21.01.2015 Views

CHAPTER V REFUTATION OF BAUDDHA PHILOSOPHY

CHAPTER V REFUTATION OF BAUDDHA PHILOSOPHY

CHAPTER V REFUTATION OF BAUDDHA PHILOSOPHY

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>CHAPTER</strong> V<br />

<strong>REFUTATION</strong> <strong>OF</strong> <strong>BAUDDHA</strong><br />

<strong>PHILOSOPHY</strong><br />

172


<strong>CHAPTER</strong> 5<br />

<strong>REFUTATION</strong> <strong>OF</strong> <strong>BAUDDHA</strong> <strong>PHILOSOPHY</strong><br />

Introduction.<br />

áa´kara refers to the three main schools of Buddhism. They<br />

are Sarv¡stivada, Vijµ¡nav¡da and á£nyav¡da. The Sarv¡stiv¡dins<br />

173


accept the reality of both the outside and the inside world 1 . The<br />

Vijµ¡nav¡dins maintain the theory that thought alone is real 2 . The<br />

á£nyav¡dins agree that everything is void 3 , but all of them agree that<br />

everything is momentary. According to Nataliya Ì¿ayeva, “As shown<br />

by the Advaitist, the Buddhists are classified under different sects in<br />

accordance with their interpretation of reality. Some maintain that<br />

everything exists ‘Sarvo ¡sti iti sarv¡stiv¡di, others allow for the<br />

existence of consciousness , that is , Vijµ¡nav¡da, and there are some<br />

who claim everything to be void, that is , á£nyav¡da. The general<br />

definition applied by áa´kara to all Buddhist schools is derived from<br />

the term Vin¡¿a, destruction, annihilation; it points out the core of<br />

174


the teaching, namely, the idea of the non-existence of Ëtman as a<br />

separate ontological reality. Therefore, Buddhism is determined by<br />

him as Vain¡¿ikamata, which can be roughly rendered as a teaching<br />

about non-existence 4 ”. áa´kara has been regarded by his opponents<br />

as a Crypto-Buddhist (Pracchanna-Bauddha). Many opponents of<br />

áa´kara regarded him as a Crypto Buddhist, because there are<br />

parallels between Advaita Ved¡nta and Mah¡y¡na Budhism,<br />

especially in connection with the principle of avidya and two truthsthe<br />

Param¡rthika (the absolute) and the Vyavah¡rika (the practical).<br />

Both these systems accept avidya as that which is to be removed, and<br />

both of them accept the twofold division of avidya-cognitional and<br />

175


conational aspects. But áa´kara gives more emphasis to investigation<br />

and inquiry. But Bauddha gives more emphasize to mind control<br />

and morality. Avidya , in its cognitional aspect , has provided a<br />

‘path’. According to Bauddha concept of Avidy¡: ‘path’ is the<br />

practice relating to prajµa. According to áa´kara, the path consists<br />

of investigation into the Ved¡nta texts , and the inquiry into<br />

Brahman. Against the Bauddha notion of momentariness, áa´kara<br />

emphasized on eternity of fundamental principle. These are the<br />

points of difference between áa´kara and Buddhists. The following<br />

concepts of Bauddha philosophy are refuted by áa´kara. They are :<br />

(1)theory of causation , (2) the concept of Ëk¡¿a, (3) the theory of<br />

176


origination of an entity from absence, (4) the concept of self intuition<br />

, (5)the concept that object entity and cognition are the same, (6) The<br />

concept that all worldly cognitions are unreal like dream, (7) the<br />

concept of svasamvedana pratyakÀa, (8) the concept of V¡sana,<br />

(9)the concept of alayavijµ¡n as the abode of v¡sana, and (10)the<br />

concept of antarjµeyar£pa as object entity.<br />

Sarv¡stiv¡da<br />

The Sarv¡stiv¡da school of H¢nay¡na Buddhism is in its<br />

approach realistic. It is divided into two: Sautr¡ntika and<br />

Vaibh¡Àika. The Vaibh¡Àika attaches itself to Vibh¡Àa ,a<br />

177


commentary on Abhidharma work and it may be called<br />

presentationalism (The doctrine that in perception the mind has<br />

immediate cognition of the object). The Vaibh¡Àika-s maintain the<br />

independent existence of mind and matter.<br />

The Sautr¡ntik¡s are attached to s£tra and they may be called<br />

advocates of representationalism. (The doctrine that perceived<br />

objects as only a representation of real external objects). The<br />

Sautr¡ntik¡s maintain the theory that all external things are<br />

inferable. But the scholars agree that both these schools are equally<br />

realistic. áa´kara refuted theses two schools bearing the name of<br />

Sarv¡stiv¡da.<br />

178


Refutation of the Buddhist theory of causation<br />

The Buddhist theory of causation is called Prat¢tya-s¡mulpada<br />

or the theory of dependent origination. Regarding the concept of<br />

causation, the Sarv¡stiv¡da holds the view that all constructed things<br />

are independently originated 5 . The famous Buddhist thinker<br />

Kamala¿ila says that it is the chief jewel among all the teachings of<br />

the Buddha. According to Dr. Vijaya Rani, this theory has a wide<br />

scope. It covers the problem of causal relationship, the theories of<br />

momentariness, of disconnected flow, of no soul, of ¿£nyata and so<br />

forth 6 . The effect elements come forth only when the cause element is<br />

there (dharma-sthitita).<br />

179


According to áa´kara, the term samud¡ya 7 can be interpreted<br />

in two ways: (1) the evolutes having as cause the elements of fire,<br />

water, earth and wind, and (2) the mentals having thought as their<br />

cause 8 . The Sarv¡stiv¡dins and their followers recognize the view that<br />

the external reality is either element or elemental and the internal<br />

reality is either mind or mental. They say that both these together<br />

make up this universe. The external<br />

world is made up of the<br />

aggregation of atoms 9 . These atoms are four kinds i.e., atoms of<br />

earth, i.e., hard, (b) atoms of water, i.e., viscid ,(c) atoms of fire, i.e.,<br />

hot, (d) atoms of air, i.e., mobile. These atoms are gathered together<br />

in to aggregates. With the connection of the internal world, the five<br />

180


personal skand¡s are the cause. They are: r£pa skandh¡, vijµ¡na<br />

skandh¡, vedan¡ skandh¡, samjµ¡ skandh¡ and samsk¡ra skandh¡ 10 .<br />

By the aggregation of these skandh¡s the internal world is produced.<br />

According to áa´kara, the above view of Sarv¡stiv¡da is<br />

unacceptable because no cause is established for the existence either<br />

of the aggregate of elements and evolutes or of the aggregate of<br />

thought and mental 11 . These two types of aggregates can never be<br />

formed at all. The unintelligent momentary atoms and the<br />

momentary skandh¡s cannot form any systematic whole. áa´kara<br />

continually says that if individual atoms could engage in activity on<br />

their own account, then their activity would never cease 12 . So there is<br />

181


no aggregation. Without the aggregation the worldly things cannot<br />

exist. But the Sarv¡stiv¡dins suppose that on the basis of the series of<br />

the dependent origination (prat¢tyas¡mulp¡da) the aggregate can be<br />

formed. Dr Vijaya Rani gives two definitions to Prat¢tyas¡mulp¡da,<br />

i.e., an origination after getting the causes, and an origination after<br />

the destruction of the causes 13 . On the basis of the formation of<br />

aggregates the series of Prat¢tyas¡mulpada can be explained’ 14 . The<br />

series is – avidy¡, samsk¡ra, vijjµ¡na, n¡ma, r£pa, Àad¡yatana,<br />

spar¿a, vedan¡, t¤À¸a, up¡d¡na, bh¡va, jati, jara, mara¸a, ¿oka,<br />

parivedana, dukha, etc 15 . Through this series an uninterrupted chain<br />

of cause and effect is constituted. This chain cannot take place<br />

182


without the aggregates. The Sarv¡stiv¡dins hold the view that the<br />

aggregates are the reality, by the s£tra: itaretarapratyay¡tvatiti<br />

cennolpattim¡tra nimittatv¡t 16 .<br />

áa´kara refutes these concepts of<br />

Sarv¡stiv¡dins. According to áa´kara, the formation of the aggregates<br />

are explained by the mutual causality of the series of dependent<br />

origination. He refutes them by saying that though the preceding<br />

one is the cause of the subsequent one, there is nothing which can be<br />

the cause of the whole of the aggregate. According to him, the atoms<br />

cannot combine themselves even when they are assumed to be<br />

permanent and eternal, because the atoms are momentary<br />

aggregates<br />

without which the nid¡nas would be deprived of an<br />

183


abode. He says that Bauddhas may accept nescience as an efficient<br />

cause for the aggregates, Since the aggregates follow one another in a<br />

series 17 . The aggregates are formed on the basis of nescience, they<br />

follow one another as a series in an endless world. It causes an<br />

aggregate being born distinct from an aggregate, which is born<br />

similar according to rule, or is born either similar or dissimilar,<br />

according to no rule. In the former case, a man could never be<br />

reborn in a different state. In the latter case, he could in an instance<br />

be transformed into something else. áa´kara argues against the<br />

Sarv¡stiv¡da concept of series by asking how aggregates can be born<br />

from other aggregates in an endless series. In that case , liberation<br />

184


would be desired by one but attained by another. So, the series<br />

stands in a relation of successive causality and it cannot be the cause<br />

of the aggregates, and there being no permanent enjoyer, there is<br />

neither any need of the aggregate. The mere existence of the<br />

preceding moment means its causal efficiency. This also cannot be<br />

acceptable because no effect can arise without imbibing the nature of<br />

the cause which is permanent as it continues to exist in the effect<br />

and thus the Bauddha doctrine of momentariness is not acceptable.<br />

Through the commentary of the s£tra –uttarolp¡de ca<br />

p£rvanirodh¡t 18 , áa´kara establishes that the successive causality<br />

spoken of in the series of avidy¡, samsk¡ra etc. is untenable. The<br />

185


Sarv¡stiv¡dins argues that everything is created; the antecedent thing<br />

would already have ceased to exist at the next moment (ulpanna<br />

vin¡Àa) 19 . According to the Abhidhar-mako¿a, “the uninterrupted<br />

succession of moments following one another is duration. The latter<br />

moment is the substitute of the former moment because of<br />

similarity” 20 .<br />

áa´kara refutes this argument thus - it is intended by the<br />

Sarv¡stiv¡din that the entity having a perfected condition in the<br />

previous moment cause of entity in a later moment. This is not<br />

possible, because of the occurrence of connection with a second<br />

moment when there is the hypothesis of the further activity of an<br />

186


entity 21 . áa´kara states that if existence (bh¡va) of the cause be its<br />

activity (vy¡p¡ra) ,then the effect is imbued with the nature of the<br />

cause. The cause lasts for more than one moment and the principle<br />

of momentariness is tresspassed. The Sarv¡stiv¡din say that existence<br />

is its activity 22 . áa´kara refuted the point saying that it is impossible<br />

because of the impossibility of arising of an effect. As that which is<br />

not imbued with the nature of the cause since everything is<br />

momentary, the antecedent thing would already have ceased to exist<br />

at the next moment, when the subsequent thing is created 23 . So it can<br />

be the cause of the other.<br />

187


According to the view Sarv¡stiv¡da, áa´kara says that the cause<br />

and effect can continue to exist without the colouring of the effect by<br />

the cause. áa´kara replies that such a position would bring about<br />

confusion.<br />

áa´kara says that the Sarv¡stiv¡din cannot admit any causal<br />

process issuing from the momentary cause and influencing effect.<br />

The characteristic of cause influences the characteristic of the effect.<br />

That concept cannot be denied by the Sarv¡stiv¡din. If it is still<br />

maintained to be the cause, then one has to accept that existence<br />

comes out of non-existence. For example, the cloth is produced by<br />

the non-existent yarns. Otherwise, one can think that clay can<br />

188


produce the cloth. The doctrine of momentariness would go against<br />

the principle that the effect is the cause in a new form. This principle<br />

shows that the cause existed in the effect, which means that the<br />

process of the causation is not momentary 24 .<br />

According áa´kara, on account of the momentariness of things<br />

‘origination and destruction’’ will be synonymous. A momentary<br />

entity as a product must go through the state of origination,<br />

existence and destruction. So, every entity must have a life span of at<br />

least three moments. áa´kara examines that three alternatives for<br />

explaining the origination and cessation. 1. Svar£pa (entity exists in<br />

its own form). 2. Avst¡ntara (entry existed in another state). 3.<br />

189


Vastv¡ntara (production of an altogether different thing) 25 . The<br />

Abhidharmako¿a also presents the concept of origination and<br />

cessation constitute by the Sarv¡stiv¡dins, through three alternatives,<br />

i.e., a thing in its own form (svar£pa), another state (avast¡ntara)<br />

and altogether different thing (vastv¡ntara) as the characteristics of<br />

dharma 26 .<br />

These alternatives pointed out by áa´kara cannot be<br />

applied logically to the Sarv¡stiv¡dins doctrine. áa´kara says that<br />

according to the first view, the origination and destruction constitute<br />

the own-formation of a given thing. So the origination and<br />

destruction are equivalent to thing itself. According to the second<br />

view, áa´kara’s position that the origination and cessation represent<br />

190


the initial and final stages of the given thing which presuppose an<br />

intermediate stage. Then the given thing will have relation with the<br />

three moments and is no longer momentary. Therefore the<br />

Sarv¡stiv¡da concept is trespassed. According to the last view, the<br />

given thing is altogether disconnected from origination and<br />

destruction. So , it must be regarded as everlasting. Therefore, the<br />

Sarv¡stiv¡da concept is refuted by áa´kara’.<br />

Some Sarv¡stiv¡dins says that the origination and cessation of<br />

a given thing signify merely the perception and non-perception. It is<br />

in opposition to the Sautr¡ntika concept. The Sarv¡stiv¡dins say that<br />

191


“there is no pram¡¸a for the cessation and origination of a given<br />

thing” 27 .<br />

áa´kara refutes this concept and says that if our perception<br />

and non-perception of a given thing constitute the birth and<br />

cessation, one will have to say that these are the characteristics of a<br />

seer, not the characteristic of a given thing. So áa´kara thoroughly<br />

says that the ultimate nature of a given thing is permanent and it is<br />

not momentary 28 .<br />

According to the Sarv¡stiv¡da concept, cause and effect exist<br />

simultaneously at the next moment. That means the cause lasts for<br />

192


more than one moment. This opinion is against the Sarv¡stiv¡da<br />

theory of momentariness .<br />

áa´kara cannot accept the theory of momen-tariness, because<br />

his Advaita principle of eternal entity is contradictory to it. That is<br />

why áa´kara refuted the concept of Sarv¡stiv¡da emphatically.<br />

Refutation of Vaibh¡Àika theory of Destruction<br />

áa´kara criticizes the Vaibh¡Àikas view that the<br />

pratisamkhy¡nirodha, apratisamkhy¡nirodha and ¡k¡¿a are<br />

indefinable, non-placeable and external. áa´kara regards these as<br />

definable, placeable and external. The pratis¡mkhya-nirodha is<br />

193


concerned with the momentary existence of dharm¡-s and is<br />

admitted to have a cause, e.g., when a jar is broken by a man with a<br />

stick. The apratisamkhy¡nirodha is concerned with the cessation of<br />

an entity, e.g., natural decay of things 29 .<br />

The famous Buddhist thinker Vasubandhu defines<br />

pratisamkhy¡nirodha as the cessation of the Sa¿ravadharmas by<br />

means of transcendental knowledge. Yamakami Sogen pointed out<br />

that this is the summon bonum of the Sarv¡stiv¡din who considers it<br />

to be synonymous with nirvana also, the Vijjµ¡nav¡dins consider it<br />

merely as a stage leading to nirv¡¸a 30 .<br />

194


Vasubandhu defines the apratisamkhy¡nirodha as a complete<br />

cessation of the mixing of elements (dharm¡-s) due to the<br />

unavailability of the required conditions 31 .<br />

The famous Buddhist logician Vasubandhu asserts that “the<br />

destruction of existent things is without any cause (¡kasmik¡hetuka);<br />

Because a produced thing has its causes but destruction is only the<br />

negation of existence and hence nothing can be done of that which<br />

itself is non-existent 32 ”.<br />

The Vaibh¡Àik¡-s think that the pratis¡mkhya-nirodha,<br />

apratis¡mkhya nirodh and ¡k¡¿ are non-placeable insubstantial<br />

and indefinable. The destruction proceeded by the mind of entities is<br />

195


known a cessation with understanding. The destruction preceded by<br />

without the mind if entity is known as the apratisamkhy¡nirodha.<br />

The absence of hindrance is known as ¡k¡¿a 33 .<br />

According to áa´kara these two kinds of destruction do not<br />

happen because the series of dependently originated dharm¡-s<br />

cannot be broken, the nid¡n¡s are related to each other as cause and<br />

effect. The nid¡n¡s of dependently originated dharmas must be<br />

inseparably connected with its previous states. So the indefinable<br />

destruction is not possible.<br />

áa´kara argues that these two kinds of destruction cannot be<br />

found in the individual members of the series. In the momentary<br />

196


existence of each member, there is no conscious destruction. It is not<br />

an unconscious destruction also, because the individual member is<br />

not altogether destroyed, e.g., When a pot is destroyed we find the<br />

existence of clay. On account of the heat, the drop of water<br />

disappears and we see it existing in the other form like steam. In<br />

Bauddha concept of vin¡¿a, there is nothing related to any other<br />

form or other substance 34 . So their concept is not accepted by<br />

áa´kara.<br />

In the words of Yamakami Sogen, áa´kara has mistaken in<br />

representing the said two nirodh¡s . áa´kara critically says that the<br />

two kinds of destruction are either the result of perfect knowledge or<br />

197


of the meaninglessness of the path. Thus, both concepts are not<br />

accepted by áa´kara. If we accept the first idea it is against the<br />

Bauddha principle of causeless destruction. If we accept the later<br />

concept, there is the cause of the meaningless of the path. Thus, both<br />

concepts are rejected by áa´kara.<br />

Refutation of the concept of Ëk¡¿a<br />

According to the Buddhist philosophy, pratisamkhy¡-nirodha<br />

and apratisamkhy¡nirodha are indefinable. Refutation of these have<br />

already been described earlier. Then he takes the third entity Ëk¡¿a.<br />

According to the Buddhistic view the Ëk¡¿a is also indefinable. The<br />

indefinability of Ëk¡¿a is refuted<br />

198


y áa´kara in Brahmas£trabh¡Àya 35 . According to Abhidharmako¿a,<br />

the Sarv¡stiv¡dins define ¡k¡¿a as that having for its<br />

measure the absence of tangible .<br />

According to Sarv¡stiv¡dins there are two kinds of ¡k¡¿a: (1)<br />

unconstructed dharma (2) the space as element. The space element<br />

included within the sense base of the visible. Ëk¡¿a as unconstructed<br />

dharma has for its nature non-hindrance .<br />

In áa´kara’s words, like the pratisamkhy¡nirodha and<br />

apratisamkhy¡- nirodha, the ¡k¡¿a is also a given thing. From verse,<br />

¡tman¡h ¡k¡¿a sambh£tah 36 we know that ¡k¡¿a is a substance. As<br />

the Bauddha do not accept the áruti as a pram¡¸a, the anum¡na is<br />

199


also be adopted to prove the substantiality of ¡k¡¿a. Ëk¡¿a is similar<br />

to earth, air, etc. They are recognized to be entities in consequence of<br />

their being the substratum of properties like smell, cold etc, similarly<br />

the ¡k¡¿a, it being the substratum of sound, ought to be recognized<br />

as an entity 37 . Therefore áa´kara refuted the Bauddha concept by<br />

saying that ¡k¡¿a should be definable.<br />

áa´kara refutes the Sarv¡stiv¡da definition of ¡k¡¿a i.e., ¡k¡¿a as the<br />

absence of material flow without hindrance (sapratigha<br />

dravyabh¡vam¡tra). He presents the example of the flying of the<br />

birds in the sky. When a bird flies in ¡k¡¿a, there is the presence of<br />

200


obstruction, hence another bird that may try to fly will find no scope<br />

for doing so. In<br />

this case, anything with the help of which the absence of obstruction,<br />

is specified will itself be the possible entity - ¡k¡¿a, and it will not be<br />

mere absence of hindrance 38 . In the series of question referred to<br />

Baudha dar¿ana, there is a question of “what is the basis of earth”.<br />

They say that the wind is the basis of earth. The next question is,<br />

“what is the basis of wind”. Their answer is the ¡k¡¿a is the basis of<br />

wind. From this we get the conclusion that if ¡k¡¿a is not a given<br />

201


thing the above answer is not correct. Therefore ¡k¡¿a must be an<br />

entity 39 .<br />

Refutation of the origination of object entity from absence<br />

According to áa´kara, the Sautr¡ntikas notion that birth as existence<br />

subsequent to non-existence (abh£tva bh¡vutpada) is questionable.<br />

Their idea is not accepted by áa´kara. Because they do not accept the<br />

permanent and eternal cause of a given thing, but they argue that an<br />

entity<br />

is derived from non-existence. For example, they say that, from the<br />

destruction of a seed a sprout is formed. Like, when the milk is<br />

202


destroyed, the curd is formed, from the lump of a clay a pot is<br />

formed. So the Sautr¡ntikas say that from the absence the entity is<br />

formed.<br />

áa´kara argues against their concept. He says that if a thing<br />

can arise out of absence, then anything can arise out of anything.<br />

áa´kara says that if this theory was true, then no one would have to<br />

exert himself to attain any end, since ends could be attain without<br />

means. If the nirv¡¸a is born from absence there would be the<br />

perfection of the lazy people also because the attainment of absence<br />

is very easy. Therefore áa´kara thoroughly refutes the view that there<br />

should be no evidence to prove that the entity is born from absence.<br />

203


Refutation of Vijµ¡nav¡da<br />

Vijµ¡nav¡da<br />

The Vijµ¡nav¡dins argue for the non-existence of external<br />

objects. In Brahs£tra¿a´karabh¡Àya, áa´kara has presented five<br />

arguments put forward by Vijµ¡nv¡dins to prove the non-existence of<br />

external objects (1) If external objects exist, they are either atoms or<br />

aggregates of atoms. But they can be neither and are therefore nonexistent.<br />

(2) Even those who admit the existence of external objects,<br />

admit different forms of their cognitions. But if forms of cognitions<br />

are admitted, they suffice for the practical purpose of our life, and<br />

204


the existence of external objects becomes unnecessary. (3) Objects<br />

and their cognitions are invariably perceived together. Therefore they<br />

are identical with each other. (4) Waking cognitions apprehend<br />

themselves like dream cognitions. Both are similar to each other.<br />

Both are not produced by external<br />

objects . (5) The variety of pratyayavaicitra is due to the variety of<br />

v¡san¡- vaicitra. These arguments are refuted by áa´kara.<br />

Refutation of self-intuition.<br />

The concept of self intuition of Buddhists is connected with<br />

the non separation of three factors that is subject, object and self<br />

205


intuition. In Pram¡¸a samuccaya, Dinn¡ga proves that these three<br />

factors are inseparable.<br />

According to the concept of the Vijµ¡nav¡dins the jµeya is not<br />

different from jµ¡na. The famous Vijµ¡nav¡di Dharmak¢rti says that<br />

when we see a blue lotus, the blue and cognition of blue are not<br />

different entities. One should recognize their difference as due to the<br />

false cognition. Like the astigmatic seeing the double moon, but the<br />

moon is single.<br />

áa´kara in his commentary on the Brahmas£tra “nabh¡va<br />

upalabdeÅ” 40<br />

tries to deny the dependent object entity of<br />

Vijµ¡nav¡da. He puts forward the five types of the p£rvapakÀins . (1)<br />

206


According to áa´kara the Vijµ¡nav¡dins note that the object entity is<br />

composed of atoms. It is untenable. If object entities are different<br />

from atoms, they can no longer be said to consist of atoms. He<br />

continually says that if they are identical with atoms they cannot be<br />

aggregates. For example, about the objects like posts, there will not<br />

be the notion of atoms etc. There is no collection of atoms such as<br />

posts, etc because of the impossibility of ascertaining the posts etc.,<br />

by means of otherness or non-otherness from atoms.<br />

(2) The Vijµ¡nav¡dins argue that the variety of cognition is<br />

explained only by the variety of sense object. Therefore, the sense<br />

object have a formation similar to their cognitions.<br />

207


(3) In áa´kara’s words, the Vijµ¡nav¡dins argue that the<br />

ascertainment of sense - object and perception are identical.<br />

(4) According to áa´kara Vijµ¡nav¡dins say that consciousness<br />

is to be considered as similar to a dream. The images occur in a<br />

dream without the presence of corresponding object entities.<br />

Likewise in the waking stage also the images occur without the<br />

eternal object entities. For example, the concepts of gandharva<br />

nagara, marumar¢cika, magic, etc, are only the imaginary subject<br />

and object, there is no eternal reality.<br />

(5) According to áa´kara, the Vijµ¡nav¡dins say that the variety of<br />

concepts can be explained by the presense of v¡sana 41 .<br />

208


These are the five arguments put forward by áa´kara for refuting<br />

the Vijµ¡nav¡din’s concept. It is very interesting to examine the<br />

refutational attempts of áa´kara against the Vijµ¡nav¡dins as a<br />

revelation of his own philosophical concept. According to áa´kara<br />

there is an external object on the ground of perception itself. There<br />

is no absence because of perception. The absence indeed of an<br />

outer object entity cannot be ascertained. The outer object entity is<br />

perceived in accordance with the notion as post, wall , pot, cloth,<br />

likewise . The absence of a thing being perceived is not possible.<br />

Refutation of Antarjµeyar£pa as the object entity<br />

209


áa´kara criticizes the famous Vijµ¡nav¡din, Dinn¡ga’s concept<br />

antarjjµeyar£pa as the object entity. He takes a verse from<br />

Dinn¡ga’s Ëlambanapar¢kÀa which defines the object entity as the<br />

inner form of knowledge which appears though it were external;<br />

“yatantarjµeyar£pan tu bahirvad avabh¡sate 42 .<br />

áa´kara raises his objection against the Vijµ¡v¡dins<br />

saying that their usage “bahirvad” betrays their acceptance of the<br />

external object-entity. “The external thing is well known to the<br />

whole world, then why do you apply the affix vat is (as if) . How<br />

should you say the affix ‘vat’ as external to objects 43 ”. áa´kara<br />

asks.<br />

210


áa´kara employs his argument for identity of objective reference<br />

against the Vijµ¡nav¡dins. According to his principle, x is y, not x is<br />

like y. This is a post, this is a wall , these type of knowledges are<br />

produced by the people for the worldly existence of the sense-objects<br />

of perception. áa´kara says that people say that “this is a cow, not an<br />

animal like cow”. If the Bauddha argues the object -entity is bahirvat<br />

(like external), on the ground of the impossibility of external things,<br />

áa´kara answers to it that the possibility or impossibility of the<br />

things is to be determined on the basis of pram¡¸a 44 .<br />

Then the Vijµ¡nav¡din says that the sense-objects correspond<br />

to our cognitions 45 . So there is no necessity of sense-object. áa´kara<br />

211


efutes the point by saying if there is no sense-object, there is no<br />

cognition also.<br />

Refutation of the theory that object entity and cognition are the<br />

same.<br />

The Vijµ¡nav¡din views that the simultaneity of notion and<br />

sense object are identical. For example, blue and the notion of blue<br />

occur simultaneously. áa´kara replies that the simultaneous<br />

experience of notion and sense-object proves only that sense-object<br />

constitutes the means to the notion.<br />

áa´kara argues that there is a distinction between sense object<br />

and its notion on the basis of the difference between vi¿eÀa¸a and<br />

212


vi¿eÀya 46 . He presents, cognition of a pot, a cloth and a jar etc as<br />

example. In connection with a white cow and a black cow, the<br />

difference lies in between whiteness and blackness. It is not based<br />

on cowness 47 . So áa´kara says that the object entity and cognition<br />

are different.<br />

Refutation of Svasamvedana PratyakÀa<br />

áa´kara refutes the Vijµ¡nav¡da concept of svasamvedana<br />

pratyakÀa Dharmak¢rti defined svasamvedana pratyakÀa as selfapprehension<br />

of every cognition and every mental phenomenon 48 .<br />

213


According to áa´kara, the Bauddha concept is that each cognition<br />

is of essential self-illuminating nature like lamp. The presence of<br />

perception indicates the presence of an external object-entity on<br />

the grounds that it is not of a luminous nature like a lamb, as is<br />

the perception 49 . The perception is not experienced for itself apart<br />

from the object-entity because of the contradictoriness of activity in<br />

itself .<br />

áa´kara says that according to the Vijµ¡v¡dins concept, the<br />

perceptions are self-luminous and they do not need to be<br />

apprehended by a witness apart from themselves. The two<br />

arguments given by the Vijµ¡nav¡dins to explain their concept are<br />

214


the following. (1) the danger of infinite regression is there that an<br />

apprehending agent would again in turn require an apprehending<br />

agent. (2) The concept of perceptions, like lamp etc, have light as<br />

their nature 50 .<br />

áa´kara explains that the witnessing self is of the nature of the<br />

knowing subject and consequently it does not need to be<br />

apprehended from the point of view of infinite regression. So we<br />

can know the diversity of the self – existence of the witness and the<br />

notion 51 .<br />

To the second argument áa´kara replies that the perceptions are<br />

self luminous like the lamp. A conscious agent does not involve in<br />

215


infinite regression. There he proceeds to affirm the necessity of a<br />

conscious agent. Such notions are like existence of thousand lamps<br />

situated in the middle of a dense cave 52 .<br />

According to áa´kara, an interior conscious agent is needed<br />

for the perception to be manifest. According to him the concept of<br />

the Ved¡ntins are differ from the Vijµ¡nav¡dins because the first<br />

phase of the perception involves the association of the eye with the<br />

lamp 53 .<br />

áa´kara points out that self is one and permanent and<br />

eternal. But the perceptions acknowledged by Buddhist are<br />

momentary and fleeting 54 .<br />

216


áa´kara considers the Vijµ¡nav¡din’s argument of infinite<br />

regression as directed against the notion of the self. They say that if<br />

perception was to be apprehended by another. Then it causes other<br />

perception and so on 55 . So there arises the problem of anavasth¡<br />

áa´kara refutes this point by saying that the witnessing<br />

self (perceiver) and the viÀaya (perceived) both are of different<br />

natures related to each other i.e., perceiver and perceived. So their<br />

result of their association does not cause the infinite regression 56 .<br />

There fore the Bauddha theory of consciousness is not acceptable to<br />

Advaita Ved¡nta because no one can say that Devadatta is the son<br />

of a barren woman. In áa´kara’s words we get the conclusion that<br />

217


the very nature of consciousness itself proves the existence of<br />

external things different from consciousness 57 . So the perception<br />

is self manifested.<br />

Refutation of the theory that all worldly cognitions are unreal like<br />

dream<br />

The Vijµ¡nav¡dins declared that the waking stage and dream<br />

stage are similar in so far as they deny the external objects. But<br />

áa´kara raises the question that if the dream state and walking<br />

state are alike, how does direct perception happen.<br />

On account of momentariness, the mental perception does<br />

not operate at the same time as sensory perception but in a moment<br />

218


afterwards. There is a question whether the mental perception has<br />

the same object in the sensory perception. Dinn¡ga says that the<br />

external object is not being denied here, but the external object of<br />

which our representation is a faithful copy is being denied. This<br />

means that the form of the inner knowable which appears as if it<br />

were external, is the object 58 . This is denied by the Vijµ¡nav¡dins.<br />

According to the Vijµ¡nav¡dins, the differences between<br />

waking state and dream state can be compared to the difference<br />

between upalabdhi (perception) and sm¤ti (remembrance). Both the<br />

mental perception and remembrance occur subsequent to the fading<br />

out of sensory perception.<br />

219


áa´kara refutes the above concept of Vijµ¡nav¡dins in the<br />

following way- how can similarity of the waking state and dream<br />

state be established . He puts forward two arguments to refute<br />

their concept. The contents of the dream state are negated by the<br />

waking state. But the contents of waking state is not negated by<br />

anything and any where 59 . This is the difference between perception<br />

and the waking state 60 .<br />

áa´kara says that the Vijµ¡nav¡da argument is not correct.<br />

Perception means the direct perception of an object. For example, a<br />

father beholds his son rather than merely remembers him 61 .<br />

220


According to áa´kara, the analogy of the dream only<br />

emphasizes the temporal gap that exists between sensory perception<br />

which is subsequent to the former. áa´kara concludes that the dream<br />

state is a kind of memory and the waking state is real perception of<br />

object entity.<br />

Refutation of the concept of v¡sana<br />

The Vijµ¡nav¡dins explain knowledge on the basis of habitual<br />

(v¡sana)<br />

energies without any reference to external object. The<br />

221


concept of habitual energy is closely connected whith ¡layavijµ¡na.<br />

The notions of ¡layavijµ¡na and v¡sana are primarily associated with<br />

karma and phala.<br />

According to Mah¡y¡nasamgraha the v¡sana means the<br />

generative cause of things by virtue of their simultaneous birth and<br />

destruction 62<br />

. The ¡layavijµ¡na and v¡sana are intended by the<br />

Vijµ¡nav¡dins to replace the external object. These ideas are intended<br />

by the Vijµ¡nav¡dins to explicate the process of action and<br />

destruction.<br />

áa´kara says that the Vijµ¡nav¡din’s concept of v¡sana should<br />

be refuted because v¡sana could not originate. If there is no external<br />

222


object entity. The v¡sana is formed by the perception of external<br />

thing 63 .<br />

The Vijµ¡nav¡dins say that the objects are not perceived externally<br />

because it is precisely owing to the perception of objects that a variety<br />

of v¡sana (mental tendencies) corresponding to the diverse objects<br />

can arise. áa´kara refuted this concept of the Vijµ¡nav¡dins by asking<br />

how a variety of tendencies can arise when no object is perceived. If<br />

these tendencies have no beginning, this infinite regression will<br />

amount to a baseless assumption like the blind leading the blind.<br />

223


According to áa´kara, the object entity is external to the mind.<br />

For the establishment of his concepts he puts forward two<br />

arguments: (1) the v¡sana cannot originate independently of the<br />

perception of external -object-entity (2) The perception of externalobject-entities<br />

can take place without the v¡sana 64 .<br />

More over, he says that the v¡sana is a kind of qualification<br />

which requires a basis. But the Vijµ¡nav¡dins deny such a basis.<br />

There fore áa´kara says that there is no birth of v¡sana without the<br />

224


perception of the object-entity 65 . He negates their concept, i.e., the<br />

v¡sana is associated which the notions of action and effect.<br />

á£nyav¡da<br />

á£nyav¡da of the Bauddhas goes counter to everything. It goes<br />

against the áruti, Sm¤ti and every other means of right knowledge.<br />

So áa´kara refuted the whole concepts of á£nyav¡da by the help of<br />

áruti, sm¤ti and yukti 66 . áa´kara dismisses the á£nyav¡da saying<br />

that system is more contradicted.<br />

Resume<br />

In the refutation of Bauddha concepts áa´kara gave more<br />

importance to yukti. Through the refutation, áa´kara<br />

225


did not distinguish between Sarv¡stiv¡da and Sautr¡ntika schools.<br />

áa´kara dismisses the á£nyav¡da by saying that the system is<br />

contradicted by Sm¤ti, Yukti and áruti.<br />

áa´kara abandoned the<br />

main principle of Bauddha (kÀa¸ikav¡da) saying that the cause<br />

lasts for more than one moment.<br />

226


NOTES AND REFERENCE<br />

1 kecit sarv¡stiv¡dinaÅ, BSSB. 2. 2. 4. 18 tadastivad¡¿iÀt¡Å yehi sarva<br />

mast¢ti vadanti at¢taman-¡gatam praty¡tpannam sarv¡stivad¡Å (A.<br />

K. and A. K. bh¡Àya v 25)<br />

2 kecitvijµ¡stivam¡travav¡din¡Å, BSSB. 2.2.4.18<br />

227


3 kecit sarva¿£nyatva v¡dinaÅ, BSSB.2.2.4.18<br />

4 Nataliya Isayeva, Sankara and Indian Philosophy.pp.146 - 147<br />

5 prat¢tyasamulp¡dopade¿apradh¡namidambhagavataÅ<br />

pravacanaratnam. T.P.p. 13.<br />

6 Dr. Vijaya Rani, Buddist Philosophy presented in m¢m¡-msa¿loka<br />

v¡r -tika. p. 110. IV<br />

7 samud¡ya ubhayahetukepi tadapr¡ptiÅ, B.S.2.2.4.18<br />

8 Yoyamubhayahetuka ubhayaprakaraÅ samud¡yaÅ pare-À¡mabhi<br />

preto¸uhetuka¿ca bh£tabhautikasamhatir£paÅ skandahetuka¿ca<br />

paµcaskandh¢r£paÅ tasminnubhayah-etukepi samud¡yeabhi<br />

preyam¡ne tadapr¡ptiÅ sy¡tsa-mud¡yapraptiÅ. BSSB.2.2.4.18.<br />

228


9<br />

bh£tam bhautikam bahyam cittam ca kamadhyantaramiti<br />

vibh¡gaÅ, Ibid.<br />

10<br />

tatha r£pavijµ¡na vedana samjµ¡ samsk¡rasamjµak¡Å<br />

paµcaskand¡Å, Ibid.<br />

11 Yoyamubhayahetuka ubhayaprak¡raÅ samudayaÅ pare-<br />

À¡mabhipreto¸uhetuka¿ca bh£tabhautika samhatir£paÅ<br />

skandhahetuka¿ca paµc-askandh¢r£paÅ tasminnubha ya he<br />

tukepi samudaye abhipreyam¡ne tadapr¡ptiÅ sy¡-<br />

dsamud¡yapr¡ptiÅ, Ibid.<br />

229


12 anyasya ca kasyacicetanasya bhoktuÅ pra¿¡siturva sthi-rasya<br />

samhanturanabhyupagam¡t nirapekÀaprav¤tyabh-yupagame ca<br />

prav¤tyanuparamaprasa´g¡t, Ibid.<br />

13 Dr. Vijaya Rani, Buddhist philosophy presented in M¢m¡msa¿loka<br />

v¡rtika. p.110. IV<br />

14 heturatra samutp¡daÅ samutpannam phalam matam.<br />

hetubh£tama´gam prat¢tyasamutp¡daÅ samutpadhyate<br />

samad¢tik¤tva phalabh£tama´gam prat¢tyasamutpann-am.<br />

evam sarv¡¸yang¡nyubhayath¡siddhyati. hetubha-lavat na caivam<br />

satyavyavasth¡ bhavantyapekÀabhed¡t. yadapekÀya<br />

230


prat¢tyasamutpado na tadevapekÀya prat¢-tyasamutpannam<br />

hetubhalavat pit¤putravacca, A.K. III.28.<br />

15 tec¡vidy¡dayovidy¡ samskaro vijµ¡nam, n¡ma r£pam Àa·¡yatanam<br />

spar¿o vedan¡ t¤À¸¡, up¡d¡nam, bhavo, j¡tirjar¡, mara¸am, ¿okaÅ,<br />

parivedana, dukham, durm-anastetyevamjat¢yaka<br />

itaretarahetukaÅ saugate samaye kvacitsamkÀipta nirdistaÅ<br />

kvacitprapaµcit¡Å, BSSB. 2.2.4.19.<br />

16 B.S.2.2.4.19<br />

17 atha manyase samgh¡ta ev¡nadau sams¡re samtaty¡n-urvartante<br />

tad¡¿ray¡¿raya¿cavidhy¡daya iti, tadapi samgh¡t¡tsamgh¡t¡ntaramul-padhyam¡nam,<br />

niyamena va<br />

231


s¡d¤¿amevolpadhyate, aniyamena v¡ sad¤¿am visa-d¤¿am<br />

volpadhyeta. BSSB.2.2.4.19<br />

18 B.S. 2.2.4.20<br />

19 kÀa¸abha´gav¡dinoyamabhyupagama uttaransmin-kÀa¸a<br />

ulpadhyam¡ne p£rvaÅ kÀa¸o nirudhyata iti. BSSB.2.2.4.20.<br />

20 uttarottara kÀa¸¡nubandhaÅ sthitiriti p£rvasya kÀa¸a-syottaraÅ<br />

kÀa¸aÅ. pratinidhibh£taÅ s¡d¤¿yatataÅ sa<br />

p£rvaÅkÀa¸¡dyapyavatiÀata, iveti k¤tvottaraÅ kÀa¸aÅ<br />

sthitirucyate. A.K.II.46.<br />

21 nirudham¡nasya niruddhasya v¡ p£rvakÀa¸asy¡bh¡vagrastatv¡duttarakÀa¸ahetutv¡nupapatteÅ.<br />

atha bh¡va-bh£taÅ<br />

232


pariniÀpann¡vasthaÅ p£rvakÀa¸a uttarakÀa¸asya<br />

heturityabhipr¡yastath¡pi nopapadhyate. bh¡vabh£ta-sya<br />

punarvy¡p¡rakalpan¡y¡m kÀa¸¡ntarasambandha-prasa´g¡t.<br />

BSSB.2.2.4.20.<br />

22 bh¡vasya vy¡p¡raÅ ityabhipr¡yasthat¡pi naivopapa-tyate. BSSB. 2.2.<br />

4.20.<br />

23 bh¡vabh£tasya punarvy¡p¡rakalpan¡y¡m kÀa¸¡ntarasambhandhaprasa´g¡t.<br />

Ibid.<br />

24 evamapy¡dhyantamadhyakÀa¸atrayasambandhitv¡tva-stunaÅ<br />

kÀa¸ikatv¡bhyu pagamahaniÅ atathatyantavyatirikt¡vevolp¡danirodhau<br />

vastunaÅ sy¡t¡ma¿vamahiÀa-vad, tato<br />

233


vastu ulp¡danirodh¡bhy¡msams¤Àamiti vas-tunaÅ ¿¡¿vatatva<br />

prasa´gaÅ. Ibid.<br />

25 apicolpadanirodau n¡ma vastunaÅ svar£pameva v¡ sy¡-<br />

t¡mavasth¡ntaram v¡ vastvantarameva v¡ sarvath¡pi<br />

nopapadhyate. Ibid.<br />

26 lakÀa¸¡nipunajanijar¡sthitiranityat¡ etani hi samsk¤tasya catv¡ri<br />

lakÀa¸¡ni yatrait¡nibhavantis¡dharmaÅsamskar-t¡lakÀyate<br />

viparyayadasamsk¤taÅ tatraj¡stust¡ndharm¡-mjanasthitiÅ<br />

sth¡payati jar¡ jarayati anityat¡ vina¿yati. A.K.11.45,46.<br />

27 taded¡k¡¿am pa¿yata iti sautr¡ntik¡Å na hyete j¡tyad-ayo dharma<br />

dravyataÅ samvidhyante yath¡bhivyaµjate kim k¡ra¸am<br />

234


pram¡¸¡bh¡v¡t. nahyeÀ¡m dravyato-stitvekiÆcidapi pram¡¸amasti<br />

pratyakÀ¡num¡nam¡pt¡-gama v¡ yath¡ r£p¡d¢n¡m dharm¡¸¡miti.<br />

A.K .II .46<br />

28 yadi ca dar¿an¡dar¿ne vastuna ulpadanirodausy¡t¡m evamapi<br />

d¤t-À¤dharmo tau na vastudharm¡viti vastunaÅ ¿¡¿vatatva<br />

prasa´ga eva. BSSB 2.2.4.20.<br />

29 dvividho hi vin¡¿a siddheÅ pratiÀedha lakÀa¸aÅ tath¡-<br />

hikÀa¸¡didharm¡ bh¡va eva k¡le vina¿yat¢ti k¤tv¡ vin¡-¿a<br />

ity¡khy¡yate yadv¡ bh¡va svabh¡va pracyutilakÀa¸a<br />

pradhvams¡paran¡ma vin¡¿¡n¡m vina¿atitatra p£rva-sminn¡¿e<br />

235


yadyayam hetumatvas¡dhana pary¡nuyogaÅ kriyate<br />

yathoktairhetubhiÅ tath¡ siddas¡dhyat¡. T.P. pp. 373-374.<br />

30 Yamakami Sogen, Systems of Buddhist Thought, p.1.6<br />

31 ulp¡datyanta vighno nirodhoapratisamkhyay¡. A.K.1.6<br />

32 ¡kasamiko hi bhav¡n¡m vin¡¿aÅ. kim k¡ra¸am k¡ry-asya hi k¡ra¸am<br />

bhaati, vin¡¿a¿c¡bh¡vaÅ. ya¿c¡bh¡-vasya kim karthavyam. A.K.<br />

bhasyam. p.569<br />

33 api ca vain¡¿ik¡Å kalpayanti buddhibodhyam tray¡danyatsamsk¤tam<br />

kÀa¸ikam ceti. tadapi ca trayam pratisaÆkhy¡pratisaÆkhy¡nirodh¡vak¡¿am<br />

cety¡cakÀate tra-yamapi<br />

caitadvastv¡bh¡vam¡tram nir£p£khyamiti man-yante<br />

236


uddhip£rvakaÅ kila vin¡¿o bh¡v¡n¡m pratisaÆ-khy¡nirodho<br />

n¡ma bh¡Àyate, tadvipar¢to apratisaÆkhy¡ nirodhaÅ. BSSB.<br />

2.2.4.22<br />

34 n¡pi bh¡vatgocarau sambhavataÅ nahi bh¡v¡n¡m nira-nvayo<br />

nir£p¡khyo vin¡¿aÅ sambhavati, sarv¡svapyav-asth¡su<br />

pratyabhijµ¡balen-¡nvay¡vaccedadar¿an¡t. Ibid.<br />

35<br />

¡k¡¿asyed¡n¢m nir¡kriyate. ¡k¡¿e c¡yukto nir£pakhyatv¡bhyupagamaÅ.<br />

BSSB. 2.2.4.24.<br />

36 Tai. Up. 2.1<br />

37 “¿abdagu¸akam¡k¡¿am”. T.S. p. 13.<br />

237


38 api c¡vara¸¡bh¡vam¡tram¡k¡¿amiccatamekasminsu-par¸e<br />

pataty¡vara¸asya. vidhyam¡natv¡tsupar¸¡ntarasyolpittisatonavakasatvaprasa´gaÅ<br />

yatr¡vara¸¡bh¡vas-tatra<br />

patiÀyat¢ticet. yen¡vara¸¡bh¡ve vi¿eÀyate tattarhi<br />

vastubh£tamev¡k¡¿amsy¡t, n¡vara¸¡ bh¡vam¡tram. BSSB.2.2.4.24<br />

39 saugate hi samaye p¤thvi bhagavaÅ kim samni¿rayaÅ ity-asmin<br />

prativacanaprav¡he ‘p¤thvy¡d¢namante’ ‘v¡yuÅ kim<br />

samni¿rayaÅ’ ity¡sya pra¿nasya prativacanam bha-vati<br />

‘v¡yur¡k¡¿a samni¿rayaÅ’ iti. tad¡k¡¿asy¡vastutve na samaµjasam<br />

sy¡t tasm¡dayuktam ¡k¡¿asyavastut-vam. Ibid.<br />

40 B.S. 2.2.4.20<br />

238


41 svapn¡divadccedam d¤Àtavyam. yath¡hi svapnam¡y¡-<br />

mar¢cyudukagandharvanagar¡di pratyaya vinaiva bahyen¡rthena<br />

gr¡hyagr¡hak¡kara bhavanti, evam j¡garita-gocara api<br />

stambh¡dipratyayam bhavitumarhant¢tyava-gamyate<br />

pratyayavi¿eÀ¡t.BSSB. 2.2.5.28<br />

42 Hattori Masaki, Dinn¡ga on perception. p.107<br />

43 atascaivameva sarve laukik¡ upalabhante yatpraty¡ca-kÀa¸am api<br />

b¡hy¡rthameva vy¡cakÀate yadantarjµeya-r£pam<br />

tadbahirvadavabh¡sata iti. tepi sarvalokaprasi-ddhameva<br />

bahiravabh¡sam¡nam samvidam pratilabh¡-m¡naÅ<br />

239


praty¡khy¡tuk¡maÀca b¡hyamartham bahirvaditi vatk¡ram<br />

kurvanti. itaretara hi kasm¡dbahirvaditi br£yuÅ BSSB. 2.2.5.28<br />

44 nanu bahyasy¡rthasyasambhav¡t bahirvadavabh¡sata<br />

ityadhyavasitam n¡yam s¡dhuradhyavasayo ataÅ pram-<br />

¡¸aprav¤tyaprav¤ttip£rvakau sambhav¡sambhav¡vadh-¡ryate na<br />

punaÅ sambhav¡sambhavap£rvike pram¡¸a-prav¤ttyaprav¤ttiÅ.<br />

Ibid.<br />

45 na ca jµ¡nasya viÀayas¡r£payadviÀayan¡¿o bhavati, asati viÀaye<br />

viÀayas¡r£py¡nupapatteÅ, bahirupalab-de¿ca Ibid.<br />

240


46 ata eva sahopalmabhaniyamopi pratyayaviÀayayorup¡-<br />

yopeyabh¡vahetuka n¡ bhedahetuka ityabhyupagana-tanvyam.<br />

Ibid.<br />

47 api ca khaajµ¡nam paajµ¡namiti vi¿eÀa¸ayoreva kha-<br />

apaayorabhedo na vi¿eÀasy¡sya jµ¡nasya. yath¡ ¿uklo gauÅ<br />

k¤À¸o gauriti ¿auklaka¤À¸ayoreva bhedo na gotv-asya. dv¡bhy¡m<br />

ca bhed¡dev¡sya siddhobhavatyeka-smacca dvayoÅ.<br />

tasm¡darthajµ¡nayorbhedaÅ. Ibid.<br />

48<br />

sarvacittacaitt¡n¡m¡tmasamvedanam. Nyaya Bindu. 1.10<br />

49<br />

b¡hyopyarthoanubhayata eveti yuktamabhyupagantum. atha<br />

vijµ¡nam prak¡¿¡tmakatv¡tprad¢pavatsvayame-v¡nubh£yate na<br />

241


that¡ bahyopyartha iticet, svatmani kriyavirodh¡dev¡. BSSB<br />

2.25.28<br />

50<br />

nanu vijjµ¡nasya svar£pavyatiriktagr¡hyatve tadapya-nyena<br />

gr¡hyam tad¡pyanyenetyanavasth¡ pr¡pnoti. api ca<br />

prad£pavadavabh¡s¡tmakatvatjµ¡neÀa jµ¡n¡-ntarm kalpayataÅ<br />

samtv¡dva¿y¡vabh¡sakabhav¡nupa-patteÅ.<br />

kalpan¡narthakyamiti tadubhayamapyasat. Ibid.<br />

51<br />

vijµ¡namubhayata eva vijµ¡nas¡kÀi¸o graha¸¡d¡na-kÀa¸olp¡d¡d<br />

anavasth¡ ¿a´k¡mupapatteÅ. s¡kÀi prat-yayayo¿ca svabh¡va<br />

vaiÀamy¡dupalabdupalabhy¡bh¡-vopapatteÅ. Ibid.<br />

242


52<br />

kimc¡nyat prad¢pavadvijµ¡namavabh¡sak¡ntaranira-pekÀam<br />

syam-eva prathat iti br£vat¡mcapram¡¸aga-myam<br />

vijµ¡namavagant¤kami-tyuktam sy¡t. ¿il¡khana madhyastha<br />

prad¢pa¿¡ghasahasraprathanavat. Ibid.<br />

53<br />

b¡damevam , anubhav¡rupatvattu vijµ¡nasyesto naÅ<br />

pakÀastv¡yanujµ¡yata iti cet. na anyasy¡avagantu¿ca-kÀuÅ<br />

s¡dhanasya prat¢p-¡diprathana darÀan¡t. atovi-jµ¡nasyaya<br />

avibh¡syatve avi¿eÀ¡tyevanyasminnavaga-ntari prath¡nam<br />

prad¢pavadityvagamyate. Ibid.<br />

243


54<br />

s¡kÀi¸ovagantuÅ svayamsiddhat¡mupakÀipata svayam prathate<br />

vijµ¡namityeÀa mama pakÀastvaya v¡coyukt-yantare¸¡¿rita iti<br />

cet. Ibid.<br />

55<br />

nanu vijµ¡nasya svar£pa vyatirikta gr¡hyatve tad¡py-anyena<br />

gr¡hyam tad¡pyanyena ityanavastha. Ibid.<br />

56<br />

s¡kÀipratyayayo¿ca svabh¡vavaiÀamy¡dupalabdhupalabhyabh¡vopapatteÅ.<br />

Ibid.<br />

57 ataÅ prad¢pavad vijµ¡nasy¡pi vyatirikt¡vagamyatva-masmabhiÅ<br />

pras¡dhitam. Ibid.<br />

58 yat analarjµeya r£pam tu bahirvad avabh¡sate sorthaÅ (quotes<br />

by Hattori Massaki Dinnaga on perception pp. 102 .61)<br />

244


59 b¡dhyate hi svapnopalabdam vastu pratibuddhasya<br />

mayopalabdhomah¡janasam¡gama iti, nahyasti……. naivam<br />

j¡garitopalabdhamvastustambh¡dikam kasya-cidapyavsthayam<br />

b¡dhyate. BSSB. 2.2.5.29<br />

60<br />

api ca sm¤tireÀ¡ yatsvapnadar¿anam upalabdhistu<br />

jagaritadar¿anam Ibid.<br />

61<br />

sm¤tyypalabdlyo¿ca pratyakÀam¡ntaram svayamanu-bh£yate<br />

sarthaviprayoga samprayog¡tmakamiÀam putram smar¡mi<br />

noplabdha up- alabddumicc¡m¢ti. BSSB. 2.2.5.29<br />

62<br />

M.S p. 226.<br />

245


63<br />

anupalabhyam¡neÀu tvartheÀu kimnimitt¡ vicitr¡ v¡s-an¡<br />

bhaveyuÅ an¡ditvepyandhaparampar¡ny¡yen¡prathiÀaiv¡navasth¡.<br />

BSSB. 2.5.30<br />

64<br />

api ca v¡san¡ n¡ma samsk¡ra vi¿eÀaÅ, samsk¡ra¿ca<br />

¡¿rayamantare¸¡ vakalpante evam loke d¤Àatv¡t. na ca tava<br />

v¡san¡¿rayaÅ ka¿cidastim pram¡¸atonupala-bdheÅ. Ibid.<br />

65<br />

sthirasvar£patve tvalayavijµ¡nasya siddh¡ntah¡niÅ api ca<br />

vijµ¡nav¡depi kÀa¸ikatv¡bhyupagamasya sam¡n¡t-vadhy¡ni<br />

b¡hy¡rthav¡de kÀa¸ikatvanibhandhanani du- Àa¸¡nyudbh¡vitani<br />

uttarolpade ca p£rvanirodh¡t itye-vam¡d¢ni<br />

t¡nih¡pyanusamgh¡tavy¡ni. BSSB 2.2.5.31<br />

246


66<br />

¿£nyav¡di pakÀastu sarva pram¡¸a vipratiÀiddha iti<br />

tadnir¡kara¸¡ya n¡daraÅ kriyate. Ibid.<br />

247

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!