16.11.2012 Views

paul-denicola-literature-pure-mediality

paul-denicola-literature-pure-mediality

paul-denicola-literature-pure-mediality

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Literature as Pure Mediality:<br />

Kafka and the Scene of Writing<br />

A Dissertation Submitted to the<br />

Division of Media and Communications<br />

of The European Graduate School<br />

in Candidacy for the Degree of<br />

Doctor of Philosophy<br />

By Paul DeNicola<br />

December 2007


Dissertation defended December 15, 2007<br />

Awarded Magna Cum Laude<br />

Committee:<br />

Friedrich Ulfers (New York University)<br />

Sigrid Hackenberg (European Graduate School)<br />

Michael Anker (European Graduate School)<br />

ii


Abstract<br />

The utilization of an instrumental model that sees language itself as a means which is<br />

capable of bringing us towards what might be called fixed “meaning,” is one of the<br />

greatest limitations in the human attempt to establish an authentic understanding of the<br />

dynamics of communication. An acceptance of language from this perspective constricts<br />

our ability to have an adequate confrontation, or more accurately, experience of/with an<br />

aesthetic work.<br />

This text explores the impact of conceiving the <strong>literature</strong> of Franz Kafka in light of what<br />

will be referred to as “Pure Mediality” via an a-teleological approach that calls upon the<br />

thinking of Nietzsche, Deleuze, Guattari, Barthes, Adorno, and Derrida - among others.<br />

My reading of Kafka presents him as profoundly skeptical of instrumental language, very<br />

much influenced by the Vienna School language critics of the turn of the century. Kafka<br />

recognizes the inherent violence in any conceptual understanding of language, and<br />

therefore conceives of <strong>literature</strong>, or more precisely, literary or poetic language, as capable<br />

of an “un-judging” that deconstructs any previously “judged” version of the real. His<br />

literary work thus constitutes an embrace of infinite relation, suspension of judgment and<br />

radical undecidabilty.<br />

Pure Mediality is not to be confused with an aesthetics of the autonomy of l’art pour<br />

l’art; rather it is suffused with an inherent ethical aspect insofar as it constitutes freedom<br />

from truth as the tyranny of univocity and teleology towards the truth of an a-topical,<br />

endlessly de-territorializing and metamorphosing world. As such, this truth is always<br />

already other in relation with itself, and thus ethical in its irreducible self-less-ness, its<br />

inherent openness to, and interrelatedness with, the other. It is the ethical structure of the<br />

“given” - not the anthropomorphically instrumentalized world - in which its<br />

interpenetrating parts exist “poetically,” as metamorphic units. The text argues that<br />

Kafka’s art of Pure Mediality is an art of alterity, constituting a “wounding” or “opening”<br />

by alterity that demands a response. It is this character of responsiveness to the other that<br />

implies ethical potentialities.<br />

iii


1. Introduction<br />

Table of Contents<br />

1.1 Language and Meaning: The Structuralist Approach 4<br />

1.2 19 th Century Developments: Kleist, Mach & Nietzsche 6<br />

1.3 From Benjamin to Deleuze and Guattari 10<br />

1.4 Derrida and the “Death of the Signified” 13<br />

1.5 Kafka: Language and Communication 14<br />

2. Moving Towards Pure Mediality:<br />

2.1 Deconstructing the Teleological Perspective 19<br />

2.3 Nietzsche and Binary Opposition 21<br />

2.4 Benjamin and the “Un-mittelbar-keit” of Language 23<br />

2.5 Derrida and Haunted Language 29<br />

2.6 Kafka and the Language of Infinite Relation 32<br />

3. Un-judging Judgment: Undecidability and Suspension in “The Judgment”<br />

3.1 The Nature of Judgment 34<br />

3.2 Undecidability in the Ancient Greek Tradition 37<br />

3.3 A Literature of Re-Reading 39<br />

3.4 Allusion: Hinting at Truth 41<br />

3.5 Closure and Violence 44<br />

3.6 Un-judging “The Judgment” 45<br />

1


3.7 Narrative Rupture 49<br />

3.8 Death by Drowning 54<br />

4. The Law Revisited: Deferred Judgment in “The Trial”<br />

4.1 The Nature of Law 58<br />

4.2 The Question of Access 59<br />

4.3 The Figures of the Law 62<br />

4.4 The Question of Transparency 65<br />

4.5 Representing Justice 67<br />

4.6 Acquittal: Incessantly Deferred 71<br />

5. “Kafka’s Networks:” A Rhizomatic Approach to “The Metamorphosis”<br />

5.1 Rhizomatic Thinking 76<br />

5.2 A Departure from Arbolic Thinking 78<br />

5.3 “Becoming-Animal” 81<br />

5.4 Food and Decay: The Unknown Nourishment 85<br />

5.5 The Violence of Demonstrative Language 90<br />

6. Music and Pure Mediality<br />

6.1 Music as A-Representative Art 95<br />

6.2 Music and Language 97<br />

6.3 From Tonality to Atonality 99<br />

6.4 “Was he an animal?” 102<br />

2


6.5 “Josephine the Singer:” 108<br />

Suspended Chords, Suspended Judgment<br />

7. “A Country Doctor:” Writing Within Infinite Relation<br />

7.1 The Space of Undecidability 115<br />

7.2 Scenes from a Pigsty 117<br />

7.3 The Role of the Doctor and Diagnosis 121<br />

7.4 Words that Wound 123<br />

8. Concluding Remarks<br />

8.1 From the De-Centered to Pure Mediality 128<br />

8.2 Kafka’s Reach 132<br />

8.3 Chiasmic Unity and the Ethics of Alterity 133<br />

9. Bibliography 137<br />

3


“Language is possible because it strives for the impossible. Inherent in it, at all its<br />

levels, is a connection of struggle and anxiety from which it cannot be freed. As soon<br />

as something is said, something else needs to be said. Then something different must<br />

again be said to resist the tendency of all that has just been said to become definitive, to<br />

slip into the imperturbable world of things. There is no rest, either at the level of the<br />

sentence or at that of the whole work.”<br />

4<br />

-Blanchot, The Work Of Fire<br />

“We touch here on one of the most difficult points of this whole problematic: when we<br />

must recover language without language, language beyond language, this interplay of<br />

forces which are mute but already haunted by writing, where the conditions of a<br />

performative are established, as are the rules of the game and the limits of subversion.”<br />

Introduction:<br />

1.1 Language and Meaning: The Structuralist Approach<br />

-Derrida, Signature, Event, Context<br />

Even in the current age, one immersed in an endless series of links that comprise the<br />

internet, readers of Kafka’s labyrinthine texts still fall into the traps set up by traditional<br />

metaphysics and structuralist linguistics. The proposed aim of this project is to attempt to<br />

avoid this trap, to approach Kafka’s texts from a perspective on media that I will refer to<br />

as “<strong>pure</strong>.” Fundamentally, the problem raised in the philosophy of language revolves<br />

around the question of the “meaning” behind words, and the “structure” of the<br />

communicative process. I begin with what is clearly recognized by deSaussure 1 , and<br />

further articulated by Wittgenstein in his Philosophical Investigations, “It is this: The<br />

individual words in language name objects - sentences are combinations of such names.<br />

1 deSaussure’s Course In General Linguistics outlines the correspondence theory of<br />

signification.


In this picture of language we find the roots of the following idea: every word has a<br />

meaning. This meaning is correlated with the word. It is the object for which the word<br />

stands” (29). What Wittgenstein is essentially referring to is an understanding of words,<br />

language and meaning via a system that separates the signifier (that sign/symbol which<br />

corresponds to a fixed, immutable thing), from a signified (that concept which embodies<br />

the presence or meaning of the sign).<br />

Preference for this instrumental model of communication that sees language as a means,<br />

which is capable of bringing us towards what might be called fixed “meaning,” is one of<br />

the greatest limitations in the human attempt to establish an authentic understanding of<br />

the dynamics of communication. An acceptance of this perspective on language, spoken<br />

or written, constricts our ability to have an adequate confrontation, or more accurately,<br />

experience of/with media and communication. Schirmacher, in his essay “Media as Life-<br />

World” attests to a concern with media viewed both from the traditional perspective of<br />

structuralism, as well as what might be called “new media” theories:<br />

When speaking or writing about media we still tend to think in terms of channels<br />

to which sender and receiver are connected, a temptingly simple but inadequate<br />

definition. Current media theory proposes the "Gutenberg Galaxy" has run its<br />

course that the electronic media itself has become the "message" and its forms are<br />

to be understood as "extensions of man." Following Marshall McLuhan and<br />

considering the stunning developments of the "new media" theorists such as Neil<br />

Postman, media is analyzed not only as a metaphor and representation of<br />

knowledge, but as an activity, one shaping our social environment and subject to<br />

media ecology. This shift in understanding necessitates a fundamental change in<br />

our relation to media, and in our thinking. Yet although the distinctions between<br />

reality and imagination, truth and fantasy seem to vanish, and the acceptance of<br />

5


media as an authentic life-world the next step, media theory is still reluctant to<br />

face this consequence. Signification, representation, the ideology of an<br />

independent reality as the measure of truth - these are compelling and long-held<br />

presuppositions not easily cast aside (4).<br />

What he notes here is that there has been reluctance, whether conscious or not, to move<br />

away from the comfortable space of the definite, the signifying and the representative,<br />

towards perspectives on communication that lend themselves to multiplicity and the<br />

possibility of infinite interpretation. This preference for the representative value of the<br />

sign over the possibility of limitless connotative understandings affords us only a<br />

constructed/constricted space for encountering forms of media; speech, <strong>literature</strong>, the<br />

visual arts, music, etc.<br />

1.2 19 th Century Developments: Kleist, Mach and Nietzsche<br />

Historical resistance to instrumental, sender/receiver, medium/message conceptions of<br />

language emerge strongly during the early nineteenth century, prominently in the<br />

<strong>literature</strong> of the German Romantics. Kleist, among others recognized the confines that a<br />

traditional understanding of language can have on attempts to communicate:<br />

And I should like to tell you everything, if that were possible. But it is not<br />

possible, for this reason if for no other: that we lack the means. Language, all we<br />

have, is not adequate to the task; it cannot depict the soul, and gives us only<br />

shreds and fragments. That is why I feel something like horror whenever I am to<br />

disclose my innermost self to anyone; not because that self is shy of being<br />

uncovered but because I cannot show the person everything, simply cannot, and<br />

6


am fearful therefore that offering only fragments I shall be misunderstood<br />

(Collected Writings of Kleist, 81).<br />

Kleist’s fears of expression resulted from what he saw as the limits of language. These<br />

limits horrified him. However, his fears were not a byproduct of his self-revelation to the<br />

other, but rather pertain to an inability to self-reveal completely and openly. The<br />

propensity he saw for the linguistic medium to be “misunderstood” and for his<br />

message/thought to be undermined by the lack of clarity of his words is indicative of an<br />

emerging skepticism of language, communication, and media that was proliferating<br />

numerous aesthetic and philosophical arenas.<br />

This resistance continues in the functionalism and logical positivism of Ernst Mach.<br />

Mach argues that all phenomena should be seen as functions of all others, each having no<br />

specified role independent of its infinite functionality, which essentially amounts to an<br />

infinite relationality. According to Mach, the function of a thing is inseparable from its<br />

form. This perspective anticipates the rethinking of medium and message as indistinct<br />

from one another or inextricably bound. He comments in his introduction to The<br />

Analysis of Sensations:<br />

Colors, sounds, temperatures, pressures, spaces, times, and so forth, are connected<br />

with one another in manifold ways; and with them are associated dispositions of<br />

mind, feelings, and volitions. Out of this fabric, that which is relatively more<br />

fixed and permanent stands prominently forth, engraves itself on the memory, and<br />

expresses itself in language. Relatively greater permanency is exhibited, first, by<br />

certain complexes of colors, sounds, pressures, and so forth, functionally<br />

connected in time and space, which therefore receive special names, and are<br />

called bodies (2).<br />

7


A functional explanation is one that relies on the decomposition of any type of system<br />

into its component parts; it explains the working of that system in terms of the capacities<br />

of the parts and the ways that the parts are integrated with one another. As a result,<br />

Mach’s thinking moves ever-closer toward a monumental paradigm shift − as the eroding<br />

of a structuralist theory of communication gives way to an a-teleological, non-<br />

instrumental view of language and media.<br />

It is Nietzsche’s thinking in the late nineteenth century that opens up the flood gates to a<br />

post-structuralist interpretation of communication. Nietzsche was acutely aware of the<br />

dynamics of understanding and misunderstanding. He speaks to the perspective of the<br />

writer’s communicative intentionality in The Gay Science:<br />

One does not only wish to be understood when one writes; one wishes just as<br />

surely not to be understood. It is not by any means necessarily an objection to a<br />

book when anybody finds it impossible to understand: perhaps that was part of the<br />

author’s intention- he did not want to be understood by just “anybody.” Every<br />

more noble spirit and taste selects its audience when it wishes to communicate<br />

itself; and choosing them, it at the same time erects barriers against “the others.”<br />

All the more subtle laws of any style have their origin at this point: they at the<br />

same time keep away, create a distance, forbid ‘entrance,’ understanding, as said<br />

above- while they open the ears of those whose ears are related to ours (81).<br />

The essential issue to address, in order to understand Nietzsche’s re-envisioning of<br />

ontology and metaphysics, is his critique of the two-value, either/or world of ultimates<br />

which, he claims, human beings have accommodated themselves to exist within. The<br />

worldview that is generally considered the "real", that is, the world of presence, logic and<br />

8


substance, is a construct for him, created out of habit for strictly utilitarian purposes. He<br />

sees this mistaken vision of reality as fiction, masquerading itself as truth, hiding behind<br />

the facade of what humans believe they perceive as the "really real." This occurs due to<br />

the human error of mistakenly taking unique phenomena, and placing them beneath the<br />

umbrella of the general or self-same. Thus, the resulting error is one of human<br />

translation. Ulfers addresses this Nietzschean perspective of “irreducible singularity” and<br />

radical uniqueness as follows:<br />

Nietzsche, in addition to calling the rationalization of irreducible singularity a<br />

construct in the sense of fiction, points to the inherent violence of identity<br />

construction done to the singularity's alterity. By alterity I mean this always-<br />

already unlikeness of the singularity. Unlikeness doesn't mean that a self, a<br />

singularity was first 'like' and then somehow became other to itself, it is the very<br />

unlikeness that is misread for the sake of some need for a utilitarian program<br />

which revolves around being versus the instability of becoming. Change, time and<br />

temporality are all features of the given world that would produce the notion of<br />

change and change-ability (EGS Lecture Transcripts, 9).<br />

It is in this rethinking of opposition that Nietzsche reveals language to be a constructed<br />

metaphysical system in need of deconstruction, as it is sorely inadequate in expressing, or<br />

attempting to express the real. He speaks of the “shadow of god” (The Gay Science, 108)<br />

that human beings will continue to live beneath, as long as grammar holds its place, as its<br />

rules act as the foundation or building blocks of language. By “shadow” Nietzsche is<br />

referring to the over-arching presence that this type of thinking continues to have, in<br />

addition to our reluctance or inability to abandon it. That being said, Nietzsche is careful<br />

to note that language, however inadequate in expressing the “real”, is necessary for the<br />

survival and evolution of the human species.<br />

9


1.3 From Benjamin to Deleuze and Guattari:<br />

The discussion surrounding a relational conception of form and function in language<br />

continues in the work of Walter Benjamin. Benjamin’s conception of language focused<br />

upon it as a medium that mediates only itself. He cites the German Romantics who, he<br />

claimed, saw language as an, “infinity not of (linear) progression, but of relationality” 2<br />

(I, 26). Following the Nietzschean deconstructive tradition, Benjamin refers to a language<br />

or medium that is not itself mediated by anything outside. What is rejected here is the<br />

two-value logic of language based on a model of representation. “Hence, it is no longer<br />

conceivable, as the bourgeois view of language maintains, that the word has an accidental<br />

relation to its object, that it is a sign for things (or knowledge of them) agreed by some<br />

convention. Language never gives mere signs” (“Of Language As Such and on the<br />

Language of Man”, 69). Benjamin was convinced that language does not function as a<br />

means to communicate meaning or message. It inherently communicates nothing other<br />

than itself:<br />

The name is that through which, and in which, language itself communicates itself<br />

absolutely…But because the mental being of man is language itself, he cannot<br />

communicate himself by it, but only in it. The quintessence of this intensive<br />

totality of language as the mental being of man is the name. Man is the namer; by<br />

this we recognize that through him <strong>pure</strong> language speaks...If mental being is<br />

identical with linguistic being, then a thing, by virtue of its mental being is a<br />

medium of communication, and what is communicated in it is- in accordance with<br />

its mediating relationship- precisely this medium (language) itself (65).<br />

2 “nicht eine Unendlichkeit des Fortgangs sondern des Zusammenhanges“ (Benjamin,<br />

Gesammelte Schriften, I, 26).<br />

10


When, in one of his 1916 correspondences with Martin Buber, Benjamin speaks of the<br />

“Un-mittelbar-keit” 3 of language, he is referring to this very conception of language and<br />

communication that transgresses any instrumental view, moving away from the binary<br />

oppositional thinking inherent to the classical signified/signifier relationship 4 .<br />

Deleuze and Guattari partake in a similar system re-visioning with their explication of the<br />

rhizome in A Thousand Plateaus. In opposition to the root-tree model, Deleuze and<br />

Guattari offer the rhizome, a structure without a centralized, hierarchical organization, a<br />

structure that, in many ways, reflects the more "natural pattern of geo-organic possibility”<br />

(8). According to them, rhizomatic systems are "finite networks of automata in which<br />

communication runs from any neighbor to any other, the stems or channels do not pre-<br />

exist, and all individuals are interchangeable, defined only by their state at a given<br />

moment - such that the local operations are coordinated and the final, global result<br />

synchronized without central agency" (17). The structure of the rhizomatic model is<br />

therefore one which allows for a more expansive ontological perspective. “A method of<br />

the rhizome type, on the contrary, can analyze language only by de-centering it into other<br />

dimensions and other registers. A language is never closed upon itself, except as a<br />

3 Benjamin, II, 141-142. It must be noted that “Unmittelbarkeit” in everyday German<br />

discourse means “immediacy.” Benjamin changes this meaning by stressing the<br />

component “mittel” whose meaning is “means” or “instrument.” What Benjamin is<br />

saying, then, is that with language as “Pure Mediality”, that is, as a system without an<br />

outside reference or signified, no medium or signifier could have an instrumental<br />

function in terms of the achievement of an ultimate signified.<br />

4 Robert Musil similarly alludes to the structure of language and the world as “Pure<br />

Mediality” when he writes that the “structure of the world” is “an unending system of<br />

interconnectedness in which there are no independent meanings.” (Werke in Neun<br />

Banden, 1002) Binary opposites, such as good and evil, are “not absolute values,” (748)<br />

but “variable functions” (1073) whose values are always dependent on “circumstances”<br />

(2507). Author’s translation.<br />

11


function of impotence” (8). This de-centered view of language and communication is one<br />

in which both the content and form of the message are seen as immanent.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari’s notion of the rhizome demonstrates that there is no central<br />

controlling agent or transcendental signified. “The rhizome is an a-centered, non-<br />

hierarchical, non-signifying system without a General and without an organizing memory<br />

or central automation, defined solely by a circulation of states" (21). Without hierarchy,<br />

embracing a view of relationality, rhizomatic systems exist in the worlds of<br />

undecidability and non-calculability. While allowing for infinite movement, flow and<br />

flux, rhizomatic systems do not allow for a transgression back to metaphysical nostalgia<br />

for stability or permanence, definition or end.<br />

The presentation of the rhizome as encompassing radical relationality, as well as the<br />

interpenetration of elements, corresponds back to Benjamin’s aforementioned<br />

understanding of the relationality or non-instrumentality of language, and by extension,<br />

the world:<br />

Mediation, which is the immediacy of all mental communication is the<br />

fundamental problem of linguistic theory, and if one chooses to call this<br />

immediacy magic, then the primary problem of language is its magic. At the<br />

same time, the notion of the magic of language points to something else: its<br />

infiniteness. This is conditional on its immediacy. For precisely because nothing<br />

is communicated through language, what is communicated in language cannot be<br />

externally limited or measured, and therefore all language contains its own<br />

incommensurable, uniquely constituted infinity (64).<br />

12


The interpenetration of elements is important in both Benjamin’s and Deleuze and<br />

Guattari’s worldviews. From both perspectives, there is no death as stasis, as final end. In<br />

fact, in neither case is the world modeled on entropic becoming.<br />

1.4 Derrida and the “Death of the Signified”:<br />

In continuing to trace the evolution of the philosophy of language from structuralism to<br />

the postmodern, one cannot fail to visit the contributions of Jacques Derrida. To begin<br />

with, his work is steeped in a view of language which embraces the perspective of<br />

relationality between form and function found previously in Nietzsche, Benjamin, as well<br />

as Deleuze and Guattari. This infinite relationality, the transgression of instrumental<br />

language, is what Derrida has come to refer to as the absence of the “transcendental<br />

signified.” His text, Signature Event Context, begins by re-examining the possibility of<br />

meaning in light of a non-instrumental language:<br />

I have been constrained to predetermined communication as a vehicle, a means of<br />

transport or transitional medium of a meaning, and moreover a unified meaning. If<br />

communication possessed several meanings and if this plurality should prove to<br />

be irreducible, it would not be justifiable to define communication a priori as the<br />

transmission of a meaning. The meaning or contents of the semantic message<br />

would thus be transmitted, communicated, by different means, by more powerful<br />

technical mediations, over a far greater distance, but still within a medium that<br />

remains fundamentally continuous and self-identical, a homogenous element<br />

through which the unity and wholeness of meaning would not be affected in its<br />

essence (1-2).<br />

13


We again find the instrumental or utilitarian view of language as suspect. Derrida is<br />

pointing to the limitations of traditional signifier/signified, medium/message,<br />

sender/receiver paradigms under which we erroneously function. Additionally, he is<br />

critical of the notion of a singular or univocal meaning, in which a comprehensive<br />

understanding or interpretation would be possible. In fact, Derrida sees a type of violence<br />

inherent to instrumental communication. An embrace of instrumental language requires<br />

the construction of a “concept” that reduces to a generality what is uniquely singular. The<br />

concept in this case results from a process of violent pacification which does not allow<br />

for pluralism or alterity.<br />

1.5 Kafka: Language and Communication<br />

From these aforementioned critical perspectives, the chapters that follow will seek to<br />

explore the impact of conceiving the writing of Franz Kafka in light of the notion of<br />

“Pure Mediality.” This will be accomplished via an a-teleological approach that calls<br />

upon Nietzsche, Deleuze, Guattari and Derrida among others. My approach implies an<br />

attempt on the part of Kafka to create a <strong>literature</strong> that does not function solely as a vehicle<br />

for the communication of conceptual meaning, but as MacLuhan noted in the early<br />

1960’s, paradoxically involves the message as well: “Apropos ‘the medium is the<br />

message’ I now point out that the medium is not the figure but the ground, not the motor<br />

car but the web of intersecting highways…in all media the user is the content, and the<br />

effects come before the invention” (Understanding Media 276). This study seeks to<br />

14


present the medium of Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong> as radically immanent onto itself, not simply, a<br />

bridge leading the reader towards a meaning that lies elsewhere.<br />

My reading, in other words, presents Kafka as profoundly skeptical of instrumental<br />

language, very much influenced in this regard by the Vienna School language critics of<br />

the turn of the century. Kafka recognized the inherent violence of any conceptual<br />

understanding of language, based as it is on cutting the chiasmic interlacing of its<br />

signifiers by way of decision or judgment, and therefore conceives <strong>literature</strong>, or more<br />

precisely, literary/poetic language, as capable of an “un-judging” that deconstructs any<br />

previously “judged” version of the real. His literary work thus constitutes an embrace of<br />

infinite relation, suspension of judgment and radical undecidabilty. This perspective is<br />

argued by Ronell in her text Stupidity:<br />

…Kafka’s works reduce not only the image and putative function of the<br />

poet-author but of writing as well. Kafka replaces the literary text with<br />

newspapers, legal documents, letters, the gesang produced by the<br />

humming sounds of a telephone and even, human flesh. In addition to<br />

metamorphosing or technologizing modern <strong>literature</strong>’s portrait of the artist<br />

and his work, Kafka’s oeuvre abandons such metaphysical comforts as a<br />

transcendental signified on the one hand and the fiction of ultimate,<br />

substantialized meaning or absolute presence on the other (188).<br />

In my reading, I will focus on Kafka’s shorter works, namely “The Judgment,” “The<br />

Metamorphosis,” “A Country Doctor,” “Josephine the Singer or The Mouse-Folk” as<br />

well as selected passages from the Diaries and his novel The Trial. I will examine what<br />

may be referred to as the primary hindrance of communication − the presupposition that<br />

15


communication is a teleologically oriented enterprise whose very ground lies in clarity.<br />

Conversely, I will argue that the precedent for communication is something far closer to<br />

what we commonly view as disturbance. Clarity is therefore not a ground, with the<br />

occurrence of disturbance acting as momentary lapse in the communicative process.<br />

Rather, what one perceives as disturbances from time to time are periodic reminders that<br />

the primal state of communication is one which is always in flux. It is never grounded in<br />

any sense of permanence or stability. Kafka recognized this, and perhaps offered his<br />

writing as a means to circumvent traditional understandings of medium, message and<br />

meaning.<br />

In his Blue Octavo Notebooks, Kafka speaks to a perspective on language and<br />

communication that is inherently allusive as opposed to one which is solely instrumental:<br />

“For everything outside the phenomenal world, language can only be used allusively, but<br />

never even approximately in a comparative way, since, corresponding as it does to the<br />

phenomenal world, it is concerned only with property and its relations” (92). It is only<br />

through this particular type of literary language, of which Kafka partook, that one can<br />

become cognizant of this notion of Pure Mediality - as it involves positioning oneself<br />

within the undecidables of metaphor and allusion.<br />

The implications of this view will be explored with a particular emphasis placed upon the<br />

dynamics of judgment and understanding. As Blanchot writes, “Our manner of excluding<br />

(judging) is at work precisely at the moment we are priding ourselves on our gift of<br />

universal comprehension” (The Work of Fire 205). Correspondingly, Derrida believes<br />

16


that the notion of understanding results from a traumatic process of violent tearing and<br />

laceration which forces meaning to appear. Both critique the problematic conception of<br />

instrumental language which compels definitive intelligibility and meaning. Kafka<br />

inherently allows for the possibilities of the traumatic in his writing. It is precisely this<br />

allowance for the “horrors” of infinite play and the radically undecidable that constitutes<br />

what Kafka saw as the necessary disruption – an opening or loosening of the rigidity of<br />

conceptual language. As Kafka puts it metaphorically in a diary entry: “Books must be<br />

the axe for the frozen sea inside us” (Diaries, 279).<br />

Given what I have stated, it would be inappropriate to use the following interpretive<br />

perspective: “Instead of…examining the meaning and function of the story’s enigmatic<br />

quality, critics have tended to want a kind of translation into a more normal code. This<br />

would imply that Kafka’s meaning is not radically different from anyone else’s but that it<br />

is expressed in a kind of private code; one goes to the diaries and letters to get the code,<br />

uses it to decode the works, and is then left with a meaning which is now independent of<br />

Kafka’s style of writing” (Ellis, 74).<br />

What I argue as my thesis is a reading of Kafka’s writing that would attempt a solution of<br />

the text’s problems from within, by an investigation of its structure. I would add that<br />

Kafka himself suggests such a reading in letters to Felice Bauer to whom he was engaged<br />

at the time. Speaking of the short story “Das Urteil” he says that it “is a bit wild and<br />

meaningless,” but that it has an “inner truth.” That is to say that my reading will present<br />

Kafka’s writing as radically immanent – whose truth is not some transcendental referent,<br />

but an aspect of the immanence that constitutes Kafka’s writing, that is, the infinite<br />

17


interconnectedness of the world, a text that has “no outside” (Limited Inc., 17) as Jacques<br />

Derrida puts it.<br />

Put differently, my thesis is that Kafka’s writing follows the logic of dreams Freud<br />

introduces in his The Interpretation of Dreams. It is a logic that ignores the Principle of<br />

Non-contradiction or the Excluded Middle. On the contrary, Freud’s Unconscious and its<br />

manifestation in dreams constitute the “middle,” in the sense of Pure Mediality, where<br />

there is no “either-or,” but only a (chiasmic) “and” whereby “[e]ach train of thought is<br />

almost invariably accompanied by its contradictory counterpart, linked with it by<br />

antithetical association” (352).<br />

18


“Who could still be captivated by the thousand years of chatter about the<br />

meaning of good and evil when it turns out that they are not constants at all but<br />

functional values…”<br />

-Robert Musil, The Man Without Qualities<br />

“One could say that when at the moment I am writing, the receiver may be absent from<br />

my field of present perception. But is not this absence merely a distant presence, one<br />

which is delayed or which, in one form or another, is idealized in its representation?<br />

This does not seem to be the case, or at least this distance, divergence, delay, this<br />

diferral [difference] must be capable of being carried to a certain absoluteness of<br />

absence if the structure of writing, assuming that writing exists, is to constitute itself.”<br />

Moving Towards Pure Mediality<br />

2.1 Deconstructing the Teleological Perspective<br />

19<br />

-Derrida, Dissemination<br />

In this chapter, I will explore some of the philosophical moves that are related to what I<br />

claim in my thesis constitutes Kafka’s writing, namely, a text of <strong>pure</strong> immanence and a<br />

kind of self-referentiality. This will involve a look at selected figures that prepare the<br />

way towards Pure Mediality. In this section, I will also briefly summarize what is<br />

involved in the teleological approach to the world.<br />

Within traditional metaphysics, human life is commonly seen as a sequence of events,<br />

radically contingent, leading toward an end. Human beings maintain the idea that the<br />

sum total of life events inevitably leads towards a sense of stable presence, permanence<br />

or being. Particular actions are not seen in their unique singularity, but rather as part of a


series of events, which are somehow to be accumulated or amassed. In this way human<br />

actions are given particular legitimacy because they are seen as part of some grander<br />

scheme, pieces in the temporal puzzle which in their finality will bring about being or<br />

permanence in a realm beyond the physical, i.e., the finite, temporal, impermanent world.<br />

With this assumption of a realm beyond the physical, that is, of a metaphysical one, as<br />

Aristotle defined it, comes the idea that eventually some fixed, immutable meaning or<br />

truth will be discovered. This meaning or definitively revealed truth(s) will be revealed<br />

not as ephemeral or transitory in character, but rather as absolute and unchanging. This<br />

end, the elucidation of purpose, is viewed as the achievement of an ultimate goal.<br />

Generally referred to as the teleological perspective, this metaphysical paradigm aimed at<br />

the discovery of permanence behind a world of change and time, of a resting-place where<br />

becoming terminated in being, absence resolved into presence, and a stability that<br />

becomes equated with the very notion of the real.<br />

It is such figures as Nietzsche and Benjamin that begin, during the late nineteenth and<br />

early twentieth century, to radically re-envision this teleology. Later in the twentieth<br />

century, this re-conception is continued by Derrida. Within the writing of all three<br />

thinkers, certain common themes are pervasive; firstly that a worldview which relies<br />

upon oppositional thinking needs to be unmasked as façade, as constructed fiction.<br />

Secondly, rather than viewing human actions as strictly goal-oriented or teleological, we<br />

need to consider the way in which they functionally relate to one another. Finally, that<br />

language does not serve as an intermediary device which should be seen as a means to an<br />

20


end in the communicative process. Rather, our perspective on language must move from<br />

a tool which signifies something outside of itself, towards an infinite chain of signifiers<br />

that point only to themselves. This chapter will examine the movement away from a<br />

teleological view of the world and its inherent opposing structures toward the evolution<br />

of what has been referred to as the Pure Mediality of which Kafka’s writing partakes.<br />

2.2 Nietzsche and Binary Opposition:<br />

It is in the work of Nietzsche that we are provided with an entryway into the nineteenth<br />

century’s discontent with teleology. In his declaration of the “death of god” in The Gay<br />

Science (108) Nietzsche accomplishes a deconstruction of the current human system of<br />

values, a metaphysical system in the sense of its hierarchization of opposites. Nietzsche<br />

found humanity to be engaged in a valuation process which favored being over<br />

becoming, foundation over surface, good over evil and end over process. In light of this,<br />

his agenda becomes clear right away:<br />

To demonstrate the absolute homogeneity of all events and the application of<br />

moral distinctions as conditioned by perspective; to demonstrate how everything<br />

praised as moral is identical in essence with everything immoral and was made<br />

possible as in every development of morality with immoral means and for<br />

immoral ends-; how, on the other hand, everything decried as immoral is<br />

considered, higher and more essential... (Will To Power 155).<br />

This desire to unmask as fiction the teleological world view is apparent in The Will To<br />

Power where he states: “There exists neither ‘spirit’, nor ‘reason’ nor ‘thinking’, nor<br />

‘consciousness’, nor ‘soul’, nor ‘will’, nor ‘truth’: all are fictions that are of no use”<br />

21


(480). Each of these concepts is constructed within the very metaphysical framework<br />

that Nietzsche aims to deconstruct. All human attempts to group unique phenomena<br />

under the umbrella of the similar become false impositions with no correspondence to the<br />

“really real.” Nietzsche points to, and criticizes the human tendency to separate and<br />

conceptualize notions such as good and evil, worthy and unworthy, truth and untruth. He<br />

comments on these artificial separations, “There are no opposites, only from logic (a<br />

human construct) do we derive the concept of opposites and falsely transfer it to things”<br />

(298). If human beings erroneously create polarities through a distorted logic, and<br />

Nietzsche removes the legitimacy of this logic by finding it to be fiction, then those<br />

created polarities no longer exist as valid for human use in anything but a utilitarian<br />

fashion. It would therefore seem that ultimate meaning, stable being, permanence, etc.<br />

are also fictions created by human beings to serve as foundational pillars for this<br />

metaphysical, teleological worldview. Ulfers addresses this as follows:<br />

First he calls it fictional, it's an interpretation, secondly, where other philosophers<br />

have spoken of the most peaceable values that we have received from a higher<br />

sphere, he call it actually a violence. It is with this second move, regarding the<br />

loss of a moral world that associates good with identity as the self-sameness of<br />

being, that is accomplished with violence perpetrated on beings that as alterities<br />

are intrinsically open to otherness, that Nietzsche de-masks the morality of good<br />

and evil as unethical…. (EGS Transcripts)<br />

The Nietszchean deconstruction of opposition, it is not strictly a destructive destruction,<br />

but also a creative destruction, one which allows for the alterity of being. He is speaking<br />

of a deconstructive process which recognizes radical singularity and infinite<br />

22


interpretation, one that allows for what Levinas will later refer to as the, “other as other 5 .”<br />

Any violence to otherness results out of this process of interpretation or conceptualization<br />

in which meaning is violently forced out of that which is irreducibly distinct.<br />

The problem that Nietzsche notes in terms of the creation of constructs lies in the human<br />

process of translation and interpretation. According to him, unique and dissimilar<br />

phenomena are categorized as selfsame via human interpretation. Human beings fail to<br />

recognize that their perceptions of the "actual world" are fictitious, because they fail to<br />

recognize their primary error: the mistaken translation of distinct phenomena into the<br />

categorical.<br />

2.3 Benjamin and the “Un-mittelbar-keit” of Language:<br />

While the movement away from binary thinking - and a view of instrumental language<br />

which is suspect- also receives significant attention from Benjamin, who writes<br />

extensively on Kafka. We see Benjamin’s initial approach to an analysis of linguistics<br />

and communications emerge in a June 1916 correspondence with Martin Buber. In this<br />

letter he states:<br />

I can understand writing as such as poetic, prophetic, objective in terms of its<br />

effect, but in any case only as magical, that is as unmediated. Every salutary<br />

effect, indeed every effect not inherently devastating, that any writing may have<br />

resides in its mystery. In however many forms language may prove to be<br />

5 Levinas’ text Otherwise than Being contains an extensive discussion of the “alterity of<br />

being” which are discussed further in my “Concluding Remarks.”<br />

23


effective, it will not be so through the transmission of content but rather through<br />

the <strong>pure</strong>st disclosure of its dignity and its nature…(Correspondence 80).<br />

Benjamin regards language as having both a “magical” quality to it. He is especially<br />

concerned here with what is traditionally referred to as the content of language as well as<br />

its utility value. In order to grasp the magical perspective of which Benjamin speaks, we<br />

must first remind ourselves of the structruralist paradigm which he is rebelling against:<br />

the point of view which accepts language as the means through which content is<br />

transmitted from a sender to a recipient. To view language in this way involves<br />

conceiving of signifiers as things which express and refer to things outside of themselves.<br />

In speaking of the utility value of signifiers, I am referring to the words/signs which<br />

supposedly serve as bridges leading towards definitive meaning. It would be ridiculous to<br />

imply that language does not function in a useful way, serving practical purposes for<br />

human beings. We use language as our primary method of communication. Our contact<br />

and experience of the world is at all times mediated in and through some sort of<br />

language. However, we must also be cognizant of the fact that simply because we are<br />

compelled to use it, does not mean that language is any less of a fictitious construct.<br />

Language therefore must be analyzed in a new light, one which is open to an intrinsically<br />

relational conception.<br />

Benjamin contrasts the utilitarian view of language by referring to what he calls the “Un-<br />

mittelbar-keit” of language. As I have mentioned, this is a conception of language and<br />

communication that transgresses any instrumental view, deconstructing the binary<br />

oppositional thinking inherent to the classical signified/signifier relationship. In referring<br />

24


to this un-mittel-bar-keit of language, Benjamin’s use of the German term “mittel 6 ” is of<br />

particular importance because of the term’s possible implications. The double-meaning or<br />

interpretation of “mittel” as both “medium” or “means” and “ends” at the same time is<br />

used by Benjamin to describe the qualities of language he believed to be largely ignored;<br />

its immediacy and infinite referentiality. In his correspondences, essays and even within<br />

his doctoral dissertation, Benjamin illustrates a theory of language and communication<br />

which is non-exclusionary, and a perspective on language which functions<br />

simultaneously as both medium and message. His linguistic perspective actually<br />

anticipates McCluhan’s “the medium is the message” thinking by some fifty years.<br />

What Benjamin is speaking of is language which itself is not mediated by anything<br />

outside, one that does not see signs as simply representational tools which serve in a<br />

functional role. He goes on to say, “Hence, it is no longer conceivable, as the bourgeois<br />

view of language maintains, that the word has an accidental relation to its object, that the<br />

sign for things (or knowledge of them) agreed by some convention. Language never<br />

gives mere signs” (“On Language as Such and on the Language of Man” 69). Language<br />

therefore does not serve the purpose of communicative tool, but instead all linguistic<br />

signifiers are infinitely relational, referential functions of one another. Benjamin’s essay<br />

is one of the first places we see him begin his departure from a model of language, and by<br />

extension of the world, in which language does not function as a means or medium<br />

leading towards a meaning (the signified) that would exist prior to language (the<br />

signifier). He continues:<br />

25


All communication of the contents of the mind is language, communication in<br />

words being only a particular case of human language and of the justice, poetry,<br />

or whatever underlying it or founded on it….What does language communicate?<br />

It communicates the mental being corresponding to it. It is fundamental that this<br />

mental being communicates itself in language and not through language.<br />

Languages, therefore, have no speaker, if this means someone who communicates<br />

through these languages” (62-63).<br />

The real departure takes place via the prepositions “in” and “through” of his statement.<br />

Typically, in would imply content inherent to signs while through would refer to the way<br />

in which those linguistic signs communicate. For Benjamin, all communication is<br />

communication of mental being which is always already in. There is therefore nothing<br />

which language communicates through. The traditional conception of language as<br />

containing content is thus flawed according to him, as language itself is the content. He<br />

states: “The answer to the question “What does language communicate?’ is therefore ‘all<br />

language communicates itself” (63). With regard to this subject of the content of<br />

language, he continues, “There is no such thing as a content of language; as<br />

communication, language communicates a mental entity-something communicable per<br />

se” (66).<br />

Perhaps the most fundamental of Benjamin’s assertions on the nature of language and<br />

mediation is the temporal framework in which it exists. To discuss how language<br />

communicates a message, or to imply that media occurs over a distance would be to miss<br />

his most significant postures; that inherently language always holds the attribute of<br />

absolute immediacy, and thus it appears magical. Similarly, Benjamin speaks of the<br />

“frontiers” of language as being not limited, but rather limitless, “For precisely because<br />

26


nothing is communicated through language, what is communicated in language cannot be<br />

externally limited or measured, and therefore all language contains its own<br />

incommensurable, uniquely constituted infinity. Its linguistic being, not its verbal<br />

contents, define its frontier (64). It is this border-less, wandering de-territorialized<br />

language, which is without center or transcendental signified that he depicts. Rather than<br />

be confined to a view of language which focuses upon fictionally constructed borders,<br />

boundaries and restrictions, he offers a perspective in which language is “purified” - the<br />

totality of all mental being:<br />

So in name culminate both the intensive totality of language, as the absolutely<br />

communicable mental entity, and the extensive totality of language, as the<br />

universally communicating (naming) entity” (But because the mental being of<br />

man is language itself, he cannot communicate himself by it, but only in it. The<br />

quintessence of this intensive totality of language as the mental being of man is<br />

the name. (65).<br />

From an ontological perspective there is a certain equivocation. That is, Benjamin’s<br />

approach identifies mental being and linguistic being as inherently the same. He states,<br />

“If mental being is identical with linguistic being, then a thing, by virtue of its mental<br />

being , is a medium of communication, and what is communicated in it is-in accordance<br />

with its mediating relationship-precisely this medium (language) itself. Language is thus<br />

the mental being of things” (66). The content or substance which is communicated<br />

through the medium language is therefore self-same for him. By its very nature, it does<br />

not point to an outside, but to the interpenetration and co-mingling of signifiers, never<br />

resulting in a transcendental signified. Sokel also speaks of linguistic being as <strong>pure</strong>:<br />

“These considerations therefore leave us a purified concept of language, even though it<br />

27


may still be an imperfect one. The language of an entity is the medium in which its<br />

mental being is communicated. The uninterrupted flow of this communication runs<br />

through the whole of nature, from the lowest forms of existence to man…” (74).<br />

Benjamin’s perspective at times, hints at an almost spiritual component to language. This<br />

conclusion needs to be approached cautiously. By looking at language as something<br />

which communicates the entirety of mental being, one can to easily misinterpret he<br />

himself to be engaged in preferencing - if one understands him to mean that language is<br />

spiritual in a metaphysical sense. My contention is that this is not the type of <strong>pure</strong><br />

language of which he was speaking. His distaste for oppositional thinking and antithesis<br />

would preclude such an approach. To break down language and describe it within a<br />

structure of opposition would undermine his perspective, and more importantly, working<br />

with this view would be a gross misunderstanding of his philosophy of language. Rather,<br />

when Benjamin speaks of the mental being of language, he is referring to the attributes of<br />

it which are infinitely functional, which can not be heirarchized, and as a result, allow<br />

language to maintain a suspended, even fluid-like quality. It is this suspended or<br />

infinitely deferred quality that characterizes language as <strong>pure</strong>. For him, a language which<br />

is <strong>pure</strong> should not be seen in contrast to one which is im<strong>pure</strong>, but one that transcends this<br />

antithetical thinking and hovers in the always-already undefined space between presence<br />

and absence, being and non-being.<br />

28


2.4 Derrida and Haunted Language:<br />

In a similar fashion, Derrida argues that communication within a new paradigm, one in<br />

which the deconstruction of opposition has occurred, involves not singularity, but<br />

minimally a double-ness. He remarks, “…it must by means of a double gesture, a double<br />

science, a double writing, practice an overturning of the classical opposition and a<br />

general displacement of the system. It is only on this condition that deconstruction would<br />

provide itself the means with which to intervene in the field of oppositions it criticizes<br />

(Margins of Philosophy 329). Derrida embraces an approach which recognizes the<br />

reductionism embodied in either/or thinking in favor of a perspective which would be<br />

open to the both/and and neither/nor. This project takes the classical search for the<br />

transcendental signified 7 , teleology and univocity, and “replaces” it with multiplicity,<br />

provisional meaning and differance 8 .<br />

Derrida says of polarizing opposition that: “…The joyous affirmation of the play of the<br />

world and of the innocence of becoming, the affirmation of a world of signs without<br />

fault, without truth, and without origin which is offered to an active interpretation. This<br />

affirmation then determines the non-center otherwise than a loss of the center” (Writing<br />

7 The "transcendental signified" is a signified which transcends all signifiers, and is a<br />

meaning which transcends all signs. It is also a signified concept or thought which<br />

transcends any single signifier, but which is implied by all determinations of meaning.<br />

8 Derrida uses the term "differance" to describe the origin of presence and absence.<br />

Differance is indefinable, and cannot be explained by the "metaphysics of presence." In<br />

French, the verb "différer" means both "to defer" and "to differ." Thus, differance may<br />

refer not only to the state or quality of being deferred, but to the state or quality of being<br />

different.<br />

29


and Difference 292). According to this perspective, playfulness, not absolute definition,<br />

is the integral part of an interpretative process. A processual world, one who’s sole<br />

constant is flux, is a-centered not de-centered. One might say that he is reverting back to<br />

nostalgia for a lost metaphysical system. However, one may only speak of it as lost only<br />

if it was at some time there to begin with. As Derrida points out, it is not the established<br />

center which is being torn apart; it is our originally erroneous belief that there was a<br />

center. The simpler truth is that the entire perspective which takes as given a world<br />

which is centered is erroneous from the outset.<br />

This spirit-like nature of language which floats incessantly between presence and absence<br />

is also taken up by Derrida. In his interpretation of this phenomenon, Derrida speaks of<br />

the ghostly elements of language and writing as they are related to what he refers to as<br />

haunting. He says, “To haunt does not mean to be present, and it is necessary to<br />

introduce haunting into the very construction of a concept- of every concept, beginning<br />

with the concepts of being and time. That is what we would be calling here a hauntology.<br />

Ontology opposes it only in a movement of exorcism” (Specters of Marx 8).<br />

Derrida is purposefully playful with his use of the neologism hauntology which in French<br />

has an identical pronunciation to ontology. Whereas ontology studies being or existence<br />

and their basic categories and relationships, to determine what entities and what types of<br />

entities may exist, hauntology refers to the paradoxical state of the specter, which is<br />

neither being nor non-being. He continues:<br />

[T]he specter is a paradoxical incorporation, the becoming-body, a certain<br />

phenomenal and carnal form of spirit. It becomes, rather, some thing that remains<br />

30


difficult to name: neither soul nor body, and both one and the other. For it is flesh<br />

and phenomenality that give to the spirit its spectral apparition, but which<br />

disappear right away in the apparition, in the very coming of the revenant or the<br />

return of the specter....One does not know whether it is living or if it is dead. (6)<br />

He is speaking here of the notion of the double, of that which resides in the realm of the<br />

neither/nor and both/and. The ghostly for him is that which remains perpetually<br />

indeterminate and involves neither total presence nor total absence. It is this<br />

unclassifiable nature which makes haunted language horror inspiring. A strictly utilitarian<br />

and thus metaphysical understanding of language constitutes an avoidance of spectrality,<br />

since to figure the ghost in terms of fact or fiction, real or not-real, is to attribute to it a<br />

foundational ground, either a positive or negative facticity that the notion of ghostliness<br />

continually eludes. It is this elusiveness that must not be ignored.<br />

Ghosts are neither dead nor alive, neither corporeal objects nor stern absences. As such,<br />

they stand in defiance of the binary oppositions of presence and absence, body and spirit,<br />

past and present, life and death. For deconstruction, these terms cannot stand in clear,<br />

independent opposition to one another, as each can be shown to possess an element or<br />

trace of the term that it is meant to oppose. In the figure of the ghost, we see that past and<br />

present cannot be neatly separated from one another, as any idea of the present is always<br />

constituted through the difference and deferral of the past, as well as anticipations of the<br />

future.<br />

31


2.5 Kafka and the Language of Infinite Relation:<br />

Let me summarize the context of immanence and absence of binary logic established by<br />

Nietzsche, Benjamin and Derrida in which my reading of Kafka will take place. Both<br />

Benjamin’s and Derrida’s linguistic arguments embrace the Nietzschean deconstruction<br />

of binary opposition, and like Nietzsche, bring forth a major paradigm shift. This shift<br />

toward an always-already mediated linguistic perspective compels us to ask; what are the<br />

dynamics of a language which communicates only itself? Is there a human disconnect<br />

which occurs with a language existing as both content and medium? What are the<br />

implications of such a view on theories of literary communication in general, and for our<br />

specific purposes, on the <strong>literature</strong> of Kafka? How does Kafka operate within a language<br />

of infinite relationality? And, how will he simultaneously use and usurp the medium of<br />

<strong>literature</strong> via his writing?<br />

Kafka’s writing implicitly recognizes and allows for multiplicity to exist within the very<br />

world which has accommodated itself to antithesis. A case in point would be any<br />

conception of language based on “judgment” – signifier versus signified – that is derived<br />

from the violent operation of de-cision on prior undecidability. Kafka’s suspicions<br />

regarding oppositional structures emerge early on. He comments upon an aversion to<br />

them in his Diaries, “My repugnance for [them] is certain…They make for thoroughness,<br />

fullness, completeness, but only like a figure on the ‘wheel of life’ [a toy with a revolving<br />

wheel]; we have chased our little idea around the circle. They [antithesis] are as<br />

undifferentiated as they are different” (157). As a result of this aversion, Kafka’s writing<br />

32


issues from a radical skepticism/criticism vis a vis language as a falsifying construction,<br />

the insight into which calls for deconstruction. “The assumption common to Kafka’s<br />

view of language is the demand that truthful speech be the direct communication of<br />

being. It is this view which Derrida has exposed as ‘metaphysical nostalgia’ for the<br />

impossible presence of the referent- reality or being- in the signifying system that is<br />

language” (Sokel, 176). Thus any attempt at interpretation originates from the very same<br />

“unstable” nucleus born of deconstruction. In the final analysis, should we dare to speak<br />

of one, Kafka’s literary project seeks to undermine language at the very level at which it<br />

operates.<br />

As I now move on to a close reading and more systematic discussion of Kafka’s literary<br />

works in the chapters that follow, these perspectives of Nietzsche, Benjamin and Derrida<br />

will be used a critical points of reference with regard to judgment, metamorphosis,<br />

suspension, allusion and wounding. While my reading of Kafka’s writing will not occur<br />

solely through the filter of these thinkers, they will nonetheless serve as pillars who have<br />

set the stage with a process-oriented thinking that is essential to any serious interaction<br />

with the texts.<br />

33


“To refrain from judgment is the ‘judgment’, the yes of the refrain. Reflection on the<br />

necessity and impossibility of judgment shows the extent to which art and artifice are<br />

wedded together…”<br />

34<br />

-Pearson, Viroid Life<br />

“The decisive moment in human evolution is perpetual. That is why the revolutionary<br />

spiritual movements that declare all former things worthless are in the right, for<br />

nothing has yet happened”<br />

- Kafka, Blue Octavo Notebooks<br />

Un-judging Judgment: Undecidability and Suspension in “The Judgment”<br />

3.1 The Nature of Judgment:<br />

The legal process and the nature of law are themes of which Kafka was consumed. More<br />

often than not, his education in the law and subsequent career in the area of workers<br />

compensation and industrial insurance claims 9 are cited as contributing to this motif<br />

which pervades his writing. There is no shortage of secondary analysis of his <strong>literature</strong> to<br />

dispel this assertion, especially in the initial half-century following his death 10 . Much of<br />

this literary criticism concerning Kafka and the law tends to deal with texts such as The<br />

Trial and “The Judgment” from a perspective that invariably portrays judgment as<br />

malevolent and alienating process. The texts are interpreted to be an expression of the<br />

9 Kafka worked from 1907-1923, first at an administrative position in a Prague branch of<br />

an Italian insurance company (Assicurazioni Generali) and then at the Workmen's<br />

Accident Insurance Institute for the Kingdom of Bohemia.<br />

10 For a discussion of Kafka from this perspective, see the literary criticism of Politzer,<br />

Padovano or Huber.


futile plight of the individual pitted against authoritarian, bureaucratic and ultimately<br />

malicious legal machinery intent upon tortuously withholding essential answers to the<br />

most fundamental of human questions. Sokel remarks that Kafka “…conveys the<br />

bewilderment, helplessness and terror of the human self suddenly confronted with a<br />

world that utterly transcends any hope for comprehensibility, familiarity and protection”<br />

(121).<br />

Existentialist criticism in particular, depicts Kafka’s protagonists as caught within the<br />

wheels of an unjust, unethical and corrupt legal framework which is unwilling to give<br />

audience to their epistemological pursuits. The search for ultimate justice or<br />

understanding bears no fruit, as the law thwarts the individual’s attempts at arriving at an<br />

explanation. Besides refusing “access” to decision, many interpretations of Kafka would<br />

lead us to believe that forces such as the law indicts, convicts and punishes without<br />

rationale or justification. Allowing the protagonists knowledge, recognition or<br />

comprehension of their transgressions is not a privilege which is granted, as it is in the<br />

nature of the law to operate and condemn in secret according to rules of which we remain<br />

unaware.<br />

Kafka’s first story, “The Judgment” has been widely interpreted as a semi-<br />

autobiographical tale that deals with such issues as the author’s inability to commit to<br />

marriage and his difficult and often contentious relationship with his father 11 .<br />

Psychoanalytic and Existentialist criticism contend that the condemnation of the father, as<br />

11 See “Letter to my Father” (1919)<br />

35


well as the subsequent self-execution of that sentence by the son, can be traced back to<br />

Kafka’s preoccupation with the law and culpability. Specifically Kafka is said to have<br />

used the law in works such as this as an overarching metaphor to explore the insecurity,<br />

uncertainty, guilt and anxiety of post-Nietzschean world. Similarly, The Trial’s Joseph K.<br />

is often seen as the victim of an authoritarian bureaucracy which imposes upon the<br />

freedom of the individual and his ability to function in the world. As a result, Joseph K.’s<br />

time is spent obsessively attempting to comprehend and extricate himself from the<br />

arresting judgments of a totalitarian conspiracy.<br />

While these have been extremely popular critical positions on Kafka’s work, I will not, as<br />

I stated earlier, espouse them here. Rather I will focus on Kafka’s understanding of<br />

language and <strong>literature</strong>, and how he communicates a radical “undecidability” with regard<br />

to the idea of judgment. This argument derives first and foremost from the fact that Kafka<br />

has a specific and perhaps peculiar understanding of the relationship between <strong>literature</strong><br />

and the self. Whereas the author of a text may view himself to be the channeling medium<br />

or creative force that gives birth to narrative, character and theme, Kafka’s understanding<br />

moves far beyond this. He speaks literally and figuratively of himself and <strong>literature</strong> as<br />

inseparable, one in the same in his Diaries, “I do not have literary interests; rather I am<br />

made out of <strong>literature</strong>, I am nothing and cannot be anything else” (428).<br />

Literature is not simply an art form, artistic medium or means of communication but<br />

rather Kafka identifies it with the entirety of self. He continues, “My whole being is<br />

directed toward <strong>literature</strong>; I have followed this direction unswervingly…, and the<br />

36


moment I abandon it I cease to live. Everything I am. And am not, is a result…It is the<br />

earthly reflection of a higher necessity” (Letters to Felice, 93). Kafka’s equation of<br />

<strong>literature</strong> and being demands an approach to his work which does not seek only to<br />

explicate characters and themes, but rather, one which takes into account how his<br />

equation is intrinsically tied to a deconstructive paradigm shift- and a new perspective on<br />

language and communication. This in turn, compels a deconstructive reading of his texts.<br />

That being said, my reading of “The Judgment” approaches it from an a-metaphysical or<br />

a-teleological perspective, that is, within the immanence of the world and language that<br />

was alluded to in the previous chapter. Within this world, language serves not as a means<br />

toward some fixed end, but as infinitely relational- thereby rupturing the comfort of any<br />

metaphysical framework.<br />

3.2 Undecidability in the Ancient Greek Tradition:<br />

The notion of suspension of judgment or undecidability, as Derrida puts it, with regard to<br />

oppositional logic is not novel by any means. In their efforts to devise a concise theory<br />

of logic, and later mathematics, the "Laws of Thought" were posited by the ancient<br />

Greeks. One such law - that of the excluded middle, states that every proposition must<br />

either be true or false. It is here, in the formalization of the either/or framework, that we<br />

see the origins of opposition begin to serve as the basis of formal logic. This framework<br />

clearly does not allow for an intermingling of substance, ontological indeterminacy, or<br />

the flux of process thinking. Aristotle would later write that when this "excluded middle"<br />

37


is approached, the issue resolves into ambiguity in the mind of the beholder, not in the<br />

fact itself: He speaks of tertium non datum 12 as follows:<br />

...it is impossible, then, that 'being a man' should mean precisely 'not being a man',<br />

if 'man' not only signifies something about one subject but also has one<br />

significance...And it will not be possible to be and not to be the same thing,<br />

except in virtue of an ambiguity, just as if one whom we call 'man', and others<br />

were to call 'not-man'; but the point in question is not this, whether the same thing<br />

can at the same time be and not be a man in name, but whether it can be in fact"<br />

(Metaphysics, 525).<br />

Heraclitus proposed that a thing could be simultaneously true and not true. His classic<br />

example of this - our inability to step into the same river twice- as perpetual movement<br />

implies changes, has secured Heraclitus’ place as one of the first philosophers of process<br />

in the western historical tradition. Plato eventually lays the foundation for what would<br />

become fuzzy logic, indicating that there is a third region (beyond true and false) where<br />

these opposites "tumble about" (Republic 97). While countless objections continue<br />

throughout the history of philosophy, the either/or framework remains the dominant<br />

perspective based upon its useful functionality.<br />

Over two millennia later, Kafka is dealing with the same fundamental metaphysical and<br />

ontological questions: How can one operate within a both/and paradigm considering that<br />

all systems of communication are built upon the utilitarian structure of the either/or? How<br />

does the artist create in an arena dominated by this type of thinking? I contend that<br />

Kafka’s writing constitutes an embrace of the excluded middle, recognizing that<br />

12 "the third is not given"<br />

38


oppositional thinking has limits which must be overcome to express the human condition<br />

as encompassing flux, indeterminacy, incessant motion and change.<br />

Generally speaking, judgment revolves around achieving determination, closure and<br />

singular or univocal meaning. By accommodating ourselves to function within a<br />

metaphysical paradigm, human beings must thereby partake in a “forgetting”, which<br />

serves us in a utilitarian way to avoid a fall into the abyss of cognitive dissonance.<br />

Kafka’s writing conversely is in no way oriented or situated toward any type of<br />

prescriptive definition, but something quite different. Rather, his <strong>literature</strong> takes part in<br />

an active “undoing of the practice of forgetfulness” (Ulfers, NYU Lecture Notes, 2002).<br />

For Kafka, writing serves an essential human need, acting as a means of “un-judging,”<br />

and thereby deconstructing, the previously “judged” version of the real toward its<br />

originary “un-judged” status.<br />

3.3 A Literature of Re-Reading:<br />

In his essay “Kafka and the Absurd”, Albert Camus writes, “The whole art of Kafka<br />

consists in forcing the reader to reread. His endings, or his absence of endings, suggests<br />

explanations which, however, are not revealed in clear language but, before they seem<br />

justified, require that the story be reread from another point of view. Sometimes there is<br />

a double possibility of interpretation, whence appears the necessity of two readings. This<br />

is what the author wanted” (93). It is this possibility and need for a multiplicity of<br />

readings that Camus points to which are necessary strategies in confronting Kafka’s texts.<br />

39


Any attempt to reduce a text like “The Judgment” to a narrative which contains meaning<br />

outside is bound to fail because implicit in the way Kafka conceived of <strong>literature</strong><br />

necessitates a reading which does not seek resolution, but constantly participates in<br />

avoiding it. By operating within an allusive language, Kafka’s texts thereby elude any<br />

final interpretation.<br />

Camus further asserts that Kafka was writing what he refers to as an “absurdist”<br />

<strong>literature</strong>. Camus’ use of the term “absurd” in this context is not meant to be understood<br />

as non-sensical- as opposed to rational. Kafka’s “absurdity” lies in the fact that his work<br />

encompasses both presence and absence, both an excess and lack which thereby forces<br />

the reader to indefinitely defer univocal understanding. This type of writing, which<br />

transcends the constraints of metaphysical opposition falls into the realm of the absurd.<br />

Camus continues:<br />

These perpetual oscillations between the natural and the extraordinary, the<br />

individual and the universal, the tragic and the everyday, the absurd and the<br />

logical, are found throughout his work and give it both its resonance and meaning.<br />

These are the paradoxes that must be enumerated, the contradictions that must be<br />

strengthened in order to understand the absurd work (94).<br />

This oscillation is achieved through the radical re-envisioning of the possibilities<br />

of language. Thus, meaning within this conception is not something which can be<br />

derived from a thinking which occurs in terms of polar opposition. Rather it is<br />

oscillation and flux which provide the any possibility for a momentary glimpse at<br />

meaning.<br />

40


To begin with, Kafka speaks of two types of language, one characterized by its<br />

communicative or instrumental value, and a second which might be called<br />

allusive, poetic, metaphoric or most appropriately “literary.” Instrumental<br />

language is utilitarian, a language which Kafka says speaks in terms of “property<br />

and its relations” (Diaries, 224). For Kafka, this is a language of grasping and<br />

conceptualization - one which attempts to possess. Through the use of this<br />

language, we describe and define- and by doing so- intrinsically limit. Critchley<br />

argues that this conceptual language is the language of philosophical thinking,<br />

and one which has inherent ethical problems: “To think philosophically is to<br />

comprehend- comprendre, comprehendre, begreifen, to include, to seize, to grasp-<br />

and master the other, thereby reducing its alterity” (29). The question then arises:<br />

Is there something lost in the process of conceptualization that by its very nature<br />

is exclusionary and violent?<br />

3.4 Allusion: Hinting at Truth:<br />

The second type of language, the language of Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong>, is one which<br />

partakes only in hinting or alluding to any sense of meaning or understanding.<br />

Thus, this poetic or literary language calls for interminable interpretation, and by<br />

extension, infinite suspension of judgment. Grasping for Kafka is both monstrous<br />

and logocentric and as a result, the need to subvert this informs his writing, and<br />

requires of us a new type of reading. His writing compels us to read<br />

hermeneutically, never achieving absolute definition, as the result of such a claim<br />

41


would be the end of hermeneutics and violence on to language. A hermeneutic<br />

reading by its very nature does not encourage a linear approach, but rather<br />

precludes linearity by rupturing this movement and thereby pointing to the limits<br />

of logocentrism. These deviations in discourse are pivotal components of the<br />

hermeneutic process clearly observed by Barthes:<br />

The hermeneutic code performs an opposite action: it must set up delays<br />

(obstacles, stoppages, deviations) in the flow of the discourse…it opposes the<br />

ineluctable advance of language with an organized set of stoppages: between<br />

question and answer there is a whole dilatory area whose emblem might be named<br />

‘reticence,’ the rhetorical figure which interrupts the sentence, suspends it, turns it<br />

aside (S/Z 75).<br />

Barthes ties the hermeneutic code’s “performance” to an alterity which only<br />

comes into being as a function of that process and open-ness. Intrinsic to the<br />

hermeneutic approach is suspension, an avoidance of any fixed notion of<br />

endpoint. Critchley too sees a hermeneutical reading to be non-reductionist and<br />

involved in an understanding of language that philosophy, with its logocentric<br />

tendencies, will not allow for. As a result, he says: “…As the attempt to attain a<br />

point of exteriority to logocentrism, deconstruction may therefore be understood<br />

as the desire to keep open a dimension of alterity which can neither be reduced,<br />

comprehended, nor, strictly speaking, even thought by philosophy” (29). It is<br />

therefore only this type of reading of Kafka’s texts which allows for a sense of<br />

alterity and infinite relationality.<br />

42


An allusive language is tied to an ethical perspective because it does not point to<br />

the exact location of truth, but rather proximity. In his analysis of the nature of<br />

literary language Sokel states:<br />

The way for <strong>literature</strong> is therefore not to try to express the truth, but to hint at it by<br />

showing the undoing of untruth…All that can be uncovered are successive layers<br />

of untruth. With this insight, the spiritualist perspective is approximated. For<br />

such a procedure demonstrates the inadequacy of all languages to express the<br />

truth. All language can show is the ‘retreat’ of untruth. The process of making<br />

untruth evident is the only ‘light’ that language can shed on truth (180-181).<br />

It is not the function of <strong>literature</strong> to express absolute truth, but rather to “hint” at<br />

it. Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong> and his literary language operate transcending the<br />

limitations of traditional metaphysical structure, thus resulting in an un-judging of<br />

any previously fixed or defined judgment. His writing does not seek at closure,<br />

but is comfortable meandering in the space of infinite suspension.<br />

Ronell makes the argument that perhaps the ultimate ethical stance with regard to<br />

a demand for absolute decisiveness would necessitate the individual to admit that<br />

he is “stupid before the other” (66). She is not speaking here of stupidity in the<br />

sense of intellectual lack. This interpretation would be a regression into the<br />

antithetical thinking of stupidity versus intelligence. Her discussion of stupidity<br />

is inherently tied to judgment, but more precisely, the suspension of judgment.<br />

Where from a classical perspective, stupidity is ultimately tied to decision, Ronell<br />

argues:<br />

43


Stupidity is…that which fails to judge - it indicates a lack of judgment. Where<br />

judgment is mangled, there is a case of stupidity. So how can it be that stupidity,<br />

on the contrary is said to be the passing of a judgment, if only an always<br />

premature judgment? How can it disclose a lack of judgment that nonetheless<br />

judges decisively? Stupidity is however precisely that which fails to judge-it<br />

indicates a lack of judgment. Where judgment is mangled, there is a case of<br />

stupidity. So how can it be that stupidity, on the contrary is said to be the passing<br />

of a judgment, if only an always premature judgment? How can it disclose a lack<br />

of judgment that nonetheless judges decisively? (70)<br />

In the failure to judge, stupidity shows no lack. Stupidity ironically avoids the errors<br />

inherent to premature judgment. Any passing of judgment results in a decisiveness that is<br />

always already premature. In its very absolution and definition, it displays its<br />

problematic ethical qualities. Rather than participating in a refusal to judge - as is the<br />

case with stupidity - judgment forces upon uniqueness that which is self-same. Its refusal<br />

to allow for singularity by forcefully compelling conceptualization via adherence to a<br />

metaphysical paradigm shows the inherently unethical nature of judgment.<br />

3.5 Closure and Violence:<br />

Our tendency and inclination to participate in passing judgment is not all that far removed<br />

from our attraction to psychological closure. Both judgment and closure in this light,<br />

serve to provide a sense of finality and end, and place parameters around the limitless. In<br />

seeking out closure, one attempts to achieve irrevocable conclusiveness. While from a<br />

utilitarian psychological point of view, closure is often considered a desired, even sought-<br />

after state, the way in which it functions is essentially exclusionary. By introducing limits<br />

44


and delineating space, we are faced with the constrictions inherent to inside/outside,<br />

either/or thinking. While the creation of parameters may be useful in psychological<br />

ordering, one must realize that the imposition of closure is a created fiction.<br />

3.6 Un-Judging “The Judgment”<br />

I now turn my attention to a close reading of “The Judgment”, a reading which explores<br />

the text as a work engaged in something quite different from what its’ title suggests-<br />

something that could actually be referred to as an active “un-judging.” By this I mean that<br />

the text consciously works on the level of avoiding closure and thereby exposes as<br />

fictitious a teleological/ arch-eological worldview which situates judgment as the<br />

endpoint of that system. “The Judgment” as text is the space in which we initially see<br />

Kafka’s departure from any perspective on conclusiveness or verdict, which is always<br />

tied to the common understanding of law. From this point moving forward, the motif of<br />

suspended judgment and incessantly deferred closure will permeate the entirety of his<br />

literary work.<br />

As Kafka’s first work, and that which is universally considered to be his literary<br />

breakthrough, he comments significantly in his Diaries about his writing process during<br />

“The Judgment”:<br />

This story, "The Judgment," I wrote at one sitting during the night of the 22 nd -<br />

23 rd , from ten o’clock at night to six o’clock in the morning. I was hardly able to<br />

pull my legs out from under the desk, they had got so stiff from sitting. The<br />

fearful strain and joy, how the story developed before me, as if I were advancing<br />

45


over water. . . . How everything can be said, how for everything, for the strangest<br />

fancies, there waits a great fire in which they perish and rise up again. . . . Only in<br />

this way can writing be done, only with such coherence, with such a complete<br />

opening of the body and the soul. . . . (212-213)<br />

This description of his experience of writing the work does not point in any way toward a<br />

sense of closure, but rather an “opening” or breach required for the birth of the literary<br />

work to take place. It is only through this fissure remaining exposed that <strong>literature</strong> can<br />

become. By speaking of exposed vulnerability as compulsory to writing, and the<br />

undivided attention necessary in the endeavor, Kafka suggests that the artist partakes in a<br />

“wounding” during the process of creation. Consequently, he refers to the writing of “The<br />

Judgment” as “the breaking open of the wound for the first time” (Diaries, 109).<br />

The very title of the work, “The Judgment” (“Das Urteil”) hints at the suspension of<br />

closure and undecidability in that the word allows underneath its everyday meaning of<br />

“judgment” that of originary distribution. As Ulfers has pointed out, the term “urteil” of<br />

which the English “ordeal” is cognate can be understood to refer to a type of distribution<br />

or allotment (“A Lesson in Reading” , 2). One such example, the friend in St. Petersburg<br />

embodies, “namely a kind of ‘share’ or ‘distribution’ that does not result from urteil as<br />

judgment, and might be interpreted as a kind of ‘endowment’ a ‘lot’ or ‘allotment’ that is<br />

informed by the notion of fortune or chance” (3). It is this “Ur-teil” that Derrida alludes<br />

to when he writes in Limited Inc of, “a space that exceeds a calculable program” and<br />

which constitutes the “experience and experiment of the undecidable” that is prior to any<br />

decision or judgment (116).<br />

46


It is my position that the disruption of any form of judgment and binary logic by way of<br />

the “urteil” as ordeal of undecidability leads to a series of narrative disturbances or<br />

ruptures that occur at particular points in Kafka’s text. These ruptures are often read as<br />

instances within the text that disrupt the narrative flow of what appears to otherwise be a<br />

fairly straight-forward short story. I contend that Kafka used these instances in a far more<br />

complex fashion: as reminders to his readers of the problems of a structuralist system that<br />

sees communication as a clear flow between sender and receiver. The ruptures are used<br />

to re-orient a view of the primordial of communication as neither linear nor orderly, but<br />

rather as groundless and always in process. These occurrences are not merely momentary<br />

breakages within the structured forward movement of the narrative, but serve as Kafka’s<br />

vehicle to express an a-metaphysical worldview and an always-interconnected theory of<br />

communication, one of Pure Mediality.<br />

I have chosen to focus on three particular instances of rupture in “The Judgment”<br />

specifically; the fiancé’s comment to Georg’s decision to have become engaged, the<br />

father’s declaration that Georg is without a friend in St. Petersburg, and finally the<br />

sentencing of Georg by the father to “death by drowning” (75). In each of these instances,<br />

the ruptures, “challenge meaning and tempt the reader/teacher to look for answers outside<br />

the text…” (Ulfers, 1) Yet it is not outside of the text that meaning can be located, but<br />

inside, as one can attempt a solution of the texts problems from within by an investigation<br />

of its structure.<br />

47


That is to say that the story’s structure explores its own infinite relationality that makes<br />

possible only provisional meanings, a context in which the narrative ruptures function to<br />

expose the presence/absence dichotomy as a fiction. With regard to this, Adorno<br />

comments of Kafka’s work that, “In an art that is constantly obscuring and revoking<br />

itself, every determinate statement counterbalances the general proviso of<br />

indeterminateness” (Notes on Kafka 97). Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong> in this light, amounts to a<br />

blurring of the lines of revealing, and results in meaning which is always indeterminate.<br />

Thus, what might be referred to as the “true ground” (indeterminacy) appears periodically<br />

to break the “artificiality” of the forward-moving narrative from a proper beginning to a<br />

determinate ending.<br />

Kafka was highly aware of the power of allusive language to circumvent the structure of<br />

opposition. He remarks, “For everything outside the phenomenal world, language can<br />

only be used allusively [as an allusion], but never even approximately in a comparative<br />

way [as a comparison in the manner of an analogy], since, corresponding as it does to the<br />

phenomenal world, it is concerned only with property and its relations” (Diaries 40).<br />

Kafka proceeds to operate within an allusive or metaphoric language in “The Judgment”<br />

using narrative ruptures to unmask the tensions between univocal meaning and<br />

undecidability. His characters serve to explore these positions, and their interaction<br />

within the story calls for a re-evaluation of the dynamics of language.<br />

As a character, Kafka’s protagonist Georg is involved in a tireless quest for absolute<br />

certainty. Ulfers refers to him as the “embodiment of a language” that is involved in<br />

48


property and its relations, i.e., in its ‘proper’ signified or meaning, compared to a<br />

language that is irreducibly ‘allusive’, and thus a ‘signifier’ that is never ‘proper’ or with<br />

‘property’ (Lecture Notes, 3). In his attempts to force signification, Georg actively<br />

participates in the exclusion of all ambiguity. This dynamic is explored through Georg’s<br />

principal relationships; the figure of the friend, (the symbol of the undecidable) his fiancé<br />

Frieda, (the world of stable being) and his father (the figure of ambiguity).<br />

3.7 Narrative Rupture<br />

The first of the story’s narrative ruptures, and a clear example of Georg’s predilection<br />

toward stable being, occurs with Frieda’s statement concerning the couple’s engagement.<br />

Their conversation begins as a discussion of the peculiar relationship between Georg and<br />

the friend, but evolves into Frieda expressing offense at Georg’s failure to inform the<br />

friend of the couple’s news: “’So he won’t be coming to our wedding,’…‘and yet I have<br />

the right to meet all of your friends” (66). In a scene which seems to shatter the forward-<br />

moving narrative and disturb any realist reading of the story, Frieda, the figure of stable<br />

opposites remarks, “If you have such friends, Georg, you should never have even gotten<br />

engaged” (66). By its nature, engagement implies a movement from the unbounded, non-<br />

committal position of the bachelor towards the definition and role of the future husband.<br />

With the decision to become engaged, there is an intentional movement on Georg’s part<br />

toward the arena of stable opposites, the distinctly categorizable. Through this decision,<br />

Georg establishes a means by which he can be defined within the structures of binary<br />

opposition. As an engaged man, Georg becomes bound to the same world of stable being<br />

49


as Frieda. By becoming tied to her in this way and committing to marriage, Georg is<br />

capable of excluding the ambiguity of the both/and dynamic represented by his friend<br />

who is a bachelor.<br />

Therefore Frieda’s statement that he should, “never have even gotten engaged” points to<br />

her horror at his association with the “friend”, who is emblematic of the monstrous, the<br />

indeterminate and the undefined. “From the stand-point of stable opposites, of which she<br />

is a figure, and to which Georg has bound himself, a relationship with the friend is<br />

anathema because as ambiguity incarnate he is the monster that threatens the stable<br />

difference represented by the couple” (Ulfers, 5). There is no direct response by Georg to<br />

what in a realist reading is a non-sequiter other than his remark, “Well we both have that<br />

cross to bear, but now I wouldn’t have it any other way” (66). In this comment, Georg re-<br />

affirms that he was compelled to become engaged - as he can not imagine operating in<br />

the indeterminate space that the friend represents. He can not live in any “other way”<br />

(67). In becoming engaged, Georg flees the world of becoming, opting for the<br />

comfortable space of stable being and definition. This rupture then, functions within the<br />

narrative structure of the text to disrupt that world of stable opposition, to provide a<br />

glimpse of the world in process, the world of the friend which Georg tirelessly attempts<br />

to conceptualize.<br />

A second significant narrative rupture occurs in Georg’s conversation with his father<br />

about the friend in St. Petersburg. In recounting his composition of a letter to the friend,<br />

Georg’s father comments somewhat strangely, “You have no friend in St. Petersburg.<br />

50


You've always been one for pulling people's legs and you haven't hesitated even when it<br />

comes to me. How could you have a friend there, of all places! I can't believe it" (70).<br />

This is another instance in which Kafka departs from the story’s forward moving<br />

narrative flow in order to disrupt the reader’s comfort in the stability of being, and to<br />

present the world in a processual state.<br />

The friend serves as an embodiment of figurative or metaphorical language, the both/and,<br />

which interrupts the laws that rest upon what Barthes calls the “wall of antithesis.”<br />

Georg must separate from the friend in order to insert himself into normal society - as the<br />

friend is the figure of ambiguity which Georg must ward off. It is the paradigm of<br />

incessant process which the friend represents that Georg seeks to arrest and thus reduce to<br />

univocity that which is a multiplicity. Georg seeks to accomplish this with absolutely<br />

rigorous observation; he vows to observe everything “completely exactly” (71), which<br />

always involves the violence of repression and exclusion.<br />

Georg attempts to define the friend by the same recognizable categories that he does<br />

himself. The friend is a business failure where Georg is a success, a bachelor where<br />

Georg is engaged, a man living in a foreign land where Georg is the son who stayed at<br />

home and the “big child” (73) where Georg is an independent man. Yet in this search for<br />

unequivocal meaning, Georg excludes contradiction and ambiguity by artificially binding<br />

unique events and translating them into concepts. In an attempt to make the world<br />

comprehensible, he practices an exclusion that Blanchot’s remarks, “…is at work<br />

precisely at the very moment we are priding ourselves on our gift of universal<br />

51


comprehension” (The Work of Fire, 118). Thus, any literary interpretation which<br />

attempts to tie meaning to identity and concept is inherently limited. This second rupture<br />

serves to circumvent that violence of conceptualization by re-introducing process,<br />

thereby allowing for multiplicity to emerge.<br />

Georg has a compelling desire to be judged by his father, a desire which remains<br />

unfulfilled as the father does not provide for this closure. For Georg, definitive judgment<br />

would confirm and validate his world view, one in which there are clear conceptual<br />

delineations. His world must be categorized and conceptualized in order for smooth<br />

functioning to occur. Any other framework results in cognitive dissonance. The father<br />

does not participate in a judgment of the son, but rather in an “un-judging,” a withholding<br />

of any decision. He appears not as Georg would like to view him, as a figure of authority,<br />

but rather as one of ambiguity. The father is beyond the paradigmatic bifurcation which<br />

his son so desperately desires. By stating, “You have no friend in St. Petersburg” (if by<br />

friend as opposed to an enemy) the father functions to transgress the son’s paradigm of<br />

oppositional structure. His suspension of judgment denies the very possibility of the<br />

univocal meaning sought by the son, as the father does not operate in terms of the duality<br />

of friend versus enemy.<br />

To his father’s remark that he is without a friend in St. Petersburg, Georg responds,<br />

“What a comedian!...but he realized just as soon the damage that had been done, and only<br />

too late bit down-his eyes bulging- so hard on his tongue that he recoiled in pain” (73).<br />

The comedian or actor, operates neither in the space of absolute truth nor untruth, but in-<br />

52


etween. Georg recognizes that the father’s suspension of judgment constitutes this<br />

ambiguous space. Therefore he is compelled to react by his relentless drive to classify.<br />

By relegating the father to the status of comedian (an “actor” who does/can not judge)<br />

Georg is able to rationalize, to reduce to a playful jest the absence of definition. Yet<br />

again, Georg can only work within the world of opposition, (jest versus serious) and<br />

continues his attempts to reduce the father’s undecidability to a conceptual singularity.<br />

To this end Ulfers comments:<br />

As far as the father is concerned in this context, must we not infer that he, in his<br />

undoing the very notion of judgment, reveals himself as a kind of fraud in terms<br />

of the authority to judge and the concomitant seriousness and foundational aspect<br />

of the law? The text hints at that via Georg’s insight that the father is an “actor”<br />

(Komödiant), playing a masquerade, and the father’s saying that he is the “local<br />

representative” of the ‘friend” in Petersburg, that is, the “undecidability” or<br />

“playfulness” Georg desires to separate from by seeking the father’s “judgment”<br />

(Lecture Notes 3).<br />

The father comments on his collusion with the friend, communicating with him in letters<br />

without Georg’s knowledge:<br />

How you amused me today, coming to ask me if you should tell your friend about<br />

your engagement. He knows it already, you stupid boy, he knows it all! I've been<br />

writing to him, for you forgot to take my writing things away from me. That's<br />

why he hasn't been here for years, he knows everything a hundred times better<br />

than you do yourself, in his left hand he crumples your letters unopened while in<br />

his right hand he holds up my letters to read through! (74)<br />

Yet this is not the conspiracy the son interprets. Rather it shows an alignment between<br />

the father and friend paradigmatically. Much like the figure of the friend epitomizes<br />

53


undecidability, so does that of the father and his refusal to judge. In a scene widely read<br />

as containing the climactic “decision” of the father, what appears is quite different- a<br />

suspension of any decision. The scene serves not to posit the judgment of the son by the<br />

father, but to display that both the father and the friend represent the worldview in which<br />

teleology and the conceptualization of the absolute crumble.<br />

3.8 Death by Drowning:<br />

A final narrative rupture occurs in the father’s subsequent “condemnation” of Georg to<br />

death. Unanticipated from any realist narrative perspective, the father remarks:<br />

So now you know there is more in the world than just you. Till now you've<br />

known only about yourself! An innocent child, yes, that you were, truly, but still<br />

more truly have you been a devilish human being!--And therefore take note: I<br />

sentence you now to death by drowning! (75)<br />

The pronouncement of Georg as both “innocent child” and “diabolical human being” (75)<br />

by the father serves to further the argument that the text participates in a deconstruction<br />

of polar opposition. In his juxtaposition and combination of the concepts<br />

innocent/devilish and child/human being, the father speaks in terms of a mixture of<br />

generally recognized opposites (innocent child/ diabolical man). Rather than a clear<br />

delineation, he chooses to amalgamate mutually exclusive items. This choice calls<br />

attention to an underlying philosophy of process that Kafka embraced, which he allows<br />

us to glimpse through a momentary disruption of the structural constraints of<br />

conceptualization. The father’s reference to Georg as, “a more truly a diabolical man”<br />

54


(75) is particularly noteworthy as the term “truly” does not have a comparative that one<br />

could describe with “more”:<br />

First, the phrase “more truly a diabolical man” cannot be read as an opposite to<br />

“truly an innocent child.” Either something is “truly” or it is not. In other words,<br />

the hyperbolic “more truly” cannot be encompassed within a binary opposition<br />

structure and thus alludes to something “beyond.” This “beyond,” is hinted at by<br />

the etymology (which Kafka was very fond of exploiting) of the word<br />

“diabolical.” Etymologically the notion of “diabolical” is not an opposite at all,<br />

but implies an element that “scrambles” opposites (from Greek diaballein: to<br />

throw through one another). Georg thus is pronounced by the father as neither<br />

innocent nor its opposite, both innocent and its opposite (EGS Lecture Notes, 8).<br />

By linguistically transgressing polarity through the reference to an exaggerated “more<br />

truly,” the father shows himself to again be aligned with a neither/nor, both/and<br />

perspective, as he “un-judges” through a scrambling of the constructs innocent and<br />

diabolical. Thus the judgment pronounced by the father, “reveals himself as part of the<br />

‘undecidable’ [das Nicht-urteilbare] and is “not so much a judgment but an undoing of<br />

Georg’s unconscious de-cision [Urteil] to cut loose from the undecidable” (EGS Lecture<br />

Notes, 6).<br />

The father’s “sentencing” is problematic in translation, specifically in understanding the<br />

subtle variances between the transitive and intransitive forms of the German verb “to<br />

drown.” The German term that can be translated into English as “to drown” is<br />

“ertrinken” which alludes to an intransitive process. Now, it is to be noted that Kafka<br />

chooses the intransitive verb to refer to a judgment and execution (i.e. to acts that are by<br />

55


definition transitive) which would necessitate the use of “ertranken” - the transitive form<br />

of “to drown.” Whereas one would expect the use of the transitive form for this<br />

sentencing/execution, (actively being held under water in order to execute the sentence)<br />

Kafka instead uses the intransitive form. This leads to my inference that the use of<br />

“ertrinken” alludes to a judgment/execution that is between active and passive and thus<br />

amounts to the father’s suspension of judgment to the very end.<br />

After the imposition of the father’s “sentence,” Georg is described as feeling “forcibly<br />

driven from the room” (75) and “driven towards the water” (75) where he feels a<br />

compulsion to immerse himself in its fluidity. The fact that the water Georg immerses<br />

himself in is a river is no coincidence. Although he longs for the stability of univocal<br />

meaning, Georg feels a strange attraction to the water which is always in motion. At the<br />

moment he throws himself from the bridge, his visualization of, “the ceaselessness and<br />

diversity of the traffic” (76) again hints at the processual nature of the world which he has<br />

always denied. This final description of the transitory nature of being, “evokes the<br />

unending oscillation, the to and fro, of the textuality of life which no reading can de-cide<br />

(de-cipher)” (Ulfers 7). Yet his death need not be construed in opposition to his life, but<br />

contributing to the ontological perspective which always includes both life and death, but<br />

never has a preference for life over death. Thus Georg’s departure from the world<br />

suggests not to a departure in the sense of loss, as existence always involves the perpetual<br />

coming into, passing away, and renewal. What some may interpret as the protagonist’s<br />

final moments, can really only be understood as such within a teleological system.<br />

56


In closing, “The Judgment” provides numerous examples of narrative rupture functioning<br />

to disrupt the forward-moving trajectory of the story. Yet one should be wary of simply<br />

reducing these occurrences to departures from a movement toward finality and decision.<br />

To do so would be to underestimate the skepticism with which Kafka approached<br />

representational language. Kafka carefully utilized these disturbances to point to the<br />

structural problems of a utilitarian communicative theory, in which messages are seen to<br />

clearly pass from sender to recipient. In using these ruptures in “The Judgment,” Kafka<br />

points to the necessity of a linguistic and ontological paradigm shift toward a conception<br />

of Pure Mediality which is always immanent. His linguistic breakages allow us entry into<br />

this space of infinite network which utility and habit have obfuscated.<br />

57


“What is deferred forever till death is entry into the law itself, which nothing other<br />

than that which dictates the delay. The law prohibits by interfering with and with<br />

deferring the ‘ference’, the reference, the rapport, the relation. What must not and can<br />

not be approached is the origin of difference: it must not be presented or represented<br />

and above all not penetrated. That is the law of the law, the process of a law whose<br />

subject we can never say ‘There it is,’ it is here or there”<br />

58<br />

-Derrida, Signature, Event, Context<br />

“Our laws are not generally known; they are kept secret by the small group of nobles<br />

who rule us. We are convinced that these ancient laws are scrupulously administered;<br />

nevertheless it is an extremely painful thing to be ruled by laws that one does not<br />

know.”<br />

-Derrida “Problems of Our Laws”<br />

The Law Revisited: Deferred Judgment in “The Trial”<br />

4.1 The Nature of Law<br />

The Trial is another work in which Kafka explores the realm of the law, and implicitly<br />

the concept of judgment. Alongside this exploration, he gives insight into his<br />

communicative perspective, presenting a point of view on the language of <strong>literature</strong> as<br />

that which defies any attempt to be totalized or understood in the classical sense. The<br />

novel is not only a sophisticated exploration of the abstract ideas of innocence and guilt,<br />

but perhaps more importantly points to the fundamental human error of expecting of the<br />

world that which it is incapable of providing. In our endless search for metaphysical<br />

presence or stable being, we apply an erroneous causality to explain a world in process<br />

from a teleological perspective. In this creation of illusory meaning in an “outside”, we<br />

assign fixity to that which is only transitory.


While Kafka’s text probes the ideas of justice and truth, it also provides an opportunity to<br />

explore the “perpetual session” (107) of a court that his protagonist Joseph K. resists, and<br />

thus provides a glimpse of a process-oriented worldview that infinitely suspends decision.<br />

My approach in this chapter will be to first examine the depiction of the figures of the<br />

legal process in order to determine how the text’s deconstruction of their traditional roles<br />

points to the breakdown of a teleological paradigm. Additionally, I will examine Joseph<br />

K.’s interaction with the painter Titorelli in an attempt to explore his demands for<br />

absolute signification and utter resistance to suspended meaning. His need to understand<br />

completely and to know precisely stems from a paradigmatic belief that the world,<br />

particularly the world of the Law, operates in a logical, causal fashion. Unwilling to shift<br />

this paradigm, Joseph K. only experiences frustration in this interchange. Though<br />

Titorelli can provide Joseph K. with insight into some of the operating practices of the<br />

legal system, he can not provide him with the set of rules by which he can expect to play.<br />

This is the ambiguity against which Joseph K. revolts. In the novel’s ultimate irony, his<br />

need for absolute understanding shows him to be far more of an authoritarian than the<br />

novel’s other characters, so often accused of this offense.<br />

4.2 The Question of Access:<br />

A foundational principle of democratic societies involves the guarantee of individual<br />

access to a legal framework that allows a means and process for mediation in civil<br />

matters and the possibility for justice in criminal. This implies that it is a human right to<br />

exist within a world in which the individual is both free from undue persecution, and<br />

59


afforded an opportunity to rectify experiences perceived to be unjust. While this is not the<br />

promise of a just outcome, it is however minimal, the promise that a search for justice can<br />

be pursued via access to a neutral legal system. This system is not relative to individuals,<br />

but operates in a standardized way, through established rules and recognized practices.<br />

This principle of access to a fair and impartial legal system has come to manifest itself in<br />

the ethical codes of conduct and professional responsibilities of the system’s<br />

constituencies – namely attorneys 13 and judges. 14<br />

Yet this presumed right of universal access to the law 15 is radically challenged in The<br />

Trial. When confronted with arrest, Joseph K. expects an explanation of the charges<br />

brought against him. When attempting to resolve this situation in the courts, he assumes<br />

access to a fair and objective system which will allow him the opportunity for<br />

vindication. However, his experiences with various court constituencies, from magistrates<br />

13 A recent statement (February 2005) of The American Bar Association contains<br />

the following as a core principle: Access to justice for all people throughout the<br />

world, which is only possible with an independent legal profession and an<br />

impartial, and independent, judiciary.<br />

14 The following resolutions were by the American Judges Association: WHEREAS, THE<br />

PROTECTION OF RIGHTS AND ACCESS TO JUSTICE are inherent rights of all<br />

people; and WHEREAS, without access to the justice system, there is no justice, and the<br />

freedoms we celebrate today would be nothing but words; NOW, THEREFORE BE IT<br />

RESOLVED, that the American Judges Association hereby declares that protection of<br />

rights and access to justice of people who are poor, elderly, or with disabilities, are major<br />

goals that all judges and lawyers should seek to provide and protect; and be it further<br />

RESOLVED, that the American Judges Association encourages the development of ways<br />

and means of implementing the above goals, through activities that will improve the law,<br />

the legal system, and the administration of justice, for all people.<br />

15 Derrida’s essay “Before the Law” is the seminal text in the discussion of this theme<br />

from a deconstructive perspective.<br />

60


to clerks and judges, tell him something very different. His “rational” expectations of the<br />

legal system will remain largely unfulfilled. Throughout the novel, Joseph K. attempts to<br />

navigate this unknown territory of the Law, becoming increasingly frustrated with his<br />

failure to access and comprehend the legal system in which he must operate. He remarks:<br />

There can be no doubt that behind all the pronouncements of this court, there<br />

exists an extensive organization. An organization that not only engages corrupt<br />

guards, inane inspectors, and mediocre examining magistrate, but that supports as<br />

well a system of judges of all ranks, including the highest, with their inevitable<br />

entourage of assistants, scribes, cops, and other sides, perhaps even executioners.<br />

And the purpose of this extensive organization? It consists of arresting innocent<br />

people and introducing senseless proceedings against them, which go nowhere<br />

(179).<br />

Joseph K.’s understanding of the court and thus the law encompasses a set of pre-<br />

conceived notions from which he operates. In partaking in the legal process; he imagines<br />

that there are established, a priori rules of engagement. These rules somehow govern the<br />

process, placing parameters around what is proper or improper, appropriate or<br />

inappropriate. When faced with a process that does not correspond to this, Joseph K. is<br />

both horrified and dumbfounded. His experience of cognitive dissonance occurs as a<br />

result of his unwillingness to see transition, and not permanence as an ontological<br />

perspective. As such, the incommensurability between Joseph K.’s expectations and the<br />

world as it presents itself in his experience with the court reminds us of man's intrinsic<br />

inability to know completely or to judge finally. It demands of us a re-envisioning of<br />

ontology and epistemology which moves away from a world grounded in the absolute<br />

and toward a perspective of Pure Mediality.<br />

61


4.3 The Figures of Law:<br />

In an analysis of the legal process, the roles of key participating individuals must be<br />

examined, principally those of lawyers and judges. By nature, each of these roles<br />

inherently involves the formulation of a judgment derived from the separation of<br />

opposites. As the traditional nature of law is understood, both attorney and judge are part<br />

of a process which seeks to bring about a conclusive end. As such, these figures must, in<br />

order to fulfill their responsibility within this system, participate in a process of exclusion<br />

in order to ultimately lead toward definition. They are not only involved in decisions<br />

about which evidence will be considered or what mitigating circumstances may have<br />

occurred, but the much larger question of ultimate guilt or innocence. In this attempt to<br />

arrive at a decision, these figures are compelled to isolate meaning and exclude ambiguity<br />

in both a utilitarian and pragmatic manner:<br />

…law in order to be law…cannot render itself dependant upon anything but rather<br />

must establish itself as primordial ground, as the authority of the past. Yet in order<br />

to fashion itself as the fundamental ground upon which order and the mechanisms<br />

of ordering are built, the edifice of the law can not risk being equated with its<br />

performative power to judge and to enforce its decisions, but must be produced as<br />

an authoritative text that exists prior to its performance (Rast, 28).<br />

However, one must ask of the implications of having a court system comprised of<br />

attorneys and judges who regularly take part in a process whose very foundation requires<br />

exclusion. From a utilitarian perspective, this process seems to make sense; yet, does not<br />

this exclusionary process conceal the possibility of revealing a greater paradigmatic truth,<br />

“Truth with a capital T” (Pondron, 54)?<br />

62


Lawyers, sought as authorities and experts on the process of law, take part in a multitude<br />

of activities that involve conceptualization and judgment; they examine, decide,<br />

determine, and ultimately generate and present an argument in order to achieve an end.<br />

The lawyer works in the arena of writs, statutes, affidavits and injunctions. He acts as<br />

representative for his client in the public arena and prides himself on his skillfulness in<br />

oral and written argumentation. Perhaps most importantly, the lawyer uses an a priori set<br />

of rules, regulations and precedents in order to elicit a desired determination. Within this<br />

conception of the lawyer’s role, it is clear that any moment of wavering suspension, any<br />

brief flirtation with indeterminacy, is perceived as a sign of weakness. Thus judgment is<br />

demanded of this role, as the lawyer whose argument is inconclusive fails at a<br />

fundamental level.<br />

In The Trial, lawyers are largely portrayed as buffoons rather than as experts on the<br />

process of law. As opposed to being viewed as negotiators of a complex territory, the<br />

lawyer is merely endured, “For the defense is not actually countenanced by the Law, but<br />

only tolerated, and there is even some controversy as to whether the relevant passages of<br />

the Law can truly be construed to include even such tolerance” (114). For the most part,<br />

lawyers are portrayed as incompetent, having little direct effect on the proceedings,<br />

“…the first petition was generally misplaced or completely lost, and even if it was<br />

retained to the very end, the lawyer had only heard this by way of rumor…” (113) It is<br />

only through informal networking relationships that certain lawyers can effect positive<br />

developments for their clients, “…but it’s another matter when it comes to behind-the-<br />

scene efforts, in the conference rooms, in the corridors, or for example even here in the<br />

63


atelier” (150-151). Joseph K. finds lawyers to be of little practical use, deeming them<br />

ineffectual “shysters” (152) who only contribute to his frustration by adding another layer<br />

of bureaucracy to the legal process.<br />

The judge, the respected critical authority figure of the court, is perhaps the ultimate<br />

emblem of the absolute. He presides over and controls the courtroom as its chief<br />

administrator, determining what information is relevant to the case at hand, and<br />

controlling how the legal process is to be conducted. The judge is empowered to interpret<br />

how established laws are to be used in changing circumstances, and is furthermore<br />

charged with determining the extent of punitive damages. Yet judges in The Trial are<br />

depicted as status conscious, vain and likely corrupt. As opposed to their portrayal as<br />

independent arbitrators of the legal system, the text presents judges as more likely to be<br />

influenced by interpersonal relationships than actual evidence: “If the judges could really<br />

be swayed as easily through personal contacts as the lawyer had suggested, then the<br />

painter’s contacts with vain judges were particularly important and should by no means<br />

be underestimated” (151). The judge’s role becomes distorted in the text, as they<br />

transform into nothing more than capricious instruments of the law, armed with the<br />

ability to exert control indiscriminately: “If I were to paint all the judges in a row on this<br />

canvas and you were to plead your case before them, you would have more success than<br />

before the actual court” (149).<br />

64


4.4 The Question of Transparency<br />

Within standard legal proceedings, it is an expectation that written records be kept<br />

documenting not only indictments and causes for action, but also the eventual<br />

case outcomes. As decisions are made over time, precedent is established and re-<br />

established as a basis for future proceedings. These precedents are the baselines<br />

used by lawyers to argue their positions before the court, as well as to facilitate<br />

points of reference. At the conclusion of the legal process, it is the judge’s<br />

responsibility to publish a public record of the determinations made in the case.<br />

The importance of providing the public access to a written document which<br />

explains the rationale behind judicial decisions is of paramount importance. By<br />

making this information available and maintaining the transparency of the legal<br />

process, its integrity and fairness can be insured. One contemporary member of<br />

the judiciary states:<br />

The process of reasoning which has decided the case must itself be<br />

exposed to the light of day, so that all concerned may understand what<br />

principles and practice of law and logic are guiding the courts, and so that<br />

full publicity may be achieved which provides, on the one hand, a<br />

powerful protection against any tendency to judicial autocracy and against<br />

any erroneous suspicion of judicial wrongdoing and, on the other hand, an<br />

effective stimulant to judicial high performance. (Kitto, “Why Write<br />

Judgments” 790).<br />

Within the structure of the courts in The Trial, Joseph K. learns that the act of recording<br />

decisions is not practiced: “The proceedings are kept secret not only from the public, but<br />

65


from the accused as well…for even the accused has no access to the court records” (115).<br />

What this lack of information amounts to is the complete absence of a framework for<br />

understanding a system in which he must participate. Joseph K. first experiences this<br />

lack of information in receiving no justification for his arrest, nor revelation of the crimes<br />

of which he is accused, “You are under arrest certainly, but this need not hinder you from<br />

going about your business. Nor will you be prevented from leading your ordinary life”<br />

(20). His despondency is amplified when Titorelli informs him that:<br />

…the proceedings are not public, they can be made public if the court considers it<br />

necessary, but the Law does not insist upon it. As a result, the court records, and<br />

above all the writ of indictment, are not available to the accused and his defense<br />

lawyers, so that in general it’s not known, or not known precisely, what the first<br />

petition should be directed against…(113)<br />

This “unorthodox” system extends the withholding of knowledge from initial arrest to<br />

final decision, “The final verdicts of the court are not published, and not even the judges<br />

have access to them; thus only legend remains about ancient court cases” (154).<br />

However, this lack of access to information should not be construed as derived from<br />

some malignant intent on the part of the court. Rather, it might more accurately be<br />

attributed to Joseph K.’s fundamental error - expecting the court, and by extension the<br />

world, to operate in an end-oriented manner. As Kafka’s text deconstructs this telos,<br />

Joseph K.’s expectations of clarity and search for closure are perpetually frustrated. As<br />

Derrida observes, the same applies to all persons coming “before the law” seeking<br />

explicit resolution:<br />

…here is a situation where it is never a question of trial or judgment, nor of<br />

verdict or sentence, which is all the more terrifying. There is some law, some law<br />

66


which is not there but which exists. The judgment, however, does not arrive. In<br />

this other sense the man of nature is not only a subject of the law outside the law,<br />

he is also, in both an infinite and a finite way, the prejudged; not so much as a<br />

prejudged subject before a judgment which is always in preparation and always<br />

being deferred. Prejudged as having to be judged, arriving in advance of the law<br />

which only signifies ‘later’ (“Before the Law”, 206).<br />

Derrida is speaking here of a judgment that is always deferred, or perpetually<br />

delayed. This involves infinite referrals which never finally lead to a referent- an<br />

unceasing referentiality. Does Joseph K. respond in the same fashion as the man<br />

from the country, who accepts perpetually deferred access to the Law? No,<br />

Joseph K. is baffled by what he perceives to be a counterintuitive structure, and<br />

can not, or will not accept a court that allows for judgment to be deferred<br />

indefinitely. From his perspective, it is the role of the court to indict, convict and<br />

judge absolutely.<br />

4.5 Representing Justice<br />

One of the essential passages of the text in which Kafka explores aesthetic multiplicity<br />

and its relationship to the law is in Joseph K.’s conversation with the painter Titorelli.<br />

This exchange begins with a discussion of the painter’s artistic rendering of the “figure of<br />

justice.” Upon first glance, Joseph K. has a difficult time deciphering the image, as it<br />

does not conform to a traditionally fixed depiction. “He was unable to interpret a large<br />

figure centered atop the back of the throne. In order to understand the image, Joseph K<br />

must minimally take a second look, “…but then he held back for a moment and<br />

67


approached the picture as if he wanted to study it in detail” (145). It is only upon further<br />

examination that the image becomes clearer to him, “Now I recognize it…there’s the<br />

blindfold over her eyes and here are the scales. But aren’t those wings on her heels, and<br />

isn’t she in motion?...That’s a poor combination…justice must remain at rest, otherwise<br />

the scales sway and no judgment is possible” (145). Titorelli’s representation corresponds<br />

to a vision of justice (judgment) as always in-process. This is clear in the reference to the<br />

figure’s wings - likely an allusion to the oscillating nature of being. With regard to the<br />

motion of the figure, Joseph K. can not, or perhaps refuses to understand how an aesthetic<br />

depiction can be accurate if it shows uncertainty with representing the Law, where he<br />

supposes that there is a stable framework.<br />

Joseph K. finds this depiction troubling, as he believes the image should be represented in<br />

a definitive fashion, reflecting its “actual” appearance as opposed to an aesthetic<br />

interpretation. Any departure from a traditionally recognizable representation becomes<br />

problematic for him. Titorelli’s artistic rendering is anything but traditional: a hybrid<br />

which combines the figure of Justice with that of Victory. It is also no coincidence that<br />

we see here an “unfinished” (145) (in-process) representation, one that remains<br />

indefinable and subject to change. “What Titorelli’s paintings have in common with other<br />

texts that represent the Law is that they cannot be grasped, that they posses no efficacy,<br />

no firm or reliable substance; like the very text given the reader, the texts of the Law are<br />

adequate only to sustain for a while the hope of the one who inquires of them, not to<br />

reward that hope” (Grossvogel, 190).<br />

68


Within Joseph K.’s world view, representation can not involve the ambiguity of<br />

hybridity. He finds Titorelli’s hybridization of justice and victory distressing, and fails to<br />

recognize that the aesthetic is perhaps the one arena which refuses to totalize, a realm<br />

which will not allow itself to be subsumed by the either/or violence of conceptualization.<br />

Because Joseph K. has not moved toward a view of the law, and by extension, the world<br />

which is in perpetual flux, he can not help but experience anxiety with what he finds<br />

counterintuitive or unidentifiable. He continues to operate by a vision of law and<br />

representation that, “fundamentally relies upon ‘enforceability’, that is, upon the promise<br />

and possibility of referentiality, the possibility of punishment in the case of the law”<br />

(Rast, 28).<br />

As the conversation between Joseph K. and Titorelli evolves, we find the painter presents<br />

Joseph K. with an unpalatable view of the inner workings of the court. Not the<br />

organized, objective institution he believes it to be, Joseph K. learns that the law does not<br />

conduct itself by what he deems to be a rational set of principles. “A number of subtle<br />

points are involved in which the court loses its way. But then in the end it pulls out some<br />

profound guilt from somewhere where there was originally none at all” (149). Titorelli<br />

informs Joseph K. that his labors to prove his “absolute innocence” (148) will bear no<br />

fruit, as his foundational understanding of the court’s functionality is fundamentally<br />

flawed:<br />

We’re talking about two different things here, what the law says, and what I’ve<br />

experienced personally; you mustn’t confuse the two. In the Law, which I’ve<br />

never read, mind you, it says of course on the one hand that an innocent person is<br />

69


to be acquitted; on the other hand it does not say that judges can be influenced.<br />

My experience, however, has been precisely the opposite (153).<br />

However, Joseph K. remains convinced that he should allocate his energies toward<br />

demonstrating some error on the part of the institution of law while failing to reconsider<br />

his own expectations of the system.<br />

Joseph K. becomes puzzled with what might be called the courts’ locale and membership.<br />

In terms of locale, his understanding is tied to a formal sense of place. From his<br />

perspective, court proceedings would naturally occur in official locations and he therefore<br />

becomes bewildered when the painter remarks, “There are law court offices in practically<br />

every attic, why shouldn’t they be here too? In fact, my atelier is part of the law court<br />

offices too, but the court has placed it at my disposal” (164). He is unable to grasp the<br />

notion of proceedings occurring in such untraditional locations. For him, there needs to<br />

be a clear delineation between the official and unofficial, and any mixture or combination<br />

of what he sees as mutually exclusive horrifies him. He is unable to recognize a<br />

perspective in which, “…it is no longer possible regularly to contrast opposites, sexes<br />

possessions; it is no longer possible to safeguard an order of just equivalence; in a word it<br />

is no longer possible to represent, to make things representative, individuated, separate,<br />

assigned…(S/Z 215-216)<br />

This blurring of court locales is related to what might be called the court’s<br />

“membership.” He is shocked that even the children living within the painter’s building<br />

are considered constituent parts of the legal system. Joseph K. learns from Titorelli that,<br />

70


“Those girls belong to the court as well…Everything belongs to the court” (150). It is<br />

these very same children that Joseph K. describes as conveying a “mixture of<br />

childishness and depravity” (141) - a reference to the combination of opposites,<br />

(childishness/depravity) from which he experiences disgust. This combination of<br />

elements is what Barthes refers to when he remarks, "Every joining of two antithetical<br />

terms, every mixture, every conciliation—in short, every passage through the wall of the<br />

Antithesis—thus constitutes a transgression" (S/Z 12). It is Joseph K.’s inability to re-<br />

orient his worldview to this notion of mixture, continuing to see it as a “transgression” of<br />

mutually exclusive opposites.<br />

4.6 Acquittal: Incessantly Deferred<br />

The notion of judgment as being deferred indefinitely is intimately explored in<br />

Titorelli’s explanation of the “options” available to Joseph K. to pursue in his case. In<br />

this portion of the text, Titorelli offers three possibilities within the realm of the Law<br />

through which Joseph K. may seek relief. He refers to these as actual acquittal, apparent<br />

acquittal and protraction. One must note that the painter only offers these options as<br />

means to “pursue” relief, not as a guarantee of such. These opportunities essentially<br />

provide only a continuation of the process, not a conclusion. Joseph K. would still be<br />

involved in legal matters on some level, as the issues are never fully put to rest, and are<br />

capable of arising at some future time without warning.<br />

71


The first option, “actual acquittal”, involves the courts reaching a determination that<br />

solely relies upon the defendant’s guilt or innocence. I this case, an objective body of<br />

evidence by which a defendant can be judged finally emerges, and a judgment based<br />

upon these factual merits is rendered. This, of course, would provide Joseph K. with the<br />

most desirable conclusion to his case. However, he learns from Titorelli quickly that such<br />

an outcome is unattainable. “I never saw a single actual acquittal…such acquittals are<br />

said of have occurred, of course…but that’s extremely difficult to determine” (154). With<br />

actual acquittal, no outside help for the defendant is possible. Titorelli comments, “…I<br />

don’t have the slightest influence on that particular result. In my opinion, there’s not a<br />

single person anywhere who could have an influence on actual acquittal” (152). Actual<br />

acquittal would amount to an upholding of the “metaphysics of presence,” which is why<br />

within this unmediated system, it remains an impossibility. It is the solution most<br />

attractive to Joseph K. because it forgoes ambiguity, and constructs metaphysical stability<br />

upon a world of dynamic change.<br />

Another option, “apparent acquittal” involves a complex process through which a<br />

representative with access to the court - such as Titorelli - agrees to serve as guarantor of<br />

the defendant’s innocence. On the defendant’s behalf, he circulates a document attesting<br />

to this innocence for other judges to sign. The document is then brought to the trial<br />

judge, who in consideration, may choose to place a moratorium on the proceedings. The<br />

process then begins in Joseph K.’s words, “all over again” (159). Thus, the proceedings<br />

continue perpetually. Titorelli remarks, “When you are acquitted in this sense, it means<br />

the charge against you is dropped for the moment but continues to hover over you, and<br />

72


can be reinstated the moment an order comes from above” (158). This approach uses<br />

personal relationships with court figures to attain some sort of case decision; however<br />

that decision is not an ultimate one- it is always temporary. Titorelli tells Joseph K. that<br />

with apparent acquittal, he would be free to some extent, “but only apparently free, or<br />

more accurately, temporarily free. Judges on the lowest level, and those are the only ones<br />

I know, don’t have the power to grant final acquittal, that power only resides in the<br />

highest court, which is totally inaccessible to you and me and everyone else” (158). “Life<br />

under ostensible (apparent) acquittal reflects the worldview of modern scientific<br />

secularism, which knows no ultimate finality or certainty, no definitive answers, no<br />

ultimate solutions, no permanent goal, and above all no justification of human existence,<br />

and whose sole absolute is survival” (Sokel, 258).<br />

In the final scenario Titorelli offers what he calls “protraction” - a term which implies a<br />

prolonging or extending of the legal process indefinitely. This scenario requires the<br />

highest level of bureaucratic interaction with the figures of the court, but enables the trial<br />

to remain at its lowest possible stage- never garnering enough momentum to result in a<br />

conviction or judgment. The approach here is to keep the trial, “…constantly spinning<br />

within the tight circle to which it’s artificially restricted” (161). Thus the protracted<br />

case’s evolution is restricted, and judgment is deferred continually. Protraction brings<br />

with it a lack of ultimate security as, “No file is ever lost, and the court never forgets.<br />

Someday- quite unexpectedly- some judge or other takes a closer look at the file, realizes<br />

that the case is still active, and orders an immediate arrest” (158-159). At no time is the<br />

73


defendant granted a judgment in perpetuity that one could equate with ontological or<br />

epistemological permanence.<br />

Rather than providing for the closure Joseph K. so desperately desires, each of these<br />

options provides the absence of a structure of finality. It is this world of infinite<br />

possibility that Joseph K. rebels against - seeking to categorize and conceptualize at every<br />

turn. He is hardly the violated victim that existentialist critics would have us believe,<br />

harassed and tortured by bureaucratic chains and a system he is prohibited from<br />

understanding. Rather, he is a character who attempts to impose definition and closure<br />

upon a world which does not operate within these limits. Kafka’s protagonist incessantly<br />

looks to the outside- to authority figures such as lawyers, judges and the court system to<br />

provide him with explanations for his ordeal, but never once entertains the possibility that<br />

the paradigm in which he functions ontologically is inherently flawed. In a certain sense,<br />

Joseph K. holds the quintessential authoritarian position - as he is unwilling to<br />

compromise and demands absolute adherence to a pre-conceived configuration of<br />

existence.<br />

The end of the novel has Kafka return to the notion that literary language is not oriented<br />

towards closure. At the conclusion of the text, Kafka remains unwilling to fall back to the<br />

stability of definition. “… (A) Verdict is never pronounced in ‘The Trial.’ It is merely<br />

executed. The only voice coming anywhere near articulating judgment, in the sense of<br />

supplying a reason for execution, is Joseph K.’s own. From the very beginning of his<br />

arrest, K’s inner tendency is to arrive at a verdict that no one gives him, and that he<br />

74


finally gives himself” (Sokel, 253). Even the novel’s closing lines, “It was if the shame<br />

was going to outlive him” (266) points more to an evolving perspective on the nature of<br />

becoming; that is, the movement through and past language as art, to a non-<br />

representational art without a signified, that is, to the geometry of a circle on the<br />

circumference of which there are no privileged positions – no hierarchy – and every<br />

ending is undecidably related to a beginning, making any finality of judgment<br />

impossible. 16<br />

16 The sheer processuality of the court system is alluded to in the “secondary meaning of<br />

the German title of Kafka’s novel: Der Prozess. The primary meaning clearly is “Trial”<br />

which is coupled with the anticipation of a verdict or judgment. The secondary meaning<br />

– and this is the meaning that Joseph K. incessantly misreads is “Process” alluding to a<br />

process that as such, is potentially endless.<br />

75


“We will never ask what a book means, as signified or signifier; we will not look for<br />

anything to understand in it. We will ask what it functions with, in connection with<br />

what other things it does or does not transmit intensities…”<br />

-Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus<br />

“Literature itself is never anything but a single text: the one text is not an (inductive)<br />

access to a model, but entrance into a network with a thousand entrances; to take this<br />

entrance is to aim, ultimately, not at a legal structure of norms and departure, a<br />

narrative or poetic Law, but a perspective [...], whose vanishing point is nonetheless<br />

ceaselessly pushed back, mysteriously opened…”<br />

“Kafka’s Networks:” A Rhizomatic Approach to “The Metamorphosis”<br />

5.1 Rhizomatic Thinking<br />

76<br />

-Roland Barthes, S/Z<br />

The concept of network as explicated in the work of Deleuze and Guattari is of<br />

paramount importance to my discussion of Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong> and perspective on<br />

language. As I have already asserted, Kafka’s literary language does not seek to present<br />

itself as a mode of communication in which there is the assignment of a fixed or<br />

immutable meaning to the sign, but rather involves an infinite chain of signifiers without<br />

ultimate resolution in a signified. His literary texts, seen from the point of view of the<br />

unlimited passageways of a network, are able to operate in a space of crossover and<br />

hybridity, never establishing absolute presence. Kafka’s texts refuse to provide over-<br />

meaning, and function in a way that promotes the suspension of definition. As such, they<br />

aesthetically subvert the utilitarian paradigm which suggests that definitive meaning is<br />

communicated from a sender to a receiver.


This chapter examines Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of the rhizome as a linguistic and<br />

communicative model of which Kafka’s writing both foresees and partakes. By this I<br />

mean that his writing, with its inability to be totalized, navigates the space of<br />

indeterminacy, and functions as a-representational art. By eluding definitive meaning,<br />

and critical approaches that suggest as much, the texts themselves compel a radical re-<br />

envisioning of permanence and stability- transcending the either/or of oppositional<br />

thinking. I examine here “The Metamorphosis” in light of the movement by Deleuze and<br />

Guattari away from the hierarchal thinking of a “tree model” and toward a rhizomatic<br />

perspective that, “deterrorializes arbolic striated spaces and ways of being” (A Thousand<br />

Plateaus, 8). It is this perspective in which, “…no point must come before another, no<br />

specific point must be connected to another point, but all points are and must be<br />

connected” (7).<br />

I then move to a discussion of Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of the “becoming-animal”<br />

– a challenge to abandon the apparently common sense viewpoint by which judgments<br />

are made on the basis of partial human perception, and the subsequent call to merge<br />

ourselves with an entire ecology of perceptions. This is a transformation which, “lets<br />

nothing remain of the duality of a subject of enunciation and a subject of the statement;<br />

but rather constitutes a single process, a unique method that replaces subjectivity”<br />

(Toward a Minor Literature, 36). Not an aberration or regression, the becoming-animal<br />

implies the crossing of a threshold into a world of “absolute de-terriorialization,” (18)<br />

where there is “no longer anything but movements, vibrations, thresholds in a deserted<br />

matter” (129). Perhaps most importantly, the “becoming- animal” does not refer to the<br />

77


imitation of the animal, or “being animal” but rather points to an ontological<br />

intermingling in which the parameters of the human/animal opposition become too fuzzy<br />

to be differentiated. As such, the identity thinking which structures via the categories<br />

“human” or “animal” breaks down.<br />

Finally, I explore the idea of the monstrous in the text- focusing particularly on the<br />

relationship between monstrosity and demonstrative language. This is approached<br />

through an examination of Kafka’s use of metaphor, and his understanding of the power<br />

of metamorphic language. It also comes to light in the Samsa family’s position that what<br />

can not be known “clearly and precisely” (37), or absolutely, must be viewed as<br />

monstrous and horrifying. Via a discussion of the family’s denial of the abject, and their<br />

rejection of a transitory understanding of being, I hope to show Kafka’s keen awareness<br />

of this tension between demonstrative and metaphoric uses of language.<br />

5.2 A Departure from Arbolic Thinking:<br />

In their text A Thousand Plateaus, Deleuze and Guattari discuss the limitations of using<br />

an arbolic system as communicative model. This is primarily due to its implicit linear<br />

and hierarchical nature. They see the arbolic model as a totalizing construct, specifically<br />

designed to function as a restrictive stratum, imposing its forms on a maximum of flows,<br />

particles, and intensities. “Arborescent systems are hierarchical systems with centers of<br />

significance and subjectification” (17). Within this model, an element only receives<br />

information from a higher unit, and only receives a subjective affection along pre-<br />

78


established paths. This type of system is rooted in a binary logic which is, “…the spiritual<br />

reality of the root-tree." (5). Deleuze and Guattari call for the abolition of this model,<br />

remarking that, “We're tired of trees. We should stop believing in trees, roots, and<br />

radicles. They've made us suffer too much” (16). To strictly centered systems, the<br />

authors contrast a-centered systems, rhizomatic systems, in which communication runs<br />

from any neighbor to any other.<br />

The rhizome is, in botany, an underground, horizontal stem of a plant that often sends out<br />

roots and shoots from its nodes. Deleuze and Guattari move past this strictly botanical<br />

definition and toward an application of this concept to describe the interaction and<br />

relationality of entities in a general sense. The stems or channels of the rhizome do not<br />

pre-exist - they are defined only by their state at a given moment. “The rhizome is not a<br />

tracing mechanism, but is a map with multiple entry points. That is, maps can exist as<br />

themselves without need for anything outside of the map to exist while tracings can only<br />

exists as representations” (12). Deleuze and Guattari argue that any point in a rhizomatic<br />

system can be connected to any other point without partiality:<br />

It is composed not of units but of dimensions, or rather directions in motion... A<br />

rhizome has no beginning or end; it is always in the middle, between things,<br />

interbeing, intermezzo. The tree is filiation, but the rhizome is alliance, uniquely<br />

alliance. The tree imposes the verb 'to be', but the fabric of the rhizome is the<br />

conjunction, 'and...and...and...'. This conjunction carries enough force to shake<br />

and uproot the verb 'to be'... The middle is by no means an average; on the<br />

contrary, it is where things pick up speed... The rhizome operates by variation,<br />

expansion, conquest, capture, offshoots... (17)<br />

79


The rhizome is not reducible to a particular that is subsumable under a generality. It is<br />

rather a singularity comprised not of units but of dimensions, or rather directions in<br />

motion. “There are no points or positions in a rhizome, such as those found in a structure,<br />

tree, or root. There are only lines…unlike trees or their roots, the rhizome connects any<br />

point to any other point, and its traits are not necessarily linked to traits of the same<br />

nature…” (A Thousand Plateaus, 8) The rhizome has neither beginning nor end, but<br />

always middle. It constitutes multiplicities within dimensions having neither subject nor<br />

object, which can be laid out on a plane of consistency.<br />

Deleuze and Guattari then move to a discussion of how a rhizomatic model can be<br />

understood specifically from the point of view of language: “In the ideal text, the<br />

networks are many and interact, without any one being able to surpass the rest; this text is<br />

a galaxy of signifiers, not a structure of signifieds; it has no beginning, it is reversible; we<br />

gain access to it by several entrances, none of which can be authoritatively declared to be<br />

the main one...for the plural text, there cannot be a narrative structure, a grammar or a<br />

logic” (6). This perspective amounts to a deconstruction of the classical ontological<br />

perspective, involving a movement away from a system of stable being and toward one of<br />

infinite relationality. The rhizome principally can be seen as a model for apprehending<br />

the constitution and reception of a text. This labyrinthine model- an irreducible<br />

metaphoricity- extends itself to a conception of Kafka’s writing as Pure Mediality and<br />

treating Kafka texts as “a rhizome, a burrow” (A Thousand Plateaus, 8).<br />

Kafka’s literary activity was oriented toward a worldview that encompasses this<br />

rhizomatic and web-like approach. That is to say that his view of language is that it is<br />

80


always-already inter-connected, spreading easily through a co-mingling of equally<br />

weighted entities. All elements within this linguistic system are related to one another a-<br />

priori. This linkage is central to his aesthetics, and also is inherent to any perspective that<br />

leaves behind the structure of duality. Thus, Kafka’s texts operating as rhizome at no<br />

point seek to ascribe univocal interpretation of meaning, but rather consciously withhold<br />

any such attempt:<br />

Thus, the art that Kafka tried to introduce is effectively no longer an art that<br />

proposes to “express” (a meaning), to represent (a thing, a being), or to imitate (a<br />

nature). It is rather a method (of writing) that consists in propelling the most<br />

diverse contents on the basis of (non-signifying) ruptures and intertwinings of the<br />

most heterogeneous orders of signs and powers (Toward a Minor Literature,<br />

XVII).<br />

5.3 “Becoming-Animal”<br />

The attention that Kafka gives to food and nourishment in “The Metamorphosis” is of<br />

paramount importance to a discussion of his literary texts as operating rhizomatically - as<br />

neither food (nor music) serves in the text as a means toward bringing about gratification<br />

in the form of a transcendental signified. On the contrary, we see a profound critique of<br />

signification masquerading itself as the real. By understanding the function of food<br />

practically, as an agent to satisfy hunger, we are immediately speaking of a relationship<br />

of utility; with food serving as a means toward achieving a goal, nutrition. It becomes<br />

clear though, that in this context, fresh food does not satisfy, if by satisfy we mean<br />

address a lack or make complete. Even though ravenously hungry, the “becoming<br />

81


animal” Gregor experiences a profound disgust with the fresh milk he is offered to eat by<br />

his sister Grete:<br />

He almost laughed with joy, for he now had a much greater hunger than in the<br />

morning, and he immediately dipped his head almost up to and over his eyes<br />

down into the milk. But he soon drew it back again in disappointment…because<br />

the milk, which otherwise was his favorite drink and which his sister had certainly<br />

placed there for that reason, did not appeal to him at all. He turned away from the<br />

bowl almost with aversion and crept back into the middle of the room. (16)<br />

Fresh food is no longer desirable, as it belongs to the world of absolute signification- of<br />

which he is no longer part. Any attempt by Gregor to attain nourishment via this food<br />

will leave him invariably unsatisfied. “The fresh food, by contrast, didn't taste good to<br />

him. He couldn't bear the smell and even carried the things he wanted to eat a little<br />

distance away” (18). This revulsion is one elicited by the presence of the absolute or<br />

permanent which no longer applies to the “becoming- animal” in a state of transition.<br />

Gregor now operates in an environment which is not oriented toward some distant goal,<br />

being, but is discontinuous, interrupted, incoherent, full of gaps within itself. His world is<br />

now non-sequential - comparable linguistically to a sentence with abrupt breaches in<br />

syntax.<br />

Julia Kristeva refers to Gregor’s revulsion as an experience of “abjection” – that which<br />

results from transgressing the boundaries of previously stable opposites.<br />

Characteristically, the abject, “does not respect borders” and “functions as the ‘in-<br />

between’ of borders....at the boundary of what is assimilable, thinkable…” (Powers of<br />

Horror, 117) Abjection is a response to the co-mingling of opposites, in a place where<br />

82


singular identity collapses and indeterminate multiplicity emerges. Kristeva speaks<br />

directly to this experience of the abject with regard to food:<br />

Food loathing is perhaps the most elementary and most archaic form of abjection.<br />

When the eyes see or the lips touch that skin on the surface of milk - harmless,<br />

thin as a sheet of cigarette paper, pitiful as a nail pairing - I experience a gagging<br />

sensation and, still farther down, spasms in the stomach, the belly; and all the<br />

organs shrivel up the body, provoke tears and bile, increase heartbeat, cause<br />

forehead and hands to perspire (Powers of Horror, 117).<br />

Gregor’s experience of the abject correlates directly to his transformation, as he now<br />

occupies the state of the in-between, neither fully human nor inhuman. He reacts to what<br />

he experiences as, “…one of those violent, dark revolts of being, directed against a threat<br />

that seems to emanate from an exorbitant outside or inside, ejected beyond the scope of<br />

the possible, the tolerable, the thinkable” (Powers of Horror, 114). In place of what was<br />

once stable identity he is faced with a new variable constitution, one that no longer<br />

capable of providing singular definition. Moving from an arbolic to a rhizomatic<br />

paradigm elicits this experience of abjection, as the rhizomatic model does not provide<br />

for the hierarchical structure or stable substance which would allow for the type of<br />

categorization that Gregor seeks.<br />

What now becomes attractive in place of fresh foods are articles in the process of<br />

decaying and food that is decomposing. It is only this transitory matter that comes to<br />

excite the “becoming – animal”:<br />

83


There were old half-rotten vegetables, bones from the evening meal, covered with<br />

a white sauce which had almost solidified, some raisins and almonds, cheese<br />

which Gregor had declared inedible two days earlier... In addition to all this, she<br />

put down a bowl—probably designated once and for all as Gregor's—into which<br />

she had poured some water... Gregor's small limbs buzzed now that the time for<br />

eating had come. (18)<br />

It is in their provisional nature that these objects hold allure for him. This is because the<br />

decaying food bears a likeness to his in-between state. The food can no longer be<br />

categorized as such, as it is neither fresh nor completely decomposed, but in a state of<br />

becoming. It does not seek to serve the explicit purpose of nourishment, or exist with a<br />

strictly functional goal. It is transitional, and not fit for “human” consumption, which is<br />

why it is attractive to the “ungeheuer.” I contend that Gregor’s predilection for these<br />

transitional objects amounts to a subversion of the poles of binary opposition and thereby<br />

provides a glimpse into a Pure Mediality in which a transcendental signified is never<br />

reached. This Pure Mediality runs congruent to Deleuze and Guattari’s rhizomatic<br />

approach to reading Gregor as “becoming - animal”:<br />

To become animal is to participate in movement…to cross a threshold, to reach a<br />

continuum of intensities that are valuable only in themselves, to find a world of<br />

<strong>pure</strong> intensities where all forms come undone, as do all the significations,<br />

signifiers and signifieds, to the benefit of an unformed matter of de-territorialized<br />

flux, of non-signifying signs (Towards a Minor Literature, 13).<br />

If bodily self-control is the prerequisite to membership in the world of the human, then<br />

we see another instance of Gregor losing this identity in his inability to control his insect<br />

limbs. These new “animal” legs are described as being involved in rapid wriggling and<br />

84


vibration over which Gregor has no power, “…he had only many small limbs which<br />

were incessantly moving with very different motions and which, in addition, he was<br />

unable to control” (14). Much like the structure of the rhizome, his limbs are not under<br />

the control of an organizing will nor central controlling agent. There is no hierarchical<br />

structure in place that is at work directing their operation. Thus, much like fresh food<br />

does not serve some utilitarian function in his transitory state, neither do these new<br />

extremities.<br />

5.4 Food and Decay: The Unknown Nourishment:<br />

From the point of view of aesthetics, the promise of art has always presumably been to<br />

fill a human need which, because of its constraints, logic and reason can not. With this in<br />

mind, one should not overlook the similarity between the role of the decaying food in<br />

“The Metamorphosis” and that of music 17 . Much like food, music does not provide for<br />

stability, permanence or absolute presence. Kafka recognized the inherent qualities of<br />

music to be its temporal and relational nature. Its very essence requires it to be<br />

continually involved in movement and change, with the end of the musical piece, its final<br />

note, never corresponding to its goal. It is then no coincidence that it is in this experience<br />

of the processual nature of music that the metamorphosing Gregor experiences “unknown<br />

nourishment”:<br />

For him it was as if the way to the unknown nourishment he craved was revealing<br />

itself. He was determined to press forward right to his sister, to tug at her dress,<br />

17 Though I discuss it here briefly, I dedicate the entirety of the next chapter to the role of<br />

music in Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong>.<br />

85


and to indicate to her in this way that she might still come with her violin into his<br />

room, because here no one valued the recital as he wanted to value it. (36).<br />

Recognizing that the music exerted a force upon him that was beyond his control, Gregor<br />

begins to self-question: “Was he an animal that music could move him so” (36)? This<br />

questioning indicates an inability to move beyond the structural dichotomy of animal<br />

versus human. “Gregor hangs between two worlds—between the insect and human<br />

worlds. For Gregor to complete the metamorphosis, he must willingly leave behind the<br />

human world of consciousness and language” (Lippit, 146).<br />

His transformation should mandate accommodation to rhizomatic operationality, without<br />

reliance upon pre-ordained structures which seek to force definition through the process<br />

of exclusion. Nevertheless, he makes attempts to adhere to his previous stable identity, to<br />

the world of the human. By defining his status through its opposite- the inhuman- the<br />

animal, Gregor continues to frame his existence via oppositional thinking. Rather than<br />

shifting paradigmatically from a perspective of absolute being to one of perpetual<br />

becoming, his reference to “animal-like” tendencies still only involves conceiving of the<br />

identity “animal” as opposite to the “human.”<br />

Gregor, clinging to a semblance of “human” identity, panics, and in an attempt to retain<br />

some remnant of this identity, responds to Grete removing the items in his room by<br />

frantically grasping on to the hanging picture which he himself had once framed:<br />

…he really didn’t know what to salvage first, then he saw hanging conspicuously<br />

on the wall, which was otherwise bare already, the picture of the lady all dressed<br />

86


in furs, hurriedly crawled up on it and pressed himself against the glass, which<br />

gave a good surface to stick to and soothed his hot belly. At least no one would<br />

take away this picture while Gregor completely covered it up (26).<br />

Gregor’s attempt to keep possession of this framed picture, a remnant of his human<br />

identity, is interesting in an ontological context. It points to the problematic worldview<br />

that understands content and format (medium/message) as intrinsically separate. It also<br />

makes apparent the demands of this framework that process be contained within<br />

absolutist constructs. As the woman in the picture has half of her arm covered in fur, (the<br />

animal) the image itself represents Gregor’s transitionary state, that of the “becoming -<br />

animal”, or that which can not be categorized within the identities human or animal.<br />

Gregor’s operating principles require that parameters be placed around becoming in order<br />

to frame that which by its nature is unruly. By this I mean that that some type of form is<br />

necessary to ensure that this previously unruly content can be categorically organized in<br />

order to make it palatable. This type of framed perspective is that which allows us to<br />

clearly delineate, to exclude with a surgical precision, the strangeness that does not fit.<br />

We are especially predisposed to exclude when it comes to the kind of “content” which<br />

involves the illicit mixture of opposites. Gregor’s attempt to hold onto this picture<br />

indicates at this stage, a holding on to the identity “human” – a remnant of the enframing<br />

that makes us a final subject - whereas the picture symbolically represents the structure of<br />

a human identity, and abandoning it would require him to begin to let go of that identity.<br />

Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong> works on the level of deconstructing the need for this framing,<br />

removing the content/form and human/animal oppositional structures, thereby allowing<br />

87


for this uncontained state to freely emerge. It goes back “before the law” began the<br />

process of defining the rules of containment and framing. Kafka’s work takes part in<br />

what might be called the un-framing of utilitarian opposition, and moves towards a<br />

rhizomatic perspective that encourages an ontology of becoming. Kafka was highly<br />

cognizant of the relationship between writing and becoming as described by Deleuze and<br />

Guattari:<br />

To write is certainly not to impose a form (of expression) on the matter of lived<br />

experience. Writing is a question of becoming, always incomplete, always in the<br />

midst of being formed, and goes beyond the matter of any livable or lived<br />

experience. Writing is inseparable from becoming: in writing, one becomes-<br />

woman, becomes-animal or vegetable, becomes-molecule to the point of<br />

becoming-imperceptible” (Literature and Life, 94).<br />

Through his use of allusive language, which achieves only temporary meaning, suspends<br />

judgment and withdraws from permanence, Kafka points to the fact that we betray the<br />

unruly by attempting to frame it. The text thus comes to work as a rhizome, in which<br />

unruly content is not judged as such, as the previously requisite hierarchical structure is<br />

no longer the working model.<br />

Gregor’s mother disagrees with Grete, believing that perhaps the family should not<br />

remove her Gregor’s personal belongings from his room. She remarks, “I think it would<br />

be best if we tried to keep the room exactly in the condition it was in before, so that,<br />

when Gregor returns to us, he finds everything unchanged and can forget the intervening<br />

time all the more easily" (24). In her reluctance to make these changes, to remove the<br />

88


items which are emblematic of her son’s human identity, she attempts to hold on to any<br />

last semblance of the world of which Gregor was once part. In her comment, “They were<br />

clearing out his room; depriving him of everything he loved…” (24), she too indicates a<br />

refusal to accept Gregor’s current state, as she can only think of these items in terms of<br />

Gregor’s former relationship with them. In her comments, we see her hope that Gregor<br />

will return to his previous identifiable state. But this return is not possible, as Gregor has<br />

forever departed from the world of stable being and clearly discernible identity.<br />

At this point in the text, a movement begins on the part of Grete to linguistically de-<br />

personalize Gregor, as she proceeds to identify him as no longer existing within the<br />

constructs of the human. In place of his previous identity as “brother” we now see his<br />

identity transform to that of an “animal.”: “But how can it be Gregor? If it were Gregor,<br />

he would have long ago realized that a communal life among human beings is not<br />

possible with such an animal and would have gone away voluntarily. Then we would not<br />

have a brother, but we could go on living and honor his memory. But this animal plagues<br />

us” (38). Gregor’s failure to fit into the constructs of the human results in the relegation<br />

of his status to that of a monstrosity. It is now this neither/nor monstrosity that must be<br />

precluded from participating in their human community.<br />

In order to release themselves from the burden of this monstrosity, the family must<br />

exclude him/it:<br />

"If he only understood us," repeated the father and by shutting his eyes he<br />

absorbed the sister's conviction of the impossibility of this point, "then perhaps<br />

89


some compromise would be possible with him. But as it is. . ." "It must be gotten<br />

rid of," cried the sister. "That is the only way, father. You must try to get rid of<br />

the idea that this is Gregor (37).<br />

This passage is also of interest from a grammatical perspective. Grete changes her<br />

pronoun usage in referring to Gregor, no longer utilizing “him.” She now turns to a usage<br />

in which Gregor becomes de-humanized, an “it.” This shift is indicative of her inability to<br />

cope with Gregor’s non-categorizable state. It thus becomes clear that what remains<br />

indeterminate, that which can not be assimilated, must invariably be done away with:<br />

Things cannot go on any longer in this way. Maybe if you don't understand that,<br />

well, I do. I will not utter my brother's name in front of this monster 18 , and thus I<br />

say only that we must try to get rid of it. We have tried what is humanly possible<br />

to take care of it and to be patient. I believe that no one can criticize us in the<br />

slightest (37).<br />

Her movement from the subjectivity of the human to the “inhuman it” is a result of her<br />

need for a stable means by which to identify. However, this is a stability which can no<br />

longer be ascribed to Gregor. In a final movement, Grete ceases referring to Gregor as an<br />

“animal” and finally begins to refer to him in the pejorative, as a “monster.”<br />

5.5 The Violence of Demonstrative Language:<br />

The relationship between the becoming-animal’s monstrosity and figurative expression is<br />

one which can be traced back to the understanding which Kafka had of the dynamic<br />

18 Emphasis mine.<br />

90


possibilities of literary language. He was of the position that only an a-representative<br />

communication involving metaphor and allusion is capable of circumventing the<br />

conceptualization inherent to demonstrative language, and thus allow for operation within<br />

the rhizomatic. His approach to writing is one which revolves around the, “staging of a<br />

contest between the conceptual and the metaphorical aspects of language, with the latter,<br />

as the language of "allusion," informing Kafka's ‘writing self’…” (Ulfers, 3) In a similar<br />

sense, Sokel remarks:<br />

This allusive use of language is obviously the kind of writing toward which Kafka<br />

aspired …language- i.e., a very special kind of non-referential, merely allusive<br />

language- is a means by which human beings may receive an inkling of the<br />

invisible, true world …To be sure, language can never hope to represent the<br />

extrasensory reality, but it can hope to point toward it and thus sharpen human<br />

awareness for it…The way for <strong>literature</strong> is therefore not to try to express the truth,<br />

but to hint at it by showing the undoing of untruth” (Sokel, 180).<br />

In Kafka’s view, it is only in a poetic or metaphoric language that “truth,” if we may<br />

speak of it, momentarily emerges or is hinted at. This type of literary language takes<br />

away the power of premature judgment and promotes the enfolding of opposites into one<br />

another- as metaphor does not seek engagement with absolute judgment or decision. As a<br />

result, his writing amounts to a conscious undermining of instrumentality and the goal of<br />

definitive comprehension.<br />

Conversely, a demonstrative language is one that is judged, discreet, isolated, calculable,<br />

countable and atomistic. Its promise of absolute signification involves a forced<br />

91


formulation of judgment. By its very nature, demonstrative language is exclusionary as it<br />

always aims at providing for the illusion of permanence. Comprehension in this light,<br />

becomes the process of taking that which is radically unique and arranging it within<br />

utilitarian categories of classification. Etymologically speaking, the term “demonstrate”<br />

is interesting for purposes of this discussion. The infinitive verb “monstrare” from the<br />

Latin translates in English into, “to show” (Mirriam-Webster, 2004), from which we<br />

derive the English term “to demonstrate.” Demonstration thus involves a presentation, a<br />

type of monstrous showing that according to Hartman, “…is a sham; it is not a science<br />

but a pragmatic and consensual exercise; one that can distract from the true cogency of<br />

speech by interposing a mechanistic model of communication” (Saving the Text, 120).<br />

Kafka was highly suspicious of the use and effects of a <strong>pure</strong>ly demonstrative form of<br />

language. For him, this type of language fosters both a limited aesthetics because it fails<br />

to allow for a multiplicity of interpretations and refuses to permit for the suspension of<br />

absolute meaning. Rather than upholding the classical signifier/signified relationship<br />

inherent to demonstrative language, Kafka’s writing disrupts that system by advocating<br />

through his use if figurative language, an a-representational communicative model that.<br />

“…disturbs the alliance of signifier with signified by deconstructing a stable ‘concept’<br />

(the glue that holds them together), or by undoing the ‘unique’ charm of particular texts:<br />

the illusion that they have a direct, even original, relation to what they<br />

represent…presence is thus a ghostly effet de realite produced by words, and is dispelled<br />

by the same means (Saving The Text, 121).<br />

92


Corngold, who writes extensively about the role of metaphor in Kafka’s work, claims that<br />

the author tampers with metaphor, and that this tampering is the very “spring of Kafka’s<br />

revolutionary force” (16). He points to the relationship between metaphor and<br />

monstrosity as one that intrinsically tied to metamorphosis. He remarks, “If I carry over<br />

from the vehicle to tenor properties in excess of the metaphor, such as the automatic<br />

adjuration and violent punishment which a devil calls forth—if I carry this violence over<br />

to a son--- then I have made the metaphor monstrous” (Lambent Traces, 15). According<br />

to him, “The Metamorphosis” as a text can be read as a metaphor for becoming in the<br />

“capacity of metaphor to engender monstrosity” (19).<br />

More than anything else, it is the movement towards a rhizomatic perspective<br />

which The Metamorphosis challenges its readers to embrace. The text works<br />

without hierarchy of structure, in which its networks are, “many and interact,<br />

without anyone being able to surpass the rest; this text is a galaxy of signifiers,<br />

not a structure of signifieds; it has no beginning, it is reversible; we gain access to<br />

it by several entrances, none of which can be authoritatively declared to be the<br />

main one…"(S/Z 6). Kafka’s accomplishes this deconstruction via a language<br />

that is radically infinite, and profoundly a-representational. In summary, his<br />

writing serves as a reminder of the “truth” we must, “simplify and thereby falsify,<br />

as well as repress, but which asserts itself in modern thought, <strong>literature</strong>, and art”<br />

(EGS Lecture Notes, 4). Any insistence upon holding fast to an understanding of<br />

being within an arbolic system will invariably lead us toward an inadequate<br />

reading of the work as, “Any <strong>pure</strong>ly ideological reading of Kafka… will miss<br />

[his] most original contribution: the figuration of that which dooms interpretation<br />

93


to failure, even a correct one… Gregor’s abjection is…more than a symptom to<br />

be read and decoded, more than a condensation of social forces or contradictions”<br />

(Santer 11).<br />

94


“I’ve often wondered whether music might not be the unique example of what might<br />

have been - if the invention of language had not intervened - the means of<br />

communication between souls.”<br />

95<br />

-Proust<br />

“We see that <strong>literature</strong>s are in fact arts of "noise"; what the reader consumes is this<br />

defect in communication, this deficient message; what the whole structuration erects<br />

for him and offers him as the most precious nourishment is a counter-communication;<br />

the reader is an accomplice, not of this or that character, but of the discourse itself<br />

insofar as it plays on the division of reception, the impurity of communication…<br />

Whereby we see that writing is not the communication of a message which starts from<br />

the author and proceeds to the reader; it is specifically the voice of reading itself: in the<br />

text, only the reader speaks.”<br />

Music and Pure Mediality:<br />

6.1 Music as A-Representative Art:<br />

-Barthes, S/Z<br />

One important aspect in Kafka’s attempt to achieve Pure Mediality in his writing is the<br />

role of music. In this chapter, I wish to discuss the phenomenon. Certain fundamental<br />

questions arise when we consider music: its aesthetic role and perhaps its communicative<br />

functionality. Does music exist solely as an artistic phenomenon which functions to bring<br />

about some ultimate sense of meaning? Is it communicating a message, and if so, is that<br />

message communicated between a sender (musician) and a recipient (listener)? Further, is<br />

music related to language, perhaps as some other form of language, or is it actually an<br />

escape from the limitations inherent to the linguistic?


Throughout my reading of Kafka’s texts I have discussed his use of language as <strong>pure</strong>, and<br />

thus not a utilitarian tool toward some teleological goal. I have argued that Kafka uses<br />

language to undermine the structuralist signifier/signified relationship and expose its<br />

inherent metaphysics. I seek now to explore the role of music as a medium that is an<br />

expression of the un-signified. Only via music, which models process thinking through<br />

its transitory and relational qualities, might a-metaphysical, a-representational<br />

communication occur.<br />

Although Kafka admits in his diaries that he felt no great appreciation for music, the<br />

presence of the musical, and more precisely the presence of music as a-representational<br />

art is present in many of his works. I focus here on two of Kafka’s works, namely “The<br />

Metamorphosis” and “Josephine the Singer, or The Mouse-Folk.” I contend that music,<br />

through its temporal and allusive nature, transcends the typical sender-receiver<br />

communicative model and exists on a plane apart from the strictly utilitarian. Music can<br />

be seen in this light as a signifying process never resolving in a signified. This has<br />

tremendous consequences for a study of the role of music in Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong>.<br />

Consideration must now be given to items such as the suspended chord and atonal music<br />

which do not allow for classical resolution, but rather infinite transition. This new way of<br />

conceiving Kafka’s communicative point of view compels a re-evaluation of his literary<br />

work and aesthetic sensibility in light of Pure Mediality.<br />

96


6.2 Music and Language:<br />

Many classical musicologists have applied to music the same treatment given to<br />

linguistics. From this point of view, music is conceived as a form of mediation which<br />

follows the sender-receiver model, participating in the communication of a message<br />

through another form of language - a musical language. This musical language is<br />

structured, signifying and strictly hierarchical. It corresponds to a given set of rules which<br />

govern its creation and articulation with regard to its constituent elements such as key,<br />

rhythm and melody. This representational model in which music is conceived of as an<br />

aesthetic medium which seeks only to communicate a message to its listener faces the<br />

same problems and limitations as the structuralist linguistic theory I have discussed<br />

previously. As Nietzsche recognizes in The Birth of Tragedy, “Language, as the organ<br />

and symbol of phenomena, can never by any means disclose the innermost heart of<br />

music; language, in its attempt to imitate it, can only be in superficial contact with music”<br />

(55). Thus, it would be an error to simply apply the rules of conceptual language to the<br />

domain of music.<br />

From an a-representational perspective, music can be seen as a medium which<br />

circumvents signification and thereby allows for communication without telos. In his<br />

Essays on Music, Adorno argues that music operates by a “different law” (116)<br />

concluding that musical interaction both retains and transgresses meaning whereas<br />

signifying language must endlessly point toward the “impossible” (116). He continues:<br />

Music shows its similarity to language once more that, like signifying language, it<br />

is sent, failing on a wandering journey of endless mediation to bring home the<br />

97


impossible. Except that its mediation unfolds according to a different law from<br />

that of signifying language, not in meanings that refer to each other, but in their<br />

mortal absorption into a context that preserves meaning even as it moves beyond<br />

that meaning with every motion (116).<br />

Music, which encompasses both form and content, which suggests in a subtle way rather<br />

than defines, which comes into being and passes away, inherently allows for radical<br />

undecidability. Music might be conceived of as an a-teleological art that transgresses the<br />

merely linguistic - “the show that does not show” which does not seek to represent<br />

something outside of itself. By remaining always ambiguous and allusive, music can<br />

only be likened to the figurative language of metaphor, which seeks to relate only<br />

indirectly.<br />

This ontological and aesthetic perspective is echoed in the contemporary work of<br />

composers, such as John Cage, who argue that certain types of music, because they<br />

operate in a sphere apart from opposition, are capable of showing a more “authentic”<br />

vision of the world - one that is neither absolute nor stable, but in process. Cage believes<br />

that music is capable of showing the world in its original state, prior to the distortion<br />

which occurs in the process of conceptualization. He remarks:<br />

Before we wished for logical experiences; nothing was more important to us than<br />

stability. What we hope for is the experience of that which is. But ‘what is’ is not<br />

necessarily the stable, the immutable. We do know quite clearly, in any case, that<br />

it is we who bring logic into the picture. It is not laid out before us waiting for us<br />

to discover it. ‘What is’ does not depend on us, we depend on it. […] And<br />

unfortunately for logic, everything we understand under that rubric ‘logic’<br />

98


epresents such a simplification with regard to the event and what really happens,<br />

that we must learn to keep away from it (A Year From Monday, 80).<br />

Thus for Cage, music involves both presence and absence as its existence involves<br />

passing into and out of being. He speaks of the insight into a “real” whose terms are<br />

complementarities, such as “presence and absence, together,” as “wisdom”: “…the<br />

thought of wisdom … which reveals in each term of duality the complement of the<br />

other…” (94). Elsewhere, he expresses that: “…the situation must be yes-and-no, not<br />

either-or. Avoid polar situations” (79). He recognizes clearly that music functions in a<br />

way that transcends oppositional structures. As music is experienced not as written<br />

notation, but as a series of physical vibrations occurring over time, musical “presence” is<br />

at once always fleeting, and can only be spoken of through the relationship of the<br />

vibrating tones to one another. Additionally, like Kafka, Cage makes use of disturbance<br />

and dissonance within the aesthetic to interrupt any linear temporal or spatial expectation.<br />

Noise functions not as a departure from music, but as a differently conceived musical<br />

paradigm.<br />

6.3 From Tonality to Atonality:<br />

One can understand musical tonality as, "the organized relationship of tones with<br />

reference to a definite center, the tonic, and generally to a community of pitch classes,<br />

called a scale, of which the tonic is the principle tone; sometimes also synonymous with<br />

key” (New Harvard Dictionary of Music). It involves the organized relationship of<br />

musical sounds, as perceived and interpreted with respect to some central point of<br />

99


eference that seems to co-ordinate the separate musical items and events, and to lend<br />

them meaning as component parts of a unified whole. By its nature, this system must<br />

function through a series of rules and prohibitions on pitch relationships and their<br />

relationship to a tonic center. In particular, what are prohibited in a tonal composition are<br />

repeated dissonances, in other words, critiques of differences. In his text A Time of Need,<br />

Barrett discusses tonal music:<br />

The whole of tonal music was a magnificent and elaborate artifice built upon a<br />

very simple foundation: the key with its tonic and dominant tones. However<br />

intricate his variations, however surprising and complex his harmonies, the<br />

composer must return to the tonic. After many wanderings through which we<br />

were never homeless, we do in fact come home… (229)<br />

Tonal music is therefore a clearly delineated system which the composer accommodates<br />

himself to working within. It provides very distinct parameters around which the musical<br />

composition can be created. Faced with a finite series of aesthetic options, twentieth<br />

century composers sought to not only challenge the limits of tonal systems, but more<br />

importantly, to deconstruct the system which by virtue of its structure, imposes these<br />

aesthetic limitations.<br />

Atonal, a departure from the structure of the tonic - is generally used to designate a<br />

method of musical composition in which the composer has deliberately rejected any<br />

system of harmonic tonality. This conception of music rejects the notion that any one<br />

particular chord is central and that all surrounding harmony is to be viewed in<br />

hierarchical relation to that single chord. Atonal music has no tonic, no dominance, and<br />

no pitch hierarchy. It is built absenting these traditional structures. To create completely<br />

100


atonal music involves an absence of repetitions, accent, durational difference, cadence<br />

and strategic placement. Composers of atonal music attempt to avoid reminders of tonal<br />

music, evading major and minor chords, scales, keys, dominant functions, regular<br />

rhythms and repetition. The absence of structure demanded by key opens the door to<br />

what is possible for music as Pure Mediality. “It is only dissonance, which destroys the<br />

faith of those who believe in harmony, that the power of seduction of the rousing<br />

character of music survives” (Adorno, 18). Hence, atonal music is a language that refuses<br />

to be constrained by “An ideology of scientific harmony…the mask of a hierarchical<br />

organization from which dissonances (conflicts and struggles) are forbidden…” (Attali<br />

61).<br />

An interesting correspondence can be made between Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong> and atonal music.<br />

Barrett remarks:<br />

Something like this happens in our encounter with Kafka. On first reading we<br />

feel that something is off key, and inevitably we listen for a key that is not there<br />

but that we expect always to be on the verge of hearing; and then we take refuge<br />

in ‘interpretations’ that would seem to supply the key but ultimately fail because<br />

they do not accord with the actual texture and surface of the narratives<br />

themselves; until finally it dawns on us this is an atonal world without any key at<br />

all (A Time of Need, 230-231).<br />

It is this dissonant and atonal world that I suggest Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong> explores - one in<br />

which the two-value world of tonality has broken down, and we can no longer rely upon<br />

the comfortable structures of old.<br />

101


To read/listen Kafka’s writing/music thus requires an exquisitely keen ear, perhaps even<br />

a different type of hearing- although it is likely that human hearing has been so<br />

erroneously preconditioned that it is no longer sufficient for this task. Perhaps this is why<br />

where music appears in Kafka’s texts, it is generally transitionary characters that are<br />

found. I suggest that it is through the musical experiences of these “becoming-animals”<br />

(those in metamorphosis) that Kafka continues to explore the paradigm of Pure<br />

Mediality.<br />

6.4 “Was he an animal…?”<br />

The role of music in metamorphosing into a transitional state, as Deleuze and Guattari<br />

put it “becoming animal” is primarily explored in “The Metamorphosis” and “Josephine<br />

the Singer.” I will address “The Metamorphosis” first. This text presents one of the<br />

earliest explorations of music and sound in Kafka’s work. Music is presented here as a<br />

force that operates in the realm of the a-representative, and as a result, does not aim at<br />

some outside signification. Through an examination of the change which occurs to<br />

Gregor’s voice as well as the influence of Grete’s violin playing, we are led to an<br />

“always-evolving” perspective on the nature of existence.<br />

Let us begin with the change in the qualities of Gregor’s voice, specifically the sounds he<br />

creates. We are told that the metamorphosing Gregor, in his attempt to communicate<br />

through the bedroom door with his inquisitive mother, "made an effort with the most<br />

careful articulation and by inserting long pauses between the individual words to remove<br />

102


“everything remarkable from his voice.” (5) We immediately see here an attempt by him<br />

to cling to the stable identity of his past. By trying to remove the remarkable from his<br />

new transforming voice, Gregor initially attempt to deny his becoming. The voice of the<br />

metamorphosing Gregor is not wholly identifiable, as it approaches meaning but<br />

simultaneously withdraws from it, thereby suspending the perception of stable identity.<br />

By attempting to use “as clear a voice as possible” (91) Gregor is clearly making a<br />

conscious effort to remain identifiable, to revert to his previously assimilated self and to<br />

deny the transformation which he is undergoing. Kafka describes the tonality of that<br />

voice:<br />

Gregor had a shock as he heard his own voice, answering hers, unmistakably his<br />

own voice, it was true, but with a persistent horrible twittering squeak behind it<br />

like an undertone, which left the words in their clear shape only for the first<br />

moment… (91)<br />

The sound of his words achieving what might be called comprehensibility is only<br />

momentary, as their sonority “…quickly rose up reverberating around them to destroy<br />

their sense, so that one could not be sure one had heard them rightly” (91). Perfectly clear<br />

to the monstrous animal, these words become garbled to the intended recipient of his<br />

speech-act. But this inability to communicate “clearly and precisely” (91) can only be<br />

considered as such along the representational lines which are part of the stable sense of<br />

identity-thinking to which Gregor clings.<br />

After this “failed” attempt at verbal communication, Gregor recognizes that he can no<br />

longer articulate himself in a way that is remotely comprehensible to his family:<br />

103


All right, people did not understand his words any more, although they seemed<br />

clear enough to him, clearer than previously, perhaps because his ears had gotten<br />

used to them. In order to get as clear a voice as possible for the critical<br />

conversation which was imminent, he coughed a little, and certainly took the<br />

trouble to do this in a really subdued way… (11)<br />

Although these sounds seem perfectly clear to him, Gregor is nonetheless in the evolving<br />

state of being in-between. His transitioning has removed the ability of language to<br />

communicate a message outside of itself, to point to something exterior. In this<br />

circumstance, language articulated with sound (speech) can no longer be conceived as<br />

communicating a discernable message from its sender to its receiver.<br />

Gregor comes to characterize even his indistinct noises, such as coughing, as inhuman.<br />

He states, “…it was possible that even this noise sounded like something different from a<br />

human cough” (92). In his remark that, “the change in his voice was nothing but the<br />

precursor of a severe chill…” (92), Gregor continues to attempt to adhere to the rules of<br />

the binary world. In his treatment of these sounds as anomalies, he relegates processual<br />

being to the status of a sickness. This becoming is seen as an aberration from the norm (a<br />

disturbance against its opposite - health) and as such, it is implied that the sickness is<br />

something which needs to be set aright and returned to its original (healthy) state. In this<br />

context, Gregor also makes the comment that he is no longer capable of making once<br />

clear judgments of his voice, “…since this noise too might not sound like a human cough<br />

for all he was able to judge” (99). His predilection to clearly separate and categorize, to<br />

conceptualize, is a remnant of the world of stable being, not of becoming. Yet one must<br />

104


not view this change as loss, but rather as transition. Any attempt to see the transitory as<br />

lack functions on the level of nostalgia for a lost teleology.<br />

Gregor’s mother still functions within this teleological world, as upon hearing the voice<br />

of her son declares him to be unwell and in need of medical attention:<br />

Did you understand a single word?" the manager asked the parents, "Is he playing<br />

the fool with us?" "For God's sake," cried the mother already in tears, "perhaps<br />

he's very ill and we're upsetting him. Grete! Grete!" she yelled at that point.<br />

"Mother?" called the sister from the other side. They were making themselves<br />

understood through Gregor's room. "You must go to the doctor right away.<br />

Gregor is sick. Hurry to the doctor. Have you heard Gregor speak yet?" (10)<br />

Her denial of the transitory nature of Gregor’s being confirms the representational point<br />

of view from which she operates. She is caught in the same trap, understanding<br />

disturbances in the communicative process to be disruptions in an otherwise teleological<br />

system. It is only the manager, a voice from outside of the life of the family, who<br />

confirms something very different about the sounds, "That was an animal's voice" (10),<br />

thereby confirming a truth she is either unwilling or incapable of seeing (hearing).<br />

The perspective that I have described on voice and sound in the story is similarly<br />

applicable to performed music. This can be established by examining the scene in which<br />

Gregor’s sister Grete begins to play the violin for the family’s lodgers. In this portion of<br />

the text, we see Kafka address the influence of sound on his “in-process” protagonist.<br />

Although Gregor secludes himself from almost all human contact throughout the story, at<br />

105


the point at which his sister commences her performance, it is if he has been summoned<br />

by a force beyond his control. He loses all of his former reluctance:<br />

The sister began to play… Attracted by the playing, Gregor had ventured to<br />

advance a little further forward and his head was already in the living room. He<br />

scarcely wondered about the fact that recently he had had so little consideration<br />

for the others. Earlier this consideration had been something he was proud<br />

of...(10)<br />

It is as if the music has a quality which overwhelms him in its stimulating and<br />

communicative power. The transitory being is attracted to the transitory sound, as it<br />

displays to him the world that he is far more “in tune” with, one of perpetual becoming.<br />

He becomes compelled to reach this musical emanation, or perhaps more precisely, to<br />

experience it (and his own becoming) more acutely, abandoning concerns over his<br />

appearance, and with no thought given to consequences:<br />

On his back and his sides he carted around with him dust, threads, hair, and<br />

remnants of food. His indifference to everything was much too great for him to lie<br />

on his back and scour himself on the carpet, as he often had done earlier during<br />

the day. In spite of his condition he had no timidity about inching forward a bit on<br />

the spotless floor of the living room (35).<br />

While he experiences this music profoundly, he is still not fully aware of the<br />

ramifications of awakening to the processual, and responds by questioning the very<br />

foundation of his identity, asking, “Was he an animal that music so captivated him” (35)?<br />

This self-questioning presents the crisis of a character that is slowly becoming aware of<br />

his transitionary nature.<br />

106


In being summoned by this music, Gregor experiences an instance of the breakdown of<br />

opposition, or what Barthes calls transgressing the “Wall of Antithesis”:<br />

…it is fatal, the text says, to remove the dividing line, the paradigmatic slash<br />

mark which permits meaning to function (the wall of the Antithesis), life to<br />

reproduce (the opposition of the sexes), property to be protected (rule of contract).<br />

In short, the story represents (we are in a readerly art) a generalized collapse of<br />

economies: the economy of language usually protected by separation of<br />

opposites… (S/Z, 13)<br />

Gregor’s stabilized conceptualizations have been transgressed as Kafka scrambles and<br />

disorients, via his use of language, the binary logic under which his character functions.<br />

It is Gregor’s attraction toward the transgressive world of becoming that is of importance<br />

here as Kafka suggests that in order to “understand” music; one must become<br />

“monstrous”, or operate in the abject world that allows for the presence of such<br />

monstrosity. As the classical oppositions of being/nothingness, subject/object,<br />

inside/outside break down, we are left with this abjection, what Kristeva describes as a<br />

“privileged place of mingling, of the contamination of life by death, of begetting and of<br />

ending.” (Powers of Horror, 149) What disturbs identity and system order presents<br />

abjection, as it, “…does not respect borders, positions, rules, the in-between, the<br />

ambiguous, the composite” (Powers of Horror, 4). I suggest that Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong>, as<br />

expressed through his treatment of music may be seen as an embrace of the dissonant, the<br />

abject, “a vision that resists any representation, if the latter is a desire to coincide with the<br />

presumed identity of what is to be represented” (Powers of Horror, 151).<br />

107


“The Metamorphosis” presents a vision of music as a signifying process that never<br />

resolves into a signified because of its very processual nature and temporality. At no<br />

single point within music can absolute presence or univocal meaning be established, as<br />

one can not judge or evaluate singular tones apart from their relationship to others. Yet<br />

the question still arises: Is anything at all revealed or communicated through music? In<br />

this regard, I am inclined to agree with Adorno in that music’s, “…quality of being a<br />

riddle, of saying something that the listener understands, yet does not understand is<br />

something it (music) shares with all art. No art can be pinned down as to what it says, yet<br />

it still speaks” (Essays on Music, 114).<br />

6.5 “Josephine the Singer:” Suspended Chords, Suspended Judgment<br />

“…Opposition is possible only at a distance, when you sit before her, you know: this<br />

piping of hers is no piping.”<br />

Perhaps the most prominent exploration of music in Kafka resides in the last story<br />

published in his lifetime, the cryptic - “Josephine the Singer, or The Mouse Folk.” Critics<br />

have long approached this text from a biographical perspective, arguing that the story’s<br />

central character corresponds to its author, and that the work serves as an opportunity for<br />

Kafka to meditate one final time on the role of the artist in society. I find this perspective<br />

far too narrow, as I believe the story encompasses a much larger space. Kafka clearly<br />

recognized the erroneous human tendency to appropriate language and via his <strong>literature</strong>,<br />

sought for its de-appropriation. I contend that he is grappling here again with an<br />

communicative theory of Pure Mediality, using the text to offer alternate models for<br />

108


aesthetics, language and communication. Music thus proves to be an aesthetic medium<br />

for this dis-appropriation.<br />

Quite unlike the words of a language which refer to a signified, music in “Josephine the<br />

Singer”, though it has a precise operationality, never has a stable reference to a code of<br />

the linguistic type. It is not a myth coded in sounds instead of words, but rather a<br />

“language without meaning” (Attali 23). While musical language bears some<br />

resemblance to linguistics, music does not represent clearly and precisely, but rather<br />

alludes to meaning. It can thus circumvent the traumatic and violent process of<br />

conceptualization generally required for meaning to be revealed. Through the narrative<br />

of “Josephine the Singer,” music retains its place as a-representational art, not<br />

functioning to signify toward some greater end. The story actively transcends the<br />

boundaries of opposition, where the utilitarian sender-receiver communicative paradigm<br />

no longer operates. As such, we have communicative immediacy which I have<br />

previously referred to as “<strong>pure</strong>.”<br />

Kafka again uses an animal protagonist to explore this medial space. His parable<br />

describes a congregation of “mouse people,” who communicate in high pitched sqeaking<br />

noises. This community partakes in the vocalization or “piping” of the protagonist,<br />

Josephine. The narrative wavers between superlative praise for Josephine and a<br />

communal indifference to her performance, between her singings evoking an effect, to it<br />

compelling no reaction at all. The nature of Josephine's piping is ultimately so deeply<br />

questioned that one wonders if her performances involve any vocalization at all.<br />

109


Within the first paragraph of the text, Kafka begins questioning what message is actually<br />

communicated in Josephine’s singing. The narrator asserts the community’s belief that<br />

they are able to grasp or comprehend a message articulated by her. Yet doubt is quickly<br />

inserted, as we move from the community “understanding” the singing to a denial of the<br />

possibility of understanding,<br />

I have often thought about what this music of hers really means. For we are quite<br />

unmusical; how is it that we understand Josephine's singing or, since Josephine<br />

denies that, at least think we can understand it. The simplest answer would be that<br />

the beauty of her singing is so great that even the most insensitive cannot be deaf<br />

to it, but this answer is not satisfactory. If it were really so, her singing would<br />

have to give one an immediate and lasting feeling of being something out of the<br />

ordinary, a feeling that from her throat something is sounding which we have<br />

never heard before and which we are not even capable of hearing, something that<br />

Josephine alone and no one else can enable us to hear (192).<br />

We learn, all too quickly, that this understanding does not occur. Rather, the community<br />

is depicted as devoid of emotional response to the singing. The narrator continues,<br />

“…that is just what does not happen, I do not feel this and have never observed that<br />

others feel anything of the kind” (192). The narrator’s description moves from<br />

Josephine’s music as being capable of having an emotional/aesthetic effect on the<br />

community to it serving no real aesthetic or use-value, as Kafka seizes another<br />

opportunity to explore the double nature (both/and) of existence through contradiction.<br />

The music is revealed as both evocative and simultaneously ineffectual, and neither<br />

wholly present nor absent. In this way, Josephine’s music resists artistic or<br />

communicative representation, and refuses to be conceptualized.<br />

110


Josephine herself recognizes that while there is general recognition of her singing by the<br />

mouse folk, she can not hope for any “real understanding”:<br />

She believes anyhow that she is singing to deaf ears; there is no lack of<br />

enthusiasm and applause, but she has long learned not to expect real<br />

understanding, as she conceives it. So all disturbance is very welcome to her;<br />

whatever intervenes from outside to hinder the purity of her song, to be overcome<br />

with a slight effort, even with no effort at all, merely by confronting it, can help to<br />

awaken the masses... (195)<br />

Disturbance as it is referred to here is not to be seen as an impediment to comprehension,<br />

but a reminder that communication, even aesthetic communication, is not comprised of a<br />

“clear” signal transmitted from sender to recipient. Clarity and consistency are<br />

conceptualizations that do not actually exist in a world unmasked as perpetually<br />

becoming. These concepts are remnants of a metaphysical system that Kafka has left<br />

behind. Josephine calls for these disturbances to intersperse themselves into the “purity”<br />

of her singing so that the absolute may be hybridized. As such, she is Kafka’s agent,<br />

embracing communicative and artistic immediacy. It is only through the presence of<br />

these disturbances that she can “awaken the masses” (195) to a re-envisioning of the<br />

world as process.<br />

The question then becomes, does Josephine’s singing in any way serve to<br />

communicate a message? Kafka again juxtaposes contradictory statements here,<br />

suggesting that the message of the music while at times seems to be purpose-less,<br />

occasionally resounds and exposes provisional meaning, allowing for a glimpse<br />

of the intermingling of presence and absence. The narrator describes the<br />

111


community’s experience of Josephine’s singing in this respect as, “fleeting and<br />

transient” (195-196) and as to the goal of her work:<br />

…her singing is supposed to save us, nothing less than that, and if it does not<br />

drive away the evil, at least gives us the strength to bear it. She does not put it in<br />

these words or in any other, she says very little anyhow, she is silent among the<br />

chatterers, but it flashes from her eyes, on her closed lips. (198)<br />

There is the implication here that meaning emanating from Josephine’s singing never<br />

fully arrives to “save us” (196) but rather appears fleetingly “flashes from her eyes” (196)<br />

as it comes into and passes out of being. The temporal existence of music is such that as<br />

one tone or series of tones decays, another must become present to allow for the<br />

continuity of melody. Yet it is only in the way that these tones relate to one another as<br />

constituent parts that music can be understood to exist.<br />

At another point in the text, the narrator speaks to the role of music within the mouse<br />

community, specifically to the lack of musical interest on the part of the older members.<br />

Interest in music is relegated to the domain of the youth: “…it is only the very young<br />

who are interested in her singing as singing, …whereas the real mass of the people—this<br />

is plain to see—are quite withdrawn into themselves” (202-203). Perhaps this is because<br />

the “old,” those unwilling to depart from a structuralist paradigm, have long since<br />

accommodated themselves to a model of communication that demands a message travel<br />

from a point of origin to a definite endpoint, as well as a belief that the purpose of art is<br />

to communicate some grander ultimate meaning. The “old” resist opening themselves to<br />

112


new “young” (unmediated) perspective, which results in alienation from a process-<br />

oriented ontology that they can not accept:<br />

We have no youth, we are all at once grown-up, and then we stay grown-up too<br />

long, a certain weariness and hopelessness…Our lack of musical gifts has surely<br />

some connection with this; we are too old for music, its excitement, its rapture do<br />

not suit our heaviness, wearily we wave it away (202).<br />

The narrator’s statement that some of the mouse folk are “too old for music” (202)<br />

reflects their unwillingness, or perhaps inability to experience the world as infinitely<br />

relational, and music as a model of that world. It is only the young, those with “fresh<br />

ears” who are attracted to, and can appreciate Josephine’s singing as singing.<br />

Much like in “The Metamorphosis”, Kafka chooses to have “Josephine the Singer” occur<br />

within the animal world. For him, this is the world of the in-between, the space most<br />

aligned with a conception of communication as immediate. In no place in his <strong>literature</strong><br />

does he have his human characters respond to music in the peculiar way his animals do.<br />

Their animality places them beyond the oppositional structure of human/inhuman and<br />

thus beyond utilitarian models of communication. Kafka reserves for his animals a place<br />

from which they can experience the world in flux, a world which is open to, but generally<br />

ignored by his human characters.<br />

Both “The Metamorphosis” and “Josephine the Singer” present music for Kafka as a<br />

realm in which the hierarchy of opposition breaks down. An a-representational art form<br />

involving relationality of tones, music is experienced temporally, and models a world in<br />

113


which one can no longer grasp onto stable being. The language of music thus reveals<br />

itself as a “<strong>pure</strong>” one that communicates only itself and not some external signified. In<br />

Gregor being summoned by the violin and Josephine’s communal piping, we see Kafka’s<br />

protagonists experience sound as the arena of the limitless. This indeterminate space is<br />

unsettling as it exposes the metaphysical world as fiction. At the same time, it opens the<br />

door to new communicative and ontological paradigms. Music disrupts that which is tied<br />

to teleology, and acts aesthetically to communicate the incommunicable without falling<br />

into artistic representation.<br />

114


“Poor young man there’s no helping you. I have found out your great wound. You are<br />

dying from this flower on your side.”<br />

-Kafka, “A Country Doctor”<br />

“I don't mean it as a joke when I tell you it's like being seasick on dry land. It's a<br />

condition in which you can't remember the real names of things and so in a great<br />

hurry you fling temporary names at them. You do it as fast as you can. But you've<br />

hardly turned your back on them before you've forgotten what you called them.”<br />

“A Country Doctor”: Writing Within Infinite Relation<br />

7.1 The Space of Undecidability:<br />

115<br />

-Kafka, Diaries<br />

I have argued that Kafka’s work is steeped in a profound a-metaphysical critique of<br />

instrumental language, and by extension, definitive judgment. His <strong>literature</strong> points to the<br />

limitations of the classical signifier/signified construct, consciously undermining it<br />

through an aesthetic approach which provides a glimpse into an ontological framework of<br />

radical undecidability and perpetual becoming. My contention has been that Kafka’s texts<br />

present what is often forgotten or ignored within a strictly utilitarian worldview- the<br />

position(s) of undecidability which, “harbor(s) within itself (a) complicity of contrary<br />

values…prior to any distinction-making…” It has “no stable essence, no ‘proper’<br />

characteristics, it is not, in any sense of the word… a substance” (Derrida, Dissemination<br />

126). Kafka’s literary undertakings thus allow for an expression of this undecidability,<br />

embracing the breakdown of the two-value world.<br />

Kafka is cognizant of the limitations of oppositional structures, and his texts participate in<br />

an active deconstruction of this paradigm. I argue that his work is permeated by the


double-nature of existence, its undecidability, which is exposed through the mixture of<br />

what in utilitarian terms, are viewed as mutually exclusive elements. This is the double-<br />

nature that Derrida describes as:<br />

Neither/nor, that is, simultaneously either or" such as, among others:" neither a<br />

plus nor a minus, neither confusion nor distinction, neither identity nor difference,<br />

neither the inside nor the outside, neither remedy nor poison, neither a presence<br />

nor an absence, neither the incised integrity of a beginning [...] nor simple<br />

secondariness. (Positions 43).<br />

With this starting point, I turn my attention in this chapter to the short story “A Country<br />

Doctor,” which works at probing the space of the undecidable. This is a text in which<br />

metaphoric and allusive language prove to be ways of circumventing utilitarian trappings,<br />

presenting instead a communicative perspective which I have referred to with Benjamin,<br />

as Pure Mediality.<br />

I focus here on three central aspects of Kafka’s story. I begin with a discussion of the<br />

opening scene in which the doctor finds within his “own house” (18) what might be<br />

called a, “transportation of immediacy” - one which no longer requires us to think<br />

ontologically in terms of means and goals. I contend that these newly discovered horses<br />

can be read as symbols of undecidability, allowing for a medial perspective which is<br />

itself unmediated. I then move to an examination of the role of the doctor, both<br />

traditionally as diagnostician, and in the text, as a figure of un-judging who’s analysis<br />

always minimally requires a “second look.” I argue that the doctor no longer views the<br />

world, “…in terms of neat, dichotomous classifications” but rather, “by way of the<br />

scrambling of opposites such as human and animal, horses and pigs, of the indeterminacy<br />

116


of the ‘aroma’ arising from the pigsty, which thus create(s) an aura of undecidability, of<br />

‘playfulness,’ that eludes the ‘proper’ or ‘propriety’ that inheres in the very notion of<br />

‘property’” (Ulfers, 2). I conclude the chapter with a discussion of the boy’s “wound,”<br />

focusing upon the power of the figurative “language of <strong>literature</strong>” to inflict a trauma<br />

which in Kafka’s words, “…hit(s) us like a most painful misfortune, like the death of<br />

someone we loved more than we love ourselves, that make use feel as though we had<br />

been banished to the woods, far from any human presence, like a suicide. A book must be<br />

the axe for the frozen sea within us” (Diaries, 77). It is this inherent power of literary or<br />

poetic language to inflict a trauma on an instrumentalized language that, “believes it has<br />

totalized and purified itself in a unified meaning, beyond the ‘wound’ of equivocity<br />

inherent in all language…” (Ulfers, 3) that Kafka embraces. From the dynamics of the<br />

scene in the pigsty to the questions raised in the process of a diagnosis, to the wound<br />

which is also a “flower”, it is my contention that “A Country Doctor” can be interpreted<br />

as a radical critique of instrumental language, a breaking through of the “wall of<br />

antithesis” (Barthes) that allows for an ontology of becoming to re-emerge.<br />

7.2 Scenes from a Pigsty:<br />

At the beginning of the text, the doctor is operating within a functional paradigm. By this<br />

I mean that he conceives of the world as structured teleologically- in terms of an ultimate<br />

achievable purpose. His desired travel to treat the sickness of his patient requires a means<br />

(horses and carriage) in order to achieve a desired end (arrival at the location). Kafka<br />

begins the text:<br />

117


I was in great difficulty. An urgent journey was facing me. A seriously ill man<br />

was waiting for me in a village ten miles distant. A severe snowstorm filled the<br />

space between him and me. I had a carriage—a light one, with large wheels,<br />

entirely suitable for our country roads. Wrapped up in furs with the bag of<br />

instruments in my hand, I was already standing in the courtyard ready for the<br />

journey; but the horse was missing—the horse. My own horse had died the<br />

previous night, as a result of over exertion in this icy winter (220).<br />

Although prepared to make the journey and transverse “all the wide space between him<br />

and me” (220), the absence of a means of transportation temporarily delays him. These<br />

first lines are wrought with an imagery that refers to the problems posed by a strictly<br />

utilitarian worldview. The doctor’s comment on the distance between him and his patient<br />

refers back to a functional perspective in which means are always separated from ends.<br />

From this point of view, the doctor can only interpret himself to be impeded by a “severe<br />

snowstorm”, which presumably blocks the “roads” that he would travel. The snowstorm<br />

is conceived of only as an impediment to reaching his goal, and the road is likewise seen<br />

only as a means toward the achievement of his purpose. At this point in the text, the<br />

doctor is clearly operating from an ontological perspective which sees the world through<br />

the oppositional structures of medium/message and content/form.<br />

According to the doctor, his own horse, his means of transportation, died “as a result of<br />

overexertion” (220) the night prior. This explanation might be understood to symbolize<br />

the over-reliance that human beings have placed upon instrumental modes of<br />

communication. In our drive toward purpose and absolution, we come to abhor any sense<br />

of indeterminacy, and thus participate in a radical exclusion of multiplicity. But the<br />

illusion of the absolute can not hold, and thus breakdown, seen in this light as death,<br />

118


ecomes inevitable. We should note that the doctor had previously utilized a single horse<br />

- another allusion to a communicative paradigm that aims at singular, univocal meaning.<br />

The death of that single horse and subsequent entry into the pigsty bring forth<br />

concomitant entry into a world of immediacy and perpetual becoming. The doctor is now<br />

confronted with dual horses, a clear allusion to an ontological perspective that is always<br />

at least double. “Two horses, enormous creatures with powerful flanks, one after the<br />

other, their legs tucked close to their bodies, each well shaped head lowered like a<br />

camel’s, by sheer strength of buttocking squeezed out through the door hole which they<br />

filled entirely” (220).<br />

These two horses, borrowed from the brutish groom are found in the doctor’s,<br />

“uninhabited pigsty” (220) which itself models this new unruly world:<br />

Distracted and tormented, I kicked my foot against the cracked door of the pig sty<br />

which had not been used for years. The door opened and banged to and fro on its<br />

hinges. A warmth and smell as if from horses came out. A dim stall lantern on a<br />

rope swayed inside. A man huddled down in the stall below showed his open<br />

blue-eyed face. “Shall I hitch up?” (221)<br />

I interpret the breaking down of the pigsty doors and the discovery of the horses as a<br />

turning point, one in which the doctor figuratively breaks through the “wall of antithesis”<br />

(Barthes) and is radically transformed. It is in the pigsty that the doctor experiences for<br />

the first time the undecidability that Derrida describes as, “a medium as element<br />

enveloping both terms [of an opposition]; a medium located between the two terms…”<br />

“What counts here is the between, the in-between-ness…” (51) It is in this atmosphere of<br />

unruliness, of the in-between, in which oppositions such as death and life co-mingle, that<br />

119


the doctor now opens himself to the immediacy of communication, and the goal-less<br />

nature of becoming.<br />

In reference to the appearance of these horses, the housemaid Rose remarks, “One<br />

doesn’t know the sorts of things one has stored in one’s own house…and we both<br />

laughed” (221). This statement and particularly their laughter are of significance.<br />

According to Ulfers, “What is getting lost in the translation of this sentence is the<br />

housemaid's reference to vorrätig - the adjective to the noun Vorrat, reserve or surplus”<br />

(3). This allusion to reserve/surplus/extra indicates an overflowing, an excess that<br />

according to Nietzsche, "was revealed as truth, contradiction; the bliss born of pain spoke<br />

from the heart of nature" (The Birth of Tragedy, 27). It is in this excess or surplus of<br />

contradictory elements that “truth”, if we can even speak of it, can emerge. Derrida refers<br />

to this as, “unbounded excess,” as, for example, in “painful pleasure,” which “partakes of<br />

both good and ill, of the agreeable and the disagreeable” (Dissemination, 99).<br />

Consequently, their laughter may be viewed as an involuntary response to that which no<br />

longer fits into the ordered world of stable being. The laughter signifies the breakdown of<br />

self-control, as one may conceive of it to be a, “manifestation of the loss of composure<br />

going hand in hand with the de-composition of the ‘proper’ order of things that ensues<br />

with the opening of the pigsty” (Ulfers 2).<br />

The most convincing example of the doctor’s movement toward an ontological<br />

and communicative perspective of Pure Mediality comes in Kafka’s description of<br />

the actual journey to his patient’s home. This is a description which does not<br />

chronicle a movement over distance and time, but rather, one that occurs<br />

120


essentially instantaneously. In describing the experience, the doctor remarks,<br />

“Then I am already there, as if the farm yard of my invalid opens up immediately<br />

in front of my courtyard gate” (222). This instantaneous arrival removes any<br />

notion of “journey” from the narrative, if by journey we mean a process involving<br />

a starting point, endpoint and medium.<br />

As opposed to the former teleological view in which the doctor would need to arrive at<br />

his destination via a means, we have now what might be called Pure Mediality or “always<br />

already with” of existence- one that is intrinsic to a philosophy of becoming. Being<br />

transported in an instance is thus an undermining of the linear conceptions of space and<br />

time.<br />

7.3 The Role of the Doctor and Diagnosis:<br />

In looking at the complex textual interaction between the doctor and the boy, one might<br />

first reconsider the traditional role of the doctor and associated expectations of the<br />

patient. In general, the doctor serves to evaluate health. He is expected to empirically<br />

arrive at a prognosis through causal reasoning, and subsequently prescribe treatment for<br />

the alleviation of symptoms. By calling upon the doctor, the patient expects definitive<br />

judgment - entering into the consultation with a low threshold for ambiguity regarding his<br />

condition. The doctor is often unrealistically expected to possess some god-like ability to<br />

make medical determinations that are far beyond the scope of what can be known in any<br />

absolute sense. Thus, the doctor who is unable to come to a conclusive diagnosis is often<br />

perceived by his patient as an anomaly - or worse, a failure. Kafka’s text alludes to the<br />

121


country doctor’s anger and frustration with such patient expectations in his observation<br />

that:<br />

Incidentally, it’s easy to write prescriptions, but difficult to come to an<br />

understanding with people…That’s how people are in my region. Always<br />

demanding the impossible from the doctor…They have lost the old faith. The<br />

priest sits at home and tears his religious robes to pieces, one after the other. But<br />

the doctor is supposed to achieve everything with his delicate surgeon’s hand.<br />

Well, it’s what they like to think. I have not offered myself. If they use me for<br />

sacred purposes, I let that happen to me as well” (222).<br />

In exploring the dynamics of a profession that generally requires a stance of decision and<br />

certainty, and then proceeding to deconstruct these assumptions, I contend that the text<br />

itself engages with the radically undecidable. This evolves via Kafka’s decision to<br />

operate from a perspective on language which radically departs from the utilitarian model<br />

by suspending the very concept of absolute decision. Rather, Kafka makes the demand<br />

that any examination by a doctor, and by extension, any examination of a literary text by<br />

a reader, must always minimally require a “double take”, as we see the doctor initially<br />

come to a prognosis, only moments later to recognize its inadequacy. In this recognition,<br />

there is the realization that the doctor must defer his prior conclusion in favor of a second<br />

examination, or attempt at interpretation.<br />

In the doctor’s first contact with the boy, the patient seems to exhibit no symptoms which<br />

can be recognized as those of a sickness, if by sickness we are referring to some type of<br />

deviation from a ground state of “well-ness.” The family is described in this context as<br />

122


anxiously anticipating his rendering of diagnosis, described as if it were akin to a court<br />

decision:<br />

Thin, without fever, not cold, not warm, with empty eyes, without a shirt, the<br />

young man under the stuffed quilt heaves himself up, hangs around my throat, and<br />

whispers in my ear, “Doctor, let me die.” I look around. No one has heard. The<br />

parents stand silently, leaning forward, and wait for my verdict (223).<br />

Thus, the doctor proceeds to render his initial judgment: “I confirmed what I already<br />

knew; the boy was quite sound…” (222) However, this is a premature rush to judgment;<br />

one that Kafka has the doctor reconsider directly following the diagnosis. It is in this<br />

reconsideration, which brings with it the possibility of a both/and ontological perspective,<br />

that we see the doctor continue to break with a vision of the world which is dichotomous<br />

and neatly constructed. This breakdown of the oppositional structure sick/healthy -<br />

indicative of the larger reorientation which began when he kicked open the door of the<br />

pigsty – is one in which there can no longer be univocal interpretation or definitive<br />

conclusion. The text can thus be conceived of as the site of the “contest of the logic of<br />

tropes and binary logic”, (Corngold, 117) in which there is ultimately a reaffirmation of<br />

the position that the language of <strong>literature</strong> has the potential to un-judge - where our<br />

habitual tendency is to reduce plurality to singularity.<br />

7.4 Words that Wound:<br />

The notion of the traumatic wound is discussed frequently within contemporary<br />

discourse. From traditional psychoanalysis to the approaches of cultural criticism, trauma<br />

pervades the modern discussion. This trauma though, is rarely discussed from a<br />

123


linguistic point of view. Although we sometimes speak of the meaning behind words as<br />

capable of eliciting an effect that may be equated with trauma, for the most part, we fail<br />

to consider the sign itself as a weapon capable of inflicting a wound. However, as<br />

Hartman observes, “Words are always armed and capable of wounding: either because,<br />

expecting so much of them, looking to them as potentially definitive or clarifying, we are<br />

hurt by their equivocal nature” (123). This potential “violence” of literary language, its<br />

ability to wound, was something of which Kafka was fully aware. He embraced this<br />

power, utilizing the literary word to inflict trauma upon the illusion of stable being.<br />

Thus, it is in the “reconsideration” of the doctor’s diagnosis of the boy’s trauma that we<br />

see the emergence of the wound as a site of abjection. In the site/symbol of the wound,<br />

we see the human reaction of horror to the threatened breakdown in meaning caused by<br />

the loss of distinction between subject and object or between self and other. As Kristeva<br />

remarks of abjection:<br />

[W]e may call it a border: abjection is above all ambiguity. Because, while<br />

releasing a hold, it does not radically cut off the subject from what threatens it -<br />

on the contrary, abjection acknowledges it to be in perpetual danger. But also,<br />

abjection itself is a compromise of judgment and affect, of condemnation and<br />

yearning, of signs and drives. Abjection preserves what existed in the archaism of<br />

pre-objectal relationship, in the immemorial violence with which the body<br />

becomes separated from another body in order to be - maintaining that night in<br />

which the outline of signified thing vanishes and where only the imponderable<br />

affect is carried out (Powers of Horror, 16).<br />

Upon the doctor’s second examination of the patient, the recognition is made that there is<br />

indeed something wrong with the boy that was not apparent during the initial inspection:<br />

124


“I was somehow ready to admit conditionally that the boy might be ill after all” (223). It<br />

is in the process of this secondary investigation that the doctor is led to his great<br />

discovery - the “Rose-red” wound within the boy’s side:<br />

On his right side, in the region of the hip, a wound the size of the palm of one’s<br />

hand has opened up. Rose colored, in many different shadings, dark in the depths,<br />

brighter on the edges, delicately grained, with uneven patches of blood, open to<br />

the light like a mine. That’s what it looks like from a distance. Close up a<br />

complication is apparent. Who can look at that without whistling softly? Worms,<br />

as thick and long as my little finger, themselves Rose colored and also spattered<br />

with blood, are wriggling their white bodies with many limbs from their<br />

stronghold in the inner of the wound towards the light. Poor young man, there’s<br />

no helping you. I have found out your great wound. You are dying from this<br />

flower on your side (224).<br />

Kafka’s description of the boy’s wound is of import, as it implicates an intermingling of<br />

both life and death simultaneously. We see it referred to as both a blossoming flower<br />

(alluding to creation or coming into being) and that which is killing the young man<br />

(destruction or passing away). The blossoming of the “flower” simultaneously signifies<br />

both vitality and impending death, as the cycle of the flower always involves a process,<br />

(bloom, death and rebirth) and not ultimate purpose. This new diagnosis of the wound<br />

shows the doctor as incapable of rendering judgment in an absolute sense any longer, as<br />

the wound indicates movement towards a process-oriented worldview, and an ontological<br />

perspective that embraces undecidability and becoming. The text continues:<br />

I came into the world with a beautiful wound; that was all I was furnished with.”<br />

“Young friend,” I say, “your mistake is that you have no perspective. I’ve already<br />

been in all the sick rooms, far and wide, and I tell you your wound is not so bad.<br />

Made in a tight corner with two blows from an axe. Many people offer their side<br />

125


and hardly hear the axe in the forest, to say nothing of the fact that it’s coming<br />

closer to them.” (225).<br />

As the world no longer makes sense in terms of the previous ordering of stable<br />

opposition, we begin to see a more synaesthetic understanding of reading and<br />

interpretation - one which transcends the strictly visual. As Hartman argues, an approach<br />

to reading such as this, involves an inherent commingling of multiple senses of<br />

perception. He remarks:<br />

Reading is, or can be, an active kind of hearing. We really do ‘look with ears’<br />

when we read a book of some complexity. A book has the capacity to put us on<br />

the defensive, or make us envious, or inflict some other narcissistic injury. When<br />

literary critics remark of <strong>literature</strong>, ‘there’s magic in the web,’ they characterize<br />

not only what distinguishes the literary from the merely verbal, but what<br />

distinguishes critical from passive kinds of reading… What active reading<br />

discloses is a structure of words within words, a structure so deeply mediated,<br />

ghostly and echoic… (128-129)<br />

The doctor may thus be seen as conducting a double- reading of this wound, a wound<br />

described as being created by an act of hearing. According to Ulfers, this stripping of the<br />

"axe in the forest" of its "visible" aspect, making its "strokes" an auditory phenomenon<br />

that is beyond the confines of sounds attached to familiar or known meanings, the<br />

"forest" (8).<br />

In transcending our habitual need for stability and demand for presence, “A Country<br />

Doctor” compels a new type of reading and an altogether different approach to<br />

interpretation. As readers, we too often view our role to be comparable to doctors<br />

126


diagnosing illness. We then apply this same mistaken logic to the search for an<br />

understanding which is “comprehensive.” However, the more we masquerade around as<br />

physicians in search of a “cure”, the more we do violence on to the text. Conversely, the<br />

more subtly we engage in a reading, the more we tend to move towards an ethics of<br />

alterity - allowing for unrestricted potentiality. “There are thus two interpretations of<br />

interpretation. . . . The one seeks to decipher, dreams of deciphering a truth or an origin<br />

which escapes play. . . . The other, which is no longer turned toward the origin, affirms<br />

play” (Of Grammatology 292). We are thus challenged by Kafka, although never<br />

overtly, to read “A Country Doctor” in a way which promotes play, one which requires of<br />

us the vigilance to keep the wound open, and the refusal to allow for it to heal. Perhaps it<br />

is only in this approach to reading that we may ever-so-briefly experience the truly<br />

nomadic nature of the text.<br />

127


“At that moment an unending stream of traffic crossed over the bridge.”<br />

128<br />

-Kafka, The Judgment<br />

“They were given the choice of becoming kings or kings’ messengers. As is the way<br />

with children, they all wanted to be messengers. That is why there are only<br />

messengers, racing through the world and, since there are no kings, calling out to each<br />

other the messages that have now become meaningless.”<br />

Concluding Remarks<br />

8.1 From the De-Centered to Pure Mediality:<br />

- Kafka, Diaries<br />

In Structure and Sign, Derrida comments elegantly on the classical conception of the<br />

universe as centered, which he argues may be coming to the end of its reign as the<br />

predominant ontological paradigm. He points to the importance of an “a-centered”<br />

ontological perspective of infinite playfulness and process rather than the fall-back<br />

teleological position that mandates absolute ground and the achievement of permanence<br />

at some ultimate end:<br />

Thus, it has always been thought that the center, which is by definition unique,<br />

constituted that very thing within a structure which, while governing the structure,<br />

escapes structurality...the center is at the center of the totality, and yet, since the<br />

center does not belong to the totality (is not part of the totality), the totality has its<br />

center elsewhere . . . The concept of centered structure is in fact the concept of a<br />

play based on a fundamental ground, a play constituted on the basis of a<br />

fundamental immobility and a reassuring certitude, which itself is beyond the<br />

reach of play (279).


The shift in perspective that comes with the absence of a center as reference point, along<br />

with the concomitant deconstruction of the binary oppositional thinking that enabled that<br />

concept of center, have served as the departure points of my argument in this project, as it<br />

is in this very a-centered universe that I contend that the <strong>literature</strong> of Franz Kafka<br />

operates.<br />

Throughout this text I have argued that Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong> is steeped in a subtle, yet<br />

revolutionary, critique of structuralist linguistics, resulting in a profound a-metaphysical<br />

paradigm shift with staggering repercussions. Following Nietzsche’s lead, Kafka’s<br />

literary texts operate within the worldview of the neither/nor and both/and, embracing a<br />

view of language and communication as free of all instrumentality. The implications of<br />

this shift in perspective allow for an evolution in communication theory toward a model<br />

in which the previous artificial separation of medium/content and sender/receiver breaks<br />

down, and language is no longer reduced to solely the vehicle of meaning. Addressing<br />

this point, Derrida continues:<br />

Is it certain that to the word "communication" corresponds a concept that is<br />

unique, univocal, rigorously controllable, and transmittable: in a word,<br />

communicable? Thus, in accordance with a strange figure of discourse, one must<br />

first of all ask oneself whether or not the signifier "communication"<br />

communicates a determinate content, an identifiable meaning, or a describable<br />

value. However, even to articulate and to propose this question I have had to<br />

anticipate the meaning of the word communication: I have been constrained to<br />

predetermine communication as a vehicle, a means of transport or transitional<br />

medium of a meaning, and moreover of a unified meaning. If communication<br />

possessed several meanings and if this plurality should prove to be irreducible, it<br />

129


would not be justifiable to define communication a priori as the transmission of a<br />

meaning (Limited Inc. 1)<br />

Kafka recognized that a language which is strictly representational, while a utilitarian<br />

necessity, is always borrowed. In order for human beings to function pragmatically, we<br />

have been driven to partake in a process that forcibly infuses meaning into signifiers.<br />

However, Kafka’s texts reveal an understanding of language and by extension,<br />

communication which moves beyond the utilitarian towards the networked. Thus, the<br />

“death of the signified” is revealed in Kafka’s writing, as his texts actively subvert the<br />

tyranny of absolute signification by way of an a-representational approach in which,<br />

“…each ‘present’ element in a linguistic system signifies in so far as it differentially<br />

refers to another element, and thus is not itself present” (Critchley, 37).<br />

I have argued that Kafka’s aesthetic use of language participates in counter-use. Through<br />

narrative disruptions, his texts stifle our unconscious drive to judge, freeing up the<br />

playfulness of the sign. Within his writing, we see a network of infinite signifiers which<br />

“acting as if in a burrow” (Towards a Minor Literature, 17), suspend absolute judgment.<br />

Rather than forcefully creating meaning by pushing everything that does not fit into the<br />

parameters of the concept, Kafka presents transitory characters that are “in process”, or<br />

incessantly becoming. His allusive, literary language thus allows for infinite<br />

interpretation. As such, “All that can be uncovered (from his texts) are successive layers<br />

of untruth…For such a procedure demonstrates the inadequacy of all languages to<br />

express the truth. All language can show is the ‘retreat’ of untruth. The process of<br />

making untruth evident is the only ‘light’ that language can shed on truth” (Sokel, 181).<br />

130


The fluidity of this literary language works its way into the fluidity of meaning as the<br />

text’s signifiers always refer ad infinitum. “We speak of different or remote places<br />

communicating with each other by means of a passage or opening. What takes place, in<br />

this sense, what is transmitted, communicated does not involve phenomena of meaning or<br />

signification” (Dissemination, 18). By this, we see the circumvention of the metaphysical<br />

ground which language, by virtue of its grasping nature, attempts to hold on to.<br />

The search for some transcendent comprehension of their human condition has been<br />

traditionally interpreted as the central preoccupation of Kafka’s characters. His figures<br />

have been understood to be faced with incessant obstacles to achieving their goals.<br />

However, as I have shown, this perspective only makes sense when viewing the texts to<br />

contain some great mystery to be solved. Once the reader abandons this telos, and<br />

recognizes that Kafka’s world is one that is radically undecidable, we begin to see that<br />

the, “…resolution of non-resolution brings the stories into being and sustains them”<br />

(Signature, Event, Context, 34). On the contrary, the achievement of unequivocal<br />

meaning would result in what might be referred to as the “death of life.” To this point,<br />

Barthes remarks that, "All criticism rests in the notion that the text contains meaning that<br />

is supposed to take its preeminence from an ‘over meaning’...now, the notion of structure<br />

does not support the separation of foundation and design, insignificant and<br />

significant...everything signifies something else" (S/Z 51). He is referring here to the<br />

recurring problems posed by functionalist utilitarian approaches to language in which<br />

every signifier is tied to a signified.<br />

131


8.2 Kafka’s Reach:<br />

Let me conclude here by addressing the impact of Kafka’s writing. The influence of<br />

Kafka’s <strong>literature</strong> is extremely far-reaching. At last count, the Library of Congress listed<br />

over 12,000 commentaries on his work; second only to Shakespeare in terms of the sheer<br />

volume of citation. Perhaps even more impressive though, is the influence he has cast<br />

upon the literary giants of the twentieth century – including the likes of Borges, Camus,<br />

Beckett and Orwell - in whose works the Kafkaesque oeuvre is unmistakable. However,<br />

Kafka’s shadow looms not only over modern and postmodern <strong>literature</strong>, but has also<br />

pervaded theatre, art, cinema, psychoanalysis and popular culture. He has been<br />

conveniently co-opted by such diverse groups as the Fantasists, Existentialists, Marxists,<br />

Abstract Expressionists and Conspiracy Theorists, among other.<br />

In light of this, it would be remiss to not pause and ask: What is it about Kafka’s writing<br />

that has touched upon, and continues to touch upon, the pulse of our age? Some have<br />

argued that it is Kafka’s heightened attenuation to the absurdity of bureaucracies, his<br />

explicit examination of existential angst and his harrowing portraits of psychological<br />

terror that make him the quintessential allegorist of a century dominated by authoritarian<br />

regimes, World Wars and genocide. I however, do not ultimately find this an adequate<br />

explanation for why his work resonates so dramatically.<br />

Instead, I offer the position that Kafka’s body of work speaks to an even greater concern.<br />

It fundamentally addresses the role that art, in this case a literary one, has in pointing to<br />

132


the truths that have been either forgotten or obfuscated by useful habit or lazy<br />

convenience. The very crux of his <strong>literature</strong> always involves an overflowing, a remainder<br />

which can not be categorized within the totalizing constructs of the pragmatic world.<br />

Consequently and by example, it points to the fact that modern art must always act as the<br />

“reminder of the remainder” vehemently refusing to provide for the closure which would<br />

assuredly be the end of not only interpretation, but of human potentiality. When Adorno,<br />

in “Notes on Kafka” says that the author’s texts actively elude understanding, he points to<br />

the essential functioning element of the works; their capacity for limitless resistance to<br />

any ultimate totalizing interpretation. In the final analysis then, there can be no final<br />

analysis. These are texts which refuse to provide a finality of meaning, whose<br />

revolutionary force lies in their radical re-envisioning of ontology and their re-opening of<br />

the gateway to infinite interpretability, without the possibility for closure .<br />

8.3 Chiasmic Unity and the Ethics of Alterity:<br />

At this point, I would like to, based on my thesis, suggest that with Kafka’s aesthetics of<br />

Pure Mediality there may be the opening of an ethics that is conceived differently from<br />

normative morality. I am making this inference based upon Levinas’ proposal of a<br />

postmodern ethics in his text Otherwise Than Being. Levinas’ central concern is that<br />

western philosophy has been preoccupied with the concept Being, the totality, at the<br />

expense of what might be called, “otherwise than Being”, or that which lies outside of the<br />

totality of Being as transcendent, exterior, infinite, the Other. In short, Levinas' ethics is<br />

situated in an "encounter" with the Other which cannot be reduced to a symmetrical<br />

133


elationship. That is, it cannot be localized historically or temporally. Ethics, in the<br />

Levinasian' sense, does not refer to what is generally understood as morality, nor a code<br />

of conduct governing how one should behave. “The ethical is the location of a point of<br />

alterity, or what Levinas calls exteriority, that cannot be reduced to the same…and ethics<br />

is simply and entirely the event in which I am related to the face of the other” (Critchley<br />

5).<br />

The figure which Levinas employs to explain this meeting or dialogue, is that of the<br />

chiasmus 19 , itself derived from the Greek letter X, which denotes a crossing, or<br />

interlacing. “It is the belonging together or interlacing of two moments, or paths, of<br />

reading- repetition and alterity- that best describes the double gesture of deconstructive<br />

reading: the figure of the chiasmus” (28). Ulfers refers to the similar notion of, “chiasmic<br />

unity,” in his discussion of Kafka - a one or a whole in the form of the entanglement of<br />

opposites, of their undecidable fusion and separation. He remarks:<br />

Chiasmic unity by definition violates the principle of non-contradiction, the<br />

principle on which binary logic is based. But this violation does not call for a<br />

“corrective reading that would lead us back to binary logic. Rather, chiasmic unity<br />

constitutes the domain of a different “logic,” a logic that makes the principle of<br />

non-contradiction dysfunction, and is viewed as prior to it. Chiasmic logic<br />

suspends the system of binary oppositions on which non-contradiction is based,<br />

but without reducing the oppositions to some form of the “same” (7).<br />

I contend that Kafka’s texts may also be seen as participating in this entanglement, in the<br />

unity of the chiasmus, which allows for an “open-ness” or vulnerability that is congruent<br />

19 The Oxford English Dictionary defines the chiasmus as, "A grammatical figure by<br />

which the order of words in one of two of parallel clauses is inverted in the other."<br />

134


with the Levinasian ethics of alterity. Thus, the Kafkan figures that withhold definition or<br />

decision – ironically seen as “unethical” in their refusal to decide/judge – are perhaps, by<br />

their very (in)action, the ethical in the sense of allowing for the “other to be other” –<br />

rather than be assimilated to sameness. The perceived “impediments” faced by the likes<br />

of Joseph K. or Georg Bendemann can only be thought of as such within a framework<br />

that does not allow for this open-ness or vulnerability. One cannot overlook that at the<br />

center of Kafka’s aesthetics is an art of suspension and deferral, of withholding, or<br />

infinite postponement of judgment and perpetual delay, which might constitute the arena<br />

of the ethical. It is only within the aesthetics of Pure Mediality that this convergence of<br />

the aesthetic and the ethical could occur.<br />

The ethics that I am alluding to here is one that Robert Musil associates with the<br />

aesthetics of “essayism” (see footnote # 4): “For me the word “essay” binds together<br />

ethics and aesthetics 20 ” (Gesammelte Werke in Neun Bänden, 8, 1334). What Musil<br />

implies with the relationship of aesthetics and ethics in the form of essayism is the ethics<br />

of a liberation from truth as the duress of univocity and the tyranny of teleology towards<br />

the truth of the world as a non-totalizable experimental site, of a world that is forever<br />

“other” to itself, and thus inherently and irreducibly open to the Other. In contrast to a<br />

world whose parts are isolated “selves,” this world constitutes an ethics of other-<br />

relatedness as its parts are chiasmically linked, making them “alterities” – corresponding<br />

to the dyadic units of poetic/metaphorical language - where each part “loses its<br />

independent meaning and gains a sense of neighborhood 21 ” (Gesammelte Werke in Zwei<br />

20 Translation: Friedrich Ulfers<br />

21 Ibid<br />

135


Bänden, 1084). It is this sense of neighborhood that Kafka approaches, as I have shown,<br />

by his “allusive” writing that in its infinite playfulness suspends the “unethical” violence<br />

of judgment that results in the closure of the open “both-and” structure, the Pure<br />

Mediality, of the world and its construction as one of “either/or.”<br />

136


Bibliography<br />

Adorno, Theodor. Essays on Music. University of California Press, 2002.<br />

---. Negative Dialectics. Continuum Press, 1983.<br />

Agamben, Giorgio. Homo Sacer. Frankfurt: Vintage Books, 2001.<br />

Attali, Jacques. Noise: The Political Economy of Music. Minneapolis: University of<br />

Minnesota Press, 1999.<br />

Baidou, Alain. Ethics: An Essay On The Understanding of Evil. New York: Verso<br />

Publishers, 2001.<br />

---. Deleuze: The Clamor of Being. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,<br />

2000.<br />

Barrett, William. Time of Need: Forms of Imagination in the Twentieth Century. New<br />

Haven: Wesleyan University Press, 1972.<br />

---. Irrational Man. New York: Doubleday Books, 1958.<br />

Barthes, Roland. Image Music Text. New York: Hill and Wang Publishers, 2001.<br />

---. S/Z. New York: Hill and Wang Publishers, 1995.<br />

---. Elements of Semiology. Noonday Press, May 1977.<br />

---. A Barthes Reader. Noonday Press, August 1983.<br />

---. The Responsibility of Forms: Berkeley. University of California Press, 1991.<br />

Bataille, George. The Accursed Share. Berkeley. University of California Press, 1998.<br />

Baudrillard, Jean. Simulacra and Simulation. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan<br />

Press, 1994.<br />

---. Seduction New York; Macmillan. London; New World Perspectives. Montreal,<br />

1990.<br />

137


Bauman, Zygmunt. Postmodernity and Its Discontents. New York: New York University<br />

Press, 1997.<br />

Benjamin, Walter. Selected Writings: Volume 1 (1913-1926). Ed. Marcus Bullock and<br />

Michael W. Jennings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2000.<br />

---. Selected Writings: Volume 2 (1927-1934). Ed. Marcus Bullock and Michael W<br />

Jennings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2000.<br />

---. Gesammelte Schriften, Ed. Tiedmann, Frankfurt and Main, 1972-1986.<br />

Bernheimer, Charles. Flaubert and Kafka: Studies in Psychopoetic Structure. New<br />

Haven: Yale University Press, 1982.<br />

Bloom, Harold. Franz Kafka: Modern Critical Views. New York: Chelsea House<br />

Publishers, 1986.<br />

---. Deconstruction and Criticism. London: Routledge, 1979.<br />

Bois, Yve-Alain. Formless: A User's Guide. Zone Books. New York, 1997.<br />

Brod, Max. Franz Kafka: A Biography. New York: Schocken Books, 1975.<br />

Cage, John. For the Birds – John Cage in Conversation with Daniel Charles Boston: M.<br />

Boyars, 1995.<br />

---. A Year from Monday: New Lectures and Writings. Middletown, CT: Wesleyan<br />

University Press, 1967.<br />

Camus, Albert. “Hope and the Absurd in the Work of Franz Kafka.” New York: Vintage<br />

Press, 1955.<br />

Chomsky, Noam. Knowledge of Language. Westport Connecticut: Praeger Publishers,<br />

1986.<br />

---. On Language. New York: The New Press, 1998.<br />

138


Corngold, Stanley. Franz Kafka: The Necessity of Form. Ithaca: Cornell University<br />

Press, 1988.<br />

---. Lambent Traces: Franz Kafka. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004.<br />

---. “Metaphor and Chiasmus in Kafka.” Newsletter of The Kafka Society of<br />

America. Number 2: December, 1981.<br />

---. “Kafka’s ‘The Judgment’ and Modern Rhetorical Theory.” Newsletter of The<br />

Kafka Society of America. Number 2: June, 1983.<br />

Critchley, Simon. The Ethics of Deconstruction: Derrida and Levinas: West Lafayette,<br />

Indiana. Purdue University Press, 1992.<br />

Davis, Colin. Levinas: An Introduction. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press,<br />

1996.<br />

Deleuze, Gilles, and Felix Guattari. Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature. Minneapolis:<br />

University of Minnesota Press, 1986.<br />

---. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Minneapolis: University of<br />

Minnesota Press, 1983.<br />

---. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Minneapolis: University of<br />

Minnesota Press, 1987.<br />

---. Difference and Repetition. New York: Columbia University Press, 1994.<br />

---. Pure Immanence. New York: Zone Books, 2000.<br />

---. The Fold: Leibniz and The Baroque. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota<br />

Press, 1999.<br />

De Man, Paul. Allegories of Reading: Figural Language in Rousseau, Nietzsche, Rilke,<br />

and Proust. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1979.<br />

139


Derrida, Jacques. Politics of Friendship. New York: Verso Publishers, 1997.<br />

---. Writing and Difference. New York: University of Chicago Press, 1978.<br />

---. Acts Of Literature: New York: Routledge, 1992.<br />

---. Limited Inc.: Evanstown: Northwestern University Press, 1988.<br />

---. Of Grammatology: Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1967.<br />

---. The Work of Mourning: New York: University of Chicago Press, 2001.<br />

---. Positions: Trans. Alan Bass Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981.<br />

---. Spectres of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning, and the New<br />

International. London: Routledge, 1994.<br />

---. Dissemination: Trans. Barbara Johnson. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,<br />

1981.<br />

DeSaussure, Ferdinand Course In General Linguistics. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1965.<br />

Ellis, John M. The Bizarre Texture of ‘The Judgment’ in The Problem of the Judgment –<br />

Eleven Approaches to Kafka’s Story, Angel Flores ed. (New York: Gordian Press,<br />

1977), p. 74.<br />

Ellison, David R. “Narrative and Music in Kafka and Blanchot: The Singing of<br />

Josephine.” New Haven: Yale French Studies, No. 93, 1998.<br />

Freud, Sigmund. The Interpretation of Dreams. New York: Avon Books, 1998.<br />

---. The Future of An Illusion: New York: Avon Books, 1997.<br />

Fynsk, Christopher. Language and Relation: That There is Language. Stanford: Stanford<br />

University Press, 1996.<br />

140


---. Heidegger: Thought and Historicity. Cornell University Press. Ithaca, New York,<br />

1986.<br />

Gasché, Rodolphe. “Infrastructures and Systematicity”. Deconstruction and Philosophy.<br />

Chicago & London: University of Chicago Press, 1987.<br />

---. The Tain of the Mirror: Derrida and the Philosophy of Reflection. Cambridge,<br />

Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986.<br />

Gilman, Sander. Franz Kafka: The Jewish Patient. New York: Routledge Publishers,<br />

1995.<br />

Gray Ronald. Franz Kafka. London: Cambridge University Press, 1973.<br />

---. Kafka: Twentieth Century Views. New York: Prentice Hall, 1962.<br />

Greenaway, Peter, Marguerite Gras (Editor) and Vernon Gras (Editor). Peter Greenaway:<br />

Interviews (Conversations With Filmmakers Series). University Press of<br />

Mississippi., 2000.<br />

Grozinger, Karl Erich. Kafka and Kabbalah. New York: Continuum Publishing, 1994.<br />

Guattari, Felix. Chaosmosis. Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1995.<br />

Hartman, Geoffrey H. Saving The Text: Literature Derrida Philosophy. Baltimore: Johns<br />

Hopkins Press, 1981.<br />

Heidegger, Martin. Basic Writings. San Francisco: Harper Collins, 1993.<br />

---. Being And Time. Harper San Francisco, 1962.<br />

---. The Question Concerning Technology, and Other Essays. Harper Collins, 1982.<br />

---. Poetry, Language, Thought. Perennial, 2001.<br />

141


Holland, Eugene W. Deleuze and Guattari’s Anti-Oedipus: Introduction to<br />

Schizoanalysis. New York: Routledge, 1999.<br />

Kafka, Franz. The Trial. New York: Schocken Books, 1998.<br />

---. Amerika. New York: Schocken Books, 1996.<br />

---. Metamorphosis and Other Stories. New York: Penguin Publishing, 1999.<br />

---. The Castle. New York: Schocken Books, 1992.<br />

---. Diaries 1910-1923. New York: Schocken Books 1976.<br />

---. The Blue Octavo Notebooks. Cambridge: Exchange Press, 1991.<br />

---. The Complete Stories. New York: Shocken Books, 1971.<br />

Kitto, Sir Frank. "Why Write Judgments?" Australian Law Journal Issue 66. 787,<br />

January 2005.<br />

Kristeva, Julia. Powers of Horror: An Essay on Abjection. New York: Columbia<br />

University Press, 1982.<br />

---. Desire in Language: A Semiotic Approach to Literature and Art. Ed.Leon Trans.<br />

Thomas Gora, Alice Jardine, Leon Roudiez. New York: Columbia University<br />

Press, 1980.<br />

Kundera, Milan. The Art of The Novel. New York: Harper Perennial Publishers, 1992.<br />

Lacan, Jacques. The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis. New York: Norton<br />

Publishers, 1978.<br />

Levinas, Emmanuel. Otherwise Than Being: Or Beyond Essence. Pittsburgh: Duquense<br />

University Press, 1998.<br />

142


---. Outside The Subject. Stanford California: Stanford University Press, 1994.<br />

---. Time & The Other. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1979.<br />

Lyotard, Jean-Francois. The Inhuman. Stanford California. Stanford University Press,<br />

1991.<br />

---. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Minneapolis: University of<br />

Minnesota Press, 1972.<br />

McLuhan, Marshall. Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man. Boston: MIT Press,<br />

1999.<br />

---. Essential McLuhan. New York: Basic Books, 1995.<br />

Murray, Jack. The Landscapes of Alienation: Ideological Subversion in Kafka, Celine<br />

and Onetti. Stanford, California: Stanford University Press, 1991.<br />

Musil, Robert. The Man Without Qualities Volume I. New York: Vintage Publishers,<br />

1995.<br />

---. Gesammelte Werke in zwei Bänden. Ed. Hrsg Von A. Frite, Reinbeck, 1978.<br />

---. Gesammelte Werke in neun Bänden. Ed. Hrsg Von A. Frite, Reinbeck, 1978.<br />

Nancy, Jean-Luc. Being Singular Plural. Stanford California: Stanford University Press,<br />

2000.<br />

---. The Sense Of The World. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997.<br />

Nietzsche, Freidrich. Beyond Good and Evil. (Translated by Walter Kaufman). New<br />

York: Vintage Books, 1967.<br />

143


---. The Birth Of Tragedy. (Translated by Walter Kaufman). New York: Vintage<br />

Books, 1967.<br />

---. The Gay Science. (Translated by Walter Kaufman). New York: Vintage Books,<br />

1967.<br />

---. On The Genealogy of Morals. (Trans. Walter Kaufman). New York: Vintage<br />

Books, 1967.<br />

---. Twilight of The Idols and The Anti-Christ. New York: Penguin Classics, 1992.<br />

---. Will To Power. (Trans. Walter Kaufman). New York: Vintage Books, 1967.<br />

Norris, Christopher. Deconstruction: Theory and Practice. London: Methuen, 1982.<br />

---. The Deconstructive Turn. London: Methuen, 1983.<br />

---. Contest of Faculties. London: Methuen, 1985.<br />

---. Derrida. London: Fontana, 1987.<br />

Pearson, Keith Ansell. Viroid Life: Perspectives on Nietzsche and the Transhuman<br />

Condition. New York: Routledge Publishers, 1997.<br />

Peperzak. Adriaan T. Ed. Ethics as First Philosophy. New York: Routledge, 1995.<br />

Politzer, Heinz. Franz Kafka: Parable and Paradox. Ithaca: Cornell University Press,<br />

1966.<br />

Rast, Hubert. “Urteilendes Urteilen: Kafka and the Law.” Newsletter of the Kafka<br />

Society of America. Number 18: December 1994.<br />

Rochlitz, Rainer. The Disenchantment of Art: The Philosophy of Walter Benjamin. New<br />

York: The Guilford Press, 1996.<br />

144


Ronell, Avital. Finitude’s Score: Essays For The End Of The Millennium. Lincoln<br />

Nebraska: University of Nebraska Press, 1994.<br />

---. Stupidity. Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 2002.<br />

Saussure, Ferdinand de. Course in General Linguistics. Edited by Bally and Reidlinger.<br />

(Trans.Wade Baskin). New York: Philosophical Library, 1959.<br />

Schirmacher, Wolfgang (ed). German 20th Century Philosophy: The Frankfurt School.<br />

The German Library 78. The Continuum International Publishing Group. New<br />

York, London, February 2000.<br />

---. Arthur Schopenhauer. Schopenhauer: Philosophical Writings. The German<br />

Library 27. The Continuum International Publishing Group. New York, London,<br />

July 1994.<br />

---. “Netculture” Poiesis 3. EGS Press. Toronto, 2001.<br />

Schrift, Alan D. Nietzsche’s French Legacy: A Geneaology of PostStructuralism. New<br />

York: Routledge, 1995.<br />

Schur, David. The Way of Oblivion: Heraclitus and Kafka. Cambridge: Harvard<br />

University Press, 1998.<br />

Smith, Gary. (Editor) On Walter Benjamin: Critical Essays and Recollections.<br />

Cambridge: The M.I.T. Press, 1991.<br />

Sokel, Walter. The Myth of the Power and the Self: Essays on Franz Kafka. Detroit:<br />

Wayne State University Press, 2002.<br />

145


Ulfers, Friedrich. “Kafka's Das Urteil: A Lesson in Reading.” Teaching Language<br />

Through Literature XXII, 1. 1982, pp. 30-38.<br />

---. “The Rose and the Wound: Images of Writing”. Fifth American Imagery<br />

Conference. November 1981.<br />

---. “The Maternal Motif in Kafka's Work.” Modern Language Association.<br />

December 1981.<br />

---. “The Idea of 'Bildung' in the Context of Nietzsche's Process Ontology.”<br />

International Conference on "Nietzsche: Society, Culture and Education."<br />

University of Durham, September 8-10, 2000.<br />

Ulmer, Gregory L. Heuretics: The Logic of Invention. Johns Hopins University Press.<br />

Baltimore, May 1994.<br />

---. Applied Grammatology: Post(e)-Pedagogy from Jacques Derrida to Joseph<br />

Beuys. Johns Hopkins University Press. Baltimore, 1992.<br />

Weber, Samuel. Mass Mediauras: Essays on Form. Technics and Media. Power<br />

Publications/ Stanford University Press. Sydney/Stanford, California, 1996.<br />

---. Religion and Media. Stanford University Press. Stanford, 2001.<br />

Zielinski, Siegfried, Gloria Custance (Translation). Audiovisions: Cinema and Television<br />

as entr'actes in History. Amsterdam University Press. Amsterdam, 1999.<br />

Zizek, Slavoj. Looking Awry: An Introduction To Lacan Through Popular Culture.<br />

Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1992.<br />

146


---. The Ticklish Subject: University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, 2001.<br />

147

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!