12.07.2015 Views

Levinas - The Levinas Reader (ed Hand)

Levinas - The Levinas Reader (ed Hand)

Levinas - The Levinas Reader (ed Hand)

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

6 IntroductionPhilosophical saying is no longer devot<strong>ed</strong> to knowl<strong>ed</strong>ge and the process ofthematization culminating in self-presence. Speech is put in question sinceit is the locus of a face-to-face relation in which the Infinite reveals itself inits absolute difference. <strong>The</strong> primacy of the other's <strong>ed</strong>ict means that languageis not simply enact<strong>ed</strong> within a consciousness, as <strong>Levinas</strong> believes itultimately remains in both Husserl and Heidegger, where it is still bound tothe process of comprehension. For <strong>Levinas</strong>, it is language which conditionsrational thought, and the primordial face to face of language constitutesreason itself. Reason lives in language, since the first signification is theinfinity of the intelligence which expresses itself in the face. For <strong>Levinas</strong>,society and sigrtification prec<strong>ed</strong>e the impersonal structures of knowl<strong>ed</strong>geand reason. This makes <strong>Levinas</strong> particularly open to artistic expression (seechapters 7 to 10) and to the entire nature of philosophical discourse (seechapter 11).This attention to language, and the meontological subjectivity which itcarries is most strongly experienc<strong>ed</strong> in Otherwise than Being or BeyondEssence. <strong>Levinas</strong>'s earlier descriptions of eros now become the basic languageof the responsibility for the other, as 'having-the-other-in-one's skin'(see p. 104 below). In the way in which this vocabulary contests 'intellectualism',it bears witness to an ethical relationship with alterity. For <strong>Levinas</strong>sees the act of saying, and the exposure ,it entails, as the mark, and thevery possibility, of ethical sincerity. Whereas ontology ultimately mustr<strong>ed</strong>uce saying to the totalizing closure of the said, saying is a state ofopenness to the other. It is for that reason that <strong>Levinas</strong> has to speak of astate that is otherwise than Being, or being's other, since the ontologicalterms of philosophy in Husserl and Heidegger dissimulate and subordinatethe primordial subjectivity structur<strong>ed</strong> as responsibility in which one findsoneself as soon as one enters language, prior to any assumption of that role.Saying is 'the commitment of an approach, the one for the other, the verysignifyingness of signification,6 prior to being a communication in which atruth is manifest<strong>ed</strong>. Saying therefore breaks through the noema involv<strong>ed</strong> inintentionality, stripping me in extreme passivity of every identical quiddity.Subjectivity is the dis-interest<strong>ed</strong> vulnerability of saying.This offering of oneself is not a role that is assum<strong>ed</strong>, but is a goodnessthat occurs despite oneself. <strong>The</strong> Biblical 'Here I am!' (I Samuel, 3: 4) whichis offer<strong>ed</strong> as a responsibility for the other prior to commitment does notinvolve the r<strong>ed</strong>uction of subjectivity to consciousness. Instead it is subjectum,subjectivity as substitution and expiation for the other. <strong>The</strong> philosophicallanguage of the book, and the book's philosophical view of language,enact a discourse in terms of 'otherwise than being' that freessubjectivity from the ontic or ontological programme.<strong>The</strong> responsibility for the other represent<strong>ed</strong> by 'Here I am!' is therefore a

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!