26.12.2013 Views

Aristotle's Definitions of the Soul: "De Anima" ii, 1-3

Aristotle's Definitions of the Soul: "De Anima" ii, 1-3

Aristotle's Definitions of the Soul: "De Anima" ii, 1-3

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Aristotle's</strong> <strong><strong>De</strong>finitions</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Soul</strong>: "<strong>De</strong> Anima" <strong>ii</strong>, 1-3<br />

Author(s): Robert Bolton<br />

Reviewed work(s):<br />

Source: Phronesis, Vol. 23, No. 3 (1978), pp. 258-278<br />

Published by: BRILL<br />

Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4182048 .<br />

Accessed: 25/11/2011 16:36<br />

Your use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Terms & Conditions <strong>of</strong> Use, available at .<br />

http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp<br />

JSTOR is a not-for-pr<strong>of</strong>it service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range <strong>of</strong><br />

content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms<br />

<strong>of</strong> scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.<br />

BRILL is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Phronesis.<br />

http://www.jstor.org


<strong>Aristotle's</strong> definitions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul: <strong>De</strong> A nima<br />

II, 1-3<br />

ROBERT BOLTON<br />

Just as in public assemblies <strong>the</strong>y are accustomed<br />

to newly introduce a law and if <strong>the</strong><br />

law newly introduced is better <strong>the</strong>y abandon<br />

<strong>the</strong> previous law, so ought one to proceed in<br />

<strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> definitions as well and to propose,<br />

oneself, an alternate definition. For if<br />

it is seen to be better and makes <strong>the</strong> thing<br />

defined clearer it is obvious that <strong>the</strong><br />

definition in force will have been abandoned,<br />

since <strong>the</strong>re are not several definitions<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same thing,<br />

Topics 151 b 12-17<br />

1. It is a philosophical commonplace that <strong>Aristotle's</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul<br />

as <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> body contains an important anti-dualist solution to <strong>the</strong><br />

mind-body problem. It is also widely understood that Aristotle was not<br />

entirely unbending in his attachment to an anti-dualist solution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

problem. He claims in various places that <strong>the</strong> intellect is not <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> any<br />

type <strong>of</strong> body and, hence, is capable <strong>of</strong> existence as a functioning entity<br />

separate from <strong>the</strong> body. And he is committed to <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> an<br />

ensouled but immaterial living being, <strong>the</strong> prime mover, who not only<br />

carries on <strong>the</strong> psychic activity <strong>of</strong> thinking but derives <strong>the</strong> greatest pleasure<br />

from it. Various attempts have been made to ei<strong>the</strong>r explain away <strong>the</strong><br />

doctrines which seem to conflict with <strong>the</strong> anti-dualist thrust <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

definition or to minimize <strong>the</strong>ir importance in <strong>Aristotle's</strong> most mature<br />

thought. But none <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se attempts has yet managed to secure and maintain<br />

significant support.'<br />

I want to <strong>of</strong>fer here a new suggestion for dealing with <strong>the</strong> problem. My<br />

proposal is that <strong>the</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> familiar definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul as <strong>the</strong><br />

form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> body has not been properly understood. When this is correctly<br />

understood, I shall argue, <strong>the</strong> definition can be seen to be consistent with<br />

<strong>the</strong> doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prime mover, with <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> separate intellect<br />

and, most interestingly perhaps, with various types <strong>of</strong> mind-body dualism.<br />

I begin with a consideration <strong>of</strong> a little noticed matter.<br />

2. The well-known definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul, as <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> a certain kind <strong>of</strong><br />

body, in <strong>De</strong> Anima II, 1, is <strong>of</strong>fered as an account which mentions something<br />

258


common to every soul (nrL XOLVOV rri. %&1s 4'Xis, 412 b 4). But at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> chapter Aristotle confesses that this account is merely a "rough general<br />

account sketched in outline" (ri . . . 'ooyEypa&pq&, 413 a 9-10). This<br />

indicates, somewhat surprisingly, that <strong>the</strong> account is in some way imperfect.<br />

But in what way?<br />

The significance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> language which Aristotle employs to qualify his<br />

definition is revealed most fully in <strong>the</strong> Topics and in <strong>the</strong> History <strong>of</strong>Animals.<br />

An account "in outline" ('rmT) is, according to <strong>the</strong> Topics, a general<br />

(xa06Xov) account which does not give an "accurate definition" (&xpLpls<br />

X6yos) but which does permit us to know (yvwpieLv) <strong>the</strong> thing described in<br />

some way (101 a 18-24). For Aristotle <strong>the</strong>re are two ways in which some<br />

thing may be made known, ei<strong>the</strong>r by reference to what is prior and more<br />

intelligible to us or to what is prior and more intelligible absolutely (141<br />

a 28-30, b 3-19; cf. PosteriorAnalytics 71 b 33, ff.). An account "in outline"<br />

belongs clearly to <strong>the</strong> former type. An account by reference to things that<br />

are more intelligible absolutely conforms to "accurate understanding"<br />

(&XpLS BLavoLCL) and this is <strong>the</strong> opposite <strong>of</strong> what is given in an account "in<br />

outline" (141 b 5-14, 101 a 21 33).2 History <strong>of</strong> Animals 491 a 7-14 (which<br />

closely parallels <strong>De</strong> A nima 413 a 9-20) fur<strong>the</strong>r describes an account "in<br />

outline" as one which gives derivative facts ('ar avA1O3x6'ra) about something<br />

in contrast to giving <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical principles (alr(aL) by reference to<br />

which such facts are explained.3<br />

The opening lines <strong>of</strong> <strong>De</strong> Anima 11, 2 characterize in detail <strong>the</strong> differences<br />

between that sort <strong>of</strong> account which is more familiar to us and which merely<br />

states some fact (TOr 6'rL) and its more perfect counterpart. Since, as we have<br />

just seen, <strong>the</strong> former type <strong>of</strong> account is <strong>the</strong> account "in outline", <strong>the</strong>se lines<br />

give us <strong>the</strong> reasons which must have led Aristotle to think that <strong>the</strong> account<br />

in outline in II, 1 was imperfect. The reasons are <strong>the</strong>se! (1) The initial<br />

account while more obvious (qvepvrpepos) than o<strong>the</strong>rs is still obscure<br />

(&aacp's) and so in need <strong>of</strong> replacement by one which is more intelligible in<br />

<strong>the</strong> order <strong>of</strong> explanation (xarar 'rv Xoyov yvpW+u.'repos) (413 a 11-13). (2)<br />

The initial account shares <strong>the</strong> fault <strong>of</strong> most definitions which people give <strong>of</strong><br />

merely displaying something that is <strong>the</strong> case ('rO 8rL) without giving <strong>the</strong><br />

essence (oUria) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thing defined (413 a 13-16). (3) The initial definition<br />

is like a conclusion (av1LuipaaVc) about <strong>the</strong> thing defined ra<strong>the</strong>r than a<br />

statement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> reason ('ob a'L'TLov) for such conclusions (413 a 16-20).<br />

Given that Aristotle is contrasting here <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> which <strong>the</strong><br />

famous account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul in II, 1 is an instance with ano<strong>the</strong>r superior<br />

type,4 we need to ask what <strong>the</strong>se contrasts imply as to <strong>the</strong> exact content <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, I and as to what precisely <strong>the</strong> defects <strong>of</strong> that definition<br />

are.<br />

259


3. As commentators have pointed out, <strong>the</strong> contrasts drawn in brief<br />

between different types <strong>of</strong> definition at <strong>the</strong> beginning <strong>of</strong> <strong>De</strong>eAnima 11, 2 are<br />

laid out at more length in <strong>the</strong> Posterior Analytics, especially in Book II,<br />

chapters 8-10. But <strong>the</strong> significance <strong>of</strong> that discussion for our questions<br />

concerning <strong>the</strong> status <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul in <strong>De</strong> A nima II, I has not<br />

been fully explored.<br />

Before turning to <strong>the</strong> Analytics, however, it will be useful to describe in<br />

some detail various problems <strong>of</strong> interpretation in <strong>De</strong> A nima II, 1-3 which<br />

are connected with our questions about <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1. Light can, I<br />

think, be shed on all <strong>the</strong>se problems by attention to <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> types <strong>of</strong><br />

definition in <strong>the</strong> Posterior Analytics.<br />

The first group <strong>of</strong> problems worth our attention here has to do with <strong>the</strong><br />

content <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definition in II, 1 - or, as we should say, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definitions in<br />

II, 1, since <strong>the</strong>re is more than one. Are <strong>the</strong>se various definitions equivalent?<br />

Here are <strong>the</strong> definitions which Aristotle <strong>of</strong>fers us:<br />

(1) <strong>Soul</strong> is <strong>the</strong> substance, in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> form, <strong>of</strong> a natural body which<br />

has life potentially (412 a 19-21).<br />

(2) <strong>Soul</strong> is <strong>the</strong> first actuality <strong>of</strong> a natural body which has life potentially<br />

(412 a 27-28).<br />

(3) <strong>Soul</strong> is <strong>the</strong> first actuality <strong>of</strong> a natural body which has organs (412 b<br />

5-6).<br />

(4) <strong>Soul</strong> is <strong>the</strong> essence and defining principle (Xoyos) <strong>of</strong> that sort <strong>of</strong> natural<br />

body which has within itself a source (&px~) <strong>of</strong> its change and stability<br />

(412 b 15-17).5<br />

We may allow that <strong>the</strong> first two definitions which Aristotle gives us pose no<br />

problem in relation to each o<strong>the</strong>r since he gives <strong>the</strong> second simply to<br />

explain what he means by <strong>the</strong> first. But <strong>the</strong> third - <strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong> soul as<br />

<strong>the</strong> first actuality <strong>of</strong> a natural body with organs - raises apparent difficulties.<br />

Aristotle treats soul as <strong>the</strong> principle <strong>of</strong> life; things are ensouled if and<br />

only if <strong>the</strong>y have life (413 a 21-2). But must something have organs to be<br />

alive? In fact we know that certain microscopic living creatures are<br />

composed <strong>of</strong> undifferentiated living tissue. They engage in life functions<br />

such as nutrition and reproduction without employing any organs for those<br />

functions and do not possess any organs at all in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> parts which<br />

perform distinctive functions not performed by o<strong>the</strong>r parts (cf. <strong>De</strong> Partibus<br />

Animalium 645 b 3 ff., at 14). We might well suppose that Aristotle didn't<br />

allow for this because <strong>of</strong> his inadequate understanding <strong>of</strong> biology. But<br />

Aristotle himself regards certain material objects, namely <strong>the</strong> stars, as alive<br />

even though he believes that <strong>the</strong>ir matter is undifferentiated and cannot be<br />

altered or moved internally in any way and that, hence, <strong>the</strong>y do not have<br />

260


organs.6 This apparent inconsistency holds, moreover, not only between<br />

<strong>the</strong> third definition and things Aristotle says elsewhere. It holds between<br />

<strong>the</strong> third definition and <strong>the</strong> second. The second definition requires only<br />

that to be ensouled7 a body must be in a certain state <strong>of</strong> readiness to engage<br />

in one or ano<strong>the</strong>r life function, whe<strong>the</strong>r it has organs or not. It will be said<br />

that Aristotle wants to argue in <strong>the</strong> <strong>De</strong> A nima that only a body with organs<br />

could be in such a state. But he doesn't argue for this. At best he merely<br />

claims it (412 a 28, f.). And even this he does not do unambiguously. For he<br />

allows that if a thing engages regularly by nature in patterned change <strong>of</strong><br />

place that is enough to make it alive (413 a 22-25). We know that he<br />

believes that <strong>the</strong> stars and <strong>the</strong> spheres in which <strong>the</strong>y move do this and that<br />

he denies that <strong>the</strong>y have organs. So we have good reason to want <strong>the</strong> second<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> soul to cover <strong>the</strong> stars. If it covers <strong>the</strong> stars, however, <strong>the</strong>n it<br />

seems incompatible with <strong>the</strong> third definition.<br />

It might be argued that <strong>the</strong> second and third definitions are not meant to<br />

be equivalent on <strong>the</strong> ground that <strong>the</strong> "body with organs" mentioned in <strong>the</strong><br />

third definition is explicitly introduced in <strong>the</strong> text as a body <strong>of</strong> a more<br />

restricted type than <strong>the</strong> "body which has life potentially" <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> second<br />

definition (412 a 27 - b 1). If this were so we could take <strong>the</strong> second<br />

definition, which covers <strong>the</strong> stars, as <strong>the</strong> accurate one and regard <strong>the</strong> third<br />

as covering not all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> living but only a certain part <strong>of</strong> it. But <strong>the</strong> third<br />

definition is said to mention "something common to every soul" (412 b 4).<br />

The fourth definition introduces fur<strong>the</strong>r problems. It apparently says<br />

that any natural body which has an internal source <strong>of</strong> patterned change is<br />

ensouled. But in <strong>the</strong> Physics (192 b 9-23) Aristotle claims that all <strong>the</strong><br />

familiar natural bodies have an internal source <strong>of</strong> patterned change. (Cf.<br />

<strong>De</strong> Caelo 268 b 27, ff.). So on his definition rocks would seem to be alive.<br />

And Aristotle would deny that rocks are alive (<strong>De</strong> Anima 412 a 13-15).<br />

Some will urge that this fourth claim is not a definition, that it only gives a<br />

necessary condition for being an ensouled body and no more. But it must<br />

do more to play <strong>the</strong> role Aristotle gives to it in its context (412 b 10-17). He<br />

argues that <strong>the</strong> thing that keeps an axe from being alive is that it doesn't as<br />

an axe have <strong>the</strong> kind <strong>of</strong> natural body that engages in its proper motion -<br />

chopping - in <strong>the</strong> cgurse <strong>of</strong> nature from some internal impulse. But rocks<br />

do engage in <strong>the</strong>ir proper motion under internal impulse in <strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong><br />

nature (Physics 192 b 12, ff. at b 18). So <strong>the</strong> argument would seem to<br />

require that <strong>the</strong>y are alive. Even if we treat <strong>the</strong> fourth claim as giving only a<br />

necessary condition for being alive, moreover, that still creates problems.<br />

For, again, <strong>the</strong> stars are alive and, hence, ensouled and <strong>the</strong>y do not engage<br />

in any proper natural movement under internal impulse (<strong>De</strong> Caelo 290 a<br />

261


27, ff., 291 b 13). On this reading, fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, <strong>the</strong> definition would<br />

require that nothing kept alive, as we say, by external artificial means can<br />

really be alive, even if it continues to engage in all its proper life functions.<br />

This would not only be an unfortunate thing for Aristotle to say, it would<br />

put <strong>the</strong> fourth definition in conflict with <strong>the</strong> second and third. On those<br />

definitions, it is enough for something to be alive that it engage in organic<br />

life functions, whe<strong>the</strong>r with external or artificial assistance or not.8 We<br />

might try to treat <strong>the</strong> fourth claim as giving only sufficient conditions for<br />

being ensouled. The definition could be read as saying that soul is <strong>the</strong> form<br />

<strong>of</strong> a natural body <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> type which has an internal source <strong>of</strong> change, bul<br />

perhaps <strong>of</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r type as well. But this interpretation, besides apparently<br />

making rocks alive, would seem to spoil <strong>Aristotle's</strong> argument. If something<br />

with ano<strong>the</strong>r sort <strong>of</strong> body than <strong>the</strong> one mentioned can be ensouled, how<br />

can <strong>the</strong> fact that an axe doesn't have that sort show that it's not ensouled?<br />

Aside from <strong>the</strong>se problems it is worth reviewing <strong>the</strong> old troubles mentioned<br />

earlier which bear on all <strong>the</strong> definitions. In <strong>the</strong> very chapter where<br />

<strong>the</strong>se definitions occur, and in many o<strong>the</strong>r places, Aristotle claims that<br />

some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> parts, that is some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> life functions, which make up <strong>the</strong> soul<br />

are separable from <strong>the</strong> body since <strong>the</strong>y are not <strong>the</strong> actualities <strong>of</strong> any body<br />

or bodily organ (413 a 6-7).9 This seems to be ruled out in advance by all<br />

<strong>the</strong> definitions, since any non-bodily entity which exercised any one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

life functions (as <strong>the</strong> intellect does, 430 a 17-22) would have to be alive<br />

(413 a 22-25)10 and hence ensouled (a 21-22). All <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definitions seem to<br />

rule out <strong>the</strong> possibility that anything o<strong>the</strong>r than a natural body can be<br />

ensouled or, hence, alive. The third definition, which supposedly mentions<br />

something common to every soul, is especially problematic in this regard<br />

since it is later explicitly claimed that "<strong>the</strong> soul which can think" (i] VOqTLXyL<br />

[iuxid) is connected with no organ (429 a 22-29).<br />

Aristotle also claims at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>De</strong> A nima II, 1 that it is not yet clear<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> whole soul11 <strong>of</strong> a living thing is <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> activity<br />

(6v?eXVXeLa) <strong>of</strong> its body as a sailor is <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> activity <strong>of</strong> a ship<br />

(413 a 8-9) - apparently leaving <strong>the</strong> door open to various forms <strong>of</strong> dualism.<br />

Since he has just said that, given <strong>the</strong> third definition, "it is unnecessary to<br />

inquire fur<strong>the</strong>r whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> soul and <strong>the</strong> body are one" (412 b 6, f.), it is a<br />

long-standing puzzle why Aristotle should make this remark.12<br />

The prime mover gives rise to <strong>the</strong> final problem. It is alive and is, hence,<br />

an ensouled entity (Metaphysics 1072 b 13, ff., cf. <strong>De</strong> Anima 402 b 5-8). But<br />

<strong>the</strong> life function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prime mover does not belong to any natural body<br />

and is, afortiori, not <strong>the</strong> first actuality <strong>of</strong> any body.<br />

The standard ways out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se difficulties involve attributing to Aris-<br />

262


totle inconsistency, change <strong>of</strong> mind, or mystery-making.13 But <strong>the</strong> inconsistency,<br />

if such <strong>the</strong>re be, is so bald that it is hard to see how Aristotle could<br />

have failed to face it. And <strong>the</strong> hypo<strong>the</strong>sized change <strong>of</strong> mind on <strong>Aristotle's</strong><br />

part is unacknowledged and has been hard to establish in any convincing<br />

way.14 So solutions depending on <strong>the</strong>se things have not been satisfying.<br />

And it seems too much out <strong>of</strong> character that Aristotle should simply have<br />

regarded <strong>the</strong> whole matter as an impenetrable mystery for that proposal to<br />

be satisfying.<br />

4. Do <strong>the</strong> remarks which Aristotle makes at <strong>the</strong> beginning <strong>of</strong> <strong>De</strong> A nima<br />

II, 2 about various types <strong>of</strong> definition and about <strong>the</strong> defects in <strong>the</strong> account<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul in II, 1 help us to more satisfactorily resolve any or all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se<br />

difficulties?<br />

As we saw earlier, <strong>the</strong> definition, or definitions, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul in <strong>De</strong> A nima<br />

II, 1 are implied by II, 2, 413 a 16, to be like conclusions (OuuR%ep&ixlrx).<br />

That word is used in Posterior A nalytics II, 10 to describe one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> three<br />

types <strong>of</strong> definition discussed <strong>the</strong>re (94 a 7-9, 13-14). This type <strong>of</strong> definition<br />

is contrasted both with <strong>the</strong> indemonstrable account <strong>of</strong> what something is<br />

and with <strong>the</strong> syllogistically based account <strong>of</strong> what something is.'5 The third<br />

type <strong>of</strong> definition,16 and hence <strong>the</strong> sort we are dealing with in <strong>De</strong> Anima II,<br />

I, is <strong>the</strong> so-called nominal definition - <strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong> what a name signifies<br />

(93 b 30).'7 What implications <strong>of</strong> this result are relevant for our purposes?<br />

A nominal definition is <strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong> some entity or phenomenon<br />

which we have at <strong>the</strong> initial stages <strong>of</strong> inquiry before we have an account <strong>of</strong><br />

its essence. The definition encapsulates <strong>the</strong> central items <strong>of</strong> information<br />

about an entity which we have at a given pre-terminal stage.'8 These<br />

central items <strong>of</strong> information'9 will, in <strong>Aristotle's</strong> view, typically concern<br />

explicable features <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> entity under investigation. So he characterizes <strong>the</strong><br />

definitions which display <strong>the</strong>se features as "conclusions"(avRnpep&u-<br />

iu,rr).20 There are, for Aristotle, two characteristic types <strong>of</strong> definition<br />

which function as conclusions <strong>of</strong> syllogisms - those which exhibit a feature<br />

(but not <strong>the</strong> whole) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> entity defined, and those which do<br />

not exhibit even an element <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence but do exhibit some proper (xLO'<br />

o0'r6) feature which is explicable by reference to <strong>the</strong> essence.2' The first<br />

type will exhibit a feature necessary but not sufficient for <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> thing. The second will, characteristically, exhibit a feature sufficient<br />

but not necessary for <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thing.22<br />

Aristotle takes it that nominal definitions signify a kind and delineate<br />

<strong>the</strong> reference <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> name <strong>of</strong> a kind.23 How do <strong>the</strong>y do this when <strong>the</strong>y only<br />

exhibit features necessary or sufficient for membership in <strong>the</strong> class denoted<br />

by <strong>the</strong> name <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> kind but not both? Aristotle holds that grasping a<br />

263


nominal definition involves a knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> members <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> class in question24 and that <strong>the</strong> definition itself involves an implicit<br />

reference to <strong>the</strong> most familiar actual instances <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> kind defined.25 The<br />

definition identifies <strong>the</strong> kind as <strong>the</strong> one to which those actual instances<br />

belong and <strong>the</strong> membership <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> kind as whatever has <strong>the</strong> same essence<br />

as those instances.26<br />

Given this, both types <strong>of</strong> nominal definitions do give necessary and<br />

sufficient conditions <strong>of</strong> a sort for being instances <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> kinds <strong>the</strong>y define.<br />

But <strong>the</strong>y do not do this by exhibiting general features <strong>of</strong> those instances,<br />

possessed by <strong>the</strong>m as instances <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir kinds, which are necessary and<br />

sufficient for belonging to those kinds. Instead <strong>the</strong>y do so by means <strong>of</strong> a<br />

reference to <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> certain actual familiar objects, an essence whose<br />

content is not spelled out in <strong>the</strong> definition but whose possession is<br />

necessary and sufficient for membership in <strong>the</strong> kind defined.<br />

5. With this material in hand we can now return to <strong>the</strong> <strong>De</strong> A nima to see<br />

what light is shed on <strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul which we find <strong>the</strong>re. As we<br />

have already seen, <strong>the</strong> famous definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul in II, I is a nominal<br />

definition. The use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term 'uuv'rrpwuvx' (413 a 16, 18) to describe it<br />

makes this clear. But what kind <strong>of</strong> nominal definition is it, one that exhibits<br />

a necessary condition <strong>of</strong> soul or one that exhibits a sufficient condition? I<br />

want to suggest that it is a nominal definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter type: It points to<br />

<strong>the</strong> most familiar (qvepavrpTa) instances <strong>of</strong> soul by means <strong>of</strong> a description<br />

which exhibits only sufficient conditions for being an instance <strong>of</strong> soul, and<br />

defines <strong>the</strong> soul as <strong>the</strong> generic form possessed by those instances.<br />

The evidence for taking <strong>the</strong> nominal definition to be <strong>of</strong> this type is <strong>of</strong> two<br />

sorts, direct textual evidence and more general inductive evidence. The<br />

more general inductive evidence is, perhaps, <strong>the</strong> more striking, so we may<br />

begin with it. If we understand <strong>the</strong> definition(s) <strong>of</strong> soul in <strong>De</strong> A nima II, 1 in<br />

<strong>the</strong> way suggested, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> various problems which we have mentioned<br />

concerning <strong>the</strong> definition(s) can all be resolved, and <strong>Aristotle's</strong> remarks in<br />

<strong>De</strong> Anima II, 1 can be seen to be consistent with all <strong>of</strong> his doctrines<br />

mentioned elsewhere.<br />

The first <strong>of</strong> our worries about <strong>the</strong> definitions in II, I had to do with<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y are extensionally equivalent. It seemed to us doubtful that<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are, but we were not reading <strong>the</strong> definitions in a way it is open to us to<br />

read nominal definitions. The definitions <strong>of</strong> II, 1 are equivalent if <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

read as nominal definitions which exhibit sufficient conditions for belonging<br />

to <strong>the</strong> kind defined. On such a reading <strong>the</strong> second definition will<br />

say that soul is that generic first actuality possessed by those (actual<br />

familiar cases <strong>of</strong>) natural bodies primed for certain life functions (which we<br />

264


ecognize as ensouled).27 It will not say that <strong>the</strong>se (familiar) bodies are <strong>the</strong><br />

only ones which have that actuality but ra<strong>the</strong>r that that actuality is <strong>the</strong> one<br />

which <strong>the</strong>y have. The third definition will say that soul is <strong>the</strong> generic<br />

actuality possessed by (<strong>the</strong> actual familiar cases <strong>of</strong>) natural bodies with<br />

organs (which we recognize as ensouled). Since <strong>the</strong> familiar bodies which<br />

are primed for <strong>the</strong> familiar life functions are, at least in part, <strong>the</strong> same as<br />

<strong>the</strong> familiar bodies with organs, <strong>the</strong> two definitions will be extensionally<br />

equivalent. The fourth definition will say that soul is <strong>the</strong> generic form<br />

possessed by those (actual familiar cases <strong>of</strong>) bodies with an internal source<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir activity (which we recognize as ensouled).28 Here <strong>the</strong> familiar cases<br />

are again, at least in part, <strong>the</strong> same as for <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r definitions. Since <strong>the</strong><br />

generic form <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se groups <strong>of</strong> entities is <strong>the</strong> same, <strong>the</strong>se<br />

definitions will all be extensionally equivalent. Given this we cannot say<br />

that <strong>the</strong> stars or <strong>the</strong> microorganisms without organs conform to <strong>the</strong> second<br />

definition but not to <strong>the</strong> third. For <strong>the</strong> third does not say that only entities<br />

with organs are ensouled. It says, merely, that only things with <strong>the</strong> same<br />

generic actuality as certain familiar bodies with organs are ensouled. Nor<br />

can we say that <strong>the</strong> fourth definition requires that rocks are ensouled. It<br />

does not say that every natural body with an internal source <strong>of</strong> its activity is<br />

ensouled. It says only that things which have <strong>the</strong> same generic essence as<br />

<strong>the</strong> most familiar cases <strong>of</strong> self-moving bodies are ensouled. And this need<br />

not, and in fact does not, include rocks.29 For similar reasons <strong>the</strong> stars do<br />

not have to be self-moved to be alive; and entities whose life is maintained<br />

artificially can still live - providing <strong>the</strong>ir essence is <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> right generic<br />

type. The definitions <strong>of</strong> II, I do not tell us directly what that type is, so <strong>the</strong>y<br />

do not settle <strong>the</strong>se matters.<br />

Earlier we noted difficulties in <strong>the</strong> way <strong>of</strong> treating <strong>the</strong> definitions as<br />

exhibiting only suffitcient conditions for <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> soul. As <strong>the</strong> sufficient<br />

conditions are treated in <strong>Aristotle's</strong> nominal definitions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> type<br />

we are considering, however, those difficulties no longer face us. The third<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul, as <strong>the</strong> first actuality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most familiar cases <strong>of</strong><br />

natural bodies with organs, is said to mention "something common to<br />

every soul." It is clear that it cannot do this if it only gives straightforward<br />

sufficient conditions for <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> soul. But on <strong>Aristotle's</strong> way <strong>of</strong><br />

construing nominal definitions which exhibit sufficient conditions it does<br />

give something common. It identifies <strong>the</strong> generic form common to all<br />

ensouled things. For Aristotle, any nominal definition identifies <strong>the</strong> kind<br />

that its corresponding real definition displays (Posterior A nalytics 93 b 38<br />

- 94 a 2).<br />

Treating <strong>the</strong> fourth definition in <strong>the</strong> way suggested, moreover, does not<br />

265


spoil <strong>Aristotle's</strong> contention that axes are not alive. Since <strong>the</strong> definition does<br />

identify <strong>the</strong> generic kind to which all ensouled things belong it can be used<br />

to rule axes out <strong>of</strong> that kind. Since it only exhibits sufficient conditions for<br />

belonging to <strong>the</strong> kind, an argument that axes are not alive which was based<br />

on it would likely not be very convincing even if sound. But Aristotle does<br />

not in fact use it to argue that axes are not alive. When he discusses <strong>the</strong> axe<br />

(412 b 10, ff.) he is only illustrating his contention that soul is <strong>the</strong> generic<br />

form <strong>of</strong> (among o<strong>the</strong>r things) a special type <strong>of</strong> body - one o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong><br />

type <strong>the</strong> axe has - and not arguing.<br />

The reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definitions in II, 1 proposed here also provides us with<br />

a simple way to resolve <strong>the</strong> worries over <strong>the</strong> conflict between those<br />

definitions and <strong>the</strong> various claims which Aristotle makes concerning <strong>the</strong><br />

separability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> intellect from <strong>the</strong> body. The definition in II, 1 - in any<br />

<strong>of</strong> its forms - does nothing to rule those claims out. If a functioning<br />

intellect has <strong>the</strong> same generic type <strong>of</strong> actuality as familiar functioning<br />

organic entities, independent <strong>of</strong> any attachmen to any body, <strong>the</strong>n it is alive<br />

and ensouled - and it is so according to <strong>the</strong> definition. The prime mover<br />

too will count as a case <strong>of</strong> a living and, hence, ensouled entity, according to<br />

<strong>the</strong> definition, since <strong>the</strong> actuality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prime mover is <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> same generic<br />

type as that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most familiar ensouled entities.<br />

Given this understanding <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1, moreover, we cannot<br />

claim that on that definition <strong>the</strong> mind-body problem does not arise. The<br />

claim made at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> I1, 1 that nothing up to that point has ruled out <strong>the</strong><br />

possibility that <strong>the</strong> soul is <strong>the</strong> actuality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> body as <strong>the</strong> sailor is <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ship<br />

is compatible with what has gone before, understood in its natural dualistic<br />

sense. The definition does require that as a whole <strong>the</strong> soul <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most<br />

familiar ensouled things, including sailors, is incapable <strong>of</strong> its full functioning<br />

apart from its body -just as <strong>the</strong> sailor is incapable <strong>of</strong> functioning as<br />

a sailor apart from a ship. But since <strong>the</strong> definition does not <strong>of</strong> itself require<br />

that every functioning soul be embodied, it by itselfleaves it open that most<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> life functions <strong>of</strong> even <strong>the</strong> familiar ensouled things can go on disembodied<br />

- just as most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> psychic functions which a sailor employs in<br />

sailing can go on apart from any ship.<br />

This constitutes <strong>the</strong> general inductive evidence for <strong>the</strong> reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul in <strong>De</strong> Anima II, 1 proposed here. If it is a nominal<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort proposed, <strong>the</strong>n we are no longer faced with inconsistencies<br />

between different works (Metaphysics XII, and <strong>De</strong> Anima II) or<br />

between different books <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>De</strong> Anima (II and III) or within a single<br />

chapter (II, 1) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>De</strong> Anima.<br />

266


6. We need now to look more closely at <strong>the</strong> text to see what direct<br />

support it <strong>of</strong>fers for our reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definition.<br />

What we should be given in <strong>De</strong> A nima II, 2, ff. according to <strong>the</strong> opening<br />

sentence <strong>of</strong> that chapter, is a new account <strong>of</strong> soul which stands to <strong>the</strong><br />

account <strong>of</strong> II, 1 as explanation to fact (IT'ra to O"Tl) and as reason to<br />

conclusion (a'L'Tov to oavIepacvia). So we should expect to find a new<br />

account from which <strong>the</strong> old account is somehow derivable. If we can find<br />

such a new account that should help us to understand what form <strong>the</strong> old<br />

account has in <strong>Aristotle's</strong> view.<br />

The conclusion <strong>of</strong> II, 2 is that a certain account <strong>of</strong> soul has been<br />

demonstrated. The conclusion reads: "It is <strong>the</strong>refore evident, from <strong>the</strong>se<br />

considerations, that <strong>the</strong> soul is a certain type <strong>of</strong> actuality and defining<br />

principle (Xoyos) <strong>of</strong> that which has <strong>the</strong> capacity for life" (414 a 27-28,<br />

reading TOLOVTOv at a 28 as at 412 a 21). This definition <strong>of</strong> soul which is said<br />

to have been established omits explicit reference to <strong>the</strong> body altoge<strong>the</strong>r,<br />

unlike <strong>the</strong> earlier definitions in II, 1. But according to this definition soul is<br />

<strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> that which has a certain capacity or potentiality and Aristotle<br />

has just said (414 a 16-17, 25-27) that what has a given potentiality is<br />

always matter <strong>of</strong> a certain sort.30 So this definition says, implicitly at least,<br />

that <strong>the</strong> soul is a certain type <strong>of</strong> actuality or form <strong>of</strong> a certain type <strong>of</strong> living<br />

body. So understood, <strong>the</strong> definition is, in its general import, equivalent to<br />

<strong>the</strong> definitions <strong>of</strong> II, 1.<br />

Is <strong>the</strong>re, <strong>the</strong>n, any o<strong>the</strong>r general definition from which this definition is<br />

derived over <strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong> II, 2? The most prominent general proposition<br />

about soul <strong>of</strong>fered in <strong>the</strong> chapter is <strong>the</strong> one introduced at 413 b 11-12:<br />

"<strong>Soul</strong> is <strong>the</strong> source (&pXA) <strong>of</strong> and is delimited by <strong>the</strong> life functions, such as<br />

nutrition, sensation, thought and motion." This proposition is <strong>the</strong> first<br />

account <strong>of</strong> soul at which Aristotle arrives after having begun, at 413 a 20,<br />

his search for a new definition. And <strong>the</strong> pattern <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discussion following<br />

this new account is what we would expect given <strong>the</strong> interpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

opening lines <strong>of</strong> 11, 2 defended earlier. The new account <strong>of</strong> soul is higher up<br />

in <strong>the</strong> order <strong>of</strong> explanation than <strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong> II, 1 since from it that<br />

earlier account is derived, as follows:<br />

(1) <strong>Soul</strong> is <strong>the</strong> source (&pyA) <strong>of</strong> and is delimited by any one or more <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

life functions - nutrition, sensation, thought and motion (413 a 22-25,<br />

withb 11-12).<br />

(2) The defining life function <strong>of</strong> plants (413 a 25-31) and that <strong>of</strong> animals<br />

(b 1-4) - though probably not all life functions (b 24-29) - are <strong>the</strong><br />

functions <strong>of</strong> an appropriate sort <strong>of</strong> body (b 27-29).<br />

267


(3) Our soul is also "that whereby" we have primarily <strong>the</strong> defining life<br />

functions which we have (414 a 12-13, from 414 a 4-12).<br />

(4) These functions are also <strong>the</strong> functions <strong>of</strong> an appropriate sort <strong>of</strong> body<br />

(414 a 19-25).<br />

(5) That whereby something has its characteristic functions primarily is its<br />

form or actuality (from 414 a 8-10 with a 14-19).31<br />

(6) So soul is <strong>the</strong> actuality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> body which has <strong>the</strong> capacity for<br />

life functions (414 a 27-28).<br />

Laying out <strong>the</strong> derivation in detail reveals that <strong>the</strong> conclusion, <strong>the</strong> old<br />

definition, must be understood in a special way. It does not say that every<br />

type <strong>of</strong> soul is <strong>the</strong> actuality <strong>of</strong> a certain type <strong>of</strong> body - in which case being<br />

embodied would be a necessary condition <strong>of</strong> being a soul. It cannot say that<br />

in view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> content <strong>of</strong> (2) and <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> derivation. In <strong>the</strong><br />

derivation three types <strong>of</strong> soul - plant, animal and human - are surveyed<br />

and found to be <strong>the</strong> actualities <strong>of</strong> certain types <strong>of</strong> bodies. But, it is, at <strong>the</strong><br />

very least, said to be a puzzle (?rropia) and to be unclear (ovi qxvepov)<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re are types <strong>of</strong> soul which are entities <strong>of</strong> a different sort (413<br />

b 13-16, 24-27).32 So <strong>the</strong> conclusion which states only what is clear from <strong>the</strong><br />

foregoing discussion (cpavep6v ix TOV'TV), cannot rule out such types <strong>of</strong><br />

soul. The conclusion must be read as saying, <strong>the</strong>n, that soul is <strong>the</strong> generic<br />

actuality certain cases <strong>of</strong> which are, necessarily, embodied. So <strong>the</strong> conclusion,<br />

<strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1, is a nominal definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort that<br />

exhibits sufficient but not necessary conditions for being an instance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

entity it defines.<br />

Consider now <strong>the</strong> new definition at (1). It says merely that soul, generally,<br />

is <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> life functions or each group <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m that<br />

subsist toge<strong>the</strong>r. It openly affirms that anything which exercises one or<br />

more <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se life functions is ensouled whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> exercise requires <strong>the</strong><br />

operation <strong>of</strong> some bodily organ or not. So <strong>the</strong> character <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> new<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> II, 2 and <strong>the</strong> details <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> derivation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1<br />

(or its nominal equivalent) from <strong>the</strong> new definition both allow our<br />

hypo<strong>the</strong>sis concerning <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, I and confirm it.33<br />

The new definition <strong>of</strong> II, 2 stands, subject to a qualification to be mentioned<br />

below, as real definition to <strong>the</strong> nominal definitions <strong>of</strong> II, 1.34<br />

7. This interpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul in II, I is supported by<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r passage in II, 2. Aristotle <strong>of</strong>fers <strong>the</strong>re an example which illustrates<br />

<strong>the</strong> way in which <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1 is defective.35 The example is a<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> a squaring or quadrature (TEpTywvLuRi6s) as "an equilateral<br />

rectangle equal (in area) to a given figure with unequal sides" (413 a<br />

17-18). This definition points to a certain very familiar case <strong>of</strong> squaring36<br />

268


ut it exhibits a sufficient and not a necessary condition for a squaring. It<br />

focuses only on <strong>the</strong> squaring <strong>of</strong> plane figures and, as Aristotle was aware,<br />

not only plane areas can be expressed as <strong>the</strong> squares <strong>of</strong> some magnitude<br />

but also numbers.37 Aristotle <strong>of</strong>fers as <strong>the</strong> correct definition <strong>of</strong> squaring,<br />

"finding a mean proportional" (413 a 19). This definition is repeated in <strong>the</strong><br />

Metaphysics (996 b 20-21) as a definition <strong>of</strong> squaring generally ('rb<br />

TE'rpaycvLCtLv) without any restriction as to type <strong>of</strong> magnitude. And it<br />

covers numbers as well as plane areas.38 In <strong>the</strong> Metaphysics this definition<br />

<strong>of</strong> squaring, "finding a mean proportional," is given as a paradigm <strong>of</strong> a<br />

statement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence (ovaia and # oTn) <strong>of</strong> something (996 b 10-12). So<br />

if this is an accurate illustration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> character <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> new definition <strong>of</strong><br />

soul in II, 2, as Aristotle intends it to be, that definition must give <strong>the</strong><br />

whole <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> soul and <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1 cannot give even a<br />

part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence. Given this <strong>the</strong>re is, again, only one type countenanced<br />

in <strong>Aristotle's</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> definition to which <strong>the</strong> familiar definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1<br />

can belong, and that is <strong>the</strong> type to which we have assigned it.<br />

8. Fur<strong>the</strong>r light on <strong>the</strong> character <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definitions <strong>of</strong> II, 1 can be gotten<br />

from closer attention to <strong>the</strong> argument which leads to <strong>the</strong> first definition <strong>of</strong><br />

soul <strong>the</strong>re. That argument is similar in structure to <strong>the</strong> one we have just<br />

been considering. It concludes that soul is substance in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> form,<br />

being <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> a natural body which has life potentially (412 a 19-21).<br />

The curious thing about this conclusion, which is <strong>the</strong> first definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1,<br />

is that it focuses, like 414 a 12-13, on a special range <strong>of</strong> life functions. In it,<br />

and in its successor, 'life' has <strong>the</strong> special signification introduced at 412 a<br />

14-15: "nourishment, growth and decay through itself." So <strong>the</strong> first<br />

definition at 412 a 19-21 says that soul is <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> those natural bodies<br />

which have <strong>the</strong> capacity for just <strong>the</strong>se elementary life functions. But it has<br />

to identify <strong>the</strong> generic form <strong>of</strong>, at least, all organic bodies (412 a 27, ff.)<br />

and, hence, to at least identify <strong>the</strong> generic form which some such bodies<br />

possess by having o<strong>the</strong>r life functions as well as <strong>the</strong>se (cf. 413 b 11, ff.). To<br />

do this <strong>the</strong> initial definition has to say that soul is <strong>the</strong> generic form which<br />

belongs to those familiar bodies which have <strong>the</strong> basic functions <strong>of</strong> nourishment,<br />

growth and ageing, leaving it open that <strong>the</strong> possession <strong>of</strong> soul can<br />

involve <strong>the</strong> capacity for o<strong>the</strong>r functions than those.<br />

Once we understand this we can see what <strong>the</strong> progression from<br />

definition to definition in II, 1-2 is. The first two definitions <strong>of</strong> soul, as <strong>the</strong><br />

form or first actuality <strong>of</strong> a natural body which has <strong>the</strong> capacity for<br />

nutrition, growth and ageing, focus on entities which possess one special<br />

type <strong>of</strong> soul. This is <strong>the</strong> type "most common" to living things (415 a 23-25),<br />

a fact which makes <strong>the</strong> first two definitions appropriate starting points.<br />

269


They characterize soul generally as <strong>the</strong> generic form possessed by entities<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> special type in question. The third definition <strong>of</strong> soul, as <strong>the</strong> first<br />

actuality <strong>of</strong> a natural body with organs, focuses on a wider range <strong>of</strong> entities.<br />

Entities characterized by any <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> special types <strong>of</strong> sould defined by<br />

reference to collections <strong>of</strong> organic functions are in focus in this definition.<br />

The fourth definition speaks <strong>of</strong> soul more generally as <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong> form<br />

possessed by a certain sort <strong>of</strong> natural body with an internal source <strong>of</strong> its<br />

activity. This definition focuses on certain natural bodies which engage in a<br />

certain range <strong>of</strong> activities but does not tie those activities down to organs.<br />

The new definition <strong>of</strong> II, 2 marks ano<strong>the</strong>r stage in <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> generalization.<br />

It defines soul as <strong>the</strong> generic form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> type possessed by whatever<br />

engages in any life function. Here <strong>the</strong> functions are nei<strong>the</strong>r tied down to<br />

organs nor tied down to body.<br />

9. Having attended to those features <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> text which support <strong>the</strong><br />

reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1 <strong>of</strong>fered here, we should consider those<br />

features which might be thought to go against it. One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se has already<br />

been alluded to. At 412 b 4-6 and b 10 Aristotle speaks <strong>of</strong> one variant <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

account <strong>of</strong> soul in II, 1 as an account which "mentions something common<br />

(TL XOLV6V) to every soul" and which "says what soul is in general (xa0o-<br />

Xov)". As we have seen, however, <strong>the</strong>se remarks are not inconsistent with<br />

<strong>the</strong> interpretation <strong>of</strong>fered here.39 The generic form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> familiar natural<br />

bodies with organs belongs even to <strong>the</strong> separate intellect and to <strong>the</strong> prime<br />

mover.<br />

Aristotle also says at 412 b 6-9 that it follows from his account <strong>of</strong> soul<br />

that we do not need to inquire whe<strong>the</strong>r "<strong>the</strong> soul and <strong>the</strong> body are one,"<br />

since an actuality and that <strong>of</strong> which it is <strong>the</strong> actuality form a unity in <strong>the</strong><br />

strictest sense. This does require that any type <strong>of</strong> soul which is <strong>the</strong> actuality<br />

<strong>of</strong> a particular body is not separable in toto from that body and that that<br />

body is not separable in toto from that soul. But it does not require that no<br />

faculty or faculties <strong>of</strong> such a soul are inseparable from <strong>the</strong> composite to<br />

which <strong>the</strong>y are attached (413 a 3-7), nor that such a faculty could not when<br />

separate engage in some life function and be, hence, alive and ensouled<br />

(413 a 20-25).40 That "<strong>the</strong> soul and <strong>the</strong> body are one" no more requires that<br />

every ensouled thing is embodied than it requires that every material object<br />

is ensouled. The phrase "<strong>the</strong> soul" is no more general than its companion,<br />

"<strong>the</strong> body." And <strong>the</strong> phrase "<strong>the</strong> body" refers not to bodies in general but<br />

to <strong>the</strong> special bodies <strong>of</strong> certain particular things (412 b 6-8, 11-17). In <strong>the</strong><br />

Metaphysics, in language which echoes that in <strong>the</strong> <strong>De</strong> Anima, Aristotle<br />

claims that in general "<strong>the</strong> proximate matter and <strong>the</strong> form are one and <strong>the</strong><br />

same thing" (1045 b 18-19). The unity in view <strong>the</strong>re is just <strong>the</strong> sort which<br />

270


obtains between soul and body (1045 a 23-33 with 1075 b 34-37). But<br />

Aristotle is not claiming <strong>the</strong>re that every form is identical with some<br />

proximate matter. He denies that in <strong>the</strong> very place where he speaks <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

form and <strong>the</strong> matter as one (1045 a 36, f.).41 It is "<strong>the</strong> proximate matter<br />

and its form" which are one (cf. 1041 b 7-9). So when Aristotle speaks in<br />

just <strong>the</strong> same way about soul and body he need only be talking about<br />

embodied souls and ensouled bodies. In <strong>the</strong> subsequent discussion <strong>the</strong><br />

terms "soul" and "body" are used in a similarly restricted way to refer only<br />

to animal soul and body (412 b 27 - 413 a 3 with 412 b 22-25).<br />

Aristotle also remarks, at 414 a 19, ff. that:<br />

Those who take it that <strong>the</strong> soul is nei<strong>the</strong>r independent <strong>of</strong> body nor a type <strong>of</strong> body are<br />

right. It is not a body but a type <strong>of</strong> thing which belongs to a body and, <strong>the</strong>refore, it<br />

exists (in&pXEL) in a body - a body <strong>of</strong> a particular sort.<br />

This too might be taken to go against <strong>the</strong> interpretation proposed here. But<br />

Aristotle is again not taLking about all cases <strong>of</strong> soul. He is using <strong>the</strong> term<br />

"<strong>the</strong> soul" here in <strong>the</strong> familiar sense <strong>of</strong> "<strong>the</strong> human soul," as <strong>the</strong> context<br />

makes clear. The "soul" which Aristotle has just been discussing is "that<br />

whereby we live and perceive and have understanding primarily" (414<br />

a12-13). This is only one in <strong>the</strong> series <strong>of</strong> types <strong>of</strong> soul which Aristotle is<br />

surveying in <strong>De</strong> A nima 11, 2- <strong>the</strong> human soul. Aristotle wants to show that<br />

this soul is, like <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs surveyed <strong>the</strong>re, "a type <strong>of</strong> thing which belongs to<br />

a body."42<br />

Finally, <strong>the</strong>re is <strong>Aristotle's</strong> suggestion that <strong>the</strong> intellect and <strong>the</strong> faculty<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical reasoning, being separable from <strong>the</strong> body, constitute "a<br />

distinct kind <strong>of</strong> soul" (4vxijs y?VOS '?'TEpov, 413 b 26). Some have read this<br />

remark to mean that <strong>the</strong> study <strong>of</strong> this faculty <strong>of</strong> soul belongs to a different<br />

science altoge<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> one whose subject is delimited by <strong>the</strong> general<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> soul in II, 1.43 If that were so <strong>the</strong>n we would not have to worry<br />

over how to make <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1 fit <strong>the</strong> separate intellect. However,<br />

Aristotle treats this faculty <strong>of</strong> soul as one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> parts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> generic entity he<br />

is discussing in <strong>the</strong> very place where he refers to it as a distinct kind <strong>of</strong> soul.<br />

(See r6t XoLrr &0pupa iris 4vxips, 413 b 27-28). He treats it in <strong>the</strong> same way in<br />

<strong>De</strong>Anima III, 4 (429 a 10, f.; cf. a 23) and speaks <strong>of</strong> it <strong>the</strong>re as a type <strong>of</strong> soul<br />

(i voqrIxi [+vx ], a 28; cf. <strong>De</strong> GenerationeAnimalium 736 b 13-16). If this is<br />

so <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1 which mentions something common to every<br />

soul must cover it. And <strong>the</strong> only way allowed by Aristotle to read a<br />

definition which makes it intelligible how <strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong> II, 1 can mention<br />

something which belongs to <strong>the</strong> separate intellect is <strong>the</strong> way defended<br />

above.<br />

10. It remains for us to deal with a ra<strong>the</strong>r technical problem concerning<br />

271


<strong>the</strong> adequacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> new definition <strong>of</strong> soul in I, 2. Does <strong>the</strong> claim at <strong>the</strong> end<br />

<strong>of</strong> II, 3 that <strong>the</strong> most appropriate account <strong>of</strong> soul (Xoyos oLxEL6TxTos . . .<br />

'nep'p ivXiAs, 415 a 13) is a serial account <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> distinct life functions,<br />

spoil in any way <strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong> II, 2? In particular does it show that <strong>the</strong> new<br />

account <strong>of</strong> soul in II, 2 does not genuinely give <strong>the</strong> explanation (t'iTLov) <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong> II, 1 or <strong>the</strong> essence (OL'Ta) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> actuality which is soul<br />

according to <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> 11, 1. A problem arises because <strong>the</strong> account,<br />

in sequence, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> special faculties is said to be most proper not as an<br />

account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> special faculties but as an account <strong>of</strong> soul simply (415 a 13).<br />

This strongly suggests that <strong>the</strong> general account <strong>of</strong> II, 2, though it explains<br />

<strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong> II, 1 in a way, is still not a full real definition or account <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> anything. And this is in fact required by o<strong>the</strong>r evidence.<br />

According to <strong>the</strong> Posterior A nalytics, <strong>the</strong> true explanation <strong>of</strong> some fact (oTL)<br />

is supposed to give <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> that <strong>of</strong> which <strong>the</strong> fact holds (90 a 5-15,<br />

93 a 3-9). And according to <strong>the</strong> <strong>De</strong> A nima no general account which covers<br />

several species <strong>of</strong> some genus can give <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> anything (414 b<br />

25-27). The doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Metaphysics (1030 a 6, ff.) that only ultimate<br />

species have definitions which, strictly speaking, give <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> anything<br />

is clearly in play in <strong>the</strong> <strong>De</strong> A nima. And given <strong>the</strong> doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Metaphysics, we must conclude that <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 2 does not, strictly<br />

speaking, stand to <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1 as account <strong>of</strong> essence to account <strong>of</strong><br />

fact. But <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 2 is in fact only put forward as one which will<br />

suffice for <strong>the</strong> time being (413 b 11-12). Did Aristotle believe <strong>the</strong>n that this<br />

definition only leads us in <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most proper explanation <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1, and that <strong>the</strong> full account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> particular faculties<br />

would provide one with such an explanation? That seems <strong>the</strong> natural way<br />

to make <strong>the</strong> conclusion <strong>of</strong> II, 3 consistent with II, 1-2. It is easy to see how a<br />

new serial account <strong>of</strong> soul as <strong>the</strong> source (ap)i') <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> various<br />

special faculties in sequence would serve to establish <strong>the</strong> claim <strong>of</strong> II, 1 that<br />

soul is <strong>the</strong> generic actuality certain cases <strong>of</strong> which belong to a special sort <strong>of</strong><br />

natural body. For many <strong>of</strong> those faculties will be explicitly shown by this<br />

account to constitute, individually or collectively, types <strong>of</strong> soul which are<br />

capable <strong>of</strong> existing only in such a body.<br />

We can, however, still speak <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 2 as giving, so far as is<br />

possible, <strong>the</strong> full essence or <strong>the</strong> real definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> genus <strong>of</strong> each type <strong>of</strong><br />

soul - remembering that no such genus can, strictly speaking, have an<br />

essence or, hence, a real definition. The definition <strong>of</strong> II, 2 does give a full<br />

explanation (ai'TLov), in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> that term employed in <strong>the</strong> Posterior<br />

Analytics, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact (orL) stated in <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, 1. (The doctrine that<br />

no genus can have an essence is not found in <strong>the</strong> Analytics.) But <strong>the</strong> new<br />

272


doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Metaphysics requires us to say that <strong>the</strong> new definition can<br />

only in a secondary way give <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> anything (1030 a 17, ff.). This<br />

qualification leaves our earlier results unaffected.<br />

The upshot <strong>of</strong> those results is that <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul as <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> body (in any <strong>of</strong> its variants) should not be understood in <strong>the</strong> usual way.<br />

Correctly understood it does not entail that every soul is embodied. It does<br />

entail that certain types <strong>of</strong> embodied forms are souls but it does not tell us<br />

which types those are. So, as far as <strong>the</strong> definition goes, not only <strong>the</strong> intellect<br />

but o<strong>the</strong>r faculties <strong>of</strong> soul as well might exist unembodied or disembodied.<br />

Aristotle does not believe that many, if any, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>r functions can<br />

exist unembodied but that is a matter which he undertakes to prove by<br />

showing that <strong>the</strong>se functions require <strong>the</strong> operation <strong>of</strong> specific bodily organs<br />

(see 413 b 13-29). The matter is not settled by <strong>the</strong> definition.<br />

It follows from this that in <strong>Aristotle's</strong> view <strong>the</strong> mind-body problem is not<br />

one that can be settled on what we would call conceptual grounds. The<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> soul in II, 1, being a nominal or semantic definition, is an<br />

account by reference to what is more familiar to us. As such it explicates<br />

what <strong>the</strong> common understanding <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul is (Topics<br />

141 b 3-14). But this common understanding focuses on certain special<br />

cases <strong>of</strong> soul and does not incorporate any fully general description <strong>of</strong> what<br />

a soul is. So one cannot say in general on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> this account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

ordinary concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul what <strong>the</strong> relation between soul and body is.<br />

11. We may conclude by noting certain implications which <strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong><br />

ur study <strong>of</strong> <strong>Aristotle's</strong> definitions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul have for <strong>the</strong> interpretation <strong>of</strong><br />

Aristotle generally.<br />

At <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>De</strong> A nima II, I Aristotle speaks <strong>of</strong> his initial account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

soul as a sketch "in outline" (Tv$vi). As we saw at <strong>the</strong> outset, he characteristically<br />

uses this expression to describe initial accounts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort which<br />

are "more intelligible to us" and which give only derivative facts about<br />

some entity ra<strong>the</strong>r than its essence." O<strong>the</strong>r passages ally accounts described<br />

in <strong>the</strong>se latter ways with nominal definitions. In Physics I, 1 (184 a<br />

16 - b 14) an account which is more intelligible to us is said to be <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

same sort as a nominal definition. And in <strong>De</strong> Anima II, 2 (413 a 13, ff.) an<br />

account which gives only a fact is said to be like a "conclusion" or nominal<br />

definition. This makes it apparent that an account "in outline" is likely to<br />

have important similarities, at least, with one or ano<strong>the</strong>r type <strong>of</strong> nominal<br />

definition.<br />

A striking proportion <strong>of</strong> what Aristotle says in his works - about everything<br />

from <strong>the</strong> syllogism to substance to <strong>the</strong> highest good - is qualified by<br />

use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> expression "in outline" and <strong>the</strong> related expressions applied in <strong>De</strong><br />

273


Anima II, 1-2 to <strong>the</strong> initial definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul.45 This highlights <strong>the</strong><br />

importance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> nominal definition in <strong>the</strong> Posterior Analytics,<br />

since that is <strong>the</strong> one place where Aristotle explains in a full way what<br />

at least one sort <strong>of</strong> account <strong>of</strong> this type is like. It also indicates that special<br />

care may need <strong>of</strong>ten to be taken not to attribute to Aristotle views stronger<br />

than those to which he is actually committed - when, as in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

famous definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul, what he says only describes <strong>the</strong> object under<br />

discussion "in outline."46<br />

Rutgers College, Rutgers University<br />

1 The standard contemporary attempts to deal with <strong>the</strong> problem are those <strong>of</strong> W. Jaeger,<br />

who argued that <strong>the</strong> dualistic doctrines are inconsistent with <strong>the</strong> anti-dualist definition<br />

and constitute an inheritance from Plato which Aristotle never abandoned (Aristotle, 2nd<br />

edn., Oxford, 1948, 217-219, 332-34); F. Nuyens, who supposed that <strong>the</strong> problematic<br />

doctrines while not inconsistent with <strong>the</strong> definition constituted with it for Aristotle a<br />

mystery whose threads he could not unravel (L'tvolution de la Psychologie d'Aristote,<br />

Louvain, 1948, Ch. VII, especially 317-318); and W. D. Ross, who argued that <strong>the</strong><br />

dualistic doctrines belonged to an earlier phase <strong>of</strong> <strong>Aristotle's</strong> thought and were abandoned<br />

by <strong>the</strong> time <strong>of</strong> writing <strong>of</strong> <strong>De</strong> A nima II ("The <strong>De</strong>velopment <strong>of</strong> <strong>Aristotle's</strong> Thought,"<br />

Proceedings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> British Academy, 43 (1957) 65-67). For <strong>the</strong> standard older views, see <strong>the</strong><br />

discussion in R. D. Hicks, Aristotle, <strong>De</strong> Anima (Cambridge, 1907), pp. lxiv-lxix.<br />

2 r4vrc and &xpl0s are standardly contrasted with each o<strong>the</strong>r. See H. Bonitz, Index<br />

Aristotelicus (Berlin, 1870), p. 779. Physics 184 a 23-26 shows that xao6Xou is sometimes<br />

used like rimy and contrasted with W' &xpOEiaS. See also Prior Analytics 46 a 10, ff.,<br />

a 28-30.<br />

3 Cf. <strong>De</strong> A nima 402 b 16, ff The account which gives <strong>the</strong> akrla is <strong>the</strong> one which gives <strong>the</strong><br />

genuine ri bL. This is presumed in <strong>the</strong> illustration at 413 a 17-20 and is required by <strong>the</strong><br />

language, as we shall see below.<br />

4 Two o<strong>the</strong>r ways <strong>of</strong> reading <strong>the</strong> opening remarks <strong>of</strong> II, 2 deserve consideration. (1)<br />

Aristotle is announcing <strong>the</strong> method which he is about to follow - beginning with matters<br />

which are "clearer to us" than <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, I (namely, <strong>the</strong> accounts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

particular faculties <strong>of</strong> soul) and working up inductively to a new account which is an<br />

improvement on that definition. (See R. D. Hicks, op. cit., p. 322. Hicks was following<br />

Simplicius, in <strong>De</strong> A nima, 96-97 Hayduck). But Aristotle does not produce a new account<br />

<strong>of</strong> soul at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> his discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> special faculties. At <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> II, 2 we have <strong>the</strong><br />

old definition reaffirmed (414 a 27-28; see below Sec. 6); and <strong>the</strong>re is no new definition<br />

after that. And <strong>the</strong> accounts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> special faculties are not and cannot be derived from<br />

any new fully adequate general account <strong>of</strong> soul as <strong>the</strong>y would be if <strong>the</strong>y were accounts <strong>of</strong><br />

soul which are "clearer to us." (Such accounts stand to <strong>the</strong> fully adequate account in <strong>the</strong><br />

relation <strong>of</strong> fact to explanation and conclusion to reason, 413 a 11-16). The relation is<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way around (see Sec. II). (2) Aristotle is beginning again from an account<br />

<strong>of</strong> soul which is more obvious to us than <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, I and working from that to<br />

establish inductively <strong>the</strong> old definition which is itself "more intelligible in <strong>the</strong> order <strong>of</strong><br />

explanation." (So, apparently, Aquinas, in <strong>De</strong> Anima, Sections 245, ff. Pirotta; but see<br />

Section 244.) But <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, I is itself an account "in outline" ('rimy), and<br />

274


Aristotle never applies this language to a fully adequate account. As shown above, an<br />

account 'rimr has <strong>the</strong> features <strong>of</strong> an account that is "clearer to us" in contrast with one<br />

which is "more intelligible in <strong>the</strong> order <strong>of</strong> explanation" and one which states <strong>the</strong> facts<br />

about some subject without giving <strong>the</strong> essence in contrast with one that gives <strong>the</strong> essence.<br />

Moreover, <strong>the</strong> only new general account <strong>of</strong> soul <strong>of</strong>fered after II, 1, at 413 b 11-13, is not<br />

derived by Aristotle, as it should be on this reading, from <strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong> II, 1 (nor can it<br />

be, since it covers <strong>the</strong> &pxij <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> functioning separate intellect and <strong>the</strong> account <strong>of</strong> II, I -<br />

taken as a fully adequate account - does not). Again, it is <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way around (see<br />

Sections 5-8 below). Also, it would be quite uncharacteristic <strong>of</strong> Aristotle to start an<br />

inquiry with an account which is better known absolutely and <strong>the</strong>n take up an account<br />

which is better known to us. This goes against his preaching and his practice (see, e.g.,<br />

History <strong>of</strong>A nimals 491 a 7-14). The reading proposed here accommodates <strong>the</strong> description<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, I at 413 a 9-10 and fits <strong>the</strong> pattern <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> II, 2. It is<br />

closest to <strong>the</strong> reading <strong>of</strong> G. Rodier (Aristote, Traite de l'Ame Paris, 1900, v. 2, 188-191),<br />

though it differs from his in various important respects.<br />

5 This remark is not normally taken as one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> definitions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul in <strong>De</strong> A nima II, 1.<br />

But <strong>the</strong> phrase "<strong>of</strong> that sort which has . . ." (TOLOV8 FxoVros . . ., b 16-17) specifies <strong>the</strong><br />

sort <strong>of</strong> body which ensouled things, as opposed to axes, have. It fills out what <strong>the</strong> "certain<br />

sort <strong>of</strong> body" (roovw& aqLsa) <strong>of</strong> b 11 is. And soul is xa%Xov <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> that sort <strong>of</strong> body<br />

(b 10-11). See, fur<strong>the</strong>r, below on this.<br />

6 See <strong>De</strong> Caelo 292 a 20 ff., b 28 f., 290 a 29 ff., 285 a 29. The rendering <strong>of</strong> owpa 6pyavLx6v<br />

(412 b 5-6) as "a body with organs" is standard and 412 a 28 - b 4 strongly supports it.<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r possible rendering is "a body which serves as an instrument." (Cf. <strong>De</strong> Partibus<br />

Animalium 642 a 14, ff.) Such a body perhaps need not have organs, but only serve as an<br />

organ for, in <strong>the</strong> case in question, <strong>the</strong> performance <strong>of</strong> some vital function. So understood,<br />

an amoeba would, perhaps, have a aupa 6pyavLxo'v. But Aristotle does not believe that a<br />

living thing can perform active functions without organs which are heterogeneous parts<br />

(<strong>De</strong> Partibus A nimalium 646 b 11. ff.). So <strong>the</strong> amoeba still poses a problem. And <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

problem remains. The stars do not use <strong>the</strong>ir bodies or any organ to move (<strong>De</strong> Caelo<br />

290 a 29, ff.).<br />

7 See 412 a 22-28 with 412 b 17-26 and 417 a 21, iff.<br />

8 These same problems would arise on any attempt to treat <strong>the</strong> fourth definition as<br />

referring to a special type <strong>of</strong> capacity for self-motion whose possession is necessary and<br />

sufficient for <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> life and soul. Cf. n. 30, below.<br />

9 See also 408 b 18, ff., 411 b 15-19, 413 b 24-27, 430 a 17-23. This claim is found also in<br />

<strong>the</strong> biological works; see <strong>De</strong> Generatione A nimalium 736 b 27-29, 737 a 7-10.<br />

10 Metaphysics 1072 b 26-27 reaffirms that <strong>the</strong> activity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> intellect (vovs) is a form <strong>of</strong><br />

life (twi). And <strong>De</strong> A nima 29 a 28 speaks <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> intellect as a type <strong>of</strong> soul (h VOq-TLX [iv 'Ix).<br />

At 413 a 8 it is soul (sAvxh) simply, in contrast (9,r a 8) to its parts (a 6-7), that is in<br />

question.<br />

12<br />

See G. Rodier, op. cit. for a concise report <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> views <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> older commentators.<br />

13<br />

See n. I above.<br />

14<br />

It is difficult to argue for an early date for <strong>De</strong> Anima III, 5 as Ross did (see n. 1), given<br />

<strong>the</strong> anticipations <strong>of</strong> its doctrines in Il 1, 2. Ross himself dropped <strong>the</strong> suggestion in his<br />

commentary (Aristotle, <strong>De</strong> Anima, Oxford, 1961, pp. 7-12).<br />

15 The commentators are not clear on this. Hicks, for example (op. cit., p. 322), identifies<br />

<strong>the</strong> definition which functions as conclusion with <strong>the</strong> type which displays <strong>the</strong> essence.<br />

16<br />

Some have tried to avoid this by introducing a fourth type <strong>of</strong> definition into Posterior<br />

275


A nalytics II, 10. This is contrary to <strong>Aristotle's</strong> assertion at 94 a I1 ,ff.(cf. 75 b 31-32) and to<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r evidence, but it is enough for our purposes in this paper that <strong>the</strong> definitions <strong>of</strong> <strong>De</strong><br />

Anima II, I belong to <strong>the</strong> type called "conclusions." Here, and in what follows, <strong>the</strong><br />

discussion draws on <strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong> "Essentialism and Semantic Theory in Aristotle:<br />

Posterior A nalytics 1I, 7-10," Philosophical Review, I 85 (1976); referred to below as ESTA.<br />

On <strong>the</strong> point in question here see ESTA, n. 14.<br />

17 This conclusion is confirmed by <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r language used to describe <strong>the</strong> definition in<br />

<strong>De</strong> Anima II, 2. The definition is said <strong>the</strong>re to merely state a fact ('r bT&) about <strong>the</strong> soul<br />

and not to specify <strong>the</strong> essence (j alrCat) which explains such facts. This language is used in<br />

<strong>the</strong> Posterior Analytics to contrast nominal with real definitions (93 a 16, ff., 93 b 29, ff.).<br />

The definition is also said to give an account <strong>of</strong> soul which is clearer to us but less<br />

knowable in <strong>the</strong> order <strong>of</strong> explanation. This language is used to characterize nominal<br />

definitions as opposed to o<strong>the</strong>r types at Physics 184 a 18, ff.<br />

18<br />

Posterior Analytics, 93 a 16-29 with 93 b 29-32 and 94 a 7-9.<br />

19 The items can change from stage to stage; 93 b 7-14 at 12-14.<br />

20 93 b38-94a9.<br />

21<br />

Some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se definitions give "something <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thing itself' (T axaroi,roe 'fp&yRaros),<br />

i.e. an element <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thing, 93 a 22-24, 27-29 with 94 a 7-9; o<strong>the</strong>rs give not<br />

an element <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence but only a feature by means <strong>of</strong> which we grasp <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> thing and are pointed to (a knowledge <strong>of</strong>) <strong>the</strong> essence (vpbs [-T C8?vai] To Tv kaTL) due<br />

to <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> feature is exhibitable in a conclusion derivable from <strong>the</strong> essence<br />

(93 a 27-29, a 35-37; cf. <strong>De</strong> Anima 402 b 21-22). There is a third type <strong>of</strong> nominal<br />

definition, one which mentions merely accidental features <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> entity defined (93 b<br />

29-37, cf. 93 a 24-26). But this type can only function as a conclusion <strong>of</strong> a syllogism or a<br />

statement that something is (Tb bTL) in a secondary way (75 b 30-32). So this type is not in<br />

play in <strong>De</strong> A nima II, 1.<br />

22 See 84 a, 11, ff. for <strong>the</strong> two permissible types <strong>of</strong> conclusions <strong>of</strong> demonstrations. The<br />

second type could, in principle, exhibit <strong>the</strong> inherence <strong>of</strong> a proprium in a thing but<br />

Aristotle thinks that such conclusions are very rare (73 a 6-7, 16-20).<br />

23 Nominal definitions are accounts <strong>of</strong> what some word or phrase signifies (0a<strong>ii</strong>wve),<br />

93 b 29-32. And signification has two components, reference and a fixing on a kind. (See<br />

<strong>the</strong> uses <strong>of</strong> ajo.clveLv at 92 b 26-34, 93 b 39-94 a 2 and ESTA, Sec. 7.)<br />

24<br />

93 a 16-29 with 93 b 29-32 and 94 a 7-9, and ESTA, Sec. 6. Cf. n. 26 below.<br />

25<br />

An example <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong> nominal definition which specifies a feature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence is<br />

'Thunder(OpovTi)<br />

is a certain type <strong>of</strong> noise in <strong>the</strong> clouds (4&pos'rs vrqGCv)' (93 a 22-23).<br />

This definition does not say that any noise in <strong>the</strong> clouds would be thunder. It says that<br />

thunder is that certain type <strong>of</strong> noise in <strong>the</strong> clouds, familiar actual instances <strong>of</strong> which we<br />

recognize as thunder. It says, hence, that something is an instance <strong>of</strong> thunder if and only<br />

if it belongs to <strong>the</strong> same kind as those familiar actual instances. An example <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> type <strong>of</strong><br />

nominal definition which specifies a proper feature not a part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> essence is 'Eclipse is<br />

<strong>the</strong> failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> full moon to cast shadows when nothing visible is in <strong>the</strong> way' (93 a 36 - b<br />

7). This definition refers us to familiar actual cases <strong>of</strong> eclipse by means <strong>of</strong> a description<br />

which provides us with a sufficient condition for <strong>the</strong> occurrence <strong>of</strong> an eclipse. It tells us<br />

that something is an eclipse if and only if it has <strong>the</strong> same essence or cause (adxiTa or &6rt1)<br />

as those actual cases <strong>of</strong> inability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> full moon to cast shadows under a visibly clear sky<br />

which we recognize as cases <strong>of</strong> eclipse. See ESTA, Sec. 9. For ano<strong>the</strong>r definition <strong>of</strong> this<br />

type see <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> a citizen at Politics 1275 a 29-33 (with a 33 ff. at b 5-7).<br />

26<br />

The indefinite 'TLS' plays a crucial role in definitions <strong>of</strong> this type (see 93 a 21-24). It<br />

276


means "that certain familiar." This is made clear by an important passage in <strong>the</strong> Physics<br />

(1, 1, 184 a 16 - b 14, at a 26, ff.) which reveals that initial (nominal) definitions in science<br />

are accounts by reference to actual cases <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> entity defined which are familiar to us.<br />

These definitions focus by means <strong>of</strong> such a reference onto a certain familiar whole (QXov<br />

n). See ESTA, Sec. 7.<br />

27 Here and in what follows I make explicit in paren<strong>the</strong>ses various features <strong>of</strong> nominal<br />

definitions which Aristotle himself normally only brings out in <strong>the</strong>oretical discussions <strong>of</strong><br />

definition. See nn. 25-26, Sec. 7 below, and ESTA, Secs. 6-9.<br />

28 In <strong>the</strong> fourth definition '"oLoa&' (412 b 16) functions as 'fIs' does in <strong>the</strong> nominal<br />

definitions at PosteriorAnalytics 93 a 22-24 to indicate that it is a special sort <strong>of</strong> body that<br />

is in question here (cf. 'roip,& a6paxn, b I 1) and not just any body with an internal source<br />

<strong>of</strong> change. That sort is "<strong>the</strong> most familiar sort" with an internal source <strong>of</strong> change and it is<br />

<strong>the</strong> function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 'roLoo00' to signify this. (Cf. Metaphysics, 1035 b 16 and 1043 a 36,<br />

where 'To&6a8E' and 'Tus' play, interchangeably, this role.) So understood <strong>the</strong> definition<br />

does provide a sufficient condition.<br />

29 It is not here assumed that Aristotle ever succeeds in adequately differentiating <strong>the</strong><br />

innate capacity for motion <strong>of</strong> living things, especially plants, from <strong>the</strong> innate impulse to<br />

motion (Physics 192 b 18) possessed by al inanimate natural objects. See F. Solmsen,<br />

<strong>Aristotle's</strong> System <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Physical World (Ithaca, 1960), 95-102. But <strong>the</strong> fourth definition<br />

<strong>of</strong> soul leaves open <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> a solution.<br />

30 This rules out <strong>the</strong> reading <strong>of</strong> 414 a 27-28 in J. Owens, "<strong>Aristotle's</strong> <strong>De</strong>finition <strong>of</strong> <strong>Soul</strong>,"<br />

in R. B. Palmer and R. Hamerton-KeUy (eds.) Philoma<strong>the</strong>s (The Hague, 1971), at n. 29.<br />

31 Assuming <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> actuality <strong>of</strong> a function to <strong>the</strong> function, as at 415 a 18-20.<br />

This step in <strong>the</strong> argument is not explicit but it is easily supplied.<br />

32 In fact <strong>Aristotle's</strong> claim at 413 b 24-27 is <strong>the</strong> stronger claim that "it is likely (Iotxe) that<br />

<strong>the</strong> intellect is a different type <strong>of</strong> soul, and it alone is separable." That 'IOLXE' has this force<br />

is clear from <strong>the</strong> parallel passage 408 b 18-29 (cf. 430 a 17-25).<br />

33 It might be suggested that <strong>the</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> II, I is a nominal definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort that<br />

exhibits necessary conditions for <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> soul. If so, <strong>the</strong>n according to <strong>the</strong> pattern<br />

at Posterior Analytics 94 a 3-9 <strong>the</strong> new definition <strong>of</strong> II, 2 would be a combination <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

old definition <strong>of</strong> II, I and what we have been calling <strong>the</strong> new definition. In that case <strong>the</strong><br />

correct new definition would be: <strong>Soul</strong> is <strong>the</strong> source (&p <strong>ii</strong>) <strong>of</strong> any group <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> life<br />

functions, which source is always possessed (as first actuality) by a natural body which<br />

has life potentially. In this case each type <strong>of</strong> soul would have to be a function <strong>of</strong> some<br />

natural body. But Aristotle denies having claimed this in <strong>the</strong> very place where he is<br />

developing his new definition (413 b 13-16, 24-29). So his new definition can hardly have<br />

this form.<br />

34 "Source <strong>of</strong> life" (&PX. Tow iv,<br />

413 b 11-13 with a 22-25) may seem ra<strong>the</strong>r thin and<br />

commonplace for a real definition. But Politics 1275 a 38 - b I shows that genera <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

type to which soul belongs are very thin in content (cf. <strong>De</strong> A nima 414 b 28-32) and <strong>the</strong> real<br />

definitions <strong>of</strong> entities <strong>of</strong> this type may be quite commonplace (see Politics 1279 a 25-27<br />

with 1278 b 8-10, ff., and for <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> definition <strong>of</strong> figure probably in view at <strong>De</strong>Anima<br />

414 b 20, ff., see Euclid, Elements I, <strong>De</strong>f. 14). The account <strong>of</strong> II, I may also seem ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

technical for a nominal definition. But even a relatively advanced account may still be<br />

what is "familiar to us" and only nominal. (See <strong>the</strong> nominal definition <strong>of</strong> squaring at 413<br />

a 16-19; cf. Politics 1275 a 29-34 and n. 25 above.)<br />

35 Note that <strong>the</strong> new definition <strong>of</strong> II, 2 is not defective in this way - ano<strong>the</strong>r reason for<br />

not taking it to be <strong>the</strong> inferior definition in view at 413 a 11, ff. Cf. n. 4 above.<br />

277


36 The squaring <strong>of</strong> a plane rectilinear figure which has been reduced to a rectangle with<br />

unequal sides. For <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>orems which Aristotle has in mind in this connection see Sir<br />

Thomas Heath, Ma<strong>the</strong>matics in Aristotle (Oxford, 1949), 191-193.<br />

37 See, e.g. Posterior A nalytics 76 b 8, and Heath, op. cit., 43-44.<br />

38 To square, i.e. to find <strong>the</strong> square root <strong>of</strong>, a number is to find <strong>the</strong> mean proportional<br />

between two factors which, multiplied toge<strong>the</strong>r, yield <strong>the</strong> number.<br />

" See above, Sec. 5. Physics 184 a 16, ff. at a 23, 25 makes clear that all nominal<br />

definitions and all accounts from <strong>the</strong> point <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong> what is more familiar are accounts<br />

<strong>of</strong> something "in general" (x066ou). The infant's notion <strong>of</strong> woman as what mo<strong>the</strong>r is<br />

contains an understanding <strong>of</strong> what a woman is xa(6Xov. It does mention a characteristic<br />

common to all women - being not a mo<strong>the</strong>r but what mo<strong>the</strong>r is - but it only does this in<br />

an indirect way. And this mention is indirect in <strong>the</strong> same way as that in <strong>the</strong> nominal<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> II, I on <strong>the</strong> reading given here.<br />

40 In view <strong>of</strong> this Aristotle cannot mean to say at 415 a 23-25 that nutrition is a faculty<br />

belonging to all living things. He says that "<strong>the</strong> nutritive soul is <strong>the</strong> first and most common<br />

faculty by which life belongs to all <strong>the</strong> things that have life, taken collectively, and is <strong>the</strong><br />

faculty most widely distributed over that collection; but not that it belongs to each<br />

member <strong>of</strong> that collection. 434 a 22-26 covers only those things which "live, and have soul<br />

from birth to death," i.e. with mortal things, as <strong>Aristotle's</strong> more careful statement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

same point at 413 a 31-32 confirms.<br />

41 Taking an essence ('ri iv elvaL, 1045 b 3, to be a form; 1032 b 1-2, with <strong>De</strong> Gen. et Cor.<br />

335 b 35. Cf. 1037 a 1-2). The entities which consist <strong>of</strong> form without matter here are <strong>the</strong><br />

categories, but that does not affect <strong>the</strong> point at issue. Aristotle, moreover, describes <strong>the</strong><br />

essence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prime mover (1071 b 19-21) and that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> separate intellect (<strong>De</strong> Anima<br />

430 a 22-23) in <strong>the</strong> same way. The substance (ov'ai) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> intellect (408 b 19,430 a 18) is,<br />

doubtless, substance in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> form (412 a 6-9).<br />

42 Cf. Sec. 6 above. The view <strong>of</strong> 414 a 19-20 is attributed by Aristotle to certain <strong>of</strong> his<br />

predecessors. When <strong>the</strong>y spoke <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul, as he points out, <strong>the</strong>y were almost exclusively<br />

discussing <strong>the</strong> human soul (402 b 3-5). Commentators agree that <strong>the</strong> view is closest to <strong>the</strong><br />

position discussed by Aristotle in <strong>the</strong> Eudemus and at <strong>De</strong> Anima 407 b 27, ff., and<br />

defended by Simmias at Phaedo, 85 e ff. (414 a 22-25 seems to recall <strong>the</strong> deficiency in <strong>the</strong><br />

view discussed at 408 a 10, f.) Simmias was talking about <strong>the</strong> human soul and so was<br />

Aristotle in <strong>the</strong> Eudemus (see W. D. Ross, Aristotle: Parva Naturalia, Oxford, 1955, pp.<br />

3-5). Cf. Politics 1340 b 14-19. At <strong>De</strong> Anima 402 a 6-10 "soul" covers only animal souls.<br />

43 See E. Zeller, Aristotle and <strong>the</strong> Earlier Peripatetics, Eng. tr. (London, 1897), 4.<br />

44 See above, Sec. 2.<br />

45 See Bonitz, op. cit., under 'T&wos', 'i'nro'runo0v', and yv6pitos and, in particular,<br />

Metaphysics 1028 b 27-32 at 31-32, 1029 b 3-12; Ethics 1094 a 25, b 19-22, 1176 a 30-32,<br />

1179 a 33-35.<br />

" An earlier version <strong>of</strong> this paper was read to <strong>the</strong> Ancient Greek Philosophy Colloquium<br />

(NYC). Many points in <strong>the</strong> paper have been improved as a result <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> discussion on that<br />

occasion and as a result <strong>of</strong> later discussion with John M. Cooper.<br />

278

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!