30.10.2012 Views

Edited by Chris Jenks - carlosmoreno.info

Edited by Chris Jenks - carlosmoreno.info

Edited by Chris Jenks - carlosmoreno.info

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

AN INTRODUCTION<br />

thesocial sciences or cultural studies ‘observation’ drags behind it an<br />

excess baggage of ontological and epistemological assumptions, albeit<br />

unexplicated, that can direct us to the origins of ‘our ways of seeing’<br />

through modernity. Three items are paramount: (1) assumptions concerning<br />

the finite and ‘visible’ character of social phenomena; (2) assumptions<br />

concerning the ‘clear sightedness’, that is, the moral and political<br />

disposition of the theorist; and (3) assumptions concerning the manner of<br />

‘visual’ relationship that sustains between the theorist and his/her<br />

phenomena. In large part these sets of assumptions have been subsumed<br />

under the analytic posture that has become both stereotyped and<br />

generalised under the blanket term ‘positivism’. Others before me have<br />

made thorough and valuable attempts to formalise the key characteristics<br />

of positivism, in the senses of it being both a technical philosophical term<br />

and also a cultural disposition, and I shall therefore only briefly rehearse<br />

some of their arguments here. 18<br />

THE DOCTRINE OF IMMACULATE PERCEPTION<br />

Positivism, for social theory, came into prominence through the highly<br />

influential works of Auguste Comte. It was he who envisaged sociology, his<br />

‘queen of the sciences’, becoming the culmination of the endeavours of<br />

positive philosophy. Sociological positivism was, for Comte, the pinnacle of<br />

an intellectual rational-reformist trajectory developed as a response to the<br />

social, and moral, instability that had been precipitated <strong>by</strong> the French<br />

Revolution. Sociology was allocated the role of completing a supposed<br />

hierarchical evolution of all scientific disciplines: it was to supersede all<br />

other forms of thought. Particularly to be transcended, within Comte’s ‘Law<br />

of Three Stages’, were the developmental stages of ‘theological’ and<br />

‘metaphysical’ forms of cognition (and we might note that ‘metaphysical<br />

questions’ have remained the anathema of positivisms, such as that of the<br />

‘Vienna Circle’, ever since). Proper (modern) scientific thought, Comte<br />

envisaged, was initially to grow out of a knowledge of great generality,<br />

relating to phenomena furthest from humankind’s own involvement, like<br />

deities. Having transcended this beginning, understanding should then<br />

metamorphose steadily onwards towards a stage of great specificity, relating<br />

to the phenomena of closest proximity to immediate human experience, that<br />

is, the law-governed things that surround us.<br />

Such an epistemological evolution heralds the advance and arrival of the<br />

‘observer’. As humankind’s attention is directed more and more closely<br />

towards itself and its immediate environment, quite simply more and more<br />

objects enter into ‘vision’. From the opaque distance required of gods, through<br />

the hazy and incalculable horizons of metaphysics, to the necessity and<br />

familiarity of things-in-themselves, inexorably the world drew nearer and<br />

nearer, it became more focused, and it assumed the vivid shapes ofempirical<br />

5

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!