11.12.2012 Views

Stumpf 's Cognitive-Evaluative Theory of Emotion

Stumpf 's Cognitive-Evaluative Theory of Emotion

Stumpf 's Cognitive-Evaluative Theory of Emotion

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Stumpf</strong> <strong>'s</strong> <strong>Cognitive</strong>-<strong>Evaluative</strong> <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Emotion</strong><br />

As a historical contribution to the current cognition-emotion<br />

debate in psychology, this article seeks (a) to bring to<br />

the readers' attention the largely ignored tradition <strong>of</strong> cognitive<br />

emotion theory within introspective psychology by<br />

reviewing what is probably the most clearly formulated<br />

cognitive emotion theory <strong>of</strong> this period, that proposed by<br />

Carl <strong>Stumpf</strong>, and (b) to point out the relevance <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong><br />

contributions to the psychology <strong>of</strong> emotions for the contemporary<br />

cognition-emotion discussion. It is suggested<br />

that <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> version <strong>of</strong> a cognitive-evaluative theory <strong>of</strong><br />

emotion deserves the serious attention <strong>of</strong> contemporary<br />

investigators and that several <strong>of</strong> his objections to noncognitive<br />

theories <strong>of</strong> emotion retain their force against modern<br />

versions <strong>of</strong> these theories.<br />

The relation between emotions and cognitions has become<br />

a much-debated topic during recent years, and the<br />

American Psychologist has been a major forum for that<br />

discussion (e.g., Birnbaum, 1981; Holyoak & Gordon,<br />

1984; Isen, 1984; Lazarus, 1981, 1982, 1984; Lazarus &<br />

Smith, 1988; LeDoux, 1989; Leventhal & Scherer, 1987;<br />

Oatley& Johnson-Laird, 1987; Russell &Woudzia, 1986;<br />

Zajonc, 1980, 1981, 1984; Zajonc, Murphy, &Inglehart,<br />

1989). The two main opposing positions in this debate<br />

are those <strong>of</strong> cognitively oriented emotion theorists, who<br />

hold that cognitions (cognitive appraisals) are necessary<br />

for emotions (e.g., Lazarus, 1982, 1984), and those <strong>of</strong><br />

noncognitive or "independent systems" theorists, who<br />

deny this claim and hold instead that cognitive appraisals<br />

and emotions are independent in principle (e.g., Zajonc,<br />

1980, 1984; Zajonc et al., 1989).<br />

In the present article we contribute to the current<br />

cognition-emotion debate with a historical study. Such<br />

a study seemed to be indicated because, apparently, it is<br />

not generally recognized that the cognition-emotion issue<br />

has been with psychology since its very beginning as an<br />

institutionalized science in the past century, and that the<br />

contributions <strong>of</strong> cognitively oriented introspectionists to<br />

the psychology <strong>of</strong> emotion remain <strong>of</strong> considerable relevance<br />

today. According to the standard account <strong>of</strong> the<br />

history <strong>of</strong> emotion research, the institutionalized science<br />

<strong>of</strong> psychology began with noncognitive theories <strong>of</strong> emotion<br />

(e.g., James, 1884; Wundt, 1896) and continued with<br />

such theories until the cognitive revolution <strong>of</strong> the 1960s,<br />

when a number <strong>of</strong> theorists—in particular, Magda B. Arnold,<br />

Richard S. Lazarus, and Stanley Schachter—revived<br />

the ancient tradition <strong>of</strong> cognitive emotion theory dating<br />

back to Aristotle (see, e.g., Averill, 1983; Frijda, 1986;<br />

Frijda, Kuipers, & ter Schure, 1989; Lyons, 1980; Mandler,<br />

1984; Solomon, 1988). In this article we show that<br />

34<br />

Rainer Reisenzein and Wolfgang Schonpflug<br />

Free University Berlin, Berlin, Germany<br />

this historical view is biased, by bringing to the readers'<br />

attention the cognitive line <strong>of</strong> emotion theorizing within<br />

introspective psychology, which is largely ignored today<br />

(e.g., Brentano, 1874/1971; Husserl, 1901/1975; <strong>Stumpf</strong>,<br />

1899, 1907a). We concentrate on what we believe to be<br />

the most clearly formulated cognitive theory <strong>of</strong> emotion<br />

<strong>of</strong> this tradition, that proposed by Carl <strong>Stumpf</strong> (see, in<br />

particular, <strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1899, 1907a).<br />

Our main motive for drawing the readers' attention<br />

to <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> contributions to the psychology <strong>of</strong> emotion<br />

is not, however, to correct a biased historical account <strong>of</strong><br />

the history <strong>of</strong> emotion research. Rather, it is with the<br />

belief that, far from being <strong>of</strong> merely historical interest,<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> views still deserve the serious attention <strong>of</strong> contemporary<br />

investigators. For one reason, <strong>Stumpf</strong> proposed<br />

a highly interesting theory concerning the nature <strong>of</strong> emotions<br />

and their relation to cognitive appraisals. For another<br />

reason, the major alternative theories <strong>of</strong> emotion to which<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> stood in opposition—namely, those <strong>of</strong> James<br />

(1884, 1890/1950) and Wundt (1896)—are direct precursors<br />

<strong>of</strong> contemporary noncognitive (or independent<br />

systems) theories <strong>of</strong> emotion (e.g., Buck, 1985; Izard,<br />

1977; LeDoux, 1989;Tomkins, 1980; Zajonc, 1980, 1984;<br />

Zajonc et al., 1989), and several <strong>of</strong> the issues raised by<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> in the intellectual exchange with these theorists<br />

are <strong>of</strong> continued relevance to the current cognition-emotion<br />

debate.<br />

We present (a) a systematic review <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> cognitive-evaluative<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> emotions, (b) a review <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> main arguments against the major noncognitive<br />

theories <strong>of</strong> his time, namely, sensualistic (e.g., James,<br />

1890/1950) and mentalistic (e.g., Wundt, 1896) feeling<br />

theories, and (c) a discussion <strong>of</strong> the relevance <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong><br />

views on emotion for the contemporary cognition-emotion<br />

debate.<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> <strong>Cognitive</strong>-<strong>Evaluative</strong> <strong>Theory</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Emotion</strong><br />

Carl <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1848-1936), a student <strong>of</strong> Franz Brentano<br />

and Rudolf Hermann Lotze, spent the main part <strong>of</strong> his<br />

Ludy T. Benjamin, Jr. served as action editor for this article.<br />

Parts <strong>of</strong> this article are based on a paper presented at the 36th<br />

Congress <strong>of</strong> the Deutsche Gesellschaft fur Psychologie in Berlin, October<br />

1988. An extended discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> theory is available in German<br />

(Reisenzein, 1992).<br />

We would like to thank Jochen Brandtstadter, Richard Lazarus,<br />

and Bernard Weiner, as well as the participants <strong>of</strong> the symposium History<br />

<strong>of</strong> Psychology in Berlin—in particular, Eckart Scheerer—for their useful<br />

comments on an earlier version <strong>of</strong> the article.<br />

Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to<br />

Rainer Reisenzein, Department <strong>of</strong> Psychology (WE 7), Free University<br />

Berlin, 1000 Berlin 33, Habelschwerdter AUee 45, Germany.<br />

January 1992 • American Psychologist<br />

Copyright 1992 by the American Psychological Association, Inc. 0OO3-O66X/92/S2.0O<br />

Vol. 47, No. 1,34-45


academic career (1894-1921) as pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> philosophy<br />

and director <strong>of</strong> the Institute <strong>of</strong> Experimental Psychology<br />

at the Friedrich-Wilhelm University, Berlin. Reflecting<br />

these positions, his publications cover a diversity <strong>of</strong> themes<br />

in philosophy as well as in theoretical and empirical psychology<br />

(cf. <strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1924, pp. 58-61). Concerning the<br />

latter, he is best known for his fundamental contributions<br />

to the psychology <strong>of</strong> music and tone (e.g., <strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1883,<br />

1890), which continue to be given at least passing reference<br />

in the contemporary literature (e.g., Krumhansl,<br />

1991). In general, however, <strong>Stumpf</strong> has become a "nearly<br />

forgotten psychologist" (Sprung, Sprung, & Kernchen,<br />

1986, p. 509), even in German psychology. He is much<br />

less well-known today than, for example, are his students<br />

Kurt K<strong>of</strong>fka, Wolfgang Kohler, Kurt Lewin, and Max<br />

Wertheimer, the founders <strong>of</strong> the Berlin school <strong>of</strong> Gestalt<br />

psychology, and Edmund Husserl, the founder <strong>of</strong> phenomenology.<br />

The cognitive-evaluative theory <strong>of</strong> emotions was first<br />

presented by <strong>Stumpf</strong> in an article published in 1899. The<br />

complementary theory <strong>of</strong> affective sensations was proposed<br />

eight years later (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1907a); this theory was<br />

defended against various criticisms by <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1916).<br />

The three articles just mentioned were reprinted in 1928<br />

as a separate volume, together with an introduction containing<br />

further clarifying remarks (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1928). The<br />

present review is mainly based on these writings, but additional<br />

material (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1907b, 1907c, 1924) was also<br />

considered when it helped to clarify pertinent issues. To<br />

get a firm grasp <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> theory <strong>of</strong> emotion, it is essential<br />

to know his general views on the nature and classification<br />

<strong>of</strong> mental states.<br />

The Nature and Classification <strong>of</strong> Mental States<br />

According to <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1907b), the mind can be conceptualized<br />

as "the totality <strong>of</strong> mental states and dispositions<br />

. . . [which] are lawfully connected among one another,<br />

their contents, and their non-conscious or non-psychological<br />

determinants" (pp. 8-9; see also <strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1924, p.<br />

48).' Nondispositional, or as we will say occurrent (e.g.,<br />

Lyons, 1980), mental states were for <strong>Stumpf</strong> first and<br />

foremost conscious mental events accessible to introspection,<br />

but he accepted that it is legitimate to postulate<br />

unconscious mental events as theoretical entities, if doing<br />

so seems to be required for explanatory reasons (<strong>Stumpf</strong>,<br />

1899, 1907b). Furthermore, following Brentano (1874/<br />

1955), <strong>Stumpf</strong> held that a characteristic feature <strong>of</strong> mental<br />

states is their intentionality (Husserl, 1901/1975) or object<br />

directedness. As Brentano illustrated this feature <strong>of</strong> mental<br />

states, if one, for example, perceives, believes, desires,<br />

loves, or hates, one always perceives, believes, desires, loves<br />

or hates something. This something (which may not actually<br />

exist) is the intentional object <strong>of</strong> the respective<br />

mental state. Intentional mental states can therefore be<br />

construed as special types <strong>of</strong> relations between the person<br />

and the object <strong>of</strong> the mental state (Brentano, 1874/1955);<br />

different intentional states can differ with regard either<br />

to their objects or to the kind <strong>of</strong> intentional relation, the<br />

"mode <strong>of</strong> mental apperception," that links person and<br />

object (Brentano, 1874/1971, p. 89; <strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1928; see<br />

also Searle, 1983). For example, believing that it rains<br />

and believing that it snows are intentional states <strong>of</strong> the<br />

same psychological mode (namely, believing), but they<br />

have different objects. In contrast, believing that it rains,<br />

desiring that it rains, and being angry that it rains are<br />

intentional mental states that have the same object, but<br />

each <strong>of</strong> them represents that object in a different psychological<br />

mode.<br />

It may be seen as a late vindication <strong>of</strong> Brentano that<br />

intentionality as a mark <strong>of</strong> (some) mental states has again<br />

become a central issue in the contemporary philosophy<br />

<strong>of</strong> mind (e.g., Chisholm, 1967; Mackie, 1975; Mohanty,<br />

1986; Sayre, 1986; Searle, 1983). Contemporary philosophers<br />

typically see the essential feature <strong>of</strong> intentional<br />

mental states in their being representational states having<br />

semantic properties; that is, they represent something by<br />

virtue <strong>of</strong> their content and may thereby refer to items in<br />

the world (e.g., Bieri, 1986; Fodor, 1981, 1987; Searle,<br />

1983). However, in contrast to <strong>Stumpf</strong>, who followed<br />

Brentano in assuming—albeit with certain reservations<br />

(<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1916)—that all mental states are intentional,<br />

most contemporary philosophers <strong>of</strong> mind agree with<br />

Husserl (1901/1975) that only a subset <strong>of</strong> mental states<br />

are intentional. In particular, sensations and other "raw<br />

feels" are usually not regarded as intentional mental states<br />

today (Rorty, 1979; Searle, 1983).<br />

Furthermore, <strong>Stumpf</strong> divided the totality <strong>of</strong> mental<br />

states into two broad categories, labeled by the technical<br />

terms intellectual and affective (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1928; see also<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1907b). Each category was thought to comprise<br />

a number <strong>of</strong> subcategories. Concerning intellectual states,<br />

the subcategory most important to the present review<br />

comprises various types <strong>of</strong> beliefs (called judgments by<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>). Concerning the affective category, it was further<br />

subdivided by <strong>Stumpf</strong> into (a) active affective states or<br />

desires, which comprise nonperformative or optative<br />

(Green, 1986) desires (i.e., desires or wishes to the effect<br />

that something should or should not be the case) as well<br />

as motivational desires (desires to do something) and volitional<br />

states (intentions, willings); and (b) passive affective<br />

states, which comprise what could be called occurrent<br />

pro-evaluations and con-evaluations, or approvals and<br />

disapprovals <strong>of</strong> a (past, present, future, or merely possible)<br />

state <strong>of</strong> affairs. <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1907a) characterized these evaluations<br />

as "affective attitudes . . . which we call acceptance<br />

or rejection" (p. 15); Brentano (1874/1971) spoke<br />

<strong>of</strong> the appraisal <strong>of</strong> an object as "good pleasurable" versus<br />

"bad unpleasurable" (pp. 88-89).<br />

It must be emphasized that intellectual and affective<br />

mental states were regarded by <strong>Stumpf</strong>, in accord with<br />

Brentano, as fundamentally different psychological modes,<br />

or kinds <strong>of</strong> intentional relations <strong>of</strong> individual to object,<br />

which cannot be reduced to one another. In particular,<br />

the affective states cannot be reduced to evaluative beliefs,<br />

that is, beliefs having evaluative contents (the latter are<br />

1 All translations from German are ours.<br />

January 1992 • American Psychologist 35


simply a subspecies <strong>of</strong> belief; see also Brentano 1874/<br />

1971). According to <strong>Stumpf</strong>, for example, wishing that<br />

it should rain (a nonperformative desire) is a mental state<br />

quite different from believing that it would be good if it<br />

rained; desiring to take a walk (a performative desire) is<br />

different from believing that it would be desirable to take<br />

a walk; and most important, taking a pro-evaluative or<br />

con-evaluative stance toward a state <strong>of</strong> affairs is to be<br />

distinguished from thinking it good or bad that this state<br />

<strong>of</strong> affairs obtains. Thus, <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> pro-evaluations and<br />

con-evaluations were conceptualized by him as unique<br />

psychological modes <strong>of</strong> relating to objects that are fundamentally<br />

different from the believing mode, even<br />

though pro-evaluations and con-evaluations may be<br />

caused by, or may cause, evaluative beliefs (and this may,<br />

in fact, be a reason why these two kinds <strong>of</strong> mental states<br />

tend to be confused). This does not mean, however, that<br />

all types <strong>of</strong> intentional states were held to be irreducible<br />

to more basic ones. On the contrary, according to <strong>Stumpf</strong>,<br />

emotions can be reduced to beliefs and evaluations.<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> assumption that performative and nonperformative<br />

desires and in particular pro-evaluations and<br />

con-evaluations are fundamentally different from beliefs,<br />

including evaluative beliefs, must be regarded as a fundamental<br />

postulate <strong>of</strong> his theory <strong>of</strong> emotion; therefore,<br />

its tenability can perhaps be judged only by the overall<br />

success <strong>of</strong> the theory in explaining emotions. However,<br />

it should at least be noted that this assumption is fairly<br />

well in accord with current theorizing in the philosophy<br />

<strong>of</strong> mind. Many contemporary philosophers think not only<br />

"that belief and desire are somehow the basic intentional<br />

states" (Searle, 1983, p. 29), but that desires, wishes, and<br />

action tendencies are different from and not reducible to<br />

(evaluative) beliefs (Marks, 1986; at least implicitly, this<br />

assumption seems to be shared by many contemporary<br />

psychologists in the areas <strong>of</strong> emotion and motivation; see,<br />

e.g.,Frijda, 1986; Kuhl, 1983). In fact, this consideration<br />

has recently given rise to a new class <strong>of</strong> cognitively oriented<br />

emotion theories, which seek to analyze emotions<br />

in terms <strong>of</strong> beliefs and (nonperformative) desires (e.g.,<br />

Green, 1986; Marks, 1982; Searle, 1983). In contrast to<br />

these recent belief-desire theories <strong>of</strong> emotion, however,<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899, 1928) thought that the central evaluative<br />

elements <strong>of</strong> emotions, namely, occurrent pro-evaluations<br />

and con-evaluations, are not reducible to desires or<br />

wishes (desiring or wishing that something should or<br />

should not be the case; for a recent discussion <strong>of</strong> this<br />

issue that might have found <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> approval, see<br />

Baier, 1986). For although pro-evaluations and conevaluations<br />

were regarded by <strong>Stumpf</strong> as being more<br />

similar to desires and wishes than to beliefs, he thought<br />

that desires, in contrast to pro-evaluations and con-evaluations,<br />

involve a phenomenologically salient, if difficultto-define,<br />

irreducible element <strong>of</strong> "things should be in a<br />

certain way" (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1928, p. XV). Perhaps one could<br />

add that pro-evaluations and con-evaluations are those<br />

kinds <strong>of</strong> unique psychological modes <strong>of</strong> relating to objects<br />

that arise if desires are believed to have been fulfilled<br />

or frustrated.<br />

36<br />

The Nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>Emotion</strong>s<br />

According to <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899), an emotion is "a passive<br />

affective state which is directed at a judged state <strong>of</strong> affairs"<br />

(p. 56). As mentioned earlier, the term passive affective<br />

state designates an occurrent intentional pro- or conevaluation,<br />

or approval or disapproval, <strong>of</strong> an object or a<br />

state <strong>of</strong> affairs. That this evaluation is "directed at a judged<br />

state <strong>of</strong> affairs" means that the evaluation is "based on a<br />

judgment" (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1899, p. 49), that is, an occurrent<br />

belief, opinion, conviction, or supposition. Closer examination<br />

reveals that <strong>Stumpf</strong> regarded the relation between<br />

beliefs and evaluations, more precisely, as being<br />

tw<strong>of</strong>old: First, there is a causal connection between these<br />

mental states; that is, the beliefs (or, more precisely, a<br />

person<strong>'s</strong> coming to hold the beliefs) cause the evaluations;<br />

they "belong to the conditions which produce [evaluations]"<br />

(<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1899, p. 58). Second, there is a semantic<br />

relation between the contents <strong>of</strong> the beliefs and evaluations:<br />

Evaluations are directed at the same state <strong>of</strong> affairs<br />

that is also the object <strong>of</strong> the beliefs. Hence, whereas causal<br />

connections link beliefs and evaluations at the physical<br />

level (i.e., at the level <strong>of</strong> their biological realization or<br />

instantiation), identical—or at least partly overlapping—<br />

contents are the glue whereby these mental states are held<br />

together at the semantic level (see also Rey, 1983).<br />

As described so far, <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> theory <strong>of</strong> emotion<br />

permits the interpretation that emotions are just evaluations<br />

and, hence, that emotions could occur or could be<br />

produced, at least in principle (e.g., in experiments using<br />

direct brain stimulation), in noncognitive ways (cf. Zajonc,<br />

1980, 1984). <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899), however, did not think<br />

so. Rather, he noted,<br />

I would not admit, however, that the intellectual states are only<br />

[emphasis added] causes <strong>of</strong> emotions. . . . Envy comprises the<br />

presentation (Vorstellung) and judgment <strong>of</strong> the good concerned<br />

as one belonging to the fellow human, and it exists only as long<br />

as these intellectual elements do exist; they belong to its substance.<br />

If the presentation disappears or the judgment changes,<br />

the affect disappears or changes as well, even though in many<br />

cases aftereffects and sensory repercussions may remain, (p. 58)<br />

It is evident from this quotation that beliefs were<br />

regarded by <strong>Stumpf</strong> not just as the typical causes <strong>of</strong> emotions<br />

(i.e., evaluations), but as derinitionally necessary<br />

causal conditions: "The presence <strong>of</strong> an emotion-relevant<br />

judgment is essential to the definition [<strong>of</strong> emotions]"<br />

(<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1907b, p. 27). That is, even though there may<br />

be evaluations that are produced in other ways than<br />

through beliefs (as <strong>Stumpf</strong>, in fact, assumed in 1899),<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> thought that such noncognitively caused evaluations<br />

are not proper emotions: An evaluation is a proper<br />

emotion only if the appropriate beliefs are also present<br />

and causally effective in the right way. One reason <strong>Stumpf</strong><br />

adopted this view was that he believed that the discriminating<br />

features <strong>of</strong> affects consist primarily <strong>of</strong> "differences<br />

<strong>of</strong> the presentations and judgments underlying the [evaluations]"<br />

(<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1899, p. 95). This assumption entails<br />

that cognitions (beliefs) are necessary for the definition<br />

<strong>of</strong> different types <strong>of</strong> emotion.<br />

January 1992 • American Psychologist


Note that <strong>Stumpf</strong> did not propose, as do some contemporary<br />

theorists (e.g., Frijda et al., 1989; Johnson-<br />

Laird & Oatley, 1989; Lazarus, Kanner, & Folkman,<br />

1980; Ortony & Clore, 1989), that emotions are complexes<br />

<strong>of</strong> mental states consisting <strong>of</strong> several elements (in<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> case, beliefs and evaluations) and, hence, that<br />

beliefs are related to emotions as part to whole. Not only<br />

does <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899, 1907b) caution against this possible<br />

misunderstanding <strong>of</strong> his position, but his assumption that<br />

beliefs are causes <strong>of</strong> emotions implies that he could not<br />

have accepted this view without rejecting what is generally<br />

regarded—at least since Hume (cf. Mackie, 1974)—as<br />

an indispensable ingredient <strong>of</strong> an acceptable scientific<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> causality (and is, in fact, also well in accord<br />

with our everyday concept <strong>of</strong> causality), namely, that<br />

cause and effect must be distinct singular events. According<br />

to this principle—which one must accept, among<br />

other reasons, if one wants to rule out self-causation—<br />

an event cannot be a cause <strong>of</strong> another event <strong>of</strong> which it<br />

is a part; in this case the effect would subsume the cause,<br />

implying that the cause partly causes itself. Rather, emotions<br />

are belief-caused evaluations, that is, that subclass<br />

<strong>of</strong> evaluations that have the appropriate causal history,<br />

that is, they have been caused by appropriate beliefs regarding<br />

the object <strong>of</strong> the emotion. In modern terminology,<br />

emotions are in part functionally specified evaluations,<br />

that is, evaluations that are partly defined by reference<br />

to their causes, analogous to, for example, the definition<br />

<strong>of</strong> "sunburn" as an "inflammation <strong>of</strong> the skin caused by<br />

over-exposure to sunlight" (Gordon, 1978, p. 125). Note<br />

that such a functional definition <strong>of</strong> emotions is in accord<br />

both with the functionalist view <strong>of</strong> mental states (see<br />

Block, 1980; Fodor, 1975)—which is regarded by many<br />

as the metaphysical backbone <strong>of</strong> contemporary cognitivism—and<br />

with the views <strong>of</strong> several earlier and later emotion<br />

theorists. Already Aristotle (1980) defined fear as a<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> displeasure or perturbation arising from the idea<br />

<strong>of</strong> impending evil; Descartes (1649/1984) defined several<br />

<strong>of</strong> his nonbasic emotions as subtypes <strong>of</strong> basic feelings<br />

whose discriminating features consist in their being<br />

caused by particular types <strong>of</strong> appraisals; and Arnold<br />

(1970) defined emotion in general as "a felt tendency<br />

toward anything appraised as good, and away from anything<br />

appraised as bad" (p. 176; for further examples, see<br />

Davidson, 1976; Gordon, 1974; Lyons, 1980; Searle,<br />

1983; Wilson, 1972).<br />

We can therefore render <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> proposal concerning<br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> emotions in the following final form:<br />

An emotion is an occurrent pro- or con-evaluation <strong>of</strong> a<br />

state <strong>of</strong> affairs, which is (a) caused by beliefs and (b) semantically<br />

linked to their contents. To use <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> example,<br />

envy may be (roughly) defined as an occurrent<br />

con-evaluation (a disapproval) <strong>of</strong> another person<strong>'s</strong> possessing<br />

a desired good that one lacks, which is caused, in<br />

part at least, by the belief that the other person possesses<br />

that good, whereas one lacks it oneself. Similarly, pride<br />

may be (roughly) defined as an occurrent pro-evaluation<br />

(an approval) <strong>of</strong> a state <strong>of</strong> affairs or an object, caused in<br />

part by the beliefs that this state <strong>of</strong> affairs or object exists<br />

and that it is relevantly "connected" to oneself (Searle,<br />

1983). In many cases, this latter belief takes the more<br />

specific form <strong>of</strong> believing that one has been causally responsible<br />

for bringing about this state <strong>of</strong> affairs (Weiner,<br />

1986). The writings <strong>of</strong> Descartes and Spinoza, to which<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> referred, as well as recent research on cognitive<br />

appraisals in emotion, suggests to us that this kind <strong>of</strong><br />

belief-evaluation analysis <strong>of</strong> emotions may in principle<br />

be possible for a wide range <strong>of</strong> affects (see, e.g., Frijda et<br />

al., 1989; Ortony, Clore, & Collins, 1988; Reisenzein &<br />

H<strong>of</strong>mann, 1990; Roseman, 1984; Scherer, 1984; Searle,<br />

1983; Smith & Ellsworth, 1985; Solomon, 1976; Weiner,<br />

1986; Wierzbicka, 1972).<br />

Additional Clarifications and Elaborations<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> further clarified the core tenet <strong>of</strong> his theory the<br />

following significant respects:<br />

1. Concerning the belief component <strong>of</strong> emotional<br />

appraisals (judgments), <strong>Stumpf</strong> emphasized—much in<br />

line with Lazarus (1982)—that the term judgment must<br />

be understood in a broad sense. <strong>Emotion</strong>-relevant judgments<br />

must not be restricted to consciously made evaluative<br />

judgments or to hypothetical or categorical judgments<br />

in the logical sense. Rather, "already the very first<br />

beginnings <strong>of</strong> nondeliberate apperception and interpretation<br />

<strong>of</strong> sense-impressions" (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1899, p. 51) are to<br />

be regarded as judgments. Elementary judgments are already<br />

involved in spatial orientation, in the distinction<br />

<strong>of</strong> one<strong>'s</strong> own body from other objects, in the recognition<br />

<strong>of</strong> objects, the apperception <strong>of</strong> similarities and differences,<br />

and the expectation <strong>of</strong> similar future cases on the basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> earlier ones. "Psychology," <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899) wrote, "will<br />

hardly be able to make do without this generalization [<strong>of</strong><br />

the concept <strong>of</strong> judgment], even though one may disagree<br />

about the best label" (p. 51). Furthermore, judgments<br />

can appear in consciousness in very indeterminate and<br />

weak forms, and an occurrent evaluative reaction can<br />

continue even after the judgment is no longer at the focus<br />

<strong>of</strong> consciousness, as presumably is <strong>of</strong>ten the case with<br />

moods. However, the affective state in the latter case is<br />

then no longer <strong>of</strong> exactly the same kind as proper emotions.<br />

Finally, to account for some apparently problematic<br />

cases, one may potentially make use <strong>of</strong> the "auxiliary<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> unconscious presentations and judgments"<br />

(<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1899, p. 50).<br />

2. The assumption that both emotions themselves<br />

and their building blocks (beliefs and evaluations) are<br />

representational mental states presupposes that there exists<br />

an internal system <strong>of</strong> representation (Fodor, 1975).<br />

Apparently, for <strong>Stumpf</strong> the most important emotion-relevant<br />

representational system was language: Usually the<br />

state <strong>of</strong> affairs at which emotions are directed are mentally<br />

represented as affirmative sentences. However,<br />

Neither linguistic formulations, nor universal concepts are absolutely<br />

necessary for [emotion-relevant] judgments. Thus, a<br />

cognized or believed state <strong>of</strong> affairs, which we would linguistically<br />

express by means <strong>of</strong> an affirmative sentence, and which we would<br />

think with the help <strong>of</strong> concepts, can also be represented in consciousness<br />

unformulated. (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1928, p. XIII)<br />

January 1992 • American Psychologist 37


That is at least without being formulated in a natural<br />

language. Whereas <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1928) was referring to a sensory<br />

or imaginal system <strong>of</strong> representation, contemporary<br />

emotion theorists generally prefer to assume a languageindependent,<br />

but nevertheless importantly languagelike,<br />

propositional medium <strong>of</strong> representation (e.g., Mandler,<br />

1984; Oatley & Johnson-Laird, 1987; see also Fodor,<br />

1975, 1981). Because emotionally relevant cognitions are,<br />

in principle, language independent, it is possible that prelinguistic<br />

infants as well as animals have emotions. That<br />

they do in fact have at least simple emotions is, according<br />

to <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1928), evident to everybody who is not prejudiced<br />

in favor <strong>of</strong> behavioristic notions.<br />

3. As has already been mentioned, it is primarily<br />

the judgments (beliefs) on which the differentiation between<br />

affects is based. Although evaluations make up the<br />

core <strong>of</strong> emotion, the differentiation that they provide is<br />

relatively crude (essentially, positive vs. negative); hence,<br />

the remaining differentiations between emotions must be<br />

due to beliefs:<br />

A present, past, or future state <strong>of</strong> affairs [must] be cognized or<br />

represented as such if an emotion is to arise, and... the quality<br />

<strong>of</strong> the emotion depends primarily on how this state <strong>of</strong> affairs is<br />

represented in our thinking. (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1899, p. 54)<br />

Because cognitions are the primary discriminating features<br />

<strong>of</strong> the emotions, they are also (together with evaluations)<br />

the natural principle <strong>of</strong> classification <strong>of</strong> emotions<br />

into larger groups. In fact, we already distinguish in common<br />

sense, for example, between affects that are directed<br />

at present, past, and future states <strong>of</strong> affairs; affects that<br />

concern beneficial and those that concern harmful events;<br />

and affects that are about our own versus others' welfare<br />

(<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1899).<br />

4. Finally, <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899) noted that his theory has<br />

an obvious ontogenetic implication: Any particular emotion<br />

can only arise once its cognitive basis is present. For<br />

example, a child can only experience envy once he or she<br />

is capable <strong>of</strong> forming a belief to the effect that a desired<br />

good belongs to a fellow human. Because <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899)<br />

believed that newborns lack the cognitive prerequisites<br />

<strong>of</strong> emotions ("the occurrence <strong>of</strong> a proper emotion presupposes<br />

a certain amount <strong>of</strong> cognitive development," p.<br />

51), he held against Wundt that genuine emotions cannot<br />

be attributed to them. This proposal seems to be supported<br />

by more recent developmental evidence (e.g.,<br />

Averill, 1982; Frijda, 1986; Rozin & Fallon, 1987).<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> s Arguments Against Noncognitive<br />

Theories <strong>of</strong> <strong>Emotion</strong> and His <strong>Theory</strong><br />

<strong>of</strong> Affective Sensations<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899) attempted to support his cognitive-evaluative<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> emotions both directly, by trying to show<br />

that it was consistent with the available evidence and that<br />

it explained the most important facts about emotions,<br />

and indirectly, by trying to demonstrate that the major<br />

existing alternative theories <strong>of</strong> emotion were inadequate.<br />

Concerning the evidence for his theory, <strong>Stumpf</strong> emphasized<br />

that it explained a variety <strong>of</strong> salient aspects <strong>of</strong> emo-<br />

38<br />

tions. In particular, it explained the intentionality <strong>of</strong><br />

emotions, and it gave a plausible account <strong>of</strong> their differentiation<br />

and discrimination; it explained the dependence<br />

<strong>of</strong> emotions on desires and beliefs and their modifiability<br />

by a change <strong>of</strong> these mental states; and it explained the<br />

links <strong>of</strong> emotion to motivation. In addition, <strong>Stumpf</strong><br />

(1899) took it to be a strength <strong>of</strong> his theory that—in<br />

contrast to the theories <strong>of</strong> Wundt and James—it was in<br />

fundamental agreement with both common sense and<br />

with what he and Brentano (1874/1971) regarded as the<br />

dominant traditional line <strong>of</strong> emotion theorizing: the cognitive<br />

tradition exemplified by Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas,<br />

Descartes, and Spinoza. Although the "surprisal<br />

value" <strong>of</strong> the theory is therefore moderate, <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899)<br />

held that "absolute originality ... in matters which were<br />

open to introspection at all times would be a recommendation<br />

<strong>of</strong> the inventiveness <strong>of</strong> the author, but not <strong>of</strong> his<br />

case" (p. 67).<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> main concern, however, was with refuting<br />

the major competing emotion theories <strong>of</strong> his time. Similar<br />

to those <strong>of</strong> today, these theories were variants <strong>of</strong> a special<br />

class <strong>of</strong> noncognitive theories <strong>of</strong> emotion that can collectively<br />

be called emotional feeling theories (Alston, 1972).<br />

The basic tenet <strong>of</strong> these theories is that emotions are certain<br />

kinds <strong>of</strong> conscious qualities that are, in many respects,<br />

similar to sensory qualities such as sensations <strong>of</strong><br />

color, odor, and taste. How close this similarity to sensations<br />

is perceived to be depends on the specific version<br />

<strong>of</strong> feeling theory. According to the first, sensualistic<br />

(Titchener, 1908) variant, the emotional qualities at stake<br />

are in fact nothing but a special class <strong>of</strong> sensations or<br />

perceptions (or patterns, complexes, etc., <strong>of</strong> these),<br />

namely, sensations or perceptions that originate from peripheral<br />

bodily events (e.g., James, 1884, 1890/1950).<br />

According to the second version <strong>of</strong> feeling theory, which<br />

may be termed centralist or mentalist and which found<br />

its most prominent proponent in <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> contemporary,<br />

Wundt (1896), the emotional qualities are not reducible<br />

to peripherally caused sensations. Their physiological<br />

source was later located, for example, in the thalamus<br />

(Cannon, 1927) or the limbic system (Papez, 1937).<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> s Objections to Sensualistic Feeling Theories<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> (1899) main objections to sensualistic feeling<br />

theories <strong>of</strong> emotion were as follows: (a) There is no correspondence<br />

between the multitude <strong>of</strong> emotions, on the<br />

one hand, and patterns <strong>of</strong> peripheral bodily changes, on<br />

the other hand, with regard to quality, intensity, and temporal<br />

course (cf. Cannon, 1927; see also Averill, 1982,<br />

concerning temporal course); (b) even if differentiated<br />

patterns <strong>of</strong> bodily changes corresponding to the different<br />

emotions existed, they are probably not represented in<br />

consciousness (cf. Zillmann, 1978); (c) it is unclear what<br />

adaptational value would accrue from a brain that is "like<br />

a tube through which every [emotional] stimulus drop<br />

immediately drains to the periphery" (p. 82). On the<br />

contrary, we must count ourselves "lucky that we do not<br />

react so sensitively" (p. 83); and (d) "a definition must<br />

be convertible" (p. 84); thus, if emotions are identified<br />

January 1992 • American Psychologist


with organic sensations without any qualification, then<br />

all organic sensations are, conversely, emotions, and one<br />

would have to "subsume under the concept <strong>of</strong> emotion<br />

. . . heart-burn, feelings <strong>of</strong> hunger and <strong>of</strong> satiation, <strong>of</strong><br />

heat and chill" (p. 84; see also, Pitcher 1965). Unless the<br />

sensualistic theorists are prepared to accept this consequence<br />

(and few are), they can identify emotions with<br />

only a subclass <strong>of</strong> (complexes <strong>of</strong>) organic sensations. But<br />

this suggestion founders on the fact that the clear phenomenal<br />

difference between the mental states ordinarily<br />

regarded as emotions (e.g., anger) and nonemotional organic<br />

sensations (e.g., heartbeat) is not paralleled by a<br />

similarly compelling difference in felt quality between two<br />

classes <strong>of</strong> organic sensations (emotional and nonemotional<br />

ones). For the sensualistic feeling theory <strong>of</strong> emotions<br />

requires that such a difference exists.<br />

It seems to us that none <strong>of</strong> the proponents <strong>of</strong> contemporary<br />

variants <strong>of</strong> sensualistic emotion theories (e.g.,<br />

Izard, 1977; Leventhal, 1984; Tomkins, 1962, 1980) has<br />

provided a fully convincing answer to these objections.<br />

Consider, for example, how contemporary sensualistic<br />

theories (that focus mostly on facial feedback) try to distinguish<br />

emotional from nonemotional bodily sensations.<br />

Typically, relational criteria are being used. It is suggested,<br />

for instance, that only facial feedback (or its activated<br />

mental representation) that is self-produced, spontaneous,<br />

or congruent with feed-forward feedback (e.g., Laird,<br />

1974; Leventhal, 1984) leads to an emotional feeling. It<br />

remains quite unclear, however, what makes a spontaneous<br />

or self-produced organic sensation emotional, and<br />

clearly there are facial expressions that meet these criteria<br />

but are not emotional at all.<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>s Critique <strong>of</strong> Mentalistic Feeling Theories<br />

and His <strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> Affective Sensations<br />

The problem <strong>of</strong> sense-feelings. The affective phenomena<br />

that <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899) primarily had in mind when he developed<br />

his theory <strong>of</strong> emotion, which that theory was first<br />

and foremost intended to explain, were paradigmatic<br />

emotions, that is, they were the referents <strong>of</strong> ordinary language<br />

emotion terms—such as joy, sorrow, anger, hope,<br />

and fear—"concerning which there can be no dispute<br />

that they belong to the concept <strong>of</strong> emotion" (p. 50). He<br />

also thought that the theory was applicable, with some<br />

reservations, to mood states. There remained, however,<br />

at least one class <strong>of</strong> prima facie affective phenomena that<br />

could not be well accounted for by the theory, the socalled<br />

Sinnesgefuhle (sense-feelings; Titchener, 1908). The<br />

term was used by <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1907a) as a "theory-neutral"<br />

expression to denote the various sensory pleasures and<br />

displeasures, including purely bodily pains and the pleasurable<br />

sensations <strong>of</strong> bodily well-being in its more general<br />

and more special forms (the latter include the pleasure<br />

component in tickling, the feeling associated with itching,<br />

and sexual pleasure feelings), as well as the pleasure and<br />

displeasure that may be connected with elementary sensations<br />

<strong>of</strong> the "special senses," such as temperature, odors,<br />

tastes, tones, and colors (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1907a) as well as with<br />

organic sensations (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1899).<br />

The problem <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> sensory pleasures and<br />

displeasures and their relation to paradigmatic emotions<br />

acquired its particular significance from the fact that it<br />

was precisely these affective phenomena with which<br />

Wundt and his followers were primarily concerned; on<br />

the analysis <strong>of</strong> these affective phenomena they founded<br />

their alternative view <strong>of</strong> emotions (see also Lehmann,<br />

1914; Titchener, 1908). Despite the fact that comparatively<br />

little systematic effort was devoted by these researchers<br />

to the study <strong>of</strong> paradigmatic emotions such as<br />

anger, fear, and joy, Wundt (1896) held that not only are<br />

feelings <strong>of</strong> pleasure and displeasure—together with the<br />

feelings <strong>of</strong> arousal, depression, tension, and relaxation—<br />

the simplest affective elements <strong>of</strong> consciousness, but that<br />

paradigmatic emotions are complex combinations or fusions<br />

<strong>of</strong> these elementary feelings (Wundt, 1896; see also<br />

Titchener, 1908).<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> original view <strong>of</strong> sense-feelings. In 1899,<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> had not only distinguished organic sensations<br />

from emotions, but had resisted the "general scientific<br />

desire for utmost reduction" (p. 58) and had also kept<br />

emotions distinct from sensory pleasures and displeasures.<br />

Although at that time he still classified these latter<br />

feelings among the class <strong>of</strong> intentional evaluative states—<br />

following Brentano (1874/1971)—<strong>Stumpf</strong> believed that<br />

sensory feelings <strong>of</strong> pleasure and displeasure are, in contrast<br />

to paradigmatic emotions, directly caused by sensations,<br />

that is, without mediating cognitions (beliefs).<br />

Therefore, he held that they do not count as proper emotions<br />

(for more on this issue, see the next section).<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> revised view <strong>of</strong> sense-feelings: The theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> affective sensations. Yet, according to the position<br />

held by <strong>Stumpf</strong> in 1899, sense-feelings still belonged to<br />

the class <strong>of</strong> intentional evaluative phenomena (i.e., the<br />

passive affective states) and, hence, were similar to proand<br />

con-evaluations, desires, and wishes. They were not<br />

"true" emotions only because, other than the latter kinds<br />

<strong>of</strong> mental states, they were not caused by beliefs. This<br />

view must have appeared increasingly problematic to<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> during the following years, and in 1907a, he proposed<br />

a more radical difference between emotions and<br />

sense-feelings (see also Titchener, 1908, for an English<br />

review). Now he posited that sense-feelings are not evaluative<br />

states at all, but rather sensations <strong>of</strong> a special kind,<br />

like sensations <strong>of</strong> color, odor, and tones (although, in contrast<br />

to the latter, they may well be centrally generated;<br />

see also <strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1916). To support his view, <strong>Stumpf</strong><br />

(1907a) carefully compared the various sense-feelings on<br />

several phenomenological dimensions and concluded that<br />

there are, at best, gradual differences between sensory<br />

pleasures and displeasures and ordinary sensations on<br />

these dimensions, whereas there are fundamental differences<br />

between sense-feelings and emotions, even though<br />

feelings <strong>of</strong> pleasure and displeasure may occasionally<br />

cause, be caused by, or accompany emotions, and although<br />

they may be related to emotions both phylogenetically<br />

and ontogenetically (for more detail, see Titchener,<br />

1908). Therefore, <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1907a) concluded, the<br />

view that sense-feelings are but a special class <strong>of</strong> sensations<br />

January 1992 • American Psychologist 39


is the most tenable or, at any rate, the most parsimonious<br />

one to take.<br />

Although <strong>Stumpf</strong>' s thesis was accepted by some <strong>of</strong><br />

his contemporaries, it was rejected by others (cf. <strong>Stumpf</strong>,<br />

1916), including his teacher Brentano (1907/1979).<br />

(Brentano proposed that sensory pleasures and displeasures<br />

should be regarded as intentional evaluations that,<br />

however, have as their objects mental states, namely, the<br />

experiencing <strong>of</strong> certain sensations [see also Chisholm,<br />

1979, and for a related contemporary view, Hall, 1989].)<br />

When considered from the perspective <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> cognitive-evaluative<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> emotion, however, <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong><br />

position is not an unreasonable one to take. For whatever<br />

else <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> (1907a) analyses do or do not show, they<br />

certainly do support his conclusion that, phenomenologically,<br />

sense-feelings resemble ordinary sensations much<br />

more than they resemble intentional evaluations and<br />

wishes—the kinds <strong>of</strong> mental states with which emotions<br />

were associated (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1899). And, <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1907a)<br />

argued, the idea that emotions (i.e., belief-caused evaluations)<br />

are somehow built up from primitive, sensationlike<br />

feelings is just as implausible as the theory that complex<br />

perceptions, judgments, and thoughts are somehow built<br />

up from elementary sensations. "Time will come,"<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> (1907a) wrote, "when the difference in principle<br />

between emotions and sensations, including affective<br />

sensations, will be regarded as being just as evident as is,<br />

already today, the difference between sensations and<br />

thoughts" (pp. 7-8).<br />

Sensory pleasures and displeasures as nonrepresentational<br />

mental states. The quotation at the end <strong>of</strong> the<br />

last paragraph points to a different and perhaps more<br />

compelling argument to defend <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> thesis that<br />

emotions are fundamentally different from sensations,<br />

including sensory pleasures and displeasures. This argument<br />

had already been presented by Husserl (1901/<br />

1975), a student <strong>of</strong> both Brentano and <strong>Stumpf</strong>, several<br />

years before <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> (1907a) article and has been reiterated<br />

by several more recent philosophers <strong>of</strong> mind (e.g.,<br />

Kenny, 1963; Pitcher, 1965; Solomon, 1976). As has been<br />

mentioned, in contrast to <strong>Stumpf</strong> and Brentano, contemporary<br />

philosophers <strong>of</strong> mind widely agree with Husserl<br />

that sensations <strong>of</strong> tastes, tones, and so forth, including<br />

pain, are not at all intentionally directed at an object (see,<br />

e.g., Rorty, 1979; Searle, 1983). For it does not seem possible<br />

for these states to be intentionally directed at objects<br />

beyond themselves, as are beliefs and evaluations, and<br />

according to <strong>Stumpf</strong>, emotions. To illustrate, if one experiences<br />

bodily pain, one does not feel pain <strong>of</strong> or about<br />

something in the same sense as when one is afraid <strong>of</strong> or<br />

angry about something (see also Searle, 1983). (One must<br />

not confuse the phenomenal localization <strong>of</strong> pain—e.g.,<br />

"my foot hurts"—with intentionality.) If this holds true<br />

<strong>of</strong> feelings <strong>of</strong> sensory pleasure and displeasure in general,<br />

as Husserl (1901/1975) proposed, then the difference between<br />

these feelings and paradigmatic emotions is just as<br />

fundamental as that between nonrepresentational and<br />

representational states <strong>of</strong> mind.<br />

Inasmuch as these considerations reinforce <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong><br />

40<br />

(1907a) conclusion that sense-feelings cannot be assimilated<br />

to evaluations, his suggestion to classify them as a<br />

special class <strong>of</strong> sensations seems certainly worth considering.<br />

It has in fact been revived by contemporary emotion<br />

theorists (e.g., Lazarus & Smith, 1988). Taking into<br />

account the distinction between representational and<br />

nonrepresentational mental states (Husserl, 1901/1975),<br />

we would then arrive at a modified, fourfold classification<br />

<strong>of</strong> mental states into cognitive versus affective intentional<br />

states (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1928) and nonintentional, nonaffective<br />

and affective raw feels (<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1907a).<br />

Significance <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stumpf</strong> s Views on <strong>Emotion</strong>s<br />

for the Contemporary Cognition-<br />

<strong>Emotion</strong> Discussion<br />

Today, more than 90 years after <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> (1899) article<br />

was published, cognitive theories <strong>of</strong> emotion have become<br />

a central paradigm <strong>of</strong> emotion research, and in their wake<br />

the issue <strong>of</strong> the relation between cognitions and emotions<br />

has become a central topic <strong>of</strong> research and theoretical<br />

discussion. Yet, <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> contributions to the psychology<br />

<strong>of</strong> emotion have not been outdated by these recent developments.<br />

Rather than merely anticipating the major<br />

tenets <strong>of</strong> contemporary cognitive emotion theories,<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> goes beyond these theories in several respects.<br />

Not only is his cognitive-evaluative theory <strong>of</strong> emotions<br />

more lucidly formulated than many a contemporary theory<br />

(with regard, in particular, to the central issues <strong>of</strong> the<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> cognitive appraisals and <strong>of</strong> emotions and the<br />

relation between these mental states), it constitutes a<br />

thoroughly interesting alternative to existing cognitive<br />

theories. At any rate, however, <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> views on emotion<br />

raise a number <strong>of</strong> issues that, although <strong>of</strong> central significance<br />

to the cognition-emotion problem, have only been<br />

given marginal attention in the recent discussions. To<br />

document this claim, we will examine three such issues<br />

in more detail: the intentionality <strong>of</strong> emotions, the nature<br />

<strong>of</strong> evaluations in cognitive appraisals, and the nature <strong>of</strong><br />

the relation between cognitions and emotions, with special<br />

consideration <strong>of</strong> the precise sense in which cognitions<br />

may be necessary for emotions.<br />

The Intentionality <strong>of</strong> <strong>Emotion</strong>s<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong> assumed—in line with his teacher Brentano, with<br />

Husserl, and with a number <strong>of</strong> contemporary philosophers<br />

(e.g., Green, 1986; Searle, 1983; Solomon, 1976)—that<br />

emotions are intrinsically intentional or representational<br />

mental states just as are beliefs and desires. If this assumption<br />

is correct, it would have far-reaching consequences<br />

for the question <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> emotional states.<br />

Not only would it be—as discussed earlier in this article—<br />

a very serious, if not fatal, objection against all those noncognitive<br />

theories <strong>of</strong> emotion that identify emotions with<br />

bodily sensations (e.g., James, 1890/1950), facial feedback<br />

(e.g., Tomkins, 1962; Izard, 1977), centrally generated<br />

"feelings" (e.g., Buck, 1985; Zajonc, 1980; Zajonc et al.,<br />

1989; see also Leventhal, 1984), or other nonrepresentational<br />

raw feels, it would also pose a serious challenge<br />

January 1992 • American Psychologist


to several popular cognitive theories <strong>of</strong> emotion. These<br />

include all those that, although taking cognitive appraisals<br />

to be causally or even definitionally necessary for emotions<br />

(see below), regard the emotions themselves as either<br />

nonrepresentational mental states (e.g., as feelings <strong>of</strong><br />

arousal [e.g., Lyons, 1980; see also Schachter, 1964] or<br />

mental qualities [e.g., Oatley & Johnson-Laird, 1987;<br />

Pekrun, 1988]), or as action tendencies (e.g., Arnold,<br />

1970; Frijda, 1986). As concerns the latter theories, although<br />

action tendencies certainly do qualify as intentional<br />

mental states, they do not have the "right" objects,<br />

that is, their objects are different from those <strong>of</strong> the emotions<br />

with which they are identified in these theories. For<br />

example, the intentional objects <strong>of</strong> the desire to flee in<br />

the case <strong>of</strong> fear or to attack in the case <strong>of</strong> anger (namely,<br />

the actions <strong>of</strong> fleeing or attacking, respectively) are different<br />

from what are most naturally construed as the intentional<br />

objects <strong>of</strong> the corresponding emotions (e.g., that<br />

one may be harmed in the case <strong>of</strong> fear or that one has<br />

been <strong>of</strong>fended in the case <strong>of</strong> anger). Therefore, although<br />

fear and anger may give rise to such action tendencies, it<br />

is hard to see how the action tendencies could be identified<br />

with the emotions.<br />

Given the significance <strong>of</strong> the issue <strong>of</strong> the intentionality<br />

<strong>of</strong> emotions, it is surprising that it has received only<br />

the most cursory attention by contemporary emotion<br />

psychologists and has played practically no role in the<br />

recent cognition-emotion debate. The reason may be that<br />

most contemporary psychologists, even cognitively oriented<br />

ones, assume at least implicitly that intentionality<br />

is not an intrinsic but only a derived feature <strong>of</strong> emotions,<br />

that is, a feature that accrues to many or most emotion<br />

instances only because they are associated with cognitive<br />

appraisals (e.g., Frijda, 1986; Johnson-Laird & Oatley,<br />

1989). Principled expositions and defenses <strong>of</strong> this nonrepresentational<br />

view <strong>of</strong> emotions are hard to come by,<br />

however, and the standard argument advanced in its support—that<br />

emotions cannot be intrinsically intentional<br />

because there are cases <strong>of</strong> objectless emotions, such as<br />

objectless anxiety and some mood states (e.g., Johnson-<br />

Laird & Oatley, 1989; Storring, 1922)—is by no means<br />

convincing. So-called objectless fears may not completely<br />

lack objects; rather, their objects may only be ill defined,<br />

vague, or difficult to verbalize (e.g., a "feeling <strong>of</strong> dread<br />

that something awful is going to happen" [italics added;<br />

Oatley, 1988, p. 357]). As to moods, it can be plausibly<br />

argued that they constitute cases in which the person appraises,<br />

simultaneously or in rapid sequence, many different<br />

states <strong>of</strong> affairs, making it difficult or impossible<br />

to single out any particular one as the object <strong>of</strong> the mood<br />

state (e.g., Isen, 1984; see also Ortony & Clore, 1989, for<br />

further considerations). Finally, even if some emotion<br />

types truly had objectless instances, it would hardly prove<br />

that all or even the majority <strong>of</strong> emotion types are intrinsically<br />

nonintentional. In short, the issue <strong>of</strong> the intentionality<br />

<strong>of</strong> emotions raised by <strong>Stumpf</strong> is far from settled,<br />

and given its significance to the cognition-emotion problem,<br />

certainly deserves more attention than it has received.<br />

The Nature <strong>of</strong> Evaluations in <strong>Cognitive</strong> Appraisals<br />

Although contemporary cognitive emotion theorists<br />

would agree with <strong>Stumpf</strong> that cognitive appraisals, whatever<br />

they are more precisely, are intentional mental states<br />

that comprise both nonevaluative or "descriptive" components<br />

(e.g., the belief that an event is more or less likely,<br />

that it is caused by certain factors, that it is controllable),<br />

and evaluative components (e.g., the evaluation <strong>of</strong> an<br />

event as good or bad), one must agree with Lazarus and<br />

Smith (1988) that beyond these assumptions there is today<br />

a good deal <strong>of</strong> "confusion about what is meant by appraisal"<br />

(p. 282). One particularly important aspect <strong>of</strong><br />

this confusion or disagreement that becomes salient when<br />

contemporary cognitive formulations are compared with<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> theory concerns the nature <strong>of</strong> the evaluative<br />

appraisal components. Are all <strong>of</strong> these components just<br />

special types <strong>of</strong> belief (i.e., beliefs having evaluative contents),<br />

or is there at least one evaluative appraisal component<br />

essential to an emotion that is a mental state entirely<br />

different from belief, as <strong>Stumpf</strong> assumed? Explicit<br />

proponents <strong>of</strong> both views exist: See, for example, Arnold<br />

(1960a, 1960b, 1970), Green (1986), Marks (1982), or<br />

Searle (1983) for the second position and Solomon (1976,<br />

1988) for the first one. (It should be recalled, however,<br />

that for Green, Marks, and Searle—in contrast to<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>—this evaluative component <strong>of</strong> emotions is a<br />

nonperformative desire.) But more frequently—particularly<br />

in the psychological literature—the issue remains<br />

unclear. Possibly, many psychologists have simply not<br />

recognized that a significant question might be at stake<br />

here.<br />

In truth, however, this issue is <strong>of</strong> central importance<br />

to the cognition-emotion problem. First, the lack <strong>of</strong> clarity<br />

about the nature <strong>of</strong> cognitive appraisals in emotion<br />

has undoubtedly fostered the recent criticisms <strong>of</strong> cognitive<br />

theories (e.g., Zajonc, 1980, 1984), for this criticism is<br />

implicitly based on the assumption that cognitive appraisals<br />

are exclusively beliefs. In fact, Zajonc (1984) apparently<br />

even assumes that cognitive appraisals comprise<br />

only nonevaluative beliefs and, as a consequence, sees his<br />

original (Zajonc, 1980) contention that evaluations do<br />

not presuppose certain kinds <strong>of</strong> belief (specifically, recognitions<br />

<strong>of</strong> objects as old vs. new) as synonymous with<br />

the claim that emotions do not presuppose appraisals<br />

(Zajonc, 1984). This is clearly a misinterpretation <strong>of</strong> cognitive<br />

emotion theories! In fact, it is precisely the affective<br />

judgments that Zajonc (1980) takes to be in part independent<br />

<strong>of</strong> cognitions—for example, "safe-dangerous,<br />

good-bad, or nice-nasty" (p. 171)—that are mentioned<br />

by cognitive emotion theorists as typical examples <strong>of</strong> (the<br />

evaluative components <strong>of</strong>) cognitive appraisals (e.g., Arnold,<br />

1960a, 1960b; Lazarus et al., 1980; Schachter,<br />

1964). Second, the failure to consider seriously the necessity<br />

<strong>of</strong> distinguishing clearly between evaluations (in<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> sense) and (evaluative) beliefs may also have<br />

been a major reason why many cognitively oriented emotion<br />

theorists found it necessary to postulate a nonappraisal<br />

component, such as perceived physiological<br />

January 1992 • American Psychologist 41


arousal (e.g., Mandler, 1984; Schachter, 1964), a felt action<br />

tendency (e.g., Arnold, 1970; Frijda, 1986), or centrally<br />

generated feelings <strong>of</strong> a Wundtian (1896) or Cannonian<br />

(1927) variety (e.g., Oatley & Johnson-Laird, 1987; Pekrun,<br />

1988) as at least an additional, indispensable component<br />

<strong>of</strong> emotion, resulting in "hybrid" theories <strong>of</strong><br />

questionable validity.<br />

The reasoning <strong>of</strong> these emotion theorists has apparently<br />

been that there must be something else to emotion<br />

other than just cognitive appraisals, something that<br />

imbues "cold cognition" with "emotional warmth." This<br />

reasoning is in fact plausible if cognitive appraisals are<br />

restricted to beliefs (including evaluative beliefs) because,<br />

as <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899, 1907b) observed, it seems indeed counterintuitive<br />

to think that emotions are just special types<br />

<strong>of</strong> beliefs (see also Frijda, 1986;Leighton, 1985). However,<br />

if it is assumed with <strong>Stumpf</strong> that, although evaluative<br />

beliefs may be important to emotions, the central evaluative<br />

component <strong>of</strong> emotions is a mental state that is<br />

fundamentally different from beliefs, then the need to<br />

postulate an additional, nonappraisal component <strong>of</strong><br />

emotions evaporates, for then the evaluative component<br />

can provide the necessary emotional warmth. As noted<br />

earlier in this article, according to <strong>Stumpf</strong> it is in fact<br />

quite unclear how, for example, perceptions <strong>of</strong> physiological<br />

arousal could be capable <strong>of</strong> imbuing cognitions<br />

with emotional warmth. On the contrary, <strong>Stumpf</strong> thought<br />

that we must resort to evaluations to explain how emotional<br />

and nonemotional arousal differ.<br />

The Relation Between <strong>Cognitive</strong> Appraisals<br />

and <strong>Emotion</strong>s<br />

The central issue in the recent cognition-emotion debate<br />

has been phrased as the question <strong>of</strong> whether or not cognitions<br />

(cognitive appraisals) are necessary for emotions.<br />

Viewed from the perspective <strong>of</strong> <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> theory, it becomes<br />

immediately apparent that this question is doubly<br />

ambiguous, first, because <strong>of</strong> the lack <strong>of</strong> consensus concerning<br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> cognitive appraisals, and second,<br />

because the type <strong>of</strong> necessity under discussion could either<br />

be that <strong>of</strong> (purely) causal (or nomological) necessity, or<br />

that <strong>of</strong> definitional necessity.<br />

The recent cognition-emotion discussion has focused<br />

on the question <strong>of</strong> whether cognitions are causally<br />

necessary for emotions. That is, the central question has<br />

been whether the only causal pathway to the elicitation<br />

<strong>of</strong> emotions in the intact organism is through cognitive<br />

appraisals, or whether there are additional natural noncognitive<br />

pathways <strong>of</strong> emotion elicitation (Lazarus, 1982;<br />

Zajonc, 1980; Zajonc et al., 1989). <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899), however,<br />

did not just claim that emotions are typically caused<br />

by cognitions (beliefs) or even that they are always caused<br />

by cognitions in the intact organism, but that cognitions<br />

belong to the defining features <strong>of</strong> emotions (i.e., emotions<br />

are functionally defined with regard to their cognitive<br />

causes). As a consequence, he held that, even if evaluations<br />

could be noncognitively caused, such evaluations would<br />

not count as proper emotions. As was mentioned earlier,<br />

a similar functional-definition view <strong>of</strong> emotions is held<br />

42<br />

by several contemporary cognitive emotion theorists (e.g.,<br />

Arnold, 1970; Davidson, 1976; Gordon, 1974; Lyons,<br />

1980; Searle, 1983; Wilson, 1972). Other contemporary<br />

cognitivists contend even that appraisals are component<br />

parts <strong>of</strong> (e.g., Lazarus et al., 1980; Oatley & Johnson-<br />

Laird, 1987; Schachter, 1964) or are identical with (e.g.,<br />

Solomon, 1976) emotions. If these latter views are correct,<br />

cognitions are not just definitionally necessary for emotions;<br />

one cannot even meaningfully say that cognitions<br />

cause emotions at all.<br />

It is clear that if a convincing case for the definitional<br />

necessity <strong>of</strong> cognitions for emotions could be made, then<br />

a very strong case would exist for the indispensability <strong>of</strong><br />

cognitions for emotions. Probably the most important<br />

consideration regarding this issue concerns the question<br />

<strong>of</strong> how the many (prima facie) emotional states <strong>of</strong> humans<br />

are distinguished from one another. For if different emotion<br />

types cannot be reliably distinguished from one another<br />

other than by reference to appraisals—if, for example,<br />

envy simply cannot be discriminated reliably from<br />

other emotions unless one takes into account the belief<br />

that a desired good that one lacks belongs to another person<br />

(<strong>Stumpf</strong>, 1899)—then cognitions are necessary for<br />

the definition <strong>of</strong> different emotion types. In evaluating<br />

this issue, it should be recalled that the attempt to provide<br />

a plausible solution to the discrimination <strong>of</strong> emotion<br />

problem was one <strong>of</strong> the major reasons for the turn toward<br />

cognitive theories in the 1960s (e.g., Arnold, 1960a,<br />

1960b; Hunt, Cole, & Reis, 1958; Schachter, 1964). To<br />

these theorists, cognitive appraisals seemed to be the only<br />

features <strong>of</strong> emotion that are differentiated enough to account<br />

for the multitude <strong>of</strong> emotional states. Today, firm<br />

evidence for the existence <strong>of</strong> a multitude <strong>of</strong> nonappraisal<br />

mental states that correspond in a one-to-one fashion with<br />

the multitude <strong>of</strong> emotions is scarcely more abundant than<br />

it was 25 years ago (see also, Zajonc et al., 1989), whereas<br />

there is now good evidence for the appraisal discrimination<br />

<strong>of</strong> emotions (e.g., Frijda, 1987; Frijda et al., 1989;<br />

Reisenzein & H<strong>of</strong>mann, 1990; Smith & Ellsworth, 1985,<br />

1987; Weiner, 1986).<br />

Finally, it must be reemphasized that the assumption<br />

that cognitions are definitionally necessary for emotions<br />

does not necessarily imply the denial <strong>of</strong> the existence <strong>of</strong><br />

affective phenomena—in a wide sense <strong>of</strong> this term—for<br />

which cognitions are not necessary even in the purely<br />

causal sense. As we have seen in the previous section, in<br />

contrast to Lazarus (1982; but see Lazarus & Smith, 1988,<br />

for a different opinion), <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899) did not feel obliged<br />

by his advocacy <strong>of</strong> a cognitive theory <strong>of</strong> emotions to<br />

maintain that all affective states necessarily presuppose<br />

cognitions. He would have readily agreed with Zajonc<br />

(1980) that there are at least some simple affective reactions<br />

(e.g., sensory pleasure and displeasure feelings) that<br />

are directly caused by sensations, that is, are unmediated<br />

by cognitive appraisals (or, more precisely, beliefs). However,<br />

in contrast to Zajonc (1984), who argued that paradigmatic<br />

emotions therefore most likely do not presuppose<br />

cognitive appraisals as well (but see Zajonc et al.,<br />

1989, for a more moderate opinion), <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1899) con-<br />

January 1992 • American Psychologist


eluded that such cognitively unmediated pleasure-displeasure<br />

feelings are not emotions proper. This move is<br />

emphatically not an immunization strategy that seeks to<br />

settle the cognition-emotion issue by definitional fiat<br />

(Zajonc, 1984). Rather, it is an application <strong>of</strong> the scientific<br />

strategy to let a theory (in this case, a theory <strong>of</strong> the structure<br />

<strong>of</strong> emotions) that seems to work well with paradigmatic<br />

cases, autodetermine its own range <strong>of</strong> application<br />

in problematic cases (Stegmiiller, 1986). This strategy is<br />

both legitimate and reasonable. For what kind <strong>of</strong> mental<br />

state an emotion is, is ultimately determined by a theory<br />

that successfully accounts for paradigmatic emotional<br />

states. If it turns out that other prima facie affective phenomena<br />

do not conform to this theory, then this is the<br />

best possible reason one can have for believing that these<br />

latter phenomena and the paradigm cases constitute different<br />

natural kinds.<br />

Conclusion<br />

Rather than being <strong>of</strong> recent origin, the cognition-emotion<br />

problem has been with psychology since its very beginnings<br />

as an institutionalized science, and the central issues<br />

seem to have remained much the same. Had <strong>Stumpf</strong> had<br />

the opportunity to comment on the recent debate, he<br />

would have agreed with the criticisms <strong>of</strong> contemporary<br />

cognitive emotion theories to the extent that these theories<br />

constitute attempts to either reduce emotions to beliefs<br />

(e.g., Solomon, 1976) or to subsume all affective phenomena<br />

under emotions (e.g., Lazarus, 1982). But he<br />

would certainly have opposed the return to noncognitive,<br />

"feeling" theories <strong>of</strong> emotion (e.g., Buck, 1985; Izard,<br />

1984; Zajonc, 1984; Zajonc et al., 1989), as well as to<br />

"hybrid" cognition-feeling theories such as those proposed<br />

by Lyons (1980), Mandler (1984), Oatley and<br />

Johnson-Laird (1987), or Schachter (1964). To some degree,<br />

this return to feeling theories may simply have happened<br />

because more plausible noncognitive theories <strong>of</strong><br />

emotions were not in sight. But it may also have been<br />

fostered by the fact that there seems to be, at least since<br />

James and Wundt, but probably since the introduction<br />

<strong>of</strong> the threefold division <strong>of</strong> mental states into cognitive,<br />

affective, and motivational ones around 1750 (see, e.g.,<br />

Brentano, 1874/1971; Hilgard, 1980; Scheerer, 1992), a<br />

deeply entrenched a priori belief among many psychologists<br />

that emotions are intrinsically nonrepresentational<br />

states similar to sensations. These psychologists may wish<br />

to seriously reconsider <strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> suggestions that (a) the<br />

mind does not just consist <strong>of</strong> intellectual representations<br />

(beliefs) and action tendencies, on the one hand, and raw<br />

feels, on the other hand, but that there are further types<br />

<strong>of</strong> intentional states such as desires and wishes <strong>of</strong> various<br />

kinds, as well as approvals and disapprovals (see also Baier,<br />

1986; Kuhl, 1983), and (b) that not all affective phenomena<br />

may turn out to be emotions on closer examination.<br />

Although read and quoted by his contemporaries,<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong><strong>'s</strong> writings on emotion did not exert much influence<br />

on the psychological literature later in this century.<br />

A probable major reason was that neither <strong>Stumpf</strong> nor his<br />

students actively propagated his ideas and developed them<br />

further. As for <strong>Stumpf</strong> himself, emotion was not his central<br />

area <strong>of</strong> interest and he did not regard his pertinent<br />

work as particularly novel or surprising. Also, he took on<br />

administrative duties (e.g., he became rector <strong>of</strong> his university)<br />

that demanded much <strong>of</strong> his time. As for his students,<br />

they were engaged in articulating and propagating<br />

their own school <strong>of</strong> Gestalt psychology, which gave little<br />

attention to emotion. We hope that this article will help<br />

to give <strong>Stumpf</strong> the place in the history <strong>of</strong> emotion research<br />

that, in our view, he deserves.<br />

REFERENCES<br />

Alston, W. P. (1972). <strong>Emotion</strong> and feeling. In P. Edwards (Ed.), Encyclopedia<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophy (pp. 479-493). New \brk: Macmillan.<br />

Aristotle. (1980). Rhetorik [Rhetoric]. Munchen, Germany: Fink.<br />

Arnold, M. B. (1960a). <strong>Emotion</strong> and personality (Vol. 1). New \brk:<br />

Columbia University Press.<br />

Arnold, M. B. (1960b). <strong>Emotion</strong> and personality (Vol. 2). New York:<br />

Columbia University Press.<br />

Arnold, M. B. (1970). Perennial problems in the field <strong>of</strong> emotion. In<br />

M. B. Arnold (Ed.), Feelings and emotions(pp. 169-185). San Diego:<br />

Academic Press.<br />

Averill, J. R. (1982). Anger and aggression: An essay on emotion. New<br />

York: Springer.<br />

Averill, J. R. (1983). Studies on anger and aggression: Implications for<br />

theories <strong>of</strong> emotion. American Psychologist, 38, 1145-1160.<br />

Baier, A. C. (1986). The ambiguous limits <strong>of</strong> desire. In J. Marks (Ed.),<br />

The ways <strong>of</strong> desire (pp. 39-61). Chicago: Precedent.<br />

Bieri, P. (1986). Intentionale Systeme: Uberlegungen zu Daniel Dennetts<br />

Theorie des Geistes [Intentional systems: Reflections on Dennett<strong>'s</strong><br />

theory <strong>of</strong> mind]. In J. Brandtstadter (Ed.), Struklur und Erfahrung<br />

in der psychologischen Forschung (pp. 208-252). Berlin: de Gruyter.<br />

Birnbaum, M. H. (1981). Thinking and feeling: A skeptical review.<br />

American Psychologist, 36, 99-101.<br />

Block, N. (1980). Introduction: What is functionalism? In N. Block<br />

(Ed.), Readings in philosophy <strong>of</strong> psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 171-184).<br />

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.<br />

Brentano, F. (1955). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt [Psychology<br />

from the empirical point <strong>of</strong> view] (O. Kraus, Ed., Vol. 1).<br />

Hamburg, Germany: Meiner. (Original work published 1874)<br />

Brentano, F. (1971). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt [Psychology<br />

from the empirical point <strong>of</strong> view]. (O. Kraus, Ed., Vol. 2).<br />

Hamburg, Germany: Meiner. (Original work published 1874)<br />

Brentano, F. (1979). Untersuchungen zur Sinnespsychologie [Investigations<br />

in sensory psychology]. Hamburg, Germany: Meiner. (Original<br />

work published 1907)<br />

Buck, R. (1985). Prime theory: An integrated view <strong>of</strong> motivation and<br />

emotion. Psychological Review, 92, 389-413.<br />

Cannon, W. B. (1927). The James-Lange theory <strong>of</strong> emotions: A critical<br />

examination and an alternative theory. American Journal <strong>of</strong> Psychology,<br />

39, 106-124.<br />

Chisholm, R. M. (1967). Intentionality. In P. Edwards (Ed.), Encyclopedia<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophy (Vol. 4, pp. 201-204). New York: Macmillan.<br />

Chisholm, R. M. (1979). Einleitung [Introduction]. In F. Brentano (Ed.),<br />

Untersuchungen zur Sinnespsychologie (1907/1979) (pp. VII-XXVI).<br />

Hamburg, Germany: Meiner.<br />

Davidson, D. (1976). Hume<strong>'s</strong> cognitive theory <strong>of</strong> pride. Journal <strong>of</strong> Philosophy,<br />

83, 744-757.<br />

Descartes, R. (1984). Les passions de Vame [The passions <strong>of</strong> the soul].<br />

Hamburg, Germany: Meiner. (Original work published 1649)<br />

Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language <strong>of</strong> thought. New York: Crowell.<br />

Fodor, J. A. (1981). Prepositional attitudes. In N. Block (Ed.), Readings<br />

in philosophy <strong>of</strong> psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 45-63). London: Methuen.<br />

Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem <strong>of</strong> meaning in the<br />

philosophy <strong>of</strong> mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.<br />

Frijda, N. H. (1986). The emotions. Cambridge, England: Cambridge<br />

University Press.<br />

Frijda, N. H. (1987). <strong>Emotion</strong>, cognitive structure, and action tendency.<br />

Cognition and <strong>Emotion</strong>, 1, 115-143.<br />

January 1992 • American Psychologist 43


Frijda, N. H., Kuipers, P., & ter Schure, E. (1989). Relations among<br />

emotion, appraisal, and emotional action readiness. Journal <strong>of</strong> Personality<br />

and Social Psychology, 57, 212-228.<br />

Gordon, R. M. (1974). The aboutness <strong>of</strong> emotions. American Philosophical<br />

Quarterly, 11, 27-36.<br />

Gordon, R. M. (1978). <strong>Emotion</strong> labelling and cognition. Journal for the<br />

<strong>Theory</strong> <strong>of</strong> Social Behaviour, 8, 125-135.<br />

Green, O. H. (1986). Actions, emotions, and desires. In J. Marks (Ed.),<br />

The ways <strong>of</strong> desire (pp. 115-131). Chicago: Precedent.<br />

Hall, R. J. (1989). Are pains necessarily unpleasant? Philosophy and<br />

Phenomenological Research, 49, 643-659.<br />

Hilgard, E. R. (1980). The trilogy <strong>of</strong> the mind: Cognition, affect, and<br />

conation. Journal <strong>of</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> the Behavioral Sciences, 16, 107-<br />

117.<br />

Holyoak, K. J., & Gordon, P. C. (1984). Information processing and<br />

social cognition. In R. S. Wyer, Jr. & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook <strong>of</strong><br />

social cognition (Vol. 1, pp. 39-70). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

Hunt, J. McV., Cole, M. W., & Reis, E. D. (1958). Situational cues<br />

distinguishing anger, fear, and sorrow. American Journal <strong>of</strong> Psychology,<br />

71, 136-151.<br />

Husserl, E. (1975). Ftinfte logische Vntersuchung [Fifth logical investigation].<br />

Hamburg, Germany: Meiner. (Original work published 1901)<br />

Isen, A. M. (1984). Toward understanding the role <strong>of</strong> affect in cognition.<br />

In R. S. Wyer, Jr. & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook <strong>of</strong> social cognition<br />

(Vol. 3, pp. 179-236). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

Izard, C. E. (1977). Human emotions. New York: Plenum.<br />

Izard, C. E. (1984). <strong>Emotion</strong>-cognition relationships and human interaction.<br />

In C. E. Izard, J. Kagan, & R. B. Zajonc (Eds.), <strong>Emotion</strong>,<br />

cognition, and behavior (pp. 17-37). New York: Cambridge University<br />

Press.<br />

James, W. (1884). What is an emotion? Mind, 9, 188-205.<br />

James, W. (1950). Principles <strong>of</strong> psychology (2nd ed.). New York: Holt.<br />

(Original work published 1890)<br />

Johnson-Laird, P. N., & Oatley, K. (1989). The language <strong>of</strong> emotions:<br />

An analysis <strong>of</strong> a semantic field. Cognition and <strong>Emotion</strong>, 3, 81-123.<br />

Kenny, A. (1963). Action, emotion, and will. London: Routledge.<br />

Krumhansl, C. L. (1991). Music psychology: Tonal structures in perception<br />

and memory. Annual Review <strong>of</strong> Psychology, 42, 277-303.<br />

Kuhl, J. (1983). Motivation, Konflikt und Handlungskontrolle [Motivation,<br />

conflict, and action control]. Berlin: Springer.<br />

Laird, J. D. (1974). Self-attribution <strong>of</strong> emotion. Journal <strong>of</strong> Personality<br />

and Social Psychology, 29, 475-486.<br />

Lazarus, R. S. (1981). A cognitivist<strong>'s</strong> reply to Zajonc on emotion and<br />

cognition. American Psychologist, 36, 222-223.<br />

Lazarus, R. S. (1982). Thoughts on the relations between emotion and<br />

cognition. American Psychologist, 37, 1019-1024.<br />

Lazarus, R. S. (1984). On the primacy <strong>of</strong> cognition. American Psychologist,<br />

39. 222-223.<br />

Lazarus, R. S., Kanner, A. D., & Folkman, S. (1980). <strong>Emotion</strong>s: A<br />

cognitive-phenomenological perspective. In R. Plutchik & H. Kellerman<br />

(Eds.), <strong>Emotion</strong>: <strong>Theory</strong>, research, and experience (Vol. 1, pp.<br />

189-217). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.<br />

Lazarus, R. S., & Smith, C. A. (1988). Knowledge and appraisal in the<br />

cognition-emotion relationship. Cognition and <strong>Emotion</strong>, 2, 281-300.<br />

LeDoux, J. E. (1989). <strong>Cognitive</strong>-emotional interactions in the brain.<br />

Cognition and <strong>Emotion</strong>, 3, 267-289.<br />

Lehmann, A. (1914). Die Hauptgesetze des menschlichen Gefuhlslebens<br />

[The principle laws <strong>of</strong> human emotions]. Leipzig, Germany: Reisland.<br />

Leighton, S. R. (1985). A new view <strong>of</strong> emotion. American Philosophical<br />

Quarterly, 22, 133-141.<br />

Leventhal, H. (1984). A perceptual-motor theory <strong>of</strong> emotion. In L.<br />

Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 17,<br />

pp. 117-182). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.<br />

Leventhal, H., & Scherer, K. R. (1987). The relationship <strong>of</strong> emotion<br />

and cognition: A functional approach to a semantic controversy. Cognition<br />

and <strong>Emotion</strong>, 1, 3-28.<br />

Lyons, W. (1980). <strong>Emotion</strong>. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University<br />

Press.<br />

Mackie, J. L. (1974). The cement <strong>of</strong> the universe: A study <strong>of</strong> causation.<br />

Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.<br />

Mackie, J. L. (1975). Problems <strong>of</strong> intentionality. In E. Pivcevic (Ed.),<br />

44<br />

Phenomenology and philosophical understanding (pp. 37-52). Cambridge,<br />

England: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Mandler, G. (1984). Mind and body. New York: Norton.<br />

Marks, J. (1982). A theory <strong>of</strong> emotion. Philosophical Studies, 42, 227-<br />

242.<br />

Marks, J. (1986). (Ed.). The ways <strong>of</strong> desire. Chicago: Precedent.<br />

Mohanty, J. N. (1986). Levels <strong>of</strong> understanding "intentionality." Monist,<br />

69, 505-520.<br />

Oatley, K. (1988). Plans and the communicative function <strong>of</strong> emotions:<br />

A cognitive theory. In V. Hamilton, G. H. Bower, & N. J. Frijda<br />

(Eds.), <strong>Cognitive</strong> perspectives on emotion and motivation (pp. 345-<br />

364). Dortrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.<br />

Oatley, K., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1987). Towards a cognitive theory<br />

<strong>of</strong> emotions. Cognition and <strong>Emotion</strong>, 1, 29-50.<br />

Ortony, A., & Clore, G. L. (1989). <strong>Emotion</strong>s, moods, and conscious<br />

awareness. Cognition and <strong>Emotion</strong>, 3, 125-137.<br />

Ortony, A., Clore, G. L., & Collins, A. (1988). The cognitive structure<br />

<strong>of</strong> emotions. New York: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Papez, J. W. (1937). A proposed mechanism <strong>of</strong> emotion. Archives <strong>of</strong><br />

Neurology and Psychiatry, 38, 725-743.<br />

Pekrun, R. (1988). <strong>Emotion</strong>, Motivation und Personlichkeit [<strong>Emotion</strong>,<br />

motivation, and personality]. Miinchen, Germany: Psychologie Verlags<br />

Union.<br />

Pitcher, G. (1965). <strong>Emotion</strong>. Mind, 74, 326-346.<br />

Reisenzein, R. (1992). <strong>Stumpf</strong>s kognitiv-evaluative Theorie der <strong>Emotion</strong>en<br />

[<strong>Stumpf</strong>s cognitive-evaluative theory <strong>of</strong> emotion]. In L.<br />

Sprung & W. Schonpflug (Eds.), Geschichte der Psychologie in Berlin<br />

(pp. 97-137). Frankfurt a. M., Germany: Lang.<br />

Reisenzein, R., & H<strong>of</strong>mann, T. (1990). An investigation <strong>of</strong> cognitive<br />

appraisals in emotion using the repertory grid technique. Motivation<br />

and <strong>Emotion</strong>, 14, 1-26.<br />

Rey, G. (1983). Concepts and stereotypes. Cognition, 15, 237-262.<br />

Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror <strong>of</strong> nature. Princeton, NJ:<br />

Princeton University Press.<br />

Roseman, I. J. (1984). <strong>Cognitive</strong> determinants <strong>of</strong> emotion: A structural<br />

theory. In Shaver, P. (Ed.), Review <strong>of</strong> personality and social psychology<br />

(Vol. 5, pp. 11-36). Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.<br />

Rozin, P., & Fallon, A. E. (1987). A perspective on disgust. Psychological<br />

Review, 94, 23-41.<br />

Russell, J. A., & Woudzia, L. (1986). Affective judgments, common<br />

sense, and Zajonc<strong>'s</strong> thesis <strong>of</strong> independence. Motivation and <strong>Emotion</strong>,<br />

10, 169-183.<br />

Sayre, K. M. (1986). Intentionality and information processing: An alternative<br />

model for cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,<br />

9, 121-166.<br />

Schachter, S. (1964). The interaction <strong>of</strong> cognitive and physiological determinants<br />

<strong>of</strong> emotional state. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in<br />

experimental social psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 49-80). San Diego, CA:<br />

Academic Press.<br />

Scheerer, E. (1992). Die Berliner Psychologie zur Zeit der Aufklarung<br />

[Psychology in Berlin at the time <strong>of</strong> enlightenment]. In L. Sprung &<br />

W. Schonpflug (Eds.), Geschichte der Psychologie in Berlin (pp. 31-<br />

47). Frankfurt a. M., Germany: Lang.<br />

Scherer, K. R. (1984). On the nature and function <strong>of</strong> emotion: A component<br />

process approach. In Scherer, K. R., & Ekman, P. (Eds.), Approaches<br />

to emotion (pp. 293-317). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University<br />

Press.<br />

Smith, C. A., & Ellsworth, P. C. (1985). Patterns <strong>of</strong> cognitive appraisal<br />

in emotion. Journal <strong>of</strong> Personality and Social Psychology, 48, 813-<br />

838.<br />

Smith, C. A., & Ellsworth, P. C. (1987). Patterns <strong>of</strong> appraisal and emotion<br />

related to taking an exam. Journal <strong>of</strong> Personality and Social Psychology,<br />

52, 475-488.<br />

Solomon, R. C. (1976). The passions. Garden City, NY: Anchor Press/<br />

Doubleday.<br />

Solomon, R. C. (1988). On emotions as judgments. American Philosophical<br />

Quarterly, 25, 183-191.<br />

Sprung, L., Sprung, H., & Kerachen, S. (1986). Erinnerungen an einen<br />

fast vergessenen Psychologen? Carl <strong>Stumpf</strong> (1848-1936) zum 50.<br />

Todestag. [Remembering a nearly forgotten psychologist? Carl <strong>Stumpf</strong><br />

at his 50th anniversary]. Zeitschrifi fur Psychologie, 194, 509-516.<br />

January 1992 » American Psychologist


Stegmiiller, W. (1986). Theorie und Erfahrung, Band III: Die Entwicklung<br />

des neuen Strukluralismus seit 1973 [<strong>Theory</strong> and experience: Vol. 3.<br />

The development <strong>of</strong> the new structuralist approach since 1973]. Berlin:<br />

Springer.<br />

Starring, G. (1922). Psychologie des menschlichen Gefiihlslebens [Psychology<br />

<strong>of</strong> human emotions]. Bonn, Germany: Cohen.<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>, C. (1883). Tonpsychologie [The psychology <strong>of</strong> tone] (Vol. 1).<br />

Leipzig, Germany: Hirzel.<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>, C. (1890). Tonpsychologie [The psychology <strong>of</strong> tone] (Vol. 2).<br />

Leipzig, Germany: Hirzel.<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>, C. (1899). Uber den Begriff der Gemiithsbewegung [On the<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> emotion]. Zeitschrift fur Psychologie und Physiologie der<br />

Sinnesorgane, 21, 47-99.<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>, C. (1907a). Uber Gefuhlsempfindungen [On affective sensations].<br />

Zeitschrift fur Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane,<br />

44, 1-49.<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>, C. (1907b). Erscheinungen und psychische Funktionen [Presentations<br />

and mental states]. Abhandlungen der preussischen Akademie<br />

der Wissenschaften, 1906, 3-39.<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>, C. (1907c). Zur Einteilung der Wissenschaften [On the classification<br />

<strong>of</strong> scientific disciplines]. Abhandlungen der preussischen Akademie<br />

der Wissenschaften, 1906, 3-93.<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>, C. (1916). Apologie der Gefuhlsempfindungen [Apology for<br />

affective sensations]. Zeitschrift fur Psychologie und Physiologie der<br />

Sinnesorgane, 75, 1-38.<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>, C. (1924). Selbstdarstellung [Autobiography]. Leipzig, Germany:<br />

Meiner.<br />

<strong>Stumpf</strong>, C. (1928). Vorwort und Einleitung [Preface and introduction].<br />

In C. <strong>Stumpf</strong> (Ed.), Gefuhl und Gefiihlsempfindung (Vol. 75, pp. VII-<br />

XVI). Leipzig, Germany: Barth.<br />

Titchener, E. B. (1908). Lectures on the elementary psychology <strong>of</strong> feeling<br />

and attention. New York: McMillan.<br />

Tomkins, S. S. (1962). Affect, imagery, consciousness (Vbls. 1, 2). New<br />

York: Springer.<br />

Tomkins, S. S. (1980). Affect as amplification: Some modifications in<br />

theory. In R. Plutchik & H. Kellerman (Eds.), <strong>Emotion</strong>: <strong>Theory</strong>, research,<br />

and experience (Vol. 1, pp. 141 -164). San Diego, CA: Academic<br />

Press.<br />

Weiner, B. (1986). An attribulional theory <strong>of</strong> motivation and emotion.<br />

New York: Springer.<br />

Wierzbicka, A. (1972). Semantic primitives. Frankfurt, Germany: Athcnaum.<br />

Wilson, J. R. S. (1972). <strong>Emotion</strong> and object. Cambridge, England: Cambridge<br />

University Press.<br />

Wundt, W. (1896). Grundriss der Psychologie [Outlines <strong>of</strong> psychology].<br />

Leipzig, Germany: Engelmann.<br />

Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Feeling and thinking: Preferences need no inferences.<br />

American Psychologist, 35, 151-175.<br />

Zajonc, R. B. (1981). A one-factor mind about mind and emotion.<br />

American Psychologist, 36, 102-103.<br />

Zajonc, R. B. (1984). On the primacy <strong>of</strong> affect. American Psychologist,<br />

39, 117-123.<br />

Zajonc, R. B., Murphy, S. T., & Inglehart, M. (1989). Feeling and facial<br />

efference: Implications <strong>of</strong> the vascular theory <strong>of</strong> emotions. Psychological<br />

Review, 96, 395-416.<br />

Zillmann, D. (1978). Attribution and misattribution <strong>of</strong> excitatory reactions.<br />

In J. H. Harvey, W. J. Ickes, & R. F. Kidd (Eds.), New directions<br />

in attribution research (Vol. 2, pp. 335-368). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.<br />

January 1992 • American Psychologist 45

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!