20.07.2013 Views

2008SP - University of Utah

2008SP - University of Utah

2008SP - University of Utah

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

ECONOMICS 5080 QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS<br />

ALL STUDY QUESTIONS<br />

ECONOMICS DEPARTMENT, UNIVERSITY OF UTAH SPRING SEMESTER 2008<br />

Question 8 is 2 in 1996sp, 1 in 1997WI, 1 in 1997sp, 1 in 1997ut, 1 in 1998WI, 1 in 1999SP,<br />

1 in 2002fa, 2 in 2003fa, 4 in 2004fa, 5 in 2005fa, 8 in 2007fa, 8 in 2008fa, 8 in 2009fa,<br />

9 in 2010fa, 9 in 2011fa, and 1 in Answer:<br />

Question 8 Can one say that happiness is the only true wealth?<br />

[1] Kevin: (graded A) Happiness and Wealth: Possible Antonyms? I do not believe that<br />

happiness is the only true wealth. In fact, I believe that happiness may at some times in life<br />

be the farthest thing from it. Wealth, defined as “anything that enhances human life,” does<br />

not seem to come from happiness at all but from struggle, sorrow, hard work, and dedication<br />

to the solution <strong>of</strong> problems in life.<br />

A look back on some <strong>of</strong> the greatest inventions <strong>of</strong> the world, things that “enhance human<br />

life,” would suggest that the inventors or those around them were not happy with their circumstances<br />

and therefore changed those circumstances. Wealth in these cases may even be<br />

the mind <strong>of</strong> the inventor and not the invention itself, or even possibly both.<br />

I suppose then the argument would be whether those inventions were really enhancing<br />

life at all but I think that may be grounds for an entirely different argument.<br />

Message [1] referenced by [2], [7], [9], and [2011fa:778]. Next Message by Kevin is [136].<br />

[2] Dyoung: Happiness and Wealth. I would agree that happiness is the only true wealth.<br />

But it is not for sale. Happiness is something you earn from life’s achievements which can<br />

come in a temporal form like money, cars, houses, jewelry, etc. Happiness is more <strong>of</strong> an<br />

emotional state <strong>of</strong> life. It is not something you can just go out and buy. Happiness is caused<br />

by external forces, where bliss is happiness in its true state without any reason for it to exist<br />

other than the moment being perfect. It can occur in any situation and at any time if you are<br />

willing to acknowledge it for what it is. Wealth has been defined as anything that enhances<br />

human life, which happiness needs to be included in this because it is the pay-<strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> that<br />

enhancement which you have received. Everyone would perceive happiness and wealth<br />

very differently. Something that may make me happy, may not make someone else equally<br />

as happy. So when it comes down to if happiness is the “only” true wealth, it does not pay<br />

your bills. So the real question is “what does being wealthy mean to the individual?”<br />

Hans: Your answer came 3 hours after Kevin’s [1], but you did not refer to Kevin’s answer, but started from scratch,<br />

with a completely different angle than Kevin’s. This is against the rules <strong>of</strong> this class. We are aiming for a discussion<br />

in which the contributions build on each other, and not a cacophony <strong>of</strong> unrelated submissions.<br />

Also you have some awkward sentences. “Happiness is more <strong>of</strong> an emotional state <strong>of</strong> life” is not appropriate<br />

for written English. I expect a more polished formulation.<br />

Message [2] referenced by [5]. Next Message by Dyoung is [28].<br />

1


2 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[5] Hans: Why does nobody notice that logarithms can’t be yellow? The answer to<br />

this question has two parts, I will number them (1) and (2):<br />

(1) First <strong>of</strong> all, you cannot say anything intelligent about this question if you don’t notice<br />

that “happiness is the only kind <strong>of</strong> wealth” is a nonsensical statement. It is like saying<br />

“laughter is the only kind <strong>of</strong> joke.” Wealth is an input into the process <strong>of</strong> living, while<br />

happiness is an output from the process <strong>of</strong> living. I elaborated on this in [1999SP:12], which<br />

I recommend as reading. (In other words, if others contribute to this same question, I expect<br />

them to have read it.)<br />

(2) The above is only the first part <strong>of</strong> the answer, so-to-say the preliminary. The more<br />

interesting part comes now: why is it not obvious to everybody that this is a nonsensical<br />

statement? Now we go from logic to sociology.<br />

The submitted answers seemed always striking to me because people are so quick to<br />

denigrate wealth. I am a Marxist. I think we are living in a society in which there is a lot<br />

<strong>of</strong> blatant exploitation, but this exploitation is hidden from those being exploited. From this<br />

starting point it is easy to come to the conclusion that this denigration <strong>of</strong> wealth is part <strong>of</strong><br />

the defence mechanism which allows everybody not to see their exploitation. If wealth is<br />

irrelevant, if it is more important to have a good attitude than to have material resources as I<br />

just happened to read in [2005fa:120], then it is easier to live with the fact that all the wealth<br />

we are producing is stolen or misappropriated.<br />

But Dyoung’s answer [2] adds a different dimension to it. When Dyoung says happiness<br />

is not for sale, and it does not pay your bills – but wealth does – he seems to identify wealth<br />

with things that can be bought and sold. But purchases and sales are not wealth itself but<br />

they are the social form which wealth takes in our society. Therefore his suspicion about<br />

wealth is also a critique <strong>of</strong> the existing social relations.<br />

Can you be convinced that you are not critical <strong>of</strong> wealth itself but <strong>of</strong> the form wealth<br />

takes in our society? Let’s imagine components <strong>of</strong> wealth which cannot be bought or sold.<br />

By taking classes at the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> you are enriching your lives – not only because<br />

you may get a better paying job afterwards but also because you know more about the world<br />

and about yourself. And the nice thing about this kind <strong>of</strong> wealth is: nobody can take it away<br />

from you.<br />

This takes me to another aspect in Dyoung’s answer, and in many answers before him.<br />

Wealth is seen as a reward for sacrifice. Again I think this is an implicit critique <strong>of</strong> our social<br />

relations, for two reasons – this time I call them (a) and (b):<br />

(a) Why should production, arguably the noblest activity humans can pursue, be considered<br />

a sacrifice? My Marxist knee-jerk answer here is: because in our society, production is<br />

bound up with exploitation. The disgusting part <strong>of</strong> our work lives is not the production part<br />

but the exploitation part.<br />

(b) Why should the incredible wealth in this society only be made available so some and<br />

not shared by everybody? If you answer: it is necessary as an incentive to produce more,<br />

then my Marxist knee-jerk answer is: We don’t need more production. More production as


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 3<br />

we know it from capitalism causes climate change and ruins the living conditions for humans<br />

on the planet.<br />

Message [5] referenced by [7], [8], [13], [14], [15], and [2008fa:18]. Next Message by Hans is [8].<br />

[7] Lev: Happiness and Wealth. Well, one could certainly say it but they wouldn’t<br />

necessarily be correct. ;-)<br />

Kevin suggested in [1] that the quest for wealth “does not seem to come from happiness<br />

at all but from struggle, sorrow, hard work, and dedication to the solution <strong>of</strong> problems in<br />

life”. It would seem however this to have the question the wrong way around. The question<br />

does not ask whether wealth provides happiness, but whether happiness is the only true<br />

wealth; the word order provides a question <strong>of</strong> significantly different quality. Hans [5] has<br />

indicated whether the question is pragmatically commensurable in the first place, but again I<br />

would point out that the question did not ask whether “happiness is the only kind <strong>of</strong> wealth”<br />

but rather it is the only true wealth; a statement itself which does fall into the “No True<br />

Scotsman” sort <strong>of</strong> fallacy).<br />

Nevertheless, many would intuitively agree with the proposition as the “quest for happiness”<br />

has been a dominant theme in intellectual thought and practical application for many<br />

years. In Plato’s “Crito”, the contemplative philosopher Socrates argues that the most important<br />

aim in a person’s life is to achieve happiness through virtuous knowledge <strong>of</strong> the good,<br />

achieved through self-development, and the cultivation <strong>of</strong> friendships <strong>of</strong> good people. It is<br />

not life, he argues, but a good life that is to chiefly valued (Crito, 48b). Aristotle, following<br />

a similar line <strong>of</strong> reasoning in the “Nichomachean Ethics”, developed a system <strong>of</strong> “virtue<br />

ethics”, arguing that the function <strong>of</strong> the human soul was to have a true life built on balanced<br />

consideration and action.<br />

It may seem surprising then that given the emphasis <strong>of</strong> the ancient Hellenes to good moral<br />

choices being the path to happiness, that some contemporary biopsychologists (e.g., Pr<strong>of</strong>.<br />

Kent Berridge, <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Michgan, Stefan Klein in The Science <strong>of</strong> Happiness (2006))<br />

argue that happiness is largely determined by neurochemical states, that is, the relative presence<br />

<strong>of</strong> natural opiates like dopamine in the brain. On a related approach some [1] have<br />

claimed that 50% <strong>of</strong> happiness is from genetic basis, and only 10-15% from socio-economic<br />

origins, although the particular study does suffer from selection bias.<br />

Countering this claim from the discipline mainstream economics and its utilitarian calculations.<br />

Some significant attempts have been made to differentiate between wealth as<br />

measured by GDP and life quality overall. These are interesting as they show exactly how<br />

far the definition <strong>of</strong> wealth in the political and economic system (as defined by exchange values)<br />

is from representing satisfaction (as defined as use values). In 2005, “The Economist”<br />

produced such a study. As one would obviously expect there was an positive correlation between<br />

GDP per capita and quality <strong>of</strong> life. However there were significant disparities between<br />

the two depending on how the GDP was used.<br />

The nations were the Quality <strong>of</strong> Life was significantly higher (10 ranks or more) than<br />

their GDP per capita in the larger economies included places like Sweden (+14), Italy (+15),<br />

Spain (+14) and New Zealand (+10). Places where the QoL index was significantly lower<br />

than their GDP per capita included the United States (-11), the United Kingdom (-16), Saudi


4 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Arabia (-23), and almost at the bottom <strong>of</strong> the list (despite being a mid-range economy according<br />

to GDP per capita), was Russia (-50). The best places to live, overall, were Ireland,<br />

Switzerland, Norway, Luxembourg, Sweden, Australia, Iceland, Italy, Denmark and Spain,<br />

Singapore and Finland.<br />

Combining the various approaches it would seem necessary to differentiate [2] between<br />

“labour”, those unpleasant activites (as Kevin illustrated) necessary to provide the necessities<br />

<strong>of</strong> life, between “work”, the payment <strong>of</strong> activity for wages, subject to the various forms<br />

<strong>of</strong> exploitation, power relations etc and “action”, the free and conscious activity without<br />

restrains, an ideal found in Arendt and especially in Herbert Marcuse (cf., Eros and Civilization).<br />

Making this differentiation, and on the upper level <strong>of</strong> activity, would allow one to<br />

define “action” as happiness as not the only true wealth, but certaily the one which is the<br />

highest form, albeit only achievable under certain conditions.<br />

1] Lyubomirsky, Sheldon, Schkade in “Pursuing Happiness: The Architecture <strong>of</strong> Sustainable<br />

Change”, Review <strong>of</strong> General Psychology 2005, Vol. 9, No. 2, 111-131<br />

2] As Hannah Arendt did in her studies on the human condition and Engels made explicit<br />

in his speech at Marx’s graveside.<br />

Message [7] referenced by [15]. Next Message by Lev is [14].<br />

[9] Hans: Wealth without Misery? Kevin [1] does not try to answer the nonsensical<br />

question whether happiness is wealth, but switches to the more interesting question whether<br />

happiness is conducive to the production <strong>of</strong> wealth. His answer is “no,” and Marx would<br />

agree. Marx says in 648:2/oo: “Where nature is too lavish, she ‘keeps [humankind] in hand,<br />

like a child in leading-strings’.”<br />

Prior to capitalism, the highest level <strong>of</strong> technology was achieved by independent artisans<br />

and peasants producing for the market (petty commodity production). But these proud and<br />

independent producers would never have agreed to the discipline <strong>of</strong> large-scale direct cooperation.<br />

One might say they were too happy in their independence, they would never<br />

have dreamt <strong>of</strong> giving it up voluntarily. Only when they lost their independence and became<br />

wage laborers <strong>of</strong> the same capitalist, could they be forced to directly co-operate. Instead <strong>of</strong><br />

a human-based production process, capital introduced a modern science-based production<br />

process, a revolution which necessarily had to go against the will <strong>of</strong> the laborers themselves.<br />

The capitalists did this only in order to be able to exploit the workers better, but the historical<br />

gift which they unwittingly made is the enormous jump <strong>of</strong> productivity when individual<br />

production was replaced by massively co-operative production.<br />

What I just wrote is spelled out in various places in Capital, see e.g. 453:1, 775:1/o.<br />

Again we see that it was not happiness but the coercion associated with capitalist exploitation<br />

that lead to more wealth. Marx recognizes this as the historical mission <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

He thinks capitalism is a phase humankind had to go through in order to develop labor<br />

productivity, but it has long outlived its usefulness and must be replaced now by a more<br />

participatory economic system.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [15].<br />

[13] CousinIt: Occupational Psychosis. In [5], Hans asks the interesting question “why<br />

is it not obvious to everybody” that the question about happiness being the only true wealth


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 5<br />

is about a “nonsensical statement.” I agree that this is the more important question. As Hans<br />

points out, the cultural tactic or strategy (conscious or otherwise) underlying notions that we<br />

can be happy even when denied some kind <strong>of</strong> equity <strong>of</strong> collective wealth at the level <strong>of</strong> the<br />

individual amounts to what Veblen called a “trained incapacity” (this is referred to in Keneth<br />

Burke’s Permanence and Change). That is, we are acculturated to accept exploitation as a<br />

necessary condition <strong>of</strong> life, a veritable “law <strong>of</strong> nature,” and this, given that we are even able to<br />

recognize exploitation when we see it, at all! We aren’t capable <strong>of</strong> seeing or evaluating even<br />

our own material relations. We are also acculturated to not even notice or acknowledge the<br />

exploitation inherent in the capitalist system, or to downplay the negative effects that such<br />

exploitation has on the lives <strong>of</strong> individuals, including our own lives in this world. There<br />

is a strong connection to this conditioned ignorance <strong>of</strong> exploitation and a notion that one’s<br />

rewards for labors in this life will be gained in some life yet to come or by means other<br />

than material means. These are, in turn, connected to notions that poor people who do not<br />

enjoy the wealth that others do in capitalist society are somehow nonetheless capable <strong>of</strong> a<br />

“greater happiness” in their poverty; a “happiness” that, interestingly enough in the folklore<br />

<strong>of</strong> our time even emerges as a characteristic property <strong>of</strong> poverty in itself! Yet, by the same<br />

token, in this country, if one were able to objectively observe common behavior without<br />

such a debilitating bias that makes everything ‘appear’ OK, one might come away with the<br />

impression that we, the American citizenry, think that the proper response to any crisis,<br />

personal or collective, is to immediately go shopping, as President Bush suggested we do<br />

immediately after September 11, 2001. To me, in my own ‘sick’ ‘pinko-commie’ mind,<br />

this conditioned ignorance and response to the material conditions <strong>of</strong> our lives as a whole<br />

is not less than massively absurd and akin to denying that human activity has effects on the<br />

biosphere, such as denying the human factor in ‘global warming.’ Some <strong>of</strong> us probably even<br />

think that slavery is a thing <strong>of</strong> the past that we have effectively eradicated.<br />

In [4], Litsyemir suggests, in reference to [3] that we have the same (or similar) conditions<br />

<strong>of</strong> selective blindness here (in the U.S.? we should for clarity’s sake, state exactly what,<br />

where, or how when making such blanket statements) in that there is a systematic indoctrination<br />

that creates a blindness in regard to exploitation. Litsyemir suggests that “capitalism<br />

has become consumption.” In fact, the situation is much much worse than Litsyemir intuits.<br />

Some folks go so far as to suggest that capitalism and democracy are the same thing, if not<br />

necessarily connected. What is ignored in such a conception <strong>of</strong> democracy as ‘freemarket’<br />

capitalism is that in a truly democratic society the citizens could vote even on what kind <strong>of</strong><br />

economic system or currency is to be used in that society. By some accounts, capitalism,<br />

which creates great disparities <strong>of</strong> wealth amongst its participants giving rise to stratified<br />

socio-economic classes, is completely and diametrically the exact antithesis to democracy.<br />

By this account democracy is a sham amongst a society <strong>of</strong> participants who do not enjoy<br />

and wield a rough equality <strong>of</strong> material wealth as individuals. This is not something you will<br />

be able to find anywhere in the popular illiterature. They didn’t teach this to us in school.<br />

In both cases, the situation is one that is not just an inaccuracy <strong>of</strong> apprehension or efficiency<br />

<strong>of</strong> indoctrination, but rather an actual illness that amounts to a wasting-away <strong>of</strong> the<br />

human species potential as a result <strong>of</strong> a mental / socio-economic / emotional / biological<br />

infirmity that ends up having very real material and biological effects on the body <strong>of</strong> the<br />

human animal as a whole, if not on the biosphere. Burke (mentioned earlier) has an entire


6 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

chapter (taking from John Dewey, a famous American philosopher <strong>of</strong> the pragmatist school)<br />

on what he refers to as “occupational psychosis.” Basically, every society has a principal<br />

mode <strong>of</strong> production which ends up dictating the worldview necessary to promote and perpetuate<br />

that very modal productivity. Worldviews are very very all-encompassing, relatively<br />

rigid, and exclusive. Anything coming from outside <strong>of</strong> the popular worldview is essentially,<br />

from inside <strong>of</strong> that worldview, unthinkable.<br />

Following Burke, a person’s or a society’s interests (e.g., one’s “best interests”) must<br />

be differentiated from a person’s or a society’s interest in a topic or along an articulated<br />

continuum <strong>of</strong> ideas, activities, beliefs, values, etc. (though surely we can see how these<br />

are always everywhere immanently in positive or negative relationship). People will pay<br />

attention to what interests them, which may or may not be what is in their ‘best’ interest.<br />

Burke claims that greatest attention is paid to those things that play to what we are interested<br />

in, all else being pushed to the periphery or the ‘back burner’ on the range <strong>of</strong> salient issues<br />

and concerns. Clearly, upon reflection and perhaps upon hindsight, we see the difference<br />

between that which we are interested in and that which it is in our “best interest” to think,<br />

say, do, etc. Burke uses the example <strong>of</strong> the laborer, who is not necessarily interested in<br />

proletariat literature, though such literature might nonetheless have as its subject the best<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> the worker (37-38). We naturally pay attention to the things that interest us in<br />

the communications <strong>of</strong> others, in the sense that it is <strong>of</strong>ten said that one ‘hears what one wants<br />

to hear,’ <strong>of</strong>ten despite the nature <strong>of</strong> our ‘best interests’ or that which we ‘ought to’ hear.<br />

In a hunting society, because the means <strong>of</strong> survival is organized around the hunt, all other<br />

ideological elements and practices take on the imaginative characteristics <strong>of</strong> the hunt as<br />

general cultural template. In terms <strong>of</strong> human relationships, women are stalked and hunted;<br />

...a tribe which lives by the hunt may be expected to reveal a corresponding<br />

hunt pattern in its marriage rites, where the relation between man and<br />

woman may show a marked similarity to the relationship between huntsman<br />

and quarry. The woman will be ritually seized. Also, the highly problematical<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> hunting, its continual stressing <strong>of</strong> the sudden, or unexpected,<br />

might instigate a cultural emphasis upon the new (39).<br />

In a capitalist techno-consumerism, because all things are operationalized and determined<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> progress as well as debit or credit, human relationships also reflect the characteristics<br />

<strong>of</strong> the dominant method <strong>of</strong> survival (or mode <strong>of</strong> production). In the current capitalistconsumerist<br />

psychosis, apprehended as it is in a psychoanalytic (that congruent with everyday<br />

systems <strong>of</strong> patriarchal authoritarianism, reduces emotional and mental life by analysis to<br />

the oedipal) personalities, practices and behaviors are leveled-out and captured by a system<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities, exchange, and institutionalization as ‘public mental health.’ Commodified<br />

human relations are bought and sold according to legal and economic enablements and<br />

constraints.<br />

Burke’s contention is that even our own society is subsumed by a psychotic split with the<br />

actual conditions <strong>of</strong> our own existence. We thus fall prey to a view <strong>of</strong> the world and our<br />

place in it that ultimately ‘cannot see’ the truth. This ultimately amounts to an illusion or


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 7<br />

hallucination <strong>of</strong> psychotic proportions. For Burke, societies, like individuals, suffer from<br />

pathological dis-ease.<br />

Reference<br />

Burke, K. (1984). Permanence and Change: An Anatomy <strong>of</strong> Purpose. Berkeley: <strong>University</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> California Press.<br />

Message [13] referenced by [14], [15], and [686]. Next Message by CousinIt is [27].<br />

[14] Lev: Occupational Psychosis. I am interested in CousinIt’s contribution [13] as<br />

it takes a very different angle to that I have been considering in Hans’ [5] statement about<br />

“nonsense”. CousinIt discussion is primarily on the distortion <strong>of</strong> consciousness due to class<br />

and especially the need to transcend these contextual biases (they are rationally available and<br />

therefore can be transcended). On that point I delight in pointing out that Ricardo famously<br />

said that the interests <strong>of</strong> the landlord class are opposed to the interests <strong>of</strong> all other classes.<br />

For my part, I would like to look at the the pragmatics <strong>of</strong> the “nonsensical question”, “Can<br />

one say that happiness is the only true wealth?” is, in my opinion, more complex than Hans<br />

is giving it credit for. To be sure, if one phrases it as “Wealth is an input into the process <strong>of</strong><br />

living, while happiness is an output from the process <strong>of</strong> living”, yes, then it makes sense to<br />

write it <strong>of</strong>f as being pragmatically nonsense (as per the comment “laughter is the only kind<br />

<strong>of</strong> joke”). However, such claims <strong>of</strong> nonsense is dependent on whether happiness is only an<br />

output and wealth is only an input.<br />

As has been previously referenced, the Hellenes considered happiness to be an output<br />

based on intention, that is, happiness is generated from morally good intentions. One can<br />

certainly posit a situation where regardless <strong>of</strong> the outcome <strong>of</strong> their actions, a person with<br />

such an intent remains happy because they know that they acted righteously. Also previously<br />

referenced is a fairly hefty study which argues that some 50% is “set-point” (largely<br />

genetically derived), some 40% is intentions and a mere 10% is circumstances (p116). Now I<br />

personally think that the particular study is significantly prone to selection bias, but that does<br />

not change the fact that both genetics and intentions are a component to where happiness is<br />

described as an input to the process <strong>of</strong> living, rather than an output.<br />

Conversely, it is arguable whether ‘wealth’ is just an input to the processes <strong>of</strong> living.<br />

Whilst wealth has come to mean an accumulation <strong>of</strong> economic value, in a more general<br />

sense it means a measure <strong>of</strong> any resource, to which ‘rich’ and ‘poor’ can be relative markers<br />

<strong>of</strong> whatever resource is being measured. Now are these resources an input or an output <strong>of</strong><br />

the processes <strong>of</strong> living? It is quite arguable that they are both, as an input derived from both<br />

nature (e.g., richness in strength), social relations (e.g., richness in inherited ownership <strong>of</strong><br />

land, capital), and as an output in the manner described by Marx in the transformation from<br />

simple commodity production to capitalist commodity production.<br />

Apropos to my previous post, I would further argue that the happiness/wealth comparison<br />

has much to do with contextual conditions. I seriously doubt, regardless <strong>of</strong> genetics or<br />

intention, whether happiness is plausible for those who are in a state <strong>of</strong> perpetual hunger.<br />

Likewise, I cannot imagine a person deriving happiness from labouring in such a such an<br />

economy even in the most non-exploitative social arrangements; in the apocryphal words<br />

<strong>of</strong> Chief Seattle, it is not existence but survival. It is indeed notable that the landlord and


8 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

capitalist classes threaten the working and renting classes with precisely this sort <strong>of</strong> rental or<br />

wage regime, which accords with David Ricardo’s twin laws (The Law <strong>of</strong> Rent, The “Iron<br />

Law” <strong>of</strong> Wages) and this does raise the point that in some economic states, it is quite possible<br />

for the threat <strong>of</strong> ‘remorseless labour’ has been surpassed in economic conditions but due to<br />

exploitative social relations it still exists for the exploited.<br />

In summary, genetic and intentional happiness is only possible in economic conditions<br />

where necessities can be satisfied. This possibility <strong>of</strong> happiness as an input only becomes<br />

a reality depending on the degree <strong>of</strong> exploitation in social relations. Once this point is<br />

reached however happiness can be both an input (genetics, intentions) and an output (further<br />

accumulation <strong>of</strong> utilitarian wealth). Happiness and wealth are both inputs and outputs and<br />

their interaction is modified by concrete circumstances.<br />

Message [14] referenced by [15]. Next Message by Lev is [24].<br />

[15] Hans: How to Investigate a Totality. The discussion about this question was never<br />

as pr<strong>of</strong>ound as this year. CousinIt’s [13] and Lev’s [7] and [14] are extremely rich, much<br />

better than what I could have produced myself. Thank you for your contributions.<br />

Lev [7] finds my explanation in [5] simplistic. About this I’d like to say something. We<br />

are looking at a society. This is a totality, i.e., a system in which everything depends on<br />

everything. Where do you begin when you try to study a totality? You just have to make<br />

some simplifications. Therefore your argument can never have the force <strong>of</strong> a mathematical<br />

pro<strong>of</strong>. But I think my explanation gives me a framework which enables me to make sense <strong>of</strong><br />

a good portion <strong>of</strong> the answers to this question in the archives. Even better evidence would be<br />

to ask the writers <strong>of</strong> these answers whether my feedback based on my theory is convincing<br />

to them – but most <strong>of</strong> these writers are no longer available. This too, <strong>of</strong> course, is not an<br />

exact criterion. Maybe the best evidence would be whether my intervention based on this<br />

paradigm would enable them to make changes in society for the better. What I am trying to<br />

say is: there are criteria how to evaluate a theory, but they are not exact criteria.<br />

But we are under a time constraint here. Our philosophical discussion about wealth and<br />

happiness should not keep us from reading Capital. Does my interpretation <strong>of</strong> Marx in the<br />

currently assigned readings, see [12], make sense to you? We should turn our collective<br />

attention to the way how Marx argues that value comes from labor.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [18].<br />

Exam Question 32 is 25 in 2002fa, 28 in 2004fa, 33 in 2007SP, 32 in 2007fa, 32 in<br />

2008fa, 35 in 2011fa, and 32 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam Question 32 Does the use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity depend on the person using it?<br />

[229] Scott: Use-value does not depend on the individual. What is a use-value? The<br />

usefulness <strong>of</strong> a commodity for human life makes it a use-value.<br />

The use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity does not depend on the individual but on whether it satisfies<br />

a human need or want. For example a car is going to be a use value for me because it<br />

fulfills one <strong>of</strong> my human needs, but it’s not going to be a use value for my friend who is in a<br />

wheel chair and cannot drive. The use-value <strong>of</strong> a thing is therefore not one <strong>of</strong> the properties<br />

<strong>of</strong> the thing, but the relationship between these properties and human needs or wants that is<br />

attributed to the thing as if it was a property <strong>of</strong> the thing.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 9<br />

Hans: I edited your original submission to make your answer more precise.<br />

(a) Wherever you had originally written “commodity” I replaced it by “thing.” Something does not have to be a<br />

commodity (i.e., produced for sale) in order to be a use-value.<br />

(b) Your last sentence was originally: “The use value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is not a property <strong>of</strong> a thing, but the<br />

relationship between the thing and human needs and wants.” This is almost a literal quote from the beginning <strong>of</strong> a<br />

sentence in the Annotations, but the beginning <strong>of</strong> the sentence alone, without the end, does not make much sense.<br />

I replaced it by the entire sentence from the Annotations (in fact, I edited my own sentence in the Annotations too,<br />

so you see here the version in the next edition <strong>of</strong> the Annotations).<br />

Next Message by Scott is [325].<br />

[231] Hans: Use-value versus neoclassical utility. My [2004fa:174] is “the” right answer<br />

to this question. Here it is again, for your convenience:<br />

No, it doesn’t. A thing has use-value if its properties are such that they<br />

are useful to humans. If Marx says that every commodity, in order to be<br />

exchangeable, must have use-value, he is thinking that it must be in principle<br />

usable, not that every single person will want to use it. If the question<br />

arises whether something is useful for a specific person, Marx uses the idiom<br />

“use-value for” that person, for instance he says that the commodity<br />

has no use-value for its producer. But without this “for,” use-values are<br />

independent <strong>of</strong> the individuals using the product.<br />

This is all you have to say in the exam, but let me give you a little background. This<br />

is a designated exam question because it highlights the difference between the classical<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> use-value and the neoclassical concept <strong>of</strong> utility. Utility is something subjective;<br />

it is the satisfaction which people derive from using a good. Use-value, by contrast, is<br />

objective; think <strong>of</strong> it as the physical properties <strong>of</strong> the good which make it useful for humans,<br />

or the menu <strong>of</strong> all possible uses <strong>of</strong> a thing. As I tried to explain in the Annotations in my<br />

comments to the first sentence <strong>of</strong> 126:1, the usefulness <strong>of</strong> a thing is a relative concept. It<br />

cannot be located in the thing alone, and also not in humans alone. The concept “use-value”<br />

attributes it to the thing, while the concept “utility” attributes it to the humans.<br />

By the way, despite the automatic message that this is an ungraded exam question, when<br />

answered during the extra credit period, these exam questions will be graded. But the extra<br />

credit period is almost over. It ends at 10:45 today (Sunday), which is 24 hours before<br />

tomorrow’s exam.<br />

Message [231] referenced by [256], [279], and [385]. Next Message by Hans is [256].<br />

Question 34 is 27 in 1995ut, 29 in 2003fa, 31 in 2005fa, 35 in 2007SP, and 34 in 2008fa:<br />

Question 34 Can you think <strong>of</strong> an example in which the quantity <strong>of</strong> something affects its<br />

quality, for instance some physical matter two litres <strong>of</strong> which are qualitatively different than<br />

one litre <strong>of</strong> it?<br />

[24] Lev: Quantity and Quality – and Crisis. The question <strong>of</strong> quantitative change effecting<br />

quality is a reasonably well-known matter <strong>of</strong> philosophical import and initially given<br />

its strong elucidation in Hegel’s “Science <strong>of</strong> Logic” (as referenced by Hans, [2007SP:2]).<br />

It is interesting that Hegel uses his particular definition <strong>of</strong> quality to illustrate evolution and


10 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

development through contradiction and negations, thereby becoming more fully “real” in the<br />

process and ultimately, in Hegelian metaphysics, the Spirit going beyond Nature.<br />

(“finitude is only as a transcending <strong>of</strong> itself”).<br />

It is perhaps not surprising that there are several well-known examples <strong>of</strong> quantitative<br />

change leading to qualitative change, starting from the most elementary to those which are<br />

most surprising and indeed counter-intuitive. Rollingrock [1995ut:6] suggests the application<br />

<strong>of</strong> heat to water as a very well-known example whereby at the critical quantitative<br />

temperatures <strong>of</strong> 0 and 100 degrees Celsius pure water at 1.0 Atm and 1.0G shall change in<br />

phase from solid, to liquid, to gas. I will raise the question however if this phase-shift, which<br />

can be understood as the form <strong>of</strong> the particle in different densities (solid the most dense, gas<br />

the least), actually represents a qualitative change.<br />

On the more counter-intuitive level, the behaviour <strong>of</strong> the Helium-3 isotope is an example<br />

<strong>of</strong> a particle decay (quantitative value) and extremely low temperatures where the Pauli<br />

Exclusion Principle is violated and the particle becomes superfluid.<br />

Multiple superfluid helium-4 particles coexist with the same quantum state. Likewise I<br />

would also like to raise the progress <strong>of</strong> logic systems where Godel’s incompleteness theorem<br />

(1931) which shows that no sufficiently strong formal system can prove its own consistency<br />

(i.e., at a certain level, a logic system can be either complete or consistent, but not both).<br />

Bresid [2003fa:2] provides an interesting example <strong>of</strong> the physiological biosystem and the<br />

interaction with anesthetics, in particular is<strong>of</strong>lurane, where a quantitative value can transform<br />

from the substance being an anesthetic to being an euthanasia agent. Hans responds<br />

[2003fa:3], quite appropriately, that the qualitative difference between an anesthetic agent<br />

and a euthanasia agent is quite moot: “Is it merely the same quality with different effects?”<br />

A matter which I find particularly interesting in the Bresid example is a closely related<br />

subject <strong>of</strong> crisis. Pithily elaborated in the opening pages <strong>of</strong> the now classic text <strong>of</strong> social theory<br />

“Legitimation Crisis” (Jurgen Habermas, Legitimationsprobleme im Spaetkapitalismus,<br />

1973). In medicine it represents a point where, regardless <strong>of</strong> individual will, the physiological<br />

system <strong>of</strong> an individual is tested to capacity in its ability to heal. In the environment,<br />

or social systems, it is also sensible to speak <strong>of</strong> crises, points in time and place where the<br />

capacity <strong>of</strong> the system is faced with a “life or death” test in its abilities to continue. In contemporary<br />

environmentalism it is typical to speak <strong>of</strong> a quantitative increase in temperature<br />

leading to a “tipping point” (between 2 and 3 degrees) where the qualitative effects are pr<strong>of</strong>oundly<br />

destructive. I am even prepared to go a bit out an a limb and refer to a crisis in<br />

literature, the point <strong>of</strong> the narrative where the protagonist, with the prior accumulation <strong>of</strong><br />

a quantity <strong>of</strong> aesthetic plot moments, either successfully confronts their antagonist (be that<br />

the setting, circumstances or another character or, in the case <strong>of</strong> tragedy, confronts their own<br />

weaknesses) as the climax <strong>of</strong> the story. Whilst on the aesthetic trajectory however, I will<br />

take the moment to strongly concur with Hans’ comment [2003fa:8] that Marx uses quality<br />

in the philosophical sense, meaning the properties belonging to the good itself, rather than<br />

the aesthetic judgment <strong>of</strong> subjective taste.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 11<br />

Where this comes into play is the relationship between quality and crisis. Hegel argues<br />

that there is a ‘right’ quantity <strong>of</strong> a thing, it’s “measure”, and then in a particular example<br />

[2007SP:1] and [2007SP:2] the measure <strong>of</strong> breast implants is normally two. If there is a<br />

right quantity, it also stand to reason that there is a wrong quantity and - in the case <strong>of</strong> crisis<br />

- a quantity that is so different that the existing state <strong>of</strong> affairs are no longer stable. It makes<br />

me question - in reference to previous comments about David Ricardo’s notorious “Iron Law<br />

<strong>of</strong> Wages” - that if there were an automated rather than punitive welfare system where, as<br />

per the discourse <strong>of</strong> radical Georgists, each individual received a portion <strong>of</strong> the site-value<br />

<strong>of</strong> all economic land, that whether the labour market would be so radically changed by this<br />

quantity <strong>of</strong> automatic income that there would be a qualitative difference in the class conflict<br />

between capitalists and workers*. I note Marx’s footnote to John Locke in the opening<br />

pages <strong>of</strong> capital in this regard: “The natural worth [value] <strong>of</strong> anything consists <strong>of</strong> its fitness<br />

to supply the necessities, or serve the conveniences <strong>of</strong> human life”.<br />

Finally, I would like to conclude on Hans’ comments in [2007fa:37]. It was a different<br />

question, relating to valid exchange values vs exchange values, but the issue <strong>of</strong> quality and<br />

quantity is raised there. Marx argues that valid exchange values <strong>of</strong> a commodity represent<br />

equal content in quality. This is raised as a counter to the use <strong>of</strong> exchange-values which<br />

are quantified (by the highly distorted relations in supply and demand), but never qualified.<br />

In doing so, it seems that neoclassical economics engaged in a mass deception to take out<br />

qualitative questions **, as they would frustratingly lead to the conclusion <strong>of</strong> the primacy <strong>of</strong><br />

labour in value determination, along (if I may reference the Georgists twice) the commonality<br />

<strong>of</strong> economic land. As such qualitative questions had to be screened out <strong>of</strong> discussion,<br />

least the lead to political unpleasant consequences. “Political Economy”, the most important<br />

moral and scientific study <strong>of</strong> the 18th and 19th century, became merely “Economics”,<br />

heralding the era <strong>of</strong> the “dismal science”. That, in itself, is arguably a qualitative change<br />

brought on by the sheer weight <strong>of</strong> arguments elucidating class exploitation.<br />

* I have written on this relationship in the past and how the operation <strong>of</strong> the labour market<br />

are vastly different from the idealised “free choice” suggested by neoclassical apologists:<br />

“Working for Welfare in the Antipodes: An Incarnation <strong>of</strong> Wage-Slavery”<br />

http://bad.eserver.org/issues/2004/69/lafayette.html<br />

** William Stanley Jevons excluded; he considered the marginal analysis as complementary<br />

rather than exclusive or as a replacement to the labour theory <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Message [24] referenced by [2008fa:20]. Next Message by Lev is [72].<br />

Question 35 is 20 in 1995WI, 35 in 2008fa, and 37 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 35 Bring other examples <strong>of</strong> relative “properties” such as beauty or use-value.<br />

[6] Litsyemir: My Neighbor Bought a Boat. My neighbor’s house is bigger than mine.<br />

He purchased additional commodities (in the form <strong>of</strong> upgrades), which I did not. These<br />

commodities make his house more “comfortable” for him. Comfort is not a property <strong>of</strong><br />

the home, but relative to my neighbor and his “need” to have a certain comfort level. The<br />

commodities he purchased - upgraded cabinetry, tile flooring, wrought iron railing, etc - all<br />

add to his level <strong>of</strong> comfort, a relative property <strong>of</strong> the commodities.


12 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

The same neighbor also bought a boat. 35 footer. With flames painted on the side to make<br />

it look faster. It’s the only one on the street. To tow his boat, he purchased a nice, new, top <strong>of</strong><br />

the line truck. He immaculately cares for his boat and his truck. The slightest speck <strong>of</strong> dust<br />

is swept away or wiped <strong>of</strong>f as quickly as possible. These commodities give him “prestige”.<br />

Again, prestige is only a relative property he attaches to the commodities.<br />

I try to use a day planner to keep track <strong>of</strong> my work, schooling and family life. My planner<br />

helps me feel “organized”. Of course, being organized is a relative property unique to me<br />

and my use <strong>of</strong> the day planner. To anyone, it might mean something entirely different.<br />

These are just a few <strong>of</strong> the examples I came up with for other relative “properties”. And<br />

yes, my neighbor does have a bigger house than I do. But he doesn’t have the boat or the<br />

truck. I kind <strong>of</strong> wish I did. Just for the opportunity to “be a man.”<br />

Hans: I don’t quite get it why you said “he doesn’t have the boat or the truck.” I thought earlier you said he did.<br />

Regarding your first example: Comfort meets the human needs for a relaxing and protected home environment.<br />

The “need to have a certain comfort level” is a derivative need created in a society in which neighbors vie for social<br />

status.<br />

Litsyemir: In response to your question Hans, I was using the purchase <strong>of</strong> a boat and truck as an example to<br />

illustrate the point. I should have been clearer about that. My apologies.<br />

First Message by Litsyemir is [4].<br />

Multiple Choice Question 46 is 599 in 2000fa and 36 in 2001fa:<br />

Multiple Choice Question 46 Which <strong>of</strong> the following is closest to Marx’s theory:<br />

(a) The use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is the utility one gets from using it; the exchange-value is<br />

the utility one gets from using those things one can trade the commodity for.<br />

(b) Use-value is the quality <strong>of</strong> the commodity, and exchange-value is its quantity.<br />

(c) Use-value is the use a commodity has to its owner, exchange-value is the use a commodity<br />

has to others.<br />

(d) Just as a painter needs a canvas as a carrier on which he can paint his painting, the<br />

capitalist needs a use-value as a carrier for the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> the products his workers<br />

have produced.<br />

[256] Hans: Exchange-value a passenger <strong>of</strong> use-value. This was one <strong>of</strong> the multiple<br />

choice questions on Monday.<br />

(a) turns both use-value and exchange-value into human attributes, while Marx looks at<br />

them as the social properties <strong>of</strong> the commodities themselves. See [231]. If you answered (a)<br />

you got partial credit.<br />

(b) Everything has a quality and a quantity, but not every use-value has an exchangevalue.<br />

Use-value and exchange-value are not two sides <strong>of</strong> the same thing. This answer is<br />

wrong because it takes a too harmonious view <strong>of</strong> our social relations. You should think <strong>of</strong><br />

use-value and exchange-value as two strangers locked into the same room. Before long they<br />

will begin fighting.<br />

(c) is wrong too. It turns exchange-value into a simple everyday human emotion, and<br />

ignores the social structures which must be in place for an economy to be an exchangeeconomy<br />

(private property laws etc.). If I desire my neighbor’s wife, this does not magically<br />

make her exchangeable. The same is true if I desire his motorcycle.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 13<br />

(d) is closest to Marx’s theory. It shows the distance between use-value and exchangevalue<br />

despite the fact that a commodity has to have a use-value in order to have an exchangevalue.<br />

Message [256] referenced by [2009fa:8]. Next Message by Hans is [268].<br />

Question 61 is 61 in 2008fa and 64 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 61 Marx discusses at length the question whether value is intrinsic to the commodity<br />

or relative. What is the view <strong>of</strong> neoclassical economics? Does it consider value to<br />

be intrinsic or relative?<br />

[16] Jenn: (content A form 95% weight 50%) Marx discusses whether values are intrinsic<br />

or relative at length. Neoclassical economics considers value to be based on an equilibrium<br />

<strong>of</strong> cost in dollars <strong>of</strong> supply and perceived or observed demand. Although I believe this<br />

way <strong>of</strong> thought takes relative value into account somewhat by using demand, it does place<br />

more <strong>of</strong> an intrinsic value on products. This intrinsic value is a result <strong>of</strong> the emphasis placed<br />

on supply costs, in dollars.<br />

Message [16] referenced by [18] and [2008fa:42]. Next Message by Jenn is [61].<br />

[18] Hans: Does Neoclassical Theory Really Have a Subjective Concept <strong>of</strong> Value?<br />

Jenn says in [16] that neoclassical theory mainly uses an intrinsic concept <strong>of</strong> value (in cost<br />

accounting), although relative value is somewhat taken into account through demand.<br />

I agree but would put a different spin on it. If you read a neoclassical textbook, value<br />

is defined as a relative concept. The value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is measured by the marginal<br />

utility you receive from using the commodity. This means the value rests in how you see<br />

the commodity, not in the commodity itself. This is called the subjective concept <strong>of</strong> value,<br />

because value comes from the subject (the user <strong>of</strong> the commodity), not the commodity itself.<br />

But when a modern firm does its accounting, it doesn’t follow this textbook wisdom but<br />

uses an objective concept <strong>of</strong> value, which attaches the value to the commodities.<br />

The contradiction between intrinsic and relative value, which Marx discusses in the assigned<br />

readings, is therefore present in modern business and economic practice.<br />

To resolve this contradiction, Marx makes a couple <strong>of</strong> inferential steps which bring him to<br />

the conclusion: value is not created in commodity circulation but it is the surface reflection<br />

<strong>of</strong> something the commodities receive in production.<br />

The class materials discuss Marx’s steps in more detail, and I will give an overview tomorrow<br />

in class. Without getting into the details <strong>of</strong> Marx’s arguments right now, it is perhaps<br />

helpful to say that a look at modern cost accounting leads to the same conclusion. I.e., the<br />

conclusions which Marx’s Capital derives in a specific and not always easy to follow fashion<br />

can also be gained by different (but related) kinds <strong>of</strong> arguments. Here is this alternative<br />

argument:<br />

In the practice <strong>of</strong> cost accounting, the value <strong>of</strong> a product is determined by its cost. There<br />

are two things wrong with this:


14 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(a) This is a circular definition! The cost <strong>of</strong> a good is simply the value <strong>of</strong> those goods<br />

entering its production, i.e., if you define value by cost you define the value <strong>of</strong> one good by<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> other goods and still don’t know where any <strong>of</strong> these goods get their value from.<br />

(b) Usually, the value <strong>of</strong> a good is greater than its cost; again, this indicates that you<br />

cannot determine value by cost.<br />

These are enough contradictions to look for the source <strong>of</strong> value not in circulation at all<br />

but elsewhere (a logical candidate is production).<br />

Message [18] referenced by [21], [307], [2008fa:42], [2008fa:46], [2008fa:583], [2009fa:1023], [2010fa:23], and<br />

[2011fa:498]. Next Message by Hans is [20].<br />

[21] SnatchimusMaximus: (graded A) I have to say that neoclassical economics views<br />

value as relative. If value were intrinsic then prices would never fluctuate because a commodity’s<br />

value is ipso facto. Thus, if prices never fluctuate then markets can never adjust and<br />

the happy state <strong>of</strong> equilibrium would never be. Neoclassical economics argues that value is<br />

indeed relative because markets are interrelated. Thus a commodity may be relative as an<br />

inferior good or normal good, or as a substitute or complement. Neoclassical economics<br />

also gives us the production function that states firms will produce until AC=MC. Hence if<br />

a commodity’s supply is dictated by its costs and costs are relative to factors <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

then a commodity’s value is relative not only to other related goods (i.e. inferior goods,<br />

normal goods, complements, etc), but the commodity’s value is also relative to its factors <strong>of</strong><br />

production. It seems the only thing intrinsic about a commodity is its costs, and even those<br />

fluctuate in the long run.<br />

Hans: Good thinking. That fluctuations <strong>of</strong> prices are necessary for adjustment to equilibrium is also a point made<br />

by Marx in 195:2/o. About the relation between prices and costs see my [18].<br />

Message [21] referenced by [2008fa:583]. Next Message by SnatchimusMaximus is [161].<br />

[307] Paul: The neoclassical view <strong>of</strong> value is definitely relative. This is because prices are<br />

always fluctuating and if value was intrinsic this would not be possible. As a result <strong>of</strong> prices<br />

fluctuating, it gives markets a chance to adapt and conform so they are able to reach the equilibrium<br />

<strong>of</strong> the expenditure <strong>of</strong> supply and the apparent demand. Value is also relative for the<br />

fact that the consumer, in reality, decides the value <strong>of</strong> any given commodity. Hans [18] says<br />

that the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is measured by the marginal utility you receive from using the<br />

commodity. Therefore different people could believe that a commodity is worth an entirely<br />

different value. Take a blood sugar monitor, a diabetic would value this product extremely<br />

high while a non-diabetic has no need for this and would deem this product valueless. This<br />

demonstrates that the given value <strong>of</strong> a commodity can be biased and personal.<br />

Hans: Yes, in neoclassical (i.e., mainstream) theory, prices are derived from utility. There is not the strict separation<br />

which Marx makes between “value” and “use-value,” but the concept <strong>of</strong> utility could be considered their concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. This value is not intrinsic in the commodities but relative, since it depends on the usefulness <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity to its owner.<br />

Next Message by Paul is [313].<br />

[347] Bennett: The view <strong>of</strong> neoclassical economics is that <strong>of</strong> maximizing your utility,<br />

or simply the satisfaction that is associated with your consumption <strong>of</strong> goods and services.<br />

Another neoclassical view is that buyers look to increase their gains from purchasing goods,<br />

and they achieve this by increasing their purchases <strong>of</strong> products until their gain from another<br />

unit is balanced by what they have to sacrifice to obtain it. The neoclassical view on value is<br />

that value is relative to the value that the person purchasing the product or service gives it.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 15<br />

Next Message by Bennett is [348].<br />

[361] Ande: To me the view <strong>of</strong> neoclassical economics is that value is intrinsic to the<br />

commodity rather than relative. They view items to be intrinsic because there is really no<br />

such thing as a relative value <strong>of</strong> a commodity. Because <strong>of</strong> all the use values and exchange<br />

values there could never be a relative value <strong>of</strong> any certain commodity. You could not have a<br />

bag <strong>of</strong> rice that has a relative value to a can <strong>of</strong> soda. It does not work like that; value has to be<br />

intrinsic and the neoclassical economics portrays this same view. This is how I interpreted<br />

it through the many readings <strong>of</strong> Marx. With money, use value and exchange value there is<br />

no way a commodity can have a value that is relative, all the values <strong>of</strong> the commodities are<br />

intrinsic, I believe this and in reading all the articles I believe that this is the same view as a<br />

neoclassical economics.<br />

Hans: I am not sure you understand that “neoclassical” economics is the mainstream economics which explains<br />

prices by demand and supply, and demand by utility functions. The value theory implicit in mainstream economics<br />

is relative or non-intrinsic in two ways:<br />

(a) since value is marginal utility, it does not rest in the commodity but in the person using the commodity.<br />

(b) Neoclassical economics does not need absolute levels <strong>of</strong> utility but only relative levels, it needs to know<br />

whether A or B is preferred.<br />

Next Message by Ande is [362].<br />

[382] Allen: In neoclassical economics value is considered to be relative. Value is relative<br />

because commodities will change prices due to changes in the economy, such as stated<br />

by Marx in 126:2. The actual value <strong>of</strong> the item changes relative to proportions and also<br />

exchange-value <strong>of</strong> an item remains relative to the commodity and changes along with different<br />

circumstances.<br />

Hans: This is Marx’s argument why exchange-value does not seem to be intrinsic to the commodity. Neoclassical<br />

economics uses the entire apparatus <strong>of</strong> the utility function to explain exchange-values, and this is indeed a relative<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> value, since the utility function is anchored in the user <strong>of</strong> the commodity, not the commodity itself.<br />

Message [382] referenced by [529]. Next Message by Allen is [385].<br />

[529] Alcameron: The neo classical view <strong>of</strong> the exchange <strong>of</strong> a commodity is that its value<br />

is relative rather than intrinsic. The very nature <strong>of</strong> the term exchange value helps us realize<br />

that the value is subject to change based on the particular exchange. Depending on the time<br />

and place (which market) you are in your commodity could have a higher or lower exchange<br />

value. Another important factor is labor and how much is in that commodity. The exchange<br />

value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is directly related to the amount <strong>of</strong> labor in that commodity.<br />

Hans: As Allen in [382], you are not describing neoclassical, i.e., mainstream economics here but you give Marx’s<br />

arguments why value does not seem intrinsic. Then in your last two sentences you are switching abruptly to value<br />

determined by labor, which is something intrinsic.<br />

Next Message by Alcameron is [530].<br />

Question 62 is 36 in 1996ut, 33 in 1997ut, 65 in 2010fa, and 73 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 62 Formulate in your own words the two contradictory statements Marx makes<br />

about the commodity when he introduces exchange-value.<br />

[283] Bmellor: Contradictory statements about the commodity. We can look at the<br />

contradictions as follows: we are all familiar with the “relativity and variability <strong>of</strong> exchange<br />

proportions.” Meaning that at different times and different places commodities might be<br />

exchanged in extravagant proportions. But in other parts Marx introduces the manifestation<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchange-value as something anchored in the commodity, as a second property which


16 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

commodities have in addition to their use-values, this is an item we are familiarized with<br />

while reading Marx’s thoughts. These two items are contradictory.<br />

Next Message by Bmellor is [288].<br />

[302] Inter: Revisiting the exchange-value contradiction. The exchange-value contradiction,<br />

that Marx explores, seems to be a contradiction <strong>of</strong> terms. Namely, that on the<br />

one hand Marx explains that the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is determined from the<br />

relation it shares with another commodity. This relation is highly variable and based on<br />

circumstance. While on the other hand exchange-value is something that is inherent to the<br />

commodity. This is a contradiction because if exchange-value is inherent to the commodity<br />

then it stands to reason that it cannot be based on relations with other commodities.<br />

In my test response, I failed to adequately explain the contradiction, because I was focused<br />

on the relative nature <strong>of</strong> exchange-value that a commodity has. I did not fully develop<br />

the idea that exchange-value is inherent to the commodity, but rather developed the idea that<br />

use-value is inherent to the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Inter is [305].<br />

[306] Dentist: Exchange-value was at first introduced as a property that was actually<br />

possessed by and intrinsic to commodities. From this, the contradiction arises in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange-relations. Because how can a property be specific to each commodity, and yet at<br />

the same time be completely relative when compared with other commodities?<br />

By an analysis <strong>of</strong> the conflict that exchange-value is attached to the commodity and yet<br />

entirely relative, the solution comes to the surface that exchange-value is not the particular<br />

essence or substance within the commodity, but it is the expressor <strong>of</strong> that substance. It is<br />

therefore this expression that is relative and not the actual properties <strong>of</strong> the commodities<br />

themselves, and that this substance is something entirely different from “exchange-value.”<br />

Later we go on to learn that this substance (value) is ultimately determined by labor.<br />

Next Message by Dentist is [311].<br />

[320] Sparky: Marx’s contradictory statements about exchange value are-<br />

1. The exchange value is something that is attached, a part <strong>of</strong> a commodity’s use-value.<br />

Exchange proportions is not up to a stand-alone commodity, it is up to its relation to another<br />

commodity, which is affected by other, outside, circumstances, which can change with the<br />

weather.<br />

2. That the exchange value is not something that belongs to a inner necessity, as said in<br />

the annotations. It shows that the relation <strong>of</strong> the commodity compared to other commodites<br />

is the real selling price <strong>of</strong> the commodites.<br />

Next Message by Sparky is [467].<br />

[325] Scott: 2 contradictory statements. When Marx introduces the exchange value he<br />

contradicts himself. He first says an exchange value <strong>of</strong> a commodity has a worth inherent in<br />

a good. He later says that exchange value is determined by the circumstances outside the <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange value. Marx doesn’t say that these statements are either true or false, but he says<br />

there must be more to the problem than he sees. Hans [1997ut:13] wrote, “The contradictory<br />

evidence surrounding the exchange value is an indication that the exchange value reaches<br />

into the invisible core <strong>of</strong> the economy. Therefore we have to take a closer look, which<br />

probes beneath the surface.” Bobdog [2004fa:10] gave a great example comparing this to a


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 17<br />

man “standing inside a building who has trouble understanding what makes the trees sway<br />

back and forth.” Marx is the same way, he only sees what is happening on the surface but to<br />

come to any conclusion he is going to have to go beneath the surface.<br />

Next Message by Scott is [326].<br />

[374] Mitternacht: graded A Contradictory statements about exchange-value. In the<br />

section where Marx introduces exchange-value he quickly comes to a contradictory point.<br />

Which is his way <strong>of</strong> uncovering truths and for seeing things as they truly are.<br />

He shows that on the one hand the exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity appears to be something<br />

that is inherent to the commodity. Since a commodity may be exchanged at set amount<br />

for various other things in different measures it would appear that this exchange-value is<br />

inherent in the commodity itself.<br />

He also demonstrates that the exchange-value for a particular thing ends up being variable<br />

depending on other conditions which contradicts the first discovery that exchange-value<br />

appears to be inherent to the commodity.<br />

Upon looking more closely Marx finds that exchange-value is just an echo, or surface<br />

reflection <strong>of</strong> an immaterial value that lies within the commodity. The value is provided by<br />

labor in the production <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Mitternacht is [784].<br />

[379] Rey: graded A In forming statements regarding exchange value Marx seemingly<br />

forms a contradiction. In Marx’s earliest introduction <strong>of</strong> a commodity’s exchange value, he<br />

presents exchange value as being independently anchored within the commodity. In addition<br />

to the idea that exchange value is anchored within a commodity, Marx describes exchange<br />

value as a second property <strong>of</strong> a commodity. This second property is described by Hans on<br />

page 20 <strong>of</strong> his annotations as “a second property, which commodities have in addition to<br />

their use-values.” In this case the exchange value is only “expressed” in the actual exchange.<br />

Regardless <strong>of</strong> when or where the commodities are exchanged their values remain constant.<br />

In summarizing this approach, the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities only “expresses” their value<br />

rather than defines it. The other half <strong>of</strong> the contradiction comes as Marx discusses the effect<br />

that variables such as time and place, can have on the exchange value. The fact that exchange<br />

value is connected somehow to the actual exchange, suggests that exchange value is in fact<br />

not anchored within a commodity. Marx is appearing to state that a certain commodity has<br />

more or less value based on the time and place <strong>of</strong> an exchange. According to this thought<br />

the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities defines value rather than simply expressing it.<br />

Hans: You have to distinguish more explicitly between exchange value and value. The weakest point in your little<br />

essay is the sixth sentence where you without comment go from exchange-value over to value. Exchange-value is<br />

a surface category, value is a category <strong>of</strong> the underlying sphere <strong>of</strong> production. Exchange-value is the expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> the value. At the very beginning Marx only talks about exchange-value; he has not yet gotten to the point that<br />

exchange-value is remotely controlled, i.e., the expression <strong>of</strong> some aspect <strong>of</strong> social production. If you only look<br />

at exchange-value without knowing yet about value, then the contradiction is that exchange-value seems inherent<br />

in the commodity (because it is the expression <strong>of</strong> something inherent, namely, value), and exchange-value seems<br />

relative (because this expression is an expression in the surface exchange relations).<br />

In your in-class answer you have underlined seemingly in the first sentence. Marx would still call it a contradiction<br />

(not just a seeming contradiction), even if it can be explained. Marx thinks that reality is full <strong>of</strong> contradictions,<br />

and I think this is indeed a helpful way <strong>of</strong> looking at things.<br />

Next Message by Rey is [386].


18 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[405] Trailrunner: content A late penalty 1% Exchange-value is related to what society<br />

will exchange regarding one product for another - an equality <strong>of</strong> each commodity, regardless<br />

<strong>of</strong> its use value. This would be the relative or relational expression <strong>of</strong> the two commodities.<br />

But there is also the instrinsic expression <strong>of</strong> the commodity which takes us to looking at what<br />

the commodity really is. Thus, we would look at the commodity as an independent unit. We<br />

would recognize that the commodity can be exchanged for many other commodities and in<br />

many different proportions. This also looks at the labor that is involved in the production <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity.<br />

Therefore, exchange value is not only about what it can be exchanged for on the market,<br />

but for what it actually is and is made up <strong>of</strong>.<br />

Next Message by Trailrunner is [406].<br />

[590] Wade: The exchange value is decided by the formality <strong>of</strong> the exchange.<br />

A commodity’s importance is decided by the exchange-value.<br />

Next Message by Wade is [731].<br />

Question 64 is 63 in 2007fa, 64 in 2008fa, 66 in 2009fa, 67 in 2010fa, 61 in 2012fa, and<br />

67 in Answer:<br />

Question 64 The French economist Le Trosne wrote that the value <strong>of</strong> a thing consists in<br />

its exchange-proportions with other things. Does Marx agree with this, or how would he<br />

re-formulate this proposition to make it correct?<br />

[17] Chris: Le Trosne’s exchange value quote. It appears from select passages in Marx’s<br />

Capital Volume 1 that Marx does think that exchange value is determined by the other objects<br />

for which it would be exchanged. However, I do not believe that he would format this<br />

opinion like Le Trosne. Marx does suggest in Capital V. 1 on page 126 that “exchange-value<br />

appears first <strong>of</strong> all as a quantitative relation, the proportion, in which use-values <strong>of</strong> one kind<br />

exchange for use-values <strong>of</strong> another kind.” Therefore, Marx does appear to be insinuating<br />

that an object’s exchange value is determined by the item for which it would be exchanged.<br />

However, Marx also mentions the importance <strong>of</strong> an object’s use value. It is in the use value<br />

that I feel Marx would re-formulate Le Trosne’s proposition.<br />

Earlier, on the same page in Capital V.1 (pg. 126), Marx suggests that a use value is<br />

simply “the usefulness <strong>of</strong> a thing.” Therefore, I think it is important to bring up the notation<br />

that one person may value an item’s usefulness differently depending on each person’s<br />

own desire to need or want its usefulness. This notation would also correlate directly to an<br />

object’s exchange value. As Marx also suggests, “use-values are only realized in use or in<br />

consumption (pg. 126).” So, we must assume or hope that the person realizing the use-value<br />

will use all <strong>of</strong> its value, or use it to the point where the person is satisfied.<br />

After reading the passages on page 126 and 127 <strong>of</strong> Capital V.1, I would presume that<br />

Marx is suggesting that a thing’s exchange value is considered as well as its use value.<br />

Therefore, Le Trosne’s quote is partly correct in Marx’s mind. I would also like to mention<br />

that Marx would re-formulate his idea <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> a thing exactly as he does on page<br />

126 and 127 <strong>of</strong> Capital V.1. On these pages he goes into great detail to explain use-value<br />

and exchange value. He then presents a commodity exchange example to give life to his


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 19<br />

explanations. These two pages introduce an important idea <strong>of</strong> placing value on given objects<br />

and can be considered a re-formulation <strong>of</strong> Le Trosne’s respective quote.<br />

Hans: You are trying to read Marx closely, but you are still overlooking a couple <strong>of</strong> things:<br />

(a) Marx always develops his thoughts, and usually very slowly. He has a much longer breath than most modern<br />

readers. Therefore you cannot just pick out individual sentences and try to interpret them by themselves; they are<br />

usually part <strong>of</strong> a longer argument. I tried to give a bird’s eye view <strong>of</strong> this argument in [20].<br />

(b) You also have to read every single word. I would like to give two examples.<br />

(b1) If Marx says in 126:1 “The utility <strong>of</strong> a thing for human life makes it a use-value” then this is not the same<br />

as saying that use-value and usefulness are one and the same thing. By “use-value” Marx means those physical<br />

properties <strong>of</strong> the things which make it useful and/or desirable for humans, but unlike modern economists he is not<br />

thinking <strong>of</strong> the degree <strong>of</strong> satisfaction which humans might draw out <strong>of</strong> this.<br />

(b2) Let me premise my next example with the reminder that the word “value” for Marx always means “labor<br />

content.” If Marx says that value manifests itself at first as a quantitative exchange proportion between commodities,<br />

this is not the same as saying that the value is determined by this quantitative exchange proportion. Let me go<br />

through these two statements in turn.<br />

(b2A) As Marx sees it, commodities are exchangeable because they contain labor. I.e., that what determines the<br />

exchange proportions does not happen on the market but it happens in production. Marx would therefore say that<br />

the exchange-value is determined by labor content, not by the exchange proportions <strong>of</strong> a good with other goods.<br />

(b2B) Now if someone produces something that is needed by society, i.e., someone has spent his or her labor<br />

in a socially useful manner, then society rewards him for this by the fact that this good is exchangeable for other<br />

things which that producer might need. That is the meaning <strong>of</strong> the sentence that the value manifests itself as an<br />

exchange proportion.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [35].<br />

[20] Hans: Does Marx agree with Le Trosne? In 126:2, Marx writes:<br />

“Exchange-value manifests itself at first as the quantitative relation, the<br />

proportion, in which use-values <strong>of</strong> one sort are exchanged against usevalues<br />

<strong>of</strong> another sort ...”<br />

and in the footnote Marx quotes Le Trosne:<br />

“The value consists in the exchange proportion between one thing and another,<br />

between this amount <strong>of</strong> one product and that <strong>of</strong> another.”<br />

Since these two sentences sound so similar, question 64 asks whether Marx quotes Le<br />

Trosne because he agrees with him? The answer is no. Marx is critical <strong>of</strong> Le Trosne. He<br />

uses Le Trosne as an example for an analysis <strong>of</strong> value which gets stuck on the surface.<br />

Here are the details about this. The biggest difference between the Le Trosne quote and<br />

the Marx quote is: the Le Trosne quote is Le Trosne’s definition <strong>of</strong> value, while the Marx<br />

quote is only one step in a long and slow development in which Marx explores the question<br />

“what is it that makes commodities exchangeable?”<br />

Let’s look at this long and slow development first. Marx begins his study <strong>of</strong> capitalist<br />

society with the commodity. Each commodity has two aspects, use-value and exchangevalue.<br />

Marx briefly says a few things about use-value. But if we want to understand the<br />

economic structure <strong>of</strong> our society we must look at the exchange-value, i.e., that quality<br />

inside the commodities which makes them exchangeable.<br />

However just when Marx gets ready to explore that which makes things exchangeable,<br />

he is hit by a big Oops moment. Namely, Marx says: oops, maybe my search for something


20 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

inside the commodities which makes them exchangeable is misguided, since the exchange<br />

proportions between commodities are so relative and variable. How can something so relative<br />

and variable be generated by something inside the commodities? And he uses Le Trosne<br />

as his witness for this: Le Trosne was indeed saying that the value <strong>of</strong> a good consists in what<br />

other goods can be exchanged for it, i.e., it is something completely relative and not inherent<br />

in the commodity at all.<br />

Although Marx calls Le Trosne as a witness, he does not agree with him. Marx’s own<br />

resolution is the following: the exchange-value itself is not inherent in the commodities, but<br />

the exchange-value is the surface expression <strong>of</strong> something that is indeed inherent, namely,<br />

the social labor-time accumulated in the production <strong>of</strong> the commodity. This accumulated<br />

labor-time Marx calls “value” as opposed to “exchange-value”. Le Trosne only sees the surface<br />

relation and does not see the inherent property <strong>of</strong> the commodities, their labor content,<br />

<strong>of</strong> which this surface relation is the reflection.<br />

Message [20] referenced by [17], [22], [258], [376], [383], [628], [2009fa:365], [2010fa:26], and [2010fa:30]. Next<br />

Message by Hans is [23].<br />

[22] Goethe: As I understand [20], Marx is associating a “labor-time” value to a commodity;<br />

if this is true then the greater the labor involved in the production <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

the greater value it will possess. I would not agree with this! And I will give an example:<br />

If I were to spend a great amount <strong>of</strong> time and labor in the production <strong>of</strong> a commodity that<br />

is not in high demand, I will only receive what the market will allow. The variable is the<br />

market value. My question here is: How do market prices affect exchange value?<br />

This is not to say that Marx’s idea <strong>of</strong> labor value is not good in theory, but realistically<br />

in today’s economy it would be very difficult to place a value on a commodity based on the<br />

labor used to produce the commodity. This also brings efficiency into the equation. If a<br />

commodity is produced with the greatest efficiency, is the value affected?<br />

I could be completely <strong>of</strong>f on this as I am not sure if Marx is looking at value and exchange<br />

value in different terms.<br />

Message [22] referenced by [23]. Next Message by Goethe is [78].<br />

[23] Hans: Can the Labor Theory <strong>of</strong> Value Work? Just a brief response to Goethe’s<br />

[22]: Yes, Marx’s theory is the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value. According to it, long run prices are determined<br />

by the supply side, and quantities are determined by demand. I.e., if a commodity<br />

which takes a lot <strong>of</strong> labor fetches a low price, then less <strong>of</strong> this commodity will be produced,<br />

until the price rises to the level which is proportional to the labor content. This adjustment<br />

happens by producers switching their labor imput from those industries with relatively low<br />

prices per labor input to those with relatively high prices.<br />

Message [23] referenced by [345]. Next Message by Hans is [29].<br />

[258] Srichardson: graded A Marx does not agree with Le Trosne that the value <strong>of</strong> a<br />

thing consists in its exchange-proportion with other things. Le Trosne’s definition <strong>of</strong> value<br />

is different <strong>of</strong> that <strong>of</strong> Marx. Marx believes as Hans points out in [20] the exchange value<br />

itself is not inherent in the commodities, but the exchange value is the surface expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> something inherent, namely the social labor-time accumulated in the production <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity. Marx calls this value while Le Trosne expresses this as exchange value.<br />

Next Message by Srichardson is [259].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 21<br />

[278] Goethe: graded A Marx would not agree with Le Trosne when he writes that the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> a thing consists in its exchange-proportions with other things. Marx sees exchange<br />

value as the exterior expression <strong>of</strong> the labor used to produce the thing. Le Trosne only sees<br />

the exterior value as exchange-value; he does not see the interior value which is the labor<br />

content.<br />

Message [278] referenced by [2010fa:193]. Next Message by Goethe is [280].<br />

[286] Chris: value relations defined by Marx. Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> a thing is<br />

much more complex. He would not start out by saying that value only consists <strong>of</strong> exchangerelations<br />

<strong>of</strong> other things. He would first explain that for a thing to have value, it must have a<br />

use-value and an exchange-value. Marx does this quite literally by even titling his first essay<br />

on the subject, on page 125 <strong>of</strong> Capital, “The two factors <strong>of</strong> the commodity: use-value and<br />

value (substance <strong>of</strong> value, magnitude <strong>of</strong> value).” The use-value would be defined by what<br />

the commodity could be used for. On page 126, Marx’s exact words are “the usefulness <strong>of</strong> a<br />

thing makes it a use-value.”<br />

After explaining the use-value, it is then necessary to define what the exchange-value <strong>of</strong><br />

a thing is. This is where I have noticed the water getting a little muddy. The exchange-value<br />

is what people would be willing to exchange for that commodity and as Marx quotes on<br />

page 126,“exchange-value appears to be something accidental and purely relative.” He says<br />

relative in regard to how much the people doing the exchange need or want the thing.<br />

As I noted previously, I think that the water gets muddy when discussing the exchangerelations<br />

<strong>of</strong> things. This is where we find human-labor coming into contest. Human-labor,<br />

as discussed by Marx, begins as a social form. Different societies producing different commodities<br />

will then exchange their commodities dependent on current and future desires. In<br />

summary, I think that Marx would re-formulate Le Trosne’s quote, by saying that the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> a thing must have both use-value and exchange-value. He would then begin his dissertation<br />

<strong>of</strong> social human-labor like he does throughout Capital.<br />

Hans: The thing that’s missing in Trosne is not the use-value, but Trosne fails to distinguish between surface and<br />

depth relations. Trosne identifies value with exchange-value, while Marx says that commodities receive their value<br />

in production, and exchange-value is the surface manifestation <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [287].<br />

[311] Dentist: Marx definitely does not agree with Le Trosne in this instance. For Le<br />

Trosne, a commodity’s value has no direct relation to the commodity itself. Value is only<br />

relative between commodities; neither <strong>of</strong> them possesses any value independently from the<br />

other.<br />

This is in opposition to everything that we have read so far. So why then does Marx bring<br />

it up? I believe that it is largely due to Marx’s particular writing style and thought process.<br />

Marx is using this quote as if to answer a possible question that may come to a reader, and<br />

then refute it. As Marx is explaining these concepts we can imagine a reader asking himself,<br />

“how can some actual, measurable and definable property <strong>of</strong> a commodity be expressed so<br />

subjectively, and vary so widely?”<br />

Marx can see this question coming and uses Les Trosne to address it. He then in effect<br />

answers the potential question by criticizing Les Trosne’s statement. And here is how. Le<br />

Trosne believes that value does not exist within commodities as an actual property, but rather


22 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

value is relative to, and between commodities. His evidence for this is the apparently subjective<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> exchange-value. Marx however sees that this idea only planes the surface<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchange value and does not go deep enough to truly understand this property.<br />

According to Marx, value is possessed by the commodity, and originated from the social<br />

labor-time necessary to produce it. This value is real and something that is actually a part <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity, and is expressed outwardly as exchange-value. And rather than exchangevalues<br />

being seemingly random and subjective, they are actually manifestations <strong>of</strong> the labortime<br />

that was necessary for their production.<br />

Next Message by Dentist is [471].<br />

[332] Jenn: graded B Le Trosne test question. Marx partly agrees with Le Tronse’s<br />

statement, but would make one change to this phrase, shown in parentheses; “The (exchange)<br />

value <strong>of</strong> a thing consists in its exchange-proportions with other things.” As Hans cites in<br />

[2007fa:105], Le Trosne believes value is defined in the market, and Marx believes value is<br />

defined in the production process. Therefore, Marx would feel that Le Trosne is not looking<br />

at value in its entirety. Exchange-value does not come from the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

itself, but is an expression <strong>of</strong> value relative to other commodities. Marx explains that value<br />

can be reduced to one factor common to all commodities - abstract labor. Labor is required<br />

for the production <strong>of</strong> all commodities, and therefore is a logical choice for the assessment <strong>of</strong><br />

the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

Hans: Labor was not “chosen” by anyone to assess the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity; it is the spontaneous outcome <strong>of</strong> a<br />

market economy that prices are proportional to labor content. See [144].<br />

Next Message by Jenn is [343].<br />

[335] Oldgreg: graded C Marx would not agree with Le Trosne, but would reformulate<br />

the proposition to be correct. Le Trosne assertion is a practical viewpoint for traders but has<br />

no application <strong>of</strong> value for the use <strong>of</strong> a commodity. Marx would argue with the seemingly<br />

contradictory dual nature <strong>of</strong> a commodity having use-value and exchange-value. With Le<br />

Trosne’s position, it is impossible to know what value a commodity has without any comparisons<br />

to other commodities. Without an ultimate use there is little foundation <strong>of</strong> what<br />

purpose a commodity ultimately has. Marx’s position is ultimately superior in that a commodity<br />

can have value inherent.<br />

Hans: Marx’s value theory is not prescriptive. It is a serious error this far into the class to have this misunderstanding.<br />

Marx argues that the actual interaction between consumers and producers in the market leads to an outcome<br />

in which commodities are treated as globs <strong>of</strong> congealed human labor, i.e., as values. I.e., the market relation <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange-value reflects the hidden relations <strong>of</strong> production. See my [144] about the mechanics <strong>of</strong> this.<br />

Next Message by Oldgreg is [336].<br />

[339] Tim: graded B– Marx does not completely agree with the proposition because he<br />

argues that exchange-value can not be inherent in the commodity. In other words Barbon<br />

[Bar96, p.6] said that nothing can have intrensik value. I think that by this he means that<br />

exchange-values vary over time, and that depending on the time and place <strong>of</strong> the exchange<br />

a commodity can go up or down in value. A commodity does not have one set value but<br />

many values depending on the situation. For example, during a rain storm a person who<br />

does not want to get wet but does not have an umbrella would be willing to give up more for<br />

an umbrella than a person who does not mind getting wet or already had an umbrella. In the<br />

umbrella example the umbrella would have a higher exchange value for the man without an<br />

umbrella who did not want to get wet. A man who does not mind getting wet or one who is


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 23<br />

already equipped with an umbrella will not want to exchange much for an umbrella. Marx<br />

would agree that the exchange value has part to do with the commodity’s ability to be traded<br />

in proportion with another commodity but there is more to it than that.<br />

Hans: You didn’t notice that Marx argues against Barbon. If you want a good grade, don’t write “there is more to<br />

it than that” without elaboration.<br />

Next Message by Tim is [346].<br />

[340] Matt: No, Marx does not agree with Le Trosne, even though Marx does say in<br />

Capital that the “exchange-value manifests itself at first as the quantitative relation, the proportion,<br />

in which use-values <strong>of</strong> one kind exchange for the use-values <strong>of</strong> another kind.” This is<br />

a similar view to what Le Trosne says <strong>of</strong> how the exchange value manifests itself. However,<br />

Marx’s thought process goes a little deeper than just the surface value between commodities<br />

and their exchange-value that Le Trosne speaks <strong>of</strong>. Marx feels that Le Trosne is leaving out a<br />

very important part <strong>of</strong> the commodity by not including its “use-value”. The use-values Marx<br />

is referring to in a commodity are the actual physical properties that make them useful in the<br />

first place. It’s like saying, “I use a shovel because I can dig holes with it.” There is a usevalue<br />

to me within the commodity “shovel,” because <strong>of</strong> its physical properties only. Marx<br />

then goes on to say the commodity’s “labor time” equals its “value,” and not the “exchangevalue”.<br />

If a lot <strong>of</strong> time/labor was put into making a commodity then it will have a greater<br />

value within itself. Though the price it fetches on the market may not equal its labor value<br />

or “labor time” according to Marx’s theory. This is where Marx’s view point differs from Le<br />

Trosne.<br />

Hans: What Trosne leaves out is not the use-value but the value. Marx thinks that exchange proportions on the<br />

market are governed by labor content, i.e., they are the expression <strong>of</strong> something that originates in production, while<br />

Trosne thinks exchange-value is a pure surface category without roots in production.<br />

Marx allows for it that prices can deviate from values; but if they do, then he assumes that there are economic<br />

competitive mechanisms which drive prices towards values.<br />

Next Message by Matt is [341].<br />

[358] Raynold: http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch01.htm#S3c3<br />

Transition from the General form <strong>of</strong> value to the Money form<br />

The universal equivalent form is a form <strong>of</strong> value in general. It can, therefore, be assumed<br />

by any commodity. On the other hand, if a commodity be found to have assumed the universal<br />

equivalent form (form C), this is only because and in so far as it has been excluded from<br />

the rest <strong>of</strong> all other commodities as their equivalent, and that by their own act. And from<br />

the moment that this exclusion becomes finally restricted to one particular commodity, from<br />

that moment only, the general form <strong>of</strong> relative value <strong>of</strong> the world <strong>of</strong> commodities obtains<br />

real consistence and general social validity.<br />

The particular commodity, with whose bodily form the equivalent form is thus socially<br />

identified, now becomes the money commodity, or serves as money. It becomes the special<br />

social function <strong>of</strong> that commodity, and consequently its social monopoly, to play within the<br />

world <strong>of</strong> commodities the part <strong>of</strong> the universal equivalent. Amongst the commodities which,<br />

in form B, figure as particular equivalents <strong>of</strong> the linen, and, in form C, express in common<br />

their relative values in linen, this foremost place has been attained by one in particular –<br />

namely, gold. If, then, in form C we replace the linen by gold, we get,<br />

The Money-Form


24 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat = 10 lbs <strong>of</strong> tea = 40 lbs <strong>of</strong> c<strong>of</strong>fee = 1 quarter <strong>of</strong> corn = 2 ounces<br />

<strong>of</strong> gold = 1/2 a ton <strong>of</strong> iron = x Commodity A = = 2 ounces <strong>of</strong> gold<br />

In passing from form A to form B, and from the latter to form C, the changes are fundamental.<br />

On the other hand, there is no difference between forms C and D, except that, in<br />

the latter, gold has assumed the equivalent form in the place <strong>of</strong> linen. Gold is in form D,<br />

what linen was in form C – the universal equivalent. The progress consists in this alone,<br />

that the character <strong>of</strong> direct and universal exchangeability – in other words, that the universal<br />

equivalent form – has now, by social custom, become finally identified with the substance,<br />

gold.<br />

Gold is now money with reference to all other commodities only because it was previously,<br />

with reference to them, a simple commodity. Like all other commodities, it was also<br />

capable <strong>of</strong> serving as an equivalent, either as simple equivalent in isolated exchanges, or as<br />

particular equivalent by the side <strong>of</strong> others. Gradually it began to serve, within varying limits,<br />

as universal equivalent. So soon as it monopolises this position in the expression <strong>of</strong> value<br />

for the world <strong>of</strong> commodities, it becomes the money commodity, and then, and not till then,<br />

does form D become distinct from form C, and the general form <strong>of</strong> value become changed<br />

into the money form.<br />

The elementary expression <strong>of</strong> the relative value <strong>of</strong> a single commodity, such as linen, in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> the commodity, such as gold, that plays the part <strong>of</strong> money, is the price form <strong>of</strong> that<br />

commodity. The price form <strong>of</strong> the linen is therefore<br />

20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 2 ounces <strong>of</strong> gold, or, if 2 ounces <strong>of</strong> gold when coined are £2, 20 yards<br />

<strong>of</strong> linen = £2.<br />

The difficulty in forming a concept <strong>of</strong> the money form, consists in clearly comprehending<br />

the universal equivalent form, and as a necessary corollary, the general form <strong>of</strong> value, form<br />

C. The latter is deducible from form B, the expanded form <strong>of</strong> value, the essential component<br />

element <strong>of</strong> which, we saw, is form A, 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat or x commodity A = y<br />

commodity B. The simple commodity form is therefore the germ <strong>of</strong> the money form.<br />

Hans: Literal quotes from Marx are unacceptable as answers to these question, because I have no way <strong>of</strong> telling<br />

how much <strong>of</strong> this quote you understand. And I don’t see how this quote is relevant to the question about Le Trosne.<br />

Next Message by Raynold is [575].<br />

[359] Slash: Difference <strong>of</strong> opinion. Marx does not agree with everything Le Trosne says.<br />

Marx defines value as the labor in producing a product. Le Trosne sees value coming out <strong>of</strong><br />

the market, which does not reflect labor in a way Marx sees things. Since Marx understands<br />

value to be the labor put into a product I should not have said in my in-class essay that<br />

Marx agrees with Le Trosne. I was confused in thinking that Le Trosne found value to be<br />

a measure <strong>of</strong> labor as Marx does, but I have now learned that they differ on principle. Le<br />

Trosne finds value in the market, where Marx find value in labor, or production. If Marx<br />

and Le Trosne where to discus the question <strong>of</strong> 20 feet <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat. Le Trosne would<br />

say that 20 feet <strong>of</strong> linen could produce a coat giving that linen value in producing use-value<br />

in the form <strong>of</strong> warmth in a coat. Marx on the other hand argues that 20 feet <strong>of</strong> linen is<br />

equal to 1 coat in means <strong>of</strong> labor, or that the process <strong>of</strong> making 20 feet <strong>of</strong> linen is equal to<br />

making 1 coat. This <strong>of</strong> course is assuming that the producer <strong>of</strong> both the linen and the coat<br />

is making this good for the propose <strong>of</strong> trade, otherwise if one kept the product it would not


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 25<br />

be a commodity and would therefore have no value. If Marx was to rephrase Le Trosne’s<br />

statement he would say something like: the value <strong>of</strong> a thing makes it exchangeable.<br />

Hans: It is not a different value judgment (way <strong>of</strong> “seeing things”) but a different theory how market prices are<br />

determined. Le Trosne says they are determined in the market, and Marx says they are ultimately determined in<br />

production.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [360].<br />

[370] Samantha: Labor is the intrinsic value <strong>of</strong> a thing. Marx would disagree with<br />

this statement, as he believes value to be intrinsic to the good because <strong>of</strong> the labor that<br />

produced the good while Le Trosne considers value to be from the exchange-proportion.<br />

This is a fundamental difference, while Marx recognizes that there is a slight relationship<br />

between exchange-proportions and value, the relationship is based not on labor but on the<br />

bourgeois determination <strong>of</strong> price. The price <strong>of</strong> a good and therefore its value (from the<br />

bourgeois perspective) is derived from the exchange-proportion and the cost <strong>of</strong> labor, but<br />

not the actual labor that went into the product. Marx would say something like “the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> a thing consists, not <strong>of</strong> its exchange-proportions, but <strong>of</strong> the labor that went into actually<br />

making the thing.”<br />

Hans: This is a good description <strong>of</strong> the difference between Marx and Le Trosne, but the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value is not<br />

a theory determining the value <strong>of</strong> a good by its costs. See my [2007fa:45], [2007fa:49], [2007fa:113]. about this.<br />

Prices are not set by the bourgeoisie, as you say in your in-class answer, but by a competitive process described in<br />

[144] in which labor content acts as the big and unspoken “elephant in the room.”<br />

Next Message by Samantha is [440].<br />

[372] Jeremy: Marx does not agree with Le Trosne’s proposition that the value <strong>of</strong> a thing<br />

consists in its exchange-proportions with other things. To correct the error, Marx would<br />

reformulate it to say that the value <strong>of</strong> a thing consists in its use-value in proportion to other<br />

things. Through this correction, it becomes obvious that value is derived not from an outside<br />

object acting upon a thing, but rather that thing’s value is an expression <strong>of</strong> itself. Marx<br />

continually states that value, also referred to as labor, is a congealed substance within a<br />

commodity. Therefore, an item by itself has inherent value without needing another object<br />

to reflect value.<br />

Marx also states that exchange proportions vary on time period, region, as well as the<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> the exchange. Because this cannot be a constant, Marx adheres to the fact that<br />

value is not in the exchange, but in the production.<br />

Hans: Marx says that value is inherent in the commodity, but he explicitly rules out use-value. In 127:4–128:1 he<br />

says: “This common substance (value) cannot be a geometrical, physical, chemical, or any other natural property<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodities.” Value is the labor used to produce the commodity treated as if it was a homogeneous physical<br />

substance inside the commodities.<br />

Next Message by Jeremy is [373].<br />

[376] Bar: graded A From [20]: In 126:2 Marx explains the relationship between exchange<br />

perportions,<br />

“Exchange-value manifests itself at first as the quantitative relation, the proportion, in<br />

which use-values <strong>of</strong> one sort are exchanged against use-values <strong>of</strong> another sort ...”<br />

The quote sounds very similar to the quote <strong>of</strong> Le Trosne, but we know that Marx thinks<br />

that the commodity is mysterious and is more than meets the eye. Marx introduces the idea<br />

<strong>of</strong> use-value and labor time, concepts into the debate <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity, where<br />

Le Trosne only sees value as to what it could be exchange for. Le Trosne does not dig deep


26 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

into the soul <strong>of</strong> the commodity like Marx; this is why Marx does not agree with him. I think<br />

Marx proves really how mysterious the commodity is when he realizes like Le Trosne how<br />

it seems like the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is constantly changing and variable to what it can<br />

be exchanged for. The whole way that Marx thinks is stepping out <strong>of</strong> the societal box and<br />

looking at the logic that surrounds something: not just explaining the system and what value<br />

is in the system, but what value is, and how it would change if the social characteristics were<br />

more altruistic than they currently are, his logic is astounding. To reinforce my previous<br />

endorsement to the falsity that Marx agrees with Le Tronse it is a resounding No.<br />

Hans: Marx’s critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism is not that it not altruistic enough. His main critique is that people relate to<br />

each other through things and therefore forget that they are dealing with people rather than things. Compare 187:1,<br />

where he criticizes people’s atomistic behavior.<br />

You are making a good observation: Marx adheres to strict, dry, abstract logical thinking so that his analysis<br />

does not get infected by the prejudices prevalent in the society he is analyzing while living in it.<br />

Next Message by Bar is [380].<br />

[383] Brandon: graded A After reading more closely I have come to realize that Marx is<br />

not so much agreeing with Le Trosne, but rather reiterating Le Trosne’s analysis <strong>of</strong> exchange.<br />

According to Hans’s interpretation <strong>of</strong> Marx in [20], Marx uses this as a stepping stone to<br />

explain the long process <strong>of</strong> determining how commodities are exchangable. In his further<br />

examination <strong>of</strong> this, Marx comes to realize that the exchange-value is not found within the<br />

commodity itself but rather the product <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

As I understand it, this represents a form <strong>of</strong> supply-side economics, in which the amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> time and labor spent on the thing determines its exchange-value. Whereas Le Trosne<br />

only views the exchange-value as proportional relationship between commodities and their<br />

use-values.<br />

Hans: Instead <strong>of</strong> “the exchange-value is not found within the commodity itself but rather the product <strong>of</strong> labor,” I<br />

think a more precise formulation would have been<br />

The source <strong>of</strong> exchange-value is not found within the physical body <strong>of</strong> the commodity itself<br />

but it is the amount <strong>of</strong> labor necessary to produce it.<br />

More details about this in [415].<br />

Message [383] referenced by [415]. Next Message by Brandon is [384].<br />

[416] Hans: Value inherent in the commodities but not derived from use-value. Several<br />

answers, [364], [387], and several others, said that Marx, unlike Le Trosne, connects the<br />

value to the use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Marx says that value is inherent in the commodity.<br />

This does not mean that it is connected with the use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Rather<br />

it is a ghost-like “value material” socially associated with the commodity, namely the labor<br />

necessary to produce this commodity.<br />

The labor that was necessary to produce the commodity no longer exists. But society<br />

associates it with the body <strong>of</strong> the commodity as if it was a physical attribute. For instance<br />

the price <strong>of</strong> that commodity is (in Marx’s theory) a reminder <strong>of</strong> that labor-time.<br />

Here is one <strong>of</strong> my dadaist fables trying to make things more intuitive: Assume an imaginary<br />

society in which all newborn babies get a tag around their wrist which says how long<br />

their mother was in labor. And these tags are elastic; they grow with the baby and are never<br />

taken <strong>of</strong>f; instead they are considered an important attribute <strong>of</strong> the person. Kids would argue<br />

in the playground “but my mother was twenty hours in labor and yours only four, nah nah<br />

nah na nah nah.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 27<br />

The price signs <strong>of</strong> commodities are analogous to these hospital tags: they point to something<br />

that really happened in the past, and this past event is carried into the present as a<br />

relevant issue. Not by the social custom to never take the hospital tags <strong>of</strong>f, but by production<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities, which turns each product <strong>of</strong> labor into a claim check on other people’s<br />

labor. Of course, there is better justification to never forget the labor time necessary to produce<br />

a commodity than to never forget the time a mother labored to give birth to her child,<br />

because the production labor time can be used to allocate social labor-time. But it is only<br />

one possible form <strong>of</strong> allocation, and the big problem with it, as Marx tried to argue in the<br />

section <strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity, that here a social relation takes the<br />

form <strong>of</strong> the property <strong>of</strong> an object, and therefore can (and does) get out <strong>of</strong> control.<br />

Message [416] referenced by [387]. Next Message by Hans is [419].<br />

[628] Rmuscolino: The French economist Le Trosne wrote that the value <strong>of</strong> a thing consists<br />

in its exchange-proportions with other things. Marx somewhat agrees with Le Trosne,<br />

but re-formulates this proposition by saying it reflects the practical concerns <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

traders, but is also one-sided. Marx states, “A theoretical analysis has no hope <strong>of</strong><br />

uncovering the real connections if it does not take all aspects into consideration, even if they<br />

are contradictory.” Marx is saying that Le Trosne’s point <strong>of</strong> view isn’t totally correct because<br />

Le Trosne is confusing the exchange-value to be within the commodity, where Marx says<br />

the exchange-value cannot be inherent in the commodity and has precedents in the literature.<br />

Hans: I can tell that you looked at the Annotations, but you didn’t understand them. You should have read it again,<br />

until you do understand it. In some respects you say exactly the opposite <strong>of</strong> what Marx tried to convey. Your in-class<br />

answer was less confused. The archives <strong>of</strong> the class discussion is a good resource, especially my contributions, for<br />

instance I think my [20] might have been helpful.<br />

Message [628] referenced by [634] and [659]. Next Message by Rmuscolino is [631].<br />

Question 68 is 277 in 1996sp, 56 in 2005fa, 67 in 2007fa, 68 in 2008fa, 71 in 2009fa,<br />

and 72 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 68 First give Marx’s arguments how one can come to the conclusion that exchangevalue<br />

is not something inherent in the commodity. Then reproduce, in your own words,<br />

Marx’s rebuttal that, despite these arguments, exchange-value seems to be something inherent<br />

to the commodity after all.<br />

[19] Bar: content B form 95% Exchange value is not inherent in the commodity as Marx<br />

puts it, “money has an exchange value.” In other words Marx is arguing about the distinct<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> the exchange price, the price <strong>of</strong> the commodity depends not just <strong>of</strong> the commodity,<br />

but <strong>of</strong> the particular value <strong>of</strong> money. In nominal terms the price <strong>of</strong> oil lets say is $3/ gallon<br />

internationally, but how is this translated into other markets lets say the Colombian peso<br />

with is a 2:1 ratio with the dollar or $1 = 2,000 pesos to them, the price <strong>of</strong> gas will be<br />

the relative 6,000 pesos relatively a much higher price. He goes on to say that through<br />

a contradiction that the commodity is not inherently linked to the exchange value, as the<br />

exchange value has value only through its value to another commodity. “a proportion that<br />

changes with time and place..... something accidental and purely relative.” What Marx is<br />

saying is that the fluctuations created in the market on the commodity in relation to other<br />

commodities creates dependant value instead <strong>of</strong> intrinsic value <strong>of</strong> the commodity, He goes<br />

on to use the word “replaceable.” He concludes that in the end there is a social relations to


28 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the commodity and the exchange value that this value could be the tip <strong>of</strong> the ice burg so-tospeak<br />

<strong>of</strong> the underlining social relation to the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity. the conclusion and<br />

rebuttal to the inferences about the relativity <strong>of</strong> exchange, is that exchange value is intrinsic<br />

to the substance inside the commodity, that this underlying relationship goes on to explain<br />

the exchange proportion. It looks like Marx is setting-up the premise for his labor theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> value, which I wonder will conclude that the substance that joins intrinsic value with the<br />

exchange value is labor involved in producing the commodity.<br />

Hans: The digression about money in the first half <strong>of</strong> your answer is out <strong>of</strong> place. Marx has not yet introduced<br />

money. Right now he is only looking at the ordinary commodities and not yet at money. Therefore everything he<br />

says must be explainable in terms <strong>of</strong> ordinary commodities.<br />

Later you say some promising things, but you only hint at them, you don’t elaborate them enough. You should<br />

write it in such a way that someone who does not understand what Marx is getting at in this passage says ”oh now<br />

I see what Marx meant.”<br />

Next Message by Bar is [99].<br />

[388] Mick: graded A Exchange value appears to not be inherent in a commodity because<br />

this value is not defined by the commodity itself, but by its value in relation to other commodities.<br />

For example, currencies are not purchased as single entities, but in pairs. They are<br />

traded in pairs because it is necessary to measure a currency (commodity) in terms <strong>of</strong> another<br />

commodity. Since supply and demand <strong>of</strong> various commodities is constantly fluctuating, the<br />

price does not seem to be inherent within the commodity itself.<br />

The fluctuations <strong>of</strong> value can be attributed to fluctuations in a substance that the commodity<br />

already contains before its exchange in the marketplace. Marx posits this question and<br />

then through deeper analysis discovers that the exchange values between two commodities<br />

is reducible to a third commodity. This third measure is value, or the abstraction from use<br />

value that functions as a consistent measure <strong>of</strong> a commodity’s exchange value. This abstraction<br />

is abstract labor, which maintains a consistent relationship with the exchange value <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity.<br />

Hans: Not all price fluctuations can be reduced to fluctuations in value. At the present very general level <strong>of</strong><br />

analysis Marx can only say that prices are remotely controlled, i.e., they are the surface expression <strong>of</strong> something<br />

that is happening in production (labor). This distance between surface and underlying production process allows<br />

other influences to affect prices as well. See 195:2/o.<br />

Next Message by Mick is [389].<br />

[483] Ken: use-values carry exchange-values? Marx argues that “use-values are the material<br />

carriers <strong>of</strong> exchange-value”. A commodity can have a use-value, even if that commodity<br />

does not have an exchange-value. However a commodity can not have an exchange-value<br />

without a use-value. Exchange-value is independent <strong>of</strong> the use-value. If a commodity can<br />

be attained without labor being necessary, the commodity does not have an exchange-value.<br />

When labor is required in order to maximize the potential <strong>of</strong> a commodity that already<br />

has a use-value, then the use-value will be the “material carrier” <strong>of</strong> the exchange-value.<br />

Exchange-value is constantly changing depending on social factors, time and place it can<br />

not be inherent in the commodity. Depending on how these factors change, the exchangevalue<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity could be drastically different. This validates Marx’s argument that the<br />

exchange-value is not something inherent in the commodity.<br />

Marx then opposes his argument, explaining how exchange-value seems to be inherent<br />

to the commodity. When a commodity is traded, an amount <strong>of</strong> something is traded for an


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 29<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> something. These two amounts are equal in worth, but are different goods. This<br />

shows that the exchange-value is inherent to the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Ken is [484].<br />

Question 79 is 78 in 2008fa and 97 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 79 “Exchange-value cannot be anything other than the mode <strong>of</strong> expression, the<br />

‘form <strong>of</strong> appearance’, <strong>of</strong> some substance distinguishable from it” (p. 127:1).<br />

a) How did Marx come to this conclusion by observing the exchange relations between<br />

commodities?<br />

b) What is this substance distinguishable from the exchange-value?<br />

c) Does mainstream economics distinguish between exchange-value and the substance expressed<br />

by exchange-value?<br />

d) Why must this substance be equal for all commodities?<br />

e) Why can it not come from their use-values?<br />

f) How does Marx come to the conclusion that this substance comes from labor?<br />

[32] Hans: Marx’s argument so far. This question summarizes Marx’s argument as I<br />

understand it, therefore I thought it a good idea to give you the answers which I had in mind<br />

when formulating the question.<br />

(a) Marx observed the contradiction that exchange-value is on the one hand something<br />

immanent in the commodities, and on the other it is something relative between the commodities.<br />

He resolves this contradiction by saying that the exchange-value is the surface<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> the value, i.e., the labor, inside the commodities. In this way he covers both<br />

poles <strong>of</strong> the contradiction: exchange-value is immanent because it is the expression <strong>of</strong> something<br />

immanent, and it is relative because this immanent substance expresses itself through<br />

the exchange relations which are relative.<br />

(b) The substance inside the commodities <strong>of</strong> which the exchange-value is the expression<br />

is the labor.<br />

(c) Marx says that every commodity has two aspects, on the one hand a use-value, and<br />

on the other, an exchange-value, which have little to do with each other and have different<br />

origins. Mainstream economics does not separate the two but tries to explain the exchange<br />

proportions by the use-values, i.e., by marginal utility. If a commodity has a high price on<br />

the market this is because people like it a lot. A capitalist makes high pr<strong>of</strong>its if he makes lots<br />

<strong>of</strong> people happy. This is quite a different way <strong>of</strong> looking at things than Marx’s interpretation<br />

which says that commodities get their value in production by the labor <strong>of</strong> the production<br />

workers.<br />

(d) On the market, people measure their commodities by a one-dimensional measuring<br />

stick, namely, money. Marx argues that in the long run, such a social interaction on the<br />

surface <strong>of</strong> the economy can only maintain itself if commodities are also one-dimensional<br />

in production. This one-dimensionality in production is the human labor needed for every<br />

commodity. Although the labors themselves are as different as the commodities, they are<br />

all performed by humans who are very versatile regarding what they can do. This versatile<br />

capacity to work is the “abstract human labor” which gives commodities their values.


30 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(e) Each individual who makes an exchange looks at both use-value and exchange-value<br />

(or price) <strong>of</strong> the goods exchanged. But if all those millions <strong>of</strong> transactions are taken together,<br />

the use-value considerations cancel out, and the only thing that remains is that each usevalue<br />

is as good as any other. That is why Marx says the exchange is characterized by an<br />

abstraction from use-value.<br />

(f) By looking at the market, one can see that people equate their commodities, but one<br />

cannot infer from these surface interactions what the basis <strong>of</strong> this equality is. Marx says<br />

labor is the “only thing” which the commodities have in common, in other words, there is<br />

no other candidate that can fill this role as convincingly as labor.<br />

Message [32] referenced by [156], [279], [2012fa:52], and [2012fa:319]. Next Message by Hans is [33].<br />

[279] Dyoung: a) Marx comes to this conclusion because like he said “the exchange-value<br />

can’t be anything other than the mode <strong>of</strong> expression and the form <strong>of</strong> appearance.” He also<br />

states that the commodities must contain something equal, but this equal thing can’t have<br />

anything to do with their use-values. He was able to see that each commodity had a different<br />

expression and appearance than the other making each commodity unique in their own way<br />

and they are the means to support human life.<br />

Hans: The above Marx quote is how you wrote it in your in-class exam, i.e., it is a quote from memory. You left<br />

out the end <strong>of</strong> the sentence. The full sentence from 127:1 is: “Exchange-value ... cannot be anything other than the<br />

mere mode <strong>of</strong> expression, ‘form <strong>of</strong> appearance’, <strong>of</strong> some content distinguishable from it.” This is the place where<br />

Marx reports his conclusion, but quoting this does not help us understand how Marx comes to this conclusion.<br />

Look at (a) in my my own answer [32] for a brief summary <strong>of</strong> the argument leading up to this conclusion. Note that<br />

Marx didn’t write that every commodity is a different expression and appearance than other commodities, but that<br />

exchange-value is the expression or appearance <strong>of</strong> something different than exchange-value.<br />

b) The substance that is distinguishable from the exchange-value would be the use-value<br />

in the market place. Each exchange-value has a different use-value to the consumer <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity.<br />

Hans: According to Marx, the substance <strong>of</strong> which the exchange-value is an expression or appearance is not usevalue<br />

but the thing which Marx calls value, which is the labor spent to produce the commodity.<br />

c) Yes it does distinguish between the exchange-value and the substance expressed by<br />

exchange-value by their use-values are qualitatively different.<br />

Hans: Yes. Mainstream economics says what you said in (b), that the exchange-value is an expression <strong>of</strong> the<br />

use-value, namely it is the marginal utility, a measure <strong>of</strong> how much people like the use-value.<br />

d) Because if it was not equal for all commodities it would create problems when trying to<br />

exchange these commodities in the market because each commodity won’t be valued fairly.<br />

Marx also states that commodities must contain something equal, but this equal thing cannot<br />

have anything to do with their use-values. He says that there is only one other thing which<br />

commodities have in common “If we then disregard the use-value <strong>of</strong> commodities, they have<br />

only one property left, that <strong>of</strong> being the product <strong>of</strong> labor.”<br />

Hans: The “must” in the formulation <strong>of</strong> the question is an inferential must, as in the sentence “you are smiling,<br />

you must enjoy this.” It was a little out <strong>of</strong> place, I re-formulated the question for the next edition.<br />

e) Because each use-value could be very different. Each use-value would depend upon<br />

the individual using the commodity and if its not from the use-value it can only come from<br />

the Labor.<br />

Hans: Use-values are different even if you don’t look at people’s preferences but the use-values themselves (my<br />

[231] tries to explain this difference).


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 31<br />

f) Marx comes to the conclusion first by saying that the common substance must be<br />

something social since it is not natural and then he introduces Labor and then he is set<br />

on Labor is the only possibility. Marx states that “Labor is the additional judgment” to<br />

determine the substance value by how long it takes to finish the commodity. Labor is the<br />

most important substance in any commodity<br />

Hans: The sentence “labor is an additional judgment” does not come from Marx but from my interpretation <strong>of</strong><br />

Marx. Only the two-column part in the Annotations is Marx himself speaking, everything else is my own efforts to<br />

understand Marx’s arguments.<br />

Thank you for the courageous act <strong>of</strong> taking on this long and difficult question. I hope my commentaries help<br />

you understand the issues better.<br />

Next Message by Dyoung is [281].<br />

Question 81 is 44 in 1996ut, 67 in 2004fa, 79 in 2007SP, 80 in 2008fa, 85 in 2010fa, 97<br />

in 2011fa, and 95 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 81 Why did Ricardo’s discovery <strong>of</strong> the determination <strong>of</strong> value by labor attract<br />

the following critique: “Mr. Ricardo’s system is one <strong>of</strong> discords . . . its whole tends to the<br />

production <strong>of</strong> hostility among classes and nations . . . His book is the true manual <strong>of</strong> the<br />

demagogue, who seeks power by means <strong>of</strong> agrarianism, war and plunder.”<br />

[31] Aaron: Ricardo value <strong>of</strong> labor. When discussing the value <strong>of</strong> labor and the finished<br />

goods, Marx recognizes the fact that the value <strong>of</strong> a good might be different to different<br />

people, according to the use-value theory. I believe that Marx observes that the value <strong>of</strong> a<br />

good might change in the blink <strong>of</strong> an eye, and “in our own hands,” because the beauty <strong>of</strong><br />

the product is in the eye <strong>of</strong> the beholder. It goes without saying that in our market place<br />

the consumer looks at a commodity as in use-value. Marx argues that the value <strong>of</strong> the same<br />

product is different in the eyes <strong>of</strong> the producer or manufacturer. The comment that the<br />

value changes “in our own hands” tells me that Marx had a keen understanding that different<br />

classes <strong>of</strong> people will value a good differently. As to say, my wealthy friend might pay 3000<br />

dollars for a painting that I would only pay 300 dollars for. The use value in this sense<br />

may be a product <strong>of</strong> class in society. The price that my friend and I are willing to pay is<br />

indifferent to the amount <strong>of</strong> labor the artist used to paint the piece. In this section, Marx<br />

does not observe the reaction that supply and demand might pull the “value.”<br />

Hans: Marx is as guilty as Ricardo <strong>of</strong> a theory which gives justification to class discontent and unrest. Both Marx<br />

and Ricardo have an objective theory <strong>of</strong> value, a theory which considers value as something real, as more than an<br />

attitude. Marx’s argument with social labor being transformed in our hands only makes the step from concrete to<br />

abstract labor. It does not turn value into something relative and subjective.<br />

Message [31] referenced by [33] and [210]. Next Message by Aaron is [53].<br />

[33] Hans: Labor Value and Class Hatred. Once I overheard two young people in the<br />

Snowbird tram – they were employees who used their employee pass to get some skiing in<br />

before or after work – say to each other: I can’t imagine having to pay full price for this. To<br />

me this seemed to be a serious deficit <strong>of</strong> imagination. What they should be imagining is that<br />

lots <strong>of</strong> people pay full price for the Snowbird tram and they don’t even care. They probably<br />

spend a couple hundred dollars per person in the restaurant after skiing, etc.<br />

The question why some people have money to burn is the incendiary question which<br />

makes the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value so “demagogic.” As long as it is just a different utility<br />

function which causes Aaron’s rich friend in [31] to pay $3000 for a painting which Aaron


32 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

himself did not find that great, then social peace can be maintained. But if the hundred dollar<br />

bills hanging out <strong>of</strong> Aaron’s friend’s coat pockets represent labor, more labor than Aaron’s<br />

friend could possibly ever have performed, then the question is inevitable: why does he have<br />

the money and not those who did the work?<br />

Message [33] referenced by [156] and [2010fa:64]. Next Message by Hans is [37].<br />

Question 84 is 82 in 2007fa and 83 in 2008fa:<br />

Question 84 Is Marx’s concept <strong>of</strong> “value material” attached to commodities, but separate<br />

from their physical material, a metaphor? Is it a phantasy, an invention, which Marx needs<br />

to hold his labor theory <strong>of</strong> value together? Is Marx going overboard here? Or does it really<br />

exist?<br />

[27] CousinIt: graded A Is “value material” a metaphor? I would flatly disagree with<br />

Ozz [2007fa:54] who states that value material is a metaphor. This is not to say that it doesn’t<br />

act metaphorically and variably, depending on the ‘reality tunnel’ that one happens to find<br />

oneself inhabiting. Metaphor and metonym are really merely matters <strong>of</strong> scale <strong>of</strong> variance<br />

and variance <strong>of</strong> scale <strong>of</strong> magnitude <strong>of</strong> repetition and pattern, are they not? As stated by Hans<br />

[2007fa:58], I, too, see value-as-‘congealed labor’ to be an actual social substance that, while<br />

being invisible as an apparent physical feature <strong>of</strong> the commodity, is nonetheless very real in<br />

its ultimate force/effect upon the real material lives <strong>of</strong> real people. This is true in much the<br />

same sense as when critical scholars <strong>of</strong> discourse, text, and rhetoric claim that words have<br />

very real material effects on people in the world.<br />

In stating my disagreement, I am taking a radical materialist stance; a stance much like<br />

that taken by quantum physicists who hypothesize very real material forces, even those that<br />

cannot be seen, that do not ‘appear’ to be ‘real’ or ‘material’, that is, those ‘invisible’ or<br />

‘ethereal’ substances <strong>of</strong> the universe that nonetheless are thought to exist. In taking this<br />

stance, I feel I must make very clear that it is my perspective that all material, everything<br />

in the universe, including thought and relationship, is made up <strong>of</strong> relations, exchanges, and<br />

transformations <strong>of</strong> energy. Further, I would state that energy is all that all material consists<br />

<strong>of</strong>. All material in a wholly material universe is in essence energy expressed in variable manifestation<br />

<strong>of</strong> form and degree <strong>of</strong> substance, some more coarse, some more refined and subtle.<br />

This includes those substances that are not tactilly manipulated or apprehended by the human<br />

physical apparatus, but also those that are manipulated and apprehended psychically,<br />

emotionally, mentally, and socially. I fully recognize that for some I may be perilously stepping<br />

out on a philosophical ontological limb, yet, I do believe that my perspective is equally<br />

as provable or dis-provable as a perspective that claims to be able to clearly delineate between<br />

the material and the non-material. Again, such a view does not necessarily exclude<br />

metaphor, but, actually gives metaphor a material basis and claim (..thus, I have now come<br />

full circle to the contradiction in my own argument that Ozz [2007fa:54] is incorrect, yet,<br />

as we now know from reading Marx and by benefit <strong>of</strong> Hans’ generous and insightful comments,<br />

contradiction is not to be avoided but rather exploited as an opportunity for deeper<br />

analysis...).


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 33<br />

From this perspective, then, Marx is not just flailing about for a bolster to his argument<br />

when positing a value material. In this sense Marx can be viewed as a hard-core radical materialist<br />

in the utmost sense, rather than accused <strong>of</strong> being some sort <strong>of</strong> surrealist illusionist<br />

or cunning rhetorician. From my perspective, to speak <strong>of</strong> value as a ‘immaterial substance’<br />

is a bit <strong>of</strong> an oxymoron. It amounts to placating those who insist on introducing some otherworldly<br />

spiritualism into the scientific materialist dialectic... i.e. a sort <strong>of</strong> a historical artifact<br />

<strong>of</strong> the time that appeals to particular superstitious perspectives that haunt our understanding<br />

even more so than labor-power ‘haunts’ the commodity. Accumulated labor power, on the<br />

contrary (rather than some sort <strong>of</strong> ’spook’), is a very real element <strong>of</strong> the commodity that<br />

manifests as commodified social relations and produces value material out <strong>of</strong> a very real<br />

material reaction between the commodity, abstract labor, and the totality <strong>of</strong> social relations<br />

in capitalist society and culture. Perhaps, in an effort to spoon-feed so as not to overwhelm<br />

or overtax, to avoid overtly challenging the superstitions <strong>of</strong> our time, Marx did not go far<br />

enough?<br />

Message [27] referenced by [29]. Next Message by CousinIt is [30].<br />

[29] Hans: It’s real because someone has a claim on it. CousinIt [27] first emphatically<br />

agrees that “value matter” is immaterial yet real, but then he thinks he needs to justify this,<br />

and after some handwaving with modern physics he says it’s not matter but energy. Marx<br />

didn’t get it right because he didn’t know Einstein’s E=mc2. (CousinIt didn’t say it in so<br />

many words but I think this was his gist. If I mis-interpret you, please speak up.)<br />

The theory <strong>of</strong> relativity and quantum mechanics are irrelevant for the issues at hand,<br />

and it is a mistake to bring them into the discussion. The explanation why past labor-time<br />

in capitalism lives on as a social substance is much more mundane. The labor-time spent<br />

on producing the commodities is a social reality because those who performed this labor<br />

need to be paid so that they can survive. Therefore the firm which produces these things is<br />

maintaining spreadsheets allocating their costs to the products produced. The past labor-time<br />

<strong>of</strong> the products has social reality because someone in society remembers it, watches over it,<br />

has a claim on it which they can enforce with the court system. You don’t need Einstein for<br />

this.<br />

Message [29] referenced by [30], [308], and [2008fa:107]. Next Message by Hans is [32].<br />

[30] CousinIt: graded as part <strong>of</strong> [27] Value material. I don’t think I was trying to refute<br />

Marx or suggest that he got it wrong, but merely to suggest another possible way we<br />

could look at the issue from a radical materialist perspective, for those for whom the idea<br />

<strong>of</strong> a ‘social substance’ seems esoteric and intangible. By referring to labor power as energy<br />

expended I was trying to make a sort <strong>of</strong> materialist warrant for the materiality <strong>of</strong> a social substance.<br />

I do realize that it is enough to say that someone is owed something in exchange for<br />

the labor put into producing a commodity, that the laborer is short-changed by the capitalist<br />

and has a valid claim, and personally have no problem with saying so. Perhaps I was a bit<br />

heavy-handed and over-zealous in bringing physical science into the discussion? I do think<br />

I was going more for an analogy about things that are real yet invisible or not-so-readilyapparent<br />

and a warrant for depth analysis, rather than a 1 to 1 correspondence...Thank you,<br />

Hans, for your comments...<br />

Hans: Let me try to explain my point again: The performance <strong>of</strong> labor is a real process. You don’t need any<br />

philosophical arguments to know that. The labor process is real because it has a real effect: without the labor<br />

process, the product would not be there. But Marx says that the labor process has two results: on the one hand it


34 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

creates the product, and on the other it creates the value <strong>of</strong> the product. In other words, society remembers how<br />

much labor was expended to produce this good, and this social memory is attached to the good. The ontological<br />

question is, since the good itself is inanimate: who keeps this memory and how is it associated with the product? I<br />

don’t see how the notion <strong>of</strong> labor as energy expended helps here.<br />

My own answer, which I tried to explain in [29], is: society does not forget how much labor went into the<br />

product because those who performed this labor have now, in turn, a claim on the labor <strong>of</strong> others. This has nothing<br />

to do with the question whether the laborer gets a full value <strong>of</strong> the product or is short-changed. In both situations,<br />

there are such claims, and there are social procedures to keep track <strong>of</strong> these claims (punch clocks, accounting<br />

spreadsheets, cash registers, etc.). These are society’s housekeeping instruments which keep track <strong>of</strong> the invisible<br />

”value material” in the products.<br />

Next Message by CousinIt is [65].<br />

[295] FacistFrank: No this is not really a metaphor, the value material is really separate<br />

from the physical properties. Only use value can be utilized by the object’s physical<br />

properties. Two commodities with the same use value cannot be exchanged for each other,<br />

that would be like exchanging a box <strong>of</strong> cigarettes for the exact same box <strong>of</strong> cigarettes! Why<br />

would anyone do this, it would be ridiculous. But this is strange because if you are exchanging<br />

two or more items for other items they must collectively have an equal value, or must be<br />

perceived to be that way. But different use values cannot be equal, that would be a logical<br />

contradiction. So the exchange value must be equal and the use values must be different,<br />

and because use values come from physical properties, the real value must not come from<br />

use value or physical properties, Marx says it comes from labor. Actual value is determined<br />

by the labor put into the making <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Actual Value, (the real price paid for the<br />

good) is a social expression that humans have toward the commodity.<br />

Hans: Your last sentence sounds as if exchange-value comes from the way the good is viewed in society. This<br />

is not Marx’s theory. He thinks labor is the elephant in the room which shapes these views, see [144] and the<br />

references there.<br />

Next Message by FacistFrank is [296].<br />

[298] Alex: graded A The statement is necessary to hold Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value<br />

together. The question is whether it is accurate, and does exist. It does exist, it can’t be<br />

false as Marx is connecting other important theories with this one. The distinction is where<br />

the reality lies. “Value” versus “physical” is heavily distinguished by Marx. In fact value<br />

theory is one <strong>of</strong> Marx’s most important distinctions. One has to understand that when Marx<br />

talks <strong>of</strong> value he means there is something in addition to physical. It is not just a metaphor,<br />

fantasy or invention, there is meaning in value. Theories <strong>of</strong> labor require an explanation <strong>of</strong><br />

materials. The entire labor process and therefore value <strong>of</strong> commodities are affected by this<br />

materials distinction. When context is given for materials it is easier to understand Marx’s<br />

writing in further chapters about fetishes, social processes, etc.<br />

Hans: Instead <strong>of</strong> saying “there is meaning in value” I think you meant to say “value is based on something real”<br />

or similar.<br />

Your argument why it can’t be false is a little cavalier. Indeed Marx, and modern critical realism, do not claim<br />

that they can’t be false. They consider themselves fallible. Of course, this is hard to tell from the way Marx is<br />

writing. He writes as if he was making a mathematical pro<strong>of</strong>.<br />

Next Message by Alex is [299].<br />

[308] CousinIt: graded A+ Value-material. Marx’s concept <strong>of</strong> “value-material” is meant<br />

to denote the actual social substance attached to commodities, i.e. the congealed abstract<br />

labor put into the commodity. Marx does not mean this as mere metaphor. The “valuematerial”<br />

is the socially necessary labor put into producing the commodity. As Hans [29]


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 35<br />

points out, someone did the labor and has to be paid for it so that they can subsist. The<br />

producer who put the labor-time into the commodity can lay claim to the labor so as to be<br />

able to exchange it for the labor <strong>of</strong> others in society (perhaps, but not always, in the form<br />

<strong>of</strong> some use-value or other). Labor-time is remembered, documented, watched over, and<br />

legitimated in capitalist society. Labor-time is a social reality that, although immaterial, is<br />

nonetheless very real in its material effects.<br />

Hans: Since this is such a good and comprehensive answer I’d like to make it even more comprehensive by pointing<br />

out two possible sources <strong>of</strong> misunderstanding:<br />

(1) From the use-value <strong>of</strong> a good it is usually apparent that this good is the fruit <strong>of</strong> human labor. (Not always;<br />

a cow looks like a natural creature, one does not immediately see the millenia <strong>of</strong> domesticating and breeding that<br />

went into it.) Marx does not mean this. Marx says that apart from its use-value, the labor content is worn by the<br />

commodity like the emperor’s new clothes.<br />

(2) The expenditure <strong>of</strong> human labor-power is a real aspect <strong>of</strong> the production <strong>of</strong> the commodity. But after the<br />

production process is finished, the labor-power has been used up and no longer exists physically. The commodity’s<br />

value-material is so-to-say the afterlife <strong>of</strong> this used-up labor-power. It continues to exist even after it has been used<br />

up, through the social convention which keeps track <strong>of</strong> it and attributes this labor-power to the product. (There is a<br />

problem with this when the labor process does not materialize itself in a tradable product; in a commodity society,<br />

those labor processes are not given enough attention, they are <strong>of</strong>ten not even recognized as labor.)<br />

Next Message by CousinIt is [309].<br />

[316] Gerund: Value material, attached to commodities but separate from their physical<br />

material, is not a metaphor or an invention Marx creates to hold his labor theory <strong>of</strong> value<br />

together, but rather an actual trait imbued into the object when it is created through labor.<br />

I think <strong>of</strong> it as being like the electric charges in atoms which hold them together. Most<br />

mass is actually empty space; tiny particles circling other tiny particles, held together by a<br />

form <strong>of</strong> energy which exhibits in the relations between the particles, but not in their physical<br />

material. Value material is present in the objects, and exhibits in their relations, but not in<br />

their physical material.<br />

Next Message by Gerund is [317].<br />

[323] PrivateProperty: ”Value Material” is Physical. According to Marx, “value material”<br />

is actually a physical part <strong>of</strong> the commodities, and not a mere phantasy or metaphor.<br />

Nature provides the raw material, and it is the worker who transforms it into a commodity.<br />

The physical makeup <strong>of</strong> the commodity, the finished product, is therefore owing to the labor<br />

that produced it. This physical makeup is an expression <strong>of</strong> the labor taken to produce the<br />

commodity, and therefore is an expression <strong>of</strong> value within the commodity.<br />

Hans: The physical materials as modified by the labor process are the use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity. These usevalues<br />

are not homogeneous, they are therefore not the “comon substance” <strong>of</strong> the commodities expressed in their<br />

exchange values. You are making here the same error which I already tried to correct in my remarks to your [209].<br />

Let me try again: Marx claims that capitalist society acts as if all commodities were filled with some immaterial<br />

homogeneous substance. It is like the emperor’s new clothes. Even the labor process itself is affected: it has a<br />

double character, because it must not only produce the use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity but also form this immaterial<br />

substance.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [402].<br />

[364] Carterryan: Value Material <strong>of</strong> the Commodity. This is a metaphor used to relate<br />

Marx’s concept, and is not a literal expression because you cannot remove the material from<br />

the commodity in a physical way. Marx is trying to compare the use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

not the materials itself. The use-value is the only factor that Marx wants to be used in the<br />

exchange or bartering <strong>of</strong> commodities, and a way <strong>of</strong> seeing the benefit to the community.


36 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Marx does not use this as a fantasy or invention to support his theory, but more as he is<br />

stating his view <strong>of</strong> what the labor and use value <strong>of</strong> this commodity can be worth.<br />

Marx is using more <strong>of</strong> an analogy to relate the material value, it is not literal and he does<br />

not seem to go overboard but just to illustrate the theory by creating a good visual for this<br />

theory.<br />

Hans: On the contrary, Marx makes a strict separation between value and use-value. And Capital is not about how<br />

Marx wants exchange relations to be determined, but this is Marx’s theory about how exchange relations are in fact<br />

determined.<br />

Message [364] referenced by [416]. Next Message by Carterryan is [365].<br />

[375] Wasatch: Marx’s concept <strong>of</strong> “value material” is a metaphor. I personally don’t see<br />

this metaphor as going overboard or being fantastic. The value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is made<br />

up <strong>of</strong> the actual physical material, which we can hold in our hands along with this added<br />

“metaphysical” value, which you cannot touch, or hold in your hand, but is very real. We’ve<br />

all held similar commodities in our hands that seem to have different “value material”. Let’s<br />

look at two chairs, both having the same use-value. One chair took much more labor-power<br />

to produce than the other. When we handle the chair with more “value material” we can<br />

feel, in a metaphysical sense, that it has more value. The other chair doesn’t contain the<br />

same amount <strong>of</strong> ghostlike value, or “value material” as the other. “Value material” is very<br />

real. Maybe consumers have a sixth sense when it comes to value that gives them the ability<br />

to feel/sense the value material that each commodity possesses.<br />

Hans: A sixth sense is not necessary; look at [144].<br />

Next Message by Wasatch is [377].<br />

[410] Aaron: Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> value material is attached to commodities and I don’t<br />

believe that it is a metaphor. I think Marx really attaches the materiality as something which<br />

is like an object without being an object itself... as Hans puts it in the annotations. I believe<br />

that this means a commodity can have words attached to it that do not necessarily mean<br />

precisely what the word says. My example would be the “top” seeded team in a basketball<br />

tournament. This does not literally mean that they are the top, meaning highest altitude,<br />

team. Much like the example in annotations <strong>of</strong> “your royal highness.” The value material<br />

seems as if it is an important concept in the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value and should be accounted<br />

for. I don’t believe that it is a fantasy or invention because no matter how much labor is<br />

involved in a commodity, certain materials have an intrinsic value to the end user. I believe<br />

that Marx uses this concept not to hold his theory together, but because he believes that<br />

“value material” can play an important role in value. Just as a ghost can consist <strong>of</strong> matter,<br />

but not in a physical manner.<br />

Hans: Your theory that “certain materials have an intrinsic value to the end user” has nothing to do with Marx’s<br />

value material.<br />

Next Message by Aaron is [411].<br />

[587] JPeel: content A late penalty 43% Marx’s concept <strong>of</strong> “value material” attached to<br />

commodities, but separate from their physical material, is more <strong>of</strong> an invention rather than<br />

a metaphor, where Marx needs to hold his labor theory <strong>of</strong> value together. Marx isn’t really<br />

going overboard because it really does exist. “The definition <strong>of</strong> materiality, as opposed to<br />

‘material’ is here: something which is like an object without being an object itself.” And<br />

Marx is saying commodities, as values, consist <strong>of</strong> a non-physical yet material-like substance


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 37<br />

called value materiality. It is somewhat a metaphor but Marx is creating more <strong>of</strong> an invention<br />

when relating it to the commodity.<br />

Next Message by JPeel is [588].<br />

[652] Nstew: I think Marx is going overboard here by basing too much <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong><br />

a commodity on labor. There are other factors that are closely related to the value <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity. I think the need or demand for a commodity plays a larger role in the value <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity.<br />

Hans: You are making it abundantly clear that Marx’s theory is not convincing to you, and this is <strong>of</strong> course your<br />

right. But the study questions must be answered from within the Marxian paradigm; they test whether you understand<br />

Marx’s theory.<br />

Next Message by Nstew is [653].<br />

Question 89 is 87 in 2007SP and 87 in 2007fa:<br />

Question 89 We know now that value consists <strong>of</strong> abstract labor. What does exchange-value<br />

consist <strong>of</strong>?<br />

[28] Dyoung: What is Value and Abstract Labor? Exchange-value is not a price, it<br />

is a social relation that takes the form <strong>of</strong> an immaterial substance inside each individual<br />

commodity. This consists <strong>of</strong> a value and abstract labor. This means that we take a nonphysical<br />

trait <strong>of</strong> a commodity like labor that is put into a certain commodity and through this<br />

process we are able to calculate the value <strong>of</strong> this commodity. Hans says “the exchange-value<br />

is the means by which the value in the commodities forces us to recognize.”<br />

I work in a jewelry store where we sell very expensive watches where it can take 8-10<br />

months <strong>of</strong> labor to create one watch, this includes a form <strong>of</strong> immaterial substance <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

which is forced to be calculated with the end value <strong>of</strong> the watch, so I agree with Hans’s<br />

statement that exchange-value does force us to look at why a certain watches are $6,000.<br />

There are many examples <strong>of</strong> commodities that take on an immaterial substance inside<br />

the process which we are all forced to recognize. This process must be included in the<br />

production <strong>of</strong> the commodity or the commodity would never become a commodity.<br />

I also think that the exchange-value that is created from this process allows individuals<br />

to buy and sell their commodities. It has been said by Jakeman [2007SP:476]: “if you want<br />

a certain commodity but you don’t think the value is worth the suggested price, then you<br />

can wait to see if the price will go down,” or I think that you can try and bargain with the<br />

person selling the item and try and agree on the true worth and value in the market that<br />

would be satisfying for both individuals without compromising the value and the abstract<br />

labor involved in creating the commodity.<br />

Hans: You are affirming and illustrating Marx’s notion that the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is an immaterial social<br />

substance residing in the commodity. Question 89 was asking something different, namely, it was asking about<br />

exchange-value as distinct from value. As I tried to argue in [2007SP:38], the question “what does exchange-value<br />

consist <strong>of</strong>” does not make sense because unlike value, exchange-value is not an immaterial substance residing in<br />

the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Dyoung is [49].<br />

Question 92 is 57 in 1997WI, 57 in 1997sp, 63 in 1999SP, 65 in 2001fa, 66 in 2002fa, 68<br />

in 2003fa, 78 in 2004fa, 77 in 2005fa, 90 in 2007SP, 90 in 2007fa, 90 in 2008fa, 93 in<br />

2009fa, 97 in 2010fa, and 117 in 2011fa:


38 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Question 92 Is it a character flaw to be lazy in an exploitive system?<br />

[35] Chris: tactical lazyness and productivity. Before giving a “yes” or “no” answer<br />

to a rather sophisticated question, I would like to first define what an exploitive system<br />

entails. One can define exploitive as “to use selfishly for one’s own ends” or “to utilize,<br />

especially for pr<strong>of</strong>it” (www.dictionary.com). From the same source, a system would be “an<br />

assemblage or combination <strong>of</strong> things or parts forming a complex or unitary whole.” From<br />

these definitions, I find it a character flaw to be a part <strong>of</strong> the formation <strong>of</strong> an exploitive<br />

system. This would entail one to have no moral attachment to the harmful labor practices<br />

(we have been discussing labor so I am using the “system” as a business and its workers and<br />

owners within it) that occur on the subjective members <strong>of</strong> the exploitive system.<br />

If these subjective members to the exploitive system understand that they are a part <strong>of</strong><br />

such an exploitive system, I find it wrong on their behalf to not stand up and try to fight<br />

such a system. I am being careful in using the word “wrong” instead <strong>of</strong> “lazy” because I<br />

do not believe that they are lazy for not standing up against the exploitive system. I say this<br />

because I am aware that each subjective member (you can think <strong>of</strong> them as workers) may<br />

have a family that they need to provide for, bills to pay; amongst other obligatory actions.<br />

In most cases, the only way for the subjective members (workers in my example) to fight<br />

against the system is by only doing the minimal amount <strong>of</strong> work. This lowers productivity,<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its for the system, and strain on the subjective members, plus they are able to keep their<br />

job and meet their obligations; whatever that may be. This action is not lazy and nor is it a<br />

character flaw. This is downright tactical and genius. So, in regards to the question, I feel<br />

that no, it is not a character flaw <strong>of</strong> the members <strong>of</strong> the exploitive system to be “lazy” in their<br />

productivity for the system.<br />

I was also quite taken back by Marx’s passage on page 130:1/o <strong>of</strong> Capital when he discusses<br />

labor (labour) productivity and value, all <strong>of</strong> which I feel tie into this question. In his<br />

words, “the less the productivity <strong>of</strong> labour, the greater the labour-time necessary to produce<br />

an article, and the greater the value.” This quote would insinuate to me that a subjective<br />

member appearing lazy by lowering their productivity is doing just that to raise the commodity’s<br />

value. This is again, not a character flaw but a knowledgeable action on behalf <strong>of</strong><br />

the subjective member. Using this select passage from Marx and my own example, I still<br />

feel that there is no character flaw present.<br />

Hans: About your last paragraph: if Marx says that lower productivity leads to higher value this does not mean he<br />

thinks lower productivity is good. It only means: if productivity is low then more labor is needed to produce the<br />

good.<br />

Message [35] referenced by [36] and [37]. Next Message by Chris is [38].<br />

[36] Ryoung: Does lazyness equal lack <strong>of</strong> integrity. Does laziness, in an exploitive<br />

system, equal a lack <strong>of</strong> integrity? I think Chris [35] in his response gave us helpful insight to<br />

what is considered an “exploitive system”. When I think <strong>of</strong> an exploitive system my thoughts<br />

immediately turn to a previous class discussion I had in a past semester. The discussion was<br />

whether or not teenage workers are exploited due to their low wages? My first response<br />

was that, yes, they are exploited. My thoughts later ran deeper on the subject. After much<br />

thought I continue to believe that most teenagers and their low wages are products <strong>of</strong> some<br />

forms <strong>of</strong> exploitation. I later asked myself if this exploitation is necessary or uncalled for? I


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 39<br />

believe that this type <strong>of</strong> exploitation is not necessary but could be beneficial for the workers.<br />

Yes, I said beneficial for the teenage worker! I say this because I believe that everyone in<br />

life have their dues to pay, and that one can learn valuable lessons being placed in such a<br />

situation as a these teenage workers. From personal experience I have learned many “life<br />

lessons” when being in situations similar to these. It has been a great benefit to my character.<br />

Chris [35] also mentioned that he feels it a “character flaw” to allow oneself to be part <strong>of</strong><br />

an exploitive system. I also tend to agree with him to a certain extent. We, as humans, find it<br />

very natural to want things without having to work for them. We tend to get very impatient<br />

and we also tend to get discouraged easily. We sometimes believe that life is awful and that<br />

nothing goes our way. It is especially easy to find ourselves thinking in such a manner at the<br />

start <strong>of</strong> our new jobs or when things aren’t exactly going the way we foresaw them going.<br />

At times like these I believe we need to take a step back and let our emotions go to truly<br />

be able to evaluate the situation. After our evaluations are complete and we feel that we are<br />

being exploited I too, like Chris, believe it to be crazy to stay in such a situation.<br />

In certain situations people may find themselves in these exploitive situations with no<br />

where else to go. In some <strong>of</strong> these cases their wage may not be directly linked to their<br />

individual production, and they in return may choose to exploit the same system that is<br />

exploiting them. This can bring us to my answer <strong>of</strong> our original question, “is it a character<br />

flaw to be lazy in an exploitive system”? I feel that the answer to this question can go both<br />

ways depending on the situations presented. For example, if a man finds himself working<br />

under an exploitive system and chooses to stay and work at a more “laid” back pace while<br />

having other options out there for him, I do believe that it is a character flaw for him. On the<br />

other hand if another man finds himself working under the same exploitive system and he<br />

has no where else to go for another job I don’t see it as a character flaw but only if he would<br />

change jobs when the opportunity provided itself. There are many things that are exploiting<br />

to us and I believe that it is up to us to do all that we can to change the situation as much<br />

as we can. I believe this question to be relative to the situation and the answer can go both<br />

ways. Do these situations <strong>of</strong> exploitation equal a lack <strong>of</strong> integrity or does it depend on the<br />

situation?<br />

Hans: You are using the right methodology. Whenever an ethical question is asked, the answer is never absolute<br />

but always depends on the circumstances and the options available.<br />

Those with enough strength that they are not destroyed by the system but who draw discipline and character<br />

growth from the blows meted out, should not underestimate their collective power. If they join hands, they can be<br />

the disciplined and united counterforce that would be necessary to put an end to capitalist exploitation.<br />

Next Message by Ryoung is [52].<br />

[37] Hans: Being Discriminating Consumers is Not Enough. Chris [35] defines “exploitive”<br />

as “to use selfishly for one’s own ends.” This is a methodological individualist<br />

definition which focuses too much on the individual instead <strong>of</strong> looking at the social structure<br />

in a holistic manner.<br />

Marx says that capitalism is an exploitive system because society is split into two classes:<br />

those who control the means <strong>of</strong> production and therefore draw income from the labor <strong>of</strong> others,<br />

and those who have nothing to sell but their labor-power, and who can count themselves<br />

happy if their wages are enough so that they can pay their bills.


40 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

The wealth <strong>of</strong> the capitalists therefore does not come from them using the system selfishly,<br />

but we all live in a society which systematically distributes wealth from the majority to<br />

a small minority, and they are rich because they happen to be in that minority. They benefit<br />

from the system but they haven’t created the system. Nobody is to blame for the system; it<br />

evolved historically and it socialized those growing up in it to play a role which allows the<br />

system to reproduce itself.<br />

We were brought up to think that our role is the one <strong>of</strong> worker and consumer. Elections<br />

are basically expressions <strong>of</strong> trust into our leaders. We do not think we have a say in the<br />

overall structure <strong>of</strong> the society where we live. We don’t have the training, we were carefully<br />

taught not to take interest in such matters.<br />

Whether you shirk work or whether you brown-nose yourself to the top, a Marxist would<br />

say that these are adaptations to the system which keep the system intact. Instead <strong>of</strong> seeing<br />

themselves as paying customers, Marxists exhort the working masses to consider themselves<br />

as the rightful owners <strong>of</strong> the system. Marxists see the need to take the system back from the<br />

elite which is getting rich <strong>of</strong>f the labor <strong>of</strong> others, and which has become so greedy that it is<br />

running the system into the ground before our very eyes.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [39].<br />

[45] Andy: According to Marx I would have to say no that it is not a character flaw to be<br />

lazy in an exploitive system because he determines the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity by the amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> the labor time spent on it. Thus making the product more valuable if a laborer was lazy<br />

which makes no sense to me. So my answer would be yes that it is a character flaw to be<br />

lazy because in order to get the most production you can’t have lazy workers. In my mind<br />

being lazy doesn’t add value but takes value away from a product. The faster you can finish<br />

production the more precise a company and even society in general will be. I believe that<br />

laziness is a weakness, and can spread like wildfire, so it should be dealt with immediately<br />

once it is found.<br />

Message [45] referenced by [63]. Next Message by Andy is [51].<br />

[46] Bmellor: When we discuss character flaws we are talking about an individual who<br />

possesses imperfections or deficiencies that prevents “them” from otherwise being functional.<br />

With respect to human labor to be functional in society, Marx suggests that we must<br />

produce the commodity in a time frame that is acceptable to the public.[129:2] Time <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

gives value however the quality <strong>of</strong> labor can be judged by a time frame expectation. For<br />

example you take your car to a mechanic and he charges you an hourly rate to fix your car.<br />

You might not know how to fix the problem yourself, but prior experience or word <strong>of</strong> mouth<br />

tells you how long to expect. You are willing to pay for the labor up to that point. Once they<br />

take more time than expected, you start to question the overall quality <strong>of</strong> the work. “Did it<br />

really take 2 hours to change a spark plug?” If it really did take 2 hours is it a better job than<br />

if had only taken 20 minutes? When your car breaks down again you will take the car to a<br />

competitor that will do the same work in less time. The labor <strong>of</strong> the lazy worker produces<br />

less value per the amount <strong>of</strong> time worked than that <strong>of</strong> the faster worker.<br />

Hans: You started with question 92 but then quickly drifted over to question 95, giving a good explanation why a<br />

lazy or unskillful laborer produces less value. But I do not really see a contribution to the ongoing discussion about<br />

92.<br />

Next Message by Bmellor is [81].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 41<br />

Question 95 is 68 in 2002fa, 72 in 2003fa, 82 in 2004fa, 80 in 2005fa, 93 in 2007SP, 93<br />

in 2008fa, 100 in 2010fa, and 118 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 95 Imagine you were studying Marxism together with a friend, and the friend said<br />

to you: Doesn’t the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value imply that, the more lazy and inept the laborer, the<br />

more valuable his commodity would be? How would you answer your friend?<br />

[41] Srichardson: graded B– studying marxism with a friend. I would point out to my<br />

friend that Marxian argument establishes a difference between quantitative and qualitative<br />

values. Marx says that “If we then disregard the use-value <strong>of</strong> commodities, they have one<br />

property left, that <strong>of</strong> being products <strong>of</strong> labor.” [128:2] I believe Marx is making a wrong<br />

statement in order to make his argument stronger. That there is a difference between these<br />

types <strong>of</strong> value and to show that use value is important in bringing forth its value.<br />

If a lazy inept worker spends more time on a product, the product’s use value is not<br />

increased, because it doesn’t add additional value beyond the use value <strong>of</strong> a more productive<br />

worker.<br />

Hans: You are working on it, but you haven’t digested it all. You are right, Marx establishes a difference between<br />

two kinds <strong>of</strong> value: but they should not be called qualitative and quantitative values, but use-value and exchangevalue.<br />

In your second paragraph you give the neoclassical, not the Marxian answer as I tried to explain in [42].<br />

Next Message by Srichardson is [69].<br />

[42] Hans: Of course a lazy worker does not produce more value. Marxist economists<br />

and neoclassical or mainstream economists have no disagreement here. It is simply a matter<br />

<strong>of</strong> common sense. An unskillful or lazy worker does not produce more value than a skilled<br />

and dexterous worker. Why would anyone ever bring this up as an issue?<br />

Unfortunately, this agreement does not go very deep, because if you ask a neoclassical<br />

economist why the slow and unskillful laborer does not produce more value, he will give a<br />

different answer than a Marxist. The neoclassical economist would say: the value which the<br />

consumer pays for is the use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity, and this use-value is the same whether<br />

it is produced by a slow worker or by a fast worker.<br />

This is where the Marxist economist disagrees. The Marxist economist says: you cannot<br />

throw use-value and exchange-value into the same pot like this! Of course the use-value <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity is an important factor in the purchase decision. But when the cashier adds<br />

up the prices in the check-out line, he or she does not add use-values, but these prices are<br />

determined by the labor-times in the products.<br />

Only at this point, if you concede to the Marxist that exchange-value comes from labor<br />

and not from use-value, does the lazy worker become an issue. It is simply the issue how the<br />

labor is measured. One cannot just use a stopwatch and measure the actual labor time that<br />

was needed to produce that product. Instead, one has to use the socially necessary labortime,<br />

i.e., the time which this product would take under the average conditions and with<br />

up-to-date technology.<br />

Why does a Marxist insist that you should not throw use-value and exchange-value together?<br />

Because if you do this, you deny that every laborer, when they work, add value to the<br />

product. The capitalists, <strong>of</strong> course, do not want to admit that all the value <strong>of</strong> their products,


42 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

including that part <strong>of</strong> the value which they stick into their pocket as pr<strong>of</strong>its, was produced<br />

by the laborers whom they have hired at a low wage.<br />

Message [42] referenced by [41] and [329]. Next Message by Hans is [44].<br />

[63] Hans: Marx supporting a bunch <strong>of</strong> lazy rascals. When I formulated this question I<br />

thought I was making up a hypothetical situation for didactical reasons only. I never expected<br />

anyone in real life to read about Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value and to actually say: “this theory<br />

does not make sense because it says that being lazy creates value.”<br />

Well, Andy’s [45] says exactly that in his essay about whether it is a character flaw to be<br />

lazy. And to top it <strong>of</strong>f, with impeccable logic, Andy continues: ergo it is not a character flaw<br />

to be lazy, because being lazy creates value.<br />

I suspect that Andy’s submission was meant as a polemic against Marx. Andy thinks<br />

Marx developed the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value to support workers, i.e., Andy makes the error<br />

I tried to explain in [62]. And Andy tries to show us where one ends up if one supports<br />

workers, namely, one ends up supporting laziness. In that respect it was a masterful and<br />

quite funny “immanent critique,” i.e., Andy criticizes Marx’s pro-working-class stance by<br />

pointing out the inner contradictions <strong>of</strong> such a point <strong>of</strong> view.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [64].<br />

Question 96 is 54 in 1997WI, 53 in 1997ut, 68 in 2001fa, 81 in 2005fa, and 120 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 96 How can labor-time be the measure <strong>of</strong> value, <strong>of</strong> a social quantity, if it seems<br />

the private matter <strong>of</strong> the producer whether he or she spends much or little time, and others<br />

may not even know?<br />

[315] Jason: Even though Labor time is defined as the amount <strong>of</strong> time and effort that<br />

went into making a product, according to Marx that is not exactly the measure a society<br />

typically uses. Once there is a large enough market for an item, and in a fairly large society<br />

that doesn’t take too much time at all, a socially acceptable amount <strong>of</strong> labor time arises.<br />

This is usually an average amount <strong>of</strong> time that it takes to make the product. Since all the<br />

competitors making this product do it independently, they have to make their products as<br />

quickly as everyone else or risk losing money for how much labor they inputted. The value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the product is therefore determined not by the labor time put into each individual product,<br />

but by the social average labor time put into that type <strong>of</strong> product.<br />

If a private producer discovered a more efficient method for creating a product, this would<br />

eventually lead to a socially acceptable labor time that is less. This would require all the<br />

other producers to either adapt this new technology or some other more efficient method.<br />

Otherwise their product would be overpriced and consumers would opt to go for the cheaper<br />

alternative.<br />

Next Message by Jason is [318].<br />

[327] Papageorgio: Commodity production. Let me start with a quote from [2001fa:169-<br />

4], “In a capitalist society, laziness and thoroughness may have the same reward when judged<br />

against the standard <strong>of</strong> socially necessary labor.” In a market system this question can arise<br />

with some difficulties. Marx feels that the labor someone puts in, for example the hand<br />

weavers in the example in our reading, is judged according to the socially necessary labor


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 43<br />

time. Not per se an average <strong>of</strong> the times but the socially necessary labor time, which is the<br />

time <strong>of</strong> the new, or faster way, which in our reading was the power loom. So as we can<br />

see value is determined by the social necessary labor time, such as the power loom, not the<br />

individual’s labor time. It is important to note as Marx did that the concrete labor is not<br />

what is giving the product its value but the abstract labor. The brain, muscle, nerves, are all<br />

working on the project each contributing, but just because someone is working longer does<br />

not mean their product is better, especially if I can create a similar product or subsitute for<br />

less time. I also now that I relook over the question enjoy the part that says, “others may not<br />

even know.” This is also evidence that well frankly when I go to the store I do not know who<br />

put the most time in the product Pepsi, or Coca Cola, and therefore it does not affect my<br />

decision. What if Coke was able to find an innovative way to create their beverage with less<br />

time than Pepsi but told no one and just started charging less because they were able to do<br />

so with their innovation, Pepsi would see the price dropping and would need to follow suit.<br />

This made a lot <strong>of</strong> sense in my head I hope I wrote it out right there. Marx and our readings<br />

definetly help us to realize once again that it is abstract labor that plays a part in the value<br />

here not necessarily the concrete labor.<br />

Next Message by Papageorgio is [487].<br />

[329] Khwai: graded A Labor-time as a measure <strong>of</strong> value. Labor-time is one <strong>of</strong> the<br />

few quantitative measures we have to measure the abstract human labor contained within a<br />

commodity and the social relationship between laborers, commodities, and consumers when<br />

an exchange takes place. We are faced with a dilemma in measuring labor-time as all laborers<br />

are not equally efficient. If a highly efficient laborer were to create a table in less<br />

time than an average worker who in turn creates the table in less time than an inefficient<br />

worker how would we quantify the labor-time used in creation <strong>of</strong> the three tables and their<br />

value? In 129:2 Marx acknowledges that some may think using labor-time to quantify value<br />

rewards the inefficient worker. He continues to clarify that the labor and labor-time we are<br />

considering is in fact “equal human labor, expenditure <strong>of</strong> the same human labor-power”.<br />

Hans continues further in [42] as the labor-time we are measuring is the “socially necessary<br />

labor-time” or “labor-time necessary the time which this product would take under the average<br />

conditions and with up-to-date technology.” Therefore the labor value contained in all<br />

three tables would be equal even though the amount <strong>of</strong> time expended by all three laborers<br />

in creating it would not – because we are in fact measuring the socially necessary labor-time<br />

and not the number <strong>of</strong> minutes or hours an individual worker needs to create a table.<br />

Throughout his writings Marx stresses the importance <strong>of</strong> looking at the social relationships<br />

between individuals as opposed to the individuals themselves. Labor-time is a socially<br />

necessary quantity as all value is created by labor or in other words price is not set, as the<br />

capitalist would argue, by the use-value a consumer places on an object but by the labor<br />

value contained within. Although others within society may not know the exact amount <strong>of</strong><br />

time invested in creating a single table, they will know the social standard <strong>of</strong> the necessary<br />

labor-time and hence the labor value <strong>of</strong> said table. In our example <strong>of</strong> the three workers the<br />

efficient worker is exerting more labor power per unit <strong>of</strong> time when compared to the less<br />

efficient workers. As others adapt and become equally efficient via improved technique or<br />

technology the socially necessary labor-time to create a table and the labor-value contained


44 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

within the table is redefined allowing labor-time to be a continually valid measure <strong>of</strong> value<br />

within society.<br />

Hans: Knowledge about labor time also seeps into the market through the pricing behavior. If your competitor<br />

<strong>of</strong>fers the good at a price which would bankrupt you, then you know he has figured out a cheaper way to produce<br />

it.<br />

Next Message by Khwai is [338].<br />

[331] Spawnblade: Labor time can be the measure <strong>of</strong> value in a very simple manner.<br />

Society doesn’t measure the value <strong>of</strong> the product by the labor-time <strong>of</strong> the individual, but by<br />

the socially necessary labor-time. Taken from this perspective, there are two scenarios.<br />

Scenario A: Worker spends four hours mowing his client’s lawn. In this situation the<br />

client knows how long he is spending, and if he is paying him by the hour he is sure to<br />

find someone who will do it in less time. This means the worker will most likely adjust<br />

his time to try and be on a competitive level. Thereby conforming to the socially necessary<br />

labor-time.<br />

Scenario B: Potter John spends four hours on a cup that takes other potters two hours.<br />

Because he spent four hours on it, he himself charges $45 for his work. However Potter<br />

Steve across the street (Due to the consistent assumption in Capitalism that the market is<br />

perfectly competitive) completed two <strong>of</strong> his cups in four hours. Potter Steve will either sell<br />

his for the amount <strong>of</strong> time he spent, assuming he feels that his labor time is the equivalent per<br />

hour <strong>of</strong> Johns, in which case he’d have two cups for $22.50, or he’ll undercut him slightly<br />

so he’ll barely be ahead <strong>of</strong> John. However John will then undercut in order to actually sell<br />

his cup, and this spiral will continue until they reach the level where they feel they will not<br />

go below in selling their wares.<br />

In this manner labor-time becomes the measure <strong>of</strong> value because people are forced to<br />

work faster and harder in order to compete with others, until they reach a point where they<br />

are unable to go faster or harder. And then what they are left with is the value. This is the<br />

basic structure which leads to the lowering <strong>of</strong> value for an increased production, thereby<br />

further lowering the value. But alas I am beginning to go in circles now.<br />

Hans: This is the right answer. In your second paragraph, there is not a race to some “reservation price” or to zero<br />

markup over cost, but where the markup is similar to what is available in other industries.<br />

Next Message by Spawnblade is [334].<br />

[366] Andy: In Class answer:<br />

Labor time can be the measure <strong>of</strong> value for an individual because the individual knows<br />

how much time he or she spent on it therefore making its value different for each individual.<br />

But in a social quality it differs because humans are capable <strong>of</strong> doing similar things. For<br />

instance I may be able to finish making a blanket faster than another guy, making our own<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> value different, but in the social aspect the value is the same because we both<br />

produced blankets that provided people with the same thing.<br />

Response answer:<br />

Social labor time indicates that it is not identical to the labor-time actually used. Labortime<br />

that is measured in a social quantity forces everyone to hurry up because everyone has<br />

to meet some minimum standards, causing everyone to be like everyone else, preventing


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 45<br />

individual unique contributions from being recognized. However, instead <strong>of</strong> forcing everybody<br />

to work like everybody else, the goal must be to elicit the unique contributions. So<br />

value can be created by the uniqueness <strong>of</strong> the product, not just the matter <strong>of</strong> how much time<br />

was put into it.<br />

Next Message by Andy is [368].<br />

[407] SnatchimusMaximus: content B+ late penalty 1% Society’s process <strong>of</strong> assigning<br />

value to goods and services consequently establishes socially accepted norms pertaining to<br />

quality. Thus value becomes the reified expression <strong>of</strong> society’s expectations. Ultimately,<br />

labor-time imputes only as much value as utility that is added. Hence, value is derived from<br />

the quality <strong>of</strong> labor rather than the quantity <strong>of</strong> labor. Norms become king in a social context<br />

and the quantity <strong>of</strong> labor-time contributions becomes subjugated to society’s expectations <strong>of</strong><br />

value.<br />

Hans: It is not part <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory that “ultimately, labor-time imputes only as much value as utility that is<br />

added.” Neoclassical economics says that, but not Marx. Marx says that the utility <strong>of</strong> a thing determines how much<br />

is produced, and the cost <strong>of</strong> a thing to society (labor) ultimately determines its price.<br />

Individual producers try to escape this iron bond between price and labor-time by finding that niche, that quality<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor which is rewarded more by the market. Marx says that these efforts to beat the law <strong>of</strong> value end up enforcing<br />

it. See Rey’s [211] about this.<br />

Next Message by SnatchimusMaximus is [409].<br />

Question 98 is 83 in 2005fa, 96 in 2007SP, 96 in 2008fa, and 103 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 98 The value <strong>of</strong> the product is determined by the socially necessary labor-time.<br />

What are the implications <strong>of</strong> this for a capitalist supervising his employees?<br />

[61] Jenn: graded B Marx defines the “value” <strong>of</strong> a commodity as how much labor was<br />

used in the production <strong>of</strong> the commodity. To clarify, Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> value differs from<br />

that <strong>of</strong> neoclassical economics. “Value” according to neoclassical economics would most<br />

likely be associated with the price <strong>of</strong> the commodity based on the law <strong>of</strong> supply and demand<br />

rather than the labor-time.<br />

Hans: Marx’s concept <strong>of</strong> value is definitely associated with the price <strong>of</strong> the commodity. The difference between<br />

Marx and Neoclassical economics is that Marx says that the long run price (i.e., what he calls ”value”) is determined<br />

by labor content, while neoclassical economics says it is determined by demand and supply. As I said in [62], for<br />

Marx the long run supply curve is horizontal.<br />

Using Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> value, this would obviously imply that a capitalist would want<br />

their employee’s labor-time to be lower than the socially necessary labor time. This is the<br />

essence <strong>of</strong> a capitalist model. The natural response <strong>of</strong> the capitalist supervisor would be<br />

to encourage (or in some cases force) the employees to produce more in less time. On<br />

the surface, it appears this could be accomplished by requiring employees to work longer<br />

hours for the same pay. Upon further examination however, one might notice a decrease in<br />

efficiency or quality as a result <strong>of</strong> these longer hours. One might argue that the capitalist<br />

might not achieve a labor-time any lower than the “socially necessary labor-time,” but may<br />

cause greater social harm through the methods they used in their futile attempt to achieve<br />

their goal.<br />

Next Message by Jenn is [120].


46 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Question 107 is 45 in 1995WI, 54 in 1995ut, 56 in 1996sp, 60 in 1997WI, 63 in 1997sp, 59<br />

in 1997ut, 79 in 2002fa, 81 in 2003fa, 90 in 2005fa, 104 in 2007SP, 105 in 2008fa, 112<br />

in 2010fa, and 131 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 107 How is the value <strong>of</strong> raw materials determined in Marx’s theory? How does<br />

the scarcity <strong>of</strong> these materials influence their value? Is Marx’s argument still valid in the<br />

case <strong>of</strong> an exhaustible resource, which is present only in finite supply?<br />

[47] Gerund: Raw Materials. In Marx’s theory, the value <strong>of</strong> raw materials is determined<br />

by the labor-time required to find them and extract them from the earth. This would include<br />

the labor necessary to break them into a saleable form. For example, copper when extracted<br />

from the earth is encrusted with other useless rock, and has to be removed from the other<br />

rock. Copper has no use-value until this step is completed.<br />

Scarce materials take a great deal more labor to find, and typically when found the desired<br />

material to useless rock ratio is much worse, so they take more labor to break into saleable<br />

form.<br />

Hans: What about exhaustible resources?<br />

Next Message by Gerund is [48].<br />

[56] Samantha: Sweat and Tears is what should raise the price. The value <strong>of</strong> raw<br />

materials, as mentioned by Gerund, is the labor-time required by the workers who must labor<br />

to discover and extract them. The scarcity <strong>of</strong> these materials according to Marx should only<br />

matter in the way that this may require workers to work harder in order to find and produce<br />

them, so instead <strong>of</strong> pricing the resources based on scarcity they would be priced based on<br />

the difficulty <strong>of</strong> the labor <strong>of</strong> the worker. The exhaustible resource would not change in Marx<br />

theory, it isn’t that it’s a material that makes it valuable in his mind, it is valuable because<br />

people toiled to find, remove and labor with it.<br />

Message [56] referenced by [62]. Next Message by Samantha is [215].<br />

[62] Hans: Important, please read. Samantha [56] thinks that the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value<br />

represents Marx’s idea how prices should be determined. This is a basic misunderstanding.<br />

Please take the time to understand this, this is important. Marx thinks that in a capitalist<br />

society prices are determined by labor content. The reason is simple: labor costs are the<br />

only costs which society has to bear; everything else is free. Nature does not charge for the<br />

useful properties <strong>of</strong> steel or oil or fish in the ocean. This is why the market value <strong>of</strong> these<br />

things is determined by the labor necessary to extract them from the earth and not by some<br />

intrinsic value <strong>of</strong> the materials themselves. And when Marx uses the word “value” he means<br />

the market value, i.e., the center <strong>of</strong> gravity where prices settle down in the long run.<br />

How does this differ from the determination <strong>of</strong> prices by supply and demand? Marx<br />

does not believe that the long run supply curve is upward sloping. If more <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

is needed, then more will be produced, without an increase in prices. In other words, the<br />

supply curve is horizontal. The location <strong>of</strong> the demand curve therefore only determines how<br />

much is produced, but not the price.<br />

We all know that Marx is critical <strong>of</strong> capitalism and says that the workers in capitalism<br />

are exploited. How does this fit together with his theory that capitalist prices are determined<br />

by labor content? Here one has to distinguish between the value the workers create through<br />

their labor and the value the workers get for their labor (i.e., their wages). Although labor


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 47<br />

creates all value, the laborer in capitalism does not get paid an equivalent <strong>of</strong> the value he or<br />

she produces, but a much smaller amount, just enough for them to pay their bills until the<br />

next paycheck. The capitalists get the rest, because they control the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Message [62] referenced by [61], [63], [67], [166], [174], [199], and [495]. Next Message by Hans is [63].<br />

Question 121 is 124 in 2009fa and 127 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 121 Marx says in 133:1 that it does not matter for the use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat<br />

whether it is worn by the tailor or by someone else. Is this correct for every use-value?<br />

If you write a computer program for yourself then you <strong>of</strong>ten obey different principles than if<br />

you write it for others to use. A program which “works for me” is <strong>of</strong>ten poorly documented<br />

and does not consider all the possible situations which different users <strong>of</strong> the program might<br />

find themselves in.<br />

[59] Matt: Use-value, produced for one’s self. If something is produced it should have<br />

a use-value otherwise it would not be produced in the first place. Marx says a coat produced<br />

has a use-value whether or not the person who consumes the coat has also produced it.<br />

Even if the coat is self-consumed by the producer and it does not technically have a trade<br />

“value”, it still has a purpose. Therefore, I personally believe that if something produced has<br />

a purpose it should indeed have a use-value. In this case there is a value to the producer <strong>of</strong><br />

the coat since it keeps him warm from the cold. As Marx says, it makes no difference to the<br />

coat whether it’s worn by the producer or a customer.<br />

Another example would be if I had eyeglasses produced just for my eyes. Even though<br />

I am the only person that can use them they still have a use-value since they help me see.<br />

And since I am able to see I can be a productive individual in the workforce. So, as long<br />

as something has a useful purpose, whether it’s by the producer or by the consumer, it will<br />

always have a use-value.<br />

Hans: The question was not whether the coat is a use-value, but whether the specialization <strong>of</strong> the producer is one<br />

<strong>of</strong> the basic requirements <strong>of</strong> production. Please look at the context <strong>of</strong> these questions in Marx’s text when you<br />

attempt to answer them.<br />

Next Message by Matt is [94].<br />

[64] Hans: The Free S<strong>of</strong>tware Movement. I added this question because the Free S<strong>of</strong>tware<br />

Movement is an important evolution <strong>of</strong> society-wide co-operation which has important<br />

implications for our ideas <strong>of</strong> socialism. Computer programmers are systematically sharing<br />

their programs so that they do not have to re-invent the wheel, and they are skillfully using<br />

copyright laws, or, as they call it, “copyleft”, the Gnu Public License (GPL), to keep their<br />

work public and to prevent its privatization.<br />

Millions <strong>of</strong> programmers work together world wide without boss and without coercion.<br />

They build incredibly complex systems, and the quality <strong>of</strong> their product is so high that the<br />

biggest commercial s<strong>of</strong>tware vendors have difficulies keeping up with them. This is the<br />

pro<strong>of</strong> that high complexity wants to be organized democratically, not in the hierarchical and<br />

secretive structure preferred by capitalist businesses.<br />

In a development which Marx did not anticipate, use-values gain an important social dimension.<br />

These s<strong>of</strong>tware systems must be engineered from the beginning to be modular and


48 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

extensible, and the individual components must have a clean enough structure that someone<br />

who did not write them can still understand them and adapt them to evolving needs.<br />

These programmers produce code, not coats. But the code which someone would write<br />

for their own use, to solve a specific problem, is quite different than the code which would<br />

be acceptable by one <strong>of</strong> the big s<strong>of</strong>tware projects, be it apache or firefox, the linux kernel, or<br />

even the much smaller code base for the mailman mailing list manager used in this class.<br />

I.e., this is an example where the use-value is quite different if you produce something<br />

for yourself than if you contribute it to one <strong>of</strong> the versatile applications which everybody<br />

can download and install on their computers. Participation in such free s<strong>of</strong>tware projects has<br />

created a completely new culture, in which everybody is acutely aware whenever they write<br />

a line <strong>of</strong> code that they are not alone, but that this is just one link in a big system, much more<br />

powerful than any individual could ever conceive by themselves.<br />

Had Marx witnessed this, he would probably have used it as additional evidence against<br />

rigid division <strong>of</strong> labor and specialization. If thousands co-operate, even if they work on the<br />

project only a few hours every week, they can achieve much more than one person who is<br />

forced to specialize on the same thing 24/7.<br />

Message [64] referenced by [68], [72], [73], [139], [2009fa:31], and [2009fa:41]. Next Message by Hans is [67].<br />

[68] Brandon: graded A Free s<strong>of</strong>tware great, but not always. There is no doubt that<br />

free-s<strong>of</strong>tware has progressed the use-value <strong>of</strong> the electronic age. Instead <strong>of</strong> relying on the<br />

lone genius to formulate a solution to a general problem, regardless <strong>of</strong> how unimportant, individuals<br />

are given free access to express and contribute to a joint effort by other individuals<br />

to solve said problem. Hans stated in [64]:<br />

“They build incredibly complex systems, and the quality <strong>of</strong> their product<br />

is so high that the biggest commercial s<strong>of</strong>tware vendors have difficulies<br />

keeping up with them. This is the pro<strong>of</strong> that high complexity wants to<br />

be organized democratically, not in the hierarchical and secretive structure<br />

preferred by capitalist businesses.”<br />

While I do not disagree with this statement, I believe this statement gives too much credit<br />

to free-s<strong>of</strong>tware as being a better alternative to priced s<strong>of</strong>tware. I’d like to use the example<br />

<strong>of</strong> the wiki s<strong>of</strong>tware (wikipedia.org); that being a client-side s<strong>of</strong>tware in which any user may<br />

write, contribute, and/or link any article regarding any topic, without proper fact checking<br />

implements installed. While its intentions are that there is not one consensus <strong>of</strong> ideas, but<br />

rather a collection <strong>of</strong> different viewpoints to create a more accurate database <strong>of</strong> ideas, there<br />

are many inherent problems with the s<strong>of</strong>tware. Often, there are not enough relevant or<br />

credible sources contributing to articles thereby causing the articles themselves to not be<br />

credible sources <strong>of</strong> information.<br />

While the wiki is a good source for ‘quick information or reference’, it lacks a hierarchical<br />

structure that allows for proper fact checking which in turn prevents it from becoming a<br />

credible s<strong>of</strong>tware for users. It is my belief that this causes its use-value to be less than, say,<br />

the use-value <strong>of</strong> an online database like Britannica would have. They both perform the same<br />

functions: a user types in a keyword about, for example, forks and is redirecting to an article<br />

describing the history, function, etymology, etc about forks. However, the user knows that


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 49<br />

the information collected from the wiki s<strong>of</strong>tware is less credible than that <strong>of</strong> Britannica. The<br />

user cannot cite wikipedia in a paper he/she is writing about forks, therefore reducing the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> the wiki s<strong>of</strong>tware.<br />

“Had Marx witnessed this, he would probably have used it as additional<br />

evidence against rigid division <strong>of</strong> labor and specialization. If thousands cooperate,<br />

even if they work on the project only a fewhours every week, they<br />

can achieve much more than one person who is forced to specialize on the<br />

same thing 24/7.” (Hans, [64] )<br />

I agree with this statement completely. It is arrogant presumption that a select few can<br />

produce a greater tool to fit the needs <strong>of</strong> a society rather than the collection <strong>of</strong> ideas and<br />

experiences <strong>of</strong> a society. However, I do believe that there still must be a form <strong>of</strong> checks and<br />

balances that do not allow for this cooperation to inadvertanly diminish the use-value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

product, as in the case <strong>of</strong> the wiki s<strong>of</strong>tware.<br />

Message [68] referenced by [70], [72], and [73]. Next Message by Brandon is [128].<br />

[70] Hans: Accuracy <strong>of</strong> Wikipedia. Wikipedia is an excellent example <strong>of</strong> non-hierarchical<br />

co-operation, which few people would have expected to work, but which nevertheless is doing<br />

amazingly well. There is a big scientific debate regarding the accuracy <strong>of</strong> Wikipedia. The<br />

most famous article about it is a 2005 study by Nature which says that, although Wikipedia<br />

is not quite as good as Encyclopedia Britannica, it is certainly in the same league.<br />

http://www.nature.com/nature/journal/v438/n7070/full/438900a.html<br />

If Brandon says in [68] that one should not cite Wikipedia, this is not an argument against<br />

Wikipedia per se but is true for any encyclopedia article. Of course, there have been attempts<br />

to abuse the Wikipedia model, a model which seems to invite abuse, and Wikipedia had to<br />

put some safeguards in place. But the dire predictions that the abuse would swamp the good<br />

energy coming from unrestrained co-operation have not materialized.<br />

Brandon’s objections are thoughtful and valid, but I think they are issues which Wikipedia<br />

is trying to work on and which can in principle be resolved. It is difficult to say whether any<br />

given problem is a wrinkle which can be ironed out or whether it signals a basic flaw <strong>of</strong><br />

the model. We are not used to this new non-hierarchical model, we are just starting to gain<br />

experiences with it and to address its specific pitfalls. Therefore I am inclined to give it a lot<br />

<strong>of</strong> credit. Wikipedia is one <strong>of</strong> the, if not the, single most used reference site on the web, and<br />

my own experiences have been generally positive.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [71].<br />

[72] Lev: Free s<strong>of</strong>tware, Free Society. By way <strong>of</strong> introduction to this topic I have been<br />

an administrator <strong>of</strong> free and open-source s<strong>of</strong>tware (FOSS) systems for some years now. I am<br />

currently the public <strong>of</strong>ficer for Linux User Victoria (cf., www.luv.org.au), and work for the<br />

Victorian Partnership for Advanced Computing (cf., www.vpac.org) whose machines have<br />

been among the most powerful in the world (cf., www.top500.org). I also contribute quite<br />

regularly to Wikipedia.<br />

If I may first respond to Brandon’s comments [68], Wikipedia does have a hierarchial<br />

structure with multiple levels <strong>of</strong> editors. It does have a dispute resolution process, it does


50 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

have fact-checking (note the “citation needed” tags), it does have internal debates, and so<br />

forth. When compared to a commercial product, such as the Encyclopedia Britannica, it<br />

compares quite well. An article in Nature in 2005 reviewing science articles showed that<br />

Wikipedia was “not quite” as accurate as Britannica, but certainly within the same ballpark<br />

figure - this is particularly important to consider that Britannica has been produced<br />

encyclopedia material since 1768, has 19 full-time editors and 4,000 expert contributors. In<br />

contrast Wikipedia was launched a mere seven years ago and has 1400 administrators.<br />

The free and open-content policy <strong>of</strong> Wikipedia does mean that it is prone to vandalism,<br />

trolling, advertising and so forth, but these are usually <strong>of</strong> a short-term nature.<br />

Now if I may respond to Hans’ comments [64] on the same subject I must at first concur<br />

with his noting <strong>of</strong> the widespread use <strong>of</strong> free and open-source s<strong>of</strong>tware. Most websites<br />

are build on a combination <strong>of</strong> a FOSS operating systems (such as Linux, FreeBSD etc) and<br />

FOSS webservers (over 65% use Apache for example). Supercomputers, clusters, grid computing<br />

and scientific applications almost invariably use FOSS systems. Heck, this mailing<br />

list is entirely generated on FOSS s<strong>of</strong>tware.<br />

Nevertheless it is somewhat idealised to suggest that FOSS projects are a community<br />

<strong>of</strong> disparate programmers working together “without boss and without coercion”. A great<br />

deal <strong>of</strong> FOSS development occurs within a standard capitalist environment or, is sponsored<br />

through educational institutions funded by public monies. They have timetables, they have<br />

bosses, they have a all the trappings and behaviour <strong>of</strong> a standard capitalist enterprise.<br />

A critical difference is that it just works better. With particular levels <strong>of</strong> complexity monopolisation<br />

<strong>of</strong> knowledge retards future development. FOSS is able to bypass this problem<br />

and because the material is sufficiently complex to begin with, any potential monopoly pr<strong>of</strong>its<br />

lost to an individual firm by making it open source are less than the potential gains made<br />

by inviting extra expertise to assist with the project.<br />

As a closing note I highly recommend Richard Stallman’s collection <strong>of</strong> essays on the Free<br />

S<strong>of</strong>tware movement. It is available (freely <strong>of</strong> course) at the following:<br />

Free S<strong>of</strong>tware, Free Society: Selected Essays <strong>of</strong> Richard M. Stallman<br />

http://notabug.com/2002/rms-essays.pdf<br />

Message [72] referenced by [76]. Next Message by Lev is [83].<br />

[73] Mitternacht: graded A Open source - left? As an open source hobbyist I was<br />

excited to see a question related to this topic. Hans’ message [64] mentioned the “copyleft”<br />

Gnu Public License to keep code public and not privatized. Prior to this I had not given much<br />

consideration to some <strong>of</strong> the larger socio-economic issues surrounding open source s<strong>of</strong>tware.<br />

I had simply viewed open source s<strong>of</strong>tware as an alternative to private s<strong>of</strong>tware which has<br />

been force fed to so many <strong>of</strong> us. Open source s<strong>of</strong>tware allows for more collaboration and<br />

input which lends itself to meeting the needs <strong>of</strong> a larger group <strong>of</strong> people as well as creating<br />

a higher quality product - I particularly liked Brandon’s [68] statement on this subject: “it<br />

is an arrogant presumption that a select few can produce a greater tool to fit the needs <strong>of</strong> a<br />

society rather than a collection <strong>of</strong> ideas and experiences <strong>of</strong> a society.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 51<br />

The open source movement has gained a lot <strong>of</strong> steam over the last few years - companies<br />

like Dell are even selling PCs with Linux operating systems pre-installed, but not everyone<br />

is jumping on the bandwagon. There are many s<strong>of</strong>tware companies that stand to lose and are<br />

losing a lot <strong>of</strong> money to the open source movement. There is even a right wing think tank<br />

called the Alexis de Tocqueville Institute which dedicates a lot <strong>of</strong> its time to discrediting<br />

open source s<strong>of</strong>tware, in particular Linux. In an article by the group’s founder, Ken Brown,<br />

titled “Intellectual Property - Left?” (http://www.adti.net/ip/laches.050405.pdf) allegations<br />

are made that open source programmers engage in all sorts <strong>of</strong> nefarious activities such as<br />

stealing source code (“intellectual property”) to create their s<strong>of</strong>tware. What is not mentioned<br />

on anywhere on the Alexis de Tocqueville Institute’s website is that most <strong>of</strong> its funding<br />

comes from very large private businesses, particularly <strong>of</strong> note is Micros<strong>of</strong>t.<br />

Marx states that it is not necessary for someone to be specialized in the production <strong>of</strong><br />

a particular commodity in order for the commodity to be produced, and that the relation<br />

between said commodity and the labour that produced it doesn’t change when production <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity becomes specialized. The quality <strong>of</strong> the commodity is not brought into the<br />

equation in the particular case presented by Marx - obviously a coat made by a tailor would<br />

be <strong>of</strong> much higher quality than a coat produced by “humans who tailored thousands <strong>of</strong> years<br />

before anyone became a tailor”, but the end result was still a coat nonetheless. The same<br />

reasoning extends to writing a computer program - obviously the s<strong>of</strong>tware produced will<br />

be <strong>of</strong> greater use and more efficient if produced by group <strong>of</strong> people specialized in writing<br />

s<strong>of</strong>tware code, but s<strong>of</strong>tware produced by a neophyte programmer is still s<strong>of</strong>tware.<br />

Hans: I am glad that you are bringing the discussion back to Marx’s text. You are right, the coat may be <strong>of</strong> a<br />

greater quality if the tailor has to specialize his whole life on coats. But perhaps society wants to forego this last bit<br />

<strong>of</strong> efficiency if it means the crippling <strong>of</strong> its laborers. Instead <strong>of</strong> specializing individual laborers, much more mileage<br />

can be gained by innovative modes <strong>of</strong> co-operation involving large numbers <strong>of</strong> laborers.<br />

Next Message by Mitternacht is [137].<br />

[76] Hans: Hierarchy. In response to Lev’s [72] that FOSS projects do have bosses,<br />

I agree that there is leadership in the FOSS movement. But this leadership is based on<br />

authority which the leaders have earned in the co-operation itself, instead <strong>of</strong> being imposed<br />

by an outside structure. Marx writes in chapter Thirteen, 450:1/o:<br />

It is not because he is a leader <strong>of</strong> industry that a man is a capitalist; on the<br />

contrary, he is a leader <strong>of</strong> industry because he is a capitalist.<br />

and a page earlier, in 449:1/o he calls the authority <strong>of</strong> the capitalist the power <strong>of</strong> an alien<br />

will. This is an important criticism <strong>of</strong> the capitalist’s leadership role. Something like this<br />

has very practical implications; one <strong>of</strong> the unexpected benefits when Netscape opened up<br />

the code for its browser was that they were able to hire the best programmers.<br />

Another issue related to all this is the One Laptop per Child project, a wonderful project<br />

designed to help children in the poor countries, which in my view is also very revolutionary.<br />

Little surprise that it has been shamefully undercut by Micros<strong>of</strong>t and Intel. Here is a good<br />

in-depth presentation about their goals and their technology:<br />

http://www.olpctalks.com/ivan krsti/ivan krstic at google.html


52 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

We could continue talking about FOSS for a long time. But if you want to make additional<br />

comments, they must be under question 888, and they will be counted as general discussion,<br />

not as homework answers. We have to move on, there is a lot more interesting stuff in Marx.<br />

Message [76] referenced by [83]. Next Message by Hans is [82].<br />

[83] Lev: Hierarchy. In response to Hans [76] I feel that you misunderstand me. I have<br />

no confusion between the difference between leadership, hierarchy and capitalist ownership<br />

<strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production. Yes, it is true, a significant amount <strong>of</strong> FOSS is produced in<br />

an environment where there is a hierarchy but no capitalists, in the manner you describe.<br />

However, it is false to suggest that all FOSS projects are like this. Indeed, it would be an<br />

interesting excersise to see what proportion actually are carried out as free coooperation and<br />

what are carried out as capitalist enterprises.<br />

Take for example, OpenOffice.org which began with Sun Microsystems released its code<br />

to the community. Significant contributions to that code are now provided by Novell. Similar<br />

comments can be made concerning Novell’s Evolution, a person information manager and<br />

mail-client or their distribution <strong>of</strong> Linux (SuSE).<br />

Whilst the formal structure <strong>of</strong> these projects is <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> a free and cooperative<br />

system with a democratic hierarchy (indeed more <strong>of</strong>ten by the person who puts their hand<br />

up), a great deal <strong>of</strong> the contribution is made, as I said, in a formal capitalist environment.<br />

In a owner and worker environment (mediated by managers) the capitalist tells the worker<br />

to write the code, the capitalist sets the timetable, and the worker receives payment for their<br />

wage labour in return.<br />

Now one may ask why a capitalist would pay a worker to contribute to an freee and opensource<br />

project when they do not receive direct compensation for this? The general answer<br />

is for market share - it is Novell’s interests (for example) that more people use Evolution,<br />

OpenOffice and SuSE Linux than Outlook, Micros<strong>of</strong>t Office and MS-Windows. Despite the<br />

fact they have given the product away, despite the fact the source is free and open, they can<br />

claim expertise and receive the consultant dollars when asked questions <strong>of</strong> implementing the<br />

s<strong>of</strong>tware in a large corporate environment, train staff and so forth.<br />

Again these actions occur in a standard capitalist fashion; the worker is actually the one<br />

who provides the knowledge, communicates their knowledge, trains the staff and receives<br />

wage compensation under the timetable set by the capitalists’ proxy, management. However,<br />

this is conduced under the title <strong>of</strong> the enterprise, and a portion <strong>of</strong> their work is expropriated<br />

from the capitalist as pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Hans: Thank you for the clarification. Point well taken.<br />

First Message by Lev is [7].<br />

Question 127 is 55 in 1995WI, 66 in 1996ut, 69 in 1997ut, 86 in 2000fa, 93 in 2002fa,<br />

121 in 2007SP, and 125 in 2008fa:<br />

Question 127 Saying that labor is the source <strong>of</strong> all wealth seems a pro-worker stance. In<br />

[mecw24]81:2, Marx argues on the contrary that the assertion that labor is the only source<br />

<strong>of</strong> use-values is a pro-capitalist and anti-worker ideology. Can you guess, without going to<br />

Marx’s text, how that can be the case?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 53<br />

[66] Sparky: Labor as a source <strong>of</strong> wealth is a true statement when concerning the worker<br />

and avoiding inputs such as nature which provides the resources <strong>of</strong> the product, and it would<br />

be easy to see why that statement could be seen as a pro-worker statement, as JT said in<br />

[2007SP:86]: “it emphasizes the importance <strong>of</strong> the laborer as the only source <strong>of</strong> use-value”.<br />

But while it is the worker that is creating value, he is not necessarily the owner <strong>of</strong> the goods.<br />

An example would be an autoworker, he goes to work and helps create a car, but creating a<br />

car and owning a car are very different things, the worker did not purchase the steel, rubber,<br />

bolts, etc. that went in to the car, nor did he own the machines he used to create the car<br />

– the car company did, and they owned all the paperwork, the title, receipts <strong>of</strong> all items<br />

needed to build the car, and the car worker’s pay stub proving that they paid the auto worker<br />

the worth that he created, which is a worth they, the capitialist, has said that he made –<br />

while giving him a half decent wage they are still exploiting the value he has created. That<br />

is why the stance <strong>of</strong> labor is the source <strong>of</strong> all wealth is a pro-capitalist and anti-worker<br />

ideology, the capitalist controls the means <strong>of</strong> production, the means <strong>of</strong> the laborer if you will<br />

– that worker could not have made that car all by himself, he did not have the means or the<br />

resources to build a complete working car that could be sold. The capitalist is controlling<br />

the production <strong>of</strong> goods, and this example is a limited one, I have chosen a field <strong>of</strong> products<br />

that is mass produced and mass advertised and is very hard for small companies to get a<br />

part <strong>of</strong>, an example is electric car companies which are having a very hard time breaking<br />

into the whole US market, which contains many regulations on the means <strong>of</strong> production –<br />

controlling pollution from the production <strong>of</strong> the car, and the regulation <strong>of</strong> the final product –<br />

such as smog emissions and safety.<br />

Hans: Your example shows very well that a modern production process contains many ingredients other than labor:<br />

not only means <strong>of</strong> production, also legal and accounting issues, pollution control, etc. Since the capitalists hire the<br />

laborers one by one, they treat them like children and usurp the laborers’ social connections for their own benefit.<br />

The laborers should unite in solidarity and tell the capitalists that they are society, they are the immense majority,<br />

and they have the right to run their own affairs.<br />

You have a lot to say but your sentence structure is pretty awful; you have to work on this.<br />

Message [66] referenced by [519]. Next Message by Sparky is [114].<br />

[67] Hans: Wealth and Labor. In answering this question you have to distinguish between<br />

two statements:<br />

(1) labor is the only source <strong>of</strong> value – right<br />

(2) labor is the only source <strong>of</strong> wealth – wrong<br />

“Value” is here, as always, commodity value, i.e., “labor is the only source <strong>of</strong> value”<br />

means: prices are determined by labor content. This is the basic assertion <strong>of</strong> the labor theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. According to this theory, pr<strong>of</strong>its only exist because the workers do not receive a<br />

full equivalent for the labor they perform.<br />

“Labor is the only source <strong>of</strong> wealth” is not true because you always need two factors to<br />

produce wealth: labor and natural resources.<br />

To say it again, nature does not produce value, because it does not charge for its services<br />

as I said in [62]. But nature does produce use-value, it plays an indispensible part in the<br />

production <strong>of</strong> any use-value.


54 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

If you say that labor is the only source <strong>of</strong> wealth you pretend that labor could produce<br />

wealth without nature. Labor cannot. It is exactly the secret <strong>of</strong> the wealth <strong>of</strong> the capitalists<br />

that they control the means <strong>of</strong> production and therefore the laborer. Instead, labor should<br />

have access to means <strong>of</strong> production and natural resources as a matter <strong>of</strong> right. As CousinIt<br />

said in [65], private property <strong>of</strong> means <strong>of</strong> production is a crime against humanity.<br />

Message [67] referenced by [238]. Next Message by Hans is [70].<br />

[238] Kevin: graded A– Wealth is free. Saying labor is the source <strong>of</strong> all wealth is a procapitalist<br />

statement even though it may appear otherwise. To say this suggests that if one<br />

labors hard enough, one will become wealthy. This is not the case. This mentality or way <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking is a way to ensure the continued effort <strong>of</strong> the laborer without adequate reward for<br />

his labor, thus keeping him exploited to the fullest by capitalism itself. Labor is not the only<br />

source <strong>of</strong> wealth, or use-value. Use-value comes from the usefulness <strong>of</strong> a commodity which<br />

may or may not involve labor. Nature produces much with use-value that requires no labor<br />

at all.<br />

Hans: Your argument needs two more steps to be complete:<br />

(a) not only nature but also produced means <strong>of</strong> production are necessary for every production process.<br />

(b) both natural resources and the means <strong>of</strong> production are owned by the capitalists.<br />

Therefore if you say “labor is the only source <strong>of</strong> wealth” you ignore the role <strong>of</strong> the resources owned by the<br />

capitalists. It is the secret <strong>of</strong> capitalist wealth that they, and not the workers, control some essential ingredients <strong>of</strong><br />

the production process. By “overlooking” these ingredients you keep it a secret and therefore help the capitalists. I<br />

tried to say the same thing in the very last paragraph <strong>of</strong> [67]; see also JT’s [2007SP:86].<br />

Next Message by Kevin is [239].<br />

[345] Brody: In a capitalist society, labor, and therefore the worker, is exploited. In a<br />

capitalist based society use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity does not determine price: rather price is<br />

determined by demand. If demand rises then price follows suit. The worker does not gain<br />

from the change in exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

By price, exchange value is meant since I find the two to be one and the same if you look<br />

at money as a commodity or even use the exchange value to determine what two objects are<br />

worth.<br />

Hans: Look at my [23].<br />

Next Message by Brody is [367].<br />

[350] Ryoung: Is Labor Bought. I believe that Marx argued this because in a capitalist<br />

society those that are rich or wealthy are believed to have had everything handed to them<br />

and all those that labor are laboring to make the rich even richer. The rich don’t like to<br />

labor, therefore they choose to buy labor to make them wealthier. In a capitalist society<br />

those that labor are lower class, and this is why I believe Marx believed that use values are<br />

an anti-worker ideology.<br />

Hans: The rich can only “choose to buy labor” and get even richer by it because they control the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

The laborers are “lower class” only because they are separated from the means <strong>of</strong> production. Saying that<br />

labor creates all wealth denies that means <strong>of</strong> production are necessary and therefore keeps it a mystery why those<br />

who control the means <strong>of</strong> production are so rich.<br />

Next Message by Ryoung is [351].<br />

[381] Clayon: Marx argues that “the assertion that labor is the only source <strong>of</strong> wealth is<br />

pro-capitalist and anti-worker ideology.” He says capitalism does not break down the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> a good sufficiently, and therefore the laborer does not receive the proper pay he deserves<br />

while the Capitalist boss walks away with a pr<strong>of</strong>it.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 55<br />

Marx notes that a good has a use value, which is the use the good provides to people, as<br />

well as a value which is a direct by-product <strong>of</strong> the labor required to produce the commodity.<br />

Thus the worker receives full wages according to his labor input.<br />

Marx states that “any body <strong>of</strong> a commodity is a combination <strong>of</strong> two elements – matter and<br />

labor.” To say that labor is the only source <strong>of</strong> wealth is inaccurate. Marx states that “labor<br />

is not the source <strong>of</strong> all wealth. Nature is just as much the source <strong>of</strong> use-values as labor.” To<br />

say otherwise robs nature <strong>of</strong> her labor to produce the raw material.<br />

Hans: Marx does emphatically not say that the worker gets full wages. The labor-theory <strong>of</strong> value does not imply<br />

that the worker gets full wages. Wages will be discussed in chapter Six.<br />

The gifts <strong>of</strong> nature are free; society does not have to pay for them. This does not mean nature cannot be robbed.<br />

But we do it at our peril, as we are experiencing with the climate catastrophe we triggered by us.<br />

Next Message by Clayon is [387].<br />

Question 145 is 86 in 1998WI, 93 in 1999SP, 98 in 2000fa, 98 in 2001fa, 138 in 2007SP,<br />

141 in 2007fa, 143 in 2008fa, 150 in 2009fa, 155 in 2010fa, and 174 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 145 If the first chapter is such a systematic discussion <strong>of</strong> value, why is it then<br />

called “Commodities” and not “Value”?<br />

[95] Slash: commodity vs. Value. Marx chose to title the first chapter “commodity,”<br />

because commodity comes with a qualifier that value does not. Value can be broken into<br />

two groups: Exchange value and use value. Exchange value is dependent upon the item first<br />

being a commodity. A commodity implies ownership, without having ownership <strong>of</strong> an item<br />

one cannot trade or exchange it, this doesn’t mean the item is without value, but rather that<br />

the item is not yet a commodity. For example an acre <strong>of</strong> land has value, people can grow<br />

wheat to eat, or simply find use value in standing in it, but if there is no ownership then the<br />

acre <strong>of</strong> land is only valued by those occupying, or cultivating it. This kind <strong>of</strong> value without<br />

ownership is use value. Jenna [2007SP:128] talked about a coat and the inherent use value<br />

(heating humans). But the demands <strong>of</strong> ownership make the coat a commodity.<br />

When a person claims water, bottles it and then sells the water it becomes a commodity.<br />

The fact that someone claimed and bottled the water doesn’t change the life saving use value<br />

<strong>of</strong> water, but rather turns the water into a commodity, which then has an exchange value, and<br />

therefore has value in a commodity market. It is because <strong>of</strong> this distinction in the term value<br />

that Marx chose to be more specific and say commodity.<br />

Hans: Slash asked me to count his reference to Jenna for his feedback requirement. Unfortunately it is not the<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> detailed feedback I am looking for. Slash is building on Jenna’s submission, this is always good and<br />

even required. Slash also adopts one <strong>of</strong> Jenna’s errors as I explain in [113]. Feedback means either correcting or<br />

clarifying, somehow making the previous submission better. I don’t have the impression that Slash tries to do that.<br />

Message [95] referenced by [96] and [113]. Next Message by Slash is [118].<br />

[96] Scott: Commodities turn into Value. Marx states “The wealth <strong>of</strong> those societies in<br />

which the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production prevails, presents itself as ’an immense accumulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities.’” Knowing this it’s important to understand exactly what a commodity<br />

is. Anything that has purpose or useful is considered a commodity. For example paper, food,<br />

iron, etc., are considered commodities because they can satisfy human needs and wants. I<br />

agree with Slash [95] when he says “a commodity implies ownership, without having ownership<br />

<strong>of</strong> an item one cannot trade or exchange it, this doesn’t mean the item is without value,<br />

but rather that the item is not yet a commodity.” This is why Marx calls his first chapter


56 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

“Commodity” because you first need to claim something as your commodity, make it productive<br />

so you can trade it, and it then has value or “exchange value”. For example if I lived<br />

on a farm, to make my many commodities such as corn and animals have value I would need<br />

to make them satisfy a human need or want. This is why societies prevail is because <strong>of</strong> their<br />

“immense accumulation <strong>of</strong> commodities” that they turn into value.<br />

Hans: Not every use-value is a commodity (as Marx uses the term), but only those use-values which are produced<br />

for exchange. You are therefore working with a different definition <strong>of</strong> a commodity than Marx. You are also saying<br />

that the echange-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity comes from its use-value, while Marx is very careful to keep them separate.<br />

I recommend that you attend the class sessions, because I always verbally explain the main elements <strong>of</strong> Marx’s<br />

theory.<br />

Next Message by Scott is [177].<br />

[113] Hans: Two Clarifications. Slash [95] shows a couple <strong>of</strong> misunderstanings which<br />

I’d like to clarify here.<br />

(1) Slash says that an object without ownership is only a use-value, but if there is ownership<br />

then it becomes also an exchange-value. Slash refers here to Jenna [2007SP:128] who<br />

indeed said:<br />

In a primitive society which does not recognize ownership <strong>of</strong> property, a<br />

coat may exist as a physical thing. It will have use value – that <strong>of</strong> warmth<br />

it provides to humans. Yet, in this society, the coat is not a commodity<br />

because it is not exchangeable.<br />

The passage in italics is not quite right. Even if the coat is not a commodity (because<br />

everybody produces their own garments, and they would never dream <strong>of</strong> wearing something<br />

produced by someone else) there is still ownership <strong>of</strong> coats. This coat here is your coat, and<br />

nobody else in society has the right to wear it. The same society may have the rule that food<br />

is always to be distributed to everybody present, nobody should be hungry if others have to<br />

eat. There is an infinite variety <strong>of</strong> possible ownership relations, ownership and exchange are<br />

not one and the same thing.<br />

It is important to keep this in mind when you read things like CousinIt’s provocative<br />

statement in [65] that private property <strong>of</strong> means <strong>of</strong> production is a crime against humanity.<br />

CousinIt does not say here that means <strong>of</strong> production should be free for the taker. Rather that<br />

only those who work the means <strong>of</strong> production should be the owners. If some other private<br />

person, who is not one <strong>of</strong> the workers, has property rights over means <strong>of</strong> production, this is<br />

as artificial and restrictive as someone else other than you owning the coat you are wearing.<br />

(2) Slash says that water becomes an exchange-value by someone claiming it and selling<br />

it. And this is indeed how CousinIt described it in [65]. But CousinIt’s description was not<br />

to be taken literally, it was a fable. CousinIt meant to say: a society which conveys private<br />

ownership rights to natural resources (which should belong to everyone) is comparable<br />

to some primitive people fencing <strong>of</strong>f a watering hole and declaring that they own it now.<br />

CousinIt wanted to convey how outrageous those property relations are which we all take<br />

for granted. Also in Marx’s case it is important to understand that he is much more critical <strong>of</strong><br />

the social relations than <strong>of</strong> the individuals playing the various roles in capitalist society. You<br />

cannot have a seller <strong>of</strong> water without first having a society in which water is a commodity.<br />

And we should be critical <strong>of</strong> these social relations, not the individuals.


Message [113] referenced by [95]. Next Message by Hans is [119].<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 57<br />

Question 156 is 66 in 1995WI, 75 in 1995ut, 79 in 1996sp, 85 in 1997WI, 87 in 1997sp, 83<br />

in 1997ut, 113 in 2002fa, 116 in 2003fa, 131 in 2005fa, and 150 in 2007fa:<br />

Question 156 Why can commodities not express their values in their own use-values? (Note<br />

that we are not asking here why the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is not determined by its use-value.<br />

The expression <strong>of</strong> value is not the same as the determination <strong>of</strong> value.)<br />

[85] Jason: Use-Value and Value <strong>of</strong> a Commodity. Commodities cannot express their<br />

values in their own use-values for a few reasons. For one, as stated in an earlier reading,<br />

their value is determined at least in part by the labor time that went into them. They are<br />

worth how much average societal labor time is put into making them. They have a value that<br />

is gained independently from how useful they are. A use-value only implies a commodity’s<br />

use to a consumer and not its value when compared to other commodities. A coat may keep<br />

you warm as its use, but it has no real comparison to, let’s say a chair. Marx says a market<br />

<strong>of</strong> some kind (or a “social relation” as said in [1997ut:109]) must be introduced with several<br />

other commodities before a real value can be determined.<br />

Hans: Value itself is not relative, but it is an immaterial social substance inherent in the commodity. Only the<br />

”expression” or ”form” <strong>of</strong> value is relative. My [88] tries to explain why value needs an ”expression.”<br />

Next Message by Jason is [93].<br />

[88] Hans: Why does value need an extra form? At the beginning <strong>of</strong> the presently<br />

assigned readings, Marx says: since a commodity is something tw<strong>of</strong>old, a use-value and a<br />

value, it needs a double form: it needs a use-value form, which is given by the body <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity itself, and then it also needs a value form.<br />

Imagine Marx teaching a class about this. Most <strong>of</strong> his students have drifted away because<br />

his reasoning is always so abstract. Those who are still listening cannot really object to it<br />

that something which has a double character needs a double form, sounds kind <strong>of</strong> logical,<br />

but they cannot really wrap their brains around it what all this means. But there is this one<br />

student, Oscar, who is a little impertinent because he always asks questions. He raises his<br />

hand and says: Sorry Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Marx, why are two forms needed, why can a commodity not<br />

use its bodily form to express not only its use-value but also its value?<br />

This was a well-placed concrete question, which forces Marx to become more concrete<br />

in his explanations. Some <strong>of</strong> the study questions try to be nosy Oscar to Marx. And Oscar<br />

is lucky because Marx clears his throat and brings the following much more concrete<br />

explanation:<br />

A commodity is something produced for exchange. It is not only a use-value but in<br />

addition also a value, because the person who produced it did not produce it for his own use.<br />

The producer put his labor into this commodity with the expectation that this commodity<br />

will give him access to the labor <strong>of</strong> others materialized in things he can use. In other words,<br />

it is not only a use-value but also a vessel containing labor, intended to serve as a claim<br />

check on the labor <strong>of</strong> others in a use-value which our producer can use. That is what I meant<br />

when I said that it has this double character <strong>of</strong> being both use-value and value.<br />

Say our commodity producer is a shoe maker. Why can’t he use the use-value <strong>of</strong> his shoes<br />

as expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> his shoes? I.e., why can’t he go to the tailor and say: “Look at


58 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

these shoes I just made. They are first-rate quality, and they contain my labor. I am willing<br />

to trade you my labor for yours, please give me the trousers you just made in exchange for<br />

my shoes.”<br />

The problem is <strong>of</strong> course that the tailor may not need shoes at the moment. The bigger<br />

the economy and the more varied its use-values, the more certain is it that the tailor will want<br />

something different and not the shoemaker’s shoes. How, then, can the shoemaker ever be<br />

rewarded for the labor which he put into the shoes?<br />

Only if the value <strong>of</strong> these shoes is cast into a form that is independent <strong>of</strong> all use-values.<br />

We all know what this form is: it is money. The shoemaker first has to sell his shoes, i.e.,<br />

turn them into money, before he can take advantage <strong>of</strong> the labor which he put into them.<br />

The money is the form which the value <strong>of</strong> his shoes has to take in order to be useful for the<br />

shoemaker.<br />

You can also look at it this way: the invisible value material which the shoemaker accumulated<br />

in his shoes during the hours <strong>of</strong> diligent work producing the shoes, is like a ghost<br />

looking for a body. This congealed abstract labor is looking for a material form, so that it<br />

can become an object <strong>of</strong> transaction between humans. No particular use-value will fit as a<br />

body for this ghost, since the ghost consists <strong>of</strong> abstract labor, i.e., labor independent <strong>of</strong> the<br />

form in which it is performed. Money is the independent material form <strong>of</strong> value, in which<br />

value has freed itself from any particular use-value. It is the materialization <strong>of</strong> the invisible<br />

value material inside the shoes.<br />

So far Marx’s speech. Oscar was lucky that Marx felt talkative at the moment. At other<br />

times Marx would just have brushed him aside with the abstract one-sentence answer: a<br />

use-value cannot be a form <strong>of</strong> value because value is independent <strong>of</strong> all use-values.<br />

Message [88] referenced by [85], [122], [281], and [385]. Next Message by Hans is [97].<br />

[281] Dyoung: Commodities have both values and use-values, Marx says “that its natural<br />

body is only a form for its use-value and therefore it needs a value form and in order to<br />

appear as a commodity you need to have the form <strong>of</strong> a commodity. There needs to be double<br />

form, a bodily form and a value form.”<br />

Value comes from the consumer <strong>of</strong> the commodity and how it benefits the individual’s<br />

human needs not itself. Value is how it fulfills the needs <strong>of</strong> the human and is it worth the<br />

price it is demanding. Marx states that the form <strong>of</strong> value is a relation which allows the<br />

commodity owners to take advantage <strong>of</strong> the value embedded in their commodities.<br />

Value is an invisible but real social substance, which the commodity acquire already in<br />

the production process. It is not obtained in the use-value because everyone would think that<br />

there commodities use-value was more valuable than the next persons commodity and things<br />

would get very expensive really quick. That is why it is important not to express value in a<br />

commodity’s own use-value.<br />

Hans: “Value is how it fulfills the needs <strong>of</strong> the human” is the mainstream neoclassical concept <strong>of</strong> utility, not Marx’s<br />

theory. Marx gives different explanations than the mainstream, don’t throw these two theories together.<br />

My [88] tries to answer this question.<br />

Next Message by Dyoung is [421].<br />

[313] Paul: Commodities cannot express their values in their use-values because you must<br />

look at the double form <strong>of</strong> the commodity. These are the commodity’s use-value form and


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 59<br />

the value form. We know that the use-value is the usefulness the commodity has to society.<br />

Since use-value is subjective to the person using the commodity if you simply determined<br />

the value by use-value there would be many different values for one given commodity. The<br />

value-form is the form for which the value is expressed. The value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is its<br />

exchange value; this means that the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is a social relation. This means<br />

that the value (abstract labor) <strong>of</strong> a commodity is expressed by how it relates with other<br />

products’ use-value. For example, a weaver knows the amount <strong>of</strong> labor time to produce X<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> linen. They also know how much use value a coat has to them. If the weaver<br />

agrees to accept a coat in exchange for X amount <strong>of</strong> linen this telling <strong>of</strong> the labor time going<br />

into the linen or the expression <strong>of</strong> the linens value. So the linens value is expressed by the<br />

relation <strong>of</strong> use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat.<br />

Next Message by Paul is [561].<br />

[348] Bennett: A use-value is determined by society, society agrees upon a certain price<br />

range for most products. But commodities can not express their values in their own usevalues<br />

because they are not relative to one another. For example things can have a use-value<br />

without having value; this is true when the commodities utility is not due to human labor.<br />

Commodities that have use-values but do not have value and fit in this category include<br />

commodities such as air and soil. These commodities have use-value but do not have value<br />

because they are not produced by human labor.<br />

Hans: I don’t get your argument and I am wondering if you understand the question. Your sentence “society agrees<br />

upon a certain price range for most products” makes me wonder what you know about Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Next Message by Bennett is [525].<br />

[362] Ande: You cannot express a commodity’s value in own use-value because it is not<br />

equal to the actual value <strong>of</strong> the commodity that is being valued. One value would be higher<br />

or lower than the other. Your own use-value is an independent value <strong>of</strong> the commodity or<br />

item you have. You might have a golf club you love and the own use-value to you is worth a<br />

lot more to you than to your friend that does not like the club, he would only say it’s worth<br />

the use-value (or market value) where as you think it is worth a lot more given it’s yours and<br />

you love it. Own use-value is not something you can go by when coming up with a price <strong>of</strong><br />

a commodity that is a value determined by ones self and own opinionated value <strong>of</strong> a certain<br />

commodity. When it comes down to it that is the reason why you cannot use ones own<br />

use-value when it comes to commodities, you need to strictly go by use-value and market<br />

value.<br />

Hans: You didn’t understand the question, and your little essay has nothing to do with Marx.<br />

Next Message by Ande is [481].<br />

[385] Allen: A commodity has both a use-value and value. Their use-value is determined<br />

by how useful that commodity is to consumers, while the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is determined<br />

by the producers because they don’t need the item itself but make the item for trade.<br />

As a result, the value <strong>of</strong> the item is determined by the process it is created while the use-value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the item is determined by how useful the item is to consumers.<br />

Hans: The question did not ask how use-value and value are determined. You might benefit from reading my [88]<br />

and [231].<br />

Next Message by Allen is [559].<br />

Question 160 is 134 in 2004fa, 158 in 2008fa, and 175 in 2010fa:


60 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Question 160 Why does Marx write “society expresses the sum <strong>of</strong> relations in which the individuals<br />

stand” instead <strong>of</strong> “society consists <strong>of</strong> the sum <strong>of</strong> relations in which the individuals<br />

stand”?<br />

[84] Rey: graded A Value, a social expression? There is a temptation when thinking<br />

about “society” as a whole, to simply explain it as group <strong>of</strong> individuals co-existing. It is<br />

not, however a mere co-existence <strong>of</strong> individuals, but something far beyond that. To understand<br />

a society one doesn’t examine each individual, but rather examines the results <strong>of</strong> the<br />

interaction and expression <strong>of</strong> roles these individuals play. This is why Marx has stated, “society<br />

expresses the sum <strong>of</strong> relations in which the individual stands.” To come to some sort<br />

<strong>of</strong> conclusion <strong>of</strong> the social workings <strong>of</strong> a society we wouldn’t focus on “Joe Johnson” on an<br />

intimate level. Rather we would examine his role as a teacher per se, and as a teacher how is<br />

it that he interacts with other roles thought to belong in the same social category. We would<br />

analyze his actions with an “administrator” or a “student” not looking at these individuals<br />

personally either, but at their role relation with “Joe Johnson” as a teacher.<br />

As we analyze how one individual acts in respect to the other individual we would begin<br />

to see a certain set <strong>of</strong> social “values” unfold. Specifically in this example we would likely<br />

come to the conclusion that our society values the benefits that come from a higher education<br />

and more experience. However, it is important to add the administrator only holds their<br />

elevated position for as long as the teachers continue to “value” those benefits that set them<br />

apart.<br />

When speaking about commodities we are able to draw a similar conclusion. A commodity<br />

only has value because its relation with other commodities has given it such and just<br />

as Marx has said it is in this interaction or exchange that we start our search for a commodity’s<br />

hidden value. Again this value is only upheld for as long as its interaction with<br />

other commodities allows it to be. It’s important to note that although value can be controlled<br />

by exchange and interaction, previous exchange and interaction make a paradigm<br />

shift extremely difficult.<br />

In conclusion we see that just as “society” is an expression <strong>of</strong> individual relations, “value”<br />

is a social expression <strong>of</strong> commodity exchange.<br />

Message [84] referenced by [86], [92], [386], and [2010fa:155]. Next Message by Rey is [107].<br />

[86] Hans: Social relations and their connections. With submission [84], Rey used the<br />

homework mailing list exactly in the way it was intended: he picked a challenging question,<br />

and formulated a carefully thought-out answer that is based on the readings.<br />

I will still criticize the answer, but I don’t count this criticism against Rey. We are dealing<br />

with difficult issues, and Rey did his part to resolve the issues, now it is my role to pick up<br />

on those things Rey didn’t see. We cannot expect to understand everything all at once; Rey<br />

showed that he made a good effort and got quite far. He will definitely get an A for this<br />

contribution despite my criticism.<br />

Ok, let me start my critique <strong>of</strong> [84] with what is correct in it? Rey understands correctly<br />

that one should not identify society with the group <strong>of</strong> individuals in that society, but with the<br />

relations between the individuals. This is a big step which has immense implications that<br />

take some time to chew through.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 61<br />

But then Rey makes a subtle switch in perspective away from this commitment to look at<br />

the social relations and not the individuals which inhabit them. He writes:<br />

To come to some sort <strong>of</strong> conclusion <strong>of</strong> the social workings <strong>of</strong> a society we<br />

wouldn’t focus on “Joe Johnson” on an intimate level. Rather we would<br />

examine his role as a teacher per se, and as a teacher how is it that he<br />

interacts with other roles thought to belong in the same social category.<br />

We would analyze his actions with an “administrator” or a “student” not<br />

looking at these individuals personally either, but at their role relation with<br />

“Joe Johnson” as a teacher.<br />

This is still too much emphasis on Joe Johnson. Rey is looking how individuals fill their<br />

social roles. This is a legitimate question, but this is not the primary question for understanding<br />

a society. To understand capitalist society, one must look at the social relations,<br />

such as those <strong>of</strong> a teacher, and administrator, but also relations outside the school like the<br />

relations <strong>of</strong> an employee or a capitalist boss. And then one must ask how these relations<br />

are connected! For instance, Marx says that there is an inexorable connection between the<br />

boss getting richer and richer and being able to take more and more extravagant vacations,<br />

and his employees coming to work year-in year-out without advancing in wealth but just<br />

able to pay their mortgage. This is probably the prime example <strong>of</strong> how different social roles<br />

are connected, but there are many other connections between different social relations. If<br />

you look at the behavior expected from an elementary school student you will find striking<br />

similarities to the behavior expected from an employee: show up on time and go through<br />

boring routines on command. Again, Marx would say this is not an accident.<br />

Message [86] referenced by [92], [309], and [386]. Next Message by Hans is [88].<br />

[92] Chris: expression on a macrocosmic level. To express something suggests that you<br />

are conveying a message, or making it known. For something to hold consistency, it would<br />

have to be made up <strong>of</strong> more than one substance. Marx does not think that a society just<br />

consists <strong>of</strong> these individuals. He thinks on a much larger and broader scale. I believe that<br />

this is what Rey and Hans were getting at in their respective articles [84] and [86] on the<br />

same question that I am responding to. I decided to still respond to the question because<br />

it is a very interesting and challenging passage by Marx and I think by using direct quotes<br />

from Capital we are able to get a better understanding <strong>of</strong> the passage. In fact, if we look<br />

on page 152:1 <strong>of</strong> Capital, we find a direct quote that gives us a better understanding <strong>of</strong> how<br />

Marx uses the word “express.” And he quotes, “the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is independently<br />

expressed through its presentation as ‘exchange-value’.” Marx presented this quote after he<br />

discussed the exchangeability <strong>of</strong> two commodities and how each is made known through the<br />

presentation <strong>of</strong> their exchange value relation.<br />

In another quote on page 150:1, Marx points out that “the body <strong>of</strong> the commodity, which<br />

serves as the equivalent, always figures as the embodiment <strong>of</strong> abstract human labour, and<br />

is always the product <strong>of</strong> some specific useful and concrete labour. This concrete labour<br />

therefore becomes the expression <strong>of</strong> abstract human labour.” What I get out <strong>of</strong> this quote is<br />

that concrete labor is made known from abstract human labor. This “body <strong>of</strong> commodity”<br />

makes me think that Marx is suggesting the commodity ‘consists’ <strong>of</strong> these forms <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

And the commodity would be more <strong>of</strong> a micro level aspect <strong>of</strong> the overall macro society. It


62 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

would be inconsistent <strong>of</strong> Marx to strain from this thought and suggest that society is a mere<br />

‘consistency’ as opposed to an ‘expression.’<br />

I used these quotes because I think they say a lot about how Marx thinks. For Marx to<br />

suggest a society in itself is made up <strong>of</strong>, or consists <strong>of</strong> these individuals would be too vague.<br />

Marx suggests that the society is an expression <strong>of</strong> the relations <strong>of</strong> these individuals. The individuals<br />

manifest themselves and are made known through interaction and communication,<br />

through the commodities for which they are exchanged and through the individuals whom<br />

exchange them. This is a direct line <strong>of</strong> expression. This society expresses these relations.<br />

Total them all together and you have the sum <strong>of</strong> expression. Therefore, it is safe to say that<br />

overall, as Marx quotes, “society expresses the sum <strong>of</strong> relations in which the individuals<br />

stand.” And like Hans mentions in [86], “one must look at the social relations, such as those<br />

<strong>of</strong> the teacher, and administrator, but also the relations outside the school like the relations <strong>of</strong><br />

an employee or a capitalist boss. And then one must ask how these relations are connected!”<br />

These relations as I mentioned earlier appear too microcosmic and do not express society<br />

unless they are totaled together. The expression <strong>of</strong> the total sum is on a much larger scale<br />

and in that respect, I think that Marx goes a great job <strong>of</strong> defining this social expression.<br />

Message [92] referenced by [97]. Next Message by Chris is [146].<br />

[97] Hans: Extensionality. In mathematics, sets are defined by the elements they contain.<br />

Two sets are identical if and only if they contain the same elements. This is called the<br />

extensionality principle.<br />

In [92], Chris writes that Marx does not think the extensionality principle should be applied<br />

to societies. Chris writes:<br />

Marx does not think that a society just consists <strong>of</strong> these individuals. He<br />

thinks on a much larger and broader scale.<br />

This is an excellent observation. Chris recognizes, I think correctly, that Marx’s aphorism<br />

Society does not consist <strong>of</strong> individuals, but expresses the sum <strong>of</strong> connections,<br />

relations, in which these individuals stand with respect to each other.<br />

is not only the critique <strong>of</strong> the view that societies are just big groups <strong>of</strong> individuals, but it is<br />

also the critique <strong>of</strong> the application <strong>of</strong> the extensionality principle to societies. In Marx’s view,<br />

societies are not defined by the elements they contain – be these elements the individuals or<br />

the relations between individuals, but societies are higher entities. They are more than the<br />

sums <strong>of</strong> their parts.<br />

That observation explains satisfactorily why Marx does not say: society consists <strong>of</strong> relations<br />

– because Marx does not want to define societies by what they consist <strong>of</strong>.<br />

Next, Chris tries to explain why Marx uses the word “express” instead, using a very<br />

reasonable methodology: he looks at other instances where Marx uses the word “express.”<br />

But I am thinking in this instance Chris is reading too much into the word “express.” I think<br />

Marx’s above aphorism is a lax formulation <strong>of</strong> what might more precisely be formulated as<br />

follows:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 63<br />

Society does not consist <strong>of</strong> individuals, but the word “society” expresses<br />

(a more modern formulation would be: signifies) the sum <strong>of</strong> connections,<br />

relations, in which these individuals stand with respect to each other.<br />

Message [97] referenced by [309], [2010fa:155], and [2010fa:485]. Next Message by Hans is [113].<br />

[304] Dentist: Marx uses the word “express” deliberately because the word implies the<br />

conveyance <strong>of</strong> an idea. Here Marx is talking about a society, which is a particular idea that<br />

a population adheres to. To say “society expresses the sum <strong>of</strong> relations. . . ” is to say that a<br />

society is the particular form that these collective relations take.<br />

Comparatively, the word “consist” implies no more than a collective sum <strong>of</strong> some number<br />

<strong>of</strong> things. Had Marx used “consist” he would have been saying that a society is no more than<br />

a collection <strong>of</strong> individuals and their inter-relationships. This is not true. Societies are much<br />

deeper than this. A society may indeed contain a certain number <strong>of</strong> individuals and their<br />

inevitable interactions, but is certainly not defined by them at the individual level or basis.<br />

The various forms that the relations between these collected individuals take and the causes<br />

<strong>of</strong> these forms, defines a society. Marx understands this and builds his arguments on this<br />

principle.<br />

Message [304] referenced by [309]. Next Message by Dentist is [306].<br />

[309] CousinIt: graded A+ the whole greater than the sum <strong>of</strong> its parts. Marx does<br />

not see society as merely a collection <strong>of</strong> individuals. Rather, society is an expression <strong>of</strong> the<br />

totality <strong>of</strong> social relations in which individuals stand, which is not just a sum, or quantity,<br />

but that has particular qualitative aspects when viewed holistically as a collective expression<br />

that is ‘greater than the sum <strong>of</strong> its parts,’ as stated by Bird [2004fa:59]. By this qualitative<br />

perspective, we are led to look deeper beneath the surface <strong>of</strong> social structure (as the total<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> the relations between individuals) to that which underlies those expressions<br />

on the surface. We must be able to apprehend the nature <strong>of</strong> the hidden real material relations<br />

which dictate the relations between individuals in order to understand the true nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

society in question. In a capitalist structure, society is not the quantitative “sum” <strong>of</strong> relations<br />

but is merely the form <strong>of</strong> expression <strong>of</strong> those relations, the true nature <strong>of</strong> which is hidden,<br />

obscured, or “mystified” by that very expression itself. The real relations <strong>of</strong> the capitalist<br />

with those who are producing not only commodities, but the value in those commodities,<br />

is hidden by the primary expression on the surface <strong>of</strong> capitalist society that is the market.<br />

As Hans [86] states, it is not the group <strong>of</strong> individuals that make up capitalist society but the<br />

structure <strong>of</strong> the qualitative relations between those individuals, as they are situated within the<br />

structure <strong>of</strong> commodity relations in the marketplace, that determines the form <strong>of</strong> capitalist<br />

society. In order to get at what the quality <strong>of</strong> these relations is, Marx digs beneath the<br />

surface to reveal the hidden stratifications and contradictions that dictate the relational roles<br />

that people must fill in order for the commodity form to persist and prevail. In doing so, we<br />

become aware <strong>of</strong> the unnatural and exploitative quality underlying the seemingly ‘natural’<br />

and ‘normal’ relations on the surface <strong>of</strong> the capitalist marketplace.<br />

Hans: This is a different, and arguably better, interpretation <strong>of</strong> the word “express” than I promoted in [97]. If<br />

I understand you right, you are saying that what we are experiencing as “society” is the empirical expression <strong>of</strong><br />

a nonempirical underlying structure <strong>of</strong> relations. That part that can be empirically verified is only the tip <strong>of</strong> the<br />

iceberg.<br />

With this in mind I can also better understand Dentist’s [304]. Dentist had the same intuition as you, but in<br />

part <strong>of</strong> his answer he located the underlying structure <strong>of</strong> relations in the realm <strong>of</strong> ideas. A depth realist would say:


64 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

society is more than an idea but a real structure. It is real because it has real effects. Some <strong>of</strong> these effects use<br />

material force (when people are thrown into jail). But many <strong>of</strong> these effects go through the socially conditioned<br />

ideas which people have in their heads.<br />

Next Message by CousinIt is [312].<br />

[317] Gerund: We are social beings. Individuals have no identity except for the ways<br />

we relate to other human beings (or in the realm <strong>of</strong> religion, to God). As such, society can<br />

express the sum <strong>of</strong> relations, showing meaning in how we all relate to each other, but it can<br />

not consist <strong>of</strong> the sum <strong>of</strong> relations because that implies that we consist <strong>of</strong> identity other than<br />

our relations. In short, the former phrasing points out the richness <strong>of</strong> meaning, but the latter<br />

reduces to meaninglessness.<br />

Hans: Marx says that social relations cannot be derived from the individuals. Nevertheless, he believes that individuals<br />

exist.<br />

Next Message by Gerund is [706].<br />

[386] Rey: graded A As I stated in my homework post [84]: “There is a temptation when<br />

thinking about ‘society’ as a whole, to simply explain it as a group <strong>of</strong> individuals co-existing.<br />

It is not, however a mere co-existence <strong>of</strong> individuals, but something far beyond that. To<br />

understand a society, [or system] one doesn’t have to examine each individual, but rather<br />

examines the results <strong>of</strong> the interaction and expression <strong>of</strong> roles these individuals play.” This<br />

is why Marx uses the word “express” rather then “consists.” In examining interaction, Hans<br />

teaches us in post [86] that we must specifically look at “how these relations are connected.”<br />

In his post Hans goes on to examine how it is an employer is related to their boss. He points<br />

out that there is an inevitable relation between the two roles, specifically that the employer<br />

gains wealth at the expense <strong>of</strong> the employee. In a capitalist society, this is how these two<br />

social roles will always be connected. Thus if we know how two individuals in different<br />

social roles interact with one another, we can determine what kind <strong>of</strong> society/system they live<br />

in. This is due to the fact Marx feels that the society/system determines these relations and<br />

that certain societies/systems will always yield certain types <strong>of</strong> interactions. Quite simply<br />

the sum <strong>of</strong> people’s relations expresses the type <strong>of</strong> society/system they live in.<br />

Next Message by Rey is [392].<br />

[588] JPeel: content B late penalty 43% Marx writes “society expresses the sum <strong>of</strong><br />

relations in which the individuals stand” instead <strong>of</strong> “society consists <strong>of</strong> the sum <strong>of</strong> relations<br />

in which the individuals stand” because he is addressing the point that society generates a<br />

way <strong>of</strong> expressing something, which may not be the actual truth. It’s easier to express what<br />

you want to consist rather than to actually consist it. So Marx brings up a very valid point<br />

<strong>of</strong> the way society works. He does this to create a better understanding <strong>of</strong> relations and the<br />

way individuals interact with each other. The roles people may play are not created by that<br />

particular person but are gradually reformed over time and become “that” role.<br />

Next Message by JPeel is [603].<br />

Question 169 is 113 in 2001fa, 123 in 2002fa, 126 in 2003fa, 143 in 2004fa, 144 in<br />

2005fa, and 167 in 2008fa:<br />

Question 169 In a capitalist economy very few commodities are directly exchanged against<br />

each other: almost all transactions involve money and a commodity. Why does Marx start<br />

his investigation with the exchange relation between two commodities, instead with the much<br />

more common relation between money and a commodity?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 65<br />

[104] Carterryan: Marx does this comparison because he looks at commodities’ value as<br />

labor based, meaning what the cost <strong>of</strong> labor that was put into the commodity in question not<br />

just the use value.<br />

Marx uses the comparison that 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen and 1 coat have the same equal value.<br />

This is a way <strong>of</strong> saying that the amount <strong>of</strong> time and raw materials used for the linen equals<br />

the same in 1 coat.<br />

Money, which is a more common use <strong>of</strong> exchange has no real value, meaning that the<br />

commodiites in exchange have real equal value. That is why Marx uses that comparison.<br />

Message [104] referenced by [119]. Next Message by Carterryan is [205].<br />

[119] Hans: Why both money and labor. Carterryan [104] says that Marx does not<br />

need money because Marx measures things by labor. Money is only needed by mainstream<br />

economics which measures things by their use-values.<br />

This is an interesting thought, but it is easily refuted, by the fact that money does play an<br />

important role in Marx. For Marx, money is the exterior measuring stick which complements<br />

the inner, hidden, communality which commodities have as products <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Here is Marx’s argument in a nutshell. He starts with two different commodities. Then<br />

he says: the fact that these commodities are exchanged with each other means they are<br />

treated as equal. Then he says: these commodities indeed have something equal in them,<br />

namely, labor. And then he says: this inner equality <strong>of</strong> all commodities as products <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

is reflected on the surface by them both being available for money.<br />

This chain <strong>of</strong> reasoning cannot start with money because money is the result <strong>of</strong> this<br />

derivation. A modern economist might say: money in this theory is endogenous, while<br />

the things Marx starts with must be exogenous.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [121].<br />

Question 170 is 106 in 1997ut, 165 in 2004fa, 168 in 2008fa, and 176 in 2009fa:<br />

Question 170 The linen weaver just said: “20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is worth one coat.” In response<br />

to this, the tailor <strong>of</strong>fers her a coat in exchange for her 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen. Is the weaver now<br />

obligated to follow through with this exchange, or can she still decline?<br />

[98] Goethe: graded A does the weaver want a coat or linen? The answer to this is<br />

relative to the situation.<br />

One scenario could be where a tailor goes to the weaver for linen. The weaver will give<br />

the tailor her price for the linen. The price will be the exchange value <strong>of</strong> the linen, and can<br />

be in any form. The tailor may ask how much linen he can get for in exchange for a coat he<br />

has made. The weaver could tell the tailor she is not in need <strong>of</strong> a coat, and the tailor would<br />

need to exchange something else for the linen. If the weaver needs a coat she will tell the<br />

tailor the quantity <strong>of</strong> linen she is willing to exchange for a coat. In this situation when the<br />

weaver says “20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen are worth one coat” the weaver is obligated to follow through<br />

with the transaction.<br />

A different scenario could be when the tailor and weaver are engaged in a conversation<br />

not related to each other’s needs. The weaver then states “20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen are worth one


66 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

coat”, when the tailor <strong>of</strong>fers the coat here, the weaver is not obligated to follow through.<br />

This is obviously not a situation <strong>of</strong> barter, and the weaver can do whatever she wants.<br />

Hans: Good thinking. But there is one subtlety which you didn’t get, and which nobody can expect you to get. All<br />

encounters between commodity owners in a barter economy should be considered sales, not purchases. Someone<br />

produces something, and the next step is to find someone who needs what they have produced. Only then can the<br />

bartering begin. I.e., the conversation between weaver and tailor did not start because the tailor wanted to buy linen<br />

with a coat, but because the linen weaver wanted to sell the linen. Marx says that the linen is active, the coat is<br />

passive.<br />

Message [98] referenced by [101] and [2008fa:465]. Next Message by Goethe is [184].<br />

[101] Ande: In Marx’s terms the weaver would be obligated to follow through with the<br />

exchange. As Marx assumes it is immediately obvious to the reading that it is an expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. It can even be used as a verbal expression. If the lined weaver says to the tailor<br />

“20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen are worth one coat,” this means that she is willing to exchange 20 yards<br />

<strong>of</strong> linen for a coat. That says it all. Marx believes that a verbal commitment is enough to<br />

follow through and exchange your linen for one coat. Although it is not a law or required<br />

that you do this, it is a verbal agreement and in Marx’s terms, that is agreement enough to<br />

feel obligated to follow through with what you agreed on.<br />

I personally feel the same way Marx does. A verbal agreement is enough to feel obligated<br />

to follow through. If you tell someone you will trade them a coat for linen you better follow<br />

through and make the trade. If that is what the market is at but you have not said anything<br />

then no you should not have to make the trade, if you don’t want a coat you should not<br />

have to trade you linen for it just because the market price says you should. The market is a<br />

whole each individual does not have to follow that market trend, and that is where Marx and<br />

I would disagree. Overall, on the issue Marx and I would agree that a verbal agreement is<br />

agreement enough, and if you told someone that you would trade a coat for linen, then you<br />

now have an obligation to follow through and make the trade.<br />

Hans: How does your answer relate to Goethe’s [98]?<br />

Next Message by Ande is [103].<br />

Question 172 is 73 in 1995WI, 81 in 1995ut, 84 in 1996sp, 85 in 1996ut, 91 in 1997WI, 94<br />

in 1997sp, 89 in 1997ut, and 148 in 2004fa:<br />

Question 172 Can one say the coat, in the equation 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat, symbolizes<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> the linen?<br />

[109] Wasatch: According to Marx, value is a social relation <strong>of</strong> production. While the<br />

same amount <strong>of</strong> labor is going into the one coat and the 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen this does not mean<br />

that the value <strong>of</strong> the linen is the same as the coat. I guess it depends on the person you are<br />

looking at. Maybe to the tailor, someone that sees linen as something that has a lot <strong>of</strong> value,<br />

the 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is worth the same amount as the coat. But, to a plumber, someone that<br />

has little use for 20 raw yards <strong>of</strong> fabric, and therefore does not see a lot <strong>of</strong> value in the linen,<br />

the coat has much more value.<br />

Hans’s example <strong>of</strong> potatoes and the coat helps us look at this value problem in greater<br />

light. Let us assume that the 10 potatoes and the coat were produced with the same amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> physical labor.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 67<br />

If a person is starving but has plenty <strong>of</strong> coats they see the potatoes as having much more<br />

value. And a person with hundreds <strong>of</strong> potatoes stored in his cellar and not a coat to wear will<br />

see the coat as having much more value than the potatoes.<br />

The value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is solely based on the relation a social group has to the producton<br />

<strong>of</strong> the product. Therefore the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity can change from one social group to<br />

another.<br />

Message [109] referenced by [121]. Next Message by Wasatch is [290].<br />

[112] Ken: The equation 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat is stating that 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen are<br />

worth one coat. This equation is evaluating the value <strong>of</strong> the linen with the use value <strong>of</strong><br />

the coat. This equation is not comparing the value <strong>of</strong> the linen with the value <strong>of</strong> the coat.<br />

Therefore this equation can not symbolize the value <strong>of</strong> the linen.<br />

The value <strong>of</strong> the linen can not be found in this equation because the use value is very<br />

different than the value <strong>of</strong> the coat. The use value depends largely on the usefulness the<br />

commodity provides to the consumer. The value however is determined by the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

labor hours that were allocated to the commodity. Since this equation compares the value <strong>of</strong><br />

linen to the use value <strong>of</strong> the coat you are unable to determine the value <strong>of</strong> the linen.<br />

Message [112] referenced by [122]. Next Message by Ken is [483].<br />

[121] Hans: Social relations are not necessarily subjective and relative. When the<br />

Annotations say that value is a social relation, Wasatch [109] thinks that this means that it<br />

depends on the individual how something is valued. If Marx wanted to say this, he would<br />

say “value is subjective and relative.”<br />

The relation between you and the policeman in his car or on the bike is a social relation:<br />

it is determined by rules which neither you nor the policeman have any power over. If you<br />

commit certain infractions he must pull you over.<br />

Marx thinks that value has a similar character. Value is determined by things which<br />

the commodity producer has no power over, namely, the socially necessary labor-time to<br />

produce this product. Our commodity producer may wake up one morning and the value <strong>of</strong><br />

his commodity just has fallen by half. Someone around the globe has invented a method to<br />

produce it, or a substitute, at a much lower cost. Then inexorably the price <strong>of</strong> this commodity<br />

will fall too. This is not under the control <strong>of</strong> the commodity producer, it is a bigger social<br />

force, and it is something which originates not in the sphere <strong>of</strong> circulation but in the sphere<br />

<strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [122].<br />

[122] Hans: How in the world can a coat represent value? Ken says in [112] that the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat bears no similiarity with the value <strong>of</strong> the linen, and it can therefore not<br />

be taken as a representation <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the linen. This is an excellent objection. It could<br />

have come from nosy Oscar in [88]. Let’s see how Marx would have answered this.<br />

Marx (or Hans, pretending to be Marx) would say to Ken:<br />

You are right, the linen weaver is not interested in representing value. She simply needs<br />

a coat, and she does in the framework <strong>of</strong> commodity production what is necessary to get a<br />

coat.


68 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

But without intending to do so, her actions also blurt out what value is. Here is what her<br />

actions say:<br />

(1) by <strong>of</strong>fering linen for coat, she says that the value <strong>of</strong> the linen is different from the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> the linen.<br />

(2) Indeed she says that the value <strong>of</strong> the linen looks like a coat, and this is exactly Ken’s<br />

objection: value simply does not look like coats. But coats are not the only thing the linen<br />

weaver accepts in exchange for her linen: she also needs many other use-values. (This is<br />

the expanded form <strong>of</strong> value). If you take all this together, the linen weaver says that value is<br />

generally something different from any use-value.<br />

(3) This is not yet all. The linen weaver is able to exchange her linen for many other<br />

commodities only if these other commodities represent their values in linen. If this becomes<br />

a social agreement, that one commodity is chosen (probably not linen, but something like<br />

gold), in which all other commodities express their value, (now we are at the general form <strong>of</strong><br />

value), this is a big step forward. Now this one commodity is directly exchangeable against<br />

all other commodities, it can buy other commodities. I.e., the owner <strong>of</strong> this commodity is<br />

no longer tied to one use-value, but he or she can effortlessly switch to any use-value they<br />

want. This is like having value itself in your pocket, stripped <strong>of</strong> all use-value.<br />

This is a summary <strong>of</strong> the main steps <strong>of</strong> Section 3. In this Section, Marx describes the<br />

process how the spontaneous activity <strong>of</strong> the commodity traders generates something on the<br />

surface <strong>of</strong> the economy, i.e., money, which is the material existence <strong>of</strong> the invisible social<br />

value material, i.e., <strong>of</strong> the abstract labor, in the commodities.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [125].<br />

Question 181 The exchange relationship between the commodities is a symmetric relationship:<br />

if 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen can be exchanged for a coat, then a coat can also be exchanged for<br />

20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen. Besides, Marx said in 126:2 that this relationship appears at first as the<br />

quantitative proportion in which commodities can be exchanged for each other. Why, then,<br />

is it wrong to consider this relationship as a symmetric and quantitative relationship?<br />

[99] Bar: graded C+ Quantitative and Symmetric commodities relationship. It is<br />

wrong to consider the quantitative relationship between the linen and a coat on Marxian<br />

observation <strong>of</strong> intrinsic value or use-value vs. exchange value. On the one hand the yarn has<br />

labor invested in its makeup <strong>of</strong> value and so does the coat, where the labor accounting for<br />

the supply <strong>of</strong> the coat to the demand created by its perceived value depending on its utility,<br />

or the scarcity <strong>of</strong> these commodities giving a quantitative price for the coat. This price can<br />

be interpreted as being 1 coat = 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen or simply put the exchange rate. Of course,<br />

in simple terms this relationship can be manipulated through the crowding-out process <strong>of</strong><br />

taxation <strong>of</strong> these commodities. Marx says that the common sense approach to this, saying<br />

that value can only be placed relative to other commodities, is a fallacy. Just because you<br />

can get 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen for one coat doesn’t mean that the linen is “worth” in the sense <strong>of</strong><br />

use-value, the same as the coat, because to increase the use value <strong>of</strong> the linen it requires more<br />

investment <strong>of</strong> labor. It’s a symmetric relationship, but it’s not quantitative in the sense that


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 69<br />

there is direct value exchange and therefore a quantitative price, only that there is a linear<br />

symmetric relationship.<br />

Hans: You are packing so much into every sentence that your writing reads like the output <strong>of</strong> a computer program<br />

designed to generate intelligent sounding sentences. Marx’s reasoning is very abstract, which means, Marx tries to<br />

penetrate into the depths <strong>of</strong> the issues. For this one cannot be rushed. You must go much more slowly.<br />

I also recommend that you apply, if only temporarily and for argument’s sake, the concepts and the paradigm<br />

used by Marx. I have the impression that you first are trying to convert everything Marx says into a neoclassical<br />

framework before you are willing to process it. This does not work because Marx’s theory and neoclassical<br />

theory are seriously at odds with each other. I think looking at the Marxian alternative can also strengthen your<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> the neoclassical framework.<br />

I would also recommend that you come to the class sessions or listen to the on-line class podcasts, see<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/audio/<strong>2008SP</strong>/index.htm<br />

You might enjoy it more than you think.<br />

After all this philosophical advice just one substantive remark about your argument why the relativity <strong>of</strong> value<br />

is a fallacy. If Marx says that the exchange relations between commodities are based on something inside the<br />

commodities, this is not the same thing as saying that the use-values <strong>of</strong> the commodities exchanged must be the<br />

same. That what gives a commodity its value has nothing to do with the use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity. (This is one<br />

<strong>of</strong> the points where Marx and mainstream economics go completely different ways.)<br />

Next Message by Bar is [106].<br />

Question 183 is 79 in 1995WI, 101 in 1998WI, 109 in 1999SP, 124 in 2001fa, 181 in<br />

2008fa, 190 in 2009fa, and 212 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 183 What does the qualitative equation “linen = coat” tell us about the coat?<br />

about the linen?<br />

[105] Allen: linen = coat. The qualitative equation shows that the coat has a value because<br />

it can be exchanged for or converted to linen. As for the linen the equation also shows that<br />

the linen has a value in which it can be exchanged for the coat. But as Marx 141:1 states,<br />

this shows us the simple form <strong>of</strong> value, because no matter what the linen weaver is willing<br />

to take in exchange for her 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen be it for one coat or any amount <strong>of</strong> coats, this<br />

equation shows everyone that these two different kinds <strong>of</strong> commodities, linen and coats, are<br />

equal to each other and can be exchanged for one another.<br />

Hans: You should reverse your emphasis. That coat and linen are equal is the obvious message. That the coat is<br />

value because linen can be had for it, and that linen is value because it can be exchanged for the coat which is value,<br />

is the deeper message which is not as obvious.<br />

Message [105] referenced by [328] and [338]. Next Message by Allen is [382].<br />

[259] Srichardson: graded A The qualitative equation that linen = coat shows us that the<br />

coat is value because you can get linen for a coat and that linen is also value because you can<br />

trade it for a coat which is value. The value <strong>of</strong> the coat is held in the labor <strong>of</strong> the coat which<br />

makes it so that the coat has value and can be equal to the linen. Therefore the opportunity<br />

shows the value and not the price at which the coat was sold for. The labor is what makes the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the coat and the linen and because they are exchangeable for each other this shows<br />

the equation linen = coat.<br />

Hans: Your first sentence is right. Then you bring labor in. This is justified because every result <strong>of</strong> Marx’s<br />

theoretical derivation <strong>of</strong> value is told by the relationship between linen and coat. Here is an attempt to bring labor<br />

into the discussion in the right way:<br />

How does the exchange relationship between linen and coat tell us that value comes from labor? Because it<br />

equates linen and coat, and labor is the only thing they have in common. (I think Marx is cheating here a little<br />

bit, he treats a fact as if it could be derived by logic. But if one considers to whom linen and coat are talking,


70 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

namely, to the commodity producers who observe the market in order to know what to produce, then labor comes<br />

in automatically: it is the main decision variable <strong>of</strong> the producers, since the same laborers are able to produce many<br />

different things.)<br />

How does the linen tell us that its value has nothing to do with its bodily properties? By expressing its value in<br />

the (woolen) coat which is an entirely different use-value than the linen itself.<br />

Next Message by Srichardson is [395].<br />

[280] Goethe: graded B Linen = coat. The value <strong>of</strong> the linen is the same as the value <strong>of</strong><br />

the coat. The value <strong>of</strong> the linen is expressed in the terms <strong>of</strong> a coat, and the value <strong>of</strong> a coat<br />

is expressed in terms <strong>of</strong> linen. The coat will have value as it can be exchanged for linen and<br />

the linen will have value as it can be exchanged for the coat.<br />

Hans: The equation “20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is worth a coat” does not mean that the value <strong>of</strong> the linen is the same as the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the coat. Rather it means that the coat is the value <strong>of</strong> the linen.<br />

Message [280] referenced by [2009fa:62] and [2009fa:384]. Next Message by Goethe is [363].<br />

[287] Chris: dissecting a not-so-simple equation. To format my dissection <strong>of</strong> the question,<br />

I referenced passages in Marx’s essay, “The content <strong>of</strong> the relative form <strong>of</strong> value”<br />

starting on page 140 <strong>of</strong> Capital. In reference to the equation “linen = coat,” Marx says on<br />

page 141 that “only the value <strong>of</strong> the linen. . . is expressed.” Linen is the only value expressed<br />

because it is used to make up the coat. The equation tells us that the coat then gains its<br />

use-value because it can be physically used (i.e. keep a person warm).<br />

To turn linen into a coat, human labor must be used. As Marx says on page 144, “a<br />

given quantity <strong>of</strong> any commodity contains a definite quantity <strong>of</strong> human labour.” Once this<br />

human labor is placed on the linen to create the coat, we realize that the coat is a mysterious<br />

embodiment <strong>of</strong> linen. I would go out on a limb to say that the coat as a commodity is the<br />

finalized version <strong>of</strong> the linen. Marx suggests on page 143 that “within its value-relation to<br />

the linen, the coat signifies more than it does outside it, just as some men count for more<br />

when inside a gold-braided uniform than they dootherwise.”<br />

An opinion that I hope is not too far from this question is that one person may find it more<br />

convenient to not go through the process <strong>of</strong> creating the coat from linen and could possibly<br />

exchange more linen to the creator <strong>of</strong> the coat to signify the human labor that was needed.<br />

It is here where we see the capitalist system begin. Capitalists control the machinery to<br />

produce the linen into coats. A Marxist would then say that the capitalists control the human<br />

labor since they control the capital (i.e. machinery). Therefore, the equation “linen = coat”<br />

signifies something much greater than just value within the linen and the coat. It represents<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> the capitalistic society on a macroeconomic level.<br />

Hans: I appreciate your close reading <strong>of</strong> the text, but the idea that the coat represents the value <strong>of</strong> linen because<br />

it is a finished product made out <strong>of</strong> linen is a misconception you must have picked up elsewhere, and you did not<br />

notice that Marx was thinking along completely different lines.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [354].<br />

[303] Dentist: The expression linen = coat tells us that the coat is the “active” expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> the “passive” linen. It also tells us that “linen” and “coat” have something, namely their<br />

value in common. This value that each commodity possesses is what equates them, because<br />

their respective physical properties, use values and the specific labor that produced them<br />

does not, and cannot. It is this third avenue <strong>of</strong> value that allows them to be related to each<br />

other as commodities in some quantitative way.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 71<br />

Whether it is expressed as linen = coat, or as coat = linen, we can conclude that both are<br />

equal to each other in some way. And since their physical properties or specific labor cannot<br />

do this, there must be a third identity that can. This identity is their respective value that<br />

comes from the general human labor used to produce either the linen, or the coat. Now we<br />

have something in common between the commodities that we can measure from to establish<br />

a specific value to both the coat, and the linen. These commodities can now be equated<br />

to each other as values, and exchanged, so long as the appropriate quantities <strong>of</strong> each are<br />

present.<br />

Hans: The linen is active, not the coat. The linen is the thing which expresses.<br />

You are deriving the substance <strong>of</strong> value from the form, while the question, and Marx’s text around the question,<br />

is concerned about a closer investigation <strong>of</strong> the form itself.<br />

In your last two sentences you say that things can be exchanged because they have something in common.<br />

This is not quite right. Things can be exchanged even if they have nothing in common. But if the exchange is<br />

as ubiquitous as in a capitalist society, then it would not make sense if goods would be exchanged, i.e., treated as<br />

equals on the market, if they did not indeed be in some way equal.<br />

Next Message by Dentist is [304].<br />

[324] Papageorgio: Linen=Coat. When we look at the qualitative equation linen = coat<br />

we first see the obvious part <strong>of</strong> this equation, simply that linen is equal to the coat. The<br />

equation as we look at it shows us that the commodity owners feel that the labor that is put<br />

into the coat is equal to the labor put into the linen. When in the reading we are told 20 yards<br />

<strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat it is putting value on both the linen and also the coat. The labor that is<br />

put into the linen is being placed equal with the labor that was put into making the coat. So<br />

therfore the equality comes from labor. I really enjoyed what Allison said, in [1995WI:324],<br />

she states, “the value is not socially {1} determined but rather socially {2} determined...by<br />

the interpersonal interactions and contact <strong>of</strong> the commodities themselves.” In this class we<br />

talk about expression <strong>of</strong> value, and this is a very good example where we can show that<br />

expression, and a very good quote by her to help back this up. I’m glad I was able to use<br />

sources in my revision and see this.<br />

If a weaver is willing to trade the linen for a coat, it is because he/she feels that the labor<br />

that was put into the linen has given it value. He/she feels that it can be put up against<br />

soemthing, exchangeable if you will. Qualitatively we look at this equation and must ask<br />

ourselves if the labor we put into something is worth what we want for it.<br />

Hans: The distinction between social {1} and social {2} was important in the earlier editions <strong>of</strong> the Annotations, but<br />

later I discontinued this notation while maintaining the meaning <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

A social {2} relationship is an interpersonal relationship, in which people indeed come in contact with each<br />

other. A social relationship as distinct from an interpersonal relationship is called a social {1} relationship.<br />

For instance value is a social relationship which can be compared to an immaterial substance inside the products<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor, i.e., which should not be understood as a social {2} relationship. Everybody in a commodity economy treats<br />

the products <strong>of</strong> labor as if they had the labor-power used in producing them still attached to them like the emperor’s<br />

new clothes. This immaterial substance needs a “form” or, in other words, an interpersonal social {2} relationship<br />

which co-ordinates the activities so that everyone indeed treats the emperor’s new clothes as if they were real. This<br />

form <strong>of</strong> value is the exchange-value and ultimately money.<br />

Next Message by Papageorgio is [327].<br />

[328] Spawnblade: The qualitative equation “linen=coat” tells us simply that the coat<br />

and linen are equal. Allen [105] explains that because <strong>of</strong> this equation, it doesn’t matter<br />

what the “weaver” will exchange her 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen for, this qualitative statement says it<br />

is irrelevant. This means the coat has the same value as the linen, and the linen the same


72 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

value as the coat, and because <strong>of</strong> this they both now have a value because <strong>of</strong> the possibility<br />

for exchange derived from their equality.<br />

Hans: Your formulation “the coat has the same value as the linen” puts the quantitative dimension back in, because<br />

this formulation usually means “the value <strong>of</strong> the coat is as big as that <strong>of</strong> the linen.”<br />

Nobody says the quantitative exchange proportion does not matter. Marx says only that this quantitative information<br />

should not overshadow the qualitative fact that coats can be had for linen. There is already a lot <strong>of</strong><br />

information in this, even without knowing the quantitative exchange proportion. In your in-class answer you are<br />

saying that as use-values, coat and linen are not the same. Marx would agree; but he would continue: if they are<br />

treated as equals (on the market) then something in them must be equal. It is not their use-value but their labor. If<br />

nothing in them were equal, then the equal treatment on the market would have no basis and the market would not<br />

be the right surface mediation for the relations <strong>of</strong> production under which they are produced. (This last sentence is<br />

not exactly Marx himself but my interpretation <strong>of</strong> how Marx must be understood.)<br />

Next Message by Spawnblade is [331].<br />

[338] Khwai: graded A+ The asymmetry <strong>of</strong> “linen = coat” The qualitative equation<br />

“linen = coat” serves to illustrate the social relation between linen and coat. Obviously we<br />

know that linen and coat are not the same commodity and so this is not a total equivalence<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> form but rather showing a relation <strong>of</strong> value. This relation is based upon the<br />

perspective <strong>of</strong> the weaver and hence the equation is qualitatively asymmetric, meaning the<br />

statements “linen = coat” and “coat = linen” are not equivalent. The weaver, who has created<br />

the linen, knows the labor-time used in the creation <strong>of</strong> the linen and hence the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

linen. This is not yet apparent to society at large as they have no means <strong>of</strong> knowing the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> linen. The weaver declares that “20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is worth one coat” As Marx states<br />

in 141:1, the quantitative measure within this statement is not important for our current<br />

discussion inasmuch as they merely modify magnitude; but the admission that both linen<br />

and coat are both “expressions <strong>of</strong> the same unit” or expressions <strong>of</strong> value is significant.<br />

The weaver has recognized the use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat and expressed their willingness to<br />

exchange linen, an object whose labor-value they are intimately aware <strong>of</strong>, for said coat. This<br />

then establishes not only the relationship between linen and coat but also society’s perception<br />

<strong>of</strong> linen and coat. Coat now is perceived as a symbol <strong>of</strong> value because it is exchangeable<br />

for linen, though this is an expression <strong>of</strong> the coat’s use-value as perceived by the weaver and<br />

may not be obvious to all. It follows that linen must also be value in order to be exchanged<br />

for coat as Marx states, “for only as value can the linen point to the coat as something<br />

equivalent with linen or exchangeable for linen”. Re-emphasizing the asymmetry <strong>of</strong> this<br />

equation Marx states in 141:2 that “only the value <strong>of</strong> the linen is expressed, not that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

coat.” The linen takes an active role exhibiting its labor-value whereas the coat is passive<br />

and serves as a symbol <strong>of</strong> value. It is through this social relation <strong>of</strong> an exchange that society<br />

is able to recognize the value <strong>of</strong> the linen.<br />

Hans provided a succinct summary <strong>of</strong> this answer in his comments on Allen’s answer in<br />

[105], “the coat is value because linen can be had for it and [the] linen is value because it<br />

can be exchanged for the coat which is value”.<br />

Message [338] referenced by [378], [2009fa:62], [2009fa:457], [2009fa:480], [2009fa:504], and [2009fa:548]. First<br />

Message by Khwai is [329].<br />

[343] Jenn: graded A– “=” equals social relationship. The qualitative equation “linen=coat”<br />

can tell us about value expression both from a market standpoint, and an individual producer<br />

standpoint. From a market standpoint, the equation shows that there is a social relationship


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 73<br />

between the linen and the coat. They both have value, and therefore contain congealed abstract<br />

labor. However, in Marx’s text, the linen is defined as being the “active” commodity,<br />

and the coat is the “passive” commodity. The value <strong>of</strong> the “active” commodity (linen) is<br />

being expressed through the “passive” commodity (coat). This equation tells us that it is<br />

socially acceptable to exchange linen for a coat.<br />

From an individual producer’s standpoint, as Hans cites in [2001fa:61], the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

linen is expressed in the use-value <strong>of</strong> the coat. The linen producer is asking his/herself<br />

whether they would accept a coat in exchange for the commodity in which they put useful<br />

labor into producing. Evaluating this equation from this perspective also demonstrates that<br />

the “=” sign represents a social relationship between the commodities, and not a quantitative<br />

value.<br />

Next Message by Jenn is [527].<br />

[346] Tim: graded B– The Qualitative equation linen = coat is an interesting statement<br />

because obviously a coat does not equal linen, but in the eyes <strong>of</strong> the linen weaver a certain<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> linen is equal in value to the coat. The weaver knows how much labor went into<br />

the linen, and the weaver knows how much he is giving up when trading a certain amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> linen for the coat. Before the trade takes place, unless you are a linen weaver, you will<br />

not know how much linen is worth a coat. The same goes for all commodities when they<br />

are being exchanged for a coat. Unless the person trading for the coat knows the true value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the item being traded, the true value <strong>of</strong> the coat can not be determined. When comparing<br />

the coat with other items, value is unknown unless, the person who made the item is there<br />

to know how much was given up in order to produce the item. This equation can be made<br />

using other items, not just linen and coats, but one must know how much <strong>of</strong> one item it takes<br />

to match the value <strong>of</strong> the other item in order to have an equal trade.<br />

Hans: “20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is worth one coat” is not a comparison <strong>of</strong> the values, i.e., it is different from saying that<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is equal to the value <strong>of</strong> the coat. Instead, in the above statement the coat is the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen.<br />

Next Message by Tim is [458].<br />

[352] Raynold: x commodity A = y commodity B, or x commodity A is worth y commodity<br />

B.<br />

20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat, or 20 Yards <strong>of</strong> linen are worth 1 coat.<br />

Here two different kinds <strong>of</strong> commodities (in our example the linen and the coat), evidently<br />

play two different parts. The linen expresses its value in the coat; the coat serves as the<br />

material in which that value is expressed. The former plays an active, the latter a passive,<br />

part. The value <strong>of</strong> the linen is represented as relative value, or appears in relative form. The<br />

coat <strong>of</strong>ficiates as equivalent, or appears in equivalent form.<br />

The relative form and the equivalent form are two intimately connected, mutually dependent<br />

and inseparable elements <strong>of</strong> the expression <strong>of</strong> value; but, at the same time, are mutually<br />

exclusive, antagonistic extremes – i.e., poles <strong>of</strong> the same expression. They are allotted respectively<br />

to the two different commodities brought into relation by that expression. It is not<br />

possible to express the value <strong>of</strong> linen in linen. 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is no<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> value. On the contrary, such an equation merely says that 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen<br />

are nothing else than 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen, a definite quantity <strong>of</strong> the use value linen. The value


74 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> the linen can therefore be expressed only relatively – i.e., in some other commodity. The<br />

relative form <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the linen presupposes, therefore, the presence <strong>of</strong> some other<br />

commodity – here the coat – under the form <strong>of</strong> an equivalent. On the other hand, the commodity<br />

that figures as the equivalent cannot at the same time assume the relative form. That<br />

second commodity is not the one whose value is expressed. Its function is merely to serve<br />

as the material in which the value <strong>of</strong> the first commodity is expressed.<br />

No doubt, the expression 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen = 1 coat, or 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen are worth 1<br />

coat, implies the opposite relation. 1 coat = 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen, or 1 coat is worth 20 yards<br />

<strong>of</strong> linen. But, in that case, I must reverse the equation, in order to express the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

coat relatively; and. so soon as I do that the linen becomes the equivalent instead <strong>of</strong> the coat.<br />

A single commodity cannot, therefore, simultaneously assume, in the same expression <strong>of</strong><br />

value, both forms. The very polarity <strong>of</strong> these forms makes them mutually exclusive.<br />

Whether, then, a commodity assumes the relative form, or the opposite equivalent form,<br />

depends entirely upon its accidental position in the expression <strong>of</strong> value – that is, upon<br />

whether it is the commodity whose value is being expressed or the commodity in which<br />

value is being expressed.<br />

http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1867-c1/ch01.htm#S3<br />

Next Message by Raynold is [358].<br />

[360] Slash: 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen equals one coat. 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen equals one coat because<br />

both linen and the coat have value. The value Marx is talking about it labor. In my in class<br />

essay I made the mistake <strong>of</strong> misunderstanding linen’s value due to it being used to make the<br />

coat. The coat itself is a separate object, displaying its use value, which is wanting to be<br />

sold, or exchanged. The coat doesn’t represent the value <strong>of</strong> the linen, but rather indicates<br />

the labor on the coat which could have been used to make linen. The linen being turned into<br />

coat is not important, because total labor needed to manufacture the coat plus all its materials<br />

equals the total labor needed to make the linen. 20 years <strong>of</strong> linen equals one coat is simply<br />

a qualitative question, because it represents the linen weaver’s decision to trade 20 yards <strong>of</strong><br />

linen for 1 coat.<br />

Hans: Perhaps you should have said: the coat does not represent the use-value <strong>of</strong> the linen, because in Marx’s<br />

terminology, making the labor in the linen visible as labor which could also have been used to make a coat is<br />

exactly what “representing the value <strong>of</strong> the linen” means.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [464].<br />

[368] Andy: In class Response:<br />

The qualitative equation “linen = coat” means that these commodities have the same<br />

value, in the sense that their exchangeable values that are the same. This tells us that the<br />

coat is equal to linen in the sense that its labor is equal therefore they are exchangeable even<br />

though their use values may be different they are an equal commodity. Meaning the owner<br />

<strong>of</strong> the coat agrees that it is an equal exchange for the linen, and the owner <strong>of</strong> the linen agrees<br />

that is an equal exchange for the warmth <strong>of</strong> the coat. However it could be a different equation<br />

if the values were thought to be different for example it could be 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen for one<br />

coat. So you must first find the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity before finding the correct equation.<br />

Out <strong>of</strong> class Response:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 75<br />

Given this equation it doesn’t matter how much linen, or how many coats is thrown into<br />

the equation. Whatever the proportion, these are things <strong>of</strong> the same nature. It is an exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong>fer that tells everyone that in some respects, the two different commodity-kinds linen and<br />

coat are equal to each other. Marx says that this equation is asymmetric, that the linen is<br />

produced by the producer regarding the labor time, skills, materials and equipment used,<br />

and the coat is a use value the linen weaver needs. The linen is <strong>of</strong>fered on the market in<br />

exchange for coats where coats can convert into linen but linen is not exchangeable for<br />

coats. So to sum this up the value <strong>of</strong> the coat may be more “dazzling” than the linen. But in<br />

society these two commodity values are generally equivalent.<br />

Next Message by Andy is [476].<br />

[369] Samantha: Equality gained through labor. The equation “linen=coat” tells us<br />

that the coat while having a value that is deemed higher by the bourgeoisie does not have<br />

a qualitative value higher than the linen. Hans in [2007fa:186] says, “(Marx) infers that<br />

commodities must have something equal inside them in order to be exchangeable”. This<br />

equality is the labor that is done to both in order to get the linen and the coat, meaning that<br />

both the labor <strong>of</strong> the person making the coat and the labor <strong>of</strong> the person making the linen<br />

should be valued equally. This is how Marx is arguing value throughout this whole section,<br />

by claiming that society makes the coat worth more, but that truly the labor and therefore<br />

the value should be equal. Regardless <strong>of</strong> the fact that the linen can be made into the coat the<br />

labor should be valued the same.<br />

Hans: You are still thinking in terms <strong>of</strong> quantitative equality. The labor making linen and the labor making coats<br />

are qualitatively equal. This is true whether the value <strong>of</strong> 20 yards <strong>of</strong> linen is more or less than that <strong>of</strong> the coat. What<br />

is your argument that the bourgeoisie values the coat higher than the linen? Please answer this question through the<br />

fill-in form in the html archives, i.e., by going to<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/<strong>2008SP</strong>/369.htm<br />

Next Message by Samantha is [370].<br />

[378] Jeremy: The qualitative equation “linen=coat” tells us many things about the coat<br />

and the linen. In terms <strong>of</strong> exchange value, they are the equivalent <strong>of</strong> each other. The labor<br />

is valued equally between both as well. The labor put into each, for the agreed upon<br />

quantity <strong>of</strong> coat and linen, is seen as equal. This statement also implies that under all circumstances,<br />

linen is the equivalent <strong>of</strong> the coat and vice-versa. Very briefly, it also implies<br />

that specialization can be reduced and even set equal to general abstract labor.<br />

Hans: Actually, the equalization <strong>of</strong> labors increases specialization: commodity producers try to escape the equalization<br />

imposed by the market by finding a niche <strong>of</strong> specialized labor which is rewarded better by the market.<br />

Your items are ok, but Marx had a different story what this equation tells us about linen and coat. It is a quite<br />

subtle kind <strong>of</strong> argument and worth looking at. To begin with, Marx considers it as an asymmetric equation. Khwai<br />

[338] gives an excellent summary <strong>of</strong> Marx’s argument as read through the lense <strong>of</strong> my Annotations.<br />

Next Message by Jeremy is [473].<br />

[631] Rmuscolino: The qualitative equation, “linen = coat” are both magnitudes <strong>of</strong> value,<br />

expressions <strong>of</strong> the same unit, and things <strong>of</strong> the same nature. Linen = coat is the basis <strong>of</strong> the<br />

equation. The exchange <strong>of</strong>fer tells us that is some respects, the two different commoditykinds<br />

linen and coat are equal to each other. Marx adds the asymmetry to this equality<br />

by looking at the individual motivation <strong>of</strong> the linen weaver and the fact that the linen is a<br />

commodity which the linen weaver has produced. The coat is a use-value the linen weaver<br />

needs. The linen is <strong>of</strong>fered on the market in exchange for coats. Marx also states that by


76 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

setting the coat as a thing <strong>of</strong> value equal to the linen, the commodity owners also set the<br />

labor embedded in the coat equal to the labor embedded in the linen.<br />

Next Message by Rmuscolino is [632].<br />

Question 223 is 216 in 2007fa, 221 in 2008fa, 234 in 2009fa, 261 in 2010fa, 225 in<br />

2011fa, and 235 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 223 How does it become plain here that it is not the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities<br />

which regulates the magnitude <strong>of</strong> their values, but rather the reverse, it is the magnitude <strong>of</strong><br />

the value <strong>of</strong> commodities which regulates the proportion in which they are exchanged?<br />

[136] Kevin: graded A– Opportunity cost vs. price. Marcellus [2007fa:103] does a<br />

great job illustrating this concept. He shows that just because someone is given something<br />

<strong>of</strong> different use-value for a commodity, it does not change the actual value <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

itself.<br />

If I understand the concept correctly, the coat, in the example by Marx, has its own value<br />

before ever coming to market. Its intrinsic value is the labor which went into making the<br />

coat. This labor includes not only the physically demanding time <strong>of</strong> creating the coat but<br />

also the skill and knowledge the laborer possessed that became woven into the coat itself.<br />

This is the value <strong>of</strong> the coat.<br />

Thus, for only the people who know what labor went into making the coat will the exchange<br />

value equal the actual value <strong>of</strong> the coat. Individuals who are unaware <strong>of</strong> the labor<br />

spent on the commodity are likely to trade it for something <strong>of</strong> greater or lesser value and<br />

have no idea. That unequal exchange does nothing to change the actual value <strong>of</strong> the coat.<br />

Even if it were to affect the next exchange value <strong>of</strong> the coat, the real value <strong>of</strong> the coat would<br />

not be affected.<br />

The value <strong>of</strong> the coat is really the opportunity cost <strong>of</strong> the creation <strong>of</strong> the coat. If that<br />

laborer had worked equally as hard at something else he was equally qualified to make, the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> that new commodity would be exactly equal to the value <strong>of</strong> the coat regardless <strong>of</strong><br />

what was traded either was traded for after production. Therefore, the opportunity really<br />

shows the value and not the price at which the coat was sold.<br />

Message [136] referenced by [144]. Next Message by Kevin is [138].<br />

[144] Hans: Market Participants’ Knowledge <strong>of</strong> Labor time. Kevin writes in [136]:<br />

Thus, for only the people who know what labor went into making the coat<br />

will the exchange value equal the actual value <strong>of</strong> the coat. Individuals who<br />

are unaware <strong>of</strong> the labor spent on the commodity are likely to trade it for<br />

something <strong>of</strong> greater or lesser value and have no idea.<br />

Such particular knowledge by the market participants is not necessary. In [2005fa:966], I<br />

compared the market to a big camera which makes an image <strong>of</strong> the otherwise invisible labor<br />

contents on the surface:<br />

Commodity circulation acts as a big photo camera that projects a picture<br />

<strong>of</strong> the otherwise invisible labor contents in the prices haggled out on the<br />

market. This photographic process works as follows: if a good is in excess


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 77<br />

demand, its price is bid up, and then the producers will switch more labor<br />

into producing this good and increase its supply and lower its price. This<br />

process goes on until prices are proportional to labor inputs, at which point<br />

nobody is motivated to switch labor around any more.<br />

In [2007SP:586] I tried to convey the same message by calling the labor content the<br />

“elephant in the room” whenever an exchange is made:<br />

Although nobody is talking about this labor content, it plays an important<br />

role in the surface interactions; it is so-to-say the elephant in the room. If<br />

market prices are above the value determined by this labor content, more<br />

suppliers will tend to appear on the market until the discrepancy between<br />

values and prices disappears, and if market prices are below value, supply<br />

will diminish.<br />

Message [144] referenced by [153], [215], [295], [296], [332], [335], [370], [375], [2011fa:90], [2012fa:206], and<br />

[2012fa:277]. Next Message by Hans is [145].<br />

Question 235 is 221 in 2007SP, 228 in 2007fa, 246 in 2009fa, and 249 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 235 Compare Marx’s derivation <strong>of</strong> money with the derivations <strong>of</strong> money in modern<br />

Economics<br />

[129] PrivateProperty: Derivation <strong>of</strong> Money: Marx v. Mainstream. Marx derives the<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> money through the exchange relations <strong>of</strong> commodities. First, he starts with the<br />

simple form <strong>of</strong> value, in which one commodity (i.e. linen) is traded against another (i.e.<br />

coat); this form expresses two commodities as an exchange relation (i.e. 20 yards linen = 1<br />

coat). Going one step further, Marx states that in this exchange, one commodity is valued in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> the other commodity(s) that can be got for it. Obviously, there are usually multiple<br />

commodities in an economy, so linen can be valued in terms <strong>of</strong> every other commodity it<br />

can be exchanged for (i.e. a certain number <strong>of</strong> coats, bushels <strong>of</strong> wheat, pounds <strong>of</strong> lead, etc.).<br />

Eventually Marx gets to a point, known as the General Form, in which every commodity is<br />

valued in relation to each other. At such a point one particular commodity becomes a standard<br />

store <strong>of</strong> value, either because it is an <strong>of</strong>ten-exchanged or easy-to-exchange commodity,<br />

or both. This commodity relates the value <strong>of</strong> all goods to one another; in other words, it is<br />

money.<br />

As Hans noted in [2007SP:281], the mere exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities does not imbue them<br />

with value. Commodities are already endowed with value from the abstract labor that is<br />

‘congealed’ inside them. The exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities simply make this value manifest. In<br />

Hans’ words, “. . . circulation is necessary to tease the hidden value out <strong>of</strong> commodities.”<br />

Modern economic thought takes commodities as universally exchangeable, and then introduces<br />

money to make exchange more efficient. This views money as a sort <strong>of</strong> tool, separate<br />

from commodities, that intermediates between supply and demand for a given commodity.<br />

Marx would say that this is nonsense, because money is entwined with the exchange <strong>of</strong><br />

all commodities, and that it is the General value relation between all commodities that allows<br />

the existence <strong>of</strong> money in the first place.<br />

Message [129] referenced by [142]. Next Message by PrivateProperty is [134].


78 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[142] Hans: First Function <strong>of</strong> Money. I’d like to repeat and emphasize what PrivateProperty<br />

said in the last paragraph <strong>of</strong> [129], namely, that the main difference between mainstream<br />

and Marxian monetary theory is that most (not all) mainstream theories <strong>of</strong> money derive<br />

money from transaction costs, i.e., its use as means <strong>of</strong> circulation, while for Marx, the first<br />

function <strong>of</strong> money is that <strong>of</strong> measure <strong>of</strong> value. Measure <strong>of</strong> value is a much more basic issue,<br />

it is the compass needle by which businesses everywhere make their decisions. The archives<br />

have occasional references to this, see for instance [2005fa:1001]. My next message will be<br />

a Wall Street Journal editorial talking about the dangers <strong>of</strong> ddebauchment <strong>of</strong> the currency.<br />

Such debauchment is so dangerous because value needs a reliable exterior measure. These<br />

are the same issues which Marx addresses in section 3 <strong>of</strong> chapter One, when he derives<br />

money as the most appropriate “expression <strong>of</strong> value.” If Keynes says that not one man in a<br />

million is able to diagnose the damage done by currency debauchment, my explanation is<br />

that they have not learnt to think in the framework Marx develops here.<br />

Message [142] referenced by [2012fa:195]. Next Message by Hans is [143].<br />

[143] Hans: The Dollar and the Market Mess. COMMENTARY by BILL WILBY<br />

Wall Street Journal January 23, 2008; Page A25<br />

http://online.wsj.com/article/SB120105077515308369.html<br />

Lenin was surely right. There is no subtler, no surer means <strong>of</strong> overturning<br />

the existing basis <strong>of</strong> society than to debauch the currency. The process<br />

engages all the hidden forces <strong>of</strong> economic law on the side <strong>of</strong> destruction,<br />

and does it in a manner which not one man in a million is able to diagnose.<br />

– John Maynard Keynes<br />

Currency debauchment is a choice. Most governments don’t want to debauch their currency<br />

– it’s just that they don’t want to take the actions that might prevent it, because those<br />

actions are perceived to be intolerably painful. Thus it was that last fall, the Federal Reserve,<br />

the world’s central bank, decided to “let the dollar go” because staying the course on interest<br />

rates might threaten the world’s financial system (or so the argument goes).<br />

Meanwhile oil prices are high, inflation is considerably above the Fed’s own stated longterm<br />

targets, and the dollar is in danger <strong>of</strong> losing its reserve currency status. Should we<br />

care? Are saving the dollar and saving the global financial system mutually exclusive alternatives?<br />

And isn’t a dollar decline necessary for “rebalancing” the U.S.’s external deficits?<br />

The answer to the first question is a resounding yes, and to the last two questions, resounding<br />

nos.<br />

Why is a weak dollar bad for America? First <strong>of</strong> all, it directly pushes up oil and other<br />

commodity prices by paying the producers with a depreciating piece <strong>of</strong> paper (thus removing<br />

the incentive to increase production), while lowering local currency oil prices for the rest <strong>of</strong><br />

the world (thus increasing oil demand at the margin). It is no coincidence that the world’s two<br />

great oil shocks in 1972-73 and 2004-2007 both came after long periods <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>f-balance-sheet<br />

global monetary expansion and subsequent dollar weakness – the growth <strong>of</strong> the eurodollar<br />

market in the late 1960s and 1970s, and the SIV and CDO expansion <strong>of</strong> the last several<br />

years.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 79<br />

Oil traders know this, and it is why the immediate consequence <strong>of</strong> the Fed’s earlier 50basis-point<br />

cut was to take the dollar down and oil prices up. One could write a separate<br />

essay on what a lower dollar and higher oil prices do to our strategic interests, such as<br />

propping up regimes like those in Iran and Russia.<br />

Second, a lower dollar reduces the wealth <strong>of</strong> the U.S. consumer in global terms, immediately<br />

through the dollar’s lower purchasing power, and longer term through the erosive<br />

impact <strong>of</strong> inflation. It hits retirees and those on fixed incomes particularly hard, and is a<br />

totally counterproductive policy for a potentially weak consumer.<br />

Third, the weaker dollar accelerates the growth <strong>of</strong> our competitors. China may be growing<br />

at 11% or more in yuan terms, but their growth in U.S. dollars in 2007 was greater than<br />

17%, and it is their dollar growth rate that is relevant for the rate <strong>of</strong> their rise in the world’s<br />

economic hierarchy. Using Europe as another example, in 2002 U.S. nominal GDP was<br />

nearly 10% larger than that <strong>of</strong> the Eurozone 15. Today it is 14.3% smaller. Although Europe<br />

has been growing more slowly, its global economic power has been rising more rapidly than<br />

that <strong>of</strong> the U.S. because <strong>of</strong> our falling greenback.<br />

Finally, if America were to lose its reserve currency status because <strong>of</strong> a continued loss<br />

<strong>of</strong> confidence in the dollar, the cost in terms <strong>of</strong> jobs and growth would be significant. The<br />

real economic benefit conveyed by the right to print the accepted global currency is called<br />

seignorage, which results in part from the lower capital cost we derive from foreigners’<br />

willingness to hold dollar cash. This country has taken for granted the benefits <strong>of</strong> our global<br />

seignorage for many years, and it is one <strong>of</strong> the reasons the U.S. has maintained a higher<br />

growth rate than the world’s other mature economies.<br />

But don’t we need a lower dollar to “correct” our large trade and current account deficits?<br />

In the first place, our accounting deficits are largely with our own overseas subsidiaries (more<br />

than 50% <strong>of</strong> world trade is intra-company trade) and reflect an increasingly globalized world<br />

economy. Second, America is the shopping mall for the world. Because our distribution<br />

system is the world’s most efficient, retail prices for the world’s goods are lower here, and we<br />

have been the shopping destination for the world’s consumers even before the dollar began<br />

its recent fall. These foreign purchases prop up retail sales (helping to explain the resilience<br />

<strong>of</strong> the U.S. consumer), depress our measured savings rate, and result in an underreporting<br />

<strong>of</strong> U.S. exports and an exaggerated measure <strong>of</strong> our imports (some significant share <strong>of</strong> our<br />

imports are actually bought by foreigners).<br />

The ability <strong>of</strong> currency moves to correct trade deficits or surpluses depends on the elasticity<br />

<strong>of</strong> demand and supply. Because <strong>of</strong> increasingly specialized world trade, the elasticity<br />

associated with our exports and imports are very low. Thus a falling dollar is likely to increase<br />

the dollar amount <strong>of</strong> our imports (the infamous J-curve), and force the bulk <strong>of</strong> the<br />

adjustment to currency moves into the “income effect” that results from our higher bills<br />

(witness the impact <strong>of</strong> higher oil prices on the U.S. consumer). Moreover, our current account<br />

deficit for a year is equal to only a fraction <strong>of</strong> the dollar’s foreign-exchange trades for<br />

a day. To say that one is either the cause or consequence <strong>of</strong> the other is almost laughable.<br />

Our external deficits are largely measures <strong>of</strong> Federal Reserve and banking-system liquidity<br />

creation, just as the dollar’s exchange rate is a function <strong>of</strong> foreign trust in holding dollar


80 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

cash or near-cash balances as a monetary store <strong>of</strong> value (these balances are the lion’s share<br />

<strong>of</strong> our so-called foreign debt). Thus, our deficits will only be ameliorated by a slowdown<br />

in liquidity creation itself. Just such a slowdown is likely now underway as a result <strong>of</strong> the<br />

mortgage crisis as we enter 2008, but any attempt by the Fed to ease at the expense <strong>of</strong> further<br />

dollar declines will likely snatch defeat from the jaws <strong>of</strong> victory, and risk a global inflation<br />

<strong>of</strong> significant proportions over the next several years.<br />

Doesn’t a failure to respond aggressively to the credit crisis by cutting rates too slowly<br />

risk a recession, or a Japan-like breakdown <strong>of</strong> the world’s financial system? Unfortunately<br />

the recession risk is high, but not because <strong>of</strong> high interest rates (which are currently negative<br />

in real, after-tax terms). The recession risk is high because <strong>of</strong> a breakdown in the absurd<br />

system that developed for the packaging and underwriting <strong>of</strong> debt, and the excess liquidity<br />

that developed from the combination <strong>of</strong> that system and a highly stimulative monetary policy.<br />

The Fed took a gamble on inflation to ward <strong>of</strong>f what was perceived as a deflationary threat<br />

in 2001-02. The inflationary consequences <strong>of</strong> that gamble are now here, with the petrodollar<br />

monetary merry-go-round fueled by the weaker dollar. Those consequences will be much<br />

easier to deal with now, rather than later. Unlike Japan, where the capital-markets risk was<br />

concentrated in a handful <strong>of</strong> thinly capitalized large banks, the very growth <strong>of</strong> the creditderivatives<br />

market that is the source <strong>of</strong> the current crisis in the U.S. has also resulted in a<br />

wide dispersion <strong>of</strong> risk in the financial system, and any recession will likely be mild and<br />

short.<br />

While we might see a number <strong>of</strong> hedge funds and some isolated banks fail, the pool<br />

<strong>of</strong> distressed asset buyers waiting in the wings would result in a needed consolidation <strong>of</strong><br />

the financial-services industry, without systemic failure. In the meantime, the systemic risk<br />

posed by the failure <strong>of</strong> one or more <strong>of</strong> these institutions is minimal compared to the moral<br />

hazard and longer-term inflation risks we incur from their bailout.<br />

Sadly, the dimensions <strong>of</strong> the Fed’s great dilemma would be much less acute had the Fed<br />

and Treasury <strong>of</strong>ficials not taken such a cavalier approach to the U.S. dollar over the past eight<br />

years. Our “strong dollar” (wink, wink) policy has never been articulated by either institution<br />

with any real conviction, and markets have rightly sensed that maintaining employment,<br />

growth and stock-market happiness has begun to take precedence over maintaining the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> money. In a world <strong>of</strong> fiat currencies, where trust is your most powerful policy tool, dollar<br />

strength is a far better indicator as to the appropriate stance <strong>of</strong> monetary policy than “core”<br />

inflation.<br />

Any further loss <strong>of</strong> confidence in the U.S. currency will cost us dearly in terms <strong>of</strong> both<br />

price stability and jobs in the long run, as it will imply a higher level <strong>of</strong> interest rates to<br />

maintain a given monetary stance. A convincing elevation <strong>of</strong> the dollar in the policy priority<br />

list for both the Fed and the Treasury would be the single greatest step that either institution<br />

could take in restoring health to the financial system.<br />

Mr. Wilby is a former head <strong>of</strong> equities at OppenheimerFunds.<br />

Message [143] referenced by [2008fa:284]. Next Message by Hans is [144].<br />

[484] Ken: exchange with or without money. Marx’s derivation <strong>of</strong> money would be<br />

described by exchange without money and exchange with money. Exchange without money


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 81<br />

would be the exchange between two people that want to exchange a commodity for a different<br />

commodity that the other person has. For example, if a farmer who produces wheat<br />

needed horse shoes for his animals, he would find a blacksmith who was in need <strong>of</strong> wheat.<br />

The farmer and the blacksmith would decide how many bushels <strong>of</strong> wheat a pair <strong>of</strong> horseshoes<br />

is worth. After a negotiation <strong>of</strong> the worth <strong>of</strong> the commodities was agreed upon, the<br />

exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities would be settled.<br />

The derivation <strong>of</strong> money in modern economics is generally exchange with money. It<br />

doesn’t matter what money is made <strong>of</strong>, as long as people agree on the value <strong>of</strong> the money.<br />

This allows people to exchange commodities without having to have a particular commodity<br />

that the other person wants. The seller <strong>of</strong> the commodity can measure the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity in money. Then the seller can exchange the commodity for money, having the<br />

money be the intermediary.<br />

Hans: In Marx, the first function <strong>of</strong> money is measure <strong>of</strong> value, while in most mainstream economics it is means<br />

<strong>of</strong> circulation.<br />

Next Message by Ken is [557].<br />

Exam Question 239 is 166 in 2001fa, 184 in 2003fa, 211 in 2004fa, 207 in 2005fa, 227<br />

in 2007SP, 250 in 2009fa, 277 in 2010fa, 245 in 2011fa, and 255 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam Question 239 What is the difference between commodity fetishism and the fetish-like<br />

character <strong>of</strong> commodities?<br />

[149] CousinIt: (graded A) fetish and fetish-like character. This question does have<br />

a simple answer: Commodity fetishism is the view from the subjective individual position<br />

(individualistic idealism), whereas the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity is the view<br />

when one looks at the overall social structure <strong>of</strong> capitalism in which individuals fill predetermined<br />

functional roles within the social structure dictated by the commodity as the<br />

basic social unit.<br />

Commodity fetishism is the mistaken belief that the physical properties <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

as a use-value, such as a table, determine the social relations as they appear at the surface.<br />

It is the same mistaken belief in appearances that causes people to think that the making<br />

<strong>of</strong> tables in mass-production is natural because people buy lots <strong>of</strong> tables every day because<br />

everybody needs tables so it is natural to make lots <strong>of</strong> tables all the time... i.e. circular<br />

solipsism(?)... It is like believing that we need to control and exploit all possible petroleum<br />

reserves because people need petroleum so we need to control petroluem reserves because<br />

people need petroleum. It is not really that petroleum is needed but that some source <strong>of</strong><br />

energy is needed, yet we mistakenly insist that it is petroleum (as the preferred commodity)<br />

that we need and see the control and exploitation <strong>of</strong> petroleum as the only and natural<br />

outcome...again, a vicious circular reasoning.<br />

We come to taking this kind <strong>of</strong> circular reasoning as ‘normal’ because <strong>of</strong> the fetishlike<br />

character <strong>of</strong> the commodity in which the social relations <strong>of</strong> production are masked by<br />

the transactions at the surface and thus mistake the surface relations as being natural...the<br />

production <strong>of</strong> things as commodities (i.e. as ’things made for sale’) is mistaken as the production<br />

<strong>of</strong> things as use-values. The commodity is mistaken as the only possible natural<br />

outcome. The real relations are obscured by the notion that everything that is made for sale


82 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(all commodity) stems from what people actually need. We mistake the commodity as the<br />

only possible natural outcome <strong>of</strong> all human labor.<br />

We are somehow blind to the fact that the making <strong>of</strong> things for sale is the cause <strong>of</strong> people<br />

making things for sale.<br />

Rather than recognizing this circularity, this outcome seems to be the most natural thing,<br />

because we believe that the physical properties <strong>of</strong> the things (taken as they appear at the<br />

surface) are the totality <strong>of</strong> their social relations. Because we fail to see underneath the<br />

surface relations <strong>of</strong> commodities to the relations <strong>of</strong> production in a commodity economy,<br />

we fail to recognize that what we take to be ‘natural’ is in fact a pathological distortion, a<br />

dis-ease, a perversion, <strong>of</strong> natural human relations.<br />

The commodity acts as the magical fetish-god that mysteriously determines yet simultaneously<br />

masks all social relations. We mistakenly believe that all human social relations<br />

naturally produce the commodity form. However, the emergence <strong>of</strong> the commodity is ‘natural’<br />

(or ‘naturalized’ by way <strong>of</strong> ideology) only under capitalism. The fact that we do not see<br />

this is the result <strong>of</strong> falling prey to the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity which masks<br />

the underlying reality <strong>of</strong> class exploitation.<br />

Next Message by CousinIt is [155].<br />

Question 241 is 213 in 2004fa, 209 in 2005fa, 229 in 2007SP, 234 in 2007fa, 239 in<br />

2008fa, and 252 in 2009fa:<br />

Question 241 If the commodity, empirically, is not mysterious, but its scientific analysis<br />

reveals that it has a mysterious character, doesn’t this mean that the scientific analysis is<br />

wrong?<br />

[161] SnatchimusMaximus: content B form 95% A commodity may be empirically accepted<br />

prima facie, whereas scientific analysis reveals that a commodity is entirely different.<br />

When empirically studying an object, especially a commodity, societal norms, traditions,<br />

and values are inevitably observed.<br />

Empirical evidence simply is not exogenous. Carefully observing ice cubes while inside<br />

<strong>of</strong> a freezer reveals that ice cubes are cold, square, and hard. Upon removing the ice cubes<br />

from the freezer an entirely different set <strong>of</strong> observations are gathered. Likewise, analyzing<br />

a commodity within in its predefined scope yields datum that appears empirically accurate.<br />

Removing the commodity from its social environment yields a set <strong>of</strong> datum pertaining to the<br />

commodity’s actual composition.<br />

In conclusion, the empirical analysis <strong>of</strong> the commodity is correct inasmuch as the analysis<br />

reflects the society in which the observation was made. The scientific analysis is also correct<br />

in that it reveals the components <strong>of</strong> which the commodity is composed.<br />

Message [161] referenced by [172]. Next Message by SnatchimusMaximus is [164].<br />

[172] Hans: The simple empirics <strong>of</strong> shadows on the wall. SnatchismusMaximus’s example<br />

<strong>of</strong> empirics in [161] may be familiar but it is not simple. Ice cubes behave completely<br />

differently in the freezer than on the kitchen floor. This cries out for a scientific explanation<br />

<strong>of</strong> what we see, why water is a liquid at certain temperatures and a solid at others. Modern<br />

physics can give this explanation based on the molecular structure <strong>of</strong> H2O. Here the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 83<br />

scientific approach is indeed, as SnatchismusMaximus says, to look at the components <strong>of</strong><br />

each water molecule. But this is not always the case; Marxists and many other social scientists<br />

would say that, if you look at a society, a look at the components (methodological<br />

individualism) is wrong.<br />

Now assume we have phenomena which do not go through mysterious phase transitions<br />

but which behave in a simple manner. Neoclassical economics explains commodities based<br />

on use-values alone without need <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> value. Introductory Micro textbooks do<br />

not begin with a rundown on things which you need to know but which you cannot see,<br />

but they are a glorification <strong>of</strong> common sense. In more advanced courses you learn how<br />

this simple theory can be formalized mathematically, and how it can be applied not only to<br />

commodities but also to the decisions whom to marry and many other situations. It gives a<br />

simple and systematic framework, isn’t this what a theory is supposed to do?<br />

As a Marxist I would say, using FacistFranks’s cave analogy from [158]: the simplicity<br />

<strong>of</strong> neoclassical economics is the simplicity <strong>of</strong> the shadows on the wall in the cave. It hides<br />

what is really going on. And how can you tell that you are looking at shadows instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> the real driving forces? The apple from the tree <strong>of</strong> knowledge, as I called it in [156],<br />

is the recognition <strong>of</strong> contradictions, which say that more is going on than what you can<br />

immediately see.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [187].<br />

[190] Hans: Unpredictability <strong>of</strong> markets. SnatchimusMaximus [164] is an optimist. He<br />

says that commodities violate all the assumptions which made by modern economics in order<br />

to model economic behavior: perfect information, rational consumers, perfect competition.<br />

He optimistically is waiting for “a model ... that accurately explains how a commodity<br />

operates.”<br />

Averil [167] is a pessimist. He says the commodity is too abstract and intangible, it cannot<br />

be predicted since “we have yet to figure out a way to see into the future.”<br />

Let me reply to Averil first: it is possible to master nature without being able to look into<br />

the future. We do not need a crystal ball, all we need is a physics book which explains the<br />

natural laws underlying it all.<br />

Am I therefore on the side <strong>of</strong> SnatchimusMaximus, am I advocating that we just need to<br />

understand the propensity to consume better and other things in order to take the mystery<br />

out <strong>of</strong> economics? No. There are people in mainstream economics (the efficient market<br />

hypothesis) who say that markets are in principle unpredictable. SnatchimusMaximus’s<br />

better model simply does not exist.<br />

What does this have to do with the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity? Marx says:<br />

not only do humans not control markets but the markets control humans. By their efforts to<br />

master the market, they do what capital needs them to do in order to grow. As I said in [156],<br />

the economic agents are the marionettes carrying out what the system needs them to do.<br />

Message [190] referenced by [202]. Next Message by Hans is [193].<br />

Question 244 is 189 in 2003fa, 216 in 2004fa, and 232 in 2007SP:


84 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Question 244 Comment on the following statement: “After a long and tedious explanation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity, Marx surprises his reader at the end <strong>of</strong> chapter One with the assertion that<br />

the commodity is mysterious. This is Marx’s last-ditch effort to drag commodity production<br />

into the dirt, after his own analysis could not turn up much that is wrong with it. Ironically,<br />

Marx admits here that his explanation <strong>of</strong> the commodity is less than satisfactory, since it<br />

mystifies something that is really plain and simple.”<br />

[154] Spawnblade: Is commodity itself really a mystery? Simply put, I agree with<br />

this statement. Marx appears to be trying to overturn logic he previously created as to what<br />

commodity is, and why it is understandable. He then tries to draw upon the unpredictable<br />

behavior <strong>of</strong> the interactions between commodities in the economic system, and then try and<br />

say it is mysterious. It is not mysterious, it is simply difficult to organize in a predictable<br />

manner.<br />

There is a very large difference between unpredictable, and mysterious. We’ve actually<br />

been discussing this in my macroeconomics class, with the current state <strong>of</strong> the economy.<br />

Remarkably it also came up in a social psychology class, dealing with the question <strong>of</strong> if<br />

social science is a real science. They all relate in one crucial point: None <strong>of</strong> them can be<br />

predicted at a 100% success rate. This is due to many factors that are unknown, or simply<br />

impossible with our resources to take into account.<br />

Macroeconomics informs us that we have general knowledge <strong>of</strong> the basic correlations <strong>of</strong><br />

the economy. It details the effects <strong>of</strong> increasing the money supply, or raising interest rates.<br />

It also gives reasons that have been evident for recessions, and price drops. However, one <strong>of</strong><br />

its most important lessons is that no two trials are ever exactly the same. In that manner we<br />

can never accurately predict it.<br />

Yet Marx attempts to say that while the use-value <strong>of</strong> commodity is not “mysterious”, the<br />

actual value <strong>of</strong> it is? I cannot see eye to eye on this, for I do not see a reasonable explanation.<br />

If the entire economy is not a mystery, but merely understood that it is too complicated to<br />

predict its behavior entirely, then why is the function <strong>of</strong> a table so mysterious? The time it<br />

may have taken to turn a plank into a eating place is unimportant. It is simply time used,<br />

that time could have been spent playing football or watching the Superbowl. Once an object<br />

becomes a commodity, it is assigned a value. I understand Marx is attempting to give all<br />

things a certain value without actually relying on capitalism and market demand to assign<br />

it... However, what, if anything, is capable <strong>of</strong> altering a value more than demand? Demand<br />

is the single-most important factor in determining the amount available <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

If there was only one hamburger left on an abandoned island, yet there were ten pints <strong>of</strong><br />

beer, and ten people. Would they choose the hamburger and live a bit longer, or would they<br />

choose the alcohol in order to make the death more bearable? However if that hamburger<br />

was just enough to keep them alive long enough for help to come, that hamburger would<br />

gain a very large amount <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Perhaps I misunderstood what Marx was trying to do, however I do not believe it is<br />

possible to claim it is mysterious, and provide that as a reason for taking away the value that<br />

market demand gives commodities.<br />

Message [154] referenced by [156]. Next Message by Spawnblade is [199].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 85<br />

[156] Hans: What is Marx’s contribution? Didn’t he just turn something simple into a<br />

complicated Hegelian construct, and now he is complaining that it is complicated?<br />

To answer this, recall the readings <strong>of</strong> the very first week <strong>of</strong> this class, which I tried to<br />

summarize in [32]: the simple view is untenable because it is contradictory. Marx says that<br />

the exchange value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is simultaneously something inherent in the commodity<br />

and something relative between commodities. Now the complication starts, because Marx’s<br />

resolution <strong>of</strong> this contradiction is that exchange value is the manifestation on the market <strong>of</strong><br />

something that is really happening in production, namely, the allocation <strong>of</strong> human labor to<br />

the specific products.<br />

Marx showing us this contradiction is like Adam eating the apple and suddenly realizing<br />

that he is naked, i.e., that he is at the same time a human and an animal. We are driven out<br />

<strong>of</strong> the paradise in which everything is determined on the market, and in which everything is<br />

fair and equitable. Spawnblade mourns the loss when he says in the last sentence <strong>of</strong> [154]<br />

that Marx “takes away” the value created on the market by demand.<br />

But the paradise Marx expelled us from was not run by God but by the devil, who bewitched<br />

us into living in a world <strong>of</strong> illusions. By separating exchange-value from use-value<br />

and attributing exchange-value to labor, Marx shows us the truth which we don’t like to see<br />

but which we feel in our bones every day: that the labor process where we earn our living is<br />

a huge rip<strong>of</strong>f. The market is the big blanket which hides the true nature <strong>of</strong> the transactions<br />

between capitalist and laborer and makes them seem fair and equitable. The details <strong>of</strong> this<br />

will be shown in chapter Six, but the basis for this is already laid now when Marx says that<br />

value is created by labor, see my [33].<br />

In the section about the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity, Marx takes his critique<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalist system to an even higher level. The problem is not the evil capitalists, but<br />

the problem is that all humans, workers and capitalists, are only the marionettes carrying out<br />

an automatic purpose built into the economic system which benefits nobody. Again, I must<br />

refer you to future readings, this time chapter Four, for details, but the point which Marx<br />

is trying to make already now is that there is an inversion <strong>of</strong> subject and object. Instead <strong>of</strong><br />

value being our product, we are the useful idiots toiling for a senseless and needless accumulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> abstract wealth. 200 years ago this was a progressive historical device pushing<br />

mankind to thoroughly reform the labor process and make it 1000 times more productive.<br />

But now, instead <strong>of</strong> enjoying this productivity and benefiting from it we are relentlessly driving<br />

on until we have suffocated the entire planet in a heat wave which will do away with the<br />

conditions for human life as we know it.<br />

The economic system has immersed us in a virtual reality. We are so preoccupied with<br />

collecting points and zapping our virtual enemies that we do not realize that the entirety <strong>of</strong><br />

humankind is sitting in a liferaft floating towards the waterfall. We better wake up and look<br />

at the real reality before the pull <strong>of</strong> the rapids makes rational concerted action impossible. I<br />

am 63 now. When the chaos breaks out I will be either dead or so old that it does not really<br />

matter to me. But chances are that for most <strong>of</strong> you this chaos will be a part <strong>of</strong> your lives. Now<br />

is the time to educate yourselves about these issues and build the mass movement I talked<br />

about in [71]. We can still turn it around, make it a Cuba-style “special period” for everyone,


86 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

which never sacrificed the protection <strong>of</strong> the poor, instead <strong>of</strong> Darfur, Iraq, and Palestine right<br />

here in the United States. (We already got a little taste <strong>of</strong> it whith Katrina.)<br />

Message [156] referenced by [158], [172], [190], and [202]. Next Message by Hans is [166].<br />

[158] FacistFrank: House and plantation slaves. Maybe I’m only at a basic level here,<br />

but I happen to be a fan <strong>of</strong> Plato. I was reminded <strong>of</strong> his cave analogy when Hans talked about<br />

Marx awakening us to the fact that value is really determined by labor and nothing else, not<br />

the markets, not use value, it is met with horror. At least when the consequences <strong>of</strong> this<br />

shift in thinking are analyzed. Plato says that if one man were to be taken from the cave and<br />

shown the blinding light <strong>of</strong> the sun, it would be the most painful thing he ever experienced in<br />

his life. Then if he returned out <strong>of</strong> a sense <strong>of</strong> duty to the cave, and tried to free his comrades,<br />

they would be shocked and horrified at the ideas he espoused. They would think that his<br />

mind had become broken, they would hate him, maybe kill him.<br />

I think that there is a lot to the idea that the man that lives in relative poverty who votes<br />

for those that exploit him, is doing it because he can’t admit that he is not rich and important.<br />

There is a stereotype that little guys talk the loudest and meanest, where big guys are gentle,<br />

well I think it is somewhat true. The little guy talks so much because he is compensating<br />

for something that he doesn’t have, he has convinced himself that he is powerful, the big<br />

guy knows he is powerful, it is a fact like how the sun shines, he doesn’t have to brag about<br />

it. Just replace big guy with the American capitalist elite, and little guy with poor exploited<br />

weak guy that votes republican (sorry had to get my shot in!) however there is also the person<br />

that sees the light and tries to fight and free his oppressed brothers, this is the person that has<br />

accepted the truth.<br />

Another analogy that I think works is the house slave and the plantation slave. The house<br />

slave actually thinks he has it good because he gets to live in the basement, eat the leftover<br />

food, and gets less beatings. The house slave loves his master, like a dog loves his owner,<br />

where the plantation slave hates his master, and at the first opportunity will kill him. The<br />

house slave sees how badly the plantation slave is treated and knows if he doesn’t protect<br />

and obey his master he could turn into one, he is thankful, this is an analogy once used by<br />

Malcolm X. It is also like CousinIt says, if the exploited man accepts the truth he won’t only<br />

lose his entire idea <strong>of</strong> self worth (which in my opinion, if it becomes absent in a human<br />

being, thats when suicidal behavior starts to manifest) he will also lose his nice spot in the<br />

basement, and the better leftover food, he may even lose his life. Assuming <strong>of</strong> course that<br />

Marx is correct that capitalism is truly exploitative and analogous to slavery.<br />

I do have to disagree with CousinIt about an earlier claim he made, I think it was CousinIt<br />

if not then I apologize. Anyone who has read any Nietzsche is aware <strong>of</strong> his will to power<br />

ideas. I believe what was claimed earlier was that human beings are driven at their core<br />

by an instinct to survive. Nietzsche says this is incorrect, because many human beings<br />

march <strong>of</strong>f into war voluntarily, and some commit suicide, some risk their very lives for other<br />

things. According to Nietzsche they are risking their lives for power, those who go <strong>of</strong>f to<br />

war may risk their lives for a higher ideal (just a powerful idea used to gain power over<br />

others) command <strong>of</strong> soldiers, glory, riches, fame, future political aspirations. Even the man<br />

that votes in the exploiter thinks he is maximizing his power. They risk their lives all for<br />

power, not to say that you have to risk your life for power, there are safer ways to gain it,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 87<br />

but to them at least power is more precious than life. This in his opinion and mine is what<br />

drives a human to live, and perhaps may even be our purpose, if it is natural, then I believe<br />

it must be right. Sometimes I scare myself when I talk about Nietzsche, because although<br />

more different than same, the Nazis had a good deal in common with him philosophically.<br />

I have a question, and perhaps this is oversimplified but is Marx saying that the entire<br />

systems <strong>of</strong> Socialism and Capitalism, come from this seed: Capitalism evolves from a belief<br />

that value is determined by markets, supply, demand, scarcity? And Socialism from the idea<br />

that all value comes from labour put into the production?<br />

Hans: The cave analogy is much better than my analogy <strong>of</strong> the paradise in [156], thank you for bringing this up.<br />

Averil [176] also finds it very fitting.<br />

Some <strong>of</strong> the things you are discussing belong into the psychology <strong>of</strong> how to fit oneself into an oppressive and<br />

exploitative society, which is a sorely neglected field. A Marxist attempt is<br />

http://www.gegenstandpunkt.com/english/psych/0-contents.html<br />

Message [158] referenced by [166] and [172]. Next Message by FacistFrank is [206].<br />

[164] SnatchimusMaximus: content B+ form 95% The commodity truly is mysterious<br />

in that it is said to play in the free market despite failing to satisfy all the open market<br />

assumptions. Open market assumptions are as follows: 1) Perfect information, 2) Rational<br />

behavior 3) Open markets.<br />

Mystery I. A commodity lacks perfect information eo ipso <strong>of</strong> being a commodity. The<br />

end user simply does not know all <strong>of</strong> materials, time, or processes that went into producing<br />

said commodity. How can commodities operate in the free market without meeting the first<br />

criteria? That is the first mystery <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Mystery II. Not all users <strong>of</strong> the commodity act in rational ways. People who smoke know<br />

that smoking kills. I think we all can agree that dying is a disutility. Why would anybody<br />

use a commodity if it brings disutility? Commodities induce irrational behavior. That is the<br />

second mystery <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Mystery III. A truly open market does not exist today. As close as we are to obtaining<br />

“free trade” through NAFTA, we are not quite there yet. How can a commodity operate and<br />

self-acquiesce on a market that truly is not open? That is the third mystery <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

The explanation <strong>of</strong> the commodity will remain less than satisfactory until a model is<br />

devised that accurately explains how a commodity operates. Until then, the commodity will<br />

remain mysterious, and markets will remain “open.”<br />

Message [164] referenced by [190]. Next Message by SnatchimusMaximus is [407].<br />

[166] Hans: Capitalism covering its tracks. FacistFrank is asking in [158] whether<br />

Capitalism evolves from a belief that value is determined by markets, supply,<br />

demand, scarcity? And Socialism from the idea that all value comes<br />

from labour put into the production?<br />

My answer here is fourfold, two points about capitalism and two about socialism.<br />

(a) Marx’s book is called Capital because he is writing a theory <strong>of</strong> capitalism, not socialism.<br />

Marx says that in capitalism, market values are determined by labor content. I already<br />

said that in [62], and I have to say it every semester, [2007SP:65] might be helpful.


88 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(b) At Marx’s time, the economic mainstream held that value comes from labor. I.e., the<br />

labor theory <strong>of</strong> value was associated with capitalism, not socialism. Only later, it became<br />

discredited – a Marxist would say that the capitalists were trying to cover their tracks.<br />

(c) Many kinds <strong>of</strong> socialism are thinkable, but an important feature shared by many socialist<br />

models is that there is no property income in socialism, only labor income.<br />

(d) But instead <strong>of</strong> having value based on labor, many socialist models want to get away<br />

from value altogether. They are trying to allocate labor to the different industries according<br />

to some conscious plan, instead <strong>of</strong> the products having to battle it out on the market after they<br />

are produced. Socialism aims for production for the sake <strong>of</strong> use-value, instead <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

with its production for the sake <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [168].<br />

[167] Averil: Re: Capitalism covering its tracks. In reading past responses to this<br />

question I can’t help but agree with the similarities between Hans’s interpretation <strong>of</strong> Marx’s<br />

views on the commodity and the capitalist market and Plato’s view <strong>of</strong> the universe. As said<br />

before, Plato set the world into four different hierarchies with the lowest two levels having<br />

especially imagined views <strong>of</strong> reality. Those unfortunate souls that were trapped in Plato’s<br />

cave knew only the reality <strong>of</strong> the shadows that danced on the wall in front <strong>of</strong> them. They<br />

knew no higher sense <strong>of</strong> truth and had no understanding to the true nature <strong>of</strong> what caused<br />

the shadows, or indeed that they were merely seeing shadows. This is similar to Hans’s<br />

statements concerning the nature <strong>of</strong> the market and how we are blinded by our economic<br />

system and are unaware that the market is a ‘big blanket which hides the true nature <strong>of</strong><br />

the transactions between capitalist and laborer and makes them seem fair and equitable.’ It<br />

seems that this could very well be the mystery that Marx is hinting at.<br />

I am <strong>of</strong> the opinion that Marx found himself unable to fully explain the commodity, not<br />

that his definition was lacking but that the concept is too abstract and intangible. I think<br />

that an explanation <strong>of</strong> commodity, like so many other things in life, is rather difficult to<br />

come by when examined closely and deeply. I am not sure that Marx really thought that the<br />

explanation was plain and simple, I think he thought it was superficially plain and simple.<br />

Question 256 is adept at listing a few plausible reasons that Marx may have said that the<br />

commodity is mysterious, but many <strong>of</strong> the reasons seem to point to the unpredictability <strong>of</strong><br />

the market and <strong>of</strong> the commodity. This is all very reasonable, we have yet to figure out a way<br />

to see into the future. Until the producer is supplied with perfect information about demand<br />

and the buyer presented with perfect information about the supply and variety <strong>of</strong> products<br />

available to them, mystery will prevail. Commodities would exist, though clearly not in the<br />

same manner, in a socialist society. It is possible that Marx was simply commenting on<br />

the difference <strong>of</strong> value on commodity between the two systems that made the commodity<br />

mysterious. I admit, that is kind <strong>of</strong> a stretch, but I do not think that Marx was necessarily<br />

trying to drag commodity through the dirt.<br />

Hans: Products would exist in socialism, but they would not necessarily take the form <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Message [167] referenced by [190]. Next Message by Averil is [213].<br />

[530] Alcameron: I disagree with the statement that Marx was unable to explain the plain<br />

and simple idea <strong>of</strong> commodity production. I believe Marx understands as well as anyone the<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> commodity production. He chooses to look beyond the surface but to a much


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 89<br />

deeper meaning. I agree that Marx should have written that the commodity is mysterious<br />

because he is simply showing that no one person’s analysis will unravel all that there is to<br />

know about commodity production. If anything this statement gives validity to his analysis<br />

because he understands and respects the depth <strong>of</strong> the principle. Lastly, I don’t believe his<br />

explanation was long and tedious, rather thourough and in depth.<br />

Hans: When Marx calls the commodity mysterious, he does not mean a lack <strong>of</strong> knowledge by the researcher. He<br />

means an objective fact. Even mainstream economics, with the efficient market hypothesis, says that prices are<br />

unpredictable. Marx puts a qualitative spin on it: commodities act as if they had their own life, independent <strong>of</strong><br />

humans.<br />

Next Message by Alcameron is [576].<br />

Exam Question 248 is 184 in 2002fa, 193 in 2003fa, 220 in 2004fa, 236 in 2007SP, 241<br />

in 2007fa, 246 in 2008fa, 287 in 2010fa, and 270 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam Question 248 Why does Marx explore the mysterious character <strong>of</strong> the commodity,<br />

which is bland and abstract, instead <strong>of</strong> picking up one <strong>of</strong> the many striking outwardly mysterious<br />

phenomena <strong>of</strong> capitalism?<br />

[141] Alex: (graded B+) The mysterious character <strong>of</strong> a commodity reveals much about<br />

true creation. However, no matter how the definition <strong>of</strong> a commodity is constructed it is<br />

important to take into account how all aspects interact to create the commodity. Very <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

economic theories and intuitions, though seemingly comprehensive, turn a blind eye to the<br />

more importan aspects <strong>of</strong> “rational” expectations, actions and decisions. What is supposed<br />

to be rational can be more cleary defined as self preserving.<br />

Self preservation is one <strong>of</strong> the most important characteristics in economics, not to mention<br />

other disciplines as well (probably most disciplines). “Human” rationalities are <strong>of</strong>ten given<br />

a pass because as a society our standards are not held consistent. For instance, you wouldn’t<br />

purposely steal from a retirement age woman. However, you might be willing to participtate<br />

in insider trading which may end up hurting millions <strong>of</strong> retirement age women. The motto<br />

“business is business” has become the status quo <strong>of</strong> capitalism. What that statement really<br />

means is “I am going to get what I can regardless <strong>of</strong> who I hurt, as long as I can point to<br />

the rules <strong>of</strong> business for justification.” Business has become an umbrella justification for bad<br />

behavior. Just ask Bernie Ebbers.<br />

This plays into Spawnblade’s discussion contribution [140]. How comprehensive is isolationism<br />

and what are its social ramifications on a micro level. There is <strong>of</strong>ten much discussion<br />

about macro policy and actions, but how different are macro choices from micro choices. We<br />

are <strong>of</strong>ten governed by the same motivations and selfishness whether as a group or an individual.<br />

Yet somehow when we act poorly as a group we somehow feel justified as we see<br />

other participating as well. Corporatism is the evolving face <strong>of</strong> capitalism, which adds new<br />

fuel to the “mysterious character” discussion.<br />

So why is the examination <strong>of</strong> the mysterious commodity so important, more so even<br />

than the discussion <strong>of</strong> capitalism? The commodity is intriguing, and truly is the root <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism. Commodities are the seeds <strong>of</strong> capitalism, and provide a means for the creation <strong>of</strong><br />

the capitalist. This social structure has created classes in a democratic society. Commodities,<br />

and therefore capitalism, provide a means whereby the rich still enslave the poor. Though


90 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

manufacturing and industry are less common today than in Marx’s time, the basic tenets<br />

remain the same.<br />

I believe all <strong>of</strong> this helps to explain why the mysterious commodity is more intriguing to<br />

Marx than the mysterious capitalism. Poor behaviour can be blamed on capitalistic tendencies<br />

which are fueled by commodities. However, the reaction to commodities are rational<br />

human behaviour. However, capitalism has given man justification for behaving poorly.<br />

Message [141] referenced by [147] and [436]. Next Message by Alex is [298].<br />

[145] Hans: The economy more real than the planet. Yesterday I saw the global<br />

warming documentary Everything’s cool<br />

http://everythingscool.org/index.php<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the persons interviewed in this movie, Bill McKibben, said that we treat the economy<br />

as a real live being, we are concerned about its growth, we say it is in recovery, it needs<br />

stimulation, there is contagion from the subprime credit market to all credits, etc. We look<br />

at it like a child which we do not want to get sick. We are so concerned about the economy<br />

that we find it more important than the real nature surrounding us. He continued that the<br />

economy is predicated on it that our natural surroundings remain the same way as we are<br />

used to, but we are in the process <strong>of</strong> drastically altering them.<br />

According to Marx, this attitude, that we treat the economy as more real than nature, is<br />

not caused by human shortsightedness or misplaced values, but its deepest reason lies in the<br />

structure <strong>of</strong> the economy itself. We treat the economy like a living being (this behavior and<br />

attitude he calls “commodity fetishism”) because the economy behaves like a living being<br />

(this objective fact about the economy he calls the “fetish-like character” <strong>of</strong> commodity,<br />

money, and capital).<br />

Then he asks: why does the economy behave like a living being? And now question 248<br />

kicks in. To answer this, he does not go to one <strong>of</strong> the obvious puzzles where the life-like<br />

and “more powerful than nature” character <strong>of</strong> the economy manifests itself. I.e., he does<br />

not try to explain why money grows when we put it into the bank, or why money, a little<br />

smelly piece <strong>of</strong> paper, is able to buy use-values whose production has obviously required<br />

real human and natural resources? Instead, he says, oh if we look carefully we see that<br />

this mysterious life-like character is already in the commodities. And then he takes out his<br />

looking glass and takes, at the end <strong>of</strong> a long chapter looking at the commodity, yet another<br />

look from a slightly different angle, one might call it a meta-look, trying to explain the subtle<br />

mysterious character <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Question 248 is called “exam question,” i.e., it is supposed to have a short “right” answer,<br />

which is <strong>of</strong>ten formulated in the Annotations right next to the question itself, and you are<br />

required to know this answer. Indeed, the sentence in the Annotations right preceding this<br />

question says:<br />

The commodity already contains in an undeveloped form many <strong>of</strong> the determinations<br />

<strong>of</strong> money and capital, and Marx asserts that also the outwardly<br />

magical and self-acting characters <strong>of</strong> money and capital have their root in<br />

the far more subtle mysteries <strong>of</strong> the commodity.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 91<br />

How is this the answer to the question? For this I’d like to use the same metaphor Marx<br />

used in the preface 89:3/o, namely, that the commodity is the economic cell form. If you<br />

look at a human or any other living being it is easy to see that it grows. But it is hard<br />

to explain why or how it grows. To understand this, you have to look at individual cells<br />

and their partition. Or if you look at the human population, it is easy to see that there is<br />

some similarity between parents and children. But in order to understand how this similarity<br />

comes about, you have to look at the genetic code inside the cells, and the chemistry which<br />

encodes it.<br />

The same with the mysterious phenomena <strong>of</strong> money and capital. They are easy to see<br />

but their true explanation requires us to step down to the cellular level. When Marx looks<br />

at the mysterious character <strong>of</strong> the commodity, he looks therefore so-to-say at the genetic<br />

code which expresses itself in the magical properties <strong>of</strong> money and the powerful self-acting<br />

tendencies <strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

Message [145] referenced by [2012fa:327]. Next Message by Hans is [147].<br />

Question 249 is 123 in 1995WI, 134 in 1996sp, 137 in 1997ut, 164 in 2000fa, 186 in<br />

2002fa, 194 in 2003fa, 221 in 2004fa, 242 in 2007fa, 247 in 2008fa, 260 in 2011fa, and<br />

272 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 249 Whether the commodity is “mysterious” or not is a value judgment which<br />

can neither be proved nor disproved. Do you agree? What would Marx say about this?<br />

[155] CousinIt: graded A value, judgement, and reality. In [2000fa:100-1] Hans comments<br />

in regard to this question by drawing attention to the fact that none <strong>of</strong> the participants<br />

answered the question by saying “yes, stating that the commodity is mysterious is a value<br />

judgement and yes it can be proved.” This is what Marx would say. The fact that so few<br />

people would answer the question in this way lays open an aspect <strong>of</strong> the ideology that we<br />

are prone to succumb to under capitalism.<br />

In [2000fa:100-1], Hans states “The theses that value assessments cannot be proved, that<br />

nothing can be inherenty good or bad or sick or mysterious, is too ingrained in all <strong>of</strong> you -<br />

and guess who benefits from it?”<br />

The fact that we seem to believe that value judgements are merely subjective and are thus<br />

unprovable is a matter <strong>of</strong> selective ideological investments that we are led to make, whether<br />

we know we are making those investments or not. This is the same kind <strong>of</strong> error that one<br />

makes who is not a capitalist (i.e. an owner <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production) who nonetheless<br />

consistently votes for the political party that is interested in protecting and extending the<br />

exploitative powers <strong>of</strong> the means-owning class.<br />

If I am one <strong>of</strong> these people who are exploited laborers yet consistently vote for the laborexploiting<br />

class’ interests, I vote for the class who is busy about pr<strong>of</strong>iting from their exploitation<br />

<strong>of</strong> my labor as well as for the class that has exploited the labor <strong>of</strong> my family and<br />

many other families in my class for many previous generations. I am voting for the one who<br />

has stolen from me the value <strong>of</strong> my labor and <strong>of</strong> the labor <strong>of</strong> my family and my class for<br />

generations. I am voting for the burgler who, aided by my blindness to my own material


92 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

relations, has robbed me, my family, and my class literally ‘blind.’ Yet, I think that somehow<br />

protecting and making my exploiter/oppressor stronger is good for me and that anyone<br />

who doesn’t agree with me is making a “subjective value judgement” that is being somehow<br />

led astray by some pinko-leftist fallacy about what it means to be “free and equal.” (Frank<br />

Zappa alluded to the provable value judgement <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> freedom in the title to one <strong>of</strong><br />

his albums called “Absolutely Free.” One is either free or not free. This is a value judgement<br />

and it can be proved....sorry.)<br />

The ideological investment <strong>of</strong> the exploited who votes for the exploiter is “too ingrained”<br />

(to quote Hans). Why is it so impossible for me to say unequivocally that I am either free or<br />

not free, equal or not equal to, etc., etc? Says who? By who’s assessment? The ideological<br />

investment that prevents me from seeing that I am not free, that I am not equal, that I am<br />

not exploited, etc., is the same investment that I make in equating my ability to buy Coke<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> Pepsi, brown shoes instead <strong>of</strong> black, with being actually free.<br />

I buy into the capitalist ideology because I do not want to acknowledge the truth (which<br />

yes, IS a value judgement AND yes, it can be proved) that I am not a capitalist, I am exploited<br />

by those who are capitalists, I am not free, I am a wage-slave, when I vote for the capitalist<br />

class I vote for my enemies and the enemies <strong>of</strong> my family who constantly steal our labor, I<br />

do not own the means <strong>of</strong> production or the rights to that which I produce through my labor,<br />

I exist in an array <strong>of</strong> social relations that are unfair and stacked against me, etc., etc. I can’t<br />

even see that I do not want to know this truth because the ability to make these kinds <strong>of</strong><br />

value judgements has been disabled by the ingraining in my mind and being <strong>of</strong> the preferred<br />

ideology <strong>of</strong> the ruling class.<br />

The main characteristic <strong>of</strong> the effects <strong>of</strong> my indoctrination is that I seem to willingly<br />

accept my position and convince myself that the fact that I can shop at Walmart while others<br />

in the world are living in shit up to their knees is a fair trade for what has been stolen<br />

from me, my family, and my class for generations thus producing the relative poverty <strong>of</strong> my<br />

position in relation to the capitalist. What is true is that my ability to make value judgements<br />

is subjected to the authority <strong>of</strong> the ideological investments that I have made, consciously,<br />

subconsciously, inadvertantly, by default, laziness, or otherwise. “The poor are poor because<br />

they are lazy”, not because they are accidently/incidently in the wrong position, filling the<br />

wrong role in the overall social structure which dictates that all roles, even the undesireable<br />

ones, must be filled by someone.<br />

We are indoctrinated to see value judgements as somehow untrue or unproveable because<br />

it is in the best interests <strong>of</strong> the status quo that certain things remain unquestioned and unexamined.<br />

If we were to question, examine, and understand our role in our own slavery, we<br />

would be bound by honor to do something about it as failing to do so means that I am sellingout<br />

my parents, their parents, my children and their children, as well as being a class-traitor<br />

by my complicity in our collective class-slavery. It may be that I would rather be a slave that<br />

enjoys an illusion <strong>of</strong> security than be a free revolutionary who recognizes and accepts a condition<br />

<strong>of</strong> unrest, insecurity, and threat <strong>of</strong> violence at the hands <strong>of</strong> my former oppressors, in<br />

the transition from slave to free human being in society with other free humans. It just easier<br />

and (by some accounts that have swallowed the ideology lock, stock, and barrel) ‘smarter’<br />

to buy the couch with the built-in refigerator, buy the HDTV, buy the Hummer, and sit down,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 93<br />

shut up, and rot intellectually as well as physically and spiritually while waiting for some<br />

fantasy freedom that somewhere-out-there exists after my death-by-TV.<br />

The truth about the mysterious nature <strong>of</strong> the commodity as the basic social unit in capitalism<br />

is a value judgement and, as Marx sets out to do, is provable by way <strong>of</strong> scientific<br />

investigation and reasoned analysis. This is the realist perspective.<br />

Message [155] referenced by [216] and [2008fa:308]. Next Message by CousinIt is [227].<br />

Question 251 is 197 in 2003fa, 224 in 2004fa, 219 in 2005fa, 239 in 2007SP, 249 in<br />

2008fa, 263 in 2009fa, 291 in 2010fa, and 264 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 251 Do you know production processes which do not require human effort?<br />

[165] Clayon: Depending on technicalities, all “products” require some sort <strong>of</strong> human<br />

effort. But if we move beyond the technicalities, we will see that products <strong>of</strong> Nature do not<br />

require human effort. This includes land/real estate, water rights, and many natural resources<br />

such as salt.<br />

All these things require human effort in harvesting the good, but the actual production <strong>of</strong><br />

the original good did not require human effort. The list could continue with Sea Shells.<br />

All food is also produced by nature, although it may be aided by human effort in cultivation,<br />

or farming for both livestock and grain.<br />

Hans: The question whether all use-values require human labor is a different question than whether there are<br />

production processes which do not require human effort. In order to make this clearer I will re-formulate this<br />

question in future Semesters to read:<br />

Do you know production processes in which humans participate without having to spend any<br />

effort?<br />

This question was posed in the context <strong>of</strong> Marx’s assertion that every production process is essentially the expenditure<br />

<strong>of</strong> human labor-power.<br />

Next Message by Clayon is [234].<br />

Question 256 is 152 in 1998WI, 170 in 2000fa, 201 in 2003fa, 296 in 2010fa, and 269 in<br />

2011fa:<br />

Question 256 Since use-value is not mysterious, the commodity’s mysterious character<br />

must come from value.<br />

a. Is a commodity mysterious because it takes labor, i.e., the expenditure <strong>of</strong> human brain,<br />

nerves, muscles, etc., to produce it?<br />

b. Is a commodity mysterious because the question how much time it takes to produce it is<br />

relevant for society at large?<br />

c. Is a commodity mysterious because the labors performed in a commodity-producing society<br />

are part <strong>of</strong> an overall social labor process?<br />

d. Is there another aspect <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity which were overlooked here that<br />

might be mysterious?<br />

[148] Inter: Mysterious character <strong>of</strong> the commodity. According to Marx, the mysterious<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> the commodity cannot be answered by A, B, or C. Marx argues that there<br />

is no mystery when people interact with one another. The mystery is when the contents <strong>of</strong><br />

the value determinations (abstract human labor, socially necessary labor-time, and exchange


94 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

value) are regulated by the interactions <strong>of</strong> the commodities in the economy as value. Or in<br />

other words, Marx establishes that the mysterious aspect <strong>of</strong> the commodity exists when the<br />

value determinations are placed in the context <strong>of</strong> a commodity producing society (the market).<br />

Marx argues that the reason why this is mysterious is because it allows the commodities<br />

to interact with each other.<br />

Take for example a handcrafted bowl. The bowl is circular, with intricate patterns, and a<br />

glossy orange glaze. All <strong>of</strong> these attributes are seen as belonging to the bowl even though<br />

initially they were the attribute <strong>of</strong> labor in the production process. The fact that it took 8<br />

labor hours to create this bowl is only reflected in the exchange-value, not in its use-value.<br />

In addition, the 8 hours <strong>of</strong> labor that it took to create this bowl, are not grounded in the<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> the bowl, meaning that no physical element <strong>of</strong> the bowl tells me that it took 8<br />

hours. In a commodity driven society, in addition to the above mentioned attributes <strong>of</strong> the<br />

bowl (circular shape, intricate patterns, and a glossy finish) the labor hours are also attached<br />

as being another attribute <strong>of</strong> the bowl. So in our commodity driven society, the attributes <strong>of</strong><br />

the bowl are: circular shape, intricate patterns, glossy orange glaze, and 8 hours <strong>of</strong> human<br />

labor. However, even though it took 8 hours <strong>of</strong> human labor to create this bowl, society is<br />

the one who can place the value <strong>of</strong> the labor. Indeed, the form <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> this bowl is<br />

based <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> the success <strong>of</strong> my marketing, not on the actual 8 hours <strong>of</strong> labor. The mysterious<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> the bowl comes when it is placed in this market, because it becomes distant from<br />

the producer and relies on the marketing. It is distant from the producer because the amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> time it took to produce the bowl does not matter, what matters is what society thinks it<br />

took, which is dependent on the marketing campaign. What the bowl now comes into contact<br />

with is other products, which are also distant from their producers and that are also relying<br />

on their marketing. It is the interaction <strong>of</strong> this glossy orange bowl with other products that<br />

creates the mystery.<br />

Hans: This is excellent!<br />

Message [148] referenced by [151]. Next Message by Inter is [162].<br />

[151] Papageorgio: The mystery that lies within the commodity. First things first, we<br />

know as the question states and as Marx tells us that the use value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is not<br />

mysterious. This leaves us to figure out what part <strong>of</strong> the commodities value makes it mysterious<br />

or “intricate”. We are told by Marx that the mystery lies within the actual commodity<br />

itself, and not in our selfish ignorance. As we look at the commodity it is important to note<br />

that the mysterious nature comes from a major component, no clarity and no control. If there<br />

is control or clarity in an aspect <strong>of</strong> the commodity it is not mysterious to us.<br />

Marx begins ruling out where the mysteriousness comes from, first ruling out A, labor and<br />

expenditure <strong>of</strong> brain, muscles, etc. These all can definitely be found in societies which are far<br />

from mysterious, and are all functions <strong>of</strong> the human organism. We also must rule out point<br />

B as all societies must look at how labor time affects them at some point is development.<br />

It is also important to rule out a social labor process as there is always interaction between<br />

men who are working. As A, B, and C, are all proven not true by Marx, we must look at C<br />

and try to figure out what is overlooked and is a mystifying quality <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

The contact <strong>of</strong> the products not the people is definitely mysterious. As we look at the<br />

products we see “quasi physical properties” that are shown to us after our own labor. This is


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 95<br />

what is mysterious to us about the form <strong>of</strong> the commodity. The mystery <strong>of</strong> the commodity is<br />

not in its production but in itself. When a product interacts with other products is when the<br />

mystery comes. The production, etc. only will affect the price or quantity made and is <strong>of</strong> no<br />

mystery especially with the social interactions.<br />

Hans: Everything is good except your very last sentence: the fact that production affects the price <strong>of</strong> the commodity,<br />

and that the co-ordination <strong>of</strong> production goes through the price, and therefore is, as Inter says in [148], “distant”<br />

from the producers, this is for Marx exactly the source <strong>of</strong> the mystery.<br />

Inter’s answer came six hours before yours; therefore you should have referred to it and built on it (although I<br />

admit Inter is a hard act to follow).<br />

Next Message by Papageorgio is [157].<br />

[152] Paul: Commodity and Mystery. Marx rules out the first 3 options so it must be<br />

D. One <strong>of</strong> the possible sources <strong>of</strong> the mystery <strong>of</strong> the commodity is how it is compared with<br />

other similar products. How these commodities are compared to one another can change the<br />

price and value <strong>of</strong> a product. Products are given different characteristics given the time it<br />

takes to produce, money it takes to produce, the demographic that it is marketed towards and<br />

other things <strong>of</strong> this nature. The mystery is how any one <strong>of</strong> these characteristics can interact<br />

with the others and raise/lower the final price <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Message [152] referenced by [153]. Next Message by Paul is [159].<br />

[153] Hans: Mystery <strong>of</strong> the market. Paul [152] sees the mystery in the market itself, in<br />

the many factors determining the price <strong>of</strong> a commodity, while Marx sees the mystery in the<br />

fact that market outcomes co-ordinate production, instead <strong>of</strong> production being co-ordinated<br />

directly by producers and consumers. All the marketing strategies mentioned by Paul would<br />

in Marx’s view not affect the value <strong>of</strong> the product. The value is given by the total labor time<br />

going into the product and all its materials etc. It is already determined before the product<br />

enters the market. Marketing strategies such as targeting specific demographics (so that<br />

you can charge higher prices to wealthier consumers) try to influence the automatic camera<br />

action I explained in [144] by which market prices reflect the invisible labor content. I.e.,<br />

they try to raise prices above the values. Marx does not discuss such things in Capital but<br />

assumes that prices and values coincide.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [156].<br />

[282] Bmellor: mysterous nature der warenform.. a. No and to prove that the mysterious<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> the commodity are indeed not mysterious because <strong>of</strong> labor Marx explains that<br />

is doesn’t matter what useful labors are performed the truth is that “they are the result <strong>of</strong> the<br />

working human organism i.e. the expenditure <strong>of</strong> human brain, nerves, etc...” which can be<br />

found in societies that are not mysterious.<br />

b. No Marx says the Following to prove his point “In all states <strong>of</strong> society, the labor-time<br />

it costs to produce the means <strong>of</strong> substance must necessarily concern mankind, although not<br />

to the same degree at different stages <strong>of</strong> development.” That means that the mystery cannot<br />

come from labor-time. He is talking about society as a whole meaning that even societies<br />

that are not mysterious must take labor into consideration.<br />

c. No mystery here either. When people are not independent self sustaining “producers”<br />

but production is part <strong>of</strong> the social fabric <strong>of</strong> which they are part, they must participate in<br />

interpersonal interaction with these producers.


96 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

d. The mysterious character <strong>of</strong> a commodity does not come from those aspects <strong>of</strong> the core<br />

structure <strong>of</strong> the economy; it comes from the commodity form. The mysterious character<br />

stems from “objectified surface relations” this judiciously controls these basic facets.<br />

Next Message by Bmellor is [283].<br />

[296] FacistFrank: a. no, this is pretty straightforward<br />

b. it is a relevant question, we must know this in order to determine its actual value,<br />

like a measuring stick. The commodity tells us the actual price after it’s introduced to the<br />

market and having been there for a certain amount <strong>of</strong> time. Our social interpretation become<br />

equalized to the actual value. But i don’t see how this is mysterious.<br />

c. i think it’s true, but i don’t see how this makes it mysterious.<br />

d. By process <strong>of</strong> elimination this must be the case. Even after Marx concludes his chapter<br />

on commodity he states the commodity still remain mysterious, perhaps how the labor makes<br />

the leap from the worker to being in the product is what is mysterious?<br />

Hans: What you say under b. is different than part b. <strong>of</strong> the question, and the fact that the labor time asserts its<br />

relevance only long after the product has been produced and on the market is indeed mysterious.<br />

Your d. is a good formulation. I tried to say more about this leap in [144].<br />

Next Message by FacistFrank is [424].<br />

[299] Alex: graded A a. No. The mysterious nature is not explained by labor or the use <strong>of</strong><br />

one’s faculties to produce it. This value is the worker’s cost, but does not totally affect the<br />

value. It is important to note that production is an essential part <strong>of</strong> all commodities.<br />

b. No. The mysterious nature is not in production. One could argue that the production is<br />

the mysterious process which contributes to the mystery. But, the mystery is still contained<br />

within the commodity itself.<br />

c. The social labor process does not explain the mystery, though it is important to note<br />

the mystery is a societal designation. However, it is not dependent on the labor process and<br />

how it fits into the overall social labor process.<br />

d. The most important aspect is something that is hinted at but never fully explained<br />

in the proceeding components <strong>of</strong> this question. It is the society, over time, losing sight<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity’s real use and value. The commodity is therefore assigned a value that is<br />

mystical and fetish based.<br />

Hans: Regarding your d., Marx would say this is only a symptom <strong>of</strong> the more basic mystery that social relations<br />

take the form <strong>of</strong> material properties.<br />

Next Message by Alex is [420].<br />

[305] Inter: Revisiting the mystery. The answer to this question is d. The mysterious<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> the commodity comes from the distance it has from its producer, when it enters<br />

the market. Because it is distant from its producer, it competes against other goods in the<br />

market. It is this interaction with other goods that is the mystery <strong>of</strong> the commodity. In<br />

essence, the mystery is when commodities coordinate production, not producers/consumers.<br />

Next Message by Inter is [430].<br />

[319] Sparky: There is another aspect <strong>of</strong> value that was overlooked when discussing the<br />

commmodity, it is the mysterious nature <strong>of</strong> the commodity and how it expresses the inner<br />

values that were placed in it during the labor process which created it and how it affects<br />

the price <strong>of</strong> the commodity on the market. From the beginning materials to the final (end)


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 97<br />

product, with everything that went into it, the wood or steel, etc. that has gone into the<br />

product which came from nature, to the abstract labor power, and the socially necessary<br />

labor-time that is associated with the end product. These factors are the contributions that<br />

come into play when the product’s exchange value comes into the picture, when the product<br />

has reached the open market and interacts with all other, similar, products and its value is<br />

then placed on its socially constructed price tag.<br />

Hans: In Marx’s theory, nature does not create value. Only labor creates value, because only labor is a cost to<br />

society. Nature acts at no cost to society.<br />

Next Message by Sparky is [320].<br />

[321] PrivateProperty: The Mystery <strong>of</strong> the Commodity. A commodity is mysterious on<br />

account <strong>of</strong> several reasons. Rather than sift through each option, I will lay the explanation<br />

out as I see it (which is I hope how Marx sees it). The commodity is mysterious because<br />

as soon as it is produced, the commodity escapes the control <strong>of</strong> the producer and enters an<br />

interaction with other comodities. At this point, the labor (and thus value) is fixed in the<br />

commodity, yet we see a great deal <strong>of</strong> post-production activity (marketing, for example) in a<br />

perverse effort to distort exchange values. Perhaps the most mysterious aspect <strong>of</strong> all is that<br />

the commodity is produced because <strong>of</strong> its “success” on the market, which then creates an<br />

endless cycle <strong>of</strong> production for that commodity. The commodity, in the capitalist system,<br />

perpetuates itself like DNA, as if it were uncontrolled by the very humans that produced it.<br />

Hans: Excellent!<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [323].<br />

[326] Scott: The mysterious character <strong>of</strong> the commodity. a. No, there is nothing<br />

mysterious about labor. It was said in the homework that labor is the commodities father<br />

and the earth is its mother. A commodity is produced by the earth and already has certain<br />

characteristics like use-value. The laborer or the father is very necessary because it shapes<br />

the commodity and allows those inherent abilities to come to life. Abstract labor is the<br />

expenditure <strong>of</strong> the human brain, nerves, muscles, and it takes those things to bring about the<br />

commodities.<br />

b. No, there is nothing mysterious about labor time either. Labor time must be looked<br />

at in every society because it deals with the social allocation <strong>of</strong> labor power. However, this<br />

doesn’t make it mysterious.<br />

c. No, the mysterious characteristic is not found here either. From the annotations we<br />

read, “Whenever people are not self-sufficient producers, but production is part <strong>of</strong> the social<br />

web; in which they find themselves, there must be social interactions between the producers.”<br />

d. We find the mysterious part when we look at what is really being exchanged. The labor<br />

that was put into the commodity is being traded in the social relationships <strong>of</strong> exchange.<br />

Next Message by Scott is [439].<br />

[365] Carterryan: The Mystery and Intrigue <strong>of</strong> the Commodity. According to Marx’s<br />

theory you cannot determine the answer from A, B, or C but you have to determine the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity from its use-value, labor value and exchange value in the community. It<br />

will be a different value is each case.<br />

An example <strong>of</strong> this is that one can trade 10 yards <strong>of</strong> silk for one fur coat. The coat will<br />

definitely keep you warm in the winter if you live in a colder climate, more than the silk


98 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

spun into a coat would for use value for the one in the colder climate but a higher exchange<br />

value if you lived in a warmer climate trading to colder climate because you have the supply<br />

and the one in the colder climate has the demand.<br />

If you lived in a warmer climate you would most likely prefer to trade the fur coat for the<br />

silk because it would be a better commodity for you but more labor might be used to create<br />

a silk coat or jacket so the value is factored by that, and that is what creates the mystery <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Carterryan is [454].<br />

[371] Mitternacht: graded A Mysterious character <strong>of</strong> a commodity. Marx establishes<br />

that there is nothing mysterious about the use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity, so he proceeds to<br />

explore where its mysterious character comes from.<br />

Firstly, he establishes that a commodity is not mysterious because it takes labor. Abstract<br />

labor produces the value <strong>of</strong> things. Value is what drives social production and therefore,<br />

even though the types <strong>of</strong> labor may vary they are more or less equal.<br />

Nor is a commodity mysterious because the time it takes to produce it is relevant for<br />

society at large. Time is concerned with the quantity <strong>of</strong> labor, but not the quality. Quantity<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor is a simple measure that also does nothing to contribute to a mysterious quality.<br />

The social interactions between laborers are also fairly straightforward. Production and<br />

exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities does bring people into social relationships, but there is nothing<br />

about these interactions themselves that would give a mysterious air to the commodity.<br />

The mysterious nature emerges at the point that something takes the form <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

Something interesting takes place when the commodity-form arises – men’s labor becomes<br />

reflected as objective characteristics <strong>of</strong> the products that they have made. In an abstracted<br />

way men’s labor is being traded, but in the form <strong>of</strong> product created by the labor.<br />

Next Message by Mitternacht is [374].<br />

[377] Wasatch: a.<br />

No. These characteristics <strong>of</strong> the production process “is entirely accessible to the senses”,<br />

as Marx claims on page 156. We can witness with our senses the labor-power used in the<br />

production process.<br />

b.<br />

No. Society must be concerned with the amount <strong>of</strong> time it takes to produce the commodity.<br />

The amount <strong>of</strong> time required for production can be gauged and therefore is not<br />

mysterious.<br />

c.<br />

No. When men work for each other “labor assumes a social form.” (pg. 160) The social<br />

interactions required in the production process are not mysterious. It is something we can<br />

see and experience.<br />

d.<br />

The mysterious aspect <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is the fact that the commodity<br />

reflects back to society the human relations used to produce the commodity. The “value


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 99<br />

material” <strong>of</strong> the commodity, which comes from society’s labor-power, is what is reflected<br />

back to society along with the physical, tangible commodity.<br />

Hans: Regarding (c), it is not only the interactions in each individual production process, but also the interactions<br />

which allow the countless production processes to fit together.<br />

Next Message by Wasatch is [756].<br />

[406] Trailrunner: content A– late penalty 1% Labor (a), time (b) and labors performed<br />

(c) do not affect the mystery <strong>of</strong> a product, thus we would not consider these to be answers<br />

to the question <strong>of</strong> a mysterious character <strong>of</strong> a commodity. What we can recognize regarding<br />

the mystery <strong>of</strong> a commodity is what the market outcome or market interaction result is, once<br />

it has become distant from the producer. What is it that the market will see as the final value?<br />

This is the mysterious character <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Hans: The information projected on the market is an inverted image <strong>of</strong> what this information is about.<br />

Next Message by Trailrunner is [441].<br />

[411] Aaron: a) The annotations note that however varied the useful labors or productive<br />

activities might be, it is a physiological truth that they came from humans in some shape or<br />

form. Whether that original form was the function <strong>of</strong> the brain, the nerves that are working,<br />

the muscles or tissues or anything else that originates with the human structure.<br />

b) The quantity <strong>of</strong> labor here is and should be distinguishable from the quality <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Any aspect <strong>of</strong> labor and commodity, the qualitative portion should be differentiated from<br />

the quantitative. This distinction does not add to any mysteriousness <strong>of</strong> a commodity, as an<br />

end user would not know exactly how much labor went into a product, in the qualitative or<br />

quantitative sense. In a Marx society, the labor is a tool used to assess a commodity’s value.<br />

c) When people in a society work for each other in any way, their labor must assume<br />

a more social form. This means that people who work for someone other than strictly for<br />

themselves, are producing something used in the society for everyone else. In this case, there<br />

must be interactions and communications between different entities, in this case meaning<br />

different people. There is no mystery involved in this interaction and social scene.<br />

d) The one thing that I think may have been overlooked here in this discussion and explanation...<br />

is the material used to make or produce a product. Different societies may value<br />

different materials higher or lower than other societies and that must be accounted for when<br />

discussing the possibilities <strong>of</strong> exchange value and purchasing a commodity.<br />

Hans: Marx is not designing a “Marx society” but the society he is talking about is capitalism.<br />

Next Message by Aaron is [550].<br />

[589] Wade: A, A could be an answer, but it is proven not to be so we are taught that<br />

commodities are used every day between us. A commodity is for sure an expenditure <strong>of</strong><br />

human brains, muscles nerves, etc.<br />

B, B definitly is no, There is definitley a difference between the quantity <strong>of</strong> the labor or<br />

the quality <strong>of</strong> the labor, labor time isn’t mysterious.<br />

C, C It isn’t mysterious that when people can’t produce what they need they are part <strong>of</strong><br />

that social web that helps them tto exchange with the producers <strong>of</strong> whatever they need that<br />

they are not able to produce themselves.<br />

D, The second that a commodity is produced it becomes a mystery, the exchange between<br />

the producers is what makes a commodity mysterious!!! All people have different wants.


100 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Wade is [590].<br />

[653] Nstew: (b) A commodity is mysterious because the time it takes to produce a<br />

commodity is relevant for society at large. The reason for this is because Marx bases the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> a commodity on the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that goes into it. Because <strong>of</strong> his theory that the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is based on the labor that goes into it, the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is<br />

mysterious to society at large because the amount <strong>of</strong> time spent on production.<br />

Hans: Marx comes to a different conclusion: he says that the amount <strong>of</strong> time spent on production is not what<br />

makes the commodity mysterious, because the time the different things cost must be <strong>of</strong> concern to all societies,<br />

even those which do not trade commodities.<br />

Next Message by Nstew is [657].<br />

Question 264 is 135 in 1995WI, 112 in 1995ut, 145 in 1996sp, 152 in 1997WI, 159 in<br />

1997sp, 152 in 1997ut, 202 in 2002fa, 209 in 2003fa, 237 in 2004fa, 232 in 2005fa, 257<br />

in 2007fa, 278 in 2011fa, and 291 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 264 Modern advertising specialists know that consumers <strong>of</strong>ten buy a certain<br />

product not because they need this particular article, but because they are trying to compensate<br />

for other unmet needs. These compensatory demands are important for the economy<br />

because they are insatiable. Advertising addresses them whenever it suggests that social<br />

recognition, happiness, etc. are connected with the possession <strong>of</strong> a certain object.<br />

Is this what Marx meant by the “fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity,” or does it contradict<br />

it, or would Marx’s theory give rise to amendments <strong>of</strong> this theory?<br />

[146] Chris: our needs determined by modern day advertisers. I would first like to<br />

explain my opinion on the goal <strong>of</strong> modern advertising, as it is crucial in answering this question.<br />

It is <strong>of</strong> my opinion that modern day advertisers are trying to reach out to consumers’<br />

unmet wants as opposed to their needs. I feel that advertisers try to make consumers think<br />

that the commodity in which they are selling will fulfill a ‘need.’ I would say that most <strong>of</strong> the<br />

time, the commodities being sold are actually fulfilling the consumers’ subconscious ‘want’<br />

unbeknownst to them. I strongly agree that these demands are insatiable like the question<br />

suggests. Consumers buy the commodities thinking they ‘need’ them and that they will fulfill<br />

internal happiness. However, these commodities very <strong>of</strong>ten do not meet the consumers’<br />

hopes.<br />

In Hans lecture on Thursday night (01/31/08), he mentioned some very important issues<br />

that correlate to answering this question. He mentioned that commodities do things that<br />

people do not understand. I think this goes along with Marx’s idea about fetishism <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity where he says on page 163, “a commodity appears at first sight an extremely<br />

obvious, trivial thing. But its analysis brings out that it is a very strange thing, abounding in<br />

metaphysical subtleties and theological niceties.” Marx then goes on to explain how people<br />

make use <strong>of</strong> items in nature (his wood example to make a table) to make a commodity. I<br />

think this is where we would begin to see an amendment by Marx to the theory presented in<br />

the question.<br />

Consumers do not need the table in Marx’s example. The people need the wood because<br />

they want to make a table. To go along with this example, we see modern day companies<br />

creating commodities out <strong>of</strong> nature (i.e., wood for homes, wood for books, etc). The workers<br />

have a blind devotion and compulsive use (fetishism) towards creating the commodities.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 101<br />

I would think that to say insatiable wants are important for an economy would go against<br />

Marxist thought. However, the fetishism involved in modern day advertising has strikingly<br />

similar ties. Just as society is blind to creating the commodities, consumers are blind towards<br />

modern day advertising. Consumers do not realize they are being sold on insatiable<br />

wants. They think they are being sold on needs and that these commodities will lift hope<br />

and happiness, only to come up short.<br />

In conclusion, I think that Marx would amend the question to explain the differences<br />

between needs and wants. He would also tie in direct examples <strong>of</strong> formulating commodities<br />

and their fetish relations (as he does in his ‘The Fetishism <strong>of</strong> the Commodity and its Secret’).<br />

I personally think that the fetishism <strong>of</strong> the commodities and their creation does correlate with<br />

modern day advertising and their fetish appeal <strong>of</strong> commodities to the general consumer.<br />

This fetish behavior is something that I feel we consumers should all be blatantly aware<br />

<strong>of</strong> because these commodities are most <strong>of</strong>ten ‘wants’ and not ‘needs’ that will not fulfill<br />

happiness as society has duped us into believing.<br />

Hans: I wouldn’t go as far as saying that people don’t need tables, and you are sometimes a little rambling.<br />

Marx definitely thinks that people should have things, even things which they may not strictly need, if they want<br />

them and if society has enough wealth to produce them. But he wants them to make their choices in freedom, not<br />

pushed by a social system which needs to produce stuff for growth. More details in [168].<br />

Message [146] referenced by [168]. Next Message by Chris is [192].<br />

[168] Hans: Can Marxists advocate lower consumption? Since workers produce much<br />

more value than they receive in their paychecks, Marxists are reluctant to say that they<br />

should consume less. But every time I teach this class I am struck by the willingness <strong>of</strong> the<br />

participants to denounce consumerism. As Chris says in [146] we are duped into believing<br />

we need many more things than we really need. More frugality is not only a moral issue but<br />

a necessity if we want to preserve a hospitable environment: it is completely clear that less<br />

consumption is necessary in order to get <strong>of</strong>f the fossil fuel dependence.<br />

Marx does not say that we should consume less or that we should only have what we<br />

need. He wants people to have control over their lives and to make their own choices. But<br />

it follows from his theory <strong>of</strong> the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodities that in a saner society<br />

people will probably want to consume less. I see two mechanisms here, one on the supply<br />

side and one on the demand side for consumption goods:<br />

(1) Our flourishing and well-being is not the goal <strong>of</strong> the economy, but consumption is one<br />

<strong>of</strong> the marionette strings by which we are coaxed into doing what is good for the economy.<br />

For instance the recent tax rebates are not given to benefit the consumers, but they are given<br />

to benefit the economy. Raising sales numbers and making people happy are two different<br />

things. If we design our own consumption plans, instead <strong>of</strong> being guinea pigs for corporate<br />

advertising, we can expect to get a higher quality <strong>of</strong> life with fewer goods and much less<br />

waste, and probably shorter working hours too.<br />

(2) Capitalism isolates people; instead <strong>of</strong> people interacting socially, things interact on<br />

the market. One might say things have stolen the social relations away from people. If<br />

people take back their own social relations and co-operate directly, instead <strong>of</strong> allowing the<br />

market to separate them, they will probably have more fulfilled social lives and again will<br />

probably need fewer goods.<br />

Message [168] referenced by [146]. Next Message by Hans is [172].


102 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Question 267 is 138 in 1995WI, 115 in 1995ut, 148 in 1996sp, 150 in 1996ut, 155 in<br />

1997WI, 162 in 1997sp, 155 in 1997ut, 265 in 2008fa, 307 in 2010fa, and 294 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 267 Make a thought experiment comparing market production, in which an artisan<br />

produces something for sale, to community production, in which the same artisan knows<br />

the people who will use the things he is producing, and these are the same people who<br />

are producing the things the artisan is consuming. If you were this artisan, would you act<br />

differently in the market situation than in the community situation? Would, over time, the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> your product and the technology <strong>of</strong> your labor evolve differently in these two<br />

situations?<br />

[150] Trailrunner: graded A Art for a Community <strong>of</strong> Friends. If I were an artisan<br />

creating things to be sold in the market vs. being sold to people that I knew from my<br />

community, I would have a tendency to take more care with the item I was creating for those<br />

that were in my community. As well, I would have the desire to create things that I know<br />

would be needed and appreciated by these people. These personal relationships would help<br />

to establish a knowledge <strong>of</strong> their needs, as well as their desires. Since Marx speaks <strong>of</strong> the<br />

“inability to fetch an appropriate price as being based on two reasons: either the good is<br />

not needed or the production methods are not efficient enough,” the knowledge based upon<br />

dealing with these people would help eliminate at least one <strong>of</strong> these reasons – the good<br />

would definitely be needed. I also believe that I would not want to provide someone with<br />

a faulty or poorly made product, recognizing that they have most likely created something<br />

that I will be using and they will have taken the same care in the creation <strong>of</strong> their product.<br />

I do recognize that this is not always the case, but I think that in the long run, I would find<br />

myself trading products only with others that took the same pride in their products as I do.<br />

One positive aspect that I can see in creating things for a market <strong>of</strong> people that I don’t<br />

know, would be that I might find myself with a bit more artistic freedom. Not knowing the<br />

specific needs <strong>of</strong> someone else, I could quite possibly create things that I might not otherwise<br />

create and it could be something truly wonderful. As well, not having a personal relationship<br />

with these people gives me the freedom to not feel like the product has to be perfect, which<br />

could help the creation process be more efficient. The negative that could arise would be that<br />

I would create something that no one else had a need for and thus, the value <strong>of</strong> my creation<br />

would be lost. I know that over time, an understanding <strong>of</strong> what would sell and what would<br />

not, would be found and thus, I would begin to create based upon these sales.<br />

My thought experiment thus brings me to this conclusion. Eventually, I would find a<br />

balance in what I was creating for the market as well as the community. There would definitely<br />

be common products, as well as a few unique products for each situation, but with<br />

this balance, there would be greater efficiency in my production/labor process. As I created<br />

more and more <strong>of</strong> these similar items, the creation <strong>of</strong> them would become more streamlined<br />

– and I might find that I could hire people to help me with some <strong>of</strong> the processes. This <strong>of</strong><br />

course, still leaves open the option to continue to create things that are different and unique<br />

and discover if they might also be needed, but I would have some basic products from which<br />

to trade for the items that I desired to consume.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 103<br />

Hans: Interesting thoughts. Just one remark about them. You are expecting that the market will be helpful and<br />

supportive <strong>of</strong> your projects. This is not always the case. Especially in an era <strong>of</strong> globalization markets can be quite<br />

incalculable.<br />

Next Message by Trailrunner is [169].<br />

Question 269 is 139 in 1995WI, 116 in 1995ut, 156 in 1997WI, 163 in 1997sp, 165 in<br />

1998WI, 172 in 1999SP, 243 in 2004fa, and 263 in 2007fa:<br />

Question 269 Give everyday examples <strong>of</strong> “material relations <strong>of</strong> persons” and “social relations<br />

<strong>of</strong> things.”<br />

[147] Hans: How to rob retired old ladies. My response to Alex’s [141] comes under this<br />

question number because his example <strong>of</strong> insider trading strikes me as an excellent illustration<br />

<strong>of</strong> what Marx calls “material relations <strong>of</strong> persons.”<br />

If you have insider information you can go to the market and make pr<strong>of</strong>itable trades. It is<br />

like opening a spigot with money flowing out. It looks like something objective and neutral,<br />

and you do not see that the trading gains credited to your brokerage account are really taken<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the pockets <strong>of</strong> retired old ladies.<br />

Marx would call this a “material relation <strong>of</strong> persons” because it is a relation between you<br />

and the retired old ladies which almost looks like a relation between you and nature. If you<br />

intend to go into the woods to collect blueberries, it is good to have the information where<br />

the blueberry patches lie. There is nothing wrong with having this information. Therefore<br />

people think if they have information where the pr<strong>of</strong>itable trades lie in the stock market,<br />

there is nothing wrong with this either. They are just taking advantage <strong>of</strong> an objective fact.<br />

But as Alex correctly observes, what they are really doing is they are taking money out <strong>of</strong><br />

the wallets <strong>of</strong> old retired ladies.<br />

Now if you wonder how we got to live in a society where one can rob retired old ladies<br />

by just entering a purchase order into the computer based on information received over the<br />

phone from a friend, Alex’s explanations have a different flavor than Marx’s own.<br />

Alex basically says that people want to misbehave, and they use the business structure to<br />

do it. A Marxist would call this explanation “voluntarism”: the intentions <strong>of</strong> the capitalists to<br />

get rich turn this society into a bad society. Marx’s explanation, as usual, does not start with<br />

the individual but with the social structure. Marx explains these long-distance robberies<br />

by the fact that we live in a society which converts our social relations into a system in<br />

which isolated individuals interact with a quasi-alive economy. The fetish-like character <strong>of</strong><br />

commodities is not consumerism but it is Marx’s terminus technicus for the fact that the<br />

market relations binding us all together have their own dynamic, their own “life,” which is<br />

beyond the control <strong>of</strong> the individuals.<br />

One might think Marx’s explanation is more forgiving and optimistic because he does<br />

not assume individuals are evil. In reality, Marx’s explanation is more pessimistic because it<br />

gives individuals fewer choices. Even if all capitalists were to suddenly shed their greed, perhaps<br />

because they finally realize that business as usual leads to inacceptable global warming,<br />

they cannot, just by no longer being greedy, switch the economy over to a self-sustaining<br />

no-growth path. They are caught in a system which cannot function and will simply break


104 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

down if there is no growth and no pr<strong>of</strong>it. Looking at the economy as a systemic issue is<br />

not an excuse letting individuals <strong>of</strong>f the hook, but it tells us the difficulties <strong>of</strong> getting the<br />

economy under control. Marxists would say it cannot be done by individuals; individuals<br />

have to consciously organize in order to achieve the necessary social changes.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [153].<br />

[318] Jason: My roommate has the habit <strong>of</strong> stealing from large chain stores such as<br />

Smith’s or Walmart. His reasoning and justification for doing this in a society that frowns<br />

upon theft is that he isn’t hurting anyone. Since it is a faceless corporation that makes<br />

ridiculous amounts <strong>of</strong> money they can stand to lose a few avocados or a book. While it<br />

may be true to some degree that his small acquisitions aren’t hurting the company’s pr<strong>of</strong>its,<br />

what he fails to recognize is that companies take shoplifting into account even prior to them<br />

feeling the effects <strong>of</strong> it. It usually results in higher prices for consumers or lower wages<br />

for employees. Either way, by “sticking it to the man” he is indirectly hurting his fellow<br />

man. You can be sure that the suits in the corporate <strong>of</strong>fice aren’t taking the hit for people<br />

like my roommate stealing. This is an example <strong>of</strong> “material relations <strong>of</strong> persons” because<br />

even though my roommate is only benefiting himself by stealing, he isn’t taking Walmart’s<br />

employees or customers into account.<br />

Hans: The company may not be able to recover all their theft losses by raising prices or lowering wages; it may<br />

also go at the expense <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its. Would that change your argument?<br />

Next Message by Jason is [452].<br />

[336] Oldgreg: graded A– Marx is describing the the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> producers in<br />

capitalism with the descriptions “material relations <strong>of</strong> persons” and the “social relations <strong>of</strong><br />

things”. The “material relations <strong>of</strong> persons” is the everyday labor a producer uses to make a<br />

commodity. A woodworker getting wood and making a chair would be a good example <strong>of</strong><br />

this. The “social relation <strong>of</strong> things” is the apparent value realized after the commodity is put<br />

into a market. This would be when the woodworker sells the chair and realizes exchange<br />

value for labor.<br />

Hans: If a woodworker makes a chair out <strong>of</strong> a pile <strong>of</strong> wood, this is a material relation <strong>of</strong> a person, i.e., a relation<br />

between a person and inanimate matter. But it is not under all circumstances the form taken by a social relation<br />

between different people. If the woodworker sits in his basement and does it as a hobby, then it is only a relation<br />

between him and the wood, not the conduit for any social relations he is involved in.<br />

Only when the woodworker produces for a market, and therefore has to make the chair in a certain way which<br />

allows it to be sold at a price that can support the woodworker’s livelihood, then he has to modify his labor process.<br />

As Marx would say, his labor process obtains a double character, not only production <strong>of</strong> use-value, but at the same<br />

time production <strong>of</strong> value, <strong>of</strong> that elusive immaterial substance inside the commodities. This would be an example<br />

where the relationship between the woodworker and all other producers in society takes the form not <strong>of</strong> a direct<br />

co-ordination and division <strong>of</strong> labor, but the form <strong>of</strong> each producer individually having a specific relation to the<br />

objects they produce.<br />

Another example would be the woodworker working for an employer. Much <strong>of</strong> the relationship between the<br />

woodworker and his employer consists in the woodworker producing things, i.e., here too a social relation takes the<br />

form <strong>of</strong> a relation between a human and a thing, i.e., a “material relation” <strong>of</strong> that human.<br />

First Message by Oldgreg is [335].<br />

[341] Matt: “Material relations <strong>of</strong> persons” would be based upon the interaction in the<br />

labor process. For example, I have a “so called” friend that only calls me when he needs<br />

help on his house. I never really talk to him other than for this purpose. The reason he calls<br />

me is because he helped me on my house. Now he feels like he can call me and ask for help<br />

whenever he feels like it. I feel like my labor is only being used as a service to him.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 105<br />

Now if we take this same example, and I do receive money for my service (by some<br />

miracle), this would be considered the “social relations <strong>of</strong> things.” This is because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

relationship between money and service. On pg 172 the annotations say, “the validation <strong>of</strong><br />

their private labors as social labor, the reality test, and any practical activity necessary to reconcile<br />

this after-the-fact reality with the already finished production, happens retroactively<br />

through the success which the products have on the market”. . . through their exchange.<br />

Next Message by Matt is [425].<br />

[380] Bar: graded A material relations <strong>of</strong> persons and social relations <strong>of</strong> things. “Material<br />

relations <strong>of</strong> persons” and “social relations <strong>of</strong> things” is in essence how the commodity transcends<br />

exchange and becomes something very complex, it becomes a social relation form<br />

material. What I find most astonishing about Marx is that he was the first Economist to realize<br />

this relationship, yet since materialism, or capitalism it has been a reoccurring theme.<br />

My favorite example <strong>of</strong> this is a gold digger, who for those who do not know is a woman<br />

who marries a man for his money. The commodity in this case money, representing the<br />

ability to acquire more commodities, replaces the social interaction <strong>of</strong> love and trust through<br />

marriage as a material relation <strong>of</strong> a person. From this example, comes a plethora <strong>of</strong> realization<br />

to the immense hold the commodity has on society. Looking back far from capitalist<br />

society in another dimension where these relations don’t exist, a human being living in a<br />

non commodity-linked society would not make decisions based on the increase or consumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity, rather socially equitable decisions would be made. The person in our<br />

society makes decisions based on how it will increase his commodities, and how this will<br />

change his status. For example, most women and some men love jewelry especially diamonds<br />

which are very expensive. Fake jewelry looking exactly the same as the real thing<br />

doesn’t replace the demand for real jewelry. In this case the commodity replaces beauty<br />

where they both look the same with scarcity. The commodity in the person’s eyes is better<br />

because it is something that they have and someone else does not, it creates class in the society.<br />

The commodity also controls desires, because it shapes desire. For example, if everyone<br />

had the same option, or all the cars were exactly the same, the commodity would have no<br />

social control over the person for desire to have a better car than someone else. There are<br />

material relations <strong>of</strong> person and social relations <strong>of</strong> things in our society, almost all relations<br />

under capitalism are because <strong>of</strong> this.<br />

Next Message by Bar is [403].<br />

[384] Brandon: graded B+ I stand by my original submission from the in-class exam<br />

regarding the material relation between a teenager and his xbox 360.<br />

However, the social relation I gave regarding gasoline was wrong. It should not be viewed<br />

as a relationship between gasoline and the buyer/society buy rather the relation between<br />

commodities. Using the classic linen:coat example, I will try to make that fit with gasoline.<br />

Most simply the relation between crude oil and refined gasoline. Just as “20 feet <strong>of</strong> linen = 1<br />

coat”, x amount <strong>of</strong> oil = 1 gallon <strong>of</strong> gasoline. This represents the social relationship between<br />

things which complements the material relationships between things and their buyers. This<br />

social relation will create the thing, in this case gasoline, which the buyer then perceives as<br />

a material relation, between himself and the thing. His material relationship is that gasoline<br />

is necessary for his vehicle to function.


106 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Resubmissions are not addenda to your in-class exam but they should give the entire answer. You also<br />

initially tried to submit both answers in the same email, which makes it difficult for me to feed them into the<br />

archive. All this is clearly explained in the instructions for the resubmission.<br />

Next Message by Brandon is [400].<br />

[409] SnatchimusMaximus: content A late penalty 1% In a society dominated by commodity<br />

production people begin to interact with the commodities, rather than with their fellow<br />

human beings. This human-commodity interaction is known as commodity fetishism,<br />

or the material relations <strong>of</strong> persons. Commodities, in return, interact with people in such a<br />

commodity driven society and commodity-human interaction replaces human-human interaction.<br />

This is referred to as the social relation <strong>of</strong> things, or the fetish like nature <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Commodities thus become the medium through which people interact with each<br />

other. This human-commodity and commodity-human interaction creates a social disconnect<br />

between humans and relationships with commodities eventually replace interpersonal<br />

relationships.<br />

As an example people in our society associate with each other by the type <strong>of</strong> car, size<br />

<strong>of</strong> house, or type <strong>of</strong> clothes worn. These relationships with physical commodities replace<br />

interpersonal relationships. These commodities interact with people, conferring notions <strong>of</strong><br />

status and prestige. Before the introduction <strong>of</strong> the commodity, the identities <strong>of</strong> mankind<br />

relied on human-human relations, not human-commodity or commodity-human relations.<br />

Hans: By social relations <strong>of</strong> things Marx means social relations between things, namely, the exchange-relations<br />

between things.<br />

Next Message by SnatchimusMaximus is [552].<br />

Question 278 is 157 in 1996sp, 163 in 1997WI, 170 in 1997sp, 172 in 1998WI, 179 in<br />

1999SP, 190 in 2000fa, 200 in 2001fa, 214 in 2002fa, 222 in 2003fa, 252 in 2004fa,<br />

267 in 2007SP, 272 in 2007fa, 290 in 2009fa, 318 in 2010fa, 296 in 2011fa, and 309 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

Question 278 Explain Marx’s metaphor that “value does not have it written on its forehead<br />

what it is.” Later in the commodity fetishism section, Marx uses the same metaphor “written<br />

on the forehead” again in a slightly different context. Compare what he says that second<br />

time with what he says here.<br />

[215] Samantha: Value hinges on Labor. The meaning here is quite easy to understand,<br />

Marx is explaining that is it “not obvious that value comes from labor.” (Hans [2007fa:129])<br />

The value <strong>of</strong> an object is not written on its forehead, therefore it is subjective. Others (the<br />

producers) see the labor and the product and do not consider it equal to the labor and product<br />

<strong>of</strong> their good, instead they haggle over the value <strong>of</strong> a good, refusing to see that value comes<br />

from labor. Marx then discusses the hieroglypics, which are the scientific methods that men<br />

then devise because they cannot see that value hinges on labor.<br />

The second mention to the ‘his forehead’ metaphor says, “These forms, which have it<br />

written on their foreheads that they belong to the social formation in which the production<br />

process has the mastery over men”. In this section Marx is upset that people are willing<br />

to accept that “the production process has the mastery over men”. He laments that instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> seeing value from labor (and those labor conditions) the people are seeing just a social<br />

formation and are not asking the pertinent questions.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 107<br />

The two references <strong>of</strong> this particular metaphor show that individuals are unable to ask<br />

the questions which will show them where value comes from. Men instead look for other<br />

explanations, hieroglypics or social formations <strong>of</strong> the production process, while the whole<br />

time value for any product comes from labor.<br />

Hans: This question will not be on the exam. It was submitted during the time when all questions are assigned in<br />

preparation <strong>of</strong> the exam. But only those questions which were previously discussed will get grades, others will be<br />

ungraded.<br />

You say that in their haggling the traders are “refusing to see that value comes from labor.” They don’t have to<br />

see this. See my [144] about this.<br />

Regarding the second occurrence <strong>of</strong> “forehead,” Marx’s main lament is that people do not have control over<br />

production. Their failure to ask the right questions just perpetuates the ideological fog coming along with this lack<br />

<strong>of</strong> control.<br />

Next Message by Samantha is [369].<br />

Question 281 is 217 in 2002fa, 225 in 2003fa, 255 in 2004fa, 250 in 2005fa, 270 in<br />

2007SP, 275 in 2007fa, 321 in 2010fa, 299 in 2011fa, and 312 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 281 Marx criticizes in 166:2/o that even after the discovery <strong>of</strong> labor as the the<br />

substance <strong>of</strong> value, this was generally considered an “immutable fact.” What else should<br />

people have thought and done?<br />

[174] Jenn: graded D Economics as a social SCIENCE. Marx provides a unique perspective<br />

on a social science when pointing out the “immutable” property <strong>of</strong> the value assigned<br />

to them. Since we exchange a higher number <strong>of</strong> unique commodities than we actually<br />

produce ourselves, it is a seemingly natural paradigm to think <strong>of</strong> products only by their<br />

exchange-value. As a result <strong>of</strong> this paradigm, it seems simple to calculate labor-time based<br />

on the exchange-value. However, Marx points out that this is an essentially backward way<br />

<strong>of</strong> calculating.<br />

When stated, this point regarding the reverse inferred calculation, this seems an obvious<br />

error. Although social sciences are not quite as straightforward as life sciences, it would<br />

seem logical to take a more scientific approach and thought process. Commodities are a<br />

production <strong>of</strong> labor, not vice-versa. One method that would have been appropriate to take at<br />

the time <strong>of</strong> this “discovery” would have been to set up analyses comparing exchange-values<br />

to labor-time. This is hard for one who has only ever witnessed a capitalist pricing system to<br />

conceptualize, but perhaps if economists at that time had taken a more scientific approach,<br />

the entire pricing structure <strong>of</strong> the world’s economy may have been different.<br />

Hans: Sorry, this is completely <strong>of</strong>f. Prices do not depend on what economists do. Please look at [62]. It seems you<br />

had these misconceptions already in your earlier submissions, but it was never as clear as here.<br />

Next Message by Jenn is [217].<br />

Question 283 is 160 in 1996sp, 173 in 1997sp, 165 in 1997ut, 194 in 2000fa, 205 in<br />

2001fa, 219 in 2002fa, 227 in 2003fa, 257 in 2004fa, 252 in 2005fa, 272 in 2007SP, 277<br />

in 2007fa, 281 in 2008fa, 323 in 2010fa, 302 in 2011fa, and 315 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 283 Commodity producers do not exchange their products because they consider<br />

the labor in these products to be equal and therefore believe the fruits <strong>of</strong> the labor should<br />

be distributed on an equal basis. Marx claims that, on the contrary, the market interactions<br />

induce them to unknowingly equalize their labors. Describe the process by which they<br />

equalize their labors, and the goals which they pursue in this process.


108 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[199] Spawnblade: Forced Equality <strong>of</strong> Labor. First I’d like to address the question:<br />

“...do not exchange their products... to be equal and therefore believe... distributed on an<br />

equal basis.”<br />

This bit confused me, because if they believed the labor in these products to be equal, then<br />

they should not have an issue with exchanging the products presuming they benefited from<br />

the trade. Unless that is what the question is indicating (That because it was equal there was<br />

no reason for an exchange.) Yet that would be a relation to utility value <strong>of</strong> a commodity on a<br />

person-to-person basis, and not on a forced equalization <strong>of</strong> labor. It’s due to this uncertainty<br />

that I’d like to take a shot at pursuing the question, and perhaps failing it miserably, but at<br />

least trying since I have seen no other current responses.<br />

Attempting to look from Marx’s point <strong>of</strong> view, all commodities are commodities because<br />

<strong>of</strong> the human labor that has taken place to form them. If this is the case, the commodity<br />

itself should be impossible to judge its actual value (because <strong>of</strong> the mysterious quality that<br />

human labor has shaped in it, according to Marx,) and due to the problem that producers have<br />

with actually discerning the unknown value, they then ‘unknowingly equalize their labors’<br />

based upon a standard comparison <strong>of</strong> time/effort/materials between themselves and other<br />

producers. By doing this they form relationships in labor, price, etc, that they feel conforms<br />

with the current ‘standard’, despite this standard being inefficient to the economy as a whole<br />

because it is not a ‘true’ standard. The main goal in doing this would be to actually assign a<br />

value to their commodity with the limited knowledge <strong>of</strong> its capabilities and uses they actually<br />

have. A secondary goal might be the ‘fitting-in’ with society, and performing their tasks as<br />

is culturally-acceptable. This reason isn’t as economically focused, but conformity plays a<br />

large part in all aspects <strong>of</strong> human behavior. And due to the social nature <strong>of</strong> economics, and<br />

the relationships <strong>of</strong> producers, it would be necessary to avoid alienation by conforming to a<br />

standard system.<br />

Hans: Please read [62] and [2007SP:65]. You are the best example <strong>of</strong> what Marx is talking about. You participate<br />

in a capitalist market which, according to Marx, exchanges things by their labor content. But you are so utterly<br />

unaware <strong>of</strong> this that, if someone tells you that this is what you are doing, you think this person is not talking about<br />

you and the system you are living in, but about some mythical alternative society.<br />

Next Message by Spawnblade is [328].<br />

[211] Rey: content A+ form 95% Value is in the labor....Naturally! “Since the exchange<br />

proportions seem to come from the nature <strong>of</strong> the product, and not from the labor process, the<br />

producers try to escape the quantitative link between labor and value by producing that use<br />

value and employ that production method which gives them the most favorable exchange for<br />

the effort they put in.” This is the exact method in which the efforts <strong>of</strong> capitalist “to outwit<br />

the law <strong>of</strong> value, implement it.” I will explain.<br />

As the question states, “commodity producers do not exchange their products because<br />

they consider the labor in these products to be equal. . . ” rather a commodity producer exchanges<br />

based on their idea that value lies with in the nature <strong>of</strong> the product. In order to gain<br />

something <strong>of</strong> a “naturally higher value” one must exchange a multitude <strong>of</strong> the “naturally<br />

lower” valued products. It is this thought that drives a producer to invest time, talents and<br />

money into discovering the most efficient way to produce a large quantity <strong>of</strong> a “naturally<br />

lower” valued product. As this means is discovered the producer is now able to produce in<br />

great volume <strong>of</strong> products that can be exchanged for “naturally higher” valued products. It


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 109<br />

is however in this very process that they are upholding the idea that labor equals value. In<br />

addition, the producer’s attention to quantity over quality only maintains the inferior relation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the good that is easy to come by, and creates a need for more labor. This again reinforces<br />

the idea that value is equal to labor.<br />

Using a real life example one can explore the products used by Marx namely iron and<br />

gold. Gold’s value does not come to it simply by its nature; rather its value comes from the<br />

fact that it is rare in respect to other metals. It takes a great deal <strong>of</strong> time and effort to discover,<br />

harvest and refine. Ore on the other hand can be found in abundance and due to its abundant<br />

nature can be discovered, harvested and refined at a much lower costs to its producer. Thus<br />

gold has the higher value. However because the commodity trader believes the value to be in<br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> the product rather than the labor seeks to find a way to produce a higher quantity<br />

more efficiently. It is this placement <strong>of</strong> quantity over quality that in fact keeps the ore inferior<br />

to the gold. The ore becomes less valuable as it becomes more common and its production<br />

easier. The producer may believe he is defeating the system because he has now found a<br />

way to easily produce more ore, however this has only upheld the system. The system has<br />

been upheld in two ways. One: The producer has now put forth the labor necessary for the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> ore to equal the value <strong>of</strong> gold. Not only has this been done through the time spent<br />

improving production, but also the improvement <strong>of</strong> production has now made it necessary to<br />

produce more ore (the increase in efficiency <strong>of</strong> production has made it necessary to produce<br />

more ore because as a product is more common and is more easily come by its value drops).<br />

Which brings us to the second way in which the producer has upheld the system. Namely<br />

it is now necessary to produce a higher quantity <strong>of</strong> ore, which obviously takes more labor,<br />

thus upholding the idea that value is attached to labor.<br />

Hans: Excellent thinking and eloquently formulated! But your original submission had too many little typos and<br />

spelling errors. People will not take you seriously and give you credit as the deep thinker that you are if you have<br />

lots <strong>of</strong> typos.<br />

Message [211] referenced by [407]. Next Message by Rey is [212].<br />

[239] Kevin: graded A Equal work does not equal value. Equalization <strong>of</strong> labor comes<br />

from the fact that transactions are blind. As two blind producers go to gain, or increase<br />

what they have relative to another, they unknowingly trade for something perceived to have<br />

greater value than what they have already. This blind trade equalizes the value <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

regardless <strong>of</strong> time or skill. In the end, in an attempt to out-perform/out-produce others all<br />

processes become similar and all labor equal anyway. No one gains advantage over another.<br />

Herein lies much destruction as a capitalist society looks to gain everything but in the end<br />

gains nothing as a whole and in fact loses everything.<br />

Next Message by Kevin is [470].<br />

[344] Brody: I find this question too contradictory and confusing to answer. If producers<br />

already consider their labor to be equal, how then do market interactions induce them to<br />

unknowingly equalize their labors? Unfortunately this may only be a cop out on proper<br />

preparation for this question but I still do not understand Marx’s argument here if producers<br />

already believe labors to be equal?<br />

Hans: They don’t believe their labors to be equal. They set their labors equal through their actions, by exchanging<br />

the products <strong>of</strong> labor, but their individual motivation for the exchange is one <strong>of</strong> getting the best deal for themselves<br />

rather than the solidarity <strong>of</strong> equal labor hinted at in the question.


110 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

This is my original answer to the test question. After further research I do now understand<br />

the question and Marx’s hints towards self-fulfilling prophecies coming to life because <strong>of</strong><br />

producers’ actions on their reactions to prices.<br />

Hans: This is still too vague and general; I cannot give you credit just for your assertion that you understand it<br />

now, I need to see some evidence. I am looking for a concrete description <strong>of</strong> the process, as was for instance done<br />

in [2007fa:133].<br />

Next Message by Brody is [345].<br />

[351] Ryoung: Equal Labor. The labor value equals themselves out according to Marx<br />

because trading an apple for an apple means that the value for apple 1 is equal to the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> apple 2 regardless <strong>of</strong> the labor that went into producing apple 1 and apple 2. The goals<br />

which they pursue are to trade for the best values out there but when trading (like mentioned<br />

above) labor input is being equalized.<br />

Hans: Apples are not traded for apples. I think what you mean is: since all goods which have the same use-value<br />

are considered equal on the market, this leads to it that the labor producing them is also equalized. This is indeed<br />

Marx’s argument, but I wanted to hear more details about how “this leads to it.”<br />

Next Message by Ryoung is [431].<br />

[387] Clayon: Marx argues that market interactions induce producers to equalize their<br />

labors unknowingly. This is done because it implies that no worker has been forced to<br />

produce more goods than he is able (as is the case in a capitalist market), therefore all<br />

workers in the market have put forth an equal amount <strong>of</strong> labor into their goods, giving them<br />

equal value.<br />

Exchange proportions do not come from the labor process, but rather the nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

product. This causes the producers to use a production method that gives them the most<br />

return for their input <strong>of</strong> Labor. This conscious decision has the “unintended” result <strong>of</strong> integrating<br />

their labor into the social division <strong>of</strong> labor, and causes the producers to have similar<br />

labor processes. This creates an “equal value” for the good in terms <strong>of</strong> labor input.<br />

If in a day’s work a person produces 2 sweaters, and another person produces 5 loaves <strong>of</strong><br />

bread, it can be said that those goods in that ratio have an equal input <strong>of</strong> labor, creating an<br />

equal value.<br />

Hans: About your sentence ”Exchange proportions do not come from the labor process, but rather the nature <strong>of</strong><br />

the product” see my [416].<br />

Message [387] referenced by [416]. Next Message by Clayon is [609].<br />

[389] Mick: graded B– The process <strong>of</strong> labor equalization that is employed by commodity<br />

producers to measure labor fails to measure total amount <strong>of</strong> labor involved in the production<br />

<strong>of</strong> their respective commodity(ies). The most commonly utilized methods such as time,<br />

or quantity produced are unsuccessful measures <strong>of</strong> labor because they do not reflect the<br />

abstract properties <strong>of</strong> labor used in producing a product such as mental anguish, physical<br />

endangerment, and other comparatively abstract properties <strong>of</strong> labor. This practice <strong>of</strong> blatant<br />

disregard for the more vague aspects <strong>of</strong> labor allows the capitalist to pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> this unmeasured/uncompensated<br />

value when he sells his products on the market place by throwing<br />

a blanket over all labor, when he knows that the labors involved are diverse and <strong>of</strong> different<br />

values. Common current techniques cannot be spun as a fair and logical basis for evaluating<br />

labor. They exploitative.<br />

Hans: When Marx speaks <strong>of</strong> equalization <strong>of</strong> labor, he not only means a measuring process, but he means that the<br />

labor processes themselves are made equal or homogeneous, with no qualitative differences.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 111<br />

We haven’t discussed wages and pr<strong>of</strong>its yet. At this point I can only say that your mental-anguish theory <strong>of</strong><br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its is different from Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its. What you call “abstract labor” has no relationship with Marx’s<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> abstract labor.<br />

Next Message by Mick is [460].<br />

Question 284 is 150 in 1995WI, 127 in 1995ut, 161 in 1996sp, 163 in 1996ut, 174 in<br />

1997sp, 220 in 2002fa, 228 in 2003fa, 258 in 2004fa, 273 in 2007SP, 278 in 2007fa, 282<br />

in 2008fa, 303 in 2011fa, and 317 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 284 Someone says: The law <strong>of</strong> value cannot hold. We are free people, we do what<br />

we want. We are not forced to price our commodities by their labor content. Explain to this<br />

person, along the lines <strong>of</strong> the argument Marx uses here, that this myopic attempt to assert<br />

one’s freedom leads to unfreedom.<br />

[170] Sparky: Law <strong>of</strong> value and the “reset” button. The law <strong>of</strong> value is the necessary<br />

social labor time that is needed to create commodities and the exchange proportions that<br />

determine how much will be willingly traded in order to receive the commodities. When the<br />

capitalist, and his free market, decide to get ahead <strong>of</strong> the rest by lowering the price if his<br />

good compared to his competitors, “in order to get ahead” as the annotations put it, what he<br />

really is doing is unknowingly pressing the “reset” button on the entire market for the good<br />

he produces. He has set <strong>of</strong>f a series <strong>of</strong> events in which the producers and consumers are<br />

thrown into a place were the good’s values is socially changing, and to become competitive<br />

– in order to survive – the other capitalists will begin to change production methods, force<br />

more work out <strong>of</strong> fewer workers, or implement other cost saving methods in order to adjust<br />

to the new market price for the good and still make money, creating a new necessary social<br />

labor time that is accepted by the consumers.<br />

This process shows how all actions are interconnected; how the “freedom” that is enjoyed<br />

by the capitalist is really the exact opposite, that in order to survive he must obey the laws<br />

that surround him and the market. Otherwise he will be put out <strong>of</strong> business for charging<br />

more than and taking more time than is viewed to be required in the production <strong>of</strong> his goods<br />

than other competitors.<br />

Hans: EW in [2007SP:221] uses the word “reset,” and you are vividly describing this process. Just one comment<br />

regarding your last paragraph: our lack <strong>of</strong> freedom does not come from the fact that we are interconnected, but<br />

from the fact that we ignore this interconnection and, instead <strong>of</strong> co-ordinating our actions, only react to the social<br />

properties <strong>of</strong> the commodities. This is like stirring in a wasp’s nest. Our actions bring forth powerful reactions<br />

which maintain our state as prisoners <strong>of</strong> the market system.<br />

Message [170] referenced by [171], [519], and [2008fa:392]. Next Message by Sparky is [225].<br />

[171] Srichardson: graded A the law <strong>of</strong> value’s ability to hold. Marx says that this<br />

narrow way <strong>of</strong> trying to achieve freedom will in the end result to unfreedom. In comment<br />

[170] Sparky explains the theory in a way that is easier to understand, why this freedom is<br />

in the end the opposite. The law <strong>of</strong> value must hold as long as there are the markets that<br />

support it. If one tries to escape these markets by setting their own price they will perish in<br />

the market. It is true that you can do what you want however you will not continue to survive<br />

in the market if you choose to “assert one’s freedom”.<br />

As [170] explains we are so dependent and tied into one another and when the “reset<br />

button” is hit the events set into place are so dependent on what others do, and it is like a set


112 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> dominos that hits the events set in place. In other words we are all dependent on the way<br />

we interact with each other.<br />

Marx believes that it is not possible to obtain these freedoms inside the market system<br />

and it will not be until we move away from this type <strong>of</strong> market assistance until we obtain the<br />

freedom that is talked about in this question.<br />

Hans: Good response to [170]. You gently rectify Sparky’s misconception that the mere strength <strong>of</strong> our interdependence<br />

is the source <strong>of</strong> our unfreedom. The word “myopic” in the question is relevant here. Our unfreedom<br />

comes from us trying to manipulate our products rather than socially coordinating our production activities.<br />

Next Message by Srichardson is [258].<br />

Question 285 is 177 in 1998WI, 196 in 2000fa, 221 in 2002fa, 229 in 2003fa, 259 in<br />

2004fa, 254 in 2005fa, 274 in 2007SP, 279 in 2007fa, 283 in 2008fa, 297 in 2009fa, 325<br />

in 2010fa, 304 in 2011fa, and 304 in Answer:<br />

Question 285 Isn’t there a blatant inconsistency in Marx’s text? At the beginning <strong>of</strong> paragraph<br />

167:1/o, the fixity <strong>of</strong> commodity prices is stressed, while towards the end <strong>of</strong> the same<br />

paragraph 167:1/o, Marx emphasizes that they fluctuate continually.<br />

[177] Scott: Inconsistent or consistent? If you don’t analyze Marx’s paragraph 167:1/o<br />

it would be simple to think that Marx is inconsistent with what he has written, but we find<br />

out that he is consistent throughout the entire thing. From his text we find out that from<br />

the invisible labor inside the commodity we are going to obtain the value. He emphasizes<br />

the fixity <strong>of</strong> commodities in the beginning only to prove that it’s the invisible labor that sets<br />

these prices. Once you know what your cost is going to be you can try to get the most out <strong>of</strong><br />

your commodity as you can. For example if I was the first person to produce cars I would be<br />

able to control the price because I was the first person to make them. The consumers would<br />

spend lots <strong>of</strong> money on them because they are new. Marx goes on and talks about fluctuation<br />

because as time goes on more people will produce cars making the price go down.<br />

Hans: I am amazed that an analysis <strong>of</strong> Marx’s paragraph 167:1/o brings you to this conclusion. Marx does not say<br />

that the fixity comes from the product being new and there only being one supplier who can set prices. He writes<br />

As soon as these proportions have attained a certain customary fixity, they seem to spring from<br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> the products.<br />

This does not look like something that is newly introduced, but something that has been traded for a long time.<br />

Besides, Marx is using iron and gold as examples, not some newfangled use-value.<br />

My quote also shows that for Marx, the fixity <strong>of</strong> exchange proportions is not pro<strong>of</strong> that ”it’s the invisible labor<br />

that sets these prices” (as you say), but on the contrary, this fixity makes it seem as if prices spring from the nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> the products. Marx continues to argue that it is the fluctuations which lead to the recognition that prices are<br />

driven by the adjustment <strong>of</strong> social labor time, just as the collapse <strong>of</strong> a house reveals the driving force <strong>of</strong> gravity.<br />

Message [177] referenced by [193]. Next Message by Scott is [178].<br />

[193] Hans: Imagine you are in a job interview. If you come up with brilliant ideas and<br />

fresh perspectives from just cursorily following the text, I am happy about this and will give<br />

you a good grade. But without doing the footwork, creativity can only get you so far; and<br />

it’s possible that your creative ideas show that you have serious misunderstandings.<br />

Many job interviews do not directly ask you: have your read this, do you know that?<br />

Instead they sound like pleasant banter. Don’t be deceived by this. Your interviewers are<br />

listening carefully which kind <strong>of</strong> knowledge and attitudes shine through on your end <strong>of</strong> the<br />

conversation.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 113<br />

Had [177] been a job inverview, the candidate would not have gotten the job. Here are<br />

the highlights:<br />

Job candidate: “If you don’t analyze Marx’s paragraph 167:1/o it would be simple to<br />

think that Marx is inconsistent with what he has written, but we find out that he is consistent<br />

throughout the entire thing.”<br />

Interviewer thinking to himself: he knows that I like Marx, but he didn’t get it that Marx<br />

does not shy away from contradictions but embraces contradictions.<br />

Job candidate: “From his text we find out that” (and then comes a theory which has zero<br />

correlation to Marx’s text).<br />

Interviewer thinking to himself: He knows that I want people to read the text carefully but<br />

this seems a little brash. How shall I deal with it? Shall I say I am surprised that he comes<br />

to this conclusion? Calm down, use the word “amazed”, this sounds friendlier. And maybe<br />

this has its upsides too. I will simply go through the text and show by letter and verse how<br />

the candidate’s theory really correlates with Marx. This is another opportunity to explain<br />

Marx’s reasoning.<br />

If I made you curious, please look at my comments to [177].<br />

Next Message by Hans is [214].<br />

[213] Averil: An initial examination <strong>of</strong> paragraph 167:1/o would lead the casual observer<br />

to think Marx is contradicting himself. Scott is right in saying that it is Marx emphasizing<br />

the fixity <strong>of</strong> commodities only to prove that it is in fact labor that determines value. Marx<br />

is asserting that it is the labor behind the production <strong>of</strong> the commodity that determines its<br />

ultimate value. It is the magnitudes <strong>of</strong> value that are ever-changing, not the production cost<br />

or value <strong>of</strong> the commodity itself. Labor-time emerges as the stabilizing force and measuring<br />

stick by which we begin to assign value and magnitude to different commodities. Scott<br />

calls it invisible labor, Marx calls it the secret hidden under the apparent shifting <strong>of</strong> values<br />

in a marketplace. Here Marx subtly reinforcing his base assertion that labor is the unit<br />

that everything must be measured. Though a market operates around a seemingly arbitrary<br />

assigned value system, Marx proves that the value arrived at is based directly upon labortime.<br />

Hans: You are referring to Scott’s original message but you seem to be ignoring the detailed feedback Scott received<br />

from me. This affects your grade.<br />

You are aware that it is a contradiction that market prices are so variable although they are the representation<br />

<strong>of</strong> values which are much less changeable. Good for you that you didn’t fall for Scott’s shortcut resolution <strong>of</strong> the<br />

contradiction, but I don’t see you <strong>of</strong>fering your own resolution <strong>of</strong> the contradiction. Here is an attempt to resolve<br />

this contradiction. Perhaps one can say: this variability comes from the fact that while expressing values, prices<br />

also have the social function <strong>of</strong> adjusting private and spontaneous production to ever-changing demand.<br />

First Message by Averil is [163].<br />

Question 290 is 157 in 1995WI, 134 in 1995ut, 167 in 1996sp, 227 in 2002fa, 235 in<br />

2003fa, 260 in 2005fa, 280 in 2007SP, 285 in 2007fa, 302 in 2009fa, 330 in 2010fa, and<br />

309 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 290 Why does Marx call Ricardo’s exchange between primitive fisherman and<br />

primitive hunter a “Robinson Crusoe story”?


114 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[210] Aaron: Robinson Crusoe. The reason Marx calls Ricardo’s exchange between<br />

the primitive fisherman and the primitive hunter a Robinson Crusoe story is because the<br />

fisherman and the hunter are allowed to determine the value <strong>of</strong> the spoils <strong>of</strong> their efforts<br />

on their own. In Kapital, Marx relates a story <strong>of</strong> Robinson Crusoe while he is stranded on<br />

the island. He collects a series <strong>of</strong> different objects that he finds from the shipwreck, and<br />

“like a good Englishman,” says Marx, he began to keep a book or catalog <strong>of</strong> all the objects<br />

he found, and how long it took to recover the object. Crusoe then uses this catalog system<br />

to determine the “value” <strong>of</strong> each item. He is using the self determined wealth theory, in<br />

which he determines his “wealth” by the time and effort <strong>of</strong> the labor used to get the final<br />

product. All <strong>of</strong> the products that Robinson found came by labor exclusively from him and<br />

became objects <strong>of</strong> utility for him and him alone. That is parallel with the reasoning for Marx<br />

referring to the exchange between the fisherman and the hunter in primitive times.<br />

Hans: Reading Marx’s passage about Robinson is necessary to answer this question, but you must put it together<br />

with other insights about commodity production that can be found in other passages <strong>of</strong> Marx. As in [31], you are<br />

reading individual sections <strong>of</strong> the readings but you can’t quite put the puzzle pieces together. I recommend that you<br />

come to class or listen to the class recordings, because there I try to give an overview and connect everything. Look<br />

at Jingle [2004fa:489] or my [2003fa:183] for a correct answer.<br />

Next Message by Aaron is [222].<br />

Question 291 is 135 in 1995ut, 228 in 2002fa, 236 in 2003fa, 281 in 2007SP, and 310 in<br />

2011fa:<br />

Question 291 Which “social” forms do the three determinations <strong>of</strong> value take in Robinson’s<br />

one-man-society?<br />

[181] Andy: The three determinations <strong>of</strong> value are labor-power, labor-time, and “the<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> interactions between the producers through which their labors are integrated<br />

into the social labor process”. However in Robinson’s situation, he is in a one man-society<br />

which is impossible to have real social relations with anyone, or anything. Take for instance<br />

labor-power and labor-time that only entails the energy or effort that Robinson himself puts<br />

into it so therefore it may help him pass time by making/creating things he needs or wants,<br />

however there is nothing social about it. Then take the third determination which says the<br />

existence <strong>of</strong> interactions between the producers and there laborers. Robinson is the producer<br />

and there are no laborers so there cannot possibly be any social relations in a one-man<br />

society.<br />

Hans: How do you come to the conclusion that Robinson cannot relate to things? And there is also a relationship<br />

between Robinson today and Robinson tomorrow. Look at [2007SP:206] for what I consider the right answer to<br />

this question.<br />

Next Message by Andy is [233].<br />

Question 295 is 180 in 1997WI, 187 in 1997sp, 232 in 2002fa, 240 in 2003fa, 290 in<br />

2007fa, 307 in 2009fa, and 335 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 295 Explain Marx’s statement that labor in medieval society did not take a social<br />

form different from its natural form.<br />

[169] Trailrunner: graded B Labor as a Commodity <strong>of</strong> Nature. It has been stated in<br />

our readings that “the laws <strong>of</strong> nature remain unchanged regardless <strong>of</strong> what people do.” It<br />

has also been stated that “people think they control the social powers <strong>of</strong> things, but this


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 115<br />

is an illusion.” In speaking <strong>of</strong> medieval society, goods were traded based upon force and<br />

exploitation, or you might say based upon masters and servants <strong>of</strong> the society. If we look at<br />

the first two statements in this paragraph, it would seem to mean to me that people do not<br />

control social powers, just as they do not change the laws <strong>of</strong> nature.<br />

Because society was set up the way that it was, it was only natural for those <strong>of</strong> “servant”<br />

status to provide labor to those <strong>of</strong> “master” status. This labor was a natural form <strong>of</strong> payment<br />

for the dependence that servants had on their masters to be able to farm the land, live in their<br />

homes, or whatever their personal situation may have been that kept them in a subservient<br />

position. Just as an ounce <strong>of</strong> silver and an ounce <strong>of</strong> gold weigh the same in nature, a servant<br />

providing labor for an opportunity to farm some land is the same in a society. It is an<br />

exchange <strong>of</strong> something <strong>of</strong> value – labor taking the place <strong>of</strong> the commodity – and is not<br />

something that the servant gives privately, but is something that is given socially.<br />

By removing the thought <strong>of</strong> labor being something “private” that was given by the servant,<br />

and opening it up to looking at it like it was simply another commodity, it is easy to see that<br />

labor in medieval society was equally a social form as well as a natural form.<br />

Message [169] referenced by [214]. Next Message by Trailrunner is [260].<br />

[214] Hans: Social form <strong>of</strong> labor different from its natural form. If a serf had to work<br />

for the landlord in the Middle Ages, he did not consider it an exchange relation but this was<br />

something he was forced to do. Trailrunner [169] re-interprets it as an exchange, and says<br />

that people considered it natural to trade labor. They were certainly told that this was the<br />

natural order and they were not allowed to leave their god-ordained place in it, but this is not<br />

what Marx means when he talks about “natural form <strong>of</strong> labor.”<br />

In the Middle Ages there were strict rules who could do what, how many shoemakers<br />

were allowed in the city, etc. This was a regulation <strong>of</strong> labor in its natural use-value form.<br />

Nowadays, all that counts is whether the product can be sold, i.e., whether this labor can<br />

hold its own in competition with all other labors. This is why Marx writes:<br />

The natural form <strong>of</strong> labor, its particularity—and not, as in a society based on<br />

commodity production, its universality—is here its immediate social form.<br />

Related with this, money was much less important in the Middle Ages, most rents were<br />

paid in kind (tithe). Marx writes:<br />

There is no need for labor and its products to assume a fantastic form different<br />

from their reality.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [216].<br />

Question 299 is 164 in 1995WI, 141 in 1995ut, 174 in 1996sp, 183 in 1997WI, 182 in<br />

1997ut, 235 in 2002fa, 244 in 2003fa, 274 in 2004fa, 269 in 2005fa, 289 in 2007SP, 297<br />

in 2008fa, 311 in 2009fa, 339 in 2010fa, 318 in 2011fa, and 332 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 299 In what ways can Christianity and the commodity relation be considered<br />

similar?


116 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[173] Dyoung: Connection between Christianity and Commodity. I feel that there is a<br />

connection between Christianity and the commodity relation. Like others I think it is only<br />

valid with modern forms <strong>of</strong> religion.<br />

We have learned from Marx that there is a relationship between useful labor and production<br />

which give the commodity its value in the world. I think that Christianity <strong>of</strong>fers a<br />

similar idea that connects the body and the soul <strong>of</strong> an individual with the idea <strong>of</strong> purification<br />

through a belief in Christ.<br />

Which includes individuals living up to certain standards and a belief in human labor and<br />

works to help themselves get into heaven. TimJim [2005fa:474] has a great quote from the<br />

bible in Rev. 20:12 which says “...and the dead were judged out <strong>of</strong> those things which were<br />

written in the book <strong>of</strong> life, according to their works.” I too know that many Christian sects<br />

believe that after this life, the rest <strong>of</strong> eternity is judged upon the good works performed in<br />

this life.<br />

So having this understanding I think that there is a connection. Christian individuals are<br />

like commodities in that they are given opportunities to perform human labor, for the hopes<br />

<strong>of</strong> gaining a greater value in the next life. Christians have to give up their our desires to<br />

make this happen.<br />

I feel that it is just like the commodity that gains value from the labor that is put into<br />

the production, which involves giving up the laborer’s hard work to the overall value <strong>of</strong><br />

the commodity, with the producer hoping for a more valuable commodity to be sold in the<br />

market.<br />

Message [173] referenced by [187]. Next Message by Dyoung is [176].<br />

[184] Goethe: graded A Religion for sale, hurry before it is to late! The relationship<br />

between the commodity and Christianity are very similar, and I will explain:<br />

First we need to look at not just Christianity but all organized religion in general; we will<br />

call this “the church”. (I am not being biased against the dominant religion; I am just using<br />

“the church” as a metaphor for all religions)<br />

The church needs to be productive and to create value, this value that the church <strong>of</strong>fers is<br />

on the outside very shiny and beautiful. What could be better than eternal happiness? In the<br />

dark ages <strong>of</strong> Europe it has been stated that the goal <strong>of</strong> the labor <strong>of</strong> men is to achieve salvation.<br />

Not much has changed, the common man who works hard to live a good life (according to<br />

the gospel <strong>of</strong> his chosen faith) strives to achieve the very thing than a man wanted 500 years<br />

ago. But the value desired is not a use value, it is not exchangeable, and it is not easily<br />

measureable. The value is a social value, it is not as it appears. The faithful believers are<br />

willing to give all they have, whether it is in the form <strong>of</strong> money or labor, most times both are<br />

required. And while I am on the subject; the penalties for not giving are eternal damnation,<br />

or worse (you might not get the invite to social activities). But the value here is intangible,<br />

unknown, and based on faith.<br />

The commodity has the same outer value placed on it as the church. We feel that we need<br />

the newest i-pod, or the latest automobile, or even a coat. We will pay whatever we have<br />

to acquire our wants, and even what we don’t have. So, do we really get what we pay for?<br />

Some may say that we get utility from our purchases, but I would argue that utility is an


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 117<br />

illusion. I look at the depth in which Marx has gone to explain the commodity, and like the<br />

church one needs to have faith that Marx is correct. Hans told the story <strong>of</strong> the Emperor’s new<br />

clothes last week; and has been on my mind since then. We are conditioned to believe what<br />

we are told to believe, as long as it makes us feel good about ourselves. When we see that<br />

our reality is not real anymore only then will we reach the next step in human development.<br />

The commodity to me is even more complex then Marx makes it. At this point I am no<br />

expert, but like the boy who noticed that the emperor had no clothes, it may be the novice<br />

or the innocent that will have the ability to see beyond the social aspect <strong>of</strong> reality and open<br />

the eyes <strong>of</strong> everyone. It has been mentioned that the true value <strong>of</strong> a commodity can be found<br />

at the quantum level. I suppose the same could be said <strong>of</strong> religion; but we can in no way<br />

examine these properties that I know <strong>of</strong>.<br />

Conclusion:<br />

Religion is a product that is packaged up real nicely and sold to the public as the answer<br />

to all our needs. Like a commodity the true value is only known to the creator, or producer,<br />

and outer value is determined by society.<br />

Message [184] referenced by [187]. Next Message by Goethe is [185].<br />

[187] Hans: Labor versus money. Dyoung says in [173] that commodity producers have<br />

to work in order to get rewarded by the value <strong>of</strong> their product, just as Christians have to live<br />

up to high standards in this life in order to get rewarded in the next life. This isn’t Marx’s<br />

point. The following sentence by Dyoung explicitly denies the point which Marx tries to<br />

make:<br />

We have learned from Marx that there is a relationship between useful labor<br />

and production which give the commodity its value in the world.<br />

Can you spot what is wrong in this sentence? According to Marx’s theory, value does<br />

not come from useful labor but from abstract labor. Labor is not recognized in its fullness<br />

but it has to go through the purgatory <strong>of</strong> the market, it has to prove that it can be turned<br />

into money, before it counts. In the same way, humans, in Christianity, are not seen in their<br />

fullness, but only in their ability to abstract from certain human traits that are considered<br />

no-no by religion.<br />

When I was a student, before I became a Marxist, I read The Plague by Albert Camus.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the characters in this novel was trying to live like a saint, and his friend, Rieux, told<br />

him: “I am trying to do something much more difficult than you, namely, be fully human.”<br />

(quoted from memory). This is when I decided to leave the church, which in Germany had<br />

the additional benefit that I no longer needed to pay church taxes.<br />

I tried to explain the downsides <strong>of</strong> abstraction in [2005fa:476] but my rant about sexuality<br />

in the second half <strong>of</strong> this submission created so much controversy that the first part tends<br />

to be overlooked. (I thought it would be interesting for you to know that Marxists think<br />

exploitation and oppression in capitalism also has a sexual dimension.)


118 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

As I am writing this, Goethe’s [184] came in. Goethe emphasizes a different aspect <strong>of</strong><br />

religion, not the abstraction. Many things can be said about religion. Prior to this Semester,<br />

the most fruitful discussion was probably in the Fall <strong>of</strong> 2003. Look at my summary<br />

[2003fa:233] <strong>of</strong> the main points made in that discussion.<br />

Message [187] referenced by [203] and [2009fa:306]. Next Message by Hans is [190].<br />

[203] Dentist: the perfectly competitive christian market. In searching the fall 2003<br />

archives to this question in accordance with the advice from Hans [187], I came across the<br />

entry from McRusho [2003fa:193], who <strong>of</strong>fers a quotation from Marx, and Hans’s comments<br />

regarding Mcrusho’s answer; I will draw upon both <strong>of</strong> these for my own answer.<br />

First the Marx quotation which says, “Every religion which is not theirs is an invention<br />

<strong>of</strong> man, while theirs is an emanation from God.” And secondly Hans, who says “Just as<br />

religious proselytizers particularize and competitively push on each other what is ultimately<br />

our shared spirituality, so do commodity traders privatize and push on each other what is<br />

ultimately the product <strong>of</strong> our joint labor.” (if I proceed to misinterpret Hans, I apologize and<br />

am sure he will correct me.)<br />

Within the Christian society exists many different doctrines and many <strong>of</strong> them can conflict<br />

with each other. As a result we now have a “perfectly competitive Christian market,” in<br />

which each denomination produces its own “Christian commodity” from a collection <strong>of</strong><br />

the various doctrines that will not conflict with each other (in theory). These “Christian<br />

commodities” are then taken and proselytized to each <strong>of</strong> us in what appears to be a quest<br />

for monopolistic control over the Christian market. There is essentially a Christian trader<br />

who tries to convince us that he has the one true commodity; that his commodity is the one<br />

“emanation from God” and that all others are an “invention <strong>of</strong> man.”<br />

The problem that lies with this is that ultimately they are trying to sell and resell us on<br />

something we already own, our “common spirituality.” (Which I feel I should point out<br />

here that this commonality is the idea that a savior is needed to obtain salvation). It is this<br />

commonality upon which Christianity exists and therefore cannot do without.<br />

This is comparable to our commodity producing society in that we are continuously being<br />

“proselytized” from traders to accept their commodity. Just as the trader in the Christian<br />

society tries to sell us, so also does this trader. Each goes about “particularizing” the minute<br />

differences between his commodity and the competitors in an attempt to convince us that he<br />

possesses the best <strong>of</strong> all the other commodities within a market, and that any other will be<br />

insufficient for our needs.<br />

As the Christian society ultimately has its shared foundation, so too does the commodity<br />

producing society. Ultimately, it is our combined labor; the factor that each <strong>of</strong> us contributes<br />

to the society and understands is one <strong>of</strong> the essential principles upon which the society is<br />

established and cannot do without.<br />

Hans: Very good. This is the kind <strong>of</strong> deep engagement with a different contribution which everyone has to do<br />

twice in this Semester.<br />

Next Message by Dentist is [208].<br />

[205] Carterryan: Christianity and the commodity relation can be considered similar in<br />

many different ways, one example is that they both need to be “sold” or taught to others. The<br />

commodity needs to be presented and convinced that consumers would need to purchase


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 119<br />

it. Christianity is related to this in that everyone needs a faith to sustain themselves and<br />

people want to have hope and structure for their lives, the different forms <strong>of</strong> Christianity are<br />

comparable to different commodities with the same use value.<br />

Commodities can be either a want or need basis item for some, Christianity can be the<br />

same. People might need for example a blanket to keep warm, others might not need a<br />

blanket but they need a form <strong>of</strong> Christianity in their life to survive. Commodities like the<br />

blanket come in different forms, shapes, sizes. Christianity is the same way in that it comes<br />

in different forms each to conform to one’s personal wants or needs.<br />

Hans: You are basically arguing, people are Christians because it is built into their utility function to be Christians.<br />

This is the kind <strong>of</strong> tautological reductionism which mainstream economics excels in and which this class is trying<br />

to get away from. Sorry for the harsh words, this is not meant personally, it is a critique <strong>of</strong> the education you all are<br />

receiving rather than a critique <strong>of</strong> your own intelligence.<br />

Next Message by Carterryan is [364].<br />

[209] PrivateProperty: Christianity and the Commodity Relation. If we look at the<br />

doctrine <strong>of</strong> Christianity as a commodity (and by doctrine I mean the sum <strong>of</strong> writings and<br />

teachings that Christians study as their religious canon), we can see that there is actually a<br />

lot <strong>of</strong> value imbued in it. It has taken a lot <strong>of</strong> labor to produce the books that comprise the<br />

New and Old Testaments, as well as to translate them over the centuries into The Bible that<br />

we have today. If we take the events depicted in The Bible (assuming they actually occurred)<br />

also as labor, this is even more value imparted to the commodity.<br />

Let me shift gears and address Christianity in a different light, by viewing the individual<br />

as the commodity.<br />

In Capitalism, the producer views a commodity in terms <strong>of</strong> its value, as if it were inherent<br />

in the commodity itself, when in fact the value is ‘brought out’ <strong>of</strong> the commodity through<br />

its exchange relations with other commodities. The producer makes the mistake <strong>of</strong> viewing<br />

every commodity as individualized representations <strong>of</strong> the same thing (value). Marx introduces<br />

a metaphor to show how bizarre this is: “It is as if, besides lions, tigers, hares, and<br />

all other real animals, . . . also the animal existed, the individual incarnation <strong>of</strong> the whole<br />

animal kingdom.”<br />

In Christianity, it is easy to see that God represents this bizarre concept <strong>of</strong> the animal.<br />

Instead <strong>of</strong> being “the individual incarnation <strong>of</strong> the whole animal kingdom”, God is the individual<br />

incarnation <strong>of</strong> the whole human race. In Capitalism it is the producer who makes<br />

this mistake. In Christianity, who would our ‘producers’ be? Well, it would be any Christian<br />

who sees individuals as representative <strong>of</strong> God without looking at their social or ‘exchange’<br />

relations. In reality, it is an individual’s behavior and interaction with his fellow men that<br />

‘brings out’ his or her ‘God-ness’ (perhaps a better word would be ‘divinity’), which is an<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> this person’s value within the Christian economy.<br />

Hans: Your first paragraph is based on a misunderstanding. Being a value and being a product <strong>of</strong> labor are two<br />

completely different things. Only those products <strong>of</strong> labor which wear the labor used up to produce them as an<br />

immaterial garment like the emperor’s new clothes are values. About what you say after you “shift gears” see my<br />

[216].<br />

Message [209] referenced by [216] and [323]. Next Message by PrivateProperty is [221].<br />

Question 300 is 210 in 2000fa and 312 in 2009fa:


120 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Question 300 In the sentence: “[The ancient social production-organisms] are conditioned<br />

by a low stage <strong>of</strong> development <strong>of</strong> the productive powers <strong>of</strong> labor, and by correspondingly<br />

limited relations <strong>of</strong> men within the process <strong>of</strong> creating and reproducing their material life,<br />

hence also between each other and between man and nature,” Marx describes the relationship<br />

between the following three: productive forces (i.e., technology), the relations {2} in the<br />

production process, and social relations {1} at large. Rephrase this relationship in your own<br />

words.<br />

[191] Mitternacht: content A form 95% Marx decides to use the example <strong>of</strong> ancient<br />

social production organisms because it is much simpler to analyze since it does not have all<br />

<strong>of</strong> the layers that are found in bourgeois society.<br />

The laborers in this case are either tied to their species-connection with other men which<br />

Marx calls “immature”, or they are involved in a more direct dominance and servitude relationship.<br />

Felix [2000fa:73] does a great job <strong>of</strong> succinctly explaining that understanding social relations<br />

must begin by first “looking at material conditions or technology”.<br />

The ancient social production organism has a low stage <strong>of</strong> development (limited technology),<br />

which means that production is limited. Since there is limited output, it follows that<br />

there are limited relations between man within the process <strong>of</strong> production. In turn the limited<br />

interaction between man in the production process impacts social relations at large.<br />

Next Message by Mitternacht is [196].<br />

Question 302 is 277 in 2004fa, 272 in 2005fa, 292 in 2007SP, 297 in 2007fa, 300 in<br />

2008fa, 314 in 2009fa, and 342 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 302 Can labor be measured in other ways than in time?<br />

[176] Dyoung: Does Labor = Time. This is a great question that really makes you think.<br />

At first I would have to agree with AJ [2007SP:232] and say Yes because you can measure<br />

labor in opportunity costs <strong>of</strong> workers, by the productivity <strong>of</strong> those workers. But even if you<br />

measure labor this way it comes down to how fast the worker is able to perform the job or<br />

how long it takes, which is where the value or price comes from.<br />

So then I would say No, because labor needs to be measured in time because labor is<br />

paid to the worker based on time spent laboring on the commodity. It has also been said<br />

that perhaps labor can be measured based on effort but I don’t agree with that either because<br />

even if good solid effort is put into labor over a certain item, if I can hire an individual who<br />

can do the same job faster then that first worker wouldn’t have a job any longer. We live in<br />

a society where time is money. Time is king.<br />

However, human labor is very important in Marxian economics, for Marx labor measured<br />

in time is the determinant <strong>of</strong> value in a commodity says Ricky [2007fa:135] who brings up<br />

a great point that one could measure labor in terms <strong>of</strong> output. This makes a lot <strong>of</strong> sense to<br />

me because I labor in an industry where I am strictly paid on commissions so my income is<br />

based on my output <strong>of</strong> goods in a certain month.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 121<br />

Output in my mind is the best way to measure labor but then it comes back to how much<br />

time did I spend trying to produce the output.<br />

Time is the only way to measure labor.<br />

Hans: “Says Ricky who ...” is not a proper construction for written text. Also the sentence starting with “It has<br />

also been said that perhaps ...” should have been broken up at least into two.<br />

You say that the worker’s pay is based on labor time performed. This is not necessarily so, it depends on the<br />

society. Marx says that it is an illusion to think that in capitalism wages are based on labor performed, we will get<br />

to this in the later readings. (It is also an illusion to think capitalism is a meritocracy.)<br />

You bring several interesting points which cry out for more discussion. It’s probably not an accident that your<br />

submission was the start <strong>of</strong> a long conversation.<br />

Message [176] referenced by [158] and [208]. Next Message by Dyoung is [261].<br />

[179] Papageorgio: Labor-time. Marx speaks <strong>of</strong> Labor a lot in the second half <strong>of</strong> 1.4 we<br />

read this week for class. Marx tells us that labor must be measured by time. Labor time is a<br />

very important factor in the deciding the value <strong>of</strong> the product and is the best way to measure<br />

labor. Specifically in concrete or abstract labor time is still the key that we should measure<br />

by. Measure <strong>of</strong> labor helps us to see how much we value anything and specifically say a<br />

commodity. If we value a commodity by how much effort went into it everything would<br />

change it would all depend on who made it, a strong or weak person, etc. Labor-time is<br />

consistent.<br />

Marx helps us see abstractly that labor does not need to be judged by blood, sweat, and<br />

tears. This would be inconsistent and this would be different in different markets and such.<br />

Time is most important to all, the buyer the seller, etc, even the people who create the product<br />

value the time they put into it a great deal.<br />

Marx makes it easy to see that the only way to measure labor is by time.<br />

Hans: Marx does not say that labor “must” be measured in time, but that commodity society treats all labor as<br />

equal and measures it in time. The value <strong>of</strong> the product is not decided by anyone, but the word “value,” as used by<br />

Marx, represents the congealed abstract labor in the product, perhaps [2003fa:133] will be helpful to you. Marx’s<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> value also does not depend on the disutility <strong>of</strong> labor, see my comment to [2004fa:633] and the entire<br />

discussion there.<br />

Next Message by Papageorgio is [180].<br />

[182] Slash: Labor and time go hand and hand. Labor is best measured in time. To<br />

describe labor using other means comes up short <strong>of</strong> measurably. Time is the same no matter<br />

how hard one works, or how back-breaking the labor is during any given time. When a<br />

commodity is produced materials, effort and location can vary, but time can not. One hour<br />

is one hour no matter what is being produced. For the simple reason that time is a constant<br />

and can be measured, all other means <strong>of</strong> measuring fall short.<br />

Time is important to both the producer and the consumer, because <strong>of</strong> this Marx say time<br />

is measurable, and the means by which labor is measured.<br />

Hans: You sound as if Marx picked a practical and relevant measure for labor. When Marx says that labor is<br />

measured in time, he means that the organization <strong>of</strong> production in a commdity society is such that labor is measured<br />

in time. This is not something decided on because it is “best” but it is built into our social structure. Is it really<br />

“best” to ignore how hard the laborer works or how backbreaking the labor is?<br />

People living in this society tend to think it is best because that’s what they are familiar with, and that’s what<br />

fits together with the other institutions in this society. You seem to tacitly assume that all labor must be considered<br />

equal. Commodity society does this, but societies could be set up differently.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [183].


122 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[186] Paul: How to value labor. It is interesting to consider another way to value labor.<br />

You could argue that the intensity in which the labor was performed would have an effect on<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> the labor. For example, if somebody is working in awful conditions and going at<br />

his absolute limit his work should be valued at a higher level than someone who is working<br />

at half the pace he is capable. This makes sense and you would hope that this would be the<br />

case. The fact is that it is impossible to put this kind <strong>of</strong> factor into the value <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

The old saying is that time equals money. Its true and everyone understands that. Everybody<br />

understands the value <strong>of</strong> time and everyone knows that one hour equals 60 minutes.<br />

Time is universally understood, therefore it is the best way to determine the value <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Hans: There are two reasons why one would want to measure labor. Either because one is interested in the value<br />

created by that labor, or because one wants to compute the value <strong>of</strong> labor, i.e., the compensation <strong>of</strong> a wage-laborer.<br />

In Marx’s theory, these two are quantitatively different, i.e., the labor created by the laborer is much greater than<br />

his compensation.<br />

In chapter One, Marx has not yet introduced the wage laborer, therefore he is only talking about the first reason,<br />

the value created by labor, not the value <strong>of</strong> labor. Also the previous answers to question 302 saw it this way. You<br />

are redefining the question and switching to the value <strong>of</strong> labor, i.e., the second reason. This is clearly not what Marx<br />

is talking about. The questions must always be seen in the context <strong>of</strong> Marx’s text.<br />

But your point with the intensity is a good one, even if one only looks at the value-creating capacity <strong>of</strong> labor. In<br />

chapter Seventeen, 660:2/o, Marx says that labor <strong>of</strong> higher intensity is the expenditure <strong>of</strong> more labor per hour. One<br />

might say labor is still measured by time, only the meter runs faster if the intensity is higher.<br />

Message [186] referenced by [188]. Next Message by Paul is [189].<br />

[188] Wade: Certainly labor could be measured in many other ways than in time. But<br />

would it be completely fair? What if someone didn’t have the same capabilities as another,<br />

should they be paid the same amount? Should they be paid on what they produce? Probably,<br />

but what if they don’t have the same capabilities? Let’s say that a mentally retarded man<br />

was working on a labor line, if he can only produce 50 <strong>of</strong> whatever they are producing,<br />

but a gifted man can produce 200, should they be paid the same? You could pay them on<br />

whatever they are producing, but by doing so the mentally retarted man would only make a<br />

fourth as the gifted man would working the same amount <strong>of</strong> time. It is a tough call, it would<br />

work out great if you could pay them according to their abilities and the quality and quantity<br />

<strong>of</strong> what they produce and the amount <strong>of</strong> time they put in, that would be extremely hard to<br />

accomplish. So the safest and most fair manner in most all cases would be to just pay by<br />

good old father time.<br />

Hans: Like Paul [186], you are not looking at the value-creating capacity <strong>of</strong> labor but only on the compensation <strong>of</strong><br />

the wage laborer – although Marx has not even introduced the wage laborer yet.<br />

Message [188] referenced by [200] and [228]. Next Message by Wade is [554].<br />

[200] PrivateProperty: In response to Wade’s [188]: If we’re following a Marxist line<br />

<strong>of</strong> thinking, and we’re talking about congealed abstract labor, then time is the only way to<br />

measure it. For in this case, labor is akin to a standard unit <strong>of</strong> measurement (like a kilogram<br />

or a meter) <strong>of</strong> the expenditure <strong>of</strong> labor-power, and thus time.<br />

It doesn’t follow that we adopt this line <strong>of</strong> thinking when looking at individual production.<br />

A retarded man producing 50 and a gifted man producing 200 should not be paid the same.<br />

Either the retarded man should be fired or the gifted man should be paid more, or both. This<br />

is referring to the compensation <strong>of</strong> the individuals. The actual value that is imparted to these<br />

commodities, however, is something entirely different.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [201].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 123<br />

[208] Dentist: Warning: clichés inside. It seems as though we are in consensus that time<br />

may not be the ONLY way to measure labor, but that under our society it is the simplest,<br />

most constant and therefore best measure. But I have some thoughts as to why this may be<br />

so.<br />

“Time is money” has certainly become quite the cliché and rightly so according to the<br />

principles <strong>of</strong> the society in which we live. In fact I am inclined to believe that money trumps<br />

even time these days, as indicated by the fact that Americans are working more hours per<br />

day and days per year than ever. We are willing to do more to obtain money these days then<br />

we are to retain our time.<br />

Certainly the argument can be made that this is due to necessity and this extra labor is<br />

being spent in order to survive. To one who may make this case I have another cliché, “The<br />

luxuries <strong>of</strong> one generation become the necessities <strong>of</strong> the next.” For instance, even those<br />

considered to be living in poverty these days, the majority still possess “necessities” like<br />

television and cellular phones.<br />

But in getting to the point, perhaps the ideas <strong>of</strong> labor being measured in terms <strong>of</strong> output<br />

or opportunity cost would not be so unrealistic if our society were not so consumed with<br />

consuming (the negative saving rate <strong>of</strong> Americans makes a good example). AJ [2007SP:232]<br />

and Hans [2007SP:243] have some interesting discussion regarding these a ideas and some<br />

<strong>of</strong> their associated problems which Dyoung [176] also seems to touch on.<br />

One problem with measuring according to productivity or output is brought to our attention<br />

by Hans [2007SP:243], which is the issue <strong>of</strong> the learning curve. It would seem possible<br />

to deal with by analyzing the daily output <strong>of</strong> an employee, and plotting them graphically.<br />

Theoretically over time the slope <strong>of</strong> the function would gradually decrease and with time<br />

approach a 0 slope. This would essentially indicate that the learning curve is over and could<br />

give a good starting point for identifying ideal levels <strong>of</strong> production for an individual. Similarly,<br />

taking some averages <strong>of</strong> the time for this to occur with several employees could give<br />

insights into how long we can expect the learning to last.<br />

There is still yet another problem with using opportunity cost or productivity that is also<br />

discussed in the prior references, which is that <strong>of</strong> measuring effort. Although more difficult,<br />

it may be possible if certain conditions are met. For instance happy workers are productive<br />

and therefore more efficient workers. Perhaps a social structure where happiness (or utility)<br />

is not defined by purchasing power, net worth, or sheer consumption, would <strong>of</strong>fer more<br />

incentive to “live to work” rather than “working to live.” This could lead to a shift away<br />

from “the almighty dollar” being valued more than our time, to a more enjoyable and healthy<br />

lifestyle where time is more important than money. I say healthy because money is now<br />

limitless in its quantity, whereas time (speaking individually) is limited. By focusing on the<br />

distribution <strong>of</strong> the finite resource, we are likely to use it more efficiently, gaining more from<br />

it and deriving more true happiness.<br />

I realize the complexity <strong>of</strong> this idea and the problems that would arise such as “necessary<br />

jobs, which people don’t aspire to do,” but I do believe it possible to at least make a decent<br />

argument (which would take more time than appropriate here). I am simply saying that<br />

“where there’s a will, there’s a way.”


124 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

At any rate, I suppose the actual question here is to be taken in the context <strong>of</strong> Marx’s view<br />

and his critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism. And under these conditions, yes time is the best and simplest<br />

measure <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Hans: The capitalist system measures labor very accurately, but its motive is not the saving <strong>of</strong> labor but pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

We cannot yet go into details here in chapter One, but the stage for this is set already now by the fact that an<br />

expenditure, the labor used up in production, takes the form <strong>of</strong> an asset, i.e., the value <strong>of</strong> the product.<br />

Message [208] referenced by [2010fa:106]. Next Message by Dentist is [249].<br />

[219] Hans: This question will not be on Monday’s Exam. Everyone except those<br />

unfortunate souls who have answered question 302 has received a grade now and extensive<br />

commentaries. And I have to rush to the airport to greet Larry Lohmann. Therefore here is<br />

the deal: Installment 1 can be downloaded from<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/l2mo/i1.pdf<br />

or, if you prefer the screen readable version,<br />

http://marx.economics.utah.edu/das-kapital/pdf/screen/i1.pdf<br />

You can also get it from the <strong>University</strong> Copy Center, they will download and print it for<br />

you when you come in. As additional answers come in due to the extra credit assignment,<br />

these URL’s will have the latest updated version. Since question 302 is not commented by<br />

me, it will not be on the Monday exam. But it may be on the Thursday exam, and by this<br />

time my comments will be there.<br />

About the exam, read pages 691-2 in the syllabus. Regarding the extra credit assignment<br />

between now and Sunday 10:45 am, see the paragraph on pp. 677/8 <strong>of</strong> the syllabus.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [228].<br />

[228] Hans: Consensus. Everyone agrees that despite the alternatives time is best, and<br />

some even say that the alternatives come down to time.<br />

None <strong>of</strong> you proposed to make the measurement <strong>of</strong> labor dependent on the kind <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Are 8 hours doing research into an interesting subject really the same as 8 hours scrubbing<br />

floors? From Marx we learn that a commodity society treats all labors as equal. This does<br />

not mean all labors are equal.<br />

Some <strong>of</strong> you did argue on the other hand that distinctions should be made among nonlabor<br />

activities: work which diminishes your leisure time is different from work which diminishes<br />

time with family or which prevents a single mother from caring for her children.<br />

Arguably, caring for children is a contribution to the social good as much or more than<br />

flipping hamburgers in a fast food outlet.<br />

Wade [188] is the only one seeing problems with it that someone who is gifted and talented<br />

and therefore produces more gets higher rewards, although I wish he had made a<br />

stronger point.<br />

None <strong>of</strong> you looked from the labor process from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the worker, as a<br />

process which trains and develops the worker, rather than a process which puts out a product.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 125<br />

Some explicitly said that the measurement <strong>of</strong> labor depends on the society we live in.<br />

I.e., it is not an eternal necessity to do it the way this society does it. Maybe things can be<br />

arranged in a better and fairer manner.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [231].<br />

Question 311 is 301 in 2007SP and 306 in 2007fa:<br />

Question 311 Why does Marx say in footnote 38 to paragraph 177:3–4 that the commodities<br />

diamond, pearl, etc., only seem to possess relativity as exchange-values? Are exchangevalues<br />

not relative by definition?<br />

[175] Bennett: In footnote 36 Marx says that, “(diamonds, pearls, etc.) possess as<br />

exchange-values to the true relation hidden behind this semblance, namely their relativity<br />

as mere expressions <strong>of</strong> human labor”. I think that Marx says this because he believes that<br />

these extravagant commodities such as diamonds and pearls are falsely valued by society.<br />

There is no real reason why these things should be valued and regarded as highly as they are.<br />

In Capital, 177:3–4, Marx says it best, “the use-value <strong>of</strong> material objects belongs to these<br />

objects independently <strong>of</strong> their material properties”. So basically what is the true value <strong>of</strong> a<br />

diamond or a pearl and why have people made these objects inflated commodities? These<br />

commodities only possess high exchange-values because society has given these commodities<br />

high exchange-values but in reality these commodities should have less worth in my<br />

opinion to that <strong>of</strong> something that is hundreds <strong>of</strong> times cheaper but much more important like<br />

food and water and other essentials that support life.<br />

Hans: The reason why pearl and diamond have high values (as Marx uses the word) is that lots <strong>of</strong> labor went into<br />

producing them. Their value is not a measure <strong>of</strong> their usefulness or social importance.<br />

In 177:3–4, Marx is ironic: he assumes that the reader immediately understands that the use-values <strong>of</strong> objects<br />

<strong>of</strong> course depend on their material properties.<br />

Message [175] referenced by [204]. Next Message by Bennett is [347].<br />

[194] Ande: Marx says that “diamond, pearl, etc., only seem to posses relativity as<br />

exchange-values” because there has never been any evidence by chemists or anyone that<br />

these items carry any such exchange-value. They have value, but their value is only what<br />

someone is willing to pay you or trade you for them. They do not carry an exact exchangevalue<br />

in Marx’s terms. As well the use-value <strong>of</strong> these items changes from person to person<br />

because the diamonds’ and pearls’ value will be different from man to man depending on<br />

what each individual thinks they are worth. They have a market exchange value but that is<br />

not a definite set price, things are only worth what someone will pay or trade you for the<br />

particular item. That is why I feel as though marx said “diamond, pearl, etc., only seem to<br />

posses relativity as exchange-values.”<br />

No I do not feel exchange-values are relative by definition, but it becomes confusing<br />

when you talk about market values and exchange-values because a market value is true by<br />

definition, but no an exchange-value is not relative by definition. The reason that they are<br />

not relative is because an exchange-value can differ from person to person and there is no<br />

relative price to an exchange-value, Marx would disagree with me a little bit there but one<br />

has to agree that some people may not want to exchange a good depending on the exchangevalue.<br />

Exchange is seen as a relation between things, but value belongs to that thing. So<br />

each item or person might have a different exchange-value for the item they have and want


126 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

to make a trade with. You can get more for your item in exchange-value terms, than you<br />

can by market value by definition. Although Marx might disagree with me, I feel as though<br />

exchange-values are not truly relative by definition.<br />

Hans: Marx does not think exchange-value is determined by what someone is willing to pay for the thing. It is a<br />

social relation, some things have high exchange-values, others low. The exchange-value <strong>of</strong> a good does not depend<br />

on the individual holding the good.<br />

Next Message by Ande is [195].<br />

[204] Raynold: In response to Bennett [175], my opinion on the reasons why these certain<br />

commodities such as diamonds and pearls are valued so highly is because <strong>of</strong> their worth.<br />

Worth, meaning the efforts it took to obtain it and also its availability to the market. But then<br />

I definitely see where Marx is coming from when he says that these (diamonds and pearls)<br />

are falsely valued by society because society allowed it to have such high exchange-values<br />

when in reality, they don’t do much but blink. These over-rated products (diamonds and<br />

pearls) definitely outweigh the cost <strong>of</strong> human necessitites such as food and drink etc.. We<br />

can see how these high-valued commodities set different standards for classes. The mid to<br />

upper class now have the luxury to show their wealth by their blink, but in actual reality,<br />

this is not useful for more important matters in the world such as sicknesses, food, drink and<br />

other beneficial tools we need to survive.<br />

Hans: Diamonds do much more than just blink, they are extremely hard and indispensable for certain production<br />

processes (oil drilling) because <strong>of</strong> this.<br />

Your main mistake is that you think Bennett in [175] has anything to do with Marx. Your own theory why<br />

diamonds and pearls have high value is much closer to Marx than Bennett’s misinterpretations <strong>of</strong> specific Marx<br />

quotes.<br />

Marx says the values <strong>of</strong> pearl and diamond come from the labor it takes to produce them. The availability <strong>of</strong><br />

the market can create disturbances which may in the short run drive prices away from values, but it does not play a<br />

role for value itself.<br />

Next Message by Raynold is [220].<br />

Multiple Choice Question 313 is 600 in 2000fa and 247 in 2002fa:<br />

Multiple Choice Question 313 Three <strong>of</strong> the following four quotes about the mysterious<br />

character <strong>of</strong> the commodity have been botched up to make them false or senseless. Only one<br />

quote is taken literally from Marx. Which one?<br />

(a) A commodity at first glance seems to be a quite complicated thing, abounding in metaphysical<br />

hairsplitting and theological niceties. But its analysis brings out that it is something<br />

obvious and trivial.<br />

(b) The mystical character <strong>of</strong> the commodity does not arise, therefore, from its use-value. No<br />

more does it spring from the forms <strong>of</strong> the value determination.<br />

(c) To the producers therefore, the social relations between their private labors do not appear<br />

as what they are, i.e., not as direct social relations <strong>of</strong> persons during their labor processes<br />

themselves, but rather as material relations <strong>of</strong> persons and social relations <strong>of</strong> things.<br />

(d) If commodities could speak, they would say this: our use-value may interest humans, but<br />

it does not belong to us as objects. What does belong to us as objects, however, is our value.<br />

[357] Hans: Difficult Multiple Choice. The unaltered Marx quote is (d).<br />

Here are the actual Marx quotes underlying the other items:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 127<br />

(a) 163:3/o At first glance, a commodity seems to be something obvious and trivial. But<br />

its analysis brings out that it is quite complicated, abounding in metaphysical hairsplitting<br />

and theological niceties.<br />

(b) 164:1 The mystical character <strong>of</strong> the commodity does not arise, therefore, from its<br />

use-value. No more does it spring from the content <strong>of</strong> the determinations <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

(c) 165:2/o To the producers therefore, the social relations between their private labors<br />

appear as what they are, i.e., not as direct social relations <strong>of</strong> persons during their labor processes<br />

themselves, but rather as material relations <strong>of</strong> persons and social relations <strong>of</strong> things.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [415].<br />

Question 318 is 173 in 1995WI, 150 in 1995ut, 183 in 1996sp, 196 in 1997WI, 203 in<br />

1997sp, 295 in 2004fa, 316 in 2008fa, 358 in 2010fa, 337 in 2011fa, and 352 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 318 Explain in your own words Marx’s phrase that the commodity owners’ will<br />

“resides” in the objects which are his property.<br />

Is this a good thing or not? Where does it have its limits in our society? Are there things for<br />

which it is desirable that people’s wills reside in them?<br />

[255] Ryoung: Thinking For Property? Marx states that the commodity owner’s will<br />

resides in objects which are his property. At first thought this is a simple idea and is easy to<br />

understand when thinking upon another thought by Marx that said the commodity can not<br />

walk itself to the market. For me this thought by Marx puts the answer to this question in<br />

simple terms. A commodity does not have the ability to walk, talk, act, or think for itself.<br />

This goes to say that in order for a commodity to function it must receive help, in one way<br />

or another, from its owner.<br />

Most commodities came to pass with a certain function that they were to perform. In<br />

order for this function to perform, for good or for bad, the owner must take action to help<br />

it out. For example in order for an alarm clock to function properly, the owner must set the<br />

alarm for a certain time in order for the alarm to sound so that the owner may arise at his/her<br />

desired time. It is the will <strong>of</strong> its owner that determines to which degree the alarm clock<br />

functions.<br />

I believe that this is a good thing as it helps the human race function at a more efficient<br />

rate in the case <strong>of</strong> the alarm clock. However it also depends on the will <strong>of</strong> the owner in<br />

order to determine if this certain commodity simplifies human life or function to its desired<br />

purpose. With all the commodities that this world has to <strong>of</strong>fer I believe that there is always<br />

the potential for the owner’s will to reside within the commodity but whether it is desirable<br />

or not depends on the will <strong>of</strong> the owner. Much <strong>of</strong> this desirability depends on how the owner<br />

uses his will and free agency. This may or may not be desirable depending on the owner.<br />

Hans: Wherever you say “commodity” in the above example, you mean “use-value.” You do not at all refer to the<br />

exchange-relations which make this use-value a commodity. This is the wrong use <strong>of</strong> the word “commodity.”<br />

Message [255] referenced by [269] and [2010fa:392]. Next Message by Ryoung is [350].<br />

[269] Hans: Property Thinking for Us. The alarm clock in Ryoung’s [255] is an excellent<br />

example <strong>of</strong> someone depositing his will into a thing. You sleep deeply, you certainly do


128 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

not want to get up, but rrrrg says the alarm clock, shaking you out <strong>of</strong> your sleep, all because<br />

you set it the night before. The alarm clock is executing your will against you.<br />

Despite the ingenuity <strong>of</strong> Ryoung’s example, this is not what Marx means by the commodity<br />

owner’s will residing in the commodity, for two reasons:<br />

(1) Marx uses the word “commodity,” not “use-value.” I.e., he does not refer to the usevalue<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity, but to those relations which make it a commodity: its exchange<br />

relations, private ownership, value.<br />

(2) The transfer <strong>of</strong> the will to the commodity is not a deliberate act on the part <strong>of</strong> the owner<br />

like the setting <strong>of</strong> an alarm clock, but the owner finds himself as the captive <strong>of</strong> the commodity’s<br />

exchange relations. Think <strong>of</strong> it this way: someone steps on the commodity (i.e.,<br />

violates the commodity’s exchange relations) and the owner says “ouch.” In [2007SP:723]<br />

I said that by <strong>of</strong>fering its body to the owner as a residence for his will the commodity acts<br />

passive-aggressively, because this is a vehicle for the commodity to get its owner to do what<br />

it wants.<br />

Someone critical <strong>of</strong> capitalism might expect this to be a bad thing; after all, this is the<br />

mechanism by which the commodities get people to do things which are not in the interest<br />

<strong>of</strong> the people but <strong>of</strong> the commodities. But without it, things may not get the necessary care<br />

and be wasted. As I already mentioned in [1997sp:170], the Soviet-Union type socialist<br />

countries were littered with unfinished investment projects, begun by one administration<br />

under one 5-year-plan, but the next administration lost interest and the project simply was<br />

never finished.<br />

Another situation where it would be a good thing if people invested their will more into<br />

an object is global warming. As I said in [71], the willful destruction <strong>of</strong> the environment is<br />

far the greatest expropriation ever, it impoverishes all <strong>of</strong> us. Yet there is not enough urgent<br />

action or public outcry as Ande observed in [195]. Is it because people do not feel that part<br />

<strong>of</strong> their property, which they own and have a right to, is stolen from them?<br />

Message [269] referenced by [2010fa:389] and [2012fa:446]. Next Message by Hans is [273].<br />

Question 320 is 297 in 2004fa, 290 in 2005fa, and 315 in 2007fa:<br />

Question 320 Explain the difference between personal and private property.<br />

[266] Matt: Personal vs Private Property. As stated in the annotations, personal property<br />

is part <strong>of</strong> your person (TV’s, Cars, clothes, iPOD). They give you the right to exclude<br />

others from using these personal things since they are part <strong>of</strong> your person. As Hans states<br />

in [2005fa:767] no one has the right to take them away from you, giving you the right to<br />

exclude others from it.<br />

Private property on the other hand is a social relationship, not a relationship between person<br />

and thing according to Marx. It’s the form personal property takes in a society driven by<br />

capitalism itself. Private property draws the meaning <strong>of</strong> respect, giving the notion that we<br />

must respect the property <strong>of</strong> others. This respect Marx speaks <strong>of</strong> is relative because we become<br />

‘protectors’ or ‘guardians’ <strong>of</strong> our own commodities. We then claim these commodities<br />

as private property and ensure as guardians that there is fair and equal exchange.<br />

Message [266] referenced by [275] and [290]. Next Message by Matt is [272].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 129<br />

[275] Hans: Personal property is not the only form <strong>of</strong> property. I consider [2005fa:767]<br />

to be “the” right answer to this question. This answer is referenced by Matt [266], but Matt is<br />

not critical enough <strong>of</strong> private property. Therefore here is an answer which makes the Marxist<br />

critique <strong>of</strong> private property more explicit:<br />

Personal property are those things for which the legal concept <strong>of</strong> private property is appropriate,<br />

i.e., those things from which people should have the right to exclude others, such<br />

as your clothes, your toothbrush, etc. In a capitalist society, factories and other large-scale<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production are private property, although they are clearly not personal property.<br />

Property relations appropriate to large-scale means <strong>of</strong> production would either be that they<br />

are collectively owned by the workers, or that they are owned by everyone, with the workers<br />

entrusted to run them for the good <strong>of</strong> everyone. Making them private property institutionalizes<br />

the class divisions in capitalist society, in which a small elite, by controlling the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production, are able to appropriate the fruit <strong>of</strong> the labor <strong>of</strong> the majority <strong>of</strong> the population.<br />

Message [275] referenced by [289]. Next Message by Hans is [322].<br />

[289] Dentist: What’s mine is yours, and yours is mine. The question placed before us<br />

for us to identify the difference between personal and private property. Rather than trying to<br />

assemble various examples <strong>of</strong> personal and private property, I think what we are supposed<br />

to see is that ultimately, private property in so far as it is defined within capitalism is a myth<br />

and creates negative effects on society.<br />

What Hans [275] has identified, is a fallacy in their relationship. Personal property are<br />

those things which we should, and correctly do have the right to exclude others from, regardless<br />

<strong>of</strong> the social structure. These are the objects that are necessary and productive to<br />

us individually and not as a collective society. This statement can be (or should be) equally<br />

interchangeable with “private property.” However, under capitalism we have things that are<br />

legally declared to be “private Property,” yet they do not fit this definition. The classic<br />

examples which Hans [275] illustrates are the factories and various means <strong>of</strong> large-scale<br />

production that are clearly not productive at an individual level.<br />

In the suggested archive reference, Hans [2005fa:767] says “Private property is the form<br />

that personal property takes in capitalist society.” I find this to be quite thought provoking and<br />

from it have come to the conclusion that personal property is real whereas private property<br />

is something that is not (any more at least). I believe Hans is saying, along with Marx that<br />

private property should be equal to personal property, but capitalism has somehow been able<br />

to add an asterisk to “private property” and redefine it; Thereby creating the opportunity to<br />

quietly and subtly remove private property from its equilibrium with personal property.<br />

Looking past this glorified slight <strong>of</strong> hand trick should reveal some enlightenment into the<br />

deceptions and exploitations that exist within the capitalist system. When we see that this<br />

equilibrium has been destroyed unknowingly to the population at large, Marx’s argument <strong>of</strong><br />

the deceived and exploited nature <strong>of</strong> the society at large becomes more readily understood<br />

and easily visible.<br />

Next Message by Dentist is [303].<br />

[290] Wasatch: personal and private property. Personal property is something that<br />

has a relation between itself and a person. The owner <strong>of</strong> this commodity is the keeper or


130 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

guardian <strong>of</strong> the commodity, as Hans writes on page 206. Personal property is a commodity<br />

that a person is not required to share with society. It is his to do whatever he wants with it.<br />

Private property is a commodity (or personal property) that is exchanged for another’s<br />

property.<br />

An example <strong>of</strong> personal property would be your personal car (you can do whatever you<br />

want with this car and no one can take it from you or tell you what to do with it) and an<br />

example <strong>of</strong> private property would be your car while you are trading it for a person’s cattle.<br />

While you are using it as a “means to access” another person’s property.<br />

Hans: Do you consider yourself the guardian <strong>of</strong> your clothes? “Guardian” or “keeper” means that the thing is in<br />

the foreground, not the person. This is applicable to private property, not personal property. Matt [266] had it right,<br />

compare also the Annotations where this word is used, 178:1/o.<br />

Grade penalty because you didn’t say how your submission relates to the three earlier submissions. For instance,<br />

I don’t know if you are even aware that Matt’s use <strong>of</strong> “guardian” is different from yours.<br />

Next Message by Wasatch is [293].<br />

[581] Bennett: Personal Property Take 2. The most important distinction between<br />

personal and private property is that others (society) must respect your property. This respect<br />

from everybody else in society makes your personal property, private. Society cannot use<br />

these commodities without your permission. With your personal property (jewelry, cell<br />

phone, house, etc.) you are the only person that has the right to let others use these things<br />

if you so choose, this ability to have this ownership <strong>of</strong> these commodities makes them your<br />

private property. Having personal ownership <strong>of</strong> commodities gives you the ability to trade<br />

for the use <strong>of</strong> others private property as well. You must have property to exchange with them<br />

in order to use their private property. According to Hans having your own private property<br />

is “the means to access others’ property.”<br />

Next Message by Bennett is [648].<br />

[584] Hans: Personal Property a Subset <strong>of</strong> Private Property. Your private property are<br />

those things which you are allowed to use for yourself, and nobody else is allowed to use<br />

them without your permission. Your personal property are a subset <strong>of</strong> your private property:<br />

they are the things which by their nature warrant such exclusive use by you because they are<br />

an extension <strong>of</strong> your person, such as your toothbrush or your clothes or your home.<br />

Marxists are critical <strong>of</strong> private property because certain things which are not an extension<br />

<strong>of</strong> your person but which, on the contrary, can only be used socially, such as factories, can<br />

nevertheless be the private property <strong>of</strong> someone. Why should someone have the right to<br />

exclude others from resources which he cannot use for himself? As a bargaining chip in<br />

order to get access to resources privately controlled by the others. Marxists think this is<br />

legalized extortion.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [585].<br />

Question 322 is 174 in 1995WI, 153 in 1995ut, 186 in 1996sp, 206 in 1997sp, 207 in<br />

1998WI, 292 in 2005fa, 312 in 2007SP, 320 in 2008fa, and 356 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 322 Which social relations must exist between producers so that they will exchange<br />

(or buy and sell) their products as commodities? Describe groups or societies which<br />

have social relations which preclude exchange between individual members.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 131<br />

[852] PrivateProperty: The Commodity Relation. Marx spends a significant portion <strong>of</strong><br />

Capital discussing the commodity as the central unit <strong>of</strong> capitalism, and for good reason. The<br />

commodity is the basis for social relations in a capitalist society, and does not simply allow,<br />

but necessitates the production and exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities on the market.<br />

Products were (and still are, in some places) exchanged on a group level rather than<br />

amongst individuals. A striking example <strong>of</strong> this occurs amongst Native American tribes,<br />

where goods such as horses and food are brokered between groups through tribe Chiefs,<br />

rather than amongst individuals. In these systems, the means <strong>of</strong> production (such as land)<br />

belonged to the entire community, and were not conceptualized as property. This is arguably<br />

a form <strong>of</strong> communism, though inefficient and highly fragmented.<br />

When private property is enforced by means <strong>of</strong> institutions, de facto and/or de jure, then<br />

the commodity arises. The commodity becames a vehicle for value, and demands to be<br />

exchanged for other commodities.<br />

The commodity relation provides the framework from which producers must operate.<br />

Producers desire to reap as much value as possible from the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities, and<br />

thus establish a control over the means <strong>of</strong> production and employ workers to produce output.<br />

This is the social relation between producers that allows the exchange <strong>of</strong> their products.<br />

In [2007SP:312] Fenix writes that the behavior <strong>of</strong> producers is regulated by law. However,<br />

this is completely misleading as regulations are a reflection <strong>of</strong> capitalist institutions to<br />

begin with. Laws are created to protect the interests <strong>of</strong> de facto powers. It’s called political<br />

economy, and it determines everything.<br />

Message [852] referenced by [2008fa:485]. Next Message by PrivateProperty is [868].<br />

Question 325 is 302 in 2004fa, 295 in 2005fa, and 320 in 2007fa:<br />

Question 325 Do the persons represent commodities because they are commodity owners,<br />

or are they commodity owners because they represent commodities?<br />

[265] Rey: graded A Commodity....Represent!!! In a capitalist system a person represents<br />

a commodity because they are the owner <strong>of</strong> that commodity. The representing <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity is a social relation and only appears once ownership <strong>of</strong> a commodity is recognized.<br />

This is illustrated by Marx when he says, “Individuals remain strangers to each other<br />

and only enter into ‘scratch your back’ relations” when seeking the exchange <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

Further elaborating Marx states, “people relate to others not first and foremost as people<br />

but first and foremost as property owners.” Marx feels social views are due to the economic<br />

systems.<br />

In discussing capitalism it is easy to see when viewing things from Marx’s perspective<br />

why one would be seen first and foremost as a commodity representative. The majority <strong>of</strong><br />

focus in a capitalistic system is on the accumulation <strong>of</strong> commodities, thus if one is always<br />

focused on accumulation <strong>of</strong> commodities one will constantly be viewing others simply as<br />

the commodity representative. The idea that this social relation is a product <strong>of</strong> the social<br />

system gives Marx a great deal <strong>of</strong> hope that individuals can see others in a more “humane”<br />

light given a change in the system.


132 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

This idea <strong>of</strong> this social view being a product <strong>of</strong> systems is also illustrated in Marx’s<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> juridical policies. Only in a capitalist society, where laws are centered on<br />

private property, can this social role even exist. If individuals are able to take commodities<br />

at will, there would be no reason to recognize anyone as a commodity owner and this social<br />

role would cease to exist. Thus we see that the reason individuals take on the social role <strong>of</strong><br />

a commodity representative, in a capitalistic system, is because they are the owners <strong>of</strong> that<br />

commodity.<br />

Hans: The quotes which you attribute to Marx are really my interpretation <strong>of</strong> Marx. Only the two-column text in<br />

German and English is from Marx himself.<br />

Message [265] referenced by [273]. Next Message by Rey is [291].<br />

[273] Hans: Both are Right. Rey’s answer [265] seems very reasonable:<br />

Individuals take on the social role <strong>of</strong> a commodity representative, in a capitalistic<br />

system, because they are the owners <strong>of</strong> that commodity.<br />

But Marx says in 178:1/o:<br />

The persons exist here for one another only as representatives <strong>of</strong> commodities,<br />

therefore as commodity owners.<br />

This wording indicates that being a representative <strong>of</strong> commodities comes first. Marx<br />

seems to say that we are commodity owners because we are representatives <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Marx’s answer is the opposite <strong>of</strong> Rey’s answer because Marx looks at the social relations<br />

as a whole. In Marx’s theory, the ultimate reason why the laws <strong>of</strong> private property exist<br />

is that they provide the legal framework which enables people to treat their products as<br />

commodities. Rey, on the other hand, looks at it from an individual point <strong>of</strong> view: individuals<br />

who find themselves in this legal framework are therefore motivated to treat their private<br />

property as commodities.<br />

Not only the laws regulating our behavior but also many other things in our society are<br />

as they are because this is a capitalist society. Capitalism has truly penetrated into every<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> our lives. This is by no means a benign state <strong>of</strong> affairs, as I tried to explain in<br />

[2007fa:304].<br />

Next Message by Hans is [275].<br />

Question 327 is 301 in 2005fa:<br />

Question 327 Marx writes that the commodities which the owners take to market are eager<br />

to exchange not only their souls but also their bodies. What would it look like if they only<br />

exchanged their souls and not their bodies?<br />

[288] Bmellor: Souls and bodies. In the last paragraph before the question there is a<br />

clarification <strong>of</strong> what Marx is talking about. In this paragraph it is explained that when Marx<br />

says “exchanged not only soul but body” is a sexual analogy. I am clarifying because if you<br />

have not read this part <strong>of</strong> the annotations it might seem a bit odd that I bring up prostitutes.<br />

Prostitutes are individuals that would perform sexual acts with whomever regardless; they<br />

deal mainly with the body exchange. Now on the other side the side that deals with the<br />

soul would be a person that interacts on a level where they share in life experiences. Such a


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 133<br />

person would be like a psychiatrist. They share with you in your life experiences. Or maybe<br />

a leader in the church with which you belong. These would be relationships or interpersonal<br />

interactions, where people are dealing with you on a “soul exchange” perhaps you bear your<br />

soul to them and they return back their feelings to you.<br />

A market system where individuals exchanged their souls and not their bodies would<br />

be one, where the car manufacturer produces a safe automobile because they are earnestly<br />

concerned for the safety <strong>of</strong> the consumer. Rather than producing an automobile that is forced<br />

to meet specific government regulations, in a means most pr<strong>of</strong>itable. In such a system there<br />

would be an influx <strong>of</strong> social entrepreneurs where people would provide a good or service for<br />

a community - this good or service is perhaps non-pr<strong>of</strong>it or less pr<strong>of</strong>itable, but yet society<br />

needs the good or service. Debt counseling services would be an example.<br />

Hans: Safe automobiles is an excellent example for what my [2005fa:811] tried to describe in general. Wholesome<br />

food comes to mind as well, as opposed to food that is sugared up to taste good, without regard <strong>of</strong> the health <strong>of</strong> the<br />

eater other than government regulations.<br />

Next Message by Bmellor is [399].<br />

Question 330 is 176 in 1995WI, 154 in 1995ut, 187 in 1996sp, 189 in 1996ut, 200 in<br />

1997WI, 207 in 1997sp, 199 in 1997ut, 208 in 1998WI, 228 in 2000fa, 241 in 2001fa, 273<br />

in 2003fa, 328 in 2008fa, 342 in 2009fa, 349 in 2011fa, and 365 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 330 In chapter Two, Marx depicts commodities as conscious beings which are<br />

eager to be exchanged, but do not care about the use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity they are exchanged<br />

for. Why are commodities, which are inanimate things, depicted here as beings with<br />

their own will, and why do they not care about the use-value <strong>of</strong> the other commodity?<br />

[848] Bmellor: Commodities are given behavioral traits because an owner <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

does not have control over its price or exchange value. This is definitely present in a<br />

perfect competition market: those involved in the competitive industry are price takers, and<br />

in chapter Two Marx explains how the commodity doesn’t care about its use-value but <strong>of</strong><br />

course the owner does. The owner is holding back the commodity from exchanging itself for<br />

something completely useless. If the owner doesn’t receive something useful then he will<br />

not exchange what he has.<br />

The reason that we have this conflict between owner and commodity is that in its basic<br />

form the commodity will leave the owner even with no exchange taking place. What does<br />

that mean, are cars going to get up and drive themselves away from a dealership? No, but<br />

someone might steal them. And in essence the commodity is leaving without having made<br />

an exchange. That is why the owner is depicted as restraining the commodity, because there<br />

is always a possibility that the commodity will leave the owner with nothing <strong>of</strong> value in its<br />

place.<br />

Hans: You say “in chapter Two Marx explains how the commodity doesn’t care about its use-value but <strong>of</strong> course<br />

the owner does” but you are not giving this explanation. Why do commodities not care about use-value? Actually<br />

you had “value” instead <strong>of</strong> “use-value” but I fixed that, because in Marx’s metaphor commodities do care about<br />

values.<br />

Your explanation why the commodity owner “restrains” the commodity is creative, but I did not mean “protect<br />

from theft” when I wrote “restrain” in [2003fa:741], or Ajax in [1998WI:199]. A “restraint” is necessary because<br />

for the commodity-owner’s taste the commodity is too eager to exchange itself. The owner has to restrain the<br />

commodity from making an exchange with another commodity whose use-value he does not like.


134 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Bmellor is [875].<br />

Question 333 is 303 in 2005fa, 331 in 2008fa, 345 in 2009fa, and 367 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 333 Marx seems to enjoy the play <strong>of</strong> words that immediately, a commodity does<br />

not have immediate use-value for its owner. Explain what he means by this.<br />

[854] Samantha: A sundial in the Shade. Marx is not presenting a contradiction in his<br />

two uses <strong>of</strong> the phrase use-value. First Marx states that use-value is the ability to use the<br />

product, a sundial in the sun shows the owner the time immediately its use value evident.<br />

However in his second use <strong>of</strong> use-value he is describing a use value specific to exchange<br />

meaning that <strong>of</strong> the producer. Though the object has an use-value, it can not immediate have<br />

the value the producer would like for the object. Think <strong>of</strong> a sundial in the shade, the sundial<br />

still has a use-value but it is not able to immediately fulfill the purpose its producer designed<br />

it for, except that in Marx’s theory it is specific to exchanging goods for its owner. As Ernesto<br />

mentions in [2005fa:744], quantity also factors into this equation, a person really only needs<br />

so many sundials and so when mass produced they no longer have the same use-value to<br />

the producer, but on exchange regain their immediate use value. This does not account for a<br />

product produced solely to be exchanged but for a more community centered excess.<br />

Hans: If you say that on exchange, commodities regain their immediate use-value, then you are also implying that<br />

their use-value as a means <strong>of</strong> exchange is not an “immediate” use-value. This is what I tried to say in [2005fa:752].<br />

First Message by Samantha is [55].<br />

[883] Wade: Immediate Use-Value. A commodity is made to be exchanged for other<br />

commodities that may be use-values to the producer. The producer makes commodities but<br />

he doesn’t have a use-value for all <strong>of</strong> them immediately, he is producing the commodities for<br />

the gain <strong>of</strong> other commodities or use-values that he may need immediately or that he may<br />

have the use-value for in the future. A great example would be a blacksmith; he labors all<br />

day producing horse shoes, but only has two horses with 4 ho<strong>of</strong>s each, so he only has the<br />

use-value <strong>of</strong> 8 horseshoes. But he has needs <strong>of</strong> commodities such as clothes, tools, and so<br />

on. The Blacksmith doesn’t have an immediate use-value for all <strong>of</strong> the horseshoes, but once<br />

his horses need a replacement on a shoe or he needs a new set <strong>of</strong> work boots the use-value<br />

<strong>of</strong> those horseshoes is immediate.<br />

Hans: In colloquial English, the word “immediately” is used in a temporal sense, meaning “right now.” Marx uses<br />

this word in its original meaning, it means “direct” or “without mediation.” Perhaps now my [2005fa:752] is easier<br />

to understand.<br />

Next Message by Wade is [900].<br />

[891] Rampton: Commodity doesn’t have immediate use-value. Marx writes that<br />

in capitalism “commodities must be realised as values before they can be realised as use<br />

values.” I take this to mean that in capitalism access to use values is mediated or impeded<br />

by values - monetary and labor-time. When someone buys a commodity it will not have<br />

immediate use value until the commodity is used and made use <strong>of</strong>. His commodity possesses<br />

for himself no immediate use-value. Otherwise, he would not bring it to the market. It has<br />

use-value for others; but for himself its only direct use-value is that <strong>of</strong> being a depository <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange value, and consequently, a means <strong>of</strong> exchange. Therefore, he makes up his mind<br />

to part with it for commodities whose value in use is <strong>of</strong> service to him. All commodities are<br />

non-use-values for their owners, and use-values for their non-owners. Consequently, they<br />

must all change hands. But this change <strong>of</strong> hands is what constitutes their exchange, and the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 135<br />

latter puts them in relation with each other as values, and realises them as values. Hence<br />

commodities must be realised as values before they can be realised as use-values.<br />

Hans: If someone buys a commodity, then it will usually be a commodity which has immediate use-value for him.<br />

Only the commodities he sells do not have immediate use-value for him. You are required to attribute and quote all<br />

Marx quotes.<br />

First Message by Rampton is [500].<br />

Question 334 is 346 in 2009fa and 354 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 334 First Marx says that the commodity has no immediate use-value for its owner.<br />

Then he says that its immediate use-value is that <strong>of</strong> serving as a means <strong>of</strong> exchange. Aren’t<br />

these two statements contradictory? Does or doesn’t have the commodity an immediate<br />

use-value?<br />

[860] Jenn: graded A “means <strong>of</strong> exchange” is not a use-value. I believe Marx brings<br />

up this supposedly contradictory statement to make a point, as he <strong>of</strong>ten does. In order to<br />

meet the criteria for a definition <strong>of</strong> a commodity, it can be <strong>of</strong> no use-value to its owner.<br />

Additionally, it must have use-value to its non-owner. When Marx says its “immediate usevalue”<br />

is serving as a means <strong>of</strong> exchange, not that its use value is a means <strong>of</strong> exchange. It<br />

is a subtle yet important change in verbage, probably just because he loves to do this to get<br />

people to further scrutinize his definitions.<br />

The commodity itself has value because it contains labor. It has exchange-value on the<br />

market. It does not however, have use-value for the owner until after the exchange has<br />

already taken place. The use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is in its natural form in which the<br />

owner will actually use it for, its raison d’etre. Commodities must be realized as values<br />

before they can be realized as use-values, and the realization <strong>of</strong> value does not occur until<br />

after the exchange process has taken place. Marx wants to point out the skin-deep argument<br />

that a “means <strong>of</strong> exchange” can be a use-value is really not a valid argument.<br />

Message [860] referenced by [2009fa:462]. First Message by Jenn is [16].<br />

Question 336 is 331 in 2007fa, 350 in 2009fa, 360 in 2011fa, 373 in 2012fa, and 360 in<br />

Answer:<br />

Question 336 Is it true that exchange is the ultimate pro<strong>of</strong> that a commodity is useful? What<br />

if the consumer who acquires the commodity in exchange takes it home and discovers that it<br />

is not useful after all?<br />

[858] Inter: Discovery <strong>of</strong> Uselessness: Continuation from fall <strong>of</strong> 2007. I would like<br />

to continue the discussion which took place in the fall <strong>of</strong> 2007. After an array <strong>of</strong> answers,<br />

Hans states in [2007fa:316]:<br />

“In the original formulation <strong>of</strong> the question I had a much more trivial usecase<br />

in mind. Assume the consumer who acquires the commodity in exchange<br />

takes it home and discovers that it is not useful after all. Does this<br />

make the labor that produced the good socially unnecessary, even though<br />

the product was sold? This still has not been resolved.”<br />

It is at this juncture that I would like to attempt to resolve the question that Hans posed.


136 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

To simply answer the question, yes this makes the labor that produced the good socially<br />

unnecessary. Marx states in 179:2 that “only their exchange can prove whether that labor is<br />

useful for others, i.e., whether its product satisfies the needs <strong>of</strong> others.” In other words, if<br />

a product does not satisfy the needs <strong>of</strong> others because it has been discovered that it is not<br />

useful, then the labor that produced that commodity was socially unnecessary.<br />

Furthermore Marx states at the beginning <strong>of</strong> section 2.2.b that commodities exchange<br />

hands because they have use-value for their non-owners. It is my interpretation that if it is<br />

later discovered that the commodity did not have this use-value which initiated the exchange,<br />

then the labor that went into to producing the commodity, which lacks use-value, is socially<br />

unnecessary.<br />

Message [858] referenced by [874] and [887]. First Message by Inter is [148].<br />

[874] Clayon: Re: Discovery <strong>of</strong> Uselessness: Continuation from fall <strong>of</strong> 2007. I agree<br />

with Inter’s analysis in [858] that a good that does not have a use-value for anyone, is socially<br />

unnecessary. But as long as someone has a use value for it, it will be exchanged. Thus we<br />

can say that it is true, “that exchange is the ultimate pro<strong>of</strong> that a commodity is useful.” For<br />

even when a consumer acquires a commodity and takes it home only to discover that it is not<br />

useful to him, he can still make use <strong>of</strong> the commodity by exchanging it yet again (assuming<br />

that someone as a use-value for it). Aristotle’s quote in annotations highlights the dual nature<br />

and value <strong>of</strong> every object:<br />

“for tw<strong>of</strong>old is the use <strong>of</strong> every object... The one is peculiar to the object as<br />

such, the other is not, as a sandal which may be worn and is also exchangeable.<br />

both are uses <strong>of</strong> the sandal, for even he who exchanges the sandal for<br />

the money or food he is in need <strong>of</strong>, makes use <strong>of</strong> the sandal as a sandal. But<br />

not in its natural way. For it does not exist for the sake <strong>of</strong> being exchanged.”<br />

A commodity will not be exchanged if there is no use-value for it.<br />

Message [874] referenced by [Answer:14], [887], and [2011fa:514]. Next Message by Clayon is [897].<br />

[876] Carterryan: The Art <strong>of</strong> Exchange. Exchange is the ultimate pro<strong>of</strong> that a commodity<br />

is useful because exchange is more for a personal use and satisfies personal needs.<br />

Exchange just takes a commodity that the first person has that they do not need as much as<br />

the commodity that they are exchanging for.<br />

If the person takes it home and realizes that they no longer need that commodity then the<br />

use value had just declined for the user. The value may still be there for another person in a<br />

new exchange, but the value for the first person has changed. So the overall outcome <strong>of</strong> the<br />

exchange tells you if the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> the exchange is useful.<br />

Message [876] referenced by [Answer:14], [887], and [2011fa:514]. First Message by Carterryan is [50].<br />

[887] Hans: Necessary Enough. If a consumer buys a gadget and after taking it home<br />

discovers that she cannot use it, then Inter [858] says that the labor producing the gadget<br />

was not socially necessary. Clayon [874] says that the labor producing the gadget was still<br />

socially necessary, because the consumer can exchange the gadget for something else. And<br />

Carterryan [876], if I understand him right, says that the labor producing the gadget was<br />

socially necessary only if the consumer can find someone who exchanges the gadget for<br />

something she can really use.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 137<br />

My own take on this question is that the labor producing the gadget has passed the test<br />

<strong>of</strong> being socially necessary in the moment the gadget is sold. Perhaps this is easiest to<br />

see if the consumer has no option to exchange the gadget for something different. If the<br />

consumer discovers that she does not need the gadget, that’s too bad for her, but that’s her<br />

private matter. From the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the society, the labor producing the gadget has<br />

been vindicated as socially necessary the minute the gadget was sold to her.<br />

Here are some other examples: assume the consumer thinks she needs the gadget but she<br />

really doesn’t. Is the labor going into the gadget socially necessary in this case? Yes it is.<br />

Assume we live in the 1950s and the cigarette companies have successfully kept the<br />

adverse health effects <strong>of</strong> cigarettes a secret. If a person buys cigarettes who would never<br />

have touched cigarettes had she known the detrimental health effects <strong>of</strong> cigarettes, then the<br />

labor going into producing the cigarettes is still socially necessary.<br />

“Socially necessary” labor is not labor that is ultimately necessary from the elevated point<br />

<strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the Last Judgment, but it is labor which passes the test for being a legitimate<br />

member in the social division <strong>of</strong> labor as far as our society goes. The sale <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

is exactly this test.<br />

Message [887] referenced by [2009fa:844]. First Message by Hans is [3].<br />

Question 337 is 178 in 1995WI, 156 in 1995ut, 189 in 1996sp, 202 in 1997WI, 201 in<br />

1997ut, 265 in 2002fa, 278 in 2003fa, and 375 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 337 Which contradictions do commodity owners face if they want to barter their<br />

products (as opposed to buying and selling them)? Make up imaginary dialogs on the market<br />

place in which these contradictions are expressed.<br />

[897] Clayon: When bartering their products, commodity owners face the contradiction<br />

between the individual dimension, and the social dimension. They want to be able to<br />

exchange their good for a commodity that will satisfy their use-value needs (This is the individual<br />

dimension). At the same time however, he wants credit for his commodity according<br />

to its value, whether or not it has use-value for the recipient (the social dimension). These<br />

two ideas contradict each other because if the second statement holds true, it means that<br />

exchange will be based upon the value and not the use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity. This forces<br />

one to accept an <strong>of</strong>fer that perhaps has less use-value to him.<br />

Next Message by Clayon is [898].<br />

Exam Question 338 is 180 in 1995WI, 191 in 1996sp, 204 in 1997WI, 211 in 1997sp, 203<br />

in 1997ut, 221 in 1999SP, 231 in 2000fa, 279 in 2003fa, 313 in 2004fa, 328 in 2007SP,<br />

352 in 2009fa, 381 in 2010fa, 363 in 2011fa, 377 in 2012fa, and 191 in Answer:<br />

Exam Question 338 Which “deed” is Marx referring to in the following passage: “In their<br />

dilemma our commodity-owners think like Faust: ‘In the beginning was the deed.’ They have<br />

therefore already acted before thinking.”<br />

[898] Clayon: The contradiction between the social and individual functions <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

could not be solved on the individual level, but only on the social level. “Society<br />

had to agree to accept a certain commodity as General equivalent.” This was something that


138 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

took place long ago, most likely without any recognition as to what was taking place. Hence<br />

we have Marx’s reference to Goethe’s drama Faust, “In the beginning was the deed,” meaning<br />

that they had acted long before they realized what was happening. As Hans notes, this<br />

mainly occurs in societies, as opposed to individuals who first think, and then act.<br />

Message [898] referenced by [2009fa:931], [2011fa:383], and [2011fa:420]. First Message by Clayon is [165].<br />

Question 340 How does the historical broadening and deepening <strong>of</strong> exchange develop the<br />

opposition between use-value and value dormant in the nature <strong>of</strong> the commodity?<br />

[885] Alcameron: opposition <strong>of</strong> use-value and value. The use value and inherent value<br />

that is dormant in commodities oppose each other and move farther apart as time moves<br />

on. The historical broadening and deepening <strong>of</strong> exchange cause the gap between these two<br />

values to widen as time goes on becuase <strong>of</strong> the process which commodities go through. Let<br />

me use an example:<br />

Copper has a dormant or inherent value as a metal. This value isn’t the value <strong>of</strong> gold<br />

or silver, but it does have value nonetheless. A couple hundred years ago copper may have<br />

been used to make tools or some sort <strong>of</strong> metal machinery. The properties <strong>of</strong> copper determine<br />

what it is useful for, and thus determine much <strong>of</strong> its use-value. Thanks to technological<br />

advancements and the discovery <strong>of</strong> electricity we know copper is a great conductor <strong>of</strong> electricity.<br />

It is used in nearly every home in wires that carry electricity to the home. Our iPod<br />

speakers have copper in them, our water pipes in our homes are <strong>of</strong>ten made <strong>of</strong> copper, we<br />

may have decorative pieces made <strong>of</strong> copper. The use-value <strong>of</strong> copper has changed drastically<br />

in the past 200 years because new discoveries and the continued exchange <strong>of</strong> copper. The<br />

inherent value <strong>of</strong> the metal and its properties have remained relatively unchanged during that<br />

time. The gap between these two values only widens as time goes on.<br />

Hans: You are defining value as the physical properties which make a thing what it is, and use-value as the uses <strong>of</strong><br />

a thing in a given society. Marx has quite a different definition <strong>of</strong> “value.”<br />

First Message by Alcameron is [479].<br />

Question 343 is 182 in 1995WI, 160 in 1995ut, 192 in 1996sp, 209 in 1997WI, 205 in<br />

1997ut, 214 in 1998WI, 233 in 2000fa, 312 in 2005fa, 343 in 2008fa, 368 in 2011fa, and<br />

382 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 343 Why is the occasional exchange <strong>of</strong> surplus products between tribes not an<br />

exchange <strong>of</strong> “commodities” but one <strong>of</strong> “products”?<br />

[901] Slash: commodities must be intended for exchange. Commodities are produced<br />

with the sole intent to be exchanged. Commodities are sold without the producer looking<br />

at creating a personal benefit with their product. For example if a tribe found animal skins<br />

useful for survival and randomly found that they had excess animal skins one year would<br />

not turn their excess animal skins into commodities, but would make them products they<br />

are willing to part with. Commodities are exchanged on a regular basis. When a tribe sets<br />

out to collect animal skins with the intent to sell the skins and does so, they then become<br />

commodities.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [902].<br />

Question 346 is 184 in 1995WI, 162 in 1995ut, 371 in 2011fa, and 385 in 2012fa:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 139<br />

Question 346 What is the difference between the exchange <strong>of</strong> products and the exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities? Why does the exchange <strong>of</strong> products usually involve surplus-products, and<br />

why does it first take place between members <strong>of</strong> different communities?<br />

[873] Andy: Exchange <strong>of</strong> products and commodities. Commodities are anything that<br />

is produced for sale or exchange whereas a product is produced for your own use or that<br />

<strong>of</strong> someone else. When you exchange products, you are exchanging things that were not<br />

originally produced for sale. Also commodities don’t have any use-value for their owners<br />

except as a means <strong>of</strong> echange. So the exchange <strong>of</strong> products usually involves surplus-products<br />

because owners use the amount they can use for themselves and use the rest for exchange,<br />

and it first took place between members <strong>of</strong> different communities because they had different<br />

surplus products so they exchanged.<br />

Next Message by Andy is [884].<br />

Question 350 is 188 in 1995WI, 199 in 1996sp, 221 in 1998WI, and 375 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 350 Why could the idea to use land as money arise only when capitalism was<br />

already developed?<br />

[859] Ken: necessary for life. Hans explains that, “Land is the most basic condition<br />

<strong>of</strong> life. Money is the most “liquid” commodity, the one which most easily changes hands.<br />

Only under capitalism, when people are generally uprooted and separated from the economic<br />

resources on which they depend, and when commodity relation are more important than life<br />

itself, will it occur to them to use land as money.” [1998WI:224].<br />

With the development <strong>of</strong> capitalism, came the privatization <strong>of</strong> property. Once land became<br />

private property people were able to exchange the property (for money) like other<br />

commodities. Claiming land as private property is an interesting phenomenon. You could<br />

compare this to a situation that happened in 2001 with Bechtel. Bechtel tried to privatize the<br />

rights to the water in Bolivia.<br />

The lower class was unable to afford the high price Bechtel wanted for water. Water once<br />

was available to all, but with capitalism pr<strong>of</strong>its became more important than life.<br />

Water is a basic commodity needed for life, just like land. Before capitalism land and<br />

water were available to everyone. Only in a capitalistic society would water and land be<br />

privatized. By privatizing land and water, they can be used as money.<br />

Hans: Water is an excellent comparison.<br />

First Message by Ken is [108].<br />

[861] Bar: graded B land as money? When referring to use land as money in Capital<br />

Marx says, “Such an idea could only in a bourgeois society, and one which was well<br />

developed. It dates from the last third <strong>of</strong> the seventeenth century, and the first attempt to implement<br />

the idea on a national scale was made a century later, during The French bourgeois<br />

revolution.” I believe Marx says this because as in many parts he puts the relevance <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

in a historical perspective. During this time there is a transition from mercantilism<br />

to capitalism, where under mercantilism created a real need for an exchangeable commodity<br />

like money for efficient transactions. He makes an interesting observation that before<br />

this humans were used as a commodity through slavery, and goes on to say after that even


140 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

then land was not seen as money. If we look at economic history the Corn Laws debates<br />

between Malthus and Ricardo show how land became money through the use <strong>of</strong> rents. Land<br />

in essence is a commodity now, which should be inherent in nature for man is used as a commodity<br />

in and <strong>of</strong> itself, and the right to own it comes from your stature, or right in society.<br />

From a nomadic tribe’s perspective this is a very interesting idea, one that would not come<br />

about if the social relations <strong>of</strong> capital were not already in place when capital was already<br />

developed. Because the commodity creates a need for ownership, society feels necessary to<br />

give everything ownership.<br />

Hans: Mercantilism took money very seriously, Mercantilists wanted trade surpluses, not because money makes<br />

transactions efficient, but because they wanted to make the transition from production for use to production <strong>of</strong><br />

abstract wealth for a surplus.<br />

First Message by Bar is [19].<br />

[865] FacistFrank: response to Bar. Today I think there is a lot <strong>of</strong> admiration for the<br />

way that the first native inhabitants used to live. They had less <strong>of</strong> a concept <strong>of</strong> ownership<br />

when it came to land, now our society does have that concept. I think that the Natives did<br />

have a concept <strong>of</strong> personal but not private property. It seems strange to me that we started<br />

in a state <strong>of</strong> less ownership, then thought that we were owners, and now are striving to get<br />

back to where we started in the respect that we don’t own anything. I believe ownership is<br />

an illusion, the only way that someone can own land is to defend their power over it with<br />

violence. The land was there before the so called owner was even alive, he didn’t create it,<br />

so how can he own it? He doesn’t own it, he takes it with violence. If you can control the<br />

land with violence, then you can exclusively reap the benefits from it.<br />

I think that land was more plentiful in Marx’s time, especially in America. Now the<br />

population is much larger, and capital has made it so the goods needed to enforce your<br />

violence on the land are much easier to make, <strong>of</strong> better quality, and <strong>of</strong> better quantity. It<br />

all stems from greed and too much individualism. The natives were more collective and<br />

communal. I believe a balance must be struck between the two.<br />

Next Message by FacistFrank is [899].<br />

[871] Clayon: I agree that the idea to use land as money arose when capitalism was<br />

developed, but I would also like to argue that, depending on the culture, the idea that land<br />

has a value predates capitalism. For any group <strong>of</strong> people that was migratory, they had no<br />

feelings <strong>of</strong> ownership to the land. But in societies where cities were established, land did<br />

have value. Any city that had a wall to protect itself from outside invaders created at least<br />

some value and idea <strong>of</strong> ownership to the land. If one wanted protection from any outside<br />

marauders, they would have to pay a price to have a spot <strong>of</strong> land within the walls. In this<br />

scenario however, the land only has value because something was done to it to add value to<br />

it (the surrounding wall and protection). The difference between this and capitalism is that<br />

capitalism gave value to land without first adding any value to it.<br />

Next Message by Clayon is [872].<br />

Question 351 One important property <strong>of</strong> gold is also that it does not deteriorate over time,<br />

it does not rust etc. Is this a reflection <strong>of</strong> the fact that value itself does not deteriorate over<br />

time?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 141<br />

[857] Jeremy: Gold Standard. Gold is a very interesting medium to be used as a measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. As pointed out in the question, it does not rust, so it does not deteriorate over time.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> its most valuable properties is its malleability. Gold, and value alike, are able to take<br />

on different forms in different situations. An ounce <strong>of</strong> gold can be made into jewelery, coin,<br />

conductors, replacement teeth, etc. Value likewise has the ability to do the same, depending<br />

upon the situation and the people involved. Therefore, it could be said that gold is not only<br />

a measure <strong>of</strong> value, it embodies value through symbolism as well.<br />

Hans: The malleability <strong>of</strong> gold is relevant not because <strong>of</strong> symbolism, but because a commodity which represents<br />

value must be divisible and re-combinable at will. But this is not what was asked. The question asked about the<br />

durability <strong>of</strong> gold, not its malleability.<br />

In general, you are not reading the material quite closely enough. You are not going the last mile trying to<br />

double-check whether the things you get out <strong>of</strong> the text are the same things Marx was concerned about.<br />

First Message by Jeremy is [372].<br />

Question 352 is 189 in 1995WI, 166 in 1995ut, 200 in 1996sp, 214 in 1997WI, 221 in<br />

1997sp, 213 in 1997ut, 290 in 2003fa, 327 in 2004fa, 321 in 2005fa, 342 in 2007SP, and<br />

377 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 352 Explain in your own words the meaning <strong>of</strong> Marx’s statement: “Although gold<br />

and silver are not by nature money, money is by nature gold and silver.”<br />

[864] Allen: nature <strong>of</strong> money. Just as Phelan [2004fa:225] said nothing is by nature<br />

money, because money mainly serves as an appearance <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity. Gold<br />

and silver are precious metals that serve as commodities because <strong>of</strong> their use-value as a<br />

metal, such as fillings for teeth, luxury items, etc. Because gold and silver are precious<br />

metals they have natural properties that can serve as a function <strong>of</strong> money but “gold and silver<br />

are not by nature money” in itself. “Money is by nature gold and silver” because money is<br />

considered the universal commodity and is a symbol <strong>of</strong> the commodity and represents it and<br />

its value.<br />

Hans: You should have spent a little more time trying to understand Phelan’s answer. The answer you are giving<br />

is pretty garbled although some <strong>of</strong> the things you are saying are right.<br />

Message [864] referenced by [867] and [872]. First Message by Allen is [102].<br />

[867] Paul: Gold and Silver. Allen in [864] is right when he says that “nothing is by<br />

nature money.” This is because the value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed by the commodities which<br />

you can buy with that amount <strong>of</strong> money. So really it would seem like there is no real physical<br />

nature to money, the physical nature is just that <strong>of</strong> the things which we associate as money.<br />

Allen states that because “gold and silver are precious metals they have natural properties<br />

that can serve as a function <strong>of</strong> money. . . ” Marx believes that gold and silver can be used<br />

as money because <strong>of</strong> the fact that the actual value <strong>of</strong> the coin is considered to be <strong>of</strong> equal<br />

value to the value <strong>of</strong> the labor put into making a given commodity. Basically if you have<br />

$50 worth <strong>of</strong> gold you are able to purchase $50 worth <strong>of</strong> labor. Also, an ability that gold and<br />

silver have that Marx believed made them ideal for the use <strong>of</strong> money was that you can easily<br />

have many different sized coins <strong>of</strong> these metals that represent different values. So because<br />

gold and silver had these properties, it made them well suited to be used as money.<br />

Hans: The sentence “the value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed by the commodities which you can buy with that amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> money” does not mean that money is a worthless thing which everyone in society agrees to accept in exchange<br />

for their valuable commodities. Marx considers such an agreement an impossibility; social relations cannot just<br />

be pretended into existence. Only if money already has value (because it is a commodity itself, as in Marx’s time,


142 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

or because it is backed by monetary policy which maintains its purchasing power, and by the US military, which<br />

makes sure everyone in the world accepts the US dollar, as in the USA today), can it function as money. The<br />

commodities it can buy are an expression <strong>of</strong> that value, not the source or basis <strong>of</strong> that value.<br />

What I just wrote is in response to your second and third sentences. The rest <strong>of</strong> your submission is ok. What<br />

you say in the last two sentences is what Marx meant when he said that “money is by nature gold and silver.”<br />

Message [867] referenced by [872]. First Message by Paul is [152].<br />

[872] Clayon: Re: Gold and Silver. In response to [864] and [867], I believe that there<br />

is an important point that we are overlooking. Yes, money does hold value based upon the<br />

faith <strong>of</strong> society to uphold the value <strong>of</strong> said money, but under the Gold Standard, gold had<br />

value not just for being gold, but also for the labor input required for mining, and producing<br />

the gold. The same can be said for Silver. We can see then that the value <strong>of</strong> money is also a<br />

funtion <strong>of</strong> labor input.<br />

Hans: You are right, Allen [864] says that gold and silver have use-values as noble metals, i.e., he seems to derive<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> gold and silver from this use-value and not the labor necessary to mine gold and silver. But you cannot<br />

blame Paul [867] for this oversight; Paul says that gold has value because <strong>of</strong> its labor input.<br />

Next Message by Clayon is [874].<br />

Exam Question 356 is 191 in 1995WI, 202 in 1996sp, 217 in 1997WI, 216 in 1997ut, 226<br />

in 1998WI, 236 in 1999SP, 280 in 2002fa, 294 in 2003fa, 331 in 2004fa, 346 in 2007SP,<br />

371 in 2009fa, 401 in 2010fa, 383 in 2011fa, and 397 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam Question 356 Marx writes: “The exchange process gives the commodity which it<br />

has designated as money not its value, but its specific form <strong>of</strong> value.” Which form <strong>of</strong> value<br />

does Marx mean here? Why does Marx call this form the specific form <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the money<br />

commodity? (Assume we are under the gold standard.)<br />

[870] Andy: Marx believes that through the exchange process, one commodity is selected<br />

as the General equivalent. This selection process does not give the General equivalent its<br />

value but gives it a specific form <strong>of</strong> value, which will be associated with that use-value<br />

alone. It cannot be decided by a social agreement how much value a commodity has, but<br />

it can be decided by social agreement which use-value everyone uses as general equivalent.<br />

Another misconception is that money is merely a symbol. Marx gives an example <strong>of</strong> how<br />

a wedding ring is a symbol, it symbolizes a relation which exists independently, while a<br />

gold coin doesn’t just symbolize value but actually is a value. However money is only the<br />

materialized form <strong>of</strong> a social relation, but this does not license us to forget that this social<br />

relation has a materialized form. Money is their symbol, and as a symbol it is attracted<br />

by commodities. Money is a symbol that represents a thing, money does not represent the<br />

values but its their equivalent.<br />

Hans: Money is not a symbol <strong>of</strong> value but it is value – but otherwise your answer is very good.<br />

Next Message by Andy is [873].<br />

Question 358 is 169 in 1995ut, 238 in 1999SP, 348 in 2007SP, and 403 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 358 How, why, and through what is a commodity already money?<br />

[216] Hans: The divinity <strong>of</strong> humans. This question refers to Marx’s aphorism (the<br />

parentheses are mine):


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 143<br />

The difficulty lies not in comprehending that money (under the gold standard)<br />

is a commodity, but in discovering how, why and through what a<br />

commodity is money.<br />

Similarly one could say:<br />

The difficulty lies not in comprehending that god (in Jesus) became a human,<br />

but in discovering how, why and through what humans are god.<br />

A related issue is that emphasized by CousinIt in [155], that we think that values are<br />

something we are imposing on reality, although they are part <strong>of</strong> reality.<br />

I am using this question number to respond to [209]. PrivateProperty comes close to saying<br />

that humans believe that god is something outside them, while in reality they themselves<br />

are the gods. They think they need god to make them good, while in reality god is only<br />

the expression <strong>of</strong> the goodness in them. (I know that I am stretching it, but if I completely<br />

misrepresent you, please speak up!) In the same way, a naive look at commodity circulation<br />

would get the impression that money gives value to the commodities and is the big motor<br />

moving commodities around, while Marx tries to show that money is the expression <strong>of</strong> the<br />

value which the commodities already have (due to the labor time in them), and money is<br />

passive. What is active is the commodities themselves.<br />

Message [216] referenced by [209] and [2010fa:982]. Next Message by Hans is [219].<br />

Question 359 is 192 in 1995WI, 227 in 1997sp, 219 in 1997ut, 297 in 2003fa, 328 in<br />

2005fa, and 387 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 359 Was Roscher in error when he said that money is a pleasant commodity?<br />

[844] Rampton: Roscher, Money is a pleasant commodity? Yes, Money is not just a<br />

commodity it is the same as the value <strong>of</strong> money. From Marinda [1995WI:566] gold may be<br />

a commodity in itself, but Roscher does not say what makes gold or any other commodity<br />

become “money.” The only thing he could have meant by calling it “pleasant” is that he<br />

thinks it is fun to have lots <strong>of</strong> it for oneself, to do with as one pleases. Money does have<br />

as Marx puts it “use-value” to the person who controls it or possesses it. Marx jokes about<br />

being “pleasant” is not a property <strong>of</strong> something with one can discover in an object. [Hans]<br />

The learned Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Roscher, after first informing us that “the false definitions <strong>of</strong> money<br />

may be divided into two main groups: those which make it more, and those which make it<br />

less, than a commodity,” gives us a long and very mixed catalogue <strong>of</strong> works on the nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> money, from which it appears that he has not the remotest idea <strong>of</strong> the real history <strong>of</strong> the<br />

theory; and then he moralises thus: “For the rest, it is not to be denied that most <strong>of</strong> the later<br />

economists do not bear sufficiently in mind the peculiarities-that distinguish money from<br />

other commodities” (it is then, after all, either more or less than a commodity!)<br />

Hans: Lots <strong>of</strong> quotes, but your answer would have needed a simple and coherent explanation why you think the<br />

answer to the question is “yes,” i.e., <strong>of</strong> Roscher’s mistake.<br />

Message [844] referenced by [846] and [853]. Next Message by Rampton is [889].<br />

[846] Mitternacht: graded A Hardly pleasant. Roscher was definitely in error when he<br />

said that money is a “pleasant commodity”. Rampton [844] does a good job <strong>of</strong> gathering


144 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

bits and pieces from previous semesters’ class discussions which relate to this question, but<br />

falters in piecing things together.<br />

We needn’t worry about whether money may take on the form <strong>of</strong> a commodity – this is<br />

one thing which Marx and Roscher agreed upon, but for very different reasons. From the<br />

small quote <strong>of</strong> Roscher I can’t even make sense <strong>of</strong> why he thinks that money is a commodity<br />

other than that it false to think money is anything more or less than a commodity. Marx<br />

jumped on top <strong>of</strong> this absurd reasoning and then to top it <strong>of</strong>f Roscher states that money is a<br />

“pleasant commodity” which Marx simply could not abide. Roscher seems to be saying that<br />

it is pleasant to have money; therefore money is a pleasant commodity. However, Roscher is<br />

mistaken about nature <strong>of</strong> money as a commodity – he only sees the surface level <strong>of</strong> exchanges<br />

being money relations and makes incorrect assumptions about the properties <strong>of</strong> money based<br />

on market interactions involving money. Money and the misunderstandings which surround<br />

it allow capitalists to participate in the exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers. Workers may also possess<br />

money, but it isn’t “pleasant” for them because it doesn’t serve the same purpose as it would<br />

for a capitalist since they don’t own the means for production.<br />

Message [846] referenced by [853]. Next Message by Mitternacht is [879].<br />

[853] Spawnblade: I like money, don’t you? I’d like to disagree with both Rampton’s<br />

[844] and Mitternacht’s [846]. When I first read over Rampton’s explanation <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

and how money is not a commodity (as we learned early on), I simply felt that saying<br />

‘no’ was too simple in this question. So for the reason <strong>of</strong> enjoyment, I’d like to take a step<br />

back and look at it in a contrary light.<br />

Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> a commodity: “an external object, a thing which through its qualities<br />

satisfies human needs <strong>of</strong> whatever kind.”<br />

Now in regards to society, money is a medium <strong>of</strong> exchange to facilitate transactions between<br />

people. According to Marx it has no use-value in and <strong>of</strong> itself. Now let’s remember<br />

what Marx also says - use-value is in the eye <strong>of</strong> the beholder. It is different for every individual.<br />

In Roscher’s view, it is possible that the presence <strong>of</strong> money actually makes him happy<br />

(or the people to whom he refers). This is one method <strong>of</strong> giving it a use-value, for a simple<br />

mood-lift. So while Mitternacht’s statement about the “nature <strong>of</strong> money” not being a commodity<br />

is true, money still takes a physical form with which to influence its surroundings, or<br />

perhaps it would only take the idea <strong>of</strong> money to induce the same influence.<br />

This is one way that money could be seen as a ‘pleasant commodity’. It also ties in<br />

with our oh-so-favorite capitalists who hoard their money in droves despite it not physically<br />

helping anyone (since it remains unused).<br />

Hans: You don’t understand Marx’s explanation <strong>of</strong> money, and you are barking up the wrong tree: the issue is not<br />

whether money is a commodity, but whether money can be said to have the attribute <strong>of</strong> being “pleasant.”<br />

First Message by Spawnblade is [140].<br />

[856] Papageorgio: Err. Many people may argue over this question as it can be very<br />

opinion based if looked at on surface value. Yes to some money feels like a pleasant commodity.<br />

Yes to some money is not pleasant. A quote from Hans in [2005fa:743] must be<br />

cited here as it shows in simplicity this dilemma, “The pleasantness <strong>of</strong> having money comes<br />

with a price, namely, the pain <strong>of</strong> those who don’t have money.” When one has sufficient<br />

money for their needs they may feel great: clothes can be washed, dishes cleaned, food put


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 145<br />

on the table, children supported and yes money feels pleasant. But on the same token as one<br />

walks the street and sees the less fortunate begging for money the pain <strong>of</strong> money can be seen<br />

by those who look on. The reason the money brings this pleasant feeling to those who have<br />

it is the fact that money can be used to be traded for all goods, it can bring them anything<br />

they feel, most people in the world feel that everything has a price and can be bought with<br />

money. Security is a feeling people receive with money and to many that is pleasant. Pleasant<br />

is probably not the word to describe money though especially as it can be so opinion<br />

based. Many things that money can lead to greed and hurt many families and lives. Money<br />

can be the cause <strong>of</strong> someone to be jumped, robbed, or in all the movies the bully stealing<br />

the lunch money. Money can bring many ills to one’s life. I feel and I feel that Marx feels<br />

that money is not what is pleasant at all it does not contain that property in itself. Something<br />

I think that is relevant to this is an example from my life, as I make money, I spend more<br />

money, I wish I had more as I get more. My friend has no job and he gets by quite well he<br />

is not unpleasant but actually quite happy without needing to spend money for all his meals<br />

and such. It is not pleasant to take advantage <strong>of</strong> the working class and Roscher really has no<br />

credibility claiming that money is pleasant.<br />

Message [856] referenced by [888]. First Message by Papageorgio is [151].<br />

[888] Andy: I believe that Roscher was not in error. Money is a commodity because<br />

it requires labor to produce it. Money holds a value which cannot be expressed except for<br />

other commodities. Money can also be exchanged for other commodities. However the main<br />

point <strong>of</strong> what Roscher means is that money is a pleasant commodity because it is pleasant to<br />

have money.<br />

Hans: Nobody doubts that it is pleasant to have money. But the last submission about this question which came<br />

before you, Papageorgio’s [856], made a good argument that it is nevertheless incorrect to call money a pleasant<br />

commodity. If you think Roscher was right you should have addressed Papageorgio’s arguments.<br />

First Message by Andy is [45].<br />

[896] Nstew: Is money a pleasant commodity? Was Roscher in error? Personally I think<br />

there are two ways to look at this. Marx has clearly stated that he considers money to be a<br />

commodity because its value is defined by the exchange <strong>of</strong> money for commodities. Money<br />

can be traded, it has an exchange value which are both characteristics <strong>of</strong> a commodity, so yes<br />

I think money is a commodity. Roscher used the phrase that money is not only a commodity<br />

but a “pleasant commodity”. What does he mean by saying it is a “pleasant commodity”?<br />

I think Roscher is referring to the pleasantness <strong>of</strong> having money and what it is worth in<br />

the economy. I think he is getting emotion mixed in by stating that money is a “pleasant<br />

commodity” instead <strong>of</strong> just looking at money for what it is. I think many people who have<br />

a lot <strong>of</strong> money might categorize money as a “pleasant commodity” but when it comes down<br />

to it money is just a commodity. So I think his statement is false.<br />

Hans: The definition <strong>of</strong> commodity is “a use-value produced for exchange.” Gold is a commodity, and Marx was<br />

living under the gold standard, therefore during his time money was a commodity.<br />

First Message by Nstew is [593].<br />

[903] Mick: graded C Roscher’s erroneous claim. Is money really a pleasant commodity?<br />

This question incites a multitude <strong>of</strong> responses that would argue the contrary. Money<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten disguises, and therefore falsely represents the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity, particularly by<br />

obfuscating the amount <strong>of</strong> labor that was required to produce a certain product. If there is<br />

inflation <strong>of</strong> the currency used to hire labor, but the price paid for the labor is the same, then


146 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

clearly the worker is not receiving just compensation for his work, because the buying power<br />

he receives as payment is mitigated through the abundance <strong>of</strong> the currency he is paid in. So<br />

through the abstraction <strong>of</strong> money, and the ability for wealthy individuals and institutions to<br />

control the circulation <strong>of</strong> money, its value is able to be artificially changed in relation to the<br />

labor it hires.<br />

Hans: Explanation <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its by manipulations <strong>of</strong> the monetary system are popular in some circles, but they are<br />

not based on Marx.<br />

First Message by Mick is [388].<br />

Question 360 is 230 in 1998WI, 298 in 2003fa, and 402 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 360 List and briefly discuss all those theories <strong>of</strong> money which Marx mentioned on<br />

pages 184:3/oo – 186:1 and about which he said they were incorrect.<br />

[892] Nstew: Theories <strong>of</strong> money. Marx says that the first misconception <strong>of</strong> money itself<br />

does not have value and the value <strong>of</strong> money is imaginary. He says its value comes from<br />

social agreement. He says that a commodity becomes money by the joint action <strong>of</strong> all other<br />

commodities, by a social agreement which decides that every commodity should express<br />

its value in that specific commodity. Since commodities can express their values only in<br />

something that has value itself then money becomes a commodity. Back when money was<br />

backed by the gold system it represented a certain amount <strong>of</strong> gold and the price <strong>of</strong> gold would<br />

fluctuate which would cause the prices <strong>of</strong> commodities to fluctuate. Through the exchange<br />

process a commodity is selected as the “general equivalent” which is given a specific form<br />

<strong>of</strong> value. By social agreement it is decided which use-value everyone uses as a general<br />

equivalent.<br />

The second misconception <strong>of</strong> money according to Marx is that “Money is merely a symbol”.<br />

He says that a gold coin does not symbolize value, it is value. What Marx is saying<br />

here is that even though money is a materialized form <strong>of</strong> a social relation, but that the social<br />

relation has a materialized form.<br />

The third misconception is that money is an arbitrary product <strong>of</strong> human reflection. If<br />

money is an arbitrary form <strong>of</strong> human reflection then the social agreement which has decided<br />

the use-value becomes unfamiliar. Marx stresses that money is a commodity and that its<br />

value is based on what commodities it is exchangeable for. Money like every other commodity<br />

can express the magnitude <strong>of</strong> its value only relatively through other commodities.<br />

The fourth misconception <strong>of</strong> money Marx talks about is the failure to identify that what<br />

distinguishes money from the other commodities. What Marx is arguing here is that a commodity<br />

is the same as money and inherently has money traits.<br />

Hans: Under the gold standard, gold does not have a price but gold is the price. And the value <strong>of</strong> money is not<br />

based on what commodities it is exchangeable for, but it is based on its labor content, and the commodities which a<br />

certain amount <strong>of</strong> money can buy are an expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money. But other than this, a very good answer.<br />

Next Message by Nstew is [893].<br />

Question 363 is 207 in 1996sp, 392 in 2011fa, and 406 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 363 Are people, by their atomistic attitude towards each other, responsible for<br />

their lack <strong>of</strong> control over their own social relations?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 147<br />

[849] Aaron: Atomistic tendencies. As Marx describes here, the fetish like characteristics<br />

<strong>of</strong> money involves the theory that commodities need not show any “initiative” <strong>of</strong> their<br />

own, and they still hold a readily usable value in the form <strong>of</strong> an existing commodity that is<br />

ready for exchange. Marx also uses interesting logic in describing the relationship <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity, to the the producer. He says that the fetish like character <strong>of</strong> commodities is a<br />

result <strong>of</strong> the atomistic attitude <strong>of</strong> the producer. As Hans notes in the annotations, the riddle<br />

<strong>of</strong> the money fetish is the same as the riddle <strong>of</strong> the commodity fetish. I believe that the<br />

answer to question 363 is Yes, according to the logic <strong>of</strong> Marx. People are responsible for<br />

their own lack <strong>of</strong> control over their own social relations because Marx believes that they are<br />

at the root <strong>of</strong> all social concerns as a producer <strong>of</strong> commodity. They themselves create fetish<br />

like characteristics <strong>of</strong> money and commodities.<br />

Hans: Against your argument that the commodity producers are responsible for the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity, Marx says in 173:1/oo that capitalism is “a social formation in which the production process has<br />

the mastery over men, and man does not yet master the production process.” Generally, Marx does not make the<br />

individuals responsible for their social relations.<br />

Message [849] referenced by [850] and [890]. First Message by Aaron is [31].<br />

[850] CousinIt: graded A+ Control <strong>of</strong> Social Relations. Due to the fetish-like character<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity, which is extended to the fetish-like nature <strong>of</strong> money as the universal<br />

equivalent commodity, human relations are carried out through things. Thus people are<br />

alienated not only from the products <strong>of</strong> their labor, but from their very humanity by way <strong>of</strong><br />

this subsumption <strong>of</strong> all things, including those things-human, and thus the alienated nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> their social relations as atomistic, individual-isolationist.<br />

This question can be read in two different ways; we can read it as (a) asking if people are<br />

responsible for creating their inability to control their social relations or we can read it as<br />

(b) asking if people are responsible for maintaining or responsible for changing their lack <strong>of</strong><br />

control over their social relations (as I interpret Panacea [1996sp:287] as doing).<br />

From the beginning <strong>of</strong> commodity production, the production <strong>of</strong> things not useful to me<br />

for the purpose <strong>of</strong> trading them for things that are useful for me, we can see the seeds <strong>of</strong><br />

atomism being planted in the deep soil <strong>of</strong> our past. As commodity production, through the<br />

demands <strong>of</strong> the exchange process, becomes mediated through a central/universal commodity<br />

(i.e. money), the atomism becomes even more entrenched in everyday thinking and action.<br />

For the capitalist, the focus is on self-valorizing capital, with little or no regard for anything<br />

else. For the worker the focus is on survival through the selling <strong>of</strong> their labor-power. In capitalism<br />

all that matters is that things are moved along and accumulation continues indefintely,<br />

regardless <strong>of</strong> the human and environmental costs.<br />

If we are asking the question according to interpretation (a) above, we might say that<br />

yes, people are responsible for their alienation because at any point along the way they<br />

could have noticed that they were losing control <strong>of</strong> their social relations and taken steps<br />

toward an alternative productive/economic system or mode <strong>of</strong> being-in-the-world ... This<br />

is another way to say what Aaron [849] is trying to say in stating that people are “at the<br />

root <strong>of</strong> all social concerns as producers <strong>of</strong> commodity.” On the other hand, we might qualify<br />

this answer by asserting that, perhaps, by the time people noticed that they were losing<br />

control <strong>of</strong> their social relations, they were already too deeply entrenched in the ideology<br />

(false consciousness? occupational psychosis?) <strong>of</strong> the commodity-exchange (a cornerstone


148 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> which is an atomistic attitude toward competitors, clients, and employer/employees) to<br />

be psychologically, physically, or emotionally able to do anything about it. It is as if we are<br />

suffering from a society-wide sociopathic disorder that is going pandemic.<br />

The other possible answer to this interpretation (a) <strong>of</strong> the question is that people are not<br />

responsible for creating their condition, but merely, both capitalist and worker, are victims<br />

<strong>of</strong> the social-economic structure that has somehow sprung-up around them as some sort<br />

<strong>of</strong> natural development <strong>of</strong> determined, pre-destined, ‘natural’ human history, as a social-<br />

Darwinist might conclude.<br />

Are people responsible for maintaining or for changing the condition <strong>of</strong> being out <strong>of</strong><br />

control over social relations, as per my interpretation (b) <strong>of</strong> the original question? As Hans<br />

points out in response to Panacea, the capitalist has more resources for making changes but<br />

by doing so puts himself out <strong>of</strong> business. It could also be said that the worker believes that<br />

he is “biting the hand that feeds” if he moves against capitalism. However, the banality <strong>of</strong><br />

the situation becomes painfully unavoidable as the damage to the environment starts to have<br />

real undeniable effects on human and other lives and as the capitalist system becomes clearly<br />

environmentally/economically unsustainable for a forseeable future when we consider that<br />

the rest <strong>of</strong> the world is beginning to demand ‘first-world’ standards <strong>of</strong> living/consumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> resources.<br />

However, if we as a people, as a species, do not take responsibility for our illness, who<br />

will? As stated by Hans in response to Panacea (and paraphrased with certain liberties taken<br />

by me), the situation will not be solved by individual action but only through universal collective<br />

scrambling to avoid extinction. Perhaps nature will seal our fate, as it does in the case<br />

<strong>of</strong> the cancer victim who does not take responsibility for her illness and thereby fails to seek<br />

out or enact a cure and dies. According to Desai (in his book “Marx’s Revenge...”), Marx<br />

knew clearly that capitalism would have to be pushed to its limits before mankind would<br />

do anything to change or abolish it. These limits are fast becoming evolutionarily apparent.<br />

The limits <strong>of</strong> capitalism are social, economic, environmental, physical, emotional, and spiritual<br />

limits. It could be said that our attitude <strong>of</strong> atomism exists on the social-spiritual plane<br />

and that it is the hardest limit to apprehend and to affect on the large scale. However, Marx<br />

also knew that precisely some sort <strong>of</strong> spiritual evolutionary step, an ‘awakening’ <strong>of</strong> human<br />

consciousness, would be the necessary pre-requisite if capitalism would ever be abolished<br />

by way <strong>of</strong> human agency, rather than by way <strong>of</strong> social-economic-environmental-cosmic disaster.<br />

My opinion is, ...better sooner than later.... I’m sick and tired <strong>of</strong> being sick and tired in<br />

a world that is crumbling where, on the surface, no one cares for anything other than their<br />

own comfort and security at the expense <strong>of</strong> the environment and the less fortunate. Capitalism<br />

systematically, attritionally, and perpetually sickens us all, including the capitalist, unto<br />

death...unto extinction....<br />

Next Message by CousinIt is [877].<br />

[890] Rampton: Social Relations. Yes according to Marx. People are responsible for<br />

themselves and their own actions and for everything they do. Marx believes that they are at<br />

the root <strong>of</strong> all social concerns as a producers <strong>of</strong> commodities. In a court decision in 1914<br />

Benjamin Cardozo wrote that every human being <strong>of</strong> adult years and sound mind has a right


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 149<br />

to determine what shall be done with his own body.... Now known as the right or principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> autonomy, this concept pervades the law, undergirding virtually all rights relating to<br />

the body, particularly those grounded in the right <strong>of</strong> privacy. Nowhere is this clearer than<br />

within the realm <strong>of</strong> healthcare law and ethics where patient autonomy has become the dominant<br />

principle governing healthcare decision-making. We live in the time <strong>of</strong> the triumph <strong>of</strong><br />

autonomy....<br />

Hans: Your first three sentences are directly lifted from [849]. The rest <strong>of</strong> your answer has nothing to do with<br />

Marx, and I am wondering if you confused the definitions <strong>of</strong> “atomistic” and “autonomous”? “Atomistic” means:<br />

disregardful <strong>of</strong> one’s social connections.<br />

Next Message by Rampton is [891].<br />

Question 373 is 236 in 1997sp, 228 in 1997ut, 238 in 1998WI, 248 in 1999SP, 259 in<br />

2000fa, 272 in 2001fa, 296 in 2002fa, 310 in 2003fa, 348 in 2004fa, 342 in 2005fa, 363<br />

in 2007SP, 373 in 2008fa, 388 in 2009fa, 404 in 2011fa, and 419 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 373 How is the value <strong>of</strong> money expressed?<br />

[408] Bmellor: Take my home for just 200,000 hamburgers. Marx suggests what all<br />

accountants know but only economists point out, the value <strong>of</strong> money is in the “possible<br />

commodities” which we can purchase with money. Some countries use 1,000’s in place <strong>of</strong><br />

one piece <strong>of</strong> currency so <strong>of</strong> course the value is not in the number printed on the paper. If it<br />

costs 30 Yuan for meal in China and the exchange rate is 1 dollar equals 7 Yuan then that is<br />

a reasonable meal.<br />

But forget the exchange rate, the money is valued in the goods you can purchase. There<br />

is a Wendy’s commercial on TV where a man is looking at a contract that he is about to<br />

sign and says: “Wow! That is 1,000,000 Junior Bacon Cheese Burgers.” The rest <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commercial shows people expressing the value <strong>of</strong> certain items: clothing, cars, furniture,<br />

speeding tickets, etc... in “Junior Bacon Cheese Burgers” instead <strong>of</strong> dollars.<br />

Essentially that is what your money is worth, the commodities you can buy. Which is<br />

essentially what all economists view when looking at the cost <strong>of</strong> something; opportunity<br />

cost gives a purchase its economic value, this comes about (partly) by looking at the other<br />

commodities you could have purchased instead <strong>of</strong> the commodity you did purchase. While<br />

an accountant looks at the dollar money you spent instead <strong>of</strong> what else you could have<br />

bought.<br />

Message [408] referenced by [415] and [426]. Next Message by Bmellor is [466].<br />

[415] Hans: The virgin birth <strong>of</strong> an expression. Bmellor [408] says that the value <strong>of</strong><br />

money consists in the things money can buy. Marx, by contrast, says that the value <strong>of</strong><br />

money is expressed in the things one can buy, but this is not the source <strong>of</strong> this value. Under<br />

the gold standard, the source <strong>of</strong> money’s value was the labor necessary to mine the gold, and<br />

nowadays I think the source <strong>of</strong> the dollar’s international value is US monetary policy, backed<br />

by its military might which, among other things, is the ultimate reason for the agreement <strong>of</strong><br />

Saudi Arabia to price oil in dollars. More about this see my [2007SP:599].<br />

In our day-to-day interactions we only see the expressions <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money and<br />

there is no direct empirical link to the source <strong>of</strong> this value. This lead to the error, which Le<br />

Trosne made in question 64, <strong>of</strong> thinking this expression just springs into existence without


150 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

some material force backing it up. This is utterly implausible just on practical grounds: so<br />

much hinges on the value <strong>of</strong> the dollar that it would have been overturned long ago had it<br />

not been backed by some real, and in fact quite formidable, material force. Brandon [383]<br />

calls Marx’s way <strong>of</strong> thinking “supply-side economics”; another possible designation would<br />

be “depth economics.”<br />

Message [415] referenced by [383], [418], [421], [426], [635], [648], and [662]. Next Message by Hans is [416].<br />

[426] Hans: Marxian Analysis <strong>of</strong> a Cheeseburger Commercial. My [415] tried to<br />

correct a careless formulation in the first sentence <strong>of</strong> Bmellor’s [408], but now I’d like to<br />

comment on his very interesting example <strong>of</strong> a Cheeseburger commercial. Bmellor writes:<br />

There is a Wendy’s commercial on TV where a man is looking at a contract<br />

that he is about to sign and says: “Wow! That is 1,000,000 Junior Bacon<br />

Cheese Burgers.” The rest <strong>of</strong> the commercial shows people expressing the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> certain items: clothing, cars, furniture, speeding tickets, etc... in<br />

“Junior Bacon Cheese Burgers” instead <strong>of</strong> dollars.<br />

The purpose <strong>of</strong> the commercial is to imprint the notion <strong>of</strong> Junior Bacon Cheese Burgers<br />

in the viewer’s brain and to let the viewer know how inexpensive these Cheese Burgers are.<br />

We can use Marx’s categories to explain how the advertisers did this.<br />

Normally, if you want to say how cheap (or expensive) something is, i.e., if you want to<br />

express its value, you simply name its price. This has two drawbacks: (a) if the ad says that<br />

a Junior Bacon is 99 cents plus tax, then people will think: if it’s so cheap it can’t be very<br />

good, and (b) who cares about these small amounts anyway.<br />

But in 189:1 Marx says that the value <strong>of</strong> money cannot be expressed by naming its price,<br />

rather it is expressed by enumerating all the things money can buy. Since the price <strong>of</strong> a<br />

Junior Bacon is approximately $1, the Wendy advertisers applied this alternative expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> value not to money but to the Junior Bacon Cheeseburgers. This cunning move eliminates<br />

both <strong>of</strong> the above drawbacks. (a) If you say “this house is worth 200,000 Junior Bacon<br />

Cheeseburgers, and that thing here is worth xx Junior Bacon Cheseburgers,” etc., then nobody<br />

will say: “the cheeseburgers can’t be very nutritious if you have to pay 200,000 <strong>of</strong><br />

them for this house.” (I am wondering if Marx has anticipated this with his mysterious pronouncement<br />

in 147:3/o that the equivalent form <strong>of</strong> value does not contain a quantitative value<br />

determination.) Rather they will think the Cheeseburgers sit at the center <strong>of</strong> the Universe if<br />

you can express the value <strong>of</strong> everything in them. And (b) the Cheeseburgers’ own low value<br />

translates into impressive high numbers for everything else.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [428].<br />

[594] Nstew: The value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed in the goods you can buy. Let’s say<br />

that I wanted to buy a taco and it cost $1 dollar. Now if I were this same taco down in<br />

Mexico it would cost me about $10 pesos which is the same cost as in the U.S. but forget<br />

about the exchange rate because your money is valued on the commodities you can buy.<br />

Opportunity cost gives a purchase its economic value and this is measured by comparing the<br />

other commodities you could buy with that same amount <strong>of</strong> money. Money only represents<br />

a common medium in order to exchange goods or services and allows us an opportunity to<br />

have a common way to place a value on commodities.<br />

Message [594] referenced by [2008fa:1149]. Next Message by Nstew is [614].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 151<br />

[629] Alex: graded C Money has many expressions in Marx’s thinking, though in the<br />

end it all relates to purchasing and exchange. Marx describes money as something that<br />

can be exchanged for a commodity. In this particular context Marx talks about money as a<br />

controlling factor for exchange largely. In later chapters Marx goes on to explain money as<br />

a means <strong>of</strong> capitalist augmentation. Not only does the capitalist own the labor power, but he<br />

also owns the money that results from the sale <strong>of</strong> the commodity. The capitalist also sets the<br />

price adding in what is more than socially necessary for the price <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Overall, Marx shows that money is not an object but is a controlling factor maintained<br />

by the capitalist. He also draws attention to the fact that the value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed<br />

in exchange value, when two parties exchange something for something more valuable, to<br />

them at least. However, true value in exchange is much more complicated than Condillac<br />

would make it seem.<br />

Hans: Pr<strong>of</strong>its do not come from prices being higher than “socially necessary.” Marx discussed this extensively in<br />

chapter Five.<br />

Next Message by Alex is [630].<br />

[632] Rmuscolino: The value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed through the expanded form <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

The expanded form <strong>of</strong> value is an endless series <strong>of</strong> equations, which become the specific<br />

relative form <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the money commodity. This endless series is already socially given<br />

in the prices <strong>of</strong> the commodities. “We only need to read the quotations <strong>of</strong> a price list backwards,<br />

to find the magnitude <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money expressed in all possible commodities.”<br />

Marx states that money does not have to work to establish its form <strong>of</strong> value. Instead, this<br />

form <strong>of</strong> value is already given. Money becomes “directly exchangeable” since all goods<br />

express their values in money.<br />

Next Message by Rmuscolino is [634].<br />

[635] Matt: The value <strong>of</strong> Money. When one first looks at money they don’t see the true<br />

value and where it comes from, all they see is what money can buy and or the expressions <strong>of</strong><br />

the value <strong>of</strong> money. But according to Hans [415], during Marx’s time the source <strong>of</strong> money’s<br />

value came from the gold standard, which equaled the labor time necessary to mine the gold.<br />

It was the labor time congealed into each piece <strong>of</strong> gold which backed the value <strong>of</strong> money<br />

and made it exchangeable.<br />

Money itself, according to the annotations, “does not have to work to establish its form <strong>of</strong><br />

value. Rather, this form <strong>of</strong> value is already given.” It is this form <strong>of</strong> value that allows money<br />

to act as the social relationship between the direct exchange <strong>of</strong> money and the commodity.<br />

The Annotations say, “Since all goods express their values in money, money becomes directly<br />

exchangeable for them.” If all goods did not express their value through money, then<br />

one could not buy a quart <strong>of</strong> milk without the direct exchange for another commodity, such<br />

as rice. Money makes the exchange process easier since everything can be bought and sold<br />

with the value that has been placed into it.<br />

Hans: You only look at money as means <strong>of</strong> circulation; you ignore its function as measure <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Next Message by Matt is [636].<br />

[638] Jenn: graded A expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money (not the source). The value<br />

<strong>of</strong> money is expressed in what commodities it can purchase. Initially, all commodities express<br />

value in the expanded relative form, and then their value is expressed in the general<br />

equivalent. Although the general equivalent (gold standard in Marx’s days) gives money the


152 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

source <strong>of</strong> its value, the money actually expresses its value when a commodity owner sells<br />

their commodity in money form at a price the seller determines themselves.<br />

I believe in my in-class answer I discussed the source <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money, not the<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money. Although, gold as a commodity is one way the value <strong>of</strong><br />

money can be expressed.<br />

Hans: I am writing this note in 2012fa since participants in this class refer to this message. The fact that I gave<br />

this message an A does not mean every sentence <strong>of</strong> it is correct. The sentence “the general equivalent gives money<br />

the source <strong>of</strong> its value” is wrong. The source <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> gold (the money under the gold standard) is the labor<br />

necessary to mine the gold. Money does not get value from being a general equivalent. The causality is the reverse:<br />

gold can become general equivalent only because it is a commodity that contains labor.<br />

I may have overlooked this since exams are a lot <strong>of</strong> work, or I may have had other reasons to give this message<br />

an A, maybe it was much better than the in-class version.<br />

Message [638] referenced by [2012fa:738]. Next Message by Jenn is [748].<br />

[648] Bennett: The value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed or represented as capital that the certain<br />

country whose currency it is, has a hold <strong>of</strong>. There needs to be enough capital backing the<br />

currency in the open market. In the U.S. there are gold reserves at Fort Knox that give our<br />

currency its value. Without a “real” object <strong>of</strong> value there would be no difference in value<br />

between a $1 bill and a $100 bill, they would just be worth the value <strong>of</strong> the paper that the<br />

money is printed on. This gives money its value, it is also known as the gold standard.<br />

Hans: You are confusing the source <strong>of</strong> one dollar’s value with the expression <strong>of</strong> one dollar’s value, compare [415].<br />

Next Message by Bennett is [649].<br />

[662] Rampton: Marx says the value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed in the things one can buy.<br />

That is not the only source <strong>of</strong> this value. The gold standard, the source <strong>of</strong> value came from<br />

the labor necessary to the mine the gold or mainly the labor. Hans, you said in [415] ...<br />

Marx, by contrast, says that the value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed in the things<br />

one can buy, but this is not the source <strong>of</strong> this value. Under the gold standard,<br />

the source <strong>of</strong> money’s value was the labor necessary to mine the gold, and<br />

nowadays I think the source <strong>of</strong> the dollar’s international value is US monetary<br />

policy, backed by its military might which, among other things, is the<br />

ultimate reason for the agreement <strong>of</strong> Saudi Arabia to price oil in dollars.<br />

I think the expression <strong>of</strong> money appears without us noticing it, nothing to back it up.<br />

Hans: Your second sentence indicates that the expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money is one <strong>of</strong> the sources <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

This is wrong. The two must be distinguished.<br />

Next Message by Rampton is [664].<br />

[663] Papageorgio: When one speaks <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money it is important to know that<br />

the value is not expressed by just saying a price. The value <strong>of</strong> money truly is expressed by<br />

the things one can buy, not to say this is the source <strong>of</strong> value. This is not the source <strong>of</strong> value<br />

but is how it is expressed. The value <strong>of</strong> money is indeed being expressed when we exchange<br />

other commodities with money, I touched on this in my original answer. The money is<br />

able to be exchanged for all commodities not just a single commodity. When commodities<br />

are purchased with money it shows an example <strong>of</strong> the expression <strong>of</strong> money although it is<br />

imperative to realize the buyer is not the one choosing the amount <strong>of</strong> money it is the seller<br />

who chooses what can be bought. It can also be <strong>of</strong> help to remember that as I wrote earlier<br />

in the gold standard gold was money but gold actually had a value as well so gold actually<br />

the value is expressed in two different ways depending on how you look at gold as an regular


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 153<br />

commodity it is expressed in its price but if we regard it as money it is expressed the same as<br />

we have been talking about by it being able to be exchanged to purchase other commodities.<br />

Which is why I stated before that it is different than in our day as our money does not really<br />

have both aspects. So money is exchangeable to all commodities which is how its value is<br />

expressed.<br />

Hans: The “mint price” <strong>of</strong> gold is economically not a price; it simply defines how much gold is represented by a<br />

monetary unit. Otherwise your answer is good. It is <strong>of</strong>ten overlooked that the fact that money can buy everything<br />

is also an expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Next Message by Papageorgio is [665].<br />

[668] Bmellor: Money value. The value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed in its exchange value.<br />

Commodities are traded for the money you have. If the money buys a lot <strong>of</strong> commodities it<br />

is valuable, if it can’t you can still use it to make a fire, at the very least it is worth the fabric<br />

or paper it is printed on.<br />

Next Message by Bmellor is [669].<br />

[670] Scott: value <strong>of</strong> money. The value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed in the things you can buy<br />

with it. For example, if I have $100, it can be expressed in the commodities I choose to<br />

purchase, such as a playstation, bike, etc.. I agree with BeckySue “The value <strong>of</strong> money is<br />

expressed through its ability to be traded for any commodity by means <strong>of</strong> direct exchange”<br />

[2002fa:149]. The power <strong>of</strong> money is shown by its ability to be exchangeable for any commodity.<br />

Next Message by Scott is [671].<br />

[694] Ryoung: Value <strong>of</strong> Money. The value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed through that which it<br />

has the power to purchase. Money is only as good as the goods that one is able to buy with<br />

it. This is the one way in which the value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed.<br />

Hans: Your middle sentence, “money is only as good as the goods that one is able to buy with it,” is the neoclassical<br />

theory which tries to say that money itself is nothing, only the real goods count. Marx understands things differently.<br />

For him, money is not an idea but a real good. It has value because labor is necessary to dig the gold out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ground. This value is expressed through the goods it can buy. This does not mean it draws its value from those<br />

goods.<br />

Next Message by Ryoung is [695].<br />

[725] Paul: The value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed through the commodities that are bought<br />

with it. If a seller <strong>of</strong> chairs says that one chair can be bought with $30 then the value <strong>of</strong><br />

the chair was just expressed through the amount <strong>of</strong> money you can buy it. All commodities<br />

express their values in money, and because <strong>of</strong> this the value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed in these<br />

commodities and what commodities you can buy for an amount <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Hans: Your in-class answer had some useful clarifications; why didn’t you take them over into your resubmission?<br />

Paul: Yes, I probably should have added those. For the sake <strong>of</strong> the archives what I said in my in class answer is<br />

that if you were to have a $10 bill, you then know that with that money you could buy a hat with that money. But<br />

you also know that you will not be able to purchase a car with it. Just by the fact that you know that you cannot buy<br />

a car with a $10 bill, the money has then expressed its value.<br />

Next Message by Paul is [726].<br />

[728] Mick: graded C The value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed in its equivalent relation to other<br />

commodities (goods and services). This is why currencies are traded in pairs, because the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> one currency must be given in terms <strong>of</strong> another currency in order for you to understand<br />

its worth. If money was only worth what it cost to produce it, then we would not use it<br />

in transactions. We would simply use real commodities with inherent use values. Money’s<br />

value is effected not only by its equivalent value in another commodity, but it is also subject


154 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

to fluctuate in value based on supply and demand. The values between a commodity and<br />

money are perpetually defining, as well as perpetually changing.<br />

The value <strong>of</strong> money has both quantitative and qualitative properties. Its quantitative property<br />

is restricted by supply, but qualitatively it has no limit. Its value is manifest both as payment,<br />

and a means <strong>of</strong> purchase. As means <strong>of</strong> payment, it is the final <strong>of</strong> a two part transaction,<br />

where as a means <strong>of</strong> purchase it is required before the good/service can be acquired.<br />

Hans: In Marx’s time, under the gold standard, money was indeed worth what it costed to produce it, and it was<br />

nevertheless used in transactions. Otherwise I recognize elements <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory in your answer, but they do not<br />

hang together, and most <strong>of</strong> them are irrelevant for the question asked.<br />

Next Message by Mick is [730].<br />

[732] Wade: “The expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity in gold – x commodity A = y<br />

money commodity – is the commodity’s money form or its price.” Example if 300 pounds<br />

<strong>of</strong> tin = the value <strong>of</strong> 3 ounces <strong>of</strong> gold then whatever the exchange rate <strong>of</strong> money for gold<br />

for 3 ounces would buy you the 300 pounds <strong>of</strong> tin. Gold is the Character <strong>of</strong> Money...... The<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> money is that money can buy everything......<br />

Hans: At Marx’s time, there was no such thing as an “exchange rate <strong>of</strong> money for gold,” but money was gold.<br />

Next Message by Wade is [775].<br />

[733] Allen: The value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed by the amount <strong>of</strong> use-value it can purchase.<br />

Money in itself has no use-value, it is only used as a means to trade one commodity for<br />

another commodity. Money is usually backed by a standard (gold, Silver) to create its value.<br />

Once the value is established it is then used to trade for commodities for their use-value.<br />

Hans: Means <strong>of</strong> circulation is not the only function <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Next Message by Allen is [734].<br />

[737] Aaron: The value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed in being money itself. Marx points out that<br />

money does not have to do any work to establish its form <strong>of</strong> value, simply because money is<br />

money, and it can buy anything and is directly exchangeable. The simple fact that money can<br />

be used to exchange for any commodity and can buy anything is a simple expression <strong>of</strong> the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> money. The value <strong>of</strong> anything is not simply a statement about the price <strong>of</strong> certain<br />

commodities in the market, but can be an expression <strong>of</strong> the social nature <strong>of</strong> production and<br />

the exchange process. The value <strong>of</strong> the actual money can be expressed in the price <strong>of</strong> a<br />

certain basket <strong>of</strong> goods as well. In today’s market, we can value the money in the market<br />

by what it can be exchanged for over a period <strong>of</strong> time. As oil prices rise, the price <strong>of</strong> most<br />

goods in the market is also rising. We can see a certain aspect <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> our money<br />

deteriorating from a past value. This may be a result <strong>of</strong> the relationship in the production<br />

and social costs <strong>of</strong> goods.<br />

Hans: Instead <strong>of</strong> saying money is directly exchangeable because it is money, the right way to express Marx’s<br />

theory would be: gold is directly exchangeable because it is the commodity which by a social act has been selected<br />

as the commodity in which all other goods express their values.<br />

Next Message by Aaron is [738].<br />

[746] Ande: The expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money is simply an expanded form <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Money does not have to work to establish its form <strong>of</strong> value. The value <strong>of</strong> the money is<br />

already given. Since goods are shown by their values <strong>of</strong> money, or what they cost, money<br />

then becomes “directly exchangeable” for any good or service. In a sense money can buy<br />

anything. The value <strong>of</strong> money is given, a five dollar bill is worth five dollars and a one dollar<br />

bill is worth one dollar its value is given it is just expressed in different ways. Although the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 155<br />

value is given the value is not relative to other forms <strong>of</strong> currency/money, the dollar is not<br />

relative in value to the euro. Over all the expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money is just a drawn<br />

out explanation <strong>of</strong> value, and as we learned by reading the book, every good in the market<br />

place has some sort <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Hans: Your very last statement “every good in the market place has some sort <strong>of</strong> value” is ambiguous. It could<br />

be understood to mean that every good in the market place has a use-value for someone, because worthless goods<br />

would not be traded. But this is not what Marx means when he uses the word “value” by itself, without the “use-”<br />

prefix. The exchange process is a process <strong>of</strong> equalization, and “value,” as Marx uses the word, is that commonality<br />

in the commodities which is expressed by this exchange.<br />

Next Message by Ande is [747].<br />

[756] Wasatch: Money expresses its value through the commodities it purchases and<br />

has the ability to purchase. Hans mentions on page 239 <strong>of</strong> our handbook that “money can<br />

buy everything is” and the fact that it can is “a powerful expression <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> money.”<br />

Money expresses its value through all commodities because “all [commodities] express their<br />

values in money” (Hans notes on pg. 239) And because the origin <strong>of</strong> a commodity’s usevalue<br />

and exchange value is something that is inherent we can see how money expresses its<br />

value through the commodity.<br />

During the gold standard era money’s value was also expressed by gold. This gold had<br />

use and exchange value. After the gold standard period money is left on its own which is<br />

why it can only express it’s value by the commodities it can purchase.<br />

CousinIt said in [577] that “Money enables the sale and purchase and <strong>of</strong> all other commodities<br />

by way <strong>of</strong> its form <strong>of</strong> value as the general equivalent”. This form <strong>of</strong> value is unique<br />

from other commodities “by the fact that it bears the stamp <strong>of</strong> social approval” (Hans [580]).<br />

This is what I call the social standard, which is as effective as the gold standard as far as<br />

giving money this form <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Hans: The expression <strong>of</strong> value and the source <strong>of</strong> value are two different things. A person may express his drunkenness<br />

by singing; but the source <strong>of</strong> his drunkenness is drinking, not singing. Modern theories which say that money<br />

does not need a source <strong>of</strong> value, that everyone just accepts money by social agreement, would be considered by<br />

Marx as irrealist as the explanation <strong>of</strong> babies by storks.<br />

Next Message by Wasatch is [757].<br />

[760] Brody: The value <strong>of</strong> money is defined by what can be purchased by that amount <strong>of</strong><br />

money. Such as in the Mcdonald’s commercials where a dollar is not defined as a dollar it is<br />

one double cheeseburger. This is a prime example <strong>of</strong> money being defined by the commodities<br />

it can purchase. The fact that money can buy everything is a powerful expression <strong>of</strong> the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Next Message by Brody is [776].<br />

[823] Bar: content B– late penalty 9% The value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed as a commodity<br />

that it represents. True, money des have a value relative to other currency as itself is a<br />

commodity, but the difference is the use-value <strong>of</strong> money which is very low. The value <strong>of</strong><br />

money is therefore expressed in relative terms. In addition to the before said, the value <strong>of</strong><br />

money is expressed in terms <strong>of</strong> society in many ways like commodity fetishism where social<br />

relation are dependent on money, for example a women marries a man because he has a lot<br />

<strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Hans: The use-value <strong>of</strong> gold is not low: its high conductivity and resistence to corrosion are very valuable properties.<br />

But this physical use-value is overshadowed by its use-value as the general equivalent, and modern money<br />

can do without physical use-value altogether.


156 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Under the gold standard, the value <strong>of</strong> money comes from gold (since money was exchangeable into a set amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> gold), but its expression is not the same as its source.<br />

Next Message by Bar is [824].<br />

Question 391 is 251 in 1997sp, 251 in 1998WI, 261 in 1999SP, 287 in 2001fa, and 380 in<br />

2007SP:<br />

Question 391 If the price <strong>of</strong> 1 ton <strong>of</strong> iron is 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold, why can the owner <strong>of</strong> the iron<br />

not use his ton <strong>of</strong> iron to “buy” whatever costs 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold?<br />

[591] Goethe: To use the ton <strong>of</strong> iron to purchase whatever costs one ounce <strong>of</strong> gold, we<br />

would need pro<strong>of</strong> that the labor put into the iron is socially necessary. The pro<strong>of</strong> is the social<br />

stamp <strong>of</strong> approval that is represented by money exchanged for the gold or iron. The money<br />

allows us to transfer the “social approval” to the sellers <strong>of</strong> the commodities we want. [580]<br />

Next Message by Hans is [596].<br />

[643] Inter: Iron and Gold. The reason why 1 ton <strong>of</strong> iron cannot buy what 1 ounce <strong>of</strong><br />

gold can is because iron does not have the social stamp <strong>of</strong> approval to act as the general<br />

equivalent. Both gold and iron have value and use-value but iron lacks the social recognition<br />

as the general equivalent. Being a general equivalent is one <strong>of</strong> the necessary aspects <strong>of</strong><br />

money.<br />

Hans: I’d like you to look at it from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> social organization <strong>of</strong> production, not the market. Iron<br />

contains labor, and this labor gives the iron producer the right to access the labor <strong>of</strong> others. But before it can do<br />

this, the labor in the iron needs to be certified that it is indeed socially necessary labor. This happens by the sale <strong>of</strong><br />

iron, which turns iron into gold.<br />

Next Message by Inter is [644].<br />

[674] Jeremy: If the price <strong>of</strong> 1 ton <strong>of</strong> iron is 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold, the iron does not have the<br />

ability to buy whatever costs 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold. This is due to a couple <strong>of</strong> reasons, first, gold<br />

is the measure <strong>of</strong> value and also has the option <strong>of</strong> being exchangeable as money. Gold is<br />

in circulation, therefore it can be used to buy products. Secondly, the owner could barter<br />

his iron for another commodity, but he cannot demand someone take his iron as a form <strong>of</strong><br />

payment because they may have no need for it or do not see it as an exchangeable item for<br />

their commodity. As stated before, gold measures value and acts as money, iron is merely a<br />

commodity that is measured by gold and does not take the form <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Next Message by Jeremy is [675].<br />

[688] FacistFrank: The more abstract Marxian answer would be that the ton <strong>of</strong> iron needs<br />

to prove that it is worth the ounce <strong>of</strong> gold, but to me this seems an impossible contradiction,<br />

because it has to exchanged for the value in other goods in order to prove itself, it think this<br />

is an example <strong>of</strong> dialectic materialism, that Marx adapted from Hegel. The contradiction<br />

is inherent unavoidable, and also serves to justify it. But maybe I don’t have a complete<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> this Marxian point. The more practical explanation to me is, the value in<br />

the ton <strong>of</strong> iron needs to enter a liquid and practical form in order to be exchanged in most<br />

cases, liquid and perhaps exchangeable. I believe this is an example <strong>of</strong> the expanded form<br />

<strong>of</strong> value.<br />

I would not like or accept payment for my labor in tons <strong>of</strong> iron, I would not be able to<br />

store it, and would have a very hard time reselling it. Only the people that need iron would<br />

be willing to be paid in iron. We need liquid and practically exchangeable money or even<br />

gold. A representation <strong>of</strong> value deprived <strong>of</strong> its bodily form and use value.


Message [688] referenced by [693]. Next Message by FacistFrank is [689].<br />

[700] Sparky: 1 ton iron = 1 ounce gold<br />

1 ounce gold= 1 ton cotton<br />

t ton iron (not =) to 1 ton cotton<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 157<br />

The reason 1 ton <strong>of</strong> iron cannot be used to “buy” whatever costs 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold, in my<br />

example 1 ton <strong>of</strong> cotton, because iron is not viewed as the general equivalent that gold is<br />

viewed as, since as the annotations say “the dominant role <strong>of</strong> money ... deprives the other<br />

commodities <strong>of</strong> the capacity to serve as the expressions <strong>of</strong> value themselves.” [p. 258]<br />

You cannot force someone to take your iron just because it may be worth 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold<br />

– that person may not have a use value for iron but would for gold because he would see the<br />

use value <strong>of</strong> the gold as the general equivalent, as that being easier to exchange for goods<br />

and services.<br />

Next Message by Sparky is [702].<br />

[711] Raynold: Given the process by which gold has been turned into the measure <strong>of</strong><br />

value and exchange-value into price, all commodities when expressed in their prices are<br />

merely imagined quantities <strong>of</strong> gold <strong>of</strong> various magnitudes. Since they are thus various quantities<br />

<strong>of</strong> the same thing, namely gold, they are similar, comparable and commensurable,<br />

and thus arises the technical necessity <strong>of</strong> relating them to a definite quantity <strong>of</strong> gold as a<br />

unit <strong>of</strong> measure. This unit <strong>of</strong> measure then develops into a scale <strong>of</strong> measure by being divided<br />

into aliquot parts which are in turn subdivided into aliquot parts. [2] The quantities<br />

<strong>of</strong> gold themselves, however, are measured by weight. The standard weights generally used<br />

for metals accordingly provide ready-made standard measures, which originally also served<br />

as standard measures <strong>of</strong> price wherever metallic currency was in use. Since commodities<br />

are no longer compared as exchange-values which are measured in terms <strong>of</strong> labour-time,<br />

but as magnitudes <strong>of</strong> the same denomination measured in terms <strong>of</strong> gold, gold, the measure<br />

<strong>of</strong> value, becomes the standard <strong>of</strong> price. The comparison <strong>of</strong> commodity-prices in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

different quantities <strong>of</strong> gold thus becomes crystallised in figures denoting imaginary quantities<br />

<strong>of</strong> gold and representing gold as a standard measure divided into aliquot parts. Gold<br />

as measure <strong>of</strong> value and as standard <strong>of</strong> price has quite distinct specific functions, and the<br />

confusion <strong>of</strong> the one with the other has led to the most absurd theories. Gold as materialised<br />

labour-time is a measure <strong>of</strong> value, as a piece <strong>of</strong> metal <strong>of</strong> definite weight it is the standard<br />

<strong>of</strong> price. Gold becomes the measure <strong>of</strong> value because as an exchange-value it is compared<br />

with the exchange-values <strong>of</strong> other commodities; in its aspect as a standard <strong>of</strong> price a definite<br />

quantity <strong>of</strong> gold serves as a unit for other quantities <strong>of</strong> gold. Gold is the measure <strong>of</strong> value<br />

because its value is variable; it is the standard <strong>of</strong> price because it has been established as an<br />

invariable unit <strong>of</strong> weight. Here, as in all cases <strong>of</strong> measuring quantities <strong>of</strong> the same denomination,<br />

stability and exactitude <strong>of</strong> the proportions is essential. The necessity <strong>of</strong> establishing<br />

a quantity <strong>of</strong> gold as the unit <strong>of</strong> measure and its aliquot parts as subdivisions <strong>of</strong> this unit has<br />

given rise to the idea that a fixed ratio <strong>of</strong> values has been set up between a definite quantity<br />

<strong>of</strong> gold, whose value is <strong>of</strong> course variable, and the exchange-values <strong>of</strong> commodities. But<br />

such a view simply ignores the fact that the exchange-values <strong>of</strong> commodities are turned into<br />

prices, into quantities <strong>of</strong> gold, before gold becomes the standard <strong>of</strong> price. Quite irrespective<br />

<strong>of</strong> any changes in the value <strong>of</strong> gold, different quantities <strong>of</strong> gold will always represent the


158 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

same ratio <strong>of</strong> values with regard to one another. lf the value <strong>of</strong> gold should fall by 1,000 per<br />

cent, then the value <strong>of</strong> twelve ounces <strong>of</strong> gold would still be twelve times bigger than that <strong>of</strong><br />

one ounce <strong>of</strong> gold, and so far as prices are concerned what matters is only the proportion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the different quantities <strong>of</strong> gold to one another. Since, on the other hand, a rise or fall in<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> an ounce <strong>of</strong> gold does not in any way affect its weight, the weight <strong>of</strong> its aliquot<br />

parts remains likewise unaffected; gold can thus always serve as a stable standard <strong>of</strong> price,<br />

regardless <strong>of</strong> any changes in its value. [3]<br />

Karl Marx<br />

Hans: I need to hear your own voice, so that I can tell whether you understand it. And the Marx quote you<br />

downloaded is not very relevant to the question at hand.<br />

Next Message by Raynold is [777].<br />

[714] JPeel: graded A The owner <strong>of</strong> iron cannot use his ton <strong>of</strong> iron to “buy” whatever<br />

costs 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold because in order to be considered an exchange-value, the gold must<br />

strip itself <strong>of</strong> its natural physical form. It cannot transform itself from something imaginary<br />

into something real. A commodity may possess a certain value shape in the form <strong>of</strong> its price,<br />

but cannot be both real iron and real gold at the same time.<br />

Next Message by JPeel is [715].<br />

[717] Carterryan: Ain’t Nothing but a Golddigger. Gold has a unique value compared<br />

to other things in a bartering equation. Gold is a universally accepted form <strong>of</strong> currency,<br />

whereas all other metals are not. Iron in this case changes due to a demand-cost basis. Let’s<br />

say that the cost <strong>of</strong> 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold is equivalent to the cost 14 ounces <strong>of</strong> silver, but the<br />

market comparison for iron to silver is 1 ton <strong>of</strong> iron for 10 ounces <strong>of</strong> silver.<br />

All <strong>of</strong> the economic factors come into play here. There is just less demand for iron in<br />

the comparison to silver and gold. Gold and silver have a higher demand and thus are worth<br />

more than iron and that is why a straight trade is not reasonable<br />

Hans: This is a completely naive explanation which does not take advantage <strong>of</strong> any scientific insights, neither<br />

mainstream nor Marxian economics.<br />

Next Message by Carterryan is [775].<br />

[721] Rey: graded A The owner <strong>of</strong> the iron cannot use his 1-ton <strong>of</strong> iron to “buy” whatever<br />

costs 1 ounce <strong>of</strong> gold because it is necessary for the iron “must be converted into money<br />

[or the general equivalent] before it can act as exchange-value itself.” Although the 1-ton <strong>of</strong><br />

iron holds what Marx calls an “imagined gold shape” it is necessary for the iron owner to<br />

actually replace his iron with gold before he is able to purchase other commodities. This is<br />

necessary because iron has not been designated as the general equivalent. In summary iron<br />

in its natural state has not received the social stamp <strong>of</strong> approval as the socially valid manner<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchange and must be converted to such in order to purchase other commodities.<br />

Hans: The gap between general equivalent and ordinary values is not as great as you make it out. Being a general<br />

equivalent is a form <strong>of</strong> value, every commodity that contains value could conceivably be a general equivalent. The<br />

labor which produces gold is not any better than the labor which produces iron. The only difference is that the<br />

labor which produces the gold represents a commodity that was sold, i.e., whose labor has proven to be socially<br />

necessary. That’s why gold has the privileged position <strong>of</strong> a general equivalent.<br />

Next Message by Rey is [818].<br />

[761] Samantha: Hamburgers and Iron. Marx discusses this in two different ways<br />

throughout his text, firstly he describes how transactions occur which brings him to point<br />

out that in capitalist societies there is a formula for goods – C-M-C. That while use-value


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 159<br />

doesn’t changes with a commodity, the direct barter system is not allowed in the structure<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalists. It must go commodity – money – commodity. Hans explained the thinking <strong>of</strong><br />

this relationship in terms <strong>of</strong> $1 hamburgers, you could not exchange one thousand one-dollar<br />

burgers for a car.<br />

After a structural recognition, Marx also mentions the value <strong>of</strong> money which is the agreed<br />

upon number by capitalists, it is not use value or labor value but something else which was<br />

constructed by capitalists. This is why the exchange cannot happen because value is defined<br />

by money, which is determined by the bourgeoisie.<br />

As Dabears mentions in Sp2007, there is another main reason, which I failed to explain,<br />

that explains this relationship. During Marx time period gold was a recognized “medium<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchange”. This is a structure recognition that Marx gives, in a non bartering economy,<br />

where there is a standard object <strong>of</strong> exchange whether it be the dollar or an ounce <strong>of</strong> gold,<br />

it is recognized by everyone what the value <strong>of</strong> a dollar is, that is not the same with other<br />

goods. Though hamburgers may be a dollar in cost, another person evaluating their value<br />

may recognize them as higher or lower, but regardless will not accept them as an exchangeable<br />

good.<br />

Hans: One <strong>of</strong> the main points <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory is that the difference between money and commodities is not as<br />

great as is commonly assumed.<br />

Next Message by Samantha is [762].<br />

Question 394 is 389 in 2007fa, 410 in 2009fa, 427 in 2011fa, and 445 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 394 Describe the contradictory and mutually exclusive relationships in the process<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchanging commodities.<br />

[430] Inter: The exchange process contradiction. The contradiction occurs as a result<br />

<strong>of</strong> trying to satisfy two different goals. These goals are: 1) exchange my product for another<br />

product that has a use-value that fulfills my needs, and 2) exchange my product for another<br />

product(s) with equal relative value. These goals are mutually exclusive because if I satisfy<br />

goal one, then it precludes goal two.<br />

For example, a potter has created a bowl to exchange on the market. The potter has the<br />

option <strong>of</strong> exchanging his bowl for 5 pounds <strong>of</strong> potatoes; the use-value <strong>of</strong> which, best satisfy<br />

his needs. However, if the potter makes this deal, he feels as though his bowl would be<br />

under-valued because other bowls have sold for 15 pounds <strong>of</strong> potatoes. If the potter still<br />

makes the deal, then he will have pursued the results <strong>of</strong> goal one. Let us assume that the<br />

potter does not make the deal for the 5 pounds <strong>of</strong> potatoes because he believes it is a rip-<strong>of</strong>f.<br />

Instead the potter approaches a weaver who <strong>of</strong>fers him 10 yards <strong>of</strong> wool for his bowl. The<br />

potter feels this is a good deal because other bowls have sold for 10 yards <strong>of</strong> wool. However,<br />

the potter is hungry not cold and therefore the use-value that best satisfies his needs is not<br />

being met by obtaining wool. If the potter decides to make this deal, he will be pursuing<br />

the results <strong>of</strong> goal two. This is mutually exclusive because if the potter decides to get the<br />

potatoes, he cannot at the same time, gain equal relative value for his bowl. If the potter<br />

decides to gain equal relative value for his bowl, then he is unable to gain product that best<br />

satisfies his needs.<br />

Next Message by Inter is [517].


160 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Question 397 is 330 in 2003fa, 370 in 2004fa, 364 in 2005fa, 386 in 2007SP, 398 in<br />

2008fa, 413 in 2009fa, 444 in 2010fa, and 453 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 397 The empirical appearance <strong>of</strong> the processes <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase encourages<br />

a naive mistake, which makes it difficult to understand the metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Which mistake?<br />

[417] Srichardson: graded A Metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> the commodity. The mistake that is<br />

made here was a hard one for me to understand. The mistake is looking at market transaction<br />

as one <strong>of</strong> bartering and exchange. When I think <strong>of</strong> a market transaction involving paper<br />

money in my normal everyday thought process I see the exchange <strong>of</strong> my money for a good<br />

that I want. For example at lunch I <strong>of</strong>ten feel that I exchange a five dollar bill for a sandwich.<br />

This is an example <strong>of</strong> the “process <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase.” I fall into the mistake <strong>of</strong> looking at<br />

is as barter. This is where the mistake is made and makes the metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> commodity<br />

hard to understand.<br />

When you look at this transaction as barter or trade, as I <strong>of</strong>ten do it is incorrect. Paper<br />

money has no real use value, it holds value but not use value. This is the difference between<br />

a barter transaction and a sale and purchase transaction.<br />

Message [417] referenced by [419]. Next Message by Srichardson is [473].<br />

[419] Hans: Are You – Gasp – Bartering Money? Srichardson [417] used to look at<br />

sales and purchases as exchanges <strong>of</strong> money for the good. After reading Marx she knows that<br />

this is the wrong way to look at it, because money does not really have use-value.<br />

My answer is: relax, you are not doing anything wrong. Here are the steps <strong>of</strong> my argument,<br />

numbered (1) to (6):<br />

(1) As a practical act, a sale and purchase is indeed an exchange between two things: the<br />

dollar bill and the commodity.<br />

(2) Marx doesn’t intend to tell the practical agents how to look at their transaction. Rather<br />

he says: “The thought processes which go into the exchange between a dollar bill and the<br />

commodity are different from those going into an direct barter between commodities.”<br />

(3) Srichardson did not tell us how she got the dollar bills she exchanged for the lunch<br />

sandwich. Let’s assume she got it from the sale <strong>of</strong> labor, which is the only commodity<br />

most <strong>of</strong> us have to sell. The barter equivalent <strong>of</strong> her purchase <strong>of</strong> a lunch sandwich would<br />

therefore be: Srichardson negotiates with the cashier at the lunch counter and they come to<br />

the following agreement: Srichardson does the dishes for 20 minutes and gets a tuna fish<br />

sandwich in exchange.<br />

(4) Here Srichardson has to decide: (a) do I really want a tuna fish sandwich or would<br />

I prefer a Cesar salad today? (b) is 20 minutes too much for this crummy sandwich? (c)<br />

is 20 minutes doubly too much in view that this is a booming economy and there is a labor<br />

shortage? (d) do I feel like doing the dishes or would I prefer to mop the floor or peel potatoes<br />

what the other restaurant needs me to do? Her thoughts are torn back and forth between the<br />

values and the use-values <strong>of</strong> both the commodity she is giving and she is receiving.<br />

(5) With money, the situation is much simpler. The only decision she has to make at the<br />

lunch counter is: do I really want to spend 5 dollars for this crummy sandwich, or shall I


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 161<br />

go to the other restaurant which has a special on Cesar Salad? The decision whether to peel<br />

potatoes instead, or whether the labor shortage entitles her to a higher salary is not made at<br />

the lunch counter, but this decision was made earlier when she sold her labor-power to her<br />

employer.<br />

(6) Marx looks at these practical activities and tries to understand the underlying social<br />

relations which lead people to do what they are doing. He says: money streamlines things<br />

so beautifully because the exchange for money is not really the exchange for another commodity.<br />

Rather it is just a form change <strong>of</strong> the commodity which you already have. When<br />

Srichardson negotiated with her employer, she turned her commodity, her labor, from its<br />

use-value form into its value-form, and now at the lunch counter, she turns her commodity<br />

back into use-value – with the big difference that this time it is a use-value which she needs.<br />

To say it again: although it is a physical exchange between the dollar bill and the tuna<br />

sandwich, the underlying thought processes are not the same as those necessary in a barter<br />

<strong>of</strong> two commodities. Srichardson does not have to think <strong>of</strong> the use-value <strong>of</strong> the dollar bill,<br />

because the dollar bill acts as value independent <strong>of</strong> any use-value. Srichardson is right to<br />

say that the dollar bill holds value: it is the value form <strong>of</strong> the commodity she sold, namely <strong>of</strong><br />

her labor. Srichardson is also right to say that the dollar bill is lacking use-value. The dollar<br />

bill is her labor commodity with its use-value erased, so that only the value remains, ready<br />

to have a new use-value written into it.<br />

In general, please note: Marx’s Capital is not a prescription how a market economy<br />

should work or what people should do in a market economy, but an analysis <strong>of</strong> the hidden<br />

things happening while people go about their ordinary business in a capitalist market<br />

economy.<br />

Message [419] referenced by [422], [727], and [2009fa:585]. Next Message by Hans is [426].<br />

[606] Trailrunner: graded A– The mistake is looking at money as a use-value. Usevalue<br />

comes from the labor that is sold during the production <strong>of</strong> a commodity. In return,<br />

money is received for this labor and the use-value is erased. With the independent value<br />

that is now held in the money, an individual can take this money and use it to purchase<br />

another commodity. Money allows a streamlining <strong>of</strong> things because it is a much more simple<br />

transaction than trying to think about the values and the use-values <strong>of</strong> the commodities being<br />

given and received.<br />

Next Message by Trailrunner is [607].<br />

[706] Gerund: The processes <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase make it appear that prices are set by<br />

ubiquitous market forces, supply and demand. This makes it difficult to recognize that prices<br />

are determined by the value <strong>of</strong> the socially necessary labor. Quantity is set by demand, prices<br />

by supply – the value <strong>of</strong> the labor needed to supply the demanded quantity.<br />

Hans: Commodity-value is not set by the value <strong>of</strong> labor but by the labor content itself. This is not the naive mistake<br />

Marx was talking about, but it is an intelligent answer to the question.<br />

Next Message by Gerund is [707].<br />

[722] Tim: graded A The mistake that is made that makes it hard to understand the metamorphosis<br />

<strong>of</strong> a commodity during a sale and purchase is that <strong>of</strong> viewing the transaction as an<br />

exchange or a barter process <strong>of</strong> two commodities. The fact <strong>of</strong> the matter is that when an item<br />

is sold and purchased the items are not exchanged but they are changed as to the form that


162 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

they hold. If the transaction is viewed by looking at the form <strong>of</strong> the commodities then the<br />

concepts will not be viewed correctly because people treat purchases and barters differently.<br />

Hans: The difference between an exchange <strong>of</strong> two commodities and a form change <strong>of</strong> one commodity is that in the<br />

exchange, two commodities are involved, but in a form change, only one. The money does not count as a separate<br />

commodity, but as a different form <strong>of</strong> the commodity that is sold.<br />

Message [722] referenced by [2009fa:1039]. Next Message by Tim is [723].<br />

[727] Spawnblade: The naive mistake encouraged by the empirical appearance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

processes <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase is the likening <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase to bartering. This is<br />

because the nature <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase is seen as one exchange instead <strong>of</strong> the two separate<br />

ones it really is. According to Hans [419], Marx does not believe we’re doing anything<br />

‘wrong’ by this, he’s just pointing out that the thought processes that go into the two are<br />

different.<br />

Looking at it from the perspective <strong>of</strong> a single transaction, and viewing money as a commodity<br />

(instead <strong>of</strong> what it really is - money) it is easy to see where the mistake is made.<br />

Bartering is the direct exchange <strong>of</strong> one commodity/use-value for another commodity/usevalue.<br />

When comparing this to the indirect exchange using money, it is clear that these are<br />

two different systems in regards to their relations with the commodity.<br />

Hans: Your sentence “the nature <strong>of</strong> sale and purchase is seen as one exchange instead <strong>of</strong> the two separate ones it<br />

really is” does not make sense to me. If anything, sale or purchase should be considered half an exchange, not two<br />

exchanges.<br />

In your second paragraph you use the formulation “it is easy to see” and “it is clear” but you are not explaining<br />

what is so easy and clear. Imagine yourself writing the book “Marx for Dummies.”<br />

Next Message by Spawnblade is [729].<br />

[741] Dentist: The common mistake made here is misinterpreting the sale and purchase<br />

process as a bartering exchange. Under the bartering exchange, a use-value is traded for a<br />

use-value, whereas the sale and purchase process takes the form <strong>of</strong> use-value in substitution<br />

for a value.<br />

In our system, money is not a commodity because it no longer has a use-value written<br />

into it. Rather, it is merely the holder or representation <strong>of</strong> previously established value and is<br />

waiting for a new use-value to be assigned. All in order to have it erased yet again and then<br />

re-written through an infinite series <strong>of</strong> substitutions known as the sale and purchase process.<br />

Next Message by Dentist is [766].<br />

Question 401 is 279 in 2000fa, 318 in 2002fa, 373 in 2004fa, 390 in 2007SP, 396 in<br />

2007fa, and 402 in 2008fa:<br />

Question 401 Compare the sale <strong>of</strong> a commodity, i.e., its exchange for money, with the barter<br />

<strong>of</strong> two ordinary commodities.<br />

[422] Rmuscolino: The sale <strong>of</strong> a commodity, or its exchange for money, depends on<br />

the commodity’s value or what we call the “price” <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Money or “price”<br />

is a measure <strong>of</strong> value. There’s a barter <strong>of</strong> two ordinary commodities, where both should<br />

have the same exchange-values. “A barter is a type <strong>of</strong> trade that doesn’t use any medium <strong>of</strong><br />

exchange, in which goods and services are exchanged for other goods and/or services. It can<br />

be bilateral or multilateral as trade” (wikipedia.com). The disembodiment <strong>of</strong> the original<br />

commodity form is effected by the sale <strong>of</strong> the commodity 203:2. Bartering is a balance <strong>of</strong><br />

economic trade. The exchange <strong>of</strong> a certain commodity for other commodities at its source


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 163<br />

<strong>of</strong> production, money is the disembodied shape <strong>of</strong> its commodity, which is the product <strong>of</strong> a<br />

sale.<br />

Hans: I added the reference for the sentence with the disembodiment. That sentence implies that the sale <strong>of</strong> the<br />

commodity is a form change <strong>of</strong> the commodity, see my [419] what this means.<br />

Regarding your next sentence, “bartering is a balance <strong>of</strong> economic trade,” a better formulation might be that<br />

bartering tries to balance the realization <strong>of</strong> value and selection <strong>of</strong> use-value for both traders, but these goals are<br />

contradictory and cannot be balanced. The best way to do justice to such contradictory goals is to split the barter<br />

into two transactions, sale and purchase, each specializing on one <strong>of</strong> the goals.<br />

If you ask what this contradiction consists in, there is a little bit about this in [2007SP:387], but the archives contain<br />

more detailed discussions in the earlier years, a good starting point may by my [1996sp:268] or KALISPEL’s<br />

[1996sp:304].<br />

Next Message by Rmuscolino is [432].<br />

[428] Hans: A Sale or Purchase is Half a Barter. If you look at it from the form side,<br />

as Marx wants us to do, a sale / purchase is the realization <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

sold for the seller, and the selection <strong>of</strong> the use-value for the money in the buyer’s hands. It<br />

satisfies therefore one function for the seller and one function for the buyer.<br />

A barter is a transaction which satisfies not one but two contradictory functions for each<br />

<strong>of</strong> the traders: for each <strong>of</strong> the traders, it must at the same time be the realization <strong>of</strong> the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity given in exchange, and the selection <strong>of</strong> the use-value into which this value<br />

is to be reconverted. I.e., a barter has altogether four functions (two for each <strong>of</strong> the traders),<br />

while the sale-purchase has only two function (one for the seller, one for the buyer).<br />

Since the two functions which the barter has for each <strong>of</strong> the traders are contradictory with<br />

each other, it is little wonder that barter transactions tend to split up into sales and purchases.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [433].<br />

Question 403 is 294 in 2001fa, 334 in 2003fa, 374 in 2004fa, 369 in 2005fa, and 391 in<br />

2007SP:<br />

Question 403 Do you purchase something with money or with the value <strong>of</strong> money?<br />

[418] Chris: could money’s value primarily be defined by a society? From a first<br />

glance by an unknowing outsider, it would appear that we are simply purchasing commodities.<br />

However, there is very specific value within these commodities that we are purchasing.<br />

Referencing Hans’ discussion <strong>of</strong> Marx and monetary expression in [415], ‘the value <strong>of</strong><br />

money is expressed in the things one can buy, but this is not the source <strong>of</strong> this value.” The<br />

source <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> commodities lies deep within their use-values, exchange-values, and<br />

the human labor needed in the production.<br />

We constantly see many factors that contribute to the overall value <strong>of</strong> our money. For example,<br />

the U.S. dollar is very weak compared to the Euro at the moment. Our dollar’s value<br />

apparently is worth less due to many macroeconomic factors. Because <strong>of</strong> this weakening,<br />

we hear on the radio, television, etc. that we should spend our money on commodities that<br />

we may not ‘need’ to revive a dismal economy. This leads us to what I think is the largest<br />

scale <strong>of</strong> value, money, and the commodity. The society.<br />

Society can dictate what money’s value should be. For example, there is status value in<br />

BMW cars along with specific clothing brands (Calvin Klein, Ralph Lauren come to mind).<br />

Money can purchase similar items with less money but without the ‘popular’ brand names.


164 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

These commodities (cars and clothing items) all have the same use-value. Common sense<br />

tells us to spend more on the commodity that does a better job, not spend money on the<br />

commodity that has a ‘better’ brand name. This leads me back to my original theory that<br />

society plays a huge dictation on money’s value.<br />

In conclusion, I feel that we purchase items with the value <strong>of</strong> money. Both on the smallest<br />

scale (value within commodities through use-value, exchange-value) and then again on the<br />

large scale <strong>of</strong> society’s hierarchy <strong>of</strong> value (purchasing brand name items). People have<br />

differing opinions on how their own money’s value should be used based on these scales<br />

along with current income stream, needs, and wants. However, I would personally like to<br />

see society placing less ‘value’ on commodities with specific brand names. It just does not<br />

make sense to me.<br />

Hans: By “value <strong>of</strong> money” you understand “what money can buy,” and you say this is, but should not be, determined<br />

by social fads and convention. Marx’s concept <strong>of</strong> “value <strong>of</strong> money” is, under the gold standard, the labor<br />

going into producing the gold coins. See [2005fa:1001] how this question can be answered using these concepts.<br />

Message [418] referenced by [421] and [577]. Next Message by Chris is [473].<br />

[421] Dyoung: Money is Both. As money is spent in the market as a purchase, the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> money becomes known as it is exchanged for other commodities. Hans [415] said that<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> money is expressed in the things that one can buy, but this is not the source <strong>of</strong><br />

the value. I would agree with Chris [418] in that the source <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> a commodity does lie<br />

with in its use-value, exchange value and the human labor needed to produce the commodity.<br />

It seems to me that the only use-value <strong>of</strong> money is that you can exchange it for things. It is<br />

the only item I can think <strong>of</strong> that can be both a use-value and an exchange value to a buyer<br />

and a seller. So unlike Chris I think that you purchase something with money and with the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Hans: If I understand you right, you say: since money can buy everything, it is the only commodity which has<br />

use-value for everyone, And because it has this use-value, it is accepted by everyone in exchange, i.e., it can buy<br />

everything. This sounds circular to me: money can buy everything because it can buy everything.<br />

Next Message by Dyoung is [520].<br />

[423] JPeel: graded D “Money is any token or other object that functions as a medium<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchange that is socially and legally accepted in payment for goods and services and<br />

in settlement <strong>of</strong> debts” (Wikipedia.com). You purchase something with both money and<br />

with the value <strong>of</strong> money. Since dollar bills are which symbolize the value <strong>of</strong> money we<br />

incorporate both when purchasing an item or service. We have to consider the fact that we<br />

use paper as our form <strong>of</strong> money or “value.” So when we buy something we use both forms.<br />

The value <strong>of</strong> money is based on the exchange value and use value. Actual money, such as a<br />

paper dollar bill, is a form <strong>of</strong> concrete value. While the value <strong>of</strong> money is an internal value<br />

and is expressed through the use value. We will only purchase something if it has value to<br />

our personal being, but, that item or commodity must be purchased with the actual paper bill<br />

<strong>of</strong> money. In this case, we are using both money, and the value <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Hans: The Wikipedia definition <strong>of</strong> money is not the same as Marx’s definition. Marx lived under the gold standard.<br />

Money was not just a symbol <strong>of</strong> value, but it had value, it either was gold coin or it gave the holder a claim on gold.<br />

What you say about value, internal value, value to our personal being, is also in a different framework than Marx’s.<br />

Message [423] referenced by [454]. Next Message by JPeel is [478].<br />

[424] FacistFrank: Money is Pure Glowing Value. The way I took it from the readings<br />

was that you purchase things with the value (measured in time, skill, and exertion) <strong>of</strong><br />

your labor, and that value is represented in the commodity you produce, which is in turn


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 165<br />

represented in the money you get for the labor you do and commodity you make. Money<br />

is a representation <strong>of</strong> pure liquid value (labor) and you go around with your pure glowing<br />

value (money) and say “I would like to buy that other glowing value” (the value in a T-shirt).<br />

I’m thinking <strong>of</strong> it like the briefcase in pulp fiction, it just helps me to relate to it better, lol.<br />

Money’s use value is that it represents pure value, but only because society says so, this is a<br />

social construct. Of course I would like to be corrected if I am wrong, rather be wrong today<br />

and right for the rest <strong>of</strong> my life, than wrong for the rest <strong>of</strong> my life. Also in our capitalist<br />

society, some steal this worth from others and make the rest <strong>of</strong> society think that it is actually<br />

theirs when it belongs to someone else.<br />

Hans: This are good formulations which are right on target, but it would be interesting to say something about how<br />

money became the representation <strong>of</strong> “pure glowing value.”<br />

Message [424] referenced by [577]. Next Message by FacistFrank is [573].<br />

[577] CousinIt: graded A the value <strong>of</strong> money. It seems that this question has proved to<br />

be a difficult one for us to get our heads around, myself included. In going back over the<br />

archives <strong>of</strong> the previous answers to this question, I am going to attempt my own interpretation.<br />

The answers from this semester seem to be attempting an understanding, dancing<br />

around the concept, some closer to, others farther from Marx’s interpretation/meaning.<br />

In the archives, Hans states repeatedly that it is the ‘form <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> money’ that enables<br />

the purchase. Even this was difficult to get my head around. After pondering this, subsequent<br />

to going over the answers and Hans’ responses in the archives, I think that I have come up<br />

with a way to say this that makes it understandable to me, though it may or may not be<br />

helpful to others.<br />

Whether or not money as paper or money as gold has any value does not really matter<br />

because it is not the value <strong>of</strong> money that enables the purchase <strong>of</strong> commodities. Rather, it is<br />

the implication <strong>of</strong> social agreement (building on Chris’ [418]) that money represents, as the<br />

commodity socially accepted as the general or universal equivalent and as an indicator <strong>of</strong><br />

the validated and affirmed socially necessary labor in the production <strong>of</strong> commodities.<br />

Money (as the representation <strong>of</strong> the relative value <strong>of</strong> all other commodities through its<br />

social stamp <strong>of</strong> approval <strong>of</strong> the labor-created form <strong>of</strong> value <strong>of</strong> the commodity form metamorpized<br />

into the general equivalent form) enables the sale and purchase <strong>of</strong> all other commodities<br />

by way <strong>of</strong> its ‘form <strong>of</strong> value’ as the general equivalent (FacistFrank’s [424] “pure<br />

glowing value”), and not by way <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the (gold or paper) money in itself.<br />

I hope this helps. I apologize if I have merely furthered the confusion.<br />

Message [577] referenced by [580] and [756]. Next Message by CousinIt is [614].<br />

[580] Hans: Private Labor Needs a Social Stamp <strong>of</strong> Approval. I fully agree with<br />

CousinIt’s [577] formulation<br />

Money enables the sale and purchase <strong>of</strong> all other commodities by way <strong>of</strong><br />

its ‘form <strong>of</strong> value’ as the general equivalent and not by way <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong><br />

the money itself.<br />

Let’s first try to understand it under the gold standard, when money is gold, and at the end<br />

I will give my take about how this extends to today’s conditions. Under the gold standard, it<br />

is not the value <strong>of</strong> the gold coin which enables the purchase, because if you have this value


166 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

in a different use-value, say in the form <strong>of</strong> a new pair <strong>of</strong> shoes, then you could not make the<br />

purchase by handing over the shoes.<br />

To anyone living in capitalism it is completely obvious that we can’t just use a random<br />

commodity which we happen to have, say a pair <strong>of</strong> shoes, and expect others to accept it as<br />

money. Nevertheless it is useful here to ask: why can’t we do this? If we have produced the<br />

shoes, why doesn’t the labor put into these shoes give us access to the other commodity we<br />

would like to buy which contains just as much labor?<br />

Answer: because we first need pro<strong>of</strong> that the labor put into the shoes is in fact socially<br />

necessary, that it fits into the social division <strong>of</strong> labor. This pro<strong>of</strong> is handed to us when we sell<br />

the shoes: the money we obtain for the shoes is pro<strong>of</strong> that our labor was socially necessary.<br />

After getting this social stamp <strong>of</strong> approval we are now able to transfer, by our own choices<br />

<strong>of</strong> what we want to buy, this social approval to the seller <strong>of</strong> the commodity we ourselves are<br />

using.<br />

The value incorporated in money therefore differs from the value incorporated in other<br />

commodities by the fact that it bears the stamp <strong>of</strong> social approval. That is its specific form<br />

<strong>of</strong> value.<br />

The transfer <strong>of</strong> the social stamp <strong>of</strong> approval from one buyer to the next seems fair and<br />

democratic, but it has one important unfair implication which is not quite obvious: in a<br />

growing economy, the money received by the sale <strong>of</strong> the commodities produced yesterday<br />

is not enough to validate all commodities produced today, because today more commodities<br />

are produced than yesterday. Therefore in a growing economy, every day some new money is<br />

needed. Under the gold standard, this was not yet terribly unfair, because one had to perform<br />

labor to get this additional gold. The only unfair advantage for the gold producer was that<br />

he did not have to go through the trouble <strong>of</strong> first getting the social stamp <strong>of</strong> approval for his<br />

labor; gold-producing labor was automatically approved by society. It was, as Marx said in<br />

one <strong>of</strong> the three peculiarities <strong>of</strong> the equivalent form, private labor which directly counted as<br />

its opposite, as social labor.<br />

The rest <strong>of</strong> this message is my own attempt to extend Marx’s theory to the present time:<br />

Today, value has been stripped out <strong>of</strong> money, but the form <strong>of</strong> value is artificially maintained.<br />

Money is no longer gold but a worthless piece <strong>of</strong> paper whose exchange-value is<br />

maintained by the Fed’s monetary policy and the worldwide military presence <strong>of</strong> the USA.<br />

As a consequence, this unfair advantage has become an “exorbitant privilege” (this formulation<br />

is attributed to Charles de Gaulle): the United States can basically print money and buy<br />

up the world’s resources with this newly printed money. The only price which it has to pay<br />

for this privilege is that it has to maintain the value <strong>of</strong> the dollar at a stable level.<br />

With the Iraq war and a monetary policy that encouraged stock market bubbles and housing<br />

bubbles, and now the bailouts connected with the bursting <strong>of</strong> the housing bubble, however,<br />

the Fed has left the terrain <strong>of</strong> sound monetary policy and is engaging in highly inflationary<br />

policy. It will be interesting to see how the world reacts to the US no longer holding up<br />

its part <strong>of</strong> an already highly skewed bargain, but the US still holding undiminished military<br />

power towering over anybody else.<br />

Message [580] referenced by [591] and [756]. Next Message by Hans is [584].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 167<br />

Exam Question 411 is 376 in 2005fa, 398 in 2007SP, 412 in 2008fa, 427 in 2009fa, 462<br />

in 2010fa, 459 in 2011fa, and 480 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam Question 411 How does Marx define a crisis?<br />

[683] Hans: We are in a Crisis Situation. All test answers gave examples <strong>of</strong> crises but<br />

didn’t define what a crisis is. Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> a crisis is quite interesting (that’s why I<br />

made this an exam question). Please read my [2005fa:957] first, and then my [2007SP:611]<br />

and [2007SP:997]. I think you will get something out <strong>of</strong> it. Here I’ll type in the answer one<br />

<strong>of</strong> you gave in the exam, because I enjoyed it. This person wrote:<br />

In truth, I cannot speak intelligently about this because I don’t remember reading it at all,<br />

so I will do my best to guess. If it’s wrong in the first few sentences, stop reading because it<br />

won’t get better.<br />

During this whole class I believe I’ve learned we’re in a crisis situation according to<br />

Marx. We, as laborers, are constantly working harder in hopes <strong>of</strong> a better, brighter future but<br />

are doing nothing but working to destroy. Destroying not only ourselves individually, but<br />

society as a whole and the environment. The crisis comes as there is very little we can do<br />

about it and we’re the ones that walked ourselves, almost blindly, down this path. The only<br />

hope is that enough people recognize this plight and organize to react. Unfortunately, this<br />

must take place at all levels <strong>of</strong> functioning society but it may be possible to accomplish and<br />

seems to be becoming more reality with the pending environmental crisis. To me, this is a<br />

Marxian crisis.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [743].<br />

Question 419 is 402 in 2004fa, 410 in 2007SP, 413 in 2007fa, 421 in 2008fa, 437 in<br />

2009fa, 473 in 2010fa, 475 in 2011fa, and 496 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 419 Explain the individual motivation for hoarding money. Do these hoards have<br />

a function for the economy as a whole or only for the individual?<br />

[431] Ryoung: Does Hoarding Prevent Money From Serving its Purpose? Marx<br />

227:3/o explains that hoarding exists because <strong>of</strong> two reasons: necessity, and passionate desire<br />

to save money. Nowadays I believe that hoarding is less likely as it seems that everybody<br />

is trying to keep up with the “Jones’.” This trend has enticed many people to continue to go<br />

into debt without having paid <strong>of</strong>f their previous debts. Many people find themselves feeling<br />

that they are too far in debt to ever get themselves out, which I believe leads them to go<br />

further into debt.<br />

Although many people are on the opposite end <strong>of</strong> the spectrum from hoarding I do believe<br />

that there are still those that are hoarders <strong>of</strong> money. I also tend to agree with Marx, and I<br />

believe that these people choose to stop the transition or the circulating <strong>of</strong> money because<br />

they either have the necessity to save or are comforted by having their share <strong>of</strong> liquid money.<br />

There are many types <strong>of</strong> people that I believe hoard money but I tend to believe that the<br />

majority <strong>of</strong> these people are <strong>of</strong> the “old school” train <strong>of</strong> thought that have been brought up<br />

taught not to go into debt.<br />

These hoards <strong>of</strong> money only serve an immediate purpose for the individuals that hoard,<br />

and do not have a function or immediate impact on the economy. Marx stated that the


168 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

hoarding <strong>of</strong> money stops the money itself from reaching its purpose which it was invented<br />

for. Money was meant to transition from coin to money and so on. Which means that when<br />

a commodity was sold the seller <strong>of</strong> that commodity was then, hypothetically, supposed to<br />

turn around with the proceeds from his sold commodity and was to spend it on another<br />

commodity that he/she needed at that moment. This pattern was to continue and was to<br />

create economic wealth when executed. This pattern or transition is halted when one chooses<br />

to hold its proceeds and not to continue to circulate it through the market place. Therefore<br />

this is why I believe that hoarding does not have a function in the economy. It is not able to<br />

serve its purpose.<br />

Hans: I assume your formulation “money was meant to transition from coin to money and so on” is based on<br />

Marx’s sentence<br />

At one time money must be attracted as coin, at another time coin must be repelled as money.<br />

in 231:3/o. “Coin” means here money actively mediating a circulation act, and “money” is money as hoard riding<br />

out the lumps in circulation, see my [435].<br />

Jeremy: Hoarding is a function <strong>of</strong> money and this function was realized by Marx. To truly see this, one must look<br />

at various opportunities to hoard money. Throughout all times in history when money has been available, there<br />

have always been those who will try to hold onto it. This accumulated wealth creates a sense <strong>of</strong> security as well as<br />

a sense <strong>of</strong> power. This too was also known by Marx.<br />

Since the inception <strong>of</strong> banking, hoarders have found their “golden ticket” so to speak. When a person places<br />

$50,000 in the bank in a savings account to secure their amassed wealth, that money is never taken out <strong>of</strong> the<br />

economy. It is used to lend money to others. Because <strong>of</strong> this opportunity cost, the account holder pr<strong>of</strong>its, the banker<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its, and the loan holder helps to circulate the money even more.<br />

The popular trend these days is to hoard your wages today to pay for tomorrow. This is happening in the form<br />

<strong>of</strong> 401(K)’s, stocks, bonds, and hundreds <strong>of</strong> other engines for building up a stockpile. While the hoarder does not<br />

enjoy their wealth immediately, they or their heirs will eventually reap the rewards. In this form, hoarding is akin<br />

to delayed gratification.<br />

In every case, hoarding continues to contribute money serving its purpose. Even when you look at true hoarding,<br />

which is rarely, if ever practiced. When someone takes that same $50,000 and removes it from the market place<br />

altogether, that lessening <strong>of</strong> money available increases the value <strong>of</strong> all other money still in circulation. By doing<br />

this, that removed money has directly impacted every aspect that gives money its value. Hoarding, in no way<br />

prevents money from serving its purpose.<br />

Hans: Jeremy, you claim that money is a veil, it cannot affect the real economy, and you are using the quantity<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> money to back this up. Just for clarification: Marx did not think money is a veil, and Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong><br />

money is not the quantity theory <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Jeremy: Hans, could you please expound on your statement that I used money as a veil? I’m also failing to see<br />

where I implied that money cannot affect the real economy.<br />

Hans: Both terms refer to economic models in which the real economy is governed by real factors (endowments,<br />

utilities, production function), and the money supply only determines the price level. If you identify savings with<br />

“deferred gratification” then you only look at the real effects with money as “veil,” and your thesis that hoarding<br />

lowers the price level is also an element <strong>of</strong> these theories.<br />

Message [431] referenced by [435] and [437]. Next Message by Ryoung is [524].<br />

[435] Hans: No Flow <strong>of</strong> Money Without Pauses. Ryoung [431] has an undialectical<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> the flow <strong>of</strong> money. Why do I say this? The following passage overlooks<br />

one <strong>of</strong> the Hegelian commonplaces, that everything contains its opposite:<br />

When a commodity was sold the seller <strong>of</strong> that commodity was then, hypothetically,<br />

supposed to turn around with the proceeds from his sold commodity<br />

and was to spend it on another commodity that he/she needed at<br />

that moment.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 169<br />

Such an idealized pure flow <strong>of</strong> money does not exist. Money cannot go from one transaction<br />

to the next without a series <strong>of</strong> smaller or longer pauses, where it waits for the next<br />

transaction to happen. These pauses are inevitable because economic transactions are inherently<br />

lumpy. Marx describes this in 231:3/o.<br />

Under a modern fractional reserve system, the banking system accommodates the fluctuating<br />

demands for money by constantly creating and destroying money. At Marx’s times,<br />

the money that was momentarily not needed for circulation did not return to the banking<br />

system but was kept by private individuals as gold hoards. The individual hoards <strong>of</strong> money<br />

had therefore a clear beneficial economic side effect. Another beneficial use for gold hoards<br />

was reserves for international transactions.<br />

The economic functions <strong>of</strong> modern consumer debt. Times have changed. Nowadays,<br />

one <strong>of</strong> the biggest contradictions <strong>of</strong> capitalism is overproduction. So much can be produced<br />

and so little is paid as wages to the producers that not enough can be sold. One way out <strong>of</strong><br />

this is that consumers go into debt. This has three benefits for the capitalists:<br />

(1) They can continue selling their stuff without raising wages.<br />

(2) Debt service payments are an easy additional source <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

(2) When the rising debt levels get to the point where they can no longer be repaid,<br />

then the indebted consumer is an easy scapegoat, shielding the system from criticism which<br />

requires this indebtedness for its functioning.<br />

While at Marx’s times, hoards had an economic function, apart from the individual motivations<br />

<strong>of</strong> the hoarders, nowadays consumer indebtedness has an economic function, which<br />

is again not intended by the individuals going into debt.<br />

Message [435] referenced by [431], [437], [445], and [2012fa:857]. Next Message by Hans is [445].<br />

[437] Spawnblade: Dragons hoard gold, people hoard debt. Ryoung [431] explained<br />

‘why’ people were inclined to hoard money, however I feel the entire question is not appropriate<br />

for the modern age. As Hans [435] explained, the modern fractional reserve system<br />

means that only 10% <strong>of</strong> the money people hoard is actually hoarded, while the other 90%<br />

<strong>of</strong> it is released as investment into various places in the economy. This prevents 90% <strong>of</strong> the<br />

usual stagnation occurring from physical hoarding <strong>of</strong> money, while allowing people to retain<br />

a theoretical 90% <strong>of</strong> the liquidity <strong>of</strong> their money. It’s clear that the mentioned ‘idealized pure<br />

flow <strong>of</strong> money’ does not, and cannot exist. However the small pause <strong>of</strong> having to travel to a<br />

bank and actually withdraw money, or the use <strong>of</strong> a credit card makes these pauses diminish.<br />

Hans indicated that in Marx’s time gold was hoarded when it was not needed in circulation.<br />

Now at this point I must play the devil’s/capitalist’s advocate (depending on your point<br />

<strong>of</strong> view in this class). So to continue, I’d like to ask: Who is to say that the money could not<br />

be used in circulation? Who’s to say it wouldn’t have stimulated the economy?<br />

As far as I can tell, there is no way to actually determine who may or may not be able to<br />

use the money. Using banks as an example, they constantly are approving loans or investing<br />

in startup companies. This does in fact empower the economy, but it also stimulates overproduction.<br />

And frankly, without the overproduction America participated in in the past, this<br />

country would not have as high <strong>of</strong> living standards as it does. I’m not saying overproduction<br />

is good, because I personally wouldn’t have a problem with going back in time and living


170 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

a simple life <strong>of</strong>f the land. Life would have a lot less stress, though at the same time people<br />

would be vulnerable to nature and its random behaviors.<br />

In continuation <strong>of</strong> the problem <strong>of</strong> overproduction, I’d like to contrast it with Hans’s comments<br />

on debt. Debt in the economy is not a direct result <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system <strong>of</strong> overproduction.<br />

It indicates an unreasonable bias against capitalism to say it is. Personal debt is<br />

instead a direct result <strong>of</strong> a consumer not being able to live within their means. The average<br />

income in America is easily enough for a single person to live comfortably on. I know I<br />

could live very comfortably <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> $2000 a month. The problem is when one person is trying<br />

to support a family <strong>of</strong> 4 on a salary <strong>of</strong> $20-30,000. For the next and (in my opinion) most<br />

prevalent reason <strong>of</strong> debt, I’d like to give an example:<br />

The two sides <strong>of</strong> my family are polar opposites. My mother’s side is very frugal, hardworking,<br />

clean, and loyal. My father’s side is carefree, lazy, dirty, and they know no ethical<br />

boundaries. Now in reference to actual income, my mother’s side has had lay<strong>of</strong>fs, lost money<br />

in real estate scams, and several other major setbacks. Whereas my father’s side has come<br />

out victorious in a multitude <strong>of</strong> lawsuits for car crashes, over the counter drugs, etc. Despite<br />

this, my father’s side has to ask money <strong>of</strong> my father constantly in order to pay their bills or<br />

buy christmas gifts for their kids. This is because they spend it all going on frivolous cruises<br />

or purchasing new cars, instead <strong>of</strong> investing/saving for times <strong>of</strong> need. It is for this reason<br />

they’ve accrued massive debts. If it were the economy that pushed people into debt, than my<br />

mother’s side would have been a victim as well judging by actual occurrences <strong>of</strong> wage loss.<br />

Now if Hans were to say that the abundance <strong>of</strong> credit spurs some people’s incapacity to<br />

control their spending, I would agree with this. It’s similar to gambling in that some people<br />

do not fall to the addiction and others do. Overproduction alone at this point basically means<br />

we could stop producing everything except the necessities and we’d have more goods than<br />

we would know what to do with. Once more, I agree that overproduction is bad, but is<br />

definitely tied to the capitalist system as it stands. However I do not believe that there is<br />

anything that actually relates it to debt. The economic function it has is purely companies<br />

abusing certain debtors lack <strong>of</strong> willpower in balancing their budget and purchasing only<br />

what they deem most necessary to them. It’s the frivolous spenders that are in fact ushering<br />

overproduction.<br />

Message [437] referenced by [445]. Next Message by Spawnblade is [444].<br />

[445] Hans: Overproduction and Sustainability. Volume 3 <strong>of</strong> Capital contains the<br />

famous passage:<br />

The ultimate reason for all real crises always remains the poverty and restricted<br />

consumption <strong>of</strong> the masses as opposed to the drive <strong>of</strong> capitalist<br />

production to develop the productive forces as though only the absolute<br />

consuming power <strong>of</strong> society constituted their limit.<br />

This is an issue deeply embedded in the structure <strong>of</strong> capitalist production. According to<br />

Marxian economics, capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its come from value which the workers produce in excess<br />

<strong>of</strong> their wages. Therefore the capitalists cannot sell their product back to their laborers but<br />

must find other outlets for it. It is possible to find those other outlets; in volume 2 <strong>of</strong> Capital,<br />

Marx builds a rudimentary input-output model which shows how this extra product can flow


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 171<br />

into investment and capitalist consumption. But this is a balancing act, and it is easy to end<br />

up in a situation where either too much is produced for the limited purchasing power <strong>of</strong> the<br />

majority <strong>of</strong> the people, or for the needs <strong>of</strong> the capitalists to make pr<strong>of</strong>its. These situations<br />

are called “overproduction crises.”<br />

Even before it erupts into a crisis, overproduction is present in capitalism: it manifests<br />

itself in planned obsolescence, where products are built in such a shoddy way that they break<br />

down quickly, in product incompatibilities, in lots <strong>of</strong> resources being spent on advertising or<br />

on the military, and in many other ways.<br />

In [435], I used the word “overproduction” without defining it. Lacking a definition,<br />

Spawnblade [437] misunderstood me in an interesting way. He thought “overproduction”<br />

was production in excess <strong>of</strong> the survival needs <strong>of</strong> humans, and he thought I was advocating<br />

a lifestyle that was environmentally sustainable but not much fun.<br />

These are relevant issues for the 21st century. How can a system which aggressively pursues<br />

waste and overproduction in the quest for pr<strong>of</strong>its produce sustainably for the environment?<br />

Sustainability and environmental justice are diametrically opposed to the principles<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalism, which is based on exploitation (i.e., injustice) mitigated by growth and the<br />

plunder <strong>of</strong> the natural environment (i.e., unsustainability).<br />

I believe a sustainable lifestyle can easily be more fun than a capitalist lifestyle. It will<br />

involve much more free time, a healthcare system which allows people to do the work they<br />

have a passion for instead <strong>of</strong> working an alienated job for a big corporation, and more culture<br />

and art. Here is an example <strong>of</strong> what I am thinking <strong>of</strong>: Some people associated with the<br />

Leonardo Center have organized a “sustainable fashion show” under the motto “Reincarnate<br />

the out-<strong>of</strong>-date!”, which will take place in the atrium <strong>of</strong> South Towne Mall tomorrow, Friday<br />

Feb 29, 6 - 9 pm. Their web site is<br />

http://www.seeingleonardo.blogspot.com/<br />

I expect that this is only the beginning <strong>of</strong> a trend. Cultural events which demonstrate how<br />

much fun a sustainable lifestyle can be will become much more commonplace in the future.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [451].<br />

Question 424 is 284 in 1999SP, 320 in 2001fa, 349 in 2002fa, 364 in 2003fa, 426 in<br />

2008fa, and 482 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 424 What is the relation between Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> a miser and Keynes’s “paradox<br />

<strong>of</strong> thrift”?<br />

[440] Samantha: Saving money is not a good thing. Keynes Paradox <strong>of</strong> Thrift, sometimes<br />

called the Paradox <strong>of</strong> savings, is basically that savings is good for an individual but<br />

bad for the economy in general, in other words if people save they are hurting the economy<br />

though helping themselves (in the short run). Consumption is what drives the economy, from<br />

Keynes effective demand, which is not possible when individuals are hoarding money. The<br />

monetary production economy, which Keynes believes we are in, instead <strong>of</strong> a barter economy,<br />

relies on demand side economics to fuel the economy, as long as people are buying<br />

things wages will continue to increase and unemployment decrease.


172 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> a Miser is <strong>of</strong> someone who hoards money, they buy little and produce<br />

much. So if classical theory is to be believed this is supply-side economics, which should<br />

fuel the economy. However, this is untrue, if everyone in society acts like the miser and puts<br />

gold away as though it “were buried in a mountain” then the economy could not function.<br />

Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> the miser is very near the same as Keynes’s Paradox, both recognize that<br />

an individual act <strong>of</strong> keeping money instead <strong>of</strong> spending or using it causes other problems<br />

for the society. As Colletchen points out in [2003fa:307], society generally looks at thrift<br />

as a good thing. Both Keynes and Marx argue that this is not the case, though for different<br />

reasons. Marx believes that the miser is trapped in the market economy and as he tries to<br />

reach his goal <strong>of</strong> becoming wealthy and accumulate he gets caught in this contradiction <strong>of</strong><br />

society, where his individual success and subsequent hoarding <strong>of</strong> money injures the rest <strong>of</strong><br />

society. Keynes doesn’t believe this to be part <strong>of</strong> the system at all, he instead believes that<br />

the ‘animal spirits’ <strong>of</strong> people including their greed are not necessarily bad but could be bad<br />

if everyone saved money to such a large extent as to be considered hoarding, he believes that<br />

some greed or want to accumulate is good, as it inspires individuals to take risks.<br />

Hans: Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> the miser does not have a macroeconomic component. Marx is not asking “who is going<br />

to buy the things the miser is producing” or “is the miser hurting others by reducing aggregate demand?” The miser<br />

is an example <strong>of</strong> individual behavior getting caught in the structural contradictions <strong>of</strong> a market economy. It shows<br />

the spell which these social relations have on people.<br />

Next Message by Samantha is [582].<br />

Question 427 is 280 in 1997sp, 269 in 1997ut, 276 in 1998WI, 287 in 1999SP, 323 in<br />

2001fa, 352 in 2002fa, 367 in 2003fa, 409 in 2004fa, 417 in 2007SP, and 420 in 2007fa:<br />

Question 427 Explain how, by the circumstances <strong>of</strong> commodity circulation, buyers and<br />

sellers may develop into debtors and creditors, and give examples.<br />

[443] Matt: Buyers and sellers. Buyers and sellers become debtors and creditors when<br />

a commodity exchanges hands before payment through money has taken place. But before<br />

this can happen a “Trust relationship” must be in place according to Marx. This relationship<br />

<strong>of</strong> trust is developed over time as the buyer and seller may have a history with each other. A<br />

good example would be the purchasing <strong>of</strong> house. Since the buyer does not have the cash to<br />

pay for the commodity upfront, Marx says he has to borrow money for a “defined period” <strong>of</strong><br />

30 years until the debt has been paid in full. The buyer will then go to the mortgage lender<br />

and request a lump sum be lent to him so he can purchase the home from the seller. Since the<br />

lender does not know the buyer personally they will check the history <strong>of</strong> payments made to<br />

other lenders (bank loans, credit cards) to make sure there can be a trustworthy relationship.<br />

Once the buyer is found to be trustworthy, the money will be lent to the buyer for a fee<br />

(interest payment). This process is where the buyer becomes a debtor to the mortgage lender.<br />

The seller will then receive full payments for the sale <strong>of</strong> his house. This transaction allows<br />

the buyer to live in the house without actually owning it. The annotations say, “only after<br />

the lease has expired has the buyer actually received the use-value <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Hans: The credit which the paper boy (and the newspaper company) gives you when he delivers newspapers before<br />

collecting the bill is more typical for this kind <strong>of</strong> credit springing from circulation than home mortgages.<br />

Next Message by Matt is [603].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 173<br />

Question 433 is 283 in 1998WI, 294 in 1999SP, 312 in 2000fa, 360 in 2002fa, 375 in<br />

2003fa, 417 in 2004fa, 426 in 2007fa, and 488 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 433 Why is means <strong>of</strong> payment, and not means <strong>of</strong> purchase, the predominant function<br />

<strong>of</strong> international money?<br />

[432] Rmuscolino: Means <strong>of</strong> payment, and not means <strong>of</strong> purchase, serve as the predominant<br />

function <strong>of</strong> international money. Marx 231:3/o states that gold hoards created by<br />

private citizens allows the quantity <strong>of</strong> the circulating medium <strong>of</strong> payments to “ebb and flow”<br />

or simply go in and out, which also served as international payments. Every nation should<br />

have a reserve fund for this circulation in the world market. The function <strong>of</strong> money plays<br />

an important role in the function <strong>of</strong> hoards. This function becomes the medium <strong>of</strong> payment,<br />

which then circulates internally out <strong>of</strong> its function as international money or “world money.”<br />

Hans: In the quoted passage, Marx does not speak <strong>of</strong> means <strong>of</strong> payment specifically but <strong>of</strong> all money in circulation.<br />

“Means <strong>of</strong> payment” is a specific form <strong>of</strong> circulation discussed in the assigned readings. One cannot understand<br />

this question, let alone answer it correctly, if one don’t know what means <strong>of</strong> payment is.<br />

Next Message by Rmuscolino is [477].<br />

[436] Alex: content B+ form 95% The international processes <strong>of</strong> money are accounted<br />

for by Marx in this section and others. It is international because it represents more than<br />

money but human capital, and value. This is extremely important in understanding the universal<br />

understood qualities <strong>of</strong> money. Though the more refined qualities <strong>of</strong> money have been<br />

refined since Marx’s work, his understanding is rudimentary yet specific to the differences<br />

in international and domestic money.<br />

However, again Marx separates the process <strong>of</strong> money as it flows into the international<br />

economy. All this relates back to Say’s law and the necessary separations in process. In<br />

fact it is not all one process, but several processes. I believe a more accurate examination <strong>of</strong><br />

Say’s law is in order.<br />

Marx goes into detail about why Say’s law is not accurate. Marx’s denunciation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

logic is based on the division <strong>of</strong> the purchaser and the seller. The money exchanged and<br />

given to the seller does not guarantee the reuse <strong>of</strong> the funds because the seller becomes a<br />

purchaser in a different act than the original transaction. But the original transaction itself is<br />

more ambigous than what Say allows. The reality is that the purchaser and seller are not so<br />

easily defined. In fact to the contrary, the purchaser could be the seller and vice-versa. It is<br />

not so easily explained as Say purports.<br />

The commodity is an important part <strong>of</strong> the transaction. The value assessed by Say is not<br />

necessarily accurate, and if nothing else is over-simplified. The transaction is not so easily<br />

ended as well. Is the purchaser really the final consumer <strong>of</strong> the product, or will it be resold.<br />

When does the commodity come out <strong>of</strong> the cycle <strong>of</strong> revenue and commodities. The final<br />

consumer is an important aspect <strong>of</strong> the initial transaction. The commodity also contains<br />

something <strong>of</strong> its opposite, during the transaction the commodity is awarded some piece <strong>of</strong><br />

its opposite. Thus there is no need to use the money immediately because the same money<br />

can be used later on.<br />

This is seemingly contrary to Keynes and the multiplier effect. Though when a more<br />

thorough examination is given to synthesizing these theories there is some room for compliance.<br />

However, this theory brings into question the validity <strong>of</strong> President Bush’s stimulus


174 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

package. Will consumers be inspired to shop, or will they hold their money knowing that<br />

they can purchase later, and that now is a time to save. The stimulus is further impacted by<br />

the fact that employment and income are not the cause <strong>of</strong> the recession, housing is. I don’t<br />

know how many will use their rebates to purchase new houses.<br />

After this examination it is important to understand the human perspective in all this.<br />

The purchase is not important, but what is the actual cost <strong>of</strong> production. The international<br />

economy disadvantages countries and entices them to devalue human life for the “payment”<br />

<strong>of</strong> goods.<br />

Hans: This contribution brims with interesting ideas, similar to [141] and other earlier contributions. But in many<br />

places your argument is too terse, <strong>of</strong>ten you are not really making an argument but just hinting at it. And you seem<br />

infected by Rmuscolino’s wrong interpretation <strong>of</strong> the word “means <strong>of</strong> payment.”<br />

Next Message by Alex is [453].<br />

[439] Scott: means <strong>of</strong> payment. The means <strong>of</strong> payment, and not means <strong>of</strong> purchase is<br />

the predominant function <strong>of</strong> international money because it is more efficient and less risky to<br />

conduct international transactions this way. It is impossible to do a transaction <strong>of</strong> money and<br />

goods at the same time because <strong>of</strong> the location barrier between buyer and seller. Because <strong>of</strong><br />

this you have to choose, either the money needs to be sent first or the goods. If the buyer<br />

sends the money overseas there is a great possibility that he will never see the goods. The<br />

logical solution to this is to send the goods first, so that the buyer has assurance that the<br />

goods exists. After which the goods can be given to the buyer after he gives the money to<br />

the seller.<br />

Hans: Finally an answer which knows what a means <strong>of</strong> payment is. I also like your simple and logical approach.<br />

Message [439] referenced by [459]. Next Message by Scott is [455].<br />

[459] Tim: I have to agree with the answer by Scott [439] that there must be an assurance<br />

that the goods have been sent in order for the payment to be made. Both must operate on<br />

faith that the other will be honest in their dealings. It only makes sense to operate this way<br />

because there are so many ways that the sender can cheat the buyer out <strong>of</strong> his money if the<br />

payment is made before the goods are shipped. Thus, means <strong>of</strong> payment and not means <strong>of</strong><br />

purchase is predominant.<br />

Hans: I am a little puzzled about your statement “both must operate on faith that the other will be honest in their<br />

dealings” when everything else you say indicates that one can not rely on the honesty <strong>of</strong> the transaction partners<br />

but that procedures must be put in place which make cheating as difficult as possible.<br />

I don’t think you said anything Scott didn’t already know. If you wanted to give feedback to Scott which is<br />

more than psychologically helpful you could have given more details about the mechanisms <strong>of</strong> the transactions as<br />

I tried in [475].<br />

Next Message by Tim is [553].<br />

[475] Hans: technicalities <strong>of</strong> international trade. Example: It is July 1st 1785. The<br />

telegraph has not yet been invented, and letters within Europe take 1-2 weeks for delivery.<br />

Merchant M in Bordeaux (France) wants to buy grain from merchant Y in Danzig (Prussia).<br />

M has an account with bank A in Amsterdam (Holland), and Y has an account with bank B<br />

in Amsterdam. Here is the sequence <strong>of</strong> events:<br />

Merchant M has an agent merchant X in Danzig, who is going to purchase and ship the<br />

grain. M sends X the instructions asking him to buy 1000 bushels <strong>of</strong> rye from merchant<br />

Y, to be shipped to Bordeaux. Along with these instructions he sends a so-called “draft”<br />

(more technically called “acceptance bill,” a more modern form <strong>of</strong> a “bill <strong>of</strong> exchange”).


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 175<br />

This “draft” is a letter in which merchant M orders his Amsterdam bank A to pay 500 florins<br />

on October 1st to bank B in Amsterdam. Merchant M also sends a copy <strong>of</strong> this draft to bank<br />

A in Amsterdam.<br />

On July 15, merchant X gets this letter, and on July 25, he takes delivery <strong>of</strong> the rye from<br />

Merchant Y and at this time gives merchant Y the draft. Merchant X loads the rye on one<br />

<strong>of</strong> his ships and sends it on the way to Bordeaux. Merchant Y sends the draft to bank B in<br />

Amsterdam.<br />

An August 10, bank B receives the draft in the mail and goes to bank A and shows them<br />

the draft. Bank A has already received a copy <strong>of</strong> this draft directly from M and therefore<br />

knows it is legitimate, and M has enough money on deposit with bank A to pay for the draft.<br />

The draft is not yet due, but bank A writes “I accept” on the back <strong>of</strong> the draft.<br />

On October 1st, bank B gives the draft to bank A and gets 500 florins in return. Bank B<br />

credits this payment to merchant Y’s account, and bank A debits the payment, with fees and<br />

interest, from merchant X’s account.<br />

In part I have this from<br />

http://eh.net/coursesyllabi/syllabi/munro/BILLEXCH.htm<br />

and in part I am just making it up to fill in the missing information. This web site does<br />

not tell me what happens if something goes wrong. Assume bank A does not accept the<br />

bill, because merchant M does not have enough money or credit with bank A. I assume then<br />

merchant X is responsible for paying Y, and merchant X, who is in possession <strong>of</strong> the rye in<br />

transit, will not deliver the rye to merchant M but try to sell it elsewhere in order to get at<br />

least partial reimbursement for the money he has to pay to Y. And this is, <strong>of</strong> course, the end<br />

<strong>of</strong> the relationship where X acts as agent for M. I am not sure about the precise mechanisms,<br />

but I am sure that such built-in safeguards exist so that breach <strong>of</strong> contract is more costly for<br />

the transactors than adhering to the contract.<br />

If anyone reading this has more info, or can point me to a book which explains things<br />

better than the above web site, please let me know.<br />

Message [475] referenced by [459]. Next Message by Hans is [480].<br />

Question 438 is 423 in 2004fa, 456 in 2009fa, and 493 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 438 Marx makes three statements about money engaged in M −C − M: (1) this<br />

money transforms itself into capital, (2) this money becomes capital, and (3) according to<br />

its determination, this money already is capital. What is the difference between these three<br />

statements? Why does Marx not say that this money is capital?<br />

[454] Carterryan: The M-C-M Process: The way to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it. Money in its<br />

original form is capital in the fact that it is going to be used through the M-C-M process to<br />

purchase commodities and then transformed from that back into more capital. When you<br />

break down the M-C-M formula you get two separate phases but they are still a part <strong>of</strong> each<br />

other. The first part <strong>of</strong> the formula, M-C, is taking the capital that is used in the beginning<br />

<strong>of</strong> the whole process to purchase the commodities for the investment return.


176 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Money in the first phase (M-C) is still in a monetary form even after it is turned into<br />

commodities. This is because the commodities are just a means to an end and are just being<br />

used to create more capital for the initial purchaser <strong>of</strong> the goods.<br />

The definition <strong>of</strong> the term “money” is: any token or other object that functions as a<br />

medium <strong>of</strong> exchange that is socially and legally accepted in payment for goods and services.<br />

. . . . . . money also serves as a standard <strong>of</strong> value for measuring the relative worth <strong>of</strong><br />

different goods and services and as a store <strong>of</strong> value. So the commodities can still be referred<br />

to as money.<br />

The second phase <strong>of</strong> the cycle (C-M) is where the commodities are then exchanged for<br />

more capital. For instance if you bought a barrel <strong>of</strong> oil for $100 and then turned around and<br />

sold it to Exxon for $120, you just made a $20 pr<strong>of</strong>it that can be returned in the M-C-M<br />

process and be able to use your capital gained on future investments.<br />

Marx denied calling this money as capital because if you say bought the same barrel for<br />

a $100 and then the demand or market for oil dropped you would not have made any pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

and so you would have no capital from the M-C-M process.<br />

Hans: This is a difficult question about the subtleties <strong>of</strong> Marx’s methodology. It can certainly not be resolved by<br />

looking up the Wikipedia definition <strong>of</strong> money, which comes from a completely different theoretical framework. I<br />

said that already in my remarks to [423].<br />

Your past submissions have shown little appreciation <strong>of</strong> the differences between Marx’s theory and mainstream<br />

economics. I urge you to read up on this. Perhaps it would be a good idea if you were to check out Duncan<br />

Foley’s Understanding Capital or some other introduction into Marx’s theory from the library (Foley is on reserve).<br />

Listening to the recordings <strong>of</strong> my class lectures might help too.<br />

Next Message by Carterryan is [716].<br />

Question 439 is 494 in 2010fa and 524 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 439 At the beginning <strong>of</strong> 248:2 Marx says that M −C − M in which the second<br />

M is equal to the first is “absurd” and “devoid <strong>of</strong> content.” Nevertheless, later in the same<br />

paragraph he says that the quantitative differences should be disregarded. Why does he insist<br />

on investigating a possibility which he just called “absurd” and which never happens?<br />

[444] Spawnblade: The absurdity <strong>of</strong> intended loss. When money is exchanged for<br />

commodity with the sole intent <strong>of</strong> exchanging that commodity back into money, it is clear<br />

that it is absurd to assume that the second M is less than the first. Marx understands this, yet<br />

he does not say that the exchange will not happen, he simply says that “if the intention were<br />

to exchange to equal sums <strong>of</strong> money...” indicating that it was not as absurd if the original<br />

intention had been to exchange the commodity for a higher sum <strong>of</strong> money and therefore<br />

remove the risks <strong>of</strong> transaction.<br />

There are two examples which I feel are appropriate for the topic: The first is the depreciation<br />

<strong>of</strong> a car. Most people purchase cars with the intent to sell them in the future, however<br />

their intent is not to make money <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> them, but to get a certain use out <strong>of</strong> them and then<br />

sell the remains in a few years. It does not follow the specific guidelines <strong>of</strong> only purchasing<br />

a commodity with the intent to sell, but it is a main intent. In fact, many people buy cars that<br />

are known to have higher resale values (such as Hondas).


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 177<br />

The other example is a stock. I feel stocks are a good modern example because they are<br />

a share in a company and should fit the definition <strong>of</strong> a commodity due to the percentage <strong>of</strong><br />

ownership in capital that they represent. And due to the global economy it is rare to have<br />

merchants participating in traveling trade, if not unheard <strong>of</strong>. When traders purchase stocks<br />

they purchase them with the intent to make money on an increase in the company’s pr<strong>of</strong>its<br />

and a rise in their share’s value. This does not always happen, however, since the monetary<br />

value <strong>of</strong> stocks are not always predictable. For this reason a person may deem it necessary<br />

to cut their losses by selling at an equal or lesser value than that which they first bought<br />

it. It was not their intent, but it was something they had to consider when making a risky<br />

purchase.<br />

I believe it is for this reason that Marx decides to investigate this ‘absurd’ possibility, and<br />

not for the reason that it “never happens.” I also believe that it is wise to disregard quantitative<br />

differences, since in a generalized form it is impossible to predict the quantitative differences<br />

due to the nature <strong>of</strong> trade and the people that participate. However, if quantitative differences<br />

were thrown out altogether, it would be impossible to judge M-C-M and really analyze the<br />

‘how’ and ‘why’ <strong>of</strong> it. So I believe it should be based on a case by case basis depending on<br />

what is actually being analyzed about it.<br />

Message [444] referenced by [450], [469], and [2010fa:599]. Next Message by Spawnblade is [538].<br />

[450] Trailrunner: graded A– Money for the sake <strong>of</strong> Money. Spawnblade [444] speaks<br />

<strong>of</strong> depreciation and the unpredictability <strong>of</strong> the eventual pr<strong>of</strong>its from the sale <strong>of</strong> an item (or<br />

in the case <strong>of</strong> his example, stocks) as the reason why M=M is absurd. I would have an<br />

interest in looking at the obsession that a capitalist has with money. If a capitalist is all about<br />

accumulating money, then wouldn’t there be pleasure in the exchange <strong>of</strong> money regardless<br />

<strong>of</strong> whether pr<strong>of</strong>its were being made with each exchange or not?<br />

The focus to me seems to be more about exchanging money for money than only looking<br />

at the pr<strong>of</strong>its. I do realize that ultimately, if pr<strong>of</strong>its are not being made, the accumulation <strong>of</strong><br />

money will never happen, but I also believe that people can some times get caught up in just<br />

“playing” with money. Isn’t that what sometimes drives people to gamble? Everyone know<br />

that the “house” always wins when you are at a casino, but there is an allure to the feeling<br />

<strong>of</strong> money in your hands....and watching it possibly grow. As is the case <strong>of</strong> the casinos never<br />

losing in the long run, there are times when they do pay out tremendous amounts <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

A capitalist, in exchanging money for money may not always walk away with a pr<strong>of</strong>it, but<br />

will very likely eventually be like the casino, and win the pr<strong>of</strong>its in the long run.<br />

I would also look at the social context in which those that carry around money find themselves.<br />

So <strong>of</strong>ten, people that are consumed with the desire to have more money, think that<br />

having it somehow makes them superior and more worthy <strong>of</strong> respect. I had a friend at one<br />

point in time that always carried at least $1000 cash in his pocket. When it came time to<br />

pay for dinner (if we were out with a group), he would pull out the wad <strong>of</strong> money and finger<br />

through it, counting it, as if he thought it would impress those around him. The reality was<br />

that people didn’t really care to see it, nor did it make them think more highly <strong>of</strong> him. Does<br />

a capitalist get caught up in this “I’m better than you because I deal in money” type <strong>of</strong> idea?<br />

And does this apply to the absurdity <strong>of</strong> the second M equaling the first M?


178 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Yes, the capitalist ultimately cares about accruing more and more money, but I believe it<br />

also has to do with feeling superior. I believe that there is an understanding that if a person<br />

keeps working at trading money for money, they will eventually come out ahead - even if<br />

some <strong>of</strong> the transactions at times seem absurd.<br />

Message [450] referenced by [469]. Next Message by Trailrunner is [473].<br />

[469] Hans: First quality, then quantity. Marx generally likes to look at quality first,<br />

i.e., first abstract from quantity, and only later take in the quantitative dimension, after he<br />

has understood the quality. This is an unfamiliar procedure since modern science tries to<br />

quantify everything and pays little attention to quality. I think Marx has a point here because<br />

a premature look at the quantity can be a distraction which yields misleading results.<br />

The best example for this is the exchange. Everybody is trying to get more in return than<br />

they have to give away. Not only in use-value but also, if possible, in value. Therefore if you<br />

only look at the quantity you miss the important fact that the exchange is a big equalizer:<br />

that all the qualitatively different commodities are equated to each other. Exchange makes<br />

the space <strong>of</strong> all commodities one-dimensional, and Marx infers from this that the commodities<br />

must be one-dimensional already before the exchange, namely, they are all products <strong>of</strong><br />

human labor.<br />

Marx’s main justification for first looking at quality and only afterwards at quantity is<br />

the very abstract logical argument that things are only then quantitatively comparable if they<br />

are qualitatively equal. Since in the case <strong>of</strong> M-C-M it is so counterintuitive to abstract from<br />

quantities, he gives in this situation additional justification. He says that a M-C-M in which<br />

the second M is equal to or smaller than the first may happen without being intended. Spawnblade’s<br />

[444] example <strong>of</strong> the stocks falls into this category: although the intent was to get<br />

more money from the sale, sometimes the best one can do is to sell at a loss. Spawnblade’s<br />

other example with trading in a car is interesting because in this situation, the intent is from<br />

the beginning to trade it in at a loss. Here M-C-M is not the main driver <strong>of</strong> the transaction,<br />

but M-C-M is only a subordinate element in a protracted case <strong>of</strong> C-M-C.<br />

Trailrunner [450] explains the disregard <strong>of</strong> the quantitative aspect by the irrationality <strong>of</strong><br />

the capitalist who acts like a gambler:<br />

If a capitalist is all about accumulating money, then wouldn’t there be pleasure<br />

in the exchange <strong>of</strong> money regardless <strong>of</strong> whether pr<strong>of</strong>its were being<br />

made with each exchange or not?<br />

The different between the capitalist and the compulsive gambler in Las Vegas is that in<br />

the long run, the gambler loses to the casino, while the capitalist in the long run is the casino.<br />

Trailrunner writes:<br />

A capitalist, in exchanging money for money may not always walk away<br />

with a pr<strong>of</strong>it, but will very likely eventually be like the casino, and win the<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its in the long run.<br />

How did the capitalist get promoted from the sorry addicted (and exploited) gambler to<br />

the casino? If you own the means <strong>of</strong> production, then markets are very kind to you, and you<br />

can make money in many different ways. Therefore it is worth while to establish yourself


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 179<br />

in the market. For years, Amazon was losing money on every book they sold, but now they<br />

are very pr<strong>of</strong>itable. And Walmart is so successful because their prices are so low. AOL has<br />

been distributing free diskettes and CDs for years and years, at great expense, in an attempt<br />

to get more customers – but in their case it was apparently less successful. One <strong>of</strong>ten sees<br />

M-C-M seemingly without regard to pr<strong>of</strong>itability, as a loss leader to establish a business<br />

which eventually may be extremely pr<strong>of</strong>itable.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [472].<br />

Question 440 is 442 in 2008fa:<br />

Question 440 Why does Marx’s investigation <strong>of</strong> M −C − M ′ take the form <strong>of</strong> a comparison<br />

with C − M −C?<br />

[448] CousinIt: graded A C-M-C vs M-C-M. The cycle C-M-C is one that we are<br />

already familiar with as it has been the focus <strong>of</strong> Marx’s discussion thusfar. The development<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodity circulation is the precursor to the emergence <strong>of</strong> capital. In the process <strong>of</strong><br />

circulation <strong>of</strong> commodities, money is the mediator which allows agents to exchange their<br />

own use-values with other use-values. The agents trade one use-value with another through<br />

the medium <strong>of</strong> money. This can be characterized as a metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> the commodity. I<br />

start with use-value and end with use-value.<br />

In C-M-C, it is the commodity that is metamorphised. That is, I am transforming usevalue<br />

<strong>of</strong> one sort into another that is more useful for myself. This end is the expenditure <strong>of</strong><br />

value and commodity exchange that ends in use-value being consumed.<br />

M-C-M is the inversion <strong>of</strong> commodity circulation. Rather than the purpose being to transform<br />

the use-value I have into a use-value that is more useful for me, what I am interested in<br />

is ‘advancing’ my capital for the sake <strong>of</strong> capital itself. Capital in itself is not a use-value, but<br />

is an accumulation <strong>of</strong> value for the sake <strong>of</strong> accumulation <strong>of</strong> value. The end <strong>of</strong> the M-C-M<br />

cycle is no longer the transformation <strong>of</strong> use-value, but rather a perversion <strong>of</strong> the circulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities with a primary purpose <strong>of</strong> the development and accumulation <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Marx compares M-C-M with C-M-C because C-M-C is a natural outcome <strong>of</strong> commodity<br />

development as well as the precondition for the emergence <strong>of</strong> capital. Marx compares C-M-<br />

C with M-C-M in order to begin to formulate an illustration and analysis <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

perversion <strong>of</strong> commodity circulation that gives rise to the M-C-M circuit.<br />

From this point, we might guess that we will encounter the fact that there are some who<br />

do not have capital (M) and therefore are caught in the C-M-C circuit, by virtue <strong>of</strong> the fact<br />

that they start only with the commodity that is their own labor and must transform it into usevalue<br />

as their end, and have little or nothing left over to be able to participate in the M-C-M<br />

circuit. These unfortunates are inevitably locked into a cycle that starts with C and ends with<br />

C. This is, however, relatively normal and necessary. The perverted and miserly capitalist<br />

begins and ends with capital (M), which has no use-value other than as a means to more<br />

capital (M). This root perversion opens the way for a plethora <strong>of</strong> pathological consequences.<br />

The comparison <strong>of</strong> M-C-M with C-M-C highlights the perversity <strong>of</strong> the M-C-M cycle.<br />

Hans: This is very good, although Marx would probably add that commodity production already has a lot <strong>of</strong><br />

perversion built in, see the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity, etc., just to make sure nobody thinks (like


180 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Proudhon) that “sane” commodity production, which does not commit the perversion <strong>of</strong> capitalism, would be<br />

possible with modern technology.<br />

Message [448] referenced by [2008fa:716]. Next Message by CousinIt is [577].<br />

Question 442 is 211 in 1996sp, 211 in 1996ut, 288 in 1998WI, 300 in 1999SP, 337 in<br />

2001fa, 366 in 2002fa, 381 in 2003fa, 426 in 2004fa, 401 in 2005fa, 433 in 2007SP, 436<br />

in 2007fa, 460 in 2009fa, 497 in 2010fa, 530 in 2012fa, and 497 in Answer:<br />

Question 442 If someone first buys a car, and after two years trades it in for a new car, is<br />

that C − M −C or M −C − M?<br />

If someone first buys a house, then after ten years decides to move and sells his house for a<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it, is this C − M −C or M −C − M?<br />

If a farmer raises wheat, then at the end <strong>of</strong> the year sells his crop and with the proceeds buys<br />

the materials to raise next year’s wheat, is that C − M −C or M −C − M?<br />

[449] Trailrunner: graded A M-C-M means, “I want more money!” In the first part <strong>of</strong><br />

the question, a person buying a car, selling it and purchasing another car, is simply looking<br />

at the consumption <strong>of</strong> the use-value <strong>of</strong> the vehicle. This individual is not out to make money,<br />

but looking at obtaining money by the sale <strong>of</strong> the first vehicle, in order to allow the purchase<br />

the second vehicle. In this case, it is C-M-C that is taking place. This individual is circulating<br />

commodities and the money is said to be expended - the money transfers from one person to<br />

another.<br />

In the second part <strong>of</strong> the question, the individual purchasing the home and then selling it<br />

for a pr<strong>of</strong>it is looking at the money/earnings that can be obtained by the sale <strong>of</strong> the home. In<br />

this case, the home has become an exchange value, as in the case <strong>of</strong> M-M’. The end purpose<br />

for the purchase <strong>of</strong> the home was an accumulation <strong>of</strong> money. There is no mention <strong>of</strong> this<br />

individual taking the money only to be able to purchase another home, thus it is the M-C-M<br />

process that is taking place. The commodity has been transformed into money and is said to<br />

be money advanced.<br />

The third part <strong>of</strong> the question looks at a farmer that is raising wheat to sell, in order to<br />

obtain money to purchase more wheat so that it can be sold again. He is working through<br />

the M-C-M process. The farmer is working in an endless cycle in which the wheat is just a<br />

commodity that is sold for more money and the cycle continues. Had the farmer taken the<br />

money from the sale <strong>of</strong> the wheat and purchased something else, like a car, the wheat would<br />

have been a commodity being traded for another commodity with a use-value for the farmer.<br />

The money in this case is “flowing back to the the person that originally spent it.” It can also<br />

be noted that this “reflux,” as Marx calls it, is not based upon the farmer selling the wheat<br />

for more than it was paid for, it is looking only at the fact that the money continues to go<br />

back to the same person over and over again.<br />

Hans: I agree with all your answers. But the reasoning <strong>of</strong> (b) should not be made dependent on the motivation <strong>of</strong><br />

the home owners, see my [2004fa:284]. If you make it dependent, you’d have to say it can go both ways, as Jason<br />

[452] and Goethe [462] do.<br />

Message [449] referenced by [452] and [462]. Next Message by Trailrunner is [450].<br />

[452] Jason: C-M-C Hummer Time. While Trailrunner in [449] already answered this<br />

question, I felt I could add a few more tidbits to his answer.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 181<br />

Buying a car, using it for a two years and trading it in is considered C-M-C like Trailrunner<br />

said. He said you buy it to use, then sell it to put the money towards another car<br />

which potentially has more use-value. It might have a nicer interior, be faster, etc. Another<br />

way to look at why it is C-M-C is to look at why it could not be M-C-M. Cars traditionally<br />

depreciate in value, there are rare exceptions, but they almost always depreciate. In fact, I’ve<br />

heard cars can depreciate by up to 25% <strong>of</strong> their value just by driving a new one <strong>of</strong>f the lot.<br />

There is no real way to use a car in the M-C-M cycle and end up with more money than you<br />

started (unless you manufactured the car), and since its purpose is the accumulation <strong>of</strong> more<br />

money, it would not fit.<br />

For the purchase <strong>of</strong> a home, I feel this situation could go both ways. Trailrunner says<br />

“There is no mention <strong>of</strong> this individual taking the money only to be able to purchase another<br />

home, thus it is the M-C-M process that is taking place.” This is how he justifies that the<br />

purchase and sale <strong>of</strong> this home is M-C-M. He bought the house and sold it for a pr<strong>of</strong>it, so he<br />

starts with money and ends with more money. Generally houses appreciate in value, though<br />

the recent collapse might make that hard to believe. One could easily purchase a house, live<br />

in it or fill it with tenants, keep it for a few years and sell it for a pr<strong>of</strong>it. Assuming you had<br />

the starting capital, buying a house is a great way to accumulate more money. However, the<br />

reason this could go both ways is because everyone, more or less, needs a house to live in.<br />

Typically when people buy houses for the sole purpose <strong>of</strong> reselling for pr<strong>of</strong>it, they either fill<br />

it with tenants, or do not wait 10 years to resell. The owner <strong>of</strong> this house could have very<br />

well needed to leave the area and the house happened to be worth more than when he bought<br />

it. I know this requires some assumptions <strong>of</strong> things not listed in the problem, but I think it<br />

is good to make the point that just because you get more money out than you put in doesn’t<br />

mean you did it just to accumulate more money. If the owner spends the money on a newer<br />

and bigger house he increased quality <strong>of</strong> life which falls under C-M-C.<br />

As far as the farmer goes, I agree with Trailrunner. The farmer is simply buying the wheat<br />

to sell for pr<strong>of</strong>it, then repeating the process each season. He may take some <strong>of</strong> the excess<br />

money to spend on other commodities, but these are irrelevant to the closed M-C-M cycle.<br />

Message [452] referenced by [449], [462], and [2009fa:910]. Next Message by Jason is [461].<br />

[460] Mick: content C form 95% Under the first scenario the individual involved undergoes<br />

a C-M-C transition, in that he/she enjoys the use value <strong>of</strong> a car (a commodity)<br />

exchanges it as a form <strong>of</strong> money, and uses its monetary value to acquire a newer automobile,<br />

thus returning to the utlization <strong>of</strong> a distinct commodity.<br />

In the second example they use money to purchase a house which they use for ten years,<br />

and then flip that house to end up with a monetary pr<strong>of</strong>it. (M-C-M)<br />

The genesis <strong>of</strong> this third instance is a crop (a distinct commodity) which is sold for<br />

M(money) which is used to purchase materials (commodities) for use to raise the wheat<br />

for the following year. Here the process is C-M-C.<br />

Hans: Your answer to (c) is wrong, and you should have referred to the earlier answers.<br />

Message [460] referenced by [462] and [464]. Next Message by Mick is [558].<br />

[462] Goethe: graded B+ What pr<strong>of</strong>it would a house sale bring in today? I am looking<br />

at Mick’s response [460]. I feel he is close but I have some input;


182 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(1) Appears to be C-M-C. . . I question which commodity was exchanged for the car.<br />

Was it the labor expressed as form <strong>of</strong> money? I can see where this could be an M-C-M. . .<br />

you exchange money for the car and then you have money again. . . the big difference here<br />

is you have a smaller amount <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

(2) This scenario could go either way. The exchange begins with money converted to<br />

a house (C) and then is traded for money. The house was utilized for several years and<br />

provided use value for the owner. The difference here is that a pr<strong>of</strong>it was probably realized,<br />

but even so, the money from the transaction most likely went to purchase another home. I<br />

see this as C-M-C-M-C if another house was purchased (if not why would the person sell<br />

after 10 years?) in another scenario if a house was purchased for a discount and improved<br />

for pr<strong>of</strong>it then sold in the short term, it would be M-C-M. . . as a means to pr<strong>of</strong>it from money,<br />

the money was held for investment and exchanged for a commodity which was held for a<br />

short time then sold for pr<strong>of</strong>it in exchange for money that will be held for reinvestment.<br />

(3) As for the farmer; this could also be M-C-M. . . .. The farmer is the owner <strong>of</strong> production<br />

and his motives are pr<strong>of</strong>it. . . but realistically this is the purest form <strong>of</strong> C-M-C. . . . the<br />

commodity corn is exchanged for money (M), and exchanged for equipment (a commodity)<br />

. . .<br />

So it looks like you nailed it other than the deal with the house, it was not stated that<br />

the intention <strong>of</strong> the house purchase was to flip it. . . . I also noticed that Trailrunner in [449]<br />

shares your opinion. . . I could be way <strong>of</strong>f but this is how I see it.<br />

Hans: You should not only look at one or two previous answers, but at all <strong>of</strong> them. This is easy if you download<br />

the pdf archives. Then you would have seen that your point about (b) was already made by Jason [452].<br />

And your and Mick’s answer to (c) are wrong. Instead <strong>of</strong> saying you may be wrong I would have preferred<br />

you using some reasoning to resolve the discrepancy. For instance as follows: if one repeats M-C-M one gets the<br />

sequence M-C-M-C-M which has a C-M-C in the middle. This is the C-M-C you see in (c).<br />

Message [462] referenced by [449] and [474]. Next Message by Goethe is [463].<br />

[464] Slash: If someone buys a car and later sells the car it would be C-M-C. This is the<br />

case because the car is used by the purchaser so the use value is taken advantage <strong>of</strong>. Later<br />

the car is sold, which would be the money, but only to be then used to purchase another car<br />

completing the cycle <strong>of</strong> C-M-C.<br />

The second example is M-C-M. When the house was purchased with money to obtain the<br />

commodities, the house, it was then turned back into money once it was sold.<br />

The third example is a case <strong>of</strong> C-M-C. Because the crop is a commodity that is sold for<br />

money. The money gained by selling the crop is then used to buy materials to raise wheat,<br />

so this is a case <strong>of</strong> C-M-C<br />

Hans: This is exactly the same thing Mick said in [460], without any extra arguments and nothing. You also came<br />

at the tail end <strong>of</strong> a long discussion, without referring to any <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [465].<br />

[472] Hans: The answers which I consider best. This question has been discussed<br />

ad nauseam in the archives. Here are my answers and references where these answers are<br />

explained in most detail:<br />

(1) is C-M-C or, better, L-M-C. See [1996ut:211].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 183<br />

(2) is M-C-M although for a long time I argued it was L-M-C. [2004fa:284] explains why<br />

I changed my mind.<br />

(3) is M-C-M, and look at the last paragraph in my comments to [2007SP:704].<br />

Message [472] referenced by [Answer:1] and [2009fa:648]. Next Message by Hans is [475].<br />

[474] Goethe: Sometimes it is better not to overthink ideas. I was close on my evaluation<br />

in [462] <strong>of</strong> the farmer as being an example <strong>of</strong> M-C-M.. But I had to look at it a little closer. . .<br />

and I missed . . .<br />

Next Message by Goethe is [504].<br />

Question 444 is 435 in 2007SP and 500 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 444 Why does Marx place so much emphasis on the “reflux” <strong>of</strong> money implied in<br />

the form M −C − M?<br />

[456] Goethe: graded A– Acid reflux anyone? The reflux <strong>of</strong> money is the motivation<br />

that drives capitalism, and it is also the dirty secret <strong>of</strong> capitalists. I think Marx recognized<br />

that to have M-C-M the initial value which equates money would need to be derived from<br />

unnatural means i.e., money received from the sale and pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>of</strong> labor power <strong>of</strong> workers.<br />

This also brings into question <strong>of</strong> where or how the initial money was acquired. This is the<br />

other illusion <strong>of</strong> capitalism, that we all have a chance to be the owner <strong>of</strong> production, the<br />

promise <strong>of</strong> wealth from hard work and honest labor.<br />

I like what CousinIt states on [446] “Your manager probably ‘classifies’ himself as being<br />

above you. He may have an education and/or he may have reached his position through<br />

work experience or simple doled privilege (he has a daddy, a mommy, a girlie, or a buddy or<br />

he is particularly socially-situated so as to be given his position as your ‘manager’)” This is<br />

in reference to someone in authority, but it has certain parallels to the current class system.<br />

In order to achieve the means to become a successful capitalist and participate in M-C-M<br />

one needs to have an advantage over the ordinary person. It is true that one in a million will<br />

find the means to break free from their working class cage, and become multi-millionaires,<br />

but even these will have some advantages not afforded the average person. I believe that<br />

Marx recognized this and was able to identify the long run effect <strong>of</strong> reflux <strong>of</strong> money; the<br />

ever widening gap <strong>of</strong> social class and the increasing exploitation <strong>of</strong> the workers’ labor for<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Conclusion: I think Hans states this best in the annotations on the top <strong>of</strong> page 326 “Capitalists<br />

get what they spend and workers spend what they get”. If we were all paid a fair<br />

wage for our labor there would be no pr<strong>of</strong>its for the owners <strong>of</strong> production, and the corporate<br />

executives will never cut pr<strong>of</strong>its in favor <strong>of</strong> their labor. It is all about sale and pr<strong>of</strong>it...resale<br />

... pr<strong>of</strong>it... the circle <strong>of</strong> capitalism. We are all caught in this vicious circle to quote Thoreau<br />

“the mass <strong>of</strong> men lead lives <strong>of</strong> quiet desperation” This is due to the fact that the mass <strong>of</strong> men<br />

do not own or monopolize the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Hans: Marx is arguing on a much more technical level than you. He claims that the structure <strong>of</strong> circulation is such<br />

that the money the capitalists advance will eventually flow back to them. This technicality allows capitalists to<br />

remain capitalists. It is one <strong>of</strong> several factors which contribute to the class inequality which you are describing.<br />

Next Message by Goethe is [462].


184 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Question 452 is 182 in 1995ut, 217 in 1996sp, 234 in 1997WI, 294 in 1998WI, 306 in<br />

1999SP, 344 in 2001fa, 373 in 2002fa, 387 in 2003fa, 442 in 2007SP, 445 in 2007fa, 455<br />

in 2008fa, and 474 in 2009fa:<br />

Question 452 Why does monetary wealth have the urge to multiply itself? (Do not describe<br />

at this point how it does it but why in modern society the unlimited accumulation <strong>of</strong> wealth<br />

is such an overriding and powerful objective.)<br />

[458] Tim: content B+ form 95% In today’s capitalist society there is most definitely an<br />

overwhelming desire for most, if not all, to gain wealth, and lots <strong>of</strong> it. There is something<br />

about being a millionaire or having an endless supply <strong>of</strong> money that tempts the poorest <strong>of</strong><br />

the poor and the richest <strong>of</strong> the rich. Wealth is an interesting thing though. Is a man only<br />

wealthy because he has money or because he has more than his neighbor? To a man on the<br />

street who has nothing, one who is living out <strong>of</strong> his car might seem wealthy. Or to a man<br />

who is worth millions, his neighbor who is worth billions will seem wealthy.<br />

Thus does being wealthy mean having lots <strong>of</strong> money or just having more <strong>of</strong> it than your<br />

neighbor. If the latter is the case, then therein lies the answer to the question <strong>of</strong> why the<br />

acumination <strong>of</strong> wealth is such a powerful objective in the capitalist society. It is not so much<br />

the accumulation <strong>of</strong> wealth that is the driving force but the accumulation <strong>of</strong> more wealth<br />

than your neighbor that is the source <strong>of</strong> the desire.<br />

In our natural desire to be more and have more than the next guy, we are obsessed with<br />

the thought that if we could only have more money, or if we can only get our hands on<br />

that nice boat, car, or house then all our problems will be dissolved. Once those objects are<br />

obtained and in our possession and the problems are still in existence then the bigger house<br />

or car becomes our desire. Thus man’s search for “happiness” continues in its competitive<br />

manner until all are possessed with the desire to have more.<br />

Hans: You are missing the structural reasons which are emphasized by Marx. A good discussion <strong>of</strong> the issues can<br />

be found in [1999SP:179] and the two other answers in the same year.<br />

Message [458] referenced by [615]. Next Message by Tim is [459].<br />

[597] Srichardson: graded A Monetary Wealth. The goal <strong>of</strong> achieving absolute wealth<br />

can never be realized. Any amount <strong>of</strong> money is limited because it can eventually be used<br />

up. In modern society worth is determined by commodity wealth therefore an individual<br />

will prove his social validity by means <strong>of</strong> conspicuous consumption which may also by the<br />

valorization <strong>of</strong> money gives a human a feeling <strong>of</strong> security or piece <strong>of</strong> mind. According to<br />

Hans in [1999SP:206] “This is where individual motivation comes into play.” He goes on to<br />

say that “the urge to multiply monetary wealth is on a social and individual level.”<br />

Hans would argue that social forces are prevalent because the individual motivations are<br />

derived from the social structure. The urge to multiply monetary wealth arises due to people<br />

needing security and economic insecurity is a way to keep people adhering to these societal<br />

norms.<br />

Next Message by Srichardson is [598].<br />

[615] Chris: Excess greed and power. I have read many intriguing submissions to this<br />

question in [1999SP:179] thanks to Hans’s reference to these discussions in Tim’s [458]. My<br />

personal thought which I think a Marxist would argue to be true is that an individual’s access<br />

to capital, control, and greed are very detrimental factors affecting capitalists’ unlimited


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 185<br />

accumulation <strong>of</strong> wealth. These individual factors are also determined by what is ‘socially<br />

acceptable.’ Veblen points this out in [1999SP:180] which Hans builds on top <strong>of</strong> in his<br />

[1999SP:206], specifically the third point. For instance, one <strong>of</strong> the most popular shows on<br />

MTV aimed at a target audience <strong>of</strong> high school and college students is the show “MTV<br />

Cribs,” where celebrities and other social elites flaunt their new “toys” which usually consist<br />

<strong>of</strong> Bentleys, Lamborghinis, and plasma TVs. Our society today is destroying culture as we<br />

know it through the use <strong>of</strong> such programs and are contributing to the multiplication <strong>of</strong> wealth<br />

and greed.<br />

There were also a few comments to Question 458 in our current class that I feel play<br />

into dissecting Question 452. I feel that our society is ingraining these new “social values”<br />

<strong>of</strong> excess greed and control and we are seeing a new addiction to such excess forming.<br />

Capitalists along with many average hardworking Americans are constantly trying to keep<br />

up with what their neighbors have in terms <strong>of</strong> materialistic goods.<br />

I think this addiction brought upon by the corruption <strong>of</strong> what is deemed “appropriate” in<br />

our society affects all individuals <strong>of</strong> all backgrounds. The multiplication <strong>of</strong> wealth is most<br />

apparent in the capitalists because they are in charge <strong>of</strong> production and are in the eyes <strong>of</strong><br />

our public society. These capitalists will accumulate as much as they can by growing their<br />

private property (factories, etc.) and personal property (cars, etc.) at the exploitation <strong>of</strong> their<br />

workers. This vice continues to multiply through corporate greed and power, which is now<br />

socially accepted by American standards as I have seen through the use <strong>of</strong> popular television<br />

programs.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [616].<br />

[623] Jason: Maverick in [1999SP:179] says that money has the ability to buy any usevalue,<br />

but it is limited in how much it can buy. Eventually you will run out <strong>of</strong> money and not<br />

be able to buy more. Therefore people want to make money to help achieve the true value<br />

<strong>of</strong> money by having as much <strong>of</strong> it as they can.<br />

Another way <strong>of</strong> looking at it is people’s social status is largely determined by how much<br />

stuff they have. This leads into an endless cycle because the more things you have, the<br />

more money you need to afford them, due to large house payments, car payments, club<br />

memberships, etc. That and if the person is looking into the future they will probably want<br />

money saved up for further expenses. Therefore in our modern society the perpetual pursuit<br />

<strong>of</strong> money is almost required. Or at least it seems like it is to most people.<br />

Next Message by Jason is [783].<br />

[625] Slash: Monetary explosion. Monetary wealth has the urge to multiply itself because<br />

money is a social imperative. Society finds that qualitatively money is unlimited,<br />

which explains why the accumulation <strong>of</strong> money is attractive with the ability to qualitatively<br />

consume and obtain goods. There is also the fact <strong>of</strong> wanting more because others in a capitalistic<br />

society have more, this is the idea <strong>of</strong> keeping up with the neighbors. If the neighbors<br />

get a new boat there is a want for a bigger newer boat, in order to show them up. This can<br />

then be seen as a symbol <strong>of</strong> status rather than the simple use-value equated with a boat alone.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [708].<br />

[686] CousinIt: graded A insatiable wealth. Monetary wealth in modern society has the<br />

urge to multiply itself indefinitely because <strong>of</strong> to main factors; the structure <strong>of</strong> capitalism


186 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

as a socio-economic system coupled with the nature <strong>of</strong> money. In the structure <strong>of</strong> capitalism,<br />

as its name denotes, the driving goal to which there is no ideological upper limit is<br />

to increase capital. More capital (as ownership <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production or as monetary<br />

wealth) equals more power and socio-economic status and security. The structure <strong>of</strong> capitalist<br />

society, which has everything to do with the ideological investments <strong>of</strong> those under<br />

its yoke, dictates a particular definition and popular vision <strong>of</strong> ‘success’ which is necessarily<br />

linked to accumulation as the prime vehicle <strong>of</strong> attainment. Money has a universal qualitative<br />

characteristic that comes into sharp contradiction with its finite quantitative characteristic.<br />

Qualitatively, money as the universal equivalent has the characteristic that it can be exchanged<br />

for any and all commodities. Because capitalist society is focused on material<br />

accumulation as the primal goal, it follows that the more money one has, the more power<br />

one has, not only over others in society but presumably over one’s own ability to survive<br />

and to enhance and secure one’s survival. The implicit underlying notion that the urge to<br />

multiply wealth is driven by is that one can never have enough money to buy or to stockpile<br />

every commodity available for purchase, that is, one can never be powerful enough to<br />

achieve immortality. The perceived need to multiply wealth is therefore infinite.<br />

Quantitatively, money has the characteristic that it comes in a finite amount. There cannot<br />

ever be an infinity <strong>of</strong> material wealth. Money always comes in a finite sum and can only buy<br />

as much as that finite sum will allow. This finite quantitative property <strong>of</strong> money comes into<br />

contradiction with money’s qualitative property as that <strong>of</strong> being universally exchangeable.<br />

These contradictory quantitative and qualitative properties <strong>of</strong> money interact with the<br />

structure <strong>of</strong> capitalism. Capitalism forms the structural and ideological ground as well as<br />

logical warrant for the insane project <strong>of</strong> trying to secure one’s immortality by means <strong>of</strong><br />

material accumulation <strong>of</strong> wealth. What this amounts to is an irrational rationalism (<strong>of</strong> the<br />

sort that Horkheimer and Adorno discuss in their book “Dialectics <strong>of</strong> Enlightenment”) that<br />

justifies and maintains the capitalist system even though it clearly has very negative and<br />

potentially fatal effects on the vast majority <strong>of</strong> human beings globally, not to mention its<br />

negative and dangerous effects on all life on the planet. This overarching irrational rationale<br />

(as popular consensus) dictates the behaviors <strong>of</strong> its participants despite the facts <strong>of</strong> its detriment<br />

to their survival as a people or as a society, and perhaps as a species. Under capitalism,<br />

we are thus victims <strong>of</strong> ‘occupational psychosis’ <strong>of</strong> the sort I have discussed in [13] earlier in<br />

the semester.<br />

Hans: The structural social reasons do not only include money as source <strong>of</strong> power and status symbol, but also the<br />

separation <strong>of</strong> the direct producers from their means <strong>of</strong> production and therefore the availability <strong>of</strong> labor-power as a<br />

commodity.<br />

Next Message by CousinIt is [690].<br />

[718] Andy: In Class Response<br />

Monetary wealth has the urge to multiply itself because <strong>of</strong> greed, and not just greed but<br />

the constant comparing <strong>of</strong> people in a society. Someone In class gave this example and<br />

I believe that they hit the nail on the head. They talk about how a man who lives in a<br />

car maybe more wealthy to a guy that has no place to sleep, or a millionare may think that a<br />

billionare is wealthy. These are some examples but monetary wealth has the urge to multiply


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 187<br />

itself because everyone is comparing themselves to their neighbor which is a never ending<br />

road, and this is what multiplies itself. Its the “they have it I need it” attitude.<br />

Out <strong>of</strong> Class Response<br />

In adding to what I said in class, Marx says qualitatively, money gives access to all usevalues,<br />

qualitatively it is universal. This qualitative univerality comes in conflict with its<br />

quantitative boundedness, since money always only exists as a limited sum <strong>of</strong> money. This<br />

conflict tries to come to a resolution by quantitative expansion. The drive for quantitative<br />

expansion belongs therefor to the nature <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

Hans: A formulation in your own words would have been better than a literal copy from the Annotations. If you<br />

don’t use your own words I have no way knowing if you understand it now, and the re-formulation <strong>of</strong> the same idea<br />

by different people in their own words also is a useful addition to the archives.<br />

Next Message by Andy is [719].<br />

[762] Samantha: Capitalists are just compulsive gamblers, unable to leave the table.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the assigned questions during this past semester was on how capitalists are like<br />

alcoholics in that they sacrifice long-term positive gains for short term fulfillment. Part <strong>of</strong><br />

the reason that wealth has the urge to multiply itself is because <strong>of</strong> this fact, that the very<br />

structure <strong>of</strong> capitalism, which is to produce, to own and to make money. Capitalism is about<br />

the exploitation <strong>of</strong> labor and maximizing gains through minimizing costs. For example it<br />

is not about making the safest car but about making a car safe enough to pass government<br />

regulations.<br />

Capitalists want to control the means <strong>of</strong> production and they are always competing amongst<br />

themselves, which causes them to want more money to compete. More than just being an<br />

alcoholic, capitalists are like compulsive gamblers, they stay at the table and play the game<br />

not like it, or because they want to but because they keep thinking they are going to make a<br />

real gain. They forget that the house always wins, capitalism is the winner, not individuals,<br />

especially the laborers.<br />

An easy example <strong>of</strong> this is Kmart. The government has limited the amount that any<br />

one company can have within a market, so instead Kmart buys out their suppliers or their<br />

distributors. They gain but it still doesn’t seem enough so they expand how many stores<br />

they have, and so on. They grow until they are unable to grow anymore, and they start to<br />

decay while another group <strong>of</strong> capitalists comes in and takes over, much like Kmart did in<br />

the beginning. The downsize then causes then to loss some the gains they had made, exactly<br />

like the gambler, unable to leave the pr<strong>of</strong>it game.<br />

Next Message by Samantha is [763].<br />

Question 457 is 310 in 1999SP, 391 in 2003fa, 516 in 2010fa, and 551 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 457 Can a situation which gives you subjective satisfaction be a situation <strong>of</strong> “enslavement”?<br />

Are there other examples for this than the capitalist?<br />

[447] PrivateProperty: Systems <strong>of</strong> Enslavement: Drugs, Sex, and The Matrix. Probably<br />

the most poignant and relevant example I can think <strong>of</strong> is that <strong>of</strong> physical addiction. In these<br />

situations, a certain thing which has provided pleasure (alcohol, sex, drugs) eventually becomes<br />

the center around which addicts make their decisions. Addicts become physically<br />

enslaved to their addictions.


188 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

In years past, Guyote [1999SP:191] made a reference to masochism (which, for the unfamiliar,<br />

is gratification, usually sexual, from pain, suffering, and restraint). The reference<br />

is interesting as it is recognized as a psychiatric disorder, the acquisition <strong>of</strong> which is hardly<br />

under one’s control; thus, one could said to be “enslaved” by this disorder, yet deriving<br />

pleasure from it. As a response, Hans made the connection that perhaps the capitalist is a<br />

sort <strong>of</strong> masochist, deriving pleasure from activities that are ultimately to his detriment. In<br />

a later thread, Raleigh [2003fa:341] points out that there is a problem with this analogy, as<br />

masochists are aware <strong>of</strong> their disorder, while capitalists are not.<br />

With this in mind, I am reminded <strong>of</strong> the situation presented in the popular film The Matrix,<br />

in which our reality is in fact a computer-generated illusion which we are plugged into. The<br />

“real world” is in fact one in which humans are enslaved by machines. In the film, the Matrix<br />

was created to keep humans unaware <strong>of</strong> their own enslavement; and the only way the Matrix<br />

could be sustainable was if there were opportunities for pleasure and happiness. Thus, I feel<br />

the Matrix is a fitting analogy for the Capitalist system, though in Capitalism the system<br />

itself is responsible for the creation and perpetuation <strong>of</strong> the enslavement <strong>of</strong> its participants,<br />

not some external agent. Or is it....?<br />

The Matrix concept is nothing new. It is essentially a modern version <strong>of</strong> the “brain in<br />

a vat” thought experiment (look it up), which presupposes a disembodied brain, placed in<br />

a vat, that is connected to a supercomputer that recreates the same electrical signals that a<br />

normal brain receives. Thus, this disembodied brain may be experiencing a reality that does<br />

not, in fact, exist. The “brain in a vat” concept is itself derived from Descartes, who, in the<br />

words <strong>of</strong> Wikipedia, wrote that “...he could not trust his perceptions on the grounds that an<br />

evil demon might, conceivably, be controlling his every experience.” Interesting, huh?<br />

Message [447] referenced by [2010fa:593]. Next Message by PrivateProperty is [505].<br />

Question 458 is 448 in 2007SP, 461 in 2008fa, 480 in 2009fa, and 517 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 458 Can one say that the capitalists are addicted to making money?<br />

[453] Alex: graded B Addiction. I don’t believe that anyone can define addiction quite<br />

as well as Marx. His views on addiction are very specific and direct, even more so when<br />

they are put in the context <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. The capitalist is truly led to believe that he is<br />

overseeing the laborer and Marx goes as far as to call it enslavement. This alienation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

process and labor is extremely important to understanding the mindset <strong>of</strong> the capitalist.<br />

What does a capitalist have to gain from enslavement <strong>of</strong> the laborer? This conversation<br />

is abstract, but describes what the capitalist “needs” to justify himself. As Marx put it the<br />

“self-valorization” <strong>of</strong> capital. What does the capitalist really have to prove. A logical person<br />

removed from the situation would wonder why a capitalist has to go to such lengths. But<br />

this comes back to addiction. Marx is not just talking about a casual addiction, he is talking<br />

about a full fledged must have addiction.<br />

One can wonder to what degree this addiction is real in today’s business world. You may<br />

not see it at the entry level position, but as you look higher and higher there is a tremendous<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> need to control, exercise power and increase your position. The top rung <strong>of</strong> a large<br />

firm is not reserved for those who are casually addicted, top jobs are saved for those who are


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 189<br />

willing to give anything for the firm. The ramifications <strong>of</strong> which are felt today just as they<br />

were in Marx’s time. Greed knows all times and all places.<br />

I am very intrigued by Marx’s definition <strong>of</strong> addiction and I wonder where it has value used<br />

elsewhere. I wonder what I am “addicted” to and I wonder about others as well. One thing I<br />

am sure <strong>of</strong> is that addiction as it relates to money is one <strong>of</strong> the most addictive addictions one<br />

can have.<br />

Hans: Marx does not use the word “addiction,” and in [2007SP:701] I try to explain why not.<br />

Hans: On re-reading this I notice that you seem to think “self-valorization” is a psychological term, that the capitalist<br />

tries to assert his value by making more and more money. This is not at all what Marx means. “Valorization”<br />

is what value does when it is in motion, namely, add to its quantity.<br />

Message [453] referenced by [578]. Next Message by Alex is [468].<br />

[576] Alcameron: Capitalists Anonymous? We’ve all heard the term Work-a-holic,<br />

referring to someone who works too much and playing <strong>of</strong>f the term alcoholic, someone<br />

who drinks too much alcohol, or has an addiction. So who are work-a-holics, workers or<br />

capitalists? In order to understand if capitalists have an addiction to making money we must<br />

look at the level <strong>of</strong> enslavement they suffer. There is no doubt that capitalists’ actions are<br />

geared toward turning a greater pr<strong>of</strong>it and acquiring more capital and more wealth. Their<br />

actions are self-destructive though, just as many addicts have self-destructive habits. Are<br />

they enslaved as capitalists or addicted?<br />

Workers are enslaved by the capitalists for their labor power. The capitalist is benefiting<br />

from enslaving the worker and acquiring more money. Some capitalists may say they are<br />

enslaved because they must choose to continue as a capitalist or sell their labor to another<br />

capitalist, so they are merely making a decision <strong>of</strong> which side <strong>of</strong> the fence to be on rather<br />

than enslaving their workers. What drives them to desire more and more money? Well an<br />

addiction is an easy answer, it just never seems to be enough. Why can they not pay a higher<br />

wage to their workers, receive less pr<strong>of</strong>it, and afford the worker a chance to receive more<br />

income for their labor? Just as a drug addict continues habits that hurt themselves and other<br />

around them, the capitalist continues to enslave workers to feed their addiction <strong>of</strong> money.<br />

By looking at some <strong>of</strong> the most powerful capitalists we can see this addiction in a glaring<br />

fashion. What need does Bill Gates have for another million, or billion dollars? If he chose<br />

not to work another day in his life, he and 3 generations could live <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> the interest accumlated<br />

by his wealth. Is work not a means to survive and supply for your loved ones? Well for<br />

the average worker it is, but for the capitalist it is a way to feed an addiction that can never<br />

be satisfied.<br />

Message [576] referenced by [578]. Next Message by Alcameron is [735].<br />

[578] Hans: Is Capitalism Based on Addiction? It would be wrong to say that capitalism<br />

exists because the capitalists are addicted to money. The necessity <strong>of</strong> economic “growth”<br />

and the concentration <strong>of</strong> wealth are powerful social imperatives. Marx does not explain them<br />

by the greed <strong>of</strong> the capitalists, but by the one-dimensionality <strong>of</strong> money and the availability<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor-power as a commodity.<br />

On the other hand, these structural imperatives are supplemented and strengthened by<br />

the motivations <strong>of</strong> the capitalists to make a lot <strong>of</strong> money. Making money can be an allconsuming<br />

obsession which harms not only the worker but also the capitalist himself, as<br />

Alcameron stresses in [576]. Marx remarked that the workers are not the only ones alienated;


190 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the capitalists are alienated too because they devote their lives to the stupid and senseless<br />

drive <strong>of</strong> money to increase itself. But if someone thinks the only choices available are<br />

either the alienation <strong>of</strong> a worker or that <strong>of</strong> a capitalist, and chooses the capitalist, this is<br />

not necessarily a sign <strong>of</strong> addiction. Perhaps these individuals are just trying to be better<br />

providers for their families. (I am using here ideas from [576].)<br />

Global Warming brings in new perspectives. Does the inability <strong>of</strong> our society to do what<br />

is necessary to save ourselves from climate catastrophe not have parallels to the behavior <strong>of</strong><br />

an addict? An addict is driven down a self-destructive path by near-term rewards and pains.<br />

I still don’t think that capitalism, as Marx understood it, can be equated to an addiction. It<br />

is more akin to an infantile disorder, to growing pains in humankind’s historical progression.<br />

But this conflictual development phase may have prepared the ground for our society’s<br />

addiction to fossil fuels. Instead <strong>of</strong> getting rid <strong>of</strong> the capitalists, the working class entered<br />

into an uneasy compromise with them based on a joint exploitation <strong>of</strong> the bonanza <strong>of</strong> fossil<br />

fuels. And now we cannot turn away from fossil fuels because neither <strong>of</strong> the classes is strong<br />

enough to shift the cost <strong>of</strong> switching to renewable energy to the other class. If this is the case,<br />

then the best strategy to avert global warming would be a mass movement strengthening the<br />

working class enough so that they can force the capitalists to eat the costs <strong>of</strong> switching to a<br />

sustainable economy.<br />

Brief comments about the previous submissions: Alex [453] explains capitalism by the<br />

addiction <strong>of</strong> the capitalists, while Alcameron [576] seems more open to the possibility that<br />

the capitalists’ relentless drive for pr<strong>of</strong>its, which goes to the extent where it no longer benefits<br />

them personally or anybody else, may not come from their own motivation but is a necessity<br />

<strong>of</strong> the system they live in.<br />

Message [578] referenced by [646], [753], and [2008fa:713]. Next Message by Hans is [580].<br />

[626] Kevin: graded A Capitalists are not addicted to making money but it is value itself<br />

that gains value and compels the capitalists to try and gain more [2007SP:701]. While<br />

it seems we are constantly tearing the capitalist down being the source <strong>of</strong> this evil, it is<br />

an unfortunate necessary evil <strong>of</strong> the capitalist’s environment that he must make money to<br />

survive. It is true that there are some capitalists that are consumed by making money which<br />

harms not only them but their environment as well, but in general capitalists are not addicted<br />

to making money. They just look for ways to improve their standard <strong>of</strong> living by taking<br />

advantage <strong>of</strong> the capitalist economy.<br />

Next Message by Kevin is [627].<br />

[673] PrivateProperty: Addiction. Yes, one could say that, in reaping surplus value <strong>of</strong><br />

workers, the capitalist experiences pleasure and wants to reproduce this sensation over and<br />

over again. In this sense it would be a chemical addiction in the brain.<br />

But the reason the reaping <strong>of</strong> this surplus value is pleasurable in the first place stems<br />

from the commodity relation and thus social structure as a whole. In this sense an individual<br />

capitalist can’t be blamed for their addiction. The entire capitalist system uses individuals<br />

(both capitalists and laborers) as marionettes to achieve the ends <strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

Just as an addiction is uncontrollable and takes on a life <strong>of</strong> its own, capital also becomes<br />

an end unto itself controlling the behaviors <strong>of</strong> market participants.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 191<br />

Hans: Your in-class answer had also the sentence: “It is actually the capitalist system in totality that is addicted to<br />

making money.” This is an important additional point that is missing in your resubmission. The accumulation <strong>of</strong><br />

monetary wealth and growth are not imposed on the system by the greed or the addiction <strong>of</strong> the capitalists, but they<br />

are built into the system.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [677].<br />

[684] Dyoung: I would say that capitalists are addicted to making money. They tend to<br />

become “workaholics” because they are so involved in making money and always trying<br />

to figure out more efficient ways to increase there pr<strong>of</strong>its. As they gain more pr<strong>of</strong>its they<br />

become addicted to exploiting their workers to make more money.<br />

Capitalists tend to hire workers for their labor power but ends up paying them just for<br />

their labor because if they do this the capitalist ends up with more gains. Which looks like<br />

an addiction to me. As employee’s work that extra hour over what he is paid the capitalist<br />

starts benefiting ten fold.<br />

There are many examples <strong>of</strong> individuals who we see as addicted to money. Bill Gates<br />

would be a great example. He already has made more money than one person could ever<br />

need in a lifetime. He never needs to work another day but we know that he still works<br />

because he loves money, “he is addicted” I believe it has to do with power, people are<br />

addicted to power and money tends to give people that power. The more money you have<br />

the more powerful you become. I don’t think that it is a good thing that capitalists are<br />

addicted to money. I believe that any addiction is not good, when you become addicted to<br />

something you can’t go without it and you will do anything to get it. Which in a capitalist<br />

case they start too work to many hours and avoid their family and social lives, they end up<br />

exploiting their employees making them unhappy about coming to work. Addictions are<br />

scary things and are something that everyone needs to be aware <strong>of</strong>. But capitalists do tend<br />

to be addicted to money because they have access to more than those who are the workers.<br />

Hans: In your second paragraph you have labor and labor-power reversed. Capitalists hire laborers, i.e., buy their<br />

labor-power, because they want to materialize their labor in a product they can sell. This labor creates more value<br />

than the value they have to pay for labor-power (the reproduction cost <strong>of</strong> their labor-power).<br />

You are also missing the systemic dimension <strong>of</strong> this addiction.<br />

Next Message by Dyoung is [685].<br />

[735] Alcameron: One cannot say that capitalists are addicted to making money. Capitalists<br />

choose which side <strong>of</strong> the fence to be on, they can either exploit workers for their labor or<br />

be exploited by another capitalist. Rather than being enslaved to another capitalist by selling<br />

their labor, some capitalists prefer to exploit the labor power <strong>of</strong> others. This still bodes the<br />

question though, why do capitalists always strive for more? No amount <strong>of</strong> money or capital<br />

ever seems to be enough. Like a drug addict the capitalists’ actions are self-destructive. In<br />

this sense it may be an addiction, but overall the capitalists’ actions play an important role<br />

in the market.<br />

Hans: If they don’t strive for more they will not remain capitalists for long. It is grow or die for them.<br />

Next Message by Alcameron is [736].<br />

[753] Clayon: An addiction is a self-destructive course one takes by ignoring long-term<br />

consequences and only focusing on the short-term wants and desires. Capitalists themselves<br />

are not addicted to making money, but capitalism indirectly has made society addicted and<br />

dependent on things such as fossil fuel and convenience (including the capitalists’). Neither<br />

the laborer nor the capitalist wants to bear the cost <strong>of</strong> changing energy sources. These costs


192 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

could altogether be avoided if we decided to live different lifestyles, heating our homes and<br />

using transportation that does not require the use <strong>of</strong> fossil fuel (horse and buggy), but society<br />

prefers the short-term convenience. Thus we see that it is the social relation to which the<br />

capitalist is enslaved.<br />

Hans: My [578] tried to explain society’s present inability to properly respond to global warming in the context <strong>of</strong><br />

the over 200-year-old class struggle between capitalist and worker. Your reading <strong>of</strong> it strips all the class struggle<br />

out and makes it a matter <strong>of</strong> human shortsightedness, laziness, and inertia. This is quite a different explanation.<br />

BTW, nobody proposes to go back to horse and buggy. People are talking about mass transit, electric cars,<br />

bicycles on a safe network <strong>of</strong> bikepaths, and reduction <strong>of</strong> urban sprawl.<br />

Next Message by Clayon is [755].<br />

[758] Ken: addiction. You could say a capitalist becomes addicted to money because <strong>of</strong><br />

the capitalistic society that he lives in. The capitalistic society creates an unlimited want for<br />

money. The more money you have the more commodities you can buy. There is a nearly<br />

unlimited amount <strong>of</strong> commodities you can buy. This is where people would consider the<br />

capitalist addicted to money because the capitalist always wants more material wealth.<br />

Hans: Capitalism is a society in which value is a dynamic, expanding quantity. This is not caused by the capitalists<br />

but by the one-dimensionality <strong>of</strong> monetary wealth (which you mention) and by the separation <strong>of</strong> the working class<br />

from the means <strong>of</strong> production and therefore the availability <strong>of</strong> the commodity labor-power on the market (which<br />

you also should have mentioned).<br />

Next Message by Ken is [759].<br />

Question 470 is 306 in 1998WI, 340 in 2000fa, 402 in 2003fa, 451 in 2004fa, 463 in<br />

2007fa, 529 in 2010fa, 545 in 2011fa, 569 in 2012fa, and 529 in Answer:<br />

Question 470 Does Marx argue in 258:2/o that capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its are middleman’s pr<strong>of</strong>its,<br />

and if buyer and seller sold directly to each other, there would be no pr<strong>of</strong>it?<br />

[481] Ande: Yes in a sense Marx argues that the capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its are the middleman’s<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its, he does not openly come out and say that but when he starts switching around the<br />

equation from M-C-M to C-M-C I personally feel he is trying to say that capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its are<br />

the middleman’s pr<strong>of</strong>its. It is a very challenging question but after doing the readings I have<br />

deciphered that Marx has a lot <strong>of</strong> hidden things in his readings and when he did switch the<br />

equations I was taking it as the capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its are the middleman’s pr<strong>of</strong>its. I have to say<br />

that although he said that about the middleman, he never once said or hinted that if buyer and<br />

seller sold directly to each other there would be no pr<strong>of</strong>it. He never said anything about each<br />

buyer and seller getting things for free, he simply talked about cutting out the middleman.<br />

In a sense if you cut out the middleman your pr<strong>of</strong>its would go down, but there would always<br />

be pr<strong>of</strong>it. The seller sets his or her own price whether he or she is selling directly to the<br />

buyer or the middleman there is always pr<strong>of</strong>it to be made. The seller is not going to give<br />

something away to the buyer for free, they will always try to make some sort <strong>of</strong> a pr<strong>of</strong>it. So I<br />

would have to agree that Marx is trying to say the capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its are middleman’s pr<strong>of</strong>its,<br />

but I do not think in the least that he is telling us that if you cut out the middleman and sell<br />

directly to the buyer there is no pr<strong>of</strong>it to be made, there is always some sort <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it to be<br />

made. Pr<strong>of</strong>it does not always come in the form <strong>of</strong> currency and that is something you have<br />

to think about when you are talking about making a pr<strong>of</strong>it, pr<strong>of</strong>it comes in many other forms<br />

than currency.<br />

Message [481] referenced by [495]. Next Message by Ande is [522].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 193<br />

[495] Hans: Do the means <strong>of</strong> production create value? Ande’s answer “yes” to the first<br />

half <strong>of</strong> the question in [481] is based on a misunderstanding. Ande takes Marx’s illustrations<br />

too literally. Marx enlivens his theoretical development by imaginary dialoges between<br />

capitalists and other commodity traders, in order to get the point across that there is nothing<br />

in the circulation process itself which could give rise to capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its. The source <strong>of</strong> these<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its must therefore be found elsewhere, not in circulation.<br />

During his answer, Ande says the following about pr<strong>of</strong>its:<br />

“The seller is not going to give something away to the buyer for free, they<br />

will always try to make some sort <strong>of</strong> a pr<strong>of</strong>it.”<br />

This is similar to Marx’s starting point in chapters 4, 5, and 6: in our society, businesses<br />

are successfully going through the cycle M-C-M’ which gives them pr<strong>of</strong>it. And this pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

is not due to overcharging, on the contrary, this pr<strong>of</strong>it is part <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the output. Not<br />

taking the pr<strong>of</strong>it would amount to giving the buyer something for free.<br />

Marx considers this a riddle, because he is wondering: if it is true that value comes from<br />

labor, then commodity-producing labor should be the only way to make an income. Where<br />

does the pr<strong>of</strong>it come from?<br />

Ande does not present it as a riddle, presumably because he has the explanation <strong>of</strong> mainstream<br />

economics in mind. In this explanation, labor is not the only source <strong>of</strong> value, but all<br />

factors <strong>of</strong> production create value. The pr<strong>of</strong>it is that part <strong>of</strong> the value created by the factors<br />

<strong>of</strong> production owned by the capitalist.<br />

Marx does not buy this explanation, and I’d like to explain here why. What do the nonlabor<br />

factors <strong>of</strong> production consist <strong>of</strong>? Nature and produced means <strong>of</strong> production. Let’s look<br />

at them one by one.<br />

Nature supplies services without charging for them. If someone charges for natural services,<br />

they use their control <strong>of</strong> nature as a means to appropriate the labor <strong>of</strong> others. They<br />

cannot justify it by saying that nature is necessary for the production <strong>of</strong> use-values. Value is<br />

a social relation, and nature is not part <strong>of</strong> society. Nature simply cannot and does not create<br />

value.<br />

Produced means <strong>of</strong> production, such as machines, contain labor. This labor was rewarded<br />

when the machine was bought. Why should this machine keep getting rewards? According<br />

to the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value, machines transfer their own value to the product, but do not<br />

create additional value.<br />

In summary, labor is the only source <strong>of</strong> value because labor costs are the only costs which<br />

society has to bear; everything else is free. I already said this [62].<br />

This is why Marx devotes three chapters to explaining where the pr<strong>of</strong>its in M-C-M’ come<br />

from. Marx’s explanation <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its is that the laborer does not get a full equivalent <strong>of</strong> the<br />

value they produce during the day, but they get less. They get full value <strong>of</strong> their labor-power,<br />

which is the commodity they sell the capitalists. This value is a reimbursement for the<br />

reproduction cost <strong>of</strong> themselves and their labor-power. But this reproduction cost is much<br />

less than the value produced during the day. They are forced to sell their labor-power, instead


194 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> benefitting from the value this labor-power produces, because they are cut <strong>of</strong>f from the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

This is the core <strong>of</strong> Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its. Marx says here that behind the egalitarian<br />

exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities lurks a very in-egalitarian and unjust class relationship. Workers<br />

do not see this injustice because they are not aware <strong>of</strong> how much value their own labor<br />

produces. They think part <strong>of</strong> the value which they themselves produce comes not from<br />

themselves but comes from the machines.<br />

Machines play only one part in this: the fact that these machines belong to the capitalists<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> being democratically controlled by the workers allows the capitalists to appropriate<br />

for themselves part <strong>of</strong> the value produced by the workers’ labor.<br />

Message [495] referenced by [Answer:3], [2008fa:144], and [2008fa:748]. Next Message by Hans is [496].<br />

Exam Question 474 is 307 in 1998WI, 341 in 2000fa, 359 in 2001fa, 391 in 2002fa, 405<br />

in 2003fa, 454 in 2004fa, 431 in 2005fa, 463 in 2007SP, 467 in 2007fa, 477 in 2008fa,<br />

549 in 2011fa, and 573 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam Question 474 Is exchange (direct barter) a transaction in which both sides gain more<br />

than they give up?<br />

[476] Andy: Marx starts <strong>of</strong>f answering this question giving an example <strong>of</strong> money saying<br />

that if you “make change” (exchange dollar bills for smaller bills or coins), you dont think<br />

you have different amounts <strong>of</strong> money, it is the same money in different form. Then he goes<br />

on to explain that if you go on to buy something with your money, you no longer have the<br />

money but you still have the same value just a different form, and this form does not change<br />

the quantity <strong>of</strong> your value. So Marx draws a conclusion from all <strong>of</strong> this saying that the lesson<br />

to be drawn from this is that circulation cannot be the source <strong>of</strong> value. Meaning that when<br />

use-values are exchanged both buyer and seller may possibly gain something, but not in the<br />

case <strong>of</strong> exchange-values. Because Marx believes that “where there is equality there is no<br />

gain”, and therefore the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities are exchange <strong>of</strong> equivalents, and it is not<br />

a method <strong>of</strong> increasing value.<br />

Hans: I am not sure you noticed that this is not a homework question but a designated exam question. In the exam,<br />

you should give a reasonably short answer, for instance: “In terms <strong>of</strong> use-values, both parties gain, but in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchange-values, it is a zero sum game: one gains what the other loses.” If you formulate it this way, you are<br />

not making the assumption that equivalents are exchanged. My [2005fa:1791] explains why this is an important<br />

question.<br />

Message [476] referenced by [566] and [574]. Next Message by Andy is [542].<br />

[566] Bmellor: Exchange is equivalent. Andy [476] is correct in his statement a quicker<br />

and more precise answer... In its pure form the exchange <strong>of</strong> commodities is an exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong> equivalents and thus not a method <strong>of</strong> increasing value. So the answer would be no, the<br />

exchange is equivalent.<br />

Message [566] referenced by [567]. Next Message by Bmellor is [614].<br />

[567] Hans: Both sides <strong>of</strong> the answer are needed. Bmellor’s answer [566] is incomplete.<br />

A complete answer must distinguish between gains <strong>of</strong> value and gains <strong>of</strong> use-value. In terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> value, exchange is a zero-sum game, i.e., one gains what the other loses. In terms <strong>of</strong><br />

use-value, both sides gain.<br />

Message [567] referenced by [574]. Next Message by Hans is [568].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 195<br />

[573] FacistFrank: it would make a lot <strong>of</strong> sense to me that the exchange is either equal<br />

or close to equal, the point is that the traders <strong>of</strong> the goods think they are equal in real value,<br />

which means they are close in real congealed labor content, or there is some kind <strong>of</strong> coercion,<br />

or the deal is being forced to occur. In modern non Marxian economics, there is a condition<br />

that is set for theoretical exercises that assumes conditions are ideal, i’m assuming that the<br />

same thing is happening here, it would be far too confusing if it wasn’t.<br />

but anyways like Hans says, in Marxian economics the labor values <strong>of</strong> the goods exchanged<br />

are equal in perfect conditions, but the use values are drastically different, because<br />

it would be absurd to exchange two exact use values. i’m also assuming that the traders each<br />

leave with better use values than they entered in with, so the trade is overall not equal, but<br />

both people gain, albeit from use values only.<br />

Message [573] referenced by [574]. Next Message by FacistFrank is [679].<br />

[574] Hans: Have it your way. I made it abundantly clear how I personally would<br />

answer this, for instance in [567] or my notes to Andy’s [476] or in many submissions in<br />

earlier Semesters such as [2004fa:429]. But others would express it in other words, and<br />

FacistFrank’s [573] is definitely in the range <strong>of</strong> answers I consider correct. He gets full<br />

credit for it. I appreciate that he does not just repeat but gives an explanation that makes<br />

sense to himself and conforms to his thinking. This is the right way to learn things, and it is<br />

instructive for others too.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [578].<br />

[575] Raynold: I would agree with Marx that “where there is equality there is no gain.”<br />

Meaning that there is no pr<strong>of</strong>it made from an equal exchange. An exchange should not be<br />

a transaction in which both sides gain more than they give up, it should be equivalent. I<br />

understand it best with the example <strong>of</strong> the dollar. If a hundred dollar bill was exchanged for<br />

change in lower bills and coins, the amount <strong>of</strong> money would be exactly the same. Now if<br />

that hundred dollars was spent on buying a commodity, then you no longer have the hundred<br />

dollars but you have something worth the same value only in different form. Because the<br />

exchange was money for a product, both buyer and seller’s use-value may catch a gain but<br />

this is not the case for exchange-value. Nothing is gained or lost for exchange value which<br />

therefore makes the exchange equivalent.<br />

Hans: This is also a right answer. You are emphasizing that no new exchange-value is created in the exchange, but<br />

you are also mentioning that in terms <strong>of</strong> use-value, both paries gain.<br />

Next Message by Raynold is [710].<br />

[583] Mick: graded B Depends what the ‘gain’ is. Obviously barter takes place because<br />

the two parties involved conclude that their subjective situations will improve in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

utility from the transaction. So yes there is a gain, but is it not empirical. It is a subjective<br />

gain....a squirt <strong>of</strong> dopamine in the brain (utility). A value gain though, like inertia, cannot<br />

be created. Any perceived gain would be purely synthetic, and therefore a delusion. In this<br />

light, value, like matter, exists and cannot be created or destroyed.<br />

Message [583] referenced by [586]. Next Message by Mick is [614].<br />

[586] Hans: Use-value is More Than Dopamine. Mick [583] says that the gain in usevalues<br />

is only imagined, it is only a chemical in the brain but cannot be measured empirically.<br />

This forgets that the dopamine in the brain is the reaction to a real improvement <strong>of</strong> the<br />

situation. It is not just imagination but a real gain if those hungry get food, and if also


196 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

otherwise the products are transferred from their point <strong>of</strong> production to those who need<br />

them. In this respect, the exchange process is indeed a real gain for all involved.<br />

Message [586] referenced by [604]. Next Message by Hans is [596].<br />

[604] Hans: Why Use-Value and Exchange-Value Must Be Distinguished. Someone<br />

wrote in the exam:<br />

Exchange is a transaction in which both sides feel they gained more than<br />

they gave up. If this were not the case, then neither party would be willing<br />

to exchange products. A person would not barter for a product that they felt<br />

was worth less than what they were giving up.<br />

This argument shows how easy it is to slip into fallacies if one fails to distinguish usevalue<br />

and exchange-value. People make exchanges because exchanges move the use-values<br />

to the place where they are needed. I.e., in terms <strong>of</strong> use-values there is a gain. The increased<br />

utility which people feel is a reflection <strong>of</strong> this, as I said in [586]. But such a gain does not<br />

mean the value <strong>of</strong> the goods has increased. If you go to a money changer to change a five<br />

into four ones and four quarters, then you don’t think the four ones and four quarters are<br />

worth more than the five. You think it is worth the same, but in a more useful form.<br />

If one does not distinguish between use-value and exchange-value (or the value inherent<br />

in commodities which guides their exchange-value), but muddles them together in some unspecified<br />

“worth,” then one comes to the conclusion that the exchange process is the source<br />

<strong>of</strong> worth. This makes is more difficult to see that by just moving things around one does<br />

not produce any additional value, and that the value (not just use-value) which the capitalists<br />

pull out <strong>of</strong> the sphere <strong>of</strong> exchange must have been put in by someone – namely by the<br />

laborers producing more value than they get in their wages.<br />

My collection <strong>of</strong> Marx’s bumper stickers, started in [2007SP:387], just got bigger: Marx<br />

also had a bumper sticker saying “use-value and exchange-value must be distinguished at all<br />

times.”<br />

Message [604] referenced by [612] and [2008fa:906]. Next Message by Hans is [620].<br />

[612] SnatchimusMaximus: Can the capitalist be blamed for grape gatorade? That is<br />

my question/response regarding the following passage in [604]<br />

If one does not distinguish between use-value and exchange-value (or the<br />

value inherent in commodities which guides their exchange-value), but<br />

muddles them together in some unspecified “worth,” then one comes to the<br />

conclusion that the exchange process is the source <strong>of</strong> worth. This makes is<br />

more difficult to see that by just moving things around one does not produce<br />

any additional value, and that the value (not just use-value) which the capitalists<br />

pull out <strong>of</strong> the sphere <strong>of</strong> exchange must have been put in by someone<br />

– namely by the laborers producing more value than they get in their wages.<br />

For the first time this semester I can half-heartedly side with the capitalist. To illustrate<br />

I will cite a recent trek through Guatemala. After days <strong>of</strong> traveling through El Salvador on<br />

countless chicken buses, I found myself in Guatemala City at the transfer station to Coban.<br />

My time in Guatemala was limited so I didn’t want to miss my ride. Upon my arrival at


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 197<br />

the transfer station I barely had enough time to purchase a ticket and board the next bus.<br />

I arrived in Coban, the next transfer station, after six hours <strong>of</strong> heat and no water. My final<br />

destination was Semuc Champey and upon arrival in Coban, I discovered that the last Combi<br />

van was departing immediately. My throat was parched and my bladder was bursting. I only<br />

had enough time to satisfy one <strong>of</strong> my body’s requests. I chose to find a secluded ally rather<br />

than a bottle <strong>of</strong> water. I felt as though I had made a wise decision as the Combi soon turned<br />

onto a washboard-riddled road that vibrated my soul to its very core. After seven hours <strong>of</strong><br />

traversing high-mountain passes, I arrived at my final location- Semuc Champey.<br />

It had been over twelve hours since any source <strong>of</strong> hydration had graced my mouth. My<br />

eyes searched the thick darkness for any flickering light that indicated the presence <strong>of</strong> a<br />

local tienda. I saw a shop owner closing his doors the ensuing surge <strong>of</strong> adrenaline quickly<br />

overpowered my throat’s cries for help. I grabbed the door out <strong>of</strong> the shop owners hands<br />

and nearly ripped it from its hinges. Immediately he began spitting pr<strong>of</strong>anity at me in his<br />

native tongue <strong>of</strong> Kakchiquel. Though I could not understand him, his intentions were clear.<br />

I reached into my pocket and pulled out the first bill that met my hands. It was a 50 quetzal<br />

bill, the equivalent <strong>of</strong> $7.00 US. I threw the bill to the man and grabbed the first fluid that<br />

befell upon my aching eyes. It was a grape gatorade. I downed half <strong>of</strong> it as quickly as I<br />

could swallow. I then returned to the man expecting my change. He informed me, this time<br />

in Spanish, that I would receive no change because each gatorade cost 100 quetzal. Not<br />

wanting to incite a riot in the tops <strong>of</strong> the Guatemalan mountains, I smiled, thanked him for<br />

the beverage, and bid him buenos noches.<br />

After my thirst was quenched and buyers remorse set in, I became upset. How could he<br />

take advantage <strong>of</strong> a foreigner in strange lands that was dying <strong>of</strong> dehydration? How could he<br />

charge me $7.00 for a gatorade when my room for the night was only $2.50? Unfortunately,<br />

this tienda was the only tienda in the village and I could not take out my aggressions by<br />

boycotting his products. While in the village I became familiar with the tienda owner’s<br />

family and I was overwhelmed by their friendship. Consequently my animosity subsided.<br />

After three days I returned to Guatemala City to end my journey.<br />

As I was exiting the bus from Semuc Champey I noticed a familiar face – it was the tienda<br />

owner’s wife. She was returning to her village from the big city and was bringing supplies<br />

for resale at her tienda. She had several bags in her hand and in the basket on top <strong>of</strong> her head<br />

she was carrying two-dozen grape gatorades. She beamed a smile from ear to ear and said<br />

“You Gringos sure like grape gatorade!”<br />

I have always found the story humorous but now I wonder–was that exploitation? Certainly<br />

not all <strong>of</strong> the 50 quetzals that I had paid for my grape gatorade was entirely pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

It had cost 100 quetzals to travel from Guatemala City to Semuc Champey, 75 cents per<br />

gatorade, and then I factored 12 hours travel time into the equation. The total price that the<br />

tienda owner paid for each gatorade is still unknown.<br />

I do not think this exploitation however. Though the tienda owners had merely “moved<br />

things around,” they had undoubtedly added a significant value to the gatorade. But had they<br />

created enough value to justify charging $7.00 for a gatorade in Guatemala? I hardly doubt<br />

that. So, in a long awaited conclusion, I can only state that not all <strong>of</strong> the capitalist’s pr<strong>of</strong>its


198 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

come from exploitation. Good fortune may shine down on the capitalist, though he may<br />

possibly be the most unworthy candidate.<br />

Additionally, I would like to ask what Marx would call this so called “good fortune.” Any<br />

takers? Hans, I know you have a clever comment. Good night.<br />

Message [612] referenced by [620]. First Message by SnatchimusMaximus is [21].<br />

[620] Hans: Gatorade in Guatemala. In response to SnatchimusMaximus’s [612] I’d<br />

like to say: don’t look at things in isolation but consider the circumstances. You didn’t just<br />

buy gatorade in a store, you got it in the middle <strong>of</strong> the night after the store was closed. As<br />

you are telling it, it was not exactly a voluntary transaction on the part <strong>of</strong> the seller. No<br />

wonder he didn’t feel obligated to give you change.<br />

Also don’t forget that you were an American tourist in an impoverished country. Of<br />

course people will sell you things above their values. They probably consider it just as getting<br />

back a little bit <strong>of</strong> the damage which the US has been doing to their countries. We have<br />

to be very gracious about this, as the relative beneficiaries <strong>of</strong> a very unjust social relation.<br />

Besides, I am not certain whether the shopkeeper should really be called a “capitalist.”<br />

He apparently put in long hours himself. Did he employ anybody in his shop besides his<br />

family?<br />

Message [620] referenced by [624] and [656]. Next Message by Hans is [646].<br />

[624] Nstew: Happiness in Guatemala. Why is it that you say in [620] the United States<br />

is doing damage to their country when we are the top importers from their country? We are<br />

providing many people in their country with jobs by importing their products. I met with<br />

Ambassador from Guatemala when he was in <strong>Utah</strong> last year and he was very happy with<br />

everything the U.S. was importing from them. I work for an importing company and the<br />

reason he visited us was to inform us <strong>of</strong> the work being done in Guatemala and trying to<br />

provide the people <strong>of</strong> his country with more opportunities for trade with the U.S.<br />

Although the shop keeper may not be a capitalist because he is not employing anyone<br />

other than his family. The question is if he had the resources and the opportunity to open up<br />

a chain <strong>of</strong> shops across the country <strong>of</strong> Guatemala and provide many people in his country<br />

with income and jobs and also make money for himself. Then he would be considered a<br />

‘capitalist’ but it seems he would only be doing more good so what would be with that?<br />

Message [624] referenced by [656]. Next Message by Nstew is [647].<br />

[656] Hans: Genocide in Guatemala. Nstew asked in [624]:<br />

Why is it that you say in [620] the United States is doing damage to their<br />

country when we are the top importers from their country?<br />

If the US sinned in Latin America, Guatemala is probably one <strong>of</strong> the worst sins. Under<br />

Eisenhower in 1954, the CIA overthrew the freely elected government <strong>of</strong> Jacobo Arbenz.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the reasons was that some <strong>of</strong> the land owned by United Fruit Company, now Chiquita,<br />

was nationalized with compensation. In the 1980s, the Guatemala military junta waged a<br />

campaign <strong>of</strong> brutal genocide against the indigenous population. This made Guatemala an<br />

international pariah state, but the US continued to support it. In 1999, U.S. president Bill<br />

Clinton stated that the United States was wrong to have provided support to Guatemalan<br />

military forces that took part in the brutal civilian killings.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 199<br />

If you want to know more about these things you should attend the classes by my colleagues<br />

Ken Jameson or Matias Vernengo.<br />

Hans: Someone (Ken Jameson?) just slipped a newspaper article under my door, saying that on January 14, 2008<br />

Alvaro Colom was sworn in as Guatemala’s first leftist president since Jacobo Arbenz.<br />

http://www.iht.com/articles/ap/2008/01/14/america/LA-GEN-Guatemala-Inauguration.php<br />

Next Message by Hans is [683].<br />

Question 475 is 432 in 2005fa, 478 in 2008fa, 497 in 2009fa, and 550 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 475 Show exactly where Condillac, in the above quote, conflates use-value and<br />

exchange-value.<br />

[477] Rmuscolino: Condillac conflates use-value and exchange-value by stating that we<br />

don’t exactly give value for value and that we actually give less for a greater value. That<br />

makes sense for use-value because we all have different preferences and have a different<br />

use-value than someone else may have. He makes the mistake <strong>of</strong> confusing the two concepts<br />

by saying, “each <strong>of</strong> the two contracting parties in every case gives a less for a greater value.”<br />

This is a mistake because each individual gets a different use out <strong>of</strong> each commodity so<br />

everyone has different preferences and tastes. So by exchanging these two commodities, its<br />

not the fact that one person is giving less for more because the the other person would be<br />

receiving just as much since they feel as though they are giving less for more as well.<br />

Next Message by Rmuscolino is [603].<br />

Question 476 is 392 in 2002fa, 406 in 2003fa, 456 in 2004fa, and 575 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 476 In what way does the following remark poke fun at Condillac? “If both the<br />

persons who exchange receive more in return for an equal amount, and part with less in<br />

return for an equal amount, then they both get the same.”<br />

[468] Alex: graded B– Poking Fun at Condillac. Condillac has some interesting thoughts,<br />

but one has to wonder what exactly his influence is. Value is certainly a center point for<br />

Marx, whether it be use or exchange. These ideas have very specific meanings and intuitions.<br />

Condillac on the other hand is very confused on his interpretations. His use value is<br />

more acurately described as a “need” value.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> course will not part with something they need, according to Condillac. As such<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is very subjective to the possessor. As such, one will only part<br />

with those things that are <strong>of</strong> lesser value to get something that is <strong>of</strong> greater value. Thus the<br />

statement “if both the persons who exchange receive more in return for an equal amount and<br />

part with less in return for an eual amout, then they both get the same.” This statement the<br />

humor in what Condillac’s argument. But the statement is nevertheless thought provoking<br />

as it relates to Condillac.<br />

What is “superflous” and what is “necessary” and how much do they actually play into<br />

value. Moreover how much can subjectivity play a role in value at all? Condillac’s arguments<br />

are still alive today as some economists strive to prove that commodities are worth<br />

more to some than others. The next section talks about this relationship between consumers<br />

and producers. This argument also <strong>of</strong>fers interesting insights into marginal utility.


200 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Though Condillac <strong>of</strong>fers some interesting suggestions, it is important to be able to see all<br />

sides <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Hans: Where I expected a detailed explanation why the sentence quoted in the question is a tease, all I get is the<br />

malformed sentence: “This statement the humor in what Condillac’s argument.” Can you run that by me again?<br />

My own “Condillac for dummies” is in [2002fa:192].<br />

Next Message by Alex is [497].<br />

[478] JPeel: content A– form 95% The following remark “if both persons who exchange<br />

receive more in return for an equal amount, and part with less in return for an equal amount,<br />

then they both get the same,” pokes fun at Condillac because Condillac says that each person<br />

who is exchanging the commodity is giving less than what they receive. This can’t be true<br />

because both parties are receiving more than what they are giving so the outcome is equal<br />

because each person’s use-value is different but the exchange value is the same. For example,<br />

one person may exchange a hair straightener for a curling iron because they already have<br />

straight hair and will get no use from a straightener. On the other hand, the person receiving<br />

the hair straightener has curly hair and will benefit from this commodity. So their use-values<br />

are very different but the exchange value for the straightener versus the curling iron are the<br />

same.<br />

Message [478] referenced by [480]. Next Message by JPeel is [498].<br />

[480] Hans: Immanent Critique. Condillac says that everybody who is exchanging<br />

commodities is giving less than what they receive. JPeel [478] writes: this can’t be true<br />

because exchange-values are equal, the traders only gain regarding the use-values they have<br />

for the commodity (and then JPeel gives a good intuitive illustration <strong>of</strong> this).<br />

Condillac’s friend Le Trosne criticizes Condillac in a fundamentally different way than<br />

JPeel, namely, he makes a so-called immanent critique. JPeel says that theory A is wrong<br />

because it differs from theory B which is the right theory. This is not an immanent but<br />

an external critique. An immanent critique takes a careful look at theory A and draws out<br />

implications which show that A cannot be right.<br />

Le Trosne does not exactly come to the conclusion that Condillac’s theory cannot be<br />

right, but he shows that Condillac’s theory implies its own opposite. How so? Let’s do it in<br />

a dialogue.<br />

Condillac: Everybody who is exchanging commodities is giving less than what they receive.<br />

Le Trosne: I am with you. And assume the difference between what they give and what<br />

they receive is equal for everybody. Doesn’t that mean that everybody is getting the same in<br />

the exchange, namely, that equal difference?<br />

Marx calls this a “tease” or “poking fun” because he as a Hegelian is used to it that<br />

everything contains its opposite. Just as the same picture<br />

http://www.mcescher.com/Gallery/switz-bmp/LW306.jpg<br />

shows fish if you look at it one way, and flying birds if you look at it in a different way, so<br />

the exchange is one in which everybody gains if you look at it one way, and where everybody<br />

has an equal outcome if you look at it in a different way. This is nothing extraordinary, a<br />

trained Hegelian can do this trick with everything. But if Le Trosne tells his friend Condillac,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 201<br />

“your big controversial theory that everybody gets more in the exchange than they give up<br />

really means that everybody gets the same in the exchange,” this is like sticking a needle<br />

into a big baloon.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [482].<br />

Question 477 is 434 in 2005fa, 480 in 2008fa, 499 in 2009fa, and 576 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 477 What does Marx mean when he says “commodities are not paid for twice<br />

over, once on account <strong>of</strong> their use-value, and a second time on account <strong>of</strong> their value”?<br />

[479] Alcameron: When Marx says “commodities are not paid for twice over, once on<br />

account <strong>of</strong> their use-value, and a second time on account <strong>of</strong> their value..” he is referring to<br />

the fact that an exchange is an event in the string <strong>of</strong> production. It is only one event <strong>of</strong> many<br />

that must take place. First you can look at the inverse to see what Marx is saying and why<br />

it makes sense. When a consumer pays for a product, the majority <strong>of</strong> the time, in a perfect<br />

market, they will pay more than the actual cost to make that product, this is where pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

comes in for companies. The consumer is willing to pay more for that product than the cost<br />

<strong>of</strong> its materials because they may not possess the means to produce it, or the use-value for<br />

them is greater than or equal to the price they are paying. They walk away happy and have<br />

“paid” for the commodity. Now if we look at the transaction in reverse, the seller <strong>of</strong> the<br />

product has raw materials that they want to sell. They would much rather have the selling<br />

price <strong>of</strong> the product in cash than have the raw materials. The seller is willing to generally<br />

sell the item for any amount more than the cost <strong>of</strong> their materials, so in a sense they can<br />

“pay” for the production as well by turning their product into cash. If this were the case it<br />

would be an endless process <strong>of</strong> production and “paying” for items. Logic says though, like<br />

Marx stated, that the product is not paid for twice over. The transaction is an event in a series<br />

<strong>of</strong> many and only goes one direction, with one party “paying” for the commodity.<br />

Message [479] referenced by [482]. Next Message by Alcameron is [509].<br />

[482] Hans: Ooh you are so happy about this chair, can you pay me a little more?<br />

Alcameron [479] approaches this question from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> mainstream utility theory,<br />

not Marx’s labor theory <strong>of</strong> value. While in Marxist theory, the buyer <strong>of</strong> a commodity<br />

only pays for the value, not the use-value, in mainstream utility theory, he only pays for the<br />

use-value, not the value.<br />

In mainstream utility theory, a buyer pays $50 for a chair if he is happier with an extra<br />

chair than with an extra $50 in his pocket. The labor going into the chair does not enter the<br />

picture, the buyer probably does not even know it and it is never discussed in the transaction.<br />

This is clearly a payment for use-value, not for value.<br />

How does Marx come to the opposite conclusion that the $50 are paid for the value <strong>of</strong><br />

the chair and not for the use-value <strong>of</strong> owning the chair? Because he looks not only at the<br />

consumer making the transaction on the market, but also at the producers whose production<br />

decisions are guided by the market outcomes. If the producers see that chairs can be sold<br />

on the market at a better price per hour <strong>of</strong> labor input than say cabbage, then they will reallocate<br />

labor from the production <strong>of</strong> cabbage to the production <strong>of</strong> chairs. The increased<br />

supply will lower the price <strong>of</strong> chairs and raise the price <strong>of</strong> cabbage, say chairs are now $45<br />

a piece.


202 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Those who would have bought chairs at $50 a piece will be even happier to get them at<br />

$45 a piece, and some <strong>of</strong> those for whom $50 is too much money for a chair will happily<br />

buy chairs at $45. The lower the price, the more happiness there is all around. But the<br />

fact alone that at each price you are looking at a different population <strong>of</strong> happy chair buyers<br />

(and unhappy cabbage eaters), should tell you that prices are not driven by the happiness <strong>of</strong><br />

the consumers at all. After production has adjusted to market demand, the happiness <strong>of</strong> the<br />

consumers only determines the quantity <strong>of</strong> chairs produced. The long-run price <strong>of</strong> chairs is<br />

determined by labor input.<br />

Therefore, if a consumer were to say, as in [479], “I am willing to pay $50 for the chair<br />

although I know that the cost <strong>of</strong> this chair to the manufacturer is only $30, because I am<br />

happier with an extra chair than with the $50 in my pocket,” then Marx would give the<br />

following reply:<br />

Marx: I am glad this purchase makes you happy. This is as it should be, since the market<br />

has the social function to transfer the products to those consumers who need them. But don’t<br />

jump to the conclusion that the chair’s price is determined by your happiness. If the seller,<br />

who sees the smile on your face, is trying to get an extra $5 happiness premium out <strong>of</strong> you,<br />

you are perfectly justified to refuse to pay this extra amount. Your $50 did not pay for your<br />

happiness, but these $50 were the fair equivalent <strong>of</strong> the labor society had to put into this<br />

chair. You paid full value for the chair, you don’t owe anybody anything. What you do with<br />

the chair, and how happy you are with it, is entirely your private affair.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [495].<br />

[726] Paul: Marx means that when you pay for a commodity you are not paying for its<br />

use-value. The use-value <strong>of</strong> a commodity is completely dependent on the person buying<br />

it. If a certain commodity is especially useful for a given person he should not have to pay<br />

more than someone for which the commodity only provides moderate usefulness. When<br />

you are paying for a commodity you are paying for the labor that went into producing that<br />

commodity. If you were to pay more than the cost <strong>of</strong> the labor based on how much use the<br />

commodity is to you then you would indeed being paying twice over.<br />

Hans: The value <strong>of</strong> a commodity does not come from the cost <strong>of</strong> the labor but from the labor itself. The cost to the<br />

capitalist <strong>of</strong> the labor, i.e., the wage paid, is much lower than the value created by that labor.<br />

Next Message by Paul is [775].<br />

[734] Allen: Commodities are not paid twice over because they can be either purchased<br />

for their use-value or for their value. If they are purchased for their use-value the item will<br />

be used for what it was made for. Then the item could be sold for what it’s worth in order<br />

to purchase another commodity, for example a car. It is bought to be used to take you place<br />

to place then sold to purchase another (C-M-C). Commodities can also be bought for their<br />

value then sold at a higher price it was bought for to another person that wants to buy the<br />

commodity for its use-value.<br />

Hans: If you mean to say that the buyer sometimes pay for the use-value and sometimes for the value, Marx would<br />

disagree. In his paradigm, you always only pay for the value.<br />

Next Message by Allen is [783].<br />

[742] Brody: When Marx states that commodities are not paid for twice over he is referring<br />

to the fact that buyers do not pay for the use-value that they will derive from the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 203<br />

commodity. A buyer must only pay for the labor-value and therefore the value <strong>of</strong> a commodity.<br />

The use-value that the buyer gains can not be seen as added value or surplus value<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity; use-value is the buyer’s concern and is only realized after he/she has<br />

taken possession <strong>of</strong> the commodity.<br />

Next Message by Brody is [760].<br />

[757] Wasatch: As Hans explains in the handbook on page 357, the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value<br />

points out that the price <strong>of</strong> a commodity does not depend on its use-value but on its value.<br />

As I see it, the consumer looks at both the use-value and the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity, but<br />

the producer <strong>of</strong> the commodity is only concerned with the value (exchange value). Because<br />

the capitalist (producer) is only concerned with the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity any use-value is<br />

added on and experienced by the consumer. The producer could care less if you get more or<br />

less use-value out <strong>of</strong> the commodity and is not rewarded or in any way affected by it. So the<br />

consumer only pays once for the commodity because the consumer can’t pay for something<br />

that the producer is not selling (use-value).<br />

Hans: The producer is affected by it how much use-value the consumer gets from the commodity: this will determine<br />

the demand for the commodity. But Marx says in the long run, demand only determines the quantities<br />

produced, not the price.<br />

Next Message by Wasatch is [778].<br />

Question 498 is 311 in 1997ut, 321 in 1998WI, 322 in 1999SP, 377 in 2001fa, 425 in<br />

2003fa, 453 in 2005fa, 485 in 2007SP, 491 in 2007fa, 501 in 2008fa, and 524 in 2009fa:<br />

Question 498 One <strong>of</strong> the conditions under which the money owner can purchase laborpower<br />

in order to do M −C − M ′ is, according to Marx, that the labor-power must be sold<br />

by the worker him- or herself. Why this latter requirement?<br />

[493] Rey: graded A The Selling <strong>of</strong> Labor Power. When considering why it is necessary<br />

that labor power must be sold at the discretion <strong>of</strong> the laborer, we must first examine the<br />

unique ability labor has to create surplus value. In the process <strong>of</strong> M-C-M it is only in the<br />

consumption <strong>of</strong> a commodity, or C phase, that can bring additional value to the money<br />

commodity. Both flanks <strong>of</strong> the M-C-M equation are a mere conversion <strong>of</strong> form. Thus<br />

in order to create surplus value money must be converted to a commodity that has a usevalue<br />

that as Marx says, “possesses the peculiar property <strong>of</strong> being a source <strong>of</strong> value, whose<br />

actual consumptions is therefore itself an objectification <strong>of</strong> labor, hence a creation <strong>of</strong> value.”<br />

Marx goes on to identify this commodity as labor-power. By definition labor power is,<br />

“the aggregate <strong>of</strong> those mental and physical capabilities existing in the physical body, the<br />

living personality, <strong>of</strong> a human being, capabilities which he has sets in motion whenever<br />

he produces a use-value <strong>of</strong> any kind.” Put simply when one invest money in labor power,<br />

this labor power brings added value as it perpetuates production. Now in considering the<br />

original question, namely why is it necessary for labor power to be sold at the discretion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the laborer? The fundamental reason Marx gives is, “In and for itself, the exchange<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodities requires that there be no other relations <strong>of</strong> dependence than those resulting<br />

form its own nature.” A commodity doesn’t become a true commodity until it becomes “free”<br />

from all other dependency. Thus in order for labor to even be considered as a commodity,<br />

it must be free from all other ties. Essentially in order for a laborer to sell his labor as a<br />

commodity he must be independent and in full possession <strong>of</strong> himself, or else the laborer


204 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

would not have the natural right to sell his labor. Once the laborer establishes himself as<br />

independent and free to sell his labor, M-C-M can take place in its truest form, if not capital<br />

cannot as Hans states, “fully develop.”<br />

Message [493] referenced by [2008fa:761] and [2009fa:981]. Next Message by Rey is [500].<br />

Question 499 is 249 in 1997WI, 313 in 1997ut, 323 in 1999SP, 357 in 2000fa, 378 in<br />

2001fa, 411 in 2002fa, 427 in 2003fa, 477 in 2004fa, 454 in 2005fa, 486 in 2007SP, 492<br />

in 2007fa, 502 in 2008fa, 525 in 2009fa, 578 in 2011fa, and 604 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 499 Why are the conditions for terminating employment regulated by law instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> being left to the free market? Does this mean that the state protects the workers against<br />

the capitalists?<br />

[488] Kevin: graded A Selling yourself for money. The conditions for terminating employment<br />

are regulated by law because it would be possible in a completely free labor market<br />

for a human to sell all his labor-power indefinitely. This would lead to nothing more than<br />

total enslavement. At this point, the laborer himself would no longer be the owner <strong>of</strong> his<br />

own and only commodity (labor) but instead would be a commodity (a slave).<br />

In a market completely free <strong>of</strong> government intervention there would be no way to stop<br />

(without using alternative means) the trade <strong>of</strong> the human being. The indefinitely sold laborpower<br />

(the person or slave themselves) would then be able to be traded just as any other<br />

commodity. This, however, does not necessarily mean that the state protects the worker<br />

against the capitalist, it just means that it keeps the worker from being completely enslaved.<br />

According to Hans, “the capitalist state does not have the purpose to ‘protect the worker<br />

from exploitation’. . . the state is, rather, interested in a smooth functioning <strong>of</strong> exploitation.”<br />

[2002fa:209]<br />

Message [488] referenced by [489], [497], [499], [501], and [504]. Next Message by Kevin is [490].<br />

[489] Dentist: can you choose to be a slave? The discussions around this question always<br />

seem to revolve around the inevitable result <strong>of</strong> slavery, and as Kevin’s response [488] has<br />

taken us there, I will try to build upon it for a moment.<br />

Slavery relies upon a compulsory means for production, whereas capitalism relies on<br />

voluntary action. If then, slavery is all about compulsion, how and why would anyone<br />

WILLINGY become a slave, as is the case we are considering (according to the conditions<br />

laid out in 6.2)? This makes no sense, why would one willingly subject oneself to the<br />

demands <strong>of</strong> another? Especially when we are “rational”, and “behave in our best interests!”<br />

Deception, I wonder?<br />

All our lives we are told <strong>of</strong> the “American dream.” The dream whereby any person, from<br />

any status can have anything they desire so long as they work hard, and persevere; that<br />

through their best efforts they will possess their own surpluses <strong>of</strong> value. This ideological<br />

dream seems quite the convenient motivational tactic for an economic system whose very<br />

life-blood is surplus-value, does it not!?<br />

These are just a few thoughts I had in reading the previous discussions in relation to Kevin<br />

[488]’s introduction to our own. In answering the specific question posed I struggled a bit,<br />

but I have gathered this so far. Capital is our economic system; it is the means upon which


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 205<br />

we depend in order to derive our sustenance. The problem however is the clashing <strong>of</strong> its<br />

social foundation. Capital is forever locked in “a concealed civil war between the capitalist<br />

class and the working class,” to which there is no real solution other than destruction. Our<br />

government is acting as the arbitrator between both forces, and thus these laws are passed to<br />

protect each from the other. In this way it seems as if the government is trying to maintain<br />

some sort <strong>of</strong> artificial equilibrium.<br />

To borrow the later half <strong>of</strong> Hans’s quotation, “. . . the state is, rather, interested in a smooth<br />

functioning <strong>of</strong> exploitation.” [2002fa:209]<br />

Message [489] referenced by [490], [499], and [501]. Next Message by Dentist is [500].<br />

[490] Kevin: graded as part <strong>of</strong> [488] Would you know if you were a slave? I believe<br />

Dentist [489] brings forward a number <strong>of</strong> excellent points as well as creates new questions.<br />

He says, “how and why would anyone willingly become a slave?” I think he makes an<br />

excellent point that no one would willingly become a slave. We could say that no one really<br />

sells themselves as slaves, but haven’t we all sold ourselves and are slaves to the idea <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism?<br />

We all struggle and work relentlessly for a vision <strong>of</strong> riches and wealth. We slave away for<br />

a myth <strong>of</strong> greater opportunities that we cannot achieve. Not wanting to sound metaphorical,<br />

but haven’t we become slaves to the idea that through our work we can become the capitalist<br />

we work so hard to serve? Do we have a choice?<br />

Message [490] referenced by [501]. Next Message by Kevin is [500].<br />

[497] Alex: graded A Selling Yourself For Money. Kevin brings up some very interesting<br />

discussion points [488] which can bring a feeling <strong>of</strong> deflation to any student looking forward<br />

to a job after college. Hans always mentions that this class may be “more <strong>of</strong> a hindrance<br />

than a help to you (students) pr<strong>of</strong>essionally.” That being said it is comments like Kevin’s<br />

that make this class valuable. Hopefully when students do get into the real world they will<br />

understand the larger system that they belong to. A large corporation is not just a business<br />

but it demands more from its employees. You give up more than just your time for your job.<br />

The deeper tones illustrated by Kevin demand more time that even a full length semester<br />

class could give. The regulation <strong>of</strong> government and the role <strong>of</strong> government is the most<br />

important question a person can ask themselves politically. In fact this question really does<br />

define one’s political beliefs. I don’t believe there is one blanket answer, but there are many<br />

facets to each political position as it relates to government. As Kevin illustrates, our economy<br />

is not truly free market and I agree with him that the consequences <strong>of</strong> a true free market<br />

economy would be disastrous for the employee.<br />

So if it is a good thing that the government watch out for the worker, why is government<br />

intervention so feared? It is because <strong>of</strong> the capitalist, and their control on the government.<br />

Many times government will make movements to better the workplace or other environments,<br />

and lobbyists for the corporations will not allow it. If one chooses to politically to<br />

believe that strong government is good, then they must also understand that what we have<br />

is a government that chooses not to act. The government chooses not to act because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist, even if the resulting action may be in the general benefit <strong>of</strong> all.


206 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

So when one decides where they stand politically they must understand the true consequences<br />

<strong>of</strong> their decisions. It is not enough just to say you feel one way over another<br />

is correct, you must act to make a difference or you are as an ineffective government. It<br />

all comes back to that most basic question, “what is the most effective and proper role <strong>of</strong><br />

government, and how does that affect the worker.”<br />

Message [497] referenced by [501]. Next Message by Alex is [503].<br />

[499] Brandon: graded B+ Labor-Power=Commodity=Slave? I think not. Kevin says<br />

in [488] that it is necessary for government to regulate the terms and conditions by which<br />

an employee, worker, may be terminated by employer because, if left up to the free market,<br />

workers will be bought and sold as slaves. He states that when the worker sells his* labor (a<br />

commodity), he is selling himself to the employer. However, Marx states that the commodity<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor and the exchange that exists between the worker and the employer is a buyer/seller<br />

relationship. This relationship works as sort <strong>of</strong> a ‘buy on credit’ example, in which the<br />

worker sells his commodity, labor, to the capitalist without immediate payment. Payment<br />

is received under the terms <strong>of</strong> the mutual contract between the two parties; specifying time<br />

and production. Once the production is completed, creating a new commodity for sale by<br />

the capitalist, then payment is made to the worker.<br />

“In every country in which the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production reigns, it is<br />

the custom not to pay for labour-power before it has been exercised for<br />

the period fixed by the contract, as for example, the end <strong>of</strong> each week. In<br />

all cases, therefore, the use-value <strong>of</strong> the labour-power is advanced to the<br />

capitalist: the labourer allows the buyer to consume it before he receives<br />

payment <strong>of</strong> the price; he everywhere gives credit to the capitalist.” (Marx)<br />

Does this mean that the worker, given the mutual contract, is free from exploitation. By<br />

all means, no. Does this mean that the capitalist may never pay the worker for his labor and<br />

time spent on production? No. However, it does illustrate that the worker, who freely entered<br />

the contract, has the freedom to leave and seek another buyer for his labor. The condition<br />

could arise, in a crippled state, whereby capitalist would ‘agree’ to hire labor under similar<br />

contract terms and never pay the worker for his service and no other alternative condition<br />

is available for the worker. The role <strong>of</strong> government, in a society, is to protect the rights <strong>of</strong><br />

individuals from these exploitations <strong>of</strong> others. One cannot expect every person in a society<br />

to honestly and truthfully uphold their responsibilities that they have agreed to in a contract.<br />

The implementation <strong>of</strong> governmental laws that regulate these conditions <strong>of</strong> contract are<br />

necessary to protect both parties from breach. The case may also be, that a worker <strong>of</strong>fers<br />

to sell his labor but fails to perform his duties required under contract. Dentist touched on<br />

this in [489] by saying “Our government is acting as the arbitrator between both forces, and<br />

thus these laws are passed to protect each from the other. In this way it seems as if the<br />

government is trying to maintain some sort <strong>of</strong> artificial equilibrium.” I agree but more to the<br />

extent that government is acting as the legal enforcement that either party can appeal to in<br />

any case that they may feel breach has occured.<br />

At the end <strong>of</strong> 6, Marx states:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 207<br />

“This sphere that we are deserting, within whose boundaries the sale and<br />

purchase <strong>of</strong> labour-power goes on, is in fact a very Eden <strong>of</strong> the innate rights<br />

<strong>of</strong> man. There alone rule Freedom, Equality, Property and Bentham. Freedom,<br />

because both buyer and seller <strong>of</strong> a commodity, say <strong>of</strong> labour-power,<br />

are constrained only by their own free will. They contract as free agents,<br />

and the agreement they come to, is but the form in which they give legal expression<br />

to their common will. Equality, because each enters into relation<br />

with the other, as with a simple owner <strong>of</strong> commodities, and they exchange<br />

equivalent for equivalent. Property, because each disposes only <strong>of</strong> what is<br />

his own. And Bentham, because each looks only to himself.”<br />

I believe this is a powerful statement that shows that unless there exists some form <strong>of</strong><br />

legal enforcement <strong>of</strong> such contracts, the very basic rights <strong>of</strong> individuals will growingly be<br />

exploited by those above them. I do not believe that this slippery-slope condition would lead<br />

to a slavery-based society, because, in my opinion, the worker holds the labor-power and<br />

will refuse to ‘sell’ his commodity for zero beneficial gain.<br />

*I use the terms “he/his” to describe the general third person. I am not trying to be<br />

gender-specific, so try not to be <strong>of</strong>fended. :)<br />

Hans: Are you aware that Marx’s famous statement about freedom, equality, and Bentham is meant ironically?<br />

Marx says here that the market, which seems so equitable, mediates a very one-sided exploitative relationship.<br />

That’s why in the next paragraph only the capitalist smirks, while the worker timidly holds back, when the capitalist<br />

leads his new employee to his workplace.<br />

Message [499] referenced by [501]. Next Message by Brandon is [513].<br />

[501] Hans: Wage Labor and Slavery. The first answer, Kevin’s [488], is what I would<br />

consider “The Right Answer” to this question. But others disagree.<br />

Dentist [489] and Brandon [499] object that workers would never sell themselves voluntarily<br />

into slavery. Unfortunately, this is not just a hypothetical question but has some<br />

history behind it. Marx, in a footnote to 270:1/o, gives examples where wage laborers were<br />

so saddled with debt which they or their children have to pay <strong>of</strong>f by labor that they were<br />

practically slaves.<br />

Kevin [490], when faced with Dentist’s objection, therefore gave up too quickly on this<br />

point <strong>of</strong> actual slavery. But he gave an interesting reply, namely, that our belief in elusive<br />

rewards which the system is not designed to provide turns us into metaphorical slaves.<br />

This is a deep point, which no longer has to do with exploitation but with alienation—and<br />

unlike exploitation, alienation is not mitigated by a comfortable wage. Alex [497] adds his<br />

warning that a corporate job not only underpays but also requires from the employees the<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> enthusiasm for your own exploitation which Kevin equates with slavery.<br />

Brandon [499] takes issue with Kevin’s formulation that the laborer sells himself for<br />

money. Brandon stresses that it is an equal buyer-seller relationship, and that the state is<br />

necessary to protect both sides against breach <strong>of</strong> contract by the other side. A Marxist would<br />

answer Brandon that equal legal treatment <strong>of</strong> two contenders who have huge differences in<br />

power and resources is not even-handed but automatically favors the stronger party.<br />

Message [501] referenced by [504]. Next Message by Hans is [502].<br />

[504] Goethe: first hand experience. This is a response to [501]


208 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

I also agree to Kevin [488] in theory... (Disclaimer; I am not a law student or an expert,<br />

I am just sick and tired <strong>of</strong> being sick and tired!) Most jobs are protected by law, but not<br />

in <strong>Utah</strong>. We live in a right to work state i.e. we can be terminated for any reason and we<br />

can leave a job as such. I am reminded <strong>of</strong> a philosophy taught in another class at the U.<br />

“be slow to hire and quick to fire” the meaning <strong>of</strong> this was explained as: the best way to<br />

run an efficient business is to take time to investigate prospective employees, and once it is<br />

discovered that an employee is worthless, terminate them immediately!!!! This is where the<br />

contradiction <strong>of</strong> right to work comes into play. To be terminated an employer must have<br />

cause or face the possibility <strong>of</strong> paying unemployment. Employers will do a couple <strong>of</strong> things<br />

to accomplish this goal.... They will put you on a disciplinary action program, give a set<br />

<strong>of</strong> goals to reach, and make the goals unattainable. I have seen this before and experienced<br />

it first hand... (I refused to let this system take advantage <strong>of</strong> me )... employers hope and<br />

count on the fact that most people do not know their rights, and will eventually become fired<br />

without compensation <strong>of</strong> unemployment insurance. This is a true form <strong>of</strong> slavery... you<br />

work very hard to please Mr. Ass-Kiss manager only to find that in the end there was never<br />

any intention <strong>of</strong> redemption. Here are some definitions <strong>of</strong> slavery...<br />

Bondage: the state <strong>of</strong> being under the control <strong>of</strong> another person<br />

The practice <strong>of</strong> owning slaves<br />

Work done under harsh conditions for little or no pay<br />

Brandon has a very interesting view about buyer-seller relationship...A strongly agree<br />

with Hans... The state does not act in the interest <strong>of</strong> the workers and protect us from powergreedy<br />

managers; they are looking out for the state and no one else. It has been brought up<br />

time and time again “Capitalist owners use our labor for their pr<strong>of</strong>it.” There is no equality for<br />

workers unless you are working for yourself, and then we are still at the mercy <strong>of</strong> corporate<br />

powers exploiting our labor. An exception would be an enterprise that was pr<strong>of</strong>itable enough<br />

to supply the needs <strong>of</strong> a good, yet not extravagant lifestyle.<br />

On the outside it appears to many that the State is looking out for the worker, but the<br />

State gains more by looking out for the employer... Hans talks about a “comfortable wage”<br />

the character <strong>of</strong> money eliminates the possibility <strong>of</strong> ever achieving a comfortable wage... the<br />

more we get the more we want...<br />

Next Message by Goethe is [544].<br />

Question 506 is 281 in 1996sp, 328 in 1998WI, 419 in 2002fa, 435 in 2003fa, 485 in<br />

2004fa, 462 in 2005fa, 494 in 2007SP, 499 in 2007fa, 509 in 2008fa, 532 in 2009fa, 569<br />

in 2010fa, and 611 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 506 Which two sets <strong>of</strong> conditions must be satisfied for labor-power to be a commodity?<br />

[492] Srichardson: graded A Labor as a commodity. The first condition that must be in<br />

place to make labor-power a commodity is: the laborer must be able to sell his labor-power.<br />

He/she must be able to be the one who makes the decision to sell his labor. He must not be<br />

forced from an outside party, it has to be his own decision. The laborer must have the right


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 209<br />

to be free to enter a contract and leave a contract, the buyer <strong>of</strong> the labor must be legally equal<br />

to the seller <strong>of</strong> the labor and the labor must only be sold for a temporary amount <strong>of</strong> time.<br />

The second condition is that the laborer is limited in that he/she can not produce a final<br />

good that could be sold on the market. This is the reason that the laborer sells their labor;<br />

they are dependent on the person who has the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Message [492] referenced by [494] and [496]. Next Message by Srichardson is [507].<br />

[494] Papageorgio: satisfectellent. I was hoping to be the first to answer this question<br />

but I was beaten to it in post [492]. Srichardson is right when she says the first condition<br />

is that a laborer must be free to sell their labor power. The right to sell his/her labor power<br />

and enter and leave contracts without coercion is very key to this question. I feel it is also<br />

important to note the third party can not sell it for him/her. Srichardson pointed out the main<br />

arguments quite nicely, 1. laborer must be able to sell the laborer power by himself without<br />

third party, 2. Buyer and seller must be legally equally held, 3. The labor must only be sold<br />

for periods <strong>of</strong> time. It is important I think though to also note that they must bring the labor<br />

to the market for sale as well. It also is important to note as Hans posted in [2007fa:488]<br />

that a laborer must have a right to enter into a wage labor contract and that serfs, slaves, and<br />

children do not have this right.<br />

The second condition I think can be worded better than Srichardson puts it though, maybe<br />

as ‘the laborer must be separated and deprived <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production’. The laborer must<br />

not have the opportunity to sell his or her labor, so they must sell the their labor power to<br />

provide life for himself, to survive.<br />

Message [494] referenced by [496] and [729]. Next Message by Papageorgio is [531].<br />

[496] Hans: The Necessity to Use Strong Language. I have the impression Papageorgio<br />

[494] was scrambling to say something that goes beyond Srichardson’s [492], which is<br />

not easy because Srichardson gave an excellent summary <strong>of</strong> the argument. Papageorgio’s<br />

strongest point is what he said about the second condition: Srichardson should have used<br />

stronger language to express the outrage that the workers are deprived <strong>of</strong> control over the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production. The most important economic decision is the investment decision; it<br />

should not be made in private corporate boardrooms but by a democratic process. This is<br />

especially urgent nowadays when the corporations insist on continuing investments which<br />

cause global warming.<br />

On the News one <strong>of</strong>ten hears outrageous facts read in a bland voice, with an additional<br />

sentence at the end that the person or entity committing these outrages denies any wrongdoing.<br />

This is what journalists are taught to do in order to stay objective. But philosophers<br />

have argued that this is in fact not objective at all. Here is a passage from Roy Bhaskar’s<br />

Possibility <strong>of</strong> Naturalism. He is not the only one arguing this way, indeed the example about<br />

Nazi rule is attributed to Isaiah Berlin:<br />

Compare the following accounts <strong>of</strong> what happened in Germany under Nazi rule:<br />

alpha ‘the country was depopulated’;<br />

beta ‘millions <strong>of</strong> people died’;<br />

gamma ‘millions <strong>of</strong> people were killed’;


210 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

delta ‘millions <strong>of</strong> people were massacred’.<br />

All four statements are true. But delta is not only the most evaluative, it is also the best<br />

(that is, the most precise and accurate) description <strong>of</strong> what actually happened. And note<br />

that, in virtue <strong>of</strong> this, all but delta generate the wrong perlocutionary force. For to say <strong>of</strong><br />

someone that he died normally carries the presumption that he was not killed by human<br />

agency. And to say that millions were killed does not imply that their deaths were part <strong>of</strong> a<br />

single organized campaign <strong>of</strong> brutal killing, as those under Nazi rule were.<br />

So far the Bhaskar quote. Instead <strong>of</strong> saying that there is global warming, maybe one<br />

should say that life as we know it on the planet is being suffocated.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [501].<br />

[637] Jenn: graded A labor-power as a commodity. The first condition that must be<br />

satisfied is that the seller must be free to sell their labor-power as a commodity. It must be<br />

socially acceptable for a laborer to sell their labor-power as a period <strong>of</strong> time. Labor-power<br />

would not be a commodity in a slave-labor society, where the “worker” does not have a<br />

choice to sell their labor-power.<br />

The second condition is that the laborer must be forced to sell their labor-power to provide<br />

means <strong>of</strong> consistence for themselves. They must lack the means <strong>of</strong> production, rendering<br />

them unable to use their own labor-power, and therefore resorting to the sale <strong>of</strong> their laborpower.<br />

Next Message by Jenn is [638].<br />

[665] Papageorgio: Resubmission Conditional. The two sets <strong>of</strong> conditions that need to<br />

be satisfied for labor-power to be a commodity are<br />

1. The laborer must be free to sell their labor power. The labor-power needs to be<br />

independent in this regard. The ability to sell your own labor-power hour by hour contract<br />

by contract is necessary for labpor-power to be a commodity. Slavery obviously does not fit<br />

here as a third party cannot be involved. Children and slaves are left out <strong>of</strong> this not having<br />

the right to enter in the wage labor market for themselves.<br />

2. The laborer must be separated from and deprived <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production. The<br />

laborer does not have the means <strong>of</strong> production so they must sell their labor-power to someone<br />

else in order to produce something that can be sold on the market. My mind was blankin on<br />

this part during the test which is dissapointing as I answered this previously in the class. But<br />

the labor is dependent on someon else he must sell his labor-power and again this shows the<br />

necessity <strong>of</strong> this condition for labor-power to be a commodity. This is also a key point Marx<br />

felt should be fought against because capitalism robs us <strong>of</strong> a means <strong>of</strong> production and leaves<br />

us reliant, instead <strong>of</strong> everyone being given access to the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Next Message by Papageorgio is [775].<br />

[671] Scott: labor-power. Condition 1 – The possessor <strong>of</strong> the labor-value (the person<br />

that has the labor-power) has to be willing to sell it as a commodity. The possessor <strong>of</strong> laborpower<br />

can only sell his labor-power for a length <strong>of</strong> time, because if he was to sell in forever<br />

he would become a slave to the capitalist. The laborer also must have the right to enter a<br />

wage labor contract.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 211<br />

Condition 2 – Because the laborer can’t sell the commodities that he puts his labor into,<br />

he needs to be desperate to sell his labor-power.<br />

Next Message by Scott is [772].<br />

[729] Spawnblade: The two conditions that must be satisfied for labor-power to be a<br />

commodity are as follows:<br />

1) The laborer must input their labor freely and without forcible coercion. It must be<br />

voluntary otherwise it would be more akin to slavery.<br />

2) The laborer must not have access to the means <strong>of</strong> production. Or as Papageorgio [494]<br />

states, “the laborer must be separated and deprived <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production.”<br />

Hans: The laborer must also have the right to sell his labor-power.<br />

Next Message by Spawnblade is [776].<br />

[740] Dentist: The first condition that must be satisfied before labor-power can become a<br />

commodity is that workers must have freedom enough to sell their labor-power to the capitalist,<br />

and freedom enough to reclaim their labor-power from the capitalist. In this way, the<br />

less than optimal conditions <strong>of</strong> slavery are avoided, while still maintaining the institutional<br />

divisions.<br />

The second condition necessary in order to allow one’s labor-power to become a commodity<br />

is that a worker must not be able to produce a whole commodity by himself. Because<br />

if he could do this, what need would he have for the capitalist? He would have none, and<br />

therefore would bring his own commodities to the marketplace and sell them. Conversely,<br />

should the worker be incapable <strong>of</strong> producing his own commodities, he would have nothing<br />

to sell in the market, except for his labor-power. This is what would be brought to the<br />

marketplace and then purchased by the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Dentist is [741].<br />

Question 516 is 286 in 1996ut, 261 in 1997WI, and 495 in 2004fa:<br />

Question 516 What does Marx mean by: “Capital ushers in a new epoch in the process <strong>of</strong><br />

social production,” and how does capital do this?<br />

[498] JPeel: graded C Social production needing some ushering. When Marx says,<br />

“Capital ushers in a new epoch in the process <strong>of</strong> social production,” he is referring to the<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> exchange for labor. It is so high at this point that there is a complex socialization.<br />

The means <strong>of</strong> payment needs to reach a certain height and the capital will only arise when<br />

the owner <strong>of</strong> the means is controlling the labor. The level <strong>of</strong> production requires means<br />

<strong>of</strong> exchange as well. The system <strong>of</strong> means by which human labor and production <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

rises to various levels that the height <strong>of</strong> the process requires a method <strong>of</strong> measurement, or<br />

indicator, that shows a new period in which the cycles emerge. Capital is able to do this<br />

because it is the means <strong>of</strong> payment relative to the evaluation <strong>of</strong> the labor or the power to<br />

control labor in the open market. For example, if a owner <strong>of</strong> a door making company is in<br />

the open market and sells his doors for $54 a piece he is going to have to pay for all sorts <strong>of</strong><br />

labor costs. In order to make money he has to make sure that his labor costs do not exceed<br />

the cost <strong>of</strong> selling the door because he would then start to lose money. Marx is saying that in<br />

this cycle, the means <strong>of</strong> payment is tied to production and matches to the market at a certain<br />

level. He uses the word “subsistence” to describe this process.


212 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: You are not very clear, but you seem to say that the capitalist can only make pr<strong>of</strong>it if he squeezes extra effort<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the laborer. Small capitalists may be squeezed themselves, they are not much better <strong>of</strong>f than wage laborers,<br />

but in Marx’s theory big capital can just shovel it in because the laborers create far more value, between two to<br />

three times more value, than what they get in wages.<br />

Next Message by JPeel is [587].<br />

Term Paper 535 is 507 in 1997WI, 507 in 1997sp, 907 in 1997ut, 907 in 1998WI, 907 in<br />

1999SP, 907 in 2001fa, and 807 in 2005fa:<br />

Term Paper 535 Essay about Chapter Seven: Labor Process and Valorization Process<br />

[473] Chris, Jeremy, Srichardson, and Trailrunner: graded B+ Labor and the Valorization<br />

Process. Term Paper for Early Birds<br />

Chapter Seven: Labor and Valorization Process<br />

The Labor Process<br />

Labor is a process that takes place between man and nature. This can occur at the hands<br />

<strong>of</strong> a capitalist, or through the co-joining function <strong>of</strong> a communistic society. What begins in<br />

nature can eventually become a raw material once man has touched it. This raw material<br />

then becomes a product <strong>of</strong> labor. An example <strong>of</strong> this would be a tree that has been milled<br />

into useable lumber. The idea <strong>of</strong> the labor process begins when a capitalist desires a product,<br />

such as a fishing vessel. The capitalist hires a laborer who takes raw material from nature,<br />

such as a tree, and through the production process turns it into a vessel.<br />

Raw materials can take on multiple use values, but in order for this to happen, it requires<br />

the labor process. With the cutting down <strong>of</strong> a tree, the labor process begins. It is milled into<br />

lumber, compiled with nails, glue, wood, other materials and a laborer as inputs, and the use<br />

value is altered, turning these raw materials into a commodity, such as the vessel. However,<br />

this final commodity does not have use value for the laborer, but for the capitalist who has<br />

purchased these various inputs, has designed the vessel in his mind and has had this vessel<br />

produced for him.<br />

There are three simple elements <strong>of</strong> the labor process that Marx refers to in his book<br />

“Capital”. They are (1) purposeful activity, that is work itself, (2) the object on which that<br />

work is being performed, and (3) the instruments <strong>of</strong> that work. During the labor process, the<br />

laborer uses instruments, or tools, in the production <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Man is sometimes<br />

referred to as a “tool-making animal.” This is a specific characteristic <strong>of</strong> the human labor<br />

process making these instruments a part <strong>of</strong> the labor process. By using these tools, supplying<br />

the labor and building a product such as a fishing vessel, the labor process moves forward.<br />

In looking at the idea <strong>of</strong> “purposeful activity”, it is Marx’s belief that how people work<br />

largely defines them. It becomes important in an individual’s sense <strong>of</strong> self. In the case <strong>of</strong><br />

a capitalist hiring a laborer to work for him, the worker makes a trade. Instead <strong>of</strong> putting<br />

his/her labor into something that will give the laborer use value, the capitalist receives the<br />

benefit. Thus, the value <strong>of</strong> working one’s own land and growing enough to feed oneself,<br />

where the use value <strong>of</strong> the commodity is used by the laborer, the laborer sells their work to<br />

make a commodity for the capitalist. The use value is now lost to the laborer and belongs to<br />

the capitalist who has purchased the commodity <strong>of</strong> their labor.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 213<br />

By putting someone to work and having them mold materials into a vessel, the capitalist<br />

is consuming labor. Marx compares the purchase <strong>of</strong> labor to that <strong>of</strong> using any commodity<br />

that goes into the process <strong>of</strong> making a commodity. “Suppose that a capitalist pays for a<br />

day’s worth <strong>of</strong> labour-power; then the right to use that power for a day belongs to him, just<br />

as much as the right to use any other commodity, such as a horse he had hired for the day.”<br />

Labor itself can also be regarded as a consumption process. When an individual puts labor<br />

to use, they use and consume other commodities. While producing the fishing vessel, labor<br />

consumes the wood, nails, and glue during the production process. It also consumes the<br />

tools that are used in the production by wearing them down. The laborer takes products and<br />

consumes them in order to make another product.<br />

Upon completion <strong>of</strong> the labor process, the product becomes property <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. The<br />

capitalist now has an option <strong>of</strong> consuming/using the commodity for himself (i.e. fishing and<br />

selling the fish that are caught) or selling the vessel. The steps that make up the labor process<br />

can give a surplus value to the capitalist. Capitalists do not produce commodities with usevalues<br />

for their own sake. Rather, they are produced only due to the fact that they have an<br />

exchange-value. Valorization, labor process, and labor power are woven together insomuch<br />

that valorization does not appear to be able to exist independent <strong>of</strong> the labor process mingled<br />

with labor-power. Capitalists exploit this relationship in order to create surplus value. It can<br />

be noted that the capitalist gains control <strong>of</strong> the surplus value by having control <strong>of</strong> the labor<br />

process, the raw material and the tools. The labor process gives the control and the financial<br />

gains to the capitalist and therefore, no control goes to the laborer. The capitalist pays the<br />

laborer his use value for the labor to build the vessel and the use value alone. The exchange<br />

value that the capitalist will gain during the exchange process <strong>of</strong> the finished commodity<br />

remains solely with the capitalist. Therefore, the capitalist buys control <strong>of</strong> the labor and the<br />

individual now works for the capitalist and no longer works for them self.<br />

The Valorization Process<br />

The valorization process is one that explains sociological factors in the production <strong>of</strong><br />

value. Marx first explains the two objectives <strong>of</strong> a capitalist on page 293, “in the first place,<br />

he wants to produce a use-value which has exchange-value. . . and secondly he wants to<br />

produce a commodity greater in value than the sum <strong>of</strong> the values <strong>of</strong> the commodities used to<br />

produce it.” This quote is <strong>of</strong> utmost importance and provides the groundwork for the rest <strong>of</strong><br />

the valorization process. It must be understood that the capitalist wants a margin <strong>of</strong> process<br />

and feels entitled to this margin.<br />

Marx explains where the capitalist finds this margin throughout the valorization process.<br />

He presents an example <strong>of</strong> turning cotton into yarn and the different values associated with<br />

its creation. It is quite apparent that labor must be used to turn the cotton into yarn through<br />

the use <strong>of</strong> a spindle. Marx does point out that even though there are many ‘steps’ in the<br />

creation <strong>of</strong> yarn, they are all a part <strong>of</strong> “the same labour process” (Capital, 294).<br />

The conflict (and rise <strong>of</strong> capital) takes form once the yarn is produced. Once created, economic<br />

theory would suggest that it would be exchanged on the open market for an equivalent<br />

commodity comprised <strong>of</strong> similar exchange and labor values. However, the capitalist feels<br />

‘cheated’ that they did not receive something in addition during the exchange considering


214 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

they had provided the capital (spindle) in the first place. Marx notes the exchange on page<br />

301 where he explains how many shillings the worker gets paid and the total value in monetary<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> the cotton, labor, and yarn. Simplicity is the key to extracting a surplus value.<br />

The fact that half a day’s labor is necessary to keep a worker alive does not mean that he<br />

cannot work more than this. The capitalist takes advantage <strong>of</strong> this ambiguity. The capitalist<br />

pays the value <strong>of</strong> a day’s labor, and therefore has it for the day. However, let’s say sustenance<br />

for the laborer only costs a half-day’s labor. Here, the value <strong>of</strong> a day’s labor-power is<br />

half a day’s labor, and the capitalist can pay the worker at that value. The other half-day’s<br />

labor goes beyond the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power, and is therefore surplus-value. Now the value<br />

the work created is double what the capitalist paid for it. Marx says, “by incorporating living<br />

labour into their lifeless objectivity, the capitalist simultaneously transforms value into<br />

capital, value which can perform its own valorization process.”<br />

The capitalist paid full value for all <strong>of</strong> the commodities he used, and then he consumed<br />

their use-value. Because <strong>of</strong> the asymmetry between the use-value and exchange-value <strong>of</strong><br />

labor, however, this allows the capitalist to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it. The worker can spend 6 hours in a<br />

24-hour time span to create the yarn in order for the capitalist to break even. It is here where<br />

we see the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. The capitalist realizes that the worker can work up<br />

to 12 hours in that same 24-hour time span and create double the amount <strong>of</strong> yarn without<br />

the capitalist spending too much more on the worker and the facility. Marx writes that the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the yarn in this example turns out to be 30 shillings and the commodities amount<br />

to a total value <strong>of</strong> 27 shillings, leaving an excess <strong>of</strong> 3 shillings to the capitalist. Hence, “the<br />

trick has at last worked: money has been transformed into capital” (Capital, 301).<br />

Marx has also made it clear that “in the valorization process it does not in the least matter<br />

whether the labour appropriated by the capitalist is simple labour <strong>of</strong> average social quality,<br />

or more complex labour.” Due to value being determined by the labor used to produce a<br />

commodity, a more complex commodity being produced requires a more skilled laborer,<br />

which in turn requires a higher price paid for labor. The labor price is a cancelling factor<br />

to the added inherent value, so no surplus-value is created. Once again, the surplus value is<br />

determined by the labor-power exploited from the laborer.<br />

In retrospect, it first appears that the excess value does rightfully belong to the capitalist.<br />

It was this capitalist that provided the capital for the worker to begin with. The capitalist<br />

could have cut their risk <strong>of</strong> owning the capital and instead, purchased yarn on the open<br />

market without going through the whole labor and employment process. However this is<br />

the point where one <strong>of</strong> Marx’s most interesting and controversial quotes can be found. On<br />

page 298 he states, “the road to hell is paved with good intentions, and he might just as<br />

well have intended to make money without producing at all.” It is realized that the good<br />

intentions <strong>of</strong> the capitalist have turned bad all within a few pages <strong>of</strong> reading Capital. The<br />

capitalist has discovered something truly detrimental to society: labor can be exploited. The<br />

more the capitalist exploits the labor, the more pr<strong>of</strong>it the capitalist will receive. In addition,<br />

the capitalist owns the capital (machinery, i.e. spindles), which gives them extra leverage<br />

against the labor. To take it to the farthest extreme <strong>of</strong> the spectrum, the capitalist eventually<br />

‘owns’ the society in which everyone lives, through the process <strong>of</strong> labor exploitation.<br />

Hans: When you say in your first paragraph: “the idea <strong>of</strong> the labor process begins when a capitalist desires a<br />

product,” you give the capitalist too much credit. Labor processes happen in every society (not just capitalism or


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 215<br />

communism), people have been involved in labor processes long before the first capitalist was born. And at the<br />

beginning <strong>of</strong> the chapter, Marx discusses the labor process in general; only later will he discuss the specifics <strong>of</strong> the<br />

labor process in capitalism.<br />

In your second paragraph, don’t call the final product <strong>of</strong> the labor process a commodity. Not every labor process<br />

produces commodities, i.e., things for the market. And not every labor process results in a product that isn’t a usevalue<br />

for the producer. This is a specific, highly alienating condition <strong>of</strong> the labor process under capitalism, which<br />

you should not make an attribute <strong>of</strong> labor in general.<br />

Even if one only looks at capitalist production processes, you are saying some wrong things here. As Marx uses<br />

the word “use-value,” the product does not have use-value for the capitalist either. The capitalist benefits from the<br />

value and surplus-value in the product, not primarily the use-value. And it is a rarity that it is the capitalist who has<br />

designed the product.<br />

Later you say: “Valorization, labor process, and labor power are woven together insomuch that valorization does<br />

not appear to be able to exist independent <strong>of</strong> the labor process mingled with labor-power.” It is Marx’s objective in<br />

writing this chapter to disentangle these things, and to show exactly how the labor process leads to valorization <strong>of</strong><br />

the capital advanced. This is the wrong place to do handwaving.<br />

Later you become more specific about pr<strong>of</strong>its, but you come up with the wrong explanation. You explain<br />

capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its by the capitalist working the worker beyond the break-even point. You write: “The capitalist<br />

realizes that the worker can work up to 12 hours in that same 24-hour time span and create double the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

yarn without the capitalist spending too much more on the worker and the facility.” This is a tautological explanation<br />

<strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its. Since the break-even point is the point at which pr<strong>of</strong>its are zero, it is clear that pr<strong>of</strong>itable capitalists work<br />

beyond their break-even points, but this does not explain pr<strong>of</strong>its. Unfortunately, the core <strong>of</strong> Marx’s explanation <strong>of</strong><br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its is given in chapter Six, which was not yet assigned when you had to write the paper. In response to your<br />

presubmission I emailed you that you need to work through chapter Six. Apparently you still have some remaining<br />

misunderstandings regarding chapter Six.<br />

Message [473] referenced by [2009fa:729]. Next Message by Chris is [486], Next Message by Jeremy is [512],<br />

Next Message by Srichardson is [492], and Next Message by Trailrunner is [539].<br />

Question 542 is 452 in 2002fa, 468 in 2003fa, 519 in 2004fa, 493 in 2005fa, 535 in<br />

2007SP, 572 in 2009fa, 635 in 2010fa, 653 in 2011fa, 682 in 2012fa, and 653 in Answer:<br />

Question 542 Explain Marx’s sentence: “The working-day is determinable but in and for<br />

itself indeterminate.”<br />

[510] Alcameron: Who makes this schedule anyway? Marx states, “The working-day is<br />

determinable but in and for itself indeterminate.” The two statements seem to contradict each<br />

other by their completely opposite nature. Hans <strong>of</strong>fers up in his notes that the working day<br />

is determinable by outside forces, such as the law, in some instances. This is definitely true<br />

and visible in many markets, such as truck drivers, or air traffic controllers. Laws determine<br />

how long and how <strong>of</strong>ten their workdays are. I would add that in some situations the workday<br />

is determinable by taking into account specific capitalists, cultures, and physiological needs.<br />

A government <strong>of</strong>fice worker in Spain has certain conditions that would allow us to calculate<br />

their workday with some sort <strong>of</strong> accuracy. We know that government <strong>of</strong>fices operate during<br />

specific hours, we would take those bounds into account. It is an accepted and expected<br />

tradition for workers in Spain to have an early afternoon nap, all businesses close their doors<br />

and <strong>of</strong>fices close. That must be taken into account. We know that there is some necessary<br />

labor for each worker because <strong>of</strong> the costs associated with employing them. All <strong>of</strong> these<br />

factors, along with physiological needs <strong>of</strong> the workers can be factored together to determine<br />

what a workday might be for a government <strong>of</strong>fice worker in Spain. The working day in and<br />

for itself though is indeterminate, because we cant apply those same factors to other markets


216 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

to determine a workday. The minimum bounds <strong>of</strong> the workday is fuzzy at best, we know a<br />

value it can’t be less than, but we can’t determine its exact value. The maximum bound is<br />

difficult to set because cultural needs are always changing.<br />

Between specific labor laws and set factors we are sometimes able to determine the working<br />

day. The very nature <strong>of</strong> the workday though is indeterminate not only from market to<br />

market, but with time as well. What I want is to meet the person who determined the length<br />

<strong>of</strong> my workday!<br />

Hans: You are telling us how the bounds <strong>of</strong> the working-day are determined, but over this you forget to tell us the<br />

most important thing, namely, that the working-day itself, as long as it is between these bounds, is indeterminate.<br />

In other words, if the working class is strong enough, they can make it shorter without lowering the daily wage<br />

(i.e., by raising the hourly wage) without breaking any laws <strong>of</strong> economics or derailing the capitalist system. The<br />

capitalists may complain because they don’t like it when their pr<strong>of</strong>its fall, but they will still make pr<strong>of</strong>its and the<br />

system is not going to disintegrate if wages are higher and pr<strong>of</strong>its are lower. On the contrary, Marx shows in this<br />

chapter that the capitalists, if left to their own devices, are too greedy for their own good. They need the input from<br />

the working class for an efficient capitalist system.<br />

Next Message by Alcameron is [529].<br />

Question 543 is 536 in 2007SP and 574 in 2009fa:<br />

Question 543 Could one not say that the minimum bound for the surplus-labor is enough<br />

surplus-labor that the capitalists can survive?<br />

[506] PrivateProperty: Minimum Bound: Clear as Mud. No, that definition <strong>of</strong> a<br />

minimum bound is fundamentally flawed, because there is no such thing as a minimum<br />

value the capitalist can survive on. The capitalist has no concept <strong>of</strong> minimums, as he is<br />

concerned with maximizing value. Anything less than this would not be “surviving.”<br />

In addition, any minimum bound <strong>of</strong> the working day is not determinable. Sure, workers<br />

have to produce at least the amount that they are paid, but this is not a minimum bound,<br />

because workers always work longer than this. In reality, the ‘bound’ is variable and the<br />

result <strong>of</strong> a power struggle. I found it interesting when Hans noted in [2007SP:781] that<br />

“...the length <strong>of</strong> the working day must always be a point <strong>of</strong> contention.”<br />

Workers want a shorter working day. Employers, longer. Regardless <strong>of</strong> where it settles,<br />

the ‘ideal’ minimum bound (where there is no surplus labor) is not known, and workers are<br />

unable to intelligently negotiate. It is in the interest <strong>of</strong> the capitalist to keep workers in the<br />

dark as to what their actual value is; by doing so he denies workers quantifiable leverage. In<br />

this way the minimum bound <strong>of</strong> the working day is a social issue.<br />

Hans: You are misunderstanding how Marx uses the word “determine.” This word does not indicate how easy<br />

it is to find out about something, but “determinate” is the opposite <strong>of</strong> “accidental” (a better translation would be<br />

“contingent”). Something is determinate if causal forces are in place that drive towards a regular outcome, while a<br />

contingent outcome only depends on the situation.<br />

Message [506] referenced by [508]. Next Message by PrivateProperty is [555].<br />

[508] Hans: The dangerous illusion <strong>of</strong> idealist explanations. Workers always work<br />

longer hours than the number <strong>of</strong> hours that merely reproduces their wage. PrivateProperty<br />

[506] tries to explain this by the capitalists’ mindset or the workers’ lack <strong>of</strong> knowledge<br />

where exactly this minimum level is. In other words, he is trying to explain the things that<br />

are really happening by what people have in their brains. Marx would say this is the wrong


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 217<br />

methodology <strong>of</strong> “idealism.” Marx would say that people’s consciousness is determined by<br />

the structure <strong>of</strong> their society, rather than determining it.<br />

There is one simple economic reason which PrivateProperty should have mentioned here:<br />

if the workers work no more than the time that produces an equivalent <strong>of</strong> their wages, then<br />

the capitalists cannot make pr<strong>of</strong>its, and the capitalists will not employ the workers if there<br />

are no pr<strong>of</strong>its. This is not a matter <strong>of</strong> mindset but <strong>of</strong> the control over the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

What about a minimum level that is not zero pr<strong>of</strong>its but that allows the capitalists to<br />

survive, wouldn’t that satisfy the capitalists? The problem with this explanation is that capitalist<br />

production is not driven by the consumption needs <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. The structure <strong>of</strong><br />

our society requires pr<strong>of</strong>its and growth, and those capitalists who do not relentlessly maximize<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its will quickly be outcompeted or bought out. Again it is important to understand<br />

that this is not caused by the attitude <strong>of</strong> the capitalists, but it is a systemic necessity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

way production is organized in capitalism, which the capitalists then adopt as their own<br />

individual motivation. This in-built necessity to grow is one <strong>of</strong> the big obstacles to sustainable<br />

capitalism. Capitalists oppose sustainability not because they are suicidal but because<br />

sustainability is incompatible with the deep structure <strong>of</strong> capitalism. Sustainable capitalism,<br />

if we can pull it <strong>of</strong>f, will be quite a different animal than the capitalism which we all are<br />

familiar with.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [515].<br />

Exam Question 544 is 395 in 2000fa, 420 in 2001fa, 453 in 2002fa, 469 in 2003fa, 521<br />

in 2004fa, 495 in 2005fa, 537 in 2007SP, 536 in 2007fa, 575 in 2009fa, 658 in 2011fa,<br />

and 687 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam Question 544 How are the minimal and maximal bounds <strong>of</strong> the working-day determined?<br />

[505] PrivateProperty: How Much Wood Does a Woodchuck Chuck? A worker must<br />

work at least long enough to produce the value that he/she is being compensated. This could<br />

be anywhere from a few minutes to a few hours. However, this is a bare minimum, and the<br />

capitalist seeks to maximize the value he or she can extract from workers. As a result, the<br />

capitalist subjects his/her workers to a working day that generates substantial surplus value,<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten unbeknownst to them.<br />

The maximum bound <strong>of</strong> the working-day is physically constrained. Marx says that<br />

“Within the 24 hours <strong>of</strong> the natural day a man can expend only a definite quantity <strong>of</strong> his<br />

vital force.” A worker needs time to sleep, eat, attend to his hygiene, and travel to and from<br />

work. Otherwise he cannot perform his job effectively. Marx also argues that the worker<br />

needs time to satisfy ‘cultural’, social and intellectual needs. I think this is nice <strong>of</strong> Marx to<br />

assert this right, but in reality, employers do not <strong>of</strong>ten recognize this. From the view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist at least, these needs are not considered in the determination <strong>of</strong> a maximum bound<br />

for the work-day.<br />

I think Marx comes up with a fair definition for how long the work day should be. He<br />

says, in Hans’ words, that “The length <strong>of</strong> the work day must be such that it does not rob the


218 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

laborer <strong>of</strong> his health or shorten his life.” Would it be humane to work if it meant harming<br />

yourself? No, it wouldn’t. Do people work anyway? Yes, <strong>of</strong> course they do.<br />

In American corporate culture, work deteriorates our health. Work stresses us out, grays<br />

our hairs, and shortens our lives. A question I pose is, are we doing this to ourselves? Or are<br />

we being forced to? Who has the power to determine how long we must work?<br />

Hans: Apparently you were not aware that this is an exam question, therefore you did not try to give an answer<br />

which covers all relevant points as tersely as possible. You did cover all relevant points, but embedded in an essay<br />

<strong>of</strong> your own. If you were to answer this question in an exam, I would be looking for a “minimal answer” as in<br />

[2007SP:1001]. Some background info about this minimal answer is given in [2003fa:432], and I also recommend<br />

[2007fa:395] if you want to fully understand this question.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [506].<br />

[509] Alcameron: When does this workday end? The minimum and maximum bounds<br />

<strong>of</strong> a work day are elastic and in the case <strong>of</strong> the minimum quite fuzzy. To put a numerical<br />

value on the minimum length <strong>of</strong> a workday we must look through two scopes. There is an<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> necessary labor that a worker must perform in order to recuperate his own labor<br />

costs. This necessary labor could be looked at from the laborer’s standpoint as a minimum<br />

bound <strong>of</strong> his workday. This view is unsatisfactory for the capitalist however. He must never<br />

let the minimum length <strong>of</strong> his laborers work day be just their necessary labor, that would<br />

eliminate all surplus labor time which is vital to his efficiency. So from a capitalist’s view<br />

point the minimum is a fuzzy length <strong>of</strong> time that is greater than the necessary labor <strong>of</strong> each<br />

worker. This necessity <strong>of</strong> the minimum bound being greater than the necessary labor <strong>of</strong> each<br />

worker is not only vital to the capitalist, but to the worker as well. The security <strong>of</strong> his job<br />

rests in part on the amount <strong>of</strong> surplus labor is produced, thus benefiting both parties.<br />

The maximum bounds <strong>of</strong> a work day are determinable, but unique to various situations<br />

and elastic as well. The first factor is there are only 24 hrs in a day, so obviously the<br />

maximum bound must be less than that. One must also consider that each day there must be<br />

time allotted to clean and maintain oneself, eat, sleep, and perform necessary daily functions<br />

<strong>of</strong> survival. This time must be subtracted from the 24 hours available in one day. These<br />

factors are grouped under physiological necessities <strong>of</strong> humans. Even further beyond these<br />

physiological needs, one has cultural needs like personal time to spend with family, time<br />

to enjoy a hobby, or spend with friends. As you can imagine the amount <strong>of</strong> cultural needs<br />

differ greatly from market to market. An executive <strong>of</strong> an American company might deem it<br />

necessary to golf several times per week, this takes away further from the maximum bound<br />

<strong>of</strong> his workday. The laborer in Spain feels it an absolute necessity to take a “siesta” (nap)<br />

in the early afternoon. Culturally this is not only acceptable but expected and must be taken<br />

into account when looking at the maximum bound <strong>of</strong> a workday.<br />

So we have our determinable yet difficult to numerate workday. A minimum bound that<br />

is greater than the necessary labor <strong>of</strong> each worker, and a maximum bound that takes into<br />

account the physiological and cultural needs <strong>of</strong> humans. Within those bounds we find the<br />

differing length <strong>of</strong> workdays many <strong>of</strong> us subject ourselves to.<br />

Hans: Executive salaries are part <strong>of</strong> surplus-value. They take the form <strong>of</strong> a wage labor relation, but a Marxist<br />

would say the content is quite different. So forget the remark about golfing. Cars and color TVs are part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

workers’ habitual means <strong>of</strong> consumption and have an economic function as such, their cost determines the wages,<br />

but golfing does not determine pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Message [509] referenced by [515]. Next Message by Alcameron is [510].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 219<br />

[515] Hans: Necessary Labor Time Versus Break-Even Level <strong>of</strong> Output. In some<br />

answers from previous years, and in this Semester’s [509], Marx’s concept <strong>of</strong> necessary<br />

labor time is equated with the break-even level <strong>of</strong> output. I want to explain here, by an<br />

example, that they are two different things. I am pulling my numbers completely out <strong>of</strong> my<br />

head, I never ran a small business in my life, but I am trying to make them kind <strong>of</strong> realistic. If<br />

you have insights where this example is unrealistic and what more realistic numbers would<br />

be, please answer this, using question number 888.<br />

If Marx says that one hour <strong>of</strong> labor, which costs the capitalist say $20 in payroll costs,<br />

adds much more than $20 to the value <strong>of</strong> the output, then this is not something alien to many<br />

employees. Look for instance at the following example. The firm has ten employees, each<br />

<strong>of</strong> whom produces one widget per hour. These widgets sell for $45 each. They require<br />

only labor and machinery, to keep the calculations simple let us ignore any materials used.<br />

Perhaps it is an ISP and the widgets are web pages, or it is an automated print shop, but<br />

we ignore paper and ink, or a beauty shop. The capitalist’s fixed cost to run the business is<br />

$650 a day. This includes $300 depreciation <strong>of</strong> the machinery, $50 advertising, and $300<br />

rent, business taxes, interest, and franchise cost for the well-established Widget-in-a-box<br />

franchise. We are ignoring telephone and utilities and income taxes.<br />

Each employee gets $160 per day in wages, and the fixed cost per employee is $65. Then<br />

the break-even output is 5 widgets per employee, because 5 times $45 = $225, which pays<br />

for the employee’s wage plus the fixed cost. Let’s say the capitalist can usually sell 60<br />

widgets per day, i.e., 6 per employee. On some days more customers come to the counter,<br />

on others fewer, and the capitalist cannot lay anybody <strong>of</strong>f, because then he would have too<br />

long waiting times and would lose customers.<br />

An employee who confuses necessary labor with the break-even point might think the<br />

necessary labor is 5 hours, and the surplus-labor is up to 3 hours, according to how many<br />

customers show up, but on average it is 1 hour.<br />

Marx would say: The socially necessary labor-time is not 1 hour per widget but 1 1/2<br />

hours per widget, namely, 1 hour and 20 minutes direct labor and 10 minutes depreciation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the machinery. If the widgets contain 1 1/2 hours and sell for $45, this means that 1 hour<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor produces a value <strong>of</strong> $30, not $45 as it may seem to the worker.<br />

The direct labor includes the waiting time, because there is no way to produce widgets<br />

without this waiting time. Remember the socially necessary time is not the minimum time<br />

but the time that it normally takes. Since the average output <strong>of</strong> the machine is 60 widgets,<br />

the $300 daily depreciation <strong>of</strong> the machine is $5 per widget, or 10 minutes per widget.<br />

The worker’s labor produces therefore $30 per hour, but wage is $20, which means that<br />

necessary labor-time is 2/3 <strong>of</strong> eight hours, that is 5 hours 20 minutes. The surplus labor time<br />

is 2 hours 40 minutes, which is a value <strong>of</strong> $80 per day. Of this surplus-value, the capitalist<br />

gets $45 per day, <strong>of</strong> which he spends on advertising $5 per day, and other capitalists and<br />

the state get $35 per day. (Rent, franchise, interest, and taxes all come out <strong>of</strong> surplus-value).<br />

This is per employee, i.e., the capitalists takes home $400 per day, about 2 1/2 times as much<br />

as the employees (and he does not have to make widgets but can take long vacations).


220 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Message [515] referenced by [675], [2009fa:729], [2011fa:498], [2011fa:627], and [2012fa:922]. Next Message<br />

by Hans is [519].<br />

Term Paper 572 is 810 in 2002fa, 810 in 2003fa, 810 in 2004fa, 568 in 2007SP, 576 in<br />

2008fa, 604 in 2009fa, 667 in 2010fa, 687 in 2011fa, and 716 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 572 Children and the Struggle around the Working Day<br />

[500] Dentist, Kevin, Rampton, and Rey: graded A Capitalism and the affliction <strong>of</strong><br />

child labor. According to Marx, the exploitation <strong>of</strong> child labor stems from a capitalistic<br />

thirst to draw all possible surplus labor from the working day. As Marx states, “surplus<br />

labor is not new in capitalism, but capitalism does bring something new” (Hans’s annotation<br />

to 344:2/o). Traditionally, people had sought to extract surplus labor as a means to live a<br />

slightly more comfortable lifestyle. According to use-values, a laborer found great benefit<br />

in surplus labor, however, with the introduction <strong>of</strong> exchange-value and accumulation as<br />

the motivation for production overwork runs rampant. As capitalism sought to extract the<br />

maximum amount <strong>of</strong> surplus labor from each working day, it introduced long working hours<br />

and horrific conditions as a means to maximize surplus labor. This was exacerbated by the<br />

fact that parents were sending their children to the workplace in order to survive.<br />

Marx defines the normal working day to be “the length <strong>of</strong> time needed by the worker<br />

every day to produce an equivalent <strong>of</strong> his or her daily wage” (Hans annotation, 340:1).<br />

Capitalism forced the working day to become much longer than this. It required the creation<br />

<strong>of</strong> as much surplus-value as possible. This implied a continuous production process and a<br />

maximization <strong>of</strong> the length <strong>of</strong> the working day. The worker however had needs that had to<br />

be met in terms <strong>of</strong> physical replenishment as well as social, intellectual and other civilian<br />

requirements. As the working day continued to absorb more <strong>of</strong> the fixed natural day, the<br />

laborer was robbed <strong>of</strong> his opportunity to acquire these necessities. The effect was, as Marx<br />

says, a shortened life expectancy as a result <strong>of</strong> an extended production-time. Leading to a<br />

very short life expectancy was pulmonary illness and was <strong>of</strong>ten the direct result <strong>of</strong> some<br />

horrific working conditions.<br />

During this time, child labor was no exception to the rule. Child labor has traditionally<br />

been a means <strong>of</strong> low cost, expendable labor. Machines increased the amount and ease <strong>of</strong><br />

production. Labor became much easier which allowed children to do the same work many<br />

skilled laborers had done previously. Children were also allowed to work in horrific conditions.<br />

Those under 13 years old were allowed to work a 6 hour half day but in many cases<br />

this age was significantly lower with hours far surpassing 6. As a result <strong>of</strong> child labor, society<br />

was forced to pay a tremendous price. Referring to excessively poor conditions Rev.<br />

Montagu Valpy describes the price society pays as a “slow sacrifice <strong>of</strong> humanity.” (Capital,<br />

353-4) Marx said:<br />

“The manufacture <strong>of</strong> matches, on account <strong>of</strong> its unhealthiness and unpleasantness,<br />

has such a bad reputation that only the most miserable part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

working class, half-starved widows and so forth, deliver up their children<br />

to it, their ‘ragged, half-starved, untaught children’.” (Capital, 356)


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 221<br />

Some workers in this industry were as young as six. The working day extended from<br />

twelve to fifteen hours, including “night-labor, irregular meal-times and meals mostly taken<br />

in the workrooms themselves, pestilent with phosphorus” (Capital, 356). To support this,<br />

Marx related testimony upon testimony <strong>of</strong> the detrimental outcomes to these conditions.<br />

One testimony has reference to William Wood, a 9 year old that had been working for a<br />

year and a half. He started at age 7 and a half working the moulds, carrying ready molded<br />

articles across the factory to the drying room then back to the empty mould room. His work<br />

began at 6am and did not cease until 9pm. Fifteen hours a day, 6 days a week at 7.5 years<br />

old.<br />

In late 19th century England led to children were nothing more than “personified labortime”<br />

(Capital, 352). Another description <strong>of</strong> these circumstances was given by Mr. Broughton<br />

Charlton in Nottingham during an Assembly Meeting. He states:<br />

“Children <strong>of</strong> nine or ten years are dragged from their squalid beds at two,<br />

three, or four o’clock in the morning and compelled to work for a bare<br />

subsistence until ten, eleven, or twelve at night, their limbs wearing away,<br />

their frames dwindling, their faces whitening, and their humanity absolutely<br />

sinking into a stone-like torpor, utterly horrible to contemplate.” (Capital,<br />

353)<br />

Marx, however, was not the only author to note the changes regarding children during the<br />

rise <strong>of</strong> capitalism. In his book The making <strong>of</strong> the English working class, E. P. Thompson<br />

describes the change <strong>of</strong> the quality <strong>of</strong> life during this time and what effects it had on the average<br />

person. During Feudalism in England children were <strong>of</strong>ten at home with their mothers<br />

during the day. Fathers worked the land on which they lived to produce for their family and<br />

to pay their landlord. As times changes into a more capitalistic society even those children<br />

not working out <strong>of</strong> the house were required to perform labors previously performed by their<br />

mothers. Mothers could no longer complete these tasks though as their labor was employed<br />

to tasks outside the home. The child laborer then went from house servant to part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

labor force in England as families endeavored towards economic success. This success that<br />

they had hoped for though never came. This caused a disintegration <strong>of</strong> the family. Fathers<br />

literally had to hire out their children so that they could eat.<br />

In The making <strong>of</strong> the English Working Class, E.P. Thompson’s thoughts and statements<br />

support Marx’s. Thompson talks about the work <strong>of</strong> children in industrial industry and the<br />

difference it has from agricultural labor under the supervision <strong>of</strong> parents. The apologists for<br />

child labor are indeed correct that it was not associated only with industrialization. “The<br />

child was an intrinsic part <strong>of</strong> the agricultural and industrial economy before 1780, and remained<br />

so until rescued by the school” (Thompson, p 332). Climbing boys and ship’s boys<br />

were subjected to very bad conditions. But most child laborers before the industrial revolution<br />

worked at “home or within the family economy” (Thompson, p 332). Fetching and<br />

carrying by very small children or work alongside parents in cotton spinning were common.<br />

“So deeply-rooted was child labor in the textile industries that these were <strong>of</strong>ten held up to<br />

the envy <strong>of</strong> laborers in other occupations where children could not find employment and add<br />

to the family earnings” (Thompson, p 332).


222 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Thompson later talked about labor in the farming industry. “In agriculture, children–<strong>of</strong>ten<br />

ill-clothed–would work in all weathers in the fields or about the farm.” (Thompson, p 332).<br />

This was different from the factory; they would have had a routine <strong>of</strong> jobs and tasks that they<br />

had to perform. These tasks were not like the chores that are required <strong>of</strong> children today. They<br />

were required to perform tasks such as winding bobbins all day long in slave-like conditions.<br />

They went from being children and mere servants in homes to factory workers in a matter <strong>of</strong><br />

years.<br />

Additionally, capitalism did not see a child for what he was, a developing person that<br />

had specific social, physical and intellectual needs. Capitalism perceived a child merely as<br />

a worker, who was distinguishable by no more than the characteristic <strong>of</strong> “half-timer” versus<br />

that <strong>of</strong> “full-timer.” And from here we can continue into capital’s perception that a worker<br />

is “nothing more than personified labour-time” (Capital, 352-353). In this way, a child<br />

was barely distinguishable from an adult, and both were hardly discernable from the very<br />

machinery they operated. As Marx put it, “food is added to the worker as mere means <strong>of</strong><br />

production, as coal is supplied to the broiler, and grease and oil to the machinery” (Capital,<br />

376).<br />

The fact that adults were being overworked and how children were being exploited for<br />

cheap labor and long hours was not the biggest public outcry, but it was the adulteration <strong>of</strong><br />

bread. Both Marx and Thompson discussed why society did nothing about these despicable<br />

conditions. They suggested a myth <strong>of</strong> a time in early capitalism that kept the oppressed working<br />

towards a fictitious past, an illusional time in history that did not really exist. Thompson<br />

described this as the “golden age.” Stories passed down from generation to generation spoke<br />

<strong>of</strong> a time when all was well and everyone was happy. Marx discussed this myth in chapter 26<br />

<strong>of</strong> Capital. He explained that the working class struggle for gain because they were told the<br />

rich have wealth through diligence, intelligence, and frugality and the poor were destitute<br />

because <strong>of</strong> laziness. In actual capitalism, this was the exact reverse.<br />

Marx believed that Capitalism manipulated and forced parents to adopt and condone the<br />

idea <strong>of</strong> children in the workplace. Though working conditions were bad, families had no<br />

choice but to work for long hours and send their children to work as well. For little to no<br />

money children would work exhausting hours, 10-15 hours a day to stay alive and not go<br />

hungry. They worked only to eat and had been reduced from a life <strong>of</strong> being a child to a life<br />

<strong>of</strong> extreme poverty.<br />

Capitalism was blind to humanity, and did not naturally act in mankind’s best interest. It<br />

acted rather, in order to quench its own thirst for the living blood <strong>of</strong> labor. (Capital, 367)<br />

Marx called attention to the horrifying acts that were thrust upon children known as child<br />

labor in order to petition the very human nature that capital ignored. By petitioning for<br />

emotional response in this way, humanity could be more easily awakened to the exploitation<br />

on the human race.<br />

Message [500] referenced by [502], [2008fa:5], and [2008fa:19]. Next Message by Dentist is [704], Next Message<br />

by Kevin is [626], Next Message by Rampton is [662], and Next Message by Rey is [610].<br />

[502] Hans: The Horrors <strong>of</strong> Child Labor in Historical Perspective. Term paper [500]<br />

deepened my understanding why children were so blatantly abused and exploited during the<br />

Industrial revolution. I thank the authors for writing an excellent and very informative paper,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 223<br />

which brought in relevant texts not only from Marx but from others. The information about<br />

the tradition <strong>of</strong> child labor in agriculture, and about attitudes towards children in general,<br />

was especially helpful.<br />

There is one item where I have to wag my Marxist schoolmasterly finger at you. In the<br />

first paragraph, the authors write: “Traditionally, people had sought to extract surplus labor<br />

as a means to live a slightly more comfortable lifestyle.” This is a fever case <strong>of</strong> methodological<br />

individualism! The extraction <strong>of</strong> surplus labor is not the result <strong>of</strong> individual decisions<br />

but <strong>of</strong> class structures. Marx says that the earlier class structures were still suffused in a<br />

humanity which was lost in capitalism. The exploitation <strong>of</strong> the laborer was exploitation for<br />

use-value, and was therefore limited by the limited consumption desires <strong>of</strong> the ruling class.<br />

Those at the receiving end <strong>of</strong> this class structure tried to be as excessive as they could imagine,<br />

by eating vast amounts <strong>of</strong> food and then vomiting to that they could eat more, or taking<br />

baths in donkey’s milk. But only when the object <strong>of</strong> exploitation was no longer use-value<br />

but value did exploitation generally become limitless and proceeded to such a level where<br />

the workers were systematically worked to death or where small children were sacrificed.<br />

Such situations were the exception in the Middle Ages or Antiquity.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [508].<br />

Question 581 is 506 in 2002fa, 524 in 2003fa, 577 in 2004fa, 529 in 2005fa, 578 in<br />

2007SP, 573 in 2007fa, 585 in 2008fa, 614 in 2009fa, 677 in 2010fa, 697 in 2011fa, and<br />

726 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 581 According to Marx, the only way to increase pr<strong>of</strong>its is to shorten the portion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the day during which the workers produce an equivalent <strong>of</strong> their wage, and to extend<br />

that portion <strong>of</strong> the day when they create unreimbursed new value for the capitalist. Are the<br />

capitalists aware <strong>of</strong> it that all their cost cutting measures, if successful, go at the expense <strong>of</strong><br />

their workers?<br />

[517] Inter: Cost cutting measures. My initial response to this question was yes, capitalists<br />

know that all their cost cutting measures, if successful, go at the expense <strong>of</strong> their workers.<br />

However, upon further consideration, my initial response was wrong. I am sure capitalists<br />

are aware that some <strong>of</strong> their cost cutting measures are at the expense <strong>of</strong> their workers. At the<br />

same time, I also believe that capitalists are unaware that some <strong>of</strong> their cost cutting measures<br />

are at the expense <strong>of</strong> their workers. The best example <strong>of</strong> the latter comes from [2003fa:452]<br />

by Oak, who explains how capitalists do not follow Marx’s ideas <strong>of</strong> labor. My example for<br />

the former is as follows:<br />

I was previously employed in a production room operating a high-speed scanner. The<br />

original scanning corps consisted <strong>of</strong> three people, including myself. It was observed while<br />

one <strong>of</strong> my co-workers was on extended leave, that two workers could finish the day’s quota<br />

in 10 hours, rather than three workers finishing the day’s quota in 8 hours. As a result, my<br />

former company “let go” the co-worker on extended leave. In this way, they were forced to<br />

pay me and my co-worker for 10 hours (4 hours <strong>of</strong> total over-time, 2 per worker) but did<br />

not have to pay for a full worker’s 8 hours. My co-worker and I did not receive any addition<br />

increase in our normal hourly wage, even though our job duties increased. I believe that the


224 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

capitalists who owned my former company were very aware that this cost cutting measure<br />

was at the expense <strong>of</strong> me and my co-workers.<br />

Message [517] referenced by [2008fa:815] and [2008fa:1127]. Next Message by Inter is [643].<br />

Term Paper 591 is 834 in 2002fa, 586 in 2004fa, 539 in 2005fa, 592 in 2007SP, 583 in<br />

2007fa, 595 in 2008fa, and 624 in 2009fa:<br />

Term Paper 591 How do modern intellectual property rights fit together with Marx’s theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalism?<br />

[614] Bmellor, Clayon, CousinIt, Mick, and Nstew: Intellectual Property Rights as it<br />

relates to Marx’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Capitalism. The idea behind modern day intellectual property<br />

rights is to grant the creator exclusive rights to allow him or her to appropriate much<br />

<strong>of</strong> the creation’s social value. The ownership <strong>of</strong> ideas implies the right to exclude others.<br />

Intellectual property law tries to draw a line between incentives for innovation and dissemination.<br />

In this essay we will highlight some examples <strong>of</strong> intellectual property law as it relates<br />

to Marx theory <strong>of</strong> capitalism; specifically the free s<strong>of</strong>tware movement, pharmaceuticals, and<br />

music.<br />

If the invention or idea has no close substitutes, granting a patent creates monopoly power.<br />

(The economic definition <strong>of</strong> monopoly means in a broad sense a single seller can affect<br />

prices, vs. the narrow way as seen in a competitive market system.) Monopolists earn a<br />

greater rate <strong>of</strong> return than “ordinary” on an investment.<br />

There are social costs associated with monopolies, which is why there are laws that prevent<br />

the formation <strong>of</strong> certain types <strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong>ficially declared monopolies. If too little <strong>of</strong> a monopolized<br />

good is produced the price will be far too high. Typically when there is current<br />

patent in effect the patented good sells a low quantity at a higher price. Once the patent<br />

expires, the price falls and the quantity increases.<br />

We issue patents to reward creative individuals and impede dissemination. The truth<br />

about intellectual property rights is this; in recent history it has been scrutinized under the<br />

magnifying eye <strong>of</strong> economic analysis. However, the economic analysis is insufficient, even<br />

today. The typical process <strong>of</strong> economic analysis involves comparing “equilibria with fixed<br />

technology” (also known as static equilibrium analysis), where intellectual property rights<br />

require an analysis <strong>of</strong> innovation and changing technology. While we may not have economic<br />

tools sufficient to provide proper insight, in the meantime, the economic analysis<br />

must proceed with the tools at hand. Besides the trouble associated with the inadequate<br />

scientific tools, intellectual property law aligns poorly with economic efficiency because the<br />

legislatures respond to politically powerful special interest groups who care about their own<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its more than the nation’s wealth. The development <strong>of</strong> high technological industries<br />

challenges both economic theory and the law.<br />

There are individuals that work in creative fields that forfeit all their intellectual property<br />

rights, while they are employed at a certain firm. For example there are contracts that s<strong>of</strong>tware<br />

developers sign that gives the company they work for rights to all creative property the<br />

individual creates while they are employed at the firm. It doesn’t matter if you create this<br />

at home or if you create it a work, the ideas you come up with are not your own. Never


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 225<br />

mind the moral dilemma that this might pose, let’s look specifically at the economic inefficiency<br />

<strong>of</strong> this contractual clause. By taking ownership <strong>of</strong> a certain individual’s creativity<br />

you limit the incentives that this individual has to develop their ideas and that limitation on<br />

development passes on to the rest <strong>of</strong> society where we are slowed down in our development.<br />

This fits nicely with Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> capitalism. Marx expounded on the labor theory <strong>of</strong><br />

value to show that according to the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value capitalists exploit the workers by<br />

depriving them <strong>of</strong> value that workers themselves create. Marx believed that the pr<strong>of</strong>it that<br />

the capitalist derived came from the value <strong>of</strong> the labor the worker created minus the wage<br />

that the worker was paid, all <strong>of</strong> these pr<strong>of</strong>its the capitalist lays claim to solely because he is<br />

the owner <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production. From a Marxist perspective the means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

should be socially owned.<br />

Do you really slow progress by giving people ownership to their intellectually property?<br />

There is valid argument for both sides; people are rewarded handsomely for the development<br />

<strong>of</strong> an idea with no substitutes. But that begs the question is the benefit <strong>of</strong> the sole individual<br />

greater than the social benefit that their product could pass on to society? Would that individual<br />

even come up with the idea in the first place if they knew that the idea was going to<br />

become socialized property, and not a monetary reward?<br />

As mentioned above, a significant critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism is inherent in the free s<strong>of</strong>tware<br />

movement. People like Richard Stallman, among others, adhere to what is called the ‘Hacker<br />

Ethic.’ Hacker ethic is a set <strong>of</strong> moral imperatives that the free s<strong>of</strong>tware movement arises out<br />

<strong>of</strong>. In the beginning <strong>of</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> computer capabilities, the source code (the programming<br />

language that makes all s<strong>of</strong>tware functional and computers useful) was freely<br />

traded and exchanged amongst a dispersed group <strong>of</strong> computer programmers and programming<br />

hobbyists. Without this free exchange, what we are now able to do with computers<br />

would have been greatly inhibited and progress along these lines significantly and indefinitely<br />

delayed. The hacker ethic is delineated by Levy (1994) as follows:<br />

“Access to computers – and anything which might teach you something about the way the<br />

world works – should be unlimited and total. Always yield to the Hands-On Imperative!”<br />

(40). According to this principle, there are essential lessons to be learned from taking things<br />

apart and re-assembling them in more useful ways, according to the whims and purposes <strong>of</strong><br />

the user. This is necessary and essential for improvement upon pre-existing machinery and<br />

should not in any way be hindered or restricted.<br />

“All information should be free” (40-41). There should be a free exchange <strong>of</strong> ideas and<br />

information so that science and technology can be developed toward more useful and efficient<br />

ends in a process that optimizes and capitalizes upon the work and insights <strong>of</strong> others<br />

engaged in any scientific pursuit. For hackers, this is the basis <strong>of</strong> the scientific method that<br />

facilitates the growth <strong>of</strong> knowledge toward optimal results.<br />

“Mistrust Authority – Promote Decentralization” (41). Hackers believe that systems<br />

should be open to scrutiny and thus to modification by the user. Authoritarian central control<br />

and proprietary secrecy are shunned. Under this rubric all source code (the code underlying<br />

s<strong>of</strong>tware that makes it work) should be open and available for manipulation according to the<br />

demands and needs <strong>of</strong> the person using it.


226 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

“Hackers should be judged by their hacking, not bogus criteria such as degrees, age,<br />

race, or position” (43). This flies in the face <strong>of</strong> conventional merit systems. A hacker must<br />

prove him or herself (though most hackers are male) by re-writing or modifying the code<br />

<strong>of</strong> a system or creating new programs. The hacker meritocracy is more about ability and<br />

the reputation <strong>of</strong> ingenuity following a person because <strong>of</strong> the work done to improve the<br />

capabilities <strong>of</strong> the system.<br />

“You can create art and beauty on a computer” (43-44). This is an example <strong>of</strong> the aesthetic<br />

sensibilities <strong>of</strong> the hacker. Code is not just pragmatic and useful, but aesthetically pleasing<br />

and enlightening in the same way that other artworks are for other sub-culture interest groups<br />

as well as for the entire culture. Coding eloquence is as important as pragmatic results.<br />

Elegant solutions to difficult problems <strong>of</strong> computing are highly esteemed.<br />

“Computers can change your life for the better” (45-46). Computers can be put to uses<br />

that enhance our lives and make them better than they were before we could get the machines<br />

to do what we want them to do. This has far-reaching potential for the role <strong>of</strong> computer<br />

technology in culture and society. One need only look to the ways in which simple computers<br />

have been used in the medical field, in data storage and analysis, and in gaming, art, and<br />

music for examples <strong>of</strong> ways that computers have enhanced abilities and potential innovations<br />

in these fields.<br />

Taken together, the hacker ethic as stated by Levy and the free s<strong>of</strong>tware movement act<br />

as a critique <strong>of</strong> intellectual property rights. This is a critique that can be extended to a<br />

critique <strong>of</strong> private property. The parallels between this set <strong>of</strong> ethics and the movement it<br />

has fostered and the critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism that Marx <strong>of</strong>fers are apparent. The free s<strong>of</strong>tware<br />

movement critiques proprietary s<strong>of</strong>tware and intellectual property rights in much the same<br />

fashion, and with the same outcomes for the general humanity, that Marx’s critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

points to. They both critique the notion <strong>of</strong> ownership <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

the critique coming from the free s<strong>of</strong>tware movement shifting that critique to the domain <strong>of</strong><br />

‘intellectual property’ in a way that Marx could not have possibly foreseen. Both allude to<br />

a decentralization <strong>of</strong> the production process, social ownership <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

and the betterment <strong>of</strong> the human condition for everyone due the efficiency <strong>of</strong> free access to<br />

information and technology as the very means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

In Part 1 <strong>of</strong> Karl Marx, Allen Wood says, “Historical progress consists fundamentally<br />

in the growth <strong>of</strong> people’s abilities to shape and control the world around them. This is<br />

the most basic way in which they develop and express their human essence.” Marxian theory<br />

asserts the conflict between human nature and the capitalist mode <strong>of</strong> production, arguing that<br />

workers are alienated from their labor, thereby arresting the progress <strong>of</strong> society through the<br />

loss <strong>of</strong> control <strong>of</strong> their own existence. This theory has practical implications in the modern<br />

debate over pharmaceutical companies and intellectual property.<br />

In 1998, several pharmaceutical companies filed a lawsuit against the government <strong>of</strong><br />

South Africa for the production and disbursement <strong>of</strong> generic drugs. This movement was<br />

an effort to provide affordable treatment to the dying AIDS population. While the suit was<br />

eventually dropped for PR purposes, the ordeal raised some ethical questions regarding the<br />

abuse <strong>of</strong> intellectual property rights at the expense <strong>of</strong> an entire society. More specifically, it


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 227<br />

ignited the debate over the use <strong>of</strong> patents as a right or a privilege. Though Marxian theory<br />

is detached from a specific moral code, it is engrossed in the philosophical understanding<br />

<strong>of</strong> human nature, and human needs. South Africa is just one example <strong>of</strong> a fundamental<br />

breakdown in capitalist principles with regards to intellectual property rights.<br />

First, the obvious argument exists that these multi-national pharmaceutical corporations<br />

value pr<strong>of</strong>it more than not only the essential needs <strong>of</strong> humanity, but <strong>of</strong> human life itself.<br />

Second, a Marxian theory suggests that denying the public the rights to such ideas and<br />

formulations, as prohibiting life saving medical treatment to a needy population, stagnates<br />

societal progress. Governments grant temporary monopolies on the belief that higher priced<br />

commodities will help finance and commercialize new products. Pharmaceutical patents<br />

remain in effect for 20 years, under the supposition that each drug requires millions <strong>of</strong> dollars<br />

to fund research, development and clinical trials. However, pharmaceutical companies have<br />

little incentive to generate innovation where there is no market. While the South African<br />

population is in desperate need <strong>of</strong> these medications, it is not pr<strong>of</strong>itable for companies to<br />

produce drugs for diseases that primarily affect the poor. This grossly prevents progress.<br />

Third, Marxian analysis suggests that multi-national corporations not only prohibit progress,<br />

but perpetuate the degradation <strong>of</strong> the proletarian worker. For example, in South Africa, a<br />

substantial portion <strong>of</strong> its population is employed by the multi-national corporations that own<br />

and run the mining industry. The workers are paid so little that they are forced to live in<br />

the mining towns alone, separated from their wives and children. The isolation persuades<br />

these workers to seek solace in prostitutes, who are largely infected with the AIDS virus.<br />

On returning home, the men infect their wives, thus continuing the rapid spread <strong>of</strong> disease<br />

and the downward spiral <strong>of</strong> the community. The multi-national corporations’ effects on the<br />

proletariat have far reaching implications. It stunts societal progress by denying workers the<br />

means to provide for themselves and their families, and it furthers the Marxian philosophy<br />

on labor alienation. Marx articulates on the dehumanization <strong>of</strong> drudgery work in his Economic<br />

and Philosophical Manuscripts <strong>of</strong> 1844, in which he says in reference to the labor <strong>of</strong><br />

the worker,<br />

That it does not belong to his nature, that therefore he does not realize<br />

himself in his work, that he denies himself in it, that he does not feel at<br />

ease in it, but rather unhappy, that he does not develop any free physical or<br />

mental energy, but rather mortifies his flesh and ruins his spirit.<br />

South Africa is but one example in which the capitalist laws <strong>of</strong> intellectual property deny<br />

progress and perpetuate the class divide criticized by Marx. Pharmaceutical companies pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

billions <strong>of</strong> dollars on the production and the distribution <strong>of</strong> medication. While capitalist<br />

theory would suggest such pr<strong>of</strong>it furthers progress, there is sufficient evidence to conclude<br />

that this advancement is limited to expanding the wealth <strong>of</strong> a few, while exploiting and<br />

worsening the conditions <strong>of</strong> many.<br />

With the rapid increase <strong>of</strong> technology, new regulations have been created to help ensure<br />

that due credit is given to the producer <strong>of</strong> such technology. Whether or not these intellectual<br />

property rights are fair or not is a real issue. New technology, or intellectual products can<br />

also be described as labor done with the mind and creative genius. Although the product


228 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

is produced on tangible objects, (CD’s, s<strong>of</strong>tware, books) the value <strong>of</strong> these goods is intrinsic<br />

with the data contained therein. Although there are many products today that were<br />

not present during Marx’s era, there are also many today that did exist during the time <strong>of</strong><br />

Marx. Analyzing how Marx treated such issues in his day can help us understand how our<br />

contemporary issues can be seen.<br />

Two main things that existed during Marx’s day that are present today as well are literature,<br />

and Music. Literature covers a wide spectrum from poetry, fantasy and fiction, to<br />

History, non-fiction, and science. It can also be broken down into two categories, 1) that<br />

which is created purely by intellectual labor, 2) and that which is a mixture <strong>of</strong> both intellectual<br />

and physical labor. Music can be analyzed much easier, since it is an absolute product<br />

<strong>of</strong> the intellect, but it can also be organized in two distinct ways; 1) the product <strong>of</strong> music<br />

manuscript, 2) and the product <strong>of</strong> a performance <strong>of</strong> such a piece.<br />

Marx states that in a capitalist economy, the laborer does not receive the fair share <strong>of</strong> his<br />

labor, and that the capitalist receives pay for a part <strong>of</strong> the work done by the laborer. Marx<br />

goes on to say that the laborer should receive all the pay for all his labor. With regard to the<br />

intellectual products mentioned above, we can see how the different societies would regard<br />

such goods.<br />

Literature that is created mainly by intellect can most <strong>of</strong>ten be given the genre <strong>of</strong> fantasy<br />

and poetry. This is the sole creation <strong>of</strong> the author. In Marx’s view, the author should receive<br />

all <strong>of</strong> the revenues <strong>of</strong> his work minus the cost <strong>of</strong> the materials (such as paper and printing),<br />

and the labor involved in producing the book. In the capitalist society, the opposite is true as<br />

the author receives a low percentage <strong>of</strong> his work. While some revenue does go towards cost<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor in producing the physical good, the surplus <strong>of</strong> it goes to the publisher, who “made<br />

possible” the printing <strong>of</strong> the book. It should be noted however that the publisher would not<br />

have work to do without the labor <strong>of</strong> the author. This is not to say that the publisher should<br />

not receive any pay, for he surely does create a vehicle for the author and his work. He<br />

provides the opportunity for mass production <strong>of</strong> this good. The relationship between the<br />

author and the publisher should be symbiotic, and each should receive the due pay <strong>of</strong> their<br />

labor.<br />

Music is conceived in the mind <strong>of</strong> the composer and he then proceeds to transcribe these<br />

revelations to paper that can be understood by the majority. Like the author, the composer<br />

has a very similar relationship to the publisher <strong>of</strong> his music. The above analysis can be used<br />

here again both for the Marxian and Capitalist perspective. Perhaps an additional complication<br />

is that besides producing printed manuscripts, music can also be performed live for<br />

the people. Thus it can be said that a concert is also a product. Here though, there can be<br />

many laborers involved. In the case <strong>of</strong> a symphony, there are various instrumentalists; the<br />

violins, cellists, brass section, woodwinds, etc. They provide their labor not only during the<br />

performance, but also in practice sessions leading up to it. Along with the musicians and the<br />

composer, there also must be a concert hall which provides seating for those in attendance<br />

as well as an acoustic atmosphere. Here, all three groups live in a symbiotic relationship; the<br />

musicians can’t play without any compositions, a composer’s work cannot become known<br />

without performances, the performance requires a concert hall, and yet there would be no<br />

concert hall without musicians and music to play.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 229<br />

The equations involved in dividing up labor is something I dare not compute for its complications<br />

and my limitations. Different musicians learn the same music at different speeds.<br />

Although one musician might learn it quicker than another, and others spend more time on<br />

it, they deliver the same end product. Do we pay according to the labor input or according<br />

to the end product? The same can be said <strong>of</strong> composers’ work. Some pieces <strong>of</strong> music come<br />

instantly to the composer and are received well by the people, while others are a product <strong>of</strong><br />

many years, and yet when finally completed receive little recognition.<br />

However the revenue is divided, Marx is clear on his stand that each laborer should receive<br />

a fair share for their labor, whether it is manual or intellectual. If any person receives<br />

some <strong>of</strong> the revenue created by the labor <strong>of</strong> another, Marx would denounce it. If either party<br />

abuses its relationship with the other when distributing the revenue, it would fall under the<br />

umbrella <strong>of</strong> capitalism. If the author receives some <strong>of</strong> the revenue created by the physical<br />

labor <strong>of</strong> producing the book, this is unjust. Likewise, if the Producer <strong>of</strong> the physical good<br />

receives revenue for the work <strong>of</strong> the author, there is an imbalance that must be addressed.<br />

Modern day intellectual property rights grant the creator exclusive rights to allow him<br />

or her to appropriate much <strong>of</strong> the creation’s social value. Intellectual property law tries to<br />

draw a line between incentives for innovation and dissemination while some would argue<br />

that these laws give the inventor an unfair advantage that costs society. In this essay we<br />

highlighted some examples <strong>of</strong> intellectual property law as it relates to Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism; specifically the free s<strong>of</strong>tware movement, pharmaceuticals, and music. From<br />

these examples we encourage the reader to derive what they feel to be just.<br />

Next Message by Bmellor is [666], Next Message by Clayon is [753], Next Message by CousinIt is [686], Next<br />

Message by Mick is [728], and Next Message by Nstew is [624].<br />

Question 592 is 237 in 1996sp, 289 in 1997WI, 354 in 1997sp, 515 in 2002fa, 535 in<br />

2003fa, 588 in 2004fa, 541 in 2005fa, 584 in 2007fa, 596 in 2008fa, 625 in 2009fa, 688<br />

in 2010fa, 708 in 2011fa, and 737 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 592 Why can we gain a scientific understanding <strong>of</strong> “the sphere <strong>of</strong> competition”<br />

only after having grasped the inner nature <strong>of</strong> capital?<br />

[516] FiveFingers: The Complexity <strong>of</strong> Competition. It is easy to say that “one must<br />

learn to crawl before they can walk”, but saying that one must understand the inner nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital before one can understand “the sphere <strong>of</strong> competition” is MUCH more complex.<br />

Before one can get a grasp on “the sphere <strong>of</strong> competition”, they must understand everything<br />

that leads up to it. He must know how Marx defines a commodity, which then helps<br />

him understand how Marx derives the value <strong>of</strong> the commodity, and then how that value<br />

shapes the capitalist society.<br />

In [2007fa:409], Hans explains that the hidden relations <strong>of</strong> production are beyond the<br />

control <strong>of</strong> the individuals. At first glance <strong>of</strong> the market, one might assume that “the sphere<br />

<strong>of</strong> competition” is driven by the commodities being exchanged. Marx’s theory explains that<br />

the value behind the commodity is driven by the abstract labor put into the commodity and<br />

the resources that go into it.


230 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Although the “sphere <strong>of</strong> competition” is what we see tangibly, it is the backbone <strong>of</strong><br />

“value” that must really be understood.<br />

Hans: In [2007fa:399], Deborah said that the commodity is basic and competition is the big picture. My response<br />

[2007fa:409] disagreed with both halves <strong>of</strong> Deborah’s statement. No, the commodity itself is not basic, but the<br />

production <strong>of</strong> value is basic, and no, competition is not the big picture, but I compared the competitive agents with<br />

marionettes with the value relations in production pulling the strings. Your answer builds on [2007fa:409] but you<br />

didn’t fully understand what I wanted to say there (that is why I summarized it once more for you).<br />

Question 593 is 589 in 2004fa, 542 in 2005fa, 595 in 2007SP, and 585 in 2007fa:<br />

Question 593 Is it necessary or useful for the capitalists themselves, in order to be more<br />

successful in competition, to know about the inner laws <strong>of</strong> “capital in general”?<br />

[514] Jason: Good, Bad or Neither? After reading all the previous responses to this<br />

question I have to agree with what seems to be the general consensus. Knowing <strong>of</strong> the inner<br />

laws <strong>of</strong> “capital in general” would not be terribly useful and definitely not necessary in order<br />

to be more successful. Just by participating as a capitalist in the system you are obeying the<br />

laws. Being aware <strong>of</strong> the laws would not give you a competitive advantage, you would just<br />

have a better understanding <strong>of</strong> why you were doing what you were doing. Any competitive<br />

advantage capitalists do have are only temporary until the rest <strong>of</strong> the gang manages to catch<br />

up.<br />

That said, Hans stated in [2007fa:417] that by being aware <strong>of</strong> the inner laws would actually<br />

be detrimental to a capitalists strategy. He says that by being aware <strong>of</strong> the inner laws<br />

capitalists would see the exploitation <strong>of</strong> their laborers and be somehow disturbed by it. I<br />

disagree with this, if you look at early capitalism before most labor laws were established<br />

you’ll see that factory owners were incredibly cruel. They forced men, women, and children<br />

to work long hours in unsafe conditions. If a laborer was injured on the job they would most<br />

likely be fired and replaced with a healthy new employee. The top dogs in early capitalism<br />

were far worse than anything the inner laws imply. As I said earlier I agree that understanding<br />

the laws will not help capitalists be more successful, but I don’t think understanding will<br />

hurt them in any way.<br />

If a large group <strong>of</strong> laborers figured these laws out however, we’d have a another matter<br />

altogether...<br />

Hans: You are right about the cruelty <strong>of</strong> capitalism. Today it is readily apparent in third-world sweatshops, while<br />

the core countries <strong>of</strong> capitalism try to to project a more humane face to their own populations. The system outsources<br />

its cruelty not only through CIA renditions. And as long as the cruelty is elsewhere, people do not seem to<br />

get too upset about it.<br />

Next Message by Jason is [521].<br />

Exam Question 596 is 218 in 1995ut, 242 in 1996sp, 293 in 1997WI, 365 in 1998WI, 366<br />

in 1999SP, 453 in 2000fa, 479 in 2001fa, 518 in 2002fa, 538 in 2003fa, 592 in 2004fa,<br />

545 in 2005fa, 598 in 2007SP, 588 in 2007fa, 600 in 2008fa, 712 in 2011fa, and 741 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

Exam Question 596 What is extra surplus-value? How is it related to relative surplusvalue?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 231<br />

[582] Samantha: Extra? There could never be enough value. As Hans says in<br />

[2007SP:989], extra surplus value is the technical innovations which have not already been<br />

used in the market by capitalists which will allow the early adopter to fetch extra surplusvalue.<br />

Relative surplus is money made once other capitalists have incorporated the technical<br />

innovation, elimating a single capitalist’s extra surplus value. The innovation can be all sorts<br />

<strong>of</strong> things. Chris in [2007SP:989] mentions that it “could be new or more efficient methods<br />

<strong>of</strong> production which decrease production costs”. Once other capitalists incorporate the new<br />

methods they will create competition which will, as Chris mentions, “drive prices down, and<br />

can affect wages.”<br />

Message [582] referenced by [585]. Next Message by Samantha is [761].<br />

[585] Hans: Relative Surplus Value is a Central Concept in Marx’s Theory. Samantha<br />

[582] does not seem to know what relative surplus-value is. The entire chapter Twelve was<br />

devoted to this concept; please read up on it. My [2000fa:170] is an attempt to explain the<br />

terms extra and relative surplus-value well enough that this question here can be answered.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [586].<br />

Term Paper 609 is 515 in 1997WI, 515 in 1997sp, 915 in 1997ut, 915 in 1999SP, 815 in<br />

2002fa, 815 in 2004fa, 815 in 2005fa, 589 in 2007SP, 601 in 2007fa, 613 in 2008fa, 642<br />

in 2009fa, 705 in 2010fa, 725 in 2011fa, and 755 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 609 Essay about Chapter Fifteen: Machinery and Large-Scale Industry<br />

[603] Aaron, Brandon, Goethe, JPeel, Matt, PrivateProperty, and Rmuscolino: Section<br />

1<br />

The Development <strong>of</strong> Machinery<br />

Machines have driven our lives for centuries. Mankind has evolved from using a needle<br />

and thread to using sewing machines, from telegraphs to e-mail and cell phones. This<br />

continual push to better our lives and production may never stop. It has consumed the true<br />

purpose in which we live, and breathe. We are here to better our lives as individuals through<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production, as a true capitalist would say. It is the machine that gives us the<br />

power necessary to accomplish the individual desires that the capitalist is searching for.<br />

Hans: The capitalist is not somebody who tries to satisfy individual desires by machinery, but somebody who tries<br />

to turn money into more money.<br />

The industrial revolution all started with the idea that the faster and more one produces<br />

the cheaper the commodity that has been produced becomes, which is known as surplus<br />

value according to Marx. The machine’s primary purpose is not only to increase production,<br />

but also to decrease the labor time it takes to produce a commodity.<br />

The first inquiry <strong>of</strong> the machine starts us “in manufacture, the revolution in the mode<br />

<strong>of</strong> production begins with the labor-power...” according to Marx. He says it is “how the<br />

instrument <strong>of</strong> labour are converted from tools to machines” and their differences. If a tool<br />

is any object used in the hands <strong>of</strong> man in the production <strong>of</strong> labor then it is considered a<br />

tool not a machine. For example; a hammer, nail, level, lever, and wedge are all tools. A<br />

machine however uses not the laborer’s hand, but the forces <strong>of</strong> nature itself, such as: water,<br />

wind, earth and including animal. For example; creating power with the use <strong>of</strong> a windmill,<br />

watermill, or the use <strong>of</strong> steam as power are all considered to be a form <strong>of</strong> machines.


232 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Marx rejects the above definition <strong>of</strong> machinery.<br />

So what does a machine consist <strong>of</strong>? Well, according to Marx, in order to have a fully<br />

developed machine it must consist <strong>of</strong> the three different parts listed below:<br />

1) Motor mechanism: Is what puts everything in motion. It must be able to generate its<br />

own power without the help human hands.<br />

2) Transmitting mechanism: It regulates the motion <strong>of</strong> the working machine. It consists<br />

<strong>of</strong> all the gears, wheels, pullies, ropes, etc...<br />

3) Tool or Working machine: Is part <strong>of</strong> the machinery, in which the tools are able to<br />

function.<br />

With these three key parts a machine takes form, by using all the previous tools necessary<br />

to complete the formation <strong>of</strong> a commodity. Replacing the once before skilled laborers and<br />

their hands on tools. Their two hands are no longer fast enough nor strong enough to produce<br />

the ever growing quantities demanded by the capitalist. Hands on laborer are now obsolete,<br />

and is now either out <strong>of</strong> a job or an assistant to the machine itself. Making sure the machine<br />

was in prime moving condition at all times.<br />

Hans: Now this is a different definition <strong>of</strong> machinery than you just said: the human is replaced not as motive<br />

power, but as the one who is holding the tools in his hands.<br />

After deriving the “real definition” <strong>of</strong> machinery, Marx discusses the development <strong>of</strong> machinery:<br />

Soon the industrial revolution started and these machines become whole factories producing<br />

an entire product without the use <strong>of</strong> a single laborer’s hand. With this rapid production<br />

came the need <strong>of</strong> a better transportation system through vessels, railways and telegraphs.<br />

“Hence the co-operative character <strong>of</strong> the labour-process is, in the latter case, a technical<br />

necessity dictated by the instrument <strong>of</strong> labour itself.”<br />

Section 2<br />

The Value Transferred by Machinery to the Product<br />

Is there a capital cost to using the “physical forces” around us? Marx says no. It does not<br />

cost us to use water from a stream or wind from the air, as it does not cost us to find a piece<br />

<strong>of</strong> gold in a mine. However, in order to make use <strong>of</strong> these “physical forces” we must build<br />

a machine to capture and produce the power we seek. A water-wheel and a windmill are<br />

examples <strong>of</strong> machines used for this purpose, which is a costly process according to Marx.<br />

So in order to increase our production levels we must first take on the costly procedures <strong>of</strong><br />

building the machines necessary. Is the cost <strong>of</strong> producing a machine worth it? Marx says,<br />

“given the rate at which machinery transfers its value to the product, the amount <strong>of</strong> value so<br />

transferred depends on the total value <strong>of</strong> the machinery.” Whereas the less labor the machine<br />

contains the less value it transfers to the product. Also, the less efficient it is the less value<br />

it passes on the finished commodity according to Marx. So if a machine is not efficient<br />

and it costs as much labor to produce it as it has saved by using the machine, then Marx<br />

says “there is nothing but transposition <strong>of</strong> labour.” A machine is therefore measured by the<br />

“human labour-power” it replaces. There are a lot <strong>of</strong> factors involved when determining the<br />

value transferred from a machine to the product. The use <strong>of</strong> the machine in the first place<br />

is driven by capitalist himself. As he is the one who has caused the need for things not


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 233<br />

previously wanted. The faster and higher the quantity produced the greater the surplus value<br />

that he himself keeps.<br />

Hans: Marx says here something completely different about capitalism, namely, that capitalism prevents the introduction<br />

<strong>of</strong> much labor-saving machinery because it does not pay the labor its full value.<br />

Here and at the beginning <strong>of</strong> the section, where Marx said something critical <strong>of</strong> capitalism, you apparently<br />

filtered it out.<br />

Section 2 (by another member <strong>of</strong> the group)<br />

The Value Transferred by Machinery to the Product<br />

The influence on machinery in the hand <strong>of</strong> the capitalists has been overestimated. The<br />

tool is not exterminated by the machine. Machinery does not create a new value, rather<br />

creates its own to the product that it serves. It forms an element in the value <strong>of</strong> that specific<br />

product, and rather than the product getting cheaper, it’s made better in proportion to the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> the machine. The systems <strong>of</strong> machinery are incomparably loaded with value than<br />

the implements used in handicrafts and manufactures. But the production <strong>of</strong> machinery by<br />

machinery lessens its value relatively to its extension and efficacy. Not only is the framework<br />

<strong>of</strong> the machine consumed by its numerous operating implements, but the prime mover is<br />

consumed by the numerous operative machines. There is a major difference between the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> a machine, and the value that is transferred by that machine to its product. The<br />

longer the life <strong>of</strong> the machine in the labor process, the greater is that difference. The degree<br />

<strong>of</strong> machines’ productiveness does not depend on the difference between its own value and<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> the implement it replaces. The difference between the labor a machine costs,<br />

and the labor it saves, doesn’t depend on the value and the value <strong>of</strong> the product it replaces.<br />

As long as the labor spent on a machine and the portion <strong>of</strong> its value added to the product,<br />

remains smaller than the value added by the workman to the product with his tool, there is<br />

always a difference <strong>of</strong> labor saved in favor <strong>of</strong> the machine.<br />

Hans: Do you expect anyone to understand what you wrote here?<br />

Section 3<br />

THE PROXIMATE EFFECTS OF MACHINERY ON THE WORKMAN<br />

Marx splits this next section into three subsections, each <strong>of</strong> which serve to describe a<br />

particular way in which the worker is exploited by the use <strong>of</strong> machinery by the capitalist.<br />

In the first subsection, which is aptly titled “The Employment <strong>of</strong> Women and Children,”<br />

Marx describes how the entire family is utilized for its labor. As machinery “dispenses with<br />

muscular power,” it becomes a means to employ those with less physical strength, namely<br />

the women and children <strong>of</strong> the household. Where the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power was once based<br />

on the value <strong>of</strong> one worker (the head <strong>of</strong> household), it is now based on an entire family. Thus<br />

the capitalist gains the additional surplus value <strong>of</strong> the entire family’s labor.<br />

In England, under what was known as the Factory Acts, children under the age <strong>of</strong> 13 could<br />

only work a maximum <strong>of</strong> 6 hours. Factories, therefore had an incentive to hire children at<br />

least 13 years old, or at least children who could pass for that age. Interestingly, many<br />

underage children became “certified,” and, as a result, were subject to the same hours and<br />

standards as adults.


234 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

English parliament established a mandatory system <strong>of</strong> education for working children<br />

under the age <strong>of</strong> 14. This system, however, was poorly regulated and was only an auxiliary<br />

institution <strong>of</strong> the working child’s life. There was no system <strong>of</strong> accreditation and instructors<br />

were <strong>of</strong>ten poorly qualified, even illiterate in some cases.<br />

In the print works it was required that children attend school for a total <strong>of</strong> 30 days and 150<br />

hours every six months; these requirements were <strong>of</strong>ten exploited. For instance, a child <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

completed the 30 days and 150 hours in the first month or two, and returned to work for the<br />

remainder <strong>of</strong> the six month period. This process would simply be repeated next period; as<br />

a result, children were subject to extreme discontinuity in their already-lacking education.<br />

It also put children at a disadvantage in the workplace as they had to adjust back to factory<br />

work. ‘Education’ simply became a cost to firms.<br />

In the next subsection, Marx explains how machinery makes the working day longer.<br />

Machinery depreciates primarily through wear and tear, until it is useless. Machinery also<br />

depreciates in another way, which Marx calls “moral depreciation,” which is just the process<br />

<strong>of</strong> becoming obsolete as better and more efficient machinery enters the market. In order to<br />

combat this depreciation, it is in the capitalist’s interest to recover the value <strong>of</strong> the machinery<br />

by working it at an optimal rate in as short a time as possible. As the operation <strong>of</strong> machinery,<br />

as previously noted, needs human labor-power, long working hours for the machinery means<br />

long working hours for the worker.<br />

When machinery is first introduced in an industry, the “social value” <strong>of</strong> the product is<br />

higher than its individual value; as newer and better machinery enters the market, the gap<br />

between these two values tightens. During this transitional period, capitalist enjoys substantial<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its, and “capitalizes” on the situation by prolonging the working-day as much as<br />

possible.<br />

Section 4<br />

The Factory<br />

Marx begins this section by defining the factory. The factory is a place where multiple<br />

machines are brought together under a single system. In one sense, the factory is defined<br />

by the labor it contains, that is, the combined efforts <strong>of</strong> all the workers tending to their<br />

machines. In another sense, one which Marx prefers, the factory is an automaton, in which<br />

its component parts (both mechanical and human) are driven by a self-regulating moving<br />

force, which is capital. In this system, workers give up themselves to their machines, not<br />

just in terms <strong>of</strong> producing output, but in terms <strong>of</strong> their skills. The machine has usurped the<br />

workman’s tools and thus his skill in using it.<br />

Marx then proceeds by explaining the division <strong>of</strong> labor within the factory. The working<br />

group comprises a head workman, who is assisted by a group <strong>of</strong> attendants. Among these<br />

attendants is a group <strong>of</strong> “Feeders” which supplies the machines with their fuel. Lastly, is the<br />

technical class, the engineers and mechanics who maintain the equipment. This class has<br />

the fewest members, who are considered the superior workmen.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 235<br />

Marx likens the environment within the factory to the military, where there is a “barracks<br />

mentality,” dividing the operatives and supervisors into “privates” and “sergeants,” respectively.<br />

He makes an additional analogy to slavery, saying that “the slave-driver’s lash is taken<br />

by the overlooker’s book <strong>of</strong> penalties.” Fines and penalties to wages ensure that workers are<br />

kept in line. For the worker, the factory is a system <strong>of</strong> enslavement that deteriorates his<br />

health and subjugates him to his machinery and to his masters.<br />

Section 5<br />

THE STRIFE BETWEEN WORKER AND MACHINE<br />

There has always existed a contest between the capitalist and the wage-laborer since the<br />

emergence <strong>of</strong> capitalism. However, it wasn’t until the industrial revolution that the laborer<br />

found himself fighting a battle against labor itself. Machinery has the ability to perform the<br />

same tasks as human power with greater efficiency and productivity. The laborer, who is<br />

replaced by a device and whose trade has been sacrificed is left with no option but to revolt<br />

against machinery.<br />

The first instance <strong>of</strong> this that Marx cites is the development <strong>of</strong> the ribbon-loom; a weaving<br />

machine in which a single person could weave more cloth in a given time than many<br />

other workers. This resulted in massive revolts across Europe, forcing governments to take<br />

regulatory steps to protect workers.<br />

“It was prohibited in Cologne in 1676, at the same time that its introduction into England<br />

was causing disturbances among the workpeople. Also, by an imperial Edict <strong>of</strong> 19th Feb.,<br />

1685, its use was forbidden throughout all Germany. In Hamburg it was burnt in public by<br />

order <strong>of</strong> the Senate (Marx).”<br />

The ribbon-loom was only one <strong>of</strong> the hundreds <strong>of</strong> industrial inventions that shook the<br />

foundations <strong>of</strong> labor in nations across Europe and the United States. The worker no longer<br />

has the ability to ‘sell’ his labor to the capitalist, for he cannot compete with the value <strong>of</strong><br />

the labor created by machine-power. When a machine, which has more production power<br />

than many workers and only needs to be operated by a few inexperienced people, is entered<br />

into an industrial market the livelihood <strong>of</strong> laborers is ultimately destroyed. The capitalist<br />

views this as only a ‘temporary inconvenience’ for the worker, who will re-enter the labor<br />

market seeking other avenues <strong>of</strong> labor-based employment. However, with an every growing<br />

machinery-driven labor market, the laborer’s chances <strong>of</strong> employment rapidly diminish.<br />

Section 6<br />

THE THEORY OF COMPENSATION AS REGARDS THE WORKPEOPLE DISPLACED<br />

BY MACHINERY<br />

“Political economists insist that all machinery that displaces workmen, simultaneously<br />

and necessarily sets free an amount <strong>of</strong> capital adequate to employ the same identical workmen<br />

(Marx).” Suppose a capitalist employs 100 workers for production. The introduction <strong>of</strong><br />

a machine in his factory will reduce the need <strong>of</strong> human labor by 50%. This, in turn, saves<br />

the capitalist 50% on wages and the efficiency <strong>of</strong> the machine is able to generate more products<br />

for sale, thus his pr<strong>of</strong>its increase. As pr<strong>of</strong>its increase, he is able to upgrade machinery,<br />

resulting in less and less required human labor.


236 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Since the laborer is displaced, he is forced to re-enter the continuously growing labor market,<br />

in which the possibility <strong>of</strong> finding new work in the industry <strong>of</strong> his trade becomes more<br />

and more unlikely. During this time, the only industries available were found in mining for<br />

raw materials and the production <strong>of</strong> machinery itself. A great demand was also created for<br />

the development <strong>of</strong> nations’ infrastructures. The need for human labor to develop “canals,<br />

docks, tunnels, bridges, and so on...”, helped generate new forms <strong>of</strong> productions brought<br />

about by the advent <strong>of</strong> machinery. The amount <strong>of</strong> laborers employed is directly proportional<br />

to the demand for these new branches <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

However, Marx deduces that due to the exploitation <strong>of</strong> labor via machinery, there existed<br />

an unproductive employment <strong>of</strong> the working class.<br />

“If we deduct from this population all who are too old or too young for work, all unproductive<br />

women, young persons and children, the “ideological” classes, such as government<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficials, priests, lawyers, soldiers, etc.; further, all who have no occupation but to consume<br />

the labour <strong>of</strong> others in the form <strong>of</strong> rent, interest, etc.; and, lastly, paupers, vagabonds, and<br />

criminals, there remain in round numbers eight millions <strong>of</strong> the two sexes <strong>of</strong> every age, including<br />

in that number every capitalist who is in any way engaged in industry, commerce,<br />

or finance.”<br />

Section 7<br />

Repulsion and Attraction <strong>of</strong> Workers through the Development <strong>of</strong> Machine Production.<br />

Crisis in the Cotton Industry.<br />

The repulsion and attraction <strong>of</strong> workers by the factory system is a result <strong>of</strong> the continued<br />

process <strong>of</strong> expansion and development <strong>of</strong> machine production. This is due to the interruptions<br />

<strong>of</strong> technical progress, as workers are removed from one factory and absorbed by<br />

another. Marx begins this section with the concession <strong>of</strong> the “respectable representatives <strong>of</strong><br />

political economy” as to the harmful effect on the workers who must compete with machinery.<br />

Although they disapprove the “slavery <strong>of</strong> the factory worker” there is the belief that in<br />

the long run the number <strong>of</strong> workers will increase. The political economists look at this as<br />

positive for the workers, when in reality the increase in workers is relative to the decrease in<br />

demand for skill needed to produce goods with machinery. Marx has discussed this throughout<br />

the chapter, the point he is making here is the way factories can move workers from place<br />

to place. He further explains that as machines replace the skilled workers, many unskilled<br />

workers will come in to take their place. Marx is making an argument against Mill’s idea<br />

that increase <strong>of</strong> machines, will result in an increase in the work force make life better for<br />

all workers. What happens is that when factories expand and technologies upgrade, there<br />

is a lag in production, which is the time <strong>of</strong> expansion and upgrade. This is what will cause<br />

workers to move to another factory, and when the next factory expands workers will move<br />

again. Marx states on pg 582 and 583 “A necessary condition for the growth <strong>of</strong> the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> factory workers is thus a proportionally much more rapid growth in the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

capital invested in factories.” The apparent growth in workers is in reality the cheapening<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor; this is the only way to expand and grow and remain pr<strong>of</strong>itable. Marx continues<br />

the discussion with a look at the cotton famine <strong>of</strong> 1862; this gave manufactures the incentive<br />

to exploit the workers by introducing an inferior grade <strong>of</strong> cotton. The workers were


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 237<br />

used in the experimentation <strong>of</strong> new forms <strong>of</strong> cotton production; which put them at risk <strong>of</strong><br />

diseases and sickness. To the owners <strong>of</strong> production; workers were not seen as people but<br />

chattel. They were disposable and easily replaceable; the skills <strong>of</strong> the past were no longer<br />

a workers greatest asset. We like to think that working conditions have improved but these<br />

conditions exist today in countries all over the world. Modern owners <strong>of</strong> production use the<br />

same methods from the past to increase their pr<strong>of</strong>its. Their way is to keep moving from one<br />

country to another, and keep ahead <strong>of</strong> worker awareness, (this is the point that Marx was<br />

making) as the factories move workers will move to gain employment. The caveat to this<br />

is when factories move out there is a surplus <strong>of</strong> displaced workers. This was apparent in<br />

Tijuana after many factories relocated to Indochina in early 2000’s. There were hundreds <strong>of</strong><br />

thousands <strong>of</strong> displaced workers in less than acceptable living conditions, the majority being<br />

women. Marx mentions this as well, females were forced into prostitution.<br />

Section 9<br />

FACTORY ACTS. SANITARY AND EDUCATIONAL CLAUSES OF THE SAME.<br />

THEIR GENERAL EXTENSION IN ENGLAND<br />

Understanding little about machinery and the effects it has on the labor force, we will<br />

notice the advantages we consume and the lives we keep out <strong>of</strong> danger with a mere sense <strong>of</strong><br />

responsibility. This is where the Factory Acts comes into play. The Factory Act is, “a series<br />

<strong>of</strong> acts passed by the parliament <strong>of</strong> the United Kingdom to limit the hours worked by women<br />

and children in the textile industry, then later in all industries”. The success <strong>of</strong> this clause<br />

has proved the possibility <strong>of</strong> education and the knowledge obtained from the experience <strong>of</strong><br />

working in the factory. Thus, meaning that the factory children only did half the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

time in school as a full time student, they were still able to obtain just as much information<br />

because they were always working <strong>of</strong>f a fresh mind. This made it possible for the factory<br />

kids to not only have knowledge in the factory, but in the classroom as well.<br />

“This can be accounted for by the simple fact that, with only being at school for one half<br />

<strong>of</strong> the day, they are always fresh, and nearly always ready and willing to receive instruction.<br />

The system, on which they work, half manual labour, and half school, renders each<br />

employment a rest and a relief to the other; consequently, both are far more congenial to the<br />

child, than would be the case were he kept constantly at one. It is quite clear that a boy who<br />

has been at school all the morning, cannot (in hot weather particularly) cope with one who<br />

comes fresh and bright from his work.”(213). These events happened due to the extreme<br />

and unethical circumstances in the work place. The simple tradition <strong>of</strong> a hard day’s work<br />

has turned into working too much for too little. It is hard to grasp that concept because we<br />

should believe that having machinery would make tasks easier and shorten the work day, but<br />

in reality has prolonged the average work day due to the excessive amount <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

In the Modern Industry we have become dependent on machinery, and in some third<br />

worlds it has become a lifestyle. The tradition <strong>of</strong> working half and half has become more<br />

in the factories in the third world countries, and a lot less in the classroom. Due to the<br />

exploitation many <strong>of</strong> the children today cannot read or go about a normal day <strong>of</strong> a modern<br />

day scholar. Robert Owen describes this as, “the germ <strong>of</strong> education <strong>of</strong> the future”. Such<br />

acts can bring down a nation and result to a weaker economy. There becomes a competitive


238 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

relationship between the worker and the machine which leads to a dysfunctional working<br />

society.<br />

Section 10<br />

The use <strong>of</strong> machines on a large scale in the industry advancing age has produced work<br />

that was free from injurious labor, as Marx notes at the beginning <strong>of</strong> his explanation <strong>of</strong><br />

this phenomenon. As noted by factual data, the numbers <strong>of</strong> workers before and after the<br />

“machine age” and large-scale industry in agriculture remained largely unchanged. As Marx<br />

recognized in the 1860’s, the machines used to produce agriculture and cultivate a much<br />

larger area in terms <strong>of</strong> land, did not actually expel any agricultural laborers employed. The<br />

need for social transformation in the class system seemed to reach the same climax in the<br />

rural countryside as it did in the capitalistic and more developed townships.<br />

It is easy to see how the new technology <strong>of</strong> machinery transformed the way the laborers<br />

worked. We have seen this phenomenon in our lifetime as the technology <strong>of</strong> computers<br />

and computing technology has completely changed the way corporations work and communicate.<br />

With the advent <strong>of</strong> new technology, the laborer and capitalist are responsible for<br />

innovating new and more efficient ways <strong>of</strong> working.<br />

Marx delves into a philosophical discussion concerning the capitalist and the population<br />

and how that affects the natural man, the earth and environments, and the physical and<br />

mental life <strong>of</strong> a worker. Marx argues that as people gather in certain areas <strong>of</strong> geography, the<br />

“metabolic interaction” between man and earth is then interrupted. Marx says in essence that<br />

the soil <strong>of</strong> mother earth is prevented from returning to its origins and the eternal and natural<br />

condition <strong>of</strong> the earth is then interrupted. I am not sure I agree with what Marx is saying here.<br />

Just because a population begins to gather at a certain region, I don’t know if that begins to<br />

destroy the health <strong>of</strong> the urban worker, and the intellectual health <strong>of</strong> the rural worker. My<br />

contention is, that a worker who lives in the rural setting, with the benefits <strong>of</strong> machinery<br />

in mass producing agriculture, will be in a better mental state than the urban worker who is<br />

probably being exploited by the capitalist who might be enslaving and suppressing freedoms<br />

<strong>of</strong> the laborer. I do agree with a further point from Marx. He correctly points out that the<br />

larger scale <strong>of</strong> agricultural production, as in the case <strong>of</strong> the United States, the more rapid<br />

the process <strong>of</strong> ecological destruction. I don’t think there is any doubt in anyone’s mind <strong>of</strong><br />

this fact. It is only logical that the more land that is cultivated, the more destruction to the<br />

land. However, with this point in mind, I think Marx went too far in attempting to diagnose<br />

the physical and mental state <strong>of</strong> the worker in either the rural or urban environment. A final<br />

comment in agreement with Marx, is that the social process <strong>of</strong> production in simultaneously<br />

undermining the original source <strong>of</strong> all wealth- the soil and the worker. When considering<br />

the source <strong>of</strong> all wealth, I believe Marx has correctly categorized the source as the soil. The<br />

ironic thing in this understanding is that as the producer cultivates and destroys the land on a<br />

large scale with the machinery, he is only destroying the very thing that makes him wealthy.<br />

In conclusion, when considering the large scale industry and the complications that it can<br />

bring into an economy, it can be difficult to deny the ideas <strong>of</strong> Marx in terms <strong>of</strong> exploitation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the worker, slavery, the destruction <strong>of</strong> the natural resources that make a capitalist wealthy,<br />

and the affects <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the products. As value is determined and the trade-<strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> value


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 239<br />

<strong>of</strong> workers and machinery occurs, it seems that the biggest concern <strong>of</strong> Marx is the worker<br />

and what this transition means to him. Much <strong>of</strong> Marx’s commentary revolves around the<br />

work day, the value <strong>of</strong> the actual labor, and the overall deterioration <strong>of</strong> working conditions<br />

for the peasant laborer.<br />

Next Message by Aaron is [737], Next Message by Brandon is [696], Next Message by Goethe is [645], Next<br />

Message by JPeel is [713], Next Message by Matt is [635], Next Message by PrivateProperty is [611], and Next<br />

Message by Rmuscolino is [628].<br />

Term Paper 611 is 917 in 2000fa, 917 in 2001fa, 817 in 2002fa, 817 in 2004fa, 614 in<br />

2007SP, 603 in 2007fa, 644 in 2009fa, and 758 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 611 Essay about Chapter Seventeen: Changes in Wages and Surplus Value<br />

[639] Ande and Ken: For our term paper we have decided to focus on one specific part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the chapter. We feel as though we will be able to go into more depth on one part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

chapter rather than trying to write about the entire chapter as whole.<br />

Chapter 17: Changes <strong>of</strong> Magnitude in the Price <strong>of</strong> Labour-Power and in Surplus-Value<br />

I. The length <strong>of</strong> the working day and the intensity <strong>of</strong> labour constant; the productivity <strong>of</strong><br />

labour variable.<br />

The value <strong>of</strong> labour-power and the magnitude <strong>of</strong> surplus-value are determined by three<br />

laws. “Firstly, a working day <strong>of</strong> a given length always creates the same amount <strong>of</strong> value,<br />

no matter how the productivity <strong>of</strong> labour, and, with it, the mass <strong>of</strong> the product and the price<br />

<strong>of</strong> each single commodity produced may vary.” What this is saying is that depending on<br />

the production <strong>of</strong> the worker, inept or dexterous, will determine the amount <strong>of</strong> value the<br />

worker is worth. The worker will not have the same value, the productivity <strong>of</strong> labor and<br />

the quantity <strong>of</strong> the product being produced will vary. The productivity value can increase<br />

or decrease depending on the productivity <strong>of</strong> the worker during the work day. Technical<br />

innovations however can increase the efficiency, by allowing productivity <strong>of</strong> the worker to<br />

increase. These technical innovations can increase productivity, however if the worker is<br />

inept productivity will show minimal gains. The dexterous worker when given technical innovations<br />

will increase productivity, not only because <strong>of</strong> the workers work ethic but because<br />

<strong>of</strong> the innovations.<br />

Hans: When Marx discusses differences in “productivity” in this chapter he does not mean individual differences<br />

between inept or dexterous laborers, but he means differences in the technology <strong>of</strong> the labor process. He tacitly<br />

assumes that all workers are average workers, or that a sufficient number <strong>of</strong> workers work together so that their<br />

individual differences cancel out.<br />

“Secondly, the value <strong>of</strong> the labour-power and surplus-value vary in opposite directions.”<br />

This tells us that if the value <strong>of</strong> the labour-power increases the surplus-value must decrease<br />

therefore if the surplus-value increases you will see a decrease in the value <strong>of</strong> the labourpower.<br />

The total value <strong>of</strong> the working day can be expressed as a constant quantity. The<br />

constant quantity equals the surplus-value plus the value <strong>of</strong> the labour-power. For example,<br />

if you have two equal variables at your starting point “3 shillings value <strong>of</strong> labour-power, 3<br />

shillings surplus-value. Then the value <strong>of</strong> the labour-power cannot rise from three shillings<br />

to four, without the surplus-value falling from three shillings to two; and the surplus-value<br />

cannot rise from three shillings to four, without the value <strong>of</strong> the labour-power falling from


240 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

three shillings to two.” This example shows us how both the value <strong>of</strong> the labour-power and<br />

surplus-value are inversely related. It is not possible for the value <strong>of</strong> labour-power and the<br />

surplus-value to increase or decrease together. As you get more in depth you will find that<br />

as the productivity <strong>of</strong> labor increases, the surplus-value will increase because labor is being<br />

exploited. In turn you will see a decrease in the value <strong>of</strong> labour-power. Inversely, if a<br />

decrease in the productivity <strong>of</strong> labor occurs, the surplus-value will decrease, and the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> labour-power will increase.<br />

In his studies Marx found that the creator <strong>of</strong> this law, Ricardo overlooked an important<br />

aspect. “It is true that they increase or diminish by the same quantity. But their proportional<br />

increase or diminution depends on their original magnitude, before the change in the<br />

productivity <strong>of</strong> labour took place.” An easier interpretation <strong>of</strong> this could be understood by<br />

saying that the surplus-value and the value <strong>of</strong> labour-power inversely increase or decrease<br />

simultaneously; however the ratios <strong>of</strong> change differ. The ratios <strong>of</strong> change depend on the proportions<br />

in which productivity change. If the proportions <strong>of</strong> change are small the ratio will<br />

be very minimal, but if the proportions <strong>of</strong> change are large the ratio will be much greater.<br />

“Finally, increase or decrease in surplus-value is always the consequence, and never the<br />

cause, <strong>of</strong> the corresponding diminution or increase in the value <strong>of</strong> labor-power.” What is<br />

being said in this third law is that if a capitalist has the market power to increase margins <strong>of</strong><br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it, the pr<strong>of</strong>its will not be created in the circulation <strong>of</strong> the product, but in the production<br />

<strong>of</strong> the product being produced. If the length <strong>of</strong> the working day is set at a constant, then<br />

an increase in pr<strong>of</strong>its can only come from a decrease in the value <strong>of</strong> the labour-power, and<br />

inversely you will see an increase in productivity. As you read on you come to find out “a<br />

change in the magnitude <strong>of</strong> the surplus-value presupposes a movement in the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

labour-power, brought about by a change in the productivity <strong>of</strong> labour.” There is a minimum<br />

and maximum amount one worker or firm can earn. There are limitations in which the firm<br />

can cut labor power, and there is a maximum level that workers can continue to provide<br />

labor.<br />

In conclusion, the main problem with Ricardo’s three laws is he fails to acknowledge<br />

several factors; the length <strong>of</strong> the working day, the intensity <strong>of</strong> labour and keeping productivity<br />

constant. If one <strong>of</strong> these three factors changes, Ricardo’s law will no longer be validate<br />

according to Marx. By not acknowledging these factors, the laws can not be used unless all<br />

factors remain constant.<br />

Hans: The above paragraph is a little confused. The three laws you formulate hold if length and intensity are kept<br />

constant and productivity is the only factor that varies. In the other parts <strong>of</strong> the chapter Marx discusses the situation<br />

that productivity and intensity are constant and the length varies, or that productivity and length are constant and<br />

intensity varies. In these two situations, the above three laws no longer hold.<br />

As a group we decided to read chapter seventeen because <strong>of</strong> our interest in the price <strong>of</strong><br />

labour-power. Chapter seventeen was informative about the changes <strong>of</strong> magnitude in the<br />

price <strong>of</strong> labour-power and in surplus-value. Given the amount <strong>of</strong> information in chapter seventeen<br />

we decided as a group to focus on only one section <strong>of</strong> the chapter. We decided to<br />

go with the first section because it laid the foundation for the rest <strong>of</strong> the chapter to build on.<br />

Marx was able to explain how the labor force, the value <strong>of</strong> the labor-value, and surplus-value<br />

can all co exist in any market place. The chapter also was full <strong>of</strong> examples and different opinions<br />

Marx had about the theory’s Ricardo had come up with. This chapter is not something


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 241<br />

that you can read once and understand. As a group we feel that the explanations that were<br />

on the class web site helped us understand and get a better understanding <strong>of</strong> how the market<br />

place can function. The material in chapter seventeen was challenging but it gave the group<br />

a better understanding that helped tie all the loose ends together.<br />

Next Message by Ande is [746] and Next Message by Ken is [672].<br />

[703] Rey: graded B Adding one small insight. The term paper presented regarding the<br />

first portion <strong>of</strong> chapter seventeen was a good attempt to tackle a difficult subject. With that<br />

being said I think by adding a single sentence taken from the chapter sheds a great amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> light on what the group is trying to say.<br />

When discussing the topic at hand one must first understand as Marx says, “a working<br />

day <strong>of</strong> a given length always creates the same amount <strong>of</strong> value, no matter how the productivity<br />

<strong>of</strong> labour, and with it, the mass <strong>of</strong> the product and the price <strong>of</strong> each single commodity<br />

produced may vary.” Simply stated Marx is saying that the value <strong>of</strong> a designated working<br />

day stays constant despite the number <strong>of</strong> commodities produced and the price <strong>of</strong> those<br />

commodities. What varies is how the value <strong>of</strong> the working day is distributed among the<br />

commodities. If a productive worker is able to produce 6 <strong>of</strong> a certain commodity in a day<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> the working day will be distributed between each <strong>of</strong> the six commodities. If an<br />

inept worker is only able to produce 3 <strong>of</strong> that same commodity in one working day, there is<br />

still a working days worth <strong>of</strong> value in the commodities, but now it is distributed between the<br />

3 instead <strong>of</strong> the six. So we see that under no circumstance can a change take place in the<br />

magnitude <strong>of</strong> value in a working day. Further a working day is divided up into two portions.<br />

The value <strong>of</strong> labour-power and surplus-value. As is stated in the term paper the value <strong>of</strong><br />

labour-power and surplus-value move in opposite directions <strong>of</strong> one another. Understanding<br />

this sets the grounds to see how productivity labor becomes the major variable in determining<br />

the relationship between the value <strong>of</strong> labour-power and surplus-value. The capitalist<br />

whether consciously aware or not, realizes there is a set value that can be produced during a<br />

designated working day. If a capitalist is able to increase productivity-labor he gains more<br />

surplus-value, enabling him to take more value home with him. So naturally they seek to<br />

make full use <strong>of</strong> the working day by increasing productivity-labour.<br />

Hans: The point <strong>of</strong> the termpaper which you resonate with most is exactly the point where the authors made a<br />

mistake. Marx is not talking about individual differences between laborers, but about the development <strong>of</strong> more<br />

efficient machinery. The difference between effective workers and inept unproductive workers is great, and it can<br />

lead to frictions on the workplace, but it is not the source <strong>of</strong> the capitalist’s pr<strong>of</strong>its. The value created by labor<br />

would be greater than the wages even if all workers were identical twins and worked equally hard and efficiently.<br />

Next Message by Rey is [709].<br />

Question 613 is 77 in 1996ut, 83 in 1997WI, 363 in 1997sp, 361 in 1997ut, 525 in 2002fa,<br />

545 in 2003fa, 599 in 2004fa, 552 in 2005fa, 625 in 2007SP, 605 in 2007fa, 617 in<br />

2008fa, 648 in 2009fa, 711 in 2010fa, 730 in 2011fa, 760 in 2012fa, and 711 in Answer:<br />

Question 613 Your employer gives you your paycheck. How do you know your pay is based<br />

on your labor and not your labor-power (and why does it matter)?<br />

[520] Dyoung: What a Paycheck is? Marx says that even though the worker sells their<br />

labor-power when they accept a new job, the worker is actually being paid according to the<br />

labor he or she performs. So the worker then believes that the paycheck he is receiving


242 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

is paying him for his labor. [Annotations 422] “...One can say that labor is traded as a<br />

commodity which has a price.” The paycheck then becomes a representation <strong>of</strong> the worker’s<br />

labor, but it is really paying him or her for their labor-power. We have learned that if a<br />

paycheck were to pay you for your full value <strong>of</strong> labor, there would be no surplus value and<br />

capitalism would not be able to exist anymore.<br />

Labor-power is the source <strong>of</strong> surplus value for the capitalist. If the laborer realized this he<br />

or she was not being paid for the surplus value that he or she was creating for the capitalist,<br />

the worker would demand a higher wage for less hours <strong>of</strong> work. I think by receiving a<br />

paycheck the capitalist is trying to disguise the exploitation that is going on by paying the<br />

worker for his labor-power and not for the value <strong>of</strong> his labor that he is creating for the<br />

capitalist.<br />

Hans: The capitalists are not deliberately disguising something. They are following the laws <strong>of</strong> demand and supply<br />

for labor. The only thing that is wrong is that the price <strong>of</strong> labor does not converge towards the value created by labor,<br />

but towards the cost <strong>of</strong> living <strong>of</strong> the laborer. Despite the fact that the paycheck <strong>of</strong> an hourly worker shows the hours<br />

worked and pays accordingly, the commodity traded between capitalist and laborer is the laborer’s labor-power, his<br />

or her ability to work, and the value <strong>of</strong> this commodity is the laborer’s cost <strong>of</strong> living.<br />

Next Message by Dyoung is [684].<br />

[522] Ande: You know that your pay is based on your labor because as Marx says, your<br />

paycheck is based on a hourly wage or on your output. You are paid in labor and your<br />

employer pays you a “wage” for your labor work. We know that we are getting paid for our<br />

labor because labor-power is what is sold. The company that is selling a product is paying<br />

you for your labor and selling what you are making or producing for labor-power. You know<br />

this because <strong>of</strong> the analogy that Marx uses when he talks about being paid in labor, if you<br />

were paid for your labor-power you would be making a lot more money and the company<br />

that is paying you would not make as much money because if they are paying you in laborpower<br />

they could not sell their product <strong>of</strong> the cost <strong>of</strong> labor because labor is much cheeper<br />

than that <strong>of</strong> labor-power. This all matters because its all based <strong>of</strong>f your labor/wage vs your<br />

labor-power/price <strong>of</strong> whatever you are doing to make a wage. It matters at the employee’s<br />

level because their wage <strong>of</strong> labor in a sense can go up and down depending on what the<br />

company is able to sell the labor-power to the economy at a certain market price. Overall<br />

labor and labor-power are two totally different things that actually rely on one another to<br />

work and make the business cycle <strong>of</strong> getting paid for making a product and selling a product<br />

to the consumer.<br />

Hans: You are saying<br />

We know that we are getting paid for our labor because labor-power is what is sold.<br />

It is exactly Marx’s point that we don’t realize that we are selling our labor-power, i.e., our ability to work, rather<br />

than the work itself, because we are getting paid according to the work.<br />

In the rest <strong>of</strong> your submission the words “labor” and “labor-power” should be interchanged. You may be<br />

interested in [2007fa:435] about this.<br />

Message [522] referenced by [523]. Next Message by Ande is [639].<br />

[523] Srichardson: graded A Understanding your paycheck. The discussion on this<br />

question that is brought up in submission [522] is somewhat confusing to me and I am not<br />

sure if I am reading it incorrectly or if there is some incorrect statements in the submission.<br />

Ande says in [522] that “We know that we are getting paid for our labor because laborpower<br />

is what is sold.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 243<br />

I don’t believe that just because labor power is sold it makes it so that you receive your<br />

labor. I believe that it is important to point out here the surplus value between the two; labor<br />

and labor power and this is what goes into the pocket <strong>of</strong> the capitalist.<br />

Another point I thought was confusing was where Ande says<br />

“This all matters because it’s all based <strong>of</strong>f your labor/wage vs your labor-power/price <strong>of</strong><br />

whatever you are doing to make a wage. It matters at the employee’s level because their<br />

wage <strong>of</strong> labor in sense can go up and down depending on what the company is able to sell<br />

the labor-power to the economy at a certain market price.”<br />

I think that the point <strong>of</strong> this question was to make you see that these are not connected.<br />

It does not matter if the amount that the company sells your labor-power for, your paycheck<br />

remains the same.<br />

I believe this is very important because it shows that the way to make more money is not<br />

to work more hours. As Hans states in [2005fa:1263] “If the working class wants to improve<br />

their position they have to force the capitalists to spread the payment <strong>of</strong> their labor-power<br />

over fewer hours every day. They cannot do this individually, they have to organize into<br />

Unions, or take the political action to raise the minimum wage”.<br />

Next Message by Srichardson is [526].<br />

Question 618 is 604 in 2004fa, 557 in 2005fa, 630 in 2007SP, 610 in 2007fa, 717 in<br />

2010fa, 737 in 2011fa, and 767 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 618 Marx says that labor cannot have value because it is the source which gives<br />

everything its value. How can labor give something which it doesn’t have?<br />

[521] Jason: Physics <strong>of</strong> Labor. After picking this question I read all the previous responses<br />

and was quite overwhelmed by how many <strong>of</strong> them there were. I think the answer<br />

using the shadow quote has been beaten to death, but for all the people who didn’t read the<br />

old answers I’ll summarize it here, then try another approach.<br />

The quote is “Labor is the cause <strong>of</strong> value in commodities, but cannot in itself have value:<br />

as the sun is the cause <strong>of</strong> shadows but cannot in itself have a shadow.” Essentially labor is<br />

like the sun and the shadows are the commodity, but you cannot create shadows without an<br />

object <strong>of</strong> some kind blocking the sunlight. Using that idea, a commodity cannot be created<br />

by just labor, a means <strong>of</strong> production is required as well, then the commodity with its value<br />

is created.<br />

I however prefer to use the Engels quote which says, “As an activity creating value, [labor]<br />

can no more have any particular value than gravity can have any particular weight, heat any<br />

particular temperature, electricity any particular strength <strong>of</strong> current.”<br />

While similar to the shadow quote, it seems to deal with the situation in a more quantitative<br />

manner which I prefer. It wouldn’t make sense for labor to have a value, the measurement<br />

would have to be some kind <strong>of</strong> abstract concept. If you used time then certain<br />

commodities would surely be created faster than others which were worth more. However<br />

labor, just like the other three examples, can have a specific quantity associated with it when<br />

taken with an additional device. Gravity requires an object with mass before that object


244 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

can have a weight. Heat requires molecules with an average energy before they can have<br />

a temperature. And electricity requires some sort <strong>of</strong> closed circuit with resistance before<br />

there is a current through it. In this regard, labor requires a means <strong>of</strong> production before the<br />

commodity can be created and have value. Labor is just one part <strong>of</strong> the equation required to<br />

make value in the market.<br />

Next Message by Jason is [600].<br />

[525] Bennett: Labor Cannot Have Value. Labor cannot have value in itself for a few<br />

reasons. First labor can obviously produce a product <strong>of</strong> value but labor itself does not have<br />

value. Labor is needed to produce something but that is not all that is needed, materials<br />

to make the product are needed as well. For example, your toilet it broken and you pay a<br />

plumber to fix it. One would think that you are paying a plumber for his “living labor,” but<br />

you are in reality paying this individual for the final product, a working toilet. The price that<br />

the plumber charges you helps to cover his cost for the materials that he used to fix your<br />

toilet. These materials are the plumber’s means <strong>of</strong> production, but using these means <strong>of</strong><br />

production the value <strong>of</strong> the fixed toilet is relative to the plumber’s “congealed labor”, rather<br />

than the plumbers “living labor”. The working toilet is his product, which is for sale, not his<br />

labor. It’s just like when you buy anything else, say a pencil, you are buying the product not<br />

the labor that went into producing this item.<br />

Next Message by Bennett is [581].<br />

[622] Jason: When I did this question in class I couldn’t quite remember the entire Engels<br />

quote. Now that I can look it up, here it is in its entirety. “As an activity creating value,<br />

[labor] can no more have any particular value than gravity can have any particular weight,<br />

heat any particular temperature, electricity any particular strength <strong>of</strong> current.”<br />

In order for labor to create value, it needs a means <strong>of</strong> production (usually owned by the<br />

capitalist). The worker’s labor combined with the means <strong>of</strong> production creates a commodity<br />

that has value. What Engels is saying is that labor is just like gravity, heat, or electricity.<br />

All <strong>of</strong> them need a means before they can have a measured interaction. Gravity requires an<br />

object with mass before it can apply a force/weight to it. Heat must have molecules moving<br />

at an average speed before a specific temperature can be determined. And electricity has to<br />

be pushed over a closed circuit with some resistance before a current can be determined. All<br />

<strong>of</strong> these are just like labor; they do not have a specific quantity until an extraneous device is<br />

added.<br />

Next Message by Jason is [623].<br />

[690] CousinIt: graded A Labor and Value. Labor does not contain value in and <strong>of</strong> itself<br />

but rather it is through labor that value is produced and only in its interaction with the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production. Nature is free. Things found in nature are made useful (or made ‘valuable’)<br />

through human labor. Thus, such labor-transformed products have value only because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

socially necessary labor that is put into their production. Thus, labor produces value only in<br />

conjunction with the means <strong>of</strong> production (or, the materials <strong>of</strong> nature that are monopolized<br />

by the capitalist). Presumably, Marx says this in order to lay bare the fallacy perpetuated to<br />

the benefit <strong>of</strong> the owners <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production (i.e., the capitalist) that a value can be<br />

placed on labor itself. In capitalism as it exists, the fallacy that labor has a value is necessary<br />

so that the capitalist can purchase the labor-power <strong>of</strong> the worker under the guise that he is<br />

purchasing the value in discreet units <strong>of</strong> labor (as a commodity) in exchange for a wage. In


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 245<br />

other words, labor-power must be ‘commodified’ (‘made’ into a ‘commodity’ that can then<br />

be purchased or sold) before a price can be placed on it.<br />

What this amounts to is a ‘hand-is-quicker-than-the-eye’ illusion that makes it possible<br />

for the capitalist to purchase the value that labor produces without paying the full price to<br />

the worker that his labor has produced. In an interesting and sometimes confusing twist,<br />

the worker thinks he is selling his labor, or the value <strong>of</strong> his labor, when in actuality he is<br />

selling only his labor-power, not realizing that he is short-selling the value produced by his<br />

labor at the price at which the reproduction <strong>of</strong> his labor-power costs which is much less<br />

than the labor-produced value in the commodity he is producing. The worker does this only<br />

because he thinks that there is value in labor, a value which is a mere fiction. Labor has<br />

no value. Labor produces value. Labor-power costs less than the value produced by labor.<br />

Labor-power is what is really being sold at cost to the capitalist. The capitalist (who owns<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production) appropriates the value created by labor (minus the cost <strong>of</strong> laborpower)<br />

as pr<strong>of</strong>it (surplus-value). The laborer thinks his labor is being paid for without seeing<br />

that the value he produced is not and therefore does not recognize that he has been cheated.<br />

Next Message by CousinIt is [773].<br />

[708] Slash: Labor only one part <strong>of</strong> value. Every day when I go to work it seems as<br />

though I am paid for the labor I perform, because <strong>of</strong> this I have always thought that my pay<br />

was a surface value <strong>of</strong> my labor I perform. Marx would say: this could not be, because<br />

labor does not have value. This would mean the price <strong>of</strong> labor is the reproduction cost <strong>of</strong> my<br />

work, not the labor itself. Labor is only one <strong>of</strong> two parts necessary to make value. The other<br />

part would be means <strong>of</strong> production. The best example <strong>of</strong> the sun: The sun is only one part<br />

in the making <strong>of</strong> a shadow, the other being the object which blocks the sun’s light in term<br />

making the shadow, but the sun itself has no shadow and is only able to make a shadow in<br />

coordination with another object, i.e. (Means <strong>of</strong> production in the case <strong>of</strong> labor.)<br />

Next Message by Slash is [775].<br />

[709] Rey: graded A Labor cannot have value because it is, as the question states, the<br />

source <strong>of</strong> all value. Marx uses the example <strong>of</strong> a 12-hour working day to illustrate his point.<br />

He tells us that it would be an “absurd tautology” to determine the value <strong>of</strong> a “12 hour<br />

working day by the 12 working hours contained in a working day <strong>of</strong> 12 hours.” An analogy<br />

that has been commonly used to illustrate how labor is able to give something it doesn’t<br />

itself have, namely value, is the same way the sun has the ability to cast a shadow. There<br />

are no shadows within the sun itself, as it is the source <strong>of</strong> all light. But it still has the ability<br />

to create a shadow when it interacts with other objects. Likewise labor is the source <strong>of</strong> all<br />

value, but as such has no value itself. When it interacts with raw materials a synergistic<br />

process produces value in commodities. Evidence <strong>of</strong> the idea that labor itself contains no<br />

value is explained thoroughly by Hans, “If labor had value, i.e., if labor were something that<br />

could be exchanged on the market, then there would be no need to exchange other products<br />

since they all derive from labor.” Simply put it is the source’s interaction with something<br />

outside itself that enables it to produce something it does not possess itself.<br />

Next Message by Rey is [721].<br />

[763] Samantha: Shadows occur and value is bestowed. Labor would not be able to<br />

give value if it had it, because then value would just be a component <strong>of</strong> labor. As Chris<br />

in [2007SP:1116] stated “The Sun cannot have a shadow, yet it is the cause for everything


246 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

else to have a shadow.” Labor is the beginning <strong>of</strong> the entire process <strong>of</strong> producing, it gives<br />

any material value by changing it, whether it is taking it out <strong>of</strong> the ground, refining it, or<br />

working with it, just like the sun gives a shadow by merely shining. Value is determined<br />

by the amount <strong>of</strong> labor-power to produce any good in the market, at every stage in that<br />

production process. The reason that prices are so low is because consumers don’t have the<br />

same understanding <strong>of</strong> value, instead believing the value to either be the use-value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

exchange rate.<br />

Next Message by Samantha is [778].<br />

Question 619 is 490 in 2001fa, 529 in 2002fa, 550 in 2003fa, 606 in 2004fa, 558 in<br />

2005fa, 611 in 2007fa, 622 in 2008fa, and 766 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 619 Why is it an absurd tautology to say that the value <strong>of</strong> a 12-hour working day<br />

is determined by the 12 working hours contained in it?<br />

[518] Sparky: the total <strong>of</strong> 12 hours <strong>of</strong> work. “As an act <strong>of</strong> creating<br />

value, [labor] can no more have any particular value than gravity can have<br />

particular weight, heat any particular temperature, electricity any particular<br />

strength <strong>of</strong> current.” Engels – Capital II p. 101:2 [Annotations p. 455]<br />

The Engels quote above from Capital is stating that the question <strong>of</strong> how can something<br />

which is used to qualitatively describe something become a numerical measure <strong>of</strong> the object<br />

that is in question, is an impossibility! The simple answer to this question is that labor does<br />

not create value, so you cannot use labor to describe the price <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Labor<br />

creates value that is true, but labor is not something that can be saved in a vault and used<br />

when in time <strong>of</strong> need, Labor does not work that way, it is not a means <strong>of</strong> storing value. The<br />

capitalist system, which thrives on its ability to taking more <strong>of</strong> the value its workers create<br />

than that which they “pay” them is crucial to this misunderstanding. In reality the worker<br />

who worked twelve hours was only paid a fraction <strong>of</strong> what he really created, but this only<br />

shows how labor can create value.<br />

Message [518] referenced by [519]. Next Message by Sparky is [528].<br />

[519] Hans: It should be a matter <strong>of</strong> course, but it isn’t. Why not? The statement “a<br />

tree is a tree” is a tautology. In a modern dictionary, “tautology” is defined as a statement<br />

that cannot be false. The philosopher Hegel had a different take on it which you should mull<br />

over because it is quite interesting. According to Hegel, the statement “a tree is a tree” is a<br />

contradiction, because you start out saying something, and then you end up saying nothing.<br />

This is <strong>of</strong> course part <strong>of</strong> the Hegelian pastime to find the opposite in everything: even if<br />

you start with the truest possible statement, a statement that cannot be false, you are still<br />

immersed in falsehood, because you pretend to say something while saying nothing.<br />

Just like Hegel, Marx was a dialectical thinker. Just like Hegel, he did not consider<br />

tautologies to be the opposite <strong>of</strong> being false, but the idea that tautologies can be false or<br />

“absurd” is not alien to him. But while Hegel uses the introspection <strong>of</strong> deep thinking to look<br />

for the reason why a tautology is absurd, Marx looks at the structure <strong>of</strong> capitalist society.<br />

At Marx’s time, the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value was part <strong>of</strong> mainstream economics. Someone<br />

who thinks that the labor theory <strong>of</strong> value correctly describes market economies would expect<br />

the following: if a worker is willing to work for 12 hours, then the market will give that


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 247<br />

worker access to 12 hours’ worth <strong>of</strong> labor by others. Marx means this naive expectation<br />

when he calls it a tautology that the value <strong>of</strong> 12 hours <strong>of</strong> labor is 12 hours <strong>of</strong> labor. Alas, in<br />

our society this expectation is wrong. Why? Because it overlooks the basic fact that in our<br />

society, the workers are separated from the means <strong>of</strong> production. The means <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

the resources which support our labor, are monopolized by others who prey on our labor.<br />

That is why the workers do not get the full benefit <strong>of</strong> their labor.<br />

Only if it is a tautology that the workers control the means <strong>of</strong> production will it follow,<br />

tautologically, that the workers are the beneficiaries <strong>of</strong> their labor. We live in a society in<br />

which the workers do not control the means <strong>of</strong> production. We are so immersed in that false<br />

state <strong>of</strong> affairs that we do not even notice that we are cut <strong>of</strong>f from something which should<br />

be our birth right. But the laughter <strong>of</strong> the capitalists all the way to the bank is too loud to be<br />

missed.<br />

This was a difficult question. If you give it a honest try, using the theoretical framework<br />

provided in this class, and miss it, I cannot give you a bad grade, and my feedback will<br />

emphasize the things you are doing right rather than those you missed. But if someone<br />

seeks out subtle and difficult questions several times, and just keeps throwing arguments at<br />

them in the hope one <strong>of</strong> them will stick, as Sparky did with [66], [170], and [518], then my<br />

reaction is: show me that you can walk before you are trying to run.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [534].<br />

Question 621 is 633 in 2007SP, 613 in 2007fa, 625 in 2008fa, 656 in 2009fa, 719 in<br />

2010fa, and 739 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 621 If labor cannot have value, does this mean labor is not a commodity?<br />

[527] Jenn: graded A labor is not a commodity. In [2007fa:451], Hans states that in<br />

this question, he wishes us to follow Marx’s argument (rather than a textbook definition <strong>of</strong> a<br />

commodity) to determine whether or not labor is a commodity. In section 2.2b, Marx states<br />

all commodities are non-use-values for the owners, and use-values for their non-owners. It<br />

is impossible to remove the social aspect that labor is actually expenditure <strong>of</strong> the worker’s<br />

time and energy. To state that a worker’s labor is a non-use-value is quite arguable by any<br />

human being. Can any person state that an hour <strong>of</strong> their time and energy is a non-use-value<br />

to them? I think not. However, if you further narrow down the worker’s labor to a particular<br />

type <strong>of</strong> useful labor, such as shoemaking, one could argue that the worker may not have any<br />

more use for their shoe-making labor. This defies the statement that labor is a commodity,<br />

and further supports Marx’s argument that labor-power, not labor, is the commodity sold on<br />

the capitalist market.<br />

Hans: Very interesting argument.<br />

Next Message by Jenn is [532].<br />

Question 623 is 227 in 1995ut, 302 in 1997WI, 368 in 1997sp, and 366 in 1997ut:<br />

Question 623 Marx argues that labor is something that cannot have value, on very fundamental<br />

grounds. Reproduce these arguments in your own words. Are they convincing to<br />

you?


248 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[627] Kevin: graded A Labor itself cannot have value because it is what creates value in<br />

other commodities. Were labor to have value it would be traded as a commodity, but it is<br />

not. Marx uses the example <strong>of</strong> the Sun not having a shadow. While the sun has no shadow<br />

it creates the shadow everything else has. It is the source <strong>of</strong> the shadow just as labor is the<br />

source <strong>of</strong> value.<br />

This is a convincing argument to me and makes perfect sense. Like at night without a<br />

sun, objects have no shadow. This is the same, without labor nothing has value.<br />

Next Message by Kevin is [781].<br />

[755] Clayon: On the surface Marx seems to contradict himself, for he declares that a<br />

good’s value is directly related to labor input. It seems natural to assume that labor is traded<br />

as a commodity which has a price. If this were true, we could say that labor does in fact<br />

have a value. But Marx counters this with some abstract ideas that simply put declare that<br />

something that gives another thing value cannot have value itself. It is rather difficult to<br />

comprehend without the aid <strong>of</strong> an everyday example. One <strong>of</strong> your students previously wrote<br />

“Labor is the cause <strong>of</strong> value in commodities, but cannot in itself have value; as the sun is the<br />

cause <strong>of</strong> shadows but cannot in itself have a shadow.” Another analogy could be as follows:<br />

Candy given to a young child creates joy for that child, yet the candy itself does not have<br />

joy. So it is with labor and its relationship to value.<br />

Although I agree with Marx that Labor does not have value in the sense that we have<br />

defined it as, I still feel that labor does have some “worth” for it is needed, and beneficial in<br />

the production process. So although it may not have value in the typical sense, it cannot be<br />

said that it is use-less, or without use-value.<br />

Hans: Yes, labor has use-value. Use-value and value are two very different things.<br />

Next Message by Clayon is [871].<br />

[759] Ken: labor and value. “If labor had value, i.e., if labor were something that could<br />

be exchanged on the market, then there would be no need to exchange other products since<br />

they all derive from labor”. Labor gives everything value, therefore labor cannot have value.<br />

Labor is not the commodity being sold by the worker, it is actually labor-power.<br />

I would agree with Marx’s argument. I do not think that labor can have value, labor-power<br />

on the other hand can.<br />

Next Message by Ken is [780].<br />

Question 644 is 223 in 1995WI, 235 in 1995ut, 261 in 1996sp, 313 in 1997WI, 385 in<br />

1998WI, 388 in 1999SP, 480 in 2000fa, and 509 in 2001fa:<br />

Question 644 In a speech which was later published as the pamphlet called Value, Price<br />

and Pr<strong>of</strong>it, Marx says that there is no such thing as a fair wage. What does he mean by this?<br />

[438] Goethe: What is my value? This was originally submitted as a contribution to the<br />

free discussion, and you get credit for it as such. But for the archives, Hans re-classified it<br />

and its responses under question 644.<br />

I am sitting here thinking about value and it comes to me that I am a commodity!!! So, I<br />

ask myself what is my value? I am an intelligent person with certain marketable skills, but<br />

I still think that I am undervalued. As my thought process continues it occurs to me that<br />

like other commodities I have been purchased for my use value, this is <strong>of</strong> course a relative


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 249<br />

value in accordance to the perception <strong>of</strong> my employer (or supervisor <strong>of</strong> the moment). The<br />

more I think about this the more I am feeling used and (not to sound to Marxist) exploited. I<br />

have started a new job where for the first time in years I am punching a time clock, and not<br />

working for commission. Now this is where it gets interesting the services I perform charge<br />

a commission to the customer, but I do not see this. I am told that I am compensated by the<br />

hourly wage. This is a bunch <strong>of</strong> pooh!!! Next my employer tells me that my school schedule<br />

could conflict with my new work schedule (this was discussed prior to my accepting the<br />

position) the options that were given to me were to drop school and concentrate on my job;<br />

“After all which is more important my job or my education?” I don’t need to tell you all my<br />

answer, but needless to say it did not go over well.<br />

This is the second time I have encountered this situation from an employer.... Go figure!!<br />

What do these people want? Mindless drones to do their bidding!!!<br />

I am convinced that our system is way out <strong>of</strong> alignment!!! The manager wants to keep<br />

others from advancing and their managers want to keep them from advancing... this continues<br />

in a downward spiral...<br />

What did Marx think <strong>of</strong> this? And what was his conclusion? I have an Idea but I would<br />

like some feedback before I give my opinion...<br />

Thank you for the opportunity to vent<br />

Message [438] referenced by [441], [446], and [451]. Next Message by Goethe is [456].<br />

[441] Trailrunner: You are not a Value, but an Input. Actually Goethe [438] you are<br />

a part <strong>of</strong> the Labor Process - the laborer. Your boss, the Capitalist, has gathered you up as<br />

an input along with other items, to create a desired product. And in the end, there is no usevalue<br />

to you <strong>of</strong> the product you are creating, as this use-value simply goes to your Capitalist<br />

boss. You are given your value, by the wage that you are paid and if you happen to work<br />

extra hard, then your boss reaps the benefits as surplus-value. Sounds like a pretty grand<br />

idea if you happen to be the Capitalist boss!!<br />

Aside from what Marx might think, I feel your pain. After living in Salt Lake for 6<br />

years, I am finally earning what I earned in California nine years ago (I received a raise a<br />

week ago). I am still many dollars away from what I was earning seven years ago prior to<br />

moving up here. I, like you, feel as if I am undervalued and this has taken me to a place<br />

<strong>of</strong> wondering what part I might have in this. Am I pursuing positions that keep me in my<br />

low paying status? Or is it simply the fact that I “live in <strong>Utah</strong> and the cost <strong>of</strong> living is so<br />

much lower, so I get paid less” as everyone continues to tell me? For me, my expenses are<br />

essentially the same, so I’m not really buying that.<br />

The one advantage I have is that I am employed by the <strong>University</strong> and therefore receive<br />

a tuition reduction. Without this, I would not be able to finish my degree (the wage that I<br />

am being paid is a HUGE factor in this). I am lucky in that my boss sees the value in my<br />

finishing my education and grants me the time to take my classes as long as I get my 40<br />

hours a week in.<br />

I agree with you that the system is out <strong>of</strong> alignment and I find this especially potent<br />

when it comes to having a government job. I give you kudos for continuing to make your<br />

education a priority and send good wishes that upon your completion, you’ll land a position


250 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

that will allow you to say “pooh” to all those that have continued the downward spiral <strong>of</strong><br />

advancement.<br />

Message [441] referenced by [451]. Next Message by Trailrunner is [449].<br />

[446] CousinIt: What do these people want? Mindless drones? In response to Goethe’s<br />

[438] question;<br />

The answer to the question is, YES! They do want people who will accept their position as<br />

a member <strong>of</strong> the underclass and they do want them to be left without any means <strong>of</strong> effective<br />

resistance or advancement. If you equal or surpass their accomplishments, or are doing<br />

anything that would facilitate this, you become a personal-social-economic threat to them<br />

and their illusion <strong>of</strong> security. Alas, (this course being an exception) even your education is<br />

penultimately just all about training you to fit into the system and not primarily aimed at your<br />

overall enlightenment/intelligence/effective democratic participation as a critically-engaged<br />

citizen. You are a consumable disposable consumer. You must find an occupation that the<br />

system you are embedded in deems to be <strong>of</strong> use-value for the system that creates you, that<br />

commodifies you. For all intents and purposes, in this society, this is the measure <strong>of</strong> your<br />

value....period.<br />

Marx would say that the problems you are facing come as a result <strong>of</strong> the fact that you do<br />

not own the means <strong>of</strong> production and are thus situated within a complex set <strong>of</strong> class relations<br />

which compell you to either accept the oppressive, restrictive conditions you are <strong>of</strong>fered or<br />

suffer the economic consequences and all <strong>of</strong> the subsequent social and health consequences,<br />

to yourself and your family, <strong>of</strong> your faulty response to your employment dilemma. You,<br />

like everyone else, are forced into a condition <strong>of</strong> ever-present economic terror that no one<br />

seems able to counter because <strong>of</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong> the society you live in, its ideological<br />

investments, assumptions, and characteristic psychoses (much like the ‘global warming’<br />

that we apparently can do nothing to stop, even though we know what is causing it).<br />

Your manager probably ‘classifies’ himself as being above you. He may have an education<br />

and/or he may have reached his position through work experience or simple doledprivilege<br />

(he has a daddy, a mommy, a girlie, or a buddy or he is particularly socially-situated<br />

so as to be given his position as your ‘manager’). He probably, like you, does not own the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production, yet imagines to himself that he is a capitalist, nonetheless. You both<br />

live in a capitalist system, and perhaps imagine that you are capitalists-by-association, but<br />

there is an important fact that is being over-looked. Chances are neither <strong>of</strong> you owns the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production necessary to compete with the other owners in the race to amass vast<br />

stocks <strong>of</strong> material wealth (and social power/privilege derived from class position).<br />

You are probably a member <strong>of</strong> the exploited labor class and are most likely to die without<br />

any real change in your status as such and you are not alone in this.<br />

As long as people buy into the notion that it is OK to exploit and objectify others as<br />

commodities, as use-values, and as long as such violence and crime against humanity is<br />

justified as ‘normal’ or as ‘human nature,’ then nothing will be done about the violence that<br />

economic terror does to our lives. Marx knew that two things would have to happen in order<br />

for you and me to get out from under the yoke <strong>of</strong> an abusive wage-slavery system.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 251<br />

Capitalism must reach its material, environmental, technical, spiritual, and intellectual<br />

limits and be unable to deal with or overcome them by way <strong>of</strong> capitalist conventions, methods,<br />

or ideological approaches<br />

and<br />

The people who are being exploited by the system (which, because <strong>of</strong> the fetish-like<br />

character <strong>of</strong> the commodity as primary relational unit, includes the owners as well as the<br />

workers) would have to have some sort <strong>of</strong> shift or metamorphosis <strong>of</strong> consciousness as to how<br />

they view and address their real material relations such that they, as a whole, are compelled<br />

to do away with the system that enslaves them, i.e., to bring about the necessary proletarian<br />

revolution (via democracy or via crisis) which hasn’t happened yet.<br />

I guess we’ll wake up when we’re darned good and ready to...hope it’s not too late....maybe<br />

we need to BUY a BIGGER BETTER alarmclock....<br />

Message [446] referenced by [451] and [456]. Next Message by CousinIt is [448].<br />

[451] Hans: We are producers, not products. The schoolbook answer to the above<br />

question is: there is no such thing as a fair wage because the wage relationship itself is<br />

unfair. Marx expected the class struggles to evolve to the point where workers are no longer<br />

fighting for higher wages but for the abolition <strong>of</strong> the wage labor system itself, and fight for<br />

a system where they no longer have to sell their labor.<br />

I always thought this was a rather theoretical view with not much practical significance.<br />

Whenever I tried to imagine workers fighting against the wage labor system, a scene in an<br />

old flick came to my mind in which the boss says to the employee: “You are against wage<br />

labor? So am I. You are fired.”<br />

But Goethe’s [438] revolves exactly around the quality <strong>of</strong> the wage labor relation, not just<br />

the quantity <strong>of</strong> wages. If the boss says that the job is more important than education, this<br />

shows that the employee is not valued as a person but only as a commodity, an input into<br />

production.<br />

Goethe’s musings “what is my value?” can be answered in two ways. On the one hand,<br />

I agree that Goethe’s value is greater than what he is paid. But on the other hand, even if<br />

Goethe got paid much more, I think this question should not have to be asked. Whether<br />

Goethe is marketable or not should not matter. Society should be organized in such a way<br />

that Goethe, and everybody else, is considered an end in himself, not a means to an end. We<br />

should be the measuring stick, not that what is being measured.<br />

Trailrunner’s answer in [441] “you are not a value” is meant in this way (if I understand<br />

it right): you are not considered an end in yourself, but a means to an end. But instead <strong>of</strong><br />

continuing “you are only an input into the production process” (not a literal quote), I would<br />

turn it around and say: “I am not a product that needs to be valued, but I am a producer that<br />

creates value economically, and that creates social relations in which everybody is respected<br />

politically and morally.”<br />

In response to the two points at the end <strong>of</strong> CousinIt’s [446], I would add a third point,<br />

namely, the need to organize. In order to change society people have to work together with<br />

many others, this cannot be done on an individual or small scale basis. Someone in this


252 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

class contacted me because they wanted to form a Marxist student organization. I think this<br />

is a good idea. I have lived through a time in 1968-70 when there was a strong student<br />

movement. These were exciting times, and we seem to be at the beginning <strong>of</strong> another wave<br />

<strong>of</strong> student activism. If you want me to give that person your email address, please contact<br />

me privately at ehrbar@lists.econ.utah.edu<br />

Next Message by Hans is [469].<br />

Term Paper 648 is 683 in 2009fa:<br />

Term Paper 648 The Vintage edition <strong>of</strong> Capital p. 681 has here the following reference:<br />

Wealth <strong>of</strong> Nations, Bk I, Ch. 8, ‘Of the Wages <strong>of</strong> Labor’. I read this chapter and did not find<br />

an obvious place where Smith said this. If you can identify the place in Smith which Marx<br />

refers to here, this is a piece <strong>of</strong> research which I would count as a term paper.<br />

[783] Allen and Jason: Marx’s reference to Adam Smith: This circumstance misled<br />

Adam Smith, who treated the working day as a constant quantity,9 into the opposite assertion<br />

that the value <strong>of</strong> labor is constant, although the value <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> subsistence may vary,<br />

and the same working day, therefore, may represent more or less money for the worker.<br />

9. Adam Smith only incidentally alludes to the variation <strong>of</strong> the working day, when he is<br />

dealing with piece-wages.*<br />

*In Wealth <strong>of</strong> Nations, BK I, Ch. 8, ‘Of the Wages <strong>of</strong> Labour’<br />

After reading the chapter several times we found this paragraph on p. 34, towards the end<br />

<strong>of</strong> the chapter, that we think Marx is referring to.<br />

The liberal reward <strong>of</strong> labour, as it encourages the propagation, so it increases the industry<br />

<strong>of</strong> the common people. The wages <strong>of</strong> labour are the encouragement <strong>of</strong> industry, which,<br />

like every other human quality, improves in proportion to the encouragement it receives. A<br />

plentiful subsistence increases the bodily strength <strong>of</strong> the labourer, and the comfortable hope<br />

<strong>of</strong> bettering his condition, and <strong>of</strong> ending his days perhaps in ease and plenty, animates him<br />

to exert that strength to the utmost. Where wages are high, accordingly, we shall always find<br />

the workmen more active, diligent, and expeditious, than where they are low; in England,<br />

for example, than in Scotland; in the neighbourhood <strong>of</strong> great towns, than in remote country<br />

places. Some workmen, indeed, when they can earn in four days what will maintain them<br />

through the week, will be idle the other three. This, however, is by no means the case with<br />

the greater part. Workmen, on the contrary, when they are liberally paid by the piece, are<br />

very apt to over-work themselves, and to ruin their health and constitution in a few years. A<br />

carpenter in London, and in some other places, is not supposed to last in his utmost vigour<br />

above eight years. Something <strong>of</strong> the same kind happens in many other trades, in which the<br />

workmen are paid by the piece; as they generally are in manufactures, and even in country<br />

labour, wherever wages are higher than ordinary. Almost every class <strong>of</strong> artificers is subject<br />

to some peculiar infirmity occasioned by excessive application to their peculiar species <strong>of</strong><br />

work. Ramuzzini, an eminent Italian physician, has written a particular book concerning<br />

such disease. We do not reckon our soldiers the most industrious set <strong>of</strong> people among us.<br />

Yet when soldiers have been employed in some particular sorts <strong>of</strong> work, and liberally paid<br />

by the piece, their <strong>of</strong>ficers have frequently been obliged to stipulate with the undertaker, that


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 253<br />

they should not be allowed to earn above a certain sum every day, according to the rate at<br />

which they were paid. Till this stipulation was made, mutual emulation and the desire <strong>of</strong><br />

greater gain, frequently prompted them to over-work themselves, and to hurt their health<br />

by excessive labour. Excessive application during four days <strong>of</strong> the week, is frequently the<br />

real cause <strong>of</strong> the idleness <strong>of</strong> the other three, so much and so loudly complained <strong>of</strong>. Great<br />

labour, either <strong>of</strong> mind or body, continued for several days together, is in most men naturally<br />

followed by a great desire <strong>of</strong> relaxation, which, if not restrained by force or by some strong<br />

necessity, is almost irresistible. It is the call <strong>of</strong> nature, which requires to be relieved by some<br />

indulgence, sometimes <strong>of</strong> ease only, but sometimes too <strong>of</strong> dissipation and diversion. If it is<br />

not complied with, the consequences are <strong>of</strong>ten dangerous, and sometimes fatal, and such as<br />

almost always, sooner or later, bring on the peculiar infirmity <strong>of</strong> the trade. If masters would<br />

always listen to the dictates <strong>of</strong> reason and humanity, they have frequently occasion rather<br />

to moderate, than to animate the application <strong>of</strong> many <strong>of</strong> their workmen. It will be found, I<br />

believe, in every sort <strong>of</strong> trade, that the man who works so moderately, as to be able to work<br />

constantly, not only preserves his health the longest, but, in the course <strong>of</strong> the year, executes<br />

the greatest quantity <strong>of</strong> work.<br />

http://books.google.com/books?id=70759KjSs0sC&dq=adam smith the wealth<br />

<strong>of</strong> nations volume 1&pg=PA34<br />

Since Adam Smith only alludes to the variation <strong>of</strong> the working day, we think this is where<br />

Marx is referencing. Throughout the chapter Smith does not show variation in the workday,<br />

but in the above paragraph he says, “Some workmen, indeed, when they can earn in four<br />

days what will maintain them through the week, will be idle the other three.” This implies<br />

that the workday is not constant. Smith then mentions that when “Workmen. . . are liberally<br />

paid by the piece, are very apt to over-work themselves. . . ,” this specifically discusses the<br />

piece-wages in which Marx is referencing. In conclusion, this paragraph seems to be the<br />

only place in this chapter Marx cited about Adam Smith.<br />

Hans: Piece wages are also discussed on pp. 35 and 51, but the paragraph you quote seems to be the main place<br />

on piece wages.<br />

Next Message by Allen is [786] and Next Message by Jason is [830].<br />

Question 655 is 668 in 2007SP, 646 in 2007fa, 659 in 2008fa, 690 in 2009fa, 754 in<br />

2010fa, 776 in 2011fa, and 805 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 655 Why a separate chapter about the time wage? Wasn’t the time wage already<br />

discussed in chapter Nineteen?<br />

[548] Papageorgio: Got to Keep em Separated. Yes time wage was discussed in chapter<br />

19 but just because it was discussed does that mean it was fully covered. Many things<br />

are discussed in various chapters but it is necessary in many cases to go further in depth.<br />

Regarding time wage we must go further in depth to discuss the forms wages take on as<br />

piece wage and time wage. Chapter 20 gives us depth on time wages structure. I know this<br />

in part by the annotations in the beginning <strong>of</strong> chapter 20 it tells us this on page 480 paragraph<br />

2, “knowing the essence behind the wage form does not yet fully define the shapes which<br />

this form can assume”. So we must read chapter 20 to find out more for example such things


254 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

as that time wage has built in tendencies to extend the length <strong>of</strong> the workday and that the<br />

time wage tries to be independent <strong>of</strong> other mechanisms.<br />

Hans: If you take the phrase “going further in depth” seriously, then chapter 19 is the one which goes into depth,<br />

while chapters 20 and 21 take a more thorough look at the surface. Marx says that it is not enough to go into the<br />

depth, i.e., to decipher what is behind the surface forms <strong>of</strong> the wage <strong>of</strong> labor, but that it is also worth while to look<br />

at the surface forms themselves, in order to see how these surface forms lead to intensification <strong>of</strong> labor, wage theft,<br />

whether they foster competition or unity between the workers, etc.<br />

I didn’t write in the Annotations that the time wage tries to make itself independent <strong>of</strong> other mechanisms, but<br />

<strong>of</strong> those mechanisms which define it. With this I meant for instance that time wages can fall although the price <strong>of</strong><br />

labor-power remains constant (if the worker has to work longer for the same wage) etc.<br />

Message [548] referenced by [2009fa:785], [2009fa:805], and [2012fa:1052]. Next Message by Papageorgio is<br />

[663].<br />

[550] Aaron: Time wages. The reason that there will be a separate discussion on time<br />

wages, in addition to the discussion in previous chapter 19, is because chapter 19 simply<br />

discussed the price <strong>of</strong> labor, which is not determined by the value <strong>of</strong> labor. As Hans noted at<br />

the beginning <strong>of</strong> chapter 20, chapter 19 established a connection between the price <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

on the surface as well as the underlying connection with production. Time wages are meant<br />

to extend the workday to a maximum effort <strong>of</strong> 24 hours per human worker. The time wage<br />

is used to trade a worker for his means <strong>of</strong> production using the function <strong>of</strong> time as a trade<br />

medium. If a worker works x amount <strong>of</strong> time, then he his paid y wage. Regardless <strong>of</strong> what<br />

he accomplishes during his work time.<br />

Hans: The following sentence is a little garbled: “chapter 19 established a connection between the price <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

on the surface as well as the underlying connection with production.” I tried to say that chapter 19 looks at the<br />

connection between the price <strong>of</strong> labor on the surface and the relations <strong>of</strong> production underneath, while chapter 20<br />

looks at the surface itself.<br />

Time wages are not meant to extend the workday, but they have an inbuilt structure which tends to extend the<br />

workday. (This is one <strong>of</strong> the results <strong>of</strong> the investigation which stays on the surface.)<br />

Next Message by Aaron is [551].<br />

[557] Ken: Why should we separate them? In chapter 19 Marx discusses the wage <strong>of</strong><br />

labor. The wage <strong>of</strong> labor is based on labor performed. The worker is paid for the labor<br />

performed not for his labor power. Marx argues that the worker is selling his labor power<br />

however the worker is actually given a wage based on labor. This situation maximizes the<br />

capitalist’s benefits. The worker is being exploited because the capitalist is paying a minimal<br />

wage for the great amount <strong>of</strong> labor being acquired. Chapter 20 and 21 discuss time wage<br />

and piece wage. Time wage and piece wage describe and define the structure <strong>of</strong> wage.<br />

Hans: Your sentence “the worker is paid for the labor performed not for his labor power” is misleading. The<br />

worker sells his labor-power and is paid for his labor-power, i.e., the total amount <strong>of</strong> wages compensates him for<br />

the reproduction cost <strong>of</strong> his labor-power. But the payment looks as if it was a payment for his labor. The weekly<br />

value <strong>of</strong> his labor-power is spread out over 40 hours and is paid according to hours worked. This is why, as you say,<br />

the worker only gets a minimal wage in exchange for a great amount <strong>of</strong> labor. This is not the capitalist bending the<br />

rules in their favor, but this is the working <strong>of</strong> the market in a situation where the capitalists monopolize the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Next Message by Ken is [639].<br />

Question 662 is 674 in 2007SP, 652 in 2007fa, 666 in 2008fa, 697 in 2009fa, 761 in<br />

2010fa, 783 in 2011fa, and 812 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 662 How can the price <strong>of</strong> labor be reduced even without changing the weekly<br />

pay?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 255<br />

[536] Jeremy: Reason behind salary <strong>of</strong>fering. From the capitalist perspective, there is<br />

a method in which they are able to create surplus value without having to increase pay for<br />

labor given. In modern days, workers are increasingly being extended the <strong>of</strong>fer to receive<br />

a salary. A salary is a concrete weekly, or more commonly, yearly gross income which the<br />

employee will receive regardless <strong>of</strong> the hours <strong>of</strong> labor given. From the capitalist’s view, they<br />

are <strong>of</strong>fering more money than what would normally be given to an hourly pay employee.<br />

The appeal to the laborer is that they will receive more income than if they were an hourly<br />

employee working 40 hours per week (under modern working conditions and expectations).<br />

The salaried employee does not receive the option <strong>of</strong> overtime pay. This is where the capitalist’s<br />

opportunity lies. Once a laborer becomes committed to a salary, the employer may<br />

increase the desired work hours in a day. The salary is locked in place, so no additional<br />

money would be earned by the laborer, yet the employer receives the benefit <strong>of</strong> additional<br />

hours <strong>of</strong> labor input. This is the method by which capitalists create surplus value. Surplus<br />

value is created when the length <strong>of</strong> the working day is extended, but the wages are frozen.<br />

The more working hours input by the laborer creates a larger margin <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it for the capitalist.<br />

Hans: Marx would say: this is a situation where the surplus-value is plain to see; but even in situations in which<br />

each hour is paid, even with overtime premium, there is surplus-value as well.<br />

Message [536] referenced by [540]. Next Message by Jeremy is [640].<br />

[540] Trailrunner: graded A The Working Day and Hourly Wages. In response to<br />

Jeremy [536], I agree with much <strong>of</strong> what he has said, but I also question one particular point.<br />

I question whether a salary being <strong>of</strong>fered is “<strong>of</strong>fering more money than would normally be<br />

given to an hourly pay employee.” In my own experience, this has not been the case, as it<br />

has been essentially an equivalent pay (a bit more vacation time is earned during each pay<br />

period as a salaried employee) with more hours expected. What actually did change was the<br />

job title.<br />

In a previous job, I worked with a group <strong>of</strong> three Supervisors who were paid by an<br />

hourly wage. All three <strong>of</strong> these supervisors worked overtime occasionally, but one <strong>of</strong> these<br />

individuals worked overtime every single day. In fact, he worked so much overtime, that he<br />

ended up making more in his overtime hours, than he did in his normal 40 hour workweek.<br />

It is absolutely true that had these individuals been placed on a salary, they would have lost<br />

all <strong>of</strong> the overtime pay, but they would have in no way been paid more on a salary than they<br />

would have in their basic 40 hour workweek.<br />

The use <strong>of</strong> the policy <strong>of</strong> overtime in this case, is an excellent example <strong>of</strong> a missed opportunity<br />

by a company, to gain a tremendous amount <strong>of</strong> surplus labor by putting these individuals<br />

on a salaried wage. If the reality is that “regular pay is depressed, so that the workers are<br />

forced to work longer because they depend on overtime pay,” as stated by Marx in 20.2.b.,<br />

then this would explain why so much overtime was paid out. Having worked very closely<br />

with these individuals though, I know that their wage was comparable to others with similar<br />

jobs and I question whether that rate is depressed or not. As well, because these individuals<br />

worked for the state, they received an additional accrual <strong>of</strong> vacation and sick days because<br />

<strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> the hours worked, thus receiving an added benefit.<br />

The above situation is contrary to the question asked <strong>of</strong> the “price <strong>of</strong> labor being reduced<br />

even without changing the weekly pay.” Had these individuals been placed on a salaried


256 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

wage, it would have been a good example <strong>of</strong> how the question can be made into a reality. I<br />

believe that if a salaried wage was in place, there would have been a great deal less overtime<br />

put in, much <strong>of</strong> which was created simply to earn the extra income anyway. The extra hours<br />

would have then resulted in the price <strong>of</strong> labor being reduced without a change in weekly pay.<br />

Hans: Are you saying the state is not as adept at exploiting its employees as private capitalists?<br />

Message [540] referenced by [2008fa:885] and [2009fa:820]. Next Message by Trailrunner is [606].<br />

Question 663 is 675 in 2007SP, 653 in 2007fa, 667 in 2008fa, 698 in 2009fa, 762 in<br />

2010fa, 784 in 2011fa, and 813 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 663 Is it true that the laborer is only interested in what he receives, i.e., the overall<br />

daily wage income, and not interested in what he gives, i.e., the overall daily labor?<br />

[539] Trailrunner: graded A Labor for money or labor for satisfaction? A laborer<br />

can be said to only be interested in what he receives when looking at the fact that what the<br />

laborer in actually interested in, is ensuring that he can earn enough income to survive. I<br />

sat in a class this past week when someone was asked what they expected in a wage. This<br />

individual stated that he looked only at what his monthly expenses were and determined<br />

what he wanted to earn based solely upon his monthly expenses. This answer would seem<br />

to validate what Marx has stated. Thus the answer to the question would be that it is true.<br />

To me, this answer looks only at the intellectual response based upon what Marx has<br />

stated in his writings. I would wonder though at the emotional response someone might<br />

give. I believe that it is true, that many people look only at the wage received in comparison<br />

to what someone else in the same pr<strong>of</strong>ession would make and whether they can pay their<br />

bills or not. But I also believe that some people look at how a job makes them feel, what it<br />

is that they are giving emotionally, as well as receiving emotionally.<br />

I have recently changed from an hourly wage to a salaried wage in my primary job and I<br />

have found my feelings toward my work effort to have changed just a bit. Recognizing that<br />

a wage is paid with the idea that a quantity <strong>of</strong> unpaid labor is included in this wage, when I<br />

was working on an hourly wage, I felt a need to fill each hour with my giving <strong>of</strong> useful labor.<br />

I also knew that I would receive overtime if I were to go over my 40 hours a week, even by<br />

a few minutes, thus I felt I was receiving some sort <strong>of</strong> benefit for my efforts.<br />

Now that I am working for a salaried wage, I do not find quite as much need to fill every<br />

hour. When I was switched over to a salaried wage, I was told that there was an expectation<br />

that I would now be working overtime on a regular basis without being paid for it. This has<br />

affected my desire to give, in that I don’t feel the need to push myself quite as hard as I did<br />

before. There are some other factors that have brought about this feeling, but recognizing<br />

that I will no longer receive overtime, I feel that everything will balance out in the long run,<br />

if I come in a bit late, or leave a bit early.<br />

Thus, I find this question quite applicable in my life at the moment as I try to balance<br />

whether I care only about what I receive versus what I give. At the same time, I look at the<br />

numerous hours I give in volunteer work in which I receive no wage in return, but receive<br />

a tremendous amount in the overall daily labor that I give. Because <strong>of</strong> the emotional wellbeing<br />

that I receive by giving in this case, I am always willing to give a little bit more. While<br />

it is my personality to give all that I possibly can to my employer and that I take a tremendous


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 257<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> pride in a job well done, I am searching for the balance between receiving and<br />

giving in my primary job.<br />

It might also be valuable to note that I have a second job where I know that I am valued<br />

very highly and that the individuals that I work for desire to pay me a wage that reflects<br />

their trust in me and my skills, as well as letting me know that there is no expectation <strong>of</strong><br />

me providing free (or unpaid) labor. Because <strong>of</strong> the dynamics <strong>of</strong> this working relationship,<br />

when I work for these individuals, I give the work <strong>of</strong> two people in order to get the job done<br />

quickly while striving to show my appreciation for the great way that they treat me. I am<br />

allowed to come and go as I please, because these people know that I will get the job done<br />

and they do not have to worry at all about any <strong>of</strong> the finances associated with their business.<br />

In this case, I am interested in what I receive, but I am also extremely interested in what I<br />

give.<br />

My guess is that there are many people who are interested only in what they receive, but<br />

there are also many people that care about what they give.<br />

Next Message by Trailrunner is [540].<br />

Question 665 is 677 in 2007SP, 669 in 2008fa, 700 in 2009fa, 764 in 2010fa, 786 in<br />

2011fa, 816 in 2012fa, and 764 in Answer:<br />

Question 665 In a system <strong>of</strong> hourly wages without a set daily minimum <strong>of</strong> hours, Marx says<br />

that “the connection between the paid and the unpaid labor is destroyed.” Explain what he<br />

means by this.<br />

[532] Jenn: graded A– hourly wage system changes paid:unpaid labor ratio. In chapter<br />

20.2, Marx says that an hourly-wage system destroys the connection between the paid and<br />

unpaid labor. In [2007SP:908], Moose explained well the challenges the worker experiences<br />

when the capitalist has the right to adjust working hours at any time without notice. I believe<br />

the connection Moose is missing is that the capitalist then has the option to pay the worker<br />

based on useful labor rather than labor power. The worker chooses to sell their commodity,<br />

labor-power, at a wage that is calculated based on their needs for subsistence. In many<br />

cases, the worker understands that some <strong>of</strong> their labor is paid, and some <strong>of</strong> their labor (the<br />

surplus-labor) is unpaid (although Marx believes that the actual understanding is masked).<br />

However, if the worker is paid hourly, the capitalist is paying the worker for their actual<br />

labor, not their labor-power, as initially agreed upon. The disconnect lies in the calculation<br />

<strong>of</strong> paid:unpaid labor ratio will be based on useful labor in an hourly wage setting, where the<br />

paid:unpaid labor ratio would have been based on labor-power in a fixed-hour setting. Marx<br />

would probably use this disconnect, or ratio change, to show another advantage the capitalist<br />

has over the worker, and can choose to pay the worker based on labor-power or actual labor,<br />

whichever is <strong>of</strong> the greater benefit to the capitalist.<br />

Hans: You seem to be on the right track. My [534] is an attempt to explain more clearly how the ratio <strong>of</strong> paid to<br />

unpaid labor is affected by the length <strong>of</strong> the working day.<br />

Message [532] referenced by [2008fa:875]. Next Message by Jenn is [637].<br />

[534] Hans: Hourly Pay and Length <strong>of</strong> Workday. Assume an average working class<br />

family needs $700 per week to live, and the conventional working-day is 40 hours per week.<br />

Then, Marx says, the hourly wage is $700/40 = $17.50. Assuming that one hour <strong>of</strong> labor


258 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

produces a value <strong>of</strong> $42.50 per hour, the capitalist will get $25 <strong>of</strong> surplus-value for each<br />

hour he employs his workers, i.e., $1000 weekly for each employee.<br />

This simple calculation has important consequences. I will give two, the first is the obvious<br />

implication, and the second a less obvious implication referred to in the question.<br />

(a) If workers know that this is how their wage is computed, and how much more value<br />

they produce than they get, they might say for instance: we want to work only 35 hours per<br />

week and get $20 per hour. This way we will also get $700 per week, which pays our bills.<br />

The capitalists will strongly resist because it reduces their weekly pr<strong>of</strong>it from $1000 per<br />

employee to $787.50 per employee. But if the workers are strong enough, well organized<br />

and militant, they could fight for this outcome (France).<br />

(b) Now assume there is a recession and the capitalist cannot sell all his product. He says<br />

to the workers: sorry, business is bad and next week I can employ you only for 35 hours.<br />

The workers have every right to say: “our cost <strong>of</strong> living does not go down just because we<br />

work 5 less hours, we need now a higher hourly wage, we need $20 per hour.” The capitalist<br />

would say indignantly “What, you want more pay for less work? Don’t you see that we<br />

are in a recession? We have to stick together in bad times.” He would conveniently forget<br />

that he never dreamt about sticking together in good times but was not ashamed <strong>of</strong> taking<br />

$25 surplus-value while the worker got only $17.50 per hour. On the contrary, even in bad<br />

times he still insists on $25 <strong>of</strong> surplus-value per hour worked, although he does not allow<br />

the workers to work long enough that they can earn enough to pay their own bills.<br />

This is what Marx means with the words “the connection between the paid and the unpaid<br />

labor is destroyed.” Previously, the capitalist got his unpaid labor after allowing the workers<br />

first to work the paid labor. Now the capitalist claims unpaid labor without allowing the<br />

workers to perform enough paid labor for themselves to live.<br />

Message [534] referenced by [Answer:9], [532], [2008fa:875], [2009fa:829], and [2009fa:1068]. Next Message by<br />

Hans is [549].<br />

[649] Bennett: The average labor class family needs a certain amount <strong>of</strong> money to live<br />

each week. To pay bills, buy food, etcetera. If the main bread winner makes a certain amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> pay every hour for the 40 hours in the work week, the weekly salary must be equal or<br />

above the amount that the family needs to live. But each hour that this employee labors<br />

he/she produces a certain value for the capitalist, the capitalists’ surplus-value is affected by<br />

how many hours the employee works. If there is a recession and not all the product is sold<br />

then the capitalist will try to reduce the hours that the employees work so that he can try<br />

to minimize some <strong>of</strong> his losses. By decreasing his worker’s hours he is also decreasing his<br />

workers salary. In so doing this, his workers now do not make as much money, but it still<br />

costs them just as much money to pay their bills and to eat as it did before the recession. The<br />

workers will say this to the capitalists but the capitalist will not listen and will still expect the<br />

same surplus-value from the workers even though he is forcing them to work less hours each<br />

week and they cannot make enough money to live <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong>. This is the destroyed connection<br />

between the paid and the unpaid labor. Before the recession the capitalist received his unpaid<br />

labor after allowing the workers to work the paid labor and then the capitalists gets his unpaid<br />

labor because he does not allow the workers to work enough paid labor so that they can pay<br />

their living expenses.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 259<br />

Next Message by Bennett is [650].<br />

[695] Ryoung: Hourly Wages. In a system <strong>of</strong> hourly wages without a set daily minimum<br />

<strong>of</strong> hours, the connection between the paid and unpaid labor is destroyed according to Marx<br />

because we do not have a set daily minimum <strong>of</strong> hours, which gives us nothing from which<br />

we can calculate which amount <strong>of</strong> the labor is paid or unpaid.<br />

A set amount <strong>of</strong> minimum hours gives us a constant variable that allows us to calculate<br />

which <strong>of</strong> the hours <strong>of</strong> labor are paid or unpaid. Without the set number <strong>of</strong> hours we have<br />

nothing to judge with.<br />

Hans: It is not just an issue for the statistician but for the laborer himself, who has to perform so much surplus-labor<br />

that the shortened workweek does not leave him enough time to perform enough paid labor to survive.<br />

Next Message by Ryoung is [699].<br />

[747] Ande: What Marx means when he says the connection between paid and unpaid<br />

labor is destroyed, he is meaning that it is destroyed because there is not set minimum<br />

amount or maximum amount <strong>of</strong> hours required to work in the working day. If there was<br />

a set minimum or maximum you would be able to have a connection between paid and<br />

unpaid labor. With no true set <strong>of</strong> hours in a working day you can not tell if the labor one is<br />

performing is considered paid or unpaid, but if you have a set amount <strong>of</strong> hours to a working<br />

day one could then tell what is paid and unpaid labor. What the capitalists argue is that there<br />

needs to be a set minimum or maximum amount <strong>of</strong> hours to a working day because if not the<br />

connection gets destroyed and that is what Marx is arguing. As well without this connection<br />

in a sense labor power and use value will not be as true to their meanings because there will<br />

be no connection between the paid and unpaid labor.<br />

Hans: You make it sound as if it was a theoretical question, that one cannot know how much labor is paid and<br />

unpaid. So what? The worker usually does not know anyway that any part <strong>of</strong> his workday is unpaid. The problem<br />

for him is that he cannot pay his bills if the hours are reduced.<br />

Next Message by Ande is [836].<br />

Question 668 is 680 in 2007SP, 658 in 2007fa, 672 in 2008fa, 703 in 2009fa, 767 in<br />

2010fa, 791 in 2011fa, and 821 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 668 How does Marx argue that longer hours are associated with a lower overall<br />

daily wage?<br />

[561] Paul: The more you work, the more the sytem works you. When a laborer is<br />

doing his job he is doing it for one reason: to get paid. Everybody needs to get paid in order<br />

to survive and “put food on the table” so to speak. The capitalist who is paying the laborers<br />

obviously wants to get away with paying them the lowest possible amount so that he can<br />

pocket the rest. This lowest possible amount that the capitalist can get away with paying the<br />

laborers while still letting the laborers sustain their lives and also leave them still wanting<br />

to work day in and day out could be called the sustainable wage for that line <strong>of</strong> work. This<br />

“sustainable wage” will be different in every type <strong>of</strong> work. The equation that Marx gives for<br />

determining the hourly wage <strong>of</strong> a worker is this sustainable wage divided by the number <strong>of</strong><br />

hours worked.<br />

Hourly wage = sustainable wage / hours worked<br />

Given this formula it is obvious to see that as the number <strong>of</strong> hours worked increases the<br />

hourly wage will decrease. If the sustainable wage <strong>of</strong> money that you need to get paid in


260 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

one day to survive is $100 and you work 8 hours a day than your hourly wage would be<br />

$12.50/hr. If you worked 10 however, your hourly wage would decrease to $10/hr. This<br />

demonstrates how if you work more hours then people are able get away with paying you a<br />

lower hourly wage.<br />

Hans: According to this formula, the overall daily wage is constant. My [570] tries to explain why the daily wage<br />

is not constant but lower.<br />

Next Message by Paul is [562].<br />

[570] Hans: The longer the day, the lower the daily wage. Marx considered it to be<br />

an empirical fact that long workdays are associated with low wages – not only low hourly<br />

wages, but even low daily wages. And he had a very interesting way to explain it.<br />

According to his theory <strong>of</strong> wages, the daily wage should be the same, whether the working<br />

day is short or long. Because the daily wage is determined by the reproduction cost <strong>of</strong><br />

the laborer, which does not differ if the worker works longer or shorter hours within some<br />

resonable limits.<br />

Even if the daily wage is the same, the workers in those industries where the workday is<br />

longer and the hourly wage is lower are worse <strong>of</strong>f than in those industries where the workday<br />

is shorter and the hourly wage is higher.<br />

And now comes the important sentence from Marx, p. 689/o:<br />

But the same circumstances which allow the capitalist in the long run to<br />

prolong the working day also allow him ... to reduce the price <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

In other words: those industries in which the working day is long are the industries in<br />

which the workers are weak. This weakness is likely to manifest itself not only in long<br />

hours but also otherwise. Therefore we can expect the daily wage to be lower than in those<br />

industries where the workers are stronger and therefore the working day is shorter, instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> being equal as the general law postulates.<br />

This is the general argument. Allen’s story in [559] is given by Marx as one <strong>of</strong> two examples<br />

<strong>of</strong> circumstances causing this weakness which at the same time prolongs the workingday<br />

and lowers the daily wage.<br />

Message [570] referenced by [561], [592], [616], [634], [2008fa:877], [2008fa:890], [2008fa:907], [2009fa:764],<br />

[2009fa:787], [2011fa:740], [2011fa:956], [2012fa:1070], and [2012fa:1316]. Next Message by Hans is [574].<br />

[592] Goethe: from [570] According to Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> wages; the daily wage should be<br />

the same whether the working day is long or short. Wage is determined by the reproduction<br />

cost <strong>of</strong> the laborer; independent from the length <strong>of</strong> the working day.<br />

Marx states on p 689; “But the same circumstances which allow the capitalist in the long<br />

run to prolong the working day also allow him to reduce the price <strong>of</strong> labor.”<br />

The industries that have long working days employ weak unskilled workers, that receive<br />

lower wages. The industries that have strong skilled workers also have shorter working<br />

days. Conclusion; Weak unskilled workers earn less and work longer days, that strong<br />

skilled workers.<br />

Hans: Skills are one factor which can improve the workers’ bargaining position, but it is not the only one.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [596].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 261<br />

[593] Nstew: The longer work day is associated with a lower overall daily wage according<br />

to Marx because the longer you work the more you produce. Marx argues that in a capitalist<br />

society you are working for $10 an hour and the commodities you producing is $40 an hour.<br />

The more hours you work the smaller the portion you are getting paid in comparison to<br />

what you are producing. Although your wage does not go down from $10 an hour the ratio<br />

between what you have produced and what you are getting paid gets smaller and smaller<br />

with each hour you work. Plus the longer the work day the weaker the employees becomes<br />

and thus the lower the wage. The contrast to this is in an industry where the workers are<br />

stronger they are going to get paid more and their work day is going to be shorter.<br />

Hans: The weakness <strong>of</strong> the employees does not come from the long hours; but the long hours are a sign that the<br />

employees are already in a weak bargaining position.<br />

Next Message by Nstew is [594].<br />

[598] Srichardson: graded A Long hours. According to Marx p. 689/o: “Circumstances<br />

which allow the capitalist in the long run to prolong the work day also allows him. . . to<br />

reduce the price <strong>of</strong> labor therefore industries where the work day is long are industries in<br />

which the workers are weak.” Given this statement by Marx it would be expected that the<br />

daily wage would be lower in industries where the workers are weaker and stronger where<br />

the workers are united and stand strong. The workers that are weaker allow the capitalists to<br />

force long hours and low wages on them. While in an industry where workers unite and are<br />

strong (i.e. Unions) the wages tend to be higher the shorter and the working conditions all<br />

around more favorable.<br />

Message [598] referenced by [2009fa:764] and [2009fa:970]. First Message by Srichardson is [41].<br />

[607] Trailrunner: graded A Marx believes that long workdays and low wages are an<br />

empirical fact. He also states that “If workers are in a situation where they must agree to<br />

work longer hours, then they are probably also forced to accept lower wages.” This type <strong>of</strong><br />

situation would occur in an industry where workers are weak. Were these workers to be<br />

stronger, they might be able to work fewer hours. Thus, these weak workers are worse <strong>of</strong>f.<br />

It is also Marx theory that the daily wage should be the same regardless <strong>of</strong> the length <strong>of</strong><br />

the working day. When the working day ends up being longer, the workers lose all gains<br />

and if no compensatory factors enter, the price <strong>of</strong> labor is lowered, resulting in a negative<br />

relation due to the reproduction costs <strong>of</strong> the laborer.<br />

Hans: It is not Marx’s theory that the daily wage should be the same regardless <strong>of</strong> the length <strong>of</strong> the working day,<br />

but that the market forces are trying to move wages in that direction.<br />

Next Message by Trailrunner is [608].<br />

[616] Chris: A lack <strong>of</strong> health = A lack <strong>of</strong> money. Marx argues that a worker’s overall<br />

productivity will drop the longer they work in a day because <strong>of</strong> the fatigue, hunger, lack <strong>of</strong><br />

motivation, etc. that will occur. If workers are continually “breaking-down” health wise,<br />

then the capitalists do not see them as much <strong>of</strong> a threat. Therefore, the capitalists can pay<br />

these workers less without necessarily worrying about the workers leaving them to find new<br />

jobs. Hans explains a similar thought in [570] by saying that “those industries in which the<br />

working day is long are the industries in which the workers are weak. This weakness is likely<br />

to manifest itself not only in long hours but also otherwise. Therefore we can expect the daily<br />

wage to be lower than in those industries where the workers are stronger and therefore the<br />

working day is shorter, instead <strong>of</strong> being equal as the general law postulates.”


262 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

I also think that if the workers are being paid in piece-wage pay, then they will see a<br />

decrease in their overall daily wage if they work longer hours. If the workers are working<br />

long hours and are losing productivity due to fatigue, hunger, etc., then they will in essence<br />

be losing wages since they cannot create as much product. This is why it would be more<br />

beneficial to work less hours in a day and keep productivity high so that the workers will<br />

make more money for themselves and <strong>of</strong> course, the capitalists.<br />

Hans: The weakness <strong>of</strong> the workers is not necessarily physical weakness and it does not necessarily come from<br />

the longer workday. Marx’s argument was that the longer workday is a sign that the workers’ bargaining position<br />

is weak.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [655].<br />

[630] Alex: graded B The capitalist is the one who wants to get as much value from labor<br />

power at as little cost as possible. The capitalist uses several methods to increase hours<br />

worked by the laborer. One such method is piece wages. If you pay by piece and not by<br />

hour you fool the laborer into believing they can earn the same wage in as much time. But<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten workers work longer hours to get the same pay. Piece wage is the first way longer<br />

hours equal lower daily wages.<br />

The second way is built into the production process and overall effectiveness <strong>of</strong> the laborer.<br />

If a laborer can produce something in four hours, and that accounts for the pay <strong>of</strong> a<br />

24 hour day the capitalist is losing money. In other words four hours <strong>of</strong> works sustain the<br />

worker over a 24 hour period. The capitalist is losing money. The laborer should have to<br />

work longer to supply the money needed to support themselves the other hours <strong>of</strong> the day.<br />

The longer work hours and less pay.<br />

Hans: You are arguing that workers work longer hours for the same pay. But why would their total pay decrease<br />

if they work longer?<br />

Next Message by Alex is [633].<br />

[634] Rmuscolino: Marx argues that longer hours are associated with a lower overall<br />

daily wage by stating, “However, the extension <strong>of</strong> the period <strong>of</strong> labor produces in its turn a<br />

fall in the price <strong>of</strong> labor, and with this a fall in the daily or the weekly wage.” He’s saying<br />

that the fall in the price <strong>of</strong> labor will not only erase the gains <strong>of</strong> workers hoped for when they<br />

agreed to work longer hours, but in the end, the daily wage will be even lower than initially.<br />

If no compensatory factor enters, the ratio <strong>of</strong> the daily value <strong>of</strong> labor-power divided by the<br />

working day <strong>of</strong> a given number <strong>of</strong> hours determines the price <strong>of</strong> labor. It shows that the<br />

prolongation <strong>of</strong> the working day itself lowers the price <strong>of</strong> labor. Also with the fact that the<br />

working day is longer than normal to begin with, this adds as a force to generate the negative<br />

relation. According to the underlying laws <strong>of</strong> capitalist production, one should expect the<br />

daily wage to be independent <strong>of</strong> the length <strong>of</strong> the working day, since it is determined by the<br />

reproduction cost <strong>of</strong> the laborer and not by the amount <strong>of</strong> labor performed. One should also<br />

expect the length <strong>of</strong> the working day to be equal for all industries.<br />

Hans: As in [628], you stopped reading the Annotations before you fully understood them. I know the Annotations<br />

are sometimes difficult to understand, therefore I <strong>of</strong>ten give the argument in a more concise form in my submissions.<br />

My [570] is your friend.<br />

Message [634] referenced by [659]. Next Message by Rmuscolino is [659].<br />

[636] Matt: Daily Wage. People work to survive. In order to live in an ever growing<br />

capitalistic society we must all drink from the everlasting cup <strong>of</strong> labor. One might think we<br />

work to survive, but after a second glance it seems we survive to work. Our bodies have been


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 263<br />

trained to work harder and longer for many many years. Marx would say we have become<br />

drunk from the labor cup and are not seeing the truth about the labor we have produced. We<br />

work more and more hours just so we can partake <strong>of</strong> what the capitalist has produced. Marx<br />

says that the more hours the laborer works to survive the lower his wage will decrease. He<br />

says, “the daily or weekly wage depends on the quantity <strong>of</strong> labor expended.” So, as more<br />

labor hours are produced the more the wage price is driven down since the quantity is higher.<br />

Mark continues to say, “. . . the lower the price <strong>of</strong> labor, the greater must be the quantity <strong>of</strong><br />

labor, or the longer must be the working day, for the worker to secure even a miserable<br />

average wage.“ This thought process can be calculated by using Marx labor ratio <strong>of</strong>:<br />

Hourly wage or Labor Power / number <strong>of</strong> hours worked.<br />

This ratio shows us that Marx’s thinking is correct, that as the laborers hours worked<br />

increase the hourly wage will decrease. For example: If a worker needs to make $250 per<br />

day to pay his bills and to eat, then he will have to make $31.25 per hr if working 8 hours<br />

per day. Now if he works 11 hrs per day then he will only make $22.72 per hr. It is hard<br />

as Americans to think <strong>of</strong> it this way as all we see is dollar signs, but the capitalist would<br />

not have it any other way. We have been caught in a labor trap that we will never get out <strong>of</strong><br />

unless we make a stand against the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Matt is [678].<br />

[644] Inter: Lower overall daily wage. Unfortunately my exam answer was only partially<br />

correct. My exam answer captured Marx’s equation for the lowering <strong>of</strong> hourly wage<br />

by stating something similar this:<br />

The line A—B-C represents the total work hours in a day. If C is extended, this does not<br />

mean that the daily wage has increased, just the total number <strong>of</strong> hours worked per day. In<br />

essence, the longer work day, at the same daily wage means that hourly wage has decreased,<br />

but not the daily wage. Marx’s equation showed this.<br />

However, this only partially explains why the daily wage has decreased. This equation<br />

shows how the capitalist is able to control the hours worked per day by extending C. This<br />

extension in the work day has a long term effect <strong>of</strong> lowering the daily wage, because in order<br />

to support yourself, you have to be willing to work the longer hours. This ability to extend<br />

the work day, in the long run becomes the ability to lower the daily wage. This extends from<br />

the logic that the groups who accept longer work days are less organized and less combative<br />

because they have yielded to the capitalist’s demands to work longer hours. In the long run,<br />

they will yield to even more.<br />

Hans: Just to make sure we are on the same page: the longer work hours do not necessarily come from the capitalist<br />

suddenly extending the workday without more pay. They could come from the hourly wage being so low but so<br />

much overtime being <strong>of</strong>fered that everybody has to work overtime, etc. Still, your argument with the weakness <strong>of</strong><br />

the working class is correct.<br />

Next Message by Inter is [745].<br />

[669] Bmellor: Salary=getting screwed. Wages are used as an incentive to induce a<br />

worker to work. Marx’s formula is hourly wage = predetermined daily wage divided by<br />

hours worked.<br />

Example:


264 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

$100 daily wage/8 hours labor= $12.50 per hour The more hours you work the less you<br />

are getting paid per hour. Easily this concept is understood by someone on salary. If you<br />

get $40,000 per year and you work 50 hours per week you are getting paid less than the guy<br />

who gets $40,000 per year and only has to work 40 hours per week.<br />

Hans: You are getting paid less per hour but the total wage is the same, $40,000. Marx by contrast says that the<br />

total wage goes down as hours increase. Why? You also did not say why and how the daily wage is predetermined.<br />

Next Message by Bmellor is [767].<br />

[675] Jeremy: Marx argues that longer hours are associated with a lower overall daily<br />

wage for multiple reasons. First, and very importantly, Marx looks at wages on a daily<br />

standard, not hourly or weekly. This is paramount because the capitalist purchases the laborpower<br />

for the day. The laborer is only able to sell his labor-power on a temporary basis,<br />

otherwise if he were to sell it all, he would become more <strong>of</strong> a slave or a simple servant to the<br />

capitalist. Exploitation could happen at an exponential rate if this were the case. The agreed<br />

upon price will be in the capitalist’s favor because his “break even” point will be met before<br />

the end <strong>of</strong> the laborer’s day. The longer the laborer gives his labor-power beyond the “break<br />

even point” (necessary labor-power), the more surplus-value is derived and the capitalist is<br />

the recipient <strong>of</strong> it. This surplus-value is what capitalist desire. The more hours worked by the<br />

laborer can be thought <strong>of</strong> like this: 1 day = 8 hours for $10, if the laborer works a 1 day shift<br />

for $10, but gives 10 hours instead, he has reduced his own wages. Instead <strong>of</strong> $1.25 p/hr,<br />

he is now making $1.00 p/hr. A modern day example <strong>of</strong> this is the employment <strong>of</strong> salaried<br />

workers. They are guaranteed a payment, but their hours are considered variable. More<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten than not, the hours worked per day are more than that <strong>of</strong> an hourly worker. Therefore,<br />

they have reduced their wages by giving more <strong>of</strong> their labor-power.<br />

Hans: You have shown that a longer day is associated with a lower hourly wage, not that it is associated with a<br />

lower total wage. And you did not explain why Marx, as you said, “looks at wages on a daily standard.” And the<br />

break-even point is not the same as necessary labor, as I tried to explain in [515].<br />

Next Message by Jeremy is [827].<br />

[689] FacistFrank: Because the capitalist only wants to pay the worker a subsistence<br />

wage or a reproduction <strong>of</strong> labor power cost, so they can steal as much surplus labor value as<br />

possible. There is an inverse relationship between working hours and pay, just like there is a<br />

dialectic between the poles <strong>of</strong> exchange and relative forms, use value and real value, it is like<br />

the opposite poles <strong>of</strong> magnets. Of course Marx was writing in the 1800’s when the capitalist<br />

was at his absolute worst (in my opinion) and paying the worker a scant subsistence wage in<br />

order to maximize their pr<strong>of</strong>its. Today in my opinion the worker is still very exploited, he is<br />

still having the majority <strong>of</strong> his surplus labor stolen. But he does get paid for a small amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> his surplus labor today. I think this is because the power <strong>of</strong> the worker has increased over<br />

the last 150 years. Perhaps some morality has been injected into economics, i think Marx<br />

has a good deal to do with this, Unions are also more powerful than they were 150 years<br />

ago. The worker is more organized. Also i think that another part <strong>of</strong> it is the capitalist pays<br />

the worker just enough so he will not blatantly see he is being exploited, and rise up against<br />

the capitalist.<br />

Message [689] referenced by [720]. Next Message by FacistFrank is [771].<br />

[702] Sparky: [688:1] It is a generally known fact that the longer the working day in a<br />

branch <strong>of</strong> industry, the lower the wages are. In the annotations, Marx’s arguments about<br />

this particular question begin with the discussion <strong>of</strong> low hourly wages, which due to the low


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 265<br />

wages workers agree to work longer hours so that they can earn a liveable wage. But Marx<br />

continues by explain how the longer hours will actually decrease the wage which is found<br />

by taking the daily value <strong>of</strong> labor power and dividing it by the working days given hours.<br />

here is just a little math – say you work just 2 hours a day, produce 10 units and get paid<br />

1 dollar an hour 10/5=2 5/2=2.5 2.5 is how much you are basically paid to produce. Now try<br />

3 hours a day producing 15 units, and still getting 1 dollar an hour 15/3=5 5/3= 1.66 1.66 is<br />

how much you are basically getting paid to produce<br />

Hans: In this example you are not even reducing the hourly wage. Marx not only says that the hourly wage is<br />

reduced, but that it is reduced more than the day is lengthened, so that the total daily wage income declines. Why?<br />

Next Message by Sparky is [705].<br />

[707] Gerund: Marx argued that longer hours are associated with an overall lower daily<br />

wage due to the balance <strong>of</strong> power between capitalists and workers. In industries where<br />

capitalists can require longer hours, they would also have the power to extort more surplusvalue<br />

by paying lower wages. When workers upset this power structure and gain the upper<br />

hand, they get higher wages and shorter days, leaving the capitalists with less surplus value<br />

and smaller pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Hans: Very good.<br />

Next Message by Gerund is [815].<br />

[710] Raynold: Marx argues that longer hours are associated with longer overall daily<br />

wage because it depends on the laborer’s reproduction cost. A weak worker can only do so<br />

much and by its production determines its wage. Although it is an empirical fact, the work<br />

wages should remain the same whether it is a long or short work day. Strong workers get<br />

higher wages because <strong>of</strong> their ability to be productive. Therefore, since they can produce<br />

more than the weak worker, they can afford to take shorter work days but have higher wages.<br />

Weak laborers have to prolong their work day because capitalists have the right to lower<br />

wages due to reproduction cost.<br />

Hans: You are saying two contradictory things at the same time:<br />

(a) wages depend on the worker’s reproduction cost.<br />

(b) wages depend on the performance <strong>of</strong> the worker.<br />

In Marx’s theory, (b) is wrong.<br />

Next Message by Raynold is [711].<br />

[713] JPeel: graded A– Marx argues that longer hours are associated with a lower overall<br />

daily wage because according to the laws <strong>of</strong> capital production the daily wage is independent<br />

<strong>of</strong> the length <strong>of</strong> the working day. The length <strong>of</strong> the working day is determined by the reproduction<br />

cost <strong>of</strong> the laborer and not by the amount <strong>of</strong> the labor performed. The length <strong>of</strong> a<br />

working day is equal for all industries which is longer than normal. Many workers are stuck<br />

in the situation where they have to agree to work longer hours where they will be forced to<br />

accept lower overall wages.<br />

Hans: The way you write it I am not sure if you really understood Marx’s argument.<br />

Next Message by JPeel is [714].<br />

[716] Carterryan: The Price <strong>of</strong> Labor is Right!!!! The reason for longer hours resulting<br />

in a lower overall wage is that the laborer in the first part, are working more hours and in<br />

turn creating more supply <strong>of</strong> labor. If a man does one and a half or two times as much as one<br />

man the output <strong>of</strong> that one man has increased, but the labor power is the same. This in turn


266 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

brings down the price <strong>of</strong> labor and also force up work hours. It really does create a bigger<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it for the capitalist but not for the worker.<br />

Next Message by Carterryan is [717].<br />

[719] Andy: In Class Response<br />

Marx argues that longer hours lead to lower overall daily wage because he believes that<br />

people need to have sleep time, social time, and extra free time to keep them happy. I believe<br />

that Marx really gets it here because he understands the people. He understands that if you<br />

work people too much you are not going to make more, but make less because you are paying<br />

them their hours but losing production because <strong>of</strong> fatigue. He understands that people need<br />

their battery recharged in order to do the best possible work they can.<br />

Out <strong>of</strong> Class Response<br />

Marx considered it an empirical fact that long workdays are associated with low wages.<br />

Industries in which working day is long are industries in which workers are weak. Therefore<br />

the daily wage is lower.<br />

Next Message by Andy is [775].<br />

[723] Tim: graded A Marx explains that in industries where the work days are longer<br />

there is a tendency for the wage to be low because those who are in a situation where they<br />

must agree to work long hours are most likely forced to accept lower wages for the work that<br />

they perform. Marx gives an example where there is surplus labor available to the market<br />

and the workers become competitors to each other in order to keep their jobs. Along with<br />

the competition that the workers bring into the job market they also bring the what almost<br />

always comes with competition, lower prices (wages). The lower wages then compel the<br />

workers to work longer hours in order to be able to put food on the table. The other example<br />

that Marx gives is that <strong>of</strong> surplus commodities, which mean lower prices that are then set<br />

as a market standard. Once the market standard price is set then the workers are forced to<br />

keep producing the same products at the same low wage so the capitalist is able to make his<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Next Message by Tim is [785].<br />

[731] Wade: Marx argues that longer hours = a lower overall daily wage. “However the<br />

extension <strong>of</strong> the period <strong>of</strong> labor produces in its turn a fall in the price <strong>of</strong> labor, and with<br />

this a fall in the daily or the weekly wage.” Marx shows us here that a fall in the price<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor lowers the amount <strong>of</strong> gains that the worker was hoping for when they agreed to<br />

work longer hours and in the end the daily wage will even be lower than the initial wage.<br />

Hans also gives us a formula to show us how this works, daily value <strong>of</strong> labor-power divided<br />

by working day <strong>of</strong> a given number <strong>of</strong> hours, by prolonging the work day lowers the price<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor. “By working more, the worker increases the supply <strong>of</strong> labor, ie., competes with<br />

himself or herself.” Also if the factory workers refuse to work longer hours they can even<br />

lose their job! “For instance, if a factory worker refuses to work the long hours which are<br />

customary, he would very shortly be replaced by somebody who would work any length <strong>of</strong><br />

time, and thus be thrown out <strong>of</strong> employment.” These examples from Marx show us that he<br />

definitely argues that the longer the hours the lower the daily wage.<br />

Hans: After your first Marx quote you write “Marx shows” although in that passage Marx does not show anything.<br />

It makes a claim that is then substantiated later in the text. The laborer competing with himself is one argument<br />

Marx gives. But there another, in my view more convincing argument which you are not bringing.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 267<br />

Next Message by Wade is [732].<br />

[738] Aaron: Marx starts his argument a little backwards in my opinion. He does not<br />

argue that the lower hourly wage is a result from actually working a longer day, but he<br />

argues that as wages go down in the market place, a laborer must work more hours to make<br />

up for the lower wage, thus creating a longer working day. He argues that the low level<br />

<strong>of</strong> wages is a stimulus for causing the average worker’s daily hours. This cause and effect<br />

relationship shows that Marx views the market from the laborer’s perspective. With the price<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor going down, the quantity <strong>of</strong> labor must rise in order to produce goods.<br />

Hans: Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> wages is backwards in the following way: he does not start with the hourly wage as<br />

the basic building block determined by fundamental economic forces, and derives from this the daily wage by<br />

multiplying the hourly wage by the number <strong>of</strong> hours worked. Instead Marx says the fundamental economic forces<br />

fix the daily wage, not the hourly wages: the daily reproduction costs <strong>of</strong> the laborer (which is the reproduction cost<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity labor-power he is selling) is the fundamental economic given. From this Marx derives the hourly<br />

wages by dividing the daily wages by the length <strong>of</strong> the working-day. This length is not determined by economic<br />

forces but by the class struggle between workers and capitalists. Therefore there is a negative correlation between<br />

wages and length <strong>of</strong> the workday.<br />

The individual worker naively thinks that he is selling labor, not labor-power, therefore he thinks that the hourly<br />

wage, not the daily wage, is given by economic fundamentals. And since he sees a low hourly wage, the only way<br />

for him to make ends meet is to work long hours. He does not see that he would have the alternative <strong>of</strong> fighting for<br />

higher wages and working shorter hours.<br />

All this only explains why a longer workday results in lower hourly wages. But Marx says more than this: he<br />

says a longer workday even results in lower daily wages. Why this would be the case is not explained by the above<br />

argument.<br />

Next Message by Aaron is [739].<br />

Question 669 is 659 in 2007fa:<br />

Question 669 Why are wages low in industries where the working-day is long?<br />

[559] Allen: Low wages, Long hours. The wages are low because there is usually an<br />

excess supply <strong>of</strong> labor in the labor market. As stated in the book by Marx, if one person does<br />

the work <strong>of</strong> more than one person, the supply <strong>of</strong> labor increases even though the supply <strong>of</strong><br />

labor-power on the market remains the same. Since each worker does more work the supply<br />

<strong>of</strong> labor increases, which causes more competition in the labor market. This is the cause<br />

that lets capitalists be able to lower the price <strong>of</strong> labor and be able to force up the hours <strong>of</strong><br />

work, because if a worker refuses to work the long hours he could be easily replaced by the<br />

increased supply <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Message [559] referenced by [570] and [2008fa:907]. Next Message by Allen is [733].<br />

Question 671 is 683 in 2007SP, 661 in 2007fa, 675 in 2008fa, 706 in 2009fa, 770 in<br />

2010fa, 789 in 2011fa, 819 in 2012fa, and 770 in Answer:<br />

Question 671 What is the difference between surplus labor time and overtime?<br />

[563] Slash: Surplus labor, a normal part <strong>of</strong> every work day. When I go to work<br />

everyday I produce an average <strong>of</strong> 60 dollars <strong>of</strong> product for my company an hour, but I only<br />

receive 10 dollars an hour. The company I work for then has a surplus <strong>of</strong> money after 10<br />

minutes <strong>of</strong> my labor every hour I work. In this capitalistic society I feel that I have been<br />

paid a wage, and that there is no surplus labor because I received a wage. Marx would say<br />

that every hour produces a value <strong>of</strong> 60 dollars this means the capitalist pays 10 dollars <strong>of</strong>


268 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

it and the remaining 50 dollars is surplus labor. Overtime is then simply an extension this<br />

situation. Surplus labor is therefor a normal part <strong>of</strong> every work day, and me receiving an<br />

extra 5 dollars an hour to my wage in an overtime situation does not change the fact there is<br />

surplus labor going on.<br />

Hans: Yes. The overtime hour also produces a value <strong>of</strong> $60, therefore it produces $45 instead <strong>of</strong> $50 surplus-value<br />

for the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [564].<br />

Question 674 is 678 in 2008fa and 797 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 674 How does the coexistence <strong>of</strong> time-wages and piece-wages enable the capitalist<br />

to cheat?<br />

[558] Mick: graded B The further abstraction <strong>of</strong> exploitation through over-working.<br />

The capitalist disguises, or in his terms creates an incentive to be more productive, because<br />

these incentives will increase his marginal pr<strong>of</strong>it per employee, thus decreasing the proportional<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> money paid out per piece <strong>of</strong> labor. To illustrate the example to which this<br />

question refers to in an algebraic inequality will further demonstrate how the coexistence <strong>of</strong><br />

time and piece wages create an opportunity for additional exploitation/pr<strong>of</strong>it. let x= the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> hours worked. 200(x), where x is equal to 1/2 an hour yields 100 hours <strong>of</strong> wages–and<br />

in this example this amount <strong>of</strong> labor is equal to the labor <strong>of</strong> one employee who labors for 50<br />

hours paid in piece wages. The capitalist is getting more productivity from overworking one<br />

employee. As a matter <strong>of</strong> fact, if this employee were to receive standard overtime wages at<br />

time and a half for exceeding a 40 hour workweek, it would still be in the capitalist’s best<br />

interest to overwork him. This overworking decreases the amount <strong>of</strong> time spent to produce,<br />

thus creating a vacancy that would provide additional opportunities to exploit others in its<br />

place.<br />

Also, one can only imagine the exponential growth <strong>of</strong> the adverse externalities that materialize<br />

as a result <strong>of</strong> this sort <strong>of</strong> malicious abasement.<br />

Message [558] referenced by [568]. Next Message by Mick is [560].<br />

[568] Hans: Piece wages and time wages in the same factory. Marx’s example in<br />

footnote 47 to 692:4/o is a little tricky and unusual for modern times. I think the following<br />

was going on:<br />

The time is 1860 and the usual workweek is 60 hours. A certain factory has 400 workers.<br />

200 are paid piece-wage, and the others are paid what Marx calls time wage, it is a flat rate<br />

per day, with no overtime. The piece wage workers work twice as hard as the time wage<br />

workers, and since they want to maximize their wage income, they work 1/2 hour overtime<br />

every day, 10 1/2 hours instead <strong>of</strong> 10 hours, Monday through Saturday. The production<br />

process is such that the time wage workers must also stay this half hour every day, but they<br />

do not get any extra pay for it. This is how the capitalists cheat: the time wage workers<br />

should be allowed to go home after 10 hours, but since they work together with the piece<br />

wage workers and the piece wage workers are willing to stay longer, the time wage workers<br />

also have to stay longer.<br />

The computation shows how much the capitalist gains from this. In half an hour, 200 time<br />

wage workers perform together 100 working hours, which is as much as 50 hours by a piece


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 269<br />

wage worker, or 5/6th <strong>of</strong> the weekly labor <strong>of</strong> a piece wage worker. This is the extra labor<br />

which the capitalist gets every day without having to pay for it: it is almost a full week’s<br />

labor <strong>of</strong> one piece wage worker.<br />

If my interpretation <strong>of</strong> the example is correct, then Mick’s remark in [558] that “the<br />

capitalist is getting more productivity from overworking one employee” is mistaken. Instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> overworking one employee, the capitalists make 200 time wage workers work a little more<br />

each day, 5 percent more than their usual workday, without paying them. This adds up.<br />

Message [568] referenced by [2008fa:879]. Next Message by Hans is [570].<br />

Question 677 is 681 in 2008fa, 712 in 2009fa, 776 in 2010fa, and 831 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 677 Explain how piece wages can become a “most fertile source for wage theft<br />

and capitalist cheating.”<br />

[544] Goethe: graded A I owe my soul to the company store. “You load 16 tons and<br />

whaddaya get??<br />

another day older and deeper in dept<br />

Saint Peter don’tcha call me ’Cause-<br />

I can’t go...I owe my soul to the Company Store”<br />

(16 Tons, Merle Travis 1946)<br />

The preceding is from a song about coal miners, it is reminiscent <strong>of</strong> the subject at hand,<br />

and I think Marx would have enjoyed it.<br />

Coal mining is a great example <strong>of</strong> how piece wages can become a “fertile source for wage<br />

theft and capitalist cheating.”<br />

In the early 1900s most miners were paid piece wages according to the amounts <strong>of</strong> coal<br />

they produced or “picked”. (piece wages) A logical assumption would be when production<br />

was low, the pay was also proportionately low, hence a worker will need to be productive in<br />

order to receive a wage, etc...<br />

The coal mining companies were the masters <strong>of</strong> wage theft and worker exploitation, it<br />

is slavery. The way they achieved this was simple; they were the owners <strong>of</strong> everything.<br />

Miners lived in company owned housing, bought goods from company owned stores, and<br />

were transported to the area by company owned railways. Workers were given credit at the<br />

company owned stores, and for company owned housing, if workers did not produce; the<br />

consequence could be disastrous. This ownership gave the mining companies a monopoly<br />

on the lives <strong>of</strong> their workers, which made them slaves to the company.<br />

Going back to the quote; Travis is telling us that it does not matter how much is produced,<br />

it is still not enough, and he will go to the grave owing the company.<br />

Given that the owners <strong>of</strong> production are also the owners <strong>of</strong> workers’ necessities, it gives<br />

great opportunity for wage theft and cheating. The supervisors are the judges <strong>of</strong> how much a<br />

worker produces. They calibrate the scales used to measure a workers pile <strong>of</strong> coal, it could be<br />

their advantage to underweigh this production. By doing this the capitalist robs the worker<br />

<strong>of</strong> his wages.


270 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

This all ended when the miners became organized, or at least it was less apparent.<br />

Conclusion: When a worker accepts pay based on the amount <strong>of</strong> pieces he produces, he<br />

places himself at the mercy <strong>of</strong> the capitalist owner. The owner <strong>of</strong> production is the evaluator<br />

<strong>of</strong> the quality and quantity <strong>of</strong> production received. This gives the capitalist opportunity to<br />

steal wages from the worker.<br />

Message [544] referenced by [549], [2008fa:888], and [2009fa:790]. Next Message by Goethe is [591].<br />

[549] Hans: Slavery Creeping into the Wage Labor Relation on Different Fronts.<br />

Goethe [544] correctly identifies the connection between piece wages and wage theft: Piece<br />

wages encourage wage theft because the capitalist is the one who measures the output.<br />

Goethe also mentions company stores and indebtedness <strong>of</strong> the workers. They are not<br />

associated with the piece wage form specifically, but their source lies in the fact that wages<br />

are paid after the labor is performed. In the meanwhile, the worker may need an advance on<br />

his wages, which puts him into debt, or he has to buy at the company store at inflated prices,<br />

because the company store gives him credit against his upcoming wages.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [565].<br />

[560] Mick: graded A The subjective/exploitive properties <strong>of</strong> quality. Quality control,<br />

and the subjective nature <strong>of</strong> quality assessment create new ways to milk the proletariat. By<br />

using quantitative comparatives, and relative terms as criteria for what is or is not acceptable,<br />

the capitalist is able to bend his quality definition to fit his self interest, proving that BS is a<br />

fertile source for both capitalists and farmers alike. Just like in baseball, anything close to a<br />

tie in terms <strong>of</strong> unacceptable quality will always go to the capitalist since he is his own umpire.<br />

Moreover, he can discreetly cinch up his evolving standards <strong>of</strong> what ‘good average’ quality<br />

is over time to strangle his employees, thereby simultaneously mitigating his employees’<br />

financial entitlements and enhancing his personal bank account.<br />

Hans: Oh I get it. BS comes from agriculture, but it can also be used by the capitalists.<br />

Message [560] referenced by [2010fa:809]. Next Message by Mick is [583].<br />

Question 680 is 691 in 2007SP, 670 in 2007fa, 779 in 2010fa, and 834 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 680 Which advantages does the form <strong>of</strong> piece-wages have for the capitalists?<br />

What does it mean for the relation between the workers?<br />

[541] Srichardson: graded A getting paid by how much you produce. When you first<br />

think <strong>of</strong> piece-wages it appears that this form <strong>of</strong> wages gives more control to the workers<br />

than the other form <strong>of</strong> wage that we have studied. It appears this way because the more the<br />

worker produces the more the worker gets paid.<br />

In reality this is not true <strong>of</strong> piece-wages. Although it may seem like it gives more power<br />

to the worker, it keeps the power in the hands <strong>of</strong> the capitalist and even becomes more<br />

beneficial to the capitalist. When there is a system <strong>of</strong> piece-wage the worker feels that he<br />

must work harder and produce more in order to make more money. This makes a greater<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> goods produced in an hour. When the worker works harder the capitalist also<br />

makes more money even though he is not putting in any <strong>of</strong> his labor.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the big advantages <strong>of</strong> piece-wages for the capitalist is that workers begin to see the<br />

other co-workers as competition. The workers then start to work against each other trying to<br />

work the hardest and longest. This makes it that much harder for workers to band together


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 271<br />

and demand fair treatment. It is a way for the capitalist to in a way divide and conquer the<br />

workers.<br />

Another advantage that piece-wages have for the capitalist is that the capitalist only has<br />

to pay the worker when they are directly in the production process. If the worker is slow the<br />

capitalist does not pay until the piece is finished. If the worker complains about the wage<br />

they receive the capitalist can say they should just produce more.<br />

When you look at the big picture piece-wages are great for the capitalist it creates pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

by cutting cost. Piece-wages put the worker at a disadvantage by making the workers work<br />

a lot to produce the wage that is necessary for them, while putting workers at competition<br />

with each other.<br />

Message [541] referenced by [547] and [554]. Next Message by Srichardson is [597].<br />

[547] Alex: graded A Piece-Wages. Srichardson brings up some very interesting discussion<br />

points [541] while talking about piece-wages and their benefits to the capitalist.<br />

However, this entry misses some crucial points <strong>of</strong> the piece-wage process while highlighting<br />

non-existent parameters. For instance, Srichardson highlights the competition that arises<br />

from piece-wages. Why would there be competition? If there were it would certainly keep<br />

the worker in line. However, such a statement makes the product sound limited, as though<br />

the workers are in a race.<br />

The actuality is that piece-wage is a very complex alienation <strong>of</strong> the worker from their<br />

product. While at the same time it allows the capitalist to lower wages based on output and<br />

not on time spent. The capitalist can do this slowly over time in a very systematic fashion.<br />

Piece-wage is meant to change the perspective <strong>of</strong> the worker. It shifts their thinking and<br />

mannerisms into a manner that is more easily manipulated by the capitalist while the worker<br />

feels they are coming out on top. As mentioned this can be a questionable method, which<br />

has not always been successful.<br />

This section does highlight the power <strong>of</strong> the worker when united. This is one <strong>of</strong> Marx’s<br />

most important results, the union and united workers. It is important to factor in that workers<br />

can fight against these initiatives and methods if they are united.<br />

Hans: If Srichardson and Marx say that piece wages separate the workers and foster competition, while time<br />

wages unite the workers, then this is not a criticism or praise <strong>of</strong> the workers. It merely characterizes the objective<br />

conditions in which the workers are placed. With piece wages, the capitalist can pretend the wage is so low because<br />

the employee does not work hard enough, and he can probably point to some other over-eager employee to make his<br />

point. Even if the employees do not feel competitive or do not want to compete, they are still placed in a situation<br />

where the achievement <strong>of</strong> one harms the other. In time wages, the exact opposite can happen. One employee<br />

is a slacker, the others have to work harder because <strong>of</strong> this, but they all get the same wage. These are different<br />

conditions. What the employees make out <strong>of</strong> these conditions, is another matter.<br />

Message [547] referenced by [551]. Next Message by Alex is [629].<br />

Question 682 is 694 in 2007SP, 673 in 2007fa, and 781 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 682 Why is piece wage the wage form most appropriate for capitalism?<br />

[528] Sparky: Piece Wages. Piece wage is the most appropriate form <strong>of</strong> wage for the<br />

capitalist system because it allows the capitalist to diminish the price paid per good, allows<br />

for a critical amount <strong>of</strong> quality control, as well as keeps workers at odds with each other.


272 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

By creating a system <strong>of</strong> which the worker gets paid per piece rather than by time – the<br />

worker will push himself harder to produce more, in order to receive more on his pay check.<br />

While it certainly does raise his paycheck, it is at the expense <strong>of</strong> lowering the price per piece!<br />

Since more time is spent producing goods – using more labor-power – it reduces the price<br />

<strong>of</strong> the labor.<br />

Quality control is now solely in the hands <strong>of</strong> the capitalist, who can on the spot turn a<br />

worker away empty handed for producing a product that is not up to their standards, even<br />

though they have spent time producing the good. Whereas in a time wage situation the<br />

worker would have been paid for the time it took to create the good.<br />

As for the workers, who under a time-wage situation would be paid the same for the same<br />

type <strong>of</strong> work that was done, which in turn uniting them on that level at the least. The piece<br />

wage allows for individuals to earn different wages due to physical or mental properties<br />

contained by some and not the others, which helps define how much an individual could<br />

produce in a day. This situation would let resentment between workers grow among them<br />

and keep frustrations away from the capitalist.<br />

Message [528] referenced by [533], [685], and [2010fa:799]. Next Message by Sparky is [700].<br />

[533] Chris: unaware <strong>of</strong> exploitation. Sparky brought up a lot <strong>of</strong> very valid and informative<br />

points in [528] when responding to the point that piece wage seems to be the most<br />

appropriate wage form for a capitalistic society. One <strong>of</strong> these points that kind <strong>of</strong> summarizes<br />

Sparky’s piece in my opinion was that “by creating a system <strong>of</strong> which the worker gets paid<br />

per piece rather than by time – the worker will push himself harder to produce more, in order<br />

to receive more on his pay check.” I could not agree more with this line, however, after<br />

reading the weekly annotations I think there is more to bring up to the topic.<br />

After reading the annotations, I realized even more that the average, everyday worker is<br />

sadly unaware <strong>of</strong> the exploitation brought on by the capitalists in control. I recently watched<br />

a documentary that mentioned the ever-growing gap <strong>of</strong> the poor and rich in the United States<br />

and not one <strong>of</strong> the poorer folk mentioned that their bosses were exploiting them. They were<br />

more concerned with feeding their children, paying for health care, and in all reality; being<br />

able to live another day. This goes back to piece wage pay because the poorer folk are sick<br />

and tired <strong>of</strong> just trying to live for one more day. They want to look ahead; one month, 1 year,<br />

and 10+ years down their lives. So the second the capitalist tells them that the harder they<br />

work (i.e. the more pieces <strong>of</strong> fabric a worker creates) the more they will get paid, the worker<br />

will work harder so that they can have more money to fund their future.<br />

Of course, the capitalist is not giving the worker more money without paying him or<br />

herself first. We have learned that there is a gap <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its to be made for the capitalist with<br />

each piece <strong>of</strong> fabric, for instance, created. The more fabric created, the more money is placed<br />

in the coat pockets <strong>of</strong> the capitalist and likewise for the worker. However, only a fraction is<br />

paid to the worker and once again, they are being exploited. But the worker is unaware <strong>of</strong><br />

this exploitation. The average, every-day poor worker only sees the increase <strong>of</strong> pay on their<br />

paycheck due to the increase <strong>of</strong> fabric created by them. This helps them to buy a few more<br />

goods at the grocery store or possibly stash a little money away in savings for future use.<br />

So in the end, piece wages cause the worker to be happy because they are unaware <strong>of</strong> the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 273<br />

exploitation and can think in terms <strong>of</strong> the future, and <strong>of</strong> course the capitalist is happy with<br />

excess pr<strong>of</strong>its in their now, new coatpockets.<br />

Hans: Chris asked me why his cross reference to Sparky did not give him credit for feedback to peer submissions.<br />

My answer: a cross reference to Sparky earns feedback credit for Chris if reading Chris’s comment would have<br />

enabled Sparky to make his own submission better, or would have helped the reader <strong>of</strong> the archives to understand<br />

Sparky’s submission better. I don’t think they would, for two reasons:<br />

(a) Sparky gave three very different reasons why piece wages are good for capitalism: they intensify labor, they<br />

have built-in quality control, and they foster disunity between workers. Chris only referred to the first point and<br />

said that this first point summarized Sparky’s piece. To me this indicates that Chris didn’t read Sparky’s piece very<br />

carefully, and this remark is also not helpful for the readers <strong>of</strong> Sparky’s contribution.<br />

(b) Chris’s own addition to Sparky’s first point is that the worker, in his reaction to the piece-wage incentives, is<br />

unaware <strong>of</strong> his own exploitation. Although I consider this an important point in general, Chris does not tell Sparky<br />

why he should have raised this point in his own answer, why his answer is somehow deficient for not saying this.<br />

I’m not surprised because I don’t think it is. Chris just took <strong>of</strong>f from Sparky’s submission to say his own thing. It<br />

is good and necessary to build on the submissions <strong>of</strong> others, but this alone is not yet the kind <strong>of</strong> detailed feedback I<br />

require from everyone three times per Semester.<br />

Message [533] referenced by [692]. Next Message by Chris is [605].<br />

[554] Wade: Piece-wage. Piece wage is the most appropriate for capitalism because the<br />

workers will only be paid for the amount <strong>of</strong> value that they create for capitalist. If the workers<br />

want to be paid more they need to produce more! “So much weight <strong>of</strong> cotton is delivered to<br />

him (the spinner) and he has to return by a certain time, in lieu <strong>of</strong> it, a given weight <strong>of</strong> twist<br />

or yarn, <strong>of</strong> a certain degree <strong>of</strong> fineness, and he is paid so much per pound for all that he so<br />

returns. If his work is defective in quality, the penalty falls on him.” The capitalist are able<br />

to negotiate with the workers, if you want more produce more, and if the worker wants more<br />

he will produce more, and by producing more, the capitalist is gaining more. The piecewage<br />

form also keeps workers more competitive with each other and focused on producing<br />

as much as they can, which reduces the possibilites <strong>of</strong> the workers banding together and<br />

rebelling against their capitalist bosses.<br />

Hans: Everything you said, except the quote about the cotton, was said before you by Srichardson [541], even the<br />

typo <strong>of</strong> writing “ban together” instead <strong>of</strong> “band together” (which I fixed in the archives.)<br />

Message [554] referenced by [2008fa:1150]. Next Message by Wade is [589].<br />

[677] PrivateProperty: Piece Wage. Piece wage is the wage form most appropriate for<br />

capitalism because it motivates the worker to maximize his productivity, producing relative<br />

surplus value for the capitalist.<br />

Workers on a piece wage will want to maximize their production in order to see an increase<br />

in pay. This has the contradictory effect <strong>of</strong> lowering wages, as the socially necessary<br />

labor time for producing a good is reduced. As wages decrease, piece wage workers will respond<br />

by increasing their productivity even more in order to maintain their previous income,<br />

leading to a downward spiral.<br />

All <strong>of</strong> this activity increases relative surplus value for the capitalist.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [793].<br />

[685] Dyoung: Marx says “that the piece-wage is nothing but a transmuted form <strong>of</strong> the<br />

time-wage just as the time-wage is a transmuted form <strong>of</strong> the value or price <strong>of</strong> labor-power.”<br />

It is the most appropriate form <strong>of</strong> wage because if a worker can make a better income due to<br />

a piece wages, then they will be better <strong>of</strong>f and this would help the piece rate to become lower<br />

in the long run. Capitalists tend to pay workers their wages after the labor is performed not


274 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

as it is performed causing some laborers to fall into debt and not be able to pay for their<br />

cost <strong>of</strong> living. The capitalist seem to always be looking out for themselves and how they are<br />

getting ahead in the market. Hans makes a great point that every experienced worker knows<br />

that this happens and this is exactly why Marx has this theory, so according to the total daily<br />

or weekly wage really depends on the worker’s cost <strong>of</strong> living and not how much the worker<br />

works. So by having a a piece-wage for the workers, they are better <strong>of</strong>f and are better able<br />

to stay out <strong>of</strong> debt because they are able to pay for their cost <strong>of</strong> living, which the capitalist is<br />

not helping accomplish this. It is very important to have theories like a piece-wage to help<br />

the economy grow.<br />

Hans: This is a smorgasboard <strong>of</strong> things you learned in this class, but does not explain why piece wages are so good<br />

for the capitalists. Look at Sparky’s [528].<br />

Next Message by Dyoung is [687].<br />

[730] Mick: graded A– Piece wages eliminate the pressure to produce at the same cooperative<br />

pace as fellow laborers. This is used as a tool <strong>of</strong> exploitation by capitalists. By using<br />

piece instead <strong>of</strong> time wages, he is able to use the most productive worker’s performance as a<br />

standard to earn the same wages he would pay to any employee compensated through time<br />

wages. This way the comparatively less efficient employees are forced to work longer hours<br />

to earn the same wage. This way the capitalist is able to increase the exploitation <strong>of</strong> his<br />

employees by reducing the amount the less efficient employees are paid per any given unit<br />

<strong>of</strong> time. This increased pr<strong>of</strong>it may be reinvested in technologies such as a faster conveyor<br />

belt, which would allow the capitalist to further reduce the piece wage while increasing the<br />

intensity <strong>of</strong> work/productive power <strong>of</strong> machinery. The increased surplus value which result<br />

from piece wages also increase the likelihood that a worker will be replaced, or required to<br />

work more intensively, because they may be used to purchase newer technologies. Piece<br />

wages only benefit the capitalist, and cause severe distress on workers. One <strong>of</strong> many adverse<br />

externalities <strong>of</strong> piece wages is that it smites the cooperative environment enjoyed by<br />

employees who are employed through time wages.<br />

Hans: Piece wages also make it easier, or even unnecessary, to supervise the worker.<br />

Next Message by Mick is [903].<br />

[736] Alcameron: The piece wage form is the most appropriate for capitalism because it<br />

encourages greater production by intensifying labor. In the piece wage system the worker<br />

is paid based on their prodution which may create some competition and disunity between<br />

workers. Each hour <strong>of</strong> work is more effective for the capitalist when this is the case. In<br />

capitalism ultimately a worker is selling his labor so if he isn’t actually working he shouldn’t<br />

be paid for that. When a worker sells his labor and is productive creating a labor-surplus then<br />

he deserves his wage. The piece wage form ultimately creates the largest labor-surplus.<br />

Next Message by Alcameron is [778].<br />

[824] Bar: content A late penalty 9% Piece wage is the most appropriate form for capitalism<br />

because piece wage is the most advantageous for the capitalist. It motivates the laborer<br />

to produce better and more <strong>of</strong> a commodity increasing surplus, while at the same time creating<br />

higher competition between the labor force. This creates a culture where very little labor<br />

organisation can take place because the capitalist has divided the labor force. Furthermore,<br />

when paid by piece the capitalist has less risk <strong>of</strong> there being money paid for less desirable<br />

workers and workers who get sick or disabled, he is only paying for the final product not the<br />

intermediate.


Next Message by Bar is [825].<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 275<br />

Question 683 is 695 in 2007SP, 674 in 2007fa, 687 in 2008fa, 718 in 2009fa, and 807 in<br />

2011fa:<br />

Question 683 How do piece-wages change if productivity rises?<br />

[545] Scott: Same money more work. Instead <strong>of</strong> paying the worker for the time and<br />

labor he puts into a project, some capitalists use what is called piece-wages. Piece-wages<br />

pay the worker by the amount <strong>of</strong> pieces produced, their purpose is to press out as much labor<br />

as possible from the worker. The worker is paid more for his labor when he produces more<br />

pieces. The underlying mathematical principle is if the wages are lowered, then the workers<br />

have to work harder and longer to produce the amount <strong>of</strong> pieces to get the same amount <strong>of</strong><br />

money. Because <strong>of</strong> this productivity goes up and the wages are lowered. It is obvious that<br />

workers would not like this type <strong>of</strong> payment because while they are making more pieces<br />

they are making the same or less money, while the price the capitalist is charging for the<br />

good has not decreased. Now it is apparent that the capitalists are pr<strong>of</strong>iting while the laborer<br />

is getting paid the same or less.<br />

Message [545] referenced by [565]. Next Message by Scott is [546].<br />

[552] SnatchimusMaximus: graded A+ Salary <strong>of</strong>fer, or <strong>of</strong>fer for the taking? It seems<br />

that a loophole exists for the capitalist in all forms <strong>of</strong> wage, whether hourly wage, piece<br />

wage, or salary. The capitalist can avoid overtime pay and full-time benefits for the hourly<br />

worker simply by hiring more workers. Piece wages may be kept artificially low to encourage<br />

workers to produce finished pieces in a frantic hurry to earn a living. Meanwhile, the<br />

most prestigious <strong>of</strong> all pay...The Salary, can prove exploitive because salaries are typically<br />

negotiated independent <strong>of</strong> hours expected to work. In all three cases the workers’ checks are<br />

kept low, the capitalists’ balance sheet grows, and the worker runs to and fro.<br />

Since we are talking about checks and balances, the system as it stands needs lots <strong>of</strong><br />

them. Hourly workers must be supervised to dissuade shirking, quality control must be<br />

implemented to regulate piece wage workers, and salary workers must be given deadlines to<br />

encourage performance.<br />

All the wasted resources that go in to administering the checks and balances are clearly<br />

indicative <strong>of</strong> a failed system. It seems that only broken systems need checks and balances.<br />

But what is the solution or is there a solution at all? –Joint ownership.<br />

Hans: The first loophole, the manipulation <strong>of</strong> the number <strong>of</strong> workers hired in order to keep wages low, can take two<br />

forms. Either the hiring <strong>of</strong> more part-time workers instead <strong>of</strong> fewer full-time workers to save benefits, or having a<br />

full-time worker work lots <strong>of</strong> overtime so that you don’t have to hire another worker with the associated taxes and<br />

benefits.<br />

Your double use <strong>of</strong> the term “checks and balances” is very funny, but the original version <strong>of</strong> your answer brought<br />

the conclusion that only broken systems need checks and balances too early, at a point where the reader cannot yet<br />

understand it. The first sentence <strong>of</strong> your second paragraph was: “Since we are talking about checks and balances,<br />

it seems that only broken systems need checks and balances.” I transplanted the second half <strong>of</strong> this sentence so that<br />

it became the second sentence in your third paragraph, and replaced it with something which I think gives a better<br />

transition.<br />

Message [552] referenced by [556] and [565]. Next Message by SnatchimusMaximus is [569].<br />

[556] Tim: Re: Same money more work. I have to agree with SnatchimusMaximus<br />

[552] in that the capitalist most definitely has the advantage over the worker when it comes


276 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

to wage and “stealing” wages from the worker. Here is an example <strong>of</strong> the loophole that<br />

exists: My wife worked for a large company as a part time employee. She was required to<br />

work only 30 hours a week but somehow she always ended up working 39.5 (just short <strong>of</strong><br />

“full time” and just short <strong>of</strong> full time wage and benefits. If she were to work an extra half<br />

hour then the company would be required to treat her as a full time employee, but because<br />

they kept her just under 40 hours then she was still considered part time. The company<br />

was full <strong>of</strong> these “part time” employees, and was able to get full time work out <strong>of</strong> part<br />

time employees with out the expense <strong>of</strong> full time employees. Capitalism took advantage its<br />

position in the relationship and used its power to steal wages.<br />

Next Message by Tim is [720].<br />

[565] Hans: More Logic Please. Scott makes three errors in [545]:<br />

(a) He confuses intensification <strong>of</strong> labor with higher productivity. When Marx talks about<br />

higher productivity, he means a technical change allowing things to be produced with less<br />

labor-time. The labor itself may be different but it should require similar effort by the workers.<br />

If the workers have to work harder, this is called intensification <strong>of</strong> labor. Technical can<br />

be designed such that labor is intensified, but for analytical purposes we should distinguish<br />

higher productivity from intensitication <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

(b) Instead <strong>of</strong> looking how increased productivity affects piece wages, Scott answers how<br />

lower piece wages affect “productivity.” Reversing the causality can lead to quite different<br />

active mechanisms. (I put “productivity” into parentheses because Scott was talking about<br />

intensity but he called it productivity.)<br />

(c) Workers don’t like the lowering <strong>of</strong> piece wages, but this does not mean that workers<br />

don’t like piece wages themselves. Some workers like piece wages because it allows them<br />

to earn more money per hour by working harder, others dislike them because they tend to<br />

increase the intensity <strong>of</strong> labor for everyone.<br />

Scott’s answer is sloppy thinking. I expect more from you in this class. An example <strong>of</strong><br />

a thoughtful and also in part humorous answer is SnatchimusMaximus’s [552]. I gave it an<br />

A+, a grade which I do not <strong>of</strong>ten give, because he came up with some original deep thinking<br />

even when the deadline was looming.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [567].<br />

Question 684 is 696 in 2007SP, 675 in 2007fa, 688 in 2008fa, 719 in 2009fa, 783 in<br />

2010fa, 808 in 2011fa, and 838 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 684 If the capitalists make higher pr<strong>of</strong>its due to technical innovation, should the<br />

workers get part <strong>of</strong> this?<br />

[542] Andy: Yes. I think that the answer to this is very simple. Yes I believe that workers<br />

should get a part <strong>of</strong> this because higher productivity means that there is higher wealth coming<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the labor process which we are all a part <strong>of</strong>, so it should be shared. If it wasn’t shared<br />

how would workers be motivated to do their job. Everyone needs to be in it together.<br />

Hans: It’s not as simple as you think. There are good arguments saying that workers shouldn’t. Are you aware <strong>of</strong><br />

those, and how would you respond to them?<br />

Next Message by Andy is [718].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 277<br />

[553] Tim: graded A Technical innovation. The answer to this question is definitely:<br />

it depends. There are situations where it is necessary for the worker to learn new skills<br />

and receive training in order to use new equipment or use a new program. There are times<br />

when advances in technology make a job harder or more complicated than it was before<br />

the technical innovation. Some innovations can take a lot more effort in order to be able to<br />

perform on the same level as before. There are also innovations that have been thought <strong>of</strong>,<br />

and developed by the workers themselves. In all <strong>of</strong> these situations I think that it is proper<br />

for a capitalist to share part <strong>of</strong> its higher pr<strong>of</strong>its with those that made it possible for these<br />

innovations to take place.<br />

On the other hand, I think that it would be wrong for the worker to feel that he deserves<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the higher pr<strong>of</strong>its for innovations with which he has nothing to do. Also some innovations<br />

might make one’s job easier to perform. If this is the case, and the worker had<br />

nothing to do with the innovations then he has no right to the extra pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Next Message by Tim is [556].<br />

Exam Question 692 is 401 in 1999SP, 496 in 2000fa, 525 in 2001fa, 565 in 2002fa, 594<br />

in 2005fa, 696 in 2008fa, and 851 in 2012fa:<br />

Exam Question 692 How does the illusion arise that the capitalist advances something to<br />

the worker when he pays him a wage?<br />

[650] Bennett: The Capitalistic Illusion. The illusion arises that the capitalist advances<br />

something to the worker when he pays him a wage because the wage is what is received<br />

for the worker’s labor. This is an illusion because the capitalist pays the worker the wage<br />

with capital that the worker has produced himself with his own labor. The worker’s labor<br />

(product) is taken by the capitalist and sold on the market, with the money that the capitalist<br />

makes by selling this product he turns around and pays the worker’s wage. The view <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist paying the worker with money out <strong>of</strong> the capitalist pocket is an illusion, the money<br />

used to pay the worker was generated by the worker himself.<br />

Hans: Very good. I can also recommend my [2001fa:372].<br />

Next Message by Bennett is [651].<br />

Question 697 is 569 in 2002fa, 592 in 2003fa, 650 in 2004fa, 709 in 2007SP, 701 in<br />

2008fa, 800 in 2010fa, 856 in 2012fa, and 800 in Answer:<br />

Question 697 Sometimes a worker has to eat while working, like a machine which needs<br />

fuel in order to keep going. Marx comments that “this, however, appears as an abuse.” Why<br />

didn’t he write “this, however, is an abuse”?<br />

[672] Ken: ulterior motive. Marx describes that there are two types <strong>of</strong> consumption;<br />

productive consumption and individual consumption. “The laborer turns the money paid to<br />

him for this labor-power, into means <strong>of</strong> subsistence: this is his individual consumption”.<br />

Individual consumption is time that the worker takes for himself. This would include eating,<br />

resting, and breaks. Productive consumption is when the worker is on the clock producing.<br />

This would be an example <strong>of</strong> when a worker has to eat while working.<br />

Marx comments that “this, however, appears as an abuse” because if the worker has to<br />

eat lunch while working, not only is the worker benefiting but the capitalist is also. The


278 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

worker is reproducing while still producing for the capitalist. The worker must eat and<br />

drink in order to be productive. If the worker is dehydrated and hungry the worker will not<br />

be as productive. The capitalist wants workers in the most productive state. That is why<br />

the capitalist is willing to give workers a break in order to eat, drink, etc. It appears like<br />

the worker is benefiting from this individual consumption but the capitalist has an ulterior<br />

motive. That is why Marx argues that it only “appears as an abuse”.<br />

Message [672] referenced by [743]. Next Message by Ken is [676].<br />

[743] Hans: Avocado Sandwich on the Assembly Line. Ken’s answer [672] has it<br />

almost right, but not entirely, therefore I’d like to explain here the entire issue from the beginning.<br />

First Marx makes the distinction between individual and productive consumption.<br />

Productive consumption is the consumption <strong>of</strong> materials etc. in the production process, and<br />

individual consumption is the final consumption <strong>of</strong> goods by the consumer. In productive<br />

consumption, the value is transferred to the end product, while in final consumption it is<br />

used up.<br />

This is material from chapter Eight. In chapter Twenty-Three, Marx adds a new dimension,<br />

namely: the final consumption by the worker is productive consumption from the point<br />

<strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> capital, because it reproduces the worker, the capitalist’s most important machine.<br />

This is at first unintuitive. The worker who enjoys a good meal in the circle <strong>of</strong> his family, or<br />

a relaxing weekend, may consider this a precious moment <strong>of</strong> his life – but as things are set up<br />

in our society, this enjoyable activity is at the same time the reproduction <strong>of</strong> the commodity<br />

labor-power.<br />

This overall social connection holds because socially, the workers are the property <strong>of</strong><br />

the capitalists even when they are not working. The worker’s consumption is productive<br />

consumption for the capitalist, whether or not the worker consumes his or her food on the<br />

job. And <strong>of</strong> course the overwhelming part <strong>of</strong> the worker’s consumption is at home or perhaps<br />

during breaks at work. But sometimes the worker does not even interrupt the production<br />

process in order to eat: he or she grabs a bite out <strong>of</strong> the sandwich between handling the tools<br />

and works while chewing. Here it is much easier to see that the worker’s consumption is<br />

productive consumption for the capitalist; the worker’s food is here analogous to the fuel<br />

consumed by the capitalist’s machines.<br />

But eating on the job is considered an abuse: the capitalist does not like it because it<br />

detracts the worker and the bread crumbs fall into the end product, and the worker does not<br />

like to be put into this situation but demands decent breaktimes during the workday. Marx<br />

calls this abuse “inessential for capitalist production,” because capitalist production does not<br />

depend on it. There are easy ways to set up capitalist production in such a way that workers<br />

do not eat directly on the job but in the lunchroom adjacent to the workshop.<br />

The most <strong>of</strong>fensive part <strong>of</strong> this is not the avocado sandwich in the worker’s mouth. The<br />

most <strong>of</strong>fensive part is that the worker’s entire life is subordinated to the needs <strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

This is not considered as abuse, this is considered just and fair. I.e., what is really an abuse<br />

does not appear as an abuse, is not considered an abuse, but on the contrary is considered<br />

just. Only when the truth <strong>of</strong> capitalist society stares them too blatantly in the eyes do they<br />

say it is an abuse, and hasten to re-arrange the surface relations so that the abuse is once<br />

again safely covered up.


Another message where I say similar things is [2004fa:519].<br />

Message [743] referenced by [2008fa:1024]. Next Message by Hans is [768].<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 279<br />

Question 700 is 653 in 2004fa, 602 in 2005fa, 712 in 2007SP, 691 in 2007fa, 704 in<br />

2008fa, and 803 in 2010fa:<br />

Question 700 Explain the sentence: The capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its, not only by what he receives from<br />

but also by what be gives to, the laborer.<br />

[651] Bennett: The Capitalist Always Pr<strong>of</strong>its. The capitalist always pr<strong>of</strong>its from the<br />

laborer. The capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its from what the laborer gives the capitalist, this is simply the<br />

laborer’s labor. When the worker gives the capitalist the product the capitalist sells the<br />

product or service and makes far more <strong>of</strong> a pr<strong>of</strong>it than the laborer does. The capitalist also<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its from what he gives to the laborer. When the capitalist pays the laborer he is paying<br />

the laborer with money that the laborer generated himself through his labor. The capitalist<br />

also pr<strong>of</strong>its from paying the laborer because the laborer needs money to live on and the<br />

fact that the capitalist provides this to the laborer makes the laborer come to work everyday<br />

which in turn benefits the capitalist because he has more and more labor and product to sell<br />

on the market. This is a continuos cycle that always leaves the laborer holding the short end<br />

<strong>of</strong> the stick.<br />

Message [651] referenced by [655], [657], and [660]. Next Message by Bennett is [770].<br />

[655] Chris: capitalist’s pr<strong>of</strong>itability. I am responding to Bennett’s [651] because I feel<br />

that there are a few justifications that can be made through his response. Bennett mentions<br />

that “ When the worker gives the capitalist the product the worker sells the product or service<br />

and makes far more <strong>of</strong> a pr<strong>of</strong>it than the laborer does.” From what I understand, the worker<br />

makes no pr<strong>of</strong>it. Bennett’s comment makes me think that workers do make a pr<strong>of</strong>it; however,<br />

the capitalists make the most. I think a better way to explain the pr<strong>of</strong>itability <strong>of</strong> a product<br />

would be by saying that the worker creates the product through the use <strong>of</strong> the capitalist’s<br />

ownership <strong>of</strong> production. The capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its from the laborer because they sell the product<br />

at a higher value than the laborer put into the product, hence, creating a pr<strong>of</strong>it which the<br />

capitalist does not give back to the laborer.<br />

I agree with Bennett where he begins discussing the capitalist’s control <strong>of</strong> the labor in<br />

his final 3 sentences. However, I had trouble dissecting this argument from these sentences<br />

due to his circular thought process. I would like to add and try to make it clearer in my own<br />

words where I think the capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its by what they give to the laborer. The capitalist<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its from what they give to the laborer through what they don’t give to the laborer. The<br />

capitalist gives the laborer a paycheck, however, this paycheck is not equal to the amount<br />

the laborer put into the creation <strong>of</strong> the product. In fact, it is usually less. By not giving the<br />

laborer the full value <strong>of</strong> what they put into the product, the capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its. Plus, they gain<br />

control over the laborer because the laborer is usually struggling to make ends meet so they<br />

must continually work whatever hours the capitalist tells them to work. This usually results<br />

in a sense <strong>of</strong> false security for the laborer.<br />

Hans: I think the sentence you quoted in your first paragraph had a simple writing error; Bennet meant to write<br />

“when the worker gives the capitalist the product the capitalist sells the product or service and makes far more <strong>of</strong> a<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it than the laborer does.” Indeed, this is the version <strong>of</strong> the sentence in the archive now.


280 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Bennett’s sentence is still inaccurate because the worker never gives the product to the capitalist. Since the<br />

capitalist has bought the worker’s labor power, the capitalist owns the product from the beginning. The worker<br />

never owns it and therefore cannot give it to anybody.<br />

Your own formulation is not quite what Marx had in mind either. It should read<br />

“The capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its from the laborer because they give the laborer a smaller value than the<br />

laborer put into the product, hence, realizing a pr<strong>of</strong>it which the capitalist does not give back to<br />

the laborer.”<br />

Saying that Bennett has a “circular thought process” without showing any circles in his arguments is not helpful. I<br />

do not have the impression that Bennett’s thoughts are circular.<br />

Despite all my criticism I appreciate your close reading <strong>of</strong> Bennett and your attempts to improve his formulations.<br />

Message [655] referenced by [679]. Next Message by Chris is [691].<br />

[657] Nstew: In theory the capitalist always pr<strong>of</strong>its but not in reality. In response to<br />

Bennett [651] I think that this example is oversimplified and that sometimes Marx creates<br />

an image <strong>of</strong> the “capitalist” who is out to exploit people and to make as much money for<br />

himself as possible. Let’s say that you have a laborer who makes boxes. The laborer is<br />

paid $10 an hour, produces 1 box per hour, and works an 8 hour work day. Let’s then say<br />

that the “capitalist” turns around and sells each <strong>of</strong> these boxes for $20. According to the<br />

simplified theory one would say the “capitalist” is not only pr<strong>of</strong>iting $10 <strong>of</strong>f each box the<br />

laborer creates but also is robbing the laborer <strong>of</strong> the additional $10 that the box was sold<br />

for. This doesn’t take into consideration overhead costs, material costs, etc... Let’s say that<br />

once everything is paid for the “capitalist” is left with 10% so if he had one laborer who<br />

is getting paid $80 per day, the capitalist is only left with $16. In order for the “capitalist”<br />

to make as much as his employees he would have to have five employees making boxes<br />

and they would each make $80 a day. Marx does not take into consideration the liability<br />

a “capitalist” takes on by opening a factory or a shop and all <strong>of</strong> the expenses that go into<br />

making it pr<strong>of</strong>itable. Once the “capitalist” takes on an employee he is now responsible to<br />

pay that employee a daily wage which is another liability for the “capitalist”. Let’s then say<br />

that the five employees decide they don’t want to work as hard and start only producing 7<br />

boxes a day during an 8 hour period instead <strong>of</strong> 8 boxes. Then each <strong>of</strong> the laborers would be<br />

making $80 a day and the “capitalist” would be left with $70.<br />

I understand what Marx is saying when he is making the argument that the capitalist<br />

is not only making money <strong>of</strong>f pr<strong>of</strong>its from the commodities sold, but also from the excess<br />

money he is not paying the laborer for what they produced. But I don’t agree with it because<br />

the laborer is not taking on much risk where as the “capitalist” has now almost all <strong>of</strong> the<br />

risk which includes paying the laborer the agreed upon wage even if the company is not<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>itable.<br />

Hans: Your criticism that Marx “sometimes ... creates an image <strong>of</strong> the “capitalist” who is out to exploit people”<br />

was anticipated by Marx. He wrote in 92:1:<br />

To prevent possible misunderstandings, let me say this. I do not by any means depict the<br />

capitalist and the landowner in rosy colours. But individuals are dealt with here only in so far<br />

as they are the personifications <strong>of</strong> economic categories, the bearers <strong>of</strong> particular class-relations<br />

and interests. My standpoint, which views the development <strong>of</strong> the economic formation <strong>of</strong><br />

society as a process <strong>of</strong> natural history, can less than any other make the individual responsible<br />

for relations whose creature he remains socially, however much he may subjectively raise<br />

himself above them.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 281<br />

Marx’s critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism is the critique <strong>of</strong> an entire social system, not <strong>of</strong> the individuals who play a role in this<br />

system.<br />

Individual capitalists may think their pr<strong>of</strong>its are justified by risk or liability. According to Marx, neither risk<br />

nor liability create value. Marx is asking where the value comes from which the capitalists reap as pr<strong>of</strong>its. As he<br />

sees it, sleepless nights <strong>of</strong> a worried small business owner do not create value. But the labor <strong>of</strong> the majority <strong>of</strong> the<br />

population who work full time and never get ahead economically creates this value. In fact, small business owners<br />

are <strong>of</strong>ten members <strong>of</strong> the working class who try to escape their class position. Their difficulties show the depth <strong>of</strong><br />

the economic trap in which the majority <strong>of</strong> the population find themselves.<br />

Message [657] referenced by [658] and [660]. Next Message by Nstew is [764].<br />

[658] Goethe: Nstew [657] seems to be confusing the small business owner with the<br />

capitalist owners <strong>of</strong> production. The small business owner may try to play the role <strong>of</strong> a<br />

capitalist, but the large corporations will eventually kill him by the very methods he attempts<br />

to emulate.... Look at small town America before and after a Wal-Mart sets up shop!!! I think<br />

you will need to be sent to CousinIt’s re-education camp for the Marxist impaired....<br />

First Message by Goethe is [22].<br />

[660] Rmuscolino: In response to Bennett [651], I agree that the capitalist always pr<strong>of</strong>its<br />

from the laborer. The capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its from the laborers because <strong>of</strong> unproductive consumption<br />

along with the production and reproduction <strong>of</strong> the one means <strong>of</strong> production that’s indispensable<br />

to the capitalist: the laborer himself. By converting part <strong>of</strong> the capitalist capital<br />

into labor-power, the capitalist augments the value <strong>of</strong> his entire capital. He pr<strong>of</strong>its not only<br />

by what he receives but also by what is given to the laborer.<br />

Hans: When Bennett said “the capitalist always pr<strong>of</strong>its” he did not mean that capitalists cannot lose money. Nstew<br />

[657] is right that some capitalists do lose money. But Bennett meant that the capitalist benefits from both sides <strong>of</strong><br />

the transaction with the laborer. Reading your answer I have the hunch that you might have been thinking about<br />

it that even if the capitalist loses money, this does not relieve the worker from his dependence. On the contrary, if<br />

capitalist business is bad, the workers are the ones who suffer most. At least this is what you should have said in<br />

order not to simply ignore Nstew’s objection.<br />

Next Message by Rmuscolino is [661].<br />

Question 703 is 408 in 1999SP, 503 in 2000fa, 532 in 2001fa, 573 in 2002fa, 597 in<br />

2003fa, 605 in 2005fa, 715 in 2007SP, 806 in 2010fa, and 862 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 703 Regarding the question to what extent consumption is productive, Marx says<br />

that the individual consumption <strong>of</strong> the laborer is unproductive for the laborer, but productive<br />

for the capitalist and the state. Comment on this.<br />

[641] Jeremy: Keeping the man down! Life is a vicious cycle for the laborer. Like all<br />

men, the laborer desires to live, but to live, basic needs such as food, shelter, and clothing<br />

must be met. The only means by which to acquire such things is to give <strong>of</strong> his labor-power<br />

in return for wages. These wages are then returned to the capitalist, as he is the producer<br />

<strong>of</strong> the clothing, landlord to the shelter, and land owner from which the food is grown. The<br />

laborer has just given all that he has made in wages to extend his days on earth. The capitalist<br />

has used the desire to perpetuate life as a means to gain wealth. Thus we have the cyclical<br />

trend for the life <strong>of</strong> a laborer, who at no point is able to become productive because he and<br />

the labor-power which he possesses will be used to maintain his life and only prolong the<br />

invisible bondage to the capitalist.<br />

Message [641] referenced by [645], [646], [647], [659], and [2010fa:946]. Next Message by Jeremy is [674].


282 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[645] Goethe: graded A In response to [641] Jeremy has some basic ideas correct about<br />

labor consumption; it is true we all need the necessities <strong>of</strong> life to survive and our most<br />

efficient source <strong>of</strong> such are the capitalists owners <strong>of</strong> production, the question here is how,<br />

and why this is unproductive. First <strong>of</strong> all I would like to comment on the brilliant insight <strong>of</strong><br />

Marx; I am amazed by his observations and ideas from a century past, and how relevant they<br />

are in today’s world.<br />

Our society is structured on consumption, we all want more. This is the fuel that powers<br />

capitalism ... We want to keep up with the Jones’s ... Veblen calls this “pecuniary emulation”<br />

.... I bring this up in reference to an observation I experienced while volunteering on the<br />

ski bus with my daughter and her peers. I overheard a conversation between a group <strong>of</strong> 4th<br />

graders about the brand <strong>of</strong> video gaming systems they owned, one had an x-box, another<br />

claimed a play station, and one an x-box 360, and another a play station 3. This went on<br />

and on; each child trying to better the other with the objects <strong>of</strong> desire; these youngsters were<br />

exhibiting true pecuniary emulation. What I took away from this was the realization that our<br />

consumption habits start at a very young age.<br />

As we become more empowered to consume we also become entangled in the web <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalist exploitation. I want to dedicate more time to my education, but I am trapped in the<br />

working world. I think this is what Marx is getting at, and what Jeremy alludes to in [641].<br />

The productivity gained by the capitalist and the state (I assume Marx is referring to the<br />

government “state”) is the continued want and perceived need to consume goods that are not<br />

necessary. The unproductiveness <strong>of</strong> the laborer comes from the consumption <strong>of</strong> cheap crap.<br />

This is the nail in the c<strong>of</strong>fin <strong>of</strong> the worker; by spending his paycheck the day it is cashed,<br />

and never being able to escape the social class life has dealt.<br />

The bigger picture here is that consumption and overproduction by the capitalist is unproductive<br />

for the capitalist in the long run. The emission <strong>of</strong> fossil fuels into the atmosphere<br />

from producing, transporting, and disposal <strong>of</strong> goods hurts everyone.....<br />

I would love to have a conversation, or even listen to what Marx would say about the state<br />

<strong>of</strong> our society. I think the closest I will get is the Environmental econ class Hans is giving<br />

this summer.....<br />

Cheers All... and remember it does not matter how much you can do as long as you make<br />

an effort to do something; we all need to start somewhere.<br />

Message [645] referenced by [646]. Next Message by Goethe is [658].<br />

[646] Hans: Trapped by Our Physical Needs. Jeremy’s answer in [641] was a good<br />

representation <strong>of</strong> Marx’s own argument: the laborer’s private consumption is unproductive<br />

for him because he never gets ahead but has to show up for work for the capitalist day-in<br />

day-out.<br />

In Jeremy’s sentence “The capitalist has used the desire to perpetuate life as a means<br />

to gain wealth” I would write “need” instead <strong>of</strong> “desire.” The capitalist benefits from the<br />

workers’ need to perpetuate their lives and allows them to do just that, perpetuate their lives,<br />

and not go beyond it.<br />

Goethe, in [645], brings in two aspects which were not mentioned by Marx but which are<br />

very relevant today:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 283<br />

(a) Consumerism. At Marx’s times the workers were not seduced by cheap trinkets, they<br />

could barely feed themselves. I don’t think Marx would have predicted that shopping in<br />

fancy shopping centers would become a favorite pastime for the working class. I don’t share<br />

the guilt about this which I sense in so many contributions submitted class over the years. I<br />

think the working class is saying: “if you reduce us to consumption machines, then let’s at<br />

least consume in style.” This shows the spirit and creativity <strong>of</strong> the masses, and I am looking<br />

forward to the times when the masses have more relevant things to do than play computer<br />

games.<br />

(b) Environmental disaster. I think there is a connection as I tried to say in [578]. The<br />

struggle between capitalists and working class never came to a decisive victory for either<br />

one, but the bonanza <strong>of</strong> cheap energy due to fossil fuels allowed both <strong>of</strong> them to make gains.<br />

Now this bonanza has come to an end, and the old class struggles arise in a new form, as<br />

a fight whether the capitalist are able to shift the costs <strong>of</strong> the switch to renewable energy<br />

to the working class, or whether the pr<strong>of</strong>it motive itself has to be dethroned as the ultimate<br />

principle governing production.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [656].<br />

[647] Nstew: In response to [641]: What if the “capitalist” who owns the factory where<br />

the laborer is spending his wages is not running a pr<strong>of</strong>itable business. What if “the man /<br />

capitalist” is struggling more than the laborer to cover his overhead costs and still provide<br />

life’s necessities for himself? In any instance when a “capitalist” buys a factory or starts a<br />

company and hires on laborers they now have to provide them with the daily wage agreed<br />

upon. The “capitalist” is the person who is carrying all <strong>of</strong> the risk. If the company is not<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>itable and he is unable to produce a pr<strong>of</strong>it which in turn causes him to close his company,<br />

he is now liable for all the debt and expenses the company has accrued. The laborer in this<br />

situation walks away without a job but can easily go find another one.<br />

Hans: Some capitalists lose money, especially new businesses. But the big capitalists on average make lots <strong>of</strong><br />

money. Marx does not explain that with risk because risk taking does not create value. Marx explains this by<br />

something which actually creates the value the capitalists reap.<br />

Message [647] referenced by [679]. Next Message by Nstew is [652].<br />

[659] Rmuscolino: In response to Jeremy [641], life is a vicious cycle for the laborer. And<br />

the only means to acquire such things like food, clothing, and shelter is to give labor-power in<br />

return for wages. But as stated by Malthus’ Definitions, etc., “The workman is a productive<br />

consumer to the person who employs him, and to the State, but not, strictly speaking, to<br />

himself.” I like this statement because it’s describing how the capitalist production process<br />

can work. Of course the laborer has to work to earn a living, which is their trade <strong>of</strong>f to give<br />

work for food, clothing, and shelter. But to answer the question to what extent consumption<br />

is productive, Marx’s idea that the individual consumption <strong>of</strong> the laborer is unproductive for<br />

the laborer, but productive for the capitalist and the state is called unproductive consumption.<br />

The extent where consumption would be productive would be when consumption is equal to<br />

the minimum.<br />

Hans: As I already remarked in [628] and your resubmission [634] which you haven’t seen yet, you are reading<br />

the text too superficially. The reading assignments require thought, this cannot be done in a hurry.<br />

First you need to understand the difference between individual and productive consumption as given in 717:1.<br />

Your last sentence above refers to 718:1/o: the capitalist considers only that part <strong>of</strong> the worker’s consumption<br />

productive which covers the bare minimum <strong>of</strong> maintaining his livelihood; everything going beyond this is<br />

unproductive to the capitalist.


284 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Marx supplements this view by looking at the worker’s consumption from the point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the worker, with<br />

the result that all individual consumption is unproductive for the worker.<br />

Next Message by Rmuscolino is [660].<br />

Question 706 is 578 in 2002fa, 602 in 2003fa, 661 in 2004fa, 608 in 2005fa, 718 in<br />

2007SP, 697 in 2007fa, 710 in 2008fa, 742 in 2009fa, 835 in 2011fa, and 865 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 706 Explain how capitalist production, just by the fact that it is happening, reproduces<br />

the separation between the worker and the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

[661] Rmuscolino: Capitalist Production Reproduces the Separation between the<br />

Worker and Means <strong>of</strong> Production. Capitalist production, just by the fact that it is happening,<br />

reproduces the separation between the worker and the means <strong>of</strong> production. “It thereby<br />

reproduces and perpetuates the condition for exploiting the laborer. It incessantly forces him<br />

to sell his labor-power in order to live, and enables the capitalist to purchase labor-power<br />

in order that he may enrich himself.” [723:2/o] This creates a society that’s separated by<br />

classes. They confront each other in the market as buyer and seller, and forces the laborer<br />

to convert his product into a means by which another can buy him. This division <strong>of</strong> society<br />

is the result <strong>of</strong> the continuous repetition <strong>of</strong> the capitalist production itself, where Marx calls<br />

this process the capital relation.<br />

Hans: This is good, but more <strong>of</strong> your answer than you yourself indicate is literal quotes from Marx. Please be<br />

precise with delineating which formulations come from you and which come from Marx. There is also a difference<br />

between reformulating a thought in your own words and paraphrasing someone else’s formulation. I consider your<br />

little essay not entirely a paraphrase, but close to it.<br />

Message [661] referenced by [666]. Next Message by Rmuscolino is [667].<br />

[666] Bmellor: bound by invisible threads. I agree with Rmuscolino [661] that the<br />

capitalist production process is a vicious cycle, “[reproducing] and [perpetuating] the exploitation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the laborer.” The owner binds the worker with “invisible threads.” The worker<br />

makes a wage <strong>of</strong> subsistence and then he is forced back into the labor maker to sell his labor<br />

power. The capitalist is enriched by the fact that he <strong>of</strong>fers the laborer a meager wage forcing<br />

him to always rely on the capitalist to use the means <strong>of</strong> production never giving the labor<br />

the opportunity to get ahead because he is always focusing on just keeping his “head above<br />

water.” The worker is forced to sell his labor power because he is estranged from the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production.<br />

One way workers are manipulated today in the same fashion, Marx may not have predicted<br />

student loans and health insurance. Upon graduating you need to pay <strong>of</strong>f student<br />

loans and you will always need insurance. Employment <strong>of</strong>fers a solution to both <strong>of</strong> those.<br />

Not only are you dependent upon the means <strong>of</strong> production but you are also dependent upon<br />

the “benefits” and steady income.<br />

Message [666] referenced by [2008fa:1050]. Next Message by Bmellor is [668].<br />

Term Paper 708 is 926 in 2000fa, 926 in 2001fa, 826 in 2002fa, 826 in 2003fa, 826 in<br />

2004fa, 826 in 2005fa, 724 in 2007SP, 700 in 2007fa, 744 in 2009fa, 811 in 2010fa, 838<br />

in 2011fa, and 868 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 708 Essay about Chapter Twenty-Six: Secret <strong>of</strong> Original Accumulation


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 285<br />

[771] FacistFrank, Inter, and Jenn: Chapter Twenty-Six: In review. Executive Summary.<br />

At this point in Das Kapital, 873:1, Marx has explained to us his theories on how money<br />

is changed into capital, and how through capital surplus value is made, and from that how<br />

more capital is made. But now the question is what started this cycle? We are in a chicken<br />

and egg sort <strong>of</strong> situation where one creates the other, then the other returns the favor and<br />

creates its creator, this is a great real world example <strong>of</strong> Dialectic that Marx adapted from<br />

Hegel. All <strong>of</strong> these components presuppose each other, but how can this be possible, that<br />

would leave no starting point to capitalist accumulation. That is the goal <strong>of</strong> this chapter to<br />

discover the beginning.<br />

Hans points out in his annotations that another important presupposition to capitalist production<br />

is that the producers must be separated from the means <strong>of</strong> production, because they<br />

are in the control <strong>of</strong> the capitalist, but then this is an after effect <strong>of</strong> accumulation. As Marx<br />

puts it, it seems to move in a defective circle. So where is the original accumulation? Well<br />

Marx begins his exploration by examining the capitalist explanation for the eginnings <strong>of</strong><br />

this accumulation; the origin must be noncapitalist, in order to presuppose capitalism. In a<br />

nutshell the capitalist explanation for this is that a long time ago there were people that were<br />

smart and hardworking, the feudal elite, and the lazy, stupid peasants. Since the elite were<br />

good and the peasants bad, the elite evolved into the good capitalist, and the peasants into<br />

the bad workers. Marx compares the ridiculousness <strong>of</strong> this explanation to the ridiculousness<br />

<strong>of</strong> the original sin fable in the bible. Marx describes original sin and the capitalist original<br />

explanation as anecdotes, which at best can only describe surface relations <strong>of</strong> real things<br />

occurring, this capitalist explanation <strong>of</strong> the origins <strong>of</strong> capitalism are insufficient. Marx proceeds<br />

to logically eliminate this as a possible explanation for the beginning <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

because the supposed originally industrious feudal elite, has now become the lazy that does<br />

nothing, where the supposed lazy peasant is now the one that works to themselves to the<br />

bone. Marx now compares this to a childish property fable meant to keep children from<br />

being bad and breaking the rules, but he has proven it false. More evidence that Marx uses<br />

to disprove this fable is that the past was rife with violent exploitation, as opposed to their<br />

idyllic explanations; this violent fact is conveniently left out <strong>of</strong> the capitalist’s explanation<br />

for his own beginnings, and the explanation <strong>of</strong> other capitalist economists in Marx’s day.<br />

In paragraph 874:1/o Marx introduces the idea that in order for commodities, such as<br />

labor, and means <strong>of</strong> production to be considered capital, they must be able to separately<br />

come into contract with one another. However this relies on the assumption that laborpower<br />

is itself a commodity. Marx explains how labor-power is a commodity because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

separation <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production and the lack <strong>of</strong> access to the means <strong>of</strong> production by<br />

the laborer, leaving him with just his labor to sell. In essence, the capitalist system can only<br />

exist where the means <strong>of</strong> production and labor can interact as capital. Marx further states,<br />

that once the capitalist system begins it will be able to constantly reproduce the separation<br />

between the means <strong>of</strong> production and the laborer. Marx makes it clear at this point that<br />

“original accumulation” is the process by which the means <strong>of</strong> production and labor become<br />

separated.


286 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Another way to look at this is to consider the functioning <strong>of</strong> nature. On the one hand<br />

there are plants, and on the other, there are animals. In and <strong>of</strong> themselves, neither plants nor<br />

animals can constitute an ecosystem. It is only at the point where these two groups interact<br />

that we see an ecosystem. Animals (humans excluded) are unable to produce their own food;<br />

therefore they are forced to center themselves near certain plants to receive substance. This<br />

forces us to presuppose that even though both plants and animals are living things, they are<br />

separate from one another. It is because these two living things are separate that we have<br />

an ecosystem. After the ecosystem has been created, it is able to reproduce and maintain<br />

itself (until humans destroy it). “Original accumulation” in the case <strong>of</strong> our ecosystem is the<br />

process by which animals and plants became separate.<br />

Marx begins with the statement in 875:1 that capitalistic economy has emerged from<br />

feudal economy. Marx continues to examine the social transition that seems to “lever” the<br />

economy into a capitalistic society. In medieval times, the social structure has been referred<br />

to as a “feudal society.” Feudal society seems to be a term combining feudalism, a term used<br />

to describe the political structure, and manorialism, which describes the economic structure<br />

<strong>of</strong> Western Europe at that time.<br />

Feudal society could be defined by its dispersion <strong>of</strong> governmental power, social classes<br />

such as lords, peasants and serfs, and a primarily agrarian economy. The presence <strong>of</strong> warriors<br />

is prominent, and much <strong>of</strong> the social order is determined by knights and warriors. It begins<br />

with a King, who delegates plots <strong>of</strong> land out to lords, who in turn help to provide for the<br />

other militia at that time. The lords also allow peasants to live on part <strong>of</strong> their land, in a<br />

manorial fashion, in exchange for a portion <strong>of</strong> their produce or labor-power. The economic<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> this society minimizes the use <strong>of</strong> money, and is primarily focused on the need<br />

for subsistence for each person. Although there is a landlord and a peasant class, similar<br />

to a capitalist-worker relationship, the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital does not seem to occur in<br />

quite so circuitous a manner as in capitalism. The manorial economy appears to emphasize<br />

commodity exchange rather than the use <strong>of</strong> a general equivalent.<br />

Marx states that the dissolution <strong>of</strong> feudal society set free the elements <strong>of</strong> capitalist society.<br />

Perhaps one <strong>of</strong> these elements is the rise in use <strong>of</strong> money. Chapters Two and Three <strong>of</strong><br />

“Das Kapital” discuss the natural progression from a commodity-exchange society to a more<br />

efficient C-M-C process. In the following chapter, Marx describes the M-C-M process, in<br />

which money is used to purchase commodities with the single purpose <strong>of</strong> acquiring more<br />

money. In the beginning <strong>of</strong> chapter 26, Marx relates a basic law <strong>of</strong> physics to an economical<br />

principle, and points out that if something can not be created from nothing; there must be an<br />

origin <strong>of</strong> capital, from which more capital accumulates.<br />

Another element that may lead to capitalism is the fact that the laborer is no longer attached<br />

to the land. In a manorial economy, the lords allow for peasants to live on part <strong>of</strong> their<br />

land, in a manorial fashion, in exchange for a portion <strong>of</strong> their produce, or labor-power. The<br />

peasants are obligated to the lords <strong>of</strong> the land on which they reside, although they may have<br />

obligations to other lords as well. In capitalism, the laborer is free to sell their labor-power to<br />

whomever they choose, regardless <strong>of</strong> their place <strong>of</strong> residence. In 875:2, Marx explains that<br />

though this gives the illusion <strong>of</strong> freedom to the serfs, it converts them to wage-workers, thus<br />

removing the obligation <strong>of</strong> the lord, or capitalist, to provide means <strong>of</strong> production or means


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 287<br />

<strong>of</strong> subsistence for their workers. This is the first illusion which starts what Marx might call<br />

the downward spiral <strong>of</strong> illusions rampant in capitalism.<br />

Marx concludes chapter 26 by summarizing that capitalism stems from the change in societal<br />

structure, or revolutions, and the illusionary freedom <strong>of</strong> a new capitalistic society <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

appeal to the men whose means <strong>of</strong> production are torn from them, laying the groundwork<br />

for his future analysis <strong>of</strong> other examples <strong>of</strong> transitions from feudalism to capitalism.<br />

Next Message by FacistFrank is [833], Next Message by Inter is [858], and Next Message by Jenn is [860].<br />

[775] Andy, Papageorgio, Paul, Scott, Slash, Wade, and Carterryan: Marx starts<br />

this chapter by stating that he has now explained “how money is changed into capital; how<br />

through capital surplus-value is made, and from surplus-value more capital.” He then goes<br />

to say that this seems to be an ongoing circle and there had to be something that started this<br />

circle; this is because capitalism requires a class <strong>of</strong> individuals that have an adequate amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> wealth, or capital, already to invest into the system to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it from it. The event that<br />

Marx supposes preceded the eventual transformation into capitalism was that <strong>of</strong> “primitive<br />

accumulation.” This accumulation as Marx states was “not the result <strong>of</strong> the capitalistic mode<br />

<strong>of</strong> production, but its starting point.”<br />

In the next paragraph Marx tells us how this event <strong>of</strong> primitive accumulation is somewhat<br />

equivalent to the story <strong>of</strong> Adam and Eve from the Bible. In that story Adam took a bite <strong>of</strong><br />

the forbidden fruit and from this act sin fell upon the human race. This can be compared to<br />

primitive accumulation since during this period is when the corner stone <strong>of</strong> the capitalistic<br />

system was put into place and poverty fell upon a certain set <strong>of</strong> people. Marx then goes to<br />

explain that there were two sorts <strong>of</strong> people during this time. First, there was the intelligent,<br />

hard working, penny-pinchers. Second, there were the lazy that would spend all their money<br />

in “riotous living.” While this seems to be a justifiable comparison Marx notes that there is a<br />

tremendous difference in the two stories. This is that while in the story <strong>of</strong> the original sin all<br />

<strong>of</strong> mankind now was befallen with the burden <strong>of</strong> sin, while the act <strong>of</strong> primitive accumulation<br />

only burdened the “lazy” people who would end up being cast into poverty, not the intelligent<br />

because they would end being the capitalists. This is because as these people accumulated<br />

their capital the others were forced to sell only themselves. So from this point, as Marx<br />

states, “dates the poverty <strong>of</strong> the great majority.” Marx then goes on to tell that these events<br />

were made possible by “conquest, enslavement, robbery, murder, briefly force...”<br />

In the third paragraph Marx makes clear how now that a certain few accumulated wealth<br />

how they were then able to convert that wealth into even more by using the capitalistic<br />

system. He states, however, that this is only made possible under certain circumstances.<br />

The first is that these two groups <strong>of</strong> people explained above now must come face to face in<br />

the market. The owners <strong>of</strong> the wealth now are also the owners <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

and <strong>of</strong> the subsistence needed to make given commodities, and who also are determined to<br />

increase their overall capital. The second circumstance is that the others must be free to sell<br />

their own labor-power. Marx describes these people as “free laborers,” first for the obvious<br />

reason that they sell their labor-power but also for the fact that they do not own any part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production. With these two circumstances taking place the “fundamental<br />

conditions <strong>of</strong> capitalistic production are given.” So, in hindsight, the single greatest event


288 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

that led to capitalistic production was that <strong>of</strong> separating the laborers from the possession <strong>of</strong><br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Marx then goes to explain that the “economic structure <strong>of</strong> capitalistic society has grown<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the economic structure <strong>of</strong> feudal society. The dissolution <strong>of</strong> the latter set free the<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> the former.” To understand this it is first important to understand what exactly a<br />

feudal society consisted <strong>of</strong>. Feudal society was the social order <strong>of</strong> much <strong>of</strong> Western Europe<br />

during the middle ages. It is characterized by mainly two types <strong>of</strong> people. First, there are<br />

the peasants or serfs that would <strong>of</strong>ten work on the farms to provide subsistence for everyone.<br />

Then there were the lords who would provide protection for the peasants and also provide<br />

them with enough subsistence to survive. The land, however, in this society was believed<br />

to not belong to anybody, but actually belong to God. But during this time <strong>of</strong> primitive<br />

accumulation it is believed that the lords began to take ownership <strong>of</strong> the land and kick the<br />

serfs <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> it, severing them from the means <strong>of</strong> production. Through this act Marx explains<br />

that these laborers who used to be the immediate producers and tied to the land in which they<br />

worked were now required to become sellers <strong>of</strong> their labor-power in order to survive. These<br />

people then had to go out into the market and find work. In doing this they were transformed<br />

from the producers <strong>of</strong> goods merely to that <strong>of</strong> wage-workers. Through this process these<br />

new “freedmen,” as Marx calls them, were stripped <strong>of</strong> any <strong>of</strong> their means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

Marx goes on to say that the forceful taking <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production from these people<br />

are “written in the annals <strong>of</strong> mankind in letters <strong>of</strong> blood and fire.” This only confirms was<br />

is affirmed earlier that this transition period, the primitive accumulation, was one which the<br />

poor people who became the wage workers did not want to happen, but it was violently<br />

enforced upon them by the owners <strong>of</strong> wealth.<br />

In the following paragraph Marx begins his analysis <strong>of</strong> the industrial capitalists. These<br />

people were the ones who eventually were able to take the power, and the source <strong>of</strong> wealth,<br />

away from the lords <strong>of</strong> the feudal society. A large cause that aided in the industrial capitalists,<br />

who started out merely as merchant capitalist, usurping the wealth from the lords<br />

was that since the lords had emancipated all <strong>of</strong> the their peasants and serfs from their land,<br />

those workers were now forced to sell their labor-power to sustain. The industrial capitalist<br />

were then able to hire this new abundance <strong>of</strong> people and hire them as wage workers. The<br />

capitalists were then able to obtain a large amount <strong>of</strong> wealth, and before long, they were able<br />

to build factories for production and industrial capitalism was put into effect.<br />

Marx concludes by stating that the “starting-point <strong>of</strong> the development that gave rise to<br />

the wage-laborer as well as to the capitalist, was the servitude <strong>of</strong> the laborer.” This clarifies<br />

that the primary circumstance that led to capitalism was that the laborers, “divorced” <strong>of</strong> their<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production and needing subsistence to survive, were forced to become the wage<br />

laborers simply because they had no other choice.<br />

In conclusion, we see that this time <strong>of</strong> primitive accumulation that fell between the collapse<br />

<strong>of</strong> the feudal society and the establishment <strong>of</strong> capitalism was one <strong>of</strong> great turmoil<br />

and mayhem for the greater part <strong>of</strong> the people involved. Hans states in [2005fa:1443] that, “<br />

sometime in history there must have been a non-capitalist process in which the direct producers<br />

were separated from their means <strong>of</strong> production, and the capitalists could amass enough<br />

money to hire them as wage laborers.” Given this, Marx paints us a picture <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong>


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 289<br />

production and the means <strong>of</strong> subsistence being brutally seized from the workers through any<br />

means possible. The new privileged class <strong>of</strong> capitalists was then able to force these people<br />

into wage labor, and by doing this was able to expand their wealth. Through these acts we<br />

see the exploitation that takes place in capitalism.<br />

Hans: At the beginning <strong>of</strong> your essay you describe certain explanations rejected by Marx as if they were Marx’s<br />

own explanations.<br />

Message [775] referenced by [777]. Next Message by Andy is [869], Next Message by Papageorgio is [788], Next<br />

Message by Paul is [787], Next Message by Scott is [791], Next Message by Slash is [797], Next Message by Wade<br />

is [794], and Next Message by Carterryan is [831].<br />

[777] Kapital and Raynold: In choosing the “Secret <strong>of</strong> Original Accumulation” in chapter<br />

26, I found a couple key points that Marx pointed out to help explain why we are placed<br />

at different standard levels <strong>of</strong> living in our society. First <strong>of</strong>f, Marx explains how there’s a cycle<br />

that’s been going on between the capitalists and the free laborers which produces means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production. He uses the term “primitive accumulation” to help explain the beginning <strong>of</strong><br />

this great transformation which produced capitalists along with its workers, the free laborers.<br />

Because free laborers had nothing but themselves to give up, the capitalists owned all<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production which gave them an increase in overall capital. In understanding<br />

the transformation, Marx splits the population into two types. The lazy people who splurge<br />

and the hard working people who save. This is how capitalism evolved. The hard working<br />

conservative people eventually rose to power by being capitalists and the unfortunate<br />

other half had nothing to give up but themselves which Marx labeled them free laborers.<br />

They (laborers) had no choice but to enter the capitalist system or else they’d face poverty.<br />

Wealth is what became <strong>of</strong> these capitalists making them stable and helping bring up the<br />

lower classes who were in great need <strong>of</strong> this change. Today, we can call this conservative<br />

group our founding heroes <strong>of</strong> humanity.<br />

I think this story relates to our society today. We see workers being exploited everyday in<br />

different parts <strong>of</strong> the world and this is because the capitalists are in full control, like it or not.<br />

I learned that there are consequences for every action you do. Whether its being productive<br />

or unproductive, there will always be a pay <strong>of</strong>f. We are living a life <strong>of</strong> incentives which is<br />

critical because it will shape us into what we want to become in the future.<br />

Hans: You write “because free laborers had nothing but themselves to give up, the capitalists owned all the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production.” The causaility is the reverse: Because the capitalists owned all the means <strong>of</strong> production, the free<br />

laborers had nothing but themselves to give up (sell).<br />

And just like [775], you mistake explanations strongly rejected by Marx as Marx’s own.<br />

First Message by Bennett is [175], First Message by Kapital is [777], and First Message by Raynold is [204].<br />

[805] Hans: Termpaper Discussion. Term papers are no longer accepted. This question<br />

number is for the discussion <strong>of</strong> previously submitted term papers, not for new term papers.<br />

Someone just tried to use it to send a term paper through. Such submissions will be ignored<br />

and they will also not show up in the archives, so don’t waste your time.<br />

Hans.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [832].<br />

Term Paper 709 is 932 in 2000fa, 932 in 2001fa, 832 in 2002fa, 832 in 2003fa, 832 in<br />

2004fa, 832 in 2005fa, 727 in 2007SP, 701 in 2007fa, 745 in 2009fa, 839 in 2011fa, and<br />

869 in 2012fa:


290 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Term Paper 709 Essay about Chapter Thirty-Two: Historical Tendency <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Accumulation<br />

[776] Dyoung, Spawnblade, and Brody: According to Marx the tendency <strong>of</strong> capital to<br />

accumulate has been driven throughout history by three ideas, which are declared in Ch. 25.<br />

First we have the statement “Capital can only increase by exchanging itself for labor-power,<br />

by calling wage labor to life.” This means that without labor, capital cannot accumulate, it<br />

is dependent on labor. Furthermore if capital could not exploit labor then it would cease to<br />

hire those workers.<br />

Second Marx states “The labor-power <strong>of</strong> the wage worker can only exchange itself for<br />

capital by increasing capital, by strengthening the power whose slave it is.” With this statement<br />

Marx tells us that labor is one <strong>of</strong> the causes for the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital and if it did<br />

not allow for, and facilitate this accumulation then capital would not hire it because there<br />

would be no room for pr<strong>of</strong>it. We can see throughout history that most <strong>of</strong> the time labor was<br />

either forced to work for free such as in slavery or serfdom, and even today labor seems to<br />

undervalue itself and the surplus value that it creates for capital.<br />

Marx’s third idea is “increase <strong>of</strong> capital is increase <strong>of</strong> the proletariat, that is, <strong>of</strong> the working<br />

class.” The increase <strong>of</strong> proletariat is what helps move the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital to its<br />

next level. For every increase in the labor force there is subsequently a proportionate increase<br />

in capital. Capital therefore uses the additional capital to hire the next labor input or<br />

in other historical times to buy the next slave to help increase its accumulation.<br />

While petty production must evolve into capitalism through individual specialization and<br />

the acquisition <strong>of</strong> private property, so to must capitalism evolve towards socialism. This<br />

theory arises from the tendency to centralize capital in an effort to increase efficiency as per<br />

the “immanent laws <strong>of</strong> capitalist production itself.” Just as there is always a larger fish, there<br />

is always a larger capitalist. This is seen frequently as capitalists wish to grow ‘larger’ by incorporating<br />

other capitalist’s capital into their own. In this method, the means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

slowly congregates into single holdings where eventually, in theory, there will only be one<br />

holder. Where Marx implies this to lead, is to socialism. If only one capitalist holds all the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production, it would not be allowed. It must be an organization that can protect the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production. This leaves two options (not stated by Marx, yet implied historically<br />

and logically found through previous chapters): A government, or the people themselves.<br />

In a way these two options are the same. The government should be composed <strong>of</strong> the people,<br />

for the people. However the world is not a stranger to corrupt governments, and this<br />

fact makes the option <strong>of</strong> a central body more difficult to regulate. When the people run the<br />

economy, however, it could equate to the small socialist communities spread throughout the<br />

world who practice these doctrines. These have proven the system could work; yet no largescale<br />

examples could be accounted for. There is <strong>of</strong> course one other flaw in the continued<br />

expropriation <strong>of</strong> capital: The law. As it stands, most countries have extremely strict competition<br />

laws in place that includes the regulation and dispersal <strong>of</strong> monopolies. This is a result<br />

<strong>of</strong> people believing it best to ensure ‘fair competition’ and to keep the economy as efficient<br />

as possible. Yet this is still a roadblock in the way <strong>of</strong> ‘natural’ expropriation. Meaning it<br />

must be forced by the people or government themselves out <strong>of</strong> an informed desire to evolve


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 291<br />

the system. On inspection, the only flaws in Marx’s theory are that <strong>of</strong> the flaws <strong>of</strong> the human<br />

condition, including that <strong>of</strong> the laws set by society.<br />

Marx goes on to say that the process as a whole is a dialectical negation <strong>of</strong> negation. Capitalism<br />

is the negation <strong>of</strong> the private property based on own labor. But capitalism produces<br />

its own negation. The result <strong>of</strong> which will be the joint ownership <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

He also sums up the historical processes <strong>of</strong> earlier accumulation and the changing aspects<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalist development, especially the processes <strong>of</strong> centralization <strong>of</strong> capital and the class<br />

struggle which Marx argues will bring the overthrow <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

Marx believes there is a transformation that takes place among the capitalist class. In the<br />

beginning stages <strong>of</strong> production, agriculture, manufacturing, etc, the proprietor is the owner<br />

<strong>of</strong> his own private property. The exploitation <strong>of</strong> the laborer comes next. Dissolution comes<br />

from this and the laborer is enslaved once again. Marx says “the transformation <strong>of</strong> scattered<br />

private property, arising from individual labor, into capitalist private property is, naturally, a<br />

process, incomparably more protracted, violent, and difficult, than the transformation <strong>of</strong> capitalistic<br />

private property, already practically resting on socialized production, into socialized<br />

property.”<br />

Marx focuses on the class struggle against capitalism between the Government and the<br />

people. Marx goes on to talk about the fact that laborers are isolated, exploited, enslaved and<br />

degraded. He also states that the lower classes, the small manufacturers, the shopkeepers,<br />

the artisan and the peasants all fight against the capitalists who are the means <strong>of</strong> social<br />

production and the employers <strong>of</strong> their wage labor. It seems to me that Marx believes that<br />

the laborers are well disciplined, organized and united where they would try to overthrow<br />

the system. I don’t think that this would ever happen however. But I think it comes down<br />

to being able to survive in a world with both the capitalist and the laborer. I don’t feel that<br />

the exploiter always wins, but I think it is a combination <strong>of</strong> what is best for society. This is<br />

a hard idea to have work in society, we do need laborers and capitalists to exist. So we need<br />

to figure out how to have both co-exist in an equal fashion. Both sides benefiting together.<br />

First Message by Brody is [54], First Message by Dyoung is [2], Next Message by Gerund is [815], Next Message<br />

by Mitternacht is [784], Next Message by Spawnblade is [813], and Next Message by Tim is [785].<br />

[778] Alcameron, Samantha, and Wasatch: Chapter 32: Historical Tendency <strong>of</strong> Capitalists<br />

is leading to Revolution. Marx has clearly stated and proved throughout Das<br />

Kapital that the historical tendency <strong>of</strong> capitalist accumulation is to exploit the masses, and<br />

other capitalists in a ever long pursuit <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it. But beyond that in Chapter 32, he poses<br />

this question “What does the primitive accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital, i.e. its historical genesis,<br />

resolve itself into?” Marx then launches the reader into an analysis <strong>of</strong> property, how moving<br />

from collective to private property has allowed capitalists to thrive. What began as a great<br />

movement toward individual land rights, allowing serfs to own their own land quickly becomes<br />

the “dwarf like property <strong>of</strong> the many into the giant property <strong>of</strong> the few”, where the<br />

proletariat is paid a wage rate determined by a capitalist who has moved them away from<br />

the modes <strong>of</strong> production. This movement was done through the “merciless barbarism” <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalists, moreover capitalists are nondiscriminatory, they will exploit all they are able to,<br />

including other capitalists, meaning that fewer and fewer in the general population will be<br />

land owners and own any private property.


292 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Through the amount <strong>of</strong> barbarism and expropriation on the working class, which now<br />

includes old society capitalists, one day enough individuals will collectively see their own<br />

exploitation and will grow to such large numbers that they will no longer allow the few bourgeoisie<br />

to control the land, the value <strong>of</strong> labor i.e. the wage-rate and the modes <strong>of</strong> production.<br />

In the footnote Marx makes one <strong>of</strong> his boldest statements that “what the bourgeoisie, therefore,<br />

produces, above all, are its own grave-diggers”, which further emphasizes his belief in<br />

the coming dissolution <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system. This final point has been <strong>of</strong> much discussion<br />

in our group and is the focus <strong>of</strong> the remainder <strong>of</strong> the paper. Specifically the discussion is<br />

broken into two groups Team A is arguing that government intervention against monopolies<br />

and for the protection <strong>of</strong> workers, has successfully destroyed this inevitability <strong>of</strong> revolution,<br />

that government policies indeed do have the ability to curb the insatiable appetite <strong>of</strong> capitalists.<br />

Team B is arguing the working class is continuing to be exploited, and that government<br />

intervention has just delayed the start date <strong>of</strong> the coming revolution.<br />

Team A: Economists see the role and impact <strong>of</strong> government intervention with regard to<br />

labor laws and workers rights differently. Marx believes that any government intervention is<br />

merely delaying the uprising <strong>of</strong> the workers against the capitalists and a complete revolution,<br />

that the nature <strong>of</strong> capitalists is such that they will always continue to grow and eliminate<br />

others from the market, regardless <strong>of</strong> what government regulations are put into place.<br />

This is not the reality in which we currently live, if Marx had seen the anti-monopoly<br />

laws and regulations on work days and child protection laws, it is plausible to believe he<br />

would have believed in the effect <strong>of</strong> government regulation more. The regulations placed on<br />

corporations in the United States have an effect, such that no capitalist is able to control an<br />

entire market. Anti-monopoly laws ensure that there are always a certain number <strong>of</strong> capitalists<br />

in the market and that other capitalist are able to enter the market, which means that there<br />

are not fewer and fewer capitalists, they are always changing. Indirectly these government<br />

regulations effectively stop any revolution that would take place with the workers. By not<br />

allowing any one particular capitalist to control an entire market there are always alternatives<br />

for laborers who are unhappy. If an employer refuses to make a concession or compromise<br />

for its laborers the laborers will obviously be unhappy. Through government regulations that<br />

promote competition there will always be another capitalist fighting for labor that can gain<br />

an advantage by making those concessions or compromises thus averting a revolution.<br />

Team B: Team A is mistaken to believe that capitalists will ever <strong>of</strong>fer concessions and<br />

compromises in the long term and will not try to exploit workers. In the model <strong>of</strong> reality<br />

you have just created there is no structural unemployment, laborers can easily move from<br />

one job to another and some capitalists see benefits to better compensation. Marx has mentioned<br />

time and again that it is the relative powerlessness <strong>of</strong> the proletariat in negotiation<br />

with capitalists that have perpetuated the cycle <strong>of</strong> exploitation that the proletariat faces unemployment<br />

by demanding concessions and even with other employers in the market does<br />

not mean that concessions will be granted. One needs only look at Wal-Mart to see that<br />

government anti-monopoly policies have not benefited the worker, as Wal-Mart <strong>of</strong>fers considerably<br />

less wages and benefits then other stores but will consume those stores if possible.<br />

In a very real way, Wal-Mart is the ultimate example <strong>of</strong> the capitalists feeding on other capitalists,<br />

but because <strong>of</strong> government regulation against monopolies in a market, they have<br />

actually bought more <strong>of</strong> the back end producers and also their distributors, lowering prices


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 293<br />

to such a point that competing companies in those markets, in order to stay in business must<br />

decrease wages and benefits. Eventually they will go out <strong>of</strong> business and then Wal-Mart will<br />

gobble them up as well, or at the very least will try to. Government regulation has made<br />

capitalists smarter, by diversifying their portfolios but it has not been able to change their<br />

underlying tendencies.<br />

Team A: Of course capitalists will also try to pay the lowest wage possible. In most<br />

markets workers are replaceable, so if a laborer decides to leave heir employer because they<br />

refuse to accept a low wage, there is always another laborer in the market who will step<br />

in and take that job. Team B argues that this immediately leads to a certain uprising by<br />

the laborers and a revolution against the capitalists? Well, again the government steps in to<br />

appease the laborers. The government has many programs, such as welfare, that fill voids<br />

for the laborers created by their capitalist employers. These programs allow the laborers to<br />

meet their basic needs while selling their labor at a low wage to the capitalists.<br />

Possibly the most crucial aspect <strong>of</strong> the government’s intervention is that it is ever changing.<br />

Issues that exist today may not have been issues decades ago. In our day retirement<br />

plans and health benefits are almost demanded by certain laborers while in the early 1900’s<br />

these things were non-issues. The government constantly intervenes to appease the workers<br />

and avert any possibilities <strong>of</strong> a revolution by the laborers. This intervention will ensure that<br />

there is never an uprising or revolution by the laborers.<br />

Team B: This appeasement that you speak about cannot last forever, and you assume<br />

that government will always be able to appease. Instead look at the lack <strong>of</strong> ability by the<br />

government to appease currently, healthcare has been a major problem for at least the past<br />

decade and nothing has changed, employers have been able to not give benefits for a long<br />

time, the government is appeasing them, not the workers. Team A assumes that just because<br />

we have not had a revolution, that we will not have one, which is completely without basis,<br />

revolutions, especially for economic purposes occur frequently throughout the world. The<br />

current unrest at the inability <strong>of</strong> government to resolve even the basic issues supports the<br />

idea that a revolution is definitely possible, because government may reach a point when the<br />

capitalists, who are becoming fewer and fewer control the government and then only seek<br />

the exploitation and not appeasement. Appeasement by and large only delays the inevitable,<br />

it does not get rid <strong>of</strong> low wages or lack <strong>of</strong> ability to own land that the proletariat still face,<br />

government can mask capitalism to make it look like workers aren’t being exploited but that<br />

doesn’t mean that they actually aren’t.<br />

Conclusion: While true that during Marx’s time government intervention was solely looking<br />

out for the employers and not the employees, it is not so completely one-sided now.<br />

Minimum wage laws, child protection law and working day laws do protect the worker at<br />

least to some degree, giving them some slight power to be used to combat the bourgeoisie<br />

controlling the system. Revolutions are always possible, but the working class raising up to<br />

overthrow the “owners <strong>of</strong> production” is and will be unless it occurs a theological discussion<br />

where much can be discussed but facts can be given on both sides. Team B is obviously correct<br />

that patches are just that, merely patches and don’t actually fix the solution, but Team<br />

A uses that argument effectively to say that the government will always be able to patch just<br />

enough to ensure that no revolution ever takes place. Time, it appears, is the great sifter <strong>of</strong><br />

Marx’s theory.


294 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Message [778] referenced by [800] and [816]. Next Message by Alcameron is [795], Next Message by Samantha<br />

is [842], and First Message by Wasatch is [109].<br />

[800] Sparky: A Critique <strong>of</strong> Chapter 32 Term Paper. The essay [778] on chapter 32<br />

started out very well, explaining Marx’s thoughts on property and the general movement<br />

from lots <strong>of</strong> property owners to the progression <strong>of</strong> a few wealthy landowners. Moving into<br />

the history <strong>of</strong> Capitalist exploitation and the general unrest that it can produce through the<br />

exploitative process – and the leading up to a great revolution in which the future holds no<br />

place for capitalists.<br />

The term paper then splits into factions, teams A and B in which they take opposite views<br />

and provide a discuses them, which was very enjoying! But there where just a few points<br />

that I wanted to discuss that I felt lacked in the discussion they received in the paper. Team<br />

A states “impact <strong>of</strong> government intervention with regard to labor laws and workers rights<br />

differently” and continues the whole paper to discuss the how this is so, only once does Team<br />

B discuss how capitalist and government are really the same thing – “Because government<br />

may reach a point when the Capitalists. . . control the government” I personally feel that the<br />

may in this statement has come and gone, Capitalist are most certainly behind the helm <strong>of</strong><br />

the government and have been for a long long time – the founding fathers <strong>of</strong> the U.S. were<br />

all business men with substantial money and land – not to mention holders <strong>of</strong> slaves!<br />

Team A next says “Indirectly these government regulations effectively stop any revolution<br />

that would take place with the workers. By not allowing any one particular capitalist to<br />

control an entire market There are always alternatives for laborers who are unhappy.” Which<br />

to the worker is only saying if you don’t like it, then beat it. The powerlessness <strong>of</strong> the worker<br />

is shown in that statement, by all means you don’t have to love your job but at the same time<br />

you do not have to despise it. As for simply moving away and trying something else, well<br />

the capitalist will only be in the new location ready to exploit you even if you can afford to<br />

move – which the capitalist is trying to stop you from doing!<br />

Team A continues with “government steps in to appease the laborers. The government<br />

has many programs, such as welfare,” “These programs allow the laborers to meet their basic<br />

needs while selling their labor at a low wage to the capitalists.” Meaning a simple worker is<br />

nothing but a slave to the system! Always forced to take scraps thrown to them by others, the<br />

reason a worker works is to provide for him/herself and their family why should you work<br />

if that still does not provide! As far as the benefits go, they are still being paid by an amount<br />

being taken out <strong>of</strong> your paycheck as well as taxes – and at this point <strong>of</strong> time large capitalists<br />

are <strong>of</strong>ten paying less taxes than regular workers! “This intervention will ensure that there<br />

is never an uprising or revolution by the laborers” Hardly the case Team A this intervention<br />

I believe is only stoking the embers <strong>of</strong> revolution, keeping them nice and hot and ready to<br />

burst into fire.<br />

First Message by Sparky is [66].<br />

[816] Tim: graded A discussion <strong>of</strong> Samantha’s term paper. In reading Samantha’s paper<br />

[778] I was impressed with how the group was able to look at both sides <strong>of</strong> the issue and<br />

argue both sides. I think that both groups were able to present their opinions and both groups<br />

were able to give valid arguments as to the tendencies and habits <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. The topic<br />

<strong>of</strong> the two group’s arguments is a very interesting one because <strong>of</strong> the fact that government


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 295<br />

intervention seems to care about certain monopolies and not others. Group A did a good job<br />

at describing the impact that government intervention has had on stopping the revolt <strong>of</strong> free<br />

laborers. I think that they agreed with Marx but said that he would probably change his mind<br />

were he to see the regulations that are in place today. I think that it would be hard to know<br />

what Marx would think but I am sure that, just as group B stated, Marx would not agree<br />

that Wal-Mart is properly regulated today. Group B was able to effectively use Wal-Mart<br />

as an example <strong>of</strong> how government regulation has no effect on certain companies. To Marx,<br />

Wal-Mart is the Capitalist Monster that we should all stay away from and I think group B<br />

effectively showed that regulation does not solve any problems it only delays them. I think<br />

that both groups showed very good arguments and did a fine job.<br />

First Message by Tim is [339].<br />

Term Paper 710 is 933 in 2000fa, 933 in 2001fa, 833 in 2002fa, 833 in 2003fa, 833 in<br />

2004fa, 833 in 2005fa, 730 in 2007SP, 702 in 2007fa, 714 in 2008fa, 746 in 2009fa, 813<br />

in 2010fa, 840 in 2011fa, and 870 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 710 Essay about Chapter Thirty-Three: Modern Theory <strong>of</strong> Colonization<br />

[770] Bennett: At the beginning <strong>of</strong> chapter 33 Marx introduces to the reader that there<br />

are two distinctly different types <strong>of</strong> private property. The first kind <strong>of</strong> property is what we<br />

as a society generally view as our private property. It is the property that is strictly used for<br />

the survival <strong>of</strong> the owner, for example food, clothing and shelter. This type <strong>of</strong> property is<br />

a direct result <strong>of</strong> the owner’s labor, rather than exploiting hired laborers and pr<strong>of</strong>iting from<br />

them. The second type <strong>of</strong> private property is a capitalist owned property that is entirely<br />

dedicated to the generation <strong>of</strong> capital by using the surplus-value taken from the capitalist’s<br />

wage-earners. In both <strong>of</strong> these examples <strong>of</strong> private property, wealth in generated by labor.<br />

Marx explains that the capitalist property owner’s pursuit <strong>of</strong> capital (second type <strong>of</strong> private<br />

property) eventually squashes the first type <strong>of</strong> private property.<br />

Next, Marx talks about colonization. He gives two examples <strong>of</strong> colonizing. The first is<br />

the capitalistic way, using machinery and thousands <strong>of</strong> working-class citizens to labor for<br />

the betterment <strong>of</strong> the colony. The second way is these working-class citizens working the<br />

land that they live on for themselves. Producing their own means to live with their own<br />

unexploited labor. Marx explains that the first way <strong>of</strong> colonization does not work, the means<br />

through which the workers would be exploited and used by the capitalist were not set in<br />

place, and rather this way backfires. The second way is much better and highly productive.<br />

When the workers work for themselves they are much more productive because if they do<br />

not succeed then they will not live. If the workers work the land for themselves the only<br />

incentive they need is that they control their quality <strong>of</strong> life.<br />

Wakefield continues this point, explaining that in the new colonies the capital produced<br />

only becomes capital when it is exploited. Before its exploitation it is a product <strong>of</strong> necessity<br />

to the laborer that produced it. But Wakefield thinks that there aren’t very many workers to be<br />

exploited in the new colonies. People came to these colonies to make their own way <strong>of</strong> life.<br />

Wakefield says it best “If all members <strong>of</strong> the society are supposed to possess equal portions<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital ... no man would have a motive for accumulating more capital than he could use<br />

with his own hands. This is to some extent the case in new American settlements, where a


296 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

passion for owning land prevents the existence <strong>of</strong> a class <strong>of</strong> laborers for hire.” (Capital Chap.<br />

33)<br />

Because there was a lack <strong>of</strong> workers for hire in the American Colonies, Wakefield believes<br />

that this is why slavery began in the US. Plantation owners needed workers that could work<br />

their lands for cheap wages and at the same time produce a high number <strong>of</strong> crops and in turn<br />

a large amount <strong>of</strong> capital. But there was a lack <strong>of</strong> workers for hire so sadly slavery was the<br />

answer for nearly all plantation owners.<br />

This chapter was interesting to me because Marx explained the difference between the<br />

two types <strong>of</strong> personal property and what ways and strategies were used successfully and<br />

unsuccessfully in the colonization processes.<br />

Bmellor: You talk about how Marx investigates the differences between the two property types. Why are these<br />

two definitions <strong>of</strong> private property necessary? Marx makes a point that the capitalist has in essence destroyed and<br />

deprived the ability <strong>of</strong> the individual worker’s own private property. Marx gives his explanation for coming to this<br />

conclusion by defining the differences between these two property types. And as you said the first type <strong>of</strong> property<br />

is owned and used by the owner for his personal benefit, the second is more devious and is used to exploit the labor<br />

<strong>of</strong> others. Wakefield’s solution to the labor shortage, Marx uses to show the hypocrisy <strong>of</strong> the system.<br />

Hans: Lots <strong>of</strong> connections missed, and you didn’t even get to the punchline <strong>of</strong> the chapter, the policies which<br />

Wakefield proposed for the colonies.<br />

First Message by Bennett is [175].<br />

[779] Chrisw, Ryoung, and Sparky: Term Paper – Colonization. Has capitalism always<br />

existed? Some have said that capitalism has existed ever since the beginning <strong>of</strong> the fall <strong>of</strong><br />

Adam, while others say that it continues to evolve. But has capitalism always existed in<br />

all places at all times? Was capitalism in existence at the conception <strong>of</strong> all countries and<br />

settlements? Or did it evolve slowly from the market place?<br />

Capitalism in the early settlement <strong>of</strong> the colonies took upon a transition phase; in fact<br />

capitalism really did not even exist at its conception! England, the mother country as E.G.<br />

Wakefield calls it, was capitalist society at its peak! At that time in England private property<br />

consisted <strong>of</strong> two different kinds, one <strong>of</strong> which was something made from the labor <strong>of</strong> the<br />

producer himself, and the other was in the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the labor <strong>of</strong> others for personal<br />

gain.<br />

At the conception <strong>of</strong> the colonies only the first type <strong>of</strong> private property existed consistently.<br />

The very producer himself and which did not involve the exploitation <strong>of</strong> labor by<br />

anyone else produced private property that existed without exploitative means. Because <strong>of</strong><br />

this, a capitalist society did not have the means to exist since capitalism can’t thrive without<br />

the exploitation <strong>of</strong> others and their labor, and this is why capitalism did not have the foundation<br />

in which it could grow during the earlier times <strong>of</strong> the colonies. The wage laborer is an<br />

essential cornerstone to the capitalist it would seem, since when a man who is not compelled<br />

to sell himself out <strong>of</strong> his own free will there can be no extortion <strong>of</strong> him by another.<br />

Although E.G. Wakefield believed that England tried some time to enforce the Act <strong>of</strong> Parliament,<br />

which aimed at manufacturing wage-laborers in the colonies, it did not last. Most<br />

<strong>of</strong> those that came over from England were those that came for the very reason capitalism<br />

was failing, the opportunity to own their own land and to produce their own goods. This act<br />

<strong>of</strong> trying to exploit those in the colonies was known as systematic colonization. The people<br />

that came over to the colonies depended on their own hands and their land to provide for the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 297<br />

necessities <strong>of</strong> life another. Wakefield’s example is brought in which merely states that when<br />

there is plenty <strong>of</strong> land for many to own, there is absolutely no reason for that man to sell<br />

himself to another since can provide for himself. Whereas in Europe the average man – read<br />

worker, does not own his own homestead and cannot accumulate for himself.<br />

During this time extra capital was not produced by the means <strong>of</strong> others working to producing<br />

goods at time/piece wages for others. The majority <strong>of</strong> the labor that was performed<br />

was the labor that was accomplished by the owners themselves. In fact most <strong>of</strong> the people<br />

who needed clothes, furniture, housing, food, and supplies would not go to the store and<br />

purchase their goods they would construct or grow them for themselves. They were a selfsufficient<br />

people that did not depend on the labor or goods <strong>of</strong> others to survive. Because <strong>of</strong><br />

this and the lack <strong>of</strong> wage labor there was not much <strong>of</strong> a market place and therefore there was<br />

not a foundation for a capitalist society to exist.<br />

With a free colony, where one simply has to set foot and claim a piece <strong>of</strong> land as his<br />

own, while still leaving the same opportunity for any others that follow in his path, this was<br />

the ability that made them so much more resistant to capitalism, since that automatically<br />

decreases the available supply <strong>of</strong> wage laborers, since many <strong>of</strong> these free men and woman<br />

till there own soil as well as practice many other trades/skills such as homemaking, furniture<br />

making, candle making, etc.<br />

Whereas in Europe there is a whole population <strong>of</strong> wage laborers that merely reproduce<br />

another generation <strong>of</strong> wage laborers, and even produces a surplus <strong>of</strong> these wage laborers,<br />

keeping capitalist exploitation secure by making the workers dependent <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. But<br />

is not the case in the Americas, since every new generation has more than enough room to<br />

grow outward into unclaimed land (disregarding Native Americans who have already spent<br />

thousands <strong>of</strong> years living there <strong>of</strong> course) and still leaving the wage labour population not<br />

only under populated but in a position <strong>of</strong> always losing workers to the freedom <strong>of</strong> owning<br />

there own land and living in such a way that the capitalist is not required. And even if<br />

the capitalist were to “import” his own supply <strong>of</strong> wage laborers to do his bidding, there is<br />

nothing stopping them form simply walking out the door and into the great wide open which<br />

was America and staking there own claim! Leaving the capitalist in a position <strong>of</strong> always<br />

wanting a simply and servant worker to do his will with out fear <strong>of</strong> him simply leaving him<br />

in need. And could eventual become his rival!<br />

Wakefield goes on to say that the Americans are in a woeful state whose own independence<br />

and fragmentation will work against them, since no great undertaking can ever take<br />

place since there is no capitol or dependable wage earner to provide the necessary work to<br />

accomplish the great task, since the means <strong>of</strong> production was split amongst so many! Then<br />

starts to explain that if only a steady source <strong>of</strong> poor, unknowing immigrants where in ready<br />

supply would with which to draw a steady supply <strong>of</strong> labor would a great work be carried<br />

out! States Capitol in an example provide by Wakefield.<br />

But Wakefield’s descriptions <strong>of</strong> American people do not show the lowly, underfed and<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten uneducated stock <strong>of</strong> the European worker, but a people <strong>of</strong> “well to do, independent,<br />

enterprising, and comparatively cultured” persons. Going on to say that in England <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

time a workhorse is better fed that a farm worker!


298 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

The beginning <strong>of</strong> the end is set into motion for the free and plentiful Americans. Where<br />

the colony no longer lets you merely stake your claim and take land for yourself wherever<br />

you feel, but rather you must pay the colony for any land that you may wish to own to<br />

the government, setting any new immigrants in a position where they must become a wage<br />

laborer as soon as they arrive for a period <strong>of</strong> time significant enough for the capitalist to take<br />

a large share <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its from, to become a dependent worker <strong>of</strong> the system for a long period<br />

<strong>of</strong> time before they have any hopes <strong>of</strong> becoming the independent land owner that was so<br />

easily obtained in the past.<br />

Under this plan, put forth by Wakefield, the worker population would be constant, with<br />

the price <strong>of</strong> land just out <strong>of</strong> reach for the typical time-wage worker so as to create the situation<br />

where they must work for years instead <strong>of</strong> months or even days like in the old system. But<br />

the true advantage <strong>of</strong> this situation is that the wage laborers would produce more capital<br />

than that which they started from, producing more capital for more workers, coming in the<br />

future, to work with! Holding the people at ransom for something that Nature simple had<br />

given and could be taken at will, the price tag put upon the land by the government, primitive<br />

accumulation, was a tool which capitalism used to begin its reign upon the Americas.<br />

All this has made America no longer the “promised land” for people trying to leave<br />

behind the great aristocrats <strong>of</strong> Europe, but rather a Capitalist haven, starting fresh with all<br />

the mistakes and problems <strong>of</strong> the past washed away and left them with a fresh population <strong>of</strong><br />

excess workers to do the work <strong>of</strong> a few. But the colonization <strong>of</strong> the Americas simply proved<br />

to show that the Capitalist system <strong>of</strong> production and accumulation does not have to be a part<br />

<strong>of</strong> life, and that an individual worker, working for him self truly can succeed.<br />

Message [779] referenced by [828]. First Message by Chrisw is [779], Next Message by Ryoung is [819], and Next<br />

Message by Sparky is [800].<br />

Question 712 is 220 in 1996ut, 301 in 1997sp, 297 in 1998WI, 729 in 2008fa, 830 in<br />

2010fa, 858 in 2011fa, and 892 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 712 Is a capitalist free to decide whether to expand his business, and how much<br />

<strong>of</strong> his pr<strong>of</strong>it to use for personal consumption? Which mechanisms, if any, constrain him or<br />

her?<br />

[701] Ryoung: Is a Capitalist Free to Decide? Is a capitalist free to decide whether to<br />

expand his business, and how much <strong>of</strong> his pr<strong>of</strong>it to use for personal consumption? According<br />

to our readings a capitalist is not free to decide whether to expand his business because<br />

there are more factors that influence an expansion than a mere decision. Any person in the<br />

world is free to chose whether or not they will try to expand their business, and they can do<br />

everything in their power to help that business expand but that does not necessarily equate to<br />

expansion. For example in order for a business to expand there must be: production, labor,<br />

consumer confidence, consumption, quality products, capital, etc... Some <strong>of</strong> these factors<br />

we can control but the majority <strong>of</strong> them we can only influence if we are lucky. We can not<br />

control the amount <strong>of</strong> consumption, or the consumer confidence, or the state <strong>of</strong> the economy,<br />

we can only hope that all those factors line up so that it will help us sell our products which<br />

will help us expand our business. This is why we can’t exactly control all expansion we can<br />

only attempt to expand and hope that everything else allows us to do so.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 299<br />

Is it up to the business owner to decide how much pr<strong>of</strong>it he can use for personal consumption?<br />

Yes it is up to the business owner to decide how much pr<strong>of</strong>it he will consume but<br />

it should depend on his financial commitments and his goals for his business. If an owner<br />

finds himself in a time <strong>of</strong> desired expansion he will have to be willing to consume less <strong>of</strong><br />

his pr<strong>of</strong>its so that the business may benefit. He should also have to see that all his financial<br />

commitments are met first before he decides to take all his pr<strong>of</strong>its. This is a plain question<br />

that should be answered easily by each individual business owner however I believe that it<br />

is not handled by all business owners in the appropriate way. Many let the money and greed<br />

get to them which causes them to be dishonest. This greed dishonesty cripples their business<br />

and those that are involved with it.<br />

Hans: Despite your caveats that individual efforts cannot necessarily make things happen, capitalism acts in many<br />

cases like a dream come true for the most greedy individuals. I.e., there is some concordance between individual<br />

greed and capitalist social structures. The capitalist is the beneficiary <strong>of</strong> social structures which he didn’t set<br />

up, although he may be politically active trying to maintain them or to get additional goodies from government.<br />

Question 712 tries to explore how far this concordance goes. Does capitalist individual decision making have a say<br />

in the social rate <strong>of</strong> accumulation, or is this ratio determined by economic factors?<br />

Message [701] referenced by [704], [705], [764], and [2008fa:1083]. Next Message by Ryoung is [779].<br />

[704] Dentist: beaten to the punch. Well much to my surprise, between checking for<br />

already submitted responses to this question and my own composition <strong>of</strong> such, Ryoung [701]<br />

has beaten me to the proverbial punch. Rather than revise my submission, I have chosen to<br />

submit it as is.<br />

Upon selecting this question, I became quite surprised to find that there has been little<br />

attention (at best) given to this question. I suppose my interest in questions surrounding<br />

freedom isn’t as popular as I would have hoped.<br />

In any case, I did find one little blurb mentioned by Hans as a response to a submission<br />

made back in 1998 (IDAHO [1998WI:259]).<br />

The phrasing <strong>of</strong> the question seems to imply an answer <strong>of</strong> yes he has some freedom, but is<br />

ultimately constrained by. . . something. And I would say that yes, the capitalist is ultimately<br />

free to choose in both cases. However, there are also at least two forces, which can constrain<br />

or influence these decisions.<br />

Hans has suggested these two mechanisms that restrain the capitalist’s freedom, firstly,<br />

internal drive. This can be defined in many different ways; greed, competitive nature, and<br />

passion are a few that immediately come to mind. So how will these internal natures restrict<br />

a capitalist’s freedom? Not too surprisingly, ALL seem to lead him toward the same end,<br />

MAXIMIZATION!<br />

I suppose I should clarify the definitions <strong>of</strong> my various “internal drives”. By “greedy<br />

capitalist,” I mean a an owner who uses every conceivable avenue to find some way to put<br />

another dollar in his pocket.<br />

I use the term “passionate” to describe an owner who truly loves what he does/produces or<br />

believes that his business can positively change something. Finally, the competitively driven<br />

capitalist; this is the business owner who driven to win, he draws his feelings <strong>of</strong> satisfaction<br />

from the defeat <strong>of</strong> others


300 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Let’s take for one example the greedy capitalist case, here we find a business owner who<br />

is sucking every possible penny from his business so that he may take it home and consume;<br />

he is maximizing HIS pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

In addition to the internal drive, there is external necessity. And just like internal drive,<br />

the ultimate end is maximization and expansion. However, the reason for the results here<br />

can be identified as the results <strong>of</strong> collisions between the various internally driven capitalists<br />

within the same industry.<br />

Building the case <strong>of</strong> our greedy capitalist scenario; he will continue to take the sum <strong>of</strong> the<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its home to support his lavish lifestyle until threats from either the passionate capitalist<br />

or the competitive capitalist arise. Now in order to support his way <strong>of</strong> life, he must sacrifice<br />

some pr<strong>of</strong>its in order to fund an expansionary effort and stay in business and continue to<br />

sustain his appetites.<br />

In the end, because <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system and its demands for infinite<br />

growth, one way or another the result is always maximization.<br />

Message [704] referenced by [705], [2008fa:1083], and [2008fa:1169]. Next Message by Dentist is [740].<br />

[705] Sparky: A capitalist that forces himself on you. The first part <strong>of</strong> this question is<br />

very intresting since you can look at it from the Marx stand point while still looking at it<br />

from a more business-capitalistic point <strong>of</strong> view, having a foot on both sides if you will. First<br />

<strong>of</strong>f Ryoung [701] did go through Marx’s statement <strong>of</strong> why a capitalist cannot expand their<br />

business, and I will only touch on some <strong>of</strong> those aspect since he did a fair job explaining<br />

them in his e-mail. Since Marx’s time we have been in a world <strong>of</strong> Rockefellers, Gates,<br />

and the like who have taken a proactive stance to the factors Ryoung mentioned – such as<br />

production, labor, and consumer confidence. They have started “vertical monopolies” where<br />

they do control the whole process from literally the ground up through production to as far<br />

as consumption by taking hold <strong>of</strong> the whole market and forcing the use <strong>of</strong> their products<br />

on the masses through moves through the goverment and advertising as well muscling out<br />

the competiton or the goverment into protecting their business. While Dentist’s response<br />

[704] to the question brings in other forces which he stated as internal drive and then gave a<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> that as “an owner who uses every conceivable avenue to find some way to put<br />

another dollar in his pocket” but then brings in the aspect <strong>of</strong> maximising his money while<br />

reveling in the defeat <strong>of</strong> his competitors! While I do agree with his definition <strong>of</strong> internal<br />

drive I do have to disagree with his <strong>of</strong> maximization – Above I brought in the example<br />

<strong>of</strong> vertical monopolies – which control every aspect <strong>of</strong> production in order to ensure their<br />

survival, while at first there is many, over time it slowly becomes a much smaller number<br />

– How can this be if every business is trying to line its pockets while still maximizing its<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its? It is done by undercutting the competion with lower prices at first and then once<br />

defeating them, they by bringing prices up to whatever level they can achieve where the<br />

truly “greedy capitalist” pokes his head out <strong>of</strong> the hole and enjoys the maximization part <strong>of</strong><br />

the capitalist culture.<br />

Ryoung’s statement “This is why we can’t exactly control all expansion we can only<br />

attempt to expand and hope that everything else allows us to do so.” does have a kernel <strong>of</strong><br />

truth, just because you are expanding does not mean as a business that you are prospering,<br />

times and technology change – A company building ham radios would have a hard time


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 301<br />

maintaning business let alone expanding business! But a extremely large company, say GM,<br />

does have the political clout and resources to put up a fight in which many fighting it could<br />

not handle!<br />

As for the second part <strong>of</strong> this question how much <strong>of</strong> a capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>it can he use for his<br />

own personal consumption? I believe Ryoung hit it right on the nose, but I would like to add<br />

the comment that businesses, and business owners, go bankrupt without a change in there<br />

personal spending. And some <strong>of</strong> the larger companies, such as automakers, were laying <strong>of</strong>f<br />

thousands <strong>of</strong> employees while giving themselves bonuses <strong>of</strong> millions <strong>of</strong> dollars<br />

Next Message by Sparky is [779].<br />

[764] Nstew: Expansion. A capitalist is free to decide whether to expand his business<br />

and how much <strong>of</strong> his pr<strong>of</strong>it to use for personal consumptions. Once a capitalist has surplus<br />

capital he can either use the surplus capital for his own personal use or he can reinvest it<br />

back into his company.<br />

In order for the capitalist to expand his business he needs to reinvest his surplus-capital<br />

back into his business. If he does not have surplus-capital then he needs to come up with<br />

capital (money) in order to expand. This expansion takes place by buying more products or<br />

materials than he has in the past to be produced. After buying more materials he then needs<br />

to hire more laborers to produce the extra materials into the commodity he is selling.<br />

Assuming the capitalist has access to excess capital in order to buy more materials than<br />

he did the year before and is able to find more labor-power there is also the aspect <strong>of</strong> supply<br />

and demand that is necessary for expansion as well. The market has a certain amount <strong>of</strong><br />

demand for a product or service and if the demand is higher than what the capitalist has been<br />

supplying in the past then this will allow him to expand and be pr<strong>of</strong>itable.<br />

Hans: Your contribution is in a similar spirit as Ryoung’s [701], which sparked an interesting discussion. Your<br />

disregrd <strong>of</strong> this discussion affected your grade.<br />

Next Message by Nstew is [789].<br />

Question 713 is 716 in 2008fa, 749 in 2009fa, 817 in 2010fa, 844 in 2011fa, and 874 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

Question 713 Which use-values must be available on the market so that accumulation <strong>of</strong><br />

capital can take place?<br />

[699] Ryoung: Accumulation <strong>of</strong> Capital. We learn that in order to be able to accumulate<br />

capital there must be three things present! Number one we know that in order to create<br />

more capital the decisions <strong>of</strong> the individual capitalist must be willing to reinvest some <strong>of</strong> his<br />

proceeds to create more products to be sold. That is that if I make $100.00 <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> selling my<br />

yarn that I have spun I must be willing to return 60% <strong>of</strong> the proceeds back into the cost <strong>of</strong><br />

production so that I can continue to spin and sell more yarn. This is a simple concept that is<br />

standard in most businesses.<br />

Number two I must be able to provide products to the market in order for them to sell.<br />

Once I spin and finish making my yarn I have to provide my yarn to the market in order<br />

for it to be sold.


302 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

And number three I have to have the labor power available in order for the yarn to be<br />

produced. An idea is only as good as and idea until you put it to work or start to produce it.<br />

I may have the best idea in the world to produce the best yarn the world has ever seen but if<br />

I don’t have the means/power to produce it it will remain an idea until I have the power to<br />

do so! This is one reason that I would have to be willing to reinvest some <strong>of</strong> my proceeds<br />

in order continue to produce. I would have to provide wages for the labor worked by the<br />

workers. Not only would I have to provide wages but I would have to provide enough wages<br />

in order to make them happy so that they may continue producing this yarn at a sufficient<br />

quality!<br />

These three reasons are essential in order to be able to continue to accumulate wealth.<br />

Message [699] referenced by [748]. Next Message by Ryoung is [701].<br />

[748] Jenn: graded A Accumulation <strong>of</strong> Capital. I think Ryoung in [699] has the right<br />

answers, but they could be clarified better. He addresses three reasons that must be present,<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> use-values as the question asked.<br />

With respect to his first reason, he says we must have capital. However, I believe we have<br />

to revisit the question “what is capital” if we want to use the word capital as a use-value. In<br />

[2001fa:226], Cleo says “Capital is the sum <strong>of</strong> values, money, that expand by going through<br />

a social process, that allows their value to increase.” Although I think one could argue that<br />

capital is a use-value, since capital is actually a money commodity, one must have money as<br />

a use-value in order to accumulate capital.<br />

The most important use-value that must be available on the market is labor-power. The<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital is the application <strong>of</strong> surplus-value as capital, and its<br />

reconversion <strong>of</strong> capital. This is not possible without the use-value <strong>of</strong> labor-power. As Marx<br />

states, “It is only necessary for capital to incorporate this additional labor-power, annually<br />

supplied by the working-class in the shape <strong>of</strong> laborers <strong>of</strong> all ages.” Surplus-value is used<br />

to purchase the means <strong>of</strong> production and pay the workers to provide labor-power. Surplus<br />

labor, or unpaid-labor results in a surplus-product. This surplus product is then sold and<br />

converted to capital, thus completing the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital. Labor-power is the only<br />

commodity that has the ability to provide surplus-value to the capitalist.<br />

Additionally, the means <strong>of</strong> production are another use-value that must be available on<br />

the market in order for accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital to occur. In order for the labor-power to be<br />

a use-value to the capitalist, the capitalist must have the means <strong>of</strong> production in which the<br />

labor-power can be applied.<br />

One interesting question that could be brought up is with respect to the stock market.<br />

If you put money into the stock market, you can accumulate more capital. This can be<br />

done without means <strong>of</strong> production or labor-power. Or perhaps the image <strong>of</strong> labor-power and<br />

production is so far removed, it is easy to overlook. Any thoughts?<br />

Message [748] referenced by [2008fa:1096], [2008fa:1166], [2009fa:1098], and [2010fa:1005]. Next Message by<br />

Jenn is [750].<br />

[765] Bar: graded B– surplus use value. The question is which <strong>of</strong> the use-values must<br />

be available to the market for these conditions to exist, therefore knowing that use-value is


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 303<br />

necessary value not conspicuous consumption. Essentially, what occurs is a use-value commodity<br />

like food has to be produced outside <strong>of</strong> its natural supply and demand. If it were not<br />

so, there would be no surplus value to reinvest, it would be a zero sum game, complete cancellation.<br />

This is a perversion <strong>of</strong> the market because it is more than fulfilling a need, food for<br />

example is overproduced when an individual only needs a certain amount to be comfortable<br />

and if more food is not consumed capitalists will be unable to invest pr<strong>of</strong>its; the capitalists<br />

are unnaturally glutting the market (pardon the pun). If an unnatural market doesn’t exist<br />

there will not be accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital “In one word surplus value is convertible into<br />

capital solely because the surplus-product, whose value it is already comprises the material<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> capital.” This goes hand in hand obviously with labor surplus contributing more<br />

to the exploitation <strong>of</strong> the worker through the perpetuation <strong>of</strong> overproduction.<br />

Hans: Your theory that pr<strong>of</strong>its come from overconsumption is original and interesting, but it has nothing to do with<br />

Marx.<br />

Next Message by Bar is [814].<br />

Question 716 is 719 in 2008fa, 752 in 2009fa, 820 in 2010fa, 847 in 2011fa, and 877 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

Question 716 How can the capitalist be compared with a conqueror who buys commodities<br />

from the conquered with the money he has robbed from them?<br />

[678] Matt: Like a thief in the night. When I think <strong>of</strong> the capitalist I think <strong>of</strong> only one<br />

thing after taking this class, the rich stealing from the poor. The capitalist is only thinking<br />

<strong>of</strong> his own wants and desires, and does not care who he pushes down on his way to the<br />

top. He is nothing more than a thief, stealing labor-power to create surplus-value from his<br />

workers. The Annotations say, this “is not only unpaid labor, but even the capital hiring this<br />

labor comes originally from the laborer himself.” The capitalist is stealing the surplus-value<br />

created by the worker to maintain his own unstoppable production <strong>of</strong> the commodity. Again,<br />

it is this stolen surplus-value that is used to fund all the additional labor-power hired by the<br />

capitalist. Each worker creates enough surplus-value to hire the next worker and the next,<br />

like a domino effect. This is why Marx says every conqueror (capitalist) has used the money<br />

(surplus-value) from the conquered (worker) to buy the commodity (labor-power).<br />

Message [678] referenced by [2009fa:1083]. Next Message by Matt is [698].<br />

[679] FacistFrank: When I think about this statement, at first it didn’t make sense. How<br />

does the capitalist buy commodities, isn’t it the other way around? But then I thought about<br />

it, and the capitalist is buying the commodity that the laborer produces at a very low price,<br />

with the surplus value from the last goods that the laborers produced, hence the theft. The<br />

commodity is worth much more because it had a lot more effort and labor used to produce<br />

it.<br />

However I think that Nstew [647] brings up some good points. I don’t know if this is<br />

what he is trying to say, or maybe it’s in my own terms. There are degrees <strong>of</strong> capitalist<br />

exploitation, some capitalists, or perhaps they are not even capitalists, but a higher cog in<br />

the wheel <strong>of</strong> workers. Anyway some capitalists do not make any pr<strong>of</strong>it, but make losses,<br />

because the market they are in is too competitive. Because the big capitalist like Walmart<br />

uses the massive amounts <strong>of</strong> surplus value they have stolen to make their prices very low.<br />

Which means the small capitalist or small business owner, either has to lower the price <strong>of</strong>


304 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

his good to match and can’t cover the costs <strong>of</strong> production, or keeps his price the same and<br />

doesn’t sell any product and doesn’t cover the cost <strong>of</strong> production. This guy is stuck with<br />

all the debt and liability. I guess the important question is this man a capitalist or another<br />

exploited member <strong>of</strong> the system in a different form than the laborer? Or perhaps a failed<br />

capitalist?<br />

I also think that minimum wage laws ensure that the worker is given some amount <strong>of</strong> the<br />

surplus labor, he is given a very small portion <strong>of</strong> it, just a little above the reproduction cost<br />

<strong>of</strong> his labor, but he still gets a little.<br />

What I think is really frustrating is that, if a business like Macdonald’s takes 10 billion<br />

in pr<strong>of</strong>it one year, then only makes 10 million the next, the year is considered a failure, and<br />

changes have to be made, it’s still stolen pr<strong>of</strong>it! They can’t be content with stealing just a<br />

little, they have to steal a massive amount. If a new CEO was responsible for this loss in<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it, the stockholders would fire him quick and replace him with the guy that was stealing<br />

10 billion. It makes it really hard to do the right thing in our society.<br />

Hans: The capitalist is not buying the product from the laborer. As I said in [655] and elsewhere, the product<br />

never belongs to the laborer, because the laborer has sold his labor-power. I.e., the commodity the capitalist buys is<br />

labor-power. But before the workers get too happy about it that the capitalist invests his surplus-value into buying<br />

more labor-power, Marx reminds them that the surplus-value was robbed from them. I.e., the capitalist first robs<br />

the laborers and then turns around and buys labor-power from the workers with the money—or surplus-value—he<br />

has robbed from them.<br />

Next Message by FacistFrank is [688].<br />

[697] Brandon: graded B Wal-Mart. I’ve noticed a lot <strong>of</strong> reference to Wal-Mart recently<br />

in these discussion, in fact, I just got done with [696] responding to a free discussion regarding<br />

them. I think that the really important thing to remember about Wal-Mart is that they<br />

have broken a boundary in capitalism for which there has never been a precedent. Wal-Mart<br />

is one <strong>of</strong> the largest corporations in the world today, and they do not produce a single thing.<br />

They are retailers. The retail business has been nothing but middlemen for producers, who<br />

sell goods at prices set by the producers based on supply and demand models. Yet somehow<br />

Wal-Mart has been able to create an authoritative power over producers, essentially dictating<br />

the price that they will sell the product at.<br />

We should look at the Rubbermaid case. Rubbermaid entered an exclusive agreement<br />

with Wal-Mart in the 1990s. Wal-Mart dictating the prices that they would sell the products<br />

at and Rubbermaid agreed. But when the cost <strong>of</strong> resin – a raw material essential to plastic<br />

production – rose, Rubbermaid had to raise prices in order to recover production costs. Wal-<br />

Mart refused to raise prices on Rubbermaid products, and even dropped many Rubbermaid<br />

products from its shelves as punishment. In short, Rubbermaid was forced into a merger<br />

with Newell just to save its own skin.<br />

Is this the rich stealing from the poor, as the question suggests? Yes and no. Rubbermaid<br />

was by no means a poor, small company. However by entering these types <strong>of</strong> agreements<br />

with name-brand producers, Wal-Mart is stealing from the smaller retailers who are rapidly<br />

becomming conquered. The relationship <strong>of</strong> conqueror:conquered is Wal-Mart:other retailers.<br />

It is almost impossible, to create a “mom and pop” retail store in the same town that<br />

has a Wal-Mart. The city <strong>of</strong> Heber, here in <strong>Utah</strong>, has been fighting for years to prevent Wal-<br />

Mart from entering their community; a community that thrives on small business. Grocers,


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 305<br />

auto parts suppliers, clothing shops, electronics stores, etc are all affected by Wal-Mart’s<br />

influence. The real question is, does this go against or perfectly coincide with free market<br />

economics? Where is the line for success? I honestly do not have a direct answer to these<br />

questions, but I would say Wal-Mart is challenging the laws <strong>of</strong> the free market to a high<br />

degree.<br />

Hans: Good little essay, but it is a little <strong>of</strong>f-topic regarding question 716.<br />

Message [697] referenced by [Answer:12]. First Message by Brandon is [68].<br />

Question 717 is 720 in 2008fa, 753 in 2009fa, 821 in 2010fa, 848 in 2011fa, and 878 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

Question 717 In what way must the laborer “buy back the fruits <strong>of</strong> his previous labor with<br />

more labor than they cost”?<br />

[739] Aaron: Buy back the fruits <strong>of</strong> my labor. This is an interesting conundrum in<br />

basically any market around the world. A capitalist who owns the means <strong>of</strong> production in any<br />

market with any product, must make his pr<strong>of</strong>its by selling a commodity for more than what<br />

it costs to produce the commodity. If it costs 10 dollars to make a book bag, the capitalist<br />

would not sell his book bag in the market for 10 dollars... if he did this, he would make no<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it and therefore would not be a capitalist. He must sell his book bag for more than 10<br />

dollars in order to make pr<strong>of</strong>its and stay in business. Therefore, if a laborer, who produced<br />

the book bag, was in the marketplace and wanted to buy the book bag, he/she would have to<br />

pay the going market price that the capitalist is willing to sell it for, for example 15 dollars.<br />

Therefore, the worker knows what went into the production <strong>of</strong> the book bag, and some <strong>of</strong><br />

the costs (because the worker would know his or her own wage), but he cannot buy it for<br />

that price. The retail price in the market must be paid. Thus, the laborer cannot buy back the<br />

fruits <strong>of</strong> his own labor at the costs <strong>of</strong> his own labor, he must pay money that he has earned<br />

in producing the book bag.<br />

Bmellor: This is a great analogy, however you are also forgetting that if it costs 10 dollars to make the bag (labor,<br />

materials, and the overhead associated with means <strong>of</strong> production) the laborer makes far less than 10 dollars. So even<br />

if the bag was sold at cost he would not be able to buy it back for what he made on that particular bag. Meaning that<br />

even if the means <strong>of</strong> production were socially owned the laborer would not be able to buy back the bag for what he<br />

was compensated on that bag.<br />

Message [739] referenced by [754]. Next Message by Aaron is [838].<br />

[754] Inter: Surplus-value: a follow-up to Aaron’s answer. I agree with Aaron’s conclusion<br />

in [739], but I will elaborate on the context in which Marx came to the conclusion<br />

that the laborer “must buy back the fruits <strong>of</strong> his previous labor with more labor than they<br />

cost.” The context to this conclusion is important because the concept <strong>of</strong> capital being created<br />

by capital, illustrates an exponential growth <strong>of</strong> capital and a further reaching exploitation <strong>of</strong><br />

the worker, which is manifested by this conclusion.<br />

Imagine our working-day time line A—B-C, as representing the annual production for<br />

a capitalist. B-C represents the annual surplus-product, and when sold for money, the<br />

surplus-value. Marx 728:3 describes surplus-product as “tribute annually extracted from<br />

the working-class by the capitalist-class.” The surplus-value then becomes reinvested by the<br />

capitalists (either by the original capitalist or a new one) in the form <strong>of</strong> purchasing <strong>of</strong> commodities,<br />

and bringing in additional labor. Later the investment will also realize a surplusvalue<br />

as well as the original investment. Thus we see the exponential growth <strong>of</strong> the capitalist


306 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

using free-labor to generate more capital. The idea <strong>of</strong> surplus-product and value is what<br />

drives Aaron’s conclusion in [739].<br />

Message [754] referenced by [768]. Next Message by Inter is [771].<br />

[768] Hans: Prices are not too high; instead, wages are too low. On the surface <strong>of</strong><br />

the economy the capitalists seem to make their pr<strong>of</strong>its by charging too much; instead <strong>of</strong><br />

charging their costs they charge more than their costs. But if one thinks a little more about<br />

it, it becomes obvious that this interpretation is problematic. It sees the source <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its in<br />

circulation, although we know that circulation does not create wealth. Circulation moves the<br />

already existing wealth from the producers to the consumers, therefore there are some gains<br />

according to use-value, but this activity cannot be the source <strong>of</strong> the steady flow <strong>of</strong> monetary<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its made by the capitalist class.<br />

Marx’s basic insight is that pr<strong>of</strong>its are not made in circulation but in production. In order<br />

to flesh this out, he needs a theory <strong>of</strong> prices, and a theory <strong>of</strong> wages.<br />

His theory <strong>of</strong> prices is the following: instead <strong>of</strong> thinking retail prices are somehow too<br />

high because they contain markups over costs, let’s assume that retail prices are on average<br />

the right prices. Marx says that these “right” prices are not determined by cost, but their<br />

ultimate determinant is the total labor input into the commodity. I wrote here “total” because<br />

it is not only the labor in the last production process, but the labor going into all materials<br />

etc. The mechanism adjusting these prices to labor content does not go through cost, but<br />

through the allocation <strong>of</strong> labor to those commodities which are in highest demand.<br />

Now if prices are determined by labor cost, wouldn’t that mean that the laborers get all<br />

the money? How can there be pr<strong>of</strong>its? Marx’s explanation here is that the workers in their<br />

paychecks do not get as much value back as their labor produces. That is his theory <strong>of</strong><br />

wages. Wages just pay enough that the worker can pay his bills and show up again to work,<br />

but this is much less than the value produced during the work time.<br />

Let’s look at the book bag example in [754]. Assume for simplicity that each hour <strong>of</strong><br />

labor produces a value <strong>of</strong> $30, and that it takes 30 minutes overall to make a book bag and<br />

the materials going into the book bag and the deprecitation <strong>of</strong> the machinery used, etc. Say<br />

the book bag factory itself needs 10 minutes direct labor, and the materials etc. per book<br />

bag cost $10 (representing 20 minutes <strong>of</strong> labor needed to produce these materials and their<br />

inputs etc.) Then the retail price <strong>of</strong> the book bag is $15.<br />

Now assume the worker makes $18 per hour. Then the cost <strong>of</strong> the book bag to the capitalist<br />

is $10 materials plus $3 labor, i.e., $13. But the capitalist sells the book bag for $15.<br />

(These $15 are not determined by the capitalist who adds some “markup” to $13, but by<br />

multiplying the half hour <strong>of</strong> labor represented by the book bag by $30. This is important,<br />

make sure you understand this!)<br />

The laborer says now: “it takes me and my peers in the other industries together 30<br />

minutes to make a bookbag. But if I want to go out and buy a bookbag, I must use 50<br />

minutes’ worth <strong>of</strong> my wages. I.e., I must buy back with 50 minutes <strong>of</strong> my time the product<br />

which I and my friends produced with 30 minutes <strong>of</strong> our time.”<br />

Message [768] referenced by [2008fa:1124], [2008fa:1151], [2008fa:1168], [2009fa:1113], [2010fa:972], [2010fa:1004<br />

[2012fa:1333], and [2012fa:1483]. Next Message by Hans is [805].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 307<br />

Question 725 is 728 in 2008fa, 761 in 2009fa, 829 in 2010fa, and 891 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 725 What does Marx mean with: “but original sin is at work everywhere”?<br />

[712] Rmuscolino: “But Original Sin is at Work Everywhere”. Marx writes, “but<br />

original sin is everywhere” to depict the meaning that as production develops, the capitalist<br />

stops being the subordinate <strong>of</strong> capital. He uses this aphorism to describe how nothing<br />

seems to overpower the capitalist. Marx goes on to say, “even though humans cannot remain<br />

subordinate to God, capital can’t overpower the capitalist.” As the capitalist forgoes individual<br />

consumption, he gains power by promoting accumulation. The quote, “original sin is<br />

everywhere” is true because to accumulate, is to conquer the world <strong>of</strong> social wealth and to<br />

increase the mass <strong>of</strong> humans exploited, and therefore to extend both the direct and indirect<br />

sway <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. This ongoing conflict between consumption and accumulation in the<br />

capitalist is a perfect example <strong>of</strong> original sin repetitively going on everywhere.<br />

Hans: You are misunderstanding my comments in the Annotations, and I am trying to formulate this better for the<br />

next edition. Instead <strong>of</strong> saying “nothing seems to overpower the capitalist” you should have said: “nothing seems<br />

to overpower the human being who has slipped into a capitalist role.” Marx probably thought that Adam and Eve’s<br />

insubordination known as the “original sin” was a good thing. In the long run, humans will not follow orders, they<br />

will only do what they think it is right. Even the capitalist will not follow the “orders” implied in his role as a<br />

capitalist. He will revolt against the systemic necessity to “accumulate, accumulate.”<br />

Message [712] referenced by [2008fa:1158], [2008fa:1170], and [2010fa:654]. First Message by Rmuscolino is<br />

[422].<br />

Question 728 is 734 in 2008fa, 767 in 2009fa, 835 in 2010fa, 863 in 2011fa, and 897 in<br />

2012fa:<br />

Question 728 What is the “Abstinence Theory”?<br />

[715] JPeel: graded C– Abstinence Theory. “He who converts his revenue abstains from<br />

the enjoyment which its expenditure would afford him. It is not the abstinence, but the use<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capital productively which is the cause <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its.” This passage, by John Cazenove,<br />

describes the “Abstinence Theory” as a reward for work. Every human action can be viewed<br />

as “abstinence” from its opposite. Hegel’s inversion “all negation is determination” is a good<br />

example <strong>of</strong> this theory. Therefore, the “Abstinence Theory” depicts a process <strong>of</strong> decision<br />

making and needs <strong>of</strong> the individual.<br />

Hans: Your original submission had a writing error which completely changed the meaning <strong>of</strong> Cazenove’s quote:<br />

where this corrected version here has “abstinence” you had originally written “capital.” Cazenove’s passage is not a<br />

definition but a critique <strong>of</strong> the abstinence theory. Neither Cazenove nor the authors <strong>of</strong> the abstinence theory thought<br />

that pr<strong>of</strong>its were a reward for work.<br />

Your last sentence is apparently lifted from the following sentence in the Annotations: “The abstinence theory<br />

therefore attributes a social process to the decision and merit <strong>of</strong> an individual.” With this I wanted to say that the<br />

“abstaining” capitalist takes credit for a social process which is pretty much going on without him.<br />

Next Message by JPeel is [806].<br />

Question 736 is 319 in 1997WI, 387 in 1997sp, 384 in 1997ut, 582 in 2002fa, 606 in<br />

2003fa, 665 in 2004fa, 612 in 2005fa, 736 in 2007SP, 707 in 2007fa, 741 in 2008fa, 774<br />

in 2009fa, 842 in 2010fa, 871 in 2011fa, and 905 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 736 The capitalist depends on the worker for pr<strong>of</strong>it, and the worker depends on<br />

the capitalist for survival. Does this mean that workers and capitalists have the same interests?


308 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[767] Bmellor: Not on the same page. The capitalist class needs the working class to<br />

accrue more wealth; the working class needs to rise up above inhibition to prosper. Capitalist<br />

holds down the working class. The working class cannot be free unless they abolish<br />

“inhumane” working conditions. An example <strong>of</strong> why these two are not on the same page<br />

is the following: Wages are used as an incentive to induce a worker to work. True, wages<br />

are used by the working class as a means <strong>of</strong> survival. (Marx’s formula is hourly wage =<br />

predetermined daily wage divided by hours worked). The capitalist uses this equation to<br />

his advantage manipulating the hours worked by the worker in a single day. The worker<br />

works for survival and to make his life better, but the harder he works the capitalist will<br />

inevitably take all the more advantage <strong>of</strong> him. So in this sense they are not working for the<br />

same interests. Just because you work harder at your job and put in longer hours doesn’t<br />

necessarily mean you will be compensated accordingly, but even if you received additional<br />

compensation your boss (he/she who owns the means <strong>of</strong> production) sees a benefit from your<br />

increased productivity and he/she doesn’t have to do a thing.<br />

Message [767] referenced by [774] and [781]. Next Message by Bmellor is [807].<br />

[774] Matt: Money, the Common Denominator. Bmellor has pointed out a couple good<br />

points in [767] as to what Marx was trying to say. However, I do believe that they do have at<br />

least one similar interest under a society driven by the capitalist. A worker works to survive<br />

by earning money, while the capitalist seeks for pr<strong>of</strong>it which also equals money. They are<br />

both using the means <strong>of</strong> production for one thing, money. Money is the driving force that<br />

brings the two parties together.<br />

The part that I do agree with Bmellor on is when he says, “The worker works for survival<br />

and to make his life better, but the harder he works the capitalist will inevitably take all the<br />

more advantage <strong>of</strong> him.” This is a correct statement as the capitalist will only hire ‘laborpower’<br />

if he can pay the worker low enough to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it, as the annotations say. This<br />

low wage will keep the worker from saving, leaving only enough money to survive on.<br />

This in turn will cause the worker to keep on working which only makes more and more<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it/money for the capitalists in the end.<br />

Hans: See [2003fa:418] and the discussion there.<br />

First Message by Matt is [43].<br />

[780] Ken: love hate relationship. In society workers and capitalists are dependent on<br />

each other. Without one, the other would not prosper. The capitalist’s focus is to accumulate<br />

as much wealth as possible. He does this by maximizing pr<strong>of</strong>its and depends on the worker<br />

to produce this pr<strong>of</strong>it. The worker’s focus is survival. In order to survive the worker must<br />

make a wage. The worker looks to the capitalist for this wage. The worker and capitalist<br />

have very different interests. The worker is working for a wage to survive. The capitalist is<br />

maximizing pr<strong>of</strong>its for wealth. The motive behind the accumulation is diverse between the<br />

capitalist and worker.<br />

The worker and the capitalist are incompatible. They use each other to attain what they<br />

want. The worker wants to obtain the highest wage possible. The capitalist is trying to<br />

reduce costs and therefore wants to exploit the worker by paying the worker a minimal<br />

wage. The relationship between the worker and the capitalist is a love hate relationship.<br />

They are dependent on each other however they have very different interests and motives.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 309<br />

Hans: You are making the relationship too symmetric. I agree that the capitalist uses the worker and needs the<br />

worker, the capitalist would not be a capitalist without the worker. But I would not say that the worker uses the<br />

capitalist, and the worker does not really need the capitalist either, arguably workers could produce much better if<br />

there were no capitalists around.<br />

Message [780] referenced by [781]. Next Message by Ken is [812].<br />

[781] Kevin: graded A+ Do we really know what our interests are? There have been<br />

some very good answers regarding this question and I think the right answer is a mixture<br />

between Ken in [780] and Bmellor in [767] but Hans will say for sure.<br />

As Bmellor says, “The capitalist class needs the working class to accrue more wealth.”<br />

The working class create value which is what makes the capitalist pr<strong>of</strong>its. Also, Ken says<br />

the worker needs the capitalist to survive and gets this from his wage. They both say that<br />

because <strong>of</strong> this their interests are different, and I would not disagree because <strong>of</strong> the many<br />

responses by Hans during 2005 Fall such as [2005fa:1538] and [2005fa:1583].<br />

What’s very interesting though is that little is talked about the means <strong>of</strong> production. I<br />

believe it is in the interest <strong>of</strong> both parties to own the means <strong>of</strong> production, the difference<br />

being who is the party in possession <strong>of</strong> that means. This is where the interests <strong>of</strong> both parties<br />

should separate, but they don’t.<br />

The capitalist obviously looks to hold those means <strong>of</strong> production independent <strong>of</strong> any other<br />

in order to exploit the workers who cannot produce things on their own. The worker would<br />

be (and should be if he thought about it long enough) interested in possessing his own means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production and thus be no longer exploited by the capitalist.<br />

In response to [2005fa:1565] Hans says, “the workers are the ones with the ultimate<br />

power, since their labor is the sole source <strong>of</strong> value and surplus-value.” Yet it doesn’t seem<br />

that way in society because the workers allows the means <strong>of</strong> production to be held by the<br />

capitalist who does nothing more than exploit them.<br />

In reality, I don’t think the worker knows what his interests are. He knows he’s interested<br />

in survival but because he’s so intent on bringing home a paycheck he doesn’t realize he’s<br />

doing nothing to support what interests he really should have. I think because <strong>of</strong> that the<br />

interests <strong>of</strong> the capitalist and the worker are the same only because the worker has no real<br />

idea what his interest should be and by working to survive is feeding the interest <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist.<br />

Message [781] referenced by [2009fa:1128]. Next Message by Kevin is [782].<br />

[785] Tim: graded A Same Interests? It is interesting to think about the relationship<br />

between employers and employees because they are almost always against each other. The<br />

one wanting to make more money while the other is trying to pay less. I think though that the<br />

answer to the question is somewhat in the question itself. The worker’s interests are survival<br />

and the capitalist’s interests are pr<strong>of</strong>its. For the most part the worker is interested in his pay<br />

check but he cannot receive a pay check if the company fails to make money. On the other<br />

hand, the capitalist, in his quest for pr<strong>of</strong>its, would be out <strong>of</strong> luck if the worker had no need<br />

for his pay check. So, in a sense they have the same interests because if the company goes<br />

under then they are both not able to reach their goals. While it almost always seems that<br />

there is a conflict between the two they seem to have the same goals in mind. Think <strong>of</strong> how<br />

much more they could get done if they realized this.


310 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: A Marxist would <strong>of</strong> course say that the conflicts between employer and employee do have deep structural<br />

reasons.<br />

Message [785] referenced by [797]. Next Message by Tim is [816].<br />

[789] Nstew: Are the workers and the capitalists working for the same thing??? On<br />

the surface it seems like the workers and the capitalists have the same interest, money! The<br />

worker needs money to survive and the capitalist needs pr<strong>of</strong>its, which are generated from<br />

the worker’s labor power, to survive. But the difference lies in that the worker is looking<br />

to survive while the capitalist is looking for a pr<strong>of</strong>it. So even though they both have the<br />

common interest <strong>of</strong> money, their reasons for wanting it are completely different. Marx is<br />

also talking about the differences between the working class and the capitalist. On a smaller<br />

scale where you have a small business, the business owner and the employee might have the<br />

common interest <strong>of</strong> survival. If the company is not pr<strong>of</strong>itable after paying overhead expenses<br />

and the employees then the business owner does not make any money himself. But this is<br />

not what Marx is talking about. Marx is talking about the differences in these two classes<br />

and while they are both after the same thing, money, this doesn’t mean they share the same<br />

interests.<br />

Hans: Yes, it is important to look at the social structures (the class structures), not the individuals. Both worker and<br />

capitalist have to survive, but workers and capitalists have very different social relations with their fellow human<br />

beings. You are also right to distinguish the small capitalists from the big corporations. Big capitalists not only<br />

exploit workers, they also exploit small capitalists.<br />

Next Message by Nstew is [790].<br />

[797] Slash: capitalist could care less. The capitalist is set only on making a pr<strong>of</strong>it. The<br />

worker is only interested in survival, which is seen as a wage from the capitalist. This then<br />

distinguishes them from having the same interests. Tim [785] says: “in a sense they have the<br />

same interests because if the company goes under then they are both not able to reach their<br />

goals” (goals meaning pr<strong>of</strong>its for the capitalist and survival for the worker). I disagree with<br />

the tone <strong>of</strong> this, but would first like to point out the obvious that, yes both the parties would<br />

like to accomplish their differing goals, but I find the way this is said is placing equality on<br />

their relationship. Yes, the worker can provide a service for the capitalist, but the capitalist<br />

has no real loyalty to the worker, the capitalist only cares about pr<strong>of</strong>it. The idea that the<br />

worker is creating what we think <strong>of</strong> as job security by working harder will only appear to be<br />

valid in times <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its for the capitalist. This sort <strong>of</strong> thinking places a responsibility <strong>of</strong> a<br />

firm’s survival on the individual worker. A capitalist controls the means <strong>of</strong> production and<br />

will only hire a worker so long as there is room for pr<strong>of</strong>it from the surplus labor. The way<br />

I understand Tim leads me to think a capitalist would be willing to give up pr<strong>of</strong>it to ensure<br />

survival for the worker. The truth is this happens today and the capitalist would fire the<br />

worker and export labor overseas to save cost on labor and ensure pr<strong>of</strong>it well before letting<br />

the firm close due to lower pr<strong>of</strong>its, therefor letting the worker know how much the capitalist<br />

depends on his particular labor in a time <strong>of</strong> no pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [798].<br />

Question 743 is 743 in 2007SP, 748 in 2008fa, 781 in 2009fa, 850 in 2010fa, 879 in<br />

2011fa, and 913 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 743 What is the “juridical illusion”?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 311<br />

[786] Allen: Juridical Illusion. Marx wrote, “Eden should have asked: who created<br />

‘the civil institutions’? From the standpoint he adopts, that <strong>of</strong> juridical illusion, he does not<br />

regard the law as a product <strong>of</strong> the material relations <strong>of</strong> production, but rather the reverse: he<br />

sees the relations <strong>of</strong> production as products <strong>of</strong> the law.”<br />

Marx implies that juridical illusion is the creation <strong>of</strong> the law by individuals. Similar to<br />

what Shannon [2007SP:1212] states in her comment, the laws are created by the actions <strong>of</strong><br />

society they are created in. They are a representation <strong>of</strong> material production because those<br />

who created the laws create them to fit the society.<br />

Message [786] referenced by [2010fa:1004]. Next Message by Allen is [829].<br />

Question 746 is 398 in 1997sp, 395 in 1997ut, 675 in 2004fa, 621 in 2005fa, 746 in<br />

2007SP, 717 in 2007fa, 751 in 2008fa, 784 in 2009fa, 853 in 2010fa, 882 in 2011fa, and<br />

916 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 746 What does Marx use the metaphor <strong>of</strong> a golden chain for? Why does he say<br />

the chain has become heavier?<br />

[772] Scott: golden chain. The metaphor <strong>of</strong> the golden chain is symbolizing the connection<br />

between the worker and the capitalist. Even though the worker may be treated more<br />

favorably and his wages may have increased he is still connected to the capitalist and is at<br />

his mercy.<br />

Remote [1997ut:381] clearly explains why the chain becomes heavier: “The chain becomes<br />

heavier only to preserve and maintain the means <strong>of</strong> production as capital. The worker<br />

is still a slave – only with slightly better treatment. This situation is conditional on the<br />

capitalist’s ability to transform his surplus product into additional capital.”<br />

You can also see the golden chain as a lifeline connecting the capitalist to the laborer. The<br />

gold chain represents wealth and is necessary for the laborer to survive. The laborer now<br />

sees his future as prosperous as long as he is attached to the gold chain. Being attached to the<br />

gold chain the laborer will be able to, as Marx said , “extend the circle <strong>of</strong> their enjoyments,<br />

make additions to their consumptions fund <strong>of</strong> clothes, furniture, etc., and lay by a small<br />

reserve fund <strong>of</strong> money.”<br />

Hans: This is quite modest wealth, i.e., the chain part <strong>of</strong> the metaphor is stronger than the gold part, and the lifeline<br />

is very conditional.<br />

Message [772] referenced by [2008fa:1199]. Next Message by Scott is [775].<br />

[773] CousinIt: graded A Slavery is slavery. Marx uses the metaphhor <strong>of</strong> the golden<br />

chain to say that slavery is slavery. A chain is a chain whether its made <strong>of</strong> gold or <strong>of</strong> iron. In<br />

comment (or extension) upon Scott’s [772];<br />

In the days <strong>of</strong> African American institutionalized slavery, you had the house slaves and<br />

the field slaves. Some slaves were allowed to have small huts and a little plot <strong>of</strong> land to have<br />

a small garden, yet they were still slaves, did not own anything, and were subject to the grace<br />

<strong>of</strong> their masters.<br />

This is still the case under capitalism. There are still ‘house-slaves’ (CEO’s and management)<br />

and ‘field-slaves’ (laborers and shopworkers). The huts have gotten a little bigger, the<br />

plots have gotten a little bigger, some freedoms have extended, and the range <strong>of</strong> mobility


312 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

has expanded a bit. Nonetheless, everyone is still under the yoke <strong>of</strong> the master. The huts<br />

are actually owned by the banks and can be taken away anytime some group <strong>of</strong> capitalists<br />

with the help <strong>of</strong> their friends in government decide that they want the peice <strong>of</strong> land to build<br />

a freeway or a shopping mall. The Hummers are a lavish neccessity for keeping the machine<br />

rolling and getting everyone to work “in style.” Even entertainment and leisure are really<br />

guises for the other part <strong>of</strong> the slave’s duty to continually consume the products stolen from<br />

him and sold back to him by the capitalist. Try not consuming anything anytime and see<br />

how far you get!<br />

No one is really free to do as they please. All activity is dictated by the demands <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist system. If you don’t think so, try getting up tomorrow and doing exactly what you<br />

want to do and then keep on doing it for the days to follow. How far do you think you will<br />

get before your activities are constrained by your cash-flow? How far do you think you can<br />

go before someone notices that you aren’t getting with the program and marching lock-step<br />

with the rest <strong>of</strong> them? Test the limits to your so-called freedom. See just how ‘free’ your<br />

freedom really is.<br />

If we think about how people are ‘surviving’ these days, piling debt upon debt upon more<br />

debt, the metaphor <strong>of</strong> the golden chain that gets heavier and harder to bear, yet inescapable,<br />

becomes very salient, and to some <strong>of</strong> us more than others. Those who are carrying such<br />

debts indeed feel the growing weight <strong>of</strong> the golden chain connecting them to the capitalist<br />

system.<br />

The golden chain is an apt metaphor for the reality that you and I live everyday. It sure<br />

looks pretty though...doesn’t it? The bigger the chain the greater the status. Ironic?<br />

Next Message by CousinIt is [850].<br />

[787] Paul: You can never escape the chain! Marx uses the metaphor <strong>of</strong> the golden chain<br />

to describe the leash that the capitalist has on their laborers. The laborers are attached to this<br />

leash for the fact that they are totally dependent on the wage they receive from the capitalist,<br />

and they have no say in how much the capitalist pays them. But the reality is, is that the<br />

laborer has attached themselves to this leash. Marx says that the chain only becomes heavier<br />

when the laborer is given a raise. This is because with this new higher wage the laborer is<br />

likely going to increase his expenditure to improve his quality <strong>of</strong> life. While the laborer is<br />

now able to afford this because <strong>of</strong> his raise, he really is only becoming more dependent on<br />

the capitalist because he now has even more things to pay for. While the laborer may feel<br />

like he is beating the system by receiving a raise in his wage, he is really just becoming more<br />

dependent on the system.<br />

Message [787] referenced by [2008fa:1199]. Next Message by Paul is [801].<br />

Question 748 is 332 in 1997WI, 405 in 1998WI, 429 in 1999SP, 524 in 2000fa, 554 in<br />

2001fa, 594 in 2002fa, 618 in 2003fa, 677 in 2004fa, 786 in 2009fa, 855 in 2010fa, and<br />

884 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 748 Does the dependence <strong>of</strong> the workers on capital decrease when wages are<br />

high?<br />

[794] Wade: The dependence <strong>of</strong> the workers does not decrease at all, what happens is<br />

the worker’s leash is simply lengthened a bit. With more cash flow the worker now has the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 313<br />

means to buy what they want, such as better furniture, clothes, and so forth. The worker has<br />

a sphere <strong>of</strong> comfort that they live within, they buy what they can without expanding outside<br />

<strong>of</strong> this sphere, when the wages are higher the sphere is expanded and the worker now has the<br />

ability to expand within that sphere. Hans uses the example “The golden chain which the<br />

wage-laborer has already forged for himself, allows this chain to be loosened somewhat”.<br />

The dependency doesn’t decrease at all, the worker’s “golden chain” is expanded a little, but<br />

his or her dependency remains the same.<br />

Next Message by Wade is [880].<br />

Question 751 is 751 in 2007SP, 789 in 2009fa, and 921 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 751 Explain how the relation between capital and wage labor can be characterized<br />

as: “the absolute movements <strong>of</strong> the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital manifest themselves as<br />

relative movements <strong>of</strong> the mass <strong>of</strong> exploitable labor-power, and therefore seem produced by<br />

the latter’s own independent movement.”<br />

[795] Alcameron: Capital accumulation vs labor power. The question is basically<br />

asking us which variable is the dependent and which is the independent, movements in<br />

capital accumulation or movements in labor-power. These two variable are obviously closely<br />

related and interconnected in their effects.<br />

Let me use an example to illustrate how they affect each other. Let’s use Target because<br />

we’ve been hearing too much about Walmart! Target executives decide that customer service<br />

is what is going to set them apart from their competition so they want to double their staff in<br />

every store. There will be costs associated with this but Target is ready to make this happen.<br />

All <strong>of</strong> the sudden there are help wanted ads all over the city looking for employees at the<br />

local Target. An observer from the outside might think that there is a shortage <strong>of</strong> labor and<br />

Target really needs more people to stay afloat. In actuality though Target has decided to<br />

use some <strong>of</strong> its capital to hire more workers as a strategy to outperform their competition.<br />

The movement in labor power is a result <strong>of</strong> the action taken by the capitalist to have more<br />

staff in every store. Nothing that the workers at Target did caused this sudden influx <strong>of</strong><br />

hirings, rather the capitalist has caused it with their absolute movement <strong>of</strong> the accumulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

The flip side <strong>of</strong> this example works as well. Target decides they’re spending too much<br />

money on needless workers and they let go a large portion <strong>of</strong> their labor force. Nothing the<br />

laborers did or no decisions they made cause this action, rather the absolute movements <strong>of</strong><br />

the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital as directed by the capitalist are the independent variables which<br />

cause changes in the dependent variable <strong>of</strong> exploitable labor power.<br />

Hans: Your examples simply say that the buyer <strong>of</strong> a commodity (here the buyer <strong>of</strong> labor-power) makes the purchase<br />

decision, not the seller.<br />

Marx’s statement is not about individual decisions, but about overall market trends: if there is a general glut<br />

or shortage <strong>of</strong> labor, it is only rarely caused by changes in the labor-supply, but usually by changes in the labor<br />

demand by capital.<br />

Next Message by Alcameron is [796].<br />

Question 754 is 334 in 1997WI, 557 in 2001fa, 792 in 2009fa, and 861 in 2010fa:


314 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Question 754 How does the fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> capital discussed in the Accumulation<br />

chapter differ from that <strong>of</strong> the commodity discussed in chapter One?<br />

[784] Mitternacht: graded A Fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> commodity and capital. The<br />

fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> the commodity described in chapter one <strong>of</strong> Das Kapital has to do<br />

with treating the social relations <strong>of</strong> men as if they were relations between commodities. This<br />

unclear, or mistaken relationship is what gives the commodity a fetish-like character. The<br />

fetish-like character <strong>of</strong> capital on the other hand is created by man becoming subservient<br />

to the very thing that he produces. Marx praises Van Thunen in his footnotes (77a) for<br />

formulating a question which sums up this contradiction quite well: “How has the worker<br />

been able to pass from being the master <strong>of</strong> capital – as its creator – to being its slave?”<br />

Message [784] referenced by [2009fa:1130] and [2010fa:1034]. Next Message by Mitternacht is [846].<br />

Question 756 is 559 in 2001fa, 727 in 2007fa, 761 in 2008fa, 794 in 2009fa, 863 in<br />

2010fa, and 896 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 756 What is the right answer to the question: “How has the worker” (and not only<br />

the worker but mankind as a whole) “been able to pass from being the master <strong>of</strong> capital—as<br />

its creator—to being its slave?”<br />

[788] Papageorgio: Mankind? It is by no accident that in this question Hans is sure to<br />

state that not only the worker but mankind as a whole has become a slave. It is not just one<br />

man one laborer but mankind who becomes slave to capitalism. The worker indeed is slave<br />

to capitalism, our society becomes influenced and slaved by its regulations and important<br />

to note the capitalist himself also is a slave. As we see mankind also becomes slave to the<br />

desire for more. More <strong>of</strong> everything, more money, land, possessions. Mankind is taken in<br />

and subject to capitalism to a extremely bad result. War is a very severe consequence <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism along with the destruction <strong>of</strong> our land we live in, the killing <strong>of</strong> the earth. As<br />

we continue along it as if we don’t even recognize what is causing us to fall into such a<br />

society. As workers, capitalists, humans we become more and more poor, worse <strong>of</strong>f than<br />

before. Some people if they were able to see through capitalism’s facade might actually<br />

evade capitalism itself and be free. But as we know this is not the case at our point in the<br />

world today.<br />

Message [788] referenced by [790] and [832]. Next Message by Papageorgio is [799].<br />

[790] Nstew: Slave? In response to Papageorgio’s answer [788] I don’t understand how<br />

the capitalist is becoming a slave and by what regulations is our society becoming a slave? In<br />

our society, a free market society, there is nothing to stop someone from starting up their own<br />

business if they are sick <strong>of</strong> working for the “capitalist”. Although many people do become<br />

slaves to their wants, or needs to have “things” to keep up with the Jones’s, there is nothing<br />

stopping one from going out and becoming a producer instead a consumer. What I mean by<br />

this is that in our society we have the choice <strong>of</strong> whether we want to produce value and wealth<br />

or if we are only going to be a consumer and continue to make other people rich. Although<br />

Wal-Mart is considered by some as the destructive “capitalist” who is destroying America,<br />

Sam Walton started out by opening one store back in Arkansas in 1962 and slowly building<br />

it into what it is today. We each have the opportunity to free ourselves from becoming a


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 315<br />

“slave” to capital or to the capitalist by figuring out what passions and strengths we have and<br />

then leveraging them to produce value and wealth.<br />

Hans: If Marx’s theory is right, then this escape route is open only to a small minority. Sam Walton can “leverage”<br />

his passions and strenghts only because tens <strong>of</strong> thousands <strong>of</strong> his employees produce value in excess <strong>of</strong> their wages.<br />

These employees are the producers <strong>of</strong> Walton’s wealth. It is not possible that everybody becomes a capitalist,<br />

because then nobody would create the value which enters the capitalists’ pockets as pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Message [790] referenced by [793]. Next Message by Nstew is [792].<br />

[832] Hans: How did we get into this mess? Papageorgio [788] says that capitalism<br />

is the result <strong>of</strong> the “desire for more,” not only by the capitalists but by everyone. In other<br />

words, it is part <strong>of</strong> human nature. Marx was not quite that pessimistic. Marx’s most fundamental<br />

critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism is that the individuals do not have control over their own social<br />

relations. How did this control slip away from us, so that commodities make social interactions<br />

for us and our means <strong>of</strong> production are our masters rather than our tools? If 187:1 is a<br />

guide, Marx blames individualism and atomism for it instead <strong>of</strong> greed. We need to do away<br />

with competition and share our resources in solidarity. This is the only way how humankind<br />

has a chance to avert climate disaster.<br />

Message [832] referenced by [2009fa:1137], [2009fa:1143], and [2010fa:1046]. Next Message by Hans is [851].<br />

Question 759 is 435 in 1999SP, 530 in 2000fa, 561 in 2001fa, 603 in 2002fa, 627 in<br />

2003fa, 761 in 2007SP, 730 in 2007fa, 764 in 2008fa, 797 in 2009fa, 866 in 2010fa, 899<br />

in 2011fa, and 929 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 759 In 773:1, Marx discusses an empirical phenomenon in which technical progress<br />

“expresses” itself. Which phenomenon is that? Why does Marx speak here <strong>of</strong> an expression?<br />

[830] Jason: Means <strong>of</strong> production. Corey in [2007fa:679] describes the phenomenon as<br />

the means <strong>of</strong> production getting more advanced and thus increasing production while reducing<br />

labor input. I think this is what Marx was referring too. Technical progress expresses<br />

itself through increased production, with less labor input. Corey used a Krispy Kreme production<br />

as an example <strong>of</strong> how one man can now do several people’s jobs. However this does<br />

not benefit the laborer that is more productive now. It benefits the capitalist who owns the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production and can now lay <strong>of</strong>f several employees.<br />

Hans: The empirical phenomenon mentioned by Marx in which technical progress expresses itself is not increased<br />

production but a higher technical composition <strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

First Message by Jason is [85].<br />

Question 767 is 611 in 2002fa, 635 in 2003fa, 694 in 2004fa, 641 in 2005fa, 769 in<br />

2007SP, 738 in 2007fa, 772 in 2008fa, 805 in 2009fa, 874 in 2010fa, 907 in 2011fa, and<br />

937 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 767 How do competition and credit help in the process <strong>of</strong> centralization?<br />

[841] Nstew: Competition... Competition is one <strong>of</strong> the most important components <strong>of</strong> a<br />

capitalist society. Competition and credit working in unison are what continue the process<br />

<strong>of</strong> “centralization”.<br />

Competition is what drives the capitalist to provide the consumer with the best quality<br />

product or the best price and it is best if you can combine the two. The consumer is usually<br />

the one who wins when there is competition because when you have multiple companies


316 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

competing against each other it prevents monopolies. I know many people think Wal-Mart<br />

has created a monopoly because the smaller stores can’t compete with their prices because<br />

Wal-Mart keeps has their prices so low that it puts the smaller companies out <strong>of</strong> business.<br />

Here is an example <strong>of</strong> a local company here in <strong>Utah</strong> doing the exact opposite; Regan Outdoor<br />

Advertising owns the large majority <strong>of</strong> billboards in <strong>Utah</strong> and particularly along I-15 in the<br />

Salt Lake Valley. Because they own most <strong>of</strong> the inventory and they know that no one else<br />

can compete with them they charge $5500.00 for a 4 week period to purchase billboard<br />

advertising through them. By creating 4 week periods instead <strong>of</strong> charging by the month,<br />

which is what all the other companies do, they have managed to squeeze in 13 periods in<br />

a year. The majority <strong>of</strong> the other outdoor advertising companies who own billboards along<br />

I-15 in Salt Lake, which are very few in comparison, charge between $2300 - $3000 per<br />

month. Here are 2 examples <strong>of</strong> companies who dominate their markets which have 2 totally<br />

different outcomes for the customer. Wal-Mart provides people with great values which<br />

most small companies can’t compete with and Regan Outdoor charges people through the<br />

nose because they own the majority <strong>of</strong> the inventory in their market. The majority <strong>of</strong> the<br />

time competition will provide customers with the best products for the best prices.<br />

When the capitalist have credit it provides him access to the financial funds needed to<br />

facilitate large scale production, which would otherwise not be available to him. This access<br />

to financial funds provided from credit speeds up the process <strong>of</strong> production which allows<br />

smaller companies to expand much faster than they would if they had to accumulate the<br />

funds on their own. When you combine competition and credit it is the machine which<br />

creates centralization.<br />

Hans: A Marxist would probably say: Regan rips <strong>of</strong>f the other capitalists due to its monopoly ownership <strong>of</strong> billboards,<br />

and Wal-Mart rips <strong>of</strong>f workers, suppliers, and the state welfare systems, eradicates many small businesses<br />

(here we see how competition aids in centralization), and gives part <strong>of</strong> the booty to the consumers. The consumer’s<br />

side <strong>of</strong> this bargain is described in [2005fa:482]<br />

Next Message by Nstew is [886].<br />

Question 779 is 623 in 2002fa, 647 in 2003fa, 706 in 2004fa, 652 in 2005fa, 780 in<br />

2007SP, 749 in 2007fa, 784 in 2008fa, 886 in 2010fa, and 949 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 779 Which violent means did capital use in its infancy to sweep away the bounds<br />

imposed on its accumulation by the natural limits <strong>of</strong> the exploitable working population?<br />

[827] Jeremy: Revolution. The violent means capital used in its infancy to sweep away<br />

the bounds imposed on it points to many possibilities. An example from the Communist<br />

Manifesto: “When, in the course <strong>of</strong> development, class distinctions have disappeared, and<br />

all production has been concentrated in the hands <strong>of</strong> a vast association <strong>of</strong> the whole nation,<br />

the public power will lose its political character. Political power, properly so called, is<br />

merely the organized power <strong>of</strong> one class for oppressing another. If the proletariat during its<br />

contest with the bourgeoisie is compelled, by the force <strong>of</strong> circumstances, to organize itself<br />

as a class; if, by means <strong>of</strong> a revolution, it makes itself the ruling class, and, as such, sweeps<br />

away by force the old conditions <strong>of</strong> production, then it will, along with these conditions, have<br />

swept away the conditions for the existence <strong>of</strong> class antagonisms and <strong>of</strong> classes generally,<br />

and will thereby have abolished its own supremacy as a class.” An example <strong>of</strong> this action<br />

would be the French Revolution. The unrest <strong>of</strong> the many turned into a full-scale civil war


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 317<br />

with the placement <strong>of</strong> a new government. The bounds placed upon capital could be counted<br />

as population controls, government forms, and level <strong>of</strong> civilization that the population is<br />

currently at. To overcome these bounds, the people rise up to gain freedom, when actually,<br />

they come into the bondage <strong>of</strong> a different oppressor, known by the name <strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

Hans: The quote from the Communist Manifesto had the words “sweep away” in it, but instead <strong>of</strong> talking about<br />

capital in its infancy it talks about the end <strong>of</strong> capital.<br />

Next Message by Jeremy is [857].<br />

[828] Spawnblade: Revolution or Devolution? (Har har). Jeremy [779] brought up an<br />

appropriate answer to the question <strong>of</strong> ‘violent means’ used in capitalisms infancy to sweep<br />

away its bounds. Yet I find myself feeling a certain distaste towards the response as a whole.<br />

I suppose the first part that doesn’t sit well is the example from the Communist Manifesto.<br />

It’s a bit too long to quote, but essentially it refers to the stage after capitalism, the period<br />

where capitalism fails and the people call for a revolution towards the next step. However,<br />

this contradicts the question itself which I see as targeting progress for capitalism, not away<br />

from it. In this respect, the French Revolution was an appropriate example <strong>of</strong> a revolution,<br />

seeing as it was the organizing <strong>of</strong> the people for the betterment <strong>of</strong> living standards, freedoms,<br />

and beliefs.<br />

Natural limits as I understand them are the labor pool size, technology, means <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> capital, and laws. As noted in the first paragraph, and in Jeremy’s post, it<br />

takes a revolution by the people to take the land/means <strong>of</strong> production/capital from the fiefs,<br />

monarch, or whoever else is in control <strong>of</strong> them previously. Revolutions were generally the<br />

most common, and most effective method for this. However, even after this you had another<br />

barrier to the growth <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. This barrier is also known as skilled labor. Before<br />

we had factories we had weavers, potters, you name it. Once mass production began, these<br />

people picketed and fought both legally and violently against these mass producers in order<br />

to keep their livelihood. It may not have been as bloody, nor as outwardly violent as revolutions<br />

were, but there were lives on the line (mostly in an economic sense.) This leads me<br />

to my final point: Not all violence is physical. As far as I can see, any kind <strong>of</strong> aggressive<br />

conflict can be considered violent – whether physical, political, or economical.<br />

Next Message by Spawnblade is [853].<br />

Question 784 is 433 in 1998WI, 583 in 2001fa, 628 in 2002fa, 652 in 2003fa, 711 in<br />

2004fa, 657 in 2005fa, 754 in 2007fa, 789 in 2008fa, 823 in 2009fa, 891 in 2010fa, and<br />

954 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 784 Why does the capitalist have the motive to get the same labor-time out <strong>of</strong> a<br />

smaller number <strong>of</strong> workers? Which economic facts did Marx refer to, and which additional<br />

economic facts go in the same direction nowadays?<br />

[812] Ken: small vs large. Keeping capital the same, the capitalist would prefer a smaller<br />

quantity <strong>of</strong> workers over a larger quantity <strong>of</strong> workers if he could still keep production at<br />

the necessary level. The smaller group <strong>of</strong> workers would have to work more hours in order<br />

to produce the same amount as the larger group; however the capitalist would prefer this.<br />

Nowadays, by having fewer workers the capitalist can reduce cost for example training costs<br />

and benefits. The capitalist would rather pay the wage <strong>of</strong> fewer employees even if he has


318 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the pay extra for the long hour; overtime wage. This wage increase would cost the capitalist<br />

less than having to train more workers and provide benefits for the additional workers.<br />

Another disadvantage to having more workers is the constant capital will need to increase.<br />

For example, the warehouses or the building in which the capitalist uses for production will<br />

need to expand. Additional machinery will need to be purchased in order to gain the most<br />

benefits from the additional workers. Overall the benefits <strong>of</strong> having fewer workers definitely<br />

outweigh having a large amount <strong>of</strong> workers.<br />

Hans: You didn’t distinguish those reasons which Marx already mentioned from those which arose more recently.<br />

Message [812] referenced by [819]. Next Message by Ken is [859].<br />

[819] Ryoung: Response to Ken. I agree with [812] that most capitalists would prefer to<br />

have fewer workers because it equates into a bigger more lucrative bottom line for them. Ken<br />

mentions that machinery would be one way in which the capitalist could produce more with<br />

less workers. I believe that this is the biggest way in which this can be pulled <strong>of</strong>f. Through<br />

technology production will increase at a more productive rate with less overhead to cover.<br />

With our technological advances this day there will be greater opportunities to produce more<br />

with less workers. Is this the trend that the production market will follow?<br />

Hans: The problem with this way out, according to Marx, is that machinery does not create value. If capitalists<br />

introduce machinery, their pr<strong>of</strong>it rate will fall, and they have to squeeze the workers even more in order to compensate<br />

for this. The workers with their surplus-labor have to generate pr<strong>of</strong>its not only for the wages they are getting,<br />

but also for the constant capital.<br />

Next Message by Ryoung is [820].<br />

Question 790 is 438 in 1998WI, 462 in 1999SP, and 657 in 2003fa:<br />

Question 790 Marx describes two mechanisms by which capital acts on both sides. Sides <strong>of</strong><br />

what? Which mechanisms? Can you think <strong>of</strong> a third mechanism which again has a similar<br />

effect?<br />

[821] Bar: graded A wages and labor mechanisms. Marx discusses how the wage market<br />

works through two mechanisms first, through labor-power, second how supply and demand<br />

manipulate this level. Capital works through the supply and demand <strong>of</strong> the labor market<br />

creating a wage that lessens how much control skilled labor has over their wage. My father<br />

is a painting contractor and I have seen how this affects his earnings and the wages <strong>of</strong> his<br />

employees. Before the housing boom, his earnings stayed at a stable level rising slightly year<br />

after year, probably just a nominal increase, but during the last housing boom his earnings<br />

increased 30% in just two years and have stayed stable since. My father owns the company<br />

so he was able during this time to buy a lot more capital, in this case he bought a lot <strong>of</strong> new<br />

paint sprayers so that his employees all could access this capital not just a few due to costs.<br />

The wages <strong>of</strong> my dad’s employees, as I am one and I know, have only slightly increased in<br />

the last few years not nearly 30%. The capital decreased the wage because we complete jobs<br />

faster, so my dad pays less in wages. This occurs because as a market’s size increases, for<br />

example the housing market, earnings increase because <strong>of</strong> the higher demand, more people<br />

enter the market and so does a rise in the demand for new more efficient capital to lower<br />

wages. A third mechanism that would create another dynamic into the labor market would<br />

be the level <strong>of</strong> labor organization. If labor can organize against capital, higher wages will be<br />

demanded, furthermore, the capitalist will have less money to invest in new capital lowering<br />

wages.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 319<br />

Hans: Twice in your essay I replaced “wages” with “earnings.” Your father’s income is a different economic<br />

category than wage income.<br />

Message [821] referenced by [851]. Next Message by Bar is [822].<br />

[851] Hans: Treacherous Labor Market. In 792:2/oo, Marx writes: “Capital acts on<br />

both sides at once.” Both sides <strong>of</strong> what? Both sides <strong>of</strong> the labor market, the demand side and<br />

the supply side. We know that capital acts on the demand side <strong>of</strong> the labor market, because<br />

it hires the laborer. But how does it act on the supply side? Marx gives two mechanisms<br />

which are briefly described in my [1999SP:471].<br />

Bar [821] brings a real-life example for one <strong>of</strong> the two mechanisms: if demand for the<br />

output goes up, the capitalist can use labor-saving equipment to produce this higher output<br />

with fewer workers than he previously needed to supply a lower output. One might say that<br />

by switching to this labor-saving machinery the capitalist sets laborers free, i.e., adds to the<br />

supply <strong>of</strong> laborers.<br />

The other mechanism mentioned by Marx is: by laying <strong>of</strong>f workers the capitalist can<br />

increase the supply <strong>of</strong> labor because those who still have a job are working harder now so<br />

that they won’t be laid <strong>of</strong>f too. You won’t find this effect with inanimate commodities. If you<br />

replace your incandescent lightbulbs with compact fluorescent ones, the refrigerator won’t<br />

say to himself “I better get my act together and quit wasting so much energy, otherwise I<br />

will be thrown out too.”<br />

I have thought <strong>of</strong> a third mechanism which is not mentioned by Marx explicitly, but which<br />

is implicit in his formulation that the supply <strong>of</strong> labor is “to a certain extent independent <strong>of</strong><br />

the supply <strong>of</strong> laborers.” If the capitalist lowers wages (or, which is the same thing, fails to<br />

raise wages with inflation), then the workers see themselves forced to work more overtime<br />

so that they can pay their bills.<br />

Bar says something about unions. Unions are indeed needed as a counterweight to this<br />

unfair advantage <strong>of</strong> the capitalists. A little further down in the same long paragraph 792:2/oo<br />

Marx says that the employed and the unemployed should organize together, in order to<br />

prevent this competition between employed and unemployed. This was done, for instance,<br />

in the Unemployed Councils during the Great Depression. Modern capitalists try to prevent<br />

labor organization by hiring undocumented workers, who they hope will not fight back for<br />

fear <strong>of</strong> deportation. The co-op miners’ strike was a big surprise to them: the workers did fight<br />

back, and despite footdragging by the NLRB they eventually kind <strong>of</strong> won. See [2003fa:663]<br />

about this.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [887].<br />

Question 800 is 472 in 1999SP, 643 in 2002fa, 726 in 2004fa, 672 in 2005fa, 801 in<br />

2007SP, 805 in 2008fa, 838 in 2009fa, 908 in 2010fa, and 941 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 800 What is pauperism?<br />

What is its relationship to the relative surplus population?<br />

Discuss contemporary forms <strong>of</strong> pauperism.<br />

Which political actions can one expect from paupers and why?<br />

[818] Rey: graded A A Pauper’s Way <strong>of</strong> Life. Pauperism is as Hans states, “not the<br />

direct result <strong>of</strong> the repulsion <strong>of</strong> labor by capital, but the result <strong>of</strong> the result <strong>of</strong> this expulsion.”


320 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

As capital replaces workers in the labor force “employed turn unemployed” and as a result<br />

these unemployed turn into Paupers, or those who are deeply entrenched in the depths <strong>of</strong><br />

poverty. In other words a pauper doesn’t descend to their status simply by being replaced<br />

with capital, but because they were replaced with capital. With wages depleted from the<br />

result <strong>of</strong> unemployment and the feeling <strong>of</strong> no other option, Paupers turn to non-traditional<br />

or “black-market” means <strong>of</strong> production to survive. Modern day forms <strong>of</strong> paupers are the<br />

homeless/beggars, drug dealers, prostitutes and other criminals. As Picard said in the fall<br />

2005 archives [2005fa:1837], “Pauperism is related to the surplus population in that it is a<br />

‘result <strong>of</strong> the existence <strong>of</strong> surplus population.’” Paupers would be nowhere to be found if<br />

a surplus population didn’t exist. I also agree with Picard when stating, “I would expect<br />

Paupers to not be involved in politics very much because they would be too preoccupied<br />

with survival to engage in political actions.” If an individual is clawing and fighting to get<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the pit <strong>of</strong> poverty they more than likely will have little interest, not to mention no<br />

leisure time, to engage in political matters. Not only will they have little interest and time,<br />

but also they most likely would have a lack <strong>of</strong> hope that real change is even possible. With<br />

this in mind we can get a glimpse <strong>of</strong> how class division hinders the democratic process.<br />

First Message by Rey is [84].<br />

Question 801 is 473 in 1999SP, 599 in 2001fa, 644 in 2002fa, 668 in 2003fa, 727 in<br />

2004fa, 673 in 2005fa, 802 in 2007SP, 771 in 2007fa, 806 in 2008fa, 839 in 2009fa, 909<br />

in 2010fa, 942 in 2011fa, and 972 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 801 What is worse: the misery <strong>of</strong> idle impoverishment or the torture <strong>of</strong> work?<br />

[806] JPeel: graded B– absolute impoverishment at its best. Absolute impoverishment<br />

is the act <strong>of</strong> making someone poor. Marx talks about the way a man is degraded at his job<br />

and put so low in the barrel that there is no escape. A man putting his life and integrity<br />

on the line every day in order to make ends meat is not a valued life. It is a world wide<br />

problem that has to be looked at from all angles. It is occurring all over the globe and is an<br />

issue that certainly does apply in today’s world. It is not right for a human being to suffer<br />

so miserably that even his family is feeling the wrath <strong>of</strong> the capital. These workers and their<br />

families are being exploited to the max. For example, when we look at workshops in third<br />

world countries we see absolute impoverishment at its best. These workers do not know that<br />

in reality they are working way more than they are getting paid. It is hurtful to them and<br />

the ones around them when exploitation like this takes control. It is a helpless process for<br />

them but they do not know any better and need any means <strong>of</strong> capital to survive. They will<br />

continue to sacrifice their lives at the cost <strong>of</strong> a penny.<br />

Hans: You didn’t read the question. And your implication is naive that the victims <strong>of</strong> third world sweatshops<br />

could end their exploitation if they only knew how valuable the product <strong>of</strong> their labor is. In some Latin American<br />

countries, union organizers are systematically killed by government-connected paramilitary forces.<br />

Message [806] referenced by [820]. First Message by JPeel is [423].<br />

[820] Ryoung: Child Labor a Sad Necessity. I think that Jpeel [806] brings up some<br />

truth in his submission regarding child labor and them being exploited. It is a sad truth that<br />

around the world there are children that are forced to work. These children not are only<br />

working but they are working in horrible conditions, long hours, and for horrible pay. In<br />

the readings that I have read regarding child labor I have come to feel for them as, like<br />

Jpeel mentioned, they are being exploited. However in most <strong>of</strong> these situations they are


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 321<br />

working out <strong>of</strong> necessity to provide for their families. The economic conditions as a whole<br />

in these countries are so horrible that I believe there is hardly any opportunity for anyone<br />

who resides there. It will be a long difficult process but I do believe that more opportunity<br />

can be brought to them but it will come with sacrifice. I have also come to find out that if<br />

the child workers were to be outlawed the economy would even fall to a worse state which<br />

would leave them and their families worse <strong>of</strong>f economically. Therefore I believe that the<br />

best solution to this would be to create parameters for these children to work and a more fair<br />

wage would have to be provided. Not only this but the conditions in which they work would<br />

have to be improved. Should children have to work? Of course not! But in order for these<br />

living conditions to improve I believe that these parameters would have to be in order.<br />

Hans: This kind <strong>of</strong> reasoning is called a TINA argument (There Is No Alternative).<br />

First Message by Ryoung is [36].<br />

[831] Carterryan: Work Hard for the Money. The misery <strong>of</strong> idle impoverishment is<br />

way worse than the torture <strong>of</strong> work. This is true socially and economically. Socially because<br />

when you do not work you are a burden to society, you do not give anything back and you<br />

still require substance to survive so you are taking without giving anything back. Also when<br />

a person works they fulfill a personal satisfaction that is better than the torment <strong>of</strong> work.<br />

The economic reason is similar to the social reason, in that when you are not working the<br />

community loses out on the economic surplus that can be used to create a decrease in the<br />

cost <strong>of</strong> goods.<br />

Next Message by Carterryan is [876].<br />

[836] Ande: This is the type <strong>of</strong> question that can be answered either way, it comes from<br />

the way you were raised how you measure wealth and value, and how you personally take<br />

the readings from Marx. I personally feel that idle impoverishment is much worse than the<br />

torture <strong>of</strong> work. I have a liking for material items and do not look at work as torture but as a<br />

form <strong>of</strong> gaining wealth, knowledge, and value. I feel that without work you will not be able<br />

to gain wealth or money to spend in the market place to buy materials for the necessity <strong>of</strong><br />

living as well as buying material items. As well when one is working they are able to gain<br />

knowledge everyday in the work place, as well as having a feeling <strong>of</strong> value for their work.<br />

I personally get satisfaction for putting in a hard day’s work. I feel that I was raised to feel<br />

this way. The family I was raised in always looked at hard work as being the only way to<br />

get far in life and be successful. That is why I feel as though idle impoverishment is a much<br />

larger torture than the torture <strong>of</strong> work. I also took a lot <strong>of</strong> what Marx has written in helping<br />

to answer this question. After reading the chapters I feel as though Marx feels that work can<br />

be torture at times but it is necessary in every aspect <strong>of</strong> life. It is not torture if you look at<br />

what you gain from it. So through personal experiences and the readings <strong>of</strong> Marx, I feel the<br />

torture <strong>of</strong> idle impoverishment is much worse than that <strong>of</strong> the torture <strong>of</strong> work.<br />

Message [836] referenced by [838]. Next Message by Ande is [837].<br />

[838] Aaron: torture <strong>of</strong> work? It is interesting to note in what Ande [836] says about the<br />

torture <strong>of</strong> work and the idle impoverishment. Marx clearly believes that work is something<br />

<strong>of</strong> a torturous task, only performed because one must, not because he wants to gain material<br />

things or wealth. Before the time <strong>of</strong> Karl Marx, work was not always irksome. There was<br />

a time when work was noble and honorable. In ancient cultures, only the best and brightest


322 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

were allowed to go hunt and work and build houses for the tribes and societies. Even in recent<br />

Native American cultures this is evident. The hunters, or workers, are the most admired<br />

group in the tribe. I wonder where society began to view work and compensation as some<br />

type <strong>of</strong> torture? Or where Marx derived the same theory, that work is to be disdained?<br />

Message [838] referenced by [839]. Next Message by Aaron is [849].<br />

[839] FacistFrank: In response to Aaron’s [838], I think that Marx would have said<br />

that actual work is not something that is tortuous, but that what capitalism has turned work<br />

into is certainly torture, at least it was in his time. There are types <strong>of</strong> work, that require a<br />

lot <strong>of</strong> effort but it feels great when you get done, because you get all the benefits <strong>of</strong> that<br />

labor. Some people like my brother love to work on cars and their engines. It gives them<br />

an immense feeling <strong>of</strong> satisfaction, or a baker who has just made a beautiful wedding cake.<br />

I think that capitalism can make it similar to torture because you are so ripped <strong>of</strong>f, when it<br />

comes to getting the full benefits <strong>of</strong> your labor. But I also agree that idle impoverishment is<br />

a worse fate. It’s like being stuck between a rock and a hard space, capitalist exploitation or<br />

grinding poverty.<br />

Next Message by FacistFrank is [865].<br />

Question 803 is 446 in 1999SP, 617 in 2002fa, 641 in 2003fa, 700 in 2004fa, 674 in<br />

2005fa, 804 in 2007SP, 773 in 2007fa, 808 in 2008fa, 841 in 2009fa, and 944 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 803 The only way the worker can improve his lot in society is to increase the<br />

productive powers <strong>of</strong> his labor. Right or wrong?<br />

[829] Allen: worker’s lot in society. I believe that the answer to the question is wrong and<br />

that a worker cannot increase his lot in society by increasing the productive powers <strong>of</strong> his<br />

labor. Marx says that “the higher the productive powers <strong>of</strong> labor the greater is the pressure<br />

<strong>of</strong> the workers on the means <strong>of</strong> employment, the more precarious therefore becomes the<br />

condition for their existence, namely the sale <strong>of</strong> their own labor-power for the increase <strong>of</strong><br />

alien wealth” [798:3]. Marx basically states that if a worker works too much he will not<br />

increase his lot in society and actually make it worse.<br />

Hans: An increase in the productivity <strong>of</strong> labor is not always connected with more work or more intense work. But<br />

such an increase in productivity is typically accompanied by more machinery per worker. Therefore the capitalist<br />

has to invest more capital per worker. This will lower demand for labor and make the laborer’s situation more<br />

precarious.<br />

Message [829] referenced by [833] and [2008fa:1257]. Next Message by Allen is [864].<br />

[833] FacistFrank: Re: worker’s lot in society. this question and answer [829] are<br />

really fascinating, Allen thinks it is false, i don’t know because i have not read the chapter<br />

yet. But perhaps i can use the limited bit <strong>of</strong> dialectic i actually learned in this class, to try<br />

and extrapolate. I do think the correct answer, is false, but perhaps a worker can improve his<br />

lot in a small way from increasing his labor power, anyways the worker can take the biggest<br />

step in improving his lot by unionizing and simply seizing the means <strong>of</strong> production. He can<br />

temporarily increase his lot by increasing labor power but it is to his long term detriment,<br />

because he increases the power <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. Whether revenue goes to his boss or his<br />

bosses’ boss, or the owner <strong>of</strong> his imputs, it still goes to the biggest capitalist fish in the<br />

ocean. However this increases the chances that the workers will revolt because conditions<br />

are getting worse as a result. so they successfully revolt, then the workers who set up a more


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 323<br />

perfect state, will get lazy and selfish, and forgetful <strong>of</strong> the lessons <strong>of</strong> the past, and i think<br />

this has a lot to do with Marx’s theory <strong>of</strong> Permanent revolution. The new workers in the<br />

“utopia” will have to use the power that capital has to produce their necessities and no more,<br />

then the rest <strong>of</strong> the time is spent reading and enlightening themselves, so they can keep the<br />

society going at a balance to not slip back into the cycle. This whole chain <strong>of</strong> logic seems<br />

to move in a circle, and the circle turns and purges itself and become less violent with each<br />

violent purge. perhaps it reaches utopia or simply turns around again in a bigger circle it<br />

is moving in., i hope this doesn’t sound like nonsense or is way <strong>of</strong>f the dialectic mark. If<br />

this is dialectic, or a more roughly missed hit, which this explanation probably is, i think it<br />

applies to everything, from the cycles <strong>of</strong> destruction and creation that work in the principles<br />

<strong>of</strong> self improvement, to the inner workings <strong>of</strong> a car’s engine. opposite forces diametrically<br />

reflecting (another word i have read Marx use) and using the force and structure <strong>of</strong> the other<br />

to support it, and enable it’s existence.<br />

P.S. this class was fantastic, Hans do you teach any other marxian classes? Or are there<br />

other marxian classes at the U, no pun intended.<br />

Hans: There are other Marxist faculty at our Department: Kay Hunt, Al Campbell, Minqi Li. Minqi Li just<br />

published an interesting article about China and Global Warming in Monthly Review, see<br />

http://www.monthlyreview.org/080401li.php<br />

Just today someone on the marxism mailing list commented about Minqi:<br />

When it comes to fusing an understanding <strong>of</strong> the ecological limits to global accumulation with<br />

an analysis <strong>of</strong> the complementarities and conflicts between US imperialism on the decline<br />

and PRC capitalism on the rise, Minqi Li is probably the most astute commentator out there.<br />

Publishing really good stuff like this, I wonder how long he will be able to occupy his perch<br />

in bourgeois academia though.<br />

As far as I can tell, Minqi’s position is solid.<br />

Next Message by FacistFrank is [839].<br />

Question 805 is 475 in 1999SP, 601 in 2001fa, 729 in 2004fa, 806 in 2007SP, 775 in<br />

2007fa, 810 in 2008fa, 913 in 2010fa, and 946 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 805 Define and discuss the law <strong>of</strong> the absolute impoverishment <strong>of</strong> the working<br />

class. Does it apply today?<br />

[842] Samantha: Sweatshops and misery. Marx states, “[A]s capital accumulates, the<br />

situation <strong>of</strong> the worker, be his payment high or low, must grow worse.” This is the basic idea<br />

<strong>of</strong> absolute impoverishment, that as the rich grow richer they must get their wealth from<br />

somewhere and that is from the poor proletariat. An example <strong>of</strong> this is sweatshop labor. The<br />

example Mopreme gives in [2005fa:605] about Nike is still valid today, the very poorest are<br />

not getting any richer, in fact they are getting poorer because with rising prices they are still<br />

getting paid the same.<br />

The other portion <strong>of</strong> this theory deals with the absolute portion <strong>of</strong> impoverishment, “All<br />

methods for raising the social productive powers <strong>of</strong> labor are put into effect at the expense<br />

<strong>of</strong> the worker; ... they distort the worker into a fragment <strong>of</strong> a man, they degrade him to the<br />

level <strong>of</strong> an appendage <strong>of</strong> a machine, they destroy actual content <strong>of</strong> his labor by turning it<br />

a torment.” [775:1/o] This is the absolute portion. Because <strong>of</strong> the lack <strong>of</strong> any benefit from<br />

the labor to the worker, people are miserable, their impoverishment is complete, not only


324 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

are they physically poor but they are poor in spirit as well, this is what Marx means and it<br />

happens all around us with today with the general exploitation <strong>of</strong> labor.<br />

Hans: But in strictly material terms here in the USA, the working class has not been impoverished enough to call<br />

it “immiseration.” True, the steady advances in the living standards have slowed down or ceased, minimum wages<br />

have not kept up with inflation, there is a health care crisis, workers are losing pensions, etc., but “immiseration”<br />

means third world conditions, or perhaps the situation <strong>of</strong> the Katrina victims.<br />

Next Message by Samantha is [843].<br />

Question 807 is 383 in 1997WI, 648 in 2002fa, 672 in 2003fa, 731 in 2004fa, 678 in<br />

2005fa, 808 in 2007SP, 777 in 2007fa, 812 in 2008fa, 845 in 2009fa, 915 in 2010fa, and<br />

948 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 807 “The poor and idle are a necessary consequence <strong>of</strong> the rich and active.”<br />

Right or wrong?<br />

[835] Scott: Lazy capitalist. A capitalist generates his wealth through the exploitation<br />

<strong>of</strong> his laborers and not through his own work. Therefore to say that the poor are idle is<br />

wrong. Skippy put it right, [1997WI:400] “if the poor were idle, the rich people <strong>of</strong> this<br />

world wouldn’t be rich.” Skippy goes on to say the quote should read as follows, “The poor<br />

and active are the necessary consequence <strong>of</strong> the rich and idle.” It is the worker who creates<br />

the use value so the capitalist can use it for his pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

Hans: Your last sentence seems to imply that the capitalist makes pr<strong>of</strong>its by marketing the use-values generated by<br />

the workers. I.e., workers are only responsible for the use-value, and the capitalists are responsible for turning this<br />

use-value into money. Marx does not give the capitalist so much credit. According to Marx’s theory, the worker<br />

not only creates use-value but also value, that which underlies the sales price. I.e., pr<strong>of</strong>its are created in production,<br />

not in circulation.<br />

Next Message by Scott is [855].<br />

Question 810 is 386 in 1997WI, 456 in 1998WI, 480 in 1999SP, 734 in 2004fa, 681 in<br />

2005fa, 780 in 2007fa, 815 in 2008fa, 848 in 2009fa, 918 in 2010fa, and 951 in 2011fa:<br />

Question 810 What is the General Law <strong>of</strong> Capitalist Accumulation?<br />

[814] Bar: graded A capital accumulation and exploitation. The most interesting idea<br />

regarding the theory <strong>of</strong> capital accumulation is as stated in annotations, “. . . The system <strong>of</strong><br />

capital accumulation has managed to integrate the labor-market into its own logic instead <strong>of</strong><br />

allowing it to disturb or constrain capital accumulation from the outside.” This argument is<br />

key in understanding how capitalism shapes the environment unnaturally through constraints<br />

on the labor market. The laborers work with the capital to produce a good, the laborers are<br />

not disturbing the market and expanding it as they wish, because they do not hold the means<br />

<strong>of</strong> production. The outside force <strong>of</strong> trade also influences this because sometimes to expand<br />

capital you have to expand trade knocking down impediments like unions and unnecessary<br />

labor to change laws or social constructs for the furthering <strong>of</strong> capital. As capital increases<br />

so does one lot <strong>of</strong> money transform into larger forms <strong>of</strong> money; M-C-M1. This equation<br />

show how important money is to the growth <strong>of</strong> capital in a capital economy. In the end,<br />

capitalists exploit the workers, because it increases the money <strong>of</strong> the capitalist, by taking the<br />

capital and labor, which is just time delayed labor, the capitalist squeezes out value from the<br />

workers by using more, and more efficient capital.


Message [814] referenced by [2009fa:1210]. Next Message by Bar is [821].<br />

U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 325<br />

Term Paper 811 is 786 in 2007fa, 816 in 2008fa, 849 in 2009fa, 920 in 2010fa, 953 in<br />

2011fa, and 983 in 2012fa:<br />

Term Paper 811 Term Paper on the Externalities <strong>of</strong> Capitalism, i.e., on the positive and<br />

negative local and global impacts <strong>of</strong> production in the name <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

[769] Alex: graded A Resources and Capitalism. When considering the positive and<br />

negative externalities <strong>of</strong> Capitalism you must realize that the effects are far reaching over<br />

both time and policy. Positive and negative externalities must be put into a concept and<br />

considered by every individual, because how you weigh the effects will probably determine<br />

your political views and governmental participation.<br />

Marx starts chapter Twenty-Five by discussing the impasse that will occur in capitalism.<br />

That is he questions “sooner or later, the accumulation <strong>of</strong> capital must run into the limitation<br />

<strong>of</strong> population growth.” This statement comes to reflect the capitalist as a person that will<br />

consume resources until they are no longer available. This first recognition <strong>of</strong> capital consumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> resources is vital in understanding a key negative externality, that being limited<br />

growth. I think time has shown that resources have been much more abundant than what<br />

could be consumed in a matter <strong>of</strong> years or decades. However, resources are not infinite<br />

and they have definite parameters as to what they can accommodate. So who determines<br />

how best to use resources? The capitalist will use all resources to facilitate growth without<br />

thought <strong>of</strong> others. As Marx brings up in earlier chapters, the capitalist will work all employees<br />

at unreasonable rates to insure the machines are always running. This problem is<br />

discussed further in the problem known as the “tragedy <strong>of</strong> the commons.”<br />

Marx also identifies the different aspects <strong>of</strong> capital as being more than just one process.<br />

He divides capital into both production and living capital, or labor power. The control <strong>of</strong><br />

labor power by the capitalist has been discussed at length in previous chapters, but it is<br />

important to understand that this is a manipulation and exploitation <strong>of</strong> the worker by the<br />

capitalist. The laborer is unable to sell their power, in the form <strong>of</strong> commodities, so they are<br />

forced to work for the capitalist. This is another negative externality <strong>of</strong> capitalism.<br />

But what <strong>of</strong> the composition <strong>of</strong> the capital? When the commodity does not necessarily<br />

reflect the generation <strong>of</strong> the commodity it must be looked at with special parameters. At the<br />

end <strong>of</strong> the scenario growth in capital is merely a reflection <strong>of</strong> its variable makeup, most<br />

notably labor-power. These variables again reflect the control by the capitalist, and his<br />

manipulation <strong>of</strong> the market. The growth is controlled by the capitalist so it constantly plays<br />

into his favor as it needs to.<br />

As capital accumulates it outgrows the ability to produce the good. This means that<br />

growth will outpace labor. Does this possibly mean a wage increase for the laborer? It could,<br />

depending on the capitalist and resources available. This is certainly a positive externality<br />

<strong>of</strong> capitalism. That being said, the laborer does not alter how the capitalist functions. In fact<br />

the opposite occurs, this process gives the capitalist increased control over the market.<br />

The growth process can continue on and on until resources limit growth. However, the<br />

valorization process is an important feature <strong>of</strong> this discussion. The most important factor in


326 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

all <strong>of</strong> these scenarios is simply that the worker is becoming more and more enslaved to the<br />

capitalist. As the growth occurs and money changes hands, the laborer is not involved or<br />

compensated justly but becomes unable to distinguish the different faces <strong>of</strong> the capitalist.<br />

Marx also discusses the plight <strong>of</strong> the proletariat. The proletariat is simply the wage laborer.<br />

But what is the worth <strong>of</strong> the laborer to the capitalist. When the laborers use has run<br />

its course the laborer is left to himself. The dependence <strong>of</strong> the laborer on the capitalist is<br />

a myth, the laborer is actually dependent on his own product. Marx does not buy into the<br />

growth factors increasing wages, he believes that it is just a nicer chain binding the worker.<br />

Marx goes onto describe the process by which the laborer has any worth. It is only by<br />

producing pr<strong>of</strong>its that the laborer has any worth. If the labor-power does not produce pr<strong>of</strong>its<br />

then it is no longer valuable. This is a seemingly simple statement but the ramifications are<br />

vast and have many underlying tones concerning social structure, and the freedom <strong>of</strong> the<br />

capitalist to invest as they see fit.<br />

Marx describes the growth as a social factor as well. It is not simply the capital growing<br />

but has more effects on the market itself. If capital contract wages shrink, as capital expands<br />

wages rise. The employment base is dependent on the movement <strong>of</strong> capital. The lifestyle <strong>of</strong><br />

the worker is dependent on the capital.<br />

Composition <strong>of</strong> capital is more complex than what Marx originally described and he goes<br />

into depth about the role <strong>of</strong> technology in capitalism. This is certainly a positive externality<br />

<strong>of</strong> capital. The capital pushes forth progress in the technical arena. However, this new<br />

variable also brings the variable in composition to a more complex level, and one could<br />

make the argument that is also continues the enslavement <strong>of</strong> the capitalist. This higher<br />

technology can make the laborer less valuable.<br />

Marx also takes a more complex look at the factors that make up capital. These smaller<br />

units are all part <strong>of</strong> a larger unit and are retracted and compulsed. The concentration <strong>of</strong><br />

capital is limited by the effects <strong>of</strong> the market. Competition among smaller capitals are fierce<br />

and can be influenced by the number <strong>of</strong> players in the equation. These smaller capitals can<br />

take control <strong>of</strong> certain productions that have not been controlled by larger markets.<br />

Capital also by its nature creates the reserve army. This reserve army is controlled and<br />

exploited by the capital. This army can be used discarded as the capital sees fit. Those in the<br />

army are forced to dependence on the capital.<br />

There exists in capital the very important links between the variables <strong>of</strong> capital the laborer<br />

and wages paid. This link is demonstrated by the capital processes and growth. This control<br />

can lead to an inferior labor power that is set in motion by the capital. Marx does concede<br />

that wages are controlled somewhat by the labor according to population. He admits that<br />

population flows can create a change in capital according to wages. This surplus population<br />

and the laborer are exploited by the capitalist, this means that someone who has only lived<br />

half a life, has already used their abilities on behalf <strong>of</strong> the labor.<br />

The flows <strong>of</strong> capital, social wealth and function along with the proletariat determine the<br />

reserve army. The constant growing army is defeated in life and health and is thus left to<br />

poverty.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 327<br />

These functions have a widespread effect on the economy. Resources <strong>of</strong> the laborer,<br />

etc, can be used up. These externalities discussed are essential for understanding capital.<br />

Though the reader is always left to their own conclusions, the judgements made from Marx<br />

will determine much about the who the reader is and how they will participate in political<br />

life.<br />

First Message by Alex is [139].<br />

Question 888 is 0 in 2005fa, 0 in 2007SP, 888 in 2007fa, 888 in 2008fa, 888 in 2009fa,<br />

888 in 2010fa, 888 in 2011fa, and 888 in 2012fa:<br />

Question 888 Free Discussion<br />

[3] Hans: Diet <strong>of</strong> Prejudice and Bias. http://www.foreignpolicy.com/story/cms.php?st<br />

Europe’s Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Failure<br />

By Stefan Theil<br />

January/February 2008<br />

In France and Germany, students are being forced to undergo a dangerous indoctrination.<br />

Taught that economic principles such as capitalism, free markets, and entrepreneurship are<br />

savage, unhealthy, and immoral, these children are raised on a diet <strong>of</strong> prejudice and bias.<br />

Rooting it out may determine whether Europe’s economies prosper or continue to be left<br />

behind.<br />

Millions <strong>of</strong> children are being raised on prejudice and disinformation. Educated in schools<br />

that teach a skewed ideology, they are exposed to a dogma that runs counter to core beliefs<br />

shared by many other Western countries. They study from textbooks filled with a doctrine <strong>of</strong><br />

dissent, which they learn to recite as they prepare to attend many <strong>of</strong> the better universities in<br />

the world. Extracting these children from the jaws <strong>of</strong> bias could mean the difference between<br />

world prosperity and menacing global rifts. And doing so will not be easy. But not because<br />

these children are found in the madrasas <strong>of</strong> Pakistan or the state-controlled schools <strong>of</strong> Saudi<br />

Arabia. They are not. Rather, they live in two <strong>of</strong> the world’s great democracies–France and<br />

Germany.<br />

What a country teaches its young people reflects its bedrock national beliefs. Schools<br />

hand down a society’s historical narrative to the next generation. There has been a great deal<br />

<strong>of</strong> debate over the ways in which this historical ideology is passed on–over Japanese textbooks<br />

that downplay the Nanjing Massacre, Palestinian textbooks that feature maps without<br />

Israel, and new Russian guidelines that require teachers to portray Stalinism more favorably.<br />

Yet there has been almost no analysis <strong>of</strong> how countries teach economics, even though the<br />

subject is equally crucial in shaping the collective identity that drives foreign and domestic<br />

policies.<br />

Just as schools teach a historical narrative, they also pass on “truths” about capitalism,<br />

the welfare state, and other economic principles that a society considers self-evident. In<br />

both France and Germany, for instance, schools have helped ingrain a serious aversion to<br />

capitalism. In one 2005 poll, just 36 percent <strong>of</strong> French citizens said they supported the<br />

free-enterprise system, the only one <strong>of</strong> 22 countries polled that showed minority support for


328 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

this cornerstone <strong>of</strong> global commerce. In Germany, meanwhile, support for socialist ideals is<br />

running at all-time highs–47 percent in 2007 versus 36 percent in 1991.<br />

It’s tempting to dismiss these attitudes as being little more than punch lines to cocktail<br />

party jokes. But their impact is sadly and seriously self-destructive. In Germany, unemployment<br />

is finally falling after years at Depression-era levels, thanks in no small part to welfare<br />

reforms that in 2005 pressured Germans on the public dole to take up jobs. Yet there is<br />

near consensus among Germans that, despite this happy outcome, tinkering with the welfare<br />

state went far beyond what is permissible. Chancellor Angela Merkel, once heralded as<br />

Germany’s own Margaret Thatcher, has all but abandoned her plans to continue free-market<br />

reforms. She has instead imposed a new “rich people tax,” has tightened labor-market rules,<br />

and has promised renewed efforts to “regulate” globalization. Meanwhile, two in three Germans<br />

say they support at least some <strong>of</strong> the voodoo-economic, roll-back-the-reforms platform<br />

<strong>of</strong> a noisy new antiglobalization political party called Die Linke (The Left), founded by former<br />

East German communists and Western left-wing populists.<br />

Message [3] referenced by [4] and [13]. Next Message by Hans is [5].<br />

[4] Litsyemir: It’s the same story here. I lived for two years in Moscow and other<br />

cities <strong>of</strong> Russia as a missionary for the LDS Church. I have seen firsthand the effects <strong>of</strong> a<br />

powerful indoctrination as discussed in [3] Diet <strong>of</strong> Prejudice and Bias. Such indoctrination<br />

binds people and makes them slaves to dogmatic beliefs. It shuts down the ability <strong>of</strong> a person<br />

to think freely and to act freely by limiting their point <strong>of</strong> view to a narrow window that only<br />

shows part <strong>of</strong> the whole picture.<br />

However, I also believe that such indoctrination has taken place and continues to take<br />

place here in America. Call me a cynic, but are we that much better than the Germans or<br />

the French who teach anti-capitalist beliefs to schoolchildren? I remember being young,<br />

but also knowing that the communists <strong>of</strong> the USSR and East Germany were the enemy, the<br />

embodiment <strong>of</strong> governmental and economic evils. Socialism, I remember being taught, was<br />

the antithesis <strong>of</strong> Capitalism - the two had no common ground and could not coexist.<br />

Maybe I just remember incorrectly. Or maybe as I’ve grown and matured I’ve connected<br />

things I’ve heard and read to what I was taught in my youth. Regardless, I feel that Americans<br />

are just as guilty, if not more so, <strong>of</strong> indoctrinating our children. Capitalism in America<br />

has become Consumption. If anything we teach our children that the accumulation <strong>of</strong> an<br />

“immense heap <strong>of</strong> commodities”, as Marx put it, at any cost <strong>of</strong> debt or work or servitude to<br />

those commodities is “the American way <strong>of</strong> life.” And more <strong>of</strong>ten than not, a commodity is<br />

acquired to be used once or barely glanced at and then tossed aside, never to be used again.<br />

I’m as guilty as the next person. Sometimes I get caught up in the trappings <strong>of</strong> our<br />

consumer driven world. But what I hope I can do is teach my children to look at the world<br />

through open eyes - to see that everything in this world isn’t just black and white, but by<br />

looking at the whole picture, good and usefulness can be seen in anything, and that true<br />

wisdom and knowledge only comes by being able to make their own choices and have their<br />

own experiences.<br />

Message [4] referenced by [13]. Next Message by Litsyemir is [6].<br />

[8] Hans: Education - Live Long and Prosper. Someone from last Semester sent in<br />

the following message, which is a response to [2007fa:601]. This person was no longer


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 329<br />

subscribed, so the message was rejected. (But participants from earlier classes are invited to<br />

re-subscribe as observers if they’d like). Since my [5] just mentioned education as wealth<br />

which one cannot buy or sell, I thought this was topical, and I am forwarding his message to<br />

the class.<br />

I think a major benefit <strong>of</strong> education for personal economic potential is that education prepares<br />

people to make more sophisticated comparisons and analysis <strong>of</strong> the pay<strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> different<br />

types <strong>of</strong> work and opportunities.<br />

For example, I’ve recently had two jobs: one based in an <strong>of</strong>fice using a computer and the<br />

other a labor job in a distribution center. Both jobs had the exact same hours and pay. The<br />

major difference between these two jobs was that the <strong>of</strong>fice job had frequent downtime and<br />

constant access to high speed Internet, while the distribution center job had no downtime,<br />

no access to the Internet and was physically exhausting. At the <strong>of</strong>fice job, I was able to not<br />

only get my work done, but also check my e-mail, read the news, check my online bank<br />

account, plan my afternoon, and still have energy at the end <strong>of</strong> the day to go to night classes.<br />

The labor job in contrast kept me less organized, less informed, and more tired, effectively<br />

shortening the amount <strong>of</strong> free time I had once I was <strong>of</strong>f work. So while both jobs had the<br />

same hours and same pay, the labor job included a significantly higher opportunity cost.<br />

While the inequalities between these two jobs were simple for me quantify in my own<br />

mind, my less educated friends who also worked at the distribution center shrugged it <strong>of</strong>f<br />

declaring “a jobs a job”. I think education is important because it can empower people to<br />

more actively quantify the cost and benefits <strong>of</strong> various opportunities. Laborers in particular<br />

really ought to do this. Because the highly educated business owners constantly calculate<br />

how they can increase output while decreasing cost. Often decreasing the cost for the business<br />

increases the cost for the laborer. And that is probably difficult to analyze if you don’t<br />

have a strong educational background.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [9].<br />

[10] Chris: Live Long and Prosper? The United States has a very large middle class.<br />

From a young age I was taught its societal basics: Go to school, Get good grades, Go to<br />

college, Get a good job, Have a family, and then Retire with monetary wealth. I am willing<br />

to bet that these underlying Western Values are instilled in most <strong>of</strong> us. Therefore, by doing<br />

these steps it would appear that we would all live long and prosper. It would also appear<br />

that by doing all these steps our society would all have the same “end” vision <strong>of</strong> happiness<br />

and prosperity. What I have noticed, is that we do not all have the same ideals and instead a<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> individuality that cannot be taught from a young age.<br />

Who classifies what living “long” is? For one person, longevity could be determined by<br />

climbing Mount Everest in their lifetime. If they do this by age 35, then this person has lived<br />

their own “long” life. For another person, it could be living those societal basics that most<br />

<strong>of</strong> the middle class in the United States would like to see achieved. I would also assume that<br />

prosperity could be defined on an individual basis as well.<br />

If a society were to implement laws governing each person’s longevity and prosperity we<br />

would see a backlash. Even if the society were to place these laws on day one <strong>of</strong> a person’s


330 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

life, that person’s individual goal to live long and prosper would be skewed enough to try<br />

and fight the governing society.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [17].<br />

[38] Chris: wine study and price manipulation. I was recently listening to the radio on<br />

my way home from school and I could not help but be reminded <strong>of</strong> the sad state <strong>of</strong> culture<br />

in which we live. On the radio, the two dj’s were talking about a wine study conducted by<br />

scientists from the California Institute <strong>of</strong> Technology and Standford <strong>University</strong>. In the study,<br />

a group <strong>of</strong> volunteers sampled glasses <strong>of</strong> wine and told the scientists which one had the best<br />

taste. The catch was that the wine enthusiasts were given the prices <strong>of</strong> the wines before<br />

they drank them. The study scientists manipulated the prices and needless to say, the wines<br />

that were given a higher price received better ratings and vice versa. All <strong>of</strong> the volunteers<br />

were hooked up to brain monitoring devices and the research showed that brain activity was<br />

stimulated more when they saw a higher price tag on the wine.<br />

Here is a link to the actual study:<br />

http://www.physorg.com/news119531708.html<br />

I am posting this because I find it rather sad that people are so motivated by a price tag<br />

and material possessions. Also, it ties in directly with our discussions in class because the<br />

volunteers placed more value on the wines that they thought were expensive. I find it even<br />

harder to fathom because this study was researching brain wave activity. This would insulate<br />

to me that the thought process <strong>of</strong> the volunteers was impossible to control (subconscious<br />

affect) and that they have been ingrained <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> pricing by the society in which they<br />

live. When will this society stop placing so much “value” on material possessions and start<br />

placing it on the stimulation <strong>of</strong> the human soul?<br />

Next Message by Chris is [91].<br />

[39] Hans: Do The World’s Poor Countries Finance the Rich Ones?<br />

http://www.populareconomics.org/<br />

Do The World’s Poor Countries Finance the Rich Ones?<br />

By Amit Basole<br />

Center for Popular Economics Staff Economist<br />

January 16, 2008<br />

Global Charity<br />

In the year 2000, the richest 10 per cent <strong>of</strong> the world’s population held 85 percent <strong>of</strong> its<br />

total income and wealth. The bottom half owned a mere 1 percent. Such glaring global<br />

asymmetries have long justified redistribution <strong>of</strong> wealth from the “Global North” to the<br />

“Global South” in the form <strong>of</strong> development aid and loans. So much so, that the stock image<br />

<strong>of</strong> a developing country that springs to mind (particularly in sub-Saharan Africa) is that <strong>of</strong><br />

a heavily indebted economy which continually borrows simply to repay its old loans and<br />

receives food and other forms <strong>of</strong> aid to feed and clothe its “naked and hungry masses.”<br />

Persistent poverty is <strong>of</strong>ten blamed on inadequate aid, and rich countries are periodically<br />

exhorted to donate more generously. This form <strong>of</strong> global charity is visible to all. But there is


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 331<br />

another flow <strong>of</strong> wealth across national borders, greater in magnitude and more clandestine.<br />

This is the flow from poor countries to the rich. Yes, the world’s poorest countries are today<br />

financing the richest. Far from being heavily indebted, many developing countries are net<br />

creditors vis-a-vis the rest <strong>of</strong> the world. How is this possible?<br />

Who is financing whom?<br />

Recent analysis <strong>of</strong> flows <strong>of</strong> income and wealth across national borders reveals a startling<br />

and different story than that <strong>of</strong> global charity towards the South. Economists have found that<br />

more money flows out <strong>of</strong> developing countries in the form <strong>of</strong> interest payments, pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>of</strong><br />

foreign corporations, and clandestine investments in financial markets <strong>of</strong> the rich countries<br />

than flows into them as loans, aid, and foreign direct investment. According to a recent<br />

United Nation’s report, in 1995 the net inflow <strong>of</strong> money into developing countries was $40<br />

billion, but by 2006 this had reversed to a net outflow <strong>of</strong> $657 billion! The global financial<br />

system is sucking wealth out <strong>of</strong> developing countries, making them poorer in the process.<br />

Sub-Saharan Africa in particular is associated with highly indebted poor countries. Indeed,<br />

in 1996 the combined external debt <strong>of</strong> 25 countries <strong>of</strong> sub-Saharan Africa, owed to rich<br />

countries and to institutions such as the IMF and the World Bank, stood at $178 billion–a<br />

large sum indeed. But even more significantly, the flow <strong>of</strong> wealth out <strong>of</strong> these same countries<br />

over 26 years (1970-1996) equaled more than $193 billion. To make matters worse, much<br />

<strong>of</strong> this wealth flowing out <strong>of</strong> poor countries ends up in the US economy, which absorbs twothirds<br />

<strong>of</strong> world savings. The ecologically-damaging consumption boom in the world’s rich<br />

countries is financed by its poor countries where consumption is a matter <strong>of</strong> survival. The<br />

insanity <strong>of</strong> this situation puts a question mark on the entire logic <strong>of</strong> the international financial<br />

system.<br />

How does this happen?<br />

But wait a minute. We might wonder, aren’t developing countries poor by definition?<br />

How then do they have resources to transfer to rich countries? We must remember here that<br />

although the majority <strong>of</strong> the population in a developing country is indeed poor, most countries<br />

have a small elite class that owns a disproportionate share <strong>of</strong> its income and wealth.<br />

In other words, the poor are poor precisely because the rich are rich. Further, a government<br />

may be highly indebted but what about its private citizens, in particular the rich ones?<br />

Several African leaders have amassed personal fortunes even as the governments they head<br />

have incurred large debts. At least in part these extraordinary assets are held abroad in rich<br />

countries. The problem is that while public debts are scrupulously recorded, many private<br />

assets are just as scrupulously concealed. To take just one famous example, the Swiss bank<br />

accounts <strong>of</strong> the family <strong>of</strong> General Sani Abacha, who ruled Nigeria for five years, reportedly<br />

contain as much as $2 billion.<br />

This phenomenon is also known as “capital flight.” There are several avenues by which<br />

money flows from the poor countries to the rich. Repayment <strong>of</strong> earlier debt and accumulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> foreign exchange reserves with Central Banks in developing countries are two big ones.<br />

Since reserves <strong>of</strong>ten take the form <strong>of</strong> US treasury bills, reserve accumulation essentially<br />

means lending scarce capital to the US, a classic case <strong>of</strong> the poor lending to the rich. But<br />

there is yet a third, more hidden, avenue as well. This is trade mis-invoicing: under-reporting


332 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

exports and over-reporting imports. Exporters in a country may understate the value <strong>of</strong> their<br />

export revenues, so that they can retain abroad the difference between their true value and<br />

their declared value, while importers may over-state the value <strong>of</strong> their imports to obtain extra<br />

foreign exchange, which can then be transferred abroad.<br />

What can be done?<br />

Should we simply chalk this up as a typical case <strong>of</strong> Third World mismanagement and corruption,<br />

a problem <strong>of</strong> “failed states,” a lack <strong>of</strong> democratic accountability and transparency? It<br />

is all that, but that is not the whole story. Rich country governments and international lending<br />

institutions are <strong>of</strong>ten complicit in maintaining corrupt rulers and in transferring their assets<br />

abroad. The Financial Times remarks in an editorial on the freezing <strong>of</strong> General Abacha’s<br />

bank accounts, “Financial institutions that knowingly channeled the funds have much to answer<br />

for, acting not so much as bankers but as bagmen, complicit in the corruption that has<br />

crippled Nigeria.”<br />

If development aid is used to amass private fortunes while external creditors look the other<br />

way, why should a developing country’s poor citizens be forced to pay the price <strong>of</strong> painful<br />

“reforms” such as cutbacks in government spending on essential services, when most <strong>of</strong> that<br />

aid has not benefited them at all in the first place? Rather citizens <strong>of</strong> developing countries<br />

and their governments could tell their foreign creditors that old debt will only be treated as<br />

legitimate if the creditors can provide evidence for how the money was used for genuine<br />

development goals. This shifts the burden <strong>of</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> onto the lenders. Needless to say, such a<br />

proposal would be extremely unpopular with rich country governments as well as with the<br />

IMF and the World Bank.<br />

In addition to “bottom-up” approaches to development, such as strengthening government<br />

accountability and democracy from below in developing countries, there is a role for us here<br />

in the developed world to play: we can do our bit by raising awareness about capital flight<br />

and odious debt, and holding our own governments accountable for who they lend or give<br />

aid to and how that money is spent.<br />

Sources: 1. Isabel Ortiz (2007) Putting Financing for Development in Perspective: The<br />

South Finances the North, IDEAS Network<br />

http://www.ideaswebsite.org/news/nov2007/Putting Financing.pdf<br />

2. World Economic Situation and Prospects, 2007- United Nation Development Policy<br />

and Analysis Division<br />

http://www.un.org/esa/policy/wess/wesp.html<br />

3. James Boyce and Leone Ndikumana (2000) Is Africa a Net Creditor? New Estimates<br />

<strong>of</strong> Capital Flight from Severely Indebted Sub-Saharan African Countries, 1970-1996.<br />

http://www.umass.edu/economics/publications/economics2000 01.pdf<br />

Message [39] referenced by [43] and [50]. Next Message by Hans is [42].<br />

[43] Matt: Do The World’s Poor Countries Finance the Rich Ones? Rich Countries<br />

Vs. Poor Countries


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 333<br />

As Amit Basole states in his paper [39], 10 percent <strong>of</strong> the world’s population held 85<br />

percent <strong>of</strong> the total income and wealth. While the bottom half owned a mere 1 percent.<br />

With such staggering numbers one would wonder why these percentages are so far apart.<br />

Amit states it’s partially because <strong>of</strong> wealth transfers, mismanagement and corruption. This<br />

is all true, but there are a few other key factors that stem from hundreds <strong>of</strong> years ago when<br />

people began to exchange goods and services, which then led to capitalism. This is one <strong>of</strong><br />

the leading factors <strong>of</strong> why there is such a high discrepancy between the wealthy vs. the poor<br />

countries in today’s world economy.<br />

Our world is full <strong>of</strong> capitalists, which is based on a principle <strong>of</strong> individual rights. I believe<br />

this laissez-faire attitude has hurt us more then has helped us as a people. Why should there<br />

be such drastic differences between rich and poor countries? Why aren’t we all stepping<br />

up to help each other? Why do we have to wear nicer clothes and drive nicer cars then our<br />

neighbors? It all stems down to capitalistic thinking in which we worrying about ourselves<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> each other.<br />

Amit also states that the global financial system is sucking wealth out <strong>of</strong> developing<br />

countries. This is true and we as Americans are all guilty <strong>of</strong> it. We and other countries have<br />

been outsourcing the production <strong>of</strong> our goods and services to poorer countries for years now.<br />

We take advantage <strong>of</strong> them by paying extremely low wage rates. We don’t care that they live<br />

in one room shacks with a family <strong>of</strong> five. As long as we have our nice houses and cars that’s<br />

all we care about. These low wage workers allow us to buy goods and services for far less<br />

than if it were produced here locally where a higher wage would be paid. We continue to<br />

take advantage <strong>of</strong> everything or person that will allow us to. This is why there are people<br />

living in impoverished conditions. This is why 10 percent <strong>of</strong> the world’s population held 85<br />

percent <strong>of</strong> the total income. And this is why we need to change. We are all human beings<br />

and we need to treat each other with a little more respect and dignity.<br />

Below I have listed the 5 wealthiest and the 5 poorest countries ranked by GDP.<br />

Richest: 1) Luxembourg 102284 GDP per capita, 2) Norway 79154, 3) Qatar, 4) Iceland,<br />

5) Ireland 58883. Poorest: 1) Burundi 127, 2) Democratic Republic <strong>of</strong> the Congo 161, 3)<br />

Liberia 195, 4) Guinea-Bissau, 204 5) Ethiopia 206<br />

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/List <strong>of</strong> countries by GDP (nominal) per capita<br />

Message [43] referenced by [44] and [65]. Next Message by Matt is [59].<br />

[44] Hans: I love the sentiments Matt expresses in [43], yet I have to raise my schoolmasterly<br />

finger and complain about Matt’s concluding sentence what we should “treat each<br />

other with a little more respect and dignity.” Such an individualist response cannot be effective<br />

because the problem is one <strong>of</strong> social structure and not just the behavior <strong>of</strong> a few bad<br />

apples.<br />

Just earlier in the same paragraph, Matt had indeed identified an important defect <strong>of</strong> the<br />

social structure. I am taking here the liberty to elaborate a little, but as I read Matt’s essay,<br />

he is arguing that even if market forces allow us to pay extremely low wages we should not<br />

do this because the workers are human beings who have the right for a life in dignity. This<br />

is a critique <strong>of</strong> the way production is structured. Labor costs should never be called costs or


334 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

treated as costs. The incomes <strong>of</strong> the workers should be considered a benefit <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

not a cost that has to be minimized.<br />

What would an economy look like in which the incomes <strong>of</strong> the laborers are not treated<br />

as a cost item? For this, the workers themselves must collectively be the bosses. This is<br />

an important requirement, but it is not enough. Many worker-owned firms have over time<br />

become just like any other capitalist firm because they cannot compete otherwise. Money<br />

has to be eliminated as the goal <strong>of</strong> production. Right now everybody is talking about the<br />

coming recession due to the subprime mortgage crisis, but the only policies we are allowed<br />

to think about are those which preserve the structures which got us into this mess. How<br />

about raising the minimum wage to $20 an hour, and nationalizing failing banks instead <strong>of</strong><br />

bailing them out? An investment boom in renewable energy and mass transportation could<br />

give us enough jobs and exports. We need rationally planned production <strong>of</strong> use-values that<br />

make sense, instead <strong>of</strong> the blind pursuit <strong>of</strong> private pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Message [44] referenced by [65]. Next Message by Hans is [62].<br />

[48] Gerund: The following was very recently circulated on another email list I am part<br />

<strong>of</strong>; my own thoughts are at the end:<br />

ON INDIVIDUALISM<br />

The tendency towards individualism in the Red Army Party organization manifests itself<br />

as follows:<br />

1. Retaliation. Some comrades, after being criticized inside the Party by a soldier comrade,<br />

look for opportunities to retaliate outside the Party, and one way is to beat or abuse the<br />

comrade in question. They also seek to retaliate within the Party. “You have criticized me at<br />

this meeting, so I’ll find some way to pay you back at the next.” Such retaliation arises from<br />

purely personal considerations, to the neglect <strong>of</strong> the interests <strong>of</strong> the class and <strong>of</strong> the Party as<br />

a whole. Its target is not the enemy class, but individuals in our own ranks. It is a corrosive<br />

which weakens the organization and its fighting capacity.<br />

2. “Small group” mentality. Some comrades consider only the interests <strong>of</strong> their own<br />

small group and ignore the general interest. Although on the surface this does not seem to<br />

be the pursuit <strong>of</strong> personal interests, in reality it exemplifies the narrowest individualism and<br />

has a strong corrosive and centrifugal effect. “Small group” mentality used to be rife in the<br />

Red Army, and although there has been some improvement as a result <strong>of</strong> criticism, there are<br />

still survivals and further effort is needed to overcome it.<br />

3. The “employee” mentality. Some comrades do not understand that the Party and the<br />

Red Army, <strong>of</strong> which they are members, are both instruments for carrying out the tasks <strong>of</strong><br />

the revolution. They do not realize that they themselves are makers <strong>of</strong> the revolution, but<br />

think that their responsibility is merely to their individual superiors and not to the revolution.<br />

This passive mentality <strong>of</strong> an “employee” <strong>of</strong> the revolution is also a manifestation <strong>of</strong><br />

individualism. It explains why there are not very many activists who work unconditionally<br />

for the revolution. Unless it is eliminated, the number <strong>of</strong> activists will not grow and the<br />

heavy burden <strong>of</strong> the revolution will remain on the shoulders <strong>of</strong> a small number <strong>of</strong> people,<br />

much to the detriment <strong>of</strong> the struggle.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 335<br />

4. Pleasure-seeking. In the Red Army there are also quite a few people whose individualism<br />

finds expression in pleasure-seeking. They always hope that their unit will march into<br />

big cities. They want to go there not to work but to enjoy themselves. The last thing they<br />

want is to work in the Red areas where life is hard.<br />

5. Passivity. Some comrades become passive and stop working whenever anything goes<br />

against their wishes. This is mainly due to lack <strong>of</strong> education, though sometimes it is also<br />

due to the leadership’s improper conduct <strong>of</strong> affairs, assignment <strong>of</strong> work or enforcement <strong>of</strong><br />

discipline.<br />

6. The desire to leave the army. The number <strong>of</strong> people who ask for transfers from the<br />

Red Army to local work is on the increase. The reason for this does not lie entirely with the<br />

individuals but also with: (1) the material hardships <strong>of</strong> life in the Red Army, (2) exhaustion<br />

after long struggle, and (3) the leadership’s improper conduct <strong>of</strong> affairs, assignment <strong>of</strong> work<br />

or enforcement <strong>of</strong> discipline.<br />

The method <strong>of</strong> correction is primarily to strengthen education so as to rectify individualism<br />

ideologically. Next, it is to conduct affairs, make assignments and enforce discipline<br />

in a proper way. In addition, ways must be found to improve the material life <strong>of</strong> the Red<br />

Army, and every available opportunity must be utilized for rest and rehabilitation in order<br />

to improve material conditions. In our educational work we must explain that in its social<br />

origin individualism is a reflection within the Party <strong>of</strong> petty-bourgeois and bourgeois ideas.<br />

I think that the greatest difficulty is in increasing understanding. For any real shift away<br />

from capitalism, we need to overcome individualism and develop social-consciousness. How<br />

this understanding can come about on a wide level, I really have no idea. I think it needs to<br />

start with a realization that <strong>of</strong> ourselves we are nothing. Not one <strong>of</strong> us has any meaningful<br />

identity in isolation from those around us. Every one is a son or daughter, mother, brother,<br />

sister, boss, employee, student, pr<strong>of</strong>essor, etc., but all <strong>of</strong> these identities are identified and<br />

attained through social relations.<br />

Hans: It would have been useful to say that the author <strong>of</strong> your long quote is Mao Zedong. See<br />

http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/mao/selected-works/volume-1/mswv1 5.htm<br />

Next Message by Gerund is [316].<br />

[49] Dyoung: Minimum Idea. I really liked Gerund comments on how “income <strong>of</strong><br />

workers should be considered a benefit <strong>of</strong> production, not a cost that has to be minimized.”<br />

I think this would also make a big difference in the way that individuals are treated in the<br />

economy and the social relationships would change and become a lot more like what Matt<br />

was talking when he thought people should be treated with more respect and dignity. I do<br />

think it is unfair and not right that in the capitalist environment people can put a minimum<br />

wage for certain jobs. It makes it impossible to survive in society being paid a minimum<br />

wage, you can’t afford to live. Gerund makes a good point about “small group mentality.”<br />

I think a lot <strong>of</strong> small businesses fall into this category because they are trying to build up<br />

their business and I think greed gets involved and then minimum wages are considered for<br />

pay and not a wage that is suitable for the individual employee. I feel that every employee<br />

should be paid according to performance. Business owners need to rethink their business<br />

plans and make sure that the employees are happy because if the employees are happy and<br />

enjoy coming to work their productivity will increase. I think that the question comes back


336 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

to the individual “whether the opportunity cost <strong>of</strong> the job is worth the wage being <strong>of</strong>fered.”<br />

I think that everyone needs to have a certain wage they feel they are worth and search until<br />

they find the job that best fits and gets the closest to that wage. I have found in my life that<br />

this works really well for me and if a job opportunity comes available, I first look at how<br />

much the company is willing to pay for me to work there and what my potential is and if<br />

it doesn’t at least meet my minimum work wage I don’t even consider the <strong>of</strong>fer and I let it<br />

go because I feel that my time is worth a certain price and my work will help benefit the<br />

production <strong>of</strong> the company and I don’t think it is fair to minimize my wage. So in the end<br />

does the individual feel that it is worth his time to go to work?<br />

Next Message by Dyoung is [173].<br />

[50] Carterryan: Do The World’s Poor Countries Finance the Rich Ones? In response<br />

to [39]: The wealth <strong>of</strong> the world comes mainly from the economic power the United States <strong>of</strong><br />

America. That is why we can afford to give financial aid to the third world poverty nations <strong>of</strong><br />

Africa and others. The problem is that we do exploit all their natural resoures and their labor<br />

within for our own benefit. That is why we have the resources to give money to Africa. Yes,<br />

their GNP surpasses their debt, but that is more private gain for individuals than government.<br />

I think if we let Africa be independent from us that they will have a more beneficial economy<br />

for themselves and it would help them be more independent from foreign support.<br />

Next Message by Carterryan is [104].<br />

[51] Andy: Do The World’s Poor Countries Finance the Rich Ones? It’s no big surprise<br />

that the richest nations would try to gain more money through the interest <strong>of</strong> their small loans<br />

to developing countries. However at the same time it’s sad that the richest nations are not<br />

really trying to help the poor nations grow but instead they are exploiting them. Some people<br />

might argue that through the lending to developing nations the rich are helping that nation<br />

grow but the fact <strong>of</strong> the matter is they are putting the developing nations into a greater debt.<br />

Message [51] referenced by [54] and [55]. Next Message by Andy is [181].<br />

[52] Ryoung: Is child labor necessary? Much discussion has been made the past 10 or<br />

so years regarding child labor laws, or the lack there<strong>of</strong>, in developing countries. Besides this<br />

there has also been much to read about for those corporations in the United States that use<br />

this child labor to produce their products. Many believe that this labor should completely be<br />

outlawed across the world. In most situations these children workers are working in horrible<br />

conditions with little nutrition and long hours. Not to mention the filth that they are working<br />

in, and the incredibly low wages they receive. I have seen documentaries in previous classes<br />

that I have taken, and it is a sad thing to see the life these kids live. I believe that everyone<br />

in life deserves a chance to chase their dreams and these kids have no opportunity to do<br />

so. However I do believe that instead <strong>of</strong> outlawing/doing away with these operations across<br />

the world I believe that they need to be regulative on a world standard if these countries<br />

want an opportunity to continue to develop. At first glance such a suggestion seems cruel<br />

and <strong>of</strong>f base but while further pondering and studying the situations that these countries<br />

find themselves in I have found out that the majority <strong>of</strong> these kids have no other choice<br />

but to work to help provide for their families. There is no doubt that these countries are in<br />

horrible economic situations. Although it would be nice to be able to immediately turn the<br />

situation around so that they flourished economically the reality is that it is going to be a<br />

long process to turn things around. Many <strong>of</strong> these countries heavily rely on these “cheap<br />

child labor” operations for economic stability, and many families rely on these operations


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 337<br />

for their income. To say the least there are not many other opportunities for sustainability,<br />

and this is why I believe that the child labor should be regulated instead <strong>of</strong> done away with.<br />

I believe that there should be a wage floor set for these workers and I also believe that there<br />

should be a maximum amount <strong>of</strong> labor for these children to be able to work, depending on<br />

their age. Whether or not this idea is amenable I do believe that it is a start to help these<br />

countries to develop and to help them with better opportunities.<br />

Message [52] referenced by [53]. Next Message by Ryoung is [235].<br />

[53] Aaron: Child Labor Laws? I have a few comments about what Ryoung said in<br />

[52]. I basically agree with what what said here. Child labor should not be outlawed in<br />

the countries that use it. If a country if using child labor to produce goods, they obviously<br />

need it to feed their economy. If it is cold turkey outlawed I believe those certain economies<br />

would collapse. I would guesstimate that the child labor accounts for a large part part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

economy. In agreement with [52], the laws should be regulated and become more strict with<br />

the passing <strong>of</strong> a predetermined lot <strong>of</strong> years. For Example, at x age, you can work y hours,<br />

but in 2 years, x+2 years can work y-2 hours per week, and so on for the next 10 years until<br />

the child labor has been extracted from the society. On a moral level, I really don’t think that<br />

child labor is a good thing, but on the other hand, I know that some economies have been<br />

built on it, and it cannot be taken away cold turkey.<br />

Next Message by Aaron is [100].<br />

[54] Brody: In response to [51]: exploitation is necessary for all economies to grow.<br />

Without the use <strong>of</strong> smaller countries for manufacturing prices in larger countries would skyrocket<br />

and the smaller countries must allow it to happen or they will have no output at all<br />

because no one will purchase their products. The only way this could not happen is if we<br />

lived in a perfect utopia shared by all the world. But I don’t want that and I would guess no<br />

one else does either because we like setting ourselves apart through status and possessions.<br />

Next Message by Brody is [242].<br />

[55] Samantha: Corruption or Exploitation? Andy’s post [51] mentioned that it is “sad<br />

that the richest nations are not trying to help poor nations but . . . exploit them,” while<br />

that exploitation is definitely deplorable and occurring, think <strong>of</strong> the downside, which is that<br />

the rich nations did not help poor nations at all. Would poor nations do better if no one<br />

loaned to them in the first place, so they could not build necessary building like hospitals<br />

and businesses? Or perhaps the answer is to not loan the money and just give it away? The<br />

conflict then arises though that the money would then not be spent on things that have a<br />

return; essentially wasted or through corruption, where it is ferreted away. It is plausible<br />

that a country may not waste the money but may not be able to repay it, in such a case there<br />

are still ample ways for a country to receive help, by extending the loan or requesting the<br />

country to release them from repayment. In either such case though the nation must prove to<br />

be using the money wisely. Are there strings attached? Absolutely, but no more than what<br />

the country knew it was getting itself into. I do not believe that giving loans is a worse evil<br />

than not giving anything to a poor nation in dire need <strong>of</strong> a hospital.<br />

Next Message by Samantha is [56].<br />

[60] Trailrunner: How far in order to conform? I am currently volunteering at the Sundance<br />

Film Festival and had the opportunity last night to watch approximately 30 minutes <strong>of</strong><br />

a movie titled “Be Like Others.” It is about a highly controversial subject and I do not bring


338 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

it up because <strong>of</strong> this controversy, but simply as something that opened my mind to issues<br />

that are currently going on in another country.<br />

In Iran, because <strong>of</strong> Islamic Law, homosexuality is punishable by death. Interestingly<br />

enough, sex-change operations are completely legal and actually very acceptable. During<br />

the portion <strong>of</strong> the film that I saw, a young man was going to the authorities to get a permit<br />

that allowed him to wear womens’ clothing. He was explaining to an <strong>of</strong>ficial why it was that<br />

he needed to get this permit (so as to prevent him from being harassed by the police), and<br />

during this time he also brought up the issue that women are held to a much higher standard<br />

<strong>of</strong> dress then the men are. In order to dress like a woman, he would have to adhere to all<br />

<strong>of</strong> the additional standards applied to women (his head must be covered, he must wear long<br />

sleeves, and more) and give up the freedoms that he had dressing as a man, and yet he was<br />

willing to accept these limitations in his life. The <strong>of</strong>ficial gave him this permit almost without<br />

question. Along the line <strong>of</strong> receiving permits allowing someone to dress a specific way, the<br />

welfare system contributes funding to those that are going through sex-change operations,<br />

although they must fill out the paperwork required by the system. Thus, the acceptance<br />

<strong>of</strong> sex-change operations is visibly acceptable in this country through the support <strong>of</strong> their<br />

welfare system.<br />

The primary focus <strong>of</strong> the film was about the fact that those that are attracted to the same<br />

sex, must deny who they are and accept the only label that is legally allowed for them and<br />

that is the label <strong>of</strong> “transsexual.” These people are willing to go through horrific surgeries in<br />

order to change their sex. Not only do they go through the surgery, but their birth certificates<br />

are changed as well. Their families, and more specifically their parents, must accept that<br />

they no longer have a brother or a son, but now have a sister or a daughter. Obviously, this<br />

is not something that just easily happens and as a result, these individuals can end up on the<br />

streets, tossed away like trash.<br />

The movie looks closely at Dr. Bahram Mir-Jalali <strong>of</strong> Tehran, who performs more sex<br />

change operations in a year than the entire country <strong>of</strong> France does in 10 years. When interviewed,<br />

he said that he tells prospective candidates that they will be going through the<br />

“operation from hell.” He explains the extreme pain that one would go through for a week<br />

afterward and the challenges associated with the surgery, yet people continue to go through<br />

this process in order to fit in.<br />

What must it be like to live in a country where you are told who you can and can not<br />

be. . . ..where you are shamed into changing who you are at your core? And can a person<br />

ever truly escape this shame and be a whole person, even with these drastic steps? Life is<br />

challenging enough with the usual day-to-day issues that we must all deal with, but to be<br />

faced with the stigmas and limitations that these people are presented with, is very sad to<br />

me.<br />

Message [60] referenced by [69] and [78]. Next Message by Trailrunner is [150].<br />

[65] CousinIt: Who pr<strong>of</strong>its at whose expense?: a problem <strong>of</strong> structure and ignorance.<br />

I am writing in response to Hans’ [44] comments in response to Matt’s [43] discussion.<br />

I agree with Hans that wealth disparity is a matter <strong>of</strong> the structural inequities <strong>of</strong> productive<br />

relations in capitalist society. Workers are not compensated equitably for their labor. Pr<strong>of</strong>its


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 339<br />

gained by the capitalist are grounded in this unfair trade <strong>of</strong> labor and the products <strong>of</strong> labor<br />

for inadequate wages. This is a characteristic <strong>of</strong> a social structure that prioritizes private<br />

ownership <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production over public wellbeing and social equality. In its<br />

structure, capitalism favors one class over all others. By some accounts private property,<br />

particularly ownership <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production and natural resources is a crime against<br />

humanity. This is a notion that many <strong>of</strong> us might find incomprehensible, if not absurd, but<br />

only because all that we know from our own individual experience is a society where private<br />

ownership <strong>of</strong> such things ‘appears’ as a given fact, as a ‘natural’ condition, as ‘just the way<br />

things are.’ Let us stop to consider, however, the radical basis and origins <strong>of</strong> the notion that<br />

any one person, or group has, by right, priority to resources and productive apparatuses <strong>of</strong><br />

domination.<br />

If we go back far enough, it is not hard to understand that the notion <strong>of</strong> ownership starts<br />

with an act <strong>of</strong> exclusion and violence; I want exclusive access to a watering hole. I decide<br />

that only myself and my friends and closest social allies will be allowed to use it as a resource.<br />

I unilaterally stake my claim to the territory. When someone other than those whom<br />

I deem as having privileged access try to use the watering hole they are driven away by<br />

threat <strong>of</strong> viloence. I then decide that I want something that falls within the territory <strong>of</strong> a rival<br />

group. They do not want to give up their claim, so I decide through threat <strong>of</strong> violence and<br />

use <strong>of</strong> violent force to drive them away, enslave them, or make them concede to let me take<br />

what I want without resistance from them. Like it or not, this is the natural history <strong>of</strong> private<br />

ownership.<br />

I would argue that this is still the underlying method <strong>of</strong> capitalist domination in modern<br />

society. Colonialism, exploitation, theft, slavery, and genocide are the means by which<br />

modern wealthy states and wealthy classes became wealthy in the first place, thus gaining<br />

an unfair advantage from the get-go. It is also the means by which they continue to amass<br />

more wealth at the expense <strong>of</strong> the exploited classes, here in the ‘first world,’ as well as in the<br />

‘second’ and ‘third world’ countries.This all works out rather well for the dominant classes<br />

for quite a while. However, because indigenous populations are shoved aside, murdered, or<br />

indentured so that capitalist firms can take the resources from under their feet, the exploitation<br />

at the heart <strong>of</strong> capitalist enterprises cannot be disputed, except by way <strong>of</strong> ideological<br />

blindness and selective ignorance. Some <strong>of</strong> the exploited are not so easily convinced that<br />

they are not the victims <strong>of</strong> a structure <strong>of</strong> violence. This is why legal systems arise whose<br />

main function <strong>of</strong> supreme importance is to protect the property rights <strong>of</strong> the wealthy. Property<br />

rights are a legal fiction invented by the needs <strong>of</strong> a particular class (in collusion with the<br />

state) to protect the spoils <strong>of</strong> violent exploitation and murderous theft.<br />

We are now at a point in world history when it is becoming more and more apparent that<br />

a) capitailism has failed to produce the utopia <strong>of</strong> a carefree world <strong>of</strong> luxury for all and b) the<br />

current mode <strong>of</strong> capitalist production and comsumption, which relies on the ‘invisible hand’<br />

<strong>of</strong> blind market forces and the pr<strong>of</strong>it motive, if intended to be expanded to include every person<br />

in a growing world population, cannot be sustained by the earth’s environment. If even<br />

all the people in China demand the same standard <strong>of</strong> living that Americans have enjoyed,<br />

the environment will surely crumble under this demand, i.e. capitalism fails unequivocally.<br />

This raises the ante from a merely moral imperitive to one that is based on species survival.


340 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

As Kenneth Burke (yes, the ‘occupational psychosis’ guy) points out in “Permanence and<br />

Change”, the current system is a system <strong>of</strong> doled-privileges that masquerades as a meritocracy.<br />

That is, it is a system in which what really determines the wealth and privilege <strong>of</strong> an<br />

individual, <strong>of</strong> a class or <strong>of</strong> a nation is a matter <strong>of</strong> being born on ‘the right side <strong>of</strong> the fence’<br />

and on who one is able to make friends with. Since this is the case, Burke contends that all<br />

people should benefit from collective wealth equally as it is the case that all people, even the<br />

poor and homeless, even those in the ‘second’ and ‘third’ worlds, fulfill a neccessary role in<br />

the perpetuation <strong>of</strong> such a society as a whole. The poor and homeless fulfill the role <strong>of</strong> the<br />

available labor pool (untapped labor power) as well as serving as the example to all the rest<br />

<strong>of</strong> us <strong>of</strong> what can happen to us and to our children if we do not agree to trade our labor at an<br />

unfair rate, as dictated by the wealth appropriating/means <strong>of</strong> production owning classes.<br />

It is interesting to me that socialism is derided as inherently evil for (among many other<br />

reasons) the reasoning that it produces sloth and removes incentives for improvement through<br />

personal pr<strong>of</strong>it. On the contrary, I would contend that a system <strong>of</strong> doled-privileges produces<br />

the very same thing (within even the privileged classes) at the expense <strong>of</strong> general social<br />

well-being and the collective benefits <strong>of</strong> individual creativity. Those on the dole are, for<br />

a large part, there by way <strong>of</strong> illusory notions <strong>of</strong> merit and entitlement that must be upheld<br />

by way <strong>of</strong> violence, exploitation, law, and economic terror for the individual, not through<br />

sustained actual creativity aimed at social well-being and equity. Human beings are shown<br />

to be an inherently ‘social’ animal (not an inherently ‘capitalist’ animal)...we all depend on<br />

the existence and mutual aid (voluntary or involuntary) <strong>of</strong> every other one <strong>of</strong> us...therefore,<br />

why not socialism? For the ‘social animal’, socialism seems to me a much more appropriate<br />

socio-economic structure (See also, Albert Einstein’s “Why Socialism?”). If the ultimate<br />

end-result <strong>of</strong> the current structure <strong>of</strong> social-productive relations amounts to species annihilation<br />

through environmental collapse or nuclear extinction in trade for private pr<strong>of</strong>its, then<br />

can we not ask ourselves “<strong>of</strong> what good is it, after all?” We may be the only species capable<br />

<strong>of</strong> inventing our own extinction. Maybe it is time to trade it for something that all people<br />

everywhere benefit from (in the form <strong>of</strong> a survivable future?). Better late than never.<br />

Message [65] referenced by [67], [71], [113], and [2008fa:44]. Next Message by CousinIt is [126].<br />

[69] Srichardson: benefits <strong>of</strong> conforming? After reading Trailrunner’s [60] about the<br />

Sundance movie showing how people go through these terrible and painful surgeries to make<br />

them fit in the only way they feel that they can. This is the only way for them to make it in<br />

their country as it is really the only option for them to follow who they feel they are.<br />

It makes me wonder why people feel threatened by people who are different than they<br />

are. Is there any kind <strong>of</strong> benefit for forcing these people to try and fit into the majority and<br />

make them the same as everyone else around them? What would Marx say about this? It<br />

seems to me that people’s differences benefit the society in general, and economically.<br />

Next Message by Srichardson is [130].<br />

[71] Hans: Greatest Expropriation in History is Going on Right Now! I am always<br />

glad to read a radical viewpoint like CousinIt’s [65], so that I am not the only Commie here.<br />

But if we talk about the genocide and theft that laid the foundation <strong>of</strong> the modern capitalist<br />

wealth, we should not overlook that the biggest expropriation ever is happening under our<br />

very eyes, and it is not yet too late, we can do something about it. I am talking about the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 341<br />

destruction <strong>of</strong> our climate system, which is going to kill billions in the poorer countries and<br />

which will also make life much more unpleasant and precarious in the rich countries.<br />

After a long period <strong>of</strong> denial that climate change is even an issue, now the ruling class<br />

is rolling out their remedies. These remedies are every bit as bad as the problem. They<br />

certainly have figured out how to turn the catastrophe for humankind which their system is<br />

causing into a source <strong>of</strong> private pr<strong>of</strong>its:<br />

(1) bi<strong>of</strong>uels which should really be called death fuels because they take food away from<br />

the hungry.<br />

(2) nuclear energy with its unresolved storage problems and which is inevitably linked to<br />

nuclear weapons proliferation.<br />

(3) carbon sequestration which is an unproven technology that gives the coal companies<br />

an excuse to promote coal. Coal and other fossil fuels must simply be left in the ground.<br />

(4) Cap and Trade which creates an entirely new form <strong>of</strong> private property, property <strong>of</strong><br />

the atmosphere’s capability to absorb greenhouse gasses, with windfall pr<strong>of</strong>its to the biggest<br />

polluters.<br />

The ruling class will not voluntarily do the right thing, which means, promote renewable<br />

energy, energy savings, sharing <strong>of</strong> new technologies world wide to avert the disaster, building<br />

a smart electric grid, feed-in tariffs which allow the little people to become involved in the<br />

energy business. A big and well informed mass movement is necessary if we want to pass<br />

on a livable planet to our children.<br />

Tonight is one <strong>of</strong> the big events <strong>of</strong> the focus-the nation campaign which the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Utah</strong> is thankfully participating in. At 6:30 in the Panorama East Room <strong>of</strong> Union Building,<br />

<strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Campus there will be the Interfaith Climate Change Panel Discussion<br />

with moderator Elaine Emmi (Quaker) and speakers Bishop Carolyn Tanner Irish (Episcopalian),<br />

Rabbi Daniel Gomez-Alaniz (Jewish), Vaughn Lovejoy (Buddhist), George Handley<br />

(Church <strong>of</strong> Latter Day Saints), and Imam Muhammad Shoeabe Mehtar.<br />

6:30 pm-8:00 pm, Olpin Union Panorama East Room. If you can fit it into your schedule,<br />

be there! It will be interesting for you and good for us all if you get involved.<br />

Message [71] referenced by [82], [156], and [269]. Next Message by Hans is [76].<br />

[78] Goethe: RE: How far in order to conform? Regarding [60], I find this fascinating<br />

that there would be a socialist program for sex-change reconstruction in a country where<br />

the president refuses to admit the existence <strong>of</strong> homosexuality. Of course this same man(?)<br />

refuses to believe the persecution <strong>of</strong> Jews took place.<br />

What are they trying to achieve? What is the reasoning here?<br />

Do they really believe that by changing the sex (surgically) it will not be a form <strong>of</strong> homosexuality?<br />

I think that there is a difference in being a homosexual and transgender. Amazing the<br />

power <strong>of</strong> a religion that can persuade or force you to comply to the socially accepted norm.<br />

What is very frightening is the fact we have a religious cleric as a front runner for the<br />

republican presidential nomination.


342 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Was it Marx who said that religion is the opium <strong>of</strong> the masses?<br />

Next Message by Goethe is [87].<br />

[81] Bmellor: Socialized medicine? Sign me up. There are two people with whom I<br />

work, who are vividly opposed to socialized medicine. The sad thing is that they are the<br />

type <strong>of</strong> individuals who stand the most to gain from such a system. One is a diabetic and the<br />

other has had multiple kidney surgeries with no success, he is on dialysis in the afternoons.<br />

I made it clear to one <strong>of</strong> them yesterday that if Hillary Clinton became president it would<br />

be to his benefit. He said something interesting in response... “Socialized medicine is a first<br />

step to complete socialism.”<br />

Luis Kahn, the famous architect said that “where there is fear, true creativity cannot<br />

exist.” When I heard that I immediately thought countries distressed by war. What Einsteins<br />

or Shakespeares might exist in those war-torn countries but don’t have that chance to develop<br />

their talents? It is hard to think <strong>of</strong> a new concept or new idea if you are constantly worried<br />

about a bomb being dropped on your house.<br />

Think about this nation and fear. What do we fear? I doubt many people are worried<br />

about bombs being dropped on their home. Many are worried about their debt; they are<br />

scared and are worried about the bills that are piling up at their homes that they cannot pay.<br />

True socialized medicine can eliminate that concern for many people, one less bill to worry<br />

about and fear. An efficient form <strong>of</strong> health care is where the Doctors collect a paycheck from<br />

not the insurance companies, or sick individuals, but the government.<br />

Some might say, “The doctors won’t participate in socialized medicine, and the quality<br />

<strong>of</strong> healthcare will decrease.” To them I would point out insurance is not paying for our<br />

nation’s weapons, yet we have the best armed forces in the world. I do not hear the military<br />

contractors complaining about the government’s compensation. The same can be true <strong>of</strong><br />

our doctors and medicine. I can see the dangers <strong>of</strong> corruption in socialism; however I can<br />

see how our healthcare system is broken, and already corrupt. We all win with socialized<br />

medicine, (unless you are an insurance company). My insurance healthcare premium has<br />

gone up 19% annually over the last two years, while my deductible has gone up as well.<br />

How long can we keep that up? Luckily I am healthy, but like most Americans I fear the day<br />

when I will no longer be healthy. Not because <strong>of</strong> the sickness, injury, or pain but because <strong>of</strong><br />

the <strong>of</strong>fset to the quality <strong>of</strong> life healthcare bills can cause. I can only imagine how those two<br />

guys at my work must feel, having to pay co-pays along with the premium each month.<br />

Message [81] referenced by [82], [87], [89], [94], [102], and [107]. Next Message by Bmellor is [250].<br />

[82] Hans: Health Care Reform – Another Bogus Solution. Those interested in the<br />

issues brought up by Bmellor’s [81] might enjoy going to the Questioning Minds forum at<br />

the SLC Main Library tomorrow, Sunday at 2 pm. I am enclosing their announcement below.<br />

Judi Hilman and Elizabeth Garbe will be presenting a proposal similar to Hillary Clinton’s<br />

approach: a law which would force everybody to buy private health insurance which, in<br />

order to be affordable, would have to have high deductibles etc.<br />

I will be there, and if you need brownie points for attendance please come up to me and<br />

give me your name. (I am really tall with white hair and a beard.) I told some <strong>of</strong> my friends<br />

from <strong>Utah</strong> Jobs with Justice about this event. They will be there too in the audience. (I hope<br />

I won’t get into troubles for this; Mike and Lynda from Questioning Minds and Linda from


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 343<br />

Jobs with Justice are both neighbors <strong>of</strong> mine in the cohousing community where I live.) Jobs<br />

with Justice will politely argue that the proposal discussed by the presenters has nothing to<br />

do with socialism but is just corporate welfare for the private insurance companies. What is<br />

really needed is a true single payer health insurance system as every other advanced capitalist<br />

country has it. They will have flyers explaining the difference.<br />

To me this whole issue is just another example <strong>of</strong> what I said in [71], this time not in<br />

the environmental arena but in health care. There is a real problem, our nation is in a health<br />

care crisis, but the “solutions” <strong>of</strong>fered by those in power are much more designed to increase<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its for the corporations than to solve the problem. One might say they use the problem<br />

as an excuse to come up with yet another pr<strong>of</strong>itable scheme for the big companies.<br />

Should be an interesting discussion. Here is the announcement by the organizers <strong>of</strong> the<br />

event:<br />

QUESTIONING MINDS 2007-2008 LECTURE-AND-DISCUSSION SERIES PRESENTS<br />

“Health Reform in <strong>Utah</strong>: Where Are We Headed and Are We On the Right Road”<br />

Judi Hilman and Elizabeth Garbe<br />

Sunday, January 27, 2008<br />

Meet and Greet: 1:45 pm. Presentation: 2:00 pm. Meeting Closes: 3:30 pm Salt Lake<br />

Main Library, 210 East 400 South, Fourth Floor Conference Room Free and Open to the<br />

Public<br />

Judi Hilman is the Executive Director <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Utah</strong> Health Policy Project. She has an MA<br />

from Cornell. Before coming to <strong>Utah</strong> in ’99 she directed development efforts at a community<br />

rehabilitation agency serving people with disabilities. More recently Judi served as Health<br />

Policy Director at <strong>Utah</strong> Issues, Center for Poverty Research and Action. Her work covers<br />

a broad range <strong>of</strong> policy issues impacting the uninsured, low-income medically underserved,<br />

people with disabilities, and ethnic minorities.<br />

Elizabeth Garbe is the Coverage Initiatives Director at the <strong>Utah</strong> Health Policy Project.<br />

She received her Masters in Social Work from the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> Denver. Elizabeth spent six<br />

years working at a variety <strong>of</strong> non-pr<strong>of</strong>its serving Wyoming youth. She worked as the Policy<br />

Analyst at the Colorado Community Health Network, Colorado’s primary care association<br />

and recently moved to Salt Lake to join the <strong>Utah</strong> Health Policy Project team.<br />

“A record number <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong>ns are without health coverage. National estimates rank <strong>Utah</strong><br />

as having a higher than average rate <strong>of</strong> uninsured residents, 17.4% or 442,000 residents,<br />

despite having much higher than average median annual income ($55,179). About the same<br />

number are under-insured. <strong>Utah</strong> is also leading the nation in small businesses dropping<br />

health insurance for their employees. From 2000 to 2004, health premiums for <strong>Utah</strong>ns<br />

increased 66%, but wages only increased 13%. If nothing is done, health premium costs will<br />

surpass household income within 20 years.<br />

This year <strong>Utah</strong>’s legislature will begin to discuss how <strong>Utah</strong> should reform its broken<br />

health system. Come listen to and discuss what is currently being proposed, an analysis <strong>of</strong><br />

the proposal and how you can become involved in the conversation.”


344 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Suggested Resources:<br />

<strong>Utah</strong> Health Policy Project<br />

http://www.healthpolicyproject.org<br />

Community Catalyst<br />

http://www.communitycatalyst.org<br />

Families USA<br />

http://www.familiesusa.org<br />

Kaiser Family Foundation<br />

http://www.kff.org<br />

Alliance for Health Reform<br />

http://www.allhealth.org/index.asp<br />

Questioning Minds is a non-pr<strong>of</strong>it, educational forum with 501(c)(3) status. Meetings<br />

are held on the second and fourth Sundays <strong>of</strong> each month, September through May, except<br />

major holiday weekends, in the Salt Lake City Main Library. See<br />

http://www.questioning-minds.org<br />

for coming events and speaker-suggested readings.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [86].<br />

[87] Goethe: efficiency <strong>of</strong> government run health care? In response to Bmellor [81]<br />

I will agree with you that we do need a health care reform that provides for everyone. I<br />

will not agree with your comparison <strong>of</strong> government weapons spending to healthcare. There<br />

are no complaints from contractors because they are paid large amounts for their services.<br />

The defense <strong>of</strong> the nation has priority over the health <strong>of</strong> its citizens. This is a contradiction,<br />

and I bet Marx would want to take a closer look at it!!<br />

I don’t have the answer for the healthcare problems we all face, but we should look at<br />

other countries who have been successful with their programs.<br />

One other observation I would like to note; health insurance does not guarantee coverage.<br />

How many <strong>of</strong> you have been denied coverage due to a pre-existing condition? WTF... If I<br />

am sick or think that I am, and I go to the doc. there is a 75% chance that they will pull the<br />

pre-existing condition clause on me. (75% is a guess I think it is close)...<br />

If we do get a health plan that is controlled by the government, it will need to be efficient.<br />

Realistically this will be another way for someone to monopolize on healthcare. The only<br />

thing worse that an HMO would be a government run HMO....<br />

Think about it!!! :)<br />

Next Message by Goethe is [98].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 345<br />

[89] FacistFrank: Re: Socialized medicine? Sign me up. The question raised in [81]<br />

about whether our country should switch to a socialized or quasi socialized/capitalist system<br />

is an interesting one and far out <strong>of</strong> my league. But this is why I am going to college, to learn<br />

more. I feel like I would be going out on a limb to give a solid answer and my solid support<br />

to any issue, but i’ll take a crack at it. I have opinion on this issue and not fact as Plato would<br />

say.<br />

Okay a common criticism I hear from those opposed to a socialized system, is that it will<br />

lower the amount <strong>of</strong> good doctors in the field and raise healthcare costs. As to how it will<br />

raise healthcare costs I cannot see, at least directly. Could it lower the amount <strong>of</strong> doctors or<br />

the quality <strong>of</strong> doctors and healthcare? I see a definite possibility that it could if mishandled,<br />

and anyone that has not been living under a rock for the last 7 years is familiar with what<br />

an incompetent bumbling government is like. Government is frequently incompetent, but<br />

not always incompetent, under bright minds it can be extraordinarily efficient. Perhaps I<br />

am thinking in capitalist terms here, but it makes sense to me that if doctors were paid less<br />

under a socialist system, we would get fewer doctors, and doctors <strong>of</strong> lesser quality, overall.<br />

If human beings were at the stage where we could all serve our fellow man for free, if we<br />

were all like Gandhi and Christ, then we would not get less doctors, but very few humans<br />

are like this, at least at this juncture in human social evolution. If under a socialized system<br />

we pay doctors even more than we do now, then we will get more doctors <strong>of</strong> better quality,<br />

as the more intelligent minds <strong>of</strong> our society gravitate to the fields that pay the highest.<br />

Look at our public education system, we pay teachers a low wage for a bachelors degree,<br />

and we get teacher shortages and incompetent teachers. Right now in America I believe<br />

the problem is the insurance companies, they make billions by raising their coverage, and<br />

they even make the prices so high that millions <strong>of</strong> hardworking Americans can not even<br />

afford health care. If we can take those billions and give them back to the people, who<br />

I believe earned that money in the first place, then we solve this problem. Unfortunately<br />

this is politically dangerous. An elected <strong>of</strong>ficial that voted for this would probably not be<br />

given the opportunity to ever vote in congress again. So instead the solution is to redistribute<br />

wealth, but mask it by <strong>of</strong>fering a government insurance program that charges fairly, enough<br />

to cover the actual costs <strong>of</strong> health care. If this is in the market, then the private insurance<br />

companies will either have to lower their prices to compete, or go out <strong>of</strong> business. Of course<br />

they do not want to give up their pr<strong>of</strong>its so they will fight this tooth and nail in the halls <strong>of</strong><br />

congress. Lyndon Johnson and FDR beat them in the past and it is possible to do it again. If<br />

too much change is introduced into a society or a person, that change will be rejected. it is<br />

like trying to swallow a jawbreaker whole, instead <strong>of</strong> devouring it over time.<br />

If wages stay high for doctors or get even higher, and costs are covered, I see no problem<br />

with a socialized health care system.<br />

Hans posted a comment earlier that I thought was incredibly brilliant, it had to do with<br />

individuality and the collective. That the individual is defined by his relationships in a collective.<br />

If there was no perspective from other people, I believe the individual would not<br />

exist. Just like how there would be no pleasure without pain, no good without evil. I believe<br />

individuality is an illusion, As Marcus Aurelius says, man is a social being that was<br />

meant to cooperate with each other. My father an I explored an analogy a few months ago,


346 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

it was whether a car engine, and all the pieces in it cooperate with each other in harmony, or<br />

compete with each other, to ultimately make the car move. The truth is they do both, those<br />

pieces are grinding against and pushing <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> each other, while at the same time cooperating<br />

and achieving their own function to make the car move. Many times if one piece breaks all<br />

the others become useless. My point is society the world and the universe works in a form<br />

<strong>of</strong> ordered cooperative competition, but this seems to be a contradiction, cooperative competition.<br />

Perhaps the universe is a contradiction, and still makes sense, some kind <strong>of</strong> taoist<br />

balance, maybe that is why we humans have such a hard time figuring it out.<br />

Message [89] referenced by [94], [100], and [102]. Next Message by FacistFrank is [116].<br />

[91] Chris: EnergySolutions nuclear waste dumping. From what I hear, EnergySolutions<br />

wants to import 20,000 tons <strong>of</strong> nuclear waste from Italy and dispose some <strong>of</strong> it here in<br />

<strong>Utah</strong>. Before approving EnergySolutions’ request, the Nuclear Regulatory Commission is<br />

holding a board meeting to get our input.<br />

What: Radiation Control Board Meeting<br />

When: Feb. 1st, 2:00 – 4:00 pm<br />

Where: Conference Room 101<br />

Department <strong>of</strong> Environmental Quality (Bldg 2)<br />

168 North 1950 West<br />

Salt Lake<br />

Next Message by Chris is [92].<br />

[93] Jason: More on Socialized Health care. When looking at socialized health care I<br />

think it’s a good idea to look at countries that have been doing it successfully for a number <strong>of</strong><br />

years and compare. Canada and several western European countries have been on a system<br />

for awhile now and the common complaints from them are as follows. Typically for any<br />

major surgery there is a long wait list since medicine is free anyone can walk in and get<br />

treated. If you are healthy enough to wait, this may not be a problem, but in the U.S. you<br />

could probably be treated immediately. Also, in more socialist countries their taxes are<br />

usually around 50% <strong>of</strong> their total income. That is a lot more than we’ve ever paid here, in<br />

the lower tax brackets anyway. Finally, since the world <strong>of</strong> medicine is so heavily driven in<br />

this country by money I’ve heard it is worlds farther ahead than most in terms <strong>of</strong> technology.<br />

I don’t think social health care is a bad thing, I just wanted to list some <strong>of</strong> the reasons<br />

against it since I haven’t heard them in this discussion yet. Most <strong>of</strong> those have a fairly good<br />

retort. Struggling families probably already have to wait in horrendous lines at free clinics<br />

when they aren’t well. The care they get there probably isn’t as good either, but due to<br />

insane health care costs they have no choice. As for the taxes, if the country rearranged it’s<br />

spending a little bit, we probably wouldn’t have to raise taxes much at all. As is, this country<br />

spends ridiculous amounts <strong>of</strong> money on defense, and because <strong>of</strong> that, even more money on<br />

interest. Have any <strong>of</strong> you seen that pie chart <strong>of</strong> U.S. military spending compared to the rest<br />

<strong>of</strong> the world? The U.S. makes up more than half <strong>of</strong> it if I remember correctly. I’ve also heard<br />

figures <strong>of</strong> up to a third <strong>of</strong> the U.S. budget is just used for paying interest on the incredible<br />

national debt. With some reworking I’m sure health care could be affordable with the current<br />

income <strong>of</strong> the country. Also welfare programs would probably need less money if the poor


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 347<br />

now have free health care. As far as the technology argument, while it is true that the U.S.<br />

is quite a bit more advanced in some fields <strong>of</strong> medicine than other countries, some <strong>of</strong> the<br />

most promising new technologies are being held back by the FDA that are being developed<br />

further in other countries. For instance, stem cell research continues on in Europe, but last<br />

I heard the U.S. has an all out ban on them. If we switched to a more social system I don’t<br />

see a huge drop technological advances. If anything a reworking <strong>of</strong> the FDA in conjunction<br />

with the new program could advance technology. Besides, most researchers aren’t usually<br />

the ones out there for huge amounts <strong>of</strong> money. If you look at most research pr<strong>of</strong>essors, they<br />

probably did not get into their line <strong>of</strong> work for the money. So as long as there is money for<br />

them to keep researching the U.S. should be okay.<br />

The cons have some weight, especially if you are rich. However I think the net gain for<br />

society by switching to a more social system, if done right, would be astronomical.<br />

Next Message by Jason is [224].<br />

[94] Matt: Socialized medicine equals better treatment for all. Is it really true what<br />

Bmellor [81] stats, that “we all win with socialized medicine”? Well, after watching the<br />

Michael Moore movie Sicko, I definitely would say YES! If you have not seen this movie<br />

now is the time since we are in an election year, and if Hillary Clinton is elected she will<br />

definitely try to socialize our current healthcare system. Why would she want to do this if<br />

our current healthcare system has been working for many many years now? As Michael<br />

Moore points out, it’s because our current system is not working for those individuals who<br />

can’t afford it. For example, I have a friend who has his own construction business and does<br />

not have insurance because it is too expensive. He would rather take his chances at getting<br />

injured than paying $1,200 per month and a high deductable. Well, the problem is he did<br />

get really hurt when he fell <strong>of</strong>f a building and shattered the bones in his leg. He now has<br />

over $300,000 in medical bills and unable to work. If we had socialized medicine everything<br />

would have been covered without the $300,000 price tag.<br />

I’m sure Socialized medicine is not free, but I know it’s got to be better than a 19 percent<br />

insurance premium increase every other year as Bmellor [81] incurred. And it’s got to be<br />

better than me paying 12 percent <strong>of</strong> my paycheck toward healthcare. If taxes increased<br />

5-10 percent and everyone could have health care our capitalistic society would be much<br />

better <strong>of</strong>f. Michael Moore actually points this out in his movie as he interviews patients and<br />

Doctors in Canada, France, and Europe. Doctors do indeed receive their paycheck from the<br />

government, but they still make a good living. One Doctor that was interviewed lived in a<br />

$700,000 house and had a $50,000 car. The doctor said that he lives just fine and that he does<br />

not need 4 nice houses and 3 nice cars as American doctors have so they can feel satisfied<br />

about the work they do. He also said the more patients <strong>of</strong> his that are healthy and that he can<br />

get to quit smoking, the more money he will get paid. Imagine that kind <strong>of</strong> thinking here in<br />

the U.S. , where we are more concerned about the people around us then money.<br />

As FacistFrank [89] states, why would doctors want to work under socialistic conditions?<br />

Well, it will most likely come down to fundamental economics <strong>of</strong> supply and demand. If<br />

a good doctor decides he wants to leave because he will get paid less under a socialized<br />

system, then patients will probably not go to him because the government will most likely


348 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

not cover services under nonparticipating doctors. Eventually the good doctor’s supply <strong>of</strong><br />

customers will decrease causing them to ultimately change over to socialized medicine.<br />

As you can tell I am definitely for socialized medicine as I feel if will bring better healthcare<br />

and treatment to everyone and not just those who can afford it. I am just worried it<br />

will never come to pass as the insurance companies and even doctors will try to prevent it<br />

from ever happening by paying congressman <strong>of</strong>f. I like to think that our society is based on<br />

morals and just money, but in the end those who have the money make the rules.<br />

Message [94] referenced by [102]. Next Message by Matt is [266].<br />

[100] Aaron: Socialized Medicine. The argument over socialized medicine in [89] is<br />

interesting and confusing to me at the same time. This is a discussion that many debaters<br />

have argued over for many years in many different economies around the world. First,<br />

the argument fascistFrank makes about the number <strong>of</strong> doctors that would be working in a<br />

socialist economy does not account for a function that I believe has much to do with whom<br />

becomes a Dr. The pay does not have everything to do with the decision to become a MD.<br />

I really do believe that there are a lot <strong>of</strong> MD’s out there that took up the pr<strong>of</strong>ession because<br />

they genuinely want to serve people. Just like members <strong>of</strong> the armed forces, who don’t make<br />

much money, who just might love to serve. Second, this argument does not mention good old<br />

fashion American ingenuity and entrepreneurship. Many doctors might love the challenge <strong>of</strong><br />

building a practice and a business from scratch, and enjoy the financial fruits <strong>of</strong> their labor in<br />

the <strong>of</strong>fice and in their business. I also, don’t understand the argument about giving the pr<strong>of</strong>its<br />

<strong>of</strong> insurance companies away and back to the public. Isn’t that the foundation <strong>of</strong> a capitalist<br />

economy? business and pr<strong>of</strong>its? The moral issues <strong>of</strong> health care costs are a separate issue to<br />

me... we can’t just have the government taking pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>of</strong> companies in an industry because<br />

they think it is not fair. Although health care costs are rising, I think the best course <strong>of</strong> action<br />

is to let the economy and business let competition help us out. A company will eventually<br />

have to come along that is cheaper than a competitor and the costs <strong>of</strong> health care will start<br />

to sink.<br />

Next Message by Aaron is [210].<br />

[102] Allen: Socialized Medicine. I agree with the two people that Bmellor [81] lists.<br />

In his email Bmellor states that the socialized system would benefit them, but the socialized<br />

system would also cause a few other problems. The government would increase taxes to<br />

pay for the program, which would basically steal money from your wallet to help pay for<br />

someone else’s health care. The program would also make it so patients would not try to<br />

find the best possible prices for the best possible services available, because every month<br />

you will pay the same amount <strong>of</strong> money and the same copay for each visit, which might<br />

cause problems with some companies that compete for other companies for employees <strong>of</strong>fer<br />

health care as an incentive. Another problem that this program would lead to would be what<br />

FacistFrank [89] states, basically it would stop a physician’s incentive to provide competitive<br />

care and the care provided would not be <strong>of</strong> the best quality because physicians would leave<br />

the system and find a better place for more opportunities for them. So as stated by Matt [94],<br />

is socialized medicine equal better treatment for all? For some that can’t afford it, I would<br />

say yes, but for the most part it will eventually lead to lesser quality <strong>of</strong> health care for more<br />

money.<br />

Next Message by Allen is [105].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 349<br />

[103] Ande: Stock Market. Is the stock market an economic boon or blight? This was<br />

one discussion i had to get in on. After reading a lot <strong>of</strong> the comments i had to laugh when I<br />

heard that the stock market is a bad thing and that the government is wasting too much money<br />

in making sure the market does not crash or put is in to a true recession. This is a total joke,<br />

the stock market is one <strong>of</strong> the best things that our economy, country, and government have.<br />

It is an incredible way for people to make money, and put money back into our country’s<br />

economy by investing it back in. It can only help us, who does not like to make money, the<br />

stock market is still the number one place to make money. I was so shocked to hear that<br />

these kids think it is a bad thing and the government needs to stop fueling the market. I<br />

think the government is doing a great job, as well I think the stock market is one <strong>of</strong> the best<br />

things our economy has and without it and the government we would be in serious trouble<br />

and probably close to a depression.<br />

Next Message by Ande is [194].<br />

[106] Bar: Socialized medicine is stupid. Socialized medicine, the always big debate<br />

topic loved by the left is always highly controversial, because as the preacher’s wife on the<br />

Simpsons always screams, “the children, what about the children! will someone think about<br />

the children!” It’s always about government helping people who can’t help themselves: the<br />

poor, children, the elderly. Society has a social obligation to protect people, even dumb<br />

people, even people that don’t save their money, even the homeless. Each <strong>of</strong> these people<br />

should be helped by the society that watches over them to a certain extent. On the other<br />

hand, society should never influence or reward self and socially destructive behaviors. Every<br />

policy should set-up the society to form a meritocracy, not the fallacy on an egalitarian<br />

Utopian society. The cold hard facts about socialized medicine is that the quality <strong>of</strong> health<br />

care drops, and the elimination <strong>of</strong> competition decreases efficiency and the importance <strong>of</strong> the<br />

individual patients. The crime <strong>of</strong> socialized medicine is that it destroys the monopolization<br />

<strong>of</strong> medicine. Leftists always whine about high priced medicines, that the little pills that<br />

cost cents to produce cost some, especially those without insurance, hundreds <strong>of</strong> dollars a<br />

month to buy. I always ask these people if they would like any cheese with their wine,<br />

but they just look at me funny. The fact that these medicines exist in the first place, is<br />

because the government, through patents gives large pharmaceutical companies like Pfizer<br />

monopoly pricing on medicines. These companies invest billions <strong>of</strong> dollars to develop and<br />

test new drugs, for the benefit <strong>of</strong> all mankind, can anyone say Viagra! The only way that<br />

these medicines can be developed is through large investment. Under socialized medicine<br />

the prices <strong>of</strong> these drugs would be reduced, just like all the generic drugs that come from<br />

Canada, to market equilibrium prices destroying the incentive to invest in new medicines,<br />

which I consider a tragedy, where paying $100 a month for insurance is not. When was<br />

the last time you heard <strong>of</strong> a company from Europe make a medical breakthrough or a new<br />

type <strong>of</strong> surgery? Heck how many hundreds <strong>of</strong> new stem cell companies have formed in<br />

the US in the past few years compared to those <strong>of</strong> Europe. I follow pharmaceutical stocks<br />

avidly and almost no foreign companies can compete with the new technologies that come<br />

out <strong>of</strong> US corporations. Why, if socialized medicine is so great and if its “human nature” to<br />

serve our fellow man by going to years and years <strong>of</strong> medical school to make no more than<br />

an undergrad, why is the US still leading the world in medicine? It’s the meritocracy in the<br />

schools and the reward <strong>of</strong> high pay, and if this is destroyed, god help us all. Now I agree that,<br />

no one is going to care about all these technological breakthroughs if they aren’t accessible


350 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

to them, unless its to spite European socialism which sometimes I see as a rational reason<br />

to do almost anything. That’s why the government has to play a role in getting health care<br />

to the lower class, but by socializing it, it does more harm than good. The best solution<br />

would be to subsidize insurance companies for lower income people and make it obligatory<br />

for those who can pay for insurance like rich people in order to reduce externalities; we have<br />

mandatory car insurance why not mandatory health insurance? This way huge tax increases<br />

are not necessary, and it doesn’t destroy the business culture that gives us all those medical<br />

goodies. I recently interned for the Untied Nations, and I worked closely with another intern<br />

from France or as I like to call it the socialist Mecca. I got to know him well, and some<br />

<strong>of</strong> his friends through Facebook, an interesting fact was that the vast majority <strong>of</strong> his friends<br />

from France worked outside <strong>of</strong> their country. Could that be because <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Euro, that the French are loved by all the people <strong>of</strong> the world, or that other countries need<br />

snotty french laborers, no, its due to their unbelievably high unemployment rate, caused by<br />

their socialist policies needing high taxes. The other horrible tragedy <strong>of</strong> socialized medicine<br />

is higher taxes. High taxes are crimes against humanity, and cause for revolution; tea tax<br />

anyone?<br />

Message [106] referenced by [111], [118], and [120]. Next Message by Bar is [123].<br />

[107] Rey: The death <strong>of</strong> the human spirit. In discussing the idea <strong>of</strong> a socialized health<br />

care system, its supporters acknowledge that it “may” be difficult to keep motivated elite<br />

physicians. They seem however to recognize it in a light hearted manner and easy explain it<br />

away. The long time critique <strong>of</strong> any socialist system is the idea that man will not perform to<br />

its fullest capabilities without an incentive, equal to the work that is required. Some time ago<br />

I read The Naked Communist by Cleon Skouson. In recent review I found several statements<br />

to be insightful. As Skousen approaches the idea <strong>of</strong> a stateless, classless society he begins<br />

with the analysis <strong>of</strong> the very nature <strong>of</strong> man. He feels strongly, as do I, that man will “always<br />

possess the desire for individual expression and self-determination, [and] the ambition to<br />

improve their circumstances and the motive to excel above others.” It is this competition,<br />

this ambition that brings innovation and progress. I am not ignorant to the fact that this<br />

“competition” can breed horrific actions, however I believe this to be a flaw in the individual<br />

rather than the system. Now in direct response to [81] Bmellor’s statement, “Some might<br />

say, ‘The doctors won’t participate in socialized medicine, and the quality <strong>of</strong> healthcare will<br />

decrease.’<br />

To them I would point out insurance is not paying for our nation’s weapons, yet we<br />

have the best armed forces in the world. I do not hear the military contractors complaining<br />

about the government’s compensation.” The reason military contractors are not complaining<br />

because they generally earn up to 150% more than a normal, govt. employed, military<br />

<strong>of</strong>ficer. This might I add has created a new problem <strong>of</strong> losing elite military personal to<br />

contracting companies such as Blackwater, which in the long run will and has, raised military<br />

spending. It is logical to think that elite physicians would create a similar corporation to<br />

protect themselves and their wages, creating the same high cost nightmare. Now if we were<br />

to keep wages high as FacistFrank has suggested we run into further difficulties. In his<br />

post he states, “. . . if costs are covered I see no problem with socialized health care system.”<br />

Therein lies the heart <strong>of</strong> the problem, covering the cost! It’s apparent that wages need to<br />

stay high, to keep incentive high, but who is going to cover the cost? It will be those who


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 351<br />

have been diligent and hard working, because it is they who have the excess production to<br />

give. Obviously taxes will rise to astronomical percentages, just as they have in countries<br />

that do provide socialized health care. Personally I don’t want Uncle Sam in my pockets<br />

anymore than he already is, on the contrary it will be me who decides when, where and<br />

to whom I provide assistance to. To examine further the danger <strong>of</strong> covering costs from a<br />

socialist point <strong>of</strong> view I will use another example from Skouson. In a classroom where<br />

a 75% grade is needed to pass there will be a wide range <strong>of</strong> students who perform above<br />

and below the standard. If the classroom were to become socialized, those who perform<br />

well because <strong>of</strong> hard work and determination will be forced to give up their excess points to<br />

those who were lazy and indolent. In the long run the hard working students would lose their<br />

incentive to perform because they know it will be stripped from them and given to those who<br />

are undeserving. Over time the high producers will sink down to a lower level <strong>of</strong> production,<br />

most likely just enough to get by. Now the overall level <strong>of</strong> production has dropped and there<br />

is no excess “points” to close any type <strong>of</strong> gap between the two classes <strong>of</strong> students.<br />

With this in mind I would note however, that there is a general consensus among humanity<br />

that is right and true to help those who simply cannot help themselves. Traditionally this<br />

has been done at the discretion <strong>of</strong> the individual who has excess production. For this I<br />

am completely supportive. However this is a far different approach than a simple socialist<br />

strategy <strong>of</strong> being forced to share excess production. In the same vain, I am supportive <strong>of</strong> the<br />

ideology that anyone with excess production has a duty to lift and help those who may be<br />

struggling. Again, however, it needs to come at their discretion.<br />

I am not entirely sure what the solution is to the nation’s health care crisis. I do feel<br />

strongly though that socializing health care or anything for that matter is not the answer. I<br />

am sure that in my rebuttal I have missed key insights and would invite you to bring those<br />

to my attention. As I would love to discuss this further. In closing I would like to simply<br />

state, it seems very evident to me that any type <strong>of</strong> socialist system would lower society to<br />

the lowest common denominator. In the meantime killing the human spirit <strong>of</strong> ambition and<br />

determination.<br />

Next Message by Rey is [211].<br />

[110] PrivateProperty: Re: Socialized Healthcare. I appreciate this discussion on<br />

socialized medicine and would like to <strong>of</strong>fer my input as well, as I consider it an important<br />

topic.<br />

Let me start by asserting that the people <strong>of</strong> the United States would be in a much better<br />

position if it were to adopt some form <strong>of</strong> socialized medicine. And by socialized medicine<br />

I don’t merely mean a Federal health insurance program, but in fact a complete overhaul <strong>of</strong><br />

the legal framework which perpetuates our extremely fragmented and inefficient system <strong>of</strong><br />

health care.<br />

Let me point out that countries with socialized programs have a much healthier populace<br />

than the United States. Socialized programs encourage its citizens to take an active role<br />

in their health care. These people go in for more checkups and are more concerned with<br />

preventative care. Medical problems are discovered earlier and therefore are more easily<br />

treated. This contrasts with the common scenario in the US, which is to wait until you feel<br />

bad in deciding to visit the doctor.


352 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

There is an argument that socialized systems do not have as advanced technology as<br />

the United States does. That is absolutely true. In fact, we have unnecessarily Because<br />

<strong>of</strong> the devastating risks <strong>of</strong> malpractice suits, physicians do everything they can to avoid<br />

legal liability, which usually involves exhausting all options for a patient. This includes<br />

incorporating the very latest technologies, which can result in very expensive procedures,<br />

with possibly very little benefit to the patient. New technology is not evaluated for its costefficiency<br />

before it is implemented. Why bother when the costs <strong>of</strong> technology are passed<br />

on to the patient? Often a hospital will acquire a new piece <strong>of</strong> equipment, and in effort to<br />

recoup their costs, pressure physicians to recommend to their patients a procedure involving<br />

the equipment, even the procedure the procedure is unnecessary. Technology in the US may<br />

be more advanced, on average. But I challenge someone to find evidence that our healthcare<br />

is significantly more EFFECTIVE (don’t even bother with ’more efficient’) than that <strong>of</strong> other<br />

nations. And what use is technology if it isn’t effective?<br />

True, a socialized system would mean paying more in taxes. However, this also means<br />

not paying for private health insurance, which is a whole other monster altogether. I would<br />

argue that a social program would end up costing patients less than under our current private<br />

system, and therefore there would be a net increase to patients’ disposable income.<br />

Also, as far as the ‘long lines’ argument against social medicine, I would challenge anyone<br />

to find evidence that supports this. If anything, the reverse may be true. My experience<br />

in private health care in the US has very <strong>of</strong>ten involved ridiculous wait times for all medical<br />

procedures, from the most routine to the most urgent. I like to contrast my lifetime experience<br />

here with my travels in the UK, which as you know has socialized medicine under<br />

the National Health Service (NHS). When I did have an appointment, wait times were very<br />

short (appointments actually meant something). One time I was in need <strong>of</strong> emergency care<br />

in downtown London. An ambulance promptly came to pick me up and I was promptly<br />

treated at a nearby hospital. I was released an hour and a half later. I didn’t pay a cent for<br />

anything, and the question <strong>of</strong> my nationality never entered the picture. The NHS didn’t care<br />

who you were, even if you weren’t a UK citizen, they were going to treat you. I found that<br />

pretty damn inspiring.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [111].<br />

[111] PrivateProperty: Socialized medicine is not stupid. Bar wrote in [106]:<br />

“The cold hard facts about socialized medicine is that the quality <strong>of</strong> health care drops,<br />

and the elimination <strong>of</strong> competition decreases efficiency and the importance <strong>of</strong> the individual<br />

patients.”<br />

I would like you to find evidence <strong>of</strong> this. How are you measuring quality <strong>of</strong> care? How<br />

fast they can get them out <strong>of</strong> the hospital? Certainly not by how many people (percentagewise)<br />

are effectively treated? Using that yard-stick, your argument wouldn’t hold up. Also,<br />

competition is not a characteristic <strong>of</strong> medicine. The industry is very fragmented and is<br />

shaped by the relations <strong>of</strong> physician groups and insurance organizations. It’s not like doctors<br />

undercut each other to draw more patients to their practice.<br />

I like to point out that countries with socialized programs have a much healthier populace<br />

than that <strong>of</strong> the United States, and as such don’t need as many serious procedures, such as


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 353<br />

surgery. These citizens invest more time and effort in preventative care, and don’t wait for<br />

their conditions to augment themselves. This very healthy behavior wouldn’t be possible if<br />

not for the virtually unlimited access to health care extended to the population.<br />

Why do we lead the world in healthcare? Is it possibly because, due to our ailing health,<br />

we have the highest demand for these very services?<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [127].<br />

[114] Sparky: Separation <strong>of</strong> State and Church. This question has been on my mind<br />

since the beginning <strong>of</strong> the presidential race. The current state <strong>of</strong> the United States and its<br />

political leaders is one that has many people feeling on edge, and the coverage <strong>of</strong> the race<br />

and how early it has started is an example <strong>of</strong> this. I am wondering what peoples thoughts<br />

are <strong>of</strong> the candidates and the roles that religion are playing in the race, with the republicans<br />

who have an ordained minister running as well as a man who served a mission for the LDS<br />

church and was bishop <strong>of</strong> a ward house, too the democratic party where the slamming <strong>of</strong><br />

candidates has involved “insulting” a candidate by calling him Muslim.<br />

Can the American “democracy” really involve a separation <strong>of</strong> state and church? In a<br />

society where the will <strong>of</strong> the people is ideally to be followed, would religion undoubtedly<br />

be played into the government and its decisions? With the republican party courting the<br />

evangelical Christian right it would seem so, even though they make up a minority <strong>of</strong> the<br />

population, they make up a majority <strong>of</strong> the voting population so it would seem to be an<br />

conundrum to the political leaders elected in to <strong>of</strong>fice, taking the will <strong>of</strong> a few and forcing<br />

it on the majority simply because the ones that voted them into <strong>of</strong>fice expect them to follow<br />

their moral obligations to their church and God. What are people thoughts about this? Living<br />

in <strong>Utah</strong>- where the majority <strong>of</strong> the population is LDS, and the leaders <strong>of</strong> the government I<br />

would expect us to have a unique view in to this aspect and how it can affect daily life and<br />

how the government reacts to certain situations.<br />

Message [114] referenced by [126] and [128]. Next Message by Sparky is [170].<br />

[116] FacistFrank: Re: Socialized medicine is stupid. The research and development<br />

side <strong>of</strong> the pharmaceutical and medical industries is considered a cost if I am not mistaken.<br />

The billions in pr<strong>of</strong>it that the insurance companies make, is after all costs including R&D<br />

cost have been paid for. So the high prices that are being paid by those with health insurance,<br />

are high because the insurance companies want billions in pr<strong>of</strong>it to go into their bank<br />

accounts. If we taxed some <strong>of</strong> that and gave it back to the actual people that earned it,<br />

we wouldn’t have the medical problems we have here today. The insurance companies are<br />

charging far beyond the actual costs (including R&D) <strong>of</strong> health care. Don’t get me wrong,<br />

there is such a thing as fair healthy pr<strong>of</strong>it that harnesses good incentive, then there is just<br />

plain robbery pr<strong>of</strong>it. Insurance and pharmaceutical companies do this not to cover costs but<br />

because they are an oligopoly that also establishes barriers to entry. This is why there are<br />

no competitors to enter the field and provide the same product for a lower price. The capital<br />

necessary to start a pharmaceutical is more than we will ever earn in a lifetime, getting your<br />

drugs approved by the FDA is another insurmountable hurdle. The scientists you have to<br />

pay are also a capital hurdle, but with the prices that insurance is charging they have already<br />

covered all these costs. This is why they are making sky high pr<strong>of</strong>its. Those pr<strong>of</strong>its would<br />

not exist unless all costs were already covered.<br />

Next Message by FacistFrank is [124].


354 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[118] Slash: Socialized medicine is stupid. In response to [106]: The problem with socialized<br />

medicine is politicians namely Democrats argue their point with comparative data,<br />

such as how France does it compared to the U.S. The problem with saying socialized countries<br />

are better by showing that they might live longer, and spend less money while cover<br />

everyone in their country is heath is more then just going to the hospital for emergency treatment.<br />

The fact is most <strong>of</strong> your heath is decided outside <strong>of</strong> the hospital, if a country eats<br />

better, exercises better, and has less stress filled life’s, but happen to have poor emergency<br />

health care that comes at a cheep price for everyone. Guess what they live longer. Ive read<br />

numbers that say 30% <strong>of</strong> over all health is gene related, 30% more is ones over all life style,<br />

diet exercises. The remaining 40% is then broken up into small groups that then covers<br />

more commonly thought heath care, about 10% <strong>of</strong> that being emergency heath care, which<br />

happens to be what The U.S.A. is best at, but then how could The U.S.A. not live as long<br />

on average as the French, could this have to do with The U.S. working more then any other<br />

country, eating worse then other countries. So when someone say socialized medicine would<br />

save us money as a nation and save the poor, well maybe but that would involve a miracle,<br />

because it would involve changing Americans eating habits, convince people to walk to work<br />

instead <strong>of</strong> driving, and many other positive things that assumed when comparing America to<br />

Europe. So people need to see that comparing our health care system the way France is comparing<br />

apples to oranges. This is also just one aspect pointing out the flaws with socialized<br />

medicine there is a huge cultural difference between how health care is seen. I think that<br />

most people who want socialized medicine live in make believe land, because they refuse to<br />

draw a line, as to what is possible and what is not, when the topic <strong>of</strong> what can be performed<br />

crossed the board. The fact is The U.S. does things that other socialized country would<br />

never dream <strong>of</strong>. Only a liberal dreamer sees it possible to have their cake and eat it to when<br />

it comes to heath care, because it cant remain good and competitive while changing into a<br />

system that flat lines competition innovation and every procedure possible. And when some<br />

shows up to the hopital and says that can afford insurence I think they should be asked how<br />

then they seem to pay their cell phone bill, and most likly their eight year old kids aswell.<br />

Its all about priority, and those who complain cant and wont change their priorities.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [182].<br />

[120] Jenn: 30 hour shifts make doctors stupid. Socialized medicine is not stupid.<br />

The US medical system is a perfect demonstration <strong>of</strong> the exploitation <strong>of</strong> workers. Bar’s<br />

statement in [106] regarding the decrease in efficiency and importance <strong>of</strong> individuals is a<br />

logical capitalist argument on the surface. However, are Americans really recieving better<br />

medical care under this system?<br />

The cold hard facts <strong>of</strong> the current US medical system (courtesy <strong>of</strong> Wikipedia): “Medical<br />

residencies traditionally require lengthy hours <strong>of</strong> their trainees. Classically, 36-hour shifts<br />

are separated by 12 hours <strong>of</strong> rest, during 100+ hour weeks. The American public, and<br />

the medical education establishment, is increasingly recognizing that such long hours are<br />

counter-productive, since sleep deprivation increases rates <strong>of</strong> medical errors. This was noted<br />

in a landmark study on the effects <strong>of</strong> sleep deprivation and error rate in an intensive care<br />

unit. The Accreditation Council for Graduate Medical Education (ACGME) has limited<br />

the number <strong>of</strong> work-hours to 80 hours weekly, overnight call frequency to no more than<br />

one overnight every third day, 30 hour maximum straight shift, and 10 hours <strong>of</strong>f between


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 355<br />

shifts. While these limits are voluntary, adherence has been mandated for the purposes <strong>of</strong><br />

accreditation.<br />

Critics <strong>of</strong> long residency hours trace the problem to the fact that resident physicians have<br />

no alternatives to positions that are <strong>of</strong>fered, meaning residents must accept all conditions <strong>of</strong><br />

employment, including very long work hours, and that they must also, in many cases, contend<br />

with poor supervision. This process, they contend, reduces the competitive pressures<br />

on hospitals, resulting in low salaries and long, unsafe work hours.”<br />

Capitalism is engrained in future physicians from the moment they sign their $250,000<br />

promissory note to pay for their medical school. Oftentimes, residents must take out additional<br />

loans even after they have completed their schooling to supplement their training<br />

salary. Some post-residency training is even unpaid. They begin their internship hundreds<br />

<strong>of</strong> thousands <strong>of</strong> dollars in debt, forcing them to complete their training in the miserable training<br />

system <strong>of</strong> the US hospitals, with no alternatives. After they complete their training, they<br />

must make enough money to maintain their lifestyle as well as pay down their huge debts.<br />

Although many physicians entered medical school with altruistic intentions, by the time they<br />

have completed their training they are disillusioned with medicine and just downright tired.<br />

This understandably leads to the desire to just make your money by seeing as many patients<br />

as possible (as physicians are paid on a per-patient basis).<br />

The socialization <strong>of</strong> medicine needs to start with the roots up.<br />

Socialized medicine is not stupid.<br />

Bar wrote in [106]:<br />

“The cold hard facts about socialized medicine is that the quality <strong>of</strong> health<br />

care drops, and the elimination <strong>of</strong> competition decreases efficiency and the<br />

importance <strong>of</strong> the individual patients.”<br />

I would like you to find evidence <strong>of</strong> this. How are you measuring quality <strong>of</strong> care? How<br />

fast they can get them out <strong>of</strong> the hospital? Certainly not by how many people (percentagewise)<br />

are effectively treated? Using that yard-stick, your argument wouldn’t hold up. Also,<br />

competition is not a characteristic <strong>of</strong> medicine. The industry is very fragmented and is<br />

shaped by the relations <strong>of</strong> physician groups and insurance organizations. It’s not like doctors<br />

undercut each other to draw more patients to their practice.<br />

I like to point out that countries with socialized programs have a much healthier populace<br />

than that <strong>of</strong> the United States, and as such don’t need as many serious procedures, such as<br />

surgery. These citizens invest more time and effort in preventative care, and don’t wait for<br />

their conditions to augment themselves. This very healthy behavior wouldn’t be possible if<br />

not for the virtually unlimited access to health care extended to the population.<br />

Why do we lead the world in healthcare? Is it possibly because, due to our ailing health,<br />

we have the highest demand for these very services?<br />

Next Message by Jenn is [174].<br />

[123] Bar: Socialized medicine is stupid after all. To address the measuring <strong>of</strong> the<br />

quality <strong>of</strong> care issue under socialized medicine, here is a quote from Wikipedia (whatever


356 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

that’s worth) “One <strong>of</strong> the major complaints about the Canadian health care system is waiting<br />

times, whether for a specialist, major elective surgery, such as hip replacement, or specialized<br />

treatments, such as radiation for breast cancer. Studies by the Commonwealth Fund<br />

found that 24% <strong>of</strong> Canadians waited 4 hours or more in the emergency room, vs. 12% in the<br />

U.S.; 57% waited 4 weeks or more to see a specialist, vs. 23% in the U.S.”<br />

“In a 2003 survey <strong>of</strong> hospital administrators conducted in Canada, the U.S., and three<br />

other countries, 21% <strong>of</strong> Canadian hospital administrators, but less than 1% <strong>of</strong> American administrators,<br />

said that it would take over three weeks to do a biopsy for possible breast cancer<br />

on a 50-year-old woman; 50% <strong>of</strong> Canadian administrators versus none <strong>of</strong> their American<br />

counterparts said that it would take over six months for a 65-year-old to undergo a routine<br />

hip replacement surgery.”<br />

“Some <strong>of</strong> the extra money spent in the United States goes to doctors, nurses, and other<br />

medical pr<strong>of</strong>essionals, all <strong>of</strong> whom receive higher compensation than their counterparts<br />

north <strong>of</strong> the border. According to health data collected by the OECD, average income for<br />

physicians in the United States in 1996 was nearly twice that for physicians in Canada.”<br />

Why would a good doctor work in Canada when he could get paid twice as much south <strong>of</strong><br />

the border?<br />

“The United States spends more on technology than Canada. The study Medical Imaging<br />

in Canada, 2004[64] reported that in 2004, Canada had 4.6 MRI scanners per million<br />

population while the U.S. had 19.5 per million. Canada’s 10.3 CT scanners per million also<br />

ranked behind the U.S., which had 29.5 per million.[65] The study did not attempt to assess<br />

whether the difference in the number <strong>of</strong> MRI and CT scanners had any effect on the medical<br />

outcomes.”<br />

For more info on the US vs. Canadian Health Care Systems and the same place I got<br />

these quotes go to<br />

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Canadian and American health care systems compared<br />

I found both FacistFrank and Slash made poignant observations about the Health care<br />

system: FacistFrank makes an excellent point about the system when he says,<br />

“The insurance companies are charging far beyond the actual costs (including<br />

R&D) <strong>of</strong> health care. Don’t get me wrong, there is such thing as fair<br />

healthy pr<strong>of</strong>it that harnesses good incentive, then there is just plain robbery<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it. Insurance and pharmaceutical companies do this not to cover costs<br />

but because they are an oligopoly that also establishes barriers to entry.”<br />

That’s exactly what they do, I completely agree with his analysis. Where I disagree with<br />

him, is I think that these pr<strong>of</strong>its are necessary for risk aversion. They make sick ridiculous<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> their drugs through the monopolies that they hold, or as he says “robbery<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its.” But these pr<strong>of</strong>its are necessary because the risk that a pharmaceutical company<br />

takes to develop a new drug is unbelievable. After investing billions <strong>of</strong> dollars to develop<br />

a new drug many times the drug stays in the testing stages <strong>of</strong> the FDA for years, and many<br />

times the drug is not approved; after spending billions on a drug, it is not approved! Ive


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 357<br />

seen some smaller pharma companies stock price drop as much as 80% after a drug has been<br />

denied. Those pr<strong>of</strong>its are a necessary evil for risk-aversion.<br />

When Slash talks about relativity <strong>of</strong> a countries health to explain life expectancy and<br />

other health comparisons he hit the nail on the head. “Super sized anyone” Americans eat<br />

like crap, that’s the sad truth and this causes many <strong>of</strong> the problems <strong>of</strong> health care in our<br />

countrie, it may even be one <strong>of</strong> the causes <strong>of</strong> rising health costs. Eating right and exercise<br />

would solve many many problems in America, but what does that have to do with the health<br />

care system? its a bad cultural aspect <strong>of</strong> our society, nothing to do with the hierarchy <strong>of</strong> the<br />

medical system. Excellent point<br />

Message [123] referenced by [124]. Next Message by Bar is [207].<br />

[124] FacistFrank: This is pretty interesting, the fact from [123] that the pharmaceuticals<br />

have to have a lot <strong>of</strong> money to cover costs if their drug is rejected. But then this brings up<br />

some other questions, are the billions in pr<strong>of</strong>its there to back up drugs that fail, or is that a<br />

cost that has already been figured into expenses, before pure leftover pr<strong>of</strong>it is determined?<br />

If I would have to make an assumption I would say that the cost needed for failed drugs<br />

is already included in standard R&D costs because pr<strong>of</strong>it is the leftover money after all<br />

costs have been covered. If they are dipping into pr<strong>of</strong>its (which I doubt) to cover expenses<br />

for failed drugs and technologies, then perhaps the high costs they pass to consumers is<br />

warranted. If not then I think it is robbery.<br />

Next Message by FacistFrank is [158].<br />

[125] Hans: Focus the Nation Events. This week you will be able to attend several<br />

environmental events on the U <strong>of</strong> U campus, during a week <strong>of</strong> co-ordinated nationwide<br />

“focus the nation” activities.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the topics <strong>of</strong> Econ 5080 is to understand the glue which holds societies together.<br />

Climate change is here an interesting experiment: what happens to the “social fabric” in a<br />

prolonged disaster, when infrastructure which we all rely on and which we take for granted<br />

is destroyed, or when there is not enough food or water to go around?<br />

A sober look at these issues can be found in the following 20-page pdf:<br />

http://www.oxfordresearchgroup.org.uk/publications/briefing papers/pdf/uncertainfuture<br />

Here is an excerpt about civil unrest:<br />

Firstly, most analysts see the threat to national security for developed countries<br />

as coming from the outside, from massive immigration. But there are<br />

other security concerns that governments should take into account in relation<br />

to their own populations. For example, if responses to the aftermath<br />

<strong>of</strong> natural disasters are inadequate, then people may begin to lose confidence<br />

in the government’s ability to protect them. At the same time, there<br />

will undoubtedly be resistance to some <strong>of</strong> the very measures that will be<br />

necessary to protect and provide for people. This may create resentment<br />

towards the government and possibly lead to a breakdown in trust between<br />

the police and general public if draconian measures need to be enforced;<br />

particularly if the police and security services are seen to be primarily protecting<br />

the interests <strong>of</strong> the political and financial elites within society. For


358 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

others, the government will not be going far enough, and a rise in protests<br />

aimed at governments over inadequate policy changes or aimed at corporations<br />

over environmental damage can probably be expected. While social<br />

and environmental movements have a long history <strong>of</strong> peaceful protest and<br />

non-violent direct action, on the fringes <strong>of</strong> such movements there are always<br />

those who will resort to violence and sabotage. In the extreme, there<br />

may even be a rise in groups using terrorist tactics to further their otherwise<br />

legitimate agendas. In the US, the FBI has observed worrying signs <strong>of</strong> an<br />

escalation in violent rhetoric and tactics amongst a small minority <strong>of</strong> environmental<br />

extremists, and they currently consider ‘eco-terrorism’ to be one<br />

<strong>of</strong> the most serious domestic terrorism threats.<br />

Terrorism is not the only alternative if those in power do not voluntarily do the right thing.<br />

Another possibility would be that the grassroots organize and by their sheer numbers force<br />

those in power to implement effective and fair policies.<br />

Here is a calendar <strong>of</strong> all the focus the nation events:<br />

http://www.sustainability.utah.edu/newsandevents/ftncalendar.htm<br />

Here is another calendar (<strong>of</strong> which I am the maintainer):<br />

http://gaia.econ.utah.edu/calendar<br />

Hans.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [142].<br />

[126] CousinIt: Separation <strong>of</strong> Church and State? I am responding to Sparky’s [114]<br />

discussion post on the role <strong>of</strong> religion in American politics. I do have an opinion on this<br />

topic. It is an opinion that I know will not be very pallatable to some folks. I think<br />

that the notion <strong>of</strong> the necessity <strong>of</strong> a separation between church and state was written into<br />

the US constitution to promote the idea that people should be able to believe in whatever<br />

super/extra/quasi-universal humanoid (anthropomorphized) diety or personal-favorite<br />

mythological variety-act that they choose but that this belief should be kept to themselves<br />

and not enter into the realities <strong>of</strong> governing and providing stewardship <strong>of</strong> the nation, its<br />

resources, and its people in general.<br />

Frankly, I am baffled by the fact that we, here in the twenty-first century, are still arguing<br />

about this stuff. We should be laughing these folks who want some kind <strong>of</strong> dark-ages<br />

theocracy right out <strong>of</strong> town on a rail, right now, thank you, goodnight!! Alas, we choose to<br />

take them seriously and encourage their continuous babbling. You would think we’d have<br />

become bored to tears by it all, by now!<br />

But, in order to understand the tragi-comic ridiculousness <strong>of</strong> this entire debate, I will<br />

need to lay some groundwork by making some very specific comments and clarifying some<br />

definitions.<br />

Mythologies are important. We need myths. Myths are the stories that we tell each other<br />

and that we recite to ourselves that act as guides through the trials and tribulations, as well<br />

as through the joys and achievements that we experience in our lives. It is through myth


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 359<br />

that we are able to give some sense <strong>of</strong> continuity to our personal and collective histories<br />

(and herstories) and through which we find appreciation for ourselves, for others, and for<br />

our world (as families, nations, cults, covens, girl-scout troops, members <strong>of</strong> a rock n’ roll<br />

band, academics, hairdressers, feminists, cross-dressers, etc.).<br />

Myths are meant to be taken as metaphors for the experiences <strong>of</strong> everyday life and as<br />

metaphors for personal and social growth toward some imagined future state <strong>of</strong> perfection (I<br />

will save my critique <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> perfection for another time). Myths are not meant to be<br />

taken and acted upon literally. Myths are not meant to represent the world or human experience<br />

in any one-to-one relationship <strong>of</strong> identity or correspondence, but are merely very broad<br />

generalizations about common human experiences that are always and everywhere subject<br />

to interpretation (...herein lies a clue to their useful uselessness in running governments).<br />

Religions are mythologies. They are collections <strong>of</strong> very nice stories that are told and retold<br />

for the purpose <strong>of</strong> helping individuals in a community or a society get through their lives<br />

by attributing meaning and purpose to lives that might otherwise seem unbearably meaningless<br />

and scary (at least to the more simple and unimaginative amongst us who are not inclined<br />

or have the talent to make-up our own personal myths). By the same token, religions<br />

are very useful if you are someone or a group <strong>of</strong> someones who wants to get another subordinate<br />

group <strong>of</strong> people to behave in predictably specific ways. We were supposed to have<br />

arrived at and overcome this impass <strong>of</strong> fantasy and superstition with “The Enlightenment”<br />

which supposedly began several hundred years ago, by some accounts.<br />

This is not to say that myths aren’t extremely powerful. The myths underlying Nazism,<br />

Radical Islamism, Manifest Destiny, The ‘Invisible Hand’ <strong>of</strong> the ‘Free Market’, Project<br />

for the New American Century, etc., are all pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the power <strong>of</strong> myth. In fact, these<br />

movements are fine examples <strong>of</strong> “myths gone wild!!!” [...and you can probably catch some<br />

<strong>of</strong> these myhtologies “going ape-sh*t” on video-disk at the Marriott Library!!! ;) ] I think<br />

that the provision for a separation <strong>of</strong> church and state was penned with the knowledge that, if<br />

left untended, myths characteristically tend to get out <strong>of</strong> control before anyone even knows<br />

they’ve sneaked-out <strong>of</strong> the bedroom window.<br />

Finally, ....my opinion? I really don’t care what kind <strong>of</strong> superheroes and fantasy-figures<br />

you have operating in your over-active imagination about what gets to count as ‘real’ in<br />

your own day-dreams about “eternal-this” and “devilish-that”. You are free to indulge in<br />

whatever fantasy-mythologies that you want to, on your own time, in your own mind and<br />

with others who enjoy the same kind <strong>of</strong> ‘dungeons and dragons’ gaming night-out-withthe-boys<br />

that you do. I could really care less. But, please do not ask or expect me to be<br />

happy and coalescent when you want to bring those fantasies and selective mythologies to<br />

bear (on real-world problems <strong>of</strong> the everyday material lives and needs <strong>of</strong> everyday common<br />

people) within the government chambers <strong>of</strong> my democracy. You will only prove to me how<br />

unreal and fantasy-laden is your conception <strong>of</strong> what a democratic government should really<br />

be about in THIS world, at THIS time.<br />

We should “get-over” ourselves and our myths (this IS the twenty-first century, after all,<br />

and just look where these out-dated mythologies have gotten us). We could, rather, get on<br />

with the problems <strong>of</strong> making the world a better place for ALL OF US (all personal fantasies


360 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

aside) while at the same time providing for a better life for those who are to follow by doing<br />

the hard yet honorable work <strong>of</strong> delaying our inevitable extinction as best we can (with at<br />

least the mythological hope that it is not already too late)..<br />

Perhaps this will require the invention <strong>of</strong> new more compelling mythologies to describe<br />

and make apprehensible the meaninglessness that is unfolding before us at the moment?<br />

Message [126] referenced by [127] and [128]. Next Message by CousinIt is [131].<br />

[127] PrivateProperty: Amen to [126].<br />

Hans: Amen is an interesting choice <strong>of</strong> words for agreeing to an atheist rant. I assume you made this joke consciously.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [129].<br />

[128] Brandon: Separation <strong>of</strong> Church and State - kinda... In response to Sparky’s<br />

[114] question surrounding the role <strong>of</strong> religion in American politics, I believe in the ideology<br />

surrounding the creation <strong>of</strong> separation <strong>of</strong> church and state in the U.S. Constitution; that being<br />

that it is illegal for the U.S. government to create a national church and that the laws <strong>of</strong> said<br />

church will influence or dictate U.S. law or legislation.<br />

Now, does this mean that we have a true separation <strong>of</strong> church and state in the legal sense?<br />

Yes. There does not exist a national church or religious organization that creates law, legislation,<br />

or collects taxes. However, because the nation was founded by members <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Christian faith, and even with the vast majority <strong>of</strong> practicing religions in this country, the<br />

American population is still predominately Christian. It is only natural, in such an enviornment,<br />

that politicians and elected <strong>of</strong>ficials will base their platforms and proposed legislation<br />

around the predominate societal view <strong>of</strong> ethics and morales. Where do these ethics and<br />

morales stem from? The Christian faith. Not soley the Christian faith (that would be an<br />

oversimplification) but rather what our society has rationally accepted as the societal norm<br />

<strong>of</strong> human behavior. Example: I don’t think there is anyone here (except maybe a follower <strong>of</strong><br />

Nietzche) who would argue for the legalization <strong>of</strong> taking a human life. (Disclaimer: I am not<br />

trying to make an insinuation about the legality <strong>of</strong> abortion with this argument; that issue is,<br />

or at least should be, a debate <strong>of</strong> science surrounding the definition <strong>of</strong> a fetus as a human life,<br />

so let’s not even go there.) Rational people, despite their religions background will agree<br />

beyond a shadow <strong>of</strong> a doubt that such a legalization would be a detriment to society. Sure,<br />

this ideology is rooted in theological beliefs, however it is a universally accepted notion <strong>of</strong><br />

any civilized society.<br />

Sparky asks in [114]:<br />

“In a society where the will <strong>of</strong> the people is ideally to be followed, would<br />

religion undoubtedly be played into the government and its decisions?”<br />

It is only natural that a society will follow and elect leaders who support the general<br />

ideals, morales, and ethics <strong>of</strong> the majority <strong>of</strong> the people. I don’t disagree that it IS ridiculous<br />

that we still debate over a politicians personal views on religion. If a Muslim is elected<br />

president tomorrow, the law prohibits him from mandating that U.S. law must adhere to<br />

the Quran. A Hindu president will be powerless in mandating that all public schools must<br />

convert children to Hinduism and implement strict participation in Deepavali. An Atheistic


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 361<br />

president would be completely unable to close churches or prevent people from practicing<br />

their faith.<br />

The national issues that are impacted most by religion are social dilemmas that have no<br />

written law but conflict with the theological standard, i.e., gay-marriage. This is an issue that<br />

the Christian-right are fighting, there is no written law forbidding it, and so they will vote<br />

for a president who will prevent this from becoming a legal form <strong>of</strong> marriage. Many here<br />

will argue that it is not right for us to ban such a marriage, however, in a democratic system<br />

let us not forget that the will <strong>of</strong> the people is what should be law. The elected <strong>of</strong>ficials are<br />

representatives, voices, <strong>of</strong> the people. If the people do not support a form <strong>of</strong> legislation they<br />

will elect someone who shares their views. So sure, religion is influencing politics; more so<br />

in the sense that religion influences the people, the people then influence politics.<br />

A Baptist minister being elected president will not further bolster U.S. legislation into<br />

adopting more “Christian” laws, however, it gives the majority <strong>of</strong> the public the security<br />

blanket that their beliefs and way <strong>of</strong> life will not be infringed on. Perhaps I’m preaching<br />

to the choir here, but I think this is an important issue that the U.S. people should take a<br />

step back and think about. The same is true for other countries. I challenge anyone to find a<br />

nation where the religion or ‘mythologies’, as CousinIt in [126] mentions, does not influence<br />

their politics. In [126] CousinIt refers to mythologies as:<br />

“collections <strong>of</strong> very nice stories that are told and retold for the purpose <strong>of</strong><br />

helping individuals in a community or a society get through their lives by<br />

attributing meaning and purpose to lives that might otherwise seem unbearably<br />

meaningless and scary (at least to the more simple and unimaginative<br />

amongst us who are not inclined or have the talent to make-up our own<br />

personal myths)”<br />

He/she also states:<br />

“The myths underlying Nazism, Radical Islamism, Manifest Destiny, The<br />

‘Invisible Hand’ <strong>of</strong> the ‘Free Market’, Project for the New American Century,<br />

etc., are all pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the power <strong>of</strong> myth.”<br />

CousinIt left out two myths (if we are to refer to political ideologies as such) and that is<br />

socialism and communism. I understand the context <strong>of</strong> myths, in which he is speaking; that<br />

these are not myths as in falsehoods but rather as fantastic ideas, stories, etc. CousinIt is<br />

right, myths do fuel societies and no matter what form <strong>of</strong> governmental agency you install,<br />

the general agreement on the myth that fuels said society will impact government.<br />

Message [128] referenced by [131] and [134]. Next Message by Brandon is [133].<br />

[130] Srichardson: Separation <strong>of</strong> Church and State. After reading Sparky’s insights<br />

<strong>of</strong> separation <strong>of</strong> church and state all I could think about was how brave the posting was,<br />

especially in a class where most <strong>of</strong> the people are <strong>Utah</strong> born. Growing up in <strong>Utah</strong> my whole<br />

life and not being religious has definitely been a learning experience. I have had many <strong>of</strong> the<br />

same thoughts that Sparky brings up but I quickly learned as a very shy person that it was<br />

just better for me to keep it to myself if I did not want to be in a very heated argument.


362 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

As issues <strong>of</strong> the separation <strong>of</strong> church and state were brought up over and over again it<br />

seemed as though my peers <strong>of</strong> a rural <strong>Utah</strong> town became more and more closed minded and<br />

when debates such as “under god” being taken out <strong>of</strong> the pledge or the ten commandments<br />

not being displayed in courthouses you were just waiting for the same individuals to get<br />

very heated and <strong>of</strong>ten make comments that where made to be sharp towards those that don’t<br />

believe exactly as they did.<br />

I think that people are very protective <strong>of</strong> their religious beliefs and do not like them<br />

questioned, and they see these fights <strong>of</strong> separation <strong>of</strong> church and state as being a question<br />

that their religion is the “right” religion. I can in a way understand being very protective <strong>of</strong><br />

your religion and beliefs, however I begin to have a problem when people have the notion<br />

that their religion is the one and only “right” way. Separation <strong>of</strong> Church and State is in<br />

the constitution so that all people can make their own choices when it comes to religion, it<br />

protects everyone, if you are Catholic, Christian, Mormon, Jewish and even yes those that<br />

are atheist!<br />

So thank you Sparky for putting that posting out there and saying things that i have <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

thought but just never said!<br />

Next Message by Srichardson is [171].<br />

[131] CousinIt: Church and State; Capitalism and Democracy; Apples and Oranges?<br />

Brandon [128] forces me to make an important distinction. Capitalism, socialism and communism<br />

are terms that denote particular types <strong>of</strong> economic systems, that is, they are alternative<br />

economic systems, not mythologies, per se, and there are selective mythologies<br />

underlying all <strong>of</strong> these (remember, mythologies are neccesary, powerful, and valuable. The<br />

question really is just a matter <strong>of</strong> which mythologies are chosen to be relevant and positive<br />

for a particular people, situated as they are in time and place).<br />

Brandon seems to imply that America as a whole believes in and practices (or should<br />

believe in and practice, as a whole) according to a set <strong>of</strong> Christian values that are widely<br />

recognized as “American” values. That being said, the question arises, Do the “Christian<br />

values” underlying right-wing American morals and politics really reflect the teachings <strong>of</strong><br />

Christ? If they do, then the following statements must be true...<br />

Christ teaches hatred and contempt <strong>of</strong> homosexuals, sinners, non-Christians, poor people<br />

on welfare, people with mental illnesses, people who lack moral judgement, and anyone<br />

who doesn’t want a purely “Christian” capitalist world to live in.<br />

Christ values the labor and rights <strong>of</strong> white male citizens more than the labor and rights <strong>of</strong><br />

immigrants, women, racial minorites, poor people, and gay/lesbians.<br />

Christ teaches that some people deserve more respect, help, and care than others deserve<br />

and that poor people are poor because they are lazy and immoral.<br />

Christ teaches that homosexuals don’t deserve the right to have families, raise children,<br />

or take care <strong>of</strong> their family’s private interests when it comes to medical issues, death and<br />

dying issues, property issues, etc.<br />

Christ teaches that women do not have the right to decide for themselves what they want<br />

to do with their own bodies.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 363<br />

Christ supports exploitation <strong>of</strong> poor and working-class people through institutionalized<br />

wage-slavery, corporate welfare, tax breaks and entitlements for the rich.<br />

Christ teaches that economic growth and the amassing <strong>of</strong> great wealth at the expense <strong>of</strong><br />

those less fortunate than oneself are elements <strong>of</strong> the correct focus <strong>of</strong> a good life.<br />

Christ teaches that violence and threat <strong>of</strong> violence is an acceptable way to solve conflicts,<br />

gain dominance over others, and as a way <strong>of</strong> taking and possessing material resources even<br />

when others are already sitting on top <strong>of</strong> said resources, especially if it means controlling<br />

the flow <strong>of</strong> petroleum and its pr<strong>of</strong>its.<br />

Christ supports the undermining and overthrow <strong>of</strong> any and all governments that do not<br />

support and participate ‘properly’ in accord with American capitalistic enterprises and interests.<br />

Christ teaches “an eye for an eye, a tooth for a tooth” and supports the seeking <strong>of</strong> revenge<br />

on those that have wronged you.<br />

Christ teaches that those who do not believe as Christians do should be forced by law to<br />

at least behave as Christians do.<br />

Christ believes that whatever is good for large transnational businesses and corporate<br />

private interests should be the invisible basis <strong>of</strong> a system <strong>of</strong> government that protects the<br />

privileges <strong>of</strong> the few over the rights and needs <strong>of</strong> the many.<br />

etc., etc., etc.,<br />

I don’t think anyone would agree that these are representative <strong>of</strong> “what Jesus would do.”<br />

However, these are the values and outcomes that some folks support in the name <strong>of</strong> a Christian<br />

ethic in American politics.<br />

On the contrary, my intuition is that Christ was/would be (in his ideology and attitudes toward<br />

humanity, human right to the products <strong>of</strong> ones labor, and mutual aid to ones comrades)<br />

something much more similar to a socialist/communist/humanitarian/anarchist....<br />

If he really did come back to save us all again, he would probably want to include homosexuals,<br />

immigrants, prostitutes, poor people, loonies, sex-<strong>of</strong>fenders, murderers, and drug<br />

addicts.<br />

We probably wouldn’t recognize him and procede to nail him up for a second time!<br />

Message [131] referenced by [133] and [134]. Next Message by CousinIt is [135].<br />

[133] Brandon: RE: Church and State; Capitalism and Democracy; Apples and Oranges?<br />

I was interested in CousinIt’s response in [131], at first I was curious where his/her<br />

semi-poetic representation <strong>of</strong> “Christ’s teachings”. I realize that CousinIt was pointing out<br />

the paradox in the Christian faith. Christ never once expresses alienation <strong>of</strong> fellow humans,<br />

nor condones anyone for their lifestyle. And yet, modern Christian faith does this on a daily<br />

basis. Not only Christian, but many theistic religions. Islam, Christianity, Judaism, Hinduism,<br />

etc. I think it is unfair for us to say that every religious person acts in this way, but i<br />

think it is safe to say, a large portion.<br />

I must make a response to CousinIt, if I may, simply as a form <strong>of</strong> correction. I was not<br />

implying that America “as a whole” believes and practices according to a set <strong>of</strong> Christian


364 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

values. Far from it. However, there is no argument that the majority <strong>of</strong> the population<br />

claims that they are Christian. It is estimated that in 2001 76.5 percent <strong>of</strong> the US population<br />

identified themselves with some form or denomination <strong>of</strong> the Christian faith Source:<br />

http://www.gc.cuny.edu/faculty/research briefs/aris/key findings.htm.<br />

But this does not mean that the whole country adheres to these religious standards. With<br />

nearly 25 percent not associating with the Christian faith, I believe it has created a unique<br />

mixture <strong>of</strong> ideas and relationships. And, while CousinIt, was somewhat distraught by, what<br />

i can only described as, a lack <strong>of</strong> social progress towards a sensitized nation without the<br />

forward presence <strong>of</strong> religion; I find it interesting the way in which our society has progressed<br />

in the tolerance and acceptance <strong>of</strong> external thoughts and ideas. Granted, this tolerance has<br />

come at a slow rate and continues to move slowly, but that is as with any form <strong>of</strong> evolution.<br />

We cannot expect some cataclysmic event to all <strong>of</strong> a sudden completely alter the minds and<br />

opinions <strong>of</strong> humans. Yet, we can recognize the forward progress. 50 years ago, an Atheist<br />

would have had a pretty hard time becomming a public figure without being associated with<br />

the Communist Party. 100 years ago a gay couple would never have been able to walk down<br />

the streets <strong>of</strong> even San Fransisco, hand-in-hand and showing each other intimate affection.<br />

I’m not saying this country has evolved to a level <strong>of</strong> godlike tolerance and we are supreme<br />

to our ancestors’ ideals, but what I am saying is we have progresed and continue to, but<br />

the change is very slow. I think generalities and stereotypes about groups fuel the urge to<br />

not progress. This comes from both sides <strong>of</strong> the political spectrum. Right-wing conservatives<br />

attack the left and their support for special interest groups, whereas the left attacks the<br />

right on their contituents who support Christian family values. When attacked, or when one<br />

group feels that their interests are threatened externally, it is only normal for that group to<br />

strengthen its arguments and prevent the antithesis from occuring. example: A democrat is<br />

elected who supports gay-marriage (i apologize for constantly using this example). A majority<br />

(that is not to say ‘all’) <strong>of</strong> Christians, who generally support the republicans, will feel the<br />

‘sanctity <strong>of</strong> marriage’ threatened in this country. In response they will call upon their elected<br />

representatives to do everything in their power to block a legalization <strong>of</strong> gay-marriage. In<br />

response to the that, the gay community and its supporters will call the republicans and conservatives<br />

bigots, hateful, etc etc etc, simply because two parties cannot agree on a single<br />

issue.<br />

Ok, i’ve preached too long, and to be honest I feel that it isn’t going anywhere. I just want<br />

to state that while I do not wholly agree with CousinIt’s perspective on how society should<br />

void <strong>of</strong> religious groups, I do agree with his arguments about the naive nature <strong>of</strong> these<br />

groups. How modern groups act almost in a complete opposite manner as their prophets,<br />

messiahs, or just really righteous dudes did. The first step to overcoming these changes<br />

would be for these groups to look internally at their own faults and rectifying these selfdilemmas<br />

before addressing the faults <strong>of</strong> others.<br />

Thank you for coming, i’ll be here next Sunday same time. (Sorry I had to laugh at myself<br />

for the rest <strong>of</strong> you...my sermon went a little long)<br />

Message [133] referenced by [135]. Next Message by Brandon is [383].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 365<br />

[134] PrivateProperty: Re: Church and State; Capitalism and Democracy; Apples<br />

and Oranges? CousinIt, I agree with you wholeheartedly that Jesus’ teachings are not<br />

evident in the way our economy functions [131]. Not that this really matters; I myself<br />

am not Christian. However, what I think Brandon is trying to say [128] is that America<br />

simply comes from a Christian tradition, which is true. Going back to the beginnings <strong>of</strong><br />

America, many <strong>of</strong> the colonists came for religious freedom, as their particular Christian sect<br />

was being persecuted back home. At the same time, these colonists were also motivated<br />

by economic reasons, for the opportunity to own their own land and become independent<br />

economic agents. The point <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> this is that despite any formal clause in the constitution<br />

that calls for the seperation <strong>of</strong> church and state, the truth is that economy and religion (and<br />

politics) were entwined from the foundings <strong>of</strong> America, and inevitably there is still a remnant<br />

<strong>of</strong> that influence today.<br />

Now, as for actually saying that America should be run according to a Christian tradition,<br />

that is completely bogus. I would have nothing but disrespect for anyone in a place <strong>of</strong><br />

influence that lets their religion infiltrate their decision-making. Unfortunately, there are<br />

individuals in our society that can’t seem to understand the importance <strong>of</strong> this seperation.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [198].<br />

[135] CousinIt: Church and State and Capitalism. Just as a clarification.... democratic<br />

practice, by some accounts, should be something with an aim that includes and seeks to accommodate<br />

all people, not just the majority (not just the most wealthy, or most privileged).<br />

Yes, the majority must be protected from the minority, but, the minority must also be protected<br />

from being dictated to by the majority, as well....a million people (or 400 million)<br />

CAN be wrong. It all depends on who “the people” are..WHICH people you are willing<br />

to include.....democracy in America, as well as in ancient Athens, has always been limited<br />

to those in the privileged class. When the founding fathers said, “We the people...”, they<br />

probably meant “We, the people here in this room....” Whether this is the case or not doesn’t<br />

really matter. What does is that we have the surviving and developing notion that people can<br />

rule themselves by being the government that they are governed by.<br />

As we have learned in this class, contradictions are an opportunity to look deeper to unearth<br />

the underlying structure <strong>of</strong> the contradiction as well as into the ideologies that depend<br />

on and make it possible to ignore the contradiction. Democracy is a process, not a thing or a<br />

product. It is ongoing and dynamic...always changing and always under contention. We are<br />

still working it out, as Brandon [133] properly points out.<br />

Capitalism is not democracy. They are not the same thing. One <strong>of</strong> the contradictions in<br />

American popular ideology is that democracy is dependent on capitalism as its economic<br />

system...the notion that they are one and the same thing. However, in a truly democratic<br />

system, we could vote capitalism out and install any alternative economy. Also, any system<br />

that has as its elements tarriffs, taxes, and contraband, by definition IS NOT ‘free-enterprise.’<br />

Capitalism is no less ‘centrally planned’ than is socialism. The difference is, in capitalism<br />

the capitalist class elites (those who own the means <strong>of</strong> production) are the ones doing the<br />

central planning, rather than the people who are their own government who all own the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production equally for the good <strong>of</strong> all rather than for the pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>of</strong> the few.


366 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

This conflation <strong>of</strong> capitalism and democracy creates a whole chain <strong>of</strong> contradictions that<br />

cause the kinds <strong>of</strong> distortions that a “Christian ethic” like the right-wing American variety<br />

exemplifies. Another such case exists in the academy that separates political economy into<br />

economic and political science as discreet disciplines. What this effectively does is prevent<br />

us from addressing the contradictions that exist in the conflation <strong>of</strong> capitalism with democracy.<br />

The capitalism stuff is studied in economics departments and the political stuff is studied<br />

in political science departments, as if the two are completely unrelated. This way the<br />

contradiction is ignored, a ‘neccessary’ connection or conflation is uncritically presumed,<br />

much the same way as homophobia and “Christ’s teachings” are uncritically accepted as belonging<br />

together under the umbrella <strong>of</strong> “Christian values.” While the contradiction is clear to<br />

a few <strong>of</strong> us, it is invisible to a large majority. Does this mean that the contradiction doesn’t<br />

exist?<br />

By some accounts, capitalism and democracy are completely diametrically antithetical.<br />

This brings up a very important set <strong>of</strong> questions;<br />

How can there be an inclusive participatory democracy in a system where money (material<br />

wealth, ownership <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production by an elite few) gets to determine what<br />

gets priority in political discussions and legislation? (By some accounts, some sort <strong>of</strong> rough<br />

economic equality within a particular range is the prerequisite for a healthy inclusive democracy).<br />

Into this discussion we might consider bringing such issues like media ownership and<br />

control as well as privileged access to the socio-economic infrastructure and financial institutions<br />

<strong>of</strong> a society. If some automatically get privileged access by being born into the right<br />

family, how democratic is this, really? (It is important to note that notions <strong>of</strong> freedom and<br />

equality co-evolved with slavery and racism. If you preach equality, yet some people in a<br />

particular category are discriminated against unfairly, you have to come up with something<br />

like racial/class/gender/religious/etc, ‘innate’ ’inferiority’ in order to explain why some folks<br />

are not as ‘equal’ as others.)<br />

People <strong>of</strong>ten presume that capitalism is a perfect system and then require that socialism<br />

(or any other alternative) be demonstrated as being ‘more perfect’ than capitalism, without<br />

having ever had the equal benefit <strong>of</strong> even trying it out! (If you think capitalism is perfect,<br />

consider that it has consistently failed to produce the things it promises....wealth, security,<br />

peace, and happiness for all...)<br />

I’ll save a critique <strong>of</strong> imagined notions <strong>of</strong> plausible perfection, while leaving the reader<br />

with this little tid-bit;<br />

“Man is the symbol-using (symbol-making, symbol-misusing) animal inventor <strong>of</strong> the<br />

negative (or moralized by the negative) separated from his natural condition by instruments<br />

<strong>of</strong> his own making goaded by the spirit <strong>of</strong> hierarchy (or moved by the sense <strong>of</strong> order) and<br />

rotten with perfection.” (Kenneth Burke, from “Language as Symbolic Action.”)<br />

“Religion is the opiate <strong>of</strong> the masses” (Marx? Engels? Maybe someone can provide me<br />

with this reference?)<br />

Message [135] referenced by [137]. Next Message by CousinIt is [149].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 367<br />

[137] Mitternacht: Myth <strong>of</strong> the rational voter. There have been some interesting emails<br />

going back and forth lately on politics so I figured that I would get in on the action. CousinIt<br />

[135] mentioned in a recent posting that a million or 400 million people can be wrong. This<br />

reminded me <strong>of</strong> an interview that I heard recently on NPR which related to the masses <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

being wrong when it comes to voting. An author and economist by the name <strong>of</strong> Bryan<br />

Kaplan was promoting his new book ‘The Myth <strong>of</strong> the Rational Voter - Why Democracies<br />

Choose Bad Policies’. I haven’t had a chance to read the book yet, but I’m quite intrigued<br />

by the argument that Mr. Caplan presents - most voters are uninformed and they continually<br />

elect politicians who seem to share (or pretend to share) the same irrational beliefs and<br />

biases, resulting in bad policies winning out over and over by popular demand. He says that<br />

he doesn’t fear that politicians won’t carry out the will <strong>of</strong> the people, instead he fears that<br />

they will. His arguments focus more on economic aspects, but translate well to a broader<br />

picture. Here’s a link to the interview if anyone is interested:<br />

http://www.npr.org/templates/story/story.php?storyId=18176724<br />

Going back to the topic <strong>of</strong> religion and politics - I think that we’d be surprised to find out<br />

where several so-called religious politicians beliefs really lie. Call me a cynic, but I believe<br />

that most politicians are insincere and make no qualms about publicly adopting beliefs and<br />

ideals contrary to their own to take advantage <strong>of</strong> commonly held beliefs <strong>of</strong> the masses, be<br />

they religious or otherwise.<br />

CousinIt - thanks to Wikipedia I was able to track down the reference for the Marx quote.<br />

The quote comes Marx’s ’Critique to Hegel’s Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Right’. Here’s the quote in its<br />

entire context (Hans may take exception to the translation):<br />

“Religion is, indeed, the self-consciousness and self-esteem <strong>of</strong> man who has either not<br />

yet won through to himself, or has already lost himself again. But man is no abstract being<br />

squatting outside the world. Man is the world <strong>of</strong> man—state, society. This state and this society<br />

produce religion, which is an inverted consciousness <strong>of</strong> the world, because they are an<br />

inverted world. Religion is the general theory <strong>of</strong> this world, its encyclopedic compendium,<br />

its logic in popular form, its spiritual point d’honneur, its enthusiasm, its moral sanction, its<br />

solemn complement, and its universal basis <strong>of</strong> consolation and justification. It is the fantastic<br />

realization <strong>of</strong> the human essence since the human essence has not acquired any true reality.<br />

The struggle against religion is, therefore, indirectly the struggle against that world whose<br />

spiritual aroma is religion.<br />

Religious suffering is, at one and the same time, the expression <strong>of</strong> real suffering and a<br />

protest against real suffering. Religion is the sigh <strong>of</strong> the oppressed creature, the heart <strong>of</strong> a<br />

heartless world, and the soul <strong>of</strong> soulless conditions. It is the opiate <strong>of</strong> the people.<br />

The abolition <strong>of</strong> religion as the illusory happiness <strong>of</strong> the people is the demand for their<br />

real happiness. To call on them to give up their illusions about their condition is to call on<br />

them to give up a condition that requires illusions. The criticism <strong>of</strong> religion is, therefore, in<br />

embryo, the criticism <strong>of</strong> that vale <strong>of</strong> tears <strong>of</strong> which religion is the halo.”<br />

Next Message by Mitternacht is [191].


368 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[138] Kevin: The things you learn from fast food. So I thought this was interesting.<br />

Yesterday we went to Chick-fil-A down and my fiancé got a kids meal. In the kids meal was<br />

a little American history flip chart. On the George Washington card it read:<br />

“During Washington’s administration, he put together the first presidential<br />

cabinet and set the groundwork for America’s early foreign policy by counseling<br />

that the nation should stay out <strong>of</strong> international affairs as much as<br />

possible.”<br />

I don’t know whether the statement is true or not, but it made me start to wonder how<br />

different things would be if we had followed this counsel. It would seem obvious to me that<br />

we wouldn’t be in Iraq or many <strong>of</strong> the other international conflict zones, but it makes me<br />

wonder whether or not that would have actually worked to our advantage. If we had always<br />

“stay[ed] out <strong>of</strong> international affairs” what kind <strong>of</strong> an economic position would we be in<br />

now? Is Washington’s counsel sound advice?<br />

Message [138] referenced by [140]. Next Message by Kevin is [238].<br />

[139] Alex: A proper understanding <strong>of</strong> the realities <strong>of</strong> separation and specialization <strong>of</strong><br />

labor require more than just an education can provide. To clarify I would like to share an<br />

example. A well educated friend <strong>of</strong> mine once stated “I don’t know why I need a college<br />

degree to do my job, it really is quite simple.” He went on to quip “I really believe that<br />

90% <strong>of</strong> the people can do 90% <strong>of</strong> the jobs.” He was not a Marxist and would certainly not<br />

admit to anything that sounded Marxist purposefully. Rather my friend had come to the sad<br />

realization that a job, no matter how tough, is usually not nearly as tough as the specialization<br />

process.<br />

A doctor may struggle with their first few years in the pr<strong>of</strong>ession. However, they eventually<br />

get their footing and usually only face new challanges as they step outside their knowledge<br />

level, something not required unless one chooses to do so. The point being, the more<br />

specialized we become the more we realize we probably did not need all the specialization.<br />

Granted, there are exceptions to every rule and some pr<strong>of</strong>essions genuinely require further<br />

specialization to push forward the realms <strong>of</strong> their respective fields.<br />

Hans [64] relays that computer s<strong>of</strong>tware has become a very interesting field to observe<br />

because <strong>of</strong> certain networks that prove more valuable than just one specialized laborer. When<br />

one laborer does all the work certain problems arise. First, one person does not have the<br />

creative genius as several people. Second, when one person is working on one project they<br />

take more time and are not as effective as several can be. Third, the specializing laborer loses<br />

out on what else he could be doing. By specializing, the laborer has limited his capacity and<br />

potential. If he can take part in many different projects the laborer can be far more effective.<br />

As labor becomes separated the production line becomes more effecient. Separation <strong>of</strong><br />

labor is not limited to the production line or factories. Separation <strong>of</strong> labor is apparent in<br />

government, white collar work, etc. I found in my first few “specialized” jobs that even<br />

though I had a degree I was still a cog in a machine. This was very difficult to handle. I<br />

wasn’t sure why my job required a degreee, and my work wasn’t more difficult than anyone<br />

elses. But the separation had many social and economic consequences. First, with my title I<br />

was given superiority over others. Second, I was paid more than those doing “trivial” jobs. I


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 369<br />

didn’t see how my having a degree made me any more qualified. I realized the separation <strong>of</strong><br />

labor was little more than a corporate way <strong>of</strong> keeping tabs on employees. Money and social<br />

ranking were there to make me believe my specialization was important. However, I quickly<br />

realized that these items were meant to keep me in place in the company.<br />

In specific situations a person could work for years to obtain a title such as “Vice-<br />

President” and gain some authority within the company. But the laborer loses out on the<br />

more important social and economic factors that come from shared labor. When all work<br />

together not only is more respect given to the laborer but a better product also emerges.<br />

Message [139] referenced by [157]. Next Message by Alex is [141].<br />

[140] Spawnblade: Where would we be without a interactive foreign policy? The<br />

subject was brought up in Kevin’s post regarding a simple comment via a kids meal history<br />

chart in [138] . He questioned where we would be if we had heeded Washington’s advice to<br />

keep to ourselves and stay out <strong>of</strong> foreign politics. This policy is referred to as Isolationism.<br />

We can be assured that if we were still isolationists, we would not be in Iraq right now.<br />

I believe the main question would be: Would Germany have won World War I? If not,<br />

what would the peace treaties have been like without America’s intervention at Versailles? In<br />

this respect, would the economically devastated countries <strong>of</strong> Europe, turned to Communism<br />

with our lack <strong>of</strong> foreign aid? If Germany lost the first war, would they have proceeded to lose<br />

the second as well, in which the turning point was America’s intervention? If not, would they<br />

have then developed the atomic bomb before us? Or would that be our only shield against<br />

impending invasion from both Germany/Europe, and Japan/Asia? Would communism even<br />

exist, with the extreme dislike the Nazis held for it?<br />

I believe we may have fought in a War against Japan, however without the aid we gave<br />

Great Britain, they may not have lasted that long, meaning the Soviets would have had the<br />

full war on their front subsequently. In these scenarios, how much <strong>of</strong> a difference did our<br />

foreign policy make? Has it preserved the world we desire and wish to see thrive? If we had<br />

followed Washington’s advice (Which in fact is advice he did clearly state. I’m surprised it<br />

was found in a happy meal. Hooray for fast food?) we may have been better <strong>of</strong>f for a time,<br />

but with the emerging/emerged global economy, could that truly have lasted?<br />

Taking these into account, I believe isolationism is not in a country’s best interests. Perhaps<br />

for a smaller country, or a different time period, it may be ideal. Washington never<br />

foresaw the colonies becoming the superpower. Otherwise I believe he may have seen a<br />

different responsibility entrusted to our government. We are protecting ourselves better than<br />

we could hope by intervening elsewhere, despite the harm we are bound to endure in the<br />

process.<br />

Interesting tidbit though, I like its application to both previous economic policies, as well<br />

as current. Not counting the military policies it entails. Thanks for bringing it up. :-)<br />

Message [140] referenced by [141]. Next Message by Spawnblade is [154].<br />

[157] Papageorgio: specialization? As I read Alex post [139] about specialization I<br />

found I disagreed or found some points to further look upon regarding specialization. As<br />

we look at someone who specializes in a certain subject, job, sport, etc. They are able<br />

to compete at a far higher level in most cases than someone who does not specialize but


370 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

tries to do all at once. Someone who specializes in making a certain commodity is able to<br />

make more <strong>of</strong> that commodity as we know from micro and macro econ classes, rather than<br />

someone who tries to make many commodities. Specialization can help us to focus on one<br />

task and become great at it, rather than medium in many. Some restrictions such as time,<br />

body type, genes, etc play a role in what we can do or have time for as well.<br />

In regard to jobs and specialization at times I wonder if it would benefit us if we lived<br />

in a society in which we were geared toward one thing, one subject, or placed in a school<br />

to get us ready for a job we will do. Instead <strong>of</strong> being able to choose anything, even things<br />

we know little about and not succeeding. So that we were taught what we would do for our<br />

living from a young age and by the time we left school we would know exactly how to do it<br />

and would be able to not really have a choice <strong>of</strong> what to do but be great at it and everyone<br />

would have there own role or job. This to us as Americans seems odd and freedom taking<br />

but can be a close reality to some communist countries.<br />

Next Message by Papageorgio is [179].<br />

[159] Paul: Social Medicine. After reading the other posts regarding Socialized Medicine<br />

I would like to <strong>of</strong>fer my opinion on the subject. I believe that the United States could benefit<br />

from providing some sort <strong>of</strong> socialized medicine. Some sources state that currently in the<br />

United States there are 45 million people without health insurance. By adopting socialized<br />

medicine all <strong>of</strong> these people would now be able to receive treatment. Another advantage<br />

would be that the price <strong>of</strong> medications would decrease immensely. This would make it<br />

much easier for people to afford the medications that they need. With socialized medicine<br />

people are more likely to go and get regular check ups and therefore make it easier to catch<br />

illnesses before they get worse. It is easier and much cheaper to treat most illnesses in the<br />

early stages so this would help cut the cost overall. Countries with social medicine that <strong>of</strong>fer<br />

universal health care are likely to spend less on countries which do not. Another economic<br />

benefit can be found in the fact that if the nation as a whole is healthier they are bound to be<br />

more productive.<br />

Message [159] referenced by [162]. Next Message by Paul is [186].<br />

[162] Inter: Social Medicine. The most important aspect about establishing a form <strong>of</strong><br />

socialized medicine is the possible impact it can have on the class gap in America. The<br />

fact that 45 million people (as referenced in [159] by Paul) do not have coverage can coexist<br />

with the many who have optional surgeries, illustrates the class antagonism quite well.<br />

By providing coverage for all, even at the expense <strong>of</strong> a higher tax, the distribution <strong>of</strong> resource/choice<br />

becomes more equitable. The importance <strong>of</strong> reducing the class gap is a matter<br />

<strong>of</strong> importance to the nation, after all this country operates because <strong>of</strong> the middle class.<br />

Next Message by Inter is [270].<br />

[163] Averil: Social Medicine. After reading the other posts centering around Socialized<br />

Medicine I would like to comment on the topic. Socialized medicine is a rather important<br />

topic, especially in light <strong>of</strong> the upcoming Presidential election and the subsequent promises<br />

made. The tried and tested argument against socialized medicine is that <strong>of</strong> poorer care.<br />

Those who argue for free market medicine assert that competition is an essential factor that<br />

increases the quality <strong>of</strong> care, America has better doctors and better health care because we<br />

don’t have socialized medicine. If this holds true, socialized medicine becomes a case expensive<br />

but superior health care for those who can afford it against lesser quality health care


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 371<br />

for all. When viewed through this lens, morality <strong>of</strong>ten comes into play. John Stuart Mill<br />

believed in the greatest good for the greatest amount <strong>of</strong> people, and would thusly be in support<br />

<strong>of</strong> socialized medicine. When viewed in purely economic terms, the equation becomes<br />

slightly trickier. I agree with Paul in saying that socialized care would decrease the overall<br />

costs for care and medicine alike. This might lead to some unforeseen consequences; drug<br />

companies make much <strong>of</strong> their pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> patents <strong>of</strong> their drugs and there is a good chance<br />

their pr<strong>of</strong>its would be reduced. If costs <strong>of</strong> medicine were reduced due to socialized medicine<br />

there is a chance that the pr<strong>of</strong>it the company once gleaned would be cut, this might lead to<br />

decreased incentive to do new research on new drugs. However, it is entirely conceivable<br />

that the federal government might make up for these reduced pr<strong>of</strong>its with subsidies to the<br />

drug companies. Unfortunately, this would just increase the cost <strong>of</strong> socialized medicine in<br />

general to the government and subsequently put a strain on the economy.<br />

Next Message by Averil is [167].<br />

[178] Scott: Free money! President Bush recently said,“When you’ve got more money<br />

in your pockets to save, spend or invest, this causes the economy to grow,” There is a new<br />

congressional bill that if passed will put up to $600 dollars into the pockets <strong>of</strong> every tax<br />

paying citizen. Is this the answer America is looking for to solve our economic problems? I<br />

say yes. I agree with President Bush, that by giving this money tax payers it will immediatley<br />

boost the economy. I am already thinking <strong>of</strong> things Im going to buy with the money, and Im<br />

positive all Americans will feel great spending $600 from congress.<br />

Message [178] referenced by [180] and [198]. Next Message by Scott is [229].<br />

[180] Papageorgio: Straight to the bank. Scott [178] talks about the recent tax rebate<br />

that most Americans will be receiveing and says that this is the answer to save the economy.<br />

Hardly. The economy needs a lot more than this quick fix to be saved. Although this quick fix<br />

is something I will enjoy to receive it is only something for the short term. Many economist<br />

argue that this money will go straight to Americans savings account which will do nothing<br />

to save the ailing economy. Last time this happened most <strong>of</strong> the money went to the auto<br />

industry who <strong>of</strong>fered zero percent financing. But who knows it can help a little but we<br />

definitely still need a lot to fix our economy.<br />

Message [180] referenced by [183] and [212]. Next Message by Papageorgio is [324].<br />

[183] Slash: Re: straight to the bank. In response to [180], spending is the most<br />

important part in the conversation <strong>of</strong> economic stimulation. When the government want to<br />

get money into the the economy they give it to the middle and lower class, because it will be<br />

spent instantly. When money is given to the rich they save it, this money is not put into the<br />

economy to by commodities and be taxed.<br />

Message [183] referenced by [185] and [196]. Next Message by Slash is [359].<br />

[185] Goethe: Re: straight to the bank. I would like to comment on the entry by slash<br />

[183]... what do you think is the true intention <strong>of</strong> this “economic stimulus” ?<br />

Think about it; where is this money coming from? Who will pay it back? And who will<br />

go without so the middleclass and low income can have a shopping spree?<br />

This is another example <strong>of</strong> the downward spiral we are caught up in; the people who will<br />

get these moneys are the people that will suffer in the long run.<br />

The mentality <strong>of</strong> big business and capitalist government is to keep the people happy!!!


372 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

“Here people go spend some money, and don’t save it, go out and have a good time!!”<br />

I would like to know who is in charge here.... It makes no sense??<br />

Message [185] referenced by [196]. Next Message by Goethe is [278].<br />

[189] Paul: Short fix. With regards to the other posts on the event <strong>of</strong> the government<br />

giving the citizens money I want to say that it will most likely make a slight increase in the<br />

economy but it won’t last long. This seems like a desperate move made by the white house<br />

to try and fix what they have done to the economy over the last 8 years. And its probably<br />

not even going to benefit the people who receive it that much. How many people are going<br />

to get loans or lease something that they really can’t afford with this “free money.”<br />

Message [189] referenced by [196], [201], and [212]. Next Message by Paul is [307].<br />

[192] Chris: OUR money. I just wanted to lend my opinion on the economic stimulus<br />

package while we are discussing it. The money we are getting back is our money that the<br />

government took from our paychecks to begin with. They are giving us a small portion<br />

<strong>of</strong> our taxes back. It is not “free money” it is “our money.” History shows that economic<br />

stimulus packages like this do little to help the economy. Where I work, as a financial<br />

analyst, there has been great debate over the stimulus package and if a recession can be<br />

“healthy” for an economy. The feds decision to slash rates does not appear to be working.<br />

The best solution appears to be to let the economy go into a recession and let the system<br />

correct itself. Recessions have occurred on average, every 4 years in America. The last<br />

recession happened about 6 - 7 years ago. It seems almost natural to let it happen instead <strong>of</strong><br />

consistently weakening the dollar and increasing inflation at this abnormal rate.<br />

Message [192] referenced by [196]. Next Message by Chris is [197].<br />

[196] Mitternacht: More government irresponsibility. I would actually prefer that the<br />

government keep the money from the proposed economic stimulus package if I could be<br />

assured that it would be used for social programs and to reduce the national debt. Currently<br />

the European economy as a whole is doing just as well if not better than the current<br />

US economy even though most European countries have a much higher tax rate than the<br />

US. The difference is that a lot <strong>of</strong> the taxes collected in Europe go towards strong social<br />

programs. Unfortunately the economic stimulus plan seems to be another in a long line <strong>of</strong><br />

irresponsible actions taken by the US government, and I for one do not trust the government<br />

to act responsibly. Billions <strong>of</strong> dollars have been spent on unjust wars and space exploration<br />

while 12% <strong>of</strong> the US population lives below the federal defined poverty level. Paul [189],<br />

Goethe [185] and Slash [183] all point out that the money received from the stimulus will<br />

most likely be spent quickly. It’s no surprise that US citizens are following the example<br />

<strong>of</strong> their government which has been spending irresponsibly for years (especially over the<br />

last 8 years). The economic stimulus may actually help out the economy in the short run,<br />

but wouldn’t it be nice if someone made a case for being financially responsible instead <strong>of</strong><br />

encouraging increased consumption <strong>of</strong> goods?<br />

I also feel compelled to respond to Chris’ [192] statement the “best solution appears to<br />

be to let the economy go into a recession and let the system correct itself”. This same hands<br />

<strong>of</strong>f approach <strong>of</strong> letting the economy correct itself was taken by economists prior to the Great<br />

Depression <strong>of</strong> the 1930’s, and obviously that didn’t turn out too well.<br />

Message [196] referenced by [197], [206], and [207]. Next Message by Mitternacht is [223].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 373<br />

[197] Chris: economic stability. I do not feel that the Great Depression was a complete<br />

representation <strong>of</strong> economists’ “hands <strong>of</strong>f approach” as Mitternacht suggested towards the<br />

end <strong>of</strong> his column [196]. I also do not think that making broad generalizations when dealing<br />

with The Great Depression in reference to our current economic state is anywhere close<br />

to accurate. The Great Depression was the result <strong>of</strong> numerous policy actions taken across<br />

the entire world. The World’s economic output declined drastically and we saw an almost<br />

600% increase in the stock market for 8 years prior to the Great Depression. There were no<br />

boundaries set in stone in monitoring the markets (this was a definite hand’s <strong>of</strong>f approach)<br />

and shareholders were making a killing in unrealized gains. As a result <strong>of</strong> this, shareholders<br />

were wildly speculating. When the Great Depression hit, many nations responded with trade<br />

barriers, which hurt job growth, etc.<br />

Maybe I should not have said the economy should utilize a “hands <strong>of</strong>f approach.” I DO<br />

think a recession at this time is inevitable. I also think the Fed’s drastic interest rate cuts are<br />

over zealous. I also feel that if given the opportunity, I could utilize my tax paying dollars<br />

better then the government can to benefit my personal well-being, those around me, and the<br />

economy as a whole.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [226].<br />

[198] PrivateProperty: Re: Free money! Hahaha, [178] was a good one. I always enjoy<br />

a healthy dose <strong>of</strong> humor on the discussion board.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [200].<br />

[201] PrivateProperty: Re: Short fix. In response to [189]: The economy would be<br />

stimulated the most if this money was primarily targeted towards the lower class. They have<br />

a higher marginal propensity to consume, thus most <strong>of</strong> every dollar would be spent rather<br />

than saved. If the government wants to promote saving and investment, leading to long-term<br />

growth, then it should do just the opposite and give the money to the upper class.<br />

I’d like to say something, that nothing in this world is free. In any payout by the government,<br />

you are either taking resources away from others, or others are taking resources away<br />

from you.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [202].<br />

[202] PrivateProperty: Unpredictability <strong>of</strong> markets. Hans said in [190]:<br />

“By their efforts to master the market, they do what capital needs them to do in order<br />

to grow. As I said in [156], the economic agents are the marionettes carrying out what the<br />

system needs them to do.”<br />

If this is the case, how do we go about having the market as a natural outgrowth <strong>of</strong><br />

human activity, and not the other way around? It seems like an endless feedback loop. Can<br />

dissenting indviduals do alright within the system, or does the entire system need to change?<br />

Also, on a different note, I noticed you (Hans) mentioned on your website that the US is<br />

attempting to militarize outer space. Could you tell me more about this? Are you referring<br />

to the Star Wars ‘missile defense’ plans?<br />

It would greatly upset me if outerspace were to be privatized in any way.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [209].


374 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[206] FacistFrank: Re: More government irresponsibility. I agree with Mitternacht<br />

[196] for the most part, except I just felt I had to get his information out there. The Federal<br />

government spends less than 0.5% (I believe it’s somewere between 0.2 and 0.3%) <strong>of</strong> its<br />

annual budget on NASA, during the Kennedy, Johnson years it reached its height between<br />

0.6 and 0.7%. We spend very little on space exploration, that’s not even 1% <strong>of</strong> annual govt.<br />

money. In fact if we spent more maybe 0.45, we could help to innovate in new technologies,<br />

that may actually end up helping us solve global warming, one famous invention was velcro,<br />

another is solar panel innovation, that came from NASA. I also think it could show Americans<br />

and the world that they could hope again, that we still can achieve great things. I think<br />

it could revive interest in intellectualism and the sciences, and take our minds <strong>of</strong>f greed for a<br />

moment. I also think that going to Mars and beyond could help all <strong>of</strong> humanity move closer<br />

to feeling as one, as we are reminded again just how small and fragile the earth is. I think<br />

NASA is a solid investment in the future <strong>of</strong> humanity that is sadly being ignored. Of course<br />

money is needed for other things, so i’d like to see a modest increase to 0.5%, we spend to<br />

much money dividing the world and killing people, lets spend a little more to try to unite it.<br />

Next Message by FacistFrank is [264].<br />

[207] Bar: Re: More government irresponsibility. Mitternacht [196] says a few things<br />

that I would like to discuss and refute: he says, he “would actually prefer that the government<br />

keep the money from the proposed economic stimulus package if I could be assured that it<br />

would be used for social programs and to reduce the national debt.” Now i would love to<br />

see how increasing social programs is going to reduce debt, higher taxes for more social<br />

programs or in other words, more spending is going to reduce debt, hmmm and sometimes<br />

2+2 equals 5.<br />

What taxes do, is lower the growth in the economy not to mention crowd out consumers<br />

<strong>of</strong> certain markets. The Keynesian (I hope I spelled that right) approach didn’t really get us<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the great depression either, supposedly government spending is suppose to increase<br />

the aggregate demand, hmmm well why didn’t we get out <strong>of</strong> the depression with all those<br />

alphabet soup programs, income taxes, and government employment, until the increased<br />

production <strong>of</strong> world war 2, I guess more than 10 years is relatively short.<br />

When he says, “Unfortunately the economic stimulus plan seems to be another in a long<br />

line <strong>of</strong> irresponsible actions taken by the US government, and I for one do not trust the<br />

government to act responsibly.” Why have more social programs then? are u a masacist?<br />

the fact <strong>of</strong> the matter is that those horrible, oppressive, racist George Bush tax cuts back in<br />

2002ish for the rich, got us out <strong>of</strong> a horrible post 911 recesion caused by, 911 and Enron.<br />

This stimulas is probably not big enough, but at least it’s something. Also the best thing to<br />

fix the defecit is to cut taxes, which will let the economy grow faster, bringing in more money<br />

then any tax increase ever would and spite all those income redistribution social programs.<br />

unemployment rates in US 2008: 4.9<br />

Other European countries:UK: 5.4<br />

Spain: 8.1<br />

France: 8.1<br />

Spain: 8


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 375<br />

Not to mention the average over the years is a lot higher than the US. Now if the EU<br />

spends more money on social programs, why is there higher unemployment? And the US<br />

average GDP growth is also slightly higher than EU.<br />

Next Message by Bar is [267].<br />

[212] Rey: Cash falling from the sky! In light <strong>of</strong> the popular discussion regarding the<br />

economic stimulus package I agree with much <strong>of</strong> what has already been said. In expressing<br />

my opinion I will use the words <strong>of</strong> Republican Senator Judd Gregg, “The rebate proposal,<br />

which amounts to flying a plane full <strong>of</strong> cash over the country toward the end <strong>of</strong> the year,<br />

will force us to charge at least 200 billion dollars to the federal credit card, and there is<br />

no guarantee it will actually work. . . A better approach would be to take the targeted steps<br />

that will stimulate the economy through job creation and economic investment.” As seems<br />

to be the popular conclusion, and has been stated directly in posts [180] and [189], I feel<br />

the stimulus is a short-term solution to a long-term problem. By putting another 500-600<br />

dollars in each individuals pocket will do next to nothing, long term for the economy. Yes<br />

maybe we will pick up that sweet pair <strong>of</strong> jeans or that new iPod we have been eyeing, but<br />

really what does that do to keep our economy stable long term. More appropriately I would<br />

like to see a bigger investment into small businesses and entrepreneurial entities. Granted<br />

this would take a little more time and research, and we are all aware we are working against<br />

the clock here. However I feel it would be worth risk and effort. Over the past year I have<br />

come in contact with several young, ambitious individuals who are looking for a way to raise<br />

capital for innovative start up businesses. It is among my biggest frustrations to see these<br />

ideas suppressed and lost due to the inability to find capital. In my own efforts I spent three<br />

to five months working with government insured programs only to be jerked around and<br />

denied in the end. I fortunately had a network with deep enough pockets to see my visions<br />

and goals get <strong>of</strong>f the ground, but again I know many who haven’t had the same stroke <strong>of</strong><br />

luck. If the government were to free up more funds for start-ups, who will be sure stimulate<br />

the economy through job production and the production <strong>of</strong> goods, we would at least begin<br />

the process <strong>of</strong> a long term solution.<br />

Next Message by Rey is [265].<br />

[217] Jenn: What came first, the demand or the commodity? My early and minimal<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> Marx believes the economy all begins with a commodity; or at least this is<br />

how he begins its analysis in Das Kapital. However, if there is no demand for a commodity,<br />

wouldn’t there be no commodity? Doesn’t it make sense to look at the economy from a<br />

demand standpoint rather than the commodity? Aside from the basic “we buy lots <strong>of</strong> things<br />

we don’t need” argument, I would love to hear some <strong>of</strong> your opinons on this “chicken or the<br />

egg” type thought.<br />

Message [217] referenced by [221], [222], [223], and [227]. Next Message by Jenn is [300].<br />

[221] PrivateProperty: Re: What came first, the demand or the commodity? Jenn<br />

makes an interesting point in [217] that if there was no demand for a commodity, the commodity<br />

would cease to exist because nobody would produce it. However, this assumes that<br />

this particular commodity already exists and is in production.<br />

Economic theory measures demand ‘a posteriori’, by analyzing the data from transactions<br />

after they have occurred.


376 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

However, looking at the concept <strong>of</strong> demand in a different way, it is possible for demand<br />

to predate the existence <strong>of</strong> the commodity. It is the demand for a particular use value that<br />

brings about a commodity that provides it. For example, if your hands are cold in winter,<br />

you will want them to be warm. You can go indoors, put your hands over a fire, a variety<br />

<strong>of</strong> things. What you care about is your hands being warm, which these activities provide.<br />

Gloves, which are commodities, were invented because they satisfy this particular use value<br />

(demand or need).<br />

So in this sense you are correct, if the demand for a use value doesn’t exist (or if the use<br />

value itself doesn’t exist) then obviously no commodity will be created in order to satisfy it.<br />

That goes without saying.<br />

Message [221] referenced by [227] and [234]. Next Message by PrivateProperty is [248].<br />

[222] Aaron: RE: What came first, the demand or the commodity? Jenn raised an<br />

interesting question in [217]. I believe that the demand for a commodity must have come<br />

first. In a society, it does not seem logical that a person would just randomly come up with a<br />

commodity and try to pr<strong>of</strong>it from it without having a demand for it in the first place. Human<br />

ingenuity tells me that as a pr<strong>of</strong>it hungry species, humans will try to maximize the desire<br />

<strong>of</strong> other humans to want an object. Not the other way around. A fisherman in a primitive<br />

society would not have a job if there was not a demand for the fish in the first place. A<br />

commodity becomes a commodity because people want it, whether it be time, money, or a<br />

tradable good.<br />

Next Message by Aaron is [410].<br />

[223] Mitternacht: Chicken/Egg. Jenn [217] I believe that Marx wasn’t necessarily<br />

saying that the commodity came chronologically before demand or anything else. His point<br />

seems to be that the commodity is the most logical starting point for examining capitalist<br />

economy/society.<br />

The question that you posed has me scratching my head a bit though ... if there were no<br />

commodity, there could be no demand for it vs. if there were no demand for a commodity<br />

why would the commodity exist?<br />

Next Message by Mitternacht is [371].<br />

[227] CousinIt: Commodity and demand. Jenn in [217] asks, “...if there is no demand<br />

for a commodity, wouldn’t there be no commodity? Doesn’t it make sense to look at the<br />

economy from a demand standpoint rather than (from the) commodity (standpoint)?...”<br />

First <strong>of</strong> all, I think it might be useful not to confuse things-made-by-humans as use-values<br />

and things-made-by-humans with the intention <strong>of</strong> putting them up for sale (the appearance<br />

<strong>of</strong> commodity) for the explicit purpose <strong>of</strong> acquiring more <strong>of</strong> the generalized commodity (or,<br />

in other words, for money...capital).<br />

I think this is what PrivateProperty [221] is getting at in his response to Jenn in saying:<br />

“it is possible for demand to predate the existence <strong>of</strong> the commodity. It is<br />

the demand for a particular use value that brings about a commodity that<br />

provides it. For example, if your hands are cold in winter, you will want<br />

them to be warm. You can go indoors, put your hands over a fire, a variety<br />

<strong>of</strong> things. What you care about is your hands being warm, which these


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 377<br />

activities provide. Gloves, which are commodities, were invented because<br />

they satisfy this particular use value (demand or need).”<br />

While it might be obvious to some <strong>of</strong> us, I do think that we need to make an important<br />

distinction (to extend what is said here) between a thing-as-commodity and a thing-as-usevalue<br />

(which PrivateProperty begins to do in the first part <strong>of</strong> this paragraph). I would contend<br />

that use-values pre-exist commodities.<br />

In the case <strong>of</strong> producing a use-value, one is making something useful for oneself, family,<br />

extended family, friends, or the chance acquaintance or stranger that one might happen upon<br />

who has similar needs. In such cases (before a thing-as-use-value is transformed into a<br />

thing-as-commodity) one would either give the thing away, show the others how to make<br />

it for themselves, or trade it for something that serves as equivalent-though-different use<br />

values for himself. The basic unit <strong>of</strong> social interaction is the actual relationship between the<br />

actual human participants.<br />

This is vastly different than making multiple copies <strong>of</strong> a particular thing with the intention<br />

<strong>of</strong> getting more out <strong>of</strong> them than you put into them (in terms <strong>of</strong> exchangable labor<br />

power imbedded in the product). Through the emergence <strong>of</strong> the commodity as the basic<br />

unit <strong>of</strong> social interaction, as that through which social relationships are mediated on a large<br />

impersonal scale, through the flow <strong>of</strong> commodities <strong>of</strong> which extraction and accumulation <strong>of</strong><br />

exploited labor power is the main purpose, society as a whole is pathologically socially ill.<br />

Yet, the diseased condition is taken as ‘natural’ and ‘normal’ due to the fetish-like character<br />

<strong>of</strong> the commodity that gives it seeming supranatural power over all, including the capitalist<br />

(exploiter and owner <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong> production).<br />

Getting back to Jenn’s original question, this begs another question. Beginning either<br />

from the commodity or from the standpoint <strong>of</strong> demand, what we might want to know is the<br />

purpose for which we are analysing the economy. If we want to know how to better exploit<br />

labor and natural resources for the sake <strong>of</strong> increasing pr<strong>of</strong>its for the owners <strong>of</strong> the means <strong>of</strong><br />

production (i.e., our ‘masters’) and thus continuing the exploitation <strong>of</strong> producers, then we<br />

might want to start from the simplistic and narrow standpoint <strong>of</strong> supply and demand which<br />

effectively obscures the facts <strong>of</strong> social production and is concerned only with a particular<br />

selectively ignorant notion <strong>of</strong> what counts as ‘efficiency’ or as ‘efficacy.’<br />

However, if we want to, by way <strong>of</strong> social scientific analysis, understand the nature <strong>of</strong><br />

the social pathology that is capitalism, its diagnosis, prognosis, and possible cures, then we<br />

must, as Marx does, start with the basic communicative medium <strong>of</strong> exchange, transport, and<br />

transmission <strong>of</strong> elemental pathogenic relations....i.e., the commodity...<br />

Next Message by CousinIt is [263].<br />

[234] Clayon: Re: What came first, the demand or the commodity? I agree with what<br />

PrivateProperty says in the third paragraph <strong>of</strong> [221]. Ultimately I believe there must be a<br />

demand for a commodity for it to be produced. A certain phrase comes to mind, necessity<br />

is the mother <strong>of</strong> inovation. Someone earlier gave an example <strong>of</strong> a hand being cold, which<br />

created the demand to create something to warm it. I believe this makes the most logical and<br />

simple sense.<br />

Next Message by Clayon is [381].


378 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[235] Ryoung: Most Experienced to Help Out Our Economy. The primaries this year<br />

have been very interesting to me. It has been a very tight race and up until Super Tuesday it<br />

looked like the Democratic and GOP races could be neck and neck all the way to the end.<br />

With Romney dropping out it looks like McCain is going to be the representative from the<br />

GOP side and it looks like the Democratic nomination will go right down to the wire. It has<br />

also been a unique election due to a woman, a black man, and a member <strong>of</strong> the LDS church<br />

(before Romney withdrew) all having a legitimate shot to win the <strong>of</strong>fice. I had always been<br />

leaning toward Romney as I believe that he has the experience and ability to help out our<br />

economy the most efficiently. Obviously he is gone and I wanted to post the question to<br />

everyone, who is most qualified to help our economy as president, and who is most likely to<br />

help our economy the most as president? Right now I seem to be leaning towards Obama.<br />

Message [235] referenced by [242]. Next Message by Ryoung is [255].<br />

[242] Brody: RE: Most Experienced to Help Out Our Economy. In response to [235],<br />

Obama is the clear choice here. He brings intelligence and a new sense <strong>of</strong> responsibility to<br />

the Democratic party. I have nothing really against Hillary other than she may have more<br />

than a few screws loose. She has stated many times that she feels she can take money by<br />

increasing taxes for large businesses but I don’t see that as helpful to the economy in any<br />

way because if a company’s taxes rise its prices rise and we are left paying more for goods<br />

and buying less. This to me is completely counteractive to the new economic stimulus plan<br />

that has finally been agreed on.<br />

Next Message by Brody is [344].<br />

[248] PrivateProperty: Re: Most Experienced to Help Out Our Economy. Though<br />

he doesn’t stand a chance <strong>of</strong> winning, Ron Paul (Republican) would do the most for the<br />

economy. He would pull all personnel out <strong>of</strong> Iraq, North Korea, and Europe (huge expenditures<br />

all around) and abolish several costly and unnecessary institutions, namely Homeland<br />

Security, the Department <strong>of</strong> Education, and the Federal Income tax. Less government, in a<br />

nutshell. All <strong>of</strong> these savings would significantly improve the economy.<br />

From the available selection, however, I think our best bet is Obama.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [321].<br />

[249] Dentist: presidential race. I think that this election the “best qualified candidate”<br />

depends on what exactly you are looking to change or have accomplished during the next<br />

presidential term. The following is what I have concluded from the candidates that have<br />

been brought up thus far.<br />

In terms <strong>of</strong> low risk, long run economic growth I think Romney would have made a great<br />

candidate, mostly due to his effects in, and knowledge <strong>of</strong> the private economic sector.<br />

Ron Paul’s drastic reduction in the overall size and therefore spending in government<br />

would theoretically produce new avenues for private sector growth; and his foreign policy<br />

would keep more <strong>of</strong> what the government still spends in our own economy. Both <strong>of</strong> which<br />

are good, again in theory; but I worry that such sudden drastic measures would cause firms<br />

and investment to decline because there is no way they can be sure that the markets will<br />

remain stable while these changes are being incorporated into our system. This would likely<br />

result in a recessionary period before long run benefits began to be realized. So while he


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 379<br />

does have some good long run ideas, the economy may be quite turbulent for a while. But I<br />

guess “drastic times calling for drastic measures” is the idea.<br />

Obama seems to be a good candidate if you are looking for something new in government,<br />

which many people are. He does have a fresh appeal and seems to have been dubbed the<br />

candidate for a new generation. This appeal could result in some actual change, but I think<br />

the greater impact would be in the potential he might have to restore confidence <strong>of</strong> the people<br />

in their government. The main problem I have with Obama is that I don’t know any specifics<br />

<strong>of</strong> his ideas. For that matter, I don’t know anyone who is really aware <strong>of</strong> exactly what he<br />

wants to do or how he wants to do it. So if anyone knows, I would be interested to hear. . .<br />

Next Message by Dentist is [289].<br />

[250] Bmellor: Communism in China does it work? China has a history that dates back<br />

at least 4000 years. Their Nation prior to communism was ruled by an emperor the last <strong>of</strong><br />

which was Puyi. The Chinese people lived for the emperor, grown men would bow and overt<br />

their eyes when he would approach them. I was recently in China, I visited the “Forbidden<br />

City” which is now a museum owned by the Chinese government. It was forbidden because<br />

only the emperor was allowed in some parts <strong>of</strong> the compound and in some rooms. People<br />

could be put to death for using the wrong door or gates in some parts <strong>of</strong> the compound. His<br />

home was 9,999 rooms, one less room than the Gods home had, and meanwhile people were<br />

dying in the streets <strong>of</strong> starvation. No one in the entire nation was allowed to wear yellow<br />

articles <strong>of</strong> clothing except for the emperor. And if you are going to make duck for dinner<br />

you had not better make “Peking Duck” because that was a dish reserved for the emperor,<br />

violation <strong>of</strong> which was punishable by death. The emperor would make outrageous requests<br />

<strong>of</strong> his people and they would follow. For example in the city <strong>of</strong> Suzhou there is a canal that<br />

spans almost 2000 km long it was built so that the emperor could take a cruise on his man<br />

powered boat, in the end it proved to beneficial for the city as means <strong>of</strong> transporting goods,<br />

but that was never it’s intent.<br />

The Chinese people are now allowed to visit the Forbidden City, tourists cross the mote<br />

and in through the main gates under a massive portrait <strong>of</strong> Mao Zedong (the first communist<br />

leader <strong>of</strong> China) reminding them that this visit was made possible by communism. I was<br />

taken back by the portrait when I stood there in Tiananmen Square, when I considered the<br />

hundreds <strong>of</strong> peaceful Chinese protesters were slaughtered right in that very square for opposing<br />

corruption in the government that Mao organized. It was an odd experince no mention<br />

<strong>of</strong> that Massacre in 1989 was ever made by our guide while we stood in that square, and<br />

certainly not by me. There are security cameras, police, and military men every 100 feet or<br />

so on that square, some Chinese don’t even know the massacre ever took place. But when<br />

I got past the square and into the “Forbidden City” I finally felt like maybe I understood<br />

why they accepted the oppressive government that they have. It was the lesser <strong>of</strong> two evils.<br />

These people wanted to “share” what the emperor had and communism made that somewhat<br />

possible. Mao asked the people to share what they felt about communism and when people<br />

did, he didn’t like it. The people who opposed him in the end were killed. This is the same<br />

government that they have today however they have had to adapt. China must be the busiest<br />

place on earth. In Shanghai where crowed streets were once filled with bikes, they are now<br />

crowed with SUV’s and brand new cars. The “developing nation” is nearly developed or already<br />

developed. The Chinese people have cell phones they communicate freely, they have


380 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

a monitored version <strong>of</strong> the internet, and they travel the world with moderate difficulty. The<br />

government that they have has become itself capitalistic. In recent years the chairman <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Chinese government has been quoted saying “to be rich is glorious.” This is not the China<br />

that Mao would have approved <strong>of</strong>. China in its present state <strong>of</strong> “hazy regulation” is working<br />

out just fine, but what happens when their trade surplus runs out? When the economic<br />

dime turns and they are no longer the powerhouse, what will happen then? The Chinese will<br />

grow accustomed to the lax form <strong>of</strong> government and will express displeasure with the government<br />

just like everyon in a democratic country going though economic hardship. What<br />

then? Will the Chinese government be tolerant <strong>of</strong> a free democratic opinion then? It is all<br />

fine and dandy when people are pleased with the government but communism in China has<br />

be historically ugly when people express anger or suggest change to the government.<br />

Their government operates extremely efficiently because information is asymmetrical.<br />

There is no transparency. You pay taxes, but there is little you can understand <strong>of</strong> how it is<br />

spent, or most importantly object to how it is spent. 55 men with one chairman make up the<br />

leadership <strong>of</strong> the government in China that is what separates them from having a militant<br />

dictator like North Korea. But who knows if or when their government will have such<br />

a leader again. For Americans Investments in China are considered extremely pr<strong>of</strong>itable<br />

however they are also extremely risky. You could be shut down tomorrow if the Chinese<br />

government desires it and there isn’t a thing you can do about it. Maybe you aren’t shut<br />

down but they declare that your company now belongs to “the nation.” At one time this<br />

was very common, I went to a silk factory once owned by Japanese and because <strong>of</strong> its<br />

success it was sequestered by the Chinese government. Where is the incentive to become<br />

an entrepreneur in China? Up until recently there has been very little incentive. In the late<br />

1990’s the Chinese government set up “free trade Zones” in certain areas, and recently that<br />

spread too many <strong>of</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> the country. People own shops and stores in hopes that the policy<br />

doesn’t change back to the way it once was.<br />

An interesting fact I noted things are cheap in China but if the same good <strong>of</strong> same quality<br />

was sold in a Chinese store and was made in North Korea or Vietnam it was even cheaper.<br />

The things you purchase in China are not necessarily “made in China.” That got me thinking;<br />

everything we buy from China is marked“ made in China.” But what if it’s not really made<br />

in China, what if it is made in North Korea but marked “made in China?” How would you<br />

know? You don’t and if you leave it to the Chinese government you will not know, when<br />

you buy a pair <strong>of</strong> shoes you could be funding the North Korean government. After this last<br />

summer’s fiasco with Kim Jong IL We should all be asking ourselves if that is something we<br />

really want to be doing? We could assume that the internet and the globalization <strong>of</strong> markets<br />

is going to make it very difficult for China to operate under a shroud <strong>of</strong> mystery but perhaps<br />

it will facilitate their ability to hide things from the rest <strong>of</strong> the world.<br />

Next Message by Bmellor is [282].<br />

[261] Dyoung: I also feel that Obama is the better choice for the democratic party. I think<br />

Obama sincerely wants to bring America to what it once was. He understands how people<br />

feel. He has worked with people to makes their lives better and he has gone to Washington<br />

to try to make a difference. He is criticized for lacking experience but I would ask what<br />

those who claim to have so much experience have done to keep us out <strong>of</strong> the problems<br />

poor government management has created? He has had experience on the street, in the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 381<br />

communities, and with groups <strong>of</strong> people who need help and he has done well with it. While<br />

others were sitting in Washington passing bills they had no idea what they were for he was<br />

helping people.<br />

I don’t really like Hillary Clinton just as Brody stated “she feels she can take money by<br />

increasing taxes for large businesses,” I don’t think this plan seems helpful at all for the<br />

economy, Like Brody I think that is will cause an increase in goods and consumers will end<br />

up buying less.<br />

Obama is my choice for the democratic party.<br />

Next Message by Dyoung is [279].<br />

[263] CousinIt: President Schmesident. I’m reading various people reproducing the<br />

campaign slogans and dissentary cliches auto-dribbling from the mouths <strong>of</strong> the candidates<br />

and I am moved to throw my pennies into the p*ss pot....<br />

The way I see it, none <strong>of</strong> the candidates are intending to, nor can they, really change<br />

anything in any significant way. After the election, things will be back to business-as-usual<br />

just as they always are. Republicrats and Democretins are just two legs <strong>of</strong> the capitalist<br />

oligomonocracy that masquerades as a two-party system (as if a two-party system is such a<br />

great expression <strong>of</strong> democracy, anyway...no tie-breaker...). Both Republicrats and Democretins<br />

all golf at the same country club where most <strong>of</strong> us can’t even use the restroom facilities.<br />

The late Bill Hicks used to tell a joke in which the story goes that when someone is<br />

newly-elected president, he is led into a dark cigarsmoke-filled screening room where the<br />

ten or so wealthiest industrialists are gathered. They roll a copy <strong>of</strong> the Zapruder film <strong>of</strong> the<br />

JFK assassination from an angle no one has ever seen before. The lights come on and the<br />

new president is asked, “Any questions?”<br />

John Edwards was the only candidate that said anything remotely proximal to what really<br />

needs to happen in America ...and the world. That is, we need to take our government back<br />

from the capitalists and start doing what is right for people and the environment, not what<br />

corporations want us to do. Of course, most people probably think that what is right for<br />

corporations is right for people because what is right for corporations is right for people because....<br />

Because <strong>of</strong> the indoctrination that they have swallowed hook-line-and-sinker, they<br />

probably can’t tell the difference between good and bad whenever there’s money around<br />

stinking up the room. It gets them all giddy and stupefied and patriotic and all ....whatever.....etc.<br />

Corporations, in fact, as was feared long ago by Thomas Jefferson, now have more rights<br />

that do individual citizens. Any and all candidates who do not address this fact are merely<br />

bag boys and check-out girls for the system. We should be laughing all <strong>of</strong> these kinds <strong>of</strong><br />

politicians out <strong>of</strong> town on a rail, tarred-and-feathered, and dump them into the ocean (except<br />

that can’t be good for the water). They are only interested in protecting the property rights<br />

<strong>of</strong> the wealthy owners <strong>of</strong> society and everything in it (who got them into a position to run<br />

for president at all in the first place) and, sorry folks, that ain’t you and me.....<br />

You can all go on politico-babbling about Schmillary Glintone and Borat Yomamma, but<br />

in the end, after the ballots are closed, settle down in front <strong>of</strong> the idiot box and get ready


382 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

to witness more and more <strong>of</strong> the same old endless pooh....no matter who gets to be president<br />

schmesident...puppet <strong>of</strong> corporate power and control...protector <strong>of</strong> capitalist interests<br />

worldwide....<br />

“Go back to bed, America...your government is in control...” -Bill Hicks<br />

Message [263] referenced by [264], [270], and [274]. Next Message by CousinIt is [271].<br />

[264] FacistFrank: Re: President Schmesident. CousinIt I respect your opinion, and<br />

from reading all the comments you have left here up until this point I was under the honest<br />

impression that you were a quite intelligent individual. However I find this last comment<br />

[263] beneath you, you seem to me to be fishing for a flame war, I won’t indulge you.<br />

You raise quite legitimate points about our problems in America, then you use inflammatory<br />

overblown language that negates all the intelligent criticisms that you made earlier. I<br />

agree America has given the corporations far too much power, and I agree we need change,<br />

however I believe the change that you want would be like a person trying to swallow a jawbreaker<br />

in one gulp. 25 years after the French revolution the country was once again under<br />

the control <strong>of</strong> a despot, it was too much change too fast. I also think you are under the false<br />

impression that JFK REALLY wanted to change things, I recently read the Kennedy men<br />

by Laurence Leamer, JFK was more concerned with his image than with changing things,<br />

he was much more conservative than Lyndon Johnson, who risked his status, and was disgraced,<br />

for social change. There is the impression out there that JFK was a super liberal,<br />

and was killed because <strong>of</strong> it, he was quite conservative. (And I am a staunch democrat!)<br />

JFK supported liberal change on a more intellectual level, where LBJ supported it on an<br />

emotional visceral level.<br />

I am an Obama supporter, I canvassed for him during the <strong>Utah</strong> primary, I am not foolish<br />

enough to believe that he is some kind <strong>of</strong> American savior, or will turn this country into<br />

a utopia. I only believe that he has the potential to help us get on the right path for the<br />

change we need, the ultimate goal, to take power from the corporations and give it back to<br />

the people, this is a long term goal, long term as in decades, it may even take a century.<br />

Even with that said change must come in the minds <strong>of</strong> Americans, he is only one man, there<br />

is only so much he can do. Who knows, If Obama is elected, he may even suffer the same<br />

fate as Jimmy Carter, Carter was too honest, he told Americans the truth about themselves,<br />

and they didn’t like it so they elected Ronald Reagan. Reagan told Americans they were<br />

perfect and the only problem was the government. It’s the exact reverse, the people have the<br />

problem, not the government. The people elected George Bush.<br />

I don’t think name calling is going to make anyone smarter, or get us any closer to identifying<br />

to the problems America has. I don’t mean to insult you or anyone else, only to <strong>of</strong>fer<br />

a criticism. It also upsets me that I am addressing a person instead <strong>of</strong> an issue. I hope you<br />

don’t take this personally.<br />

Message [264] referenced by [271]. Next Message by FacistFrank is [294].<br />

[267] Bar: Corporations, Marx, and Thomas Jefferson. Put down the Michal Moore<br />

movies, and stop drinking the kool-aid. If I get this straight CousinIt thinks corporations<br />

are evil, and we are going to solve all the “problems” in America by killing corporations<br />

through more regulation, more government control, and socialization. God I’m so happy<br />

my generation doesn’t vote. Anyways, the fact <strong>of</strong> the matter is it’s not solely corporations


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 383<br />

running the government, it’s special interest groups: Farmers and their “farm subsidies,”<br />

unions, and even the corporations and their lobbyists, not to mention, MoveOn.org, the gun<br />

lobbyists, big oil, educations unions, pro-choice and pro-life groups. There are many right<br />

and left wing groups who have a lot <strong>of</strong> control in the government, because these minority<br />

groups usually have substantial amounts <strong>of</strong> money and because their groups are small, they<br />

can easily organize, but the corporation bad? I don’t think so. Corporations create a culture<br />

<strong>of</strong> meritocracy, not egalitarian bull; success is what matters, goals, and accomplishments.<br />

The stupid argument that corporations manipulate our tastes and preferences soooo much<br />

that really we don’t make decisions, is so dumb, Marx really shouldn’t have based his psychological<br />

premises from physiologist theory <strong>of</strong> the time, that believed 110% in nurture and<br />

nothing in nature – Blank slate bull. Today developmental physiologists believe that genes<br />

also play a huge role in development <strong>of</strong> our tastes and preferences, not just our socialization.<br />

Thomas Jefferson was not an ideologue, he also didn’t believe in Federalism, didn’t<br />

like investment in manufacturing, or expansion westward, but in the end he made the decision<br />

to embrace Federalism, saw how large scale manufacturing benefited the country, and<br />

made the Louisiana Purchase. If he were alive today he would embrace the corporation.<br />

In conclusion, “when people say power to the people” referring so socialized anything and<br />

getting rid <strong>of</strong> privatization or the corporation, you need to go back and read 1984, and see<br />

how Orwell shows how big government manipulates the “prols,” heck, look at Stalinism,<br />

Che and Fidel, Cambodia, and all those sooo successful leftist movements and see how well<br />

big government worked. People give up liberty through more government; they don’t gain<br />

power, what Thomas Jefferson really worried about.<br />

Message [267] referenced by [271]. Next Message by Bar is [292].<br />

[268] Hans: The US State <strong>of</strong> Denial. Here is an excerpt from today’s blog on Creative-I<br />

by William Bowles:<br />

http://www.creative-i.info/?p=211<br />

Frankly, I find it extremely difficult to communicate the nature <strong>of</strong> contemporary US society,<br />

it’s so over the top as to defy description even for someone raised in a so-called developed<br />

country like the UK or for someone who lived in the Big Apple for seventeen years.<br />

And as the contradictions <strong>of</strong> a capitalism in crisis increase, so too does the frantic nature <strong>of</strong><br />

its desire to justify itself by any means necessary, including the use <strong>of</strong> the enormous force <strong>of</strong><br />

the machinery <strong>of</strong> state.<br />

It’s the impact on people, like a very close friend <strong>of</strong> mine here that typifies the paradox<br />

involved, for when confronted with the reality <strong>of</strong> life here by my writings, she gets defensive,<br />

even as she knows that as a black woman, she has borne the brunt <strong>of</strong> this society for her<br />

entire life. But who can blame her, she has to live here and deal with it 24/7, who wants<br />

to be reminded <strong>of</strong> the fact, especially by a foreigner like myself, friend or no friend. For<br />

the fact is, I like Americans, they are a generous, friendly and uninhibited people, especially<br />

working class Americans, people I find I have more in common with than the Brits (which<br />

is perhaps one <strong>of</strong> the reasons I lived here for seventeen years).<br />

But at the same time they are totally ignorant <strong>of</strong> the real state <strong>of</strong> the world and their<br />

own country and kept that way by a corporate media and an mis-education system that


384 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

corrupts young minds. Blind even to the reality <strong>of</strong> their own lives because they have been<br />

brainwashed into thinking that ‘failure’ is the result <strong>of</strong> their own personal failure as human<br />

beings, not that <strong>of</strong> the system which screws them every which way, literally from cradle to<br />

grave.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [269].<br />

[270] Inter: RE: President Schmesident. The remarks in post [263] are well taken. I<br />

think there is one fundamental question which needs to be asked: do think the United States<br />

would be in the same position that it is in today if Al Gore had won in 2000?<br />

Depending on how you answer that question, illustrates what type <strong>of</strong> choice we have in<br />

the election, and the potential differences between the candidates.<br />

Next Message by Inter is [302].<br />

[271] CousinIt: Giddy-er by the minute... In response to [264] and [267] ...<br />

Well, I can tell which hook, line, and sinker you both are choking on...it gagged me,<br />

too....had to spit it out....you have my deepest sympathies..<br />

Orwell is talking about the kind <strong>of</strong> Republicrat babble we have been stupid enough to even<br />

acknowledge ever since 9-11-2001, no government spends more or bigger than a republicrat<br />

one, and oh yeah, ‘egalitarian’ would be baaaad...fake ‘meritiocracy’ that is really a system<br />

<strong>of</strong> doled-privilege is a lot better ;) ...the kind <strong>of</strong> ‘issues’ that are talked about in the electorobabble<br />

are smoke-screen issues designed to keep us from addressing the fact that we are<br />

being lied to and are cheated by everyone currently in government who are only interested<br />

in looking like they are making slight tweeks to the status quo here and there...real change<br />

would mean ditching the very structure that doesn’t work and scrapping the fake casinoeconomy,<br />

even though you want to imagine that it is working...well, good luck with that,<br />

Gunga Din...you are a better man than I, and I can tell you know it...<br />

Close your eyes, breathe deeply, exhale and repeat the popular godblessthecorporation<br />

mantras you’ve been memorizing along with that Chris Hannity jerk and everything will be<br />

just fine...<br />

....it’s so cute!!! Makes the big monkeysuit-and-tie-wearing daddies proud, I’m sure.<br />

It is interesting, if not tragically amusing, how far you all will go to justify your corporationsuckling<br />

in the warm embrace <strong>of</strong> false sense <strong>of</strong> security...<br />

keep that corporo-facist glow burning bright...<br />

What is insulting to me, because my daughter has to live in this sh*t-hole republicrats<br />

and democretins are creating, is that you think a world run by fake elections administered by<br />

corporate and special interests is better than a world run by actual democratic government<br />

<strong>of</strong> the people, for the people and by the people...<br />

I have no problem with production or big government as long as we, the people, own the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> production and the government, the economy, and our lives are run by us, the real<br />

people on the streets. I do not fear big government that is mine. I do fear big government<br />

that is run by the corporation because the corporation historically doesn’t give a damn about<br />

people, especially when it goes beyond their tax write-<strong>of</strong>f limit or starts to threaten projected<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its, even if you do really want to imagine that they do with your whole tiny little heart.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 385<br />

We have to get special interests and corporations out <strong>of</strong> our government, start taxing<br />

religions who are really fantasy-barking corporate money-machines with tax-exemptions,<br />

and start doing what is right for the global collective instead <strong>of</strong> what is ‘pr<strong>of</strong>itable’ for<br />

private interests....I’m tired <strong>of</strong> contributing to their moral- and intellectual-vacation packageprogram...<br />

Of course this is something that, from within the occupational psychosis <strong>of</strong> eternal corporosuck<br />

godblesscapital, is impossible for the occupationally psychoticized to begin to<br />

imagine...Marx knew this would be the case...<br />

It’s not your fault, you’re just very well-healed and very well-trained...now don’t forget<br />

to put the seat down, go back to bed and let the Fortune 500 and the ‘coalition for a better<br />

liberal lobby’ work it all out...<br />

Sorry if you don’t get it or if you are <strong>of</strong>fended by the fact that I don’t buy any <strong>of</strong> the<br />

politico-babble on the TV gameshow we like to call “Election” Blah Blah Blah.....<br />

If you think things are really getting better because <strong>of</strong> greater-freedoms-and-bigger-taxcuts-for-capital<br />

and that New Perfect America is lurking around the next corner and that that<br />

is what it’s all about, then there is nothing more to say but,<br />

Goodnight America!!! Sweet Dreams!!!<br />

Marx told us all about that kind <strong>of</strong> thinking process, too, and knew that nothing would<br />

change until that kind <strong>of</strong> thinking was abolished once and for all....nevermind....it’s time to<br />

go to back to bed...<br />

Message [271] referenced by [274]. Next Message by CousinIt is [276].<br />

[274] Trailrunner: Fearing to Respond. I found myself awake in the middle <strong>of</strong> the<br />

night reflecting on some <strong>of</strong> the responses the last few days having to do with the presidential<br />

elections. I realize that email is a wonderful things, but it can also be an evil thing at times.<br />

We are not able to hear the inflection in someone’s voice, see their eyes or facial expressions<br />

or always truly understand the meaning behind their words.<br />

What I have felt from CousinIt [271] and [263] the last few days, has been anger and<br />

it has made me wonder if I should even say anything (after all, I could be misinterpreting<br />

what is being said). Then I began reflecting on all <strong>of</strong> the shootings lately that have taken<br />

place in classrooms and other locations throughout the States (a subject that was casually<br />

brought up in class on Thursday evening by Goethe) and wondered at the correlation that<br />

might be there. Why is it that every time there is a message from certain people on this<br />

mailing list, I find myself tensing up and wondering what negativity might be heading out<br />

into the universe? My gut tells me that this is to be a forum where thoughts are shared and it<br />

is recognized that everyone has a right to their own opinion, whether we agree with it or not.<br />

A place where we can share our thoughts without the fear <strong>of</strong> being “beat up” for sharing.<br />

One <strong>of</strong> the keys to healthy dialogue is that all those participating feel safe in sharing their<br />

thoughts and speaking up. I feel that some <strong>of</strong> this safety has been lost lately and once again,<br />

it took me back to thinking about random shootings.<br />

Do I need to start wearing a protective vest when I attend this class? I realize this is a bit<br />

overboard and I am taking this to a limit, but the point I would like to make is that there is


386 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

a way to respond to people that allows them to feel respected and to not feel threatened for<br />

voicing an opinion. After all, we are all individuals with different experiences in our lives<br />

and thus will always feel differently about things. We can continue to have strong opinions<br />

about those things that are most meaningful to us, but it doesn’t mean that everyone else has<br />

to feel the same way and it certainly doesn’t mean that we have the right to put someone else<br />

down and make them feel small in the process <strong>of</strong> sharing our thoughts. As well, what is it<br />

that makes a person purchase a gun, enter a classroom and start shooting? Are there signs<br />

that are missed and would one <strong>of</strong> those signs be anger directed at random people that are<br />

simply participating in a classroom assignment?<br />

I apologize to CousinIt for using those two particular reponses and singling out this individual,<br />

but these responses happen to be what started this whole line <strong>of</strong> thinking. My<br />

thoughts go back to the comment made by Goethe the other night regarding all <strong>of</strong> the random<br />

shootings lately and simply hope that this type <strong>of</strong> thing is something that none <strong>of</strong> us<br />

ever has to experience.<br />

Message [274] referenced by [276] and [277]. Next Message by Trailrunner is [297].<br />

[276] CousinIt: You can lead a horse to water, but... In reference to [274]...<br />

Wow!! Someone brings up the fact that, in a capitalist society you will never deal with<br />

the exploitation until you recognize that capitalism is exploitive and will do whatever it has<br />

to do to maintain and perpetuate itself and everyone starts freaking out and talking about<br />

shooting people and stuff...an interesting reaction...<br />

The reason I brought up the election-babble is that I thought there should be some other<br />

voice that wasn’t parroting the same old “...well I think the puppet on the right appeals to<br />

me...well, I think the puppet on the left is more to my liking....” conventional ballyhoo.<br />

The next thing I know people are throwing the same tired-old “get <strong>of</strong>f Michael Mooore..”<br />

crap instead <strong>of</strong> dealing with the original comment which was, by the way, that Hillary and<br />

Obama are just more <strong>of</strong> the same old “protect capitalism in America and the world” poohpooh.<br />

Isn’t it interesting how everybody’s unconscious “godblesscapital” “everything’s OK as<br />

long as we keep the capitalists happy” indoctrination kicks in, in ways that they can’t even<br />

see or recognize because they think that the way they are thinking is “normal” or “natural”?<br />

....just like they think capitalism is “normal” and “natural”...(we all know that, for Chrissake<br />

!!!)...<br />

Look folks, capitalism is not normal, is not natural, and is not moral. It hasn’t made<br />

everyone rich or even prosperous. It was built on slavery and theft. It is merely a stage in<br />

our species-development and it’s time to get on with the next stage where we decide that it’s<br />

more important to take care <strong>of</strong> everybody, quit mucking up the environment, and make the<br />

world a good place for children to come to, instead <strong>of</strong> trying to convince them that it’s OK to<br />

murder, exploit, and let die. If you think the tasks I have mentioned as important ones in our<br />

further development as a species are a bad list <strong>of</strong> bad things to do, you might want to stop<br />

for a minute and see how absurd it is that you think so....we are not “homo economicus” or<br />

“homo capitalus”...we are an explicitly “social” animal...so why not social-ism?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 387<br />

I am in a warranted position to judge capitalism, because we have tried it and it doesn’t<br />

work. You cannot judge a socialism that has never been tried (I know you think that we<br />

did try it in the Soviet Union and in China and Norway and Holland, but we haven’t, even<br />

though you think we have....Sorry...I will probably have to explain this as well, and then<br />

people will start talking about lobbing atomic warheads at each other.....).<br />

This little email exchange we’ve been having should be instructive/illustrative <strong>of</strong> one <strong>of</strong><br />

the important (and apparently most difficult points) being made in this class. We do not<br />

know that we are brainwashed (indoctrinated, spellbound, ideologized...whatever you want<br />

to call it..) and we will attack anyone who says that we are (or at least try to get them to<br />

shut up and sit down so we don’t have to have the conversation...see how that works? Cool<br />

huh?)....<br />

Thanks to all <strong>of</strong> you who participated in illustrating this very important point....do you<br />

see it? ...I would be willing to bet my “hillary/barak for president schmesident” posters that<br />

most people probably don’t (or won’t, no matter what the cost! That’s how deep the river <strong>of</strong><br />

blinding pooh can run...).<br />

Do you know how I know who doesn’t know? Because I can tell when someone is still<br />

thinking that the answers to the problems facing the nation and the world will be provided<br />

by or within a framework <strong>of</strong> capitalism. I can tell when someone still thinks capitalism is a<br />

good thing and refuses to see that it is over. It cannot sustain itself. It doesn’t work. I know<br />

you think it does and wish that it would, and I’m sorry, but, it doesn’t and it won’t and you<br />

probably don’t know it, yet, or you wouldn’t think I was talking about Michael Moore or<br />

mall/highschool/college shootings.<br />

(I have another theory about why these kinds <strong>of</strong> shootings happen that I’m sure no one<br />

would want to think or hear being talked about either.... it’s OK...turn on the TV and go back<br />

to sleep, America....Big Brother Capital will make everyone safe and warm if you will just<br />

shut up, sit down, get out <strong>of</strong> the way, and let capital do everything and anything anywhere it<br />

wants...Goodnight boys and girls....tomorrow we will all be trillionaires...)<br />

Message [276] referenced by [294]. Next Message by CousinIt is [277].<br />

[277] CousinIt: Evil, evil, everywhere..... It seems that Tailrunner [274] wants everyone<br />

to be able to say whatever they want as long as no one is presenting an uncomfortable point<br />

<strong>of</strong> view or is confrontational about things that should really matter, but that only get paid<br />

lip-service, so that we can look like we really care alot...<br />

Just because someone has a strong opinion and thinks it is worth arguing about doesn’t<br />

mean they are going to come to school with a gun and start blowing heads <strong>of</strong>f. I don’t even<br />

own a gun because I mentally walked through the process <strong>of</strong> having to use it on another<br />

human being and decided that it was something I was not willing to do.<br />

Stop looking for “evil” in things that you fear or merely find hard to understand. Maybe<br />

we are watching too much useless “news” these days. There is evil in the world, but you<br />

might be surprised when you find it in your own everyday choices and tastes...that’s the place<br />

to start looking...<br />

“Am I evil? I am man. Yes, I am....” -Hetfield<br />

Next Message by CousinIt is [308].


388 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[291] Rey: Oh ya.....What are you gonna do about it? All this t-shirt revolution talk<br />

is quite cute! I wonder if CousinIt read the inner flap on the same Anti-Flag CD that I did<br />

while I was in high school. It would appear so, because all I can hear between mumbles<br />

is “down with the corporations, down with the corporations!” Now I am not ignorant to the<br />

fact that corporations and lobbyist have far too much power than they should (in fact I would<br />

consider myself more educated than most in this area), but let’s take a little accountability<br />

on ourselves to induce change. Rather then sit around and read books all day living in some<br />

abstract play land where hope is a strategy, I would hope you recognize that we have the<br />

personal responsibility to pull “the power” downward, protect ourselves and create our own<br />

destiny. It ’s quite extreme to blame everything wrong with America on big business. I<br />

know you are intelligent enough to see that the idea <strong>of</strong> free enterprise is one <strong>of</strong> the beautiful<br />

things that has made America what it is today. With as much bad that has come from this<br />

abuse <strong>of</strong> power within the system there is much good at the same time. The right people<br />

in the right system will give us right results. A flaw in the individual is not a flaw in the<br />

system. In fact as a third generation Chicano I have seen the “American dream” from an<br />

intimate perspective. I take pride in the fact that my Grandfather came from a growing up in<br />

a box car on the west side <strong>of</strong> Salt Lake, to owning and operating a successful business and<br />

becoming a member <strong>of</strong> the <strong>Utah</strong> legislature. All the while paving the way for me to stand on<br />

his shoulders and keep improving my social and economic situation. So in regards to biting<br />

this so called propaganda hook line and sinker, I guess I am just another sucker. At some<br />

point “the people” need to stop pointing fingers and take action! Not in direct reference to<br />

CousinIt, because I would have no way <strong>of</strong> knowing, all to <strong>of</strong>ten it has been my experience<br />

that those who lounge around and criticize the system all to <strong>of</strong>ten lack the ambition to go<br />

out and place themselves in a position to do anything about it. To which they may respond<br />

with their rhetorical excuse “you can’t change the system from within the system, because<br />

it’s the system that ends <strong>of</strong> changing you.” This sounds like to me they would rather stay in<br />

bed, besides its easier that way. Wake up America, and lets go get our hands dirty!!<br />

In additional comments I would like to make note <strong>of</strong> the fact that I feel zealous debate<br />

is a healthy part <strong>of</strong> the learning process. It’s what being part <strong>of</strong> a university is all about, all<br />

to <strong>of</strong>ten we are quick to curl up and hide anytime our views are challenged. Granted we all<br />

need to be respectful, but we also need not be so quick to be <strong>of</strong>fended. We need to cut the<br />

PC garbage out <strong>of</strong> our learning process and see things for what they are.<br />

Message [291] referenced by [297] and [312]. Next Message by Rey is [379].<br />

[292] Bar: Central Planning CousinIts “Special Friend”. CousinIt instead <strong>of</strong> addressing<br />

any <strong>of</strong> my arguments in my last submission, he resorts to ad hominid attacks and fallacies,<br />

he attacks conservatism, and the political process in general, well I guess that’s all you<br />

can do when you have no rebuttal. He satires my view by saying, “and oh yeah, ‘egalitarian’<br />

would be baaaad...fake ‘meritiocracy’ that is really a system <strong>of</strong> doled-privilege is a lot better<br />

;)”<br />

Which, is the equivalent to a teenager talking back to their mom, well I guess if your thirteen<br />

your rhetoric my be useful. Furthermore, I would love to understand first, what a “fake<br />

casino-economy” is, and second, how that is related to the US economy—maybe CousinIt<br />

has a gambling problem, he wouldn’t be the first Marxist I’ve know who does. I’ll always<br />

keep my “corporo-facist” glow burning bright, because with all <strong>of</strong> them out there, in a sense


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 389<br />

it is another separation <strong>of</strong> power between the people and the government—game theory anyone?.<br />

CousinIt goes on to say, “What is insulting to me, because my daughter has to live<br />

in this sh*t-hole republicrats and democretins are creating, is that you think a world run by<br />

fake elections administered by corporate and special interests is better than a world run by<br />

actual democratic government <strong>of</strong> the people, for the people and by the people...” Hmmm<br />

yeah so you have an ideal, hmm how would this ideal work? So if everything were run by<br />

the people, the people would have means <strong>of</strong> production, like you state later in your piece. Ok<br />

Utopian, so the only way I know to give the power to the people is through pure government<br />

central planning, where we the people would make every little decision from great to small<br />

by the majority <strong>of</strong> people. If the people truly make the decisions and you want to minimize<br />

or get rid <strong>of</strong> corporations, private property needs to be abolished- all private property. If<br />

not, how can the people truly make decisions when someone may have more power and<br />

influence than another? For everything to work, we would have to have pure equality. Like<br />

there is any other option? Of course not, if evolution has taught us anything it’s that we are<br />

all equal. And lastly, all special interest groups would have to be abolished, how can the<br />

government work while people are organizing against it? We can’t have for example, a car<br />

manufacturer like GM who pays their assembly worker employees an average <strong>of</strong> $100,000<br />

a year not to mention a spectacular medical plan, and the same pay each year for their pension,<br />

while making $0 pr<strong>of</strong>it on each car sold(they only make money through financing).<br />

This would create inequality for others in the economy. Ok so far, the government or “the<br />

people” control my wage, my car option, my IQ. Now let’s look at other institutions, I have<br />

my education which would be under the control <strong>of</strong> the people, I can’t go to a liberal or conservative<br />

school, I have to go where “the people” decide that to go. Hmm, I couldn’t choose<br />

my religion, that evilest <strong>of</strong> all the special interest group, that <strong>of</strong> coarse needs to be taxed–<br />

right to congregate? What the hell were those founding fathers thinking, putting that into the<br />

bill <strong>of</strong> rights? Power to the people through central planning, you’ve convinced me CousinIt<br />

forgive me, I’ve seen the light through your quaint new world, god bless the people. My perspective<br />

was all wrong, I’ve been brainwashed so many years now I didn’t even realize that<br />

the corporations are evil. All we need to do now is sing Kum By Ya, or even better Imagine!<br />

Like you said: “Of course this is something that, from within the occupational psychosis <strong>of</strong><br />

eternal corporosuck godblesscapital, is impossible for the occupationally psychoticized to<br />

begin to imagine...Marx knew this would be the case...” Does that refer communism or capitalism<br />

I always get that confused and yeah I addressed this already, not everything is nurture,<br />

and your argument is flawed. Hard data shows that our genes contribute to our wants and<br />

desires also– take a developmental psychology class, Marx didn’t have this knowledge when<br />

he was developing his theories. I’ve explained some social aspects <strong>of</strong> why central planning<br />

doesn’t work, which is the way Marxian’s give “power to the people.” Economically this<br />

doesn’t work either, because it creates huge free rider problems and transaction costs, not to<br />

mention a million other market inefficiencies, and reducing the wealth in society, which the<br />

majority <strong>of</strong> theses problems are solved by creating better stronger private property rights.<br />

The reason the US economy works and is not a “casino economy” is because it and all other<br />

countries with British institutions create good governments with similar constitutions and<br />

an emphasis on separation <strong>of</strong> powers, and small government etc–The exact opposite <strong>of</strong> central<br />

planning–Note: the USSR and China obviously are still under that economy because it<br />

worked sooo well.


390 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Bar is [330].<br />

[294] FacistFrank: Re: You can lead a horse to water, but... Cousinit [276] I think<br />

you have interesting ideas that are intelligent and well thought out. But I also think you are<br />

a dogmatist, this is the problem I have with the comments you are making, you state these<br />

things as if they were clear as the sky is blue, when to me the sky is hazy. I myself am not<br />

so sure, I think these things could be true, in some cases are even probably true.<br />

Anyway, on another subject, I had a thought to myself recently that Adam Smith was<br />

only half right. He says that competition is a good thing, that when all people compete<br />

for their own interests, it works out to the benefit <strong>of</strong> the whole, (this should be modified to<br />

when all people compete for their own interests AND the interests <strong>of</strong> the whole, it works<br />

out to the benefit <strong>of</strong> both). If everyone fights for the last piece <strong>of</strong> pizza, they destroy the<br />

pizza to the detriment <strong>of</strong> all. I think he was right about competition being a good thing,<br />

but he fails to realize that the ultimate goal <strong>of</strong> competition is the destruction <strong>of</strong> competition.<br />

In anything competitive, there must be a winner and a loser. When the winner wins, he<br />

proceeds to abuse the losers. We need government to restore competition after competition<br />

has ended. If competition were never to end, it could never begin, and therefore not exist. It<br />

is in competition’s essential nature to die, and be reborn.<br />

Next Message by FacistFrank is [295].<br />

[297] Trailrunner: Thank you for Proving a Point. In [291], Rey proved the one point I<br />

was trying to make in my comments yesterday. It seems that I’ve been placed in what I would<br />

call the “granola” category and that I prefer not to see or participate in a healthy debate.<br />

Debate is wonderful, especially if it opens our eyes to see things from a different perspective<br />

and if it enlightens us and helps us learn. Learning from someone else’s perspective and<br />

experiences can change our entire outlook on a certain subject. BUT, it can all be done with<br />

respect. Attack the issue not the individual!<br />

Rey spoke <strong>of</strong> his personal experience and proved the point that he could respond by<br />

addressing the issues and he did so in an intelligent and respectful way. Thank you Rey!!<br />

Next Message by Trailrunner is [405].<br />

[300] Jenn: S<strong>of</strong>ten up for the babies. Trailrunner, I share your opinion. Thank you<br />

for speaking up. I am a little disappointed because I feel that CousinIt had some really<br />

interesting points, but now I find myself pushing the delete button before I am even finished<br />

reading. We are all taking this class to learn and I think FacistFrank put it really well with the<br />

“swallowing the jawbreaker whole” analogy. We are all “socialist babies” and need to be fed<br />

milk, not solid food right away. The hostility that seethes in some <strong>of</strong> CousinIt’s responses<br />

causes me to close my ears to the valuable points he has to make.<br />

CousinIt, you obviously take a leadership role in these email discussions. Despite your<br />

hostility, I have a lot <strong>of</strong> respect for what you have to say - and I’m sure other people feel the<br />

same way.<br />

You have an opportunity to reshape our minds.<br />

I hope you realize what an amazing opportunity this is. So I challenge you to step up and<br />

do this. S<strong>of</strong>ten a little so you can reach out to the socialist babies. Please, for the sake <strong>of</strong> our<br />

country’s dire economic situation. Consider it your “tour <strong>of</strong> duty.”


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 391<br />

Next Message by Jenn is [301].<br />

[312] CousinIt: My Apologies. I would like to commend Rey [291] for this comment:<br />

In additional comments I would like to make note <strong>of</strong> the fact that I feel<br />

zealous debate is a healthy part <strong>of</strong> the learning process. It’s what being part<br />

<strong>of</strong> a university is all about, all to <strong>of</strong>ten we are quick to curl up and hide<br />

anytime our views are challenged. Granted we all need to be respectful, but<br />

we also need not be so quick to be <strong>of</strong>fended. We need to cut the PC garbage<br />

out <strong>of</strong> our learning process and see things for what they are.<br />

Bravo!!, comrade....<br />

I am not <strong>of</strong>fended by those who think that attacking me, my intelligence, and my conviction,<br />

will change the fact that capitalism is wrong. What is interesting is that some folks<br />

think they are being attacked personally, when what I attack is certain notions, attitudes,<br />

and a political process that will never address capital as long as capital is its patron and the<br />

notion that capitalism is OK keeps the conversation within particular bounds. The attempts<br />

to take my comments out <strong>of</strong> context and suggest that I am dangerous and that I have some<br />

evil intent is a typical ploy made by those who want other people with unpopular opinions<br />

to shut up and sit down so that they can get their peice <strong>of</strong> the exploitation <strong>of</strong> others before<br />

exploitation is made illegal.<br />

I do have one critique <strong>of</strong> the “Oh yeah...what are you gonna do...” perspective. The thing<br />

about true democracy and a critical perspective on the problems <strong>of</strong> capitalism is that the<br />

answers are not pre-determined, are not part <strong>of</strong> a master ideology, and are not as easy as<br />

staying within the boundaries using only certain colors to exclusion <strong>of</strong> other possibilities.<br />

This means that I do not have all the answers. I don’t have any answers as to what I would<br />

do because, obviously, the answers are probably ones we haven’t thought <strong>of</strong> because we<br />

think that they lie in the realm <strong>of</strong> the impossible. The kind <strong>of</strong> answers that “Oh yeah, what<br />

are you gonna do about it” wants are easy one-liner solutions. Real solutions must emerge<br />

out <strong>of</strong> healthy (even if sometimes heated and impassioned) debate and deliberation by the<br />

collective. Idealism is OK, if not necessary and inevitable. To criticize someone for being<br />

an idealist is really saying something like, “I know you are but what am I?” and gets us<br />

nowhere. The real answers are way too difficult to demand that one person come up with a<br />

complete program to fix it all on his own, so I won’t grace such a question with an answer.<br />

Also, I don’t mind using terms like “free-enterprise” but it is <strong>of</strong>fensive to me when this<br />

term is used to describe the economic system we are forced to live under. Any system that<br />

designates certain commodities as “contraband,” which has differential tarrifs and taxes on<br />

certain items, and places certain laws and restrictions on certain trades and commodities,<br />

thus giving other favored trades and commodities unfair access to the market is not freeenterprise,<br />

but is restricted trade and controlled-enterprise. I am not suggesting that freeenterprise<br />

is even optimal or possible, but what we are doing is certainly not free.<br />

Also to say that “America is wonderful because I know a member <strong>of</strong> an underprivileged<br />

class who was able to ‘make it’ and achieve ‘The American Dream’” is called a “Horatio<br />

Alger” story. Such stories are used to say, “If you can’t ‘make it’ in the current system it is<br />

your own damn fault and not because there is anything structurally unfair or exploitative in


392 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

the structure <strong>of</strong> society.” This is a common tactic used by those who feel they have “made<br />

it.” It is designed to make those who point to the structural failings in society to shut up, sit<br />

down, and be happy that they are allowed to walk around amongst us, the “beautiful people.”<br />

This being said, Rey....Bravo!! Extraordinary conditions require extraordinary tactics,<br />

like the “Guerilla Ontology” I am attempting as a way to try and break through the naturalizing<br />

fog <strong>of</strong> the capitalist psychosis. If all I ever posted made people happy and applauding,<br />

nothing would be gained. The fact that I upset people lets me know I’m doing something<br />

useful.<br />

Be clear that I do not intend to attack people (as has been unrightfully attributed to me in<br />

ad hominem attacks leveled against me in various postings) but that my intention is to attack<br />

particular ridiculously selective and tautalogical political and social attitudes and political<br />

cartoon characters that are darn well worthy <strong>of</strong> criticism and derision because they are just<br />

more <strong>of</strong> the same old crap that keeps something as inhumane and environmentally destructive<br />

as capitalism going. We don’t have time to be nice and comfortable in our discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> these issues. The time for niceities is over. Things like climate change, continuing imperialism<br />

and slavery, and people who are suffering every second at the hands <strong>of</strong> corporate<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>its cannot ethically or practically wait another minute longer for those who refuse to see<br />

to wake up and vote America a consciousness. This is why the method I choose is “Geurilla<br />

Ontology.” I have lost patience with the “God Bless Capitalism” crowd long ago...<br />

I apologize if I make you angry or uncomfortable. I really don’t care how upset you<br />

are. We should be upset. We’ve been buying into a lie for our entire lifetimes. The fact<br />

that it does upset us so simply illustrates, in very graphic and emotionally salient if ugly<br />

terms, the width and the depth <strong>of</strong> the prevailing ideological psychosis...and the fact that I<br />

have accomplished at least part <strong>of</strong> what I set out to do in the first place.<br />

“Anger is an energy” -John Lidon<br />

Message [312] referenced by [367]. Next Message by CousinIt is [356].<br />

[330] Bar: Is free speech dead? I find it really interesting that some people on this post<br />

are actually discomforted by others expressing their views. Whoever, should be able to say<br />

whatever they want, as long as its not some kind <strong>of</strong> slander or goes into the illegal realm.<br />

The point <strong>of</strong> free speech is to be able to criticize society, policy, and individual, especially<br />

to criticise arguments and rhetoric by government figures without fear <strong>of</strong> retribution. Even<br />

further, no one should have to apologize for their view. These kinds <strong>of</strong> things happen all the<br />

time in the media, Don Imas for example and many others have lost their jobs for expressing<br />

a joke or a view that society doesn’t agree with. People have the right to be racist bigots,<br />

just as much as they have the right to be enlightened individuals. People should not be able<br />

to control others ideas, the founding fathers understood this, that’s why they emphasized<br />

protecting minority rights. Arguments and rhetoric, in all forms, even personal attacks, can<br />

be effective and healthy for debate. I would like to put a question to all the forum members.<br />

Do you think that people should have the right to say whatever they want on this forum<br />

without having to apologize?<br />

Message [330] referenced by [337], [354], and [356]. Next Message by Bar is [376].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 393<br />

[337] Spawnblade: Dead Free Speech, or Dead Etiquette? “Do you think that people<br />

should have the right to say whatever they want on this forum without having to apologize?”<br />

– Bar [330]<br />

No. They should not have the right to say ‘whatever they want’ without having to apologize.<br />

Instead <strong>of</strong> an absolute you have specified a limitless declaration. Both absolutes<br />

and limitless (I’m unsure <strong>of</strong> any ‘pr<strong>of</strong>essional’ term for this) statements should always be<br />

denied in my opinion. There are limits and freedoms that should be applied in all (hah,<br />

contradiction?) situations.<br />

Is killing always wrong? Is dying never necessary? Is 2+2 always equal to 4? Are<br />

political parties always useless? (Ok perhaps we have our exception here.)<br />

If you all recall, there was a class specifically to teach internet etiquette. I’m sure most <strong>of</strong><br />

you spend time outside <strong>of</strong> class browsing the internet, maybe skimming facebook/myspace<br />

and perhaps the groups affiliated with those social networking sites? I know I personally am<br />

a member <strong>of</strong> several groups, I used to be a member <strong>of</strong> several more before I took a look at<br />

their forums...<br />

... I had never seen so much flaming in my life. Here is an excerpt that took merely 2<br />

minutes <strong>of</strong> browsing to find. The group was “If this group gets 1,000,000 members, Keyan<br />

will streak at Superbowl 42.”<br />

Post topic: Legality Issue?<br />

Mr. Civil: “Even if this guy IS bound by a legally notarized document–<br />

which I somehow doubt– I suspect that it is illegal to strip at the super<br />

bowl, and therefore the ‘legally binding’ document would not be legally<br />

binding, because they would not notarize it if it pertained to illegal stuff, at<br />

least that’s what I think. Even if they did notarize it I would think that he<br />

still wouldn’t have to honor it, because it would be illegal.”<br />

Mr. Flamer 1: “(Mr. Civil) your such a fag go suck a !$@#” (Replaced<br />

names with their corresponding pseudos.)<br />

Mr. Anti-Flamer 1: “haha your so funny (Mr. Flamer 1) stfu this guy makes<br />

a valuable point and you go act like a tough guy maybe if you were so tough<br />

youd have your own faggot %$$ picture up”<br />

Mr. Flamer 1: “hahah a your so funny (Mr. Flamer 1) you a faggot and<br />

what the !$@# does a pic have to do with anything fag”<br />

Well that’s the gist <strong>of</strong> it, though it wasn’t an exceedingly long one, I didn’t feel like gathering<br />

all the continuing posts. From reading this I am very confident in the education these<br />

college students are receiving... Right. Frankly I know I am not alone in not wanting these<br />

discussions to deteriorate into that. Otherwise you only have one point <strong>of</strong> view posting in<br />

the discussions because other people do not want to deal with being harassed when framing<br />

an alternative view.


394 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

That really is the distinction to address. I think I may go and reread the documents that<br />

Hans linked us to on etiquette, but I believe it is important to note whether you are passing the<br />

line on harassing the person you are ‘discussing’ things with. Keep in mind that a discussion<br />

takes two people, and the point <strong>of</strong> having two points <strong>of</strong> view is to enrich the debates by the<br />

meeting <strong>of</strong> the two sides. If this enrichment isn’t occurring then something is wrong.<br />

Hopefully I didn’t <strong>of</strong>fend anyone with the clip from the forums. I figure you can find it<br />

anywhere so it wasn’t inappropriate to post, I apologize if I was mistaken in that.<br />

Message [337] referenced by [355] and [356]. Next Message by Spawnblade is [390].<br />

[354] Chris: here’s my expression <strong>of</strong> free speech. In reference to Bar’s [330] I would<br />

like to say that yes, people do have a right to say whatever they would like without having to<br />

apologize. However I would like to point out that no one to my knowledge asked CousinIt to<br />

apologize and as a person with common sense I don’t quite find this contradiction he posted<br />

as an apology: “I apologize if I make you angry or uncomfortable. I really don’t care how<br />

upset you are.” That’s nice CousinIt, the feeling is mutual. Just like he decided himself to<br />

say whatever he wanted to, so did those who posted rhetoric against him. And obviously, so<br />

am I. The door swings both ways. Another thing I would like to point out is that just because<br />

people have the right to say whatever they want, doesn’t mean they ought to sound like an<br />

idiot doing it. There are many ways to post discussions on forums and in class with respect<br />

and dignity to their fellow classmates. I personally feel that people on this email forum are<br />

not upset at certain classmates’ views but upset at their lack <strong>of</strong> respect towards others. I find<br />

it disheartening. Am I <strong>of</strong>fended? Absolutely not. Do I come on here and find relentless<br />

bantering at all mind changing? Absolutely not. Like someone noted a few postings ago,<br />

any attempt by some <strong>of</strong> you to change others’ minds has long been thrown down the drain.<br />

Start over because this is beginning to remind me <strong>of</strong> some Jr. High/High School rantings<br />

and no, that’s not a compliment.<br />

Message [354] referenced by [356]. Next Message by Chris is [355].<br />

[355] Chris: my last posting on free speech. Just one last thing that I would like to say<br />

while we are still talking about free speech. I would just like to say thank you to Spawnblade<br />

for posting [337]. I feel that he really hit the point I was hoping to say, but he said it much<br />

better. Thank you also for the example and for noting internet etiquette.<br />

Message [355] referenced by [356]. Next Message by Chris is [418].<br />

[356] CousinIt: Focus on issues. In reponse to [355] [354] [337] .... etc. etc. and so on<br />

and so on....<br />

Bar [330] has it right! In the ensuing discursive battle over who has been naughty and<br />

rude, those who continually refuse to address the issues I have raised are the same ones who<br />

accuse me <strong>of</strong> attacking people, in the same breath that they are attacking me! I have never<br />

once named someone by pseudonym or aimed any <strong>of</strong> my comments at a specific individual.<br />

I aim to destroy absurd attitudes and crass notions <strong>of</strong> entitlement. I have nonetheless become<br />

the scapegoat for people who want to discredit without addressing the issues that are alluded<br />

to in Capital, by the way, that I have raised repeatedly, in the absence <strong>of</strong> any well-thoughtout<br />

rebuttals on the same issues. Everyone is only interested in making CousinIt say things<br />

in a way that is comfy-cozy....“CousinIt this and CousinIt that and etc. etc.” How about<br />

addressing the real “issues,” as you all are paying lip-service to doing?


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 395<br />

Initially, I criticized the notion that any politics-as-usual operating within the framework<br />

<strong>of</strong> corporo-fascist capitalism will have any effect at all on the fact that we do not control<br />

our lives, that we are compelled by the commodity to comply (even if this means destroying<br />

the environment) and that capitalism is all about exploitation <strong>of</strong> the less privileged in the<br />

world so that a few can have more than they will ever need in 100 lifetimes, and that it will<br />

stop at nothing, including genocide, murder, environmental destruction, and calandestinism<br />

to achieve its goals and maintain its hegemony.<br />

None <strong>of</strong> these issues have been addressed by subsequent postings, nor, unfortunately and<br />

according to the restriction <strong>of</strong> discourse in American political debate, will they be addressed<br />

by the candidates for president (John Edwards being the possible exception, but, to the relief<br />

<strong>of</strong> the capitalist, he has gone away for the moment).<br />

There are many words in the Engllish language and none <strong>of</strong> them are useless. Certain<br />

words are able to say certain things. In some cases, no other words will do the job. If I have<br />

<strong>of</strong>fended people by my sense <strong>of</strong> humor, my criticism <strong>of</strong> attitudes/positions that I find equally<br />

as <strong>of</strong>fensive as any words could ever be, and my crude descriptions <strong>of</strong> the ugly world that<br />

capital is making for us, they might consider that humor and black comedy are important<br />

critical tools. They might ask themselves why they are so violently <strong>of</strong>fended.<br />

No one has commented on the illustration <strong>of</strong> the deep-seatedness <strong>of</strong> denial and demonstration<br />

<strong>of</strong> occupational psychosis that these discursive exchanges have effectively elicited<br />

from those screaming the loudest in defense <strong>of</strong> the current system., who continually hide<br />

behind an attempt to control the discourse in a direction that lets them wiggle out <strong>of</strong> addressing<br />

the issues as they have been continually raised (and ritually ignored). This is what<br />

people do who can’t come up with rebuttals that are anything but the same old parroting <strong>of</strong><br />

the discourse they learn to memorize and recite on the capitalist-owned TV, radio, and their<br />

printed counterparts in crime....i.e., the propaganda leg <strong>of</strong> the capitalist behemoth.<br />

If you are defending capitalism and the current political system that protects and maintains<br />

it, then you are defending genocide, murder, exploitation, and environmental irresponsibility.<br />

Sorry, I don’t know how to put that politely. At least do us all the service <strong>of</strong> coming<br />

up with valid intelligent arguments for defending such a system, rather than waste everyone’s<br />

time quibbling over etiquette. Even Adolf Hitler at least did that. The ‘etiquette’ <strong>of</strong><br />

capital’s ‘polite society’ has ended and destroyed the lives <strong>of</strong> many people, communities,<br />

and families throughout its history. The demand for ‘polite speech’ has effectively silenced<br />

many dissenters to many criminal programs....just a few examples <strong>of</strong> the dangers <strong>of</strong> ‘polite’<br />

speech. I do find the feigned politeness <strong>of</strong> current political discourse very very personally<br />

<strong>of</strong>fensive, indeed.<br />

There is a very interesting discussion <strong>of</strong> environmental irresponsibility that is seemingly<br />

beyond our power to address going on in parallel to the continual whining about etiquette<br />

some <strong>of</strong> us are obsessed with.<br />

Address the issues, please! I beg you!<br />

Enlighten me to the wonders and the beauty <strong>of</strong> the corporo-fascist system you are determined<br />

to defend, rather than trying to discipline my right to speak out against it, even to<br />

point out things that I find ridiculously <strong>of</strong>fensive to our intelligence and our humanity. My


396 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

ridicule is reasoned and purposeful, whether you think it is or not, and is about addressing<br />

issues, attitudes, and illuminating absurdities, not “getting at” the people behind them. They<br />

can’t help themselves and I know this. I do not blame them but the structural facts <strong>of</strong> the<br />

society that they live in. If you see yourself in the cynically-laced cartoons I am painting<br />

such that you feel the violent compulsion to attack me for saying so, is that my fault? Isn’t it,<br />

rather, something you might benefit from reflecting upon? Where does this undying devotion<br />

to the Imperial machine come from? Ever wonder why you think what you do? I do...You<br />

are not the capitalist, but the exploited proletariat. Yet, you are dead-set on defending your<br />

oppressor. Is that not a glaring contradiction? Doesn’t that seem very very odd to you? It<br />

does, to me.<br />

Yes! Issues, issues, issues, please.....anytime you’re ready....I am still waiting....<br />

Next Message by CousinIt is [397].<br />

[363] Goethe: NO FUN!!! The postings from the past week have been very interesting,<br />

and entertaining! CousinIt seems to have some very strong opinions about the realities <strong>of</strong><br />

human existence. I must agree with the majority <strong>of</strong> what has been posted. Capitalism has<br />

reached its point <strong>of</strong> diminishing return..... We truly live in a world where supply powers<br />

demand. I have been a student <strong>of</strong> economics for less than a year so these ideas are all new<br />

to me, I keep an open mind and an open heart as I weigh and consider all that I absorb.<br />

Was Marx on to something? I think that his ideas (what I have read so far) are logical,<br />

and he was a man ahead <strong>of</strong> his time. A comment was made to me the other day about Marx<br />

being the father <strong>of</strong> communism... I am curious <strong>of</strong> the class’s opinion on this!! Communism<br />

as we know it exploits human rights, participated in genocide, and is ruled by a central<br />

dictator. The father <strong>of</strong> this was Joseph Stalin!!! CounsinIt is correct that our current system<br />

“maintains genocide, murder, exploitation, and environmental irresponsibility.” But it is not<br />

the fault <strong>of</strong> the system, it is human nature that is doing this. And the reality is that it will not<br />

stop until it is too late....<br />

Our system is not perfect but we still go to Wal-mart and buy the cheap electronics that<br />

have been manufactured by third world workers with their pain and suffering. We will<br />

continue to consume; we must, the foundation <strong>of</strong> the world depends on our consumption.<br />

It does not matter if we need stuff as long as we go out and buy it. Capitalist, Socialist or<br />

Communist; we are in a global economy and the actions <strong>of</strong> one country affect all others.<br />

I appreciate your humor Cousinit and I do get it... I also see that you are too intelligent to<br />

believe that capitalism is the root <strong>of</strong> all evil. As you stated “man is evil” for it is man (and<br />

women) that is the root <strong>of</strong> the problems we all face.<br />

So what to do? We can take the Thoreauian approach and go out, live <strong>of</strong>f the land and<br />

produce for ourselves the basic necessities. That would be no fun!!!<br />

“No fun to hang around<br />

Feelin’ that same old way<br />

No fun to hang around<br />

Freaked out for another day” -Stooges


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 397<br />

:)<br />

Message [363] referenced by [397] and [2012fa:560]. Next Message by Goethe is [438].<br />

[367] Brody: In response to CousinIt. I personally agree with CousinIt [312] as far as<br />

solutions coming from debate and passionate discussion, but cousinit must present at least a<br />

start to a solution. To continually whine about capitalism and not have at least a suggestion<br />

to the start <strong>of</strong> something or the presentation <strong>of</strong> an idea is to do the same thing as those<br />

caught in the debate over etiquette. It is just more noise and whining. One thing i do not<br />

understand about cousinit’s argument on capitalism being environmentally harmful is; how<br />

can you blame that on capitalism specifically and not on mere human nature? China now<br />

runs on a socialist economy and has been one <strong>of</strong> the worst countries as far as pollution goes.<br />

it was a closed communist economy and still managed to help destroy the environment.<br />

Furthermore many cases <strong>of</strong> genocide are not in capitalist countries and are in countries<br />

that do not thrive from other capitalist economies, i.e. North Korea. To blame the worlds<br />

problems on capitalism is not really looking for a solution, it is only using it as a scapegoat.<br />

what cousinit does to capitalism is what he/she has stated that he/she feels others are doing<br />

to him/her in the discussion on internet ettiquette.<br />

I feel capitalism is an economic system built for survival <strong>of</strong> the strongest. Robert Green<br />

brings this to light in “48 Laws <strong>of</strong> Power”. Corporate culture is built on power and the pursuit<br />

<strong>of</strong> power, society in general and values forged from Christianity have helped to strip us<br />

<strong>of</strong> our desire for power and taught us that it is bad or evil when it is merely natural. What<br />

i feel cousinit is saying is that society should help everyone or that nobody should have the<br />

power that is brought forth by capitalism. This will never happen because people are selfish<br />

and more concerned with themselves than others, and society has once again tried to teach<br />

us that this is bad that selfishness is bad and that we should protect the meek and mild because<br />

they can not protect themselves or create legitimate power for themselves. Capitalism<br />

does the most good for the most people in everyone doing what is best for themselves and<br />

according to Adam Smith the invisible hand evens everything out. another example <strong>of</strong> a<br />

system other than capitalism failing is in russia in the 1970’s and 80’s the products created<br />

in the communist economy were <strong>of</strong> such poor quality that economy failed.<br />

so for cousinit i would recommend that if you want to have a discussion and or debate<br />

on how you feel capitalism harms the things you are claiming it harms, then come up with<br />

some facts and specific examples to help others participate in your wanted debate. what<br />

politician enters a debate with the same mundane argument that something is being hurt<br />

without some sort <strong>of</strong> idea for bettering that issue? According to your last posting you feel<br />

that you don’t need to present one, but if that is the case you are not helping to facilitate a<br />

debate or discussion on the issue you are concerned with. This will cause your arguments to<br />

merely be perceived as pointless bantering.<br />

Good luck with your future debates as to the harmful effects <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

Love Brody<br />

Message [367] referenced by [397] and [404]. Next Message by Brody is [742].<br />

[373] Jeremy: Leveling the playing field. What purpose is served by leveling the playing<br />

field? In the United States, as it is today, we are becoming obsessed with the idea that<br />

fairness is a right granted to every individual. I would like to cite the current mortgage crisis


398 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

as one <strong>of</strong> many examples <strong>of</strong> leveling the field. This year, if left untouched by outside forces,<br />

the United States will experience more foreclosures and bankruptcies than any year to date.<br />

Some people gasp at the idea that hundreds <strong>of</strong> thousands <strong>of</strong> people will lose the ro<strong>of</strong> over<br />

their head. Others will balk at the thought <strong>of</strong> interest rate hikes experienced until the recent<br />

months. Then you will have those people who just don’t care what is going on in the housing<br />

market.<br />

The question I would like to pose is, “Did anyone see this coming?” If not, your eyes<br />

were closed, your ears were plugged, and you must have been sitting in a dark room. Over<br />

the past four to five years, the housing market has experienced unprecedented double-digit<br />

increases on a consistent basis. That is not sustainable over the long haul. Locally, a house<br />

that was $100,000 in the year 2002 would easily have fetched $150,000 towards the end <strong>of</strong><br />

2006. This was great if you owned a home, but woeful if you were looking to buy. Every<br />

time in history that the market has ballooned in a similar manner, there has always been<br />

a deflation <strong>of</strong> that same balloon... we’re deflating now. In <strong>Utah</strong>, we are lucky because the<br />

increases tended to be on the lower end <strong>of</strong> the pricing scale because our housing market is on<br />

a different level than say California, Florida, etc. During this balloon deflation period, these<br />

people have lost more in home value than most <strong>of</strong> our homes cost. Here lies the problem.<br />

Because <strong>of</strong> such a rush to get in on the buying game, we seem to have checked common<br />

sense at the door. Adjustable Rate Mortgages (ARM’s), sub-prime lending, even PMI evading<br />

has become all too prevalent. People saw opportunity and decided that it was time to up<br />

the risk to make a buck. The common term “predatory lending” is now being thrown around<br />

to explain the crisis. Very few people going through the housing crunch have been preyed<br />

upon. Drawing upon personal experience, when signing papers for a mortgage, the numbers<br />

are laid out in front <strong>of</strong> you. Before you sign any paper, you have the option to read it, or better<br />

yet, most mortgage companies have someone there to explain what has been written. If<br />

you have an ARM, the rate schedule is explained and potential payments are covered. There<br />

is little deception in mortgages due to past legislation and the concept <strong>of</strong> ethical lending.<br />

What we have now are people that couldn’t truly afford the home that they entered into<br />

a contract to purchase, so now comes the time to jump ship. Because people are sheepish<br />

together, many people are in this predicament. What happens when people gather... they<br />

gain attention, and it just happens to be the media and government they are influencing<br />

to get their way. Because <strong>of</strong> ignorance, these people are now able to skirt their payments,<br />

default on loans, or lock in lower rates all in order to avoid what they should have never done<br />

in the first place... buy something they couldn’t afford. The government will once again step<br />

in to bail out the private sector. Mortgage companies rolled the dice with their risky lending<br />

and came up a loser. If you increase your risk in Las Vegas and come up a loser, you are out<br />

as much as you bet. The type <strong>of</strong> capitalistic society that is preached is rarely practiced, and<br />

this is just one more example <strong>of</strong> it. Other examples are the bailout <strong>of</strong> credit card companies<br />

two years ago, automobile manufactures being given grants to sustain pr<strong>of</strong>itability every<br />

year, increasing needless government spending <strong>of</strong> tax dollars around every corner to cover<br />

the market in one way or another, oh yeah, and the Federal Reserve adjusting rates to correct<br />

what businesses have done wrong.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 399<br />

Competition is good, but it creates a loser now and then. As a society, we need to accept<br />

that some people or companies will lose. We can’t always be found coddling the masses or<br />

we will be weakened as a whole in the end.<br />

Message [373] referenced by [399]. Next Message by Jeremy is [378].<br />

[390] Spawnblade: Immigration, the Economy, and You. And once more immigration<br />

is swamping the paper as people moan and groan on both sides <strong>of</strong> the argument. Legalize<br />

all immigrants?! Blasphemous! Deport all immigrants?! Blasphemous! Can they not come<br />

to some sort <strong>of</strong> decision, oh I don’t know... -compromise-?! Our government seems not to<br />

know the meaning <strong>of</strong> the word. Instead <strong>of</strong> compromising, they secretly set up deals to sell<br />

their votes to one another, seems inefficient. And in this situation, they can’t exactly sell<br />

their votes.<br />

So then we come to the reasons why I feel a deportation movement like those that are<br />

being initiated in some states is necessary:<br />

1. Illegal immigrants do not pay taxes.<br />

2. If you’ve ever known illegal immigrants, you’d know that many <strong>of</strong> them are not actually<br />

interested in staying in the United States. (Not so much from Cuba, but from other<br />

Latin American countries, specifically Mexico)<br />

3. Instead <strong>of</strong> staying in the US, they work night and day for 10 years, return to Mexico<br />

with $200,000 and purchase hotels or other major businesses that allow them to live in<br />

remarkably high comfort conditions. This is possible because <strong>of</strong> how much cheaper capital<br />

is there.<br />

4. Besides the eventual amount they have saved, they continuously send any extra money<br />

to their home country.<br />

5. Result: 80 wage hours <strong>of</strong> income per week is sent to another country and removed<br />

completely from the US economy, per person.<br />

Solution: I’ve heard people say Bush has proposed this, but I have not taken the time<br />

to check on the validity <strong>of</strong> these statements: Offer legalization for any illegal immigrant<br />

holding a job. Anyone who does not seek legalization should be deported because it is clear<br />

they either do not want to pay taxes (most if not all fall into this category.) or they wish to<br />

return to Mexico and they will not be able to as a citizen if they legalize themselves in the<br />

US.<br />

This provides the option for those who are hard workers and a contribution to the US<br />

economy, whereas those who are simply trying to abuse the system while damaging the<br />

economy and bolstering our lovely neighbor’s GDP (and potentially using medicare or other<br />

social services) would be sent back to the country they wish to return to anyway.<br />

Quicknotes version:<br />

If someone, anyone, wishes to benefit a country, they should be allowed to remain there<br />

and do so.<br />

If someone, anyone, wishes to simply use a country for their own benefit, the country has<br />

no reason to allow them to do so.


400 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Message [390] referenced by [400] and [414]. Next Message by Spawnblade is [413].<br />

[392] Rey: Generalziations involving Immigration, the Economy and You! I would<br />

suggest you broaden your association with illegal immigrants before you start running your<br />

mouth and generalizing! I myself have had a fair amount <strong>of</strong> experience with the matter.<br />

In fact I have seen the efforts my own sister had to go through to become a citizen <strong>of</strong> the<br />

United States. She was born in Guatemala and came to the United States legally when she<br />

was adopted into our family. She spent a good portion <strong>of</strong> her adult life fighting her way<br />

through the red tape that blocks hard working, ethical immigrants from becoming legal.<br />

Now I recognize this particular situation is somewhat different then the issue you seem to be<br />

addressing. I only reference it because I have seen the strain and effort that is necessary to<br />

become legal in this country, even when having pure intentions. In addition to my own sister<br />

I have met several hard working individuals who have a desire to do live their lives legally<br />

within the United States. Not to provide any excuses, but indeed provide understanding, the<br />

process is long and difficult. In fact I would venture to say most Americans couldn’t even<br />

pass the written exam necessary to become a legal citizen <strong>of</strong> the United States. Don’t get<br />

me wrong by no means am I an advocate for amnesty or open boarders, but I do believe<br />

a change needs to be made that will simply the process for “good intentioned” immigrants<br />

to become American Citizens. It is my experience that a majority <strong>of</strong> immigrants do have a<br />

desire to become legal, but they know that the process is long and expensive.<br />

In addition I think it to be a little extreme to think that the majority <strong>of</strong> illegal immigrants<br />

abuse the system in the manner you have described. I would challenge you to present a<br />

resource for your conclusion. Also the entire 80 hours <strong>of</strong> wages leaving the country is an<br />

absurd generalization once again, seeing as these individuals do have to have some means<br />

<strong>of</strong> living while they are here in the United States.<br />

Lastly while we are on the subject <strong>of</strong> stripping GDP from one country and injecting it to<br />

another country. I would suggest you do a little research along the lines <strong>of</strong> how the US has<br />

been able to change and distort foreign tax laws for the same purpose. One place to start<br />

would be to examine Paul Bremer’s (head <strong>of</strong> reconstruction in Iraq) Order #39.<br />

Although your “Quicknote” presents a logical case, your path to that conclusion is irrational<br />

and full <strong>of</strong> generalizations.<br />

Message [392] referenced by [413]. Next Message by Rey is [493].<br />

[395] Srichardson: Immigration. I see that there is a need for change in the way that we<br />

deal with immigration in this country. When reading both spawnblade and Reys comments<br />

I see myself siding with Rey on the point that it does need to be easier for immigrants to<br />

be legal. I also think that since most <strong>of</strong> us are econ majors it is important to look at the<br />

economical effect that these immigrants have on our nation. When Spawnblade says that<br />

illegal immigrants do not pay tax’s it reminded me <strong>of</strong> an article that I have read for another<br />

class, the Urban Institute put out a paper with the myths about illegal immigrants this is what<br />

they had to say about immigrants paying taxes<br />

Undocumented immigrants pay the same real estate taxes—whether they own homes or<br />

taxes are passed through to rents—and the same sales and other consumption taxes as everyone<br />

else. The majority <strong>of</strong> state and local costs <strong>of</strong> schooling and other services are funded by<br />

these taxes. Additionally, the U.S. Social Security Administration has estimated that three


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 401<br />

quarters <strong>of</strong> undocumented immigrants pay payroll taxes, and that they contribute $6–7 billion<br />

in Social Security funds that they will be unable to claim. Some <strong>of</strong> this information<br />

was from Porter, Eduardo. 2005. “Illegal Immigrants Are Bolstering Social Security with<br />

Billions.” New York Times, April 5.<br />

I think it is very important to think <strong>of</strong> these things when talking about immigration, while<br />

I know that there is different studies that say all different things about immigration but it is<br />

important to look into these things.<br />

Message [395] referenced by [400] and [413]. Next Message by Srichardson is [417].<br />

[397] CousinIt: The golden rule. In response to [367].<br />

The point <strong>of</strong> this course, as I understand it, is not to come up with the solution to capitalism,<br />

but to understand what capitalism is. How can we even begin to address the problems<br />

if, as a collective, we don’t even understand the material conditions <strong>of</strong> our own existence?<br />

(But we all know that Marx is just an evil ‘pinko’ and a raging lunatic, that’s why he is so<br />

easy to understand, huh?)<br />

The ‘human nature’ argument doesn’t really hold water. The term ‘human nature’ is just a<br />

‘stand-in’ term that we use to describe something that we cannot point to, define, or explicate<br />

sufficiently. Like ‘gravity,’ as a term we use as a stand in for something that we do not know<br />

exactly ‘what it is,’ we use ‘human nature’ to stand for something that we do not understand<br />

so that we can talk about things and make the kinds <strong>of</strong> claims made in [367] without being<br />

required to prove their validity. It is conventionally assumed that we all know what we are<br />

talking about and agree on a definition that does not exist when in reality, we really don’t<br />

know, but need to use the stand-in terms as provisional place-holders in order to move things<br />

along a particular path.<br />

I do not buy that it is ‘human nature’ to exploit and mow-over the weak and underprivileged<br />

any more than I believe that capitalism is the ‘natural’ pinnacle <strong>of</strong> human socioeconomic<br />

acheivement. To accept such absurdities as warrrant for the defense <strong>of</strong> capitalism<br />

is to say that we should just take anything we want anytime anywhere from anybody who<br />

isn’t strong enough to keep us from taking it. According to this plan we should mow-over<br />

the deaf, dumb, blind, physically/mentally handicapped, the sick, the poor, old people and<br />

children, take whatever we want from anyone who we are stronger than and deprive them <strong>of</strong><br />

things/social goods that they cannot secure for themselves and send them packing <strong>of</strong>f to hell<br />

for being less capable <strong>of</strong> violence and theft than we are. The frightening thing is that alot <strong>of</strong><br />

people with this kind <strong>of</strong> orientation to humanity, who imagine that they are capitalists also<br />

believe they are Christians, as well! Comical? ...or tragic?<br />

Guess what the precursory socio-economic conditions to Hitler’s fascism were.....?<br />

To use forms <strong>of</strong> state-capitalism (like China and Russia) as examples to warrant some<br />

notion that socialism is a failed concept is as absurd (to the educated socialist) as saying<br />

that apples are not apples because they aren’t oranges. Not only do we need to understand<br />

capitalism, but also alternative forms. For example, some folks don’t know that socialism<br />

isn’t socialism unless everyone is doing it, which has never been tried.<br />

Why can’t socialism succeed as an economic system without everyone doing it?


402 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Because it will do things not just for pr<strong>of</strong>it, but because they are the right things to do,<br />

which sometimes ends up costing money in the name <strong>of</strong> social gains, rather than produciing<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>it. It doesn’t base its notions <strong>of</strong> prosperity and social wealth on theft and exploitation<br />

and will therefore always be outrun by capitalism that doesn’t pause to consider such trivialities<br />

as collective well-being for all living creatures (That would be a weakness according<br />

to the ‘survival <strong>of</strong> the fittest’ crowd, I suppose). By the way, the Chinese have always been<br />

capitalist businessmen to some degree (This might also be some kind <strong>of</strong> response to [363]’s<br />

question about communism...we haven’t tried it yet because we can’t even get to the prerequisite<br />

socialism part, as <strong>of</strong> yet....the wall <strong>of</strong> ignorance is too thick and wide...).<br />

Try to imagine that only everyone in China and Russia (and not the rest <strong>of</strong> the world’s<br />

population) demand the same kind <strong>of</strong> standard <strong>of</strong> living/lifestyle that Americans have enjoyed<br />

and don’t want to have any restrictions on polluting the environment that Americans<br />

didn’t have during the initial stages <strong>of</strong> industrialization. Imagine that they want to be able to<br />

consume, pollute, and throw away garbage at the same rate as Americans do, including oil,<br />

food, water...everything. How far do you think that kind <strong>of</strong> stress on the planet’s resources<br />

can be sustained?<br />

I don’t need to know exactly what to do to know that what I am doing is wrong. I don’t<br />

need to have the right solution to know that the one I am attempting is failing.<br />

I wonder if Brody will be so fond <strong>of</strong> his ‘survival <strong>of</strong> the fittest’ theory/orientation to<br />

human relations when the Chinese call in the debt and decide to come and take from us what<br />

we aren’t strong enough to hold on to? Live by the sword, die by the sword. Haven’t we<br />

learned anything about what that kind <strong>of</strong> hard-guy cowboy knee-deep-in-bullstance gets us?<br />

Maybe not. Maybe it’s time we learned that lesson, eh?<br />

Ok, how about the ‘golden rule’ as a starting point for a solution? That is, “Do unto<br />

others as you would have them do unto you.”<br />

Gee, I wonder why those darn ‘terrorists’ hate us?<br />

Next Message by CousinIt is [446].<br />

[399] Bmellor: Destroying the playing field so no one can play? In response to [373]<br />

Leveling the playing field?<br />

In the attempt to “level the playing field” historical examples suggest you will instead<br />

destroy “the playing field” by putting up a fence that people do not want to “play with” or<br />

“around.” You can still make socialism-like policy in a capitalist society, proving that most<br />

socialist policy doesn’t work. It has been done before even here in the United States, and I<br />

am not talking about Social Security. Should the government force gas prices down if gas<br />

gets too expensive? Think about the fuel crisis <strong>of</strong> the 70’s... the government tried to control<br />

the prices and a shortage <strong>of</strong> fuel took place. In more recent history Hugo Chavez (a leftist<br />

capitalist) tried to make it government policy to control food prices. Good luck finding a<br />

place to buy milk or beef in Venezuela, his polict created a shortage <strong>of</strong> food. Markets have<br />

to make decisions for themselves they are a “living thing” like unto a wild beast. You cannot<br />

keep it caged within certain perimeters, should you do so the result will be a violent reaction<br />

or the system will curl up and die.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 403<br />

People must have incentives to work and produce, an “even playing field” doesn’t work.<br />

I have witnessed firsthand the horrible living conditions that the production <strong>of</strong> sugar has<br />

forced on the people in South America. I would go so far as to not buy sugar from the<br />

companies that treated those people I met that way, (good luck finding out where that sugar<br />

went.) Would I get on a plane to South America, touring the continent to encourage and<br />

convince those people to rise up against their “capitalist oppressor?” There was one man in<br />

recent history that tried to do just that, Ernesto “Che” Guevara. No doubt if you don’t know<br />

who Ernesto “Che” Guevara is, surely you have seen his chiaroscuro portrait on a t-shirt. Che<br />

took his (and Fidel Castro’s) socialist ideas across South America and ended in Bolivia. In<br />

Bolivia the people Che was trying to “free” turned on him, they wanted to live the way they<br />

had been living, under a capitalist system. The result? “Che” died in Bolivia. If people don’t<br />

like the way they are living in the conditions they are living it is the responsibilities <strong>of</strong> those<br />

who are being afflicted to fight to fix things. This was true <strong>of</strong> American steel workers <strong>of</strong> the<br />

past, and is still true <strong>of</strong> the coal miners in <strong>Utah</strong>. There are few who should get a government<br />

“hand out” and those are the disabled, the people who can’t physically or mentally work, the<br />

elderly, and young children. This is the only way to assure against “free riders.” That is as<br />

fair as you are going to get.<br />

“But what if I want to sit at home and play the guitar all day, or paint a picture instead <strong>of</strong><br />

going to the factory to work?” You can! If you’re good enough that someone wants to pay<br />

you for it. If not, you starve until you are good enough, or get a job at the factory. Then<br />

you can paint and play guitar in your free time. This is how we live, working is awful at<br />

times, but imagine the alternative. A revert back to primal living sounds just great, fresh air,<br />

mountain living until you think about how cold it is in the winter and 30-35 years old is your<br />

life expectancy.<br />

Next Message by Bmellor is [408].<br />

[400] Brandon: Immigration. In response to Srichardson [395] and Spawnblade [390].<br />

I think that Spawnblade started his argument correctly by stating the flaws with the two<br />

extreme proposals to regulate illegal immigration. Immediate legalization is unfair to the<br />

legal immigrant seeking work in the US by going through the proper channels only to lose<br />

that job to someone who jumped the fence and cut to the front <strong>of</strong> the line. Also, immediate<br />

deportation in this country would be a major strain on our economy as well as our resources<br />

(i.e., law enforcement, judicial system, etc).<br />

In [395] Srichardson implies that illegal immigrants in fact benefit our own economy<br />

through real estate taxes (which are paid by the landlords via rent) as well as contributing<br />

to the Social Security fund. However, the American taxpayer still has to pay the bill every<br />

time an illegal immigrant needs to seek medical care, put a child into the education system,<br />

or even during imprisonment.<br />

The Center for Immigration Studies filed a report that found that in 2002 alone, the<br />

illegal population created a fiscal deficit - at the federal level - <strong>of</strong> just over $10 billion<br />

(http://www.cis.org/articles/2004/fiscalexec.html). Keep in mind, this deficit is an after-tax<br />

report. This means that, even though they do pay “some” taxes, they are still a drain on the


404 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

taxpaying American or legal resident who must make up the difference. Here are a few items<br />

the report found:<br />

“1. Households headed by illegal aliens imposed more than $26.3 billion in costs on the<br />

federal government in 2002 and paid only $16 billion in taxes, creating a net fiscal deficit <strong>of</strong><br />

almost $10.4 billion, or $2,700 per illegal household.<br />

2. Among the largest costs are Medicaid ($2.5 billion); treatment for the uninsured ($2.2<br />

billion); food assistance programs such as food stamps, WIC, and free school lunches ($1.9<br />

billion); the federal prison and court systems ($1.6 billion); and federal aid to schools ($1.4<br />

billion).<br />

3. With nearly two-thirds <strong>of</strong> illegal aliens lacking a high school degree, the primary<br />

reason they create a fiscal deficit is their low education levels and resulting low incomes and<br />

tax payments, not their legal status or heavy use <strong>of</strong> most social services. (www.cis.org)”<br />

The other problem, as Spawnblade pointed out, is that most <strong>of</strong> the wages earned by illegal<br />

immigrants are sent back to their native country and benefit that country’s economy.<br />

I come from an immigrant family, my father left his home in Malaysia went to college<br />

in India, and eventually was <strong>of</strong>fered a job in the United States. He filed all the necessary<br />

paperwork, received a resident alien card and is now a permanent resident. Because <strong>of</strong> his<br />

actions, he pays all <strong>of</strong> his taxes and is able to benefit from many social programs that illegals<br />

may not. I understand the lines are currently long, primarily for Latin American immigrants,<br />

to be come a legal resident in US, but for some reason we feel that is valid cause for breaking<br />

our immigration and labor laws to accommodate these individuals who inevitably drain our<br />

economy. I do not buy the argument that “they do the work we don’t want to do”. That is a<br />

cop-out and an excuse which is fueling our already growing apathy in this country towards<br />

low-income labor. Trust me, if the illegal immigrants were never here, someone would be<br />

doing those jobs. They sure as hell would not be happy about it, but when you have to ‘put<br />

food on the table’, the job will be done.<br />

I do not have a great solution to this immigration problem, but I do have a solution and<br />

it has been presented many times. I know most <strong>of</strong> you have heard <strong>of</strong> this, but I will explain<br />

it in more detail using another country which already has utilized this method. The method<br />

being, guest worker program. I want to give a personal example <strong>of</strong> my Aunt Usha living in<br />

Malaysia. She is middle-class and married with two children. Like the U.S., many immigrants<br />

work in service industries and low-skilled labor and most <strong>of</strong> these immigrants come<br />

from Indonesia. The Malaysian government has <strong>of</strong>fices in hundreds <strong>of</strong> cities in Indonesia<br />

where a worker can apply for a worker’s card and will be assigned a job in Malaysia. Now<br />

in the case <strong>of</strong> my Aunt, she currently has a maid who performs all <strong>of</strong> the housekeeping<br />

duties, as well as, looking after the children while my Aunt and Uncle are at work (this is<br />

very common in South Asian countries). Bi-monthly my Aunt must pay her a fixed wage as<br />

determined by the government. However, she cannot pay the immigrant directly, instead she<br />

must send the check to the department <strong>of</strong> labor, who then takes out the necessary taxes such<br />

as medical, social security, etc., and then deposits the worker’s income in a bank account<br />

back in Indonesia. This is to ensure fair pay <strong>of</strong> the worker and also makes sure that proper<br />

taxes have been paid to the state.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 405<br />

Because <strong>of</strong> this system, there lacks an incentive for immigrants to smuggle themselves<br />

into the country to find work. They know that through their worker cards, they will receive<br />

fair, consistent wages, medical coverage, and will be able to support their families still living<br />

in their native country. When their time <strong>of</strong> work has expired, they will return to their<br />

country having made more money than could have ever been achieved without emigrating.<br />

Furthermore, they now have little cause to emigrate again, for they have been afforded the<br />

ability and experience to open their own business in their home country, hire local workers,<br />

and further benefit themselves and their economy.<br />

I am not saying this is the best solution, but it definitely fulfills all needs from both parties<br />

and creates mutually beneficial exchanges at both the individual and federal levels.<br />

Message [400] referenced by [402] and [414]. Next Message by Brandon is [414].<br />

[402] PrivateProperty: Immigration. Brandon [400] cites a report by the Center for Immigration<br />

Studies (CIS) in order to support the argument that illegal immigrants are a drain<br />

on our economy. The figures are sobering, but do they mean anything? CIS is just another<br />

think tank, and like all think tanks, it exists for the advancement <strong>of</strong> someone’s agenda. In<br />

its mission statement the CIS says it “...seeks fewer immigrants but a warmer welcome for<br />

those admitted.” We all know that you can conduct studies in various ways in order to get<br />

the results you are looking for. Statistics can be vague, depending on the methodology used.<br />

I do not believe CIS for a second. If such a study were published by a State <strong>University</strong> or<br />

some independent task force without an agenda, then I would be willing to look at it more<br />

closely.<br />

Even if the data meant something, let’s take a step back here and ask ourselves a fundamental<br />

question: Who are we to be so stringent in deciding who can come into the country?<br />

The United States is a relatively young country, and only a few hundred years ago there<br />

was nobody but Native Americans picking berries up and down the Eastern Seaboard. Unless<br />

you are descended from Natives, you are in America today because <strong>of</strong> immigration. These<br />

immigrants came for the same reason Mexicans are immigrating illegally today, for a new<br />

life, for opportunity. The only reason we deem so many <strong>of</strong> these immigrants ‘illegal’ is that<br />

America has had over 300 years to develop institutions that continually serve to protect the<br />

pie at home.<br />

The ‘issue’ with illegal aliens in the country is really just a legal distinction and not much<br />

<strong>of</strong> an issue at all. The real problems lie with how these people are socialized into America.<br />

If anything, these people need to be treated with more respect and openness. It is not right<br />

for these individuals to be relegated to the fringes <strong>of</strong> society. While it is the duty <strong>of</strong> illegals<br />

to integrate themselves better into US society, it is also the duty <strong>of</strong> the American people and<br />

government to make this integration easier.<br />

Message [402] referenced by [413] and [414]. Next Message by PrivateProperty is [404].<br />

[403] Bar: Capitalism. Marxists, Communists, and Socialists all say that the system is<br />

broken, and for the most part, they say the system is broken without giving any ideas to<br />

how to solve the problems associated with replacing capitalism. I am a capitalist and believe<br />

that this system eventually will solve all <strong>of</strong> the problems in society through technology. For<br />

example, Capital in every aspect, will become so efficient, practical, and cheap, that almost<br />

all manual labor will be eliminated. An evidence <strong>of</strong> this is how the majority <strong>of</strong> jobs in our


406 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

society have already gone from labor intensive to capital intensive, look at farmers where<br />

in colonial times the majority <strong>of</strong> people were farmers; only 1% <strong>of</strong> Americans are farmers<br />

today. In addition, less and less people work in manufacturing jobs, the majority <strong>of</strong> people<br />

45% work in service information industries now. Food, is abundant in the world and cheap(if<br />

socialist farmers didn’t rip <strong>of</strong>f America with farm subsidies would be so much cheaper)<br />

and the only reason famines exist in areas <strong>of</strong> Africa and other underdeveloped countries<br />

is because <strong>of</strong> market inefficiencies and corrupt governments. Capitalism is ever evolving;<br />

it becomes more efficient and solves many problems that government cannot solve. For<br />

example, the fallacious idea that capitalism hurts the environment or it’s the systems fault<br />

for problems in the environment is by far, the dumbest, 1-dimentional argument I have every<br />

heard, and I am dumber for having entertained the idea. The market doesn’t create choices<br />

and preferences it reflects the tastes and preferences <strong>of</strong> society as a whole. Just because<br />

someone sells it doesn’t mean you have to buy it, and if you didn’t buy it, the market would<br />

stop selling it.<br />

I argue that capitalism is good for the environment because <strong>of</strong> the simple principle <strong>of</strong><br />

inferior goods and substitute goods. The best example <strong>of</strong> this is the new hybrid cars and<br />

flexfuel cars, and alternative fuel. These thing were talked about for years, and we’ve know<br />

about the problems <strong>of</strong> global warming for years, but the problem has not been addressed<br />

until oil increased from $1 in the nineties(when gas companies barley made any pr<strong>of</strong>it at all)<br />

to $3+(where everybody has a heart attack because they finally turn a pr<strong>of</strong>it) The market is<br />

solving the problem <strong>of</strong> carbon emissions not through regulation, not because the government<br />

put a gun to my head and said don’t use oil or I’ll kill you, but because <strong>of</strong> an increase<br />

in demand for oil. Education on the matter even has changed our tastes and preferences:<br />

recycling, conserving electricity, using our car less is working and companies are filling<br />

this demand with, for example, new more efficient light bulbs. These changes have taken<br />

place with little or no obligation from the government, granted a new car gas regulation was<br />

recently passed, but these changes had already taken place, the government is already behind<br />

on everything and some actually want to increase the size <strong>of</strong> government?<br />

Since the industrial revolution, the standard <strong>of</strong> living has increased in almost every country<br />

in the world, medical advances and the average life expectancy has increased more than<br />

any other time in the world. Knowledge and technology increase at an exponential rate. All<br />

this is due to Capitalism since the industrial revolution; in that short amount <strong>of</strong> time all these<br />

great and wonderful things have taken place. Not under feudalism (which has many similar<br />

characteristics to socialism and communism) and mercantilism, which used central planning<br />

in the government to control trade. The reason that these things have happened under capitalism<br />

is because capitalism creates a more equitable economy and more freedom through<br />

choice, yeah you heard me right Marxists, more equitable!<br />

I challenge all the socialists in this class to prove me wrong, by not attacking capitalism,<br />

but by showing how socialism would be better than capitalism in the following areas:<br />

Free Rider Problems<br />

Special Interest Groups (you can’t just say, “get rid <strong>of</strong> corporations” that’s not a solution;<br />

replace it with what?)


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 407<br />

Freedom (when everything is centrally planned how you can lessen corruption and government<br />

Stalinism for example)<br />

Incentives the workforce to work productively<br />

Message [403] referenced by [404]. Next Message by Bar is [765].<br />

[404] PrivateProperty: Capitalist Competition: An Unnecessary Struggle. I think it is<br />

a moronic paradigm to separate our arguments into a Capitalism v. Marxism battle in which<br />

there can only be one victor. It is not a zero-sum game like many <strong>of</strong> us think. The current<br />

framework we live in is Capitalism, and there is no point in denying or resisting that fact.<br />

That being said, as no system is perfect, what harm can there be in seeing what Marxism has<br />

to <strong>of</strong>fer?<br />

Capitalism is a necessary phase <strong>of</strong> the human condition, and it has produced spectacular<br />

results. As Bar mentions in [403], the institutions <strong>of</strong> capitalism have played an important<br />

role in the development <strong>of</strong> technology and explosions in productivity growth across a wide<br />

number <strong>of</strong> industries, as well as the spawning <strong>of</strong> new ones. However, there comes a time<br />

when it is necessary to pause, take a step back, and ask why the system does what it does.<br />

Capitalism is a system in which the market is the dominant institution, and all other institutions<br />

are clustered around it. This might surprise some, but capitalism is a relatively new<br />

phenomenon in human history. It evolved out <strong>of</strong> mercantilist practices <strong>of</strong> European powers<br />

from the 1500-1700s. Prior to these developments, an economy was a socially relegated<br />

institution. Social relations determined who supplied what and what prices were charged.<br />

Most everything was produced in individual households. Compared to our current production<br />

in America, this system was wildly inefficient. With time it would be necessary for<br />

a new system to evolve, which indeed came with the Industrial Revolutions in the 1800s,<br />

bringing production away from households and consolidating it into the factory system we<br />

recognize today. Now America has a GDP no one would have thought possible.<br />

The stark truth is that capitalism today is a sick and violent way <strong>of</strong> relating with your<br />

fellow man. Each one <strong>of</strong> us is caught up with his or her individual struggle to survive in the<br />

jungle that is the US economy. With all the advancements we have made, one would think<br />

that our society would also be more integrative and cohesive. Instead, we find ourselves vying<br />

for position in corporate America, where one’s success <strong>of</strong>ten comes at another’s expense.<br />

Competition not only has significance in business parlance, but extends into our social relations,<br />

our very existence. Competition is tension, pain, and suffering, mediated through<br />

business. Our system is fundamentally violent.<br />

Brody in [367] asserts that it is human selfishness that creates capitalism. However, it is<br />

capitalism that creates human selfishness. People are not choosing to be one way or another.<br />

It is the pre-existing structure that determines the behavior <strong>of</strong> the people. If we happened to<br />

live in a society that reinforced social cohesion and cooperation, we would be acting in quite<br />

different ways.<br />

It is very hard, some would say impossible, to detach ourselves from the very system we<br />

grew up in. But this detachment, this true awareness <strong>of</strong> our social relations, is necessary in<br />

order for change to take place.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [447].


408 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[413] Spawnblade: “Generalizations” on Immigration revisited. The following post is<br />

brought to you by: “Line breaks and paragraph spacing are your friends.”<br />

And now to continue:<br />

I would like to begin by responding to Rey’s [392] post, and perhaps “run my mouth” a<br />

bit more.<br />

The first comment <strong>of</strong> note is “I myself have had a fair experience with the matter. In<br />

fact I have seen the efforts my own sister had to go through to become a citizen <strong>of</strong> the<br />

United States.” Then continues to explain that she was born in Guatemala and came to the<br />

US legally.<br />

Yes Rey, this situation is completely different. I believe that makes her legal, yes? As you<br />

said. Now you say there was a remarkable amount <strong>of</strong> strain and effort to become legal. Yes,<br />

yes there is. Should there be? No, no there shouldn’t.<br />

I believe in my post I stated that the current system is not fair to illegal immigrants,<br />

since really legal immigrants aren’t a concern, are they? My post suggested a method <strong>of</strong><br />

legalizing illegal immigrants, the ones that benefit our economy. Now does it even matter if<br />

I were to actually specify a particular percentage <strong>of</strong> the population? No, not really, because<br />

I generalized and said anyone that will pay taxes and work for the betterment <strong>of</strong> our society<br />

deserves to be a citizen.<br />

Yet for some reason you bashed my ‘generalization’ and went on to speak <strong>of</strong> the difficulties<br />

<strong>of</strong> becoming legal, etc... Did you read my post? I will assume so, but your post really<br />

indicates that you stopped at the header where I presented the current debate.<br />

Do I think that anyone that isn’t willing (They do not have to be presently) to contribute to<br />

the country should be deported? Yes. Does this include people who are willing to go through<br />

a standardized legalization process if a system were to be implemented? No, I would very<br />

much like to have people with such a work ethic in our society, it could only be a benefit<br />

to us. I believe I made this quite clear despite my animosity towards those who abuse the<br />

system. And I would like to point out any statistics that I could find for you on how many<br />

actually would or would not pay taxes are pointless. If they were to survey every illegal<br />

immigrant, that would require knowing who was illegal or legal, and furthermore would<br />

require the person to tell the truth. I base my analysis on word <strong>of</strong> mouth on a second-hand<br />

basis from managers in the food industry.<br />

If you didn’t have to pay taxes, would you?<br />

Please next time read my post, and if you did and I simply didn’t clarify my words enough,<br />

then I apologize and I will try to make it more obvious next time.<br />

In regards to Srichardson [395], I wish to clarify that I would like legalization to be<br />

possible for illegal immigrants. As far as legalization in general, I haven’t looked into that<br />

so I am unaware <strong>of</strong> the difficulties.<br />

However in response to the points on real estate tax/sales tax/SS tax, these are very good<br />

points, and I shall address them individually:


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 409<br />

1. Real estate - Generally illegal immigrants live collectively. That is they live in large<br />

family-like communities with 15 or so compromising a condominium or multiple cells near<br />

each other in other residential housing. IE. three condos each with 2-3 times the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

people that might normally live there. I searched for exact statistics with no luck, so I’m<br />

basing my knowledge on prior/outdated tv news reports from the deportation policies that<br />

were put into place in Florida (I believe.)<br />

2. Sales Tax - Yep, don’t have much to say on this one. It is a good point, except for the<br />

states that don’t have a sales tax. Though generally no sales tax means a higher real estate<br />

tax.<br />

3. Social Security Tax - We know at least 6.2% is taken from the employers for their<br />

wages. I -believe- most businesses have the amounts automatically taken from the employees<br />

pay checks as well. However, is that -always- the case, is it required by law? And luckily<br />

Srichardson answered this by noting that it is estimated three quarters pay these taxes.<br />

In regards to that though, assuming all illegal immigrants pay 6.2, and their employers<br />

pay 6.2, that would be 12.4% <strong>of</strong> their total wages. Now taking the figures that Srichardson<br />

provided: 6-7 billion in social security.for 3/4s <strong>of</strong> illegal immigrants. We can figure the total<br />

income from a third party’s information (to address PrivateProperty’s concern <strong>of</strong> using the<br />

CIS studies.) to be 64.5-75.3 billion.<br />

So according to a reverse engineer <strong>of</strong> the Social Security Administrations figures on “Social<br />

Security Boosting”, the U.S. is receiving 6-7 billion in social security, and having 58-69<br />

billion disappear. A safe estimate is that 30-35 billion is siphoned to other countries. Though<br />

it is clear that the benefits to children that are born here are quite straining on the economy<br />

as well. However I personally don’t have a problem with -that- since I believe those losses<br />

are an investment for the future.<br />

Lastly I would like to respond to PrivateProperty’s [402] comments on the validity <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Center for Immigration Studies. Assuming that CIS is wrong, I simply wished to readdress<br />

the data from the “Social Security Boosting” article that was initially written to be proimmigration,<br />

or at least to give the ‘bright side’ <strong>of</strong> things. I would also like to add that<br />

statistics from third parties that require surveys are just as useless as potentially biased data.<br />

In response as to why we shouldn’t just allow anyone in the country... I used to ask myself<br />

that question, until I realized just how many people would like to come to the U.S. I imagine<br />

our country’s population could jump 10% within two years if that was allowed. I believe the<br />

actual numbers would be much higher however. Thinking <strong>of</strong> the logistics problems is a pain<br />

as well since most <strong>of</strong> them would not be spread out across the country.<br />

In regards to the ‘hard’ factor <strong>of</strong> immigration. The system makes it quite easy for Western<br />

Europeans to come to this country and get citizenship. I imagine you could factor in<br />

Australians as well. I don’t have the actual statistics <strong>of</strong> the quotas, but if I recall the process<br />

is easier, and the allowed amounts are much higher. We spoke on this in history in high<br />

school, where the quotas were adjusted several times throughout history. I believe the last<br />

major adjustment occurred to prevent both “communists” and asians to come because <strong>of</strong> the<br />

fear <strong>of</strong> spies (due to World War II, and the subsequent Cold War... relations were obviously<br />

quite poor.) I could be wrong, and most likely an alteration has occurred since then. As far


410 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

as the latin american countries go (As to which this most applies,) my main belief is that the<br />

politicians who set the quotas simply don’t want people who aren’t like them from coming<br />

to this country.<br />

I personally believe we do in fact need quotas, but I believe they should be a percentage<br />

ratio to give people the ‘equal opportunity’ our country so promises.<br />

Now... time for bed.<br />

Next Message by Spawnblade is [437].<br />

[414] Brandon: Immigration. I thought initially I would give my two cents on this issue<br />

and move along, but I have to respond to this post.<br />

Respectfully, it seems to me that PrivateProperty [402] latched onto one element <strong>of</strong> my<br />

post regarding the data I used and disregarded the rest <strong>of</strong> what I had to say, which was really<br />

the essence <strong>of</strong> what I was trying to articulate (see second half <strong>of</strong> [400] ).<br />

We could go on and on regarding the “validity” <strong>of</strong> statistics and where they originate.<br />

Whether they are biased or not, or whether they came from a credible source <strong>of</strong> information.<br />

Agree or disagree with the Center for Immigration Studies’ mission statement, this is an<br />

organization which has devoted over 20 years to collecting data on immigration pertaining<br />

to the US and the effects caused by it (good and bad). If we are to say that there exists an<br />

organization that will conduct a study without any form <strong>of</strong> bias or agenda then we must be<br />

completly ignorant. Even at the <strong>University</strong> level there exist biased researchers and pr<strong>of</strong>essors<br />

who produce papers and data based around their own personal beliefs. It is so rare that we<br />

will ever find a statistic that is not biased.<br />

Ok, I’m done with that debate. I agree that the CIS may have an agenda but I do not<br />

discredit them. Nor do I discredit the report regarding illegal immigrants and their contributions<br />

to Social Security. However, we all use statistics to bolster our arguments, but the<br />

ones we use usually leave out other relevant data that may contradict them. Case in point,<br />

Srichardson’s source vs. mine.<br />

Moving on I want to address the issue in PrivateProperty’s comment:<br />

“Who are we to be so stringent in deciding who can come into the country? The United<br />

States is a relatively young country, and only a few hundred years ago there was nobody but<br />

Native Americans picking berries up and down the Eastern Seaboard.”<br />

This truly is apples and oranges (not that this cliché hasn’t been beaten to death in this<br />

class). I’m not trying to be callous here, but you are taking a moment in history where a<br />

group <strong>of</strong> people left their established, native countries to seek land where they could create<br />

their own communities, eventually nation(s). Yes there were Native Americans living on the<br />

continent when they arrived but this is not the same as if they were to land on an established<br />

piece <strong>of</strong> land that was under the rule <strong>of</strong> a sovereign nation. There did not exist a unified,<br />

regulated government entity that controlled the lands and had authority to grant or deny<br />

entry. (Obviously I am playing Devil’s advocate here from the perspective <strong>of</strong> the colonists.)<br />

The case today is that we live in a country that is civilized and has a intricate structure <strong>of</strong><br />

laws and regulations to protect our economy, as well as, our national security. To sit here<br />

and use the example <strong>of</strong>, ’well, we did it to the Native Americans so who are we to say the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 411<br />

illegals can’t come in’ is absurd. Was anyone here alive or commit any atrocities against<br />

Native Americans in the name <strong>of</strong> creating a sovereign state apart from England? No. I am<br />

so sick <strong>of</strong> people living in the past and using it as an excuse to deal with modern problems.<br />

We have a problem at hand regarding a massive inflow <strong>of</strong> illegal immigrants, which will<br />

only continue to rise unless some form <strong>of</strong> viable regulation is implemented. But for some<br />

reason we hide behind 300 year old ideology and actions as a way <strong>of</strong> trying to justify illegal<br />

actions <strong>of</strong> others in our ever growing P.C. world. I have already proposed what solutions I<br />

believe should be implemented [400] so I will not repeat it.<br />

Also, PrivateProperty states: “Unless you are descended from Natives, you are in America<br />

today because <strong>of</strong> immigration.” He’s right. I am first generation Malaysian-American <strong>of</strong><br />

Indian decent. However, somehow my dad was able to file the necessary papers, wait for<br />

the processes to clear their chain <strong>of</strong> command, and entered the country legally. He worked<br />

here legally for 30 years, paid his taxes, put his children through school, and gave them a<br />

better life than any Indian-blooded Malaysian can achieve in his native land. Sounds like the<br />

general motive <strong>of</strong> any immigrant right? However, as Spawnblade pointed out in [390] most<br />

current illegal immigrants from Latin America (primarily Mexico) have figured out that because<br />

<strong>of</strong> our flawed system <strong>of</strong> regulation, they can simply abuse our labor and immigration<br />

laws to support themselves and their families back home at the expense <strong>of</strong> US citizens and<br />

legal residents. THIS is the problem. I have no objection to anyone who has the courage<br />

to attempt to better their lives by leaving their home land to another that can provide more<br />

opportunities for themselves and their families. At the same time, if they are not willing to<br />

legally enter the latter country and abide by the laws <strong>of</strong> said nation, they have no right to<br />

enter or reside. I don’t think anyone would like it if I said, ‘my life sucks. my girlfriend<br />

beats me, she takes my money. my apartment sucks. The ceiling is cracked, the shower<br />

leaks, so I am going to break into your nice home, plop down in your spare bedroom, watch<br />

your big TV, and not even ask your permission to do these things nor will i pay my share <strong>of</strong><br />

rent.’ This is a crude argument, but I think it paints a pretty applicable picture.<br />

Ok, its 3:00 am and I’m sick <strong>of</strong> ranting. PrivateProperty, do not think I was in anyway<br />

trying to personally attack you, but simply the ideology <strong>of</strong> your post. I mean c’mon we’re<br />

group members right!? haha. g’night all.<br />

Message [414] referenced by [425]. Next Message by Brandon is [499].<br />

[420] Alex: Comments on immigration. Immigration has become such a devisive issue,<br />

there must be more to the subject than what is on the surfaces. National security has become<br />

a shield for the weak to hide behind. National security does not play into the real analysis<br />

<strong>of</strong> this divisive issue. National security is the only realistic argument that can be made for<br />

immigration. Economics is not means for discrimintation, immigrants are the backbone <strong>of</strong><br />

our economy.<br />

Those opposed to immigration need to state the real reasons: hate and class creation. If<br />

those opposed to immigration actually spoke the truth they talk about how they don’t want<br />

immigrants living in their neighborhoods and attending the same schools as their children.<br />

They would talk about how they think immigrants are inferior and should be kept out. Some<br />

nations have even taken discrimination to “scientific” levels. The Germans have long been<br />

strict on immigration. Hitler marked the way with his “studies” that showed the Jews were


412 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

inferior. Today Germany is still strict on immigration allowing very few to stay in the County<br />

for more than a few months.<br />

I wonder why so many are against letting others into the county. Borders, after all, were<br />

constructed by man in the first place.<br />

Message [420] referenced by [425]. Next Message by Alex is [436].<br />

[425] Matt: Illegal Immigration – a good thing? I agree with Brandon [414] that we<br />

Americans do indeed have the right to protect our borders from those coming over illegally.<br />

I loved Brandon’s example in his last paragraph that says, “. . . my apartment sucks. The<br />

ceiling is cracked, the shower leaks, so I am going to break into your nice home, plop down<br />

in your spare bedroom, watch your big TV, and not even ask your permission to do these<br />

things nor will I pay my share <strong>of</strong> rent.” We have the right to protect our borders just as much<br />

as we do our houses. We pay 30% <strong>of</strong> our paychecks in taxes so we can enjoy the society in<br />

which we have built.<br />

So why don’t we crack down on Illegal immigration by protecting our borders? The truth<br />

is we have. Even though the United States is protecting its borders by policing them, it is<br />

with minimal effects. Since the Mexico border is so large, most illegal immigrants take the<br />

small chance <strong>of</strong> being apprehended to have a chance at a better life by participating in our<br />

growing economy. Mexican farm workers are able to earn seven to ten times as much in the<br />

United States as at home. The truth is that Illegal Immigrants get jobs over native workers<br />

because they are willing to work for less causing our unemployment rates to increase.<br />

After doing some research I found an article by Adam Davidson, “Illegal Immigrants<br />

and the U.S. Economy”, that says the labor supply increased between 1980 and 2000 from<br />

immigration, which reduced the average annual earnings <strong>of</strong> U.S. citizen men by an estimated<br />

$1,700 or roughly 4 percent. And the impact was even larger for those born in the United<br />

States who did not graduate from high school (the poorest one-tenth <strong>of</strong> the work force)<br />

reducing wages by 7.4 percent. This reduction in earnings occurred regardless <strong>of</strong> whether<br />

the immigrants were legal or illegal. It is the presence <strong>of</strong> additional workers that reduces<br />

wages, not their legal status. So what would happen if we were to reduce the inflow <strong>of</strong> illegal<br />

immigrants? Well, according to Davidson it is predicted that a dramatic change would occur<br />

if illegal immigration is drastically truncated. “Supporters <strong>of</strong> a crackdown argue that the<br />

U.S. economy would benefit if illegal immigrants were to leave, because U.S. employers<br />

would be forced to raise wages to attract American workers. Critics <strong>of</strong> this approach say<br />

the loss <strong>of</strong> illegal immigrants would stall the U.S. economy, saying undocumented workers<br />

do many jobs few native-born Americans will do.” So as the supply <strong>of</strong> low-skilled workers<br />

increases causing wages to go down, we Americans benefit since we end up paying lower<br />

prices for things like; restaurant meals, agricultural produce and construction.<br />

A recent estimate from the Council <strong>of</strong> Economic Advisors was done, and as a whole,<br />

immigrants (not just illegal immigrants) add about $37 billion per year to the United States<br />

economy. Illegal immigrants add to our economy through the savings they provide through<br />

their low wages. They are willing to work just as hard as an American born citizen for less.<br />

If you were a farmer and you could hire me for $11.50 per hour or an Illegal immigrant for<br />

$7.50, who would you hire? That’s an easy question, right? You would hire the lower paying<br />

wage worker as it puts more money in your pocket. Agricultural economists have estimated


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 413<br />

that without illegal workers, the retail cost <strong>of</strong> fresh produce would increase about 3 percent<br />

in the summer-fall season and less than 2 percent in the winter-spring season.<br />

Illegal immigrants have carved a place for themselves as temporary workers on the fringes<br />

<strong>of</strong> the industry. In urban areas like New York and Los Angeles, these mostly male illegal<br />

immigrants gather on street corners, in empty lots to sell their labor by the hour or the day<br />

for $7-11 an hour. Because so many <strong>of</strong> our legal and illegal immigrant labor is concentrated<br />

in such fringe, low-wage employment, its overall impact on our economy is extremely small.<br />

A 1997 National Academy <strong>of</strong> Sciences study estimated that immigration’s net benefit to the<br />

American economy raises the average income <strong>of</strong> the native-born by only some $10 billion<br />

a year—about $120 per household. And that meager contribution is not the result <strong>of</strong> immigrants<br />

helping to build our essential industries or making us more competitive globally, but<br />

instead merely delivering our pizzas and cutting our grass. Illegal Immigrant workers certainly<br />

do take jobs that would otherwise go to legal workers. But these jobs are <strong>of</strong>ten some<br />

<strong>of</strong> the country’s least attractive, such as: meat packing, janitorial, construction and agriculture.<br />

If there weren’t workers available for those jobs, native born workers would have to do<br />

them. So by taking the jobs that we don’t want, they are actually giving Americans an economic<br />

boost by allowing us to focus on the highly skilled/ non-farm jobs. Illegal emigrants<br />

are doing more for our economy then we give them credit for, and I think we all owe them a<br />

little more respect then what has been shown. So as Alex says in [420], “immigrants are the<br />

backbone to our economy.”<br />

Next Message by Matt is [443].<br />

[433] Hans: Why does Obama seem to be rolling toward the White House? The<br />

following essay posted by Joaquin Bustelo to the Marxism list today gives probably some<br />

<strong>of</strong> the best thinking among Marxists and Progressives about the election campaign. I can<br />

recommend the Marxism list if you want to read about or discuss political issues from a<br />

Marxist angle. See<br />

Hans.<br />

http://www.marxmail.org/index.htm<br />

Here is Joaquin’s essay:<br />

Fred Feldman wrote:<br />

“It seems to me that sometime after Super Tuesday, a substantial sector <strong>of</strong><br />

the ruling class swung to the idea <strong>of</strong> giving Obama the Democratic nomination<br />

and electing him president? The campaign <strong>of</strong> Hilary Clinton, who<br />

seemed to have the mandate <strong>of</strong> heaven for quite a while, suddenly became<br />

like a doomed Lost Patrol.”<br />

“Super Tuesday could have been used by the mainstream to rev up the Clinton<br />

campaign and protect the basic status quo <strong>of</strong> bourgeois politics. After<br />

all, she won New York and California. How these things get interpreted<br />

allows room for the media barons to choose emphases. It did not have to be<br />

interpreted as a draw. Instead, they used it to set up the Clinton collapse.”


414 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

I think Fred’s description <strong>of</strong> deliberations by some ruling class collegium –even if meant<br />

only metaphorically– don’t do enough justice to the relative autonomy and randomness <strong>of</strong><br />

things in the week-to-week coverage <strong>of</strong> the presidential campaign. Especially when a disruptive<br />

element that breaks previous patterns enters the scene, like Barack Obama, and whatever<br />

swell from the deep he’s succeeded in riding in his campaign.<br />

Being involved in the coverage <strong>of</strong> super-Tuesday, I’ll tell you why so much <strong>of</strong> the tone<br />

on TV was pro-Obama. Because he won, and won well in places where he was expected to<br />

barely squeak by, and even in some he was expected to lose.<br />

California was Hillary’s sole bright spot. But California was the last state in having polls<br />

close (at 11 pm eastern). And the early exit poll results in California fit the pattern: they<br />

showed Obama losing, but by a narrow margin, doing better than expected. It was not until<br />

the final wave <strong>of</strong> the exit poll came in sometime after 11 pm Eastern that it started to become<br />

clear that Obama would not do better than expected in California, but it was only AFTER<br />

adjustment based on actual precinct results, which didn’t take place until two or three hours<br />

later, that the full extent <strong>of</strong> Clinton’s strong California showing became clear.<br />

However, the margin <strong>of</strong> Hillary’s victory was due overwhelmingly to the Latino vote,<br />

both that it was so heavily for her and that is was so high, almost double in percentage<br />

terms the Latino turnout in the previous two Democrat presidential primaries. It was like a<br />

deus-ex-machina and thus hard to figure into calculations for the ongoing campaign.<br />

This highlights something that’s been an issue with both pre-contest and exit polls this<br />

year. They’ve been <strong>of</strong>f. That’s because the polling is designed to capture a representative<br />

sample <strong>of</strong> the voters (or likely voters, in the case <strong>of</strong> pre-election polls). With a markedly different<br />

electorate, the polls are not capturing a sample that is really representative <strong>of</strong> THESE<br />

voters.<br />

The electorate –especially in the Democratic Party race– is DIFFERENT. Turnouts have<br />

been unprecedented, especially among young people and Blacks. A lot <strong>of</strong> this is associated<br />

with Obama.<br />

But I would argue that the California Latino vote shows that this phenomenon is bigger<br />

than Obama, and indeed Obama’s tremendous success is based on his having been able<br />

to somehow channel or come to represent to people or embody for people that political<br />

motion/desire that is driving them to the polls in unprecedented numbers for this kind <strong>of</strong><br />

race.<br />

It is not just that people are sick <strong>of</strong> politics as usual in Washington, the gridlock and<br />

scandals, the things you read in the paper now and again about gazillion-dollar handouts<br />

to corporations and so on. This is the 10th national election cycle that I’ve been deeply<br />

involved in the coverage, and it is ALWAYS true that regular people are sick <strong>of</strong> Washington.<br />

That’s why the Democrats advanced in the 1990 midterms, why Bush lost the 92 campaign,<br />

why in 94 The Republicans were able to take over Congress, all the way to 2006’s reversal<br />

<strong>of</strong> that “Revolution.”<br />

I think part <strong>of</strong> what’s different has to do with Bush. September 11 gave him as powerful<br />

a mandate as any president has had in my lifetime, and he used it for narrow, petty goals, for


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 415<br />

a lot <strong>of</strong> idiotic bureaucratic make-work in the name <strong>of</strong> fighting terrorism (airport screening),<br />

for one phony terror scare after another, to invade Iraq based on some grandiose neo-con<br />

dream <strong>of</strong> simply remaking the country in the likeness and image <strong>of</strong> Wichita, Kansas, and<br />

assorted other stupidities.<br />

And it should be stressed that Bush proved not only unable to maintain the good will<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Democrats, he could not control and lead his own party. He announced a program<br />

to convert undocumented immigrants into guest workers under what is essentially a new<br />

bracero program.<br />

HIS OWN MAJORITY IN THE HOUSE trashed the plan, going on a nativist rampage<br />

that was a major factor in their losing control <strong>of</strong> Congress and has probably pushed the<br />

Republicans near to “minor party” status in the Latino community.<br />

Bush has shown himself to be a catastrophically bad president, so much so that even Karl<br />

Rove has dumped him. And I don’t mean bad for working people or something, he’s been<br />

bad for the ruling class. Given a golden opportunity to make progress on countless fronts by<br />

September 11, he lacked the imagination, political will, and skill to do it. He already has the<br />

lowest approval rating <strong>of</strong> any president in history since polling began, and looks set to break<br />

his own record several more times before leaving <strong>of</strong>fice.<br />

At any rate, I think perhaps all the bullshit has had on the younger generation that’s<br />

growing up or coming <strong>of</strong> age in these past few years an impact similar to McCarthyism on<br />

the youth <strong>of</strong> the late 50s and 1960s, except much more compressed.<br />

In the Latino community, a lot <strong>of</strong> it has to do with the vicious assault <strong>of</strong> these past few<br />

years, and the economic crash that the community has been suffering from for a year or<br />

more, and is only going to get worse as it becomes generalized to the economy as a whole.<br />

The “ruling class” probably doesn’t have a better handle on a lot <strong>of</strong> this stuff, the change<br />

in underlying popular moods, the zeitgeist, than we do. I don’t think they’re necessarily operating<br />

on the level <strong>of</strong> the ruling class’s politburo ordering Clinton to stand down or Obama<br />

to take a dive at this point. They’re probably as intrigued as some <strong>of</strong> us here are by this<br />

phenomenon, but feeling .<br />

I DO believe figures in ruling class political circles do play a big role in this. Obama was<br />

CHOSEN and sponsored by important circles and operators in the Democratic Party. He was<br />

just a state legislator from Illinois when he gave the keynote the 2004 Democrat convention.<br />

Obama, starting from having a layer <strong>of</strong> people in ruling class political circles that recognized<br />

early on that he was an extraordinarily gifted politician –or, at least candidate– first<br />

consolidated around him the younger layers <strong>of</strong> voters. That’s how he won Iowa. And a<br />

Black guy winning the first contest in all-white IOWA was BOTH an underdog story and<br />

a man-bites-dog story, archetypal media narratives and immediately uncapped a big layer<br />

<strong>of</strong> latent support he already had, but that wasn’t finding expression in the polls because so<br />

many people assumed he just couldn’t win.<br />

That in turn led to a gusher <strong>of</strong> dollars flowing into his campaign, in many cases from the<br />

same sorts <strong>of</strong> people or the same people as are backing Hillary, and were just covering their<br />

bets, but also a torrent <strong>of</strong> small donations from regular people especially via the Internet.


416 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Clinton’s missteps in South Carolina and the complete collapse <strong>of</strong> her support in the Black<br />

community led to Obama winning more victories on Super-Tuesday than Clinton, instead<br />

<strong>of</strong> her delivering the knock-out punch that her campaign had predicted and was structured<br />

around.<br />

Sure, Clinton won New York, but that was taken for granted. It was also considered not<br />

very significant that her “home state” advantage would extend to New Jersey and Connecticut.<br />

Obama’s beating her in Connecticut showed the surprising strength <strong>of</strong> his candidacy.<br />

Obama was expected to take Georgia easily, 55-45. In fact, he crushed her, 66% to 31%,<br />

despite the Democrat Party <strong>of</strong>ficialdom –Black and white– backing her solidly. In Black<br />

precincts near where I live, her votes were in single digits, Obama’s in the hundreds. And<br />

Georgia’s results were the very first available on Super Tuesday, and so it played a big role<br />

in setting the narrative for the night.<br />

But I’m not sure that if California had closed at 7:00 PM and Georgia at 11:00, the net<br />

result would have been that different. It would have started out that Clinton was delivering,<br />

but as the night wore on, it would all have been about Obama’s come-back. He won more<br />

states and more delegates than she did, when she was the favorite AND had built her campaign<br />

around the idea that she was the inevitable candidate, almost as if she were a sitting<br />

president.<br />

At any rate, Georgia just by itself nullified most <strong>of</strong> Clinton’s California victory in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> delegates. Obama got 35 more delegates than she in GA, Clinton 44 more than he in CA.<br />

Since then Clinton’s campaign has been floundering. The campaign manager and second<br />

in command have been fired; the campaign’s message is a muddle: one day Obama’s a<br />

dangerously inexperienced gasbag, the next she’s honored to be in the race with another<br />

candidate <strong>of</strong> such a high caliber.<br />

Their policy differences are –consciously– small. He is to the left <strong>of</strong> her (slightly) on Iraq,<br />

Cuba and foreign policy generally and on immigration, to her right (slightly) on healthcare.<br />

So his pitch is that he’s the one who can actually get things done with the explicit argument<br />

being he can bring people together around the table and so on (something for which there is<br />

simply no evidence) but the implicit, underlying real argument being that he can sway public<br />

opinion and build up enough political pressure to get things done, on which he has a much<br />

better case than any other politician around in this country.<br />

The Clintonites tried to reduce this to the caricature that he just gives good speeches, and<br />

then sought to torpedo that straw man with the plagiarism charge. Obama used a sentence<br />

or two his campaign co-chair gave him without starting, “as my friend so-and-so says.” Her<br />

campaign tried to present it as a High Crime and Misdemeanor worthy <strong>of</strong> impeachment but<br />

vox populi soon came back saying it wasn’t even a parking ticket.<br />

Incredibly, the Clinton campaign is so tone-deaf that AFTER the plagiarism charge had<br />

gotten laughed out <strong>of</strong> court, she levied it again at the debate last Thursday, leading to two immediate<br />

results: First, the audience boo’s her. Second, a bunch <strong>of</strong> us hacks gleefully started<br />

pouring over her speeches and immediately his pay dirt with the kind <strong>of</strong> stock sentences you<br />

constantly find in campaign rhetoric that others had said before. So she got slammed for


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 417<br />

making a mountain out <strong>of</strong> a molehill, for being completely out <strong>of</strong> touch with popular sentiment,<br />

for being a hypocrite, having done the same thing Obama did, and for being stupid,<br />

copying while she herself was drawing attention to the issue.<br />

And to top it all <strong>of</strong>f, one <strong>of</strong> the Clinton spinmeisters after the debate said it was OK for<br />

her to copy as she wasn’t running for president on the basis <strong>of</strong> giving good speeches!<br />

This is not untypical <strong>of</strong> campaigns whose candidate, for whatever reason, turns out to be<br />

less attractive to a broad general public than their competitor and there are no substantive issues.<br />

They wind up flailing at the opponent without rhyme or reason, <strong>of</strong>ten doing themselves<br />

more damage<br />

I think Fred is right in the sense that IF the ruling class or a bunch <strong>of</strong> people in their top political<br />

circles started thinking there was a BIG problem with Obama THEN you would have<br />

seen some ultra-heavyweight write an article about the tremendous significance <strong>of</strong> Clinton’s<br />

win in California and New York, which had been obscured by the byzantine proportional<br />

representation math, and so on. And all <strong>of</strong> a sudden the sorts <strong>of</strong> internal lists I’m on at the<br />

place where I work would be hit by a message by the top boss pointing to the significance<br />

<strong>of</strong> this article, interviews would pop up on all the cable channels, TIME would pitch in with<br />

something on Obama’s image problems, etc.<br />

My point is that this did not happen, the evolution <strong>of</strong> the coverage increasingly in favor<br />

<strong>of</strong> Obama is simply a reflection <strong>of</strong> his success as a candidate and the reality that he already<br />

has been vetted and blessed by important Democratic Party circles that have been pushing<br />

his candidacy. No additional intervention “from above” was needed or took place, as far<br />

as I can see. And part <strong>of</strong> the reason for there not being a heavy-handed intervention to put<br />

Clinton ahead are, I’m sure, those calculations Fred outlines about a likely big economic<br />

storm and the need for a charismatic yet expendable figure under whom significant policy<br />

changes, concessions and so on can be pushed through, if necessary.<br />

Joaquin<br />

Next Message by Hans is [435].<br />

[455] Scott: Social Security. The truth is that our Social Security is going broke, and<br />

if we want our children or anybody in the future to have Social Security we need to solve<br />

the problem. We have been warned that by 2014 current tax revenues will be insufficient<br />

to pay current benefits, and by 2029 the Social Security Trust Fund will be empty. It is<br />

mandatory to give the current beneficiaries and participants the benefits they were promised.<br />

The solution to this problem is we need to invest a portion <strong>of</strong> the budget surplus into the the<br />

Social Security trust fund to provide Social Security to those who were promised it. Second,<br />

we need to change the current Social Security system with personal accounts.<br />

Senator John Mccain realizes there is a problem and has created a plan to solve it. On his<br />

website he gives his stance on the reformation <strong>of</strong> Social Security, “Senator Mccain believes<br />

that we may meet our obligations to the retirees <strong>of</strong> today and the future without raising<br />

taxes. Senator Mccain supports the plan to switch the Social Security system with personal<br />

accounts.” This plan allows the Government to keep its promise to those who are retiring<br />

and also provides a solution for the future.


418 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Social Security is definitely a problem that we cannot put aside or ignore. There is 5<br />

trillion unfunded liability in the US in the form <strong>of</strong> Social Security Trust Fund. If we find a<br />

way to put the money in quick, by using our budget surplus, and then we will be able to get<br />

people to invest their payroll taxes into investments <strong>of</strong> their choosing. By doing this it will<br />

make a giant difference in the status <strong>of</strong> their retirement fund.<br />

I agree 100% with Senator Mccain that this is a problem that is not going anywhere and<br />

we need to address it. Giving the American people the opportunity to invest in personal<br />

accounts, and solving the problem at hand that there is not going to be enough money in a<br />

few years is what Americans want to hear and see done.<br />

Message [455] referenced by [461] and [471]. Next Message by Scott is [545].<br />

[461] Jason: Is Social Security that bad <strong>of</strong>f? I’ve heard a lot <strong>of</strong> negative things about<br />

the Social Security issue, but last semester I heard something fairly different. I can’t remember<br />

where I heard it from, but I believe it was an econ pr<strong>of</strong>essor I took Current Economic<br />

Problems from. He (or at least I think it was him) said that the Social Security problem is<br />

no where near as serious as most people make it out to be. Since it is a trust fund and more<br />

money is getting paid into it everyday it will not be empty for quite some time. The statistic<br />

I heard was that if nothing was done to resolve the issue by the time we (referring to the<br />

average college aged student) were ready to retire we would receive roughly 70% <strong>of</strong> what<br />

people get now. I’m not sure, but I am assuming that includes adjustment for inflation. If<br />

this is the case then, while far from optimal, it is hardly the catastrophic failure I’ve heard it<br />

will be.<br />

Does anyone know if what I heard last semester is the case, or is the problem more like<br />

what Scott said in [455]?<br />

Message [461] referenced by [463], [465], [466], and [471]. Next Message by Jason is [514].<br />

[463] Goethe: We are hating it!!! In response to Jason [461]. . . start saving your nickels<br />

pal. . . if the best case scenario is 70% on SS. . . . Then I will be working on the day <strong>of</strong> my<br />

death. But the good news is that if we continue expand the population, use fossil fuels, and<br />

do nothing to improve society. . . .. We won’t need SS. . . because we won’t be here. . .<br />

Goethe<br />

Next Message by Goethe is [474].<br />

[465] Slash: Re: Is Social Security that bad <strong>of</strong>f? In response to [461]: The problem<br />

with seeing social security is that social security is completely subjective according to the<br />

numbers and graphs looking at it. All <strong>of</strong> the data that is debated over is speculated and over<br />

so many years that its a real shot in the dark.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [563].<br />

[466] Bmellor: Social security is safe and will never go away... Jason [461] and I must<br />

have taken the same Current Economic Problems class, because I remember the same topic<br />

coming up.<br />

Some are worried about social security because in the beginning, around the time social<br />

security was first enacted, baby boomers were first entering the work force. There were<br />

7 people supporting every 1 retired person a decent enough ratio that it enabled the U.S.<br />

government to build up a 1.9 trillion dollar trust fund which really is nonexistant because it<br />

sponsors other programs the United States is involved in (like wars)... Baby boomers begin


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 419<br />

their retirement in 2008 and by 2020 instead <strong>of</strong> a 7 to 1 ratio we may be faced with as low<br />

as a 2 to 1 ratio (two people supporting every one person on social security).<br />

Never fear there are 6 ways to save social security, they are the following:<br />

1. Increase taxes. Regan increased taxes by .65% over ten years and insured that social<br />

security would be “safe” for around 50 years. A 4% increase spread out over 300 years<br />

would make social security last forever.<br />

2. Increase fertility. More children means more people that will eventually enter the work<br />

force and support those that are retiring. (Or more imigrants)<br />

3. Increase retirement age. Right now the retirement age is 65 change that to around 71<br />

years old.<br />

4. Change benefit indexing. The theory is that those who are wealthy don’t really need<br />

social Security; therefore they are given little or no social security.<br />

5. Increase the tax ceiling.<br />

6. Change trust fund savings to a GNMA. Nicknamed Ginnie Mae, a government-owned<br />

corporation that is an agency <strong>of</strong> the Department <strong>of</strong> Housing and Urban Development. Ginnie<br />

Maes are pools <strong>of</strong> residential mortgages. GNMA guarantees, with the “full faith” and<br />

credit <strong>of</strong> the US Government, that investors will receive full and timely principal and interest<br />

payments even if mortgages in the pool are not paid on a timely basis.<br />

Social Security was never meant to be a full retirement. However today’s benefits provide<br />

at least 50% <strong>of</strong> the income <strong>of</strong> 66% <strong>of</strong> the elderly and 90% <strong>of</strong> the income <strong>of</strong> 30% <strong>of</strong> the elderly.<br />

The real plan is that social security should be around 19% <strong>of</strong> your yearly expenditures<br />

<strong>of</strong> retirement.<br />

When you watch the news for some reason lately you hear a lot about private accounts<br />

being the solution to Social Security reform. While the decision still needs to made as<br />

to what plan <strong>of</strong> action needs to be taken to reform Social Security, President Bush’s main<br />

focus for reform is on “changing the benefit indexing” not providing private Social Security<br />

accounts.<br />

Now no matter what your views are <strong>of</strong> the private accounts program there is an immediate<br />

problem with this plan. The Bush administration’s plan calls for the government to lose 30%<br />

<strong>of</strong> revenues needed to pay current obligations, people who presently are receiving benefits.<br />

The plan calls for 30% <strong>of</strong> social security to be diverted into private markets. In a “pay as you<br />

go system” like we have now this can be complicated. The government will have to either<br />

cut funding or borrow money to make up the deficiency. There will be a transaction cost <strong>of</strong><br />

2 trillion dollars over 10 years. And this could also be seen as added debt obligations due<br />

to the transformation <strong>of</strong> the system. Not mention the cost added because <strong>of</strong> advisors that<br />

would oversee these private accounts. Private accounts would appear to not be the perfect<br />

answer, but we as Americans like them because our little ears stick up when we hear about<br />

actually having personal control over 30% <strong>of</strong> the money we pay for social security. If the<br />

government puts money into a mutual fund for us we think “Yes! That is less money that<br />

I have to save for my own retirement.” Not true, some countries have tried private accounts


420 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

already (Argentina, Great Britain) and failed, and are now scrambling to get back to the<br />

system that we have now.<br />

Social Security reform is about making it last. It is about assuring the public that no<br />

matter what the government will always be able to pay disabilities, pensions etc... Assuring<br />

that social security will always be able to cover 19% <strong>of</strong> your retirement. President Regan<br />

increased taxes by not even 1% over ten years and it assured that Social Security would be<br />

around for at least 50 more years. Experts say that if you were to increase taxes by 4% during<br />

an infinite amount <strong>of</strong> time you will always have enough money for social security. This being<br />

said the problem is not whether or not we will have Social Security in the future, it is “What<br />

do we go about doing so that social security meets the needs <strong>of</strong> the American people?” There<br />

is always a solution to solving a Social Security crisis, raising taxes. However the first plan<br />

<strong>of</strong> action is how do we better plan and manage the funds we already posses? That is what is<br />

debatable; Social Security will always be around.<br />

Message [466] referenced by [467] and [471]. Next Message by Bmellor is [485].<br />

[467] Sparky: Social Security more than baby-boomers. In response to all the Stats.<br />

and allegation that Social Security is just a “baby-boomer” problem, and that only retirees<br />

are the ones that benefit and that we will only benefit from the system once we retire, I<br />

would just like to point out that the system is so much much more than that. The Social<br />

Security system acts as a safety net for many people in America today. I am writing this out<br />

<strong>of</strong> personal experience, My mother, who is only 52, is receiving social security checks every<br />

month, as well as my 11 year old sister and my 16 year old brother, due to a certain event<br />

that happened in my family the government has stepped in and is giving help to my family.<br />

This is the social security system, it is not just for the old and retired.<br />

While the system made up <strong>of</strong> greatly older persons, there is the younger people that the<br />

system is caring for and that is one fact that is easily forgotten. We constantly hear about<br />

the aging population <strong>of</strong> the United States and how in the next ten or so years the majority<br />

<strong>of</strong> them will be retiring and that the system will suddenly take on more pressure. We need<br />

to remember that there are many others, <strong>of</strong> many different ages, which could just as easily<br />

start taking money from the system, leaving even less for others (Us!) when it comes time to<br />

retire. And just touching on Bmellors idea 3 in [466] his idea to change the age <strong>of</strong> retirement<br />

to 71, I don’t know about anyone else but I believe that is a terrible, terrible thing to even<br />

suggest, I for one think that 65 is to far and that people should be able to retire at any age, I<br />

would say as low as 50 if not lower- I don’t want to spend my life working but living!<br />

The system as we know it must be watched and guarded, it is not perfect and it has it<br />

faults and limitations just like any other government institution but I believe that by simple<br />

thinking over the name <strong>of</strong> this institution- Social Security, you will realize that it is more<br />

important that many many <strong>of</strong> the other institutions that we have built up in our government.<br />

Message [467] referenced by [470] and [471]. Next Message by Sparky is [518].<br />

[470] Kevin: Who should be Socially responsible for Security? All this talk about<br />

Social Security has me thinking. I fully believe that there has to be some institutionalized<br />

social security network <strong>of</strong> some kind. There are people in the United States that are, for<br />

whatever reason, incapable <strong>of</strong> making a full and complete living, such as Sparky’s family<br />

[467]. I completely understand that at a point in an individual’s life it becomes impossible


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 421<br />

to work anymore but there must be an ability to support one’s self. But the question all this<br />

raises is, who should really be socially responsible?<br />

Not that I’m saying this would easy, the social “norm” or cool thing to do, or even practical<br />

in many situations, or that this is even something I WANT to do, but shouldn’t the social<br />

security <strong>of</strong> individuals after retirement fall to the children? Shouldn’t we be responsible for<br />

our parents’ welfare and not the government? Wouldn’t that be the socially responsible thing<br />

to do?<br />

Again, I realize that this would not, and could not, always be the case, but seriously, how<br />

many Americans take a financially active role in the life <strong>of</strong> their parents once their parents<br />

reach the age <strong>of</strong> retirement? Maybe this is just the white, middle-class male showing in me<br />

and I’m completely ignorant <strong>of</strong> any most situations outside <strong>of</strong> my socio-economic group but<br />

I don’t believe anyone here in America does anything more than put their parents in an old<br />

folks home. In my experience, it’s only when the government’s social security doesn’t cover<br />

the tab that people make a financial contribution to their retired parents whatsoever.<br />

Next Message by Kevin is [488].<br />

[471] Dentist: my two cents on SS. I would like to weigh in on this social security<br />

discussion as I am also debating the system in another class that I am currently taking.<br />

While I certainly make no claims on being an expert, I feel there are some contributions and<br />

clarifications I can make.<br />

Bmellor [466] has already gone a long way in bringing some clarifications to the issue,<br />

and I would like to respond to a few <strong>of</strong> his “6 solutions.”<br />

Firstly, I agree that decreasing the dependcency ratio though either fertility or immigration<br />

are real solutions to the funding issue, and to you “over-populists” I would also like to<br />

say that an indirect way to affect this ratio is through productivity. We have become vastly<br />

more productive then the baby boom generation and as such the dependency ratio does not<br />

directly need to be changed. When one man today can perform the work that it took 10 or<br />

more in a previous generation, the same result is reached without affecting population.<br />

Secondly, in terms <strong>of</strong> adjusting the payroll ceiling tax, which Scott [455] has also discussed.<br />

I agree that this is a solution and I would like to (kindly) correct Scott [455] on some<br />

<strong>of</strong> figures. According to the 2007 trustees report (again from the SSA website) payments<br />

will not begin to exceed income until 2017, and even then the trillions in surplus that have<br />

been accumulating since the Reagan Administration will sustain the system without making<br />

any changes until 2041. And as stated previously, they will still manage to pay out nearly<br />

70% <strong>of</strong> estimated benefits.<br />

As far as the controversial switch to private accounts, is irrelevant because that switch<br />

will change the fundamental purpose <strong>of</strong> the SSA from insurance to investment (which most<br />

people now think it is anyway). I am not stating my opinion for or against this change, but<br />

it is worth pointing out that private accounts aren’t a solution to the funding issue, they are<br />

fundamental change in what social security is designed to be, and thus a different debate.<br />

The solution to the problem does not need to be a dramatic change.<br />

Actually it can be solved quite simply. According to the most recent economic report <strong>of</strong><br />

the president, in order to fix the “problem” 3.4 trillion dollars will be needed, which sounds


422 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

daunting. However, merely eliminating payroll tax ceiling <strong>of</strong> 97,000 dollars, the SSA would<br />

receive 10.9 trillion! And by making an adjustment from 97,000 to 170,000 dollars the SSA<br />

would gain 5 trillion. These are two simple and relatively small changes that show how<br />

easily the problem can be resolved.<br />

Thirdly, I am not sure I agree with the non-existant nature <strong>of</strong> the surplus that Bmellor<br />

[466] suggests. The SSA sells its surplus income in the form <strong>of</strong> bonds, the bulk <strong>of</strong> which<br />

the government purchases. So it’s true the money is not directly there, but is loaned to the<br />

government, which has NEVER defaulted on a loan, with the promise <strong>of</strong> being returned with<br />

interest. So the surplus is there in the same way that your savings account is in your bank.<br />

Moving along in the discussion, as pointed out by sparky [467] and Bmellor [466] social<br />

security is not merely a retirement program. In fact it is not a retirement program at all!<br />

Social security is an INSURANCE system set up by the federal government as a part <strong>of</strong><br />

FDR’s new deal to bring an end to the great depression. It is designed to keep money in the<br />

pockets <strong>of</strong> people who have less capacity to earn it for one reason or another (whether it be<br />

due to age, disability, ect.), not to keep the recipients from starving per say, but to keep the<br />

economy from starving. You are simply the means through which the government satisfies<br />

its end.<br />

To any critics <strong>of</strong> my claim, this is directly from the SSA website’s FAQ’s, “Q: Should I<br />

count on Social Security for all my retirement income? A: No. Social Security was never<br />

meant to be the sole source <strong>of</strong> income in retirement. It is <strong>of</strong>ten said that a comfortable retirement<br />

is based on a ‘three-legged stool’ <strong>of</strong> Social Security, pensions and savings. American<br />

workers should be saving for their retirement on a personal basis and through employersponsored<br />

or other retirement plans.”<br />

So you alone are responsible to plan and make your own retirement happen. And your<br />

social security benefits are merely a input to be considered in the overall function.<br />

As far as the “terminal” state <strong>of</strong> social security, Jason [461] does remember correctly<br />

that even if the SSA does become completely insolvent it will still be able to pay out approximately<br />

70% <strong>of</strong> your benefits. And should this be the case, which it won’t because the<br />

quickest way to stir a man to action is to threaten his pocketbook, it is likely the government<br />

will step in and find a way to subsidize the other 30%. After all, they have to keep the<br />

monster fed.<br />

I am sure by now I have gone on long enough, leaving all <strong>of</strong> you bored, and myself open<br />

to my own misinterpretations and error. So I suppose “that’s all I have to say bout’ that.”<br />

Next Message by Dentist is [489].<br />

[503] Alex: Socialism. I have been intrigued by the response to Governor Huntsman’s<br />

health plans. The general definition <strong>of</strong> socialism can be defined but I am not sure most<br />

<strong>Utah</strong>ns understand that definition. Whenever the government steps out <strong>of</strong> a preconceived<br />

notion to do some good in the community it is automatically considered socialism. This is<br />

small minded and will continue disproportionate growth.<br />

Next Message by Alex is [547].<br />

[507] Srichardson: Socialism. I am also surprised about the publics views when it<br />

comes to the proposed health plans. I also do not think that <strong>Utah</strong>ns understand the definition


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 423<br />

<strong>of</strong> socialism. The main reason that i believe <strong>Utah</strong>ns do not have a basic understanding is<br />

because until this class I had no real concept <strong>of</strong> socialism.<br />

I have grown up in <strong>Utah</strong> and received all <strong>of</strong> my education through the <strong>Utah</strong> public school<br />

system, and although I can not remember a specific incident where socialism was discussed<br />

as a bad system,it somehow got into my head that it was an inferior system to what we had<br />

here in the US and that it didn’t work for anyone. So now that we are trying to solve some<br />

<strong>of</strong> our problem when it comes to health care <strong>Utah</strong>ns still hold a stigma against anything<br />

socialist. <strong>Utah</strong> needs to be educated about what the definition <strong>of</strong> socialism really is.<br />

Next Message by Srichardson is [523].<br />

[512] Jeremy: Why the need for labels? Something that I’ve noticed over the years is the<br />

need for humans to place a name or label upon everything. This habit causes devision and<br />

grouping simultaneously. If I enjoy the outdoors, I’m a tree hugger or an environmentalist.<br />

If you are Hispanic, people now wonder if you are here illegally. If you take a class that<br />

analyzes Karl Marx, you must be a communist.<br />

These, and most all groups are stereotyped with correct and incorrect information as well.<br />

In the example above, enjoying the outdoors doesn’t mean I want to chain myself to a tree<br />

to prevent clear cutting. While there may be some truth to a stereotype such as a tree hugger<br />

enjoying the outdoors, however they don’t all eat granola, have braids or dread locks, and<br />

wear clothing made <strong>of</strong> hemp. Why do we need to classify everything? How can we break<br />

the cycle <strong>of</strong> stereotyping?<br />

Message [512] referenced by [513] and [538]. Next Message by Jeremy is [536].<br />

[513] Brandon: RE: Why the need for labels? I think this is an important question that<br />

goes beyond looking at how particular societies relate to one another in the social sense. I<br />

think it gets down to primal nature. All <strong>of</strong> have certain characteristics and attributes that we,<br />

not so much flaunt, but allow to define ourselves. For example, I fit the ‘rocker’ stereotype.<br />

I play guitar, I work at a rock radio station, I dress the part, etc because thats who I am and<br />

I’m comfortable being in that niche. I am a lot <strong>of</strong> other things but the people who know<br />

me generally associate me with that stereotype. We all gravitate towards groups because we<br />

like to surround ourselves we what is familiar and what will support our lifestyles. Now<br />

on the larger scale that Jeremy pointed out in [512] concerning general stereotypes that we<br />

label on people whom we don’t know, is definitely a problem in our society that, I believe,<br />

can never be stopped. We look at other people’s individualisms and immediately feel the<br />

need to categorize them. The most detrimental form <strong>of</strong> this is in regards to race as Jeremy<br />

pointed out. People look at a black person and this there’s a gangster, or uneducated, etc.<br />

Hispanics=illegal. I recently was working the Les Claypool show on Wednesday night, and<br />

afterwards I went up to a girl and asked to bum a cigarette. I’m half east Indian and I<br />

have a little beard thing going on, and she looked and me and said, “i’m not giving you<br />

a smoke Dirka Dirka, you f***ing currymuncher”. Well she got currymuncher right, I do<br />

love me a nice bowl <strong>of</strong> curry, but this is an example <strong>of</strong> how our modern society views other<br />

nationalities, and we are even willing to spew racist rants at people we dont know. Me<br />

personally, I’m not <strong>of</strong>fended by someone else’s ignorance. I believe we are only <strong>of</strong>fended<br />

if we allow ourselves to be. To answer Jeremy’s last question “How can we break the<br />

cycle <strong>of</strong> stereotyping”, I don’t believe that is possible. By not feeding into stereotyping and


424 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

constantly battling over a ideological war such as this, is personally how I deal with it. But<br />

thats just me...<br />

Message [513] referenced by [531]. Next Message by Brandon is [603].<br />

[524] Ryoung: Have Obama’s Chances Been Hurt As Of Late? I wanted to get the<br />

opinions <strong>of</strong> others in the class on if Obama has been hurt by the comments <strong>of</strong> Rev. Jeremiah<br />

Wright or not?<br />

Personally I am not 100% familiar with the recent comments <strong>of</strong> Rev. Jeremiah Wright<br />

but I have noticed that it has been recieving a lot <strong>of</strong> air time in the news and on the internet.<br />

I believe that the media is always trying cause problems and for this reason I have not given<br />

it much thought. I wanted to see the opinions <strong>of</strong> everyone else. I believe that it will not hurt<br />

Obama because I believe that he is a classy enough guy to overcome what has been thrown<br />

his way, and I still believe that he will come away with the Democratic nomination.<br />

Next Message by Ryoung is [692].<br />

[526] Srichardson: Obama campaign. I personally do not believe that Obama’s campaign<br />

has been hurt because <strong>of</strong> the recently brought up comments <strong>of</strong> comments <strong>of</strong> Rev.<br />

Jeremiah Wright. I believe that many <strong>of</strong> the comments that have been shown on T.V over<br />

and over again have been blown out <strong>of</strong> proportion by the media. I do not think that a presidential<br />

candidate is responsible for the actions <strong>of</strong> everyone he/she knows. I hang out with<br />

people that I do not believe in everything they say and I do not personally think that it is<br />

necessary for you to believe everything that your pastor says if you are a religious person.<br />

Next Message by Srichardson is [541].<br />

[531] Papageorgio: label me. Brandon in [513] talks about labels that are put on people,<br />

regarding race, activities, etc. It is interesting to live in where people are judged <strong>of</strong>f the bat<br />

by color or who they associate with. I think we must first worry about ourselves and make<br />

sure we are not hypocrites, that when we say we do not label that we watch ourselves and be<br />

sure to truly not label people. That we look at people for who they are. It is interesting to me<br />

that our society is still affected by racism. It seems to have no place in the common crowd yet<br />

seems so alive today. It is very plain to me at least from my eyes that race is not an issue, that<br />

no matter what color someone is does not set them apart, the color or race is not what makes<br />

them different than others, so accordingly I feel color language should be dropped. That<br />

people should not refer to people as black or white or red or yellow or brown because that is<br />

not what makes them different. What makes a person unique, different, or act a certain way<br />

would more likely be described by where they lived, grew up, the culture <strong>of</strong> how that person<br />

was raised. If you take someone who was raised in an affluent area <strong>of</strong> America and begin<br />

that person’s life over but raise them in say a poor African country they will be a completely<br />

different person, with no regard to color. They will act as those Africans act and work how<br />

they work. No matter what it is culture and where you are raised that helps you become who<br />

you are not your color. If a white kid from the suburbs in middle America was raised in say<br />

the ghetto on the east coast he would take on aspects <strong>of</strong> that culture. Labels on things like<br />

race such as black and white, also hurt us and continue to bring racism and dwelling on the<br />

past instead <strong>of</strong> looking to the future. Labels need to stop and all must remember we are the<br />

human color.<br />

Message [531] referenced by [562]. Next Message by Papageorgio is [548].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 425<br />

[538] Spawnblade: Alright I will label you. I find the other three posts correlating to this<br />

discussion to exaggerate things quite drastically in regards to the subject <strong>of</strong> labeling. Jeremy<br />

[512] remarks that enjoying the outdoors can be misinterpreted as trying to save the forest<br />

by placing yourself in front <strong>of</strong> a chainsaw. This is something I believe any rational person<br />

(and this a topic that can really only apply to rational people) might see as deteriorating the<br />

point.<br />

The reason I find it important not to exaggerate with this topic, is because we have (as<br />

humans) a need for labels. People may claim to not like labels, stereotypes, and judging<br />

things by appearances... But can you imagine what the world would be like if we didn’t<br />

have them?<br />

Yes, you’d be neutral towards everyone... But in the same regards, you would then have<br />

to use a great amount <strong>of</strong> processing power in order to acquire information about someone<br />

which you really should have simply discerned from their appearance. Assuming that you’re<br />

only discerning reasonable conclusions.<br />

This leads me to the real problem with labels: When people come to irrational conclusions<br />

and judgements about a person that do not correlate to their actions or appearance. If someone<br />

is wearing gangster clothing, its a reasonable assertion that they’re either a wannabe, or<br />

a gangster. If a woman is standing on the corner <strong>of</strong> the street, half naked, and waving in<br />

passing cars... It’s reasonable to assume she’s a prostitute, and not just an extraordinarily<br />

friendly woman with too much time on her hands.<br />

It would be nice if people removed incorrect stereotypes from their organizing.. But I can<br />

say that a great deal <strong>of</strong> those stereotypes are a result <strong>of</strong> hollywood. We take in a lot <strong>of</strong> our<br />

labels from actions that people do in movies... And in movies, what race(s) are most likely<br />

to be the criminal? How about a white collar crime?<br />

Despite these problems, labels are still a necessary function. We simply do not have<br />

enough mental power to process unbiased information about everyone. In psychology I<br />

learned that there are certain states <strong>of</strong> mind we do in fact process things more thoroughly<br />

with less reliance on labels... However, it is generally when you have enough energy and<br />

cognition to spare.<br />

In regards to the topic <strong>of</strong> racism and labels relating to it... I highly recommend the movie<br />

American History X. It is an excellent film <strong>of</strong> which I wish we’d see others like it. And I<br />

think that it will answer Jeremy’s question about ‘What we should do?’ (The most obvious<br />

answer being... To overturn stereotypes by introducing people to real life examples. This<br />

requires a more diverse community, which many parts <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> are lacking.)<br />

Next Message by Spawnblade is [621].<br />

[546] Scott: Private accounts. We talk a lot about privatizing our accounts and how this<br />

will help our problem, but why are we still talking about it if we know England failed when<br />

they tried the same thing? I think the United States’ <strong>of</strong>ficials should examine what went<br />

wrong in England before pushing private accounts onto Americans. For private plans this is<br />

what America needs to do; look at what went wrong in the United Kingdom and implement<br />

controls in our system to ensure the same issues do not arise.<br />

Message [546] referenced by [564]. Next Message by Scott is [670].


426 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[551] Aaron: I agree with [547] that the United States should look at what went wrong<br />

with the British version before we try and implement our own. However, there are a lot <strong>of</strong><br />

differences in our system <strong>of</strong> money and banking and economics than the British systems.<br />

For example, the federal system for retirement, like our social security is a bit different and<br />

subtle differences in the economic machine can amount to large gaps in how government<br />

programs can efficiently run. Just because the British system didn’t work as planned doesn’t<br />

mean that another country can’t do it.<br />

Next Message by Aaron is [601].<br />

[555] PrivateProperty: Flood <strong>of</strong> emails. I think it’s really amusing that there are virtually<br />

no contributions to the mailing list for two weeks, and then 20 people en masse send their<br />

contributions right before deadline.<br />

Don’t get me wrong, I’m guilty <strong>of</strong> waiting until the last minute, but this is ridiculous.<br />

There is too much content in my inbox to even skim over this week, much less actually read<br />

and respond to. Moral <strong>of</strong> the story: space out your contributions.<br />

Message [555] referenced by [599]. Next Message by PrivateProperty is [602].<br />

[562] Paul: We’ll always label. Papageorio [531] makes a case that we should not label<br />

people based on their race for the more determining factor <strong>of</strong> what type <strong>of</strong> person you will<br />

be has to do with the culture in which you were raised. While I believe that the culture<br />

you grow up in has a bigger part <strong>of</strong> making you who you are than the color <strong>of</strong> your skin<br />

is this really a better way to label someone? I think not. Instead a labeling people black,<br />

white, Asian, Inuit, Arab, whatever, your just going to label them things like rich kid, ghetto,<br />

country boy, or suburban punk. Is this any better than labeling by color? Maybe. The fact<br />

is that it is human nature to distinguish oneself from the crowd and we are going to label<br />

people no matter what the criteria.<br />

Next Message by Paul is [725].<br />

[564] Slash: Private accounts. In response to [546], I find it interesting that almost every<br />

president has at one time or another pushed for private accounts. I know McCain has. I<br />

understand the importance <strong>of</strong> looking at why England failed, but when doing there needs<br />

to be understanding as to the social demands that could be different. I find myself wanting<br />

private accounts. My main reason would be to eliminate the hoops <strong>of</strong> insurance companies.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [599].<br />

[569] SnatchimusMaximus: Re: Private accounts. Are we talking about health care or<br />

Social Security checks? After all, they are two entirely different things. Fixing health care,<br />

if we dare to say that it is broken, has nothing to do with making Social Security solvent.<br />

Next Message by SnatchimusMaximus is [612].<br />

[599] Slash: Re: Flood <strong>of</strong> emails. PrivateProperty [555] made comments as to the flow<br />

<strong>of</strong> emails contributed to this site. I have also seen this, but unlike PrivateProperty I don’t<br />

find him, or anyone one guilty. This is how the real world works, its called procrastination,<br />

and as long as there are deadlines this is how people will respond. I don’t want to seem like<br />

PrivateProperty hasn’t made a point worth pointing out, but I don’t see why this would be<br />

any other way. I find also that if someone finds a problem that the best way to make change<br />

is recommend a solution, such as lets split this class up into three groups and have deadlines<br />

throughout the semester to break them up, oh yeah we do.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [625].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 427<br />

[600] Jason: Piracy vs Pervasiveness. I was having a conversation with my friend the<br />

other day about music. We were talking about how since the advent <strong>of</strong> Napster music sales<br />

have dropped by a huge number. No one wants to buy music anymore when they can just<br />

download entire albums for free in minutes. Anyway, we were talking about how despite the<br />

massive sales loss the record industry is taking right now musical awareness is at an all time<br />

high. The major losers here are primarily the production companies who take the bulk <strong>of</strong> the<br />

sale anyway. That and the very popular mainstream musicians.<br />

The positive aspect we were discussing though, is that much smaller time musicians are<br />

getting the exposure they deserve without the big record labels okaying them and taking 95%<br />

<strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>its. Even though no one is really buying their music, the sheer amount <strong>of</strong> exposure<br />

allows them to go on tour and make money that way. Also, most <strong>of</strong> the independent small<br />

time musicians generally are doing it because they want too, not to become filthy rich. They<br />

really just want to be heard. I’d say overall the advent <strong>of</strong> the internet has had a positive effect<br />

on the music industry and has allowed a lot more lesser known work come out.<br />

The same thing is starting to happen with movies. Small time movie makers are able to<br />

upload their entire films to sites like Google Video. Another neat effect is the difficulty <strong>of</strong><br />

censorship. When Lust, Caution came out in China it was edited down from the equivalent<br />

<strong>of</strong> an R rating to a PG. The director said he wasn’t too worried about it because he knew the<br />

people that really wanted to see the real version could find it online.<br />

Another nice thing is the legal s<strong>of</strong>tware out now that lets people hear huge amounts <strong>of</strong><br />

music for free. Sites like Pandora.com let you create internet radio stations that play music<br />

similar to whatever band you type in.<br />

So what do you guys think? Is music/movie piracy a bad thing or a good thing overall?<br />

Next Message by Jason is [622].<br />

[601] Aaron: Piracy benefits and apple music. Piracy is an interesting discussion in<br />

the sense that it is debatable as to who the winners and losers are. I believe that the losers<br />

are the production companies who receive the bulk <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>its from album sales. On the<br />

other hand, it is important to note and mention that apple is now the largest music retailer in<br />

the world. They recently overtook wal-mart. With the market domination <strong>of</strong> the Ipod brand,<br />

and the naming <strong>of</strong> apple as the largest music retailer, it is easy to deduce that the general<br />

public are actually buying the songs legally. I have to say, that I personally do not pay for<br />

my music, I download it from a file “sharing” website. I believe that most <strong>of</strong> the popular and<br />

niche musicians make most <strong>of</strong> their money from concert tours and appearances rather than<br />

album sales, but I could be <strong>of</strong>f on that. I agree with the earlier comment that this new age<br />

wave <strong>of</strong> music purchasing and sharing really helps the smaller and lesser known musicians.<br />

Message [601] referenced by [602] and [621]. Next Message by Aaron is [603].<br />

[602] PrivateProperty: Piracy benefits and apple music. I agree with what Aaron says<br />

in [601]. I also use a file-sharing program (called ‘DC ++’ if you’re interested) to download<br />

music and movies for free. I find the music industry to be quite ridiculous in general, as a<br />

lot <strong>of</strong> it is just a marketing orgy that collapses onto itself over and over again. The music<br />

we end up listening to is really a complex web <strong>of</strong> relationships between TV, film, radio, and<br />

grassroots support, which definitely should be the most important (by far) factor in a band’s<br />

success.


428 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Even saying that a band is ‘successful’ or not is ridiculous. Music is music, it has a<br />

purpose, and that is to be enjoyed. If you care about money more than your music, you<br />

are not a musician. And no, those two things are not related, except for the idea <strong>of</strong> buying<br />

equipment to make your music.<br />

You can’t just introduce a band as the next big thing, and introduce them as such, and<br />

expect people to buy into it precisely because you’ve said they are the next big thing. Yet<br />

that is exactly what happens. It makes no sense (recall endless marketing orgy, above).<br />

Anyway, don’t buy any media (music, movies, whatever) unless you really support and<br />

respect that particular artist. Otherwise you are just feeding the monster.<br />

Message [602] referenced by [621]. Next Message by PrivateProperty is [603].<br />

[605] Chris: cheap music. I have read many interesting columns from artists and consumers<br />

in regards to the recent decline <strong>of</strong> record sales. Some bands stream their entire cd on<br />

websites such as myspace.com before the street release date <strong>of</strong> the album. For instance, the<br />

metal band In Flames have done this with their recent release. I have found a few websites<br />

from Russia that <strong>of</strong>fer whole album downloads for about $1.00 - $3.00. I read that in Russia<br />

you can pick up an album at a local record store for about $5.00. This makes me think<br />

that the United States record labels are ripping <strong>of</strong>f consumers and artists alike by charging<br />

$15.00 to $20.00 per album. To relate this to our Marx class, the record companies are exploiting<br />

consumers and artists by taking a large portion <strong>of</strong> excess pr<strong>of</strong>its from them. It is<br />

sad to see artists struggle with record sales. This causes them to be out on tour more to gain<br />

sales through merchandise, ticket sales, etc. and spend less time at home with their families.<br />

Personally, I find it important to support the artists that we like. I just am having problems<br />

supporting the capitalists who exploit the artists and the consumers.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [615].<br />

[609] Clayon: Re: Piracy benefits and apple music. There are are couple points that<br />

I would like to talk on with respect to downloading music from the internet. I agree with<br />

what was said about how internet downloads open the market up to smaller name musicians,<br />

which gives all musicians a more equal starting point. I also agree that it is healthy for the<br />

industry in the sense that it lessens the producers power and influence over the musicians.<br />

I did want to bring up the point that the musicians themselves still deserve reimbursement<br />

for their work in recording an album. Revenue from going on tour is good, but it is not what<br />

puts bread on the table. Generally what makes giving a concert worth the musicians time is<br />

the revenue brought in by cd sales at the concert. If no ones buying cd’s (or not paying for it<br />

on the Internet) its hard to justify the concert. I agree that a musician’s main intent shouldn’t<br />

be to get filthy rich, but I do believe that they should receive what they deserve, hopefully<br />

enough to support a family without needing a second job.<br />

A couple <strong>of</strong> years ago I was a piano performance major. It was some <strong>of</strong> the most enjoyable<br />

years <strong>of</strong> my college experience. After a couple <strong>of</strong> years I decided to be more practical and<br />

study something that I could support a family with. I left music not because I wanted to,<br />

but because it would be hard to make a living in the industry. I know many others that have<br />

done the same. I only mention this to show that free downloads have the potential to take<br />

revenue away from musicians and force them out <strong>of</strong> the market, ultimately leaving us with<br />

less variety.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 429<br />

What would be beneficial is for each musician to have their own site where they can sell<br />

their music and directly receive the money from the consumer without the middle man. $1 a<br />

song seems pretty decent, similar to what itunes is, but again without the middle man.<br />

Message [609] referenced by [621]. Next Message by Clayon is [614].<br />

[610] Rey: Justification...it’s so beautiful! The music debate is something I seem to find<br />

myself in quite <strong>of</strong>ten. I am a firm believer in paying for one’s music! First things first, it<br />

is illegal to steal music, and for some reason otherwise law abiding citizens have found a<br />

way to justify illegal downloading. Ask that same individual if they would walk into a store<br />

and steal that CD and the majority <strong>of</strong> the time these individuals would say no. For some<br />

reason, however, a good majority <strong>of</strong> people who steals music act as if they are leading some<br />

type <strong>of</strong> crusade against major record labels. Let’s cut the crap people and call it how it is!<br />

You are just too cheap to purchase the album <strong>of</strong>f the shelves <strong>of</strong> a store. Sure record labels<br />

make money, but so do the artist (although you are correct in acknowledging it to be a small<br />

amount), it still doesn’t justify theft.<br />

Second if you really are that upset about the astronomical revenue record labels are generating<br />

<strong>of</strong>f the backs <strong>of</strong> the artist you are probably listening to trash anyway. The only labels<br />

creating these empires are the ones pumping the same mundane, trendy, manufactured noise<br />

through the radio! I could list dozens <strong>of</strong> independent artist who have self produced their own<br />

albums and then gone on to create labels that have assist other aspiring artists flourish in their<br />

respected industry. For example, the hardcore band Nora has been a staple in the hardcore<br />

genre for over a decade now and they have done wonders to help the genre progress through<br />

their label, Ferret Music. Another great example, the independent hip-hop artist Immortal<br />

Technique (Disclaimer: He drops some sick tracks which are highly controversial and extremely<br />

radical. Although he has a very strong showing most <strong>of</strong> the time, I do not agree with<br />

everything he is about) who sold over 200,000 records from his trunk and has now created<br />

a label to self produce and help other rising artist. So give me a break people if you really<br />

are concerned with perpetuating the capitalist machine in the music industry stop listening<br />

to garbage.<br />

Now I will give credit where credit is due. Illegal downloading and file sharing has done<br />

wonders to eliminate weak “one hit wonder” tracks and promote otherwise lesser known<br />

bands (I purposely abstain from using the now cliche “underground” tag here. Most people<br />

are too quick to slap the tag <strong>of</strong> “underground” on stuff that’s playing from the ro<strong>of</strong>tops).<br />

All in all I think the iTunes approach is a good start in resolving the situation, anyone who<br />

isn’t willing to pay 99 cents for a track doesn’t deserve to be listening to it anyway. The<br />

monopoly that iTunes has created may be a different monster all together, but in reality who<br />

cares who’s getting paid people! As long as I have my music and my artist aren’t cutting<br />

their creativity short to get their music to the people, then I really don’t care who gets the<br />

check. Besides my artists are smart enough to protect themselves, I don’t need to do it for<br />

them!<br />

Message [610] referenced by [611]. Next Message by Rey is [703].<br />

[611] PrivateProperty: Re: Justification...it’s so beautiful! ‘Stealing music’ [610] Does<br />

that phrase not sound ridiculous? The issue here is that music can be stolen in the first place.<br />

I’m talking about m-u-s-i-c. Those pleasant sound waves that enter your ear. Please do not<br />

equate file-sharing with robbing a store. That is plain ridiculous.


430 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Nobody is ‘justifying’ file-sharing. What you feel is the ‘cold, hard truth’ is, believe it or<br />

not, your opinion. I’d like to address its illegality in some forms is not helpful in ascertaining<br />

whether it’s morally right or wrong to file-share. Being prosecuted and going to jail and/or<br />

paying fines is compelling reason enough to not participate. But that does not tell us anything<br />

if it is wrong or not.<br />

So is it wrong? Well, that depends who you are in this situation.<br />

The fundamental issue is whether or not a recorded music file is a commodity that belongs<br />

under the realm <strong>of</strong> private property.<br />

Obviously, a CD is one thing, in that it is a physical object taking up space on a shelf.<br />

There are significant costs that go into producing the CDs, completely extraneous to the<br />

actual recorded content and much more that go into distribution, all <strong>of</strong> which takes place<br />

after recording. It’s expensive. You have to pay for a CD.<br />

As you may realize, however, CDs are now obsolete. They have been replaced by computer<br />

files, which are completely different. There are virtually no costs involved with reproducing<br />

music files, such as those sold on iTunes. You can literally make a million copies<br />

<strong>of</strong> a music file, and all you need is a hard drive the size <strong>of</strong> a breadbasket and a fast-enough<br />

computer. Distribution? All you need is a website and a server. Not expensive.<br />

But there are costs involved, so it can’t be free. $0.99 per file? Seems reasonable for the<br />

listener. But in the case where I want to ‘check out’ a band or explore some new music, I<br />

am turning to file sharing.<br />

The thing about file-sharing is that is that the networks are unreliable and hard to navigate.<br />

Plus, a lot <strong>of</strong> content simply never makes it onto a network, for one reason or another. This<br />

fact alone will always drive listeners, even avid ‘music pirates’ (little does the industry know<br />

that being a pirate is fashionable these days) to music retailers. I go to iTunes all the time.<br />

Keep in mind, also, that file-sharing (in addition to MySpace) greatly increases the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> listeners and fans who just wouldn’t have heard the music otherwise. Music is more<br />

about exposure and influence than it is about sales (even though those elements certainly<br />

feed <strong>of</strong>f each other). Everyone, except the middleman, should be embracing <strong>of</strong> file-sharing.<br />

Message [611] referenced by [2008fa:675]. Next Message by PrivateProperty is [673].<br />

[621] Spawnblade: Re: Piracy benefits and apple music. Aaron [601], PrivateProperty<br />

[602], and Clayon [609] continue the discussion about file sharing. I didn’t expect to see<br />

anyone talk about music ‘sharing’ or ‘stealing’ on this forum <strong>of</strong> discussion, but when I think<br />

about it, it fits the course content quite well.<br />

In response to these three, and the others on the issue, I would like to detail what I learned<br />

when I was doing research on the issue. I actually was debating starting up a website that<br />

took ‘donations’ from people who wanted to support the artist. This has been done before,<br />

but only once, and long ago. However, to give people a retrospect idea <strong>of</strong> why I personally<br />

don’t buy music but instead pay for concerts:<br />

1) In the past, the average 15 dollar CD gave the artist themselves 10%. So $1.50 per CD.<br />

CD prices have <strong>of</strong> course dropped drastically, but that percentage they’re paid has not.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 431<br />

2) As PrivateProperty [602] stated, the publishing companies are simply getting crap<br />

artists and chugging out the same formulated music. There is no love for music (which art<br />

should be based around), there is only pr<strong>of</strong>it.<br />

3) Now that labels don’t need to manufacture and distribute cds, (which used to cost them<br />

about 1$ per cd), you’d think they’d get paid that share <strong>of</strong> the cost... But, nope! They actually<br />

get paid -less-. If they received 10% <strong>of</strong> a 15$ cd, which is now 10$, they only receive 5-7%<br />

<strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> those 99c iTunes songs! So even when Weird Al sells 4.5 million singles,<br />

how much does he get?... A couple hundred thousand dollars... And the rest for the label?<br />

Wow!<br />

4) Despite taking over 90% <strong>of</strong> the artist’s earnings, labels also do not pay the artist until<br />

they’ve “paid the label back” for the initial recording/production costs.<br />

5) Last year Radiohead released the first ‘free cd’ by a major name band. They completely<br />

bypassed the label (since they were no longer under contract) and <strong>of</strong>fered to sell their cd at<br />

whatever amount the people who listening to it felt it was worth. 50% <strong>of</strong> the sales were<br />

‘special edition’ albums that sold for 40$ a piece. That clocked in at a couple million (those<br />

actually had set prices due to the added material content). The other 50% was based on<br />

several million users, both new and devoted, who ended up paying an average <strong>of</strong> 4-5$ (from<br />

most likely deflated statistics). This average was -much- higher than the normal amount<br />

artists got, however. And yet the label companies have tried to say it was a failure.<br />

Besides just ruining music, label companies do their bests to make the artists dependant<br />

on them so they can leech <strong>of</strong>f their talent. If users are ‘stealing music’ then I’d say labels are<br />

stealing the ‘soul’ <strong>of</strong> music.<br />

P.S. When I looked into a website that allowed donations, one <strong>of</strong> the most difficult parts is<br />

that 99% <strong>of</strong> bands are under contract saying they cannot take payment from outside sources.<br />

(This includes ‘donations’, and probably anything not approved by the label) I imagine the<br />

labels simply didn’t want the artist to go and sell cds on their own... But because <strong>of</strong> this most<br />

artists simply won’t even attempt to receive the money.<br />

Oh and if they were making 1$ a song without the middle man... (and without apple’s cut<br />

which is rather hefty) then they’d be -much- better <strong>of</strong>f.<br />

Next Message by Spawnblade is [727].<br />

[633] Alex: The New Mixed Use Project at the U. The U. just announced its plans to<br />

turn the parking lot just west <strong>of</strong> the stadium into a mixed use project. This is a bad idea. I am<br />

not opposed to developments that claim to be progressive and sustainable, however at what<br />

cost. During my time at the U. I have been perplexed about the lack <strong>of</strong> parking. Now the plan<br />

is to take some away, or make it more cumbersome. The parking structure being planned in<br />

this development should have been planned for other, more crowded, areas <strong>of</strong> the <strong>University</strong>.<br />

The <strong>University</strong> is greatly limiting itself by not providing enough parking as it is. To put it<br />

into perspective, can the U. grow? No the U. cannot grow, there is no room. The <strong>University</strong><br />

needs to be realistic and realize that if the <strong>University</strong> is to progress they must be more wise<br />

about freeing up existing uses by providing strategically placed structured parking. I am not<br />

against this development, but why is it that the U. is more concerned about what happens in


432 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

a parking lot with a non university related use when the rest <strong>of</strong> us have to suffer with poor<br />

planning on the campus.<br />

Next Message by Alex is [769].<br />

[640] Jeremy: Is the internet the ”Great Equalizer” or the ”Veil for Cowardice” Due<br />

to recent posts to the class site, the question came to mind as to what hidden purpose, or<br />

rather, benefit does the internet give us. This is not directed at any specific individual, but<br />

rather at the population as a whole. The internet has advanced the spread <strong>of</strong> information at a<br />

quickstep pace, but have our social skills advanced, in regards to internet ettiquette/manners,<br />

along with the information splurge?<br />

In face to face interaction, there are unspoken rules <strong>of</strong> engagement, such as not interrupting<br />

when someone is speaking, proper and improper gestures and language, stating <strong>of</strong><br />

opinions at the proper junctures, etc. With the internet, it appears that we, as a society, feel<br />

that these are more <strong>of</strong> a nuisance and have chosen to lay them aside. What could cause us to<br />

do such a thing? Is it that these are more <strong>of</strong> traditional mores that we, as the up and coming<br />

generation, would like to let die with our forefathers? Are they meaningless acts that no<br />

longer have a place amongst us? Or is it that we are lazy and just want to get to the point<br />

without dilly dallying around it? My thought is that we are now using the internet as a veil.<br />

As noticed in several posts for this class, things have been said that would not be acceptable<br />

in a physical social setting. I am doubtful that most <strong>of</strong> the derogatory comments made here<br />

would have been made if we were all in a classroom together. The reason for this could be<br />

fear <strong>of</strong> repercussion, be it verbal or physical, shyness, or actual human inhibition and the old<br />

saying <strong>of</strong> “if you don’t have anything nice to say, don’t say anything at all.”<br />

As a veil, the internet has given those <strong>of</strong> us who are shy the ability to speak freely and not<br />

feel as if we would be attacked for our thoughts or opinions. It has given a forum to those<br />

who were once thought <strong>of</strong> as geeks and nerds to speak up and have a voice. I think that<br />

the ability to share intelligence has been increased. In opposition to that, we have also seen<br />

that for the good that is provided, there must also be bad. We now see people that, because<br />

they have no fear <strong>of</strong> consequence, express themselves to an extreme that can be annoying,<br />

or largely to a point, distasteful.<br />

I feel that you can learn much about a person by removing fear and letting them speak<br />

as they wish. This is what truly distinguishes the inner character <strong>of</strong> a human. That which<br />

is said or done when no one else can see is generally the true desire <strong>of</strong> that person’s heart.<br />

With that, I would take a moment to reflect on what we have all posted to glimpse inside<br />

ourselves to see if we are acting more as a person we can take pride in being or if there are<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> our lives which need adjustment to bring us in line with our true potential.<br />

Next Message by Jeremy is [641].<br />

[664] Rampton: Freakonomics Today. I found it amazing that there are so many ways<br />

to look at the ideas <strong>of</strong> men. The different way that you can put economics in life. He poses<br />

such questions as, Which is more dangerous, a gun or a swimming pool? Why do drug<br />

dealers still live with their parents? How did the legalization <strong>of</strong> abortion affect the rate <strong>of</strong><br />

violent crime? These are some <strong>of</strong> the questions that Freakonomics Author talks about in his<br />

book. It seems like a very interesting topic. I am sitting here in the audience excited to hear<br />

what he is going to talk about!


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 433<br />

Next Message by Rampton is [804].<br />

[667] Rmuscolino: Freakonomics. The book “Freakonomics”, by Steven Levitt, was so<br />

interesting! It talks about what factors motivate people and how people get what they want. It<br />

relates some crazy things as well such as, “What Do School Teachers Have in Common with<br />

Sumo Wrestlers?” and “How Is the Ku Klux Klan Like a Group <strong>of</strong> Real-Estate Agents?”<br />

The authors present surprising and enlightening examples <strong>of</strong> how economics can be used<br />

to describe why people do the things they do. The book criticizes some <strong>of</strong> the conclusions<br />

presented in the economy, and contends that its strength lies with the questions it asks, rather<br />

than the answers it <strong>of</strong>fers. It’s a great book and definitely worth reading!<br />

Next Message by Rmuscolino is [712].<br />

[676] Ken: health care crisis. The U.S. health care system is in a crisis. The reason I<br />

feel like the health care system is in a crisis because only a specific group <strong>of</strong> people benefit<br />

from our health care system. “For Rawls, the central task <strong>of</strong> government is to preserve and<br />

promote the liberty and welfare <strong>of</strong> individuals.” (Munson, 759, 2004). Rawls’s theory <strong>of</strong><br />

justice uses utilitarianism, principles <strong>of</strong> justice and a “veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance”. A veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance<br />

would hypothetically be created by causing a group <strong>of</strong> people to become completely<br />

ignorant. These people would be unaware <strong>of</strong> their personal welfare and status. They would<br />

then create policies that would give everyone a chance at achieving opportunities, wealth<br />

and power. Because the people in this hypothetical group are ignorant, they would be unable<br />

to create policies that would benefit themselves. (Munson, 760, 2004). “It would never be<br />

right, in Rawls’s view, to exploit one group <strong>of</strong> people or even one person for the benefit <strong>of</strong><br />

others.” (Munson, 762, 2004). If a health care policy were created under a veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance,<br />

coverage would provide equal benefits and be available to everyone. The plan would not<br />

only ensure equal opportunity for health coverage but also increase utility for most individual.<br />

If the U.S. implemented a plan that was created under a veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance our health<br />

care system would be much better <strong>of</strong>f.<br />

Message [676] referenced by [687]. Next Message by Ken is [758].<br />

[687] Dyoung: health care crisis. I would have to agree with Ken [676] when he says “If<br />

a health care policy were created under a veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance, coverage would provide equal<br />

benefits and be available to everyone. The plan would not only ensure equal opportunity for<br />

health coverage but also increase utility for most individual. If the U.S. implemented a plan<br />

that was created under a veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance our health care system would be much better <strong>of</strong>f.”<br />

I also think that the health care system is not fair. I attended a lecture yesterday where I was<br />

greatly surprised how unfair the system really is. There are people out there who are doing<br />

their best to provide for their families or themselves and they can’t get basic health care.<br />

It was very sad to hear about all the people who are denied basic care because <strong>of</strong> a system<br />

that is very one-sided. I learned that some <strong>of</strong> the treatments needed for someone would only<br />

cost $3.00 a month. We live is a society that waits for individuals to crash before we will<br />

give them help, which I feel is stupid and wrong. When a person crashes completely, it ends<br />

up costing $200,000 plus dollars to help them, but if we had a better health care system<br />

that helped in the preventative side we would only have to spend that $3.00 instead <strong>of</strong> the<br />

hundreds <strong>of</strong> thousands. It is unfair and something needs to change in our society to help out<br />

the less fortunate.


434 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Hans: Since you agree with Ken’s (or Rawls’s) principle <strong>of</strong> “veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance,” it would have been appropriate to<br />

explain better than Ken what the veil <strong>of</strong> ignorance is and how it helps improve our health care system. It is also not<br />

obvious how this principle is connected with preventive health care which you are advocating.<br />

Message [687] referenced by [693]. Next Message by Dyoung is [776].<br />

[691] Chris: Wal-Mart’s lawsuit against its own employee. I heard about this story a<br />

few weeks ago and thought it would be a good time to bring it up right now while we are<br />

talking about our health care system. Here is my summary and opinion: There is a Wal-Mart<br />

employee that was recently in a car crash and suffered about $400,000 in medical costs. This<br />

employee was covered by a Wal-Mart health care plan and could barely meet her and her<br />

family’s needs. After the accident, she sued the trucking company who’s driver had crashed<br />

into her to cover the damages. She won the lawsuit and received $417,000 in compensation<br />

to cover the medical costs. So, what does Wal-Mart think <strong>of</strong> all this? Well, they have a<br />

clause in their contracts saying that they can sue their own employees if they win a lawsuit<br />

for such actions so Wal-Mart decided to sue their employee for $400,000. However, they<br />

have decided to drop the charges because <strong>of</strong> the negative publicity they were receiving. This<br />

is the only reason in my opinion for why they would drop the lawsuit. I would classify<br />

myself as leaning towards free-market enterprise in most situations. This has gone too far<br />

though. Corporate greed has surpassed a new low and there are thousands <strong>of</strong> stories out<br />

there that are even worse than this.<br />

http://i2.democracynow.org/2008/4/2/after adverse publicity wal mart drops<br />

Message [691] referenced by [692], [696], and [698]. Next Message by Chris is [809].<br />

[692] Ryoung: Walmart And Its New Low. Responding to Chris’ post [691] on Walmart<br />

and it having pursued a lawsuit against an employee <strong>of</strong> theirs, I too believe that in this<br />

situation Walmart had definitely crossed the line. I am all for the ability <strong>of</strong> one to pursue<br />

financial freedom whether it be a coorperation or an individual it is all the same to me but I<br />

first and foremost believe that during this pursuit one should not lose sight <strong>of</strong> how “Human<br />

Beings” should be treated. This particular case <strong>of</strong> Walmart claiming a lawsuit against this<br />

employee is obviously a case <strong>of</strong> losing sight <strong>of</strong> treating individuals correctly. This is one<br />

example <strong>of</strong> what gives those who achieve wealth a bad name.<br />

Hans: Ryoung emailed me privately that he wanted this counted as one <strong>of</strong> his two obligatory detailed feedback<br />

submission. This reminder was necessary. I wouldn’t have guessed that he thought this was a detailed feedback.<br />

He didn’t even give the message numbers he was referring to (I had to do this). Enthusiastic approval without going<br />

into the details what he other person was saying satisfies the requirement <strong>of</strong> building on others’ submission, but not<br />

that <strong>of</strong> detailed feedback. You can read more about this in my comments to [533].<br />

Message [692] referenced by [693]. Next Message by Ryoung is [693].<br />

[693] Ryoung: Health Care. Responding to the Health Care post <strong>of</strong> Dyoung [687] and<br />

Ken [688] sparked my thoughts on our current health care systems. The health care systems<br />

that currently exist are very one-sided like Dyoung mentioned. Not only are they one-sided<br />

but they are also very difficult to obtain in the case <strong>of</strong> health care insurance packages. I am<br />

self-employed and it is darn near impossible to find a carrier that would cover me, and once<br />

I found some coverage the expense was so great that I wondered if it was even worth it!<br />

I believe that the Health Care crisis is a problem for all demographics in the country, and<br />

something needs to be done! It is as though a basic insurance package is only worth it in<br />

case <strong>of</strong> a catastrophe! This is not how it should be and I hope to see improvements in the<br />

near future!


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 435<br />

Hans: Your own experience adds to what Ken and Dyoung were saying, but as I said in my remarks to your [692],<br />

this does not satisfy the criteria <strong>of</strong> “detailed feedback.”<br />

Next Message by Ryoung is [694].<br />

[696] Brandon: RE: Wal-Mart’s lawsuit against its own employee. Wow I cannot<br />

believe this. I had never heard <strong>of</strong> this story [691] until today and I’m pretty shocked. For<br />

most <strong>of</strong> this class, I haven’t never really agreed with a lot <strong>of</strong> Marxian philosophy and its<br />

‘assesment’ <strong>of</strong> capitalism. I’ll be honest and say that I still agree with capitalism and free<br />

market economics, however, I have never been a supporter <strong>of</strong> Wal-Mart and its blatant abuse<br />

<strong>of</strong> producers, consumers and especially its employees. It isn’t even fathomable to think that<br />

a multi-billion dollar corporation really needs to collect $400,000 in ‘lost’ medical expenses<br />

for their own employee covered by their medical plan. We could go on and on about how<br />

terrible Wal-Mart’s practices are and the fine line they walk on a daily basis <strong>of</strong> unethical<br />

practices, but I actually want to <strong>of</strong>fer a corporation that has done the antithesis and has<br />

succeeded in the corporate world.<br />

I used to work for Starbucks C<strong>of</strong>fee, for about 4 years, until last May. Say what you<br />

will about Starbucks as a corporation, they would have responded to an incident like this<br />

180 degrees the other way. Employee safety, rights, and welfare are the top priorities in<br />

Starbucks’ policies. Not only do they provide full benefits (medical, dental, 401k, stock<br />

options, etc.) for part-time employees (who work a minimum <strong>of</strong> 20 hours a week/ or 240<br />

hours per quarter) but they also have a private fund made up <strong>of</strong> contributions from fellow<br />

employees to assist partners who go through tramatic experiences and need time <strong>of</strong>f from<br />

work but cannot sustain their living expenses. Almost every partner contributes to this “CUP<br />

Fund” usually at a dollar per paycheck. What Starbucks has done put their employees almost<br />

above their own customers. They do not start <strong>of</strong>f new-hires at the base minimum wage but<br />

rather determine minimum pay <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> the local standard <strong>of</strong> living. For example, when I was<br />

hired at Starbucks in Seattle (2003), the minimum wage was around $6.50/hr. I was started<br />

at $7.15/hr, receiving increases in pay every six months. I then moved to Park City, UT in<br />

2004, my pay was raised to $8.75/hr because Starbucks recognized that I was working/living<br />

in an area with higher costs <strong>of</strong> living. I was also able to contribute 8% <strong>of</strong> my paycheck to a<br />

401k plan, which Starbucks began matching at 25% after 1 year. I don’t know <strong>of</strong> any other<br />

corporation that gives back to employees, essentially working in a ‘fastfood’ environment,<br />

as much as Starbucks. Not to mention the $500 tuition reimbursement every semester ($750<br />

after 36 mos., and $1000 after 60 mos.). This should be the model that corporations, like<br />

Wal-Mart, should be following. Instead, their model is to not provide any extra dime to<br />

employess in order to completely maximize pr<strong>of</strong>its. To be honest, I do not know why anyone<br />

would even consider applying for a job there.<br />

Message [696] referenced by [697]. Next Message by Brandon is [697].<br />

[698] Matt: Walmart, the true Capitalist. If you have ever been in Walmart it seems<br />

to be a happy place to shop. There are door greeters who are always smiling, clerks who<br />

are always willing to help. They all even have aprons or T-shirts that say, “How may I help<br />

you.” However, underneath all the smiles and happiness lies the truth. It is all a show and a<br />

scam to get your dollar. This “show”, you have to remember, is all run by the capitalist.<br />

The story Chris [691] brought up about Walmart is shocking in one way but not surprising.<br />

Walmart has grown beyond leaps and bounds since they started over 40 years ago. The


436 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

key to their success and pr<strong>of</strong>its is due to their cheap prices, as one might say. However these<br />

cheap prices are due to the fact that they, as the capitalist, control the means <strong>of</strong> production<br />

on all levels. When they hire people it is usually at minimum wage. They also hire workers<br />

to work 30 hour weeks instead <strong>of</strong> 40 so they don’t have to pay them full benefits. And, they<br />

also sue their own employees (as Chris pointed out) whenever possible. These methods are<br />

all part <strong>of</strong> how a true capitalist makes a nice pr<strong>of</strong>it for themselves. They hire a worker for<br />

their labor-power which they turn into surplus-value. This surplus-value is not in turn given<br />

back to the worker but is instead used to hire more workers and to pay for CEO’s salaries<br />

and lucrative vacations. Our society is based on the principal <strong>of</strong> pushing others down to get<br />

ahead, and to do whatever it takes to make an extra buck. We should learn from our mistakes<br />

by stopping the capitalist from taking advantage <strong>of</strong> us. We deserve the surplus-value that the<br />

capitalist has taken away from us.<br />

Next Message by Matt is [774].<br />

[720] Tim: RE: Walmart, the true Capitalist. In response to [689]: I will admit that I try<br />

to stay out <strong>of</strong> walmart as much as possible, but just because they know how to make a pr<strong>of</strong>it<br />

doesn’t mean that they don’t help people out. Do they pay thier employees minimum wage?<br />

Yes, but where else are most <strong>of</strong> those people going to work? Walmart provides thousands<br />

<strong>of</strong> jobs for unskilled workers that would not be able to find jobs anywhere else. Sure they<br />

don’t provide the best bennifit packages for thier employees, but at least they provide a way<br />

for people to put a little food on the table. I don’t agree with everything they do either but<br />

before walmart is made out to be the worst thing that ever happened to America, read this,<br />

http://walmartstores.com/media/factsheets/fs 2315.pdf<br />

and it might change your mind a little.<br />

Next Message by Tim is [722].<br />

[745] Inter: Literary critique <strong>of</strong> feudalism. I just want to present a couple <strong>of</strong> quotes<br />

from one <strong>of</strong> my favorite pieces <strong>of</strong> literature, Utopia by Sir. Thomas More [1515-16].<br />

Just like how Marx is writing a critique <strong>of</strong> capitalism in Das Kapital, so does Thomas<br />

More write a critique <strong>of</strong> English feudalism in Utopia. Chapter 26 <strong>of</strong> Das Kapital also speaks<br />

<strong>of</strong> the origin <strong>of</strong> capitalism in feudalism; therefore, I feel these quotes are relevant to our<br />

class discussion. These are critiques <strong>of</strong> the “commonwealth” by Thomas More through the<br />

character <strong>of</strong> Raphael.<br />

“What kind <strong>of</strong> justice is it when a nobleman or a goldsmith or a moneylender, or someone<br />

else who makes his living by doing either nothing at all or something completely useless to<br />

the public, gets to live a life <strong>of</strong> luxury and grandeur? In the meantime, a laborer, a carter,<br />

a carpenter, or a framer works so hard and so constantly that even a beast <strong>of</strong> burden would<br />

perish under the load. Although this work <strong>of</strong> theirs is so necessary that no commonwealth<br />

could survive a year without it, they earn so meager a living and lead such miserable lives<br />

that a beast <strong>of</strong> burden would really seem to be better <strong>of</strong>f.”<br />

“What is worse, the rich constantly try to grind out <strong>of</strong> the poor part <strong>of</strong> their meager<br />

wages, not only by private swindling but by public laws. It is basically unjust that people<br />

who deserve most from the commonwealth should receive least. But now they have distorted


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 437<br />

and debased the right even further by giving their extortion the color <strong>of</strong> law; and thus they<br />

have palmed injustice <strong>of</strong>f as “legal.”<br />

Next Message by Inter is [754].<br />

[750] Jenn: Subprime market recovery. One <strong>of</strong> the common debates you hear on the<br />

news these days is what should be done with the subprime mortgage borrowers, or people<br />

upside-down in their houses? I am conflicted on this debate. On one hand, I feel people<br />

should be responsible for the financial choices they make. Period. On the other hand, if they<br />

were misled on the loan market, they should be compensated. However, if you are signing<br />

for a loan, I hope you would read for yourself what you are signing. If the government<br />

intervenes, ultimately I am paying for someone else’s poor planning, which I am not too<br />

happy about. Especially for those sniff poor Californians and their million-dollar houses....<br />

http://www.npr.org/templates/story/story.php?storyId=89505982<br />

Any thoughts?<br />

Message [750] referenced by [782]. Next Message by Jenn is [771].<br />

[782] Kevin: Subprime mess. In response to Jenn [750]:<br />

I listened to the same thing on npr the other day and too am torn on how I feel about that<br />

and all the other economic bail outs that are going on right now.<br />

Personally, I’m torn. Huge companies are getting money handed to them all the time.<br />

Not just now, but have always. Just look at Delta when they declared bankruptcy. If that<br />

happened to a smaller company they would have to close their doors and deal with it. Delta<br />

gets to merge with Northwest and they’re going to a monster company. Makes you think<br />

going bankrupt would be a good business strategy.<br />

All these financial companies too are getting support and help. All the bailing them out is<br />

going to do is let them know they can take risks as large as they want and someone’s always<br />

going to be there to hold their hand.<br />

I feel the same way about individuals. As these people took huge risks (understanding<br />

or not the consequences) they’re learning that someone’s always going to bail them out.<br />

What’s to stop people from doing this again if someone’s going to be there to catch them<br />

when they fall. And who’s really doing the catching? Who’s really bailing them out? The<br />

people responsible enough to pay for what they have, pay their taxes, and let everyone else<br />

take advantage <strong>of</strong> them.<br />

First Message by Kevin is [1].<br />

[791] Scott: cocktail. What reasons does the government have for not making the drug<br />

cocktail for aids patients more accessible?<br />

This is a question that was asked one <strong>of</strong> my classes that caught my attention.<br />

Government <strong>of</strong>ficials place restrictions on how the United States’ money can be spent<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> international aid. Many communitites in Pap New Guinea want a system <strong>of</strong><br />

community testing and community based counseling and education. However when groups<br />

attempted to set up these programs international organizations said no to the funding request<br />

because these programs violate individual privacy rights, according to these organizations.<br />

Message [791] referenced by [792]. Next Message by Scott is [835].


438 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[792] Nstew: RE: cocktail. In response to [791]: It all comes down to money$$! Aids is<br />

a very pr<strong>of</strong>itable business for the drug companies and the drug companies are in bed with the<br />

FDA. An aids drug cocktail treatment in the United States costs about $15,000 a year, but<br />

by using generic versions, countries like Brazil and India have dropped the prices <strong>of</strong> those<br />

cocktails down to $3,000 and $1,000, respectively. In the case <strong>of</strong> Brazil, the government<br />

<strong>of</strong>fers free treatment and has set up clinics that have improved the lifestyle <strong>of</strong> AIDS victims.<br />

Unfortunately, the reaction <strong>of</strong> drug manufacturers has been to curtail these countries’ access<br />

to generic versions <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> the 12 drugs used to make the cocktail. The worldwide<br />

pharmaceutical industry is about a $650 billion a year business while making close to $8<br />

billion a year <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> the aids cocktail.<br />

Message [792] referenced by [798]. Next Message by Nstew is [817].<br />

[793] PrivateProperty: Re: Mankind? In response to Nstew [790], I think it is naive<br />

to think that individuals have a simple choice <strong>of</strong> either working for somebody or starting<br />

your own company. Very few people can just start ‘producing’ and expect to make money.<br />

The market has to be favorable to you. The cold hard truth is that the vast majority <strong>of</strong> new<br />

enterprises fail within the first year. The success stories you hear about are 1 in a million<br />

cases and mistakenly considered ‘normal,’ when they are in fact rare. You don’t hear about<br />

the losers in the capitalist game. Granted, I’m all for being optimistic and shooting for the<br />

top, and it IS important to take risks. But which vanilla-flavored American dream are people<br />

choosing, anyway? Let’s be realistic with ourselves. Capitalism is largely responsible for<br />

defining what exactly ‘success’ is.<br />

In the case <strong>of</strong> Wal-Mart, which today is the largest retailer in the world, Sam Walton<br />

started with a small store that was successful because it had lower prices than everybody<br />

else. Because <strong>of</strong> this low-cost philosophy, Wal-Mart has grown into what it is today: A<br />

retail monstrosity that retards local businesses, <strong>of</strong>ten driving them into the ground (though<br />

this only happens because <strong>of</strong> the people that continue to shop at Wal-Mart regularly). Why<br />

is this bad? Because there is no local ownership, and thus no presence in the community.<br />

Individual owners, however, do have a role and presence here. I am not one <strong>of</strong> those anti-<br />

Wal-Mart hippies that diligently follows these kinds <strong>of</strong> things. But, I do care about my<br />

community, and I think it’s important to at least by wary <strong>of</strong> buying into everything at the<br />

lowest possible price just for the sake <strong>of</strong> saving money.<br />

This is an important issue, because capitalism does not treat people as ends unto themselves,<br />

as it should be. Rather, money perpetuates. The sad thing is money (and commodities)<br />

is how many people relate to each other, not as human beings.<br />

Next Message by PrivateProperty is [852].<br />

[796] Alcameron: The Sub-prime disaster....intentional? I heard an interesting point<br />

<strong>of</strong> view about the subprime market that makes me wonder how much <strong>of</strong> an accident it really<br />

was.<br />

The basis <strong>of</strong> the subprime mess is that lenders were irresponsible and put buyers in loans<br />

that they could not afford or in high risk loans. These companies are run by intelligent,<br />

successful business men who have had experience in the mortgage industry for decades.<br />

What incentive do they have to <strong>of</strong>fer loans to underqualified applicants or to write high risk<br />

loans? The answer could just be they wanted the buyers to default! Let me explain...


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 439<br />

Many <strong>of</strong> the loans that are defaulting are risky loans in which a buyer has a low minimum<br />

payment at the beginning <strong>of</strong> the loan and that payment gradually rises for a pre-determined<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> time until the full payment has been reached. Many buyers could afford the<br />

initial low payment, but the final payment amount in 5 or 10 years was out <strong>of</strong> their budget.<br />

To achieve such a low payment at the outset the equity in the home is used to pay the<br />

“remaining” amount <strong>of</strong> the minimum payment, so essentially your loan is going backwards<br />

for the first few years. Now why would any intelligent business man want to put someone<br />

in a loan that they wont be able to afford 3, 5, 10 years down the road? Well the market<br />

at the time these loans were written was booming. Home values were rising 15-20% every<br />

year. The equity needed to <strong>of</strong>fset the low payments was easily made up for and surpassed<br />

by the appreciation <strong>of</strong> real estate in the booming market. When a buyer could no longer<br />

afford their loan in X amnt <strong>of</strong> years they would either sell their home and they lender keeps<br />

all the points and origination fees as pr<strong>of</strong>it, or the home-owner defaults on the loan and the<br />

lender now owns a home worth MUCH more than the amount <strong>of</strong> the loan they have. In the<br />

thriving market it wont be difficult to find another underqualified buyer for the home and eat<br />

up the equity as pr<strong>of</strong>it. Not only do you make money on the way in <strong>of</strong> a purchase, but on<br />

the way out too! Pr<strong>of</strong>its come from every direction. Is it realistic that NOBODY saw the<br />

consequences <strong>of</strong> writing these types <strong>of</strong> loans? I find it hard to believe that some investors<br />

didnt know what they were doing to people. They simply chose to make as much pr<strong>of</strong>it as<br />

possible at the expense <strong>of</strong> home-owners. Well now their plan has backfired and both the<br />

home-owner and the investor find themselves in a precarious situation.<br />

Next Message by Alcameron is [885].<br />

[798] Slash: Cocktail. In response to [792], one <strong>of</strong> the major arguments for not having<br />

socialized, or universal health care is limiting the earnings <strong>of</strong> pharmaceutical companies,<br />

which could effect the ability for them to invest in research, this was the topic that almost<br />

stopped Switzerland from becoming a universalized country in 1994. Today though they are<br />

still one <strong>of</strong> the top ranking countries for producing new drugs, but I would argue without<br />

some creativity. The U.S. would lose much <strong>of</strong> its new drug making abilities without them<br />

having such huge earnings, but on the other hand what’s the point <strong>of</strong> having new drugs if no<br />

one can afford them.<br />

Next Message by Slash is [901].<br />

[799] Papageorgio: Mandatory or not. A debate in one <strong>of</strong> my classes is on health care<br />

and wether we would like to see a mandatory system or a non mandatory system. Hillary<br />

Clinton is backing a system in which health care is required for everyone it is mandatory<br />

and all will recieve it because they have to. This can be good becuase it ensures all have it<br />

and reduces our or the governments charges when a non insured person goes to the E R. It<br />

is said to be similar to car insurance how it is required in most states for a driver. The other<br />

side is Obama’s plan it to is to help everyone recieve health care but not mandatory it is not<br />

required although it actually is required for young children. Which plan seems better?<br />

Message [799] referenced by [801]. Next Message by Papageorgio is [810].<br />

[801] Paul: Make it mandatory. In response to Papageorgio [799] I believe that the<br />

better option is to make health coverage mandatory for everyone in the united states. By<br />

doing this is should greatly reduce the cost for everybody who already pays for health coverage<br />

and those who truly cannot afford it will be given subsidies by the government. As<br />

Papageorgio stated the government is forced with paying the bill when uninsured people


440 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

visit the emergency room. Another cost saving benefit to a mandate would be the fact that<br />

everybody would be able to receive preventive care, making it much easier to catch certain<br />

illnesses therefore dramatically decreasing the money spent trying to treat which would then<br />

lower the premiums for everyone. There is also evidence that enforcing a mandate would<br />

also greatly reduce the cost <strong>of</strong> prescriptions.<br />

Next Message by Paul is [866].<br />

[804] Rampton: Mortgage Crisis. Everyone talks about the Mortgage Crisis, the only<br />

real value that is being lost is paper value. I think the Fed should step in and help people to<br />

avoid a crisis. Sure, people should not have gotten into things that they could not afford. The<br />

credit crisis is no longer just a sub-prime problem. As home prices fall and banks tighten<br />

lending standards, people with good, or prime, credit histories are falling behind on their<br />

payments for home loans, auto loans and credit cards at a quickening pace, according to<br />

industry data and economists. The rise in prime delinquencies, while less severe than the<br />

one in the subprime market, nonetheless poses a threat to the battered housing market and<br />

weakening economy, which some specialists say is in a recession or headed for one.<br />

Until recently, people with good credit, who tend to pay their bills on time and manage<br />

their finances well, were viewed as a bulwark against the economic strains posed by rising<br />

defaults among borrowers with blemished, or subprime, credit.<br />

It’s seems like it’s Socialist for the rich but not for the poor. There is so much potential in<br />

the USA. It will only be realized if there is people that are willing to stand up.<br />

Message [804] referenced by [807]. Next Message by Rampton is [844].<br />

[807] Bmellor: RE: Mortgage Crisis. The irony <strong>of</strong> the whole mess is that like Rampton<br />

said in [804] it is socialism for the wealthy, the first to start crying foul when there are<br />

changes in the minimum wage, or any type <strong>of</strong> increase in taxes. Now there is a bailout<br />

and these same individuals are benefiting. Where is the “pull yourself up by your boot<br />

straps” attitude? The Fed went before the government and explained why they bailed out<br />

Bear Sterns, likening it to a weak place in a dam. If that banking institution goes it all<br />

goes. I don’t believe it. (How can an administration justify the bail out by bringing up the<br />

“Great Depression,” when it can’t even seem to learn from history enough to keep us out<br />

<strong>of</strong> a Vietnam-like sequel?) This capitalist society is structured around the purge <strong>of</strong> those<br />

companies and institutions that can’t keep up. Why are we bending the rules now? I would<br />

bet that Bear Sterns is contributing handsomely to some political campaigns.<br />

Message [807] referenced by [809], [813], and [815]. Next Message by Bmellor is [808].<br />

[808] Bmellor: perfect storm <strong>of</strong> narcissism. My wife got an e-mail the other day that<br />

was from her sister who she hasn’t spoken with in almost 2 years, a casual e-mail, avoiding<br />

real conversation, inviting her to look at her family’s blog. I am 26 years old however I feel<br />

clueless and geriatric when I look at people’s blogs and myspace pages. I don’t understand<br />

how people my same age, adults, participate in the overdose <strong>of</strong> self-promotion, this perfect<br />

storm <strong>of</strong> narcissism technically called “social networking.”<br />

I would never invite people to come into my house and look through my photo album<br />

anytime they want, so why would I think it is a good I idea to invited friends, neighbors,<br />

acquaintances and even perfect strangers to peek into our private lives whenever the feel<br />

like through a blog. For some this isn’t their private lives despite what they portray, it is a


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 441<br />

fabricated reality. Photoshop pictures to make the scene depict the ideal, only using images<br />

that give a false impression. What are the long term effects <strong>of</strong> this type <strong>of</strong> society?<br />

To answer this question we have to understand that although the medium may be new, the<br />

symptoms are all too familiar.<br />

They are lies, these fabricated reality blogs are lies. The narcissistic FaceBook pages<br />

boasting, bragging, all fueled by pride. I’m far from being the arbitrator <strong>of</strong> what is moral<br />

and good. I tell lies, making me familiar with the terrible consequence. I fear that we are<br />

distancing ourselves from true reality and from learning valuable lessons. Things men and<br />

women used to grow out <strong>of</strong> when they left high school or college now seem to be present<br />

into their thirties, middle age individuals that still behave like adolescents. And what about<br />

today’s children who don’t know how to be bored anymore, they are losing the creativity<br />

associated with being bored. I heard on the news the other day that not having a MySpace<br />

page can be bad for people looking for employment because it makes your employer think<br />

that you have something to hide. WHAT? I do have something to hide my damn privacy. I<br />

don’t believe that news story for a moment.<br />

There are things you can never take back; among those are things you post on the internet,<br />

words you post on the internet. First impressions are lasting impressions no matter the<br />

media.<br />

Children in Davis County are texting images <strong>of</strong> their private body parts to classmates.<br />

These children now have rap sheets, forced to grow up too early.<br />

Mothers amidst gossiping on their BlogSpot they discuss, “How could this happen?”<br />

gossiping now made easier than ever through their new media. Someone explain to me why<br />

a 14 year old needs a cell phone with a camera?<br />

Same crap different day.<br />

Message [808] referenced by [810] and [817]. Next Message by Bmellor is [811].<br />

[809] Chris: Bear Stearns bailout. Bmellor really got me thinking in his [807] where<br />

he brought up the point that Bear Stearns may contribute handsome sums to political campaigns.<br />

I did a little research on the website and found a few links:<br />

http://www.sourcewatch.org/index.php?title=Bear%2C Stearns %26 Co.%2C Inc.<br />

http://www.newsmeat.com/ceo political donations/James Cayne.php<br />

The second link, Newsmeat, is one <strong>of</strong> the most interesting websites that I have never heard<br />

<strong>of</strong>. You can literally type in any person’s name and find out how much they are contributing<br />

to each party/candidate. If Sourcewatch and Newsmeat are reputable sites, then it appears<br />

that Bear Stearns is contributing heavily towards campaign funds and lobbying groups. So<br />

in the end, it looks like there are alternative motives for the bailout.<br />

First Message by Chris is [10].<br />

[810] Papageorgio: RE: perfect storm <strong>of</strong> narcissism. Maybe you should quite focusing<br />

on the negative an think about the positive, [808] was a real negative post. Maybe its for<br />

some people its a good way to stay in touch with those who live far away or those they dont


442 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

see much anymore, you said your wife has not spoken to her sister in 2 years so maybe she<br />

would enjoy looking at the blog since she does not see her sister much, geez.<br />

Message [810] referenced by [811]. Next Message by Papageorgio is [856].<br />

[811] Bmellor: RE: perfect storm <strong>of</strong> narcissism. In response to [810]: If an individual<br />

only uses their blog or their myspace page for interacting with individuals that is pretty<br />

tragic. Especially if it is family.<br />

Next Message by Bmellor is [848].<br />

[813] Spawnblade: Just who are they bailing out? Bmellor [807] asks why Bear Stearns<br />

doesn’t pull itself up out <strong>of</strong> the muck? Of course your average small business owner would<br />

have to simply shut down their business if something went wrong. Due to all sorts <strong>of</strong> corporate<br />

protections, the corporate heads themselves would not be liable unless they did something<br />

fraudulent. So the only thing that is bailed out for them is their jobs. However, if a<br />

bank really does go down, what will Americans think about it? Sure, everyone with money<br />

deposited in the bank will receive up to 100k from the government, but can you imagine<br />

the cost that would take on the government? Honestly, I believe that would cost more than<br />

it took to ‘bail out’ Bear Stearns. This is because not everyone will withdraw their money<br />

immediately (at least the government hopes.) Aside from simply the economical factor, I<br />

believe strongly that the perception <strong>of</strong> the people is very important. I have to give inflation<br />

and the strength <strong>of</strong> the dollar as an example. These two representatives <strong>of</strong> our economy are<br />

virtually meaningless on their own. Inflations only real detriment is the adaption-lag that<br />

it takes to get used to the price changes (which is relatively small unless we’re talking <strong>of</strong><br />

hyperinflation.) Just as the strength <strong>of</strong> the dollar is merely a representative <strong>of</strong> our GDP compared<br />

to the amount <strong>of</strong> money in circulation. Yet you hear people constantly talk about how<br />

these two things are getting worse and worse, and we’re falling into some ‘dark economical<br />

pit’. Sayings like this are the things that give these adjectives their true power, by instilling<br />

images in the minds <strong>of</strong> the people that affect the way they go about their day to day life.<br />

Message [813] referenced by [815]. Next Message by Spawnblade is [828].<br />

[815] Gerund: Bear Stearns bailout. Spawnblade in [813] is correct that bailing out a<br />

depository bank generally would be cheaper than paying <strong>of</strong>f FDIC insurance for all accountholders.<br />

(Contrary to popular belief, FDIC has inadequate deposits to save anything larger<br />

than a medium-sized bank, pay<strong>of</strong>fs are made by the government, with taxpayers’ money.)<br />

This was shown in the 1970s when a couple major banks failed, and again in the 1980s when<br />

Congress was forced to organize the S&L’s bailouts.<br />

However, Bear Stearns is not a depository bank, it is an investment bank. The function<br />

<strong>of</strong> the bailout was similar to the bailout <strong>of</strong> Long Term Capital Management in 1997. The<br />

company suffered serious losses on their mortgage assets, which they were required to write<br />

down under new accounting rules that were adopted early last year. With the write-downs<br />

done, it became evident that the bank was essentially insolvent. If they were allowed to<br />

fail, they would have been forced to liquidate all their remaining assets, which would have<br />

collapsed other financial markets. This was the rationale for the bailout. (Which answers<br />

[807].)<br />

This idea <strong>of</strong> ‘too-big-to-fail’ has its own problems, introducing moral hazard into the<br />

markets. It is now in every bank’s best interest to expand as much as possible, regardless <strong>of</strong>


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 443<br />

the risk <strong>of</strong> failure, because if they do fail they’ll be bailed out, and if they succeed they’re<br />

the Kings <strong>of</strong> Capital.<br />

First Message by Gerund is [47].<br />

[817] Nstew: RE: perfect storm <strong>of</strong> narcissism. In response to Bmellor’s post [808] on<br />

narcissism I think the stance that he has taken is entirely too negative, cynical and somewhat<br />

ignorant. You are one <strong>of</strong> the smart / lucky ones who is married at the age <strong>of</strong> 26 and never had<br />

to use these types <strong>of</strong> “networking” sites to connect you with people. There is a huge number<br />

<strong>of</strong> people who are your age and older using blogs, Facebook, My Space etc... to try and meet<br />

people. If you aren’t into the bar scene or the LDS singles scene and you have graduated<br />

from college and are working, your chances <strong>of</strong> meeting someone are not very good. I think<br />

it is the adolescence’s who should not be allowed to have Facebook, My Space, and other<br />

such accounts. They are getting into fare more trouble on these internet sites than those who<br />

are your age or older. A lot <strong>of</strong> families who do not have the luxury <strong>of</strong> living close to each<br />

other use the blogs and other types <strong>of</strong> sites to stay in touch and keep each other updated on<br />

what’s going on in their lives. For those people who are blogging and using these sites for<br />

constructive purposes I think they have found it as a great way to meet people.<br />

With that being said I am not oblivious to the fact that there a lot <strong>of</strong> people out there who<br />

fall directly into the category <strong>of</strong> what Bmellor is talking about. I happen to know the teenage<br />

kids up in Davis county who were the ones taking pictures <strong>of</strong> their private areas and sending<br />

them via text message. It has been a horribly tragic situation for them and their families.<br />

Kids in grade school have cell phones these days and in junior high if you don’t have a cell<br />

phone you are among the minority. This is the world we live in and all you can do to change<br />

it is control your actions and influence others to follow suit. But to categorize everyone who<br />

is into blogging, Facebook, My Space, ect... as being narcissistic is an ignorant statement to<br />

make.<br />

Next Message by Nstew is [841].<br />

[822] Bar: social networking. Well in response to Bmellor makes an interesting assessment<br />

about culture here, I agree with him that myspace and facebook are a waste <strong>of</strong><br />

time, and are impersonal in one sense, I hate spending time on something like that, but on<br />

the other hand sites like facebook reduce transaction costs a ton, with dating, business, and<br />

one hundred other things it is a great way to increase wealth in society why do you think<br />

that micros<strong>of</strong>t wants to own facebook so bad? it is a really good thing, now regarding your<br />

wife’s sister not talking to you for two years, it seems that email reduced the weight <strong>of</strong> that<br />

transaction cost <strong>of</strong> talking in person or personally so that she could finally talk to your wife<br />

I think that that is actually a pretty great thing. Lots <strong>of</strong> new things seem trivial, but the<br />

majority <strong>of</strong> things especially technology exist because they reduce some kind <strong>of</strong> cost in our<br />

society, dating is a huge thing because if you run the numbers its more likely that you meet<br />

more people through dating sites because <strong>of</strong> the economies <strong>of</strong> scale bettering your chances<br />

<strong>of</strong> meeting someone you like.<br />

Next Message by Bar is [823].<br />

[825] Bar: Organ donation is broken. something that I don’t understnd is why do<br />

organs cost so much money if organ donations are free? I am an organ donor and definitely<br />

think that it is something positive, but why shouldn’t I be able to sell a kidney if I need the<br />

money? If society allowed this, the price <strong>of</strong> organs would drop <strong>of</strong>f, the cost <strong>of</strong> a transplant


444 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

would plummet, and society would increase in wealth. The fact <strong>of</strong> the matter is the market<br />

is broken, it is a hyper socialized industry where good people like to help others through<br />

organ donation, but the government keeps an unaturally low supply on organs by not letting<br />

the market create the socially natural level. A pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> mine suggested a way to get the<br />

market equalibrium price for organs: By placing your organs as collateral on a life insurance<br />

policy, thereby receiving free life insurance, and the insurance company gets your organs<br />

when you die to sell to hospitals. This is a great idea! because the price is extremely high<br />

right now due to a shortage and all types <strong>of</strong> lists for organ donation, this would create a<br />

surplus making the price <strong>of</strong> orgnas plummet and lowering medical costs.<br />

Message [825] referenced by [837]. Next Message by Bar is [861].<br />

[837] Ande: Response to Bar on organ donation. In response to Bar [825] about organ<br />

donation being broken, I personally disagree with what was said about the issue on organ<br />

donations and transplants. The system is not broken in any way shape or form. There is<br />

just an extreme demand and a very limited supply on organs to be donated. Yes I agree that<br />

organs are very expensive to get but allowing people to sell their organs is not the answer.<br />

Bar said that selling your organs would help with fixing the system, and partly help out the<br />

economy and bring wealth to people. First <strong>of</strong>f the medical board will not let you sell part<br />

<strong>of</strong> your body that you could need in the future, as well being able to sell your organs would<br />

destroy the entire program, people would start being killed for organs and people would be<br />

in a sense selling their body parts as a way to create wealth and get out <strong>of</strong> working. The best<br />

answer to the shortage <strong>of</strong> organs for transplants in my opinion and the best answer to fixing<br />

the program is technological advances. The more people can donate to hospitals and research<br />

facilities the better. There is no way to get more organs and people will always be needing<br />

transplants, so if technology can keep going eventually science will create artificial organs<br />

that work like the real thing. There is no real answer to the issue but I certainly disagree with<br />

selling your organs as a way to solve the transplant and donor issues and shortages.<br />

First Message by Ande is [101].<br />

[843] Samantha: Fwd: supply and demand only work when the item at stake is a want<br />

not a need. I am shocked by Bar’s assertion that organs should be allowed to be sold so<br />

that more people would be able to get them. Unfortunately Ande did not go far enough, not<br />

only will the medical board not allow organs to sold but the reason we don’t just sell them is<br />

because capitalism itself does not with certain social needs. This is the reason that we have<br />

government regulation, price caps and floors, to set a reasonable price on goods that the<br />

public has to have. If we allowed capitalism to work unhindered in the medical sector, the<br />

few richest among us would get medical treatment because they could pay a billion dollars<br />

for a organ when the next among us could pay substantially less. The typical supply demand<br />

curve doesn’t work when negotiation is one sided because <strong>of</strong> possible loss <strong>of</strong> life. Thank<br />

heavens that organ donation does not work that way, but is rather based on the need level <strong>of</strong><br />

the patient and not the cost. I agree with Ande, the program isn’t broken we just need more<br />

people to donate.<br />

Next Message by Samantha is [854].<br />

[855] Scott: Uninsured <strong>Utah</strong>ns. 10.6 percent <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong>’s population were uninsured last<br />

year. This is a serious issue that needs to be addressed. Those in <strong>Utah</strong> that lack health insurance<br />

include: Young adults 19-26, <strong>Utah</strong>ns with incomes at or below 200% <strong>of</strong> the poverty


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 445<br />

level, those without a high school diploma and <strong>Utah</strong>ns who are <strong>of</strong> Hispanic or Latino ethnicity.<br />

The majority <strong>of</strong> the uninsured <strong>Utah</strong>ns had an employer with a sponsored insurance<br />

plan, but most declined the insurance because <strong>of</strong> the cost or even because they thought they<br />

didn’t need it. Health insurance is something that everyone should have. Each state should<br />

take control and make efficient plans available for everyone.<br />

Some factors that contribute to the increase in uninsured <strong>Utah</strong>ns are the lack <strong>of</strong> employers<br />

who <strong>of</strong>fer insurance, the high cost <strong>of</strong> insurance premiums to the employers/employees and<br />

the economic conditions that are affecting all <strong>of</strong> us today. Fortunately, there is a plan to help<br />

<strong>Utah</strong>ns become insured while still being able to pay their bills. This plan helps employees<br />

get health insurance through their employers health plan. Jennifer Erikson from the <strong>Utah</strong><br />

department <strong>of</strong> Health explains the program, “If an employer <strong>of</strong>fers health insurance, qualified<br />

individuals and families may receive up to $150 per adult each month from the program<br />

to help cover their monthly premium payment.” This plan will play a huge roll in allowing<br />

families to keep paying the bills while still taking care <strong>of</strong> themselves.<br />

I understand that every state has different issues but we should take Governor Romney’s<br />

approach as a textile. He made it mandatory for every citizen <strong>of</strong> Massachusetts to be insured.<br />

He did this by allowing them to pick their own individual policies. Gov. Romney said<br />

regarding the issue, “Those who couldn’t afford them, we helped them buy their policies.<br />

And you know what? It cost us no more money to help people buy insurance policies that<br />

they could afford than it was costing us before handing our free care.” By making this type<br />

<strong>of</strong> policy mandatory for each state, however adjusting a little for each state, I feel we would<br />

see great improvement.<br />

First Message by Scott is [96].<br />

[866] Paul: social security. The current state <strong>of</strong> the Social Security program in the United<br />

States is in need <strong>of</strong> a large change. If we do not change the current method <strong>of</strong> funding the<br />

program soon, generations in the future are the one that are going to suffer the consequences.<br />

The present administrations push to make it more privatized most likely will not produce a<br />

satisfactory impact on the on the funding <strong>of</strong> the Social Security program. Another vast<br />

problem with the existing system is that it favors the wealthy when it is the poor that depends<br />

more on the money provided for them through Social Security.<br />

The annual spending on Social Security will exceed what it generates through taxes in the<br />

year 2018, increasing the already large deficit. As a result, the trust fund will be empty by<br />

2042. One big reason for this is that today there are only 3.3 people paying Social Security<br />

for every one person using it, compared to sixteen people paying in 1950. The easiest way<br />

for us to fix this problem would be to increase taxes.<br />

Next Message by Paul is [867].<br />

[869] Andy: Health Care. Should health care reform be undertaken at the state or federal<br />

level? The majority <strong>of</strong> Americans under the age <strong>of</strong> 65 receive health insurance coverage<br />

through their employers and almost all the elderly are covered through Medicare, however<br />

46.1 million nonelderly Americans lacked health insurance in 2005. The number <strong>of</strong> uninsured<br />

continues to grow steadily, and most <strong>of</strong> the growth in the uninsured occurred among<br />

adults and those with low incomes, between 2004 and 2005 1.1 million <strong>of</strong> the 1.3 million had


446 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

family incomes <strong>of</strong> less than twice the poverty level. The majority <strong>of</strong> the growth in the uninsured<br />

since 2000 has been among people earning less that $38,000 a year for a family <strong>of</strong> four.<br />

Overall two-thirds <strong>of</strong> the uninsured are low-income with one-third living in poverty, which<br />

is earning less that 19,000 a year for a family <strong>of</strong> four. So health care should be reformed<br />

on the federal level and also on the state level. On the federal level, to try and decrease the<br />

overall number <strong>of</strong> uninsured people in the U.S. by creating plans that individual states can<br />

reform their own individual health policy. Each state is different. Take <strong>Utah</strong> for example:<br />

in 2007 there were about 287,200, or 10.6 percent <strong>of</strong> the population was uninsured with<br />

87,800 being children and 101,900 adults who had full time jobs. These numbers may be<br />

better or worse than other states so they may have to have a different policy to accommodate<br />

to different situations. So I believe that it is also very important that each individual state<br />

also reforms their policy to better help their own situation.<br />

Message [869] referenced by [893]. Next Message by Andy is [870].<br />

[875] Bmellor: Self fulfilling the imminent doom. The company I work for is owned by<br />

the employees. We are not all management <strong>of</strong> course, and some own more <strong>of</strong> the company<br />

than others but there isn’t one main guy that I would call the boss, I have never seen anyone<br />

get fired. Nor do can I think <strong>of</strong> anyone that should be fired. Everyone works well together,<br />

as has been the case for the last 2 years. Over that time though the company has grown at<br />

least 50% bigger, by that I mean a firm <strong>of</strong> 60 people has now become a firm <strong>of</strong> around 120<br />

people in just two years. With this growth has come a lot pr<strong>of</strong>it. Even those <strong>of</strong> us on the “low<br />

end” have gotten bonuses every 3 months right on queue... until December. It just stopped,<br />

our happy meetings <strong>of</strong> “Good Job,” “Way to go Guys, here is some more money” suddenly<br />

changed... a substantial number <strong>of</strong> people have quit. We are losing money.<br />

“Well there is recession looming in the midst, this should be expected.” But that is just<br />

it, there is too much work for even our staff to do... we are in a “recession pro<strong>of</strong>” industry.<br />

But yet the staffing charts with respect to hours billed are skewed. When the numbers are<br />

added up we are getting feedback that suggests that we have 12 too many people. Employees<br />

work hard and govern themselves, and when they are done with their task they come and get<br />

more work, they do this because they are not necessarily working for one individual, they<br />

are working to make the “whole” succeed.<br />

Why are we losing pr<strong>of</strong>its? Here is my theory: when you get in the car on your way to<br />

work, you hear about all the signs that our society is destroying itself, the world is getting<br />

too warm, the war will never end, gas will never stop being expensive, your owe more on<br />

your house than it’s worth, and most important “you still have your job but plan on losing<br />

it soon.” So we get out <strong>of</strong> cars after hearing all <strong>of</strong> this and we go to work, and while we are<br />

working we think “Once I finish this job... will they give me another one? And if not what<br />

will I do? I should slow down I get paid the same and they can’t lay me <strong>of</strong>f as long as I am<br />

working.” never mind the fact that the company is backed up and we need people to work<br />

harder than ever. I think <strong>of</strong> this as self fulfilling the “eminent doom.” There are real threats<br />

to our society the above listed are all true, but we must not lose optimism.<br />

80 years ago all we had to “fear was fear itself” the same is true today.<br />

First Message by Bmellor is [46].


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 447<br />

[880] Wade: Which country to buy from? The United States has imported raw materials<br />

and oil from third world Countries now for years. It used to be that the United States would<br />

import from Countries such as Canada, European Nations and Japan. It is amazing how the<br />

choice <strong>of</strong> which country the United States buys oil from can affect so many lives. Third<br />

world countries don’t benefit from U.S. oil purchases. GDP from foreign Countries has<br />

shifted from 2.5 percent in 1990 to 6 percent in 2006. And the biggest imports come from<br />

Countries with the lowest wages. The wages are a small percent <strong>of</strong> what they should be, and<br />

the rising purchases <strong>of</strong> oil and other raw materials, is raising the work hours <strong>of</strong> the laborer<br />

and lowering the wages even more.<br />

Next Message by Wade is [881].<br />

[881] Wade: Christmas Time. During the Holidays last year sales only rose by 3.6<br />

percent! That is the lowest performance in the past four years. And even one third <strong>of</strong> that<br />

was from gas purchases. That is horrible news for our economy; we are very dependent on<br />

free-spending shoppers for our growth. This is a result <strong>of</strong> delaying hiring plans, reduction in<br />

work hours and laying <strong>of</strong>f <strong>of</strong> workers. Once a downturn starts in our economy it is very hard<br />

to stop. Many Americans are not prepared for tough times. The past six years American<br />

economic growth has been great but this year it hasn’t gone as well. The ease <strong>of</strong> borrowing<br />

money in the past few years has made it easy for Americans to live beyond their means. Now<br />

we are seeing the results <strong>of</strong> what happens when times get going tough.<br />

Next Message by Wade is [882].<br />

[882] Wade: Tax Refunds? Tax-Refunds?<br />

In trying to help slumping economy by giving it a jolt, Congress has turned to different<br />

familiar ways that have worked in the past Economic downfalls. Which measure will work<br />

best to accomplish the goal <strong>of</strong> bringing the Economy back to where it should be? Funnel<br />

more money to States, or spend more on programs like unemployment insurance? Tax rebates?<br />

These are all factors, but tax rebates seem to look more appealing, they are designed<br />

to give money back to consumers, hoping that they will spend the money received giving a<br />

boost to manufacturers <strong>of</strong> consumer goods, instead <strong>of</strong> saving it to pay <strong>of</strong>f debts. But as we<br />

learned in 2001 with the tax rebates a small sum <strong>of</strong> Americans, only 22%, spent their rebates<br />

immediately. Would it benefit the Economy to give tax-rebates to Americans again?<br />

Next Message by Wade is [883].<br />

[884] Andy: Social Security. The current state <strong>of</strong> Social Security funding is constantly<br />

debated in the United States. In my opinion to this topic <strong>of</strong> Social Security I believe that<br />

currently we do not have a problem, but in the distant future we may run into some difficulties.<br />

The projections show that there will likely not be a problem, but if there is a problem<br />

we can currently do things to change what will happen in the future.<br />

Firstly, it has been projected that people will be able to withdraw benefits until the year<br />

2047, but after that there may be a problem. Many <strong>of</strong> the projections that have been made<br />

by the SSA have been proven to be incorrect. For instance the projections over ten years ago<br />

said that Social Security would be predicted to end in the year 2030. Our current numbers<br />

have disproved this projection. The SSA has been proven to be quite conservative on their<br />

projections about Social Security.


448 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Secondly, I believe that after the year 2047 we may not be able to receive our full benefit<br />

pay. There would still be enough money to pay out 74% to everyone, but the 1935 SSA Act<br />

guarantees that we receive a 100% payout. Even this prediction <strong>of</strong> only receiving 74% <strong>of</strong><br />

our benefits is projected if we don’t have any economic growth or productivity, which would<br />

be highly unlikely. The SSA would have to pay the excess 26% out <strong>of</strong> its trust fund, which<br />

is highly unlikely. If this were to happen we would have to require that there is no economic<br />

growth between now and 2047.<br />

Thirdly, if there are even projections that by the year 2047 the Social Security taxes will<br />

be less that the Social Security pays, we can do something now to help prevent this. Some<br />

things that have been discussed are increasing taxes on some things. In my opinion I believe<br />

that we should tax the upper class on some <strong>of</strong> the things that they don’t pay taxes on. For<br />

example when the wealthy receive cars, home, and other things for pay they don’t have to<br />

pay tax on it. I believe by taxing these people this would help the problem <strong>of</strong> even wondering<br />

if there would be enough tax money to pay out the benefits. Also, I believe by taxing their<br />

payroll would help the system benefit greatly.<br />

There was a discussion about this with Barack Obama and he stated in his argument<br />

about Social Security: “Social Security is not in crisis; it is a fundamentally sound system,<br />

but it does have a problem, long-term. We’ve got 78 million baby boomers, who are going<br />

to be retiring over the next couple <strong>of</strong> decades. That means more retirees, fewer workers<br />

to support those retirees. We are going to have to do something about it. The best idea<br />

is to lift the cap on the payroll tax, potentially exempting middle-class folks, but making<br />

sure that the wealthy are paying more <strong>of</strong> their fair share, a little bit more.” This argument<br />

helps support my issue in that I also believe that we aren’t currently in trouble with Social<br />

Security. I believe that in the distant future we might run into some difficulties and by taxing<br />

the wealthy now we are able to assure in the future that we won’t have any problems.<br />

Message [884] referenced by [886]. Next Message by Andy is [888].<br />

[886] Nstew: Social Security. In response to [884], the U.S. Social Security system is in<br />

need <strong>of</strong> reform. Its trustees forecast that, absent changes, contributions will fall below benefits<br />

in 2012, and the system’s trust fund will be exhausted in 2030. Many have discussed<br />

achieving system’s solvency by raising taxes and cutting benefits, but recently a more fundamental<br />

reform has been proposed, namely, “privatization” <strong>of</strong> some or all aspects <strong>of</strong> Social<br />

Security. Before analyzing whether the public or private sector can better achieve its underlying<br />

goals we need to look at some <strong>of</strong> the more salient features <strong>of</strong> the current system. It<br />

provides a forced savings, or income that cannot be spent prior to retirement. It provides<br />

insurance against earnings loss, disability, and longevity. It redistributes income from high<br />

to low lifetime earners. It is mainly an unfunded, or pay-as-you-go, system. It is controlled<br />

and administered by the government and it is a defined-benefit plan. The Social Security<br />

system is a collective one. Each worker’s Social Security taxes are not put aside to pay his<br />

or her eventual benefits; instead, they are used to finance the system in general, largely for<br />

current retirees. This is known as a pay-as-you-go system, which is where current workers’<br />

taxes are used to pay pensions to current retirees. We are rapidly approaching the time where<br />

the amount <strong>of</strong> people taking out <strong>of</strong> the Social Security fund will be greater than those who<br />

are putting into it. The baby-boomers are creeping up on retirement and they make up 26%<br />

<strong>of</strong> the population where as the group before them who are now between the ages <strong>of</strong> 55 - 69


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 449<br />

make up only 12% <strong>of</strong> the population. So as you can see we are headed for some very tough<br />

times keeping up with social security in the not so distant future.<br />

Next Message by Nstew is [892].<br />

[889] Rampton: American Idol. I find it funny that Carly Smithson had won rave reviews<br />

from all 3 judges – but apparently not votes from viewers – after performing “Superstar”<br />

from “Jesus Christ Superstar” on Tuesday’s Andrew Lloyd Webber-themed performance<br />

show she was booted tonight from the show. Apparently, people did not agree with the<br />

judges but the masses voted and this is what came about. I also find it interesting that<br />

President Bush and first lady Laura Bush appeared in a taped message to announce the “Idol<br />

Gives Back” charity event had raised more than $65 million for underprivileged children. In<br />

such a capitalistic society there are so many things that we could do to help others<br />

Next Message by Rampton is [890].<br />

[893] Nstew: Health Care. In response to [869]: I am among the millions <strong>of</strong> Americans<br />

who pay exorbitant insurance premiums every month and feel that quality <strong>of</strong> care is going<br />

down as price goes up. There is no doubt that the growth rate <strong>of</strong> health care expenditures<br />

must be curbed both as a cost to society and a cost to patients. Many people have put their<br />

faith in the idea <strong>of</strong> government control <strong>of</strong> the health care system. Many point to Canada or<br />

other countries that have gone that route. I think going that route would be a decision we<br />

would strongly regret. Most industrialized nations on earth have a distinct health care system<br />

and the common thread throughout the rest <strong>of</strong> the industrialized world is that government<br />

is the health care provider or at least a last resort. Although there are many advantages to<br />

having a single-payer-system, I believe the disadvantages outweigh them.<br />

I like the idea <strong>of</strong> socialized medicine in theory but not in practice. I feel the most important<br />

aspect in any industry is competition and individual ingenuity, which allow the consumer<br />

to receive the best possible service for the best price. I feel we have the best doctors and<br />

technology readily available for us here in the United States because we have a free market.<br />

Next Message by Nstew is [896].<br />

[900] Wade: Future Us Economy? With the Economy as bad as it is, it isn’t good that<br />

the national debt is at an all time high. What can be done to help this problem? There are<br />

many ideas, it seems that everyone has an idea <strong>of</strong> how to help the debt go away, but what is<br />

the answer? We are taught in Economics that the Economy is always changing, GDP and<br />

GNP ranges change yearly. The United States was doing great the past few years, businesses<br />

were booming, mortgages were being taken out as if they were free. Lots and lots <strong>of</strong> people<br />

were making lots and lots <strong>of</strong> big bucks. Then what happened? With all the mortgages being<br />

given as low as they were, people were refinancing, and spending their equity like it was<br />

play money. As soon as the Economy started a downward turn the media caught wind <strong>of</strong> it<br />

and had a hay day with it. People are now saving their money in these thought] times, and<br />

when that happens the circular money flow takes a big hit! When people aren’t spending<br />

or consuming, producers aren’t making the money they should and in return this hurts the<br />

consumers. We are headed into a recession, two annual quarters <strong>of</strong> loss. What needs to<br />

happen to turn our Economy around? We know that an Economy is like a roller coaster and<br />

is always going up and down. As we sit back and watch we will see that in the next few<br />

years our Economy will level out and all will be fine and dandy!<br />

Message [900] referenced by [902]. First Message by Wade is [188].


450 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

[902] Slash: Re: Future Us Economy? Way to hit the nail on the head Wade everything<br />

you’re saying in [900] is true. I too see the economy as a problem. I plan to make a change<br />

<strong>of</strong> this downward trend in any way I can, that might only be at the poles, but thats a start.<br />

Way to study up on the topic and may this next year bring you peace and happiness.<br />

First Message by Slash is [95].<br />

889 is 889 in 2007SP, 889 in 2009fa, 889 in 2011fa, and 889 in 2012fa:<br />

889 Course Evaluation Econ 5080/6080<br />

[862] Dentist: final thoughts. well i would just like to add a final thought or two on the<br />

class, and those <strong>of</strong> you who are still checking in may feel inclined to do the same.<br />

i must admit i enjoyed it more than i had supposed i would. there seemed to be a much<br />

more continuous dialogue and debate than in previous courses i have had that were similar<br />

to this one. and for all those that contributed to this process, i <strong>of</strong>fer my thanks.<br />

similarly, i must compliment Hans on this course structure as it seemed to greatly aid the<br />

steady flow <strong>of</strong> opinion and insight. i will admit that i had a difficult time keeping track <strong>of</strong><br />

so many deadlines and criteria, but as it has exposed a weakness that i had in my academic<br />

habits, i can take it as another lesson that i learned.<br />

while i may not be ready to adhere to Marx’s philosophies, at least i can now say that<br />

i understand a few <strong>of</strong> them. and that this has allowed me to be a more properly informed<br />

individual. i now have a much greater perspective <strong>of</strong> the world in which i live and a more<br />

open mind.<br />

blah blah blah and so what, right? for those who happen to read this, i would finally like<br />

to say, good luck in personal academic pursuits whatever they may be and wherever they<br />

may take you. i hope all <strong>of</strong> us can take time to enjoy and reflect on the great opportunity it<br />

is to get a college education, and the countless ways that it will enrich our lives.<br />

Message [862] referenced by [868]. Next Message by Dentist is [863].<br />

[863] Dentist: final, final thoughts. and good luck to all during their finals!<br />

First Message by Dentist is [203].<br />

[868] PrivateProperty: more final thoughts. Thank you Dentist [862] for sharing your<br />

thoughts and perspective. I’d like to share mine.<br />

I came to this class knowing next to nothing about Marxism, and I’ve come away with an<br />

understanding <strong>of</strong> capitalism. Not many people really understand how capitalism operates.<br />

And most that do are the most avid capitalists <strong>of</strong> all, the Captains <strong>of</strong> industry, the owners<br />

<strong>of</strong> production we talk about in class. To understand what capitalism is and say ‘no, this is<br />

not right’ is very powerful,. The things I have learned in this class have affirmed underlying<br />

feelings that I’ve had.<br />

I have had a great experience in this class and I want to thank everyone for their contributions.<br />

Everyone who has let their voice through and shown their passion on such issues.<br />

We are all in this together, and what we talk about is human issues. Yes there are ‘laborers’<br />

and ‘managers’ in the economy, but one just as well may be the other. The distinction is not<br />

important.


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 451<br />

Remember, capitalism is a game that we are forced to play from birth. There are other<br />

games out there, but it’s hard to see that. Many <strong>of</strong> you are concerned about being successful<br />

in this world (I know I am), but it’s important to not let the capitalist framework define what<br />

success is for you.<br />

And that being said, best <strong>of</strong> luck on finals everybody. It’s time for summer.<br />

Final Grading Note by Hans: It is my pleasure to write this letter <strong>of</strong> reference for (PrivateProperty). He took<br />

only one class from me, the writing intensive Econ 5080 in the Spring 2008. The class is a close reading <strong>of</strong> Marx’s<br />

Capital, which is not only an economic but also a philosophical work. Emphasis was on Marx’s methodology,<br />

whose depth realist and structuralist view <strong>of</strong> society is <strong>of</strong>ten difficult to grasp for students steeped in modern<br />

methodological individualism. The students have to make written comments about the readings, and also respond<br />

to each other.<br />

(PrivateProperty) loved this class and dove right into it, doing far more than the minimum required. And he<br />

excelled. Re-reading his essays and contributions to the free discussion was a pleasant and moving experience<br />

for me. (PrivateProperty) is charming and passionate. He combines conservative and liberal points <strong>of</strong> view in his<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>ound humanism. He does not try to copy Marx but picks and chooses. He clearly understands that Marx did<br />

not criticize people but social relations, and made this his main plank. He had a good understanding <strong>of</strong> Marx’s<br />

difficult philosophical arguments and used them to enrich his own system <strong>of</strong> values. He spoke with a voice that has<br />

to resonate with the mainstream but incorporates deep ethical and also social-critical points <strong>of</strong> view without being<br />

a pessimist about society. I think Law School is a good choice for him. He has the stuff to be a memorable and<br />

impressive a lawyer or judge. I can recommend him whole-heartedly. He is a robust worker who will not disappoint<br />

you.<br />

First Message by PrivateProperty is [110].<br />

[899] FacistFrank: thanks all. This is now my fourth completed year at college, and I<br />

think this class may have been the most influential one I have taken. Thanks everybody, for<br />

your open minds and willingness to discuss and get further to the truth. Good luck to all in<br />

your endeavours whether they be <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> this society and culture, or <strong>of</strong> another. A<br />

lot <strong>of</strong> Marxism has rubbed <strong>of</strong>f on me.<br />

Karl Marx rules!<br />

Final Grading Note by Hans: In June 2010 Hans wrote a letter <strong>of</strong> reference for FacistFrank. Here is an excerpt:<br />

FacistFrank did not need much handholding. He is self-motivated and intellectually curious. He does not always<br />

follow the majority opinions in <strong>Utah</strong>, but he is very aware <strong>of</strong> the counterarguments against his positions and careful<br />

to say only things things he can back up scientifically.<br />

Since you are also asking about his weaknesses, perhaps it can be considered a weakness that his writing style<br />

does not do justice to the depth <strong>of</strong> his thinking. He writes like he speaks and does not spend much time editing or<br />

polishing his formulations afterwards. He also makes more spelling errors than one would expect from someone<br />

who is intellectually as sophisticated as he. It is my hunch that this disregard <strong>of</strong> how he presents himself works<br />

against him, that he does not always get enough credit for his intellectual work because he does not try to sound<br />

smarter than the next guy.<br />

First Message by FacistFrank is [89].<br />

935 is 350 in 2005fa, 350 in 2007SP, 935 in 2008fa, 935 in 2009fa, 935 in 2010fa, 350 in<br />

2011fa, and 350 in 2012fa:<br />

935 Marx and the Environment<br />

[108] Ken: global warming. Humans may not be the only factor in the global warming<br />

situation. However, industry growth and human negligence are increasing the environmental<br />

problem. Greenhouse gases such as carbon dioxide, methane, nitrous oxide, fluorinated<br />

gases are dispersed into the environment because <strong>of</strong> human activity and some natural<br />

processes. Human activity is increasing the rate in which the greenhouse gases are being


452 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

released into the environment. Human activity can not be blamed entirely for the global<br />

warming problem, however it is a large factor in the global warming problem.<br />

Next Message by Ken is [112].<br />

[195] Ande: Global Warming. Global warming is one <strong>of</strong> the most talked about topics<br />

in today’s society and it seems everyone you talk to about it has their own theory on the<br />

issue. If you read all the discussions on the issue it proves my point, everyone thinks a little<br />

differently about the issue, and each person thinks their theory is the best. I feel as though it<br />

is possible that global warming is a real thing, but it is not anywhere as big <strong>of</strong> issue as society<br />

has made it out to be. There is some evidence that it is a real thing but it is not proven, I<br />

mean look at the winter we are having it’s a banner year. I do feel as though the summers<br />

have gotten a little bit warmer year after year, but that is because the world is becoming<br />

more populated, just like when you put a lot <strong>of</strong> people in one room, that room is going to<br />

get warmer from everyone being in there but the walls are not going to come crashing down<br />

just because it is getting warmer in that room. The world is not getting overly hot, the whole<br />

polar ice caps melting is the only thing that I think we need to worry about. That is due to<br />

the major use <strong>of</strong> fossil fuels but if it was that big <strong>of</strong> an issue the government would be finding<br />

out a solution to stop the melting ice caps, I mean we put people on the moon if we wanted<br />

to stop ice from melting the government would figure something out and stop the melting.<br />

So overall, yes global warming is definitely a real thing but it is not as big <strong>of</strong> an issue as<br />

people make it out to be. If it was that major <strong>of</strong> an issue society and the government would<br />

be a lot more worried about that than the current war in Iraq, or what reality t.v. show will<br />

come out next.<br />

Message [195] referenced by [220], [224], and [269]. Next Message by Ande is [361].<br />

[220] Raynold: RE: Global Warming. In response to [195], a little insight i know about<br />

this problem we call global warming is that the heat, or CO2 emissions we the earth is giving<br />

<strong>of</strong>f, is tearing up our ozone layer which i believe protects us from harmful things that lay in<br />

the outer space such as ultra-violet light rays! Because we are burning lots <strong>of</strong> fossil fuels<br />

emitting CO2, it joins the O3 in our stratesphere ozone causing it’s layer to get too thin<br />

which can cause serious problems for us such as burning our skin more which can lead to<br />

skin cancer, and even heating up the earth. I feel that keeping an eye on global warming is<br />

definately important for us now because it can become serious for our future generations.<br />

We should keep the problem controlled and continue to find other ways to help it so that it<br />

won’t grow in the future.<br />

Message [220] referenced by [224] and [272]. Next Message by Raynold is [352].<br />

[224] Jason: More Global Warming. Raynold [220] is right about one aspect <strong>of</strong> global<br />

warming, CO2 emissions are bonding with the O3 in the ozone to tear it apart. However<br />

there are several causes <strong>of</strong> global warming, and only one facet <strong>of</strong> it is necessarily human<br />

involved. We are definitely making our presence on earth known though and at least some<br />

sort <strong>of</strong> plan to reduce it would not be a bad thing. The main reason I wanted to write this<br />

was to address a common misconception I saw in Ande’s [195]. He mentioned the record<br />

winter we have been having here for snowfall and how global warming must not be that big<br />

<strong>of</strong> a deal then. Global warming doesn’t always imply a gradual increase everywhere on the<br />

planet. The earths climate is one <strong>of</strong> the most complex systems we’ve tried to understand and<br />

causing certain parts <strong>of</strong> the planet to heat up could very well lower the temperature <strong>of</strong> other<br />

parts. Kind <strong>of</strong> like how global warming caused a huge snow storm in the entire northern


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 453<br />

hemisphere in “The Day After Tomorrow”. I’m sure Hollywood took ample liberties with<br />

that movie, but the point still stands. Besides, even though we are having a record snow<br />

season, it hasn’t been overly cold, whereas last winter around this time it was painfully cold.<br />

We didn’t have much snow though.<br />

Message [224] referenced by [225]. Next Message by Jason is [315].<br />

[225] Sparky: Global Warming bad description. Jason in [224] brings up a good point.<br />

Global Warming is a very misleading name, has it implies that everything is heating up, I<br />

took a alternative energy class at the U from Dr. Peterson, a very very eccentric physics<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>essor (but aren’t they all!), who refered to it as global climate change, due to the fact<br />

that the world’s ecosystem is so complex and so variable that even the slightest change in<br />

one aspect could have adverse impacts on a seemlingly unrelated aspect. From taking his<br />

class, which I strongly encourage everyone to take, I learned the different opportunities that<br />

lie in the future <strong>of</strong> the energy sector and how humans can build energy producing capabilities<br />

that do not harm the Earth but can even help the Earth! But the point he drove home most<br />

was that there are going to be global changes, some areas will be colder (perhaps that is<br />

happening here in <strong>Utah</strong>), some warmer, some wetter (the greening <strong>of</strong> the Sahara), and some<br />

drier, which is why global climate change should be used when discussing this topic, rather<br />

than global warming.<br />

Next Message by Sparky is [319].<br />

[226] Chris: unstoppable global warming. While we are on the topic <strong>of</strong> global warming,<br />

I would just like to suggest a book that everyone should read. The book is entitled,<br />

“Unstoppable Global Warming” by Fred Singer and Dennis Avery. You can find this book at<br />

the Salt Lake County Libraries and probably at the <strong>University</strong> Library (I have not looked).<br />

The book presents a very detailed look at the Earth’s current state along with that <strong>of</strong> the past,<br />

and future. It discusses the Earth’s climate cycle and is chalked full <strong>of</strong> references. Please<br />

check it out if you find this a topic <strong>of</strong> interest.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [286].<br />

[233] Andy: Global Warming free discussion. The topic <strong>of</strong> global warming brings a lot<br />

<strong>of</strong> opinions. Probably the most popular being that <strong>of</strong> Al Gore’s, that the world is doomed<br />

unless we make drastic changes in our lives that would cost us billions <strong>of</strong> dollars. I agree,<br />

there is indisputable evidence that certain glaciers are melting and ocean temperatures are<br />

rising ever so slightly. But there is also evidence that is not brought about mainly because<br />

Al Gore does not focus on it in his documentary: “An Inconvenient Truth.” If you do your<br />

research, you’ll find that the ice mass in Antarctica is actually higher than it has been in the<br />

past century. Also known among weather habits is that the weather also goes in cycles. These<br />

are more just opinions based on websites and information i have heard that are contrary to<br />

the common opinion that the world is doomed. I believe we must do our part to conserve<br />

energy and find cleaner sources <strong>of</strong> power, but disagree that the world is facing its immediate<br />

end unless we change. Don’t panic, just be smart.<br />

Message [233] referenced by [272] and [293]. Next Message by Andy is [366].<br />

[260] Trailrunner: Are you Green? I have always found it important to be a person<br />

who is concerned about and works toward a sustainable future. I am from San Diego and<br />

we began recycling programs there many years ago. Not only for the usual recyclables like<br />

aluminum cans and newspapers, but also glass, plastic and yard waste. Thus, when I moved<br />

to Salt Lake a few years ago and they didn’t have these programs in my neighborhood, I was


454 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

a bit saddened. Luckily the blue recycle trash cans became available for a fee shortly after I<br />

moved here and they are now beginning a yard waste program as well.<br />

In San Diego, I worked for a solar heating company for many years and my family has<br />

a home in Baja California in which we use solar to heat the hot water and photovoltaic<br />

cells to generate all <strong>of</strong> our electricity. It really is very easy to be “green” – at least in some<br />

small ways. I have recently received my Master Gardener certificate which continues to<br />

keep me focused on the earth and ways to keep things growing and help create a healthier<br />

environment in which to live.<br />

Here at the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> we have the “Office <strong>of</strong> Sustainability.” The Office <strong>of</strong> Sustainability<br />

views sustainability as “balancing the relationships between environmental stewardship,<br />

economic development, and social responsibility while meeting the needs <strong>of</strong> the<br />

present without compromising the ability <strong>of</strong> future generations <strong>of</strong> people and ecosystems to<br />

meet their own needs.” I had heard <strong>of</strong> this <strong>of</strong>fice in the past, but had not really given much<br />

thought to what they were all about until I received an email yesterday about an upcoming<br />

workshop. The department I work for is giving out 10 scholarships to employees or students<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Health Science Campus if they want to attend the workshop. As I began to read about<br />

it, I found myself excited at the possibility <strong>of</strong> being able to attend.<br />

The workshop is titled “Fostering Sustainable Behavior.” The Office <strong>of</strong> Sustainability<br />

states that if you design or fund programs to encourage individuals or businesses to engage<br />

in behaviors beneficial to a sustainable future (such as energy and water efficiency, waste<br />

reduction, watershed protection, transportation, etc.), this workshop will have relevance for<br />

you. Here is the link for more information about the workshop in case any <strong>of</strong> you have an<br />

interest in this subject.<br />

http://www.sustainability.utah.edu/dmmworkshop.htm<br />

With all <strong>of</strong> the talk about global warming that seems to be a part <strong>of</strong> our lives these days, I<br />

thought there might be a few people out there that would find this information relevant and<br />

<strong>of</strong> value.<br />

Message [260] referenced by [334]. Next Message by Trailrunner is [274].<br />

[272] Matt: Global Warming – Wake Up! Andy in [233] has some good points, but<br />

I do believe there is more evidence for Global Warming than not. According to scientists<br />

from around the world (and Al Gore) Global Warming is causing our ozone layer to deplete.<br />

This layer is protecting us from ultra violet light produced by the sun as Raynold says in<br />

[220]. The ozone layer can be viewed as a vital resource for life, and should be protected at<br />

all costs. If it is destroyed life on earth will not be sustainable. As Global Warming begins<br />

to kick in, the world’s weather is changing. Extreme weather events are becoming more<br />

common and more intense. Seasons are less steady and some agriculture is less reliable.<br />

The majority <strong>of</strong> us don’t notice these changes because <strong>of</strong> our lifestyles and technologies.<br />

We drive from our garages to our covered parking spots at work; we never get good and wet<br />

anymore from a rain storm. If it’s too hot outside, turn up the air conditioning. Personally<br />

I have not noticed the changes in our weather, and agriculture, I dare say most Americans<br />

have. Perhaps that’s why we are doing nothing to stop this growing problem. I think we can<br />

all counter global warming by changing one simple thing, the vehicles we drive. Why would


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 455<br />

you need to drive 4x4 all-terrain vehicles to get to the supermarket or school (because we<br />

live in <strong>Utah</strong>)? So in order for us to counter global warming we need to alter our way <strong>of</strong> life<br />

by driving less miles and fewer gas inhalers. We must think and do things differently. As<br />

Marx would say, the only thing driving up consumption is our lifestyles under a capitalistic<br />

society.<br />

If we don’t start making changes now we are not only going to further Global Warming<br />

but we are also going to run out <strong>of</strong> our fuel supply, Oil! Drilling for more oil and building<br />

more power plants is not the answer to the problem. By using more fuel and energy we<br />

are only causing more pollution and we are using up all <strong>of</strong> the worlds fossil fuel. We must<br />

wisely use our resources without compromising the ability <strong>of</strong> future generations to meet<br />

their needs. Arguably, no generation should inherit less human and natural wealth than the<br />

one that precedes it. Each generation inheriting the earth should take care to use natural<br />

resources reasonably and ensure that life on our planet will continue prosperously. We must<br />

all do our part by making changes in our lives because ultimately, it is up to us to decide<br />

the future that we which to have for ourselves, future generations, and most important our<br />

children.<br />

Next Message by Matt is [340].<br />

[293] Wasatch: what is being done? Global warming!!! I really enjoyed Andy’s comments<br />

[233]. It does seem that society is going a little over board with the whole thing<br />

though. I did see Al Gore’s documentary, which I think was more <strong>of</strong> a political/money making<br />

move than a representation <strong>of</strong> his true concern for the planet and it’s people. Although he<br />

might have underlying motives for producing the movie, it did bring up some concerns about<br />

the large amounts <strong>of</strong> CO2 emissions, but the panicked response to this problem doesn’t seem<br />

like the best way to fix the problem. I really think there are too many people that love to<br />

claim that the sky is falling but fail to do much about it. Instead <strong>of</strong> arguing over the fact that<br />

it might be happening or not seems like a waste <strong>of</strong> energy and time that should be used to<br />

fix the problem. More bite and less bark. What are you doing to fix the problem? Cause if<br />

someone that drives a car that runs on more than a battery and is truly worried about global<br />

warming better park it in the garage and buy themselves a good pair <strong>of</strong> walking shoes.<br />

Next Message by Wasatch is [375].<br />

[301] Jenn: What can YOU do? In this class, we have had lots <strong>of</strong> discussions on the<br />

environment. Many <strong>of</strong> us have confirmed that we are not headed in a good direction. Since<br />

this is sort <strong>of</strong> a grass-rootsish class, I have a proposal to make. My raised awareness <strong>of</strong> the<br />

state <strong>of</strong> our global enviornment has magnified my need to be accountable to actually make<br />

changes in my life to reduce my carbon emissions. However, it is so easy (for me as well as<br />

others) to just fall back to where you are comfortable - your car, your warm-in-the-wintercool-in-the<br />

summer house, your nice hot shower. I would like to have some sort <strong>of</strong> group <strong>of</strong><br />

people that I could be accountable to so I really stick to my guns with the changes I make.<br />

And email is a good forum. Here are some <strong>of</strong> my ideas....<br />

The take-the-bus-to-work group<br />

The five-minute-shower group<br />

The save-money-to-buy-a-low-water-toilet group


456 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

The no-bottled-water group<br />

The reduce-my-junk-consumption group<br />

Although these all sound kind <strong>of</strong> silly, they would make a real difference. Anyone interested<br />

in joining me in getting my a...ummm...... bum out <strong>of</strong> bed 15 minutes earlier to take<br />

the bus (or just calling me out on my laziness)? Although if I shorten my shower, I could<br />

<strong>of</strong>fset the sleep deficit....hmmmm<br />

Message [301] referenced by [334]. Next Message by Jenn is [332].<br />

[322] Hans: Students Will Meet with Representative Matheson to Discuss Solutions to<br />

Global Climate Change. Here is an announcement from the <strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong>fice <strong>of</strong> Sustainability.<br />

If you are interested in participating in the meeting on Thursday, please email or call<br />

Elsa Gustavson at elsava85@gmail.com or (801) 585-9352.<br />

Hans.<br />

Here is a message by Craig Forster:<br />

As a follow-on to the U’s Focus the Nation effort, a team <strong>of</strong> students from the U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

has arranged to meet with Representative Matheson on Thursday February 21 at 2:45 pm.<br />

Their goal is to discuss possible solutions to global climate change (global warming) with<br />

Representative Matheson. Please circulate this information to students at the U, and at other<br />

<strong>Utah</strong> institutions <strong>of</strong> higher education, who might want to participate.<br />

For additional information, and to indicate how many students are interested in participating<br />

in the meeting (a head count is needed to size the meeting room), please contact Elsa<br />

Gustavson at elsava85@gmail.com (801) 585-9352<br />

Thank you for helping <strong>Utah</strong> students to engage their political leadership in discussing the<br />

critical issue <strong>of</strong> global climate change.<br />

Craig Forster<br />

Interim Director<br />

Here is a message from Elsa Gustavson:<br />

From: Elsa Gustavson<br />

Sent: Thu 2/14/2008 2:16 PM<br />

Subject: Meeting with Representative Matheson<br />

Good news everyone! We got a meeting with Representative Matheson at his Salt Lake<br />

Office on Thursday February 21st at 2:45pm.<br />

If you would like to join us in a conversation with our representative about the results <strong>of</strong><br />

Focus the Nation and how we can work together in <strong>Utah</strong> for solutions to global warming,<br />

please meet us in advance at the Office <strong>of</strong> Sustainability on campus at 1:15pm on Thursday<br />

the 21st. At that time we will prepare our comments, have a brief lobby-type training and<br />

then carpool over to his <strong>of</strong>fice.<br />

I do need to know how many people will be coming so that Matheson’s staff can prepare<br />

an appropriately sized room and so we have enough room for everyone in a car, so please


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 457<br />

RSVP ASAP!!! Please feel free to forward this invitation on to other students who may<br />

be interested and participated in Focus the Nation so we have people to talk about their<br />

experiences!<br />

Hope to hear from you soon!!!<br />

Cheers,<br />

Elsa Gustavson<br />

Intern<br />

Office <strong>of</strong> Sustainability<br />

<strong>University</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Next Message by Hans is [357].<br />

[334] Spawnblade: Well, I suppose I could... ...Walk to class (BrrrrrrrrRrr...) - group.<br />

(Perhaps this would lead to a freeze ourselves group?)<br />

...Turn <strong>of</strong>f the water while brushing your teeth - group.<br />

...Turn <strong>of</strong>f the water while shaving - group.<br />

...Turn <strong>of</strong>f unnecessary lights - group.<br />

...Population growth-rate zero/negative - group.<br />

Generally whenever I should be focusing on something, my mind enjoys wandering to<br />

the afflictions we’ve placed as humans on the planet. As Jenn [301] says, these things<br />

sound silly, but really they can help the environment. I really don’t believe any huge impact<br />

will occur without government intervention (As if that will happen at this rate), or a large<br />

movement. I have taken a class on Climate Change and gone to several outside lectures<br />

regarding the subject. I feel like many others taking this class that it is fact, and that for<br />

some odd reason people are either denying it, or trying to hide this looming dilemma.<br />

Am I green? [260]<br />

No Trailrunner, most definitely I’m not. At this point in time no human is, though to<br />

survive we’re essentially forced to not be green. But maybe a shade <strong>of</strong> yellow, I’d like to<br />

think my concern for the environment has some shade <strong>of</strong> color in me. I know I’d like to get a<br />

website launched among the thousands <strong>of</strong> others that pushed for Green. Or perhaps instead<br />

I should focus on the other side <strong>of</strong> Green. Brown maybe? It seems negative critique is a<br />

far more effective political tool than positive. Odd the way society works, flawed in its own<br />

way as many here say, but I must disagree when people say it is broken.<br />

Say ‘no’ to bottled water!... Well either that, or don’t complain about gas prices which<br />

are actually much less than that <strong>of</strong> your equivalent source <strong>of</strong> plastic-tasting refreshment ;).<br />

(To whomever this statement may concern.)<br />

Next Message by Spawnblade is [337].<br />

[485] Bmellor: A solution to create an America independent <strong>of</strong> oil. Oil prices fluctuate<br />

greatly from month to month year to year. OPEC gets together and makes decisions on what<br />

the prices will be, and in my opinion they agree on the same reason for raising the price:<br />

war, hurricanes, political unrest... they usually don’t mention greed.


458 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

My plan is that we always pay 3.50 cents a gallon or some other fixed price. (I am just<br />

pulling that number out <strong>of</strong> hat, there is absolutely no calculation in that number). When gas<br />

prices drop a tax would kick in, to keep the gas price where it is at. The reasoning behind<br />

this is to initially cause the consumer some pain, but through this pain the consumer changes<br />

habits i.e.: walks more, carpools more, and there is greater demand for technology that runs<br />

<strong>of</strong>f alternative fuel sources. This week it was reported for the first time in 29 years the United<br />

States has actually cut fuel consumption by 1%, we are changing our habits. Slowly it sunk<br />

in that the consumption <strong>of</strong> gasoline is not only harming our environment but also harming<br />

our way <strong>of</strong> life. Call me cynical but I don’t think its drowning polar bears causing people to<br />

buy less gas, I think it is the fact that people are sick <strong>of</strong> paying $3.00+ for gas. (However by<br />

no means am I denying that Global Warming is taking place, I just don’t think that is what<br />

is making people changing their habits.)<br />

In 1998, 10 years ago, we were paying 89 cents a gallon for gasoline here in <strong>Utah</strong>. What<br />

if we go back to that even for just few months? OPEC may still be able to do that. What<br />

happens then? The progress we have made over the last few years will die. Hybrid cars will<br />

go back to being embarrassing to drive, supply <strong>of</strong> that technology will decrease and hybrids<br />

will become so expensive that no one will buy them. But if when OPEC tries to kill <strong>of</strong>f the<br />

competing alternative fuels by cutting prices, the United States Government could step in<br />

and place a tax on the gasoline and we as consumers won’t even notice the difference. Gas<br />

stays the same price as always. OPEC might try and fight back by raising the price above<br />

the tax price... In which case they are hastening the demise oil usage. The higher the price<br />

goes for oil the faster the technology will develop to take its place. As proven by this year’s<br />

record high gas prices and the sustained decrease in the US’s fuel consumption, we will get<br />

by with less gas if it gets too expensive. 2007 proved that gasoline may not be as inelastic<br />

as we have suspected.<br />

Message [485] referenced by [486] and [487]. Next Message by Bmellor is [566].<br />

[486] Chris: oil prices rise. solutions anyone? Thank you Bmellor, for bringing up<br />

the topic <strong>of</strong> rising oil prices along with a possible solution in [485]. I had never heard the<br />

fixed cost approach to that degree, so it brought up interesting questions, concerns, and<br />

feedback. In some cities (New York City, Los Angeles, etc.) cost <strong>of</strong> living is much higher.<br />

By instigating a fixed cost to gas prices across all <strong>of</strong> the country, I think that it may be unfair<br />

to those individuals living in cities (Salt Lake City for example) to pay the same prices. At<br />

the same time, the expensive cost <strong>of</strong> living cities would probably benefit more since they<br />

would probably have their costs cut down since a fixed cost would land somewhere between<br />

the lower end and higher end <strong>of</strong> the oil price scale. I also do not see oil as elastic as you are<br />

viewing it. A 1% cut back is not much in my opinion. Sadly, I would think that people would<br />

have to undergo radical life events to cut their consumption <strong>of</strong> gas and make a difference in<br />

lowering gas costs. I also think that if some fixed cost were to be set in place, we would need<br />

to adjust it to inflation levels. The price <strong>of</strong> gas in the 1980’s was no where near the same<br />

nominal cost. Therefore, if we had a fixed cost on gas that was not adjusted for inflation, we<br />

would see gas prices drop due to this lack <strong>of</strong> adjustment. As a result, consumption would<br />

increase.<br />

While I do not completely think fixing gas prices would result in cheaper gas and a<br />

consumption decrease, I thank Bmellor for bringing up the topic. I do not have the answer


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 459<br />

either, but healthy discussion leads to innovation and leading to answers. There is a problem<br />

with price gouging and I, like everyone else, am getting sick <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

Next Message by Chris is [533].<br />

[487] Papageorgio: Gassious. Bmellor [485] is an interesting post, first <strong>of</strong> all I wonder<br />

if he has been on one <strong>of</strong> those meetings with OPEC, because who knows what they decide<br />

it those meetings it could very well be greed and wealth. [485] mentions a fixed gas price<br />

forever. This does not make much sense to me having a fixed price on gas or anything else<br />

and when the price drops we pay a tax to pay the diff.? thats odd, or does the producer pay<br />

the tax? as taxes are <strong>of</strong>ten split between producer and consumer? What if the price rises<br />

above the fixed price, do we then continue paying the lower price, I doubt producers would<br />

agree to that. Prices with things change over time, a bottle <strong>of</strong> soda used to be 79 cents now<br />

1.19, would leaving the price at a fixed cost help the producer? I do agree with [485] that<br />

the pain <strong>of</strong> the cost makes us use diff. methods. Alot <strong>of</strong> things have no great substitute in<br />

the short run, but many have a subsitute in the long run like gas. For example switching<br />

to carpools, walking, hybrid cars, etc as Bmellor said. I also agree with [485] that it is not<br />

so much environmental worry that is changing peoples habits as it is the ridiculousness <strong>of</strong><br />

filling up an suv with 50 plus dollars <strong>of</strong> gas every week. maybe a good quality in a president<br />

would be someone who would look into gas prices not someone who will jack them up.<br />

Next Message by Papageorgio is [494].<br />

[596] Hans: Environmentalists joining with Peace and Social Justice Movements.<br />

Marx is relevant for today because his theory helps us understand that the capitalist system<br />

has some very strong in-built tendencies which do not depend on the will <strong>of</strong> the individuals<br />

living in today’s society. From this follows that strong counter-interventions are needed to<br />

get the system <strong>of</strong>f its suicidal path towards climate catastrophe. Such interventions can only<br />

come from mass grassroots organizing.<br />

The <strong>Utah</strong> Moms for Clean Air are the best local example for mass organizing in the face<br />

<strong>of</strong> climate change. Their target is not climate change per se, because it is difficult to motivate<br />

around long term goals against a danger which at present manifests itself only in subtle ways.<br />

Their target is a related problem, air pollution, and recent scientific findings that air pollution<br />

is much more harmful than previously assumed, especially for little children. They organize<br />

the mothers. The mother <strong>of</strong> a child which is endangered turns into a lion. They have had<br />

spectacular success with this approach.<br />

The Moms for Clean Air are very careful to be a single purpose group, gathering together<br />

everybody concerned about clean air. They do not want to be perceived as Democrats <strong>of</strong><br />

Liberals etc., they want everybody concerned about clean air to join them. This single-issue<br />

approach is very successful, they regularly talk to the governor, have good press coverage,<br />

etc.<br />

Another coalition <strong>of</strong> political and social justice groups in this valley is trying the opposite<br />

approach. They say that the looming climate catastrophe is intertwined with many other<br />

issues, and that the most effective approach is to address all these issues all at once. Tomorrow,<br />

Saturday April 5, 12-2:30 pm, they have organized a march and rally beginning and<br />

ending at the City Government Building (451 South State) which addresses several tightly<br />

interwoven issues:


460 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

(a) the right to be healthy independent <strong>of</strong> economic status is addressed by a call for a<br />

single payer health system. Global Warming means the spread <strong>of</strong> more contagious diseases,<br />

and it is in the interest <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> us that everybody has access to decent health care.<br />

(b) tomorrow’s rally calls for withrawal <strong>of</strong> the US out <strong>of</strong> Iraq. Instead <strong>of</strong> adversarial<br />

control <strong>of</strong> fossil fuels we need a peaceful world wide transition to clean energy.<br />

(c) tomorrow’s rally calls for environmental justice. The costs <strong>of</strong> a switch to clean energy<br />

must not be shifted on those who can least afford it.<br />

(d) By advertising the goal <strong>of</strong> 350 parts per million CO2 this rally calls for much more<br />

urgent and effective carbon reduction policies than are presently even being contemplated.<br />

This is a new approach. The environmental organizations are reluctant to take on the<br />

hot issues <strong>of</strong> health care or the occupation <strong>of</strong> Iraq. Like the <strong>Utah</strong> Moms, they want to<br />

stay focused on a single issue. I think this strategy misses out on important opportunities,<br />

and they would do better to combine with the other movements. If today’s social justice<br />

movements, anti-war movements, labor movement, and environmental movements combine,<br />

they can be extremely influential. As I see it, the environmental movement will be the big<br />

engine for this coalition. Not a week passes without more disaster news from the global<br />

warming front. It is a certainty that the environmental movement is only in its infancy; more<br />

and more people realize what is going on and it will be huge. This will also give other issues<br />

the punch which they need to break through and make some differences. Tomorrow’s rally<br />

is a test <strong>of</strong> this hypothesis, and an attempt to push such a coalition forward. If it is a success,<br />

this will be big News not only in <strong>Utah</strong> but for the whole nation. If you show up tomorrow,<br />

preferably with your bicycle, this will help this coalition effort, it will be educational, and it<br />

will be fun.<br />

Here is a detailed announcement / press release:<br />

APRIL 5 HEALTHY PLANET MARCH<br />

CAN 350 CYCLISTS ALL BE WRONG?<br />

Healthy Planet March and Rally Spurs Cyclists to Action<br />

Cyclists in Salt Lake City will lead the pack this Saturday, April 5th, at a march and rally<br />

to promote a healthy planet beginning and ending at the City Government Building, 451<br />

South State Street. Riders will take to the streets at noon to call for peace, health care and<br />

healthy air.<br />

Rocky Anderson, former Salt Lake mayor, is just one speaker slated to raise public awareness<br />

and support. The April 5th Healthy Planet Rally aims to spotlight three causes: ending<br />

the occupation in Iraq, providing universal single payer health care for all citizens and reducing<br />

carbon emissions to halt global warming.<br />

Carbon emissions are exactly where the 350 cyclists come in. They will represent the<br />

350 parts per million <strong>of</strong> CO2 needed to create a sustainable atmosphere. We are currently<br />

at 383 parts per million. Cyclists, walkers and one electric car will drive the message home:<br />

to protect our planet, we need to reduce CO2 emissions now. If you would like to join the


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 461<br />

parade with your bicycle, please come to the West Steps <strong>of</strong> the City Government Building<br />

(known as the “City County Building”) a little before noon on Saturday April 5.<br />

Saturday’s march will also launch Bill McKibben’s global 350 Campaign. Environmentalist<br />

and author McKibben, who spoke in Salt Lake City last month, encouraged local activists<br />

to round up 350 cyclists to kick <strong>of</strong>f the April 5th rally. Salt Lake will be the first U.S.<br />

city to host a 350 event with our own CO2 cyclists.<br />

The one o’clock rally, led by moderators Troy Williams <strong>of</strong> KRCL and Diana Lee Hirschi<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Salt Lake Quakers, features live music by Rich Wyman and Orion, speeches by Green<br />

Party activist Peter Miguel Camejo and Iraq War veteran Chris Conway. Poets Shae, Repo<br />

and Flora will join Rocky Anderson, along with Barbara Toomer from Disabled Rights Action<br />

Committee and Brian Moench from <strong>Utah</strong> Physicians for a Healthy Environment.<br />

Additionally, soldiers’ combat boots representing each <strong>Utah</strong> military casualty in Iraq will<br />

be on display in the Eyes Wide Open: The Cost <strong>of</strong> War exhibit. Dr. Martin Luther King<br />

was assassinated forty years ago, on April 4th, trying to end the war in Viet Nam and secure<br />

peace, justice and equality. The Healthy Planet Rally honors his memory by marching on<br />

April 5th to secure a healthy planet with healthy lives for all.<br />

Cyclists, activists, families–add your voice to the call for peace, health care and healthy<br />

air. Come join Rocky and the gang at the Healthy Planet Rally, April 5 from noon till 2:30<br />

at 451 South State Street. For more information, go to http://agenda08.org<br />

Hans.<br />

Next Message by Hans is [604].<br />

[608] Trailrunner: Sustainability - Some Easy Changes. This past week, I spent two<br />

days at a workshop put on by the Office <strong>of</strong> Sustainability at the <strong>University</strong> called “Fostering<br />

Sustainable Behavior.” While this workshop was geared for people that are working to create<br />

changes in sustainable behavior as a part <strong>of</strong> their job, there are a few things that we can do<br />

in our individual lives that are easy to do and yet make a contribution to a more sustainable<br />

life.<br />

Some <strong>of</strong> the things that can be done within your own home are as follows:<br />

Lower the temperature on your hot water heater<br />

Make sure your hot water heater is wrapped with an insulation blanket made for this<br />

purpose<br />

Use low-flow shower heads<br />

Take 4 minute showers<br />

Get a composter and use it<br />

Raise the height <strong>of</strong> your lawn mower - keeping the grass longer helps retain moisture,<br />

meaning less watering<br />

When it comes to your car:<br />

If you are sitting in your car waiting for someone don’t leave the car running for more<br />

than 10 seconds


462 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

Make sure your tires are properly inflated - this provides safety, better fuel efficiency and<br />

reduced emissions<br />

In a certain area <strong>of</strong> Canada where public transportation is highly promoted, they have a<br />

special voucher program. If someone is hesitant to use public transportation because maybe<br />

they have a child in school across town from where they work and they are afraid that if an<br />

emergency arose, they would not be able to get to their child quickly enough, these vouchers<br />

can be used to obtain a free taxi ride for this emergency. These vouchers are monitored so<br />

there is no mis-use, but it is a creative way to help promote public transporation. I’m sure<br />

there are many other creative programs out there as well.<br />

There are always little things that we can do to help keep the earth a bit more healthy and<br />

many <strong>of</strong> them require just a small change in thinking or in habit. Taking that first step can<br />

lead to many more and every little bit helps.<br />

First Message by Trailrunner is [60].<br />

[766] Dentist: human footprint. so i just watched a television program on the national<br />

geographic channel called “Human Footprint,” i would really like to hear some opinions <strong>of</strong><br />

and reactions to this program, so i hope that i am not the only one who saw it.<br />

for those who did not see it, I’ll summarize and perhaps you may still feel inclined to<br />

share what you know/feel. The show was simply a look at what a single American consumes<br />

over a lifetime. It hinted at how much energy is wasted and how gluttonous we are in our<br />

consumption. in doing so it revealed the immense quantities <strong>of</strong> energy that is uselessly<br />

wasted. one example i found somewhat humorous (although quite sad) was that a single pair<br />

<strong>of</strong> shoes will travel farther just to get to your closet, than you could ever walk in them!<br />

Recently i have been contemplating if we as humans are really making as large <strong>of</strong> an impact<br />

on the world as we are made out to be. Honestly, i was having a bit <strong>of</strong> trouble accepting<br />

this idea and was inclined to believe that we thought to much <strong>of</strong> ourselves. however, seeing<br />

this program put into perspective a few things, and i now i truly believe that we our footprints<br />

are becoming so deep that soon enough they could become our graves. that being said, i still<br />

am quite skeptical that we are going to purge life from earth and leave it a desolate mass<br />

floating in space. while we our more than capable <strong>of</strong> destroying ourselves, i believe that<br />

earth will be quite abel to continue on without us.<br />

at any rate, i am now rejuvenated in my personal efforts to run lifestyle in more productive<br />

and efficient way. and part <strong>of</strong> this motivation has come from this program, so i would<br />

encourage everyone to watch it and think about some <strong>of</strong> the ways that they can personally<br />

make an impact.<br />

“By just recycling the cans from all the soda that you will drink in your lifetime, you<br />

could save enough energy to power a t.v. for over 130,000 hours.” (at least they put it in<br />

terms the common American can relate too, right? soda and t.v.!! hahaha)<br />

Next Message by Dentist is [862].<br />

[877] CousinIt: Struggle for existence. It is arguable that without capitalism many <strong>of</strong> the<br />

advancements in our quality <strong>of</strong> life would not have been made possible. It is through science<br />

and technology (<strong>of</strong>ten in the service <strong>of</strong> the war machine and certainly in the service <strong>of</strong> increased<br />

productivity, power, and pr<strong>of</strong>its) that many <strong>of</strong> the things that we take for granted that


U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong> Econ 5080 <strong>2008SP</strong> 463<br />

have made our lives more comfortable, fulfilling, and easier were created. Capitalism has<br />

been an engine <strong>of</strong> creativity and ingenuity, by this account. It could be said that capitalism<br />

was a neccessary step forward in human evolution.<br />

The original impetus for the development <strong>of</strong> technology, according to Herbert Marcuse<br />

(in his book “One-Dimensional Man”), is the “pacification <strong>of</strong> the struggle for existence”<br />

or we could say “to make life as human beings survivable and prosperous” or “to protect<br />

human survival from the threats to it from the ravages <strong>of</strong> nature.” As a species, clearly, we<br />

have been able to achieve this goal for a portion <strong>of</strong> the total human population to a significant<br />

degree, surely far surpassing what the first technologists (who invented clothing, shelter, and<br />

the use <strong>of</strong> fire) would have thought humanly possible. According to Marcuse, the problem<br />

is that we have not extended this ability to pacify the struggle for existence to the masses but<br />

have instead unwittingly strayed from this path onto the ‘yellow brick road’ to extinction.<br />

Clearly, capitalism as a productive economic social system has gone way beyond the mere<br />

pacification <strong>of</strong> the struggle for existence. Capitalism, though it has been a major contributing<br />

factor in the development <strong>of</strong> technology, has gone beyond its usefulness to the species in<br />

this regard, even to the point <strong>of</strong> creating technologies and environmental effects that actually<br />

threaten to destroy life.<br />

This threat to the environment and life is an interesting development that Marx was not<br />

so concerned with and perhaps wasn’t able to foresee in as dire manifestation as is now<br />

upon us. Marx, as well as Marcuse, are both more interested in freeing people from the<br />

struggle for existence so that they can enjoy more fulfilling and creative everyday lives, a<br />

condition which they believe would facilitate the development <strong>of</strong> technologies and other<br />

cultural artifacts and behaviors in a direction more enhancing <strong>of</strong> the human condition than<br />

those being produced at the demand <strong>of</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>it motive. In other words, the world that<br />

they envision is a world more conducive to the development <strong>of</strong> the human spirit and its<br />

potential in all areas <strong>of</strong> human life and activity, in a way that actually enhances and nourishes<br />

human beings as individuals, thus making a better society all the way around...a creative<br />

intelligent society <strong>of</strong> self-ruling individuals whose collective aim is to mutaully aid one<br />

another in the fulfillment <strong>of</strong> individual and collective potential and well-being for all, not<br />

just the privileged few (though it is questionable that capitalism has done even that much for<br />

the wealthy capitalists, every bit as much capitalism’s victims as are the working poor).<br />

Since we do not collectively recognize that capitalism as a mode <strong>of</strong> social economic<br />

production has failed in the pacification <strong>of</strong> the struggle for existence and in effect “gone<br />

too far in the wrong direction”, and has in fact exacerbated the struggle, what is happening<br />

is that nature is stepping in and forcing us to make the changes necessary, lest we, as a<br />

species, perish. Marx knew that capitalism would have to reach its limits before it would<br />

become imperative that it be dismantled and replaced with socialism as the remedial form<br />

<strong>of</strong> an ultimate development <strong>of</strong> human society as a collective communal social system that<br />

seeks the betterment <strong>of</strong> all humans, a betterment that includes, like it or not, reduction or<br />

elimination <strong>of</strong> the negative impact that human beings have on the environment as a requisite<br />

for continued health, prosperity, and indeed, for survival.<br />

Despite what the popular discourse has brainwashed many <strong>of</strong> us into thinking, we have<br />

not tried socialism or communism...these did not fail because they weren’t ever tried as


464 <strong>2008SP</strong> Econ 5080 U <strong>of</strong> <strong>Utah</strong><br />

world systems, which they must be in order to succeed. “Socialism” and “Communism” as<br />

we know them, are actually forms <strong>of</strong> ‘state-capitalism’ that could not but fail. We have apparently<br />

not reached the requisite subtlety <strong>of</strong> consciousness or intellect necessary to produce<br />

the awareness to be able to do real socialism. However we are being pushed to just some<br />

such kind <strong>of</strong> shift in consciousness by the necessities <strong>of</strong> species survival.<br />

Capitalism is a cruel, unfair, exploitive, degenerate, socio-economic system that has outlived<br />

its usefulness and has become environmentally, physically, emotionally, and spiritually<br />

unsustainable. It worked for a while to get us to a point where we could somewhat<br />

effectively protect our species from the elements <strong>of</strong> nature that threatened our survival and<br />

prosperity and to develop a particular kind <strong>of</strong> consciousness that has facilitated the development<br />

<strong>of</strong> technology and wealth but that has ultimately become a pandemic socio-ideologic<br />

pathology. The human species and the environment are seriously chronically ill because <strong>of</strong><br />

capitalism. The Earth, as a living body, is doing what any living body does to pathogens<br />

that do not harmonize with the overall health <strong>of</strong> the living organism. It is releasing antigens<br />

to destroy the threat to the organism’s survival. Human beings, under capital, are the cancer,<br />

the virus, that must be harmonized with the larger living organism or, alternatively, that<br />

which must be destroyed. The sad thing is that we may have already missed the window <strong>of</strong><br />

opportunity to return to some kind <strong>of</strong> sustainable harmony with the larger organism and are<br />

already marked for extinction.<br />

As an optimist, I believe that the only chance we have <strong>of</strong> improving our chances <strong>of</strong> survival<br />

is the immediate dismantling <strong>of</strong> the capitalist system and its replacement with a humane,<br />

environmentally responsible socialism whose aim is the community <strong>of</strong> all humans<br />

and all other life on the planet, i.e. a true communalism.... a true communism as the dominant<br />

characteristic attitude <strong>of</strong> the human species in realization <strong>of</strong> its full existential potential.<br />

Now is the time to become a full citizen <strong>of</strong> the world and to join other responsible citizens<br />

in collectively remaking our world into a world that is a good place to exist for everyone.<br />

Now, how could this as a goal, by any stretch <strong>of</strong> the imagination, be a bad thing to do?<br />

(Unless <strong>of</strong> course the imagination that we possess has become so ill that it cannot see such<br />

good possibilities as anything other than evil....i.e., a pathologically psychotic imagination<br />

that can no longer grasp the reality <strong>of</strong> its condition.)<br />

Have a wonderful life and good luck always, comrades all... I hope we live through this...<br />

Message [877] referenced by [879]. First Message by CousinIt is [13].<br />

[879] Mitternacht: RE: Struggle for Existence. I just wanted to add one last comment<br />

regarding the last posting [877] and the class in general.<br />

Thank you CousinIt for your positive and optimistic take - it’s hard to not be pessimistic<br />

given the current state <strong>of</strong> affairs. I’m holding out hope that people can and will work together<br />

to make the world a better place; if not out <strong>of</strong> concern for one another as human beings, then<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the need for self preservation.<br />

Thanks to all <strong>of</strong> you for your contributions and insight - it definitely made this class more<br />

enjoyable. I wish you all the best in your future endeavors.<br />

First Message by Mitternacht is [73].<br />

Compiled by Hans G. Ehrbar 2013-07-07 04:13:46.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!