10.02.2014 Views

Sonia K. Katyal - UCLA Law Review

Sonia K. Katyal - UCLA Law Review

Sonia K. Katyal - UCLA Law Review

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

1642 57 <strong>UCLA</strong> LAW REVIEW 1601 (2010)<br />

political ramifications—irreconcilable, nonrivalrous, and yet contradictorily<br />

self-referential.<br />

A third extension of Crenshaw’s work is more analytically normative, as<br />

opposed to descriptive. The concept of intersectionality might help us in exploring<br />

the ideal role for the government to play in regulating the hybrid character<br />

of trademarks as mixed public and private goods, and as mixed commercial<br />

and expressive speech. Just as the law’s regulation of race affects its intersection<br />

with gender, the law’s regulation of the realm of private goods—the commercial<br />

realm of trademarks—affects its intersection with the realm of public goods like<br />

information. How should the government navigate the world of the commercial<br />

marketplace, as distinct from the marketplace of ideas? Should trademarks be<br />

regulated by the same standard in both contexts, or by a standard that recognizes<br />

how trademarks occupy the intersection of both marketplaces? Should it aim to<br />

be viewpoint-neutral, as in the context of noncommercial speech, or contentsensitive,<br />

as in the trademark context? Just as Crenshaw valuably exhorted<br />

scholars to take into account how each category affected the other (how the<br />

regulation of race affects gender, and vice versa), this Part argues that the law<br />

must also take into account the intersection of a trademark’s commercial and<br />

expressive facets, how each impacts the other, and how the law’s governance<br />

alters the interaction between a trademark’s economic value and social meaning<br />

in the marketplace.<br />

A. Mediating the Marketplace<br />

The marketplace of ideas and the marketplace of goods are both founded on<br />

the simple principle that they are inherently truth-seeking institutions. 183<br />

Yet the<br />

question of whether the marketplace—of goods or of ideas—actually leads to<br />

truth or to distortion has led to multiple opposing viewpoints, often leaving the<br />

proper role of government an open-ended question. 184<br />

Writing in 1974, Ronald<br />

Coase mused that if the government favored noninterference in the marketplace<br />

of ideas, then why not take the same approach in the marketplace of goods? 185<br />

For Coase, the government’s inconsistent approach suggested, at the very least,<br />

183. See Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting) (“[T]he best<br />

test of truth is the power of the thought to get itself accepted in the competition of the market . . . .”).<br />

184. For a few of these perspectives, see C. Edwin Baker, Scope of the First Amendment Freedom of<br />

Speech, 25 <strong>UCLA</strong> L. REV. 964, 974–81 (1978); Kent Greenawalt, Free Speech Justifications, 89 COLUM. L.<br />

REV. 119, 135–38 (1989); Stanley Ingber, The Marketplace of Ideas: A Legitimizing Myth, 1984 DUKE<br />

L.J. 1, 1–6.<br />

185. See R.H. Coase, The Market for Goods and the Market for Ideas, 64 AM. ECON. REV. 384 (1974);<br />

see also Tamara R. Piety, Market Failure in the Marketplace of Ideas: Commercial Speech and the Problem That<br />

Won’t Go Away, 41 LOY. L.A. L. REV. 181 (2007).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!