10.02.2014 Views

Sonia K. Katyal - UCLA Law Review

Sonia K. Katyal - UCLA Law Review

Sonia K. Katyal - UCLA Law Review

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

1644 57 <strong>UCLA</strong> LAW REVIEW 1601 (2010)<br />

Trade Commission is afforded broad authority to stop “deceptive” and “unfair”<br />

advertisements, and has defined “unfair” to include ads that “‘cause[ ] or [are]<br />

likely to cause substantial injury to consumers which is not reasonably avoidable<br />

by consumers themselves and not outweighed by countervailing benefits to<br />

consumers or to competition.’” 190<br />

This view portends a deep divide between the marketplace of goods and<br />

the marketplace of ideas: While the political marketplace of ideas is designed to<br />

foster and encourage dissent and debate, the commercial marketplace is premised<br />

largely on persuasion; it is not designed to permit a reciprocal exchange of<br />

information between seller and consumer. 191<br />

A trademark’s dual strands—its<br />

expressive and commercial facets in the marketplace of goods—thus translates<br />

into two potential lines of analysis regarding the proper degree of constitutional<br />

scrutiny that should be afforded to section 2(a). One intuition, which this Part<br />

explores, wholly characterizes trademarks as commercial speech, and little else.<br />

Yet another view, quite reasonably, might posit that while a trademark is certainly<br />

used for commercial purposes, it is also used for expressive purposes as<br />

well. These dichotomous uses bring up a fundamental question about the level<br />

of constitutional scrutiny that should be afforded to these marks. While advertisements<br />

generally (and trademarks specifically) are considered to be well within<br />

the purview of commercial speech, immoral, scandalous, or disparaging marks<br />

might also be compared to the same host of issues that animated related<br />

controversies surrounding other categories of low-value speech, like obscene or<br />

indecent speech, as well as hate speech.<br />

Like other forms of low-value speech, certain types of commercial<br />

speech receive less protection under the First Amendment. Commercial speech,<br />

because of its singular focus on economic profit, is thought to make a qualitatively<br />

different contribution to the marketplace of ideas. 192<br />

The Court has<br />

reasoned that regulating false or misleading speech in the commercial context is<br />

more justified because it “lacks the value that sometimes inheres in false or<br />

misleading political speech,” 193 and because consumers are less likely to have the<br />

acumen or information to question an advertiser’s claims. Moreover, the government<br />

has opted to regulate such speech on the grounds that commercial<br />

190. Patricia A. Davidson & Christopher N. Banthin, Untangling the Web: Legal and Policy Tools to<br />

Restrict Online Cigar Advertisements, 35 U.S.F. L. REV. 1 (2001) (citing 15 U.S.C. § 45(n) (1994)); see also<br />

15 U.S.C. § 45(n) (2006).<br />

191. See Helen McGee Konrad, Note, Eliminating Distinctions Between Commercial and Political<br />

Speech: Replacing Regulation With Government Counterspeech, 47 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 1129, 1136 (1990)<br />

(citing Va. State Bd., 425 U.S. at 765).<br />

192. See U.S. Healthcare, Inc. v. Blue Cross of Greater Phila., 898 F.2d 914, 933–34 (3d Cir. 1990).<br />

193. Rubin v. Coors Brewing Co., 514 U.S. 476, 496 (1995) (Stevens, J., concurring).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!