10.07.2015 Views

Intertemporal Substitution and Recursive Smooth Ambiguity ...

Intertemporal Substitution and Recursive Smooth Ambiguity ...

Intertemporal Substitution and Recursive Smooth Ambiguity ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

3. On the subdomain C × M, we obtain a pure risk setting where only the second-stager<strong>and</strong>omization is present. In this case, the model reduces to (12).4.4. Risk Aversion <strong>and</strong> <strong>Ambiguity</strong> AversionAs discussed before, the function W describes intertemporal substitution. Now, we discusshow ambiguity aversion is separated from risk aversion in the two-stage r<strong>and</strong>omization approach.We begin by characterizing risk aversion. In doing so, we restrict attention to thesubdomain C × ∆ (L) without subjective uncertainty. In this case the utility representationtakes the form in (18). Because there is two-stage r<strong>and</strong>omization, we have two risk attitudestoward the risk in the two stages (or in the first-order <strong>and</strong> the second-order).For the risk in the second stage, we remove the first-stage risk by assuming that the firststage lottery is degenerate. We then obtain the representation of recursive risk preferencegiven in (12). We can define risk aversion in the second stage in a st<strong>and</strong>ard way <strong>and</strong> showthat it is completely characterized by the concavity of u.Turn to risk aversion in the first stage. We define absolute risk aversion in the first stageas follows:Definition 7 The decision maker with preference {≽ s t} exhibits risk aversion in the firststage if for all s t , c ∈ C <strong>and</strong> l, l ′ ∈ L, λ ∈ [0, 1],(c, δ[λl ⊕ (1 − λ)l ′ ]) ≽ s t (c, λδ[l] + (1 − λ)δ[l ′ ]). (19)We can similarly define risk loving <strong>and</strong> risk neutrality in the first stage. In Definition7, λδ[l] + (1 − λ)δ[l ′ ] ∈ ∆ (L) represents a lottery in the first stage <strong>and</strong> δ[λl ⊕ (1 − λ)l ′ ]represents a degenerate lottery over the mixture λl ⊕(1−λ)l ′ in the second stage. Accordingto this definition, the decision maker may not be indifferent between these two lotteries, eventhough they give the same final outcome distribution. In particular, if the decision makerbelieves that the degenerate lottery is like a sure outcome <strong>and</strong> must be preferred, then hedisplays risk aversion in the first stage.Note that if we replace ≽ s t with ∼ s t in (19), we obtain a dynamic counterpart of Seo’s(2009) Reduction of Compound Lotteries axiom. Thus, according to our Definition 7, violationof the Reduction of Compound Lotteries reflects the decision maker’s attitude towardthe risk in the first stage. The following proposition characterizes this risk attitude.Proposition 3 Suppose {≽ s t} satisfies Axioms B1-B7. Then {≽ s t} exhibits risk aversionin the first-stage if <strong>and</strong> only if v ◦ u −1 is concave.23

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!