13.06.2015 Views

The Physical Basis of The Direction of Time (The Frontiers ...

The Physical Basis of The Direction of Time (The Frontiers ...

The Physical Basis of The Direction of Time (The Frontiers ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

4.6 <strong>The</strong> <strong>Time</strong> Arrow in Various Interpretations <strong>of</strong> Quantum <strong>The</strong>ory 127<br />

quantum theory in a deterministic way. However, this is not surprising, since<br />

it leaves Schrödinger’s wave function entirely unchanged, while the assumed<br />

trajectories for classical states, which would determine all observed quantities<br />

according to this model, have to remain unobservable and in drastic<br />

conflict with classical intuition (‘surrealistic’) in order to reproduce the empirically<br />

confirmed quantum probabilities by means <strong>of</strong> their postulated statistical<br />

distribution. Because <strong>of</strong> the ‘phenomenological’ wave–particle dualism<br />

(see Sect. 4.3.2), it also remains controversial in this theory whether the classical<br />

configurations must contain photon positions or electromagnetic fields<br />

(Holland 1993).<br />

Although wave functions and trajectories in configuration space are equally<br />

assumed to be real in this theory, 8 they are treated quite differently. While<br />

the former are usually regarded as ‘given’, the latter are always represented<br />

by an ensemble (without thereby contributing to the entropy). <strong>The</strong>ir initial<br />

probability distribution in this ensemble, which has to be regarded as incomplete<br />

information, is postulated to comply with the Born rule. Since the<br />

Bohm trajectories themselves remain unobservable, they can be said to serve<br />

as no more than artificial and empirically unfounded selectors for the ‘active’<br />

branch <strong>of</strong> the global wave function, to which the actual trajectory would be<br />

confined according to its dynamics. For example, entropy is calculated, in<br />

the form S[ ˆP |ψ〉〈ψ|] with an appropriate Zwanzig projection ˆP ,fromsucha<br />

component ψ – as though the wave function had been reduced by a real collapse<br />

(see Sect. 5 <strong>of</strong> Dürr, Goldstein and Zanghi 1993). While this description<br />

requires the same fact-like time asymmetry <strong>of</strong> the global wave function as decoherence,<br />

the selection <strong>of</strong> subsets <strong>of</strong> trajectories defines an external arrow <strong>of</strong><br />

time. A justification <strong>of</strong> this different treatment <strong>of</strong> wave functions and Bohm<br />

trajectories is not at all obvious (see Zeh 1999b).<br />

Similarly to Bohm’s theory, collapse theories (Pearle 1976, Ghirardi, Rimini,<br />

and Weber 1986) and the Everett interpretation (Everett, 1957) also<br />

assume the wave function to represent a real physical object. This is in contrast<br />

to genuine hidden variables theories, which intend to derive or explain<br />

the wave function from some (hoped-for) more fundamental level <strong>of</strong> description.<br />

<strong>The</strong>se latter theories are affected by various no-go theorems (such as<br />

Bell’s theorem) if they are assumed to be local. Otherwise, however, it is hard<br />

to see what could be gained from them in comparison to the global wave<br />

function itself as a nonlocal object.<br />

While collapse theories propose stochastic modifications <strong>of</strong> the Schrödinger<br />

equation, the Everett interpretation is based on the concept <strong>of</strong> ‘splitting ob-<br />

8 “No one can understand this theory until he is willing to think <strong>of</strong> ψ as a real<br />

objective field rather than just a ‘probability amplitude’ ” (Bell 1981). This<br />

statement may apply to quantum theory in general – quite in contrast to an<br />

analogous statement about Bohm’s trajectories, which are empirically unfounded<br />

and thus have no more than ‘religious’ status. A stochastic theory can always be<br />

deterministically completed by means <strong>of</strong> unobservable variables: any by definition<br />

unobservable (pseudo-)random number generator will do.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!