Many think capitalism is a meritocracy. Marx<br />

says: what counts is not merit but control over the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Next Message by Amcelhiney is [1259].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 223<br />

Question 805 is 668 in 2007SP, 646 in 2007fa, 655 in 2008SP, 659 in 2008fa, 690 in<br />

2009fa, 754 in 2010fa, and 776 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 805 Why a separate chapter about the time wage? Wasn’t the time wage already<br />

discussed in chapter Nineteen?<br />

[1052] Bimmer: graded B The surface <strong>of</strong> surfaces forms. In chapter 19, Marx focuses on<br />

the relationship between the wage at which a worker is paid and the price <strong>of</strong> labor-power. As<br />

Bandit in [2011fa:707] states,, “in this chapter he doesn’t fully explore the surface forms <strong>of</strong><br />

labor. Marx criticizes main stream economics as being obsessed with things on the surface,<br />

while neglecting the different shapes these forms can take.” Hans states in his remarks to<br />

[2008SP:548], “Marx says that it is not enough to go into depth i.e, to decipher what is<br />

behind the surface forms <strong>of</strong> the wage <strong>of</strong> labor, but that it is also worthwhile to look at the<br />

surface forms themselves in order to see how these forms lead to intensification <strong>of</strong> labor,<br />

wage theft, whether they foster competition or unity between workers, etc. Chapter 20 and<br />

21 take a more thorough look at the surface.” Marx discusses how surface forms try to make<br />

themselves independent <strong>of</strong> the underlying mechanism while arguing at the same time how<br />

the forms mediate their underlying mechanism and how the resulting effects are explored.<br />

Utilizing the discussion regarding surface forms, Marx establishes the argument that time<br />

wage and piece wage both have the ability to impact the length <strong>of</strong> the work day; whereas,<br />

the piece wage has the ability to impact the intensity <strong>of</strong> labor. It is nearly impossible to<br />

formulate a valid argument regarding the discussion <strong>of</strong> time wage after determining the


224 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

wage form from just chapter 19. The argument is purely based on the analysis <strong>of</strong> surface<br />

forms and their effects. This is why another chapter is needed. Time wages, needs a separate<br />

chapter in order to analyze the actual wage along with the economic laws that show that they<br />

not only originate in the sphere <strong>of</strong> production, but also on the surface. So to reiterate what<br />

Hans states, we must look more thoroughly at the surface itself versus just taking an in depth<br />

approach to decipher what is behind the surface forms as it is not enough to curb an argument<br />

and this is why Marx writes as separate chapter on time wages.<br />

Hans: The rules for the homework answers are that you have to use your own words. You bring a collage <strong>of</strong><br />

quotes, and then you paraphrase these quotes. I am not satisfied with this. I want you to tell me in your own words,<br />

using your own thinking, not copying someone else’s thinking, and using one coherent argument, not a multitude<br />

<strong>of</strong> different threads, why after chapter 19 Marx found it necessary to also write chapters 20 and 21.<br />

Message [1052] referenced by [1074]. Next Message by Bimmer is [1125].<br />

[1074] AR: graded B– weight 25% Separate chapters are needed to discuss time wages<br />

because as Hans states, “Chapter 19 established connection between the price <strong>of</strong> Labor on<br />

the surface and the underlying relations <strong>of</strong> production.” Deeper shapes also define the surface<br />

<strong>of</strong> price <strong>of</strong> labor and show a combination <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> labor power and the length <strong>of</strong> the work<br />

day. The main shapes are time wage and piece wage. Both <strong>of</strong> these shapes extend and<br />

intensify labor. Time-wages need another chapter in order to analyze the economic laws <strong>of</strong><br />

the actual wage and the sphere <strong>of</strong> production. By knowing that workers’ wage is calculated<br />

from the price <strong>of</strong> labor-power, in the later chapters the discussion <strong>of</strong> time-wage can take<br />

place.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 225<br />

Hans: Most <strong>of</strong> what you are writing is already covered in [1052]. Since your understanding <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory is<br />

not very strong, you should concentrate on questions about the structure <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory, and leave the details <strong>of</strong><br />

how he composed the book Capital to others. As long as you don’t know what Marx is saying, you have no basis<br />

to judge his exposition.<br />

I am therefore not surprised that your second sentence starting with “Deeper shapes” is unintelligible. Regarding<br />

your third sentence, the point <strong>of</strong> chapters 20 and 21 is exactly that they do not look at the links to the sphere <strong>of</strong><br />

production but that they stay on the surface.<br />

Next Message by AR is [1075].<br />

Question 806 is 691 in 2009fa and 755 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 806 What does one miss if one does not look at the form itself but only at that <strong>of</strong><br />

which it is the form?<br />

[1077] Nunu: Importance <strong>of</strong> surface forms. Marx says that labor wages have many<br />

forms and Hans further adds in the annotations that labor wages are a form <strong>of</strong> labor-power<br />

and that this form itself can take many shapes. If one does not look at this form itself and<br />

the many shapes that this form can take, many side effects can be missed. There is much to<br />

be said about the sphere <strong>of</strong> production but also about the things on the surface, for example<br />

labor wages. Labor wage forms effect the length and intensity <strong>of</strong> labor, and competition<br />

between workers, among other things and without looking at the forms themselves these<br />

relationships would be missed (Hans [2009fa:833]). Furthermore these side effects help the<br />

sphere <strong>of</strong> production keep going but they happen as surface relations, and so, to get the


226 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

bigger picture it is equally important to understand the surface relations. Jojo [2009fa:805]<br />

adds that, “By ignoring the surface form effects, participants in a capitalist system are not<br />

able to take control <strong>of</strong> their social relations.”<br />

Next Message by Nunu is [1358].<br />

Exam Question 808 is 671 in 2007SP, 662 in 2008fa, 693 in 2009fa, 757 in 2010fa, and<br />

779 in 2011fa:<br />

Exam Question 808 Wages have two main forms: time wages and piece wages. Why does<br />

Marx discuss time wages first?<br />

[1063] Nunu: Time wages. Time is valuable; it is the one measure that can directly<br />

account for the worker’s labor-power, which is what he is selling. A person’s labor-power<br />

does not exist infinitely because the worker must take time to refuel and regain their energy.<br />

In addition, time is not a flexible resource, it cannot be reused or recycled, it only exists once.<br />

In other words labor-power has boundaries and the worker is subject to those boundaries<br />

<strong>of</strong> time and energy. If workers exert themselves infinitely beyond these boundaries, their<br />

labor-power would not be theirs, they would be more like slaves. In the words <strong>of</strong> Bone<br />

[2009fa:864], “If [labor-power] wasn’t [sold] over a finite period <strong>of</strong> time people would be<br />

selling themselves into slavery”, Hans also makes this point in the annotations on page<br />

571 along with Amy [2007SP:953], Rexmanning [2010fa:801], Bandit [2011fa:836]. Marx<br />

begins his discussion on wages with time-wages because it considers the most basic things


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 227<br />

that the worker exchanges for wages, those being his labor-power and the time necessary to<br />

contribute to the production <strong>of</strong> the given commodity.<br />

Hans: Despite your many quotes (which have it right), you misunderstand the connection between time wage and<br />

slavery. You think too long work hours are so exhausting that they reduce the worker to an animal existence. This<br />

is not what Marx means with slavery. Marx says it is important that periodically, every day or week, the laborer<br />

has the right to re-sell his or her labor-power, i.e., it is important that the market is maintained as the mediator <strong>of</strong> a<br />

relationship which by its content is not much different from a slave relationship.<br />

Next Message by Nunu is [1077].<br />

[1089] KapitalSB: graded B Time wages first. Marx gives three main reasons as to why<br />

he discuss time wages first. In [2007SP:953] Amy pointed out the three reasons why. Those<br />

three reasons can be found on page 571 <strong>of</strong> the text. First reason, “time wage can only be<br />

sold for limited periods <strong>of</strong> time”. As explained in the annotations we discussed in Chapter<br />

6 “Sale and Purchase <strong>of</strong> Labor-Power” where it says, “it is essential characteristic <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity labor-power that it can only be sold for limited periods <strong>of</strong> time.” Second reason,<br />

time wage always takes place for specific periods <strong>of</strong> time (weekly, daily, hourly). This is<br />

according to 683:2 where it says “the sale <strong>of</strong> labor-power, as will be remembered, always<br />

takes place for specific periods <strong>of</strong> time.” Last reason, “whatever form <strong>of</strong> the wage, it must<br />

contain a measure <strong>of</strong> time”. We can learn from this that labor-power is going to happen<br />

over a period <strong>of</strong> time. Thus in [2009fa:864] Bone explains that wages have to involve some<br />

compensation for the workers’ expenditure <strong>of</strong> labor power.<br />

Hans: The capitalist buys the labor-power, not the expenditure <strong>of</strong> labor-power. The expenditure <strong>of</strong> labor-power is<br />

the consumption by the capitalist <strong>of</strong> the labor-power he bought.


228 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by KapitalSB is [1126].<br />

[1119] Alee: Marx discusses time wages first rather than piece wages because piece wage<br />

is nothing but a transmuted form <strong>of</strong> the time wage just as the time wage is a transmuted<br />

form <strong>of</strong> the labor power. Piece wages are involved with measuring the labor expended by<br />

the worker by the number <strong>of</strong> pieces he has produced. In time wages the labor is measured by<br />

its immediate duration and in piece wages by the quantity <strong>of</strong> products in which the labor has<br />

become embodied during a given time. The price <strong>of</strong> labor time itself is finally determined by<br />

this equation: value <strong>of</strong> a day <strong>of</strong> labor = daily value <strong>of</strong> labor power. The output in the piece<br />

wage is not measured by labor but labor is measured by the output. In previous chapters<br />

we also saw that the length <strong>of</strong> the working day must be regulated. Whatever the form <strong>of</strong><br />

the wage it must always directly or indirectly contain a measurement <strong>of</strong> the time for which<br />

the labor power is hired out. In time wages this measurement is made directly and in piece<br />

wages it is made indirectly.<br />

Next Message by Alee is [1232].<br />

[1133] Pepe: graded A Marx describes piece wages as a ‘transmutation’ <strong>of</strong> time wages,<br />

thus time wages are discussed first. Piece wages are derived from time wages, and time<br />

wages are derived from labor-power. Thus if A is derived from X, you would discuss and<br />

understand X before A.<br />

Next Message by Pepe is [1139.1].<br />

[1144] Abysmal: graded B Marx discusses time wages first as all wages are ultimately<br />

determined by the amount <strong>of</strong> labor-time, as the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is determined by the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 229<br />

number <strong>of</strong> hours <strong>of</strong> abstract labor congealed in it. Piece wages are indirectly based on labor<br />

time as well; the idea that they are based on a worker’s productivity and effort is false, and<br />

the product <strong>of</strong> system <strong>of</strong> capitalist exploitation. They are therefore a transmuted form <strong>of</strong><br />

time wages. Time wages are doubly important given that relative surplus value is a direct<br />

reflection <strong>of</strong> the amount <strong>of</strong> time spent by workers producing surplus value. All wages (even<br />

piece wages) are essentially time-wages, which are pre-determined by capitalists, but are<br />

made to look like a reflections <strong>of</strong> a worker’s effort to conceal the capitalists’ exploitation.<br />

Hans: Your first sentence is exactly wrong. Wages do not derive from the value produced by the labor, but from<br />

the reproduction cost <strong>of</strong> the worker.<br />

Next Message by Abysmal is [1145].<br />

[1149] ImmanentMaterialist: For Marx, it was <strong>of</strong> the utmost importance that he introduce<br />

time-wages before piece wages as (appearances to the contrary) piece-wages are<br />

themselves a reformulated version <strong>of</strong> the former. That is to say, the worker is not selling the<br />

capitalist the product <strong>of</strong> his labor directly (as workers are so <strong>of</strong>ten lead to believe under this<br />

particular wage system). Instead, the worker is being paid by the amount <strong>of</strong> time that “experience”<br />

has dictated goes into the creation <strong>of</strong> the commodity. So essentially, the piece-wage<br />

is a kind <strong>of</strong> insidious metamorphoses <strong>of</strong> the time-wage form—hence the necessity <strong>of</strong> Marx’s<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> the time-wage preceding the piece-wage.<br />

First Message by ImmanentMaterialist is [225].<br />

[1165] Stig: test resubmission. Like he does by starting Das Kapital with the commodity,<br />

Marx explains the simpler concepts that we are more familiar with, first. He knows that we


230 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

must first understand time wages (the capitalist paying for labor-power by time), and how<br />

the capitalist exploits the worker by buying labor-power before we can understand the more<br />

intricate process <strong>of</strong> exploitation by paying piece wages; as that at first seems like the laborer<br />

is selling the product <strong>of</strong> his labor, not his labor-power to the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Stig is [1215].<br />

[1171] SVN: Test 2 Resubmission Question 808. Time wages are discussed first because<br />

the concept <strong>of</strong> time is a crucial element to the functioning <strong>of</strong> capitalism. The laborer sells<br />

his labor power to the capitalist for a set amount <strong>of</strong> time (day, month, hour, year). This is<br />

very important because it is a transaction where the laborer voluntarily sells his ability to<br />

work for a certain amount <strong>of</strong> time, and at the end <strong>of</strong> that time period they are free to leave,<br />

or return to work for that company again. It paints the illusion <strong>of</strong> freedom to the laborer. If<br />

time wage were not firmly established, the capitalist could purchase their labor power for<br />

an indefinite time period and it would be a system <strong>of</strong> complete slavery. Time wage is also<br />

the best direct measurement <strong>of</strong> total labor power. The capitalist can know exactly how much<br />

labor power he has purchased and use this to be able to accurately measure his production<br />

potential and forecast the pr<strong>of</strong>its he will make.. Without time wage being firmly established,<br />

the capitalist system could not function.<br />

Next Message by SVN is [1469].<br />

[1178] RikkiAllie: Marx argues that piece wages are only a mutate form <strong>of</strong> time wages.<br />

Therefore without knowing what the significance and role <strong>of</strong> time wages, we wouldn’t understand<br />

piece wages.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 231<br />

Next Message by RikkiAllie is [1319].<br />

[1188] Villa: graded A+ Time-wage is the basis <strong>of</strong> necessary labor and surplus labor,<br />

understanding its relation to the capitalist system first helps better identify with piece-wage.<br />

I would also say time-wages prevail in capitalist society.<br />

Hans: Yes, time wages are more prevalent than piece wages. This is a good supporting argument, and I think<br />

nobody said that so far in the archives.<br />

Next Message by Villa is [1353].<br />

[1212] KATES: Wages have two main forms: time wages and piece wages. Marx discusses<br />

time wages first because this wage is directly related to labor time. Piece wage on<br />

the other hand is an indirect relationship. Time is an important influential factor because<br />

laborers only sell their labor power in limited amounts <strong>of</strong> time. If laborers did not sell labor<br />

power the relationship between the capitalist and laborer would collapse. The measurement<br />

<strong>of</strong> time is also the easiest way to measure labor power put forth by the worker.<br />

Next Message by KATES is [1213].<br />

[1220] Reeree: Marx discusses time wage first because it has to do with the wage that is<br />

paid for the labor time. Piece wage is more <strong>of</strong> an indirect wage. A capitalist will pay the<br />

worker a certain amount <strong>of</strong> wage for their labor-power and will keep the remaining surplus.<br />

Hans: I am not sure if you understand the transformation <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power into the wage <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Next Message by Reeree is [1221].<br />

[1257] Tim: graded A– Time wage demonstrates the attempt <strong>of</strong> the employer to differentiate<br />

employment from slavery by framing himself as a purchaser <strong>of</strong> hour sized packets


232 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> the labor power commodity, rather than buying the laborer themselves. This relationship<br />

illustrates the conduct <strong>of</strong> the labor market more clearly than a discussion <strong>of</strong> the piece wage<br />

system.<br />

Hans: The wage form is misleading in various ways, but this does not mean it intentional deception.<br />

Next Message by Tim is [1258].<br />

[1309] Extraterrestrial: graded B– Marx discusses time wages first because it is simpler<br />

to do so. Time wages are the base way that a worker will get paid. In today’s capitalistic<br />

society, time wages are a principal way <strong>of</strong> exploiting workers, where capitalists seek for<br />

surplus values. Things get more complicated when you try to discuss how many widgets or<br />

services an employee has produced (piece wage). It is easier to manipulate and exploit using<br />

time wages. It is easier to collect surplus value using time wages. I do not think, however,<br />

that it is impossible to exploit workers using piece wages, I just believe it is more difficult to<br />

do so.<br />

Hans: Marx says it is easier to exploit workers using piece wages.<br />

Next Message by Extraterrestrial is [1523].<br />

[1371] Batgirl: Marx discusses time wages first because they dictate or provide context<br />

for piece wages. Time wages are measured hourly, daily or weekly. Where as piece wages<br />

are simply a transmuted form <strong>of</strong> time wages, not what one would originally assume piece<br />

wages are. When first presented, piece wages seem like he is selling his direct labor to the<br />

capitalist. This is not true. His labor can be measured by time.<br />

Next Message by Batgirl is [1544].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 233<br />

[1461] Steve: Marx discusses time-wages first because time-wages are more practical<br />

and more <strong>of</strong>ten/widely utilized. Since labor power can be sold according to a concrete time<br />

frame (daily, hourly, etc.), time-wages neatly define a work schedule and pay schedule.<br />

Time-wages are more immediately relevant to the working class because they define their<br />

standard <strong>of</strong> living and lifestyle. (See: the 24 hour-a-day worker-life revolves around work.)<br />

Next Message by Steve is [1483].<br />

Question 813 is 675 in 2007SP, 653 in 2007fa, 663 in 2008SP, 667 in 2008fa, 698 in<br />

2009fa, 762 in 2010fa, and 784 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 813 Is it true that the laborer is only interested in what he receives, i.e., the overall<br />

daily wage income, and not interested in what he gives, i.e., the overall length <strong>of</strong> his work<br />

day?<br />

[1053] JEP: Wages and Quality <strong>of</strong> Work. In terms <strong>of</strong> the question, I believe that the<br />

laborer is more interested in what the capitalist system can provide them in wages rather<br />

than the quality <strong>of</strong> the labor that they put into it. The laborer is motivated to work in order<br />

to pay their bills, not by producing quality products for the rest <strong>of</strong> society.<br />

However, this leads me to think about two different instances in our modern society in<br />

which individuals take jobs that <strong>of</strong>fer them the most utility. The first are those scenarios<br />

are the laborers who take lower paying jobs that <strong>of</strong>fer more utility. Often times highly<br />

educated and capable people decide that a paycheck is not the most important aspect <strong>of</strong>


234 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

labor, rather <strong>of</strong>fering a quality and beneficial service is <strong>of</strong> the utmost importance. Such jobs<br />

that immediately come to mind include teachers, social workers, and nurses. All <strong>of</strong> these<br />

careers are lower paying and sometimes taken for granted in our society, but <strong>of</strong>fer some<br />

satisfaction to those who work these jobs. This willingness to receive less pay contradicts<br />

my belief that wages drive labor and is the opposite <strong>of</strong> the second scenario. Laborers who<br />

are highly capable also find utility in large paychecks. These people are willing to work<br />

more hours and take on more stress in order to get paid more.<br />

So why not find a career that is most suited for each individual? Both <strong>of</strong> the previous<br />

scenarios are only options for a select group who are <strong>of</strong>ten times educated and highly trained.<br />

In our capitalist society many pr<strong>of</strong>essions are forced upon laborers out <strong>of</strong> necessity, rather<br />

than personal utility. These jobs are <strong>of</strong>ten low paying which requires more working hours,<br />

creating less time for education or training to improve one’s job. In this instance society<br />

dictates individual’s roles and creates a class system in which the capitalist is able to exploit<br />

the laborer. The exploited worker is the driving force in a capitalist society and creates the<br />

belief for me that wages are more important than quality <strong>of</strong> work.<br />

Hans: Please read the question. It asks explicitly whether the laborer is interested in the number <strong>of</strong> hours he has<br />

to work, it says nothing about the quality <strong>of</strong> the labor that they put into their work or the satisfaction they derive<br />

from their work. This misunderstanding <strong>of</strong> the question is widespread in the archives, but even a common misunderstanding<br />

is still a misunderstanding. The best explanation <strong>of</strong> and answer to this question is my [2011fa:745].<br />

When Senior said that the workers do not care how long they have to work, he was speaking in code.<br />

Next Message by JEP is [1126].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 235<br />

[1065] Jess: graded A+ Interests <strong>of</strong> the Laborers. Although at first glance it appeared<br />

that Marx was arguing that the laborer only cares about what he received, I soon found out<br />

that this was not the case. Marx includes a passage within his footnotes that states, “The<br />

worker is principally interested in what he receives, the nominal sum <strong>of</strong> his wages, not in<br />

what he gives, the quantity <strong>of</strong> labor”. This was the passage that first threw me <strong>of</strong>f, for it<br />

seemed like a very capitalistic way <strong>of</strong> thinking. I discovered that this was actually Marx’s<br />

paraphrase <strong>of</strong> and comment on a quote from Nassau William Senior from 1830. Senior was<br />

a British economist who was greatly influenced by Adam Smith, which made the passage<br />

a lot easier to understand. Hans also states in his annotations to this footnote that “If the<br />

worker is forced by low wages to accept a long workday, this doesn’t mean that the worker<br />

is not interested in the length <strong>of</strong> the workday.” Piecing these two clues together, I came to the<br />

understanding that no, the laborer is not only interested in what he receives. In a capitalist<br />

society, the workers have no choice but to accept longer workdays. Under the mentality that<br />

Senior was proposing, the capitalists justify paying a lower wage to the workers, because<br />

they may simply lengthen the work day in order to maximize their supply <strong>of</strong> cheap labor.<br />

This practice is extremely detrimental to the worker’s health and well-being, because as<br />

the workday increases, it becomes more intense. The worker, unknowingly, accepts these<br />

dire circumstances not because he is only interested in making a dollar no matter what, but<br />

because the structure <strong>of</strong> a capitalist society has allowed a “compromise” to be made between<br />

the capitalist and the worker. This compromise is for the worker to get the wages that they<br />

want, but only if they are forced to lengthen their workday to meet the needs <strong>of</strong> the capitalist.


236 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Excellent. I like the little story how you discovered the real meaning <strong>of</strong> this sentence. I did some editing to<br />

make it even better, because I hope many will read it.<br />

Elias: Yeah Jess!<br />

Next Message by Jess is [1440].<br />

[1203] RedRyder: Question 813 Is it true that the laborer is only interested in what he<br />

receives, i.e., the overall daily wage income, and not interested in what he gives, i.e., the<br />

overall length <strong>of</strong> his work day?<br />

The laborer is only interested in what he receives and not what he gives. Let us assume<br />

that everyone is inclined to, like water, take the path <strong>of</strong> least resistance. Now man, having<br />

some necessities and inner desires must relegate himself to work to achieve certain needs<br />

and wants which we call sustenance. Man will only attain, for the most part, that level <strong>of</strong><br />

capability that allows him to live as such. He does not care how long he must work to acquire<br />

the funds necessary for such sustenance, he must in fact be first interested in attaining that<br />

level <strong>of</strong> income which will allow him his sustenance which for simplicity we will say is<br />

dependent on his capability. Only after his circumstances change either explicitly (such as<br />

mine with having a second child) or implicitly thru anticipated change will he ever pursue a<br />

differing course that will allow him a greater level <strong>of</strong> sustenance as dictated by his change<br />

in circumstances. But once having attained a new level <strong>of</strong> capability, such as thru a college<br />

degree, he will once again like water, take the path <strong>of</strong> least resistance ie working whatever<br />

hours regardless only concerned with personal sustenance and be directed by one thing —<br />

wages which provide sustenance. The cave man was concerned with one thing — survival.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 237<br />

He did not care if it took him an hour or 24 to get his sustenance, what mattered was his<br />

sustenance and attaining such.<br />

Modern man is the same, he will get his sustenance and achieve such thru whatever means<br />

necessary, this <strong>of</strong> course being dictated by his personal capabilities. Capabilities will change<br />

to meet new levels <strong>of</strong> required sustenance and will only be pursued as necessary. Man<br />

will continue to be driven by sustenance (wages) before hours. Taking the course <strong>of</strong> least<br />

resistance to achieve his required level <strong>of</strong> sustenance man will work whatever is necessary<br />

to achieve his sustenance or required wage level. Is he concerned over how much time —<br />

probably, emotionally. But are his observed actions — hardly, because man must survive.<br />

Man will always be driven by wages first than hours. Its how college grad choose jobs,<br />

first we compare salaries followed by hours. Where do grads go? To the money. Because<br />

sustenance and wages drive man. Not working hours.<br />

Hans: It is interesting for me to see how intelligent people argue something that is patently absurd.<br />

By the way, some anthropologists say that cavemen had lots <strong>of</strong> free time.<br />

Next Message by RedRyder is [1206].<br />

[1211] Shelly: graded A+ Who cares? The workers, that’s who! Of course not. The<br />

laborer is interested in what he gives also. If he wasn’t, this would be like saying the workers<br />

do not care if they have to work 18 hours a day as long as they get their paycheck. They<br />

care, they just can’t do anything about it because the capitalist owns the means to production<br />

and therefore has the upper hand.<br />

Hans: Very eloquent without being too wordy.


238 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Shelly is [1451].<br />

[1321] AJH: What the labor is truly interested in. The laborer should not only be<br />

interested in what he receives such as his daily wage income and he should focus more on<br />

what he gives as determined by his overall work day length because if the laborer earns a<br />

wage <strong>of</strong> $10 per hour, $80 per 8 hours <strong>of</strong> work and can produce a value <strong>of</strong> $30 per hour he<br />

would only want to work 2 hours and 40 minutes because that is the time it takes him to<br />

produce a value equal to his daily wage and after this time he works for free. The necessary<br />

labor is what the worker looks at and should be focused on rather that his daily wage. In the<br />

capitalist model the worker is forced to compromise and work long days to receive a wage<br />

that may have only taken him 3 hours to produce his daily wages. After this necessary labor<br />

his labor is free because he is producing a surplus value for the firm.<br />

Hans: Where you had originally “less than 3 hours” I edited it to say “2 hours and 40 minutes” because this more<br />

precise number gives the reader a better indication how you arrived at it. The number “3 hours” threw me <strong>of</strong>f<br />

because on first reading I thought you were arguing that it takes you 3 hours to earn, in wages, the value which you<br />

produce in 1 hour. Although this is true, it is not what you mean. What you mean is that it takes you 2 hours and<br />

40 minutes to produce the value which you earn in 8 hours.<br />

Next Message by AJH is [1322].<br />

[1475] Skylerp: Laborers are interested in their overall daily wage income, but are also<br />

interested what he/she gives. Laborers want to be paid for their full labor value, not just<br />

for their labor power. This is why unions and strikes are constantly a problem. If necessary<br />

labor was equal with labor then firms would have no pr<strong>of</strong>its. There must be a relative surplus


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 239<br />

labor for firms to function. Also if laborers were not interested in their labor value they would<br />

work longer days, because they wouldn’t be aware <strong>of</strong> the relative surplus labor and would<br />

believe they are being paid for the labor value they are creating or investing.<br />

Hans: Of course, Marx would not consider unions the problem, but unions are the workers’ response to what is<br />

really the problem, their separation from the means <strong>of</strong> production which forces them to sell their labor-power and<br />

which gives the capitalists the power to keep wages low.<br />

Next Message by Skylerp is [1488].<br />

Question 816 is 677 in 2007SP, 665 in 2008SP, 669 in 2008fa, 700 in 2009fa, 764 in<br />

2010fa, 786 in 2011fa, and 764 in Answer:<br />

Question 816 In a system <strong>of</strong> hourly wages without a set daily minimum <strong>of</strong> hours, Marx says<br />

that “the connection between the paid and the unpaid labor is broken.” Explain what he<br />

means by this.<br />

[1067] Carol: Brokenness <strong>of</strong> the paid and unpaid. By stating that “The connection<br />

between the paid and unpaid labor is broken,” Marx illustrates how the exploitation under<br />

the capitalist system <strong>of</strong>ten forgoes the necessary labor that the worker needs in order to make<br />

ends meet for the sake <strong>of</strong> surplus-labor. This is best explained by forming a scenario. For<br />

example, if a worker’s needs $1,000 a week to support a family, and he/she has a standard<br />

full employment <strong>of</strong> 8 hours a day working schedule. We get an hourly wage <strong>of</strong> $25 for<br />

the worker by dividing working hours per week (5 days x 8 hours = 40 hours/week) from<br />

$1,000. Let’s say the worker’s labor creates a value <strong>of</strong> $50 per hour. The capitalist then gets


240 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

a surplus value <strong>of</strong> $25 dollars per hour. This is already an 100% exploitation on the worker<br />

for every hour he/she works.<br />

In the situation Marx gave, the laborer was not allowed to perform the necessary labor<br />

needed for his/her survival. This example really comes to life during an economic downturn.<br />

Imagine a company that produces leisure products. During economic downturns, the market<br />

generally has a reduced demand for leisure products. As result, the capitalists <strong>of</strong> these companies<br />

might have to cut production because he/she cannot find markets to sell the products.<br />

Cutting production <strong>of</strong>ten causes the capitalist to cut the number <strong>of</strong> hours worked by the employees.<br />

Now, if our worker is told to work 30 hours per week instead <strong>of</strong> 40 hours, he/she<br />

would be making $750/week while still being held to the original $1,000/week cost <strong>of</strong> living.<br />

The capitalist is still making his/her $25/hour surplus-value labor out <strong>of</strong> the employee<br />

while cutting short the worker’s wage by $250 a week. This is particularly exploitative because<br />

if the capitalist was not trying to maintain his/her $25 surplus value, the capitalist<br />

could increase the worker’s wage per hour to $33. This would ensure that the worker still<br />

receives the necessary hours he/she needs in order to make a living while simultaneously<br />

giving the capitalist a more than decent amount <strong>of</strong> surplus-value. This example shows that<br />

in conditions like these, only the laborer is being harmed.<br />

In [2011fa:715] TKOberle said that the connection between paid and unpaid labor “has<br />

do with the surplus value that the capitalist receives by only using that worker for a certain<br />

period <strong>of</strong> time needed.” The time period does not help retain the connection between paid


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 241<br />

and unpaid labor. When Marx is pointing out that the connection is broken, he is saying that<br />

when times are good, laborers were allowed to meet their cost <strong>of</strong> living while generating<br />

surplus value for the capitalist. But when times are hard, the capitalistic still receives equal<br />

amounts <strong>of</strong> surplus value without letting the laborer meet his/her cost <strong>of</strong> living.<br />

Hans: Very good explanation <strong>of</strong> this subtle point. Only one quibble. You had “the worker’s labor power value per<br />

hour is $50,” which is exactly wrong, because this means that the value <strong>of</strong> the labor-power is $50. What you clearly<br />

meant to say is that the worker’s labor (not labor-power which is potential labor, but actual labor) creates a value<br />

<strong>of</strong> $50 per hour. I edited the correct formulation in, in order not to throw <strong>of</strong>f future readers.<br />

Next Message by Carol is [1224].<br />

Exam Question 819 is 683 in 2007SP, 661 in 2007fa, 671 in 2008SP, 675 in 2008fa, 706<br />

in 2009fa, 770 in 2010fa, 789 in 2011fa, and 770 in Answer:<br />

Exam Question 819 What is the difference between surplus labor time and overtime?<br />

[1082] Agloeck: Surplus labor time vs. overtime. Overtime is only a part <strong>of</strong> wages<br />

which Hans says is surface category [2007fa:493]. It is usually a higher wage for additional<br />

hours worked in a single day. Surplus labor-time is a fetish concept that disguised the true<br />

value <strong>of</strong> labor-power and helps the capitalist exploit the worker. Hans states, “Since the<br />

worker’s wage is less than the value produced in that time, every hour, or every minute or<br />

second, contains surplus-labor, namely, labor for which the worker effectively does not get<br />

paid. Overtime labor also contains surplus-labor, although a little less than the regular hours<br />

(before overtime kicks in) due to the overtime premium” [2007fa:493].


242 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Marx wouldn’t call surplus-value a “fetish concept” but rather a concept which captures the true essence <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism, a concept which shows that capitalism is a class society.<br />

Next Message by Agloeck is [1083].<br />

[1125] Bimmer: (graded A) Overtime vs Surplus. Overtime labor is labor done following<br />

a normal work-day’s labor. It’s the extra labor done that is not typically done. The<br />

typical labor attributed with a regular work day, is normally referred to as 8 hours; yet, in<br />

different societies and different industries, variations <strong>of</strong> what a work-day-s labor is, occur.<br />

Furthermore, overtime labor has a higher pay rate or wage associated with it.<br />

Surplus labor on the other hand, is the labor that the worker or laborer, does not get<br />

paid for. A worker’s pay or laborers pay, is less than the value they produce. Essentially<br />

what this says, is that the worker is paid less than whatever product or value <strong>of</strong> the product<br />

they produce. Of course, this can be measured in various times and if you break down the<br />

worker’s pay, his/her pay will be less than the value produced given a certain time, whether<br />

it be minutes, seconds, hours, days, years, etc. However, surplus labor, is the only form <strong>of</strong><br />

labor that contains labor for which the worker is not paid for.<br />

Overtime labor, also employs some surplus-labor. However, overtime contains only a<br />

small about <strong>of</strong> surplus-labor compared to the amount contained in normal work-day’s labor<br />

due to the fact that overtime pays a premium and a laborer or worker is only going to work<br />

as much overtime as required versus in a regular day where the worker or laborer works via


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 243<br />

a schedule. Overtime labor will not be used everyday, it will only be used when beneficial<br />

and required.<br />

Hans: I don’t agree that overtime labor contains only a small amount <strong>of</strong> surplus-labor. The capitalist does not have<br />

to pay extra benefits for overtime labor, and a longer day means lower costs for depreciation etc. Overtime may<br />

easily be more pr<strong>of</strong>itable than normal time, despite the higher overtime pay.<br />

Next Message by Bimmer is [1277].<br />

Question 820 is 679 in 2007SP, 657 in 2007fa, 702 in 2009fa, 766 in 2010fa, and 790 in<br />

2011fa:<br />

Question 820 In Chapter Twenty, Marx mentions two abuses connected with the wage<br />

which he thought would be abolished with the legal limitation <strong>of</strong> the working-day but which<br />

weren’t. Which are those?<br />

[1030] Gladwell: graded A The pay’s not great, but... In Chapter 20, Marx mentions two<br />

abuses connected with wages that he thought would be abolished with the legal limitation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the working day, but both <strong>of</strong> them survived. The first abuse is the desire <strong>of</strong> the employer<br />

to pay an hourly wage, instead <strong>of</strong> a daily wage [2011fa:704]. By paying an hourly wage,<br />

the employer can use the worker only when he needs him. Paying hourly wages gives the<br />

capitalist the ability to cut hours at his pleasure, but doing so is to the detriment <strong>of</strong> the<br />

worker, who may still have a job, but is now stuck with lower income.


244 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

The Second abuse is shown most clearly by a comment I’ve <strong>of</strong>ten heard people say:<br />

“The pay’s not great, but I get lots <strong>of</strong> overtime.” This abuse is the erosion <strong>of</strong> the separation<br />

between normal time and overtime [2010fa:744]. What occurs is that regular wages are held<br />

low, forcing workers to depend on overtime to sustain themselves. By <strong>of</strong>fering overtime,<br />

capitalists have an excuse for lowering wages, but what they’re really doing is forcing the<br />

worker to work longer.<br />

Message [1030] referenced by [1202]. Next Message by Gladwell is [1078].<br />

[1202] Gladwell: graded A+ Hourly Wages and Overtime. The first abuse that was not<br />

abolished with the legal limitation <strong>of</strong> the working day is the desire <strong>of</strong> the employer to pay<br />

an hourly wage, instead <strong>of</strong> a daily wage [2011fa:704]. This switch allows the capitalist to<br />

employ laborers when he needs them, and to cut hours when he doesn’t. The laborer depends<br />

on this income for survival so the capitalist can now cut hours at the expense <strong>of</strong> the laborer’s<br />

livelihood [2012fa:1030]<br />

The second abuse is the erosion <strong>of</strong> the separation between normal time and overtime<br />

[2010fa:744]. By <strong>of</strong>fering overtime, the capitalist has an excuse to hold regular wages low,<br />

which barely meet the needs <strong>of</strong> the laborer. The laborer is then forced to work overtime to<br />

sustain herself, resulting in further exploitation.<br />

Next Message by Gladwell is [1204].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 245<br />

[1464] AbeFroman: Two Correctable Abuses. The two abuses that Marx thought would<br />

be abolished were: the hourly wage and overtime pay. Marx saw an hourly wage (as opposed<br />

to a daily wage) as something that allows capitalists to push for longer working hours.<br />

Capitalists are able to affect both the amount <strong>of</strong> hours a worker works and the wage a worker<br />

is paid, so they will be motivated to lower wages and pay less. In addition, capitalists may<br />

<strong>of</strong>fer over-time pay but lower wages overall in order to pay for the overtime. Marx noted that<br />

those who are vulnerable to being forced to work extra hours are also in a position to have<br />

to take lower pay, so they are not benefiting from either hourly (vs. daily) wage or overtime.<br />

They are simply tools by which capitalists can extract additional value.<br />

Next Message by AbeFroman is [1465].<br />

Question 821 is 680 in 2007SP, 658 in 2007fa, 668 in 2008SP, 672 in 2008fa, 703 in<br />

2009fa, 767 in 2010fa, and 791 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 821 How does Marx argue that longer hours are associated with a lower overall<br />

daily wage?<br />

[1070] Jag: Long hours for low wages. Marx argues that the more hours worked results<br />

in a lower wage for the worker. Marx starts the argument with low wages because when a<br />

worker is <strong>of</strong>fered a low wage, they agree to work longer hours each day so that they can<br />

survive, just as Hans notes on page 584 on annotations. The capitalist in a way is manipulating<br />

the worker into working longer hours by <strong>of</strong>fering such a small wage. A capitalist is not


246 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

going to reward a worker for working longer hours because the capitalist’s goal is already to<br />

find the amount <strong>of</strong> time a worker is able to work before he practically collapses. If a worker<br />

has to work longer hours to survive, then he has already accepted lower daily wages.<br />

Hans: You are describing it as a question <strong>of</strong> power, the capitalist has the power to manipulate the worker. Marx’s<br />

explanation is superior because Marx shows that the social heft <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> value supports the capitalist’s power<br />

game.<br />

You explain why longer hours lead to lower hourly wages, not why they also lead to lower daily wages. Look<br />

at [2008SP:570] for an explanation.<br />

Message [1070] referenced by [1075]. Next Message by Jag is [1088].<br />

[1075] AR: Question 821 feedback. For Marx the longer the working day means generally<br />

the lower the wages. A Fixed low level <strong>of</strong> wage will cause the laborer to accept longer<br />

hours to work in order to fulfill their basic needs. Jag [1070] is correct in stating that “the<br />

capitalist in a way is manipulating the worker into working longer hours by <strong>of</strong>fering such<br />

a small wage.” Marx believes that correcting this manipulation can be done by making the<br />

daily wage and the length <strong>of</strong> the work day independent and equal across all industries.<br />

Hans: Interestingly, you like Jag’s wrong perspective <strong>of</strong> looking at the relationship between capitalist and laborer<br />

as a personal relationship rather than a class relationship, and you think Marx is promoting reforms <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

rather than the abolition <strong>of</strong> capitalism. To me, this seems to be another way <strong>of</strong> pouring sand over Marx’s incendiary<br />

message as I said in [169], <strong>of</strong> denying the necessity following from Marx’s theory for a different social order.<br />

Next Message by AR is [1374].<br />

[1316] Frankie: graded A Double Exploitation. Marx argues that longer hours are associated<br />

not only with a lower hourly wage but also a lower overall daily wage. Mainly it is


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 247<br />

due to the fact that in jobs where longer hours are present are typically the jobs in which the<br />

worker has little power to negotiate his wage and is forced to accept the lower wage. The<br />

capitalist also pays an hourly wage thereby creating the longer work days so that the worker<br />

can earn enough to maintain living expenses. In [2008SP:570] Hans uses a sentence from<br />

Marx and then elaborates on it validating the argument I wrote above. It says “And now<br />

comes the important sentence from Marx, p. 689/o:<br />

‘But the same circumstances which allow the capitalist in the long run to<br />

prolong the working day also allow him . . . to reduces the price <strong>of</strong> labor’<br />

In other words: those industries in which the working day is long are the industries in<br />

which the workers are weak. This weakness is likely to manifest itself not only in long<br />

hours but also otherwise. Therefore we can expect the daily wage to be lower than in those<br />

industries where the workers are stronger and therefore the working day is shorter, instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> being equal as the general law postulates”.<br />

This shows us why longer working hours are associated with a lower overall daily wage.<br />

Next Message by Frankie is [1498].<br />

[1394] IrwinFletcher: graded B– Max argues that longer hours are associated with a<br />

lower overall daily wage by pointing out that if the capitalist withholds the laborer from<br />

fullfilling emotional and psychological needs then he has surpassed the maximum period <strong>of</strong>


248 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

work. At this point the laborer will enter the principle <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns. It is unwise to<br />

do so because the value <strong>of</strong> the labor begins to steadily decline.<br />

Hans: You are answering the question why too-low wages diminish the value created during the day.<br />

Next Message by IrwinFletcher is [1400].<br />

[1419] Novatore: I work an eight hour day. I produce the value <strong>of</strong> my wage in four hours<br />

while the other four hours produces surplus value, and my daily wage is eighty dollars.<br />

Now, if my labor hours are extended to sixteen hours I am working twice as long for the<br />

same wage. Initially I was making ten dollars; after my hours increased I made five dollars<br />

an hour.<br />

Hans: In your example, longer hours are associated with a lower hourly wage, but your daily wage remained the<br />

same.<br />

Next Message by Novatore is [1420].<br />

[1422] Tiburon: It is the goal <strong>of</strong> the capitalist to create more revenue and get more labor<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the worker. Overall lower wages could come when a worker has to spend longer<br />

hours at work because the employer extends the working day and/or because extraordinary<br />

circumstances. There are many circumstances that could cause this effect in the economy.<br />

Marx gives an example <strong>of</strong> two <strong>of</strong> them. In the first case there is an excess supply <strong>of</strong> labor in<br />

the market, and this drives employees to work extra hard and in some cases they work extra<br />

hours to remain valuable to the employer, and thus resulting in a lower overall daily wage.<br />

The second example is when an economy has an excess supply <strong>of</strong> the finished commodity,<br />

which produces low wages as well as it produces low prices.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 249<br />

So not only extending the working day <strong>of</strong> the laborer brings lower wage averages, but<br />

this combined with special or extraordinary circumstances can cause this effect in wages.<br />

Hans: It is not sufficient to say that longer hours are associated with lower daily wages because the capitalists want<br />

it to be this way. The capitalists always want long hours and low wages. The negative correlation comes from the<br />

workers’ differential ability to resist this drive for pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Next Message by Tiburon is [1423].<br />

Question 826 At first sight, the piece-wage seems to indicate that the worker sells the product<br />

<strong>of</strong> his labor to the capitalist. Which evidence does Marx give to support his claim that<br />

this appearance is false and that the piece-wage is only a transmuted form <strong>of</strong> time-wages?<br />

[1068] Curtis: graded A+ Piece-wage is still a wage. Marx first points out, in 692:3,<br />

that both piece wages and time-wages “exist side by side, at the same time, in the same<br />

branches <strong>of</strong> industry.” Because the capitalist prefers to employ labor that ensures that he<br />

earns a surplus-value, this should be considered a signal that the two forms <strong>of</strong> wage labor<br />

are not radically different, and that the capitalist is likely still earning a surplus value<br />

from the piece-wage laborer. Marx even discovers piece-wage and time-wage laborers in<br />

the same shop doing the exact same labor [692:4]! This evidence throws doubt on the suggestion<br />

that piece-wage laborers are selling the product <strong>of</strong> their labor to the capitalist. The<br />

reason why, again, is because it seems unlikely that the capitalist would earn a surplus-value<br />

from his time-wage laborers and no surplus-value from his piece-wage laborers; why are<br />

the piece-wage laborers employed by him? This suggests the two forms <strong>of</strong> wages, while


250 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

different, seem to serve the same purpose and are <strong>of</strong> the same substance. The capitalist is<br />

still purchasing their labor-power; he merely uses a different standard to purchase it.<br />

Next, Marx shows that piece-wage laborer is working longer hours than the time-wage laborer.<br />

The piece-wage laborers find themselves working many hours overtime, more so than<br />

the time-wage laborers, and produce far more surplus-value for the capitalist who employs<br />

them. As said in the Reports <strong>of</strong> the Inspectors <strong>of</strong> Factories in footnote 47, “The work <strong>of</strong> [the<br />

piece-wage laborers] for half an hour <strong>of</strong> the day is equal to one person’s work for 50 hours,<br />

or 5/6 <strong>of</strong> one person’s labor in a week, and is a positive gain to the employer”. This suggests<br />

that the capitalist is merely using the piece-wage form <strong>of</strong> labor to draw more labor from his<br />

workers, and is only using a different unit to measure their labor rather than purchasing the<br />

product <strong>of</strong> their labor.<br />

How is it, then, that the capitalist is able to earn a surplus-value from piece-wage labor as<br />

he does from time-wage labor? The reason why is that the nature <strong>of</strong> the compensation is the<br />

same; it is not based on the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity produced, but on the level <strong>of</strong> compensation<br />

to the laborer that is necessary to ensure the sustenance <strong>of</strong> the worker. The capitalist<br />

is not paying the worker to receive the commodity the worker has produced, because the<br />

worker does not own that commodity. The capitalist owns that commodity, and is simply<br />

paying a wage intended to ensure the worker’s survival, and the only difference between the<br />

two is the unit for which the wage is payed.<br />

Message [1068] referenced by [1459]. Next Message by Curtis is [1069].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 251<br />

[1169] SVN: The piece wage workers are pitted against one another. They are paid on the<br />

quality <strong>of</strong> the commodity but are also expected to make a certain quantity <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

The piece wage laborers are working against one another because there is an incentive to be<br />

the best producer. Since the piece wage workers are incentivized to be extra productive, their<br />

labor per hour is more intense than that <strong>of</strong> the time wage laborers. The capitalist benefits<br />

because now he has a bunch <strong>of</strong> piece wage laborers working themselves to the bone everyday<br />

just to be the best producer they can for the capitalist. The piece wage wage workers have<br />

incentive to work longer days. So instead <strong>of</strong> working 10 hour days, they are working 12<br />

hour days to make sure that the commodities they make are <strong>of</strong> the highest quality and that<br />

they made enough <strong>of</strong> them.<br />

The capitalist also has time wage workers working with the piece wage workers. The<br />

two types <strong>of</strong> workers must work together to produce commodities. The time wage workers<br />

are paid a flat rate per day regardless <strong>of</strong> how long they work. So now with the piece wage<br />

workers working longer hours the time wage workers must work longer hours too. The<br />

capitalist is then receiving 2 hours per day, per worker <strong>of</strong> the unpaid labor from the time<br />

wage laborers plus the increased productivity <strong>of</strong> the piece wage workers.<br />

Besides this, the piece wage worker does not even own the means to production. The<br />

capitalist does, so when the commodity is finished, the capitalist owns the commodity, not<br />

the laborer. The laborer only owns the labor-power that he sold at a price well beneath what<br />

market value for it should be.


252 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Therefore the piece wage laborer is not better <strong>of</strong>f than the time wage laborer. He is<br />

getting exploited just the same, but it is in a slightly different form than the time wage<br />

laborer. The piece wage laborer’s wage is still at the discretion <strong>of</strong> the capitalist and subject<br />

to his standards, so the piece wage laborer is not working for himself in any shape or form,<br />

just working harder than he has to for the capitalist.<br />

Hans: The wage is not at the discretion <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. The daily wage must be enough to cover the daily<br />

reproduction cost <strong>of</strong> the laborer.<br />

Next Message by SVN is [1170].<br />

[1185] Villa: graded A The means <strong>of</strong> production is still owned by the capitalist. The<br />

worker has sold his labor-power and is compensated in the form <strong>of</strong> piece-wage just as with<br />

time-wage. Now it being transmuted from time-wage, I believe, is because piece-wage<br />

employees can be further exploited; they tend to work longer hours, compete against other<br />

piece-wagers, thus driving up the average products expected to be made and create more<br />

surplus value for the capitalist. They both serve the purpose <strong>of</strong> supplying surplus labor to<br />

the capitalist, they tend to work side by side for the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Villa is [1186].<br />

[1363] Batgirl: Piece wages and time wages are very similar in the fact that they “exist<br />

side by side, at the same time”, Marx states in 692:3. They even can exist in the same<br />

workplace, happening at the same time (692:4). This debunks the impression that piece<br />

wage laborers are selling the product <strong>of</strong> their labor to the capitalist. If they both exist in the<br />

same work place then one could assume that the capitalist is earning a surplus value from


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 253<br />

both these types <strong>of</strong> workers. Thus they are <strong>of</strong> the same cloth, so similar in their forms they<br />

are serving the same purpose yet different in the delivery <strong>of</strong> payment for labor. So yes, piece<br />

wages and time wages are different in the fact they are different measurements or vehicles<br />

for delivery however piece wages are a weaker measurement for labor.<br />

Next Message by Batgirl is [1368].<br />

[1459] Steve: The piece-wage is only a transmuted form <strong>of</strong> time-wages because the worker<br />

is selling his labor-power, not the product <strong>of</strong> his labor-power, to the capitalist. Many times,<br />

the piece-wage will be used by the capitalist to make a higher pr<strong>of</strong>it—as Curtis [1068] points<br />

out, ‘the piece-wage laborer is working longer hours than the time-wage laborer...the capitalist<br />

is merely using the piece-wage form <strong>of</strong> labor to draw more labor from his workers,<br />

and is only using a different unit to measure their labor rather than purchasing the product<br />

<strong>of</strong> their labor.’<br />

Hans: Your in-class answer had the following piece <strong>of</strong> empirical evidence: “piece wages are secondary to, dependent<br />

on time wages. Commissions are incentives in addition to regular hourly wages.” This is indeed the kind <strong>of</strong><br />

evidence Marx used.<br />

I consider it more convincing evidence than the longer hours worked by piece wage workers in your resubmission.<br />

Many company exectutives work long hours. Long hours are pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> exploitation only if you know that the<br />

worker does not get the full value they produce during this time.<br />

Next Message by Steve is [1460].<br />

Question 830 is 680 in 2008fa, 711 in 2009fa, and 775 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 830 Why is the form <strong>of</strong> piece wage just as irrational as that <strong>of</strong> time wages?


254 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1069] Curtis: (graded A) Irrationality <strong>of</strong> piece-wages and time-wages. First, how are<br />

wages, in general, “irrational”? The word “irrational” does not refer to the decision making<br />

process <strong>of</strong> the capitalist; it’s perfectly rational for the capitalist to earn surplus-value from<br />

the labor-power he has purchased by requiring that labor-power to give more value than he<br />

paid. It is also not “irrational” for the worker to accept employment by the greedy capitalist;<br />

the capitalist controls the means <strong>of</strong> production, and the worker cannot earn a living with his<br />

labor-power without this means <strong>of</strong> production, and so, because he is trapped, it is rational<br />

for him to accept employment even though he’s being cheated. It would be irrational for him<br />

to reject employment and starve. So, the word “irrational” must not refer to the character<br />

<strong>of</strong> either the employer or the worker. This seems to be the error made by Capitalist in<br />

[2009fa:789]; she seems to write as if it is the individual participants in the capitalist system<br />

who are irrational, which is not the case <strong>of</strong> either <strong>of</strong> them.<br />

As Hans said in his comment to [2009fa:789], “[w]hen [Marx] calls the piece wage an<br />

irrational form he simply means that there is no connection between the value <strong>of</strong> the product<br />

and the piece wage paid for the product.” This is the case for both piece- and time- form <strong>of</strong><br />

wages. Neither piece-wages nor time-wages are based upon the value <strong>of</strong> the end-product,<br />

and therefore both are considered “irrational”. The word “irrational” refers to the nature <strong>of</strong><br />

the exchange, not the state-<strong>of</strong>-mind <strong>of</strong> the participants <strong>of</strong> the exchange, and the nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

exchange for both piece-wages and time-wages is the same.<br />

Message [1069] referenced by [1323]. Next Message by Curtis is [1150].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 255<br />

[1323] Jason: graded A+ The Irrational Piece Wage. As Curtis [1069] explained to us,<br />

the form <strong>of</strong> piece-wages is not irrational because the participants in the piece-wage transaction<br />

have an irrational decision making process. The capitalists are trying to generate<br />

surplus-value. The workers, having no access to means <strong>of</strong> production sufficient to sustain<br />

themselves, must work for a wage, in whatever form, to acquire the means to purchase their<br />

subsistence.<br />

Instead, what makes the form <strong>of</strong> piece-wages just as irrational as that <strong>of</strong> time-wages is<br />

the fact that the value produced per piece has no connection to the equivalent the worker<br />

receives in the form <strong>of</strong> his or her piece-wages - much like the form <strong>of</strong> time-wages has no<br />

connection to the value produced in a given time.<br />

There is the misconception the capitalist is paying the worker for the product <strong>of</strong> his or her<br />

labor with piece-wages, but really the worker is still selling their labor-power (the same for<br />

time-wages). Each piece contains surplus-labor - effectively unpaid labor - just like a time<br />

increment for which a worker is paid a time-wage contains surplus-labor. It is this disconnect<br />

between the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power, and the value produced by labor that Marx says is just as<br />

irrational in piece-wages as time-wages.<br />

The wage, no matter the form, is mystified, causing the worker to believe they sell labor to<br />

the capitalist, when they actually sell their labor-power. This makes invisible the exploitation<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor by capital.


256 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

First Message by Jason is [3].<br />

Question 831 is 677 in 2008SP, 681 in 2008fa, 712 in 2009fa, and 776 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 831 Explain how piece wages can become a “most fertile source for wage theft<br />

and capitalist cheating.”<br />

[1054] Basil: Piece Wages for Bankers. The capitalist has the opportunity to cheat<br />

the worker and steal wages because, using piece wages, the capitalist is able to measure<br />

the quality and quantity <strong>of</strong> output arbitrarily. In Annotations [P 595] it describes that piece<br />

wages measure “the labor expended by the worker by the number <strong>of</strong> pieces he has produced.”<br />

This is backwards, as the labor expended by the worker should be measured by the amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor-power expended in a given period <strong>of</strong> time.<br />

A present day analogy to time wages and piece wages is hourly wages v/s a wage paid on<br />

commission. Both <strong>of</strong> these forms result in surplus-labor and pr<strong>of</strong>its for the capitalist, but the<br />

structure and terms <strong>of</strong> the wage are very different.<br />

The example <strong>of</strong> a time wage used by Marx, which correlates to our understanding <strong>of</strong> an<br />

hourly wage, is a working day containing 12 hours, <strong>of</strong> which 6 are paid, 6 unpaid. The<br />

example <strong>of</strong> a piece wage, which is like payment on commission, assumes the value <strong>of</strong> a<br />

single piece is 6 cents, where the worker receives 3 cents per piece. The surplus in both


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 257<br />

cases result in pr<strong>of</strong>it for the capitalist. From these examples, we can see how an increase in<br />

the length <strong>of</strong> the workday in both cases can increase pr<strong>of</strong>its for the capitalist.<br />

But the reason why the piece wages are the most appropriate form for the capitalist mode<br />

<strong>of</strong> production is because they not only have the tendency to extend the length <strong>of</strong> the workday<br />

as time wages do, but also the tendency to intensify labor. In order to demonstrate the truth<br />

<strong>of</strong> this statement, I will use a present day example.<br />

Most people may think <strong>of</strong> investment bankers on Wall Street as the quintessential example<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalists who exploit and hold down the proletariat, but I am going to show that this<br />

is a misconception, and that bankers fall into the capitalist system <strong>of</strong> exploitation just as<br />

much, if not more, than any other pr<strong>of</strong>ession—primarily due to the piece wage.<br />

Investment banks are very structured hierarchies that utilize both time wages and piece<br />

wages to exploit their workers. At the top are the shareholders, who manage the company<br />

through the CEO and other executives. At the bottom are analysts, and in between are<br />

different levels <strong>of</strong> associates, managers, vice presidents, and directors.<br />

Analysts are hired on and receive most <strong>of</strong> their compensation through a salary, or time<br />

wage, based on their hours worked. As they move up the ranks, and become associates,<br />

VPs, etc. their wages shift away from a time wage and more toward compensation based on<br />

commission or a “bonus,” which correlate to the piece wage described by Marx, but with the<br />

added component <strong>of</strong> meeting a quota.


258 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

The bonus received by bankers gives them an incentive to increase the intensity <strong>of</strong> their<br />

work in order to meet expectations. That is why bankers <strong>of</strong>ten work 100+ hour weeks, and<br />

require a very high level <strong>of</strong> education and skill. Bcause the structure is a hierarchy, and<br />

directors oversee VPs, and VPs oversee associates, the intensity <strong>of</strong> labor by the workers directly<br />

under an individual directly correlate to that individual’s compensation. This drives<br />

each level <strong>of</strong> the bank to intensify the labor <strong>of</strong> the workers below them. Or as Marx describes,<br />

“Here the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the worker by capital takes place through the medium <strong>of</strong><br />

the exploitation <strong>of</strong> one worker by another” (Annotations P 597).<br />

Even the CEO is pressured by the incentives <strong>of</strong> shareholders, and is legally obligated, to<br />

maximize market value in order to receive compensation. This is why “piece wages therefore<br />

form the basis for . . . a hierarchically organized system <strong>of</strong> exploitation and oppression”<br />

(Annotation P 596). So, the common misconception is that bankers themselves are the<br />

capitalists, when in reality the majority shareholders <strong>of</strong> the company are the capitalists, and<br />

bankers fall into the capitalist cycle <strong>of</strong> oppression.<br />

I recognize that compensation for bankers are much different than the wages <strong>of</strong> people<br />

working “blue collar” jobs. I credit that to the fact that banking is educated labor, requiring<br />

much more skill than uneducated labor. My purpose was to show that bankers on Wall Street<br />

still fall into the capitalist system, and that they are a quintessential example <strong>of</strong> how piece<br />

wages can become a “most fertile source for wage theft and capitalist cheating.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 259<br />

Hans: Your examples illustrate how piece wages increase intensity <strong>of</strong> labor, not only among productive workers<br />

but even among bankers. But with the exception <strong>of</strong> a brief mention in your first sentence, which cries out for an<br />

elaboration, your entire submission says nothing about wage theft and cheating. As long as you answer question 831<br />

and not 836, you should have brought examples <strong>of</strong> wage theft and cheating rather than examples <strong>of</strong> intensification<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Message [1054] referenced by [1059]. Next Message by Basil is [1138].<br />

[1059] ImmanentMaterialist: Piece Wages and Exploitation. As opposed to timewages,<br />

piece-wages have the potential to increase the degree <strong>of</strong> exploitation perpetrated<br />

by the capitalist to a significantly greater degree. Under the standards <strong>of</strong> the piece-wage<br />

system, for a worker to be paid for the creation <strong>of</strong> a particular commodity (or component <strong>of</strong><br />

a commodity) it must reach a certain level <strong>of</strong> quality. This works to prevent workers from<br />

churning out poorly made products and ensures a certain standard for the workers to reach<br />

for in a manner that is self-enforcing and regulative. As Basil notes, this has a “tendency to<br />

intensify labor” [1054].<br />

According to Hans, this practice, which is one <strong>of</strong> the more distinct features <strong>of</strong> the piecewage,<br />

is such “that the quality control <strong>of</strong> the product” itself comes to be built into the labor<br />

process (595:1). As Marx puts it, “the quality <strong>of</strong> the labor is here controlled by the work”<br />

(694:1). Such a practice opens the door for reductions in wages and allows the capitalist to<br />

cheat their workers to an ever-greater extent. This potentiality <strong>of</strong> the piece-wages is due in<br />

large part to the fact that the intensity <strong>of</strong> labor necessary for the worker to ‘earn’ his keep<br />

is pre-determined. This pre-determined standard is fixed and determined by “experience”


260 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

which stamps each commodity with a value in line with its socially accepted labor-time. So,<br />

with advances in the use-value form <strong>of</strong> a commodity (changes in fashion, style, popularity,<br />

etc.) that necessitate adjustments in the production process, a “competition” is triggered<br />

between the laborers and the capitalist in regards to the appropriate social labor-time for<br />

its production (694:2). Once this is determined (so, commodity-X is now considered to be<br />

worth a half-hour <strong>of</strong> labor-time) this becomes the standard by which all workers, regardless<br />

<strong>of</strong> prior experience, are judged. If they are unable to meet this new marker <strong>of</strong> production<br />

they are let go.<br />

This in turn introduces two important changes within the labor process: that <strong>of</strong> revising<br />

the role <strong>of</strong> the capitalist as supervisor, and that <strong>of</strong> mediated exploitation. In regards<br />

to the first, as noted above, the worker is forced to regulate his own productivity for fear<br />

that lapses will lead either to a deficit in wages which will make difficult his subsistence<br />

and/or his termination. Under the piece-wage then the “superintendence <strong>of</strong> labor” by the<br />

capitalist becomes superfluous; the factory owner’s dominance over the laborer becomes<br />

less present visibly as the workers necessarily becomes charged with furthering the degree<br />

<strong>of</strong> their own exploitation (695:1). Further, this move towards the piece-wage allows for the<br />

role <strong>of</strong> parasitic middleman to interpose themselves between the capitalist and the laborer.<br />

These middlemen, who operate as “chiefs” <strong>of</strong> groups <strong>of</strong> laborers, make contracts with the<br />

capitalist for the production <strong>of</strong> a certain amount <strong>of</strong> commodities. The contractor is able to


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 261<br />

hire and fire laborers at will in order to ensure that only the most seasoned and skilled workers<br />

operate within his outlet, and his own pr<strong>of</strong>its are generated from the difference between<br />

what the capitalist pays for their labor and the wages which the contractor actually allows his<br />

workers to be paid. This mode <strong>of</strong> exploitation, a mode made more capable <strong>of</strong> actualization<br />

due to the introduction <strong>of</strong> the piece-wage, becomes one that is more insidious that thought<br />

previously, as in this case, “the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the worker by capital takes place through the<br />

medium <strong>of</strong> the exploitation <strong>of</strong> one worker by another” (695:1).<br />

Next Message by ImmanentMaterialist is [1146].<br />

[1073] Hans: Is this form <strong>of</strong> cheating too obvious to mention? Wage-theft happens<br />

when the capitalist charges penalties for shoddy work not because the work is too shoddy<br />

but because the capitalist uses the quality <strong>of</strong> the work as an excuse to pay lower wages.<br />

Neither <strong>of</strong> the two answers said this clearly enough for my taste, therefore I am sending this<br />

little note. Does anyone know real-life examples <strong>of</strong> this?<br />

Shelly: An example that I can think <strong>of</strong> would be paying piece wage to a worker for building cabinets. After the<br />

worker completes the project, the person paying him could easily assess the work and find a flaw (or make one up).<br />

In fact, this happens a lot in construction. After the product is complete, the contractor or builder <strong>of</strong>ten find a teeny<br />

tiny problem (which is <strong>of</strong>ten unavoidable since humans are not robots) and use this to pay the worker half the price<br />

promised. They base their decision on quality <strong>of</strong> work when really they might be over-budget on the project and<br />

looking for ways to reduce costs.<br />

Hans: Yes, Shelly’s example is a good one. After reading GTIguy’s [1093] it occurred to me that simply setting<br />

the piece wage so low that only the most attentive and dexterous workers get normal wages and a normal worker


262 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

gets substandard wages, is also a form <strong>of</strong> wage theft. Such a too-low piece wage cannot be spotted as easily as say<br />

a time wage <strong>of</strong> $5 an hour.<br />

Message [1073] referenced by [1093] and [1094]. Next Message by Hans is [1079].<br />

[1093] GTIguy: Incentive Pay Bordering on Wage Theft. Here is an example as requested<br />

in [1073]. My wife works for a company that pays many <strong>of</strong> its employees on a piece<br />

rate scale and I have witnessed this first hand. Her work is a form <strong>of</strong> data entry where she<br />

enters scanned copies <strong>of</strong> medical claims (PDF format) into a database. She works directly<br />

for company A who receives work from company B. Company B expects a minimum accuracy<br />

rating <strong>of</strong> 95%. They enforce this by frequently and randomly checking the medical<br />

form against what was entered into the database. Company A, in an effort to keep their client<br />

happy, expects a 100% accuracy rating and established a pay structure to enforce this benchmark.<br />

There are three pay tiers within company A’s pay structure. The “A” tier (highest pay<br />

rate per claim) is achieved when the worker is accurate between 99 1/2% and 100%, “B” tier<br />

is 99 1/2% and 99%, and “C” tier (lowest pay rate per claim) is 99% and below. Company<br />

A also has its own quality control team that also conducts random audits <strong>of</strong> the claims. The<br />

employees are paid per claim processed at a rate equal to their current quality tier.<br />

Each claim consists <strong>of</strong> roughly 150 fields. An incorrect entry in any <strong>of</strong> the fields results<br />

in the entire claim being flagged as failed. On average my wife is capable <strong>of</strong> processing<br />

about 900 claims in a two week pay period. That means that she is only allowed to make 4<br />

mistakes out <strong>of</strong> roughly 135,000 entry fields in order to make it into the “A” pay tier.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 263<br />

The pay structure rewards employees in two different ways, speed and quality. If you<br />

process claims very fast you are more likely to make a mistake and get bumped to a lower<br />

pay tier, however, if you process claims very slowly to remain in the high pay tier you will<br />

likely not be able to process as many claims. Each employee is left to find their own happy<br />

medium. Company A reaps the benefit <strong>of</strong> both types <strong>of</strong> employee. The slow employees<br />

keep the quality standard high while the fast employees churn through the claims. Company<br />

B remains happy because Company A is providing high quality work at a fast pace but<br />

Company A does not necessarily pass on the rewards to its workers.<br />

Hans: This is a sophisticated method <strong>of</strong> speedup by playing the fast and the precise workers against each other. If<br />

rate “C” is so low that a worker with 95% accuracy, i.e., a worker who meets company A’s quality requirements,<br />

gets a substandard wage, then it is also wage theft.<br />

Message [1093] referenced by [1073] and [1159]. Next Message by GTIguy is [1290].<br />

[1094] Littlerock: graded A A Real Life Example. Hans [1073] asked if anyone has a<br />

real life example. I believe I do. I have two examples from my current place <strong>of</strong> employment<br />

both <strong>of</strong> which reflect this kind <strong>of</strong> cheating, and <strong>of</strong> which the second infuriates me more<br />

than the first for obvious reasons. I work at a third-party call center that is contracted to<br />

take customer service calls for Verizon Wireless. First <strong>of</strong> all, Verizon Wireless pays my<br />

call center by how many calls we take, so it is a piece rate. One way in which they cheat,<br />

however, is by not counting calls that are transferred to a different department. They also<br />

set rules as to when we must transfer to other departments <strong>of</strong> Verizon Wireless. Many times<br />

these calls are only transferred after an extensive amount <strong>of</strong> time has already been spent by


264 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

us on other vital parts <strong>of</strong> the calls. So regardless <strong>of</strong> whether or not we performed the same<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> useful labor on transfer calls as on other calls, they are not counted in what my<br />

call center as a whole gets reimbursed.<br />

The second example that I have concerns the way that the call center I work at pays us. We<br />

are also partly paid by a piece rate. People whose calls are, on average, less than 8 minutes<br />

long get paid approximately 2 dollars an hour higher than people whose calls are longer than<br />

that. The average is taken daily. Also, every day, a survey is sent automatically, by random,<br />

to one <strong>of</strong> the customers with whom we spoke. Part <strong>of</strong> the survey asks if we resolved their<br />

reason for their call. We are paid, in part, based <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> the percentage <strong>of</strong> people who said<br />

“yes” for the last 20 surveys. What the breakdown amounts to, is there is approximately a<br />

$2 decrease in pay for every “no” that we receive. That $2 decrease in our hourly wage lasts<br />

for the next 20 days.<br />

While this appears to make sense on a surface level, imagine the implications. If a particulary<br />

difficult customer calls in, and I have not yet received my results for the survey for the<br />

day, I will take as long as it takes on that call to try and make that customer happy with me<br />

so I will not fail my survey. This requires much more mental exertion and emotional stress<br />

than a normal call, resulting in a higher amount <strong>of</strong> labor power expended in a shorter amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> time. Additionally, that call is likely to last much longer than a normal call, thus raising<br />

my average call time for that day, thus risking a $2 per hour decrease in my pay for that day.<br />

If the customer, despite my best efforts, says that I did not resolve the reason for their call,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 265<br />

my pay is decreased by $2 per hour for the next 20 days as well. What that results in, then,<br />

is a substantial (for me it’s substantial) pay decrease for a call which requires a much greater<br />

expenditure <strong>of</strong> labor power than the other easier calls for which I would not end up with a<br />

pay decrease.<br />

Previously this was partly remedied through a dispute process in which, if we could<br />

demonstrate that we had attempted everything possible and strictly followed all <strong>of</strong> the rules<br />

which Verizon and my call center impose, then a failed survey could be removed and our pay<br />

would not be docked. That was changed, however. There is no more dispute process, and<br />

thus even if on a call we expended much more labor power than usual, and even if we tried<br />

much harder resulting in a much higher quality call than usual, our pay is still significantly<br />

reduced. That way, we get paid less for working harder.<br />

In general, the long calls are the difficult calls, and the short calls are the easy calls, so<br />

a person with a low call handling time has most likely expended less labor power than a<br />

person with a high average call handling time on any given time. The capitalist is able to use<br />

piece rate to rob us by paying us less the harder we work.<br />

Message [1094] referenced by [1159]. Next Message by Littlerock is [1283].<br />

[1159] Curtis: graded A Piece-wage exploitation: what I missed on the exam. The<br />

following was my answer on the exam:


266 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Piece-wages appear to be the sale <strong>of</strong> a commodity by the laborers, but really<br />

are just another form <strong>of</strong> wage. Whereas with time-wages, workers<br />

are less likely to work overtime–and if they do, they earn a higher wage–<br />

piece-wages encourage working overtime and at the same rate as during the<br />

normal working day, allowing the capitalist to extend the working day and<br />

earn even more surplus value while at the same time paying the same wage.<br />

Thus piece-wages can be even more exploitative than time-wages.<br />

After reading answers in the archives, I see that my answer is insufficient. “Wage-theft”,<br />

as Hans explains in [1037], occurs when the capitalist does not pay a full wage for “shoddy”<br />

work, claiming quality to be the reason for the reduction <strong>of</strong> the wage. Numerous real-life<br />

examples were given, by Shelly in [1037] (the comments), GTIguy in [1093], and Littlerock<br />

in [1094]. Bone in [2009fa:788] gives perhaps the best explanation as how wage-theft in<br />

piece-wages can occur; the capitalist reduces wages for “poor quality”, and since the capitalist<br />

is the “judge, jury, and executioner” in regards to quality control, the capitalist has<br />

plenty <strong>of</strong> opportunities to effectively steal from the workers’ wages for unrealistic expectations<br />

in quality ([1093] explains how 99% quality is graded as “C” for quality). It’s a<br />

pathetic excuse by the capitalist to earn more surplus-value.<br />

Another reason that capitalists cheat was presented by Ashley in [2008fa:935]; should<br />

the worker become more productive, he may see a temporary increase in his income. But<br />

the capitalist will adjust the piece-wage such that the worker’s pay is reduced to the same


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 267<br />

level but now requires much more intensity to maintain. The capitalist thus earns more<br />

surplus-value from the worker for the same wage, and the worker is further cheated <strong>of</strong> his<br />

labor-power.<br />

Hans: Marx distinguishes between exploitation and theft, although they <strong>of</strong>ten occur together. Exploitation does<br />

not have to include theft, i.e., it need not violate the ownership principles <strong>of</strong> a commodity society. Theft is such a<br />

violation, and <strong>of</strong> course the capitalist are not the only thieves in this society.<br />

First Message by Curtis is [4].<br />

[1336] KapitalSB: graded B– Marx starts his discussion on time wages because time is<br />

limited. However with piecework wage how much is produced not on how long it takes,<br />

the capitalist only pays the piecework. Piece wage is considering wage theft because the<br />

capitalist is able to exploit the worker, thus the capitalist is cheating and taking away time<br />

from the worker. In Das Kaptial we learn that time is one <strong>of</strong> the most valuable assets the<br />

laborer has. When workers accept piece wages he is at mercy <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. Therefore the<br />

worker is subject to the capitalist stealing wages from the worker.<br />

Hans: Marx distinguishes between exploitation and wage theft. Not every exploitation takes the form <strong>of</strong> wage<br />

theft.<br />

Next Message by KapitalSB is [1337].<br />

[1452] Jag: Piece wage is based <strong>of</strong>f the quality <strong>of</strong> the laborer’s work. Piece wage can<br />

become a “most fertile source for wage theft and capitalist cheating” because if the laborer’s<br />

final product is not perfect or has some flaw, the capitalist can refuse to pay him for his lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> production or lack creating a pr<strong>of</strong>it producing product. So although the laborer has been


268 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

working all day, he still may not be paid. Piece wage also causes a high level <strong>of</strong> competition<br />

amongst laborers which just leads to a higher level <strong>of</strong> productivity and higher pr<strong>of</strong>its for the<br />

capitalists.<br />

Next Message by Jag is [1453].<br />

[1496] Chris: Peace wages can become a “most fertile source for wage theft and capitalist<br />

cheating” when the worker does not produce as many pieces as possible during the day.<br />

Meaning if the worker works very hard for the first part <strong>of</strong> the day and produces 30 pieces<br />

and then only produces 10 pieces in the second half <strong>of</strong> the day then wage theft has occurred.<br />

The worker was not constantly working to their potential.<br />

Capitalist cheating can occur when the capitalist does not pay the worker for each piece<br />

produced by not counting each piece properly or correctly. The capitalist could deny payment<br />

for “improper” pieces or those not “done to standard.” There is a lot <strong>of</strong> room for<br />

disagreement between the capitalist and the worker because the capitalist wants to pay as<br />

little as possible.<br />

Hans: Do I understand you right that in your view the worker commits theft if he does not work as hard as he can<br />

all day, even if he is paid only for his actual output?<br />

The word “wage theft” in the question was intended to mean theft by the capitalist not paying the wages which<br />

the worker is entitled to, i.e., it is similar to “capitalist cheating.”<br />

First Message by Chris is [182].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 269<br />

Question 832 is 689 in 2007SP, 682 in 2008fa, 713 in 2009fa, 777 in 2010fa, and 802 in<br />

2011fa:<br />

Question 832 Time wages and piece wages have opposite effects on the competition between<br />

workers. Explain.<br />

[1098] AndyUte: graded A– Hourly Vs. Commission. This was a fun chapter for me to<br />

read, and a question for which I was excited to come across and be able to answer. Marx<br />

explanation <strong>of</strong> Piece Wage and Time Wage is spot on.<br />

The effects on those that earn time wages and piece wages contrast each other so much<br />

because <strong>of</strong> the components on which the capitalist bases the wage. When a capitalist pays<br />

time wages he evaluates the overall labor power <strong>of</strong> his workers over a certain amount <strong>of</strong><br />

time and then sets the time wage to an amount that is pr<strong>of</strong>itable for the capitalist and is a<br />

satisfactory amount for the laborer. On Page 685 in Capital Marx says that “Given the price<br />

<strong>of</strong> labour, on the other hand, the daily or weekly wage depends on the quantity <strong>of</strong> labour<br />

expended daily or weekly.” The time wage is based on an overall team performance from<br />

the laborers and is not at all dependent on individual labor efficiency. This encourages team<br />

work and a more collective efficiency.<br />

On the other hand, when a capitalist chooses to implore piece wages, he chooses to entice<br />

competition among laborers. Regarding Marx, in Capital he says that “the piece wage is<br />

nothing but a converted form <strong>of</strong> the time-wage, just as the time-wage is a converted form <strong>of</strong>


270 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the value or price <strong>of</strong> labour-power.” The piece wage pays and rewards individual efficiency<br />

and accomplishment. The laborer is paid according to his production. This is a way that<br />

capitalists can take advantage <strong>of</strong> laborers. Through piece wages laborers continually strive<br />

to increase their production and efficiency so that they can make more than their colleagues.<br />

This increases production and pr<strong>of</strong>its for the capitalist.<br />

I currently work for a company that pays both time and piece wages. We are paid commission<br />

for sales on top <strong>of</strong> an hourly base rate. There is definitely some insights I gather<br />

from my experience. First, when sales are hard to come by my coworkers and I are still<br />

able to maintain a healthy and friendly working environment because we know we are still<br />

earning an hourly base rate for trying to sale. At the same time, competition and competition<br />

thrive based on the commission we earn. Seeing coworkers earn extra commission pushes us<br />

to work harder and earn more than what we make hourly. I have been able to see the benefits<br />

<strong>of</strong> both the collective efforts rough about by time wages as well as the competitiveness <strong>of</strong><br />

piece wages.<br />

Hans: While reading chapters 21 and 22 don’t forget chapters 6 and 19! In other words, while looking at the<br />

surface relations don’t forget what they are the surface <strong>of</strong>. You did forget this when you wrote: “the capitalist ...<br />

sets the time wage to an amount that is pr<strong>of</strong>itable for the capitalist and is a satisfactory amount for the laborer.”<br />

According to Marx, the capitalist cannot “set” the time wage but the time wage is determined by the law <strong>of</strong> value:<br />

the hourly wage is the weekly value <strong>of</strong> labor-power divided by the number <strong>of</strong> hours worked on average per week.<br />

Next Message by AndyUte is [1102].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 271<br />

[1272] Smalls: When employees are paid time wages, they are <strong>of</strong>ten rewarded for their<br />

skill. An employee on his first day would make less per hour, than someone on the job five<br />

years. The employee with more experience should produce more for the capitalist. The<br />

capitalist is willing to pay more for the experience in exchange for the additional surplus<br />

value he will collect from the experienced worker. Piece wages create competition among<br />

workers. A young, eighteen-year-old worker, his first week on the job, may be able to<br />

work harder, faster, and produce more than a forty-year-old worker with twenty years <strong>of</strong><br />

experience. This will create unhealthy competition between the two workers. If piece wages<br />

are paid and one worker can produce more than the others, there is competition among<br />

workers that creates a negative working environment, but the workers need one another. The<br />

young worker needs training or has lots <strong>of</strong> questions, and if he is constantly outproducing the<br />

experienced worker, the experienced worker will not want to train or help the new worker.<br />

When workers are paid for their time and experience they are willing to help the capitalist<br />

train workers. The competition <strong>of</strong> piece wages between the two workers will create problems<br />

for the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Smalls is [1365].<br />

[1280] Shickadance: graded A Time wages and piece wages are used in measuring the<br />

labor <strong>of</strong> the worker to ensure that the capitalist is getting the full use <strong>of</strong> the labor-power<br />

which he purchased. This is how they are similar: however, the way in which they foster<br />

competition among a company make them different.


272 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Time wage earners all earn the same amount, no matter the output. Therefore, it becomes<br />

the desire <strong>of</strong> the time wage worker to unite with his fellow laborers to produce the required<br />

yield because there is no incentive to “out-produce” the people in their same work environment.<br />

When time wage workers have a goal <strong>of</strong> compiling 30 accounts before the end <strong>of</strong><br />

the month, competition loses its appeal and the laborers will labor together to accomplish<br />

their goal. This type <strong>of</strong> wage compensation makes competition lose its appeal. Piece wage<br />

earners are motivated to go above and beyond everyone else because their earnings are directly<br />

related to output. As someone in a sales company sells more and more, he will earn<br />

more than those he “outproduces” and will receive recognition and extra compensation for<br />

his diligence. This type <strong>of</strong> wage breeds heavy competition amongst workers.<br />

Next Message by Shickadance is [1469].<br />

[1379] Ruffian: Time wages and piece wages have opposite effects due in part to the<br />

method a capitalist bases the wage he pays his employees. When the capitalist pays wages<br />

based on the time spent producing he considers the overall effectiveness <strong>of</strong> all his workers<br />

over a set amount <strong>of</strong> time. He can then dictate how much to pay the employees based on<br />

minimal production. This in turn forces the worker to only accomplish enough production to<br />

maintain his/her current lifestyle and thus maintain employment. In piece labor he options<br />

for competition amongst the workers. Works are no longer paid based on the time they put<br />

in, but the amount produced. This favors and rewards a worker’s efficiency and production.<br />

This is <strong>of</strong> course beneficial for the capitalist as increased competition and efficiency amongst<br />

workers results in higher pr<strong>of</strong>its for the capitalist.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 273<br />

Hans: The economic law that workers don’t make more money than that to preserve their lifestyle does not come<br />

from a lack <strong>of</strong> effort by the workers. Marx says this is a systemic law based on the structure <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

First Message by Ruffian is [620].<br />

[1380] Amcelhiney: Time wages hold less motivation for workers to increase productivity.<br />

These workers will get paid the same amount regardless <strong>of</strong> their productivity. Time wages<br />

take away the competition which increase production. Piece wages motivate the worker to<br />

produce as much as possible to earn as much as possible. Piece wages increase competition<br />

while increasing productivity. While different pay wages may benefit the worker more than<br />

others it is clear that the value the workers create is still exploited by the capitalist.<br />

Hans: This sounds as if piece wages allow the workers to make more money than time wages. Your in-class<br />

answer says this explicitly, it says: “Piece wages allow the worker to be the only thing holding them back from<br />

the opportunity to make more money.” Marx does not think so. The fact that the capitalist owns the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production is what holds the workers back from the opportunity to make more money, whether this money be paid<br />

in time wages or piece wages. Time wages and piece wages are just different ways for the capitalist to get as much<br />

labor out <strong>of</strong> the worker as possible.<br />

Next Message by Amcelhiney is [1382].<br />

Question 833 is 690 in 2007SP:<br />

Question 833 Is there something wrong with the worker’s sense <strong>of</strong> “liberty, independence<br />

and self-control” engendered by piece-wages?


274 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1076] Tim: graded A Thoughts on the liberation <strong>of</strong> working for piece-wage. My sense<br />

is that the notion <strong>of</strong> liberty inspired by working for piece-wage is at best a fallacy, and at<br />

worst a force which undermines the well being <strong>of</strong> the worker in general. The tendency <strong>of</strong><br />

this scheme is to perpetually lengthen the duration <strong>of</strong> the work day and pit workers against<br />

one another; according to Marx, “It is moreover now the personal interest <strong>of</strong> the laborer to<br />

lengthen the working-day, since with it his daily or weekly wages rise” (670). Workers who<br />

fail to surrender increasing amounts <strong>of</strong> their time to keep pace with their more enthusiastic<br />

peers find themselves falling behind the accepted average level <strong>of</strong> output resulting in the less<br />

willing workers’ elimination; or at least I assume this to be the eventual outcome. In addition<br />

to an ever lengthening and intensifying work day, the competition inspired by this wage<br />

scheme undermines worker solidarity and assists the capitalist in dividing the interests <strong>of</strong> his<br />

workers. I tend to think that the competition generated in this manner to be a constant advantage<br />

for the capitalist. I therefore disagree with Orestes’ [2007SP:937] assertion that worker<br />

competition in large quantities would undermine the interests <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. Orestes argues<br />

that overly competitive workers would interfere with operations by refusing to work<br />

together and would thus compromise the output potential <strong>of</strong> a given production scheme. It<br />

would seem an odd production configuration indeed if this were the case. My assumption<br />

is that as the necessity for cooperation increases, so too does the likelihood that time-wages<br />

will be employed or some other coercion might be employed to incentivize civility.<br />

Hans: I think Orestes agrees with you that competition between workers is generally good for the capitalists. But<br />

I agree with Orestes that too much competition between the workers may poison the work atmosphere so much that


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 275<br />

it reduces overall productivity. Capitalists are certainly aware <strong>of</strong> this. I remember that Lester Thurow in his 1983<br />

book Dangerous Currents talks about this. The fact that it is so important to the capitalists how the workers get<br />

along shows how much power the working class would have if only they decided to rise up in solidarity.<br />

Next Message by Tim is [1256].<br />

Question 838 is 696 in 2007SP, 675 in 2007fa, 684 in 2008SP, 688 in 2008fa, 719 in<br />

2009fa, 783 in 2010fa, and 808 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 838 If the capitalists make higher pr<strong>of</strong>its due to technical innovation, should the<br />

workers get part <strong>of</strong> this?<br />

[1058] Snowball: graded A Laborers as Machines. While I tend to side with the workers<br />

throughout this course, I believe the answer to this question leans more heavily to the<br />

capitalists. When a laborer applies for a job and begins employment, he is <strong>of</strong>ten under the<br />

illusion that he is paid for his product, when, in fact, he has simply sold his labor-power to<br />

the capitalist.<br />

When a capitalist upgrades technology, he essentially makes better use <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

labor-power he bought. Though it may be unflattering, a way to think <strong>of</strong> this is that the workers<br />

are reduced to machines that the capitalist has purchased. The capitalist has made his<br />

“machines” more efficient while the “machines” remain with the same initial labor-power.<br />

Of course, there are exceptions to this rule. If the worker creates the technical innovation,<br />

then the pr<strong>of</strong>it should go to him. In fact, the entirety <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>it should go to him. If, for


276 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

example, a worker types documents, and discovers an innovation that makes him type twice<br />

as fast, he should be rewarded for it.<br />

The capitalist can certainly pay more if he prefers, but he is in no way obligated to do so.<br />

He bought labor-power at a certain price and has no duty to his “machines” to pay more.<br />

Hans: Are you assuming the better technology is created by the capitalist? See my [2011fa:713].<br />

Message [1058] referenced by [1135]. Next Message by Snowball is [1134].<br />

[1071] Frankie: graded A Double Edged Sword... The answer to the question is not as<br />

simple as some <strong>of</strong> the past answers have led one to believe. There are a multitude <strong>of</strong> factors<br />

that play into whether or not the proceeds from a technical innovation should be shared or<br />

whether the capitalists should keep all the pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

In answer [2009fa:763] Kay correctly states that “in no way are capitalists obligated to<br />

share the higher pr<strong>of</strong>its with their employees.” This statement is correct as noted by Hans,<br />

however the question is, as I interpret it, referring to more <strong>of</strong> a moral stance <strong>of</strong> should the<br />

additional pr<strong>of</strong>its be shared, not if the capitalist has an obligation to do so. The resounding<br />

answer within the archive seems to be that if the worker helps contribute to the technical<br />

innovation, or if the worker adds to the process then they should receive part <strong>of</strong> the higher<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its. Others like Chad in answer [2008fa:899] think that because the capitalist is taking<br />

all the risk, in regards to the investment <strong>of</strong> the technical innovation, that the capitalist should<br />

not share these higher pr<strong>of</strong>its with the worker.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 277<br />

My answer in part to this would be, does the worker play any part in the higher output or<br />

technical innovation leading to the higher pr<strong>of</strong>its? If so, then I believe the worker to be entitled<br />

to a share <strong>of</strong> these higher pr<strong>of</strong>its. As to how much <strong>of</strong> a share that will be the decision <strong>of</strong><br />

the capitalist. However, if the worker does not contribute to the higher pr<strong>of</strong>its, that meaning<br />

either in the technical innovation itself or in the following higher production resulting from<br />

the innovation, that the worker should not receive any additional compensation for his work.<br />

If the worker continues to provide the same amount <strong>of</strong> output, resulting in similar pr<strong>of</strong>it until<br />

the advent <strong>of</strong> the technical innovation, why should he receive more compensation? The reverse<br />

is true as well, if the worker does contribute to a higher pr<strong>of</strong>it why should he not then<br />

receive more compensation? Karl states this well in [2011fa:691] saying “If the workers<br />

had a hand in the technical innovation then yes they should get a part <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>it. If the<br />

workers had nothing to do with the technical innovation then they should not receive part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>it. Technical innovation comes from people, and the person or group <strong>of</strong> people<br />

should receive part <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>it from their innovation.”<br />

In short the worker should receive the extra marginal pr<strong>of</strong>it, in correlation with the extra<br />

marginal pr<strong>of</strong>it he provides.<br />

Next Message by Frankie is [1096].<br />

[1079] Hans: The pitfalls <strong>of</strong> not seeing things from a class perspective. All answers<br />

this Semester and most answers in the archives make the mistake <strong>of</strong> considering technical<br />

progress to be something the capitalists bring to the labor process. Perhaps in future


278 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Semestes I should assign chapter Thirteen, about co-operation, for reading too, because in<br />

this chapter Marx explains that the co-operation <strong>of</strong> the workers is a productive force in addition<br />

to the workers’ individual contributions. The capitalitst cream <strong>of</strong>f the benefits <strong>of</strong> this<br />

productive force for themselves, because they oversee the co-operation <strong>of</strong> the workers. As<br />

long as the workers sell their labor to the capitalists one by one, they have no standing to<br />

claim this benefit <strong>of</strong> their joint labor process for themselves. And your answers looked at<br />

the worker as one individual selling his or her labor-power. This is not the right way to look<br />

at it.<br />

Marx claims it is more accurate if the workers see themselves as members <strong>of</strong> the working<br />

class, and if they see capitalism as a system in which the class <strong>of</strong> owners <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production exploits the working class. It is not a relationship between individuals but a<br />

class relation. The benefits <strong>of</strong> co-operation should go to the working class, because it is the<br />

workers who co-operate, not the capitalists. If the wage-labor relations allows the capitalists<br />

to take it for themselves, then this is just an additional aspect <strong>of</strong> the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

working class.<br />

What is true for co-operation in general is also true for technical progress, which is impossible<br />

individually and necessarily a co-opeative process. Capitalists are rich not because<br />

they produce wealth, but because social relations exist which channel into their pockets the<br />

wealth created in this society, which should belong to everyone. It is high time that the real<br />

creators <strong>of</strong> this wealth, the working class, call them on this.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 279<br />

Message [1079] referenced by [1135] and [1355]. Next Message by Hans is [1160].<br />

[1135] Snowball: graded B+ Pr<strong>of</strong>its for the ”Machines” When a laborer applies for a<br />

job and begins employment, he is <strong>of</strong>ten under the illusion that he is paid for his product,<br />

when, in fact, he has simply sold his labor-power to the capitalist.<br />

When a capitalist upgrades technology, he essentially makes better use <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

labor-power he bought. Though it may be unflattering, a way to think <strong>of</strong> this is that the workers<br />

are reduced to machines that the capitalist has purchased. The capitalist has made his<br />

“machines” more efficient while the “machines” remain with the same initial labor-power.<br />

Does this mean the capitalist should not share his higher pr<strong>of</strong>its? He is not obligated to,<br />

<strong>of</strong> course, but he should. The capitalist may have the means <strong>of</strong> production and the capital to<br />

conduct the research that leads to technical innovation, but that innovation would be impossible<br />

without the workers. The capitalist must have the ability to observe the workers and<br />

learn from them before any technical advancement is possible.<br />

On a side note, if the worker creates the technical innovation, then the pr<strong>of</strong>it should go<br />

to him. In fact, the entirety <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>it should go to him. If, for example, a worker types<br />

documents, and discovers an innovation that makes him type twice as fast, he should be<br />

rewarded for it.<br />

Hans: You are simply repeating your [1058] without taking my response [1079] into consideration.<br />

Next Message by Snowball is [1136].


280 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[1141.1] Basil: Pr<strong>of</strong>its to the Workers. If capitalists make higher pr<strong>of</strong>it due to technical<br />

innovations, the workers should not only get part <strong>of</strong> this, they should get all <strong>of</strong> it. The reason<br />

is that technical innovation is inherently social—it only occurs through cooperation among<br />

workers. Because workers create all the value, they should reap all the pr<strong>of</strong>its. Unfortunately,<br />

because capitalists control the means <strong>of</strong> production, they are able to dictate cooperation and<br />

retain all extra pr<strong>of</strong>its that result from technical innovation.<br />

Hans [2011fa:713] has further explained that “Technical innovation is not really the work<br />

<strong>of</strong> any one individual. It is the result <strong>of</strong> a social process. Those workers who work the<br />

machines designed by the engineers create the practical experiences which nurture further<br />

improvements. A case can be made that the benefits <strong>of</strong> this social process should be shared<br />

by everyone, down to the person sweeping the floors. But due to their control <strong>of</strong> the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production, the capitalists are able to syphon <strong>of</strong>f the benefits <strong>of</strong> co-operation into their<br />

pockets.” This quote further qualifies the conclusion described above, that workers should<br />

receive all and any pr<strong>of</strong>its that result from technical innovation.<br />

Next Message by Basil is [1266].<br />

[1197] Leont: Marx sees this to be an issue with the worker and what they believe they<br />

are selling. They are selling the labor-power not labor, but with this oversight they will<br />

continue to be exploited by the capitalist. Also with the amount <strong>of</strong> labor-power given for<br />

said commodity would decrease with technical innovation which highlights the difference<br />

between value produced and value <strong>of</strong> labor-power.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 281<br />

Hans: This answer still needs some work. The resubmission would have been a good opportunity for this.<br />

Next Message by Leont is [1198].<br />

[1208] Rowlsroyce: If the workers did not innovate anything then no. After reading what<br />

Marx says in [700:1] paragraph 62. A machine was innovated that could make 240 yds. <strong>of</strong><br />

fabric when the previous one could only make 160 yds. <strong>of</strong> fabric. Therefore the company<br />

sells 1d instead <strong>of</strong> 1 1/2d that it did previously. Leaving what earnings to about the same as<br />

they made before. This is true unless it makes more labor for the worker to run the machine<br />

or process the fabric as DO mentions in [2011fa:756] then the worker is entitled to more<br />

money. If not, maybe the capitalist would steal more business with his/her cheaper cost to<br />

build and then the factory would get more money/business and in a way pay the employee<br />

more money, but that is just hypothetical.<br />

At the same time the Capitalist has all <strong>of</strong> the risk involved and deserves the pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Next Message by Rowlsroyce is [1209].<br />

[1229] AndyUte: graded B The value <strong>of</strong> labor-power for which workers are hired is based<br />

on the value created by the laborer’s labor-power. The capitalist always expects the value<br />

created by labor-power to exceed that the actual labor-power. The capitalist owns the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production and when the means <strong>of</strong> production becomes more efficient, through technical<br />

innovation for example, he is able to gain more pr<strong>of</strong>its. This does not change at the value<br />

labor-power. Therefore, the capitalist has no obligation to raise wages. Unless a specific


282 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

laborer played a role in this innovation he would in no way be paid more because the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> his labor-power has stayed the same.<br />

Hans: This was one point <strong>of</strong> view in the discussion, but others had different points <strong>of</strong> view. On what basis can it<br />

be argued that the worker has a claim on these pr<strong>of</strong>its?<br />

Next Message by AndyUte is [1230].<br />

[1250] Neela: graded B If the capitalists make higher pr<strong>of</strong>its due to technical innovation,<br />

the workers should not get part <strong>of</strong> this, because they did not invent that technology that<br />

made the firm more productive. However, if the worker did help invent that technology then<br />

they should receive part <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>it, because it is due to their invention <strong>of</strong> the new process,<br />

s<strong>of</strong>tware, etc. that improves the efficiency and productivity. They should only receive part <strong>of</strong><br />

the pr<strong>of</strong>it, because although that technology is boosting the productivity <strong>of</strong> the firm, it will<br />

require less work on behalf <strong>of</strong> the worker, so they’re not working more or harder therefore<br />

they should only receive partial pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Hans: Capitalist social relations are such that workers are not only deprived <strong>of</strong> the fruits <strong>of</strong> large portions <strong>of</strong> every<br />

day’s labor, but they are also excluded from reaping the full benefit <strong>of</strong> general social progress. Instead <strong>of</strong> seeing<br />

this as a deplorable fact, you raise it to a normative principle. You say that, even if a worker himself invented the<br />

technology, they should only get full benefit if on top <strong>of</strong> it they also have to work harder. As you see it, capitalists<br />

are allowed to reap full benefits from their inventiveness, workers are not. In a class reading Marx, I can count this<br />

as a fully correct answer only if you argue why your answer should be preferred over the answer to this question<br />

suggested by Marx’s theories.<br />

Next Message by Neela is [1251].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 283<br />

[1324] Bimmer: graded A There are two aspects <strong>of</strong> this question that must be looked at in<br />

order to answer it entirely. One must look at the capitalist’s view and the worker’s view. If<br />

we look at the capitalist’s view, he pays the worker for their labor-power. There is a constant<br />

wage that is given to the worker. However, if the worker does not go through any technical<br />

innovation, but the capitalist makes improvements to the machines that assist the workers,<br />

then the workers are in no way entitled to receive part <strong>of</strong> the higher pr<strong>of</strong>its achieved from<br />

this efficiency. The reason behind this, is that the worker is neither increasing their production<br />

or increasing their efficiency <strong>of</strong> production through any means <strong>of</strong> innovation. What is<br />

happening, is the capitalists is making the investment through upgrading his machines or<br />

robots in order for more product to be produced. Therefore, since the capitalist bears all the<br />

costs associated with the increased efficiency in order to increase pr<strong>of</strong>its, the worker does<br />

not deserve any <strong>of</strong> the higher pr<strong>of</strong>its achieved.<br />

Another way to look at this, is to see if the technical innovation is invested in the worker.<br />

Let’s say the capitalists is paying for additional training for the worker, in order to either<br />

learn a new set <strong>of</strong> skills or to find ways in which to decrease the times it takes to produce a<br />

commodity or increase efficiency. If we look at it like this, the technical innovation is still<br />

being made by the capitalist, since he is bearing he cost; yet, it is the worker who is learning<br />

and improving and receiving the investment in order to increase efficiency. Therefore, since<br />

the worker has acquired additional training and or new skills, the worker is able to sell his<br />

new labor-power and overall should be given some increase in wage. The big issue though,


284 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

is how much. Should the worker(s) receive all <strong>of</strong> the higher pr<strong>of</strong>its associated with the<br />

technical innovation? I do not think so. The capitalist is greedy and will therefore increase<br />

wages, but only to an amount where he/she is still making a higher pr<strong>of</strong>it than before.<br />

Overall, the worker or workers will receive only part <strong>of</strong> the higher pr<strong>of</strong>its achieved if<br />

they are the ones that went through a form <strong>of</strong> technical innovation. If not, than since the<br />

investment is made in machines which the capitalist owns and bears all costs associated with,<br />

the capitalist should keep all higher pr<strong>of</strong>it attained from the technical innovation investment<br />

he/she made.<br />

Next Message by Bimmer is [1325].<br />

[1328] JEP: At first thought during the exam I viewed the technical innovation that increased<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its an advancement solely created by the capitalist, neglecting the fact that labor<br />

does not become easier through all technical innovations. I was under the assumption that<br />

the person who created the technical advancement, in this example the capitalist, was responsible<br />

for the pr<strong>of</strong>its and assumed labor would remain the same, although production<br />

increased, because labor-time remained the same. I didn’t consider that labor may become<br />

more strenuous through technical innovations as capitalists continually demand higher production.<br />

After reading the annotations and notes I now believe that as pr<strong>of</strong>its increase for the<br />

capitalists through the labor-power <strong>of</strong> the worker that some <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>its should be shared<br />

with the worker.<br />

Next Message by JEP is [1485].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 285<br />

[1341] TMM: If the capitalist make a higher pr<strong>of</strong>it due to technical innovation, the worker<br />

should but ultimately does not get part <strong>of</strong> this pr<strong>of</strong>it and there are plausible reasons as to<br />

why. The laborer essentially is under the impression that they are paid for based on the<br />

product the make, when in all actuality the laborer is basically selling his labor-power to<br />

the capitalist. The capitalist bought the labor-power from the worker at a specific price,<br />

which was allowed by the worker himself. The laborer essentially does not have access<br />

to the means <strong>of</strong> production, as the capitalist does. Because the capitalist has the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production he is able to exploit the worker as much as he possibly can in order to produce<br />

more and this is what might allow the capitalist to make technological advances and more<br />

efficient methods in the future. This is a difficult question to answer because this hits a moral<br />

parameter for humans, but ultimately (as stated by Kay in [2009fa:763]) the capitalist are in<br />

no way obligated to share higher pr<strong>of</strong>its from its employers. The capitalists simply take on<br />

much risk in the investment <strong>of</strong> the new technological advancements; the worker should get<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the increased pr<strong>of</strong>its from new technological advances if they in fact had something<br />

to do with the new technology, kind <strong>of</strong> like a royalty. However the capitalist is not obligated<br />

to do so, it would be in good heart for the capitalist to include the worker in more earning<br />

capabilities. If anything, the technological advancements might even neglect the need for<br />

a worker in the first place, so ultimately the caveat to new technology is that the creators<br />

might be destroying their own livelihood. Additionally, attaching the worker to the produce<br />

in the form <strong>of</strong> a “piece wage,” which is performance based pa,y the capitalists can allow the<br />

worker to earn wages based on the amount <strong>of</strong> “pieces” they produce. Pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>of</strong> the capitalist


286 2012fa Econ <strong>5080</strong> U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

should certainly be shared with employees, as Kibosh [2007fa:467] said that this monetary<br />

raise should be a portion <strong>of</strong> the marginal increase due to the technology because the cost <strong>of</strong><br />

the capital while simultaneously bringing attention to the added risk <strong>of</strong> using that specific<br />

technological good (not knowing the reliability and overall increase in output) until actual<br />

use. However, Marx says in 700:1: “The capitalist rightly rejects such claims as being gross<br />

errors as to the nature <strong>of</strong> wage-labor. He cries out against this presumptuous attempt to lay<br />

taxes on the progress <strong>of</strong> industry, and declares roundly that the productivity <strong>of</strong> labor does<br />

not concern the worker in the least.” Where the capitalist is not obligated to give the worker<br />

a more <strong>of</strong> the higher pr<strong>of</strong>its and Marx suggests not to.<br />

Hans: Your in-class answer had a good train <strong>of</strong> thought which you abandoned in your resubmission.<br />

Next Message by TMM is [1342].<br />

[1355] Glister: If the capitalist makes a higher pr<strong>of</strong>it from technical innovation then the<br />

worker should receive a higher wage. The capitalist is taking advantage <strong>of</strong> the workers and<br />

using them in the first place. Technical innovation will make an extra surplus but the worker<br />

will still put the time into the product. It all comes down to whether the worker is getting<br />

paid for the commodities he has produced or whether he is being used for his labor power<br />

that he sold to the capitalist. If the workers have to change the way they work in order for<br />

the capitalist to make a higher pr<strong>of</strong>it then I feel the worker should receive a higher wage for<br />

his higher productivity.<br />

Hans: Your last sentence backtracks from your first sentence. The reason why all workers should get higher wages<br />

if there is technical progress is not that they have to change their work. It is also not, as you say in your in-class


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ <strong>5080</strong> 2012fa 287<br />

answer, that the generation <strong>of</strong> this technical progress takes labor time. The reason, as I tried to explain in [1079], is<br />

that technical progress is a result <strong>of</strong> the production process, and the workers are engaged in the production process.<br />

The workers are the producers, not the capitalists. The capitalists are parasites on production.<br />

Next Message by Glister is [1356].<br />

Compiled by Hans G. Ehrbar 2012-12-07 14:49:26.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!