14.12.2012 Views

+ [R] - Gabriele Jutz - Sonance.net

+ [R] - Gabriele Jutz - Sonance.net

+ [R] - Gabriele Jutz - Sonance.net

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

gabriele.jutz@uni-ak.ac.at<br />

FILMAVANTGARDE I:<br />

DIE 1920ER JAHRE<br />

READER<br />

Deutschland: Abstrakter Film<br />

Frankreich: Dadaismus, Surrealismus<br />

Sowjetunion: Kino der Montage<br />

Universität für angewandte Kunst<br />

Wintersemester 2009/10


Dieser Reader darf nur für Studienzwecke benutzt werden.<br />

Der Reader ist nach Text durchsuchbar.<br />

Bei der Erstellung wurde eine automatische Texterkennung verwendet.<br />

Daher sind vereinzelt Schreibfehler möglich.


Filmavantgarde I: Die 1920er Jahre (Universität für angewandte Kunst, Wien, WS 2009/10)<br />

gabriele.jutz@uni-ak.ac.at<br />

LITERATURLISTE<br />

[R] = Text befindet sich im Reader; online unter: http://jutz.sonance.<strong>net</strong>/<br />

[H] = Buch befindet sich im Handapparat (Bibliothek)<br />

BLOCK 0<br />

ALLGEMEIN EINFÜHRENDE LITERATUR<br />

Andreas HUYSSEN: The Hidden Dialectic: Avantgarde – Technology –<br />

Mass Culture (1980). In: Ders.: After the Great Divide. Modernism,<br />

Mass Culture, Postmodernism. Bloomington: Indiana University Press<br />

1986, S. 3–15. [R]<br />

Bernd HÜPPAUF: Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden. Die Zeit,<br />

Avantgarden und die Gegenwart. In: Wolfgang Asholt, Walter<br />

Fähnders (Hg.): Der Blick vom Wolkenkratzer. Avantgarde,<br />

Avantgardekritik, Avantgardeforschung. Amsterdam: Rodopi 2000,<br />

S. 547–579. [R]<br />

Hans SCHEUGL und Ernst SCHMIDT JR: Eine Subgeschichte des<br />

Films. Lexikon des Avantgarde-, Experimental- und Undergroundfilms,<br />

Bd. 1 und Bd. 2. Frankfurt/M. 1974. [H]<br />

Heinrich KLOTZ: Kunst im 20. Jahrhundert. Moderne, Postmoderne,<br />

Zweite Moderne. München: Beck 1994. [H]<br />

Leicht zu lesende Einführung in den Moderne-Begriff der bildenden Kunst<br />

Anne FRIEDBERG: The End of Modernity: Where Is Your Rupture? In:<br />

Dies.: Window Shopping. Cinema and the Postmodern. Berkeley:<br />

University of California Press 1994, S. 157–179. [H] + [R]<br />

Thematisiert die Frage nach der filmischen Moderne


Filmavantgarde I: Die 1920er Jahre (Universität für angewandte Kunst, Wien, WS 2009/10)<br />

gabriele.jutz@uni-ak.ac.at<br />

Danny BIRCHALL: The Avant-Garde Archive Online. In: Film<br />

Quaterly,Vol. 63. University of California 2009, S. 12-14. [R]<br />

BLOCK 1<br />

DEUTSCHLAND – ABSOLUTER/ABSTRAKTER FILM<br />

Helmut HERBST: Mit der Technik denken: Konstruktion einer<br />

Augenmusik. In: Sound & Vision – Musikvideo und Filmkunst. Katalog<br />

zur gleichnamigen Ausstellung im Deutschen Filmmuseum/Frankfurt/M.<br />

1994, S. 37–41. [R]<br />

Thomas MANK: Die Kunst des Absoluten Films. In: Sound & Vision –<br />

Musikvideo und Filmkunst. Katalog zur gleichnamigen Ausstellung im<br />

Deutschen Filmmuseum/Frankfurt/M. 1994, S. 73–87. [R]<br />

Holger WILMESMEIER: Deutsche Avantgarde und Film. Die<br />

Filmmatinee „Der absolute Film“ (3. und 10. Mai 1925). Münster,<br />

Hamburg: LIT Verlag 1994. [H]<br />

Christine N. BRINCKMANN: „Abstraktion“ und „Einfühlung“ im<br />

deutschen Avantgarde-Film der 20er Jahre. In: Dies.: Die<br />

anthropomorphe Kamera und andere Schriften zur filmischen Narration.<br />

Zürich: Chronos 1997, S. 276–275.<br />

BLOCK 2<br />

FRANKREICH – DADAISMUS UND SURREALISMUS<br />

Hans RICHTER: Le coeur à barbe. In: Ders.: Dada – Kunst und<br />

Antikunst. Köln: DuMont 1964, S. 194–196. [R] + [H]<br />

Wieland HERZFELDE: Zur Einführung (1920). In: Uwe M. Schneede


Filmavantgarde I: Die 1920er Jahre (Universität für angewandte Kunst, Wien, WS 2009/10)<br />

gabriele.jutz@uni-ak.ac.at<br />

(Hg.): Die zwanziger Jahre. Köln: DuMont 1979, S. 31–34. [R] + [H]<br />

Thomas ELSAESSER: Dada/Cinema? In: Rudolf E. Kuenzli (Hg.): Dada<br />

and Surrealist Film. Cambridge, London: MIT Press 1996, S. 13–27. [R]<br />

+ [H]<br />

Judi FREEMAN: Bridging Purism and Surrealism: The Origins and<br />

Production of Fernand Léger's Ballet Mécanique. In: Rudolf E. Kuenzli<br />

(Hg.): Dada and Surrealist Film. Cambridge, London: MIT Press 1996,<br />

S. 28–45. [R] + [H]<br />

Sandy FLITTERMAN-LEWIS: Dulac in Context: French Film<br />

Production in the Twenties. In: Dies.: To Desire Differently. Feminism<br />

and the French Cinema. Univ. of Illinois Press 1990, S. 78-97. [R]<br />

Sandy FLITTERMAN-LEWIS: From Fantasy to Structure of the<br />

Fantasm: The Smiling Mme Beudet and The Seashell and the Clergyman.<br />

In: Dies.: To Desire Differently. Feminism and the French Cinema. Univ.<br />

of Illinois Press 1990, S. 98-140. [R]<br />

Linda WILLIAMS: Un Chien andalou. In: Dies.: Figures of Desire. A<br />

Theory and Analysis of Surrealist Film. Univ. of Calif. Press 1981, S.<br />

53–105. [R] + [H]<br />

BLOCK 3<br />

SOWJETUNION – KINO DER MONTAGE<br />

Mark JOYCE: The Soviet Montage Cinema of the 1920s. In: Jill Nelmes<br />

(Hg.): An Introduction to Film Studies (second edition). London, New<br />

York: Routledge 1999, S. 417–450. [R] + [H]<br />

Sergej M. EISENSTEIN: Über die Reinheit der Filmsprache (1934). In:


Filmavantgarde I: Die 1920er Jahre (Universität für angewandte Kunst, Wien, WS 2009/10)<br />

gabriele.jutz@uni-ak.ac.at<br />

Ders.: Schriften 2, Hans-Joachim Schlegel (Hg.). München: Hanser<br />

1973, S. 141–150. [R]<br />

Dziga VERTOV: Wir. Variante eines Manifestes (1922). In: Franz-Josef<br />

Albersmeier (Hg.): Texte zur Theorie des Films. Stuttgart 1979, S. 19–<br />

23. [R]<br />

Dziga VERTOV: Kinoglaz (1924). In: Franz-Josef Albersmeier (Hg.):<br />

Texte zur Theorie des Films. Stuttgart: Reclam 1979, S. 39–41. [R]<br />

Vlada PETRIC: Constructivism in Film. The Man with the Movie<br />

Camera. A Cinematic Analysis. Cambridge University Press 1987. [H]<br />

Prüfungsmodalitäten<br />

*****<br />

Fragenkatalog, der zu Hause auf der Basis des Readers und der<br />

Lehrveranstaltung beantwortet werden soll.<br />

– 1. Abgabetermin: bis 11. März 2010<br />

– 2. Abgabetermin: bis 10. Juni 2010 (letzter Termin!)<br />

*****<br />

Gastvortrag Stephen Zepke am 12. Jänner


BLOCK 1<br />

Deutschland – Abstrakter Film<br />

FILMLISTE<br />

Hans Richter<br />

Rhythmus 21 (1921, stumm, 4 Min.)<br />

Rhythmus 23 (1923, stumm, 4 Min.)<br />

Filmstudie (1926, 5 Min.)<br />

Dadaistische und surrealistische Filme von Richter:<br />

Vormittagsspuk (1927–28, 7 Min.)<br />

Race Symphony (1928–29, 7 Min.)<br />

Zweigroschenzauber (1928-29, 2 Min.)<br />

Inflation (1927–28, 3 Min.)<br />

Alles dreht sich, alles bewegt sich (1929, 3 Min.)<br />

Viking Eggeling<br />

Diagonal Symphonie (1921? 1925?, s/w, stumm, 8 Min.)<br />

Walter Ruttmann<br />

Opus IV (1925, stumm, 3 Min.)<br />

Weekend (1930, Hörspiel, 11 Min. 10 Sek.)<br />

Oskar Fischinger<br />

Muratti greift ein (1934, Farbe, 2 Min.)<br />

Spiritual Constructions (1927, s/w, 7 Min.)<br />

Study N° 7 (1931, s/w, 2 Min. 30 Sek.)<br />

Study N° 8 (1931, s/w, 5 Min.)<br />

Kreise (1933, Farbe, 2 Min.)<br />

Allegretto (1936, Farbe, 3 Min.)<br />

Motion Painting N° 1 (1947, Farbe, 11 Min.)<br />

Filmavantgarde I: 1920er Jahre<br />

Universität für angewandte Kunst, WS 2009/10<br />

gabriele.jutz@uni-ak.ac.at


BLOCK 2<br />

Frankreich – Dadaismus und Surrealismus<br />

Marcel Duchamp<br />

Anémic Cinéma (1926)<br />

Fernand Leger<br />

Le Ballet Mécanique (1924)<br />

René Clair<br />

Entr’acte (1924)<br />

Man Ray<br />

Le retour à la raison (1923)<br />

Emak Bakia (1927)<br />

L'étoile de mer (1928)<br />

Filmavantgarde I: 1920er Jahre<br />

Universität für angewandte Kunst, WS 2009/10<br />

gabriele.jutz@uni-ak.ac.at<br />

Germaine Dulac<br />

La coquille et le clergyman (Die Muschel und der Kleriker) (1927)<br />

Luis Buñuel, Salvador Dali<br />

Un chien andalou (1929)<br />

BLOCK 3<br />

Sowjetunion – Kino der Montage<br />

Esfir Shub<br />

The Fall of the Romanoff Dynasty (1927) – Ausschnitt<br />

Sergej M. Eisenstein<br />

Streik (1924) – Finalsequenz<br />

Panzerkreuzer Potemkin (1925) – Analyse von 14 Einstellungen<br />

Dziga Vertov: The Man with the Movie Camera (1929)


BLOCK 0<br />

ALLGEMEIN EINFÜHRENDE LITERATUR


Andreas HUYSSEN: The Hidden Dialectic: Avantgarde – Technology –<br />

Mass Culture (1980). In: Ders.: After the Great Divide. Modernism,<br />

Mass Culture, Postmodernism. Bloomington: Indiana University Press<br />

1986, S. 3-15.<br />

1<br />

The Hidden Dialectic:<br />

Avantgarde—Technology—<br />

Mass Culture (1980)<br />

I<br />

Historical materialism wishes to retain that image<br />

of the past which unexpectedly appears to<br />

man singled out by history at a moment of danger.<br />

The danger affects both the content of the<br />

tradition and its receivers. The same threat<br />

hangs over both: that of becoming a tool of the<br />

ruling classes. In every era the attempt must be<br />

made anew to wrest tradition away from conformism<br />

that is about to overpower it.<br />

Walter Benjamin<br />

Theses on the Philosophy of History<br />

When Walter Benjamin, one of the foremost theoreticians of avantgarde<br />

art and literature, wrote these sentences in 1940 he certainly did<br />

not have the avantgarde in mind at all. It had not yet become part of<br />

that tradition which Benjamin was bent on salvaging. Nor could Benjamin<br />

have foreseen to what extent conformism would eventually<br />

overpower the tradition of avantgardism, both in advanced capitalist<br />

societies and, more recently, in East European societies as well. Like a<br />

parasitic growth, conformism has all but obliterated the original iconoclastic<br />

and subversive thrust of the historical avantgarde 1 of the first<br />

This essay was first published in The Myths of Information: Technology and Postindustrial<br />

Culture, ed. by Kathleen Woodward (Madison, Wis.: Coda Press, 1980), pp. 151-164.


4 AFTER THE GREAT DIVIDE<br />

three or four decades of this century. This conformism is manifest in<br />

the vast depoliticization of post-World War II art and its institutionalization<br />

as administered culture, 2 as well as in academic interpretations<br />

which, by canonizing the historical avantgarde, modernism and<br />

postmodernism, have methodologically severed the vital dialectic between<br />

the avantgarde and mass culture in industrial civilization. In<br />

most academic criticism the avantgarde has been ossified into an elite<br />

enterprise beyond politics and beyond everyday life, though their<br />

transformation was once a central project of the historical avantgarde.<br />

In light of the tendency to project the post-1945 depoliticization of<br />

culture back onto the earlier avantgarde movements, it is crucial to<br />

recover a sense of the cultural politics of the historical avantgarde.<br />

Only then can we raise meaningful questions about the relationship<br />

between the historical avantgarde and the neo-avantgarde, modernism<br />

and post-modernism, as well as about the aporias of the avantgarde<br />

and the consciousness industry (Hans Magnus Enzensberger), the<br />

tradition of the new (Harold Rosenberg) and the death of the avantgarde<br />

(Leslie Fiedler). For if discussions of the avantgarde do not break<br />

with the oppressive mechanisms of hierarchical discourse (high vs.<br />

popular, the new new vs. the old new, art vs. politics, truth vs. ideology),<br />

and if the question of today's literary and artistic avantgarde is<br />

not placed in a larger socio-historical framework, the prophets of the<br />

new will remain locked in futile battle with the sirens of cultural<br />

decline—a battle which by now only results in a sense of deja vu.<br />

II<br />

Historically the concept of the avantgarde, which until the 1930s was<br />

not limited to art but always referred to political radicalism as well, 3<br />

assumed prominence in the decades following the French Revolution.<br />

Henri de Saint Simon's Opinions litteraires, philosophiques et industrielles<br />

(1825) ascribed a vanguard role to the artist in the construction of the<br />

ideal state and the new golden age of the future, 4 and since then the<br />

concept of an avantgarde has remained inextricably bound to the idea<br />

of progress in industrial and technological civilization. In Saint Simon's<br />

messianic scheme, art, science, and industry were to generate and<br />

guarantee the progress of the emerging technical-industrial bourgeois<br />

world, the world of the city and the masses, capital and culture. The<br />

avantgarde, then, only makes sense if it remains dialectically related to<br />

that for which it serves as the vanguard—speaking narrowly, to the<br />

older modes of artistic expression, speaking broadly, to the life of the<br />

The Hidden Dialectic 5<br />

masses which Saint Simon's avantgarde scientists, engineers, and artists<br />

were to lead into the golden age of bourgeois prosperity.<br />

Throughout the 19th century the idea of the avantgarde remained<br />

linked to political radicalism. Through the mediation of the Utopian<br />

socialist Charles Fourier, it found its way into socialist anarchism and<br />

eventually into substantial segments of the bohemian subcultures of<br />

the turn of the century. 5 It is certainly no coincidence that the impact of<br />

anarchism on artists and writers reached its peak precisely when the<br />

historical avantgarde was in a crucial stage of its formation. The attraction<br />

of artists and intellectuals to anarchism at that time can be attributed<br />

to two major factors: artists and anarchists alike rejected<br />

bourgeois society and its stagnating cultural conservatism, and both<br />

anarchists and left-leaning bohemians fought the economic and technological<br />

determinism and scientism of Second International Marxism,<br />

which they saw as the theoretical and practical mirror image of the<br />

bourgeois world. 6 Thus, when the bourgeoisie had fully established its<br />

domination of the state and industry, science and culture, the avantgardist<br />

was not at all in the forefront of the kind of struggle Saint<br />

Simon had envisioned. On the contrary, he found himself on the<br />

margins of the very industrial civilization which he was opposing and<br />

which, according to Saint Simon, he was to prophesy and bring about.<br />

In terms of understanding the later condemnations of avantgarde art<br />

and literature both by the right (entartete Kunst) and by the left<br />

(bourgeois decadence), it is important to recognize that as early as the<br />

1890s the avantgarde's insistence on cultural revolt clashed with the<br />

bourgeoisie's need for cultural legitimation, as well as with the preference<br />

of the Second International's cultural politics for the classical<br />

bourgeois heritage. 7<br />

Neither Marx nor Engels ever attributed major importance to culture<br />

(let alone avantgarde art and literature) in the working-class<br />

struggles, although it can be argued that the link between cultural and<br />

political-economic revolution is indeed implicit in their early works,<br />

especially in Marx's Parisian Manuscripts and the Communist Manifesto.<br />

Nor did Marx or Engels ever posit the Party as the avantgarde of the<br />

working class. Rather, it was Lenin who institutionalized the Party as<br />

the vanguard of the revolution in What Is to Be Done (1902) and soon<br />

after, in his article "Party Organization and Party Literature" (1905),<br />

severed the vital dialectic between the political and cultural avantgarde,<br />

subordinating the latter to the Party. Declaring the artistic<br />

avantgarde to be a mere instrument of the political vanguard, "a cog<br />

and screw of one single great Social Democratic mechanism set in


6 AFTER THE GREAT DIVIDE<br />

motion by the entire politically conscious avantgarde of the entire<br />

working class," 8 Lenin thus helped pave the way for the later suppression<br />

and liquidation of the Russian artistic avantgarde which began in<br />

the early 1920s and culminated with the official adoption of the doctrine<br />

of socialist realism in 1934. 9<br />

In the West, the historical avantgarde died a slower death, and the<br />

reasons for its demise vary from country to country. The German<br />

avantgarde of the 1920s was abruptly terminated when Hitler came to<br />

power in 1933, and the development of the West European avantgarde<br />

was interrupted by the war and the German occupation of Europe.<br />

Later, during the cold war, especially after the notion of the end of<br />

ideology took hold, the political thrust of the historical avantgarde was<br />

lost and the center of artistic innovation shifted from Europe to the<br />

United States. To some extent, of course, the lack of political perspective<br />

in art movements such as abstract expressionism and Pop art was a<br />

function of the altogether different relationship between avantgarde<br />

art and cultural tradition in the United States, where the iconoclastic<br />

rebellion against a bourgeois cultural heritage would have made neither<br />

artistic nor political sense. In the United States, the literary and<br />

artistic heritage never played as central a role in legitimizing bourgeois<br />

domination as it did in Europe. But these explanations for the death of<br />

the historical avantgarde in the West at a certain time, although critical,<br />

are not exhaustive. The loss of potency of the historical avantgarde<br />

may be related more fundamentally to a broad cultural change in the<br />

West in the 20th century: it may be argued that the rise of the Western<br />

culture industry, which paralleled the decline of the historical avantgarde,<br />

has made the avantgarde's enterprise itself obsolete.<br />

To summarize: since Saint Simon, the avantgardes of Europe had<br />

been characterized by a precarious balance of art and politics, but since<br />

the 1930s the cultural and political avantgardes have gone their separate<br />

ways. In the two major systems of domination in the contemporary<br />

world, the avantgarde has lost its cultural and political explosiveness<br />

and has itself become a tool of legitimation. In the United States, a<br />

depoliticized cultural avantgarde has produced largely affirmative culture,<br />

most visibly in pop art where the commodity fetish often reigns<br />

supreme. In the Soviet Union and in Eastern Europe, the historical<br />

avantgarde was first strangled by the iron hand of Stalin's cultural<br />

henchman Zhdanov and then revived as part of the cultural heritage,<br />

thus providing legitimacy to regimes which face growing cultural and<br />

political dissent.<br />

Both politically and aesthetically, today it is important to retain that<br />

image of the now lost unity of the political and artistic avantgarde,<br />

The Hidden Dialectic 7<br />

which may help us forge a new unity of politics and culture adequate to<br />

our own times. Since it has become more difficult to share the historical<br />

avantgarde's belief that art can be crucial to a transformation of society,<br />

the point is not simply to revive the avantgarde. Any such attempt<br />

would be doomed, especially in a country such as the United States<br />

where the European avantgarde failed to take roots precisely because<br />

no belief existed in the power of art to change the world. Nor, however,<br />

is it enough to cast a melancholy glance backwards and indulge in<br />

nostalgia for the time when the affinity of art to revolution could be<br />

taken for granted. The point is rather to take up the historical avantgarde's<br />

insistence on the cultural transformation of everyday life and<br />

from there to develop strategies for today's cultural and political context.<br />

Ill<br />

The notion that culture is a potentially explosive force and a threat to<br />

advanced capitalism (and to bureaucratized socialism, for that matter)<br />

has a long history within Western Marxism from the early Lukacs up<br />

through Habermas's Legitimation Crisis and Negt/Kluge's Offenthchkeit<br />

und Erfahrung. 10 It even underlies, if only by its conspicuous absence,<br />

Adorno's seemingly dualistic theory of a monolithically manipulative<br />

culture industry and an avantgarde locked into negativity. Peter Burger,<br />

a recent theoretician of the avantgarde, draws extensively on<br />

this critical Marxist tradition, especially on Benjamin and Adorno. He<br />

argues convincingly that the major goal of art movements such as<br />

Dada, surrealism, and the post-1917 Russian avantgarde was the<br />

reintegration of art into life praxis, the closing of the gap separating art<br />

from reality. Burger interprets the widening gap between art and life,<br />

which had become all but unbridgeable in late 19th century aestheticism,<br />

as a logical development of art within bourgeois society. In its<br />

attempt to close the gap, the avantgarde had to destroy what Burger<br />

calls "institution art," a term for the institutional framework in which<br />

art was produced, distributed, and received in bourgeois society, a<br />

framework which rested on Kant's and Schiller's aesthetic of the necessary<br />

autonomy of all artistic creation. During the 19th century the<br />

increasingly categorical separation of art from reality and the insistence<br />

on the autonomy of art, which had once freed art from the fetters<br />

of church and state, had worked to push art and artists to the margins<br />

of society. In the art for art's sake movement, the break with society—the<br />

society of imperialism—had led into a dead end, a fact painfully<br />

clear to the best representatives of aestheticism. Thus the histori-


8 AFTER THE GREAT DIVIDE<br />

cal avantgarde attempted to transform l'art pour l'art's isolation from<br />

reality—which reflected as much opposition to bourgeois society as<br />

Zola's j'accuse—into an active rebellion that would make art productive<br />

for social change. In the historical avantgarde, Burger argues,<br />

bourgeois art reached the stage of self-criticism; it no longer only<br />

criticized previous art qua art, but also critiqued the very "institution<br />

art" as it had developed in bourgeois society since the 18th century."<br />

Of course, the use of the Marxian categories of criticism and selfcriticism<br />

implies that the negation and sublation (Aufhebung) of the<br />

bourgeois "institution art" is bound to the transformation of bourgeois<br />

society itself. Since such a transformation did not take place, the<br />

avantgarde's attempt to integrate art and life almost had to fail. This<br />

failure, later often labelled the death of the avantgarde, is Burger's<br />

starting point and his reason for calling the avantgarde "historical."<br />

And yet, the failure of the avantgarde to reorganize a new life praxis<br />

through art and politics resulted in precisely those historical phenomena<br />

which make any revival of the avantgarde's project today<br />

highly problematic, if not impossible: namely, the false sublations of<br />

the art/life dichotomy in fascism with its aesthetization of politics, 12 in<br />

Western mass culture with its fictionalization of reality, and in socialist<br />

realism with its claims of reality status for its fictions.<br />

If we agree with the thesis that the avantgarde's revolt was directed<br />

against the totality of bourgeois culture and its psycho-social mechanisms<br />

of domination and control, and if we then make it our task to<br />

salvage the historical avantgarde from the conformism which has<br />

obscured its political thrust, then it becomes crucial to answer a number<br />

of questions which go beyond Burger's concern with the "institution<br />

art" and the formal structure of the avantgarde art work. How<br />

precisely did the dadaists, surrealists, futurists, constructivists, and<br />

productivists attempt to overcome the art/life dichotomy? How did<br />

they conceptualize and put into practice the radical transformation of<br />

the conditions of producing, distributing, and consuming art? What<br />

exactly was their place within the political spectrum of those decades<br />

and what concrete political possibilities were open to them in specific<br />

countries? In what way did the conjunction of political and cultural<br />

revolt inform their art and to what extent did that art become part of<br />

the revolt itself? Answers to these questions will vary depending on<br />

whether one focuses on Bolshevik Russia, France after Versailles, or<br />

Germany, doubly beaten by World War I and a failed revolution.<br />

Moreover, even within these countries and the various artistic movements,<br />

differentiations have to be made. It is fairly obvious that a<br />

montage by Schwitters differs aesthetically and politically from a<br />

photomontage by John Heartfield, that Dada Zurich and Dada Paris<br />

The Hidden Dialectic 9<br />

developed an artistic and political sensibility which differed substantially<br />

from that of Dada Berlin, that Mayakovsky and revolutionary<br />

futurism cannot be equated with the productivism of Arvatov or<br />

Gastev. And yet, as Burger has convincingly suggested, all these phenomena<br />

can legitimately be subsumed under the notion of the historical<br />

avantgarde.<br />

IV<br />

I will not attempt here to answer all these questions, but will focus<br />

instead on uncovering the hidden dialectic of avantgarde and mass<br />

culture, thereby casting new light on the objective historical conditions<br />

of avantgarde art, as well as on the socio-political subtext of its inevitable<br />

decline and the simultaneous rise of mass culture.<br />

Mass culture as we know it in the West is unthinkable without 20th<br />

century technology—media techniques as well as technologies of transportation<br />

(public and private), the household, and leisure. Mass<br />

culture depends on technologies of mass production and mass reproduction<br />

and thus on the homogenization of difference. While it is<br />

generally recognized that these technologies have substantially transformed<br />

everyday life in the 20th century, it is much less widely acknowledged<br />

that technology and the experience of an increasingly<br />

technologized life world have also radically transformed art. Indeed,<br />

technology played a crucial, if not the crucial, role in the avantgarde's<br />

attempt to overcome the art/life dichotomy and make art productive in<br />

the transformation of everyday life. Burger has argued correctly that<br />

from Dada on the avantgarde movements distinguish themselves from<br />

preceding movements such as impressionism, naturalism, and cubism<br />

not only in their attack on the "institution art" as such, but also in their<br />

radical break with the referential mimetic aesthetic and its notion of<br />

the autonomous and organic work of art. I would go further: no other<br />

single factor has influenced the emergence of the new avantgarde art<br />

as much as technology,-which not only fueled the artists' imagination<br />

(dynamism, machine cult, beauty of technics, constructivist and productivist<br />

attitudes), but pe<strong>net</strong>rated to the core of the work itself. The<br />

invasion of the very fabric of the art object by technology and what one<br />

may loosely call the technological imagination can best be grasped in<br />

artistic practices such as collage, assemblage, montage and photomontage;<br />

it finds its ultimate fulfillment in photography and film, art forms<br />

which can not only be reproduced, but are in fact designed for mechanical<br />

reproducibility. It was Walter Benjamin who, in his famous<br />

essay "The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction," first<br />

made the point that it is precisely this mechanical reproducibility which


10 AFTER THE GREAT DIVIDE<br />

has radically changed the nature of art in the 20th century, transforming<br />

the conditions of producing, distributing, and receiving/consuming<br />

art. In the context of social and cultural theory Benjamin conceptualized<br />

what Marcel Duchamp had already shown in 1919 in<br />

L.H.O.O.Q. By iconoclastically altering a reproduction of the Mona Lisa<br />

and, to use another example, by exhibiting a mass-produced urinal as a<br />

fountain sculpture, Marcel Duchamp succeeded in destroying what<br />

Benjamin called the traditional art work's aura, that aura of authenticity<br />

and uniqueness that constituted the work's distance from life and<br />

that required contemplation and immersion on the part of the spectator.<br />

In another essay, Benjamin himself acknowledged that the intention<br />

to destroy this aura was already inherent in the artistic practices of<br />

Dada. 13 The destruction of the aura, of seemingly natural and organic<br />

beauty, already characterized the works of artists who still created<br />

individual rather than mass-reproducible art objects. The decay of the<br />

aura, then, was not as immediately dependent on techniques of mechanical<br />

reproduction as Benjamin had argued in the Reproduction<br />

essay. It is indeed important to avoid such reductive analogies between<br />

industrial and artistic techniques and not to collapse, say, montage<br />

technique in art or film with industrial montage. 14<br />

It may actually have been a new experience of technology that<br />

sparked the avantgarde rather than just the immanent development of<br />

the artistic forces of production. The two poles of this new experience<br />

of technology can be described as the aesthetization of technics since<br />

the late 19th century (world expos, garden cities, the cite industrielle of<br />

Tony Gamier, the CittaNuova of Antonio Sant'Elia, the Werkbund, etc.)<br />

on the one hand and the horror of technics inspired by the awesome<br />

war machinery of World War I on the other. And this horror of<br />

technics can itself be regarded as a logical and historical outgrowth of<br />

the critique of technology and the positivist ideology of progress articulated<br />

earlier by the late l9th-century cultural radicals who in turn were<br />

strongly influenced by Nietzsche's critique of bourgeois society. Only<br />

the post-1910 avantgarde, however, succeeded in giving artistic expression<br />

to this bipolar experience of technology in the bourgeois<br />

world by integrating technology and the technological imagination in<br />

the production of art.<br />

The experience of technology at the root of the dadaist revolt was<br />

the highly technologized battlefield of World War I—that war which<br />

the Italian futurists glorified as total liberation and which the dadaists<br />

condemned as a manifestation of the ultimate insanity of the European<br />

bourgeoisie. While technology revealed its destructive power in the big<br />

Materialschlachten of the war, the dadaists projected technology's destructivism<br />

into art and turned it aggressively against the sanctified<br />

The Hidden Dialectic 11<br />

sphere of bourgeois high culture whose representatives, on the whole,<br />

had enthusiastically welcomed the war in 1914. Dada's radical and<br />

disruptive moment becomes even clearer if we remember that<br />

bourgeois ideology had lived off the separation of the cultural from<br />

industrial and economic reality, which of course was the primary<br />

sphere of technology. Instrumental reason, technological expansion,<br />

and profit maximization were held to be diametrically opposed to the<br />

schöner Schein (beautiful appearance) and interesseloses Wohlgefallen (disinterested<br />

pleasure) dominant in the sphere of high culture.<br />

In its attempt to reintegrate art and life, the avantgarde of course did<br />

not want to unite the bourgeois concept of reality with the equally<br />

bourgeois notion of high, autonomous culture. To use Marcuse's<br />

terms, they did not want to weld the reality principle to affirmative<br />

culture, since these two principles constituted each other precisely in<br />

their separation. On the contrary, by incorporating technology into<br />

art, the avantgarde liberated technology from its instrumental aspects<br />

and thus undermined both bourgeois notions of technology as progress<br />

and art as "natural," "autonomous," and "organic." On a more<br />

traditional representational level, which was never entirely abandoned,<br />

the avantgarde's radical critique of the principles of bourgeois<br />

enlightenment and its glorification of progress and technology were<br />

manifested in scores of paintings, drawings, sculptures, and other art<br />

objects in which humans are presented as machines and automatons,<br />

puppets and mannequins, often faceless, with hollow heads, blind or<br />

staring into space. The fact that these presentations did not aim at<br />

some abstract "human condition," but rather critiqued the invasion of<br />

capitalism's technological instrumentality into the fabric of everyday<br />

life, even into the human body, is perhaps most evident in the works of<br />

Dada Berlin, the most politicized wing of the Dada movement. While<br />

only Dada Berlin integrated its artistic activities with the working-class<br />

struggles in the Weimar Republic, it would be reductive to deny Dada<br />

Zurich or Dada Paris any political importance and to decree that their<br />

project was "only aesthetic," "only cultural." Such an interpretation<br />

falls victim to the same reified dichotomy of culture and politics which<br />

the historical avantgarde had tried to explode.<br />

V<br />

In Dada, technology mainly functioned to ridicule and dismantle<br />

bourgeois high culture and its ideology, and thus was ascribed an<br />

iconoclastic value in accord with Dada's anarchistic thrust. Technology<br />

took an entirely different meaning in the post-1917 Russian avantgarde—in<br />

futurism, constructivism. Droductivism, and the proletcult.


12 AFTER THE GREAT DIVIDE<br />

The Russian avantgarde had already completed its break with tradition<br />

when it turned openly political after the revolution. Artists organized<br />

themselves and took an active part in the political struggles, many of<br />

them by joining Lunacharsky's NARKOMPROS, the Commissariat for<br />

Education. Many artists automatically assumed a correspondence and<br />

potential parallel between the artistic and political revolution, and their<br />

foremost aim became to weld the disruptive power of avantgarde art to<br />

the revolution. The avantgarde's goal to forge a new unity of art and<br />

life by creating a new art and a new life seemed about to be realized in<br />

revolutionary Russia.<br />

This conjunction of political and cultural revolution with the new<br />

view of technology became most evident in the LEF group, the productivist<br />

movement, and the proletcult. As a matter of fact, these left<br />

artists, writers, and critics adhered to a cult of technology which to any<br />

contemporary radical in the West must have seemed next to inexplicable,<br />

particularly since it expressed itself in such familiar capitalist<br />

concepts as standardization, Americanization, and even taylorization.<br />

In the mid-1920s, when a similar enthusiasm for technihcation, Americanism,<br />

and functionalism had taken hold among liberals of the<br />

Weimar Republic, George Grosz and Wieland Herzfelde tried to explain<br />

this Russian cult of technology as emerging from the specific<br />

conditions of a backward agrarian country on the brink of industrialization<br />

and rejected it for the art of an already highly industrialized<br />

West: "In Russia this constructivist romanticism has a much deeper<br />

meaning and is in a more substantial way socially conditioned than in<br />

Western Europe. There constructivism is partially a natural reflection<br />

of the powerful technological offensive of the beginning industrialization."<br />

15 And yet, originally the technology cult was more than just a<br />

reflection of industrialization, or, as Grosz and Herzfelde also suggest,<br />

a propagandistic device. The hope that artists such as Tatlin, Rodchenko,<br />

Lissitzky, Meyerhold, Tretyakov, Brik, Gastev, Arvatov, Eisenstein,<br />

Vertov, and others invested in technology was closely tied to the<br />

revolutionary hopes of 1917. With Marx they insisted on the qualitative<br />

difference between bourgeois and proletarian revolutions. Marx had<br />

subsumed artistic creation under the general concept of human labor,<br />

and he had argued that human self-fulfillment would only be possible<br />

once the productive forces were freed from oppressive production and<br />

class relations. Given the Russian situation of 1917, it follows almost<br />

logically that the productivists, left futurists, and constructivists would<br />

place their artistic activities within the horizon of a socialized industrial<br />

production: art and labor, freed for the first time in history from<br />

oppressive production relations, were to enter into a new relationship.<br />

PerhaDS the best examDle of this tendency is the work of the Central<br />

The Hidden Dialectic 13<br />

Institute of Labor (CIT), which, under the leadership of Alexey Gastev,<br />

attempted to introduce the scientific organization of labor (NOT)<br />

into art and aesthetics. 16 The goal of these artists was not the technological<br />

development of the Russian economy at any cost—as it was for the<br />

Party from the NEP period on, and as it is manifest in scores of later<br />

socialist realist works with their fetishization of industry and technology.<br />

Their goal was the liberation of everyday life from all its material,<br />

ideological, and cultural restrictions. The artificial barriers between<br />

work and leisure, production and culture were to be eliminated. These<br />

artists did not want a merely decorative art which would lend its<br />

illusory glow to an increasingly instrumentalized everyday life. They<br />

aimed at an art which would intervene in everyday life by being both<br />

useful and beautiful, an art of mass demonstrations and mass festivities,<br />

an activating art of objects and attitudes, of living and dressing, of<br />

speaking and writing. Briefly, they did not want what Marcuse has<br />

called affirmative art, but rather a revolutionary culture, an art of life.<br />

They insisted on the psycho-physical unity of human life and understood<br />

that the political revolution could only be successful if it were<br />

accompanied by a revolution of everyday life.<br />

VI<br />

In this insistence on the necessary "organization of emotion and<br />

thought" (Bogdanov), we can actually trace a similarity between late<br />

19th-century cultural radicals and the Russian post-1917 avantgarde,<br />

except that now the role ascribed to technology has been totally reversed.<br />

It is precisely this similarity, however, which points to interesting<br />

differences between the Russian and the German avantgarde of the<br />

1920s, represented by Grosz, Heartfield, and Brecht among others.<br />

Despite his closeness to Tretyakov's notions of art as production and<br />

the artist as operator, Brecht never would have subscribed to Tretyakov's<br />

demand that art be used as a means of the emotional organization<br />

of the psyche. 17 Rather than describing the artist as an engineer of<br />

the psyche, as a psycho-constructor, 18 Brecht might have called the<br />

artist an engineer of reason. His dramatic technique of Verfremdungseffekt<br />

relies substantially on the emancipatory power of reason and on<br />

rational ideology critique, principles of the bourgeois enlightenment<br />

which Brecht hoped to turn effectively against bourgeois cultural<br />

hegemony. Today we cannot fail to see that Brecht, by trying to use the<br />

enlightenment dialectically, was unable to shed the vestiges of instrumental<br />

reason and thus remained caught in that other dialectic of<br />

enlightenment which Adorno and Horkheimer have exposed. 19<br />

Brecht, and to some extent also the later Beniamin. tended toward


14 AFTER THE GREAT DIVIDE<br />

fetishizing technique, science, and production in art, hoping that modern<br />

technologies could be used to build a socialist mass culture. Their<br />

trust that capitalism's power to modernize would eventually lead to its<br />

breakdown was rooted in a theory of economic crisis and revolution<br />

which, by the 1930s, had already become obsolete. But even there, the<br />

differences between Brecht and Benjamin are more interesting than<br />

the similarities. Brecht does not make his notion of artistic technique as<br />

exclusively dependent on the development of productive forces as<br />

Benjamin did in his Reproduction essay. Benjamin, on the other hand,<br />

never trusted the emancipatory power of reason and the Verfremdungseffekt<br />

as exclusively as Brecht did. Brecht also never shared Benjamin's<br />

messianism or his notion of history as an object of construction. 20 But it<br />

was especially Benjamin's emphatic notion of experience (Erfahrung)<br />

and profane illumination that separated him from Brecht's enlightened<br />

trust in ideology critique and pointed to a definite affinity between<br />

Benjamin and the Russian avantgarde. Just as Tretyakov, in his<br />

futurist poetic strategy, relied on shock to alter the psyche of the<br />

recipient of art, Benjamin, too, saw shock as a key to changing the<br />

mode of reception of art and to disrupting the dismal and catastrophic<br />

continuity of everyday life. In this respect, both Benjamin and Tretyakov<br />

differ from Brecht: the shock achieved by Brecht's Verfremdungseffekt<br />

does not carry its function in itself but remains instrumentally<br />

bound to a rational explanation of social relations which are to be<br />

revealed as mystified second nature. Tretyakov and Benjamin, however,<br />

saw shock as essential to disrupting the frozen patterns of sensory<br />

perception, not only those of rational discourse. They held that this<br />

disruption is a prerequisite for any revolutionary reorganization of<br />

everyday life. As a matter of fact, one of Benjamin's most interesting<br />

and yet undeveloped ideas concerns the possibility of a historical<br />

change in sensory perception, which he links to a change in reproduction<br />

techniques in art, a change in everyday life in the big cities, and the<br />

changing nature of commodity fetishism in 20th-century capitalism. It<br />

is highly significant that just as the Russian avantgarde aimed at creating<br />

a socialist mass culture, Benjamin developed his major concepts<br />

concerning sense perception (decay of aura, shock, distraction, experience,<br />

etc.) in essays on mass culture and media as well as in studies on<br />

Baudelaire and French surrealism. It is in Benjamin's work of the<br />

1930s that the hidden dialectic between avantgarde art and the Utopian<br />

hope for an emancipatory mass culture can be grasped alive for the last<br />

time. After World War II, at the latest, discussions about the avantgarde<br />

congealed into the reified two-track system of high vs. low, elite<br />

vs. popular, which itself is the historical expression of the avantgarde's<br />

failure and of continued bourgeois domination.<br />

The Hidden Dialectic 15<br />

VII<br />

Today, the obsolescence of avantgarde shock techniques, whether<br />

dadaist, constructivist, or surrealist, is evident enough. One need only<br />

think of the exploitation of shock in Hollywood productions such as<br />

Jaws or Close Encounters of the Third Kind in order to understand that<br />

shock can be exploited to reaffirm perception rather than change it.<br />

The same holds true for a Brechtian type of ideology critique. In an<br />

age saturated with information, including critical information, the<br />

Verfremdungseffekt has lost its demystifying power. Too much information,<br />

critical or not, becomes noise. Not only is the historical avantgarde<br />

a thing of the past, but it is also useless to try to revive it under any<br />

guise. Its artistic inventions and techniques have been absorbed and<br />

co-opted by Western mass mediated culture in all its manifestations<br />

from Hollywood film, television, advertising, industrial design, and<br />

architecture to the aesthetization of technology and commodity aesthetics.<br />

The legitimate place of a cultural avantgarde which once carried<br />

with it the Utopian hope for an emancipatory mass culture under<br />

socialism has been preempted by the rise of mass mediated culture and<br />

its supporting industries and institutions.<br />

Ironically, technology helped initiate the avantgarde artwork and its<br />

radical break with tradition, but then deprived the avantgarde of its<br />

necessary living space in everyday life. It was the culture industry, not<br />

the avantgarde, which succeeded in transforming everyday life in the<br />

20th century. And yet—the Utopian hopes of the historical avantgarde<br />

are preserved, even though in distorted form, in this system of secondary<br />

exploitation euphemistically called mass culture. To some, it<br />

may therefore seem preferable today to address the contradictions of<br />

technologized mass culture rather than pondering over the products<br />

and performances of the various neo-avantgardes, which, more often<br />

than not, derive their originality from social and aesthetic amnesia.<br />

Today the best hopes of the historical avantgarde may not be embodied<br />

in art works at all, but in decentered movements which work<br />

toward the transformation of everyday life. The point then would be to<br />

retain the avantgarde's attempt to address those human experiences<br />

which either have not yet been subsumed under capital, or which are<br />

stimulated but not fulfilled by it. Aesthetic experience in particular<br />

must have its place in this transformation of everyday life, since it is<br />

uniquely apt to organize fantasy, emotions, and sensuality against that<br />

repressive desublimation which is so characteristic of capitalist culture<br />

since the 1960s.


Bernd HÜPPAUF: Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden. Die Zeit,<br />

Avantgarden und die Gegenwart. In: Wolfgang Asholt, Walter Fähnders<br />

(Hg.): Der Blick vom Wolkenkratzer. Avantgarde, Avantgardekritik,<br />

Avantgardeforschung. Amsterdam: Rodopi 2000, S. 547-579.<br />

DAS UNZEITGEMASSE DER AVANTGARDEN<br />

Die Zeit, Avantgarden und die Gegenwart<br />

Bernd Hüppauf<br />

The present is a period of rapid change and continuous innovation<br />

through the electronic revolution, the creation of a cyberspace and the<br />

emergence of a virtual reality. Yet, there is no connection with the<br />

movements that, from the middle of the 19' century on, associated<br />

themselves with the new and the future, namely the avantgardes.<br />

Compared to the present, their language and concept of time seem<br />

anachronistic. It is the contention of this essay that the avantgarde<br />

movements were determined by a specific relationship to time. This<br />

relationship can be interpreted through Nietzsche's term of 'untimeliness'.<br />

However the avantgardes tended to isolate one dimension of the<br />

complexity of an untimely relationship to the present and remained<br />

modernist in a way that current changes in the relationship to time<br />

and space associated with the electronic revolution (or the post-modern)<br />

make them obsolete.<br />

Die Gegenwart ist eine Periode der schnellen und ununterbrochenen<br />

Innovation durch die elektronische Revolution, die Herstellung eines<br />

Cyberspace und das Entstehen einer Virtual reality. Es gibt jedoch<br />

keine Verbindung mit den Bewegungen, die sich selbst seit der Mitte<br />

des 19. Jahrhunderts mit dem Neuen und mit der Zukunft assoziierten,<br />

mit den Avantgarden. Im Vergleich mit der Gegenwart erscheinen ihre<br />

Sprache und ihr Zeitbegriff anachronistisch. Dieser Aufsatz stellt die<br />

These aufi daß die Avantgarde-Bewegungen durch ein spezifisches<br />

Verstandnis von Zeit bestimmt waren. Dies Verhältnis läßt sich mit


548 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

Nietzsches Begriff des 'Unzeitgemäßen' interpretieren. Die Avantgarden<br />

tendierten jedoch dazu, lediglich eine Seite der Komplexität des<br />

Unzeitgemäßen im Verhältnis zur Gegenwart herauszugreifen, und so<br />

blieben sie auf eine Weise modernistisch, daß die gegenwärtigen, mit<br />

der elektronischen Revolution (oder der Postmoderne) assoziierten<br />

Wandlungen im Verhältnis zu Raum und Zeit die Avantgarden obsolet<br />

machen.<br />

Die Avantgarden gehören in die Welt von gestern. Dem Namen<br />

haftet etwas erstaunlich Anachronistisches an. Die Avantgarden waren<br />

ein Produkt der Epoche des Fortschrittsdenkens, dessen Höhepunkt<br />

im 19. Jahrhundert lag und das seit der Erfahrung des Ersten<br />

Weltkriegs unwiderruflich verloren ist. Ihr Selbstverständnis war<br />

eng mit der Rhetorik von einer Entwicklung der Kunst und Literatur<br />

und ihrem Ende in einer sich beständig beschleunigenden Rationalisierung<br />

und Technisierung verknüpft. Ihre Programme und ästhetische<br />

Praxis lassen sich nicht als ein Symptom dieser umfassenden<br />

Entwicklung der Rationalisierung verstehen, sondern müssen als eines<br />

ihrer konstitutiven Element aufgefaßt werden. Wie die Rhetorik<br />

vom Ende der Literatur und Kunst bald ihre Herausforderung einbüßte<br />

und bloß historisch wurde, so erreichten auch die Avantgarden<br />

bemerkenswert rasch ein Ende. Allerdings ist keineswegs ausgemacht,<br />

ob nicht der avantgardistische Gedanke eines Abschlusses<br />

sich verwirklicht hat, Literatur und Kunst ihr Ende bereits hinter<br />

sich haben und in der Welt von Elektronik und Hypertext zur Bedeutungslosigkeit<br />

absinken, 1 ohne davon bisher Kenntnis genommen<br />

zu haben. Unabhängig von der Frage, ob die Literatur ihr Ende bereits<br />

hinter sich habe, ist jedoch das Ende der Avantgarden offensichtlich.<br />

Von einem Rückblick auf die Avantgarden zu sprechen,<br />

gibt der Distanz der Gegenwart zum Gedanken einer Avantgarde<br />

und des Avantgardistischen Ausdruck. Mit der im Wort „Rückblick"<br />

des Tagungstitels implizierten These, daß die Avantgarden historisch<br />

geworden sind, dürfte ein zentraler Aspekt im Verhältnis der<br />

Gegenwart zu den Avantgarden getroffen sein. 2 Die Zeit der Avantgarden<br />

liegt hinter uns, und sie leben auch nicht mehr als Teil der<br />

Erinnerung an die literarischen Bewegungen des Jahrhunderts, sondern<br />

sind in die Literaturgeschichte entrückt. 3 Das Denken in Vorstellungen<br />

einer Speerspitze oder Vorhut der literarischen und künst-<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 549<br />

lerischen Entwicklung ist anachronistisch geworden. Ich halte den<br />

Niedergang des Avantgardistischen für bemerkenswert und erstaunlich,<br />

insbesondere insoweit es sich, besonders prominent im<br />

Futurismus, in deutlicher Anlehnung an die technologisch definierte<br />

Moderne entworfen hatte. 4 Der Gedanke einer Verlängerung des<br />

Avantgardistischen in die Postmoderne scheint sich anzubieten.<br />

Aber von einer solchen Beziehung kann nicht die Rede sein. Die<br />

Welt des Cyberspace weiß nichts von der Technikbewunderung des<br />

Futurismus, und die neue Privilegierung von Raum gegenüber Zeit<br />

sowie die Wiederentdeckung von konkreter, primitiver Lokalität<br />

schließen nicht an den Surrealismus an.<br />

In der Gegenwart entsteht so viel Neues wie selten zuvor. Die<br />

Gegenwart ist auf eine Weise von Innovationen und vom Vertrauen<br />

auf das Neue geprägt wie wenige frühere Zeiten. Die Veränderungen<br />

durch elektronische Datenverarbeitung und Digitalisierung oder<br />

das Entstehen eines Cyberspace halte ich für Neuerungen einer Dimension<br />

und Auswirkung, die in der Geschichte wenig Vorbilder<br />

haben. Die Avantgarden betrieben einen Kult des Neuen, und ihre<br />

Obsession war der Vorgriff auf die Zukunft. Zukunft wird in der<br />

elektronischen Welt der Gegenwart so umfassend hergestellt wie in<br />

wenigen früheren Epochen. Dennoch wäre es ein Anachronismus,<br />

von Silicon Valley als einem Ort der Avantgarde und vom Zukunftsschub<br />

der Digitalisierung in Wörtern aus der Sprache der<br />

Avantgarden zu reden. 5 Den Pionieren des Cyberspace oder der<br />

Virtual reality selbst liegt es ganz fern, von sich als einer Avantgarde<br />

zu sprechen. Die abstrakte Bewunderung des Futurismus für moderne<br />

Technologie wird durch den elektronischen Hypertext, so<br />

ließe sich argumentieren, zur Wirklichkeit einer neuen Literatur<br />

transformiert.<br />

Die Frage nach dem Verhältnis der Avantgarden zur Postmoderne<br />

ist oft gestellt worden. Eine häufige Antwort ist, daß die<br />

Postmoderne das Erbe der Avantgarden angetreten habe, da bereits<br />

die Avantgarden Elemente der Populärkultur, der Unterhaltungsindustrie<br />

und der Volkskunst, Variete, Kabarett und andere Formen<br />

der kommerziellen Kleinkünste aufgenommen hätten (vgl. u.a. Fischer-Lichte/Schwind,<br />

1991 und Riese 1990). Folgt man den technologiefreudigen<br />

Theorien vom Cyberspace, hätte sich der Traum<br />

der Avantgarden von einer neuen und von den Fesseln der bürgerlichen<br />

Kultur befreiten, erneut das Ganze der menschlichen Existenz


550<br />

Bernd Hüppauf<br />

umfassenden Literatur verwirklicht. „Cyberspace ist eine Wohnstätte<br />

der Einbildungskraft, eine Wohnstätte für die Einbildungskraft...<br />

der Ort, an dem sich bewußtes Träumen mit unbewußtem<br />

Träumen trifft, eine Landschaft des rationalen Zaubers, der mystischen<br />

Vernunft, der Ort und Triumph der Dichtung über die Armseligkeit,<br />

des 'so kann es sein' über das 'so soll es sein.'" (Novak<br />

1991: 225-226) 6 Die optimistische Einschätzung einer Verbindung<br />

von Mystik und Rationalität im Traum der Zukunft stammt in diesen<br />

glaubensfesten Theorien der Technologie aus einem ungebrochenen<br />

Vertrauen auf den Fortschritt, das auf den Futurismus zurückverweist,<br />

aber nicht von allen Avantgarden geteilt und selbst im Futurismus<br />

weniger linear verstanden wurde. Solche optimistischen Einschätzungen<br />

sind nicht unwidersprochen geblieben. 7<br />

Die Unterschiede zwischen den Avantgarden und dem postmodernen<br />

Cyberspace sind vielfältig. Die Sprache der avantgardistischen<br />

Manifeste war emphatisch, da ihr propagiertes Ziel in weiter<br />

Ferne schwebte; die Gegenwart hat wichtige Fortschritte auf dem<br />

Weg zur Verwirklichung der technologischen Träume gemacht. Ihre<br />

Sprache ist nüchterner geworden. Aber nicht nur ist das Vokabular<br />

der Avantgarden verbraucht, sondern die mit ihm bezeich<strong>net</strong>en Dispositionen<br />

kommen in den Neuerungsbewegungen der Gegenwart<br />

nicht mehr vor. Ihre Technologien verändern die Lebenspraxis tiefgreifend<br />

und ununterbrochen, aber ohne Programm und Erneuerungspathos.<br />

Die Reste des Heroischen, der modernen Epen, die in<br />

den Avantgarden nachwirkten, haben sich nun auch zersetzt. Die<br />

Avantgarden blieben bei aller Provokation der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft<br />

und Opposition gegen ihre Literatur noch immer, wenn auch<br />

durch Negation, an den Kanon gebunden und bewegten sich, wenn<br />

auch durch Widerspruch, im Feld der Literaturgeschichte und des<br />

gedruckten Buches. Trotz ihrer Faszination durch das Primitive,<br />

Gewalt und das Fremde blieben sie eurozentriert, weiß und männlich.<br />

Nicht die Kunst der Primitiven oder Kenntnisse ihrer Gesellschaften<br />

beeinflußten die avantgardistischen Theorien und<br />

Kunstproduktion, sondern sie konstruierten sich die Gegenwelt eines<br />

Mythos des Primitiven (vgl. Rubin, 1984: 6f). Eine solche Faszination<br />

durch die Gegenwelt des Primitivismus gibt es nicht mehr. Der<br />

' schwarze Kontinent' ist zu einer Fortsetzung des Marktes für elektronisches<br />

Gerät geworden. Die Avantgarden bauten weiterhin auf<br />

ein rationales Zeitverständnis, das die Erkennbarkeit und Planbarkeit<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 551<br />

von Zukunft einschloß. Diese Bindungen der Avantgarden an die<br />

Tradition wirken in der Welt der Digitalisierung und des Cyberspace<br />

nicht mehr. Eine Theorie der Zukunft und des Neuen, die Adorno im<br />

Hinblick auf die Avantgarden emphatisch vertrat, 8 gibt es für diese<br />

Welt beständiger Innovationen nicht, und sie ließe sich kaum noch<br />

als ein Desiderat bezeichnen. Die Theorien der Postmoderne und der<br />

virual reality stellen nicht diesen Anspruch, und es ist fraglich, ob<br />

ein solches Bedürfnis nach theoretischem Begreifen überhaupt besteht.<br />

Es ist ebenso bemerkenswert, daß auch die Theorien der<br />

Avantgarden keine Angebote enthalten, das Neue der Gegenwart auf<br />

den Begriff zu bringen. Sie sind gegenüber der Eigendynamik der<br />

technologischen Neuerungen sprachlos. Ein Rückgriff auf sie läßt<br />

eher Hilflosigkeit als Ansätze des Verstehens aufkommen. Aber<br />

daraus entsteht kein Unbehagen.<br />

Eine Differenz liegt darin, daß der Cyberspace eine total abstrakte<br />

Verräumlichung aller Informationen der globalen Systeme<br />

zur Informationsverarbeitung anstrebt. Die uneingeschränkte Präsens<br />

aller Benutzer zu allen Zeiten und ihre vollständige Gleichstellung<br />

gegenüber den Informationen und den Systemen der Informationsverarbeitung<br />

macht die Simulation realer und virtueller Welten<br />

und die Interaktion mit allen Teilnehmern in der realen Welt zu jeder<br />

Zeit auf der Ebene einer vollständigen Gleichheit und Gleichzeitigkeit<br />

möglich. Der Preis ist die vollständige Entkörperlichung<br />

der Teilnehmer ihres Raums. Die Avantgarden hielten dagegen am<br />

Primat der Zeitlichkeit fest. Lediglich der surrealistische Kult des<br />

Unbewußten als einem zeitlosen Raum ließe sich als ein Vorgriff<br />

auf die Entzeitlichung durch Elektronik verstehen.<br />

Die von den Avantgarden aufrecht erhaltenen Grenzen, die<br />

Grenze zwischen Gegenwart und Zukunft, hoher und populärer<br />

Kunst, Anwesenheit und Abwesenheit lösen sich in der elektronischen<br />

Postmoderne auf. Unterscheidungen, die in den Avantgarden<br />

stets erkennbar blieben, 9 werden zur vollständigen Unkenntlichkeit<br />

zersetzt. Mit ihnen zerfällt das Zeitbild der Moderne. Die an Differenzierungen<br />

in der Zeit gebundenen qualitativen Unterscheidungen<br />

fallen in der technologischen Gegenwart der Gleichzeitigkeit und<br />

Abstraktion des Raums zum Opfer. Sie mußten erkennbar bleiben,<br />

solange eine Herausforderung des angesprochenen bürgerlichen Publikums<br />

intendiert war. Nur aus der Differenz ließ sich der Effekt<br />

der Verstörung und des Schocks eines bürgerlichen p ublikums, an


552 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

das sich die Avantgarden richteten, gewinnen. Die Dissonanz wurde<br />

für die Avantgarden bedeutend. Schoenberg stellte die „Emanzipation<br />

der Dissonanz" ins Zentrum seiner Ästhetik einer schockierenden<br />

musikalischen Avantgarde. Die Dissonanz wurde in der Wiener<br />

Schule nicht nur zu einem Kompositionsprinzip erhoben, sondern<br />

wirkte ebenso in der musikalischen Praxis, indem sie hergebrachte<br />

Harmonien im Leben der Konzertbesucher zersetzte, Differenzen<br />

schuf und Widerstand herausforderte. Die Postmoderne kennt die<br />

Dissonanz nicht. Sie geht von einem grundsätzlich veränderten<br />

Kunstverständnis aus, in dem Widersprüche zurückgezogen und<br />

Gegensätze geglättet werden. Innovation und Destruktion werden<br />

zunehmend entkoppelt. Die hohe Kunst ist nicht mehr neu, schließt<br />

sich nicht ab und destruiert nicht mehr das Vorhandene, um Platz zu<br />

gewinnen und aus den Trümmern das neue Eigene zu schaffen.<br />

Auch ist die Unterhaltungskunst nicht länger die popularisierte hohe<br />

Kunst von gestern. Die Unterhaltungskunst ist nicht mehr als ein<br />

Zitat in einem ihr fremden Kontext hoher Kunst erkennbar, sondern<br />

ist ununterscheidbar von der E-Kunst. Der Ausgang in den imaginierten<br />

Raum der elektronischen Gegenwart läßt die Unterschiede<br />

zwischen technischer Erfindung, künstlerischer Kreativität und gesellschaftlicher<br />

Lebenspraxis verschwinden. Der Cyberspace der<br />

Postmoderne zielt darauf, Grenzen in Gegenden der Verbindung zu<br />

verwandeln und die konventionellen Bewertungen irrelevant zu machen.<br />

An ihm nimmt ein anders konstituiertes Publikum Teil. Das<br />

Selbstverständnis der Avantgarden ist ihr fremd und geradezu entgegengesetzt.<br />

Die Postmoderne versteht sich als die Überwindung<br />

der Moderne, und mit der Moderne überwindet sie auch deren Zeit<br />

und die Zeit der Avantgarden. Es ist eine eigene Frage, ob sie sich<br />

der Politik der Ausgrenzungen und Hierarchisierung, der sich die<br />

Avantgarden ausgeliefert fanden, entziehen kann. Es ist jedoch offensichtlich,<br />

daß ihr Verhältnis zur Zeitlichkeit sich nicht als eine<br />

Fortsetzung der Praktiken der Avantgarden verstehen läßt.<br />

Warum das Denken in den Vorstellungen des Avantgardistischen<br />

in der Gegenwart anachronistisch wirkt, ist nicht leicht zu verstehen.<br />

Ich will mich im folgenden auf einen Aspekt konzentrieren,<br />

der in der Behandlung der Avantgarden wenig Beachtung gefunden<br />

hat und leicht übersehen wird, weil er offensichtlich zu sein scheint,<br />

nämlich das Verhältnis der Avantgarden zur Zeit. Meine erste These<br />

lautet, daß die Avantgarden von einem Verhältnis zur Zeit ausge-<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 553<br />

zeich<strong>net</strong> waren, das sie restlos relational machte. Sie waren, im Unterschied<br />

zu Epochen, Bewegungen, die sich an den homogenen<br />

Zeitstrom der Moderne anpaßten. Sie inszenierten den modernen<br />

Kult des Neuen, das von einem stets Neueren abgelöst wird, um Zukunft<br />

herzustellen. In einem linearen Zeitverständnis läßt sich keine<br />

absolute Position bestimmen, von der aus zu definieren wäre, was<br />

die Zukunft ist. Die Zukunft des Jetzt ist in jedem Augenblick stets<br />

schon Vergangenheit.<br />

Was eine Avantgarde, die sich als die Vorhut ihrer Zeit versteht,<br />

sein könnte, geht im Fluß der Zeit verloren. Sie kann keine Grenzen<br />

ziehen, die ihr eine Identität geben könnten. Nicht einmal die oft<br />

emphatisch betonte Abgrenzung zur Vergangenheit ist von dem beständig<br />

sich bewegenden Grund der Avantgarde zu denken, Avantgarden<br />

sind ihrer Zeit immer schon voraus. Obwohl sie sich in dieser<br />

Hinsicht gern einer Illusion hingaben, existierten sie jedoch nicht<br />

in einem geschichtlichen Niemandsland, und so ist die Frage nicht,<br />

ob eine Avantgarde sich auf eine Vergangenheit bezog, sondern auf<br />

welche Vergangenheit sie sich bezog. Und die Antwort auf diese<br />

Frage veränderte sich mit dem Bild, das eine Avantgarde von der<br />

Zukunft entwarf. Das Verhältnis der Avantgarden zu Vergangenheit<br />

und Zukunft machte sie zu einem weiteren instabilen Moment in der<br />

Zeitstruktur der Moderne, die alle festen, substantiellen Beziehungen<br />

auflöst.<br />

In der Bezeichnung 'Avantgarde' selbst kommt zum Ausdruck,<br />

daß ihr Denken über Literatur, Kunst und Lebenswelt eine räumliche<br />

Beziehung verzeitlicht. Das Wort stammt aus der Militärsprache<br />

und bezeich<strong>net</strong> die kleine Vorhut, die vor dem Heer auf das<br />

Schlachtfeld zieht und einen Raum erkundet und klärt, der vor dem<br />

Heer selbst liegt. 10 Die Avantgardebewegungen in Kunst und Literatur<br />

projizierten diese räumliche Beziehung zwischen sich und einer<br />

Mehrheit in die Zeitlichkeit eines Denkens in Begriffen von<br />

Entwicklung und Fortschritt, das sie in ein Oppositionsverhältnis zur<br />

Gegenwart brachte. In ihrem Selbstverständnis sind die Avantgarden<br />

wohl ohne Ausnahme durch Formen der Opposition zu ihrer Gegenwart<br />

ausgezeich<strong>net</strong>. Breton spricht einmal vom Prinzip der totalen<br />

Auflehnung (insubordination). 11 Dies Eigenbild gilt für alle<br />

Avantgarden, auch für den Futurismus, obwohl sich Mari<strong>net</strong>ti zu einer<br />

Verherrlichung der Gegenwart als dem Zeitalter der Industrie<br />

und Geschwindigkeit bekannte. Aber dies Zeitalter war, in seiner


554 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

Einschätzung und der anderer Futuristen, in Italien noch nicht angebrochen.<br />

Für die Futuristen galt daher ebenso wie für alle nennenswerten<br />

Avantgarden, daß sie sich aus dem Denken von Widerstand,<br />

aus einer Opposition zur Gegenwart verstanden. Die literarischen<br />

Avantgarden erkundeten und klärten einen imaginären Raum. Diesen<br />

Raum nahmen sie in einer Richtung, nämlich vorn wahr und interpretierten<br />

ihn als eine Zeit nach dem bevorstehenden Ende der eigenen<br />

Gegenwart, als Zukunft. Die Verzeitlichung im Eigenbild ist<br />

ein signifikantes Element für das Verständnis der Avantgarden, das<br />

über die bloße wörtliche Bedeutung des ihnen zugeschriebenen Namens<br />

hinausgeht und das Zentrum der meisten Avantgarden trifft.<br />

Sie trugen zur Verzeitlichung und damit zur Abstraktion des Denkens,<br />

das die Moderne seit der frühen Neuzeit auszeich<strong>net</strong>, bei und<br />

nahmen darüber hinaus an der Beschleunigung der ästhetischen Prozesse,<br />

die das 20. Jahrhundert vor allen früheren Epochen auszeich<strong>net</strong>,<br />

aktiven Anteil.<br />

Ihr Zeitbild erschöpfte sich jedoch nicht in den Abstraktionen<br />

der rationalisierten Zeit der Moderne. Es war in sich widersprüchlich,<br />

und ihre Programme lassen sich auch als Widerstand gegen<br />

diese grenzenlose Auflösung lesen. Sie hielten an einem inhaltlich<br />

konkretisierten Zukunftsbild fest. Dies Bild war nicht einheitlich. Es<br />

konnte ebenso apokalyptische wie paradiesische Züge tragen. Die<br />

Beziehungen der Avantgarden zu christlich heilsgeschichtlichen<br />

oder apokalyptischen wie zu jüdisch eschatologischen Geschichtskonstruktionen<br />

sind verschlungen. Aber an der Wirksamkeit dieser<br />

Beziehungen für das Zeitdenken der Avantgarden kann kein Zweifel<br />

bestehen. Gerade in ihrem Versuch, das Denken und Schreiben zu<br />

modernisieren, ohne sich jedoch der Rationalisierung auszuliefern,<br />

läßt sich eine Ursache dafür sehen, daß sie schließlich aus derzeit<br />

herausfielen und in der Postmoderne in Bedeutungslosigkeit versinken.<br />

Wie alle Programmatik zum alsbaldigen Veralten neigt, sind<br />

auch die Avantgarden, die stets programmatische Bewegungen waren,<br />

wie Asholt und Fahnders kürzlich wieder zu Recht betonten<br />

(Asholt/Fähnders 1995), vom Veralten noch nachhaltiger betroffen<br />

als andere avancierte Positionen in der Dynamik des Entwicklungsdenkens<br />

der Moderne. Im Gegensatz zu dieser Anpassung blieben<br />

sie jedoch - und dies bildete den Boden ihrer Opposition - der Zeit<br />

dgs Gestern auf eine emphatische Weise verpflichtet. Die Opposition<br />

zum modernen Ideal des Universalismus hat zu einer Rehabili-<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 555<br />

tierung von Ort und Region geführt, und aus einem anhaltenden Widerstand<br />

gegen die Abstraktion des verzeitlichten Raums in der Tradition<br />

Newtons und Kants folgt eine Wiederentdeckung des Konkreten.<br />

In der damit entstehenden mentalen Topographie büßt das<br />

Avantgardistische seine Faszination ein. Auch an die dazu in einem<br />

krassen Gegensatz stehende Abstraktion des Raums im Cyberspace<br />

kann die Avantgarde nicht anknüpfen, da sie einem anderen Bild<br />

von Technik und technischem Fortschritt verpflichtet blieb.<br />

Ich will die Avantgarden im folgenden beim Wort nehmen und<br />

sie aus ihrem Verhältnis zur Zeit verstehen. Ein ambivalentes Verhältnis<br />

zur eigenen Gegenwart und zur Zeit verknüpft die vielen literarischen,<br />

künstlerischen und lebenskünstlerischen Avantgarden bei<br />

allen weitreichenden Unterschieden zu einem Zusammenhang. Dem<br />

empirisch begründeten Plural der Avantgarden kann aus ihrem Verhältnis<br />

zur Zeitlichkeit ein Begriff des Avantgardistischen entgegengestellt<br />

werden. Auf der Metaebene läßt sich vom Verhältnis der<br />

Avantgarden zur Zeit sprechen, ohne daß dies Verhältnis sich in ein<br />

Bündel von Einzelbeobachtungen auflöst. Ein theoretisch begründeter<br />

Begriff der Avantgarde und des Avantgardistischen bildet die<br />

notwendige Voraussetzung für ein Verständnis der Avantgarden, das<br />

sich über die Ebene der Deskription erheben soll. Die Welt, in der<br />

wir lebten, meinte Breton über die Jahre 1924/25 bis 1931, war den<br />

Surrealisten vollkommen fremd, und sie wiesen ihre Prinzipien<br />

kompromißlos zurück. „Wir fühlten, daß eine veraltete Welt auf<br />

dem Weg in den Untergang sich nur noch halten konnte, indem sie<br />

Taboos durchsetzte und Verbote vermehrte, und wir wollten ihr auf<br />

eine radikale Weise entkommen... wir waren von einem Bedürfnis<br />

nach einer allgemeinen Subversion erfaßt." 12 Die Surrealisten waren<br />

in dieser Hinsicht repräsentativ. Sie standen in einer gespannten Beziehung<br />

zu ihrer Gegenwart, und stellten sich der Gegenwart, die sie<br />

als Zwang und Beengung, als inauthentisch empfanden, im Namen<br />

einer zu gewinnenden Zukunft entgegen. Sie intendierten, die Tyrannis<br />

der Gegenwart zu brechen, indem sie die eigene Zeit zielbestimmt<br />

zu beschleunigen suchten. Aber dies Verhältnis zur Zeitlichkeit<br />

verhinderte gerade, daß sie sich von der Dominanz der Rationalisierung<br />

lösten. Ihre Konstruktion von Zeit blieb dem Zeitverständnis<br />

der Moderne so tiefgreifend verbunden, daß ihre Opposition aus<br />

der heutigen Distanz als eine Variation des Bekämpften erscheint


556 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

und sie aus dem Abstand unserer heutigen Perspektive selbst zum<br />

Gestern werden.<br />

Die Avantgarden bezogen aus einem spezifischen Verhältnis<br />

zur Zeit ihre Dynamik und Dramatik, und aus ihm konstituiert sich<br />

eine Einheit der Avantgarden. Unsere eigene Gegenwart ist durch<br />

ein verändertes Verhältnis zur Zeit charakterisiert, und so verlor das<br />

avantgardistische Denken seinen Bezugsrahmen. Zeit büßt zunehmend<br />

an Bedeutung ein. Die Verzeitlichung, die seit der frühen<br />

Neuzeit das Sein und das Denken auf eine in der Geschichte einmalige<br />

Weise durchdrungen hat, verliert ihre Kraft und ihren universalen<br />

Anspruch. Gegen die Rationalisierung der Verzeitlichung regte<br />

sich seit dem 19. Jahrhundert ein oft anti-moderner Widerstand, dessen<br />

literarische und philosophische Dimension im Anti-Newtonismus<br />

und Anti-Kantianismus zu finden ist. 13 Das Abseitige und Eskapistische<br />

des Anti-Modernismus, das noch bis in die Schriften von<br />

Ludwig Klages wirkt, streifte dieser Widerstand bald ab. Die Wiederentdeckung<br />

des Konkreten, des Partikularen und der ortsgebundenen<br />

Raumerfahrung befreite sich von der bloß romantischen Verehrung<br />

des Alten. Zunehmend war die Gegenwart von der Wiederkehr<br />

des Räumlichen geprägt. In diese Entwicklung kann man den<br />

Begriff der Postmoderne einbeziehen, wenn auch ihre Position in<br />

dieser Entwicklung zwiespältig ist. Dem Wiedergewinnen eines<br />

konkreten und ortsgebundenen Raums steht die totale Abstraktion<br />

von Raum in Cyberspace und Virtual reality gegenüber.<br />

Die Opposition der Avantgarden gegen die eigene Gegenwart<br />

büßte ihre Dramatik und Herausforderung ein, sobald die Herrschaft<br />

des modernen Zeitbegriffs gebrochen schien. Der mangelnden Authentizität<br />

sowie der Abstrahierung und Rationalisierung des Lebens<br />

den Kampf anzusagen und sich als die Speerspitze der Zukunft in<br />

der eigenen Gegenwart zu definieren, erfüllt gegenwärtig weder die<br />

Funktion des Schockierens, noch ist die Programmatik, mit der sich<br />

alle Avantgarden aus der eigenen Gegenwart auf meist aggressive<br />

Weise verabschiedeten, eine Herausforderung der Gegenwart durch<br />

das Neue. Die Wirkung solcher Opposition verflüchtigte sich in dem<br />

Maß, wie sich diese Programme doch wiederum in ihre Zeit einschrieben.<br />

Die Gegenwart ist gegenüber aggressiver Programmatik<br />

indifferent geworden. Zukunftsprogrammatik dient ihr allenfalls als<br />

ein Mittel der Werbeindustrie für die Zukunftsbranchen der Elektronik<br />

oder der Gentechnologie. Das Verhältnis zur Zeit, das die Ge-<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 557<br />

genwart bestimmt, ist distanzierter und weniger erwartungsgeladen<br />

als das in der hinter uns liegenden Phase der Moderne. Die Tyrannei<br />

der Verzeitlichung scheint in der Gegenwart ihre Macht zu verlieren.<br />

Sie ist daher nicht länger durch die gespannte und aggressive,<br />

oft verkrampfte Distanz bestimmt, die im Zentrum aller Avantgarden<br />

wirkte. Wir lesen heute die aufgeregte Sprache vieler avantgardistischer<br />

Programme ohne großes Verständnis und mit Verwunderung<br />

über den emotionalen Aufwand in der Distanzierung von der<br />

Gegenwart.<br />

Die von Peter Bürger eingeführte Assoziation der Avantgarden<br />

mit Melancholie ist unter diesem Gesichtspunkt fragwürdig. „Der<br />

barocken Abwertung der Welt zugunsten des Jenseits steht in der<br />

Avantgarde eine geradezu enthusiastische Weltbejahung gegenüber,"<br />

meint Bürger ganz zu Recht im Hinblick auf eine Dimension<br />

der Avantgarden. Er sieht diese Zuwendung zur Welt modern gebrochen<br />

und melancholisch (Bürger 1974: 97). Aber nicht durch<br />

Melancholie, nicht durch einen unüberwindbaren Schmerz über einen<br />

Verlust zeich<strong>net</strong>en sich die Avantgarden aus. Vielmehr begannen<br />

sie programmatisch das Experiment, die Zukunft einer anderen<br />

Wirklichkeit zu schaffen, ohne doch von der Zeit der eigenen Gegenwart<br />

endgültigen Abschied nehmen zu wollen. Sie vermieden<br />

den radikalen Gedanken vom Tod der geschichtlichen Zeit und damit<br />

die Melancholie des Allegorikers, von der Bürger im Anschluß<br />

an Benjamins Thesen über den Barock sprach. Ihre Praktiken führten<br />

nicht in den Verlust, über den sich der Melancholiker nicht hinwegtrösten<br />

kann. Sie wollten die Gegenwart abschaffen, weil sie<br />

leer war, und hielten doch gleichzeitig an der Zeit der Moderne fest,<br />

die diese Leere schuf; und sie wollten aus der Zeit herausspringen,<br />

machten aber gleichzeitig den Versuch, an einem Ideal der Zukunft<br />

festzuhalten. Dies zeitliche Kontinuum schloß die Abwertung, nicht<br />

die Abschaffung der Wirklichkeit der Moderne ein.<br />

Mit der Melancholie wird auch die Rede vom Scheitern der<br />

Avantgarde-Projekte fragwürdig. Was könnte es bedeuten, von einem<br />

Scheitern von literarisch-kulturellen Programmen in der Lebenspraxis<br />

zu sprechen? Welche Programme wären je erfolgreich gewesen<br />

und politisch verwirklicht worden? Es gehört in die Natur der<br />

literarisch-kulturellen Programme, Ideale zu postulieren, ohne sich<br />

um deren gesellschaftlich konkrete Verwirklichung zu besorgen.<br />

Das 'Prinzip Hoffnung', von dem Bloch so nachdrücklich philoso-


558<br />

Bernd Hüppauf<br />

phierte und dessen Glaube an die Zukunft einigen Avantgarden nahesteht,<br />

ist nicht so zu verstehen, daß sich diese Hoffnung in einer<br />

nahen oder fernen Zukunft in die Realität von Lebenspraxis umsetzen<br />

und damit sich selbst abschaffen würde. Auch konventionelle<br />

Teleologie stellt nicht die Forderung nach solchem Finalismus, und<br />

die eschatologische Dimension in Blochs Denken steht den Avantgarden<br />

fern. Die avantgardistische Forderung nach einer Veränderung<br />

der Lebenspraxis durch Kunst ist nicht so zu verstehen, daß die<br />

avantgardistischen Manifeste als politische Programme zu lesen wären.<br />

Sobald sie auf diese Weise gelesen werden, werden sie banal<br />

oder lächerlich. Ihre Forderungen sind eine literarische Konvention,<br />

ein Topos, den die Avantgarden wiederholten, indem sie ihn in die<br />

Semantik der Moderne übertrugen, ihn gleichzeitig als Zukunftsvision<br />

gegen die eigene Gegenwart kehrend. Die Erwartung einer politischen<br />

Realisierung literarischer Programme als gelebte Wirklichkeit<br />

beruht auf einer unzulässigen Vermischung eines imaginären<br />

Raums mit einem politisch definierten Raum. Das Verhältnis ästhetischer<br />

Programme zur gelebten Wirklichkeit muß komplexer vorgestellt<br />

werden als es eine monokausale Linie vom Text ins Leben zuläßt.<br />

Eine Erziehung der Sinne, einschließlich des Zeit- und Raumsinnes<br />

läßt sich nicht in Programme politischer Parteien umsetzen,<br />

auch wenn einige der avantgardistischen Programmschriften selbst<br />

solchen Illusionen Ausdruck gaben. 14 Anstatt vom Scheitern der<br />

avantgardistischen Zukunftsprojekte zu reden, scheint es mir aufschlußreicher<br />

zu sein, ihre Beziehungen zu den sich verändernden<br />

Raum- und Zeitverhältnissen zu bedenken und das Verhältnis avantgardistischer<br />

Theorien und Praktiken zur Zeit und konkreten Gegenwart<br />

zu beschreiben.<br />

Ein Unterschied zwischen verschiedenen Avantgarden ist oft in<br />

der Frage gesehen worden, wie sie das Verhältnis zwischen Literatur<br />

und Geschichte verstehen. Je enger politisch dies Verhältnis gedacht<br />

wird, desto näher liegt der Gedanke eines Scheiterns. Anders gewendet:<br />

kann eine Avantgarde, die sich aus dem Programm einer<br />

Erneuerung der Lebenspraxis entwirft, also eine politische Zukunftsprojektion<br />

verfolgt, das Ziel eines radikalen Bruchs mit der<br />

Praxis der Gegenwart überhaupt praktizieren, ohne sich selbst aufzugeben?<br />

Der Futurismus kann als ein Beispiel dienen. Er inszenierte<br />

sich noch extremer als der Surrealismus als eine umfassende<br />

Opposition und spottete gegen jede Bedeutung: vernichtet zu wer-<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 559<br />

den verdienten die Metaphysik, der Klerikalismus, der Intellektualismus,<br />

das Feminine, die Bourgeoisie, die Subjektivität. Dieser Widerstand<br />

gegen alles Existierende war identisch mit einem Programm<br />

zur Abschaffung der Geschichte. Geschichte kann nicht<br />

mehr gedacht werden, sobald alle ihre Agenten verbannt sind. Das<br />

avantgardistische Denken des Futurismus war innovativ in dem<br />

Maß, wie es die Moderne von allen Inhalten zu reinigen suchte und<br />

damit in sich widerspruchsfrei wurde. Erhalten blieb dann ein formalisierter<br />

Fortschrittsgedanke, und Zeit reduzierte sich auf eine bedeutungslose<br />

Chronologie. Die Zukunft wird beschworen, aber<br />

schrumpft zu einem bedeutungslosen Wort. Wie wäre die Zeit zu<br />

denken, in der die verachtete Gegenwart ans Ende gekommen wäre<br />

und eine neue Existenz entstehen könnte? Aus dem Jetzt wäre in ein<br />

Dann nur durch einen unvermittelten Sprung zu gelangen, etwa wie<br />

sich Kierkegaard den Sprung in den Glauben dachte. Dem Futurismus<br />

fehlt aber jede inhaltliche Bestimmung einer theologischen<br />

Welt. Er kann daher nur einen Sprung in die Leere denken. Mehr: er<br />

muß die Paradoxe des Denkens als Paradoxe der Lebenspraxis denken.<br />

Kontinuität und Brüche, Beschleunigung und Zeitlosigkeit<br />

müssen simultan sein, soll an diesem - ungeschichtlich entworfenen<br />

- Fortschrittsglauben festgehalten werden. Sobald das avantgardistische<br />

Programm fordert, Humanismus durch Krieg und verstaubte<br />

Bibliotheken durch Stahl, Glas oder Giftgas zu ersetzen, verschreibt<br />

es sich einer Totalität des Augenblicks. Damit endet das Denken in<br />

Affirmation, der beständigen Bewegung im Cyberspace nicht unähnlich.<br />

Fortschritt als entleerte Bewegung ist identisch mit Stillstand.<br />

Wenn die Dynamik der Technologie zum antibürgerlichen<br />

Moment der Geschichte avanciert, wird der Fortschritt zur Bewegung<br />

auf der Stelle. Die resignative Einsicht der Postmoderne unterscheidet<br />

sich von den Theorien der Avantgarden durch die vollständige<br />

Abwesenheit von Erwartungen. Sie kennt keine Hoffnung auf<br />

eine bessere Zukunft mehr und will den Gedanken von Zukunft gar<br />

nicht mehr denken. Sie will die Apotheose des Jetzt. Die Avantgarden<br />

dagegen entwickelten ein Programm zum Vorstoß in die Zukunft.<br />

Aber ihr Verhältnis zur Zeit blieb auf eine Weise der entleerten<br />

Zeit der Moderne verhaftet, daß dieser Vorstoß bloß abstrakt<br />

blieb. Nicht eine Überwindung technischer Zivilisation der Gegenwart,<br />

sondern einen Kult des ins Technische transformierten Lebens<br />

forderte der Futurismus, und andere avantgardistische Bewegungen


560 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

folgten einem vergleichbaren Muster. Die Anpassung der Avantgarden<br />

führte zum Bedeutungsverlust der unzeitgemäßen Ideale einer<br />

humanen Gesellschaft, von der Peter Bürger ausgeht, und gleichzeitig<br />

zum Sieg des Avantgardistischen, das als Vorhut der Bewegung<br />

vorauseilte und, angeschmiegt, zu ihr gehörte, am Triumph des<br />

Technologischen partizipierend. Scheitern setzt die Alternative des<br />

Gelingens voraus, und die gab es in einem praktisch-politischen<br />

Sinn für die Programme der Avantgarden nicht.<br />

Der Beginn der Avantgarden, wird oft argumentiert, läßt sich<br />

auf Jahr und Tag genau festlegen: die Veröffentlichung von Mari<strong>net</strong>tis<br />

Futuristischem Manifest. Die Bedeutung dieses Ereignisses<br />

wird nicht reduziert, wenn man darauf hinweist, daß Innovationen<br />

nie abrupt und aus einem Nichts entstehen. Die Diskontinuität in der<br />

Literatur- und Geistesgeschichte dieser Jahre war radikal und schokkierend,<br />

da sie radikale Diskontinuitäten auf einen sehr kurzen Zeitraum<br />

kondensierte. Dennoch erweckt die künstliche Isolation, die in<br />

vielen Literaturgeschichten die Avantgarden aus der Geschichte der<br />

Literatur und Kunst herausreißt, ein verzerrtes Bild. Ich denke, daß<br />

ein besonderes Verhältnis zur Zeit, das sich seit dem 19. Jahrhundert<br />

ausgebildet hatte, einen Rahmen abgab, innerhalb dessen sich der<br />

Bruch der Avantgarden, der sich auf bemerkenswerte Weise mit einer<br />

Kontinuität verknüpfte, als Element einer problematisch werdenden<br />

Temporalstruktur der Moderne verstehen läßt, ohne sie von<br />

den literarischen, künstlerischen und philosophischen Kontexten zu<br />

isolieren. Zwar scheinen mir Verweise auf die Frühsozialisten, Fourier<br />

und die politische Welt der Julirevolution ein unpassendes politisches<br />

Assoziationsfeld anzusprechen. Aber die größere geschichtliche<br />

Tiefe, die in dieser Zurückverlegung der Anfänge der Avantgarden<br />

wirkt, wird dem avantgardistischen Denken eher gerecht als<br />

die Identifikation mit der Technikverherrlichung, die mit dem Futuristischen<br />

Manifest in der Literatur unvermittelt einzusetzen<br />

schien. 15<br />

Ich will nun meine Ausgangsthese erweitern und hinzufügen,<br />

daß der Relativismus der Avantgarden in widersprüchlicher Weise<br />

mit einem teleologischen Zeitverständnis verschränkt blieb. Im<br />

Zentrum der Avantgarden stand ein Verhältnis zur Zeit und eigenen<br />

Gegenwart, das mit dem Adjektiv unzeitgemäß zu charakterisieren<br />

ist. Soweit ich sehe, benutzte als erster Nietzsche diese Bezeichnung<br />

in seinen Unzeitgemäßen Betrachtungen, und er benutzte nicht nur<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 561<br />

das Wort, sondern entwickelte auch eine Philosophie des Unzeitgemäßen,<br />

die sich in radikale Opposition zur Zeit stellt, aber nicht auf<br />

das Denken der Revolution zurückgreift. In offensiver Distanzierung<br />

zum hegelschen Geschichtsmodell und zur marxistischen Revolutionstheorie<br />

greift das Denken des Unzeitgemäßen auf ältere Quellen<br />

zurück und versteht die Theorien des bürgerlichen 19. Jahrhunderts \<br />

über Zeit und Gegenwart als eine Verirrung.<br />

Das Problem des Zeitgemäßen oder Unzeitgemäßen ist eminent<br />

modern. Das Bewußtsein einer unlösbaren Spannung zur Zeit und<br />

der Gefahren und Möglichkeiten des Unzeitgemäßen entwickeln<br />

Literatur und Philosophie erst, wenn ihr Verhältnis zur Gegenwart<br />

auf eine grundlegende Weise gestört ist. Gesteigerte Bewußtheit,<br />

Zweifel und kalkulierte Inszenierungen von Schreiben gehen damit<br />

einher. Es verweist, wie Nietzsches dramatische Genealogie dieser<br />

Störung im Verhältnis zur Zeit herausarbeitet, auf einen elementaren<br />

Bruch. Das Anti-Natürliche der Kunst der Moderne, das Nietzsche<br />

auf Euripides und Sokrates zurückverfolgte (Nietzsche 1980), hat<br />

seinen Ursprung in der Störung einer Einheit, in die das Bewußtsein<br />

einbricht, „...im Anfang war alles beisammen: da kam der Verstand<br />

und schuf Ordnung" zitiert Nietzsche in seiner sarkastischen Abrechnung<br />

mit den Verderbern des Lebens und der Kunst durch das<br />

Denken, Sokrates und Euripides, den ersten Satz des Anaxagoras<br />

(Nietzsche 1980: 87), der bekanntlich die Philosophie aus Kleinasien<br />

nach Athen brachte. Etwas tritt dazwischen, die Einheit ist gestört,<br />

Trennung entsteht und verlangt nach Ordnung, und sie wiederum<br />

benötigt den Verstand, der Dinge scheidet und damit, so<br />

meinte Anaxagoras, eine Unlust in die Welt bringt. Mit der Trennung<br />

entstand das Bewußtsein, argumentiert Nietzsche, und mit ihm<br />

ein Unbehagen, bewußte Erkenntnis, die stets mit Schmerz verbunden<br />

sei. Der Traum und das Nicht-Rationale werden nun zum bloß<br />

„Unverständigen" der Dichtung degradiert, in der sich das ursprüngliche<br />

Beieinander von allem erhalten konnte, aber nun abgewertet<br />

als bloßer Rausch, als ein Irrationales, als der von Sokrates<br />

und Euripides und auch vom „göttlichen Plato" als Lüge verschrieene<br />

Traum. So entstand, argumentiert Nietzsche, das Denken,<br />

das in die von ihm verachtete Gegenwart führte, und dessen Grundsätze<br />

seien, „alles muss bewusst sein, um schön zu sein" sowie „alles<br />

muss bewusst sein, um gut zu sein." Mit der Trennung des Alls<br />

durch den Nous endete die Welt, in der „noch alles in einem chaoti-


562 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

sehen Urbrei beisammen" war, und die Ordnung entstand (Nietzsche<br />

1980: 87). Ordnung macht ein Eingreifen notwendig und ist eine<br />

Störung der Welt durch den Verstand. Mit der Öffnung im Chaos<br />

kamen das Bewußtsein, die Rationalität und die Unlust in die Welt.<br />

Die neue Ordnung der Welt bedeutete eine Verarmung und führte<br />

zur Herrschaft des Bewußtseins, das die Welt aufteilt, die Einbildungskraft<br />

verdrängt und die Poesie abwertet. Das Unzeitgemäße<br />

läßt sich als eine spezifische Reaktion in der Moderne auf dies anhaltend<br />

gestörte Verhältnis zum Leben verstehen. Es stellt sich dem<br />

Problem eines Verlusts von authentischem Leben, indem es die Zeit<br />

zu verkehren sucht. Die Avantgarden waren unzeitgemäß, indem sie<br />

den Versuch einer Umkehr erneuerten. Sie paßten. sich ihrer Zeit<br />

/ nicht an, um aus dem Abstand das seit Euripides verkehrte Verhältnis<br />

zur Imagination grundlegend zu verändern.<br />

Als „unzeitgemäß" bezeich<strong>net</strong>e Nietzsche vier heterogene Essays,<br />

die er zwischen 1873 und 1876 verfaßte und zu einer Publikation<br />

zusammenstellte. Aber warum sollte es eigens hervorzuheben<br />

sein, daß Essays über Schopenhauer oder über den „Nutzen und<br />

Nachteil der Historie" sich durch das Moment des Zeitgemäßen oder<br />

Unzeitgemäßen auszeichnen? Nietzsche geht von einer neuen Erwartung<br />

gegenüber einem philosophisch-literarischen Lext aus. Indem<br />

er im Titel die Frage der Zeitgemäßheit erhebt, weist er ihr eine<br />

besondere Bedeutung zu, und mit seiner Antwort geht er auf ironisch-sarkastische<br />

Distanz zur eigenen Zeit. Er bezeich<strong>net</strong> seine Betrachtungen<br />

als unzeitgemäß, weil er vom Gegenteil überzeugt ist.<br />

In dem Attribut spricht sich die Erwartung aus, daß eben in dem<br />

Maß, wie diese Essays sich ihrer Zeit nicht anpassen, sondern aus<br />

ihr planvoll herausfallen, sie von Ihrer Zeit sprechen. Sie stellen<br />

Fragen, die niemand zu stellen wagte, die geradezu peinlich vermieden<br />

wurden, weil die „öffentliche Meinung," wie Nietzsche schreibt,<br />

sie „zu verbieten" schien (Nietzsche 1980: 159). In diesem Sinn bezieht<br />

sich „unzeitgemäß" auf die eine Form der in diesem Wort liegenden<br />

Negation: das Unangepaßte des nicht-Zeitgemäßen ist eine<br />

Zurückweisung der Gegenwart. Das Schreiben verweigert sich der<br />

Zeit, verstanden als Präsens, indem es ablehnt zu passen, sich anzupassen,<br />

sich dem Maß der Zeit zu fügen. Eine andere Bedeutung ist<br />

jedoch gleichzeitig auch anwesend. Sie folgt aus dem Wort „Unzeit",<br />

das auch in diesem Adjektiv steckt. Die Zeit selbst ist in dieser<br />

Lesung als ungemessen und falsch definiert. Eine Unzeit ist - wie<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden<br />

563<br />

ein Ungetüm, Unheil, Unmensch und viele andere Wortprägungen<br />

mit 'un' - mit sich selbst zerfallen und ihr eigener Gegensatz. Der<br />

Zeit, insoweit sie ohne Maß und mit sich selbst uneins ist, sind die<br />

ihr gewidmeten Betrachtungen dann gerade 'angemessen'. Auch<br />

diese Lesung des Adjektivs geht von einem ironischen oder sarkastischen<br />

Verhältnis zur Zeit als einer Zeit der Nicht-Identität aus. Essays,<br />

die ihre Gegenwart als 'Unzeit' beurteilen, um sich programmatisch<br />

als ihr 'gemäß' zu bezeichnen, müssen durch einen tiefen<br />

Bruch von ihrer Zeit getrennt sein. Dem Handeln, Sprechen oder<br />

Schweigen zur Unzeit liegt, wie zahlreiche literarische Beispiele von<br />

Parzival zu Oskar Mazerath zeigen, eine fundamentale Störung zugrunde,<br />

für die ursprünglich allein das Subjekt verantwortlich war.<br />

In einer Umkehrung dieses Topos wird bei Nietzsche - die Anfänge<br />

dieser Entwicklung lassen sich allerdings bis in die Gegenaufklärung<br />

des späten 18. Jahrhunderts zurückverfolgen - die Zeit selbst<br />

zur Störung, zu einer Unzeit. In Nietzsches Hauptthema der frühen<br />

Jahre, Dekadenz, Kritik am Rationalitätsideal der Moderne und eine<br />

Rehabilitation von (apollinischem) Traum und dem (dionysischen)<br />

Irrationalen, liegen wesentliche Übereinstimmungen mit dem avantgardistischen<br />

Denken.<br />

Die Betrachtungen gehören, versichert der Titel in jeder der<br />

beiden Lesarten, nicht der Zeit. Aber, so muß man fragen, wem und<br />

wohin gehörten sie dann? Wo findet sich der Leser, dem sie gehören,<br />

wenn nicht in der Gegenwart? Und gehören sie in die Vergangenheit<br />

oder in die Zukunft oder in einen zeitlosen Raum? Wie wäre<br />

der zu denken und woher stammt die Autorität, mit der die Diagnosen<br />

des Zeitgemäßen oder Unzeitgemäßen gestellt werden, wenn die<br />

eigene Zeit kein Bewußtsein davon hat, was ihr gemäß ist und nottut?<br />

Doch muß die Zeit wohl, in Nietzsches Einschätzung, ein Organ<br />

haben, um die Botschaft, die sie sich selbst verbietet, dennoch aufnehmen<br />

zu können. Dies Spannungsverhältnis zur eigenen Zeit, in<br />

dem der Autor eben das als ihr wahrhaft gemäß bezeich<strong>net</strong> und ausspricht,<br />

wogegen sie sich wehrt und was sie aus sich ausschließen<br />

will, läßt sich als ein Grundelement nicht nur in Nietzsches Selbstverständnis,<br />

sondern im Verhältnis von Philosophie und Literatur<br />

der Moderne zur Zeit verstehen und findet seine letzte Steigerung im<br />

avantgardistischen Denken. Dessen programmatische Unzeitgemäßheit<br />

gilt in vier verschiedenen Weisen; es betrifft die Zeit, die in<br />

ihm zu einem der großen Probleme gemacht wird, den Zeitraum der


5 64 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

eigenen Präsenz, mit dem es sich nicht als synchron empfinden will,<br />

die Zukunft, auf die hin es sich entwirft, blindlings und, durch die<br />

futuristische Zukunftsemphase bloß notdürftig verhüllt, mit gesteigertem<br />

Unbehagen, und schließlich die Welt, deren Ungemessenheit<br />

den avantgardistischen Denkern und Experimentierern kein Zuhause<br />

bietet. Nur insoweit sie sich außerhalb der Zeit stellen und eine andere<br />

Zeit gewinnen, schaffen sie die Chance, den „Wahn", in dem<br />

die Zeit nach Nietzsche verfangen ist, aufzudecken und ihm zu entfliehen.<br />

Nur_soweit Literatur ihrer Zeit und der Zeit nicht gehört,<br />

kann sie sich erhoffen, zu ihrer Zeit zu sprechen und etwas zu sagen<br />

zu haben. Das ist die Botschaft der Avantgarden, die sich aus ihrer<br />

Unzeitgemäßheit ableitet. Diese Botschaft wird in der Postmoderne<br />

nicht mehr vernommen. Das ambivalente Unzeitgemäße ist aus der<br />

Welt der Elektronik und der Hypertexte verschwunden.<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße entwickelt sein Widerspruchsverhältnis gegenüber<br />

der eigenen Zeit, indem es eine Distanz zum Ideal erhebt,<br />

aber gewinnt doch nur in dem Maß Bedeutung, wie es zugleich die<br />

Zeit als eine Unzeit trifft. Nietzsche stellt dies doppeldeutige Verhältnis<br />

wiederum in einen zeitlichen Horizont. Zukunft habe nur<br />

eine Kultur, die die Kraft aufbringe, sich unbequemen Wahrheiten<br />

zu stellen und den Wahn der Gegenwart als Wahn zu erkennen bereit<br />

ist, und die Rechtfertigung des Unzeitgemäßen verlegt er in ein<br />

Denken, das sich an der Dimension der Zukunft orientiert. Die Zukunft<br />

erfordere das Unzeitgemäße, gerade gegenüber einer Zeit, die<br />

auf sich selbst „stolz" ist und ihre technologischen Errungenschaften<br />

als eine profane Religion verehrt, so daß es besonders schwer ist,<br />

nicht mit ihr zu gehen (Nietzsche 1980: 246). 16 Sie ist, meint Nietzsche,<br />

in der Illusion ihrer Überlegenheit befangen, da sie ihre Rationalität<br />

mißversteht und den aus der Herrschaft des Bewußtseins<br />

folgenden Kult des Neuen nicht als eine tödliche Bedrohung des Lebens<br />

erkennt.<br />

Nietzsche beschreibt seine Position seiner eigenen Zeit gegenüber<br />

durch eine komplizierte Temporalstruktur, in der die Erinnerung<br />

an eine lange zurückliegende Zeit den Blick auf die Gegenwart<br />

schaffe, der diese von sich selbst entfernt. Nur insofern er der „Zögling<br />

älterer Zeiten, zumal der griechischen," sei, sieht er sich in die<br />

Lage versetzt, „als Kind dieser jetzigen Zeit zu so unzeitgemäßen<br />

Erfahrungen" (Nietzsche 1980: 247) zu kommen. 17 Er sieht den<br />

„Sinn" der klassischen Philologie in seiner eigenen Zeit darin, „un-<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 565<br />

zeitgemäß - das heißt gegen die Zeit und dadurch auf die Zeit und<br />

hoffentlich zu Gunsten einer kommenden Zeit - zu wirken."<br />

(Nietzsche 1980: 247) Aus einem Kontrast zur Herde, die nicht<br />

weiß, „was Gestern, was Heute ist...und... kurz angebunden mit ihrer<br />

Lust und Unlust, nämlich an den Pflock des Augenblicks," (Nietzsche<br />

1980: 248) lebt, definiert er die Fähigkeit, die Vergangenheit<br />

als ein Gedächtnis mit sich zu tragen. Den Menschen gibt es nicht<br />

ohne Bewußtsein und Erinnerung, doch zugleich sind sie eine Last,<br />

und so stemmt er sich „gegen die große und immer größere Last des<br />

Vergangenen." (Nietzsche 1980: 249) Die Erinnerung an Vergangenes<br />

ist wie ein „Wunder", denn die Gegenwart ist ein Nichts, „der<br />

Augenblick, im Husch da, im Husch vorüber, vorher ein Nichts,<br />

nachher ein Nichts, kommt doch noch als ein Gespenst wieder und<br />

stört die Ruhe eines späteren Augenblicks." (Nietzsche 1980: 248)<br />

Dagegen stemmt sich der Mensch vergeblich und tut es doch immer<br />

wieder. Ist das Gedächtnis eine Voraussetzung für Unzeitgemäßheit,<br />

so entsteht sie doch erst aus dem Gegensatz, dem Vergessen.<br />

Gedächtnis schwächt das Verhältnis zum Leben. Der unzeitgemäße<br />

Widerstand gegen die Zeit erfordert die aktive Leistung, Erinnerung<br />

zu vernichten. Erst wenn die Fähigkeit, zu vergessen, gegen die<br />

Forderungen der historistischen Epoche wiedergewonnen wird, läßt<br />

sich die moderne Zeit destruieren und aus dieser Destruktion die<br />

Umkehr gewinnen. Nur aus diesem gewollten Abstand wird das<br />

Unzeitgemäße nicht erlitten, sondern läßt es sich in zukunftsgerichtete<br />

Tat verwandeln.<br />

Dieses verschobene Verhältnis der kritischen Subjektivität zum<br />

Sein in der Moderne und ihrer Literatur und Philosophie zur Zeitgemäßheit<br />

ist nicht als eine dialektische Spannung zu verstehen,<br />

vielmehr ist es eine Aporie, aus der keine Synthesis herausführt und<br />

aus der es keinen Weg ins Freie oder nach oben gibt. Es ist eine Erfahrung<br />

von „quälenden Empfindungen", die, so schreibt Nietzsche<br />

bereits in dieser frühen Phase, das Ich auf sich selbst zurückwirft.<br />

Dies Ich, das sich mit einer „Naturbeschreibung" seiner Empfindungen<br />

hervorwagt, isoliert sich und erscheint in Relation zur „mächtigen<br />

historischen Zeitrichtung" als „unwürdig" (Nietzsche 1980:<br />

246). Es ist diese Position des Solipsismus (vgl. Jünger 1963: 392),<br />

die den einsamen und verachteten Diagnostiker der Zeit aus seiner<br />

Zeit herausdrängt und nach unpassenden Ausdrucksmitteln suchen<br />

läßt, die er doch als die einzig passenden empfindet. Zum „schwa-


566 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

chen" Ich der Moderne (Nietzsche 1980: 324) gehört die Flucht in<br />

ein Draußen, aus der Zeit ins Unzeitgemäße und Unangemessene.<br />

Es findet sich dort in einer paradoxen Lage, in der gerade seine<br />

Schwäche und Isolation in eine Position von Stärke, Aggression und<br />

Zurückweisung der Zeit überführt wird. Denn im herrischen Zurückweisen<br />

der Zeit durch das gewollt Unzeitgemäße ermächtigt<br />

sich das Ich. In dieser paradoxen Lage wird das Unpassende und<br />

Unzeitgemäße zum einzig Passenden und Zeitgemäßen. Um sich der<br />

Zeit stellen zu können, überführt das schwache Ich etwa den philosophischen<br />

Diskurs durch Ironie und Zynismus in innere Widersprüchlichkeit<br />

oder verweigert sich, Nietzsches eigenes Werk liefert<br />

das Beispiel, den Erwartungen der Zeit auf Bestätigung und Versicherung,<br />

entzieht im Unangemessenen der Produktion die Übereinstimmung<br />

mit ihrer Rationalität und ihrem Bewußtsein. Durch<br />

Krieg, Traum, Gewalt, das Vorbewußte, Irrationale, Primitive versuchten<br />

die Avantgarden, das Arsenal dieser Techniken der Verweigerung<br />

ins Unerhörte zu steigern.<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße widersetzt sich dem „Götzendienst des Tatsächlichen"<br />

und empört sich gegen die „Tyrannei des Wirklichen",<br />

wie Nietzsche in einer Polemik der Unzeitgemäßen Betrachtungen<br />

gegen Hegels Lehre von der „Bewunderung vor der 'Macht der Geschichte'"<br />

schreibt. Führe Hegels Dialektik nicht nur zu einer Abstrahierung<br />

vom Wirklichen, sondern letztlich zur „Bewunderung<br />

des Erfolgs" und zum „'Ja' zu jeder Macht, sei dies nun eine Regierung<br />

oder eine öffentliche Meinung oder eine Zahlen-Majorität"<br />

(Nietzsche 1980: 309f), so schätzt das Unzeitgemäße den Erfolg gering,<br />

entfernt sich aus der Gegenwart und macht sie fremd. Aber<br />

sein Verhältnis zur Wirklichkeit erschöpft sich nicht in einem bloßen<br />

'Nein'. Vielmehr ist die Distanz zur Gegenwart die Voraussetzung<br />

dafür, die Wirklichkeit anzuerkennen, nämlich sie als die gelebte<br />

und nicht zur Geschichte abstrahierte Wirklichkeit überhaupt<br />

wahrzunehmen. Das Unzeitgemäße hält am Anspruch fest, auf die<br />

Zeit zu wirken. Ihm wird alles zur Gegenwart. Es fordert, die Zeit<br />

des geschichtlichen Denkens zu verlernen und auch das Vergangene<br />

als Gegenwart zu verstehen, da es zum Entstehen der Welt im Kopf<br />

nicht weniger beiträgt als das zeitlich Präsente. Das ist auch eine<br />

Form des Vergessens. Das Unzeitgemäße denkt die eigene Gegenwart<br />

aus einer zeitlichen Tiefe, die das Historische übersteigt, um<br />

aus dieser Position jenseits der eigenen Zeit die Unabhängigkeit zu<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 557<br />

gewinnen, die notwendig ist, um die Zwänge der unverstandenen<br />

Bindungen zu sehen und sich aus ihnen zu lösen. Für das Unzeitgemäße<br />

ist die Zeit der Geschichte das eigentliche Problem.<br />

Wenig Jahre nach Nietzsche stellte Sigmund Freud ganz unzeitgemäße,<br />

nämlich unheldische Betrachtungen über Krieg, Zivilisation<br />

und Tod an und bezeich<strong>net</strong> sie ausdrücklich als Zeitgemäßes<br />

über Krieg und Tod (1915). Zur selben Zeit schreibt Thomas Mann<br />

sehr Zeitgemäßes über den Krieg. In den verdrehten Betrachtungen<br />

eines Unpolitischen (1918), die er als „Gedankendienst mit der<br />

Waffe" bezeich<strong>net</strong>e, zu dem „nicht Staat und Wehrmacht..., sondern<br />

die Zeit selbst" ihn eingezogen hatte (Mann 1974, Bd. XII: 9; Bd.<br />

XI: 108-144), setzte er das Denken des Unzeitgemäßen in die Literatur-<br />

und Kulturtheorie des beginnenden 20. Jahrhundert fort. Er<br />

bezeich<strong>net</strong>e seinen langen Essay in Anlehnung an Nietzsches Titel<br />

als Betrachtungen eines Unpolitischen. Auch Nietzsches Betrachtungen<br />

waren ja durch einen Krieg, den deutsch-französischen Krieg<br />

von 1870/71 ausgelöst worden.<br />

Ernst Bloch hat später dem Unzeitgemäßen einen anderen Namen<br />

gegeben. Er sprach von „Ungleichzeitigkeit". In Erbschaft dieser<br />

Zeit entwickelt er diese Vorstellung eines Lebens aus dem Widerspruch<br />

zur 'eigenen' Zeit damals noch sehr kritisch. Er sah in der<br />

Zeit des Triumphs der Nationalsozialisten die bedrohliche, die geschichtszerstörende<br />

Seite der Widersprüche, die sich, gemessen an<br />

Marx's Modell der simultanen geschichtlichen Entwicklung auf ein<br />

Ziel hin, als ungleichzeitig denunzieren ließen, reaktionär, gegenrevolutionär,<br />

anti-humanistisch. Seine Einschätzung des Ungleichzeitigen<br />

änderte sich später, nahm die Unterschiede im Widerstand<br />

gegen die Zeit wahr und entdeckte das Offene, Umstürzende,<br />

Selbstbestimmte in ihm. Bloch kam nie von der Faszination des<br />

Temporalen los, und zumindest in dieser Hinsicht gehört sein Denken<br />

in die Avantgarden. Was ihn später zum Gedanken des Unzeitgemäßen<br />

hinzog, benannte er zunächst als das Utopische.<br />

„Mit etwas gehen, das kann sehr wohl feige sein. Ist dann dasselbe,<br />

wie wenn einer den Mantel nach dem Wind hängt." (Bloch<br />

1963: 121-124) Diesen Mitläufern, die stets mit der Zeit mitmachen,<br />

gilt seine Verachtung. Er entdeckt im Mitläufertum die Interessen,<br />

die kurzfristigen und standpunktlosen Verbiegungen des Ichs. Denn<br />

„dasjenige, was im Schwange ist, findet seine Mitläufer nicht so<br />

sehr, weil es modisch als weil es vorteilhaft ist." Von der Zeit und


568 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

ihren Moden abweichen, sich gegen die Zeit stellen, kann zwei Ursprünge<br />

haben: die Schwäche der Zurückgebliebenen und dann findet<br />

er darin die Haltung des „ganz gängigen, ... Typen, ... die nur<br />

verhinderte smarte sind..." Das ist die Haltung des Ressentiments,<br />

der Spießer, die sich jeder Ideologie, die Anerkennung verspricht, in<br />

die Arme werfen, und sich gegen die Zeit zu stellen, von der sie sich<br />

benachteiligt glauben. Aber dann spricht er von den anderen Ungleichzeitigen,<br />

„weit weg vom Strom der Zeit, in abgelegener Gegend;<br />

so bereits viele Kleinstädter." „Vor allem aber gibt es Berufsgruppen<br />

(Fischer und unter den Bauern nicht nur die Waldbauern),<br />

deren Sein und Arbeitsweise noch durchaus Züge aus früheren Zeiten<br />

trägt. Neue Arbeitsmittel, Zeitung Radio und so fort haben hier<br />

gewiß gewirkt und abgeschliffen, gleichzeitig machend. Dennoch<br />

leben noch Typen aus verschiedenen Jahrhunderten unter uns, trotz<br />

des wachsenden Abschliffs." Eine Idealisierung des Alten, Ursprünglichen<br />

auf dem Land ist nicht zu überhören. Eine Nähe zu<br />

Heideggers Romatisierung der angeblichen Bauernschuhe auf van<br />

Goghs Bild liegt nahe. Aber es geht Bloch um etwas anderes. Nicht<br />

mit allen Schwingungen der Zeit mitzumachen, macht die Beziehung<br />

zu einer anderen Zeit notwendig. „Vielmehr lebt hier ein Widerstand<br />

gegen ein herrschend Schlechtes in der Zeit wie auch echte<br />

Zustimmung zu übergehend Bedeutendem in ihr. Und beides wächst<br />

dann auf dem gleichen Holz: auf dem Baum des Morgens im Heute.<br />

Demgemäß und um die Geburt des Morgen zu befördern, ist sein<br />

Denken zwar mitten in der Zeit, doch so, daß es sie weisen kann und<br />

überholt."<br />

Blochs Denken ist mit dem Denken in utopischen Zukunftsbildern<br />

so durchsetzt, daß der ganz und gar anti-temporale Boden dieses<br />

Gedankens ihm entgeht. Er kämpft den Kampf Friedrich Engels<br />

gegen die utopischen Sozialisten und rettet das Unzeitgemäße der<br />

Utopisten, indem er ihre Utopien verzeitlicht. Vom Gedanken der<br />

Entwicklung auf das Ziel in der Zukunft kommt er nicht los. Selbst<br />

die Fischer und Bauern sieht er zu dieser Entwicklung beitragen,<br />

obwohl doch der Gegensatz zu den „herrschend Gleichzeitigen", die<br />

er die „Männer up to date" nennt, sie ganz offensichtlich zu den Unzeitgemäßen<br />

macht, von denen Nietzsche sprach. Sie haben ihren<br />

Ort, und den bewahren sie vor der Zeit, die von Kapitalisten wie von<br />

Utopisten gleichermaßen gemacht wurde.<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 569<br />

Ich will nun als weitere These formulieren, daß das „Unzeitgemäße"<br />

und die zugehörige ästhetische Disposition das Verhältnis der<br />

Avantgarden zur Zeit auszeich<strong>net</strong>e. Der Kampf der Avantgarden<br />

war unzeitgemäß und galt der Zeit der Moderne, deren Wert vom<br />

zeitgemäßen Denken zu einer profanen Religion erhoben wurde. 18<br />

Ein Wert für die Vorbereitung auf das „Leben", das neue Stichwort<br />

der Unzeitgemäßen, wurde der historischen Zeit der Moderne seit<br />

dem späten 19. Jahrhundert immer mehr bestritten. Je moderner das<br />

Denken, desto nachdrücklicher entwertete es den Gedanken der Erinnerung.<br />

'Los vom Historismus' war die Maxime der akademischen<br />

Diskussion. In den Avantgarden gewann dieser Kampf als Entwertung<br />

der rational geord<strong>net</strong>en Zeit eine sprachbildende Kraft. Sie<br />

suchten sich zwischen-Naturwissenschaften (Neurologie, Astrophysik,<br />

Paläontologie) und traditionellen Formen des Literarischen neu<br />

zu schaffen. 19 Die Unzeitgemäßen kombinierten eine Kampfansage<br />

an die Gegenwart mit der Forderung nach einer Konstruktion von<br />

Zukunft aus der wiederzugewinnenden Imagination. Es gab für sie<br />

keine Wirklichkeit. „Es gibt das menschliche Bewußtsein," schreibt<br />

Benn, „das unaufhörlich aus seinem Schöpfungsbesitz Welten bildet,<br />

umbildet, erarbeitet, erleidet, geistig prägt." (Benn 1984: 344)<br />

Der Wunsch der Avantgardisten, die Zeit der Moderne zu destruieren,<br />

um Kunst und Leben zu versöhnen, hat hier seine philosophische<br />

Grundlage.<br />

Intellektuelle verstanden sich seit dem 18.Jahrhundert in betonter<br />

Weise als der Zeit im Sinn eines übersehbaren Zeitraums ebenso<br />

wie als Teil eines geschichtlichen Verlaufs zugehörig. Die kritische<br />

Funktion von Intellektuellen, Schriftstellern und Philosophen in der<br />

Tradition von Voltaire oder Zola basierte auf der Teilhabe an der eigenen<br />

Gegenwart. Diese Anteilnahme wurde im 19. Jahrhundert<br />

fragwürdig, und die Zugehörigkeit verlor ihre Selbstverständlichkeit.<br />

Sie wurde zunehmend als ein Problem empfunden. Die Eigenund<br />

Fremddefmition bezog das Verhältnis zur Zeit als ein neues<br />

Problem ein. Die Zugehörigkeit zur eigenen Gegenwart wurde nicht<br />

länger als ein fragloses Verhältnis erfahren. Dies Verhältnis war nie<br />

spannungsfrei oder kritiklos gewesen. Aber nun wurde diese Spannung<br />

selbst zum Thema und die Distanz als nicht überbrückbar empfunden.<br />

Aus diesem Zerfall entstand die Angst, aus der eigenen Zeit<br />

herauszufallen, ebenso wie ein Bedürfnis, nicht zu dieser Zeit zu gehören,<br />

sich ihr zu entziehen oder sich ihr gegenüberzustellen und der


570<br />

Bernd Hüppauf<br />

Zeit als dem elementaren Konstitutionselement der Moderne den<br />

Kampf anzusagen. Das Unzeitgemäße, als Angst wie als Begehren,<br />

setzt einen intellektuellen Bruch und eine emotionale Ambivalenz<br />

voraus, die unter den spezifischen Bedingungen der Moderne im<br />

Lauf des 19. Jahrhunderts entstanden. Das Unbehagen in der Kultur<br />

war nicht so zeitlos, wie es Freud erschien. Es war der Grund für<br />

Widerstand gegen die Zeit und benannte eine Mentalität, die - sobald<br />

sie nicht einen subjektiven und bloß partikularen Eskapismus<br />

meint - für die Konstruktion der Avantgarden konstitutiv war. Die<br />

Avantgarden entstanden aus diesem Unbehagen und waren unzeitgemäß,<br />

jedoch auf eine selektive Weise. Sie wichen Nietzsches radikaler<br />

These vom Ursprung der Gegenwart in der Herrschaft des<br />

Kalküls aus und blieben, bei aller exponierten Unzeitgemäßheit,<br />

dennoch an das rationalistische Zeitmodell der Moderne gebunden,<br />

das sie radikalisierten, so daß sie den Rahmen der zurückgewiesenen<br />

Gegenwart nicht verließen, sondern im Opponieren doch exponierter<br />

Teil der zurückgewiesenen Zeit blieben.<br />

Das avantgardistische Kunstwerk verweigert die Sinnerfahrung<br />

des konventionellen Werks. Diese Verweigerung schließt eine Interpretation<br />

der Gegenwart als einem die Biographie mit der kollektiven<br />

Zeit vermittelnden Zusammenhang aus. Fragmentierung zersetzt<br />

das avantgardistische Werk ebenso wie die Verbindung zwischen<br />

dem Ich und seiner Gegenwart. Das avantgardistische Werk ist in<br />

sich widersprüchlich und bleibt sich undurchsichtig. Es widersetzt<br />

sich der Anpassung an die Zeit, der es entstammt und die dennoch<br />

nicht zu seiner eigenen Zeit wird. Es stellt für die Rezeption die<br />

Aufgabe, einen Zusammenhang zwischen sich und der Zeit zu erfinden.<br />

In dieser nie abzuschließenden Aufgabe, einen Zusammenhang<br />

zu konstituieren, liegt neben der provozierenden Abwendung von<br />

der Gegenwart die Spekulation auf eine Reaktion der Aufmerksamkeit<br />

der zurückgewiesenen Gegenwart. In der unterschwelligen Erwartung<br />

ließe sich eine Ursache dafür vermuten, daß die Avantgarden,<br />

aus der zeitlichen Distanz betrachtet, ihrer Zeit stärker verhaftet<br />

blieben als ihr Eigenbild zuläßt.<br />

Mir scheint, daß die Avantgarden in anderer Weise als Epochen<br />

des Widerstands, etwa das Junge Deutschland oder der Naturalismus,<br />

Anlaß zu Fragen nach der Synchronizität geben, eben den Fragen,<br />

die das Unzeitgemäße aufwirft. Das Problem von Nähe oder<br />

Ferne zwischen dem literarischen Werk und der Zeit, zwischen indi-<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 571<br />

vidueller Zeit und kollektiver Zeit ergeben sich aus den von den<br />

Avantgarden bevorzugten Gattungen, Themen und ästhetischen<br />

Praktiken, die auf einem Anti-Werk-Verständnis von Kunst aufbauen,<br />

Narrativität unterlaufen und Zeit fragmentieren. Einer Ästhetik<br />

der Distanzierung durch eine betont nicht-mimetische und konstruierende<br />

Sprache korrespondiert eine Provokation der Gegenwart<br />

Die bevorzugten literarischen Formen wie Gedicht, Kurzprosa, Experimentaltheater<br />

oder Varietesketch schaffen durch ihre spezifische<br />

Poetik nicht so sehr Konjunktionen mit der Zeit als eine Distanz.<br />

Sprechen Nietzsche und die Autoren des Unzeitgemäßen von<br />

der Isolation des Ichs gegenüber der eigenen Zeit, der gegenüber<br />

ihre Einstellung als „unwürdig" erscheine, so trifft auf die Avantgarden<br />

diese Charakterisierung ebenso zu. Sie sind unwürdig und<br />

verachtet und sind es mit Bedacht. Dada und der Surrealismus verstießen<br />

gegen das Rationalitätsgebot und rehabilitierten den Traum<br />

und das Irrationale. Der Futurismus stellte die Systeme der Repräsentation<br />

und der Wahrnehmung in Frage und löste Zeitthemen wie<br />

Krieg und Gewalt, Subjektivität und die Zukunft aus ihrer Zeitbezogenheit,<br />

und stellte sie in schockierende literarische oder anthropologische<br />

Bezüge. Alltag wurde durch Metaphorik in 'unzeitgemäße'<br />

und 'unpassende' ferne Imaginationsräume entrückt. Unter den Bedingungen<br />

der überwältigend 'großen' Gegenwart überführte das<br />

schwache Ich mit den Mitteln der Imagination seine Schwäche in<br />

die Stärke der Zurückweisung, indem es die eigene Zeit vergaß oder<br />

ihr eine andere Zeit gegenübersetzte. Das machte die Avantgarden<br />

unwürdig, jedenfalls für einige Zeit, bis schließlich ihr Widerstand<br />

eingeord<strong>net</strong> war und selbst ihre radikalen Widersprüche konsumierbar<br />

wurden. Dann gewannen sie Würde, die ihnen vom Markt verliehen<br />

wird. Was am Schreiben zeitgemäß ist und was unzeitgemäß<br />

im Sinn Nietzsches, also die Zeit gegen sich selbst aber im Namen<br />

der Zukunft anspricht, verschränkte sich auf komplexe Weise in den<br />

Avantgarden.<br />

In Deutschland war die Avantgarde schwach entwickelt. Das<br />

„Expressionistische Jahrzehnt" kann nicht als Avantgarde verstanden<br />

werden. Dada war die einzige avantgardistische Bewegung, und<br />

teilte das Schicksal der Avantgarden, einen Sprung aus der Gegenwart<br />

zu wollen aber sich in die Zeitlichkeit der Moderne zu verstrikken.<br />

An den Rändern der europäischen Avantgarden schrieben einzelne<br />

Autoren, die von Futurismus oder Surrealismus beeinflußt wa-


572 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

ren und aus der Opposition zur Zeit an dem von Nietzsche erneuerten<br />

Schreiben einer Umkehr teilnahmen. Das Unzeitgemäße erwies<br />

sich als eine Position, die der als Unzeit verstandenen der Moderne<br />

am ehesten gewachsen zu sein schien, die Illusionen der politischen<br />

Revolution vermeidend. In diesem Feld des radikal Unzeitgemäßen<br />

bewegten sich die Werke des frühen Döblin, Brecht, Benn und Musil.<br />

Sie hatten für die Ambivalenzen des Unzeitgemäßen ein offenes<br />

Gespür und vermieden die Einseitigkeiten der Avantgarde und die<br />

Euphorien des Revolutionären. Den Widerstand gegen ihre Zeit und<br />

gegen die Tyrannei der Zeitlichkeit der modernen Existenz mit den<br />

Avantgarden teilend, gelang es ihnen eher, sich davor zu bewahren,<br />

in den Sog des Fortschrittsdenkens gezogen zu werden und letztlich<br />

doch selbst zum Opfer der Zeit der Moderne zu werden. Der frühe<br />

Döblin lieferte Beispiele für die innere Widersprüchlichkeit, in die<br />

diese Position jenseits des Revolutionären aber mit radikalem Anspruch,<br />

außerhalb der Avantgarde aber mit avantgardistischem Engagement<br />

führen konnte. Zwischen Berge, Meere und Giganten und<br />

Das Ich über der Natur kann es keine Vermittlung geben. Dennoch<br />

war diese unscharfe Position des Unzeitgemäßen nicht so leicht von<br />

der Zeit einzuholen wie die der Avantgarden und erhielt sich vor<br />

dem Fall ins Anachronistische.<br />

Gottfried Benns frühe experimentelle Prosa und Lyrik liefern<br />

ein machtvolles Beispiel für die unzeitgemäße Opposition zur Zeit.<br />

Sie nehmen eine „Kälte des Denkens, Nüchternheit, letzte Schärfe<br />

des Begriffs,... vor allem aber die tiefe Skepsis, die Stil schafft,"<br />

(Benn 1984: 362) für sich in Anspruch. Seine frühe Lyrik ist aus<br />

dem Bewußtsein eines Ichs geschrieben, für das „die Welt in jedem<br />

einzelnen Augenblick fertig ist und ihr Ende erreicht." Benns Begriff<br />

„Stil" bezeich<strong>net</strong> das zentrale Moment in der Position, die das<br />

Unzeitgemäße im Verhältnis zur Moderne einnimmt. Die Dadaisten<br />

und später die Surrealisten gebrauchten ein anderes Vokabular, das<br />

jedoch Benns Rede von „Stil" und „Form" weitgehend entspricht.<br />

Aus Benns Bemerkungen über mangelnde Popularität und Anerkennung<br />

spricht nicht unbedingt die Enttäuschung, sondern ebenso<br />

eine Genugtuung: er ist stolz darauf, für niemanden in seiner Gegenwart<br />

zu schreiben, aber er hat gleichzeitig keinen Zweifel daran,<br />

daß er gegenüber den vielen, die ihn nicht wahrnehmen wollen, 'im<br />

Recht' ist, daß sein Werk in diese Zeit nicht gehört, aber daß seine<br />

Zeit kommen wird. Ein beinahe prophetischer Ton des einsamen<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 573<br />

Sprechers in der Wüste liegt über mancher seiner Aussagen über<br />

seine von der Gegenwart ungeliebte Dichtung, die sich keinen Kompromissen<br />

unterwirft, sondern einem avantgardistischen Ideal der<br />

Zukunft verschreibt. Es hätte ihn mißtrauisch gemacht, wäre er gelesen,<br />

verstanden, geliebt worden. Er wollte Opposition gegen die Gegenwart,<br />

gegen den Erfolg, der stets durch Anpassung und Aufgabe<br />

des Eigenen und des Eigensinns erkauft werde. Es sind Töne der<br />

Aggression und eines Triumphes, mit denen er einmal feststellt, Literatur<br />

sei eine Sache von fünfzig Lesern, und von denen seien die<br />

meisten psychisch gestört. Er bittet keineswegs um Verständnis oder<br />

Vergebung für solche Störungen und Abweichungen, die er an sich<br />

selbst beobachtet, für das Schizoide an sich und in seinem Werk.<br />

Ganz im Gegenteil: Er verachtet die Normalität. Um der Produktivität<br />

und Genialität willen, die sich in diesen Störungen und Abweichungen<br />

ausspricht, besteht nach seiner Anschauung die menschliche<br />

Gesellschaft. Sie rechtfertigen, ganz im Gegensatz zu den Idealen<br />

der egalitären und demokratischen Gegenwart, jedes Opfer. Die<br />

Wunde, die das Bewußtsein der Natur schlägt, läßt sich nicht schließen.<br />

Der Verstand, der das Leben bedroht, kann in dieser Sicht nur<br />

durch die Produktion einer imaginierten Welt, durch Literatur und<br />

Kunst gerechtfertigt werden. Aber diese Schöpfung einer Welt aus<br />

Kunst und Literatur ist nur aus der Distanz zur Zeit, in Opposition<br />

zur Selbstgenügsamkeit und Selbstgerechtigkeit der eigenen Gegenwart<br />

zu gewinnen. Erfolg zu haben, ist daher in Benns Augen<br />

notwendig kompromittierend. Das Unzeitgemäße erfordert eine Immunisierung<br />

gegenüber dem unverständigen Wunsch nach Anerkennung<br />

und Erfolg in der Gegenwart.<br />

Aus diesem gebrochenen Verhältnis zum Erfolg und zur Anerkennung<br />

spricht nicht nur eine persönliche Vorliebe, es ist keine<br />

Bennsche Idiosynkrasie. Vielmehr ist diese Opposition gegen die<br />

Zeit und die Suche nach einer Position des 'Außen', jenseits ihrer<br />

Bindungen und Gratifikationen die Folge eines tiefen Mißtrauens<br />

gegen das Allgemeine. Dies Mißtrauen kann ebenso wie das vieler<br />

Avantgarden als Grundlage von Benns Ästhetik verstanden werden.<br />

Die objektivistischen und universalisierenden Tendenzen einer Gegenwart,<br />

die noch immer im Bann der rationalistischen Aufklärung<br />

stand, will Benn, in der Tradition der Gegenaufklärung und der Romantik<br />

denkend, als epochalen Irrtum decouvrieren und als den<br />

letzten Schritt auf dem Weg der „Zerebralisierung" zersetzen. „Daß


574 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

dies das Leben sei," reflektiert Rönne einmal, könne nur angenommen<br />

werden, solange man an „das an von leitender Stelle aus Geregelte,<br />

...das staatlich Genehmigte, ja Vorgeschriebene...." glaube<br />

(Benn 1984: 53). In diesem verdrehten Anfangssatz der Erzählung<br />

„Die Insel" verbirgt Benn seinen Zynismus gegenüber der Normalität<br />

in der Anschauung von „Leben". Dieser Satz ist keineswegs<br />

ironisch. Er weist ebenso radikal wie die Avantgarden, die versöhnende<br />

Ironie verachten, jede Versöhnung durch Ironie zurück. So,<br />

durch Genehmigungen und Vorschriften geregelt, ist das Leben in<br />

der Tat, sagt Rönne, solange er als Arzt einem geregelten Leben<br />

nachgeht, erkrankte Knie behandelt und gerötete Rachen bepinselt.<br />

Aber daß dies das Leben sei, ist eine Annahme, die bei der ersten<br />

Gelegenheit zu denken, zerstiebt. Sobald das Ich sich von Arbeit<br />

und den auferlegten Regeln befreit und eigene Zeit gewinnt, beginnt<br />

es zu phantasieren, „denken", wie Benn schreibt. Aus diesem<br />

Augenblick der Befreiung entstehen die Avantgarden und ihre Forderung<br />

nach einer anderen Welt und einem anderen Leben. Wenn<br />

dies also nicht das Leben ist, stellt sich die Frage, wo, außerhalb<br />

dieser Bahnen des Vorgeschriebenen und Geregelten, das Leben zu<br />

suchen wäre. Rönnes Antwort in der kurzen Erzählung „Die Insel"<br />

ist so ambivalent wie in allen frühen Texten Benns: es läßt sich nicht<br />

finden, es muß ausgedacht werden. Rönne hat nach dem Ende des<br />

Dienstes als Arzt ein wenig Zeit, und da fängt er an zu „denken" und<br />

erfindet sich in einem assoziativen Strom an Gedanken einen konkreten<br />

Ort der Entfernung, eine Insel der Südsee. Er versetzt sich in<br />

deren zeitlosen Raum, imaginiert eine Zimternte, ein Dasein in<br />

ursprünglicher Sinnlichkeit und schließlich eine Liebesszene, die ihn<br />

aber in Angst versetzt, da er die Festigkeit des Bodens, das männlich<br />

Sichere tatsächlich zu verlieren droht. Da scheut er vor den<br />

Konsequenzen seiner eigenen, avantgardistischen Phantasie zurück.<br />

Die nietzscheanische Auffassung des Lebens als einer rein<br />

ästhetisch zu rechtfertigender Leistung ohne die Hilfe der Metaphysik<br />

löst in diesem Text Furcht aus und veranlaßt Rönne, in die<br />

geord<strong>net</strong>e Zeit aus Regeln und Vorschriften des Dienstes zurückzukehren.<br />

So teilt Rönne das Schicksal der Avantgarden.<br />

Der junge Brecht schrieb aus der Haltung der unzeitgemäßen<br />

Destruktion. Seine Gedichte sprechen von einem gesteigerten Bewußtsein<br />

von der Problematik des Subjekts in der Zeit. In provokanter<br />

Opposition zum geschichtlichen Denken seiner Zeit und zu<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 575<br />

den verachteten Werten des 'bürgerlichen Zeitalters' lassen seine<br />

frühen Gedichte Vergangenheit und Erinnerung aus der Vorstellungswelt<br />

verschwinden. Zeit wird subjektiviert, und Erinnerung hat<br />

sich vor der Instanz der ungeschichtlichen Subjektivität zu rechtfertigen.<br />

Die Hauspostille läßt sich als ein bedeutendes Beispiel des<br />

Unzeitgemäßen sowie des Avantgardistischen lesen. Das Zerstören<br />

der Erinnerung ist eines der durchgehenden Themen. Im Gedicht<br />

„Von den Resten älterer Zeiten" heißt es „An den großen neuen<br />

Antennen/Ist von alter Zeit/Nichts mehr bekannt." (Brecht 1988: Bd.<br />

3, 308) In der technischen Welt verliert die Erinnerung an die gute<br />

alte Zeit, das Ideal der Klassik und Romantik, ihren Wert. Diesen<br />

Wertverlust konstatieren Brechts Gedichte auf allen Ebenen. „Ich<br />

erinnere mich ihres Gesichts nicht mehr" und „Man sagt mir, ihr<br />

Gesicht vergaß sich schnell" (Brecht 1988: Bd. 1, 21; Bd. 3, 302)<br />

beziehen das Vergessen auf das Erinnernswerteste, was es in den visuellen<br />

und emotionalen Beziehungen zwischen einem Ich und der<br />

Welt der Anderen gibt, das Gesicht. Das Verlernen des Sich-Erinnerns<br />

und des überlieferten Wissens (etwa im „Lied der verderbten<br />

Unschuld"), oft mit Hilfe der „guten Droge" (Opium oder Kokain)<br />

macht „das Subjekt sehr vergeßlich." Und schließlich erklärt ein<br />

Gedicht das Vergessen zum Prinzip des Lebens und preist „das<br />

schlechte Gedächtnis des Himmels/Und daß er nicht /Weiß euren<br />

Nam' noch Gesicht..." (Brecht 1988: Bd. 3, 302; Bd. 1, 77)<br />

Die Avantgarden bezogen ihre Vitalität aus der Entfremdung vom<br />

Hier und Jetzt. Trotz ihres unzeitgemäßen Widerstands gegen die<br />

Zeit blieb ihre Literatur und Kunst aber an die Utopie der zukünftigen<br />

Gesellschaft, die sie im schönen Schein entgegen der entwerteten<br />

Gegenwart anwesend machten, gebunden. Das Dionysische des<br />

Südens, der Tropen, Asien, die Südsee, das dunkle Afrika wurden zu<br />

geographischen Hieroglyphen für die Orte, an denen die Ketten der<br />

Rationalität gesprengt werden und das Leben in größerer Fülle erfahren<br />

werden konnte. Diese andere Welt konnte, etwa bei Benn,<br />

Brecht oder Jünger, die Züge der kalten Mitleidlosigkeit einer<br />

Traumwelt, die Blutigkeit des Kriegs und die Gewaltsamkeit eines<br />

rechtlosen, archaischen Zustands annehmen. Der Surrealismus oder<br />

Benn und der frühe Brecht haben zu einer Literatur, die eine andere<br />

Zeit erfahrbar zu machen sucht, wesentliche Beiträge geleistet.<br />

Längst bevor Brecht von Mei Lanfang und der Penkinger Oper


576 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

hörte, hatte er seinen Osten entdeckt, und der war wilder und destruktiver<br />

als die gut organisierte chinesische Oper. Benn lernte das<br />

Unzeitgemäße in den Sezierräumen der Charite und im Sprechzimmer<br />

des Militärarztes in Belgien. Brechts anarchische und Benns zerebrale<br />

Lyrik und Prosa sind avantgardistisch in dem Maß, wie sie<br />

modern und gleichzeitig auch das Gegenteil sind: kalkulierte Formen<br />

von eruptiver Gewalt, Transformationen des Magischen im<br />

Gewand der Rationalität. Das rationale Denken ist ein Sonderfall<br />

des Denkens, das im Dunklen und Vorbewußten lauert und das Ich<br />

jederzeit überwältigen kann. Benns und Brecht Sprache betonen die<br />

Rationalität der Moderne, wenn sie von Experiment, Labor, Analyse,<br />

Wissenschaft sprechen, und sie betonen ebenso die Moderne,<br />

wenn sie vom Irrationalen, Mystischen, Primitiven reden. Es gibt<br />

keinen Widerspruch zwischen diesen beiden Dimensionen in der<br />

Literatur der Moderne, und darin war das unzeitgemäße Denken uneingeschränkt<br />

modern. Es verstellt den Blick auf das Eigentliche des<br />

Unzeitgemäßen, diese Gleichzeitigkeit als mangelhafte Inkonsistenz<br />

aufzufassen. Ein Verständnis der Moderne als Projekt der Rationalisierung<br />

ist fehlgeleitet und basiert auf ihrer Halbierung. Das Unzeitgemäße<br />

hatte seit langem eine ebensolche Daseinsberechtigung in<br />

der Moderne wie das Zeitgemäße, und es setzte sich von einem<br />

Denken ab, das durch eine Verknüpfung von Aufklärung und Revolution<br />

gekennzeich<strong>net</strong> war. Die Entfernung der Gegenaufklärung<br />

und weiter Felder der Literatur und Philosophie aus der Moderne<br />

macht das Unzeitgemäße unsichtbar. Die Avantgarden hatten daran<br />

partiell Anteil. Ihr Kompromiß koppelte sie an das Schicksal der<br />

Moderne.<br />

Die Avantgarden blieben dem Zeitmodell der Moderne auf eine<br />

Weise verpflichtet, daß ihnen die andere Dimension in Nietzsches<br />

Vorstellung des Unzeitgemäßen entging. Sie verstanden das Unzeitgemäße<br />

als den Sprung von einer Kritik der Gegenwart in eine Position<br />

außerhalb der Zeit, aber suchten diese Position doch wieder innerhalb<br />

des Fortschrittsdenkens der Moderne. Sie verstanden ihre<br />

Gegenwart als eine Unzeit. Aber sie strebten - mit divergenten Mitteln<br />

- danach, die in ihr verborgene authentische neue Zeit aus den<br />

Fesseln der Tradition und der Gegenwart zu befreien. Sie entwikkelten<br />

keinen Sinn für das Wiedergewinnen einer ganz anderen<br />

Wirklichkeit jenseits der Abstraktionen moderner Zeitlichkeit, einer<br />

Welt der Konkretheit, Partikularität und Örtlichkeit. So erscheint<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 577<br />

uns das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden heute so vergangen wie die<br />

Vergangenheit, gegen die sie kämpften, aber aus deren kategorialem<br />

Rahmen sie sich nicht zu lösen vermochten, aus dem sie sich gar<br />

nicht lösen wollten.<br />

Anmerkungen<br />

1 Vgl. Landow und Rosello, 1994.<br />

2 Die Historisierung der Avantgarden und die These von ihrem Ende entwickelte<br />

bereits Peter Bürger 1974.<br />

3 Die Boheme, wie Helmuth Kreuzer sie definiert, gehört dagegen in die<br />

Moderne und Postmoderne (vgl. Kreuzer, 1968). Kritiker versuchten dagegen,<br />

die Boheme zu historisieren und sprechen von ihrem Ende, analog<br />

zum Ende der Avantgarden (vgl. Roberts, 1995).<br />

4 Das Fortschrittskonzept reiche nicht aus, stellt Marquard in einer Erörterung<br />

des Verhältnisses von Literatur und Zeit fest, „weil zur Wirklichkeit<br />

nicht nur der Fortschritt gehört, sondern vor allem auch das Ausrangierte<br />

und seine Wiederkehr... Darum ist das Fortschrittsmodell... in die Krise geraten,<br />

und es muß ein anderes - differenzierteres - Wirklichkeitsmodell<br />

herbei..." (Marquard 1994: 18).<br />

5 Im Streit um die Frage, ob der Name „Avantgarde" für historische Bewegungen<br />

des Jahrhunderts zwischen etwa 1830 und 1940 oder eher im Sinn<br />

eines systematischen Begriffs, für jede avancierte Position, die einer neuen<br />

Periode vorausgeht, verstanden werden sollte, ist eine solche Beobachtung<br />

von rückwirkender Kraft. Die Historisierung der Avantgarden als je spezifische<br />

Bewegungen scheint mir eine unausweichliche Folge ihres Bedeutungsverlustes<br />

seit den dreißiger Jahren zu sein.<br />

Die Beziehungen zum Surrealismus sind bis in die Formulierungen hinein<br />

offensichtlich. Die Formulierungen weisen auch auf eine Nähe zu Robert<br />

Musils Erdensekretariat der „Genauigkeit und Seele" hin, und legen die<br />

Verbindung von Cyberspace-Theorien, Musil und Surrealismus nahe. Vgl.


578 Bernd Hüppauf<br />

auch Michael Heim, 1998, der sich an einer Metaphysik des Cyberspace<br />

versucht.<br />

7 Vgl. etwa die Sammlung von skeptischen Beiträgen in Markley, 1996.<br />

8 Zur Kritik an Adornos Theorie des Neuen im Horizont der Avantgarden<br />

vgl. Bürger, 1974: 120ff.<br />

9 Peltier macht darauf aufmerksam, daß Periodisierungen und Hierarchisierungen<br />

nach dem Muster der modernen europäischen Kunstgeschichte auch<br />

auf die Kunst der Primitiven angewandt wurden, so daß eine „Klassifikation<br />

der Objekte in Hinsicht auf ihre plastische Wertigkeit - je geometrischer<br />

die Objekte desto höher ihr Wert - und eine vermutete Wildheit der<br />

Gruppen, die die Kunstwerke produzierten", entwickelt werden konnte<br />

(Peltier 1984: 109).<br />

10 Zur Geschichte der Bezeichnung vgl. vor allem Calinescu, 1974, und<br />

Lohner 1976.<br />

11 In einem aufschlußreichen Interview mit Andre Parinaud über den Ersten<br />

Weltkrieg, Apollinaire, Vache und die Ursprünge des Surrealismus (Breton,<br />

1969).<br />

12 Interview mit Andre Parinaud über hypnotischen Schlummer und die gefährlichen<br />

Landschaften der Nachkriegszeit. (Breton, 1969: 71).<br />

13 „Kant - das ist der Erzfeind, auf den alles zurückgeht." schreibt Ball,<br />

1992: 21. Ball, der in den Jahren vor dem Ersten Weltkrieg und im folgenden<br />

Jahrzehnt in die Avantgarde gehörte, teilte deren ambivalentes Verhältnis<br />

zur Zeit.<br />

14 Eindrucksvolle Beispiele versammelt der Katalog zur Ausstellung im<br />

Deutschen Hygiene-Museum Dresden (Lepp/Roth/Vogel, 1999).<br />

15 Von der Fragestellung nach der „Phantasie als Organ der Poesie" ausgehend,<br />

entwickelt Karlheinz Barck (1993) diese historische Tiefe, aus denen<br />

die Avantgardebewegungen des 20. Jahrhunderts entstanden.<br />

16 Der Vertreter der anti-modernen Langsamkeit, Sten Nodolny (1994: 11),<br />

spricht von dieser unbefragten Identifikation mit der eigenen Zeit: „Aber<br />

wenn wir 'zeitgemäß' sagen, meinen wir meistens die Zeit in wichtigen,<br />

angeblich besonders fortgeschrittenen Regionen." Und das sind stets die<br />

eigenen Regionen.<br />

Das Unzeitgemäße der Avantgarden 579<br />

17 Er sieht sich veranlaßt, seine Leser um Nachsicht für seine Unzeitge­<br />

mäßheit zu bitten.<br />

Die entgegengesetzte Position findet sich in diesen Jahren prägnant in<br />

der Philosophie und Literatur der engagierten Linken vertreten. Nur in einem<br />

eschatologischen Geschichtsdenken, argumentiert Lukäcs in „Geschichte<br />

und Klassenbewußtsein" oder, um Benjamins Lieblingsvokabel<br />

zu benutzen, nur in einer „messianisch" gedachten Geschichte könne das<br />

Subjekt sich aus der Entfremdung befreien und als wahrhafter Einzelmensch<br />

seiner Bestimmung entsprechend entstehen. Das eschatologische<br />

Denken von Geschichte will das Singulare am Menschen an den Gedanken<br />

der Erlösung durch ein Ende von Geschichte binden. Aus der Perspektive<br />

des unzeitgemäßen Denkens führt die Eschatologie jedoch gerade<br />

dazu, das einzelne in Prozeß des Allgemeinen verschwinden zu lassen.<br />

19 Die Entwicklung dieser Entwertung von Gedächtnis und Erinnerung ist<br />

nicht abgeschlossen. Das Wort 'Gedächtnis' wird im elektronischen Zeitalter<br />

für die Speicherung von Daten im Computer benutzt, obwohl zwischen<br />

der mechanischen Speicherung von Daten, die jederzeit unverändert<br />

abgerufen werden können, und dem Gedächtnis, das kein Speicher ist und<br />

keinen festen Ort im Hirn hat, sondern aus einem beweglichen Zusammenspiel<br />

zahlreicher Hirnfunktionen entsteht und seine Inhalte beständig verändert,<br />

kaum eine Gemeinsamkeit besteht. Das lebendige Gedächtnis hat in<br />

diesem neuen Konkurrenzverhältnis mit dem mechanischen Datenspeicher<br />

keine gute Zukunftsprognose. Die Ursache für das allmähliche Ableben des<br />

Gedächtnisses ist nicht der Computer. Die Entwicklung ist älter, und der<br />

Siegeszug der Speicher ist das Symptom einer langen Geschichte, nicht die<br />

Geschichte selbst. Die Daten im 'Gedächtnis' der datenverarbeitenden<br />

Maschinen sind nie unzeitgemäß. Sie mögen nicht auf dem neuesten Stand<br />

sein. Dann sind sie veraltet. Aber sie sind nicht unzeitgemäß und haben<br />

kein Eigenleben, keine Richtung und sind daher nie gegen etwas, auch<br />

nicht gegen eine Zeit gerichtet.


Anne FRIEDBERG: The End of Modernity: Where Is Your Rupture? In:<br />

Dies.: Window Shopping. Cinema and the Postmodern. Berkeley:<br />

University of California Press 1994, S. 157-179.<br />

THE END OF MODERNITY: WHERE IS YOUR RUPTURE?<br />

Post: the term itself demands a cultural seismology—an attempt to measure<br />

the magnitude and moment of rupture with the modern, and to appraise<br />

its effects. 2 But too frequently arguments about postmodernity take positions<br />

on modernism but not modernity. The murky quality of much of<br />

the debate about the postmodern would become more focused by a simple<br />

clarification: the use of separate terms for the social and philosophical<br />

dimension—modernity and postmodernity—and for its concurrent cultural<br />

movements—modernism and postmodernisms (i.e., we live in postmodernity<br />

but the arts may exemplify modernism). 3<br />

In each of the various arts where postmodernism has been debated—<br />

literature, art, architecture, music, dance, performance—modernism itself<br />

has meant something different. The term, postmodernism, has been used<br />

in literature since the early 1960s, 4 since the middle 1970s in architecture, 5<br />

since the late 1970s in dance and performance, 6 and applied to film and<br />

television only in the 1980s. 7 In film and television criticism, postmodernism<br />

has come to be used as a descriptive term for a genre or a period style<br />

but without an account of how the cultural configurations of postmodernity<br />

have themselves been profoundly altered by cinema and the television.<br />

As I have been suggesting, cinematic and televisual spectatorship has produced<br />

a new form of subjectivity; and this subjectivity is produced apparatically,<br />

whether or not the style per se is "postmodern."<br />

In the following chapter, I will argue against the type of critical applicationism<br />

that adopts the adjective postmodern to describe contemporary<br />

cinematic styles. First, film theorists and film historians have yet to agree<br />

on what is "modern" in cinematic terms. Second, a description of the<br />

cinematic apparatus itself will demonstrate the further difficulty of defining<br />

what is "modern" or "postmodern" in cinematic terms. But first, since<br />

much of the debate about the postmodern (in both aesthetic style and social<br />

effect) has taken its terms and assumptions from the architectural model,<br />

it is first necessary to demonstrate how architectural postmodernism does<br />

not fit as an analogy for film stylistics.


THE ARCHITECTURAL MODEL For architecture, the rupture between modern and<br />

postmodern is dramatically visible. Architectural historian Charles Jencks—<br />

the self-proclaimed definer and typologist of "postmodern architecture"—<br />

points to a precise moment when the modern ended and the postmodern<br />

began: the dramatic destruction of the Pruitt-Igoe housing project in St.<br />

Louis ( "Modern Architecture died in St. Louis Missouri on July 15, 1972,<br />

at 3:32 P.M." 8 ). The image of a dynamite explosion leveling these buildings<br />

provides an arresting visualization of the "end" of architectural modernism.<br />

In Jencks's description, "postmodern" style is marked by its departure<br />

from the aesthetic purity and streamlined functionalism of modernist International<br />

Style architects like Mies van der Rohe, Le Corbusier, or Walter<br />

Gropius. The postmodern reaction to these forms of architectual modernism<br />

relies instead on the pluralist combination of modern and premodern<br />

architectural styles. The hybrid buildings of Robert Venturi, Peter Eisenman,<br />

Michael Graves, James Stirling, Aldo Rossi, John Portman, and Arata<br />

Isozaki are models for Jencks's description of "Post-modern Architecture


as "half-Modern, half-conventional." 9 Graves's Portland Building (1982),<br />

for example, incorporates the boxy functionalism of modern architecture<br />

and the classical columns and ornamental motifs of premodern architecture.<br />

Monumental buildings such as Philip Johnson's AT&T Building in New-<br />

York (1978-1982)—a modernist box with a Chippendale top—or Portman's<br />

Bonaventure Hotel in Los Angeles (1976)—a medieval fortress of mirrored<br />

glass—are vivid illustrations of this additive style. 10 In addition, vernacular<br />

architecture—condominium units, storefront design, shopping malls, and<br />

what in Los Angeles is called a "pod mall" or "mini-mall"—also provides<br />

examples of this combination of stylistic elements from High Modernism's<br />

nautical railings to portholes and glass surfaces, all decorated with the follycsque<br />

colors of mint and salmon. 11<br />

Postmodern architecture, in Jencks's terms, reintroduced elements of<br />

sryle that modernism had purged—ornament, metaphor, historical allusion—and<br />

built spaces that were intended to be more popular, more<br />

human, and more individually oriented than the spartan Le Corbusier and<br />

Mies glass boxes of High Modernism. Although he partially attributes the<br />

stylistics of postmodern architecture to a reaction to the social failure of<br />

modern archirecture, Jencks defines postmodernism most assertively in<br />

terms of style: a "double-coding" of the elite and the popular, the old and<br />

the new, a continuation of modernism and its transcendence.<br />

Jencks makes many of his distinctions between "modern" and "postmodern"<br />

using analogies with other forms of visual art. Modernists, he<br />

claims, took the process of art as their subject, while postmodernists take<br />

the history of art as their subject. As a typologist, Jencks becomes very shrill<br />

about "category mistakes" in which Late Modernists are confused with<br />

Postmodernists. Late Modernists still rely on a concept of the "new,"<br />

whereas Postmodernists have a new relation to the past. 12<br />

As we will see, it would be difficult to find an analogy in film history<br />

for the Pruitt-Igoe housing failure. Does one assume that the model of<br />

"modern" cinema was the "classical Hollywood film" with its economy of<br />

structure, its narrative continuities, its popular appeal, its reducrion of metaphor—a<br />

sort of refined glass box, efficient in its production of narrative<br />

pleasure? If so, what moment or film would instantiate such a dramatic<br />

rupture? Did it occur with the narrative bricolage of Orson Welles's Citizen<br />

Kane in 1941? Or earlier—before the classical Hollywood "mode of practice"<br />

took hold—in the montage exercises of Eisenstein and Vertov in the<br />

1920s?


Jameson confounds this distinction by considering as "modern" a list of<br />

filmmakers including Fellini and Bergman—whose films have been thought<br />

of as a challenge to the Hollywood model—along with the films of Alfred<br />

I litchcock, that master of "classical" editing. In a sentence that requires a<br />

good deal of parsing to detect its meaning, Jameson discusses symptoms of<br />

the "postmodernism" style in film:<br />

It can be witnessed in film, not merely between experimental and commercial<br />

production, but also within the former itself, where Godard's "break" with<br />

the classical filmic modernism of the great "auteurs" (Hitchcock, Bergman,<br />

Fellini, Kurosawa) generates a series of stylistic reactions against itself in the<br />

1970's and is also accompanied by a rich new development of experimental<br />

video (a new medium inspired by but significantly and structurally distinct<br />

lrom experimental film). 13<br />

This sentence, a key sentence for Jameson's catalog of the postmodern<br />

changes in cinematic form, has an incredibly tangled sense of where the<br />

actual "breaks" are. We are left with a series of unanswered questions: Is<br />

the break between modern and postmodern the same as the break between<br />

commercial and experimental? Are Hitchcock, Bergman, Fellini—the<br />

"auteurs"— exemplars of cinematic modernism while Godard is postmodern?<br />

If Bergman and Fellini are modernists, does this make the classical<br />

Flollywood cinema premodernist? And what does that say about earlier<br />

cinematic forms, before the codes of cinematic narrative were well established?<br />

What do we say about conventions of narrative construction that<br />

evolved in other national cinemas? How do they relate to "postmodernism"?<br />

Certainly, the "classical model"—a model deemed in retrospect—<br />

was challenged in its own day by a variety of avant-gardes that were otherwise<br />

involved in all that modern came to mean in the other arts. 14<br />

All of these questions form fault lines underneath the surface application<br />

of modern and postmodern as stylistic terms. As I will continue to argue, the<br />

very apparatus of the cinema makes the stylistic categories of modernism<br />

and postmodernism inappropriate.<br />

THE CINEMA AND MODERNITY/MODERNISM: THE "AVANT-GARDE" AS A TROUBLING<br />

THIRD TERM Because the invention of the cinema was coincident with the<br />

urban and cultural changes that marked modernity, the cinema has been<br />

commonly thought of as a "modern" apparatus. And yet most work on<br />

cinema and modernism retreats from theorizing modernity itself, leaving<br />

the relation between modernity and cinematic modernism ambiguous at<br />

best. Cinematic modernism has been most frequently described in analogy<br />

to the aesthetic challenges to the mimetic mandate of representation in<br />

painterly modernism or literary modernism. 15<br />

To complicate matters, in historical accounts of cinema, as in the other<br />

arts, there remains a profound and lasting conflation of what is considered<br />

"modernism" and what is considered the "avant-garde." 16 While the warring<br />

definitions of cinematic modernism and the cinematic avant-garde are<br />

largely a historiographical debate, to examine cinematic modernism one<br />

cannot avoid a discussion of the history of the cinematic "avant-garde.<br />

Hence, even to approach a discussion of the cinema in postmodernity,<br />

wades further into a nominalist quagmire.<br />

Cinema and the "Avant-Garde" Both Peter Burger ( Theory of the Avant-<br />

Garde) and Andreas Huyssen (After the Great Divide) have attempted to<br />

correct an assumed coextensivity between the avant-garde and modernism,<br />

a conflation assumed by critics as diverse as Renato Poggioli, Irving Howe,<br />

and Jiirgen Habermas. 18 But if this correction has had any impact on our<br />

current concept of a cultural avant-garde, it has largely been to exile it to<br />

a fixed historical period (now referred to as "the historical avant-gardes")<br />

rather than address it as an ongoing front. 19 In Theory of the Avant-Garde,<br />

Burger makes the distinction between modernism, which attacks the conventions<br />

of language, and the avant-garde, which attacks the institutions<br />

of art.<br />

The history of the French cinema, a key battleground for these semantic<br />

disputes, will provide us with an illustrative case of how Burger's distinctions<br />

do not fit cinema history. One 'of the implicit agendas of both the<br />

"first" and "second" French "avant-gardes" was to have the cinematic<br />

medium taken seriously as an art form. Much of this campaign took place<br />

as a discursive struggle in the French journals, such as Le Film, Le Journal<br />

du Cine-Club, Cinea, Cinea-Cine-pour-tous, and later, in international journals,<br />

such as Close-Up and Experimental Film. 20 The language of these critics,<br />

many of whom became filmmakers, was to announce the cinema as a<br />

"new art." 21 Filmmakers and their discursive supporters wished for the<br />

incorporation of the cinema into the institutions of high art, preferring to<br />

build cathedrals for their art than to challenge the idea of its institutionalization.


Filmmakers Marcel L'Herbier and Louis Delluc, for example, employed<br />

the terms impressionist and impressionism as self-descriptive labels, drawing<br />

the parallels between their cinematic visuality and painterly or musical<br />

impressionism. 22 In this case impressionism was used contemporaneously,<br />

not just in historical retrospect. Richard Abel has attempted to clarify the<br />

various labels used in French film histories (impressionism, avant-garde,<br />

modernism). Abel is dubious of terms that narrowly define modernism as<br />

anti-illusionist and antinarrative and wants to open modernism to include<br />

die "narrative avant-garde." 23 Abel appeals to the historical distinction<br />

between the "First Avant-garde," which included feature-length narrative<br />

filmmakers (Delluc, Germaine Dulac, Jean Epstein, L'Herbier, and Abel<br />

Gance) between 1919 and 1924, and the "Second Avant-garde," composed<br />

of abstract or non-narrative films from 1924 to 1929. In these distinctions,<br />

the avant-garde includes narrative and non-narrative films. Rather than<br />

make an exact distinction between modernism and the avant-garde, Abel<br />

combines them.<br />

The film experiments of this avant-garde were not confined to a single<br />

national cinema and also attempted to cross another borderline, that<br />

between cinema and the other arts—literature, painting, sculpture, music.<br />

Films such as painters Viking Eggeling and Hans Richter's Rhythmus 21<br />

(1921) and Symphonic Diagonale (1922); photographer Man Ray's Le retour<br />

a la raison (1923); cubist painter Ferdinand Leger's Ballet mecanique (1924);<br />

Luis Bunuel and Salvador Dali's Un Chien Andalou (1929) were received<br />

in the realms of high art, exhibited in galleries or ciné-clubs, separate from<br />

the venues of the burgeoning new "mass cultural" popular cinema.<br />

The above experimental films were part of a campaign to challenge the<br />

assumptions that cinema was a (lowly) form of mass entertainment and<br />

was, instead, worthy of inclusion in the academies of high art. Hence the<br />

cinema has its own convoluted history of allegiance to the principles of the<br />

"avant-garde," and does not neatly fit into Burger's assumptions about the<br />

avant-garde attacking the institutions of art. In addition, Burger defines the<br />

techniques of crosscutting and montage as essentially avant-garde. This<br />

would make every film from Birth of a Nation to Potemkin to Psycho an<br />

avant-garde film.<br />

Cinema and Modernism The cinema also has a paradoxical place in critical<br />

discourse about modernism. The narratological and mimetic conventions<br />

that developed as the cinema became a popular mass cultural form are<br />

precisely the conventions of representation that modernisms were challenging.<br />

The cinema can be seen as a "modern" form embodying distinctly<br />

anti-modern narratological conventions (closure, mimesis, realism) disguised<br />

in "modern" technological attire.<br />

A useful approach to such a terminological impasse about cinematic<br />

"modernism" is offered by Huyssen's formulation of the "divide" between<br />

modernism and mass culture. Modernism, Huyssen maintains, was constituted<br />

"through a conscious strategy of exclusion, an anxiety of contamination<br />

by its other: an increasingly consuming and engulfing mass culture."<br />

24 In this context, Huyssen also examines the rhetorical treatment of<br />

"Mass Culture as Woman," a discursively debased partner in a long-standing<br />

and bitter cultural divorce. 25<br />

But Huyssen's effort to locate the chasm on a discursive plane—placing<br />

a "great divide" between mass culture and modernism—makes it somewhat<br />

easier to chart a rupture or break between the modern and the division. 26<br />

The concept of a great divide forces the seismological cleavage, the division,<br />

onto a cultural rather than temporal model. Attempts to simply periodize<br />

the modern and the postmodern thus become misplaced road signs supported<br />

by a misleading post.<br />

If the "divide" between mass culture and modernism is properly understood,<br />

Huyssen posits, then the postmodern can be welcomed for its potential<br />

to reconcile, to fuse these disjunctures. In all of this, the avant-garde<br />

(a "hidden dialectic") asserts itself as a historical paradigm that rejected the<br />

"divide" from mass culture, and offers a heritage that Huyssen wishes to<br />

resurrect. The "historical avant-garde" (which includes Russian constructivism,<br />

Berlin Dada, and French surrealism) would be Huyssen's chosen<br />

genealogical forebear for the postmodern.<br />

Once one endorses the concept of such a divide, it is no longer useful<br />

to trace a singular history of high art; one must, instead, examine the<br />

bifurcated lineage of art and its relation to mass culture. Even though the<br />

boundary between what has been considered the "avant-garde" and what<br />

has been considered "modernism" may be very fluid, Huyssen maintains<br />

that the distinction rests in their respective attitudes toward mass culture.<br />

And because the conflation of modernism with the avant-garde only occurs<br />

later within art critical discourse, Huyssen wants to point out that the avantgarde,<br />

unlike modernism, always rejected the separation from mass culture.<br />

Huyssen uses the "historical avant-gardes" as a wedgelike presence, to<br />

sharpen modernism's relationship between high art and mass culture, but


the cinematic avant-gardes fall into a tricky terrain. The avant-garde film<br />

is generally defined in distinction from the mass cultural entertainment<br />

film, placing its experiments on the modernist side of the divide. Perhaps<br />

because of the conflation with modernism(s), these cinematic "avantgardes"<br />

have been defined in strict separation from mass culture.<br />

Postmodern art, Huyssen wants us to note, follows the lineage of the<br />

historical avant-garde, in that it has been driven to cross boundaries, to<br />

force intersections between the spheres of high and low, or public and<br />

private, which modernism wished to keep separate. In these terms, postmodern<br />

art exists in new configurations with modernism, with mass culture,<br />

and with the avant-garde. In Huyssen's view, the "postmodern condition"<br />

in literature and the arts is one where the distinctions between high<br />

art and mass culture have become quite blurred. Huyssen's "divide"<br />

between mass culture and modernism—and its undercurrent, the avantgarde—suggests<br />

that the cinema is, unlike all other art forms, uniquely<br />

poised to be "postmodern."<br />

As if following this lead, J. Hoberman has attempted to rehistoricize the<br />

American avant-garde and to apply the (early eighties) debates about postmodernism<br />

to a historical account of the cinematic "avant-garde." 27 In an<br />

essay entitled "After Avant-Garde Film," Hoberman provides a historical<br />

survey of the range of manifestations of "avant-garde" filmmaking, and<br />

adds the strategies often equated with postmodernism—appropriation,<br />

quotation, pastiche—to his description of the resurgence of "fringe" filmmaking<br />

in New York in the late 1970s. The films of Beth and Scott B.,<br />

Vivienne Dick, Becky Johnston, James Nares, Eric Mitchell, Charlie<br />

Ahearn, and others, Hoberman asserts, were a "postmodernist repetition"<br />

of the New York underground of the mid-1960s. Postmodernist because<br />

the repetition was "second generation," sometimes parodic, sometimes<br />

homagistic allusions to Warhol, Fellini, and Antonioni. Although Hoberman<br />

doesn't claim this explicitly, he is also calling this work "postmodernist"<br />

because these filmmakers were positioned against what had become an<br />

"avant-garde ghetto"—the institutionalized empires of the Museum of<br />

Modern Art, Anthology Film Archives, and their academic alliances. These<br />

filmmakers were challenging what Burger would call "the institutions of<br />

art." It is as if the cinema only became "avant-garde" after modernism.<br />

Hoberman also offers a polemical rereading of Peter Wollen's earlier<br />

polemic, "The Two Avant-Gardes" (1975), which traced the historical<br />

bifurcation between an avant-garde that followed the formalism of cubist<br />

cinema and an avant-garde that followed the political concerns of the Soviets.<br />

28 Hoberman argues that Wollen was describing a subtextual conflict<br />

between two "postmodernisms"—"the genuinely populist, Sixties postmodernism<br />

of Pop Art and underground movies versus the mandarin Seventies<br />

postmodernism of continental theory." 29 Although the ramifications<br />

of these two postmodernisms—the populist and the mandarin—aren't fully<br />

elaborated, Hoberman has begun to hint at a cinematic instance of what<br />

Huyssen described as the "great divide." At the time Hoberman was writing,<br />

this divide split between films that were aligned with mass culture<br />

(DePalma's wanton appropriation of Hitchcock and Antonioni)—and<br />

films that were aligned with the poststructuralist avant-garde (Yvonne Rainer,<br />

and what Hoberman and others called "the New Talkies"). Hoberman<br />

concluded with a hint that video art might offer "the perpetuation of a<br />

postmodern avant-garde." In this sense, Hoberman positioned what might<br />

be deemed "avant-garde" aesthetic practice in an otherwise foreclosed terrain<br />

of the televisual.<br />

Hoberman's piece seems marked now as one written from the vantage<br />

of the mid-1980s. Are there two postmodernisms? In contemporary film<br />

culture, does this split between stylistic and political art practices still pertain?<br />

Is there a formal cinematic postmodernism as opposed to a political<br />

cinematic postmodernism? If the distinctions between high art and mass<br />

culture have become ever more blurred, how can we discuss postmodern<br />

film in terms of style and neglect its place in the larger cultural apparatus?<br />

Certainly the dissolution of an "avant-garde" into the totality of consumer<br />

culture was a cultural deficit of the socioeconomic configurations of<br />

the Reagan 1980s. When, in 1987, Hoberman turned his review of the<br />

Whitney Biennial into a bleak prophecy, a distressed obituary for the cinematic<br />

avant-garde ("Individuals persevere, but the movement seems moribund.<br />

... the real irony is that a major reason for the marginalization of<br />

the avant-garde is precisely the absence of a commodity to exploit." 30 ), he<br />

was criticized for his aging standards and his own dismissals. As a letter to<br />

the editor complained:<br />

It would never have occurred to him during the heyday of '60s underground<br />

film to allow an institution like the Whitney Museum to define what was<br />

innovative and compelling in filmmaking. 31


Hoberman described that year's Whitney Biennial as "the most dismal<br />

selection of avant-garde films since the Biennial began including the form<br />

in 1979." And yet, like modernism's inclusion in the institutions of acad­<br />

emy, the institutionalization and academicization of the cinematic avant-<br />

garde has had its critical effects.<br />

As if to seal the fate of the avant-garde film, two years later, New York<br />

Times critic Caryn James, reviewing the next Whitney Biennial, queried:<br />

"How can avant-gatde filmmaking survive in a consumer culture so pervasive<br />

that it seems to absorb its own critics?" 32<br />

JAMESON AND THE CINEMATIC "POSTMODERN" To date, Jameson has provided<br />

the most detailed account of the role of cinema in postmodernity. In two<br />

essays, "Postmodernism, or the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, and<br />

"Postmodernism and Consumer Society," Jameson directly addresses the<br />

symptomatic aesthetics of postmodernism and film. 33 In these essays, and<br />

in his other discussions of postmodernism, Jameson has deftly peeled away<br />

the first layers of postmodernism's mirrored skin. His descriptions, as we<br />

will see, offer the depth of cultural insight that is only available to a theorist<br />

who takes the risk of evaluating a range of aesthetic products—from architecture<br />

to music to the visual arts. Jameson provides a detailed diagnosis of<br />

postmodern cultural practice, covering a wide range of symptomatic cases<br />

with a thin sheen of analytic brilliance. Jameson locates his analysis of film<br />

and the postmodern in a discussion of the "nostalgia film." 34 The "nostalgia<br />

film" may indeed be an indication of a key aesthetic symptom, a cinematic<br />

version of postmodern style, but, as we will see, the phenomenon of nostalgia<br />

extends well beyond this one genre or period style; it is an inherent<br />

feature of the photographic and cinematic apparatus itself.<br />

Although Jameson doesn't perform an exact taxonomy, his descriptions<br />

divide the "nostalgia film" into: 1) films that are about the past and set in<br />

the past Chinatown, American Graffiti); 2) films that "reinvent" the past<br />

(Star Wars, Raiders of the Lost Ark); and 3) films that are set in the present<br />

but invoke the past (Body Heat; we could add Miami Vice, Moonlighting,<br />

Batman). The "nostalgia film" is described in stylistic terms—cases where<br />

a film's narrative and its art direction confuse its sense of temporality. Films<br />

such as Chinatown and The Conformist take place in "some eternal Thirties;<br />

beyond historical time." 35<br />

But if we extend this analysis of diegetic temporality to include the<br />

apparatus's inherent capacity to alter the spectator's relation to temporality,<br />

then every film has the jumbled relation to the historical referent that Jameson<br />

finds exclusively in the "nostalgia film." As I began to illustrate in the<br />

last chapter, all films—now in the age of easily replayable, accessible timeshifting—provide<br />

a temporal mobility for the spectator as "time-tourist."<br />

Perhaps because Jameson is one of the few theorists in the postmodern<br />

debate who has attempted to account for the role of cinema and the televisual,<br />

his work has become the cornerstone of most subsequent discussions.<br />

But it will be necessary to take his analysis a few steps further to<br />

theorize the institution of the cinema and its larger cultural role in the<br />

contemporary figuration deemed postmodernity.<br />

When Jameson first began writing on postmodernism in the early 1980s,<br />

he began by remarking on the "inverted millennarism" implicit in discourses<br />

that proclaimed an "end" of ideology, an "end" of history, an<br />

"end" of modernism. 36 Jameson wanted to posit a coupure and to theorize<br />

the historiographical problems involved in demarcating a rupture between<br />

the modern and the postmodern.<br />

One of Jameson's key contributions as theorist of the postmodern has<br />

been his assertion that the emergence of postmodernism is directly connected<br />

to ("late") consumer capitalism and the "postindustrial" 37 society<br />

that matured after World War II. 38 In the essay, "Postmodernism, or the<br />

Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism," Jameson asserts this relation:<br />

Postmodern culture is the internal and superstructural expression of a whole<br />

new wave of American military and economic domination throughout the<br />

world. 39<br />

Both internal and superstructural: Jameson argues that the cultural effects<br />

of American military and economic domination have produced a particulat<br />

aesthetic form, a superstructural detritus, "postmodern cultute." This is a<br />

reflection theory, where the schizophrenic, decentered, panicked subjectivity<br />

produced by late capitalism produces, in turn, cultural products that<br />

are embodiments of such fragmentation.<br />

At the core of Jameson's discussion of the postmodern is a shift in cultural<br />

groundworks which, Jameson claims, gives a different signification<br />

and valence to aesthetic strategies. Here, the separate terms of modernity<br />

and modernism might sharpen Jameson's argumenr. When, for example,<br />

he describes postmodenism as a new social formation, not simply an extension<br />

of modernism, he is describing postmodernity, where modernisms have


een canonized into the academy and are no longer shocking. The stylistic<br />

similarities between modernist art and what is called "postmodernist" art<br />

have to be read, he would argue, in terms of the major differences in the<br />

socioeconomic context in which they are received. (In short, "modernism(s)"<br />

read differently in "postmodernity.")<br />

In a slightly earlier essay, "Postmodernism and Consumer Society"<br />

(1983), Jameson first proposed the idea of a cultural "dominant":<br />

Radical breaks between periods do not generally involve complete changes of<br />

content but rather the restructuration of a certain number of elements already<br />

given: features that in an earlier period or system were subordinate now<br />

become dominant. 40<br />

By shifting away from a purely stylistic description, Jameson describes how<br />

modernisms, once oppositional atts, had, in theit day, a different social<br />

function than contemporary arts, which "may have all the same formal<br />

features of the older modernism" but have shifted their cultutal position<br />

and lost some of their oppositional force.<br />

In the later essay, "Postmodernism, or the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism"<br />

(1984), Jameson elaborates the concept of a "dominant." He questions<br />

his own "empiiical, chaotic and heterogenous" list of postmodernist<br />

texts and offers a "periodizing hypothesis," 41 which, instead of simply supplying<br />

a roster of stylistic innovation, asserts that postmodernism is not a<br />

style but a "cultutal dominant" 42 or a "force-field." 43 The term cultural<br />

dominant, then, supplies a mote historiographically rigorous explanation of<br />

the continuity and discontinuity between the modern and the postmodern;<br />

it allows for the coexistence of the featutes of both. The idea of a "cultural<br />

dominant" requires a dialectical imagination of history, where the coupure<br />

is not temporal but discursive and epistemological. 44 My discussion of postmodernity<br />

parallels Jameson's theorization of a "cultural dominant."<br />

Rather than proclaiming a temporal moment of rupture, I have traced the<br />

subtle transformation produced by the increasing cultural centrality of the<br />

image producing and teproducing apparatuses.<br />

Warhol's Multiple: An Aesthetic Symptom If we digress briefly to examine<br />

Jameson's analysis of the work of Warhol, it will illustrate some of the<br />

limitations in Jameson's initial conceptualization of the cinema and the<br />

postmodern. Jameson's consideration of Warhol's work will provide us with<br />

an insight as to why his account of film in postmodernity slights the multiple<br />

metonmyic distribution of cinema over time.<br />

Jameson uses the aesthetic product—a symbolic document of its time<br />

such as Van Gogh's Peasant Shoes or Munch's The Scream—as an indication<br />

of a shift in the "dynamics of cultural pathology" from modernity to postmodernity.<br />

He maintains that the twin symptoms of modernity—anxiety<br />

and alienation—have given way to a new cultural pathology of fragmentation.<br />

Jameson finds symptoms of this fragmentation in the wotk of Warhol,<br />

whose Marilyn series (1962) and Shoes (done with diamond dust, 1980)<br />

are, to him, symptomatic documents of postmodernity. In these works, as<br />

in many of Warhol's silkscreen multiples, the pieces are produced by repeating<br />

a single, celebrated photographic image. Jameson asserts that it is the<br />

"black and white substratum of the photographic negative" that brought<br />

Warhol into the "age of mechanical reproduction." 45<br />

But it was not just that Warhol was using the photogtaphic negative in<br />

his silkscreened works which brought Warhol into a new configuration<br />

with reproduction and distribution. A key element of Warhol's work was<br />

the metonymic display of the multiple: identical images repeated (like<br />

unchanging film frames) in serial—but not sequential—repetition.<br />

Grounded in rubber stamp multiples, a staple of the commercial art<br />

illustration world when Warhol enteted it in the late 1940s, the multiple<br />

became a central strategy in Warhol's work. 46 Not only were works produced<br />

in silkscreen series, they were exhibited in multiple serialized display<br />

{Eighty-Two Dollar Bills [1962]; Marilyn x 100 [1962]; Thirty Are Better<br />

Than One [1963]; Dollar Signs [1981]). The subject here was fragmented by<br />

its identical reproducibility. 47 In this way, Warhol used mechanical reproduction<br />

both diachronically and synchronically—spatially and temporally.<br />

In a sense, even before Warhol began making "movies," his silkscreen work<br />

followed the historical trajectory from photography to film. As he spatially<br />

reproduced his close-up "part objects" (Marilyn's lips, Coke bottles) they<br />

became temporalized into a series of repeated "part objects" that produce<br />

an image of timelessness. 48 (In fact, Warhol's film work frequently<br />

employed a static camera, producing an almost unchanging series of images<br />

frame to frame; when his film work is reproduced in still illustration it is<br />

done in the form of a film strip in order to illustrate the frame arrangement.<br />

Each frame appears as an image in multiple. 49 )<br />

As Warhol retrospectives cover the globe (the Museum of Modern Art<br />

retrospective travels to the Georges Pompidou in Paris then on to Prague,


Andy Warhol, "Thirty Are Better Than One," 1963.<br />

© Andy Warhol Foundation for the Visual Arts /<br />

ARS, New York.<br />

Hungary, Yugoslavia, and Warsaw. Will Moscow be far behind?), the polv<br />

valent slippages of context—of political context and the passage of time<br />

force us to rethink these silk-screen images. Hailing so blatantly from the<br />

United States as if in colorful multiples, they unfurl the flag of Americanbased<br />

consumer culture. What do these images do, if not celebrate a culture<br />

of abundance and multiplication? Warhol's work provides an aesthetic<br />

sanction to these proliferations of spectacle—billboards, supermarkets<br />

advertisements. Or, if not condoning commercialism, his work provided a<br />

lesson of adjustment. We live among all of these images, equal under the<br />

sign of signage: the hammer and sickle is equal to Marilyn or Mao or<br />

Reagan-for-Van Heusen shirts. Warhol's work makes natural what—in the<br />

1960s and 1970s and even in the waning Utopian hopes of the 1980s—we<br />

hoped it might critique. His work had an aesthetic of rebellion that became<br />

an aesthetic of sanction, an acceptance of the values of the culture of consumption<br />

that it first intended to critique. The work was forged not out<br />

of the conviction to relinquish the pleasures of ownership but to celebrate<br />

it, not an abstraction of commercial signage but instead its prophetic landscape.<br />

Jameson, unlike many theorists of the postmodern, has forced a political<br />

analysis of positions in the debate ("every position on postmodernism in<br />

culture ... is necessarily an implicitly or explicitly political stance on the<br />

nature of multi-national capitalism today" 50 ).<br />

By 1987, when Jameson wrote "Postmodernism and Utopia," he had a<br />

manifest nostalgia for the dialectic, detecting the faint echoes of a "Utopian<br />

vocation" of "collective cultural fantasies" in the work of contemporary<br />

artists Salle, Haacke, and Wasow. 51 In this essay, Jameson has a more<br />

affirmed sense of modernity's passage, a more digested sense of postmodernism's<br />

effects. (Phrases such as "the sharp pang of death of the modern<br />

and "the modern is sealed for good" assure us of this. 52 ) And, as he rethinks<br />

modernity and postmodernity in terms of time -and space, Jameson makes<br />

a distinction between modernism's experience of existential time and deep<br />

memory and postmodernism's discontinuous spatial experience. 53 Jameson<br />

suggests a " 'great transformation'—the displacement of time, the spatialization<br />

of the temporal" 54 —which separates the postmodern and its new<br />

spatial aesthetic" where "older form[s] of place" have disappeared, replaced<br />

by the "Disneyland simulacra of themselves." 55


These more recent descriptions of postmodern temporality suggest a<br />

productive route for an adequate consideration of cinematic and televisual<br />

forms.<br />

CINEMA AND POSTMODERN/TV Despite these semantic battles, the term postmodern<br />

has entered into the critical vocabulary of film style. If, as James recently<br />

asserted in the New York Times, "post-modern films rejuvenate old genres—westerns,<br />

adventure serials and musicals—by being them and mocking<br />

them at the same time," 56 how do we find a coupure, a historical or stylistic<br />

moment that separates the categories modern and postmodern? 57<br />

In a more sophisticated version of the same definition, Linda Hutcheon<br />

suggests, if not a manifest break between the modern and the postmodern,<br />

a more nuanced relationship, one of metareferentiality. What happens,<br />

Hutcheon asks, when a film like Stardust Memories parodies a "modernist"<br />

film like 8 1//2<br />

What happens, I think, is something we could label as "postmodernist,"<br />

something that has the same relation to its modernist cinematic past as can be<br />

seen in postmodern architecture today—both a respectful awareness of cultural<br />

continuity and a need to adapt to changing formal demands and social<br />

conditions through an ironic challenging of the authority of that same<br />

continuity. 58 (emphasis added)<br />

For Hutcheon, whose work on postmodernism has consistently defended<br />

the ctitical potentials of parody and dialogism, double-voiced ironic parody<br />

becomes a corrective antidote to that other form of recalling the past, nostalgia.<br />

This assumption, that postmodern style involves citation, the invisible<br />

quotation marks of parody ("being them and mocking them at the same<br />

time") has come to be an agreed-upon currency of its ctitical usage. In<br />

James's definition, the "old genre" is made the object of representation,<br />

not necessarily as parodic travesty—for humor or critique—but also with<br />

the possible intention of endorsing, repeating, underlining the earlier<br />

form—recapitalizing, in a sense, on a past success.<br />

But before we assume that the "post" implies a teferentiality back to an<br />

earlier instance of representation, it seems imperative that we again consider<br />

the apparatus of the cinema itself. Certainly the cinema is not the first<br />

story-telling medium where the same stories are consistently retold. 59 From<br />

its beginning, the cinema has rejuvenated and replayed its own gentes and<br />

narratives. The cinematic apparatus is unique in its facility to replay and<br />

repeat its own exact form—the identical replication made possible by its<br />

photographic base allows the same film to be teprojected at a variety of<br />

points in time. Hence one cannot say that only postmodern cinema (as<br />

distinct from modern cinema) takes its own history, its own form, as a<br />

subject. 60<br />

To investigate this assertion, let us briefly consider a particularly cinematic<br />

form: the remake. From the very beginning of film production, films<br />

were remade. 61 Once one begins to examine the abundance of historical<br />

examples of this form, it seems necessary to attempt a taxonomy to distinguish<br />

how such intertextual teferentiality might opetate between the "original"<br />

and the remake. The remake itself can produce a mise en abyme of<br />

references, an "original" that is ever-receding:<br />

i) Films based on stage or literary properties: Dashiell Hammett's Maltese<br />

Falcon was made three times in ten years; first in 1931 directed by Roy del<br />

Ruth with Bebe Daniels and Ricardo Cortez; then as Satan Met a Lady<br />

(1936) directed by William Dieterle with Bette Davis and Warren William;<br />

in 1941 as Maltese Falcon, directed by John Houston with Humphrey<br />

Bogart, Mary Astot, and Peter Lorre. In these examples, the referent—the<br />

soutce for the remake—is litetary rather than cinematic.<br />

2) Films that are remakes of earlier films: D. W. Griffith remade his 1911<br />

one-reeler The Lonedale Operator with Blanche Sweet as The Girl and Her<br />

Trust with Dorothy Bernard one year later, in January 1912. In these examples,<br />

the referent is cinematic not literary.<br />

3) Films that are remade as technology improves: Films that wete made in<br />

the silent era and later remade as sound films; or films made in black and<br />

white remade in color. Fannie Hurst's novel, Back Street, was made in 1932<br />

(directed by John Stahl with Irene Dunne and John Boles; by Robert Stevenson<br />

in 1941 with Margaret Sullavan and Charles Boyer, and then [in<br />

colot] in 1961 by David Miller with Susan Hayward and John Gavin).<br />

4) Films that are remade to update or change historical details: Four Horsemen<br />

of the Apocalypse, made first in 1921 (Rex Ingram) as a World War I<br />

story with Rudolph Valentino and then remade in 1961 (Vincente Minelli)<br />

with Glenn Ford as a World War II story.<br />

The intertextual referentiality between a remake and its "original is<br />

largely extratextual, outside the film text itself in the historical or discursive


context of the film's production or reception. [Parodic remakes may have a<br />

more directly intertextual referentiality.<br />

Remakes may or may not refer back to the earlier version, but sequels<br />

always do. Given the recent seasonal dependence on the sequel, it may<br />

appear that the sequel itself is a postmodern form. (The summer and fall<br />

releases of 1990—Die Harder, Two Jakes, Robocop II, Young Guns II, God­<br />

father III—illustrate that the sequel is a reigning conception of successful<br />

industrial film production.)<br />

But there are historical precedents for this rash of sequels. Series filmmaking—capitalizing<br />

on a known, market-tested good—was an early staple<br />

of film production. Serial films—different from series films that were complete<br />

in each installment—were another successful marketing strategy as<br />

the film industry began to experiment with longer narratives. The serial<br />

was a transitional form in the market war between the standardized onereel<br />

format of the Motion Picture Patents Trust companies and the renegade<br />

"independents" who attempted films of a "feature" length. 62 Based<br />

on the pulp pop-cultural format of the serialized western, comic book, or<br />

melodrama, the serial connected otherwise complete narratives by frustrating<br />

their narrative closure. Louis Feuillade's serial detective, Fantomas (Gaumont,<br />

1913—1914), based on the serial novel by Pierre Souvestre and Marcel<br />

Allain, was such a successful cinematic venture that it spawned imitations.<br />

The Pathe serial, Perils of Pauline (1914), produced in the United States<br />

with the American actress Pearl White, was the first American serial. 63 (The<br />

serial was a form that was also present in other national cinemas: Germany's<br />

Homunculus, Italy's Tigris.)<br />

By 1916, the serial film was already parodying itself. As Abel records, the<br />

French film La Pied qui etrient (1916) parodies the first Perils of Pauline,<br />

The Clutching Hand, and the then newly renowned Charlie Chaplin.<br />

Epstein's Les Aventures de Robert Macaire (1925) was a parody of Henri<br />

Fescourt's Mandarin (1924) , 64<br />

The genre film, itself a safe staple of the industry, has offered a solace of<br />

familiarity in its iconography and narrative concerns. Some would assert<br />

that a melange of genres or period styles—from forties noir to ni<strong>net</strong>ies sci-<br />

fi—becomes a particularly "postmodern" pastiche of past forms. If this is<br />

the case, it is unclear where one draws the stylistic line: is postmodernist<br />

style the additive quality of pastiche or is it the stylistic "literalization" of<br />

broader cultural symptoms? 65<br />

Film production has always teetered on this precipice between orig-inalirv<br />

and repetition. The cinema has repeated and remade the same stories from<br />

myths and fables to plays and novels that are endlessly returned to for source<br />

material. But more than this form of repetition, where the textual reference<br />

is reencoded in a new text, the cinema has a metonymic capacity of repeating<br />

the exact same film over time: reissuing it, redistributing it, reseeine ir<br />

At its very base, then, the cinematic apparatus has the capacity to renlav<br />

itself ("being them and mocking them at the same time"). The repeatability<br />

of cinema products means that the apparatus can exactly quote itself, repeat<br />

its earlier form, if not its earlier context.<br />

Consider, for example, a Victor Fleming film produced in 1939, set in<br />

1863, but shown in 1992 {Gone with the Wind). Or a film produced in 1968,<br />

set in 2001, but shown in 1992 (2001: A Space Odyssey). Or more exactly, a<br />

film made in the city of Paris in 1964, set in a future world, but seen in<br />

1992 in the city of Los Angeles {Alphaville), or a film made in Los Angeles<br />

in 1982, set in Los Angeles 2019 {Blade Runner), but seen in Los Angeles<br />

in 1992. The exact temporal referent of each of these films is quite slippery.<br />

As work on the genre of the historical film has shown, the particular<br />

moment of production will determine its view of the past. 66 And as work<br />

on exhibition has shown, the particular moment of exhibition will determine<br />

the audience's reception of the past. 67<br />

In Benjaminian terms, the "aura" of the event has already disappeared<br />

in the mechanical reproduction itself, but the aura of the original moment<br />

of exhibition also disappeared. Whereas cinematic spectation is most frequently<br />

discussed in spatial terms—the elsewhere produced in the cinematic<br />

effect—it is equally important to interrogate the elsewhen.<br />

Jameson has dramatized the schizophrenia of the postmodern subject<br />

because "the ideal schizophrenic's experience is still one of time, albeit or<br />

the eternal Nietzschean present." 68 It is this subjective timelessness that provides<br />

an implicit parallel between the "postmodern condition" and cinematic<br />

and televisual spectatorship. But this subjective timelessness is not<br />

just a factor of diegetic temporality, it is a condition of the mobilized virtual<br />

gaze of spectatorship itself.<br />

POSTMODERNITY WITHOUT THE WORD A range of cultural diagnosticians have<br />

assessed related social and cultural effecrs of the technologies of the mechanical<br />

reproduction without relying on the terms modern and postmodern.<br />

THE END OF MODERNITY I 7|


How, for example, is postmodernity different from what the frequently<br />

dismissed sociologist Daniel Boorstin called the "Graphic Revolution"? In<br />

his 1961 book The Image: A Guide to Pseudo-Events in America, Boorstin<br />

assessed the impact of making, preserving, transmitting, and disseminating<br />

"images." 69 Although Boorstin does mention Benjamin, whose "The Work<br />

of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction" would seem to be the Urtext<br />

for such assessments, he nevertheless described a familiar loss of aura<br />

of the original. The Grand Canyon, Boorstin proclaimed, has become only<br />

a faint reproduction of the Kodachrome original. While not using semiotic<br />

terms, Boorstin posits the ascendance of a Kodachrome signifier, the inversion<br />

of the established sign-signifier relation, as a symptom of modernity.<br />

As an illustration of the reversed priority of the image, Boorstin coined the<br />

term pseudo-event for the photo-opportunity staging of image-determined<br />

"events."<br />

I Debord also diagnosed a similar impact of representation on culture<br />

without invoking the terms modernity or postmodernity. In his aphoristic<br />

Society of the Spectacle, Debord pronounces, "everything that was directly<br />

lived has moved away into a representation," and he describes the effects<br />

that this has on our concept of history and memory. In a section called<br />

"Spectacular Time," Debord describes the spectacle as:<br />

the present social organization of the paralysis of history and memory. . . . the<br />

abandonment of history built on the foundation of historical time, is the false<br />

consciousness of time. 70<br />

A "false consciousness of time" still implies that there is a "true" one, and<br />

that the mystifications of the society of the spectacle are a veil that can be<br />

somehow lifted. Debord and other Situationists elevated their own form<br />

of appropriation, detournement, as one of the ultimate counterstrategies.<br />

Baudrillard takes this same phenomenon—representation of the thing<br />

replacing the thing—and extends it into a mise en abyme of a "hyperreal"<br />

where signs refer only to signs. Hyperreality is not just an inverted relation<br />

of sign and signifier, but one of receding reference, a deterence operation<br />

in the signifying chain. "Body, landscape, time," writes Baudrillard in "The<br />

Ecstasy of Communication," "all progressively disappear as scenes." 71<br />

Committing his own detournement, Baudrillard does not mention Debord<br />

or any of the Situationists whose ideas he roundly appropriates. Baudrillardian<br />

theory abandons ideological analysis in irs move toward the hyper­<br />

real. In each stage of detournement, the loss of the referent seems to coin-<br />

cide with a waning of the political. Simply put, the representation of politics<br />

has been displaced by the politics of representation.<br />

Another media theorist, Joshua Meyrowitz, describes related cultural features.<br />

In his book No Sense of Place: The Impact of Electronic Media on Social<br />

Behavior, he claims:<br />

The evolution of the media had decreased the significance of physical presence<br />

in the experience of people and events. One can now be an audience to a<br />

social performance without being physically present; one can communicate<br />

"directly" with others without meeting in the same place. 72<br />

In this passage, Meyrowitz is outlining the effect that television has had on<br />

the "situational geography of social life." 73 Meyrowitz describes how electronic<br />

media reorganize social space, breaking down the boundaries<br />

between here and there, live and mediated, personal and public. To describe<br />

the social impact of these changes, Meyrowitz uses the word "homogenized,"<br />

a concept that implies a classless, genderless world where home,<br />

office, slum, and government building all have the same access to the world<br />

through the media. He maintains that the electronic media have not only<br />

reshaped our sense of "place," but have also blurred the boundaries between<br />

childhood and adulthood, and masculinity and femininity.<br />

In all of these cases, the media technologies dematerialize, deindividualize,<br />

decenter the subject. Without the word postmodern there is no need<br />

for periodization, a marked break dramatizing these changes. Yet without<br />

the word, these theorists are less concerned with the stylistic variances in<br />

cultural products than with the totality of cultural impact, the mode of<br />

reception determined entirely by the mode of production. 74<br />

Having examined the subjective changes produced by industrialized<br />

space and time—when the social configurations of the modern began—<br />

and by the types of experiences that were first commodified in the middle<br />

of the ni<strong>net</strong>eenth century, the subjectivity of the "postmodern condition"<br />

appears to be a product of the instrumentalized acceleration of these spatial<br />

and temporal fluidities. Postmodernity is marked by the increasing centralization<br />

of features implicit (from the start) in cinema spectatorship: the<br />

production of a virtual elsewhere and elsewhen, and the commodification<br />

of a gaze that is mobilized in both time and space.


Danny BIRCHALL: The Avant-Garde Archive Online. In: Film<br />

Quaterly,Vol. 63. University of California 2009, S. 12-14.


TALKING POINT DANNY BIRCHALL<br />

THE AVANT-GARDE ARCHIVE ONLINE<br />

The Inter<strong>net</strong> may have finally delivered avant-garde film­<br />

makers the audience they always claimed they wanted. With<br />

experimentation rejected by the moving-image industry, and<br />

moving image shunned by commercial art galleries until the<br />

1970s, film and video artists in the twentieth century relied<br />

on film festivals, grassroots film clubs, artist-run co-operatives,<br />

and art school curricula as channels of distribution. For any­<br />

one interested in avant-garde films outside the charmed<br />

circles of distribution in academia and a few metropolitan<br />

centres, it could be hard to see anything at all.<br />

Since broadband became a domestic reality, the pro­<br />

liferation of moving image online, including a substantial<br />

amount of archival material, has swelled to bewildering di­<br />

mensions. Even the most enthusiastic individual now has<br />

access to more than enough historical avant-garde film and<br />

video to reward their interest. For the audience, the problem<br />

now is less how to see it than where to begin, and how to<br />

organize, or even understand, it. For archives, co-ops, and<br />

filmmakers themselves, the question is whether a vast new<br />

audience for the work comes at an unacceptable cost to the<br />

integrity of the works themselves.<br />

Imagine that you decide to educate yourself in the his­<br />

tory of avant-garde film and video. Armed only with your<br />

home computer and broadband Inter<strong>net</strong> access, you sit<br />

down to spend an afternoon watching work that you've<br />

heard of but never seen. Searching YouTube, you easily<br />

find Fernand Leger's Ballet mécanique (1924). It's divided<br />

into two sections, but moving from part one to part two<br />

doesn't interrupt the film for more than a couple of sec­<br />

onds. There's even a fairly nuanced (for You Tube) debate in<br />

the comments section about the appropriateness of the use<br />

of George Antheil's soundtrack. It's been uploaded by some­<br />

one called "Andyfshito," whose other videos are a mixture of<br />

experimental films and live performances of trance music.<br />

More than 35,000 people have watched this particular<br />

upload.<br />

Looking for more, you find the whole of Dziga Vertov's<br />

Man With a Movie Camera (1929), split into nine parts. It<br />

looks like this has been taken from a commercial release: the<br />

rights-holders might not be too happy. You also locate<br />

Norman McLaren's Love on the Wing (1938) on the British<br />

Film Quaterly, Vol. 63, No. I, pps 12-14, ISSN 0015-1386, electronic ISSN 1533-8630.© 2009 by the Regents of the University of California.<br />

All rights reserved. Please direct call requests for permission to photocopy or reproduce article content through the University of Califorina Press's<br />

Rights and Permissions website, http://www.ucpressiournals.com/reprtnrinfo.osp. DOI: 10.1525/FQ.2009.63.1.12.<br />

FALL 2009<br />

Film Institute's YouTube channel. The High Definition ver­<br />

sion is recommended, and pretty good it is, too: the BFI have<br />

published this as a promotion for a compilation DVD of<br />

experimental and documentary films.<br />

Searching further afield, you find Stefan and Franciszka<br />

Themerson's The Eye and the Ear (1945) on Luxonline, a<br />

dedicated education resource for avant-garde film and video.<br />

Luxonline also provides plenty of biographical and back­<br />

ground information on the artists. Back on YouTube, there is<br />

a fragment of Stan Brakhage's Mothlight (1963): the quality<br />

is terrible, and there's no indication that what you're watch­<br />

ing isn't the complete film. The University of Westminster<br />

has been hard at work digitizing the Arts Council of England's<br />

collection of films, mostly documentaries on artists, but also<br />

a few experimental works. Malcolm Le Grice's Whitchurch<br />

Down (Duration) (1971) is among them, but it's too bad if<br />

you don't work at a British university, because although the<br />

catalogue is public, the works themselves are only available<br />

to users in the .ac.uk domain.<br />

Moving onto video art, UbuWeb has Bill Viola's Anthem<br />

(1983) in its totality; the image is good, and there are some<br />

contextual notes. There's also a compilation by Pipilotti Rist<br />

(1992-2003), but other than a list of the works, there's noth­<br />

ing more about Rist. Tank.tv is a relative newcomer as an<br />

artists' moving-image gallery, but archives all its presenta­<br />

tions, including a good number of works by Ken Jacobs and<br />

Ian White. Getting right up to the minute, on the Animate<br />

Projects website, you find a short by Apichatpong Weeraseth-<br />

akul, Phantoms of Nabua (2009), which is available in high<br />

quality complete with full credits, synopsis, artist's statement,<br />

production stills and sketches.<br />

Having watched all this, hopefully you'll you've had an<br />

entertaining afternoon and learned something about the evo­<br />

lution of avant-garde film and video. None of what you've<br />

seen has been hard to find, but the quality of both the mate­<br />

rial and context has been highly variable. While by reputa­<br />

tion you can trust Luxonline, YouTube doesn't even tell you<br />

when a film is incomplete (though the BFI's YouTube chan­<br />

nel can be considered reasonably authoritative). Perhaps<br />

more importantly, you've been responsible for your own edu­<br />

cation, from early European experiments to recent global<br />

video works. Nobody has given you a list of required watch­<br />

ing, and the works mentioned above arc merely a tiny frac­<br />

tion of what you could have watched.


Though the archive remains, inevitably, an incomplete<br />

and incoherent collection of fragments, the unprecedented<br />

level of availability has reconfigured these fragments.<br />

Institutional, educational, and informal channels of distribu­<br />

tion have been replaced by commercial, public, and personal<br />

channels. To understand the effects of this, it helps to look at<br />

the platforms and means by which it has become available:<br />

for some as a deliberate and concerted effort, for others as a<br />

side effect of the larger boom in online video.<br />

Like the rest of the Google empire, which provides<br />

aggregating and organizing functions through which adver­<br />

tising can be sold, YouTube itself isn't particularly interested<br />

in the nature of video content. Intellectual property rights<br />

have inevitably become an issue, but a combination of en­<br />

thusiasm on the part of individuals, and the limited resources<br />

of filmmakers and their estates, means that at any given time<br />

there will be an unknowable amount of historical avant-garde<br />

material available on YouTube. At the same time archives<br />

like the BFI and the National Film Board of Canada have<br />

established partnerships with YouTube to deliver high-quality<br />

legitimate archival content. This both reduces the costs of<br />

<strong>net</strong>worked distribution of the archive material, and attracts a<br />

larger audience than might otherwise be drawn through the<br />

organizations' own websites.<br />

While YouTube suits public organizations attempting to<br />

reach new audiences, the choice of the avant-garde connois­<br />

seur has always been UbuWeb. Less user-friendly than You­<br />

Tube, the film section greets you with a tightly set four-column<br />

list of over 350 artists and filmmakers in alphabetical order.<br />

Here you'll find everything from Dziga Vertov's early Russian<br />

Kino-Eye (1924) to Jean-Luc Godard's Dziga Vertov Group<br />

as well as Vito Acconci's discomfitingly intimate performance<br />

videos, Anthony Balch and William Burroughs's cut-up films,<br />

over forty short Fluxus films, Vicki Ben<strong>net</strong>t's sound-and-<br />

vision collages, and Stan YanDerBeek's stop-motion dada<br />

funnies, accompanied by a good number of related art docu­<br />

mentaries, audio interviews, and other sound pieces.<br />

Concrete poet Ken<strong>net</strong>h Goldsmith began UbuWeb in<br />

1996 as a repository for "lost" avant-garde poetic and sound<br />

works. UbuWeb's approach, summed up in the statement "if<br />

it's out of print, we feel it's fair game," has been largely wel­<br />

comed for these forms. Film and video have been more prob­<br />

lematic: the first UbuWeb film section rapidly disappeared<br />

after a slew of complaints. It reappeared, but Goldsmith and<br />

his collaborators took an aggressive approach to those who<br />

had requested removal of their work, listing them in a "hall of<br />

shame" for keeping their work out of the public domain.<br />

UbuWeb has since moderated its stance, and taken a more<br />

collaborative approach: some distributors, like Re:Voir work<br />

www.animateprojects.org<br />

artsonfilm.wmin.ac.uk<br />

www.canyoncinema.com<br />

LINKS<br />

expandedcinema.blogspot.com<br />

www.luxonline.org.uk<br />

www.mellart.com<br />

www.re-voir.com<br />

www.tank.tv<br />

www.twitter.com/ubuweb<br />

www.ubuweb.com<br />

www.youtube.com/bfifilms<br />

www.youtube.com/nfb<br />

with UbuWeb to make clips available. Nevertheless, many<br />

traditional distributors of artists' film continue to see UbuWeb<br />

as beyond the pale. One of the issues is what counts as "in<br />

distribution": for UbuWeb, the absence of an affordable<br />

DVD or VHS is sufficient license to make the work available<br />

online; whereas to the film co-ops, 16mm print-distribution<br />

libraries not only maintain an opportunity to see the films as<br />

they were intended to be seen, but also offer financial support<br />

to the artists and filmmakers themselves through a direct<br />

share of rental profits, an already fragile business model that<br />

stands to suffer from making artists' work available online.<br />

In summer 2009 I asked some of the traditional distribu­<br />

tors of avant-garde film what impact online video has had on<br />

their business. Dominic Angerame, director of long-standing<br />

Bay Area film co-op Canyon Cinema welcomes the Inter<strong>net</strong><br />

as the realization of the 1960s dream of a film projector in<br />

every home. What failed to happen with 16mm and even<br />

8mm, is now a reality for digital video: the work of film artists<br />

now reaches right into the home and classroom. However,<br />

"the threat of Ubu and YouTube to Canyon becomes when<br />

teachers of cinema ask their students to view the films being<br />

taught in the classroom on these sites," says Angerame. "It<br />

becomes a disservice to both the artist and the experimental<br />

film distributors both economically and aesthetically." Stu­<br />

dents don't see the work as it should be seen, and the artists<br />

fail to see any income from the screenings.<br />

In the U.K., however, the presence of public funding has<br />

allowed another venerable film co-op to make its work avail­<br />

able on its own terms. Heir to the London Film-makers' Co-op<br />

(LFMC) and London Video Arts archives, LUX embarked on<br />

an ambitious digitization project funded by lottery cash. The<br />

resulting website, Luxonline, provides access to a significant<br />

amount of digitized video including, but not limited to, the<br />

FILM QUARTERLY


LFMC archive. Many works are represented by clips, but you<br />

can also currently see complete works by the Themersons,<br />

Guv Sherwin, and one of George Barber's Scratch Video<br />

pieces. Luxonline's ambition has been matched by changing<br />

attitudes towards making digitized works available in their en-<br />

tiretv. "[We] started at a time when people were much more<br />

uncertain about putting work online, and we shared that un­<br />

certainty. Now we don't," LUX director Ben Cook tells me.<br />

Animate Projects makes the most of online technology to<br />

accompany the screen-based works it commissions, with pro­<br />

duction blogs and commentaries from artists illuminating<br />

the filmmaking process. An impressive back catalogue of<br />

nearly a hundred artists with an international flavor includes<br />

Young-hae Chang, Elodie Pong, and Joji Koyama. While<br />

born-digital work presents a challenge for many traditional<br />

film archives, Animate Projects treats the web as a fully-<br />

fledged channel of distribution and begins the archiving pro­<br />

cess before the work is even complete.<br />

LUX and Animate are exceptions; for the most part,<br />

what's online does not do justice to the source material.<br />

While the film industry's anti-piracy messages highlight the<br />

deterioration of quality in unauthorized images, its fear of<br />

file-sharing comes from the knowledge that for most feature<br />

films a single viewing in any medium is the deal done. In<br />

contrast, artists' film has more frequently been understood as<br />

experiential, and David Lynch's anti-cellphone tirade that<br />

"it's such a sadness that you think you've seen a film on your<br />

fucking telephone" (watch it on YouTube —"David Lynch<br />

on iPhone") reflects the sentiments of many filmmakers.<br />

Nevertheless, just as the ubiquity of digital media in­<br />

creases the perceived value of live music and performance, so<br />

the prevalence of avant-garde moving image online returns<br />

some of the original films' aura as artistic objects —intended<br />

to be seen in a certain way, but about which we can learn<br />

through other media. Cook suggests that an online education<br />

in avant-garde film and video would be akin to "studying art<br />

history and only looking at photos of paintings"; but a realiza­<br />

tion of the role of this kind of digital surrogate might be driv­<br />

ing a growing liberality in artists' and rights-holders' approach<br />

to allowing online versions of their work to be distributed.<br />

With such wealth to hand, what strategies can be ad­<br />

opted for making sense of the archive? One answer is to<br />

curate it yourself. YouTube and UbuWeb encourage the re-<br />

embedding of videos in your own website, and some writers<br />

and critics are taking advantage. Professional art curator Joao<br />

Ribas's Expanded Cinema blog emphasizes "an overlooked<br />

facet of the archival function of new media" in selecting indi­<br />

vidual artists' work for re-presentation and commentary. Poet<br />

and writer Marco Milone's Mellart blog focuses on anima­<br />

FALL 2009<br />

tion, presenting experimental abstract works by James<br />

Whitney and John Latham alongside newer films. Both blogs<br />

are driven by individual sensibility rather than any kind of<br />

curriculum or program, but nevertheless offer an informed<br />

narrative or sequence to follow.<br />

This combination of diffuse presentation and personal<br />

curation is the future of the avant-garde archive. The ease of<br />

access to the Inter<strong>net</strong> as a publication platform means that<br />

where possible artists, archives, and co-ops will continue to<br />

make their work available in their own context. As well as<br />

being decentralized, the avant-garde archive will certainly<br />

also remain incomplete. Large institutional film archives<br />

contain lacunae that speak of the discernment and prejudices<br />

of the collection's selectors; the distributed archive, having<br />

no remit or limit, will contain the holes of reluctance or sim­<br />

ple forgetting. Artists who are unwilling to see their work dig­<br />

itized or presented through aggregators like UbuWeb may<br />

find themselves written out of future canons. "Those film­<br />

makers who decide not to proceed in this way will risk the<br />

fate of not having the work viewed and possibly ignored by<br />

history," according to Angerame.<br />

Digital distribution and archiving are likely to be standard<br />

for funded artists. Artists whose films don't fit this model, or<br />

who work without funding or through informal organizations,<br />

may find it harder to find a secure berth for their works. But<br />

the archive of avant-garde film and video will remain some­<br />

thing different from its exhibition. As moving image continues<br />

to make inroads into the gallery's white cube, the conditions of<br />

its reception remain important; even the traditional black-<br />

cube film program will retain a correspondingly necessary in­<br />

tensity of experience. While traditional archives and co-ops try<br />

to provide reasonable access at the same time as preserving<br />

both the works and their own organizational integrity, the on­<br />

line archive may come to look something more like an art li­<br />

brary: a resource for reference rather than the works themselves.<br />

Through portals like UbuWeb, working without pro­<br />

grams or academic curricula, the public understanding of<br />

avant-garde film may change. The pleasures of being led give<br />

way to the pleasures of leading as we share new discoveries<br />

with each other throughout the spectrum from academic<br />

blogs to Twitter, pointing out the works we love, and feel are<br />

important. Profitable opportunities for extra-institutional cu­<br />

ration are no longer so severely limited by lack of access to<br />

material. Beyond the gallery and the screening room, the<br />

Inter<strong>net</strong> is where a popular audience for experimental film­<br />

making has at last been found.<br />

DANNY BIRCHALL lives, works, and writes in London.


BLOCK 1<br />

DEUTSCHLAND – ABSOLUTER/ABSTRAKTER FILM


DEUTSCHER ABSTRAKTER FILM<br />

Die Filmmatinee „Der Absolute Film“ 3. und 10. Mai 1925 in Berlin<br />

Deutscher abstrakter Film<br />

Filmavantgarde I/WS 2007/G. <strong>Jutz</strong><br />

Literatur:<br />

– Holger WILMESMEIER: Deutsche Avantgarde und Film. Die Filmmatinee „Der Absolute Film“ 3. nd 10. Mai 1925.<br />

Münster, Hamburg: LIT Verlag 1994.<br />

– Thomas MANK: Die Kunst des Absoluten Films. In: Sound & Vision – Musikvideo und Filmkunst. Katalog zur<br />

gleichnamigen Ausstellung im Deutschen Filmmuseum/Frankfurt/M. 1994, S. 73-87. [R]<br />

Der Zeitraum der ersten Experimente zum abstrakten Film: April 1921 – Ruttmanns Uraufführung von<br />

Opus 1 in Frankfurt bis 3. Mai 1925 mit der legendären Matinée „Der absolute Film“ im UFA-Palast<br />

in Berlin, wo Filme von Richter, Eggeling, Ruttmann u.a. wahrscheinlich mit Musikbegleitung<br />

vorgeführt wurden.<br />

Veranstaltet von der „Novembergruppe“ in Gemeinschaft mit der Kulturabteilung der UFA. Dieses<br />

inzwischen als legendär bezeich<strong>net</strong>e Ereignis war insofern herausragend, als erstmals, „Werke der<br />

absoluten Filmkunst einem breiteren Publikum zugänglich gemacht“ wurden. Bei einem Großteil der<br />

in diesem Programm enthaltenen Filme handelte es sich um Uraufführungen. Die ursprünglich als<br />

„einmalig“ geplante Veranstaltung wurde eine Woche später wiederholt (10. Mai 1925). Eine dritte<br />

Vorführung fand am 22. Mai 1925 abends in Hannover auf Einladung der Kestner Gesellschaft statt.<br />

Dies blieben die einzigen Vorführung abstrakter Filme in den 20er Jahren. Erst die späteren Musik­<br />

Tonfilme von Fischinger wurden von einem breiteren Publikum gesehen.<br />

Die Vorführungen gewinnen dadurch an Bedeutung, daß sie gleichzeitig den Höhepunkt und das jähe<br />

Ende der „absoluten Filmkunst“ darstellen. Zwar gab es auch nach 1925 weiterhin einen<br />

avantgardistischen Film in Deutschland, doch wurden die abstrakten Filmexperimente von Ruttmann,<br />

Eggeling, Richter u.a. zunächst nicht fortgesetzt. Bis auf wenige Filmkünstler, allen voran Oskar<br />

Fischinger, wandte man sich von der gegenstandslosen „Augenmusik“ ab und der abgefilmten<br />

Realität, z.B. dem Dokumentarfilm, zu.<br />

Für die Matinee in Berlin war folgendes Programm vorgesehen:<br />

1. Dreiteilige Farbensonatine Hirschfeld-Mack, Bauhaus Dessau<br />

Reflektorische Farbenspiele<br />

2. Film ist Rhythmus H ans Richter<br />

3. Symphonie Diagonale V iking Eggeling<br />

4. Opus 2, 3 und 4 W alther Ruttmann<br />

5. Images Mobiles (später: Ballet mécanique) Fernand Leger und Dudley Murphy<br />

6. Entr’acte Francis Picabia und René Clair<br />

Das Programm versammelte erstmals die Ergebnisse einer Filmkunst, die nicht literarischen<br />

Ursprungs war, sondern ihre Wurzeln in der bildenden Kunst hatte.<br />

Das Lichtspiel von Hirschfeld-Mack als einziger nicht-filmischer Beitrag der Matinee glich am<br />

ehesten einer musikalischen Darbietung. Die Matinee ist heute nur noch fragmentarisch<br />

nachzuvollziehen. Das Lichtspiel existiert nicht mehr. Es muß angenommen werden, daß alle Beiträge<br />

musikalisch begleitet wurden; in jener Zeit vor Einführung des Tonfilms hätte eine stumme<br />

Vorführung nicht der damaligen Kinopraxis entsprochen. Die Komposition von Paul Hindemith für<br />

Images Mobiles gilt als verschollen. Für die übrigen Filmbeiträge war vermutlich keine eigene Musik<br />

vorgesehen, möglicherweise wurden sie von Improvisationen begleitet.


„Das Drängen der expressionistischen Malerei nach Bewegung, die kinohafte Hastim<br />

rasenden Durcheinander der tausend Anspielungen eines futuristischen Bildes - diese<br />

ganze Unmöglichkeit, eine zeitliche Reihe von Vorgängen oder Assoziationen im räumli­<br />

chen Nebeneinander zu bannen: Sie findet in der neuen Filmkunst ihre Erfüllung - ihre<br />

Erlösung aus dem Raum in die Zeit. Die Malerei hat sich mit der Musik vermählt. Es gibt eine<br />

Augenmusik." 1<br />

Der Kunstkritiker Bernhard Diebold propagierte in der Ausgabe der Frankfurter<br />

Zeitung vom 2. April 1921 in seiner Rezension einer Projektion von Walther Ruttmanns<br />

LICHTSPIEL OPUS l einen neuen Begriff: die „Augenmusik des Films". Was er da auf einer<br />

Frankfurter Kinoleinwand sah, inspirierte ihn zu der Prophezeiung, daß „neben der<br />

Dichtung, der Musik, den bildenden Künsten und der Architektur künftig eine neue Kunst<br />

genannt werden muß."Diebold hat hier mit sicherem Instinkt für das Neue einen zentralen<br />

Begriff für die konstruktivistische deutsche Filmavantgarde der zwanziger Jahre geprägt. |<br />

Es gab einmal-zwischen den beiden Weltkriegen-in den zwanziger Jahren, als die<br />

Filme noch keine Tonspur hatten, eine Gruppe von Künstlern, die, alle von der Malerei<br />

herkommend, sich eine neueTechnik und ein neues Medium von Grund auf aneig<strong>net</strong>en und<br />

mit Hilfe dieser Technik eine neue Kunstform schufen. Die Redeistvon Walther Ruttmann,<br />

Viking Eggeling, Hans Richter, Oskar Fischinger und anderen. Ihr Medium war der Kinofilm,<br />

ihre Technik die Filmtechnik - präziser: die EinzeLbildaufnahme von grafischen Vorlagen<br />

oder Gegenständen mit Hilfe der 35-mm-Stummfilmkamera auf dem Tricktisch. Der<br />

Zeitraum, in dem dies geschah, läßt sich durch zwei historische Daten eingrenzen: den<br />

April 1921 mit der bereits erwähnten Uraufführung von Ruttmanns OPUS 1 in Frankfurt und<br />

den 3. Mai 1925 mit der Matinee „Der absolute Film" im UFA-PaLast in Berlin.<br />

Jene denkwürdige Matinee, in der unter anderem Filme von Richter, Eggeling,<br />

Ruttmann und in einer „Performance" die Reflektorischen Farbenlichtspiele von Hirsch-<br />

feld-Mack mit Musikbegleitung aufgeführt wurden, blieb die erste und einzige öffentliche<br />

Vorführung dieser konstruktivistischen Filme in den zwanziger Jahren. Eine Handvoll<br />

kurzer Filme, geschaffen von einer Handvoll Malerin einer Handvoll Jahre - die lediglich<br />

von ein paar Künstlerkollegen und Kritikern in ihrer Bedeutung erfaßt wurden - entfalte­<br />

ten via Zeitungsartikel und theoretischer Aufarbeitung eine nur sekundäre Wirkung. Erst<br />

die späteren Musik-Tonfilme von Oskar Fischinger aus den dreißiger Jahren, die auf dem<br />

Ideen- und Formenrepertoire der frühen Zwanziger aufbauten, wurden überhaupt von<br />

einem breiteren Publikum gesehen.<br />

Ruttmann und Richter- Eggeling starb bereits 1925 -wandten sich schon bald von<br />

einer freien künstlerischen Weiterentwicklung ihrer konstruktivistischen Filme ab und dem<br />

Werbefilm zu. Für den Bruch mit dieser autonomen Kunstform fehlt es nicht an Erklärun­<br />

gen. Da werden die Uraufführung von Eisensteins PANZERKREUZER POTEMKIN 1926 und der<br />

Einfluß der russischen Montagekunst als Gründe genannt, die französische Avantgarde<br />

und die „Weiterentwicklung" der am „absoluten Film" beteiligten Künstlerpersönlichkeiten<br />

ins Feld geführt. Der in meinen Augen ausschlaggebende Grund für die kurze Blüte dieser<br />

Kunstform war jedoch die Tatsache, daß keiner ihrer Schöpfer von diesen Filmen leben<br />

konnte, ja daß sie vermutlich nicht einmal einen Bruchteilihrer Kosten wieder eingespielt<br />

hatten.<br />

Dabei war der Einfluß dieser brotlosesten alLer Künste a Heine durch die Tatsacheihrer<br />

Existenz gewaltig. Die radikalen Positionen ihrer Schöpfer wurden überalL diskutiert, und<br />

die deutsche Filmindustrie begann schon bald damit, sich die Ergebnisse der von ein paar<br />

experimentierenden Filmemachern kostenlos gelieferten Grundlagenforschung zunutze


zu machen. Es galt ja in den zwanziger und dreißiger Jahren noch nicht die erst von Jonas<br />

Mekas und dem New American Cinema durchgesetzte moralisierende Trennung zwischen<br />

sogenanntem kommerziellem Kino und sogenanntem Underground. So schuf Ruttmann<br />

1924 für Fritz Langs NIBELUNGEN die abstrakte Sequenz des „Falkentraums". Bereits ab<br />

1922 realisierte er für Julius Pinschewer in Berlin kurze Werbefilme mit abstrakten<br />

Sequenzen für Excelsior-Reifen, für Kantorowicz-Likör, für die AEG und viele mehr. Auch<br />

Hans Richter produzierte nach eigenen Angaben zwischen 1926 und 1929 Werbefilme, von<br />

denen die meisten aber als verloren gelten. Erhalten sind ZWEIGROSCHENZAUBER (1928), ein<br />

Werbefilm für die Kölnische Illustrierte Zeitung, und ALLES DREHT SICH, ALLES BEWEGT SICH<br />

(1929), ein Werbefilm für die Produktions- und Verleihfirma Tobis. Oskar Fischinger<br />

arbeitete ab 1926 als Spezialist für Trickeffekte an mehreren Filmprojekten mit, unter<br />

anderem für die UFA.<br />

Daß der stolze Filmkünstler lediglich die unbezahlte Forschungsarbeit liefert,<br />

aber an der kommerziellen Nutzung seiner Ideen nicht mehr beteiligt ist, diese merk­<br />

würdige Aufgabenteilung existiert erst seit der erwähnten Trennung in Underground<br />

und Kommerz in den sechziger Jahren. Sie hat dazu geführt, daß das Millionengeschäft<br />

der Videoclips zu einem beträchtlichen Teil mit formalen Erfindungen aufgezogen<br />

wurde, die man aus den Experimentalfilmen der sechziger und siebziger Jahre „kosten­<br />

neutral" herausgetrennt hatte. Die aus dem Arsenal der Filmgeschichte entwendeten<br />

Fetzen - neben dem Experimentalfilm werden vor allem die frühen fantastischen Filme<br />

geplündert -hängt man dem jeweiligen Musik-Hit als eine Art maßgeschneiderte Aura<br />

um.<br />

Als Eggeling und Richter um 1920 den Plan zu einer „Bewegungskunst" faßten,<br />

gingen sie davon aus, daß die Techniker in den UFA-Studios die komplizierten Bewegungs­<br />

abläufe mitihrem Knowhow leicht ausführen könnten. Hans Richter berichtet: „Schließlich<br />

kam der Tag, an dem Major Gray uns die Erlaubnis gab, in der Trickabteilung der UFA bei<br />

Herrn Noldan zu arbeiten. Das taten wir auch mit durchaus negativem Erfolg. Der<br />

Techniker, dem wir ein Blatt, einen ,Akkord' in unserer Rolle, vorhielten, um ihn in<br />

Bewegung zu setzen, zeigte uns nur seine Verachtung. ,Damit ich Ihre Zeichnung in<br />

Bewegung setze, müssen Sie mir erst einmalzeigen, welche Figur anfängt, wann und wohin<br />

sie sich bewegt, wann und wohin sich die anderen bewegen, und wie schnell oder wie<br />

langsam, und dann: wann und wo sie verschwinden soll' Darauf hatten wir keine Antwort.<br />

Es zeigte sich mir mit brutaler Deutlichkeit, daß wir eben als Maler und nicht als Filmer<br />

gedacht hatten." 2<br />

Zum Glück haben Eggeling und Richter auch weiterhin als Maler gedacht und sich -<br />

wie Ruttmann und Fischinger- die analoge Aufzeichnungstechnik unter der Trickkamera<br />

selbst angeeig<strong>net</strong>. Und indem sie sich diese Technik aneig<strong>net</strong>en, lernten sie, mit ihr<br />

gestalterisch zu denken. Dieser Kooperation von ästhetischer und technischerlnnovation,<br />

wie sie auch Moholy-Nagy für die Arbeit am Bauhaus programmatisch gefordert hat<br />

- „Das traditionelle Bild ist historisch geworden und vorbei" 3 - verdanken wir ihre Filme.<br />

Viele, die heute mit den sogenannten Neuen Medien arbeiten, verzichten von vornherein<br />

darauf, sich diese oft sehr komplizierten Techniken selbst zu erarbeiten; sie verlassen sich<br />

auf die Programme der Techniker. Daß man aber, um in einem neuen Medium etwas<br />

Persönliches zu schaffen, mit seiner Technik denken lernen muß, diese einfache Grundre­<br />

gel ist auch heute noch in Kraft. Die Fülle von modischem Schnickschnack und die<br />

Hochstapeleien heutiger Computerkunst beweisen das.


Die Filme, von denen hier die Redeist, sind konstruktivistische Filme, sie glauben an<br />

eine Formensprache, die nicht mehr den Einzelnen, sondern ein Kollektiv ansprechen soll<br />

Es bestand in den zwanziger Jahren so etwas wie eineinternationale der Konstruktivsten,<br />

die sich an sozialistischen Ideen orientierte, ehe sich angesichts des heraufziehenden<br />

Stalinismus auch diese Utopie verflüchtigte. Die Vorstellung eines konstruktivistischen<br />

Meta-Raumes beherrschte das Denken der international arbeitenden Konstruktivsten, er<br />

materialisierte sich in den verschiedensten Werken an den verschiedensten Orten, in seiner<br />

Zeit-Dimension in den Filmen der Berliner Maler. Dieser konstruktivistische Meta-Raum<br />

ließ sich mathematisch-geometrisch definieren. In seinem Buch „Expressionismus und<br />

Film" - es erschien 1926, ein Jahr nach der berühmten Matinee im Berliner UFA-PaLast-<br />

beschreibt Rudolf Kurtz die Mathematik als Zentrum der neuen „absoluten Filme". Der<br />

Begriff „Expressionismus" im Titelist von heute aus gesehen irreführend, denn Kurtz de­<br />

finiert den absoluten Film streng konstruktivistisch: „ ... müssen die letzten Anklänge an<br />

individuelle Naturformen abgestreift werden und nurdie mathematischen Formen bleiben;<br />

denn die Mathematik ist die anschaulichste Form der Unbedingtheit. Das ist die Einstellung<br />

der ,absoluten Kunst'. Ihr Subjekt ist nicht mehr der im Atelier schaffende Künstler,<br />

sondern der kolLektive Mensch... Im Film ist dieses Programm von dem jüngst verstorbenen<br />

Viking Eggeling und von Hans Richter verwirklicht worden... Die elementaren Formen<br />

treten in Beziehung zueinander, und in dieser Komposition entfalten sich die Dramen des<br />

Geistigen... Die Psychologie ist restlos ausgeschaltet, durch bewußte Konstruktion er­<br />

setzt, durch aktive Arbeit des Geistes. Nach hundert Jahren klingt es wie die Neu­<br />

konzeption eines romantischen Satzes des Novalis: Das Leben der Götter ist Mathematik."''<br />

Aus heutiger Sicht scheint es so, als hätten sich die Maler Eggeling, Richter,<br />

Ruttmann, aLs sie sich nach dem Ersten Weltkrieg Gedanken über eine Ausweitung ihrer<br />

MaLerei in die Zeit-Dimension machten, nur notgedrungen des analogen Aufzeichnungs­<br />

verfahrens 35-mm-Kinofilm bedient; denn ihre konstruktivistischen Animationskonzepte<br />

ließen sich mit den Mitteln des Trickfilms trotz immensen Arbeitsaufwandes nur un­<br />

vollkommen realisieren. Moderne Computeranimationen von Lissitzky-Arbeiten beispiels­<br />

weise zeigen, wie dergleichen Animationskonzepte nach einer solchen Technologie<br />

verlangen, sie herausfordern. 5 Es handelt sich im Grunde genommen um einen typischen<br />

Fall von „zu früh/zu spät". Was heute in Archiven und Museen von diesen Filmen noch zu<br />

besichtigen ist, sind - analoge - Kopien von Kopien von Kopien von Kopien..., die die<br />

ursprüngliche Qualität der Streifen nur noch ahnen lassen. Es wäre an der Zeit, einige<br />

dieser Filme einmal mit der Hilfe hochauflösender Computer zu restaurieren. Auch gibt es<br />

von Hans Richter Notizen und theoretische Überlegungen zu einer Farbgestaltung seiner<br />

Filme, die ihm damals aus technischen Gründen noch nicht möglich war.<br />

Mich machtimmer wieder betroffen, in welchem Maße Computerkünstler heute ohne<br />

filmhistorische Kenntnisse arbeiten. Umso größer ist dann die Verblüffung und die<br />

Begeisterung, wenn ich bei einem der so beliebten Computer-Symposien diese alten<br />

zerkratzten Filme aus den zwanziger und dreißiger Jahren projiziere, von deren Existenz<br />

viele der Teilnehmer noch nie gehört haben. Zwischen diesem alten Medium und dem<br />

neuesten Medium stellt sich ein Arbeitszusammenhang her, der uns sowohl einen neuen<br />

Blick auf die Filmgeschichte als auch einen vorwiegend kritischen auf moderne Computer­<br />

animation vermittelt. Bei einer solchen Diskussion brachte ein Teilnehmer das Dilemma<br />

auf die einfache Formel: „Die hatten damals eine große formale und philosophische<br />

Kompetenz, aber nur eine unvollkommene Technik für die Umsetzung; wir haben eine<br />

fantastische Technik, aber ganz selten auch die formale und philosophische Kompetenz."


Bei diesen Projektionen erringt jedesmal ein später Film von Oskar Fischinger<br />

den größten Beifall. Sein Titel ist ALLEGRETTO. Fischinger schuf ihn 1936 in Amerika<br />

auf eine Musik Ralph Raingers. Er verweist die meisten computeranimierten Filme mit<br />

seiner Verbindung von Musik und Bild künstlerisch auf die Plätze, und zwar „mit nahe­<br />

zu unermüdlichem Erfindungsreichtum, mit herzlichem Humor und der heiteren Würde<br />

seines philosophischen Anliegens", wie es Fischingers Biograf William Moritz formuliert<br />

hat. 6<br />

Fischingers Filmarbeit begann in den Jahren 1921 bis 1926 mit den sogenannten<br />

WACHS-EXPERIMENTEN. Diese merkwürdigen Film-Stücke, die den meisten als ein skurriles<br />

Nebenprodukt in Fischingers Werk erscheinen, lassen sich von heute aus gesehen als eine<br />

Art systematischer Erforschung chaotisch-dynamischer Systeme interpretieren. Nur, daß<br />

der gelernte Ingenieur Fischinger dies nicht mit Hilfe der Mathematik unternahm, sondern<br />

in einer manuell-halbautomatischen, analogen Simulation mit der von ihm konstruierten<br />

Wachsschneidemaschine. Von diesen filmischen Versuchen sind mehrere hundert Meter<br />

Filmmaterial erhalten, die zum großen Teil noch nicht veröffentlicht sind. Im November<br />

1922 verkaufte Fischinger eine Lizenz für die Wachsschneidemaschine an Ruttmann, der<br />

diese Technik als optischen Effekt bei Lotte Reinigers Film DIE ABENTEUER DES PRINZEN<br />

ACHMED (1923-1926) einsetzte: In einem weitgehend vom Zufall gesteuerten Prozeß wird<br />

ein sich frei formendes Objekt aus Kaolin, feine Tonerde, in einen Wachsblock eingeschlos­<br />

sen. Dieses dreidimensionale, erstarrte chaotische Objekt übersetzt dann eine 35-mm-<br />

Kamera mittels Einzelbildaufnahme in das Zeitkontinuum des Films. Zu diesem Zweck<br />

schneidet die Maschine hauchdünne Scheiben von dem Wachsblock, wobei ein Kopplungs-<br />

mechanismusjeweils den Kameraverschluß auslöst. Bei der Projektion des Films entstehen<br />

Bildfolgen, die eine erstaunliche Ähnlichkeit mit computererzeugten Visualisierungen<br />

fraktaler Mathematik haben.<br />

Als der Lichtton um 1930 die Filmproduktion eroberte, ist er das bei weitem<br />

fortgeschrittenste Reproduktionsverfahren für den Ton. Bereits in den zwanziger Jahren<br />

hatte sich die Schallplattenindustrie des Tri-Ergon-Verfahrens bedient, um die Qualität<br />

ihrer Musikaufnahmen zu verbessern. Die Lichttonfilme dienten als AusgangsmateriaLfür<br />

die Übertragung auf die Schallplatte. Die Filmavantgarde, vor allem aber den Ingenieur<br />

Fischinger, faszinierte die schmale, neben den Bildern auf dem Filmstreifen aufgezeichne­<br />

te Lichttonspur, auf der sich mit einiger Übung nicht nur die Dynamik der aufgezeich<strong>net</strong>en<br />

Musiken, sondern auch einzelne Klangfarben anhand ihrer charakteristischen grafischen<br />

Merkmale bestimmen ließen. Instrumente und ihre einzelnen Töne ebenso wie Vokale der<br />

menschlichen Sprache waren damit optisch „lesbar". Hier tat sich für die Verbindung von<br />

Musik und Film ein neues Arbeitsfeld auf. Jetzt ließ sich der gezeich<strong>net</strong>e, abstrakte Film<br />

bis auf den hundertsten Teil einer Sekunde genau - wenn man die vier Perforationslöcher<br />

beim 35-mm-Film berücksichtigt- mit einer vorher auf einen Lichttonfilm aufgezeichne­<br />

ten Musik synchronisieren. Man mußte lediglich die leeren Bildfelder neben der Lichtton­<br />

spur fortlaufend numerieren, um einen perfekten Fahrplan für die Trickaufnahmen zu<br />

erhalten. Die Strukturen von Musik und Sprache ließen sich jetzt sehr genau untersuchen,<br />

ja man konnte auch, wie bereits 1929 der Münchener Trickfilmzeichner Rudolf Pfenniger<br />

mit seiner „tönenden Handschrift" bewiesen hatte, das Verfahren umkehren: Ein mit Hilfe<br />

von Schablonen hergestellter grafischer Ton verwandelte sich bei der Projektion des Films<br />

in ein völlig synthetisch hergestelltes Musikstück, beispielsweise 1932 in Offenbachs<br />

„Barcarole". Der erste Synthesizer! Auch Fischinger experimentierte 1932 mit syntheti­<br />

schem, gezeich<strong>net</strong>em Lichtton.


Auf der Grundlage des als Zahlenfolge in einen Trickfahrplan übertragenen Lichttons<br />

gelangen Fischinger in den dreißiger Jahren seine schönsten Filme wie KREISE (1933),<br />

KOMPOSITION IN BLAU (1935) oder ALLEGRETTO (1936). Es waren bereits Farbfilme im<br />

subtraktiven Drei-Farben-System, die er nach dem von ihm verbesserten Gasparcolor-<br />

Verfahren mit der Einzelbildkamera aufnahm. Die Choreographie der abstrakten Elemente<br />

schafft ein Beziehungssystem, in dem visuelle und akustische Bilder sich gegenseitig<br />

steigern und erhellen. In den vierziger 3ahren wurden Oskar Fischinger und seine Filme<br />

damit zum wichtigsten Bindeglied zwischen der deutschen Avantgarde und dem damals<br />

entstehenden amerikanischen Experimentalfilmkino der Westküste. „Eine Augenmusik<br />

konstruieren", das wollten auch die Brüder Whitney, Jordan Belson und viele andere. Aus<br />

dieser Tradition stammte das für dieses Kino typische synästhetische Bestreben, Farben,<br />

Formen und Musik „kosmisch" zu verbinden, bis hin zu seinen Auswirkungen auf Kubricks<br />

2001: A SPACE ODYSSEE (1968).<br />

Die Untersuchung der Beziehungen zwischen optischer und akustischer Musik ist<br />

auch heute noch ein Thema experimenteller Film- und Videoarbeit. So beruhen beispiels­<br />

weise Klaus Wybornys Augenmusik-Konstruktionen auf der musikalischen Organisation<br />

von Folgen einzeln aufgenommener Bilder. Die Struktur dieser Sequenzen gibt eine<br />

Klavierkomposition Wybornys vor, die ein Computer in Bezug auf Dynamik und Tonhöhe<br />

auswertet und in eine Aufnahmepartitur als Fahrplan umwandelt. Bestimmte Tonhöhen<br />

sind bestimmten Farbfiltern zugeord<strong>net</strong>. Eine einfache Elektronik programmiert die Super-<br />

8-Kamera nach dieser Partitur und erlaubt dem Filmemacher innerhalb der vorgegebenen<br />

Strukturen eine Reihe von „Improvisationen". Die einzelnen, den Filmstreifen entspre­<br />

chenden, Stimmen werden schließlich auf einer optischen Bank übereinanderkopiert.<br />

Mir scheint, daß die neuere Computerkunst an der strengen Konstruktion von<br />

Augenmusik zur Zeit weniger interessiert ist. Vielmehr wendet man alle technische und<br />

künstlerische Innovation für interaktive Installationen auf, die vorgefundenes oder<br />

zufälliges Bildmaterial in Töne umsetzen beziehungsweise Töne Bilder generieren lassen.<br />

Aus der Sicht des Musikers geht es hierbei um die Erfindung von „Musikinstrumenten", aus<br />

der Sicht des Malers um die Erforschung von „Bildinstrumenten". Die autonome Konstruk­<br />

tion von Augenmusik scheint an die Existenz bestimmter künstlerisch-philosophischer<br />

Grundüberzeugungen gebunden zu sein, wie sie uns die konstruktivistischen Filme der<br />

zwanziger Jahre vor Augen führen.


Am Sonntag, dem 3. Mai 1925, fand im UFA-Theater auf dem Berliner Kurfürstendamm<br />

vormittags um 11.30 Uhr die legendäre Matinee „Der Absolute Film" statt, organisiert von<br />

der Novembergruppe und der Kulturabteilung der UFA. Die ursprünglich als „einmalig"<br />

geplante Veranstaltung wurde eine Woche später wiederholt. Eine dritte Vorführung fand<br />

am 22. Mai 1925 abends in Hannover auf Einladung der Kestner-Gesellschaft statt. Zur<br />

Aufführung kamen sieben Filme und ein Lichtspiel:<br />

Ludwig Hirschfeld-Mack: Dreiteilige Farbensonatine<br />

Hans Richter: Film ist Rhythmus<br />

Viking Eggeling: Symphonie Diagonale<br />

Walther Ruttmann: Opus 2, 3 und 4<br />

Fernand Leger/Dudley Murphy: Images mobiles<br />

Francis Picabia/Rene Clair: Entr'Acte<br />

Das Programm versammelte erstmals die Ergebnisse einer Filmkunst, die nicht<br />

literarischen Ursprungs war, sondern ihre Wurzeln in der Bildendenden Kunst hatte. Das<br />

Lichtspiel von Hirschfeld-Mack als einziger nichtfilmischer Beitrag der Matinee glich am<br />

ehesten einer musikalischen Darbietung.<br />

Die Matinee ist heute nur noch fragmentarisch nachzuvollziehen. Das Lichtspiel<br />

existiert nicht mehr, abgesehen von dem Vorderteil des Lichtspielapparates und einiger<br />

Partiturzeichnungen. Es muß angenommen werden, daß alle Beiträge musikalisch beglei­<br />

tet wurden; in jener Zeit vor der Einführung des Tonfilms hätte eine stumme Vorführung<br />

nicht der damaligen Kinopraxis entsprochen. Ein Foto von der Vorführung des Lichtspiels<br />

zeigt Hirschfeld am Klavier, seine Partitur für die Farbensonatine ist in Teilen erhalten<br />

Die Kunst des Absoluten Films<br />

73<br />

Ludwig Hirschfeld-<br />

Mack, Lichtspiel-<br />

apparat, Vorderteil,<br />

1925/63


Teilen erhalten, während die Komposition von Paul Hindemith für BALLET MECANIQUE<br />

(= IMAGES MOBILES) als verschollen gilt. Für die übrigen Filmbeiträge war vermutlich keine<br />

eigene Musik vorgesehen, möglicherweise wurden sie von Improvisationen begleitet. Für<br />

diese Annahme spricht, daß Walther Ruttmann bei späteren Aufführungen beispielsweise<br />

den Maschinenton des Projektors in den Zuschauerraum übertragen ließ.<br />

Die Veranstaltung und die Wiederholung waren bereits durch den Vorverkauf voll­<br />

ständig ausverkauft, bei einem Fassungsvermögen von 900 Sitzplätzen. Die Reaktionen<br />

des Publikums auf die Matinee war teilweise recht heftig, entsprechend reagierte die Kritik<br />

bisweilen sarkastisch: „Die Leute fielen buchstäblich vom Stuhl- wenn auch nicht gleich." '-<br />

Im Kunstblatt findet man eine ausführliche Besprechung der Veranstaltung von Willi<br />

Wolfrad, in der unter anderem zu lesen steht: „Vollends Hans Richters eingebungsloses<br />

Gestammel ist nur geeig<strong>net</strong>, die gesamte Bestrebung zu diskreditieren." 2 Zu Ruttmanns<br />

Film schrieb Rudolf Arn heim: „Die absoluten Formen gebärden sich sehr menschlich, womit<br />

sie zwar die Absicht ihres Schöpfers stark überschritten, dafür aber aufgekratzte Stimmung<br />

erzeugten...". 3 Hirschfelds Farbensonatine, die, auch wenn sie ohne Musikbegleitung<br />

vorgeführt worden wäre, musikalisch wirkt, erweckte bei manchen Kritikern mehr Interes­<br />

se. So wurde die Farbensonatine in den kritischen Rezensionen der Tagespresse zwar als<br />

„ein gelungenes Experiment, vielleicht eine Spielerei ohne Entwicklung, aber interes­<br />

sant" 4 bezeich<strong>net</strong> und man rühmte in der Regel die differenzierten Variationen der<br />

farbigen Formen und ihre Wirkung auf den Betrachter. 5<br />

Eine Rede von Dr. Edgar Beyfuß, Dramaturg des Kulturfilmressorts der UFA, eröff<strong>net</strong>e<br />

die Berliner Matinee. Die UFA, zu diesem Zeitpunkt noch nicht vom nationalistischen<br />

Medienzaren Hugenberg übernommen und durchaus liberal gesonnen, was die organisatori­<br />

sche Zusammenarbeit mit der sozialistischen Novembergruppe ermöglichte, förderte


ereits 1921 die ersten Filmexperimente von Richter und Eggeling. Rudolf Kurtz, damaLs<br />

Leiter des Kulturfilmressorts und Vorgänger von Dr. Beyfuß, veröffentlichte 1926 das erste<br />

Buch über jene neue Kunst mit dem Titel „Expressionismus und Film". Auch nach 1925<br />

beauftragte die UFA Künstler wie Ruttmann oder Oskar Fischinger mit der Ausführung von<br />

Spezialeffekten für Kultur-, Dokumentär- und Spielfilme. Von der Förderung der Künstler<br />

erwartete sie sich unter anderem auch die Entwicklung neuer Animations- und Trick­<br />

techniken.<br />

Die Novembergruppe war ein Zusammenschluß bildender Künstler und Architekten<br />

als Reaktion auf die Novemberrevolution von 1918, in deren Folge der deutsche Kaiser<br />

abgedankt hatte und die Republik ausgerufen worden war. Gegründet Ende 1918 in Berlin,<br />

etablierte sich die Novembergruppe rasch. Ihr gehörten zahlreiche in- und ausländische<br />

Künstler an, darunter Raoul Hausmann, Hannah Hoech und Hans Richter. „Schließlich<br />

bildeten besonders die Bauhausmeister und einige ihrer Schüler einen festen Bestandteil<br />

der Novembergruppe. Zu ihnen gehörten Walter Gropius, Oskar Schlemmer, Lyonel<br />

Feininger, Wassily Kandinsky, Laszlo Moholy-Nagy, Paul Klee, Johannes Itten, Georg<br />

Muche, Nicholai Wassilief, Vincent Weber und Werner Graeff. Zwischen Weimar - später<br />

Dessau - und Berlin bestand ein reges Hin und Her." 5 Die Künstler wollten mit dem Volk<br />

zusammenarbeiten, an allen öffentlichen und staatlichen Arbeiten beteiligt werden,<br />

lehnten aber den Staat ab. Die Idee anonymer Werke wurde diskutiert, die Bilder sollten<br />

nur monogrammiert werden. 6 Kern der Gruppe war das Berliner Aktionskomitee, dem sich<br />

neben einzelnen Künstlern auch andere Gruppen wie beispielsweise „De Stijl" in Holland<br />

als sogenannte Ortsgruppen anschlössen.<br />

Obgleich die Betitelung der Matinee sich offensichtlich am Begriff der Absoluten<br />

Kunst orientierte, muß bereits hinsichtlich der Auswahl der verschiedenen Beiträge an der<br />

Eindeutigkeit dieses Begriffes gezweifelt werden. Für die deutschen Beiträge gilt das Wort<br />

von Rudolf Kurtz: „Das ProbLem des Absoluten ist eine Frage der Metaphysik. Sie ist<br />

gleichbedeutend mit dem Problem des Gesetzes, als der allgemeinsten Aussage. Die<br />

absoluten Künstler sind hierdurch in die Zwangslage gebracht, daß sie zu ihren Schöpfun­<br />

gen eine Weltanschauung mit verabreichen müssen." 7 Weltanschauungen gab es zahlrei­<br />

che, so daß die Betitelung der Matinee aus heutiger Sicht eher als Subsumtion der<br />

unterschiedlichen Tendenzen der zeitgenössischen Avantgarde verstanden werden muß,<br />

innerhalb derer der Absolute FiLm als Fallbeispielim Diskurs um eine neue ki<strong>net</strong>ische Kunst<br />

besteht.<br />

Kandinsky verstand 1910 unter der Verbindung zweier Künste, der Malerei und der<br />

Musik, den Vorbildcharakter der Musik als einerungegenständlichen, reinen Kunstfüreine<br />

ebensolche neue Malerei. Die Filmkünstler übernahmen die musikalische Terminologie<br />

ganz direkt, wenn sie mit dem FiLm ebenso direkt rhythmische Vorgänge in der Malerei auf<br />

die Zeit ausdehnten. Das Ziel war die auf einfachen Linearen Elementen beruhende<br />

Formensprache nach den Regeln eines bildnerischen Kontrapunkts. In den frühen Zeich­<br />

nungen Eggelings läßtsich der Weg seiner abstrakten Formen zurückverfolgen: Ursprüng­<br />

lich NaturdarstelLungen, wurden diese immer weiter reduziert zu scheinbar rein ornamen­<br />

talen Elementen, deren eigentliche Funktion die eines universellen Alphabets werden<br />

sollte. Die Suche nach einem „Generalbaß der Malerei" kündete ebenso vom Bezug zur<br />

Musik, insbesondere derjenigen Bachs, wie zu Goethes Farbenlehre, worin dieser als<br />

ÄquivaLent für die Harmonie in der Musiklehre Ähnliches für die Farbenlehre suchte. Die<br />

Vorstellung von einer universellen Sprache findet sich auch in den Ideen der De-Stijl-<br />

Gruppe um Theo van Doesburg und Konzepten der Konstruktivsten.<br />

Die Kunst des Absoluten FiLms<br />

75


Aus der Synthese unterschiedlicher Prinzipien sollte eine Formsprache entwickelt<br />

werden, die anwendbar sei auf alle Bereiche der Kunst. So schrieb Hans Richter 1921 in De<br />

Stijl IV: „Die ästhetischen Prinzipien des Alphabets zeigen den Weg zum Gesamtkunstwerk,<br />

und zwar deswegen, weil diese Prinzipien, derer man sich undogmatisch synthetisch<br />

bedient, nicht nur für die Malerei maßgebend sind, sondern in gleichem Maße für Musik,<br />

Sprache, Tanz, Architektur, Schauspiel." 8 Wie fern dabei aber Richter und Eggeling dem<br />

Medium Film geblieben waren, wie verhaftet doch der klassischen Malerei, zeigt sich an den<br />

fehlgeschlagenen Versuchen, ihre grafischen Entwürfe direkt auf das Filmmaterial zu<br />

übertragen. Ohnejede technische Erfahrung, ohne die Erkenntnis der Gesetzmäßigkeiten<br />

dieses technischen Mediums, erwies sich die große Zahl einzeln zu zeichnender Bild­<br />

sequenzen als enormes Hindernis.iUm die gewünschte Wirkung auf der Leinwand zu<br />

entfalten, durften die einzelnen Zeichnungen nur minimal voneinander abweichen, umso<br />

in der Abfolge eine kontinuierliche Abfolge der Formen zu erreichen. Nach einem Bericht<br />

Theo van Doesburgs, der Eggeling und Richter Weihnachten 1920 in ihrem gemeinsamen<br />

Aufenthaltsort Klein-Kölzig besuchte, waren für diese ersten Versuche rund 300 Einzel­<br />

bilder vorhanden. Legt man 16 Bilder pro Sekunde als Frequenz zugrunde, so entspricht<br />

das einer Vorführdauer von lediglich 18 Sekunden! Ein weiteres Problem stellte die<br />

Vergrößerung der Zeichnungen dar, die sich in der Projektion zwangsläufig ergab. Auch<br />

wenn die Zeichnungen exakt angefertigt zu sein schienen, macht die Vergrößerung noch<br />

die kleinsten Feh leraufder Leinwand sichtbar. Nach mehr als einem Jahr verwarfen Richter<br />

und Eggeling die Ergebnisseihrergemeinsamen Arbeitais ungenügend. Teile des Materials<br />

verwendete Richter später in seinem Film RHYTHMUS 21.


Eine Zäsur brachte 1922 die Bekanntschaft Richters mit dem damals zwanzigjährigen<br />

Bauhausschüler Werner Graeff. Ihm kommt das Verdienst zu, als erster im metrischen<br />

Charakter des Mediums die Grundlage für die konsequente Entwicklung einer visuellen<br />

Musik erkannt zu haben. „Im Gegensatz zu Eggeling und Richters Rollen waren meine von<br />

vornherein als wirkliche Partituren entworfen; daher können sie auch nicht im beliebigen<br />

Tempo vor- oder rückwärts gerollt werden. Gerade weil diese Kollegen bis 1922/23<br />

filmtechnisch nicht zurecht kamen, schlug ich ihnen vor, man müsse sich mit dem<br />

Tricktisch-Operateur über eine eindeutige ,Notenschrift' verständigen; und vor allem: sie<br />

müßten in ihren Entwürfen radikal einfacher werden, wenn sie technisch zurechtkommen<br />

wollten. Denn bis dahin hatten sie nur Mißerfolge." 9<br />

Mit den Partituren für seine Filme KOMPOSITION 1/22 und KOMPOSITION 11/22 demon­<br />

strierte er die Möglichkeit von Film in Form einer quasi-musikalischen Notation, der die<br />

Gegebenheiten der Projektion zugrunde liegen: Die Maße des querliegenden Bildfensters<br />

verwendete Graeff als Berechnungsgröße für die Takteinheit, ebenso orientieren sich die<br />

einfachen Motive - Quadrat, Rechteck, Linie und Punkt - an den Maßen des Projektions­<br />

fensters. Thema ist die Variation des Zeitmaßes, das Ab- und Zunehmen der Formen im<br />

Dreiviertel-Takt. Damit gelang es Graeff, tatsächlich musikalische Gesetzmäßigkeiten auf<br />

den Film anzuwenden, indem er dessen Vorgaben in die Konzeption mit einbezog. Wegen<br />

Geldmangels konnte Graeff die Partituren seinerzeit nichtin Film umsetzen und holte dies<br />

erst fünfzig Jahre später nach.<br />

Hans Richter, Studie<br />

zu „Präludium", 1919


Graeffs Einfluß, insbesondere auf Richter, geht über die bloße technische Hilfestel­<br />

lung hinaus. Vergleicht man die früheren Entwürfe Richters für eine Filmpartitur, ist die<br />

Ähnlichkeit mit Arbeiten Eggelings unverkennbar; es dominieren die komplizierten<br />

geschwungenen Linienverläufe, die sich auch in Eggelings Diagonalsinfo nie wiederfinden.<br />

Die Bearbeitung der Fläche, die für die Richter-Filme typisch ist, tritt hier noch nicht in<br />

Erscheinung. Anders dagegen die Partiturrolle „Rhythmus 23" von 1923. Hiermit kam er<br />

nicht nur den Partituren von Graeff näher, sondern es finden sich auch Ähnlichkeiten mit<br />

dessen freien Arbeiten. Zufällige Synchronitäten einmal ausgeschlossen, verweist das<br />

Verhältnis beider Künstler auf den Einfluß des Bauhauses, namentlich Laszlo Moholy-<br />

Nagys und Theo van Doesburgs, beides die wichtigsten Lehrer Werner Graeffs.<br />

Für Walther Ruttmann, derin Bezug auf theoretische Äußerungen zu seinen Filmen<br />

eher zurückhaltend war und im Unterschied zu Richter und Eggeling die Filmtechnik<br />

praktisch beherrschte, „gehört die Kinematographie ... unter das Kapitel der bildenden<br />

Künste, und ihre Gesetze sind am nächsten denen der MaLerei und des Tanzes verwandt." 10<br />

Nach den ersten Filmversuchen 1919 gab er die Malerei auf und wurde Filmemacher, das<br />

heißt, er eig<strong>net</strong>e sich die technischen Voraussetzungen des Filmemachens an, entwarf<br />

eigene Verfahren zur Herstellung und Kolorierung von Trickfilmen. Zwar galt Ruttmanns<br />

Hans Richter,<br />

„Rhythmus 23", 1923


Laszlo Moholy-Nagy,<br />

Lichtrequisit einer<br />

elektrischen Bühne,<br />

1930<br />

künstlerisches Interesse weiterhin der Fläche, doch ermöglichte es der Film, diese Fläche<br />

durch die Zahl der Einzelbilder zu multiplizieren, um ein Motiv in einer zeitlichen Abfolge<br />

zu gestalten. Das Medium blieb dabei ein Mittelzum Zweck und hatte aus sich heraus keine<br />

unmittelbare künstlerische Bedeutung. „Es handelt sich gewöhnlich darum, Vorgänge, die<br />

jenseits des Sichtbaren liegen, denen ein unwirklicher Charakter anhaftet, in eine bildlich<br />

wirksame, der Tageswelt enthobene Form ausdrücken." ll Ruttmann war neben Oskar<br />

Fischinger der einzige der Film-Künstler, der tatsächlich auch Filmemacher war. So wie der<br />

Maler um Farbe und PinseL wissen muß, um seine künstlerischen Ideen optimal umsetzten<br />

zu können, muß auch der „Filmbildner", wie Ruttmann sich nannte, sein Handwerkszeug<br />

beherrschen.<br />

Mit der Matinee und ihren beiden Wiederholungen erlebte der Absolute Film seinen \<br />

ersten und letzten Höhepunkt. Allen Beiträgen gemeinsam ist die Weigerung, narrativ<br />

sein im Sinne des literarischen Films, wie er sich zu dieser Zeit bereits als Kunst-Kino<br />

allgemein etabliert hatte. Na.ch^l925 wendete die Kritik den Begriff „Absoluter Film"nur<br />

noch auf die Filme Oskar Fischingers an. Fischinger hatte bis zu seiner Übersiedlung nach<br />

Hollywood 1936 mit seinen Arbeiten großen Erfolg in Deutschland, wo sie als Inbegriff des<br />

abstrakten Films galten. Gleichzeitig waren seine Werbefilme, beispielsweise für die<br />

Zigarettenmarke Muratti, beim Publikum so beliebt, daß Kinobesitzer damit in ihren<br />

Anzeigen warben. Die konkrete Fortführung im Sinne einer in haltlichen Bearbeitung erfuhr


der Absolute Film im Rahmen der ki<strong>net</strong>ischen Gestaltung durch Laszlo Moholy-Nagy, deren<br />

Höhepunkte 1930 das Objekt „Licht-Raum-Modulator" und der Film LICHTSPIEL SCHWARZ-<br />

WEIß-GRAU darstellen.<br />

Der heute kaum noch gebräuchliche und in seiner vielfachen Deutbarkeit mißver­<br />

ständliche Begriff des Absoluten wurde bereits von den Künstlern der zeitgenössischen<br />

Avantgarde hinsichtlich der Bedeutung des einfachsten gemeinsamen Merkmals „Gegen­<br />

standslosigkeit" unterschiedlich interpretiert. Laszlo Moholy-Nagy bezeich<strong>net</strong>e mit der<br />

absoluten Malerei die „Beziehungs- und Spannungsverhältnisse" von Formen, Farben,<br />

Helligkeitswerten, Lagen, Richtungen, deren „biologische Funktion allen Menschen grund­<br />

sätzlich zugänglich sei durch den gemeinsamen fysiologischen Apparat". 12 Stilistische<br />

Unterschiede in der Kunst verschiedener Perioden verbLeiben für Moholy-Nagy letztlich<br />

„zeitliche Formveränderungen derselben Erscheinung". Ein Bild wirkt „schon durch die<br />

Harmonie seiner Farben und Hell-Dunkelverhältnisse". Zwar könne in dieser Weise ein<br />

Kunstwerk, gleich welcher Epoche angehörig, „genügende Werte für die malerische<br />

Beurteilung bieten". Aber es würden zur Erkenntnis des Wesens eines Kunstwerkes auch<br />

seine Darstellungsabsichten hinzugehören. „Nur in dem untrennbar waren Zusammen­<br />

hang von Farbigkeit und Darstellungsabsicht dokumentiert sich sein Wesen. Doch ist es<br />

uns wohl möglich, mit Hilfe des Begriffs: ,absolute Malerei' manche von den Komponenten<br />

auseinanderzuhalten, welche auf die elementaren Spannungsverhältnisse und die, welche<br />

auf die zeitbedingte Form zurückzuführen sind." Absolute Malerei als vom Zwang des<br />

AbbiLdens befreite Kunst bezieht sich hier auf die Auseinandersetzung mit den ursächli-


chen Elementen bildnerischen Komponierens: „Dem Welt-Interesse und Welt-Gefühl<br />

entsprechend" treten an die Stelle der anachronistischen malerischen Darstellungs­<br />

methoden die „mechanischen Darstellungsverfahren". Beides gemeinsam findet sich<br />

gleichwertig wieder in der „optischen Gestaltung". 13<br />

Malerei mit Zeit - so Walther Ruttmann über seine Filme - war auch die Auseinan­<br />

dersetzung mit neuen Technologien und Medien, die nicht nur über die Künstler vehement<br />

hereinbrachen. Dort, wo mit der absoluten KunstderVersuch gemacht wurde, an die Stelle<br />

der Narration die Logik der Konstruktion zu setzen, war das Kunstwerk dem tradierten<br />

Verständnis eines breiten Publikums entzogen, das auf der optischen Wiedererkennung als<br />

Zugang zum Kunstwerk angewiesen war. Diesem Dilemma setzten die Künstler ihre<br />

Erwartung einer Bewußtseinsveränderung im Zuge des erhofften politischen Wandels zu<br />

einer neuen Gesellschaft entgegen und betrachteten ihre Kunst als Teil eines neuen<br />

Ganzen, in dem die Kunst nicht mehr dem Einzelnen vorbehalten sein würde, sondern als<br />

Teil des Ganzen gestaltend wirksam wäre. In diesem Sinne wollte der Künstler seLbst nicht<br />

mehr länger das schöpferisch-geniale Individuum der bürgerlichen Kultur sein, sondern<br />

sich dem Anspruch hingeben, als Teil das Ganze mitzugestalten. „Darum geben wir den<br />

Individualismus auf " schrieb Werner Graeff 1922.<br />

Als am 22. Mai 1925 in Hannover das Programm der Matinee auf Einladung der<br />

Kestner-Gesellschaft in einer Nachtvorstellung gezeigt wurde, hielt der Künstler Friedrich<br />

Vordemberge-Gildewart einen einführenden Vortrag. Vordemberge-Gildewart, zu jener<br />

Zeit 26 Jahre alt, hatte 1924 bereits die „Gruppe K" - das K steht für Konstruktivismus -<br />

gegründet und eine erste erfolgreiche Ausstellung in der Kestner-Gesellschaft organisiert.<br />

Er war Mitglied der „Abstrakten Hannover" und stand 1925 am Beginn einer Karriere als<br />

Maler, Architekt und Designer. „Für eine absolute Kunst", lautete denn auch das Thema.<br />

Im Mittelpunktder Ausführungen stand die Forderung nach einernotwendigen Erneuerung<br />

des klassischen Kunstbegriffs im Sinne des „elektrischen Jahrhunderts". Ähnlich wie<br />

Moholy-Nagy definierte Vordemberge-Gildewart das Kunstwerk primär aus seiner Erschei­<br />

nung heraus; die Form ist zugleich der Inhalt, denn auf das „Was kommt es nicht an,<br />

sondern auf das Wie". 15 Dabei ist der Anspruch des „AbsoLuten", Gedanke und Material in<br />

einer „reinen Form" zusammenzubringen, ohne dabei auf einen anderen als den material­<br />

immanenten Zustand hinweisen zu wollen, die Überführung der gegenstandslosen Kunst<br />

hin zu einer „inhalts-losen" Gestaltung. „Die wirklich absolute Kunst allerdings kennt<br />

keinen Inhalt." 16 Wo für Kandinsky die abstrakte Kunst eine zeitgemäße Äußerung des<br />

Subjekts blieb als Ausdruck des schaffenden Geistes, wird das Kunstwerk auf seine<br />

materielle Ordnung und das physiologische Vermögen seines Betrachters reduziert: „Denn<br />

hierin gibt es eben nur ein Hören, Betrachten, Sehen und dergleichen." 17 Wo Form und<br />

Inhalt identisch sind und aus der Kunst zugleich Gestaltung wird, scheint das Prinzip<br />

allgegenwärtig und anwendbar auf alle Bereiche des Lebens: eine absolute Gestaltung.<br />

Schon 1922 hatte Werner Graeff geschrieben: „Wir schaffen das Gesamtkunstwerk. Die<br />

Zusammenarbeit von Architektur und Plastik und Malerei (gemeinsam) mit Industrie und<br />

Technik, Leben." 18<br />

Auch das Selbstverständnis des Künstlers paßt sich dem an. Er will nicht mehr das<br />

Genie im Sinne eines bürgerlichen Ideals sein, dessen Eingebungen letztlich quasi-<br />

reLigiöser Natur sind, sondern der heutige GestaLter. Theo van Doesburg nennt den neuen<br />

Künstlertyp in einem Aufsatz aus dem Jahr 1924 den modernen Konstrukteur und Walter<br />

Gropius forderte 1916 „Architekten, Bildhauer, Maler, wir alle müssen zum Handwerk<br />

zurück! ... Der Künstler ist eine Steigerung des Handwerkers." 19


Für den „heutigen Gestalter" sind die traditionellen Mittel der Kunst nicht mehr<br />

ausreichend: „Viel zu gefühlvoll! Zu sehr Valeur!" 20 Um erfolgreich arbeiten zu können,<br />

muß der Künstler diese Mittel in ihrer Bedeutung neu bewerten. „So ist Farbe zwar ein<br />

gewaltiges Mittel, aber für den heutigen Gestalter nicht mehr befriedigend." Einzig ab<br />

Kontrast gestattete Vordefnberge-Gildewart der Farbe eine künstlerische Funktion. „Hier­<br />

zu kommt das Moment der Bewegung." Der fragwürdige Begriff vom Gesamtkunstwerk<br />

erhieltin einer absoluten Gestaltung eine neue Bedeutung. Wichtigist dieäußere Form des<br />

Werkes ebenso wie sein Zustand, die Präsentation und die Funktion mit dem Ziel, „den<br />

Raum endgültig zur dynamischen Spannung zu bringen..." 21<br />

Diese dynamische Spannung des Raumes ist für eine absolute Gestaltung von<br />

zentraler Bedeutung; Vordemberge-Gi Idewart differenzierte zwischen einem tatsächlichen<br />

Raum, dessen Begrenzungen beispielsweise durch Mauern gegeben sind und dem gestalt­<br />

baren Raum, der im Unterschied zum tatsächlichen ein „Raum im Raum" 22 sein kann. Theo<br />

van Doesburg faßte den Raumbegriff folgendermaßen zusammen: „Für den modernen<br />

schaffenden Künstler ist Raum nicht meßbare begrenzte Oberfläche, vielmehr der Begriff<br />

der Ausbreitung, die entsteht durch das Verhältnis eines Gestaltungsmittels (z.B. Linie,<br />

Farbe) zu einem anderen (z.B. Bildfläche). Dieser Begriff Ausbreitung oder Raum berührt<br />

die Grundgesetze der bildenden Kunst, weil der Künstler hiervon eine grundsätzliche<br />

Auffassung haben muß. Außerdem bedeutet ihm Raum eine gewisse Spannung, die im<br />

Werke durch Verstraffung von Formen, FLächen oder Linien entsteht. Das Wort Gestaltung<br />

bedeutetihm Sichtbarmachen des Verhältnisses einer Form (oder Farbe) zum Raum und zu<br />

anderen Formen oder Farben." 23<br />

Die Gestaltungsmittel zur Errichtung eines solchen „Raumes" sind nicht mehr<br />

plastischer oder flächiger, sondern rhythmischer Natur. Ton, Geräusch, Lichtstrahl sind als<br />

Äußerungen eines zeitlichen Ablaufs zu betrachten, weil sie, ähnlich wie ein Musikstück,<br />

bestimmbar sind durch Anfang, Ende und Intensität. Sie dienen weniger der Beschreibung<br />

einer begrenzten Oberfläche, sondern vielmehr der Gliederung des Raumes in einer<br />

zeitlichen AbfoLge. Die klassischen Gestaltungsmittel waren damit zugunsten der Raum-<br />

Spannung überwunden. Vordemberge-Gildewart nennt es das Intervall, das Wann-etwas-<br />

geschieht. 24 In einer solchen konkreten Anwendung des Gestaltungsfaktors „Zeit" in der<br />

künstlerischen Arbeit ist die Perspektive zu einer endgültigen Gestaltung gegeben. Das<br />

Medium Film ist hier nur von sekundärer Bedeutung; entscheidend ist, daß dieses<br />

seinerzeit neue Medium anbot, den Faktor Zeit auch außerhalb einer musikalischen<br />

Struktur, gleichwohl innerhalb der Malerei transportieren zu können. Erst hier wird die<br />

besondere Bedeutung des Absoluten Fi lms sichtbar; esist„tatsächlich zum ersten MalFi Im.<br />

Etwas, was ganz den Möglichkeiten des Films entspricht, kühn heran bis zu dem, was dem<br />

Film charakteristisch ist, ich möchte fast sagen, was dem Film elementar ist." 25<br />

In mehreren Schriften, erschienen zwischen 1922 und 1932, befaßten sich Laszlo<br />

Moholy-Nagy und Theo van Doesburg jeweils mit den Problemen eines rein gestalteten<br />

Films. Dargestellt anhand eines kurzen Abrisses der noch jungen Filmgeschichte, vollzieht<br />

.sich nach Doesburgs Auffassung das Entstehen einer Kunstgattung in drei Etappen:<br />

Imitation - Darstellung - Gestaltung. Demzufolge steht am Anfang die Absicht, die<br />

„Illusion des Natürlichen [zu] steigern." 26 Beweis seiner Theorie einer linearen Entwick­<br />

lung ist ihm die Analogie zeitgleicher Entwicklungen in der modernen Kunst und der<br />

Fotografie im Vergleich mit den Eigenschaften des Auges: „Die Retina nimmt neue<br />

Eindrücke auf, und der Geist bereichert sich um neue plastische Gebiete." "


Mit der bloßen Abbildung sind für Doesburg die rein reproduzierenden technischen<br />

Möglichkeiten aber noch nicht erschöpfend entwickelt. Im Sinne des Nachahmungstriebes<br />

kann noch mehr gedacht und entworfen werden aLs für die zweidimensionale Leinwand<br />

notwendig wäre. „Fotografie - Stereoskop -Stereoskopfilm sind aLso die drei prinzipiellen<br />

Vorgänge, die wirins Auge fassen müssen, wenn wir die Materie des Films, anstattin ihrer<br />

Verwendung für reproduktive, für rein schöpferische Zwecke verstehen wollen." 28 Nach<br />

dreißig Jahren Film waren deshalb die technischen Voraussetzungen für eine eigenstän­<br />

dige Filmkunst noch nicht erfüllt, die von Doesburg entworfene Entwicklungslinie in drei<br />

Schritten nicht zu Ende gebracht. Doesburg kritisierte hier nicht nur die aLs ideal gedachten<br />

Vorstellungen der Filmkünstler. Die Entwicklung des Films zum künstlerischen Ausdrucks­<br />

mittel hatte das Stadium der Darstellung noch nicht überschritten. „Da man aber in den<br />

Versuchen für eine authentische Filmkunst notwendigerweise noch beschränktist auf diese<br />

vorhandenen technischen Möglichkeiten, ist der angestrebte rein gestaltende Film, nur<br />

mit den Elementen des Films konstruiert, nicht möglich..." 29<br />

Neben der Filmtechnik, deren ideale Form sowohL nach Moholy-Nagys als auch nach<br />

Doesburgs Auffassung erst in einer noch nicht absehbaren Zeit realisierbar schien, blieb<br />

als der entscheidend zu verändernde Faktor die Projektionsebene. Obgleich Doesburg<br />

nicht zuletzt durch seine Arbeit aLs Herausgeber von De Stijl in den Jahren zuvor<br />

maßgeblich die Konzeptionen eines Absoluten Films beeinfLußt hatte, stellt er hier<br />

nunmehr fest, daß der Film als unabhängige, schöpferische Gestaltung in den letzten zehn<br />

Laszlo Moholy-Nagy,<br />

Ki<strong>net</strong>isch konstrukti­<br />

ves System, 1922


Jahren keine großen Fortschritte gemacht hatte. Die Aussicht, in Bezugnahme auf die<br />

originären Materialeigenschaften des Films eine entsprechend eigenständige Kunst ent­<br />

wickeln zu können, die letztlich sogar die statische Malerei ersetzen sollte, hatte sich nicht<br />

erfüLLt. Stattdessen wiederholte die Vorstellung von einer quasi malerischen Funktion der<br />

Projektionsleinwand lediglich das Motiv des überwunden geglaubten statischen Bildes. Für<br />

einen rein gestaltenden Film muß nicht nur in seiner formalen Konzeption, sondern auch<br />

in dertechnischen Umsetzung der Charakter des Bildhaften überwunden werden. „Was uns<br />

bislang als abstrakter Film geboten wurde, beruhtauf dem Irrtum, die Projektionsfläche<br />

sei eine Ebene, etwa wie die Bildfläche der konstanten Malerei." 30<br />

Doesburg verweist auf den Unterschied zwischen realistischen und gestalteten<br />

Filmen. Die Differenz ist eine qualitative. Der gestalterische Film soll über den Rahmen der<br />

„Leinwand" hinauswirken, und wo dies nicht gelingt, muß der Versuch einfach wirkungslos<br />

bleiben, denn der realistische Film ist in diesem Rahmen von stärkerer Wirkung. Die<br />

Forderung, über die Leinwand hinaus zu einem Lichtraum oder Filmkontinuum zu gelan­<br />

gen, ist daher wörtlich zu verstehen: Aus der Zweidimensionalität der Fläche soll eine Drei­<br />

oder Mehrdimensionalität werden. „Dort und nirgends anders liegt die schöpferische<br />

Sphäre des gestaltenden Films!" 31 Ähnlich wie Moholy-Nagy fordert Doesburg eine<br />

vielflächige Leinwand, welche die Erstellung einer Art „Filmplastik" ermöglicht. „Auf der<br />

zweidimensionalen, flächigen Leinwand eröff<strong>net</strong> sich dem Zuschauer lediglich ein winziger<br />

Teil des Film-Licht-Raumes, und zwar die dem Zuschauer zugewandte Fläche." 32 Doesburgs<br />

praktische Beschreibungen eines polydirnensionalen Raumes verbleiben mehr auf der<br />

theoretischen Ebene, wenn er von einem raumzeitlichen Filmkontinuum schreibt, das es<br />

zu entdecken gilt.<br />

Moholy-Nagys Entwurf eines „simultanen oder Polykinos" 33 dagegen orientierte sich<br />

an seinen praktischen Erfahrungen mit bühnentechnischen Versuchen, wie er sie unter y<br />

anderem mit Schlemmer und Farkas Molnar für die Bühne des Dessauer Bauhauses<br />

entworfen und realisiert hatte. Wesentliches Element ist der Raum, bei Moholy-Nagy in der<br />

Betonung einer physikalischen Bedeutung. Die räumliche Tiefe wird ausgenutzt beispiels­<br />

weise durch hintereinander versetzte Leinwände oder eine gewölbte Leinwand, die in<br />

jeweils entsprechenderweise dramaturgisch und filmgestalterisch anders zu bearbeiten<br />

wären, als es im herkömmlichen Kino der FaLL ist. Der Raum bei Moholy-Nagy ist also ein<br />

wirklicher, ein Ereignis räumlicher Tiefe.<br />

Die Argumentation beziehungsweise Begriffsdefinitionen für die Perspektiven der<br />

ki<strong>net</strong>ischen Gestaltung sind bei Moholy-Nagy und Doesburg ähnlich, insoweit es die<br />

Einbeziehung des Films in eine umfassendere Diskussion über eine „absolute", respektive<br />

„reine" Gestaltung betrifft. So bespricht Moholy-Nagy die Arbeiten Ruttmanns und<br />

Eggelings sowie die Lichtspiele Hirschfeld-Macks im Rahmen einer Tradition von Bilder­<br />

und Bühnenmaschinen, an deren Anfang die Lichtorgel und das Farbktavier stehen. Jeder<br />

Bestandteil hat seine Funktion innerhalb dieser Entwicklung, stellt aber jeweils nur einen<br />

Aspekt eines allumfassenden Konzepts ki<strong>net</strong>isch-optischer Gestaltung dar. Während der<br />

Trickfilm noch mit dem Aspekt der direkten zeichnerischen Bearbeitung arbeiten muß und<br />

ebenso wie der „fotografische" Lichtfilm an das farblose Filmmaterial gebunden ist, kann<br />

das Lichtspiel unabhängig von einem Trägermaterialfarbliche Elemente benutzen. Moholy-<br />

Nagy nennt neben den Versuchen von Hirschfeld, Schwerdtfeger und Hartwig am Weimarer<br />

Bauhaus die Experimente von Thomas Wilfried, der 1920 in Amerika mit dem sogenannten<br />

Clavilux wechselnde gegenstandslose Bildvariationen vorführte und die Untersuchungen<br />

von Raoul Hausmann zu seiner Theorie einer „Optopho<strong>net</strong>ik". Gerade Letztere beziehen


sich auf die Arbeit des von Moholy-Nagy gleichfalls genannten Pater Castel, der im 18.<br />

Jahrhunderts physikalische Untersuchungen über die mögliche Beziehung zwischen Farbe<br />

und Ton vorgenommen hatte und bereits eine Lichtorgel konstruiert haben soll.<br />

Seit dem Mittelalter ist die Idee der Entsprechung von optischen und akustischen<br />

Eindrücken unter dem Begriff der „Synästhetik" bekannt. Nicht zuletzt angeregt durch<br />

Erlebnisse, wie sie nun das Kino vermitteln konnte, nahm das Interesse an den künstleri­<br />

schen Möglichkeiten von synästhetischen Ereignissen spätestens seit den zwanziger<br />

Jahren des 20. Jahrhunderts zu. Hans Richter schrieb 1929, indem das Interesse des<br />

Kinozuschauers „für Handlung und das äußere der Gegenstände abnimmt, wächst es für<br />

etwas, was trotz dieserim Film (selbst im schlechtesten noch faszinierend) vorhanden ist;<br />

für das, was hinter der Spielhandlung auf der Leinwand vor sich geht." 3<<br />

Am Bauhaus waren synästhetische Experimente mit Ton und sichtbarer Form nicht<br />

zuletzt durch die Zwölftonkompositionen des Wiener Komponisten Josef Matthias Hauer<br />

inspiriert. Hauers Kompositionen basierten bereits vor 1912 - mithin vor Arnold Schön­<br />

bergs Zwölftonmusik - auf einem System aus zwölf Tönen, das von der harmonischen<br />

Beziehung von Tönen und Farben zueinander ausging und die Grund Lage einer mystisch­<br />

religiösen Weltanschauung bildete. Sein 1920 erschienenes Buch mit dem Titel „Vom<br />

Wesen des Musikalischen" wurde 1922 von Johannes Itten in Kreisen der Bauhausschüler<br />

bekannt gemacht, und Hauers Zwölftonmusik spukte in den Köpfen vieler Bauhäusler so<br />

sehr herum, daß es „an Gesprächsstoff niemals fehlte." 35<br />

Ein direkter Einfluß Hauersist heute nicht nachzuweisen, und vor allem am Bauhaus<br />

bLieben die Versuche, synästhetische Ereignisse zu erzeugen, nicht ausschließlich in der<br />

Erforschung des grundsätzlichen Verhältnisses von Licht und Ton zueinander begründet.<br />

Vielmehr schienen - ähnlich wie bei Richter und Eggeling - musikalische Strukturen<br />

geeig<strong>net</strong>es Vorbild zu sein für eine vergleichbare Ordnung optischer Elemente. Die<br />

Versuche, eine künstlerisch wie physikalisch gegebene Analogie von Licht und Musik zu<br />

finden, führten zu Ergebnissen unterschiedlichster Qualität. Die Abkehr von der Idee eines<br />

Absoluten Films als reine Gestaltung belegt, daß der Film, zumindest in diesem Stadium<br />

der künstlerischen Entwicklung, nicht wirklich für das ZieL einer universellen Sprache<br />

taugen konnte. Unabhängig von der Bewertung der jeweiligen Arbeiten jedoch stand die<br />

sich an der Bildenden Kunst ausrichtende Konzeption des Absoluten Films -jenseits der<br />

Ordnung, wie sie zu dieser Zeit bereits im Kino festgeschrieben schien - für eine<br />

notwendige Erweiterung des modernen Kunstbegriffs.


Christine N. BRINCKMANN: „Abstraktion“ und „Einfühlung“ im<br />

deutschen Avantgarde-Film der 20er Jahre. In: Dies.: Die<br />

anthropomorphe Kamera und andere Schriften zur filmischen Narration.<br />

Zürich: Chronos 1997, S. 276–275.


«Abstraktion» und «Einfühlung» im<br />

deutschen Avantgardefilm der 20er Jahre<br />

[1997]<br />

247<br />

Form spricht nur für sich, ist keine<br />

Attrappe und hat keinen Kontakt<br />

mehr mit den Naturerscheinungen.'<br />

Fast scheint der abstrakte oder «absolute» Film der frühen 20er Jahre aus<br />

dem filmhistorischen Nichts zu kommen. 2<br />

Jedenfalls gründet er nicht<br />

auf den Spielfilmen und dokumentarischen Werken, die im Kino liefen,<br />

auch wenn die Künstler durchaus mit den Entwicklungen im Medium<br />

Film vertraut waren. Es ging auch nicht darum, ein Gegenkino zu schaf­<br />

fen. Die kurzen, ungegenständlichen, malerisch-musikalischen Experi-<br />

mentalfilme der frühen deutschen Avantgarde traten nicht in Konkur­<br />

renz zum kommerziellen Filmschaffen, sondern begriffen sich als bil­<br />

dende Kunst. Sie wurden, wenn überhaupt, in Sondervorstellungen<br />

gezeigt.<br />

Ich habe drei dieser Filme ausgewählt, um sie einer näheren Betrach­<br />

tung zu unterziehen: Viking Eggelings Symphonie Diagonale (1921-1924),<br />

Walther Ruttmanns Opus I (1921) und Opus III (1923/24). Auch die<br />

frühen Arbeiten Hans Richters oder Oskar Fischingers wären für eine<br />

1 Friedrich Vordemberge-Gildewarts Schlußwort seiner Einführung zum film<br />

programm «Der absolute Film», Hannover 1925. Abgedruckt in: Uwe M. Schneede<br />

(Hg.): Die zwanziger Jahre. Manifeste und Dokumente deutscher Künstler. Köln 1979,<br />

S. 258.<br />

2 Es gab allerdings gewisse Vorläufer oder Vorstufen - die Maler Hans Stoltenberg<br />

und Leopold Survage oder die italienischen Futuristen Bruno Corra und Arnaldo<br />

Ginna. Doch sie stellen individuelle Sonderfälle dar, und ihre Werke waren den<br />

Künstlern, die hier betrachtet werden, vermutlich nicht zugänglich. Zu den frühen<br />

experimentellen Filmansätzen vgl. Birgit Hein/Wulf Herzogenrath (Hg.): Film als<br />

Film, 1910 bis heute. Vom Animationsfilm der zwanziger zum Filmenvironment der<br />

siebziger Jahre. Stuttgart 1978; das - immer noch unentbehrliche, aber längst vergrif­<br />

fene - Nachschlagewerk von Hans Scheugl/Ernst Schmidt jr.: Eine Subgeschichte des<br />

Films. Lexikon des Avantgarde- , Experimental- und Undergroundfilms. Frankfurt a. M.<br />

1974; Monika Zurhake: Filmische Realitätsaneignung. Ein Beitrag zur Filmtheorie, mit<br />

Analysen von Filmen Viking Eggelings und Hans Richters. Heidelberg 1982; und Hol­<br />

ger Wilmesmeier: Deutsche Avantgarde und Film. Die Filmmatinee «Der Absolute Film»<br />

(3. und 10. Mai 1925). Münster/Hamburg 1994.


248<br />

solche Analyse in Frage gekommen; auch sie sind abstrakte Animations­<br />

filme, die allein den sukzessiven synthetischen Arbeitsschritten am Trick­<br />

tisch entspringen, also kein Korrelat in einer vorhandenen profilmischen<br />

Realität haben, die man fotografisch aufzeichnen könnte. Mit ihnen<br />

verwandt sind auch die Lichtprojektionen, wie sie zum Beispiel Ludwig<br />

Hirschfeld-Mack schuf - immaterielle «Farbenspiele», die nach einer Art<br />

Partitur live an die Wand geworfen wurden, also ohne Kamera und Pro­<br />

jektor auskamen.3<br />

Die Wahl fiel auf die genannten Filme zum einen, weil sich in ihnen<br />

der Beginn der Bewegung festmacht: Die beiden Maler Ruttmann und<br />

Eggeling entdeckten die bildnerischen Möglichkeiten des neuen Medi­<br />

ums etwa zeitgleich, aber unabhängig voneinander zu Beginn der Deka­<br />

de. Zum andern wegen des ästhetischen Rangs der Werke, die außer­<br />

dem, dank ihrer so unterschiedlichen Sensibilität und Ausrichtung, die<br />

formale Spannbreite des absoluten Films dokumentieren können. Und<br />

schließlich, im Falle Ruttmanns, weil sich hier im Sprung vom ersten<br />

zum dritten Opus eine Entwicklung aufzeigen läßt von den frühen male­<br />

risch-grafischen Ansätzen zu einer komplexeren und mehr fotografi­<br />

schen Arbeitsweise - und damit eine Verbindung zum späteren Schaf­<br />

fen der filmischen Avantgarde. Von dem schon 1925 verstorbenen Viking<br />

Eggeling ist nur der eine Film erhalten geblieben; doch sind seine Vorar­<br />

beiten in Zeichnungen dokumentiert.<br />

Im folgenden sollen die Filme historisch und biografisch situiert und<br />

in ihren visuellen und technischen Besonderheiten vorgestellt werden.<br />

Vor allem aber geht es um eine Reihe von Fragen, die an alle drei<br />

Beispiele zu richten sind, um ihre ästhetischen Konzepte zu erschließen:<br />

In welcher Weise, welcher Hinsicht sind sie «abstrakt» oder «absolut»,<br />

welche Vorstellungen und Gestaltungsweisen verbergen sich hinter die­<br />

sen Etiketten? Wie erklärt sich und was bedeutet jeweils der Rekurs auf<br />

die Musik, der sich - mit «Symphonie» und «Opus» - programmatisch<br />

in den Titeln ausdrückt? Wie «filmisch» sind diese Werke, wenn sie<br />

nicht an das Kino, sondern an Malerei und Grafik anknüpfen? Geht es<br />

ihnen beispielsweise um Tiefenillusion oder betonen sie die komposito­<br />

rische Fläche? Setzen sie das Licht modellierend ein, wie die Fotografie,<br />

oder ist es nur technisches Mittel zum Zweck? Sind sie zentrifugal oder<br />

3 Schon vor und parallel zum Aufkommen des abstrakten Films vollzieht sich die<br />

Entwicklung von bewegten musikalischen Licht- und Farbexperimenten, Projek­<br />

tionen, «Orgeln» und dergleichen. Vgl. Sara Seiwood: «Farblichtmusik und ab­<br />

strakter Film». In: Karin von Maur (Hg.): Vom Klang der Bilder. Die Musik in der<br />

Kunst des 20. Jahrhunderts. München 1985, S. 414ff., mit vielen Zitaten, Nachweisen<br />

und Illustrationen.<br />

zentripetal angelegt, deuten sie auf ein Off, das jenseits der Leinwand<br />

imaginär fortzudenken ist, oder beschränken sie sich auf das projizierte,<br />

geschlossene Rechteck? Und schließlich: In welchem Maße begünstigt<br />

oder verhindert die filmische Gestaltung die Einfühlung? Kommt es zu<br />

empathischen Prozessen beim Publikum, zu anthropomorpher Beseelung<br />

- oder bleibt das Geschehen in der Tat «abstrakt»?<br />

Das geistige Umfeld, aus dem heraus der abstrakte Film entstand, kann<br />

hier nur sehr pauschal skizziert werden. - Am Ende der 10er Jahre sind<br />

die apokalyptischen Erfahrungen des Ersten Weltkriegs und seiner Nach­<br />

beben noch äußerst gegenwärtig und der Schock der Russischen Revo­<br />

lution noch allenthalben spürbar. Visionen des gesellschaftlichen Chaos,<br />

des Zerfalls der Werte, der Überwältigung durch die Technik gehen teils<br />

zusammen mit kultureller, konservativer Rückbesinnung, teils mit dem<br />

Aufbruch in neue Denkmuster und fortschrittliche ästhetische, politi­<br />

sche und soziale Entwürfe. In der europäischen Kunst sind die 10er und<br />

frühen 20er Jahre die Zeit der Manifeste und «Ismen»: Futurismus,<br />

Vortizismus, Konstruktivismus, Technizismus, Kubismus, Abstrakti-<br />

vismus, Suprematismus, Expressionismus, Dada und Merz - um nur<br />

einige zu nennen. 4<br />

Manche dieser Zusammenschlüsse sind lokal und kurzlebig, andere<br />

persistent und international, um die kulturellen Zentren Paris, Amster­<br />

dam, Berlin, München, Zürich, Wien und Budapest gruppiert und in<br />

regem Austausch begriffen. Allen gemeinsam ist die innere Unruhe und<br />

die Suche nach innovativen Formen der Darstellung. Vielfach ist der<br />

Motor, vor allem der bildenden Kunst, die beschleunigte Bewegung des<br />

technischen Zeitalters, die eine neue Wahrnehmung erfordert.5 Gleich­<br />

zeitig gilt es, sich vom überkommenen Realismus zu lösen. Wo nicht<br />

Anarchie und Negation das Programm bilden, steht - insbesondere im<br />

deutschsprachigen Raum - häufig die Überwindung der materiellen<br />

Welt im Zentrum, sei es durch eine metaphysische Geistigkeit, sei es mit<br />

den formalen Mitteln der Abstraktion oder Atonalität. Kunst soll Über­<br />

zeitliches ausdrücken, soll Systematiken entwickeln und mentale Ge­<br />

setzmäßigkeiten finden, um Künstler und Rezipienten zu einer höheren<br />

geistigen Klarheit und Wahrnehmungsfähigkeit zu führen oder, in den<br />

4 Vgl. das 1925 erschienene, dreisprachige Buch von El Lissitzky und Hans Arp: Die<br />

Kunstismen/Les Ismes de V art/The Isms of Art. Neudruck Rolandseck 1990.<br />

5 Die Zusammenhänge zwischen Technizität, beschleunigter Wahrnehmung, bilden­<br />

der Kunst und Avantgardefilm hat Joachim Paech in seinem Aufsatz «Bilder von<br />

Bewegung - bewegte Bilder. Film, Fotografie und Malerei» dargelegt. In: Monika<br />

Wagner (Hg.): Moderne Kunst. Das Funkkolleg zum Verständnis der Gegenwartskunst.<br />

Reinbek 1991.<br />

249


250<br />

Worten Kandinskys, «um die menschliche Seele in Vibration zu brin­<br />

gen».6<br />

Da die innerste Funktion der Kunst so absolut gesetzt wird, öffnen<br />

sich die Grenzen zwischen den Gattungen. Allenthalben entdeckt man<br />

übergreifende Affinitäten, Analogien und Synästhesien 7<br />

, die zur Ver­<br />

schmelzung der Künste im Gesamtkunstwerk herausfordern. Dank die­<br />

ser programmatischen Durchlässigkeit kommt es zu intensiven Kontak­<br />

ten zwischen Malern und Dichtern, Architekten, Designern, Tänzern<br />

oder Musikern, die oft zu längeren Symbiosen führen. Viele kleine Kunst­<br />

zeitschriften fördern und pflegen die internationale Kommunikation.<br />

Eine Gruppierung wie der «Blaue Reiter» in München veröffentlicht<br />

ihren Almanach nicht nur für den eigenen Kreis; die holländische Zeit­<br />

schrift De Stijl oder die ungarische Zeitschrift Ma unterrichten über<br />

avantgardistische europäische Strömungen. Sie bilden ein Forum für die<br />

theoretische Selbstdarstellung, die von den Künstlern sehr ernst genom­<br />

men wird. Einerseits konstatieren insbesondere die abstrakten Maler<br />

eine zunehmende Entfremdung des Publikums, das nach wie vor einen<br />

gegenständlichen Realismus bevorzugt; die eigenen Werke müssen er­<br />

läutert werden, so daß Kunst und Kommentar plötzlich in einer Hand<br />

liegen8 Andererseits erwächst bereits aus dem moralisch-didaktischen<br />

Anspruch der Kunst die Verpflichtung, in den kulturellen Verständnis­<br />

prozeß einzugreifen. Wollen sie der materiellen Welt wirksam begeg­<br />

nen, müssen die Künstler Sorge tragen, daß ihr Potential auch aufgeht,<br />

ihre Konzepte verstanden werden. Im Bauhaus als der größten und<br />

einflußreichsten Gruppierung der 20er Jahre fließen diese theoretischen,<br />

pädagogischen, ästhetischen, praktischen und sozialen Impulse auf ex­<br />

emplarische Weise zusammen.<br />

Zugleich dienen einige Klassiker als gemeinsame gedankliche Basis<br />

der abstrakten Künstler. Neben Goethe und Novalis - selbst Grenzgän-<br />

6 Die Formulierung ist eine Art Leitmotiv in Kandinskys Schrift von 1911: Uber das<br />

Geistige in der Kunst. Bern 1952, und kommt dort an vielen Stellen vor.<br />

7 In dem von Karin von Maur herausgegebenen Ausstellungskatalog Vom Klang der<br />

Bilder (wie Anm. 3) werden die Querbeziehungen der Künste vielfältig herausgear­<br />

beitet und illustriert. Vgl. außerdem Wilmesmeier (wie Anm. 2), Kapitel 3 «Der<br />

abstrakte Film und die Musik»; Karl Sierek: «Die unterirdischen Kanäle. Zur Bezie­<br />

hung zwischen Musik, Malerei und Film». In: Stefan Gyöngyösi (Hg.): Art of Vision:<br />

Zeitfluß 93. Katalog zum FilmFestival, Salzburg 1993. Zum Verhältnis von Film und<br />

Malerei vgl. den Ausstellungskatalog Peintute, cinema, peinture. Marseille 1989/<br />

1990.<br />

8 Vgl. Wolfgang Max Faust: Bilder werden Worte. Zum Verhältnis von bildender Kunst<br />

und Literatur im 20. Jahrhundert oder vom Anfang der Kunst im Ende der Künste.<br />

München 1977, insbesondere das Kapitel «Abstrakte Kunst: Konzeption und Er­<br />

scheinung», S. 113ff., mit vielen weiteren Nachweisen.<br />

ger zwischen Theorie und Praxis -, neben dem Philosophen Henri<br />

Bergson, dessen Werk L´ evolution creatrice (1907; deutsch 1912) sehr<br />

intensiv rezipiert wird, und neben den musiktheoretischen Texten von<br />

Ferruccio Busoni (Entwurf einer neuen Ästhetik der Tonkunst, 1907) und<br />

Arnold Schönberg (Harmonielehre, 1911) sind es vor allem zwei Schriften,<br />

die für den absoluten Film primäre Bedeutung haben: Wassily Kandin­<br />

skys schmales Buch Über das Geistige in der Kunst von 1911 und Wilhelm<br />

Worringers Dissertation Abstraktion und Einfühlung: Ein Beitrag zur Stil­<br />

psychologie, die er 1908 veröffentlicht.<br />

Auch Kandinsky rekurriert auf Goethe, wenn auch nur am Rande,<br />

und natürlich auf Schönberg, mit dem er freundschaftlich verbunden<br />

war. Sein Plädoyer für die abstrakte Malerei behandelt die Musik als<br />

eine Art Vorreiter, da sie die «heute unmateriellste Kunst»9 sei, und<br />

begründet damit ein gedankliches Paradigma des Vergleichens, der Ana­<br />

logie zwischen den Gattungen, die voneinander lernen sollen, um zum<br />

je Eigenen zu finden. Zentrum seiner Ausführungen ist der Gedanke<br />

von der «inneren Notwendigkeit» aller ästhetischen Formung, welche<br />

die Kunst von der gegenständlichen Nachahmung der Natur befreit, um<br />

sie für die Darstellung des Geistigen freizusetzen. Kandinskys Zusam-<br />

menschau abstrahierender Tendenzen in der Literatur (Maeterlinck),<br />

Musik (Debussy, Skrjabin, Schönberg), Malerei (Cezanne, Matisse, Pi­<br />

casso) und im Tanz (lsadora Duncan) gipfelt in dem Gedanken, daß eine<br />

neue «Bühnenkomposition" - aus malerischen, musikalischen, tänzeri­<br />

schen Komponenten -, überhaupt eine «monumentale Kunst» in der<br />

Verschmelzung der Gattungen zu verwirklichen sei. Über das Geistige in<br />

der Kunst fasziniert heute durch seine eigenartige Mischung von luzi-<br />

den, präzisen Beobachtungen mit mystischen und genialischen Tönen.<br />

Wilhelm Worringers theoretische Arbeit ist, wie er selbst in einem<br />

Rückblick konstatiert, «zu einem «Sesam öffne dich» [...] für einen gan­<br />

zen Umkreis zeitwichtiger Fragestellungen» geworden. 10<br />

Daß seine Schrift<br />

«im tieferen Sinne aktuell» sei, wußte Worringer jedoch schon im Vor­<br />

wort zur ersten Ausgabe. Seine Theorie setzt bei Alois Riegls Stilfragen<br />

9> Kandinsky (wie Anm. 6), S. 54. «Wie unendlich gut (wenn auch nur verhältnismä­<br />

ßig!) haben es die Musiker in ihrer so weit gekommenen Kunst. Wirklich Kunst, die<br />

das Glück schon besitzt, auf reinpraktische Zwecke vollkommen zu verzichten.<br />

Wie lange wird wohl die Malerei darauf warten müssen?», schreibt Kandinsky in<br />

einem Brief vom 9.4.1911 mit dem für die visuellen Kunstler damals so typischen<br />

Neid. Vgl. Helena Hahl-Koch: «Kandinsky und der


252<br />

von 1893 und Theodor Lipps' Grundlegung der Ästhetik von 1903 an, um<br />

Abstraktions- und Einfühlungsdrang als zwei polare Impulse des Kunst­<br />

wollens zu definieren.<br />

Wie der Einfühlungsdrang «seine Befriedigung in der Schönheit des<br />

Organischen findet, so findet der Abstraktionsdrang seine Schönheit im<br />

lebenverneinenden Anorganischen, im Kristallinischen oder allgemein<br />

gesprochen in aller abstrakten Gesetzmäßigkeit und Notwendigkeit». 11<br />

Wenn auch Naturvorbilder abstrahiert werden, dann jedenfalls «mit<br />

dem Bestreben, das einzelne Objekt der Außenwelt [...] aus seiner Ver­<br />

bindung und Abhängigkeit von den anderen Dingen zu erlösen, es dem<br />

Lauf des Geschehens zu entreißen, es absolut zu machen». 12<br />

Worringer<br />

geht in seiner Arbeit darauf ein, welche Bedingungen innerhalb einer<br />

Kultur zur Dominanz des Abstraktions- respektive des Einfühlungs­<br />

drangs führen:<br />

Während der Einfühlungsdrang ein glückliches pantheistisches Vertraulich-<br />

keitsverhältnis zwischen dem Menschen und den Außenwelterscheinungen<br />

zur Bedingung hat, ist der Abstraktionsdrang die Folge einer großen<br />

inneren Beunruhigung des Menschen durch die Erscheinungen der Au­<br />

ßenwelt und korrespondiert in religiöser Beziehung mit einer stark trans­<br />

zendentalen Färbung aller Vorstellungen. Diesen Zustand möchten wir<br />

eine ungeheure geistige Raumscheu nennen. 13<br />

Die abstrakte Malerei der 10er und 20er Jahre (sowie der absolute Film)<br />

scheinen damit, als Reaktion auf die spezifische «Außenwelt» der Zeit,<br />

prophetisch vorhergesagt. Allerdings darf man nicht übersehen, daß<br />

Abstraktion - als Loslösung vom Gegenständlichen - nicht pauschal mit<br />

dem «Abstraktionsdrang» Worringers gleichzusetzen ist, der ja auch<br />

innerhalb einer grundsätzlich gegenständlichen Darstellung walten kann.<br />

Und ebenso schließt eine abstrakte Form den Einfühlungsdrang nicht<br />

aus. Die lebhafte materielle Sinnlichkeit vieler nicht-gegenständlicher<br />

Kunst widerspricht daher Worringers Theorie nur scheinbar. Auch die<br />

Tatsache, daß sich viele abstrakte Maler auf sein einflußreiches Buch<br />

beriefen, hat mit dem eigentlichen Inhalt dieser Theorie oft weniger zu<br />

tun als mit der Suche nach einem prominenten Gewährsmann. Die<br />

Nomenclatur ist häufig irreführend oder hat sich verselbständigt.<br />

Die Anwendbarkeit der Begriffe «Abstraktion» und «Einfühlung»<br />

auf den abstrakten Film, wie sie der Titel dieses Aufsatzes suggeriert, ist<br />

11 Worringer (wie Anm. 10), S. 16.<br />

12 Worringer (wie Anm. 10), S. 33.<br />

13 Worringer (wie Anm. 10), S. 27.<br />

daher in vieler Hinsicht nur eine bedingte. Außerdem finden sich bei<br />

Worringer, der statische Kunstwerke vergangener Epochen betrachtet,<br />

keine Kategorien für die Dynamisierung der Wahrnehmung oder die<br />

musikalische Prozeßhaftigkeit, wie sie die Filme prägt; gerade die Bewe­<br />

gung bringt aber fast zwangsläufig Raumempfindungen mit sich, so daß<br />

sich die «Raumscheu» Worringers relativiert. Doch es soll auch nicht<br />

darum gehen, seine dualistische, spekulative, ideologisch befrachtete<br />

Betrachtungsweise auf die gegenwärtige Untersuchung zu übertragen.<br />

Vielmehr bilden die beiden Begriffe - damals wie heute - ein anregen­<br />

des heuristisches Instrumentarium, auch außerhalb des Gedanken­<br />

gebäudes ihres Urhebers, mit dem sich einige zentrale Unterschiede in<br />

Konzept und ästhetischer Gestaltung der Werke Eggelings und Rutt-<br />

manns fassen lassen: Unterschiede, die sich allerdings schon darin aus­<br />

drücken, daß Eggeling sich intensiv und direkt mit Worringers Gedan­<br />

kengut auseinandersetzt, während der jüngere Ruttmann ihn wohl eher<br />

osmotisch, im expressionistischen Kontext des «Blauen Reiter» rezipier­<br />

te, einer Gruppe, die sich schon früh - und nicht ohne «kreative Mißver­<br />

ständnisse» 14<br />

- über Worringers Schrift zu legitimieren suchte.<br />

Der Maler Viking Eggeling, 1880 in Schweden geboren, kam 1918 über<br />

Berlin und Paris in die Schweiz. 15<br />

253<br />

In Zürich stieß er zur DADA-Gruppe<br />

und begann eine mehrjährige Zusammenarbeit mit Hans Richter. Als<br />

sich die Zürcher Gruppe auflöste, zogen beide nach Berlin, um ihre<br />

gemeinsamen Studien und Experimente fortzusetzen. Eggeling hatte<br />

bereits seit längerem abstrakte Zeichnungen entwickelt, mit denen er<br />

prinzipielle grafische Grundformen, insbesondere Analogien und Pola­<br />

ritäten, zur künstlerischen Anschauung brachte; sie bargen, obwohl sta­<br />

tisch, schon früh dynamische Elemente. Allerdings entsprang diese Ten­<br />

denz etwas anders gelagerten künstlerischen Vorstellungen als den in<br />

der Malerei der 10er und 20er Jahre vielfach feststellbaren Versuchen,<br />

auf Bewegungsaspekte des Sujets zu verweisen oder dem Auge der<br />

14 Vgl. Gregor Wedekind: «Die Verdoppelung der Kultur um ihren Gegensatz: Über<br />

den Kunsthistoriker Wilhelm Worringer». In: Neue Zürcher Zeitung, Nr. 56, 8./9.<br />

März 1997, S. 70. Wedekind weist auf tiefliegende Unterschiede zwischen dem<br />

eigentlich konservativen Worringer und den Künstlern des «Blauen Reitet- hin<br />

und betont, daß dieser sich jedoch «willig zu den neuen und von ihm durchaus<br />

nicht angestrebten Ufern» habe ziehen lassen.<br />

15 Die folgenden Ausführungen sind in vieler Hinsicht Louise O'Konors umfassender<br />

Monografie: Viking Eggeling 1880-1925. Artist and Film-maker, Life and Work. Stock­<br />

holm 1971, verpflichtet. Vgl. außerdem Peter Wollen: «Lund Celebrates Dada Child.<br />

The Inaugural Viking Eggeling Lecture». In: Pix, Nr. 2, 1997, der vor allem den<br />

Künstlerkreis um Eggeling betrachtet.


254<br />

Betrachter sukzessive Wahrnehmungsprozesse innerhalb des Bildes zu<br />

vermitteln.<br />

Mit Richter zusammen erfolgte der erste Schritt in Richtung Film,<br />

die Entwicklung von Rollenbildern in Anlehnung an ostasiatische Mo­<br />

delle, in denen sich Bewegungsphasen abstrakter Figuren aneinander­<br />

reihten. An diese Vorarbeit schloß sich organisch eine - leider verlorene<br />

- filmische Umsetzung solcher Abläufe an, das Horizontal-Vertikale Or­<br />

chester (1920), das auf Rollenbild-Entwürfen basierte. 16<br />

Die frühe pionier­<br />

hafte Arbeit an diesem abstrakten Film war von einem theoretischen<br />

Manifest begleitet, das aus der Feder Eggelings (unter Beteiligung Rich­<br />

ters) stammte und von mehreren europäischen Zeitschriften der Avant­<br />

garde, in nur leicht variierten Versionen, abgedruckt wurde: «Prinzipiel­<br />

les zur Bewegungskunst». 17<br />

Darin war eine Kunst gefordert, die einem äußerst hochgesteckten<br />

ethischen Anspruch dienen sollte, «der Vollendung des Individuums in<br />

einer höheren Organisationsform». Und weiter heißt es programma­<br />

tisch: «Kunst ist nicht subjektive Explosion eines Individuums, sondern<br />

organische Sprache des Menschen von allerernstester Bedeutung und<br />

muß deshalb in [ihren] Grundlagen so irrtumsfrei und so lapidar sein,<br />

daß [sie] als solche: als Sprache der Menschheit, wirklich benutzt wer­<br />

den kann.» 18<br />

Dies sei zu leisten durch eine «Form-Sprache», die aus einer<br />

Art Alphabet bestehen sollte - oder, wie Eggeling in Anlehnung an<br />

Goethe später sagte, einem «Generalbaß». Damit sollten «gestaltende<br />

Evolutionen und Revolutionen in der Sphäre des rein Künstlerischen»<br />

geschaffen werden - «analog etwa den unserem Ohr geläufigen Ge­<br />

schehnissen der Musik». Und der Artikel endet mit dem visionären<br />

Hinweis:<br />

Es ist zweifellos, daß das Kino als neues Arbeitsfeld der bildenden Künst­<br />

ler, von Produktionen der bildenden Kunst schnell und stark beansprucht<br />

werden wird. [...] Für diese neue Kunst ist es absolut erforderlich, eindeu­<br />

tige Elemente zu haben. Ohne diese kann zwar ein (noch so verführeri­<br />

sches) Spiel entstehen, aber niemals eine Sprache. 19<br />

l6 Beschreibungen dieses verlorenen Werks durch Zeitgenossen sowie Abbildungen<br />

vieler Zeichnungen finden sich in O'Konor (wie Anm. 15), S. 46-51 und S. 208-217.<br />

17 So unter Eggelings Namen in der ungarischen Zeitschrift Ma, unter Richters Na­<br />

men (mit Zusatztext) in der holländischen Zeitschrift De Stijl, beide 1921.<br />

18 O' Konor (wie Anm. 15), S. 90.<br />

Kl O´Konnor (wie Anm. 15) S 91<br />

Es ist charakteristisch für Eggeling - anders als für Richter - daß er diese<br />

absoluten, utopistischen Forderungen bis zur letzten Konsequenz in die<br />

Tat umzusetzen suchte. Sein filmisches Werk, das mit der Gefälligkeit<br />

vieler späterer Animationsfilme nichts zu tun hat, entspringt einem<br />

zutiefst philosophisch-transzendentalen Geist. Die ästhetische Verwirk­<br />

lichung der Theoreme mag zwar andere Prozesse im Publikum auslö­<br />

sen, als die Visionen Eggelings voraussahen; doch das Werk gewinnt in<br />

jedem Falle an Transparenz, wenn seine geistigen Grundlagen mitgedacht<br />

werden.<br />

Eggeling und Richter trennten sich nach einem Zerwürfnis im Jahre<br />

1921. So ist Eggelings Hauptwerk und einzig erhaltener Film Symphonie<br />

Diagonale ohne Zutun Richters entstanden, auch wenn er auf gemeinsam<br />

entwickelte Arbeitsmethoden zurückgeht. Diese Methoden waren von<br />

eher simpler handwerklicher Natur, 20<br />

255<br />

stellten Eggeling aber gleichwohl<br />

vor technische Probleme, weil sie sehr präzis ausgeführt werden muß­<br />

ten, um dem Wesen seiner komplexen absoluten Kunst gerecht zu wer­<br />

den; allzu leicht konnte der Eindruck kunstgewerblicher Bastelei entste­<br />

hen. Außerdem erforderten die etwa acht Minuten, die das Werk wäh­<br />

ren sollte, eine zähe Ausdauer, weil der Film Kader für Kader erstellt<br />

werden mußte. Die Arbeitsmittel waren: eine 35mm-Kamera mit Einzel­<br />

bildschaltung, die es außerdem erlaubte, auf- und abzublenden sowie<br />

den Filmstreifen zurücklaufen zu lassen, um ihn ein zweites Mal zu<br />

belichten; ein rudimentärer Tricktisch, bestehend aus einem Kasten mit<br />

höhenverstellbarer mattierter Glasplatte, über der die Kamera fix mon­<br />

tiert war; ein einfaches Beleuchtungssystem (ein Rechteck aus Glühbir­<br />

nen, unter der Glasplatte); Stanniolfolie, die stark genug war, um plan<br />

auf einer Fläche aufzuliegen, aber so fein, daß man filigranhafte Formen<br />

aus ihr herausschneiden konnte. 21<br />

Eggelings Figuren selbst sind komplexe zeichenhafte, teilgeo­<br />

metrische, zweidimensionale Gebilde (die fast identisch in seinen Zeich­<br />

nungen vorkommen und an deren Verfeinerung er seit Jahren arbeitete).<br />

Sie bestehen aus zarten Strichen und Bändern verschiedener Stärke,<br />

gekrümmten Bögen mit sprossenartigem Innen- oder Anbau, einseitig<br />

20 Eggeling und Richter hatten in der Trickabteilung der Ufa diverse Versuche unter­<br />

nommen, sich mit dem Stand der Technik vertraut zu machen und Animations-<br />

verlahren zu entwickeln. Die Ergebnisse wie die Kosten hielten sie jedoch davon<br />

ab, diesen Weg weiterzuverfolgen.<br />

21 Vgl. «Erinnerungen an Viking Eggeling» (l977) von Re Soupault (vormals Erna<br />

Niemeyer), der Mitarbeiterin Eggelings, die über die technischen Schwierigkeiten<br />

der Animation berichtet. In: Hein/Herzogenrath (wie Anm. 2), S. 24ff.


256<br />

geöff<strong>net</strong>en Rechtecken, denen sich Wellenlinien anlagern, Dreiecken mit<br />

gerundetem Seitenbuckel aus parallelen Streifen, gezackten und ge­<br />

schwungenen Kleinelementen, großen S-förmigen Linienkonglomeraten,<br />

die sich mit kammartigen Klammern vereinen, und dergleichen mehr.<br />

Eggeling schnitt die Figuren zunächst - als Schlitze - in die Folien ein,<br />

legte eine Folie auf die Glasplatte und erhellte sie von unten, so daß es so<br />

aussah, als ob die Schlitze lichte, selbstleuchtende Gebilde auf dunklem<br />

Grund seien. Durch Ab- und Aufblenden der Kamera konnte der An­<br />

schein vermittelt werden, als entstünden sie aus dem Nichts oder lösten<br />

sich ins Nichts auf. Durch teilweises Zu- und Aufdecken, eine Art Lege-<br />

trick, entstand der Eindruck von Wachsen und Vergehen, von selbsttäti­<br />

gem Ab- und Aufbau der Elemente. Durch Verschiebung schienen die<br />

Figuren über die Fläche zu wandern. Und durch Doppelbelichtung war<br />

es möglich, gleichzeitig mehrere Gebilde in je verschiedenem Rhythmus<br />

sich verwandeln, wandern oder gegenläufig kommen und gehen zu<br />

lassen.<br />

Der Film wirkt minimalistisch in seiner Beschränkung auf sparsa­<br />

mes kontrastives Schwarzweiß, dessen Polarität einzig durch gelegent­<br />

lich schwächer leuchtendes oder verglimmendes Grau gemildert ist (we­<br />

gen der punktuellen Helligkeit der Glühbirnen und als Ergebnis VON<br />

Doppelbelichtungen und Abblenden). Die Figuren, eher klein, fragil,<br />

schwerelos und ein wenig karg, behaupten sich nicht bildfüllend, son­<br />

dern beanspruchen jeweils nur einen Teil der schwarzen Grundfläche.<br />

Kaum jemals erwecken sie die Illusion von Tiefe, obwohl sie sich bewe­<br />

gen und begegnen. Denn Eggeling vermeidet Überlappungen, die<br />

Dreidimensionalität suggerieren könnten, und inszeniert nur wenig<br />

(Schein)Bewegung aus der Bildtiefe heraus oder in sie hinein. Und eben­<br />

so vermeidet er es, das Leinwand-Rechteck als Ausschnitt aus einem<br />

größeren Raum erscheinen zu lassen. Indem alle Formen im Bild entste­<br />

hen und zergehen, nur innerhalb der Bildfläche wandern und sie nie<br />

über die Ränder verlassen, konstituiert sich kein filmisches Off, keine<br />

Illusion eines unbegrenzten Raumes, in dem die Bewegungen und Figu­<br />

ren sich fortsetzen, unabhängig von ihrer temporären Sichtbarkeit wei­<br />

terexistieren könnten. 22<br />

Auch die Fläche selbst bleibt immateriell, ein<br />

schwarzes Nirgendwo, das keinen Halt gibt und kein Hindernis bietet.<br />

Im Grunde ist nicht einmal festgelegt, ob wir sozusagen von vorn oder<br />

von oben auf das Geschehen blicken. Worringers Beobachtung von der<br />

«Raumscheu» der Abstraktion ist hier ein Denkmal gesetzt - bewußt,<br />

22 Vgl. Siereck (wie Anm. 7), S. 92, der darüber hinaus bemerkt, daß Eggelings For­<br />

men bereits die Nähe zum Bildrand meiden und daher «keine Verbindungsglie­<br />

der» zu einem «Bereich des Abseits» darstellen.<br />

wie Eggelings dokumentierte Auseinandersetzung mit dessen Theorie<br />

nahelegt. 23<br />

Nicht ein Mangel an filmischer Imagination, sondern der<br />

Wille zur konsequenten absoluten Abstraktion liegt der räumlichen und<br />

gegenständlichen Askese der Symphonie Diagonale zugrunde. 24<br />

Eggelings Abstraktionswille äußert sich auf einer weiteren Ebene.<br />

Anders als ein Gemälde, eine Zeichnung - oder, wie noch zu zeigen ist,<br />

die Filme Ruttmanns - verweist die Symphonie Diagonale nicht auf die<br />

Person ihres Schöpfers oder den Prozeß, dem sie ihre Entstehung ver­<br />

dankt. Nichts, das einem Pinselstrich vergleichbar wäre oder auf die<br />

Arbeit der Kamera und die verwendeten Materialien verwiese; im Ge­<br />

genteil, die Figuren scheinen «absolut» aus dem Leeren zu kommen und<br />

in ihrer anorganischen Abstraktion nur immateriell zu existieren. Damit<br />

dürfte eine besondere Qualität dieser Figuren zusammenhängen: Bei<br />

anderen abstrakten Animationsfilmen - beispielsweise von Oskar<br />

Fischinger - stellt sich ja rasch und unwillkürlich im Publikum das<br />

Gefühl ein, die Formen seien beseelt (eben animiert), eine Art Lebewe­<br />

sen mit eigenem Willen und individueller Persönlichkeit. Sobald sie als<br />

diskrete Einheiten identifizierbar sind und sich selbsttätig zu bewegen<br />

scheinen, schreibt man ihnen Intentionen und Interaktionen zu - Kon­<br />

flikte, Vereinigungswünsche, Wettläufe, Fluchtversuche -, als seien sie<br />

fiktionale Protagonisten.<br />

Doch die Figuren der Symphonie Diagonale widersetzen sich solcher<br />

Einfühlung. Dies wohl deshalb, weil sie in ständiger Verwandlung ihrer<br />

Kontur begriffen sind, so daß keine hinreichend stabilen Gestalten ent­<br />

stehen, welche als Einzelwesen in Erscheinung treten könnten. Selbst<br />

wenn mehrere Formen zugleich auf einer Fläche aktiv sind, löst sich jede<br />

vermeintliche Beziehung sogleich wieder auf, da die Figuren sich in sich<br />

selbst auf- oder abbauen, statt aufeinander zu reagieren. Fast wäre es<br />

richtiger, hier gar nicht von «Figuren» zu sprechen, die sich bilden und<br />

regen, sondern von einem Etwas, das sich an verschiedenen Orten zu<br />

immer neuen Zeichen ausformt, ohne zu Ruhe oder Stabilität zu kom­<br />

men. Eine «Zauberschrift», ein magisches Entstehen und Vergehen, das<br />

sich in schwebender Balance hält zwischen Metamorphose und figürli­<br />

cher Gestaltwerdung.<br />

23 Louise O'Konor hat aus allen erhaltenen Manuskripten und Notizen Eggelings eine<br />

Kunsttheorie extrahiert, in der der Einfluß Worringers - wie der Kandinskys und<br />

Bergsons - allenthalben faßbar ist. O'Konor (wie Anm. 15), S. 73fl.<br />

24 Natürlich ist mitzubedenken, wie Wilmesmeier (wie Anm. 2, S. 126) überlegt, in­<br />

wieweit die gewählte Tricktechnik Eggelings filmische Ästhetik einschränkte und<br />

bestimmte. Doch scheint mir unwahrscheinlich, daß Eggeling etwas wesentlich<br />

anderes intendiert hätte, als sich in der Symphonic Diagonale ausdrückt.<br />

257


258<br />

Nicht daß ein diffuses Pulsieren entstünde - Eggelings Film ist<br />

äußerst klar, diszipliniert und gebändigt. Doch dies nicht dank vor­<br />

hersehbarer, einfühlbarer Interaktion der Elemente, sondern durch<br />

formale Variation, durchgezogene, erneut auftretende Motive und<br />

rhythmische Entsprechungen. Von der Vorstellung Eggelings war ja<br />

bereits die Rede, daß seine - und möglichst jede - Kunst universelle<br />

Polaritäten zur Anschauung bringen solle. Entsprechend lebt die Sym-<br />

phonie Diagonale von binären formalen Kontrasten wie: offen/geschlos­<br />

sen, voll/entleert, schwer/leicht, groß/klein, heftig/schwach, gera­<br />

de/ gekrümmt, symmetrisch/asymmetrisch, vollendet/fragmenta­<br />

risch, einfach/mehrfach und, nicht zuletzt, horizontal/vertikal, dia­<br />

gonal/rechtwinklig. Diese Polaritäten bieten ein reiches Potential,<br />

nach dem die Formen sich konstituieren können, ohne auf Wiederho­<br />

lungen angewiesen zu sein. Und außerdem herrscht neben dem Prin­<br />

zip der Polarität das der Analogie, das Verwandtschaften auslotet<br />

und mit Ähnlichkeiten operiert. So kommt es nie zu einer formalen<br />

Dürre, vielmehr spielen die Formen sehr graziös in unerschöpflicher<br />

Metamorphose.<br />

Es gehört zur Besonderheit der Symphonie Diagonale, daß man Mühe<br />

hat, die Gesamtstruktur zu erfassen oder zu memorieren. Nicht nur fehlt<br />

jegliche «narrative» Entwicklung, die Anhaltspunkt für ein kausales<br />

Nacheinander oder eine nicht umkehrbare Abfolge gäbe. Die Bewegun­<br />

gen scheinen auch keinen definierbaren Spannungsablauf, kein drama­<br />

turgisches Konzept zu berücksichtigen, keine konflikthafte Auseinan­<br />

dersetzung von Elementen zu liefern, die durchgespielt würde, um sich<br />

schließlich zu erschöpfen. In nervöser, schwebender Gleichzeitigkeit<br />

laufen kleine Prozesse an verschiedenen Stellen des Bildes ab, die zwar<br />

synchron verfolgt, aber nicht auf einen Begriff gebracht werden können.<br />

Fast scheint der Film auf der Stelle zu treten - aber er hält die Wahrneh­<br />

mung in Bann, setzt sich über die bestehenden acht Minuten ohne Bruch<br />

geläufig fort, in einer zeitverschlingenden Zeitlosigkeit, wie Bergson sie<br />

in seiner Theorie der Durchdringung von Gegenwart und Vergangen­<br />

heit postuliert hat. Die kleinen Figuren sind jeweils im Moment des<br />

Werdens und Vergehens gefaßt, beinhalten beides auf ungewohnte,<br />

radikale Weise.<br />

Obwohl dieser Eindruck in sich ruhender Prozeßhaftigkeit auch<br />

nach mehrfachem Sehen nicht schwindet, lassen sich doch Strukturen<br />

einer Entwicklung in der Zeit herausarbeiten. So hat Louise O'Konor<br />

einen dialektischen Prozeß erkannt - von Bewegung und Gegenbewe­<br />

gung, These, Antithese und Synthese -, der sich vor allem im Bereich der<br />

dominanten Diagonalen im Verbund mit horizontalen und vertikalen<br />

Motiven ereig<strong>net</strong>. 25<br />

minütigen Fragment ausgeht) 26<br />

259<br />

Monika Zurhake (die leider nur von einem zwei­<br />

hat die filmischen Segmente nach musi­<br />

kalischen Prinzipien aufgeschlüsselt: nach Halb-, Viertel- und Achtel-<br />

werten, nach Triolen und Quartolen, Synkopen und Pausen, und ein<br />

komplexes Geflecht verschiedener Bewegungen konstatiert. Doch diese<br />

Form unhörbarer, in eine grafische Sprache transponierter musikali­<br />

scher Strukturierung ist ungewohnt und schwer faßbar, auch wenn ihre<br />

Wirkung sich unterschwellig mitteilt. Sie bleibt zunächst fremd wie das<br />

System der Tonstufen im Chinesischen oder der Längen und Kürzen in<br />

der antiken Metrik.<br />

Es versteht sich, daß die Symphonie Diagonale stumm projiziert wur­<br />

de. Eine musikalische Begleitung war nicht vorgesehen, hätte auch<br />

Eggelings Konzept der absoluten Kunst widersprochen. Denn diese Kunst<br />

erhebt den Anspruch auf totale und essentielle Geltung, da sie das<br />

geistige Universum in all seinen Polaritäten und Analogien zu repräsen­<br />

tieren sucht. Unterlegt man den Film dennoch versuchsweise mit Musik,<br />

so zeigt sich, daß keine Ergänzung oder Bereicherung, sondern eine<br />

Störung seines subtilen visuellen Rhythmus entsteht. 27<br />

Das Verhältnis<br />

zur Musik ist eines der inneren Verwandtschaft, nicht der Ergänzung<br />

oder Kooperation. Eggeling ging es nicht um das Gesamtkunstwerk im<br />

Sinne einer Verschmelzung der Künste, sondern im Sinne eines Rück­<br />

griffs auf ihre gemeinsamen geistigen Prinzipien.<br />

Walt(h)er Ruttmann, 28<br />

geboren 1887 in Frankfurt am Main, ist fast acht<br />

Jahre jünger als Viking Eggeling. Er besuchte die Malklasse der Münch­<br />

ner Kunstakademie, befreundete sich mit Paul Klee, Lyonel Feininger<br />

und dem Komponisten Max Butting und hatte sich schon vor Ausbruch<br />

des ersten Weltkriegs als Maler und Grafiker einen Namen gemacht."<br />

25 O'Konor (wie Anm. 15), S. 133.<br />

26 Zurhake (wie Anm. 2), S. l08f. Offenbar ist Zurhake einer gekürzten Version auf­<br />

gesessen, möglicherweise verführt von der Kompilation «Forty Years of Experi<br />

ment. Hans Richter 1921-1961», in der Richter seinen eigenen Werken ein Bruch<br />

stück der Symphonie Diagonale voranstellt, ohne auf die Unvollständigkeil dieser<br />

Fassung hinzuweisen.<br />

27 Ich möchte behaupten, daß die Symphonie Diagonale in dieser Hinsicht eine Beson­<br />

derheit darstellt; denn die meisten Filme, gleich welcher Gattung, lassen sich mit<br />

Musik kombinieren. Natürlich ist die Wahl der Begleitmusik nicht beliebig, doch<br />

fast jedes Musikstück wird am gegebenen Film etwas ausrichten, Synergien mit<br />

ihm eingehen, ihn auf die eine oder andere Weise intensivieren.<br />

28 Ruttmann strich das «h» in seinem Vornamen Ende der 20er Jahre, im Zuge der<br />

Neuen Sachlichkeit.<br />

29 Die biografischen Angaben zu Ruttmann, aber auch viele Gedanken und Zitate der<br />

folgenden Seiten sind vor allem |eanpaul Goergens materialreichem Band Walter<br />

Ruttmann: Eine Dokumentation Berlin 1989 verpflichtet


260<br />

Die Kriegsjahre, die er zum Teil als Soldat erlebte, führten zu einer<br />

tiefgreifenden Krise und einer künstlerischen Neuorientierung<br />

Ruttmanns. Über Vorstufen in expressionistischen Bildern, bei denen<br />

die Bewegung fast bis zur Explosion getrieben wird, kommt er schon<br />

früh auf den Film. In dem Manuskript «Malerei mit Zeit» (um 1919/20)<br />

entwirft er die Vision einer kinematografisch beflügelten Malerei, die<br />

sich rhythmisch-dynamisch - und abstrakt - entfalten soll.30 «Es wird<br />

sich [...] ein ganz neuer, bisher nur latent vorhandener Typus von Künst­<br />

ler herausstellen, der etwa in der Mitte von Malerei und Musik steht».<br />

Und er schildert fiktive (expressionistische) Beispiele einer solchen Kunst,<br />

in der «die unendlich vielen Verwendungsmöglichkeiten von Licht und<br />

Finsternis, Ruhe und Bewegtheit, Geradheit und Rundung, Masse und<br />

Feingliedrigkeit und deren unzählige Zwischenstufen und Kombinatio­<br />

nen» zur Geltung kommen sollen.<br />

Ruttmann denkt, ähnlich Eggeling, in Polaritäten und Nuancen, wenn<br />

auch weniger «absolut», weniger philosophisch-metaphysisch als die­<br />

ser. So leitet er seine Vision aus der Analyse und Anschauung der<br />

Gegenwart und den verspürten Defiziten der gegenwärtigen Kunst ab,<br />

deren «starren, reduzierten zeitlosen Formen» er das «Tempo» entge­<br />

gensetzt, das die technische Revolution dem Individuum abfordert. Da­<br />

mit werde der «Zeit-Rhythmus des optischen Geschehens» zu einem der<br />

wichtigsten Elemente einer neuen Kunst. Insgesamt stellt der Text eine<br />

Mischung eher essayistisch hingeworfener Gedanken mit sensuellen<br />

ästhetischen Vorstellungen dar, die zu großer Konkretion gelangen. Er<br />

schließt mit pragmatischen Überlegungen zur Zielgruppe und einer<br />

autobiografischen Erklärung:<br />

Seit fast zehn Jahren bin ich von der Notwendigkeit dieser Kunst über­<br />

zeugt. Erst jetzt bin ich der technischen Schwierigkeiten Herr geworden,<br />

die sich der Ausführung entgegenstellten, und heute weiß ich, daß die<br />

neue Kunst sein und leben wird - denn sie ist wurzelfestes Gewächs und<br />

nicht Konstruktion. 31<br />

In der Tat gelingt es Ruttmann schneller als Eggeling, der sich mit der<br />

Technik schwer tat und viele Rückschläge in Kauf nehmen mußte, sich<br />

das filmische Rüstzeug zu verschaffen. Er experimentiert mit der Kame­<br />

ra, und er erfindet einen eigenen Tricktisch zum «Herstellen kinemato-<br />

30 Das Manuskript, das sich undatiert im Nachlaß fand, ist bei Goergen (wie Anm.<br />

29), S. 73f, abgedruckt.<br />

graphischer Bilder», der 1920 so ausgereift ist, daß er patentiert wird. 32<br />

Der Tisch besteht aus drei übereinander montierten, zum Teil verschieb­<br />

baren Glasplatten, die von unten beleuchtet sind. Damit wird die Kom­<br />

bination verschiedener Bildebenen möglich, wobei je nach Bedarf auf<br />

allen oder nur auf einer Ebene Veränderungen der aufzunehmenden<br />

Motive erfolgen können. Die über dem Tricktisch angebrachte Einzel­<br />

bild-Kamera ist zwar festgeschraubt, aber durch Verstellen der Platten­<br />

höhe läßt sich die Distanz zwischen Objekt und Objektiv kleinschrittig<br />

verändern; so kann im projizierten Film der Eindruck von Heran- oder<br />

Hinwegbewegung simuliert werden. Als malerisches Material ist viskö­<br />

se Farbe vorgesehen, die lange feucht bleibt, so daß sie von Aufnahme<br />

zu Aufnahme weiterbearbeitet werden kann. Natürlich lassen sich auch<br />

ausgeschnittene Formen verwenden oder mit der Farbe kombinieren -<br />

einer Farbe, die allerdings vom Schwarzweiß-Material nur in ihren Hell/<br />

Dunkelwerten registriert wird.<br />

Doch ähnlich wie die Kinoregisseure der Zeit sah Ruttmann keinen<br />

Grund, auf die Farbe zu verzichten. Als farbgebende Techniken standen<br />

damals mehrere Verfahren zur Verfügung: die Tonung (monochrome<br />

Einfärbung der dunklen Bildteile bei der Entwicklung); die Virage (mo­<br />

nochrome Farbbäder der fertigen Kopie, wobei die hellen Bild teile die<br />

Farbe annehmen); die Schablonenkolorierung (bei der einzelne Partien<br />

des Bildes nacheinander mit verschiedenen Farbtönen überzogen wer­<br />

den können) oder auch der manuelle Farbauftrag. Auch konnten die<br />

einzelnen Verfahren kombiniert werden, um eine Fülle von Effekten zu<br />

erzielen.33 Nachteile waren jedoch, daß jede Kopie individuell bearbeitet<br />

werden mußte und daß die Schablonen- und vor allem die Handkolorie-<br />

rung viel Aufwand erforderten. Dennoch scheint Ruttmann von Anfang<br />

an in Farbe gedacht zu haben, während Eggeling sie zwar als eigentliche<br />

Vollendung seiner filmischen Kunst vor Augen hatte, sich aber in der<br />

Praxis mit Schwarzweiß begnügte - als einer Vorstufe, über die er durch<br />

seinen frühen Tod nicht hinausgelangen sollte.<br />

Lichtspiel Opus I entstand 1921, ist etwa neuneinhalb Minuten lang und<br />

koloriert. 34<br />

Verglichen mit Eggelings zarten Linien und abstraktem, for-<br />

32 Der Antrag an das Patentamt, eine Beschreibung des Geräts und eine schematische<br />

Zeichnung sind bei Goergen (wie Anm. 29) S. 75ff., abgedruckt.<br />

33 Zu den verschiedenen Farbverfahren des Stummfilms vgl. Gerd Koshofer: Color.<br />

Die Farben des Films. Berlin 1988.<br />

34 Opus I galt lange als verloren, das Negativ ist bis heute unauffindbar. Doch es<br />

gelang Enno Patalas 1977, den Film in einer sowjetischen Kopie zu identifizieren<br />

Material, das Ruttmann wohl in den 20er Jahren anläßlich einer Filmreise nach Ruß-<br />

261


malen Vokabular wirken Ruttmanns Figuren sehr viel malerischer, pla­<br />

stischer und taktiler. Sie sind hauptsächlich durch von der Glasplatte<br />

fortgewischte dunkle Farbe entstanden, bestehen also, technisch gespro­<br />

chen, aus transparenten Flächen, durch die von unten das Licht dringt.<br />

Meist tragen sie noch die sinnlichen Spuren ihrer Genese: ungleichmä­<br />

ßig harte Ränder sowie gelegentliche Reste der viskosen Farbe und ihrer<br />

263<br />

manuellen Verwischung in Form einer weichen, wolkigen Maserung.<br />

Außerdem lagern sich hin und wieder (wohl eher unbeabsichtigte)<br />

Übermalungshöfe um die Figuren. Zwar sind auch Ruttmanns Kreatio­<br />

nen abstrakt, jedoch mehr im Sinne von «ungegenständlich» als im<br />

Sinne einer immateriellen Geistigkeit. Teils dem geometrisch-stereome­<br />

trischen Inventar entlehnt - Kreise oder Kugeln, Dreiecke, Kegel, Rauten<br />

- , teils eher von organischer, biomorpher Gestalt und Textur, erschei­<br />

nen sie bereits durch Maßstab und Ausdehnung substanzhafter, neh­<br />

men mehr Platz in Anspruch und entwickeln mehr Energie als die<br />

kleinen ätherischen Gebilde der Symphonie Diagonale.<br />

Auch Ruttmanns Figuren schweben in Undefinierter Schwärze, die<br />

ebensogut als Hintergrund wie als dunkle Tiefe gedacht werden könnte<br />

- ein «Behälter ohne Dimensionen», wie Malewitsch es formulierte. 35<br />

Doch sie erfüllen ihn mit dreidimensionalem Leben. Schon die modellie­<br />

rende Maserung der Oberflächen verleiht ihnen eine gewisse Prallheit<br />

oder sphärische Krümmung, und auch die Farbe trägt zu diesem Ein­<br />

druck bei. 36<br />

Ruttmann hat seinen Film offenbar zunächst im Ent­<br />

wicklungsbad bläulich getont, wobei das Blau nur an den Rändern der<br />

Figuren und in den weniger lichtdurchlässigen Zonen durchschlägt; wo<br />

die Formen fest umrissen und klargewischt sind, heben sie sich weiß<br />

vom schwarzen Hintergrund ab. Dort, aber auch neben der bläulichen<br />

Tonung, wurde gelegentlich von Hand nachkoloriert. 37<br />

Daher erstrahlen<br />

land zurückgelassen hatte (vgl. Goergen, wie Anm. 24, S. 97f.). Diese Kopie war<br />

koloriert und vermutlich von integraler Länge.<br />

35 Zitiert nach Rudolf Kurtz: Expressionismus und Film. Zürich 1965 (1926), S. 88.<br />

36 Uber die Farbe kann ich nur anhand der mir zugänglichen Kopie (aus dem Verleih<br />

LightCone, Paris) berichten, die eine Annäherung an die von Patalas gefundene<br />

darstellt. Dabei ist jedoch zu bedenken, daß für die Farbgebung kein eigentliches<br />

Original existiert, da jede Kopie individuell bearbeitet werden mußte und damit<br />

auch verschieden koloriert werden konnte. Diskrepanzen in der Beschreibung<br />

zeitgenössischer Kritiker - zum Beispiel dem weiter unten zitierten Text von Alfred<br />

Kerr - können der individuellen Wahrnehmung, dem fehlerhaften Gedächtnis oder<br />

auch tatsächlichen Unterschieden des gezeigten Werks entspringen.<br />

37 Möglicherweise hat Ruttmann bereits für Opus I statt der Handkolorierung eine<br />

Methode verwendet, wie sie Lore Leudesdorff für spätere Arbeiten beschreibt:<br />

Abdecken bestimmter Bildzonen (mit entfernbarem Lack), so daß sie bei Farbbädern<br />

der Kopie unbehandelt bleiben - eine Art Batik. (Vgl. Goergen, wie Anm. 29 , S. 25.)


264<br />

einzelne Formen in sattem Rotorange, während andere in zartes Rosa,<br />

Lila oder Blaugrün getaucht sind oder aber sich weiß behaupten. Da sich<br />

die Blauschattierung, die meist das «hintere», stumpfere Ende der Figu­<br />

ren kennzeich<strong>net</strong>, als Distanzierung auswirkt, die rote Farbe dagegen<br />

größere Nähe suggeriert, kommt die Spannung zwischen beiden Tönen<br />

der räumlichen Illusion zugute.<br />

Hauptfaktor der Tiefenillusion ist jedoch die Bewegung. Ruttmanns<br />

Figuren kommen und gehen in stetiger, den Blick bannender Aktion,<br />

und ihr musikalischer Rhythmus akzentuiert das Tempo. Sie wölben<br />

sich, beugen sich nach innen, gleiten in leichter Drehung durchs Bild,<br />

stechen aus den Ecken diagonal hervor, fallen von beiden Seiten symme­<br />

trisch zur Mitte oder pendeln hin und her, wobei sie sich wie organische<br />

Gebilde leicht deformieren, stauchen oder strecken. Auch der Kontrast<br />

zwischen weichen und harten Umrissen trägt zur Illusion der Bewegung<br />

bei; denn die harten Ränder schärfen sich sozusagen in Fahrtrichtung,<br />

während die weichen die Figuren am hinteren Ende (wie ein Kometen­<br />

schweif) ausklingen lassen.38 Auch Bewegung aus oder in die Tiefe -<br />

Größer- oder Kleinerwerden - kommt gelegentlich vor. Außerdem ein<br />

Spiel mit dem Rahmen: Oft gewinnt man den Eindruck, als zögen sich<br />

die Figuren zurück in ein Gelände außerhalb der Bildgrenzen, ein Off<br />

von unbekannter Ausdehnung, dessen Existenz das Bild als Ausschnitt<br />

definiert (in den man wie durch ein Fenster blickt). Oder sie scheinen an<br />

die Bildgrenzen wie an imaginäre Wände zu stoßen, von ihnen abzu­<br />

prallen. Damit erfolgt eine gewisse Verortung oder Anerkennung räum­<br />

licher, materieller Gegebenheiten, eine tentative Auseinandersetzung<br />

mit der dritten Dimension.<br />

Die Figuren bewegen sich rasch oder getragen, aber jeweils zielsi­<br />

cher und gleichsam selbstbewußt, auch wenn sie gelegentlichen Meta­<br />

morphosen und Instabilitäten unterworfen sind. Allerdings finden sie<br />

immer wieder zurück zu faßbaren, mehr oder weniger bekannten und<br />

suggestiven Formen. Meist scheinen sozusagen zwei Parteien, von je<br />

unterschiedlicher Gestalt, zum Zuge zu kommen: Zacken gegen Zungen<br />

zum Beispiel, oder Kreise gegen Strahlen. Aber auch aus der Farbge­<br />

bung erwachsen Allianzen. Vielfach existieren auch mehrere Exemplare<br />

derselben Art, die im Verbund agieren. Die Figuren umspielen sich in<br />

Choreografischer Präzision, weichen einander in eleganten Kurven aus<br />

oder ducken sich, so daß es selten zu Berührungen kommt. Knappe<br />

Vermeidung, spielerisches Risiko der Kollision kennzeich<strong>net</strong> dieses<br />

38 Ein Brief an Oskar Fischinger vom 17. Juli 1922 dokumentiert, daß Ruttmann<br />

größten Wert auf die Bewegungskonturen legte. Abgedruckt in Hein/Herzogenrath<br />

(wie Anm. 2), S. 22.<br />

Schauspiel. Nur ganz selten ereignen sich Aggressionen, die Figuren<br />

überfahren einander oder reißen sich in den Abgrund.<br />

Angesichts solcher filmischen Vorgänge ist die Versuchung groß,<br />

die agierenden Formen sowohl gegenständlich zu identifizieren wie mit<br />

Eigenschaften und Intentionen zu beseelen. In der Beschreibung erge­<br />

ben sich solche Attributierungen fast zwangsläufig, denn jedes sprachli­<br />

che Erfassen arbeitet mit Vergleichen, Ähnlichkeiten, Assoziationen. Doch<br />

das Beispiel Symphonie Diagonale zeigt, daß nicht jeder abstrakte Film in<br />

gleichem Maße konkrete Äquivalenzen evoziert; Eggelings und Rutt­<br />

manns Werke unterscheiden sich hier wesentlich.<br />

Dies kommt bereits in den zeitgenössischen Texten zu beiden Künst­<br />

lern zum Ausdruck, die bei Ruttmann regelrecht in Beseelung schwel­<br />

gen 39<br />

, während bei Eggeling vor allem die strenge Abstraktion betont<br />

wird: «Wie in der Musik ist auch hier jede Assoziation an Gegenstände<br />

oder Vorgänge der Natur ausgeschlossen.» 40<br />

265<br />

Texte über die Symphonie<br />

Diagonale sind typischerweise eher theoretisch gefaßt und von seriöser<br />

Zurückhaltung. Dagegen liest sich die Kritik zu Opus I, die Alfred Kerr<br />

im Berliner Tageblatt vom 16.6.1921 veröffentlichte, fast wie ein kulinari­<br />

sches kleines Kunstwerk:<br />

[...] Was Ruttmann flimmern läßt, ist nur ein Gemeng von schwebend-<br />

huschend-schrumpfend-zuckenden Kringeln, Ringeln, Kugeln, Spitzheiten,<br />

Rundheiten; von erglühtem Umriß, schwindsamer Füllung, bunten Er­<br />

gänzungen; von Tauchendem und Sinkendem.<br />

Irgendeine violette Raupe wächst zum gekrümmten Kolben; rollt sich zu<br />

einem Edamer; zu einem Mond; zu einem immer kleineren Edamer; zu<br />

einem Apfelsinchen. Fischähnlich wie ein unbekanntes Zaubertier gleitet<br />

allerhand leuchtendes Gebild' in holden Windungen schleifensanft über<br />

das Flimmerlaken ... Ein Sonnenstreif, zitronig, fegt wie ein Besen von<br />

links nach rechts, erblaßt, verklingt. Ein gelbliches Dreieck schießt in die<br />

Höh' ... entwimmelt und zerduftet. Etwas Grünglitzerndes schwillt,<br />

schwimmt, schwindet. (Es ist nicht genau so - doch die Sprache muß das<br />

nachsingen.)<br />

Man denkt an Expressionistenbilder. Die sind aber unbewegsam. Chagalls<br />

Leuchtparadiese bleiben doch starr. Die Funkelfuturismen der neuesten<br />

39 Offenbar wirkten die Ruttmannschen Formen auf die Zeitgenossen auch suggestiv<br />

im sexuellen Sinne. Jedenfalls wird der erotische Charakter der Opus-Filme immer<br />

wieder, und oft mißbilligend, herausgehoben. Opus II wurde sogar unter Jugend-<br />

verbot gestellt-ob aus erotischen Gründen oder weil man hypnotische Reaktionen<br />

des Publikums befürchtete, ist unklar. Vgl. Wilmesmeier (wie Anm. 2), S. 51 ff., mit<br />

einschlägigen Zitaten.<br />

40 B. G. Kawan. In: Film Kurier, Nr. 276, 27. November 1924.


266<br />

Pariser versteinern reglos - im Rahmen. Hier aber flitzen Dinge, rudern,<br />

brennen, steigen, stoßen, quellen, gleiten, schreiten, welken, fließen, schwel­<br />

len, dämmern; entfalten sich, wölben sich, breiten sich, verringern sich,<br />

kugeln sich, engen sich, schärfen sich, teilen sich, krümmen sich, heben<br />

sich, füllen sich, leeren sich, blähen sich, ducken sich; blümein und ver­<br />

krümeln sich.<br />

Kurz: Expressionismus in Bewegtheit. Ein Rausch für die Pupille ... Aber<br />

kein Menschenfilm.<br />

Alfred Kerrs einfühlsame Akzentuierung biomorpher Prozesse wird<br />

durch viele Eigenschaften des Films gestützt. Schon die Gestalt und<br />

Gestik mancher der Figuren gibt ihm recht, insbesondere das Körper­<br />

verhalten der «fischähnlichen» Gebilde, die auf- und niedergleiten, als<br />

tummelten sie sich im Wasser, sich zur Schmalseite hin verkürzen, leich­<br />

te Drehungen vollziehen und sich wieder zur Breitseite strecken. Solche<br />

Augenblicke evozieren in der Tat ein Aquarium. Ähnlich wirkt sich<br />

Ruttmanns Nutzung physikalischer Gegebenheiten aus, wie die feste<br />

vordere und weiche hintere Kontur, dank derer er ein natürliches stoffli­<br />

ches Phänomen imitiert. Und das Hauptmotiv des Films, das Sich-Aus-<br />

weichen der Figuren, schließt wie von selbst eine Beseelung ein, denn sie<br />

scheinen einander wahrzunehmen, aufeinander zu reagieren.<br />

Doch Kerr läßt sich hinreißen. Schon die Wortwahl - «Edamer» oder<br />

«Apfelsinchen» - schießt über das gerechtfertigte Maß hinaus, denn<br />

Ruttmanns Film enthält wenig Niedliches, obschon er streckenweise<br />

sehr gefällig ist. Der Vorbehalt Bernhard Diebolds (der den Film bewun­<br />

derte) ist nicht ganz ungerechtfertigt: «Dieser Versuch hat noch kunstge­<br />

werblichen Anstrich trotz innerlichem Willen.» 11<br />

Allerdings fängt<br />

Ruttmann die Anlehnung an die Natur und ans Narrative vielfach durch<br />

Abstraktionen und formale Spannungen wieder auf. Einerseits lädt er<br />

zwar immer wieder zur Einfühlung ein und gewinnt dabei an emotiona­<br />

ler Wärme; aber andererseits bildet diese Tendenz nur ein Element<br />

innerhalb eines wesentlich größeren Registers, in dem es zugleich um<br />

grundsätzliche visuelle Polaritäten wie Licht/Dunkelheit, Farbe/<br />

Schwarzweiß, Kantigkeit/Rundung, Linie/Fläche geht und um musika­<br />

lische Grundstrukturen wie Kontrast und Interaktion der Motive, Varia­<br />

tion, Wechsel der Instrumentierung, Wechsel der Tempi. Daß diese for­<br />

male Auseinandersetzung bei der Rezeption leicht ins Hintertreffen ge­<br />

rät, weil der empathische Sog der Figuren so stark ist, könnte Ruttmanns<br />

41 Bernhard Diebold: «Eine neue Kunst. Augenmusik des Films». In: Frankfurter Zei<br />

tung, 2. April 1921.<br />

Unerfahrenheit zuzuschreiben sein. Als Maler war er mit dem Phäno­<br />

men nicht konfrontiert, daß sich auch ungegenständliche Formen durch<br />

Bewegung «animieren» und verselbständigen können.<br />

Ruttmann, dem es darum ging, möglichst viele Künste in einem<br />

sensuell möglichst reichen Film zu vereinen, hatte den Komponisten<br />

(und Freund) Max Butting gebeten, eine Begleitmusik zu schreiben<br />

Butting selbst leuchtete ein solches Zusammenspiel der Künste nicht<br />

unbedingt ein. 42<br />

In der Tat besteht auch die Gefahr, daß die musikalische<br />

Grundstruktur des Films - der zudem in einer Art Sonatenform drei<br />

Sätze umfaßt, die durch kurze Schwarzfilm-Pausen voneinander ge­<br />

trennt sind - in Konkurrenz zur Musik tritt. Oder die Musik muß sich,<br />

umgekehrt, «hüten, zu selbstherrlich zu werden, sonst wird die Augen­<br />

kunst zur Illustration». 43<br />

267<br />

Doch das Streichquartett, das Butting, wohl aus<br />

Gefälligkeit, komponierte, rechtfertigt diese Befürchtung nicht;44 ohne<br />

redundante Parallelisierung, ohne Mickey-Mouse-Effekte und ohne Süße<br />

erfüllt sie den Film mit Schmelz und Tiefe.<br />

Opus III, der 1923/24 unter Mitarbeit der Bauhaus-Schülerin Lore<br />

Leudesdorff entstand, war, wie Berndt Heller anhand der Begleitmusik<br />

42 Vgl. die Zitate aus einem Brief Buttings (vom 5. September 1950 an die Filmhistoriska<br />

Samlingarna) bei Goergen (wie Anm. 29), S. 22f. Anläßlich einer Besprechung der<br />

Farblichtmusik Alexander Laszlos formulierte Butting seine grundsätzliche Skepsis<br />

gegenüber den synästhetischen Euphorien seiner Zeitgenossen:


268 269<br />

Hanns Eislers nachweist 45<br />

, ursprünglich dreieinhalb Minuten lang. Über­<br />

lieferte längere Kopien enthalten noch Motive aus Opus I und II, die dem<br />

Werk seine Geschlossenheit nehmen und seinen Rhythmus stören. Die<br />

mir zugängliche Kopie ist (inklusive dieser Zusätze) 46<br />

segmentweise in<br />

verschiedenen gedämpften Farben getont. Diese Kolorierung erscheint<br />

dem Film angemessen und dürfte authentisch sein; denn hier treten,<br />

ungleich Opus 1, keine Formen auf, die sich zur handkolorierten Akzen­<br />

tuierung geeig<strong>net</strong> hätten, und die meisten Oberflächen sind bereits in<br />

sich strukturiert oder silhouettenhaft schwarz. Ruttmann verfügte zu­<br />

nächst über keine Begleitkomposition, sondern wählte musikalisch-aku­<br />

stische Ad-hoc-Lösungen (zum Beispiel Trommeln bei einer Londoner<br />

Aufführung, 1925). Hanns Eislers «Präludium in Form einer Passacaglia»,<br />

ein Werk für Kammerorchester, das später mit dem Film aufgeführt<br />

wurde, entstand erst 1926. 47<br />

Opus III greift - wie auch Opus 11 oder der letzte Film der Reihe, Opus<br />

IV - manche Formen und Strukturprinzipien von Opus I wieder auf. Es<br />

ist interessant zu beobachten, wie Ruttmann hier zugleich Früheres<br />

weiterentwickelt und zu Neuem vorstößt. Vieles ist prägnant geklärt,<br />

das im ersten und zweiten Film noch unentschieden geblieben oder<br />

noch wenig ausgearbeitet war, und in deutlicher Richtung weitergetrie­<br />

ben - manchmal bis zu einer neuen, prinzipielleren Ambiguität. Opus IV<br />

wird dann zwar seinerseits formale Gedanken dieses Films fortsetzen,<br />

gibt sich aber insgesamt harmonischer und bietet weniger Vielfalt. Opus<br />

III soll daher diese Untersuchung beschließen.<br />

Zu betrachten ist zunächst der Hintergrund, Untergrund oder Raum<br />

des Geschehens. Schon in Opus II zeigen sich neue Auffassungen, schon<br />

hier ist die durchgehend schwarze Tiefe des Bildraums, die Opus I und<br />

die Symphonie Diagonale kennzeich<strong>net</strong>, streckenweise einer strukturier­<br />

ten (und damit auch farbigen) Bearbeitung gewichen. Maserung,<br />

flickerndes, flimmerndes Licht, Veränderung und Bewegung kommen<br />

45 Vgl. Berndt Hellers Ausführungen zur Rekonstruktion des Films in Kinemathek<br />

Berlin, 20. Jg., Heft 62: «Film in den Niederlanden gestern und heute», Juni 1983,<br />

S. 21f.<br />

46 Die Kopie wird von LightCone, Paris, stumm verliehen; beigelegt ist eine Ton­<br />

kassette mit Eislers Musik, die jedoch wegen abweichender Läng schwer plazierbar<br />

ist.<br />

47 Eislers Komposition wurde 1927 an den Baden-Badener Kammermusiktagen in<br />

doppelter Form aufgeführt: sowohl live mit Orchester wie als integrierte Tonfilm­<br />

kopie nach dem Tri-Ergon-Verfahren. Leider ist diese Kopie verloren. Eislers Mu­<br />

sikstück ist in seine «1. Orchestersuite op. 23» als erster Satz eingegangen. Vgl.<br />

Heller (wie Aura. 45) und in: Christian Kuntze (Hg.): Hanns Eisler - Komposition für­<br />

den Film. Dokumente und Materialien zu den Filmkompositionen Hanns Eislers.<br />

Materialienheft Nr 12 der Freunde der deutschen Kinemathek Berlin 1982 S 43ff


270<br />

nun in Opus III allenthalben vor und heben den Unterschied zwischen<br />

agierender Form und sie umgebendem freien Raum auf. Nur noch gele­<br />

gentlich bewegen sich Figuren in einer immateriellen Arena, und auch<br />

diese ist oft hell gehalten, so daß sich die Wertigkeit von Figur und<br />

Grund immer wieder umkehrt. Meist behauptet sich gar kein durchge­<br />

haltenes figürliches Eigenleben - und es gibt, wie erwähnt, auch keine<br />

farbliche Sonderbehandlung einzelner Formen mehr -, sondern das Bild<br />

verwandelt sich in einem Prozeß, der alle Zonen erfassen kann. Damit<br />

ist der Eindruck einer klaren dreidimensionalen Leere aufgegeben zu­<br />

gunsten eines ambivalenten Raumgeschehens, in dem Fläche und Tiefe<br />

stufenlos ineinander übergehen können und räumliche Verhältnisse zwar<br />

immer wieder angedeutet sind, sich aber nicht zu einer zentral­<br />

perspektivischen Tiefenillusion verfestigen. Einerseits ist Opus III daher<br />

weniger räumlich als Opus 1, doch gibt es andererseits keinerlei «Raum­<br />

scheu» mehr, keine Isolation der Figuren im Absoluten. Eine taktile<br />

Materialität kennzeich<strong>net</strong> das ganze Bild. Es ist konkreter geworden,<br />

aber auch instabiler, metamorphotischer, kühler, abstrakter. «Abstrakt»<br />

jedoch wiederum nicht im geistigen Sinne Eggelings, sondern im Sinne<br />

ungegenständlicher Sinnlichkeit oder abstrahierter Wirklichkeit.<br />

Diesem Befund entspricht auch der Charakter der Formen. Nur<br />

ausnahmsweise tragen sie organische, an Lebewesen erinnernde Gestalt<br />

oder bewegen sich in biomorphem Gestus. Statt der züngelnden, gerun­<br />

deten Gebilde und fischähnlichen Scheiben von Opus I beherrschen eher<br />

tektonische Konstruktionen die Leinwand. Stäbe, die die Komposition<br />

teilen, kontrastieren mit Flecken und Schlieren ohne eindeutige Kontur;<br />

Rechtecke, die aufeinander aufbauen, sich verschieben, ersetzen, über­<br />

lappen, bilden Subkadragen oder Podeste, auf denen sich ein weiteres<br />

Geschehen ereig<strong>net</strong>, liegen auf einem Grund amorpher Texturen oder<br />

werden von ihnen überzogen. Kommt es gelegentlich zu konkreteren<br />

Formen und Bewegungen, so folgen sie eher maschinellen Mustern und<br />

erinnern an die Dynamik von Pleuelstangen, das Stampfen von Kolben<br />

oder die Windung von Transportbändern - doch ohne daß etwas Be­<br />

stimmtes identifizierbar würde. Vielmehr geht es um die Essenz maschi­<br />

nellen Verhaltens, das, ähnlich den Windkanal-Phänomenen von Opus I,<br />

manchmal auch in seinen physikalischen Eigenschaften evoziert wird.<br />

Die zeitgenössische Faszination an der Technik ist unverkennbar.<br />

Empathie oder beseelende Projektion kommen angesichts solchen<br />

Geschehens nicht oder nur noch in minimalen Ansätzen, etwa bei Mo­<br />

menten der Schwerkraft, auf. Das Interesse am Verhalten der Figuren ist<br />

durch ein reiches Angebot komplexer Vorgänge ersetzt. Es gibt viel und<br />

vieles gleichzeitig zu beobachten. Die Technik ist differenzierter und<br />

perfekter geworden, der Formenkatalog erweitert und verfeinert. Die<br />

Kompositionen wechseln oder wandeln sich rasch und oft radikal, rhyth­<br />

mische Spannungen und Kontrapunkte bauen'sich auf und zergehen,<br />

Übergänge und Umschwünge vollziehen sich elegant und überraschend.<br />

Vor allem aber ist eine Dimension hinzugetreten, die in Opus I noch<br />

kaum zu ahnen war, sich in Opus II allerdings schon deutlich ankündigt:<br />

das Wirken von Licht und Schatten, zentrales Prinzip der Fotografie.<br />

Natürlich spielt das Licht auch im ersten Film eine Rolle, wenn es<br />

von unten durch Glasplatten und Farbverwischungen dringt, wurde<br />

dort aber - ähnlich wie bei Eggeling - nicht als aktive Größe eingesetzt,<br />

sondern nur zur technischen Erzeugung von Hlelligkeit. Lediglich in den<br />

wolkigen Maserungen von Opus I ist ein gewisses Flimmern aufgeho­<br />

ben, das aber gegenüber der Farbbehandlung in den Hintergrund (ritt.<br />

In Opus II ist diesem Phänomen schon mehr Beachtung geschenkt, die<br />

Oberflächen oszillieren, trotz Einfärbung, als erstrahlten sie von innen<br />

mit pulsierendem Licht, und gewinnen dadurch eine eigenartig lebendi­<br />

ge Tiefe. Eine Modellierung durch Licht und Schatten, wie sie durch<br />

einfallende Strahlen entsteht, kommt aber erst in Opus III wirklich auf.<br />

Hier tritt neben die malerisch-grafische Behandlung von Hell- und<br />

Dunkelheit oder den stationären pulsierenden Lichteffekt der Eindruck<br />

von Lichthöfen um manche Objekte oder Lichtflecken in bestimmten<br />

Bildzonen, von grell erleuchteten Formen oder aber Silhouetten, die sich<br />

vor gegensätzlichen Hintergründen abheben, oder sogar von gelegentli­<br />

chen Schatten, welche die Figuren auf den Untergrund werfen. Damit ist<br />

Opus III zwar nicht zum Abbild eines künstlich beleuchteten Raumes<br />

oder einer Landschaft geworden, auf die das Mondlicht fällt; viel zu<br />

sporadisch oder auch widersprüchlich verhalten sich die Effekte, um<br />

eine illusionäre Konstanz zu behaupten. Doch der Reichtum potentieller<br />

Wahrnehmungsweisen und Suggestionen, das Spannimgsfeld zwischen<br />

Abstraktionen und Konkretisierungen ist immens und um spezifisch<br />

fotografische Parameter gewachsen.<br />

Eher verborgen im üppigen Gefüge der Formen enthält Opus III<br />

schließlich einen grundsätzlichen Bruch mit der bisherigen Arbeitswei­<br />

se. 48<br />

Zwar herrscht auch in den früheren Filmen kein Purismus der<br />

Methoden, der Tricktisch erlaubte neben der Wischtechnik jederzeit<br />

auch Legeprozesse oder die Arbeit mit Schablonen, die scherenschnitt­<br />

artig in Erscheinung treten, sich staffeln oder überschneiden; darüber<br />

48 Vgl. den Bericht über die Arbeit Ruttmanns mit Lotte Reiniger von Guido Seeber:<br />

Der Trickfilm in seinen grundsätzlichen Möglichkeiten. Berlin 1927 (Nachdruck Frank­<br />

furt a. M. 1979), S. 190f.<br />

271


272<br />

hinaus hat Ruttmann auch mit Sand oder Wachs experimentiert. Doch in<br />

Opus 111 manifestiert sich plötzlich ein abgefilmtes dreidimensionales<br />

Objekt: eine schwarze, silhouettenhafte Spiralstange (möglicherweise<br />

ein Bohrer), die in langsamer Drehung aufgenommen ist und deren<br />

Ausbuchtungen am Schaft fast nur in der Kontur sichtbar werden. Doch<br />

leichte Glanzlichter verraten die Rundungen des Objekts. Die Stange<br />

reiht sich zwar wie selbstverständlich in die übrigen Formen ein oder<br />

wird von ihnen vorbereitet, nimmt aber durch ihre Verweildauer und<br />

den klaren weißen Hintergrund eine gewisse Sonderstellung ein. Offen­<br />

bar fasziniert vom optischen Potential des realen Objekts ließ Ruttmann<br />

sich hier auf ein heterogenes fotografisches Register ein - wenn auch<br />

diskret eingebunden in den übrigen Film und nicht mit dem Effekt der<br />

Collage. Andeutungsweise sind die Maschinen-Abstraktionen seiner spä­<br />

teren Werke vorweggenommen.<br />

Ruttmann ist, in den Worten von Rudolf Kurtz, «nicht darauf aus, die<br />

Kräfte des Lebens in mathematisch bestimmte, zeitlose Formen auszudrü­<br />

cken, er stellt die Einfühlung, den dekorativen Reiz, die psychologische<br />

Wirkung in seine Rechnung ein». 49<br />

Während Eggeling sich auf radikale<br />

Weise enthält, die Einfühlung zu ermutigen oder ein verbindendes Raum­<br />

gefühl aufkommen zu lassen, und daher «absolut» im wesentlichen Sinne<br />

des Wortes bleibt, sucht Ruttmann den schwelgerischen Reiz auch in der<br />

Abstraktion. Zwar entwickelt er sich deutlich weg von beseelten, schein­<br />

bar intentional handelnden Figuren hin zu strengerem formalem Ernst,<br />

doch seine Formen gewinnen zugleich an lebendiger Sensualität und<br />

Taktilität und verschmelzen mit einem ebenfalls taktilen Grund. Damit<br />

ist Ruttmann von Worringers Charakterisierung des Abstraktionsdranges,<br />

bei dem «das Leben als solches [...] als Störung des ästhetischen Genusses<br />

empfunden» werde, denkbar weit entfernt; es geht ihm nicht darum, «in<br />

der Betrachtung eines Notwendigen und Unverrückbaren erlöst zu wer­<br />

den vom Zufälligen des Menschseins überhaupt, von der scheinbaren<br />

Willkür der allgemeinen organischen Existenz». 50<br />

Auch in der Auffassung ihrer Rolle als Künstler unterscheiden sich<br />

Ruttmann und Eggeling sehr nachdrücklich. Während Eggeling jede<br />

Subjektivierung ablehnt, sich gleichsam aus dem eigenen Werk heraus­<br />

hält, da er sich nur als Vermittler der Vergeistigung auffaßt, ist in<br />

Ruttmanns abstrakten Filmen ein prozeßhafter, impulsiver, genießeri­<br />

scher Gestus spürbar, der auf den Künstler, seine emotionalen Spannun­<br />

gen und seinen Umgang mit dem Material verweist.<br />

49 Kurtz (wie Anm. 35), S. 102.<br />

Die Unterschiede und Gemeinsamkeiten in Eggelings und Ruttmanns<br />

Formensprache und abstraktem Ansatz wurden den Zeitgenossen 1925<br />

in der legendären Filmmatinee «Der absolute Film» vor Augen gestellt,<br />

die am 3. Mai von der Novembergruppe in Zusammenarbeit mit der<br />

Kulturabteilung der Ufa veranstaltet wurde: im Berliner Ufa-Theater,<br />

das immerhin 900 Plätze bot. Eggelings Symphonie Diagonale kam unmit­<br />

telbar vor Ruttmanns Opus 11 - IV zur Aufführung (Opus I fehlte) 51<br />

. Als<br />

weiterer abstrakter Film wurde Hans Richters Film ist Rhythmus (ca.<br />

1921-24) gezeigt. Eingeleitet war das Programm durch Ludwig Hirsch-<br />

feld-Macks Lichtreflexionen Dreiteilige Farbensonatine und Reflektorische<br />

Farbenspiele. Und als Gegengewicht zum abstrakten deutschen Film dien­<br />

ten zwei französische, eher dadaistisch-surreale Werke: Fernand Leger/<br />

Dudley Murphys Images Mobiles von 1924 (das unter dem Titel Ballet<br />

Mecanique in die Filmgeschichte eingegangen ist) und Rene Clair/ Francis<br />

Picabias Entr' acte, ebenfalls von 1924.<br />

Die Matinee erwies sich als Erfolg und Skandalon zugleich. Einer­<br />

seits stieß sie auf so große Nachfrage, daß man sie eine Woche später<br />

wiederholte (und auch anderweitig, in Hannover, aufführte). Doch an­<br />

dererseits reagierte ein Großteil des Publikums mit unverhohlener Ag­<br />

gression, Gehässigkeit, Verständnislosigkeit. Auch die meisten Kritiken<br />

spiegelten eine solche Haltung. Sie strotzten von «Mißfallensfloskeln»;<br />

aber sie belegen auch eine «unübersehbare Niveaulosigkeit», die einem<br />

«psycho-physiologischen Wahrnehmungsdefekt' der weitgehend lach­<br />

fremden Kritiker entsprang, wie Wilmesmeier ausführt. 52<br />

273<br />

Obwohl die<br />

mangelnde Qualifikation von Publikum und Presse auch den Filmema­<br />

chern nicht entgangen sein dürfte, mag sie dennoch ihre Wirkung entfal­<br />

tet und sie darin bestärkt haben, von der mühevollen Arbeit am I rick­<br />

tisch Abstand zu nehmen. 53<br />

Dennoch überrascht die Kürze der Blüte, die dem absoluten abstrak­<br />

ten Film beschieden war. Angesichts der vielen Hoffnungen, die in ihn<br />

gesetzt wurden, der Manifeste, die ihn heraufbeschworen, und der Eil­<br />

st Möglicherweise erschien der Film durch seine noch unausgereifte Technik und<br />

insbesondere die beseelten Formen überholt; möglicherweise war er auch den<br />

inzwischen sehr erfolgreichen - Werbefilmen zu ähnlich, die Ruttmann parallel<br />

zum Opus-Zvklus schuf.<br />

52 Wilmesmeier (wie Anm. 2) hat die Rezeption der Filmmatinee einer eingehenden<br />

Analyse unterzogen.<br />

53 Ruttmann, an Erfolge gewöhnt und auf sie bedacht, ahnte auch, daß dem abstrak<br />

ten Avantgardefilm ein ähnliches Schicksal beschieden sein möge wie der atonalen<br />

Musik: «Soll er in schlecht besuchte Konzertsäle abwandern, sich klösterlich destillieren<br />

für eine kleine Gemeinde ästhetisch Anspruchsvoller, die über die Reinheit<br />

seiner Struktur wachen?» Zitiert nach Goergen (wie Anm. 29), S. 37.


274<br />

phorie jener Künstler und Kritiker, die ihn als neue Kunst und notwen­<br />

dige Entwicklung gefeiert hatten, wäre eine größere Vitalität dieser<br />

Kunstform zu erwarten gewesen - von der überzeugenden ästhetischen<br />

Qualität der Filme ganz zu schweigen. Allerdings ist zu berücksichtigen,<br />

daß viele Grundsätze und Theorien, auf die sich der deutsche abstrakte<br />

Film bezog, in der Vergangenheit wurzelten. Der Entschluß, sich als<br />

Maler des Mediums Film zu bedienen, war zwar radikal und modern<br />

und schien eine neue Ästhetik zu versprechen; doch er bildete eher eine<br />

Art Kulmination malerischer Bewegungstendenzen und künstlerischer<br />

Grenzüberschreitung, wie sie die ersten beiden Dekaden des Jahrhun­<br />

derts geprägt hatten. Im Medium Film lagen dagegen Möglichkeiten der<br />

Fotografie und der Montage beschlossen, die in ganz anderer Weise, auf<br />

einer ganz anderen Ebene die zeitgenössische Ästhetik herausforderten.<br />

So basiert der französische Film Ballet Mecanique, der in der Matinee<br />

enthalten war, auf einer lebendigen Collage heterogener Elemente. Er<br />

integriert malerisch-grafische Bilder mit fotografischen Abstraktionen,<br />

kaleidoskopisch verfremdeten Alltagsutensilien oder Maschinenteilen,<br />

mit Straßenaufnahmen, inszenierten Personen, fragmentarischen Ge­<br />

sichtern oder auch gestalteter Schrift. Die zentralperspektivisch-fotogra­<br />

fische Illusion wechselt mit geometrischen Kompositionen, blitzende<br />

Lichtreflexe kontrastieren mit flächiger Farbe. Auch das «Cinema pur»,<br />

ein anderer Ansatz der französischen Avantgarde, versucht sich ganz<br />

auf die medienspezifischen Eigenschaften des Films zu besinnen, die in<br />

lyrischer Weise ausgelotet werden. In den Filmen von Henri Chomette -<br />

Jeux des reflets et de la vitesse von 1923-25 oder Cinq minutes de cinema pur<br />

von 1925 - gibt es beispielsweise fließende Übergänge von abstrahieren­<br />

der Fotografie zu gegenständlichen Realaufnahmen, technische Verfrem­<br />

dungen durch Geschwindigkeitsmanipulation, Mehrfachbelichtung oder<br />

Wechsel zum Negativ neben stimmungsvollen Naturmotiven oder tech­<br />

nischer Dynamik.<br />

Gleichzeitig propagierte Laszlo Moholy-Nagy, der ab 1923 am Bau­<br />

haus tätig war, die künstlerische, «produktive» Nutzung von Fotografie<br />

und Film, die er ihrem reproduktiven Gebrauch entgegensetzte. «Der<br />

fotografische Apparat hat uns überraschende Möglichkeiten geliefert,<br />

mit deren Auswertung wir eben erst beginnen», schreibt er 1925 in<br />

seinem Buch Malerei, Fotografie, Film. Und zwei Jahre später zählt er die<br />

filmischen Funktionen des Lichts auf:<br />

Wechselnde Lichtintensitäten und Lichttempi. Bewegungsvariationen des<br />

Raumes durch Licht. Erlöschen und Aufblitzen des ganzen Bewegungs­<br />

organismus, unseres Gehirns. Lichtgreifbarkeit. Lichtbewegung. Lichtferne<br />

und Lichtnähe. Durchdringende und aulbauende Strahlung: stärkste opti­<br />

sche Erlebnisse, die den Menschen zuteil werden können.54<br />

Schon 1921/22 hatte Moholy-Nagy die «Skizze zu einem Film­<br />

manuskript» Dynamik der Großstadt entworfen - ein Projekt, das jedoch<br />

nicht zur Ausführung kam. Vorgesehen waren vor allem Aufnahmen<br />

technischer Prozesse, wie Hausbau, Rangierbahnhof, Straßenverkehr,<br />

die in Bewegungskontrasten, formalen Analogien, Wechsel visueller<br />

Abstraktionen zu konkreten Bildern montiert werden sollten.55 Hier wa­<br />

ren Möglichkeiten einer Verklammerung von fotografischem Realfilm<br />

und abstrakter Kunst ausgelotet, die in eine ganz andere Richtung wie­<br />

sen als die «absolute» Animation.<br />

Nach 1925 setzte nur Oskar Fischinger die Arbeit am abstrakten<br />

animierten Film fort - allerdings in einem beschwingt-gefälligen, be­<br />

kannte Werke der Musikgeschichte illustrierenden Stil. Viking Eggeling<br />

war verstorben; Hans Richter wandte sich mit Filmstudie (1926) einer<br />

Mischform zu, die nach französischer Art abstrahierende und gegen­<br />

ständliche Fotografie kombiniert, und drehte teildokumentarische expe­<br />

rimentelle Kurzfilme, die vor allem mit virtuosen Montage-Effekten<br />

spielen. Walter Ruttman nutzte seine Animationstechnik nur noch im<br />

Werbefilm. Seine berühmte formalistische Studie von 1927, Berlin. Die<br />

Sinfonie einer Großstadt, erinnert in vielem an Moholy-Nagys Berlin-<br />

Projekt und bezeugt, in welchem Maße die Faszination des Realfilms<br />

auch Ruttmann erfaßt hatte.<br />

54 Laszlo Moholy-Nagy: «Die beispiellose Fotografie». In: i 10, Jg. 1, Nr. 3. Amsterdam<br />

1927. Zitiert nach Schneede (wie Anm. 1), S. 245.<br />

55 Moholy-Nagys «Skizze., ist in seinem Buch Malerei, Fotografie, Film abgedruckt<br />

(Mainz 1967, Faksimile der Ausgabe von 1927, S. 122ff.).<br />

275


BLOCK 2<br />

FRANKREICH – SURREALISMUS UND DADAISMUS


Hans RICHTER: Le coeur à barbe. In: Ders.: Dada – Kunst und<br />

Antikunst. Köln: DuMont 1964, S. 194-196.<br />

Le coeur á barbe (Das bärtige Herz)<br />

Die Reaktion auf diesen unverzeihlichen Mißgriff war zunächst das Gegenteil<br />

von dem, was Breton beabsichtig hatte. Spontan schlossen sich die 'alten Dadakämpfer'<br />

gegen Breton zusammen und stellten sich für das Gegen-Manifest<br />

Tzaras >Le coeur á barbe< zur Verfügung. Das Pamphlet war geschrieben<br />

von Huidobro, Peret, Satie, Serner, Rrose Selavy (Duchamp), Soupault etc.:<br />

»Die Unterzeich<strong>net</strong>en ziehen ihr Vertrauen und ihre Mitarbeit an dem Kongreß<br />

zurück: Satie, Tzara, Ribemont-Dessaignes, Man Ray, Eluard, Zadkine,<br />

Huidobro, Metzinger, Charchoune, Radiguet, Emmanuel Fay, M. Herrand,<br />

l?erat, Roch Gray, Raval, Nie. Bauduin, Zborowsky, van Doesburg, Zdanevitch,<br />

Voirol, Pansaers, Survage, Mondzain, Marcelle Meyer, Arp, Dermée, Celine,<br />

Romoff, Peret, Sauvage, Arlan, Cocteau.«<br />

Der Riß in der Dadafront zeigte sich öffentlich zuerst in einem Frontalangriff<br />

Picabias auf Dada und Tzara. In >Comedia< wurde unter dem Titel<br />

>Picabia trennt sich von DadaLe PILHAOU-THIBAOU391391< vertiefte den Riß mit jener diabolischen Konsequenz,<br />

die Picabia zur Verfügung stand. Darauf verließ die Mehrzahl von<br />

Picabias Mitarbeitern den 'Verräter'. Selbst sein treuester Freund Ribemont-<br />

Dessaignes wechselte zu Tzara über. Picabia lud eine neue Equipe zur Mitarbeit<br />

an >391< ein, unter denen für die Dadaisten Cocteau ein spezieller Dorn<br />

im Fleische war. Aber auch Ezra Pound und der Belgier Clément Pansaers<br />

zählten zu den neuen Mitarbeitern. Picabia selbst änderte indessen weder<br />

seinen Stil noch seine Angriffe. Mit einem speziellen Pamphlet >La pomme de<br />

pinns< gegen Tzara nahm er Bretons Partei gegen all die Unterzeichner, die mit<br />

Tzara die Angriffe des >Le coeur á barbe< unterstützten.<br />

Die entscheidende Wende kam am 6. Juli 1923 im Théatre Michel mit<br />

einer großen Abendvorstellung Dadas. Der Katalog versprach Erstaufführungen<br />

von Werken Aurics, Milhauds, Saties, Strawinskys, dazu Tänze in Kostümen<br />

von Sonja Delaunay vor Dekorationen von van Doesburg, verschiedene<br />

Filme von Sheeler, Hans Richter und Man Ray, >Mouchez vous< von Ribemont-<br />

Dessaignes, Lautgedichte von Iliazde und Gedicht-Rezitationen von Marcel<br />

Herrand (Cocteau, Soupault und Tzara). . . der Clou des Abends war ein Stück<br />

von Tzara: >Les coeur ä gaz


PARIS-DADA 1919-1922<br />

von >Le coeur á gaz< gekommen war, wurden die Darsteller in ihrem Spiel<br />

abrupt unterbrochen. Heftige Proteste ertönten aus dem Publikumsraum.<br />

Dann ein unerwartetes Zwischenspiel; - Breton kletterte auf die Bühne, und<br />

fing an, auf die Darsteller einzuschlagen. Diese, eingezwängt in Sonja Delaunays<br />

Kostüme aus steifem Karton, konnten sich gegen die Schläge nicht verteidigen<br />

und versuchten, mit kleinen Schrittchen zu entfliehen. Ohne Rücksicht<br />

ohrfeigte Breton Crevel, und mit einem Schlag seines Stockes brach er<br />

Pierre de Massot den Ann. Das überraschte Publikum fing nun auch an zu<br />

reagieren. Der erbarmungslose Angreifer wurde zu Boden geworfen. Aragon<br />

und Peret kamen ihm zu Hilfe. Alle drei wurden überwältigt und gewaltsam<br />

und mit zerrissenen Jacken hinausgeworfen. Die Ruhe im Raum war<br />

wiederhergestellt, als nun Eluard seinerseits auf die Bühne stieg. Bei einem<br />

Freunde von Tzara überraschte diese Geste. Aber die Zuschauer befaßten sich<br />

nicht mit solchen Feinheiten, und der Autor von >Répétitions< wurde sofort<br />

von einem ganzen Trupp angegriffen, der durch die vorhergehende Keilerei<br />

schon in Schwung gekommen war. Eluard unterlag der Übermacht und rollte<br />

über die Rampe in einige Scheinwerferlampen, die explodierten. Die Freunde<br />

versuchten, den zarten Dichter vor weiteren Repressalien zu schützen, während<br />

im Saal nach der Polizei gerufen wurde. Nachdem sich der Krach allmählich<br />

gelegt hatte, erschien die Ruhe anormal. Ich höre noch die Stimme<br />

des Direktors des Theétre Michel, der sich über die heruntergerissenen Vorhänge,<br />

die zerbrochenen Polstersessel und die verwüstete Bühne die Haare raufte:<br />

»Ma bonbonniere, ma bonbonniere!« (Georges Hug<strong>net</strong>. in >L'aventure DadaDas bärtige Herz — Le cceur á barbe< und >Le cceur á gaz< — waren Dadas<br />

Schwanengesang. Es ging nicht mehr, weil niemand mehr wußte, worum es<br />

ging. So kam es zu Verdächtigungen, Beleidigungen, Verleumdungen einer<br />

Gruppe gegen die andere, ja einer Zeitschrift (>391Merz< ab.<br />

Aus der > Conference sur la fin de Dada< Weimar 1922:<br />

» D e a d a m a r c h e e<br />

lui-mdme. De tous ces dgoüts il ne tire d'ailleurs aucun parti, aucun orgueil<br />

et aucun profit. Il ne combat méme plus, car il sait que cela ne sert ä rien, que<br />

tout cela n'a pas d'importance. Ce qui interesse un dadaiste, c'est sa propre<br />

facon de vivre. Mais ici nous entrons dans le grand secret.<br />

Dada est un etat d'esprit. C'est pour cela qu'il transforme suivant les races<br />

et les événements. Dada s'applique á tout, et pourtant il n'est rien, il est le<br />

point oü le oui et le non et tous les contraires se recontrent non pas solennellement<br />

dans les chateaux des philosophies humaines, mais tout simplement aux<br />

coins des rues, commes les chiens et les sauterelles.<br />

Dada est inutile comme tout dans la vie.<br />

Dada n'a aueune prétention, comme la vie devrait etre.<br />

Peut-etre me comprendrez-vous mieux quand je vous dirai que dada est un<br />

microbe vierge qui s'introduit avec l'insistance de l'air dans tous les espaces<br />

que la raison n'a pu combler de mots ou de Conventions.« Tristan Tzara<br />

Noch einmal bewies Dada eine gewisse Solidarität im Widerstand und in der<br />

Negation. Mari<strong>net</strong>ti und Russolo veranstalteten ein bruitistisches Konzert und<br />

wurden von ihren früheren Freunden ausgepfiffen. Beide waren Vorläufer<br />

und Wegbereiter für Dada. Der Krach endete damit, daß Dada buchstäblich<br />

'ä l'instant' aus dem Theater Champs Elyseé, wo die Veranstaltung stattfand,<br />

herausgeworfen wurde.<br />

Picabia, vorsichtshalber abwesend, hatte sich völlig auf sein eigenes Dada-<br />

Schloß zurückgezogen, als der letzte Sturm begann.<br />

Breton hatte inzwischen 1923 seine Kräfte organisiert und in Barcelona zur<br />

Eröffnung einer Picabia-Ausstellung einen programmatischen Vortrag über den<br />

Charakter (und die Charaktere) der Entwicklung in der modernen Kunst gehalten.<br />

Es versteht sich von selbst, daß Tzara und seine Freunde darin nicht<br />

mehr vorkamen.<br />

Picabia fuhr fort, seine Unabhängigkeit ständig wieder unter Beweis zu<br />

stellen. In der Malerei war seine Maschinen-Periode vorbei. Jetzt zeich<strong>net</strong>e er<br />

197


Wieland HERZFELDE: Zur Einführung (1920). In: Uwe M. Schneede<br />

(Hg.): Die zwanziger Jahre. Köln: DuMont 1979, S. 31-34.<br />

Wieland Herzfelde<br />

Zur Einführung<br />

1920<br />

Die größte Dada-Manifestation ist die Erste Internationale Dada-Messe 1920 in der Berliner Galerie<br />

Dr. Otto Burchard. Gezeigt werden nach Auskunft des Faltblattes, das zur Ausstellung erschien, 174<br />

Werke, nicht nur von Berliner Dadaisten; auch Arp, Baargeld, Dix, Max Ernst, Picabia, Schlichter,<br />

G. Scholz sind vertreten. Für die Berliner Dada-Gruppe ist dies das letzte gemeinsame Auftreten.<br />

Ausstellungsbeiträge von George Grosz und Rudolf Schlichter führen zu einem Prozeß wegen angeblicher<br />

Beleidigung der Reichswehr. Grosz und sein Verleger Wieland Herzfelde werden zu Geldstrafen<br />

verurteilt.<br />

In seiner Einführung zum Faltblatt äußert sich Wieland Herzfelde zur Methode des Dadaismus, vor<br />

allem zum Prinzip der Normenzersetzung und zum Prinzip des fruchtbaren Dilettantismus.<br />

Dem wiedergegebenen Text folgen Erläuterungen zu einzelnen Ausstellungsstücken - hier weggelassen,<br />

weil sie keine grundlegende Bedeutung haben.<br />

Dereinst wird die Photographie die gesamte<br />

Malkunst verdrängen und ersetzen.<br />

Wiertz.<br />

Wenn sich ein Künstler der Photographie<br />

bediente, wie man sich ihrer bedienen muß,<br />

dann würde er sich zu einer Höhe aufschwingen,<br />

von der wir keine Ahnung haben.<br />

Delacroix.<br />

Sonne, Mond und Sterne bestehen noch -<br />

obwohl wir sie nicht mehr anbeten. Gibt es<br />

unsterbliche Kunst, so kann sie nicht daran<br />

sterben, daß der Kunstkult gestürzt wird.<br />

Wieland Herzfelde.<br />

Die Malerei hatte einst den ausgesprochenen<br />

Zweck, den Menschen die Anschauung<br />

von Dingen, Landschaften, Tieren, Bauten<br />

usw., die sie selbst nicht mit eigenen Augen<br />

kennenlernen konnten, zu vermitteln. Diese<br />

Aufgabe haben heute Photographie und<br />

Film übernommen und lösen sie unvergleichlich<br />

viel vollkommener als die Maler<br />

aller Zeiten.<br />

Doch starb die Malerei mit dem Verlust ihres<br />

Zweckes nicht ab, sondern suchte neue<br />

Zwecke. Seitdem lassen sich alle Kunstbestrebungen<br />

dahin zusammenfassen, daß<br />

sie, so verschieden sie auch sind, gemein­<br />

sam die Tendenz haben, sich von der Wirklichkeit<br />

zu emanzipieren.<br />

Der Dadaismus ist die Reaktion auf alle<br />

diese Verleugnungsversuche des Tatsächlichen,<br />

die die Triebkraft der Impressionisten,<br />

Expressionisten, Kubisten und auch<br />

der Futuristen (indem sie nicht vorm Film<br />

kapitulieren wollten) gewesen sind; aber<br />

der Dadaist unternimmt es nicht etwa wieder,<br />

mit dem Photographenapparat zu konkurrieren,<br />

oder ihm gar eine Seele einzuhauchen,<br />

indem er (wie die Impressionisten)<br />

der schlechtesten Linse: dem menschlichen<br />

Auge den Vorzug gibt, oder (wie die<br />

Expressionisten) den Apparat umdreht und<br />

dauernd bloß die Welt im eigenen Busen<br />

darstellt.<br />

Die Dadaisten sagen: Wenn früher Unmengen<br />

von Zeit, Liebe und Anstrengung auf<br />

das Malen eines Körpers, einer Blume, eines<br />

Hutes, eines Schlagschattens usw. verwandt<br />

wurden, so brauchen wir nur die<br />

Schere nehmen und uns unter den Malereien,<br />

photographischen Darstellungen all dieser<br />

Dinge auszuschneiden, was wir brauchen;<br />

handelt es sich um Dinge geringeren<br />

Umfangs, so brauchen wir auch gar nicht<br />

Darstellungen, sondern nehmen die Gegen-<br />

31


Erste Internationale Dada-Messe, Kunsthandlung Dr. Otto Burchard, Berlin 1920 (v. 1. n. r.: Raoul<br />

Hausmann, Dr. Otto Burchard, Hannah Hoch, Johannes Baader, Wieland Herzfelde, Margarete<br />

Herzfelde, Otto Schmalhausen, George Grosz, John Heartfield). An der linken Wand ein Gemälde<br />

von Dix, rechts eines von Grosz (beide seit dem Dritten Reich verschollen), an der Decke eine Puppe<br />

von Schlichter<br />

stände selbst, z. B. Taschenmesser, Aschenbecher,<br />

Bücher etc., lauter Sachen, die in<br />

den Museen alter Kunst recht schön gemalt<br />

sind, aber eben doch gemalt.<br />

Nun die berühmte Frage: Ja, aber der Inhalt,<br />

das Geistige?<br />

Im Laufe der Jahrhunderte hat wie auf allen<br />

Gebieten die ungleiche Verteilung der<br />

Lebens- und Entwicklungsmöglichkeiten<br />

auch auf dem Gebiete der Kunst unerhörte<br />

Verhältnisse gezeitigt: auf der einen Seite<br />

eine Clique sogenannter Könner und Talente,<br />

die teils durch jahrzehntelanges Training,<br />

teils durch Protektion, Sesselkleben,<br />

teils auch durch ererbte Spezialveranlagungen<br />

das Monopol in bezug auf alle Frage<br />

der Kunstwertung an sich gerissen hat -<br />

32<br />

während auf der anderen Seite die Menge<br />

von Menschen, deren anspruchsloses und<br />

naives Bedürfnis: die Vorstellung in sich<br />

und die Vorgänge in der Umwelt darzustellen,<br />

mitzuteilen und bauend zu verarbeiten,<br />

von jener Clique Tonangebender niedergehalten<br />

wird. Heute muß der junge Mensch,<br />

wenn er nicht auf jegliche Ausbildung und<br />

Verbreiterung seiner ursprünglichen Anlagen<br />

verzichten will, sich dem durch und<br />

durch autoritativ aufgebauten System der<br />

künstlerischen Erziehung und des künstlerischen<br />

öffentlichen Urteils unterwerfen.<br />

Die Dadaisten hingegen sagen, Bilder herstellen<br />

ist keine Wichtigkeit, wenn es aber<br />

geschieht, so soll wenigstens kein Machtstandpunkt<br />

aufgezogen werden, so soll den


eiten Massen die Lust an gestaltender Beschäftigung<br />

nicht durch die fachmännische<br />

Arroganz einer hochmütigen Gilde verdorben<br />

werden. Aus diesem Grunde können<br />

die Inhalte dadaistischer Bilder und Erzeugnisse<br />

außerordentlich verschieden sein<br />

und desgleichen die Mittel. An sich ist jedes<br />

Erzeugnis dadaistisch, das unbeeinflußt,<br />

unbekümmert um öffentliche Instanzen<br />

und Wertbegriffe hergestellt wird, sofern<br />

das darstellende illusionsfeindlich, aus dem<br />

Bedürfnis heraus arbeitet, die gegenwärtige<br />

Welt, die sich offenbar in Auflösung, in einer<br />

Metamorphose befindet, zersetzend<br />

weiterzutreiben. Die Vergangenheit ist nur<br />

noch insofern wichtig und maßgebend, als<br />

ihr Kult bekämpft werden muß. Insofern<br />

sind die Dadaisten einig, sie sagen, was die<br />

Antike, die Klassik, all die >großen Geister<<br />

geschaffen haben, darf nicht (es sei denn<br />

wissenschaftlich historisch) gewertet werden<br />

in bezug auf die Zeit, da es geschaffen<br />

wurde, sondern so, als ob heute jemand<br />

34<br />

diese Dinge herstellt, und niemand wird bezweifeln,<br />

daß heute kein Mensch, und sei er<br />

auch, um mit der Kunstsprache zu reden,<br />

ein Genie, Werke herstellen kann, deren<br />

Voraussetzungen Jahrhunderte und Jahrtausende<br />

zurückliegen.<br />

Die Dadaisten rechnen es sich als Verdienst<br />

an, Vorkämpfer des Dilettantismus zu sein,<br />

denn der Kunst-Dilettant ist nichts anderes<br />

wie das Opfer einer Vorurteils vollen, hochmütigen,<br />

aristokratischen Weltanschauung.<br />

Die Dadaisten anerkennen als einziges<br />

Programm die Pflicht, zeitlich und örtlich<br />

das gegenwärtige Geschehen zum Inhalt ihrer<br />

Bilder zu machen, weswegen sie auch<br />

nicht >Tausend und eine Nacht< oder<br />

>Bilder aus Hinterindien


Thomas ELSAESSER: Dada/Cinema? In: Rudolf E. Kuenzli (Hg.): Dada<br />

and Surrealist Film. Cambridge, London: MIT Press 1996, S. 13-27.<br />

I. ESSAYS<br />

Cinema-An Invention without Origin or Use?<br />

Dada/Cinema?<br />

Thomas Elsaesser<br />

There is something altogether appropriate about the fact, noted by film historians,<br />

1 that the cinema has no origin other than the multiplicity of chemical,<br />

technical, optical, and scientific discoveries and devices which made<br />

possible the first public showings around 1896. It cautions anyone looking at<br />

cinema history not to imbue it with an ontology or to ascribe to its development<br />

a particularly stringent logic.<br />

We tend to forget, for instance, how many of the decisive discoveries or<br />

applications were, in fact, "by product[s] of other more urgent concerns" 2 and<br />

the workings of "objective chance." Such is the case of Marey's chronophotography,<br />

which its inventor hoped would facilitate medical research<br />

into cardiac and vascular diseases. The desire of analyzing movement needs<br />

to be distinguished from the ability of reproducing it mechanically. The development<br />

of mechanical aids for drawing, for portraiture, and for achieving<br />

likeness can be shown to antedate photography and the cinema, but they are<br />

clearly crucial to an understanding of the ideology of self-representation<br />

which has marked the cinema as a social institution. On the other hand, the<br />

will to record, classify, collect, describe, observe, and analyze, which Michel<br />

Foucault sees as characteristic of the eighteenth and ni<strong>net</strong>eenth centuries,<br />

has left its mark on many of the early uses of photography and the<br />

cinema with its tributary inventions benefited from the need for precision<br />

instruments to satisfy the scientific rage for order. "Physiology applied to the<br />

field of optics" 3 is one way of designating the probing, investigative urge<br />

underpinning the cinema, but it does not fully explain why and how the desire<br />

for the di-visible became the fascination for the visible. If we owe the<br />

cinema to certain advances in the applied technologies- the same, it has<br />

been remarked, that produced the sewing machine and the telegraph tapeit<br />

is no<strong>net</strong>heless true that the desire for the cinema, for the perfect reproduction<br />

of appearance and vision, existed well before the machinery of its<br />

realization had been assembled.<br />

Dada and the Cinema<br />

The cinema, displaying a flagrant (and ironic) discrepancy between the<br />

bricolage of its mechanical, optical, chemical processes on the one hand, and<br />

the homogeneity, unity, illusory cohesion of its effects on the other, would<br />

seem to be a quintessentially Dada artifact-a contention which conversely<br />

13


might suggest that Dada artifacts are quintessentially ni<strong>net</strong>eenth-century<br />

technological fantasies.<br />

The combination Dada/cinema is thus interlaced with the more general<br />

history of inventions and apparati, and with the crises provoked in the arts<br />

when it became impossible to separate technology from technique or scientific<br />

from artistic experiment. The explosive development of new means of<br />

representation and reproduction towards the end of the ni<strong>net</strong>eenth century,<br />

indicating for the first time that aesthetic effects can be attributed to<br />

machine-made objects or images, had profoundly ruptured a traditional relation<br />

between art and mimesis. It had also cruelly exposed the delicate relationship<br />

between crafted object and art object in respect to labor, skill, and<br />

value.<br />

Two aspects are worth singling out. One is to look, especially in the context<br />

of Germany and Berlin Dada, at the forms of spectatorship and pleasure<br />

that might be associated not so much with watching Dada films but watching<br />

films as Dada. The second point concerns the kinds of reflection which<br />

the cinema as total apparatus—psychic, economic, erotic — occasioned<br />

among the avant-garde and Dadaists in particular, as a model or metaphor<br />

for representing the relation of body to social environment, or even for conceptualizing<br />

the art-work as event, rather than as object, no longer as products<br />

but as circuits of exchange for different energies and intensities, for the<br />

different aggregate states matter can be subjected to between substance and<br />

sign through an act of transposition, assemblage, division, and intermittence.<br />

The cinema, in other words, between photo-montage and metamechanics.<br />

Unlike "Surrealism and Cinema," on which one can consult volumes, the<br />

subject "Dada and Film" has not entered into the histories of the movement,<br />

nor into film history as a distinct entity. Apart from a short, mainly autobiographical<br />

essay by Hans Richter in Willy Verkaufs monograph, 4 references<br />

to Dada films have until a few years ago only turned up in histories of avantgarde<br />

cinema, experimental or abstract him. 5 The focus of these accounts<br />

tends to sever the examples from their Dada connections and to annex them<br />

as the precursors of a tradition either of graphic or structuralist cinema.<br />

Dada films thus appear briefly in the prehistory of the New American<br />

Cinema, but the connections seem rather tenuous compared, again, to the<br />

profound influence of Surrealism on the American him avant-garde.<br />

The problems of talking about Dada him are twofold. Firstly, the question<br />

of attribution and contribution. Should one resist calling Ballet mecanique a<br />

Dada film, because Leger is usually considered a Cubist? Hans Richter did<br />

not think so:<br />

Though Leger was never a Dadaist, his Ballet mecanique is 100% Dada. 6<br />

Do Francis Picabia's disagreements with the Paris Dadaists disqualify<br />

Entr'acte? We know that the ballet Reldche, for which Picabia and Rene Clair<br />

conceived Entr'acte, was in part a protest against Breton's takeover of the<br />

Surrealist movement. 7 By a reverse logic, should Hans Richter's Rhythm 21<br />

and Rhythm 23 be discussed as Dada films because Richter makes a case for<br />

Dada art as abstract art? Candidly, he himself admitted:<br />

14<br />

After I have stated this fact "Dada equals abstract art" I happily wish to insist on the<br />

other point, "Dada equals non-abstract art." And this is also true if not truer. 8<br />

Ambiguity of one form or another surrounds most other potential candidates.<br />

Duchamp's Anemic cinema is usually called a Dada film, with which<br />

Duchamp would presumably not have quarreled, if he had not baulked at<br />

calling it a film at all, preferring to see it as part of his "precision optics." 9 In<br />

Man Ray's case, we have Retour a la raison, first performed at the famous<br />

"Soiree du Coeur a barbe" in July 1923, an occasion which signaled the breakup<br />

of Paris Dada. Man Ray considered his subsequent two films Emak Bakia<br />

and L'Etoile de mer to be Surrealist films. Hans Richter calls his own Filmstudie<br />

"rather more surrealist." 10 This only leaves two or three short films by<br />

Richter: Ghosts before Breakfast and Two-Penny Magic as uncontested Dada<br />

films.<br />

The second problem is chronology. If one takes a generous view, one can<br />

start with 1920, the year Richter and Eggeling applied for facilities and funds<br />

to the UFA Film Company in order to carry out work which resulted in<br />

Rhythm 21, Rhythm 23, and Diagonal Symphony. In the same year Duchamp<br />

and Man Ray conducted the first and almost lethal experiments with revolving<br />

glass discs and 3-D stereotypes, out of which grew Rotating Demisphere<br />

and Anemic cinema. It is not until 1923 that Retour a la raison appears, and in<br />

1924, Entr'acte. Ballet mecanique follows in 1925, and in 1926 comes Hans<br />

Richter's Filmstudie, Man Ray's Emak Bakia, and Duchamp's Anemic cinema.<br />

Finally, in 1927 Richter completes Ghosts before Breakfast and Two-Penny<br />

Magic, and in 1928 Man Ray's L'Etoile de mer is shown. No chronology of<br />

Dada stretches that far.<br />

The reasons for the sparse and late appearance of Dada films are in part financial<br />

and in part geographical. There was little commercial interest in<br />

either Richter's or Eggeling's work, even though it was sponsored by the<br />

powerful UFA Studio, which successfully marketed other types of animation<br />

film (Walther Ruttmann's or Lotte Reiniger's). Entr'acte was specifically<br />

commissioned, and Man Ray's films were made with money from a wealthy<br />

expatriate, Arthur Wheeler, who had tried to persuade Man Ray at one stage<br />

to become a professional film-maker, with his backing. During the 1920s,<br />

France was more receptive to experiments in the cinema, not least because<br />

the flourishing cine-club movement gave film-makers an outlet and a form of<br />

distribution, however marginal in relation to the commercial cinema. 11 In<br />

Germany, by contrast, the artistic avant-gardes were quite hostile to the<br />

cinema during most of the 1910s and early 1920s mainly for political reasons:<br />

Germany had a very powerful and successful commercial film industry, and<br />

only the arrival of the "Russenfilme" sparked off practical interest in an "alternative<br />

cinema." 12 There was, in consequence, less of a viable exhibition<br />

system for experimental shorts produced outside the film industry.<br />

One of the few times that one can talk of a Dada film soiree occurred in<br />

May, 1925, in Berlin, when Eggeling's Diagonal Symphony, Richter's Film is<br />

Rhythm (the two Rhythm films spliced together) Ruttmann's Opus I, II and<br />

TV, Leger's and Murphy's Ballet mecanique, Picabia's and Clair's Entr'acte, as<br />

well as three films by Moholy-Nagy (made at the Bauhaus) were screened together.<br />

13<br />

15


More recent literature has in contrast stressed the ways in which Dada<br />

techniques or practices were inherently "cinematic." Anton Kaes, in an article<br />

on "Verfremdung als Verfahren: Film und Dada," 14 argues that the<br />

cinema suggested to the Dadaists the need to represent "the hectic acceleration<br />

of life," and in particular, he compares Hans Richter's work with the<br />

"Cinematism" in painting (Balla's famous Dog on a Leash), with "Fotodinamismo"<br />

and the multiple-exposure studies popular among not only avantgarde<br />

photographers in the early teens. 15 But more important for Kaes is the<br />

fact that a revolutionary conception of cinema has in common with Dada the<br />

principle of montage "because it problematizes the relationship between object<br />

of perception and the subject of perception. Montage does not allow for<br />

a coherent perspective in which the subject is in control." 16 Kaes quotes<br />

Franz Kafka and Thomas Mann to indicate that even the commercial cinema<br />

caused an experience of shock to its earliest spectators.<br />

This approach goes beyond the more traditional histories of avant-garde<br />

movements, where Dada or Surrealist films are simply searched for examples<br />

of techniques already familiar from the literary or visual productions.<br />

Kaes can point to a potential area of research, where historical investigations<br />

of Dada converge with questions of current film theory, once more<br />

interested in the ideas about spectatorship first formulated by Siegfried<br />

Kracauer and Walter Benjamin, and recently given a more explicitly psychoanalytical<br />

turn. 17<br />

The Tyranny of the Eye<br />

The general shift from an environment experienced through all the senses<br />

to one increasingly dominated by the eye and obeying its control undoubtedly<br />

forms part of both the history of the cinema and of Dada. The confusion<br />

of active and passive roles under the rule of spectacle is well caught in a<br />

poem by George Grosz: "I am like a film-strip and like a child in a thousand<br />

luna parks . . . someone is always cranking the handle." 18<br />

In this sense, the cinema is indeed that "phenomenon par exellence which<br />

has to be traced along the minute cracks and fault-lines that run through late<br />

Victorian society in Europe." 19 It is the expression of a sensibility excited by<br />

motion, by the means of locomotion, relishing dioramas and panoramas,<br />

flocking to world fairs, crowding into the Crystal Palace and climbing the<br />

Eiffel Tower. The need for physical mobility, spatial displacement, for the<br />

bird's eye view and for being driven or carried along precede the cinema at<br />

the same time as these pleasures were significantly transformed, realized,<br />

and interpreted by the cinema. Their social dimension leads one inevitably<br />

to demographic facts: for the cinema is unthinkable without the big cities.<br />

Perhaps the best guide through its prehistory is Benjamin's Baudelaire. In<br />

order to understand the changes in perception forced upon people living in<br />

the cities as well as for intimating the implications of those changes, Benjamin<br />

constructed a Baudelaire who serves him as a poetic "precision instrument"<br />

to trace those very fault-lines. The poem about wandering the suburbs<br />

at daybreak like a fencer thrusting and parrying imaginary blows suggests to<br />

Benjamin that Baudelaire reacted to "ennui," the spectre of specular fascina-<br />

16<br />

tion and voyeuristic control, by a new involvement of the body in the very<br />

act of writing, modeled on the experience of fighting one's way through<br />

crowded streets and public places:<br />

The meaning of the hidden configuration (which reveals the beauty of that stanza to<br />

its very depth) probably is this: it is the phantom crowd of the words, the fragments,<br />

the beginnings of lines from which the poet, in the deserted streets, wrests the poetic<br />

booty. 20<br />

However fanciful this reading may be to a Baudelaire scholar, Benjamin<br />

isolates an important aspect of Dada technique: a reaction to, as well as an<br />

exploitation of the tyranny of total vision which invaded the early decades of<br />

the century. When characterizing the (to him ambiguous) contribution made<br />

by Dada to avant-garde art, in his essay on the "Work of Art in the Age of<br />

Mechanical Reproduction," Benjamin sees Dada objects replacing one kind<br />

of spectatorship (contemplation) with what he calls "a new tactility":<br />

In the decline of middle-class society, contemplation became a school for asocial behavior;<br />

it was countered by distraction as a variant of social conduct.... From an alluring<br />

appearance . . . the work of art of the Dadaists became an instrument of ballistics.<br />

It hit the spectator like a bullet, it happened to him, thus acquiring a tactile quality.<br />

21<br />

One might compare this negation of contemplation to Duchamp's categorical<br />

demand to destroy the "retinal" aspect of painting, and thus to counteract<br />

the supremacy of the eye. Whereas the Russian post-revolutionary avantgarde<br />

abandoned painting and turned to film and photography, Duchamp<br />

and other Dadaists on the whole rejected the cinema, not least because, even<br />

in its avant-garde forms, it seemed too close to the synesthesia of the Impressionists<br />

and the advocates of the Gesamtkunstwerk. That the difference in<br />

political situation between East and West played its part is accurately<br />

perceived by Benjamin:<br />

Dadaism . . . sacrificed the market values which are so characteristic of the cinema in<br />

favor of higher ambitions. . . . The Dadaists attached much less importance to the<br />

sales value of their work than to its uselessness for contemplative immersion. The<br />

studied degradation of their material was not the least of their means to achieve this<br />

uselessness. 22<br />

Dadaism in many of its manifestations was reactive, seeking ways of radically<br />

short-circuiting the means by which art objects acquire financial, social,<br />

and spiritual values. Thus, while from the point of view of the material<br />

base, the cinema seemed an art of waste-products, and its conditions of<br />

reception were anything but auratic, the very popularity of films meant that<br />

the cinema soon represented tremendous financial, and with it, social value.<br />

This paradox marked the Dadaists' involvement from the start: the cinema<br />

seemed initially anti-contemplative as an entertainment, and at least Benjamin<br />

saw in its visual forms an element of tactility; but it soon acquired its<br />

own aura: that of glamor and total specular entrancement. It is therefore perhaps<br />

not surprising that interest of some Dadaists focused in the first instance<br />

on the behavior of the crowds, the character of a happening, and the<br />

"degraded" nature of film spectacle, parodying subversively the theater and<br />

17


the concert hall. A certain physicality and body-presence of the first cinema<br />

audiences is what might be called the Dada element in film.<br />

"Das Kino"<br />

While few theorists today would be very satisfied with drawing a dividing<br />

line between Melies and Lumiere when it comes to establishing an opposition<br />

between "realism" and "fiction" or documentary and fantasy, there has<br />

recently been a great deal of interest and controversy around the possibility<br />

of distinguishing between so-called "primitive cinema" (up to 1917) and<br />

"classical narrative cinema" on the basis of different types of spectator ship.<br />

Alongside oppositions such as commercial versus avant-garde cinema, illusionist<br />

versus materialist film, historians have speculated on the kind of involvement<br />

and participation elicited by early cinema. In one of the most interesting<br />

formulations, Noel Burch contrasts two kinds of Imaginary underpinning<br />

different practices: the "Edisonian" (a fascination with the apparatus<br />

of cinema in view of a total simulacrum of life, and the "analytical" one, aiming<br />

to break down movement into smaller and smaller particles. 23 Both seem<br />

relevant to Dada, whose interest in the cinema was in some sense a nostalgic<br />

one, attached to the him performance of the 1910s and the figure of the inventor-bricoleur.<br />

What remains problematic about both the generic distinction<br />

and the definition of a filmic avant-garde in the context of early cinema<br />

is that we still know very little about the actual viewing experience during<br />

the period in question.<br />

In a typical program, say in Berlin in 1913 (but surviving in the suburbs<br />

well into the early 1920s), non-narrative films would be mixed with sketches<br />

and fantasies. The Kaiser (or Hindenburg) would be shown on parade right<br />

after a filmed variety number. The items would be introduced, a lecturer<br />

would stand at the back of the room or hall and comment sarcastically or<br />

pathetically on the action, explain, or provide the kind of epic distance that<br />

Brecht, copying from the cinema, tried to create in his theater. There was<br />

little sense of "illusionism" or any suspension of disbelief.<br />

Skepticism and sarcasm mingled freely with wonder and amazement. The<br />

viewing experience seemed, as it were, embedded in drinking and furtive<br />

sex, and if it was "structured," it derived this structure from the ambience of<br />

the event as much as from the films. "Das Kino" or "Kintopp" was characterized<br />

by its communality of reception on the one hand, and its discontinuous<br />

flow on the other. Here is an early testimony of a film-show in Berlin:<br />

The room is darkened. Suddenly the Ganges floats into view, palms, the temple of the<br />

Brahmins appears. A silent family drama rages with bon vivants, a masquerade-a<br />

gun is pulled. Jealousy inflamed. Mr. Piefke duels headlessly and they show us, step<br />

by step, mountaineers climbing the steep, demanding paths. The paths lead down<br />

through forests, they twist and climb the threatening cliff. The view into the depths is<br />

enlivened by cows and potatoes. And into the darkened room-into my very eyeflutters<br />

that, that... oh, dreadful! One after the other! Then the arc lamp hissingly announces<br />

the end, lights! And we push ourselves into the open . . . horny and<br />

yawning. 24<br />

18<br />

Van Hoddis's response is to the total environment, of which the film is only<br />

one part. The interest in early cinema on the part of today's theorists like<br />

Noel Burch resides in the fact that the so-called "codes of representation"<br />

have not yet become hierarchized and subjected to certain "laws" whose ideology<br />

a later (film-)avant-garde was to deconstruct. This hierarchy is above<br />

all one organized around the dominance of the look; it becomes the distinguishing<br />

mark of the cinematic watershed between "primitive" and "Grifnthian"<br />

film-making. To quote from an article by Pascal Bonitzer:<br />

The look in Griffith was not something that had been there since the beginning of the<br />

cinema. There was, first of all, the 20 years during which the cinema was content<br />

merely to be the object of viewing, recording phenomena and movements and the<br />

sights of the world. When today we see these early films ... we are seeing the varied<br />

fruits of a cinematic Eden where the coldness and sophistication of the look had not<br />

yet pe<strong>net</strong>rated. ... A cinema where the only currency was that of gesture, where the<br />

viewers' eyes are functioning but not looking. According to Edgar Morin ... it wasn't<br />

until 1915-1920 that the gesticulation typical of actors gave way to a degree of immobility.<br />

This is the turning point represented by Griffith. . . . What we have here is a<br />

cinematic revolution. With the arrival of montage, the close-up, immobile actors, the<br />

look (and its corollary - the banishment of histrionics) an entire facade of the cinema<br />

seemed to disappear and be lost forever, in a word, all the excrement of vaudeville.<br />

. . . The cinema was innocent and dirty, it was to become obsessional and fetishistic.<br />

The obscenity did not disappear ... it passed into the register of desire. 25<br />

As Bonitzer goes on to show, it is the look circulating within the fiction that,<br />

inducing desire, produces narratives, which are in turn based on subjecting<br />

to a more or less rigid logic the articulation of cinematic space and sequence.<br />

And as Bonitzer also remarks, it is the German Expressionist cinema which<br />

for the first time systematically exploited the look as the cinematic signifier<br />

par exellence. The introduction of the look into the film diegesis thus constitutes<br />

the end point of a development, the final cornerstone of the edifice of<br />

control and containment which has governed the development of mainstream<br />

cinema. If I claimed that Dada spectatorship is nostalgic, it is perhaps<br />

because the presence or absence of the charged look as the agent and<br />

motivator of both continuity and discontinuity, of sequence and cut distinguishes<br />

Surrealist interest in film (consider the importance of the eye and of<br />

point of view in Un Chien andalou) from Dada interest in cinema.<br />

Not the Film, But the Performance Is Dada<br />

What was Dada in regard to cinema was not a specific film, but the performance,<br />

not a specific set of techniques or textual organization, but the spectacle.<br />

One might argue that in order for a film to have been Dada it need not<br />

be made by a Dadaist, or conversely, that there were no Dada films outside<br />

the events in which they figured. "What is a Dada film?" would resolve itself<br />

into the question "When was a film Dada?" This gives a special place to the<br />

screening of Entr'acte as part of Relache (as opposed to its cinema premiere a<br />

year later at the Studio des Ursulines), and to the Soiree du Coeur a barbe. At<br />

a time when the cinema had become itself a thoroughly respectable (and "in-<br />

19


stitutionalized") form of entertainment, both film text and viewing context<br />

had to combine in order to defamiliarize the occasion, in order to recapture<br />

the cinema's "excremental" age of scandalously guilty innocence.<br />

Entr'acte works hard at "deconstructing" what had already become set as the<br />

conventions of the feature film and the cinema experience. It mocks the solemnity<br />

of state-occasions as they might have been presented in contemporary<br />

newsreel. By its satirical look at funerals, parades, and photo features from<br />

the world of arts, entertainment and leisure, Entr'acte explodes the conventions<br />

of the newsreel in forms themselves borrowed from the cinema (American<br />

slapstick, the Keystone Cops, for instance), and thus could be considered<br />

as being in turn part of a filmic genre - that of parody, were it not for the event<br />

for which it was conceived.<br />

Picabia and Satie had wanted the audience to whom Entr'acte was shown<br />

during the intermission of the ballet Relache to provide their own "musical"<br />

accompaniment by the mumbling, scraping, protesting, guffawing and general<br />

noise to be expected during an intermission. To their disappointment<br />

the spectators remained respectfully in their seats, silent, staring at the<br />

screen. The projection failed to ignite into a Dada performance. 26<br />

This incident, I think, is symptomatic of a problem that made film a less<br />

than perfect medium at Dada events. For the conditions of a reception in the<br />

cinema-the dark room, the stable rectangle of the screen, the fixed voyeuristic<br />

position of the spectator-all counteract not only the sense of provocation,<br />

but they also compensate for the absence of a coherent diegesis and for<br />

the non-narrative organization in the filmed material. Under normal viewing<br />

conditions, that is, in a movie theatre and not as part of a performance<br />

aspiring to the condition of the happening, Dada films such as Entr'acte,<br />

Ballet mecanique, or Hans Richter's works are almost inescapably contained,<br />

unified and finally recuperated in a way that the classic examples of Surrealist<br />

cinema are less vulnerable to, for reasons which have mainly to do with<br />

the fact that Surrealist films so closely mimic the figurative operations of narrative<br />

cinema, and compensate for the ruptures of their time-space continuum<br />

by a massive investment in the on-screen and off-screen look, which<br />

lures the spectator into the play of projection, fetish, and identification<br />

described by Bonitzer as typical for illusionist cinema.<br />

"Geist" and "Stoff"<br />

Film technology confers on even the most banal object the aura of erotic<br />

presence. The scandal resides in the cinema bypassing aesthetics while at<br />

the same time providing a source of aesthetic appeal. It opened an old<br />

wound in German literary culture-the debate about "form" and "material"<br />

("Geist" and "Stoff"). The very achievement of classical literature (no less than<br />

of Romantic art) had been the suppression of materiality, its total transfiguration<br />

into "form." What for some writers categorically excluded the<br />

cinema from being art ("in the cinema, the material substance is preserved in<br />

its crude factuality, whereas in drama the material is wholly consumed and<br />

transformed by form, of which the main agent is language" 27 ), was for others<br />

the cinema's chief claim to attention: that it could produce emotion of an<br />

20<br />

aesthetic kind out of pure materiality. Thomas Mann recognized the same<br />

dilemma when in 1928, after seeing the first film version of his novel Die<br />

Buddenbrooks, he wrote:<br />

A pair of lovers, both young and beautiful, who in a real garden with billowing grass<br />

say goodbye "forever"... who could resist, who would not enjoy letting it all pour out.<br />

This is pure material, not transformed by anything. 28<br />

Mann concluded from this that it was pointless to try to apply to cinema<br />

the criteria developed by classical aesthetics. Sixteen years earlier, Georg<br />

Lukacs had already warned against solving the problem in this fashion:<br />

.. . something new and beautiful has developed in recent times, but instead of taking<br />

it as it is, people are attempting to classify it. . . . The cinema is regarded either as an<br />

instrument of education or as a cheap substitute for the theater; either didactic or economic.<br />

Few people if any remember that something beautiful belongs first and foremost<br />

to the realm of beauty and its definition and evaluation is properly a task for aesthetics.<br />

Lukacs, in other words, recognized clearly that the cinema posed a challenge<br />

to classical aesthetics which had to be answered, and not as Mann was<br />

to suggest, by merely relegating it to the side of "life" as opposed to "art."<br />

Lukacs goes on:<br />

The images of the cinema ... possess a life of a completely different kind [from those on<br />

the stage]; in one word, they become-fantastic. But the fantastic is not the opposite to<br />

living, it is another aspect of life: life without presence, without fate, without causality,<br />

without motivation; a life with which the core of our being will never be identical, nor<br />

can it be; and even if it - often- yearns for this kind of life, this yearning is merely after<br />

a strange precipice, something a long way off, inwardly distanced. The world of the<br />

cinema is a life without background or perspective, without difference of properties or<br />

qualities. [The cinema] is a life without measure or order, without being or value, a life<br />

without soul, mere surface ... the individual moments, whose temporal sequence<br />

brings about the filmed scenes, are only joined with each other insofar as they follow<br />

each other without transition and mediation. There is no causality which could join<br />

them, or more precisely, its causality is free from and unimpeded by any notion of content.<br />

"Everything is possible": this is the credo of the cinema, and because its technique<br />

expresses at every moment the absolute (even if only empirical) reality of this moment,<br />

"virtuality" no longer functions as a category opposed to "reality": both categories become<br />

equivalent, identical. Everything is true and real, everything is equally true and<br />

real; this is what a sequence of images in the cinema teaches us. 29<br />

What Lukacs here analyzes with a certain lugubrious melancholy is nothing<br />

other than what Raoul Hausmann or Kurt Schwitters celebrate: "Everything is<br />

true and real, everything is equally true and real." The fundamental Dada<br />

paradox, namely that the real is the material, but that this irreducible materiality<br />

has no reality other than as a sign or a representation, finds its implicit<br />

resolution, if Luckacs is right, in the cinema-except in a cinema equated<br />

philosophically if not empirically with life itself. It is in this theoretical impasse<br />

that Dadaists remained caught when thinking about the cinema, and it<br />

gives some justification to Benjamin's assertion that the Dadaists' attitude to<br />

the new technologies of visual reproduction and imaging was retrograde, but<br />

necessarily so, given their radical aspirations:<br />

21


The history of every art form shows critical epochs in which a certain art form aspires<br />

to effects which could be fu!iy obtained only with a changed technical standard, that<br />

is to say, in a new art form. The extravagances and crudities of art which thus appear<br />

. . . actually arise from the nucleus of its richest historical energies . . . : Dadaism attempted<br />

to create by pictorial-and literary-means the effects which the public today<br />

seeks in the cinema. 30<br />

From Benjamin's perspective and vantage point this estimation of Dada<br />

technique as anachronistic in relation to a revolutionizing technology seems<br />

at least strategically plausible. But it may also (perhaps deliberately) misread<br />

Dada activities and their main thrust. The Berlin Dadaists, for instance,<br />

were finally only interested in two kinds of cultural objects: live performance<br />

and the newspaper, prototypes of an interventionist use of the massmedia.<br />

In both cases, by utilizing already existing forms and formats, maximum<br />

effect could be achieved through a minimum of effort—a reversal of<br />

bourgeois value-creation which the labor-intensive and time-consuming<br />

process of filmmaking does not exemplify particularly well. The principle of<br />

the ready-made (the spectacular ratio of effort to effect of an upturned urinal<br />

labeled "Fountain" and exhibited in a gallery) was generally of cardinal importance<br />

to the Dadaists, not only because it suited the movement's libidinal<br />

economy (the excremental against the obsessional): it demonstrated Dada's<br />

anti-mimetic concept of realism (preferring material literalism over metaphoric<br />

constructions of the materials of art), while at the same time undercutting<br />

the traditional equation of skill, effort or inspiration with art, value,<br />

status and morality. Wieland Herzfelde wrote:<br />

The tasks [of painting] have been taken over by photography and film, and they solve<br />

them infinitely more perfectly than painting ever could. . . . [Since their invention] all<br />

art movements can be characterized as having, despite their differences, a common<br />

tendency to emancipate themselves from reality. Dada is the reaction to all these attempts<br />

at disavowing the factual, which has been the driving force of impressionists,<br />

expressionists, cubists and even futurists (in that they refused to capitulate to film);<br />

however, the Dadaist doesn't try to compete with the camera, or to breathe soul into it<br />

(as did the impressionists) by giving the worst lens-the human eye—priority, or (like<br />

the expressionists) turn the apparatus round and simply depict the world inside their<br />

own bosom.<br />

The Dadaists say: Whereas once inordinate amounts of time, love and exertion were<br />

expended on the depiction of a body, a flower, a hat, the shadow cast by a figure, etc.,<br />

today all we have to do is take a pair of scissors and cut whatever we need out of the<br />

paintings, the photographic reproductions of these things; if the objects are small, we<br />

don't even need the representations, but take the objects themselves, e.g. pocket<br />

knives, ash trays, books, etc.-things which in the museums of old art are wonderfully<br />

painted, but only painted. 31<br />

This passage from Wieland Herzfelde's "Zur Einfiihrung in die Erste Internationale<br />

Dada Messe" seems to illustrate Benjamin's point even as it tries to<br />

embrace the cinema, only to reject film as not material enough. Herzfelde,<br />

despite his bold polemics, does not fully rise to the challenge of the problem<br />

already posed by Lukacs: how does the apparently unmediated reality conveyed<br />

by the photographic image constitute itself as a sign?<br />

In practice, Dada products were often far from subscribing to Herzfelde's<br />

22<br />

naive literalism of taking the objects themselves and putting them on display.<br />

The typical Dada artifact, the photomontage, indicated that the materials<br />

were not primary materials, but already formed by mechanical processes,<br />

which meant that what in one context constitutes the end-product is<br />

treated by Dada as raw material. Likewise, the point about Duchamp's<br />

ready-mades is that a semantic transformation has taken place, and not only<br />

a transgression of space, status, and use. The shift from end to means in the<br />

case of Duchamp especially is always doubled by what might be called a<br />

process of semiotization, where an object of little or no value is transformed<br />

not into a value but into an (ironic) signifier of value. Raoul Hausmann, in<br />

looking back at Berlin Dada, makes a similar point:<br />

Anti-art withdraws from things and materials their utility, but also their concrete and<br />

civil meaning; it reverses classical values and makes them half-abstract. However,<br />

this process was only partially understood and only by some of the Dadaists. 32<br />

Hausmann's notion of "half-abstract" would be worth following up further, if<br />

one wanted to situate more precisely the Dadaists' use of images and the<br />

critical status of photographic or filmic illusionism in the early practice of<br />

photomontage. 33 From the vantage point of an interest in non-linguistic sign<br />

systems and visual sign production, the work of Grosz, Hausmann, and<br />

Heart&eld has yet to be fully explored, because-and here Benjamin is undoubtedly<br />

right-Dada "anti-art" contributed less to the overturning of contemporary<br />

value systems than it participated in the transformation of a perceptual<br />

apparatus which the cinema changed so drastically and rapidly that<br />

it seemed to put the intellectual avant-gardes on the defensive.<br />

Meta-Mechanics and the Perceptual Apparatus<br />

The pre-history of the cinema, as mentioned earlier, comprises two quite<br />

distinct strands: that of the spaces and places where the new mass-public<br />

gathered for entertainment-fairgrounds, traveling circuses, vaudeville and<br />

nickelodeons —, and that of the optical or scientific toys, such as the zoetrope<br />

or the phenakistoscope, where images-painted, printed, or photographeddeceived<br />

the eye into perceiving movement and continuity where there was<br />

merely intermittence. If the Dadaists took an interest in the phenomenon of<br />

the masses eroticized by cinematic spectacles, they were equally alert to the<br />

fact that here was a machine organized in a peculiarly contradictory way: the<br />

cinematic apparatus is devised to function so as to disguise the actual movement<br />

ofthe image (passing through the projector gate) in order to create a nonexistent<br />

movement in the image. Energy in the cinema appears not as in productive<br />

machines, to transmit, transfer, or transform movement, but in order<br />

to nullify, disguise, and revalue movement: mechanics has become the metamechanics<br />

of imaginary motion. This gives the cinema, in terms of its apparatus,<br />

the status not of an optical toy, but rather, it makes it available as a<br />

philosophical toy, a machine transforming the useful energy of cogs and<br />

transmission belts into a useless energy of illusionist simulation. It is this<br />

aspect of the cinema-the devaluation of matter through its perfect reproduction,<br />

as in the photograph, but coupled with the transformation of mechanical<br />

23


movement from one aggregate state to another-which is explored and<br />

elaborated in Duchamp's Anemic cinema. The film grew out of lengthy and<br />

dangerous experimentations with glass discs on which geometrical segments<br />

and lines were painted in such a way as to produce particular illusionist effects<br />

when put in revoking motion.<br />

The rotoreliefs by themselves were illusionist devices, where motorization<br />

created a sense of depth and of spatial extension, a movement from inward to<br />

outward and vice versa. As such, Duchamp's work is comparable to that of<br />

Richter and Eggeling, only that Anemic cinema plays with more overtly anthropomorphic<br />

sensations of heaving or breathing, and thus focuses on the<br />

eroticizing effect of animating the inanimate by a cunning arrangement of<br />

geometrical lines. But what decisively distinguishes Duchamp's film from<br />

other work is that the painted discs are intercut with other discs on which a<br />

series of ingeniously punning sentences are inscribed, whose semantics and<br />

syntactics exploit the mirror effect of syllabic division ("L'aspirant habite Javel,<br />

et moi, j'avais l'habite en spirale"). The two types of discs taken together create<br />

contrasts between flatness and depth, between negative and positive space,<br />

between reading and illusion, between literal and metaphoric. 34 Furthermore,<br />

the puns themselves, which are almost all erotic, interact by a sort of metaphoric<br />

contagion with the shapes and movements of the discs, to create the<br />

impression of seeing male and female protruberances in endless motion,<br />

whose consummation is frustrated through the intervention of the machine, a<br />

typically Duchamp topos.<br />

Indeed it is not simply the intervention of one machine, but rather the synchronization<br />

of two machines: the recording camera and the revolving<br />

motor that spins the discs—two circular motions, distinct from each other,<br />

synchronized and dephased to produce endlessly closed circuits. Useless<br />

energy has been transformed into semiotic energy, via punning and mirroring<br />

effects, and the film —referring the spectator to the apparatus that makes<br />

its effect possible —reveals itself as peculiarly auto-erotic. The cinemamachine<br />

has become a bachelor-machine. 35<br />

Manipulating Materials of Expression or Reproduction<br />

The insertion of art into the sphere of technological, capitalist modes of production<br />

becomes, according to Benjamin, the only position from which a critique<br />

of that mode of production is possible. In this respect, the idea of<br />

cinema, viewed from the perspective of its particular apparatus, could serve<br />

as a sort of model for the representation of the relation between body and<br />

matter, "Geist" and "Stoff," which goes beyond the disavowal of Thomas<br />

Mann as well as the polemical-sadistic materialism of the Berlin Dadaists.<br />

When Hausmann compares the soul of the Berlin bourgeois to a "libretto<br />

machine with a reprogrammable morality disc," 36 the metaphor brutally<br />

substitutes the spiritual connotations of soul with the image of a gramophone.<br />

Hausmann's Tatlin at Home or Grosz's The Engineer Heartfield, on the<br />

other hand, depict precision machines carefully inserted in the place of<br />

brains and heart respectively. Clearly there is a difference, both actual and<br />

intended, between these two uses, and it highlights the ambiguity of the<br />

24<br />

machine metaphor in much Dada work, poised between futurist machines,<br />

which were, invariably, mimetic representations of machines in the conventional<br />

media of bourgeois art (oil paint, bronze, etc.), and constructivist<br />

machines which were, in a fundamental sense, real machines.<br />

In Picabia's Portrait of Marie Laurencin, however, the machine parts<br />

neither propose a likeness, nor a polemical statement. The work suggests a<br />

coalescence of heterogeneous attributes whose perfection, harmony, or<br />

subtle interaction is signaled by machine elements. Similarly, in Man Ray's<br />

famous Dancer/Danger, the cogs are interlocking so tightly that, as a<br />

machine, it cannot function. The picture needs a dancer, a human element<br />

with the precision and dexterity of a machine, to make the mechanism turn.<br />

But it also remains blocked as long as it is viewed as the representation of a<br />

real machine. Only when we notice and thereby activate the energy of the<br />

pun (doubled by the fact that it works in two languages) does the cog of the<br />

letter G "make the connection": the Dada machine is not so much a metaphoric<br />

machine, as it is a metonymic machine which solicits the imaginary<br />

participation by an act of dis-placement, requiring the viewer to look and<br />

think in several dimensions at once. Secondly, as the examples from<br />

Duchamp, Man Ray, and Picabia make apparent, Dada machines are word<br />

machines; they explicitly semiotize the relations that exist between the<br />

parts.<br />

Dada practice, like the cinematic apparatus, redefines the relation of part<br />

to whole, the relation of part to part. It is the cut, the montage principle that<br />

makes the energy in the system visible and active. However, unlike the cinematic<br />

apparatus, where heterogeneity at the level of the material components<br />

and technologies becomes "retinal" and fantasmatic, Dada machines,<br />

whether drawn on paper or printed, enacted in front of a public or built out<br />

of glass and wire, use the contradictions and frictions in the system to remain<br />

non-mimetic. A Duchamp ready-made invites both tactile and conceptual<br />

viewing, but never contemplative attention. The bicycle wheel<br />

mounted on a stool is only complete as a "work" when it arouses the desire to<br />

make it revolve, and it apparently was installed in a place where, to Duchamp's<br />

quiet satisfaction, no-one passed without at least attempting to give<br />

it a furtive spin.<br />

Where the Dada machine thus differs from the cinematic apparatus is that<br />

at the level of the representations it remains intentionally anti-psychological.<br />

The obsessional, projective-intrqjective functions of the cinema contrast<br />

with Duchamp's lifelong exploration of natural processes, of mechanics and<br />

optics in search of material supports for the play of ideas which are antiintentional<br />

and non-expressive, but articulate themselves as traces of a<br />

presence figured in metonymies. Duchamp's representational systems and<br />

constructs - even those which most obviously parody the cinema by figuring<br />

it as "nature morte," such as Etant donnes—eschew the kinds of closure and<br />

homogeneity which typify the developments of him form.<br />

Thus, the complex combination of mechanics, optics, chemistry and timelag<br />

which makes cinematic reproduction possible was an invention very<br />

rnuch in the Dada spirit, for the Dada object always manipulates the materials<br />

of technical reproduction (and not those of expression). The few Dada<br />

25


experiments in him pushed in this direction, as did Dada interest in spectatorship,<br />

since it recognized the cinema as a machine not only in view of the<br />

recording/screening apparatus of camera, film-strip and projector, but also<br />

as a social machine, in which the spectator had a programmed place, physically,<br />

physiologically and economically.<br />

Yet that which made cinema so powerful a social institution-its ability to<br />

simulate in its textual effects the psychic apparatus as a desiring machine (the<br />

cinema as the most efficient simulacrum of the psychic apparatus when<br />

mapped onto the perceptual system, as has consistently happened since<br />

Freud-by and large ran counter to Dada: it was the Surrealists who saw in<br />

filmic processes a way of representing the relation of psychoanalysis to matter,<br />

mediated through rhetoric and figuration. 37 If, as Benjamin suggested,<br />

there is something anachronistic about Dada and cinema, the difference between<br />

Dada and Surrealism in this respect parallels and repeats the development<br />

of the cinema generally: the first focus of attraction for a paying public<br />

was the machinery itself, its novelty, its intricacy, its basic effects. Only<br />

subsequently was this fascination displaced to the stories, the stars, the spectacular<br />

and the specular. Recent film theory, however, seems to indicate that<br />

interest in the apparatus has staged its own return. 38 Perhaps the contradictions<br />

and frictions of Dada/cinema may yet become productive.<br />

Notes<br />

1. Eric Rhode, A History of the Cinema (Harmondsworth, 1978), 3-29.<br />

2. Ibid., 15.<br />

3. Ibid., 5.<br />

4. Willy Verkauf, ed., Dada: Monographic einer Bewegung (Teufen, 1957), 66.<br />

5. See, for instance, Stephen Dwoskin, Film Is.. . (London, 1975), or Sheldon Renan,<br />

An Introduction to the American Underground Film (New York, 1967). Perhaps the best<br />

study of European avant-garde cinema as part of a tradition of non-narrative, noncommercial<br />

cinema is David Curtis, Experimental Cinema (New York, 1971).<br />

6. Verkauf, 68.<br />

7. Mimi White, "Two French Dada Films: Entr'acte and Emak Bakia," Dada/ Surrealism<br />

13(1984): 37.<br />

8. Verkauf, 68.<br />

9. "I would regret it if anyone saw in this . . . anything other than 'optics.'" M. Duchamp,<br />

Marchand du Sel, ed. Michel Sanouillet (Paris, 1958), 185.<br />

10. Quoted in Curtis, 36.<br />

11. White, 37.<br />

12. Toni Stooss, "Erobert den Film! oder 'Prometheus' gegen 'Ufa' & Co.," in Wemgehort<br />

die Welt (NGBK Berlin, 1977), 482-524.<br />

13. This Dada film screening may have occurred to commemorate Eggeling, who<br />

died that month.<br />

14. Anton Kaes, "Verfremdung als Verfahren: Film und Dada," in W. Paulsen, ed.,<br />

Sinn aus Unsinn-Dada International (Berne, 1982), 72-73.<br />

26<br />

15. See for instance Pontus Hulten, ed.,FuturismoeFuturismi (Milan, 1986), 479-480.<br />

16. Kaes, 73.<br />

17. See the forthcoming issue of New German Critique on "Early German Film<br />

Theory."<br />

18. Quoted in Hanne Bergius, "Zur Wahrnehmung und Wahrnehmungskritik im<br />

Berliner Dadaismus," Sprache im Technischen Zeitalter 55 (June-Sept., 1975):244.<br />

19. Rhode, p. 24.<br />

20. Walter Benjamin, Illuminations, trans. Harry Zohn (New York, 1969), 165.<br />

21. Ibid., 238.<br />

22. Ibid., 237.<br />

23. Noel Burch, To the Distant Observer (London, 1979), 61-67.<br />

24. Jakob van Hoddis, "Variete," Der Sturm 47 (1911):374.<br />

25. Pascal Bonitzer, "It's Only a Movie," Framework (England) 14:23.<br />

26. Richter, 198.<br />

27. Moritz Heimann, "Der Kinomatographen-Unfug," in Kino-Debatte, ed. Anton<br />

Kaes (Tubingen, 1978), 37.<br />

28. Thomas Mann, "Uber den Film," in Kino-Debatte, 165.<br />

29. Georg Lukacs, "Gedanken zu einer Aesthetik des Kinos," in Kino-Debatte,<br />

113-115.<br />

30. Benjamin, 237.<br />

31. Wieland Herzfelde, "Zur Einfuhrung in die Erste Internationale Dada-Messe," in<br />

Dada Berlin,ed. Karl Riha and Hanne Bergius (Stuttgart, 1977), 117-118.<br />

32. Raoul Hausmann, "Dada emport sich, regt sich und stirbt in Berlin," in Dada<br />

Berlin, 10-11.<br />

33. See Bergius, 242-44.<br />

34. "Glyphes et graphes s'engendrent indefmiment du meme mouvement, dans un<br />

espace en quelque sorte sans realite, espace tropologique du jeu de mots, espace illusoire<br />

de 1'effet optique." Jean Clair, MarcelDuchamp. Catalogue raisonne (Paris, 1977),<br />

119.<br />

35. See G. Deleuze and F. Guattari: "A genuine consummation is achieved by the<br />

new machine, a pleasure that can rightly be called auto-erotic, or rather automatic:<br />

the nuptial celebration of a new alliance ... as though the eroticism of the machine<br />

liberated other unlimited forces." Anti-Oedipus, Capitalism and Schizophrenia (Minneapolis,<br />

1983), 18.<br />

36. Raoul Hausmann, "Pamphlet gegen die Weimarische Lebensauffassung," xnDada<br />

Berlin, 50.<br />

37. See, for instance, Linda Williams, Figures of Desire: A Theory and Analysis ofSurrealist<br />

Film (Urbana, 1981).<br />

38. Among the recent literature on the "Cinematic Apparatus," one could single out<br />

Jean Louis Baudry, L'Effet Cinema (Paris, 1979], S. Heath, T. de Lauretis, eds., The<br />

Cinematic Apparatus (London, 1979), and Constance Penley, "Feminism, Film Theory<br />

and the Bachelor Machines," m/f 10 (1985).<br />

27


Judi FREEMAN: Bridging Purism and Surrealism: The Origins and<br />

Production of Fernand Léger's Ballet Mécanique. In: Rudolf E. Kuenzli<br />

(Hg.): Dada and Surrealist Film. Cambridge, London: MIT Press 1996,<br />

S. 28-45.<br />

Bridging Purism and Surrealism:<br />

The Origins and Production of<br />

Fernand Leger's Ballet Mecanique<br />

Judi Freeman<br />

Completed and first presented publicly in late September 1924, Fernand<br />

Leger's film Ballet Mecanique was created at the moment when the artist's<br />

painted output shifted from the exploration of diverse images of machine<br />

age life to the study of relatively abstract, closeup views of objects. In a<br />

sense his painted work stood at the crossroads between Purism and Surrealism,<br />

two endeavors seemingly without overlap but in fact-and this is certainly<br />

evident from Leger's particular position between them —possessing<br />

considerable interconnections. His films, like his other collaborative, noneasel<br />

painting projects, generally have been considered apart from the dialogue<br />

about the traditional fine arts in the early twentieth century. 1 When<br />

critically examined, however, it is clear that his films and other activities<br />

are integrally tied to these movements as well. Curiously, although Ballet<br />

Mecanique, along with Viking Eggeling's Symphonie diagonale (1921), Marcel<br />

Duchamp's Anemic Cinema (1926), and Man Ray's Emak Bakia (1926-27),<br />

most often are presented together in series devoted to Dada and Surrealist<br />

films or to avant-garde cinema, Ballet Mecanique always seems to be uncomfortably<br />

situated in this context.<br />

The peculiar nature of Ballet Mecanique, both in the context of Leger's<br />

career and within a notion of Dada and Surrealist him, is testimony to its<br />

significance within Leger's oeuvre as well as to the particular contributions<br />

of Leger's collaborators. The him was of such importance to the artist that in<br />

the final years of his career, he planned to remake it, in collaboration with<br />

Henri Langlois, in a version to be called Ballet des couleurs. 2 It is worthwhile,<br />

then, to reconstruct the genesis and development of the Ballet Mecanique<br />

project and to resolve how Leger made the film and how it fits into the<br />

painting he produced in the 1920s. 3<br />

Among the earliest French avant-garde artists to recognize the potential of<br />

cinema within the fine arts, Leger enthusiastically embraced the medium in<br />

numerous writings. As an active member of Ricciotto Canudo's Club des<br />

amis du septieme art (Club of the friends of the 7th art), he attended regular<br />

screenings and dinners with directors, film editors, and other realisateurs in<br />

the burgeoning French film industry. Clearly, though, Leger did not possess<br />

sufficient technical know-how to realize a film. But by 1923, when he embarked<br />

on the making of Ballet Mecanique, he had amassed considerable ex-<br />

28<br />

perience of the filmmaking industry. His first hands-on participation was in<br />

the making of Abel Gance's La Roue [The Wheel), in 1922. Although Gance's<br />

film was highly narrative, it contained notable passages of rapid montage<br />

that led later to his more sophisticated use of this technique in Napoleon<br />

(1927). In his admiring essay devoted to these montage sequences, Leger<br />

highlighted the portion of the film where the "machine becomes the leading<br />

character, the leading actor":<br />

This new element is presented to us through an infinite variety of methods, from<br />

every aspect: close-ups, fixed or moving mechanical fragments, projected at a heightened<br />

speed that approaches the state of simultaneity and that crushes and eliminates<br />

the human object, reduces its interest, pulverizes it . . . The plastic event is no less<br />

there because of it, it's nowhere else; it is planned, fitted in with care, appropriate,<br />

and seems to me to be laden with implications in itself and for the future.<br />

The advent of this film is additionally interesting in that it is going to determine a<br />

place in the plastic order for an art that has until now remained almost completely descriptive,<br />

sentimental, and documentary. The fragmentation of the object, the intrinsic<br />

plastic value of the object, its pictorial equivalence, have long been the domain of<br />

the modern arts. With The Wheel Abel Gance has elevated the art of film to the plane<br />

of the plastic arts. 4<br />

Not only was Leger present at the film's debut at the Gaumont-Palace in<br />

Paris in December 1922, but he also witnessed the film's shooting in Nice<br />

and the French Alps. Leger joined his old friend, the poet Blaise Cendrars,<br />

who at this time served as Gance's key assistant and troubleshooter on the<br />

film, involved with every aspect of the production-from arranging for<br />

props to paying bills. 5 Also present was Jean Epstein, then a young writer<br />

on film and the arts in Lyon, who was observing portions of the shooting. 6<br />

Leger discussed his impressions of the film and his general ideas on<br />

cinema's potential with Gance, who, in turn, encouraged him and commissioned<br />

him to write on the film as part of the carefully orchestrated publicity<br />

campaign surrounding La Roue's release in December 1922 (Fig. I). 7<br />

Following the film's premiere, Leger supplied Gance with his view of the<br />

audience's response to the film, telling the director that the "simultaneous<br />

passage" was the most successful but that other parts of the film had considerable<br />

problems. 8<br />

It is interesting to note how Leger initially asked Gance to describe him in<br />

the biographical note to be attached to Leger's promotional article on the<br />

film which appeared in Comoedia:<br />

Fernand Leger is the modern French painter that first considered the mechanical element<br />

as a possible plastic element; he has incorporated the concept of equivalence<br />

into numerous pictures. Abel Gance has asked him to offer his view of the plastic<br />

value of his film La Roue. 9<br />

Leger's paintings of 1922 were not devoted to mechanical elements seen in<br />

close-up. In 1918-19 Leger had produced several canvases on themes of<br />

mechanical elements or disks but his paintings of 1922 and 1923 continued<br />

themes begun in 1920-women, still lives of ordinary household objects<br />

situated in an interior, figures at work in the city or country-with equiva-<br />

29


Figure 1<br />

lences established between seemingly unrelated forms. For the artist, the<br />

link between his earlier works and his current pursuits was the exploration<br />

of plastic values. Ballet Mecanique served as an opportunity to test his ideas<br />

on these values in another medium by selecting aspects of that medium that<br />

permitted their expression.<br />

30<br />

The actual making of Ballet Mecanique is complicated by several conflicting<br />

accounts. Leger is known to have collaborated with four Americans<br />

resident in Europe: aspiring cameraman Dudley Murphy, fledgling composer<br />

George Antheil, the poet Ezra Pound, and the artist-photographer<br />

Man Ray. Their precise contributions to the film, however, are clouded by<br />

the contradictions present in their individual written accounts. Dudley<br />

Murphy, for example, recounted his perceptions of how the film was made:<br />

One day, when I was visiting Ezra Pound and talking about my work, he told me<br />

that a friend of his, Ferdinand [sic] Leger, wanted to make a movie. Also George Anteil<br />

[sic], the young protege of Stravinsky would like to make a movie. So he brought<br />

the three of us together and we decided to make one. I had met an attractive American<br />

divorcee who had a beautiful house in Paris and who was intrigued with me,<br />

Gladys Barbour. I told her of my plans and she lent me the money to buy a movie<br />

camera.<br />

The tools of a film-maker can be very simple. It is really a camera and film. So, having<br />

the camera, we only needed film, so Leger and I financed our film equally with<br />

the understanding that he would have the European rights of the finished film and I<br />

would have the American rights. We talked over ideas and I set out with my camera<br />

and the film, executing the ideas we had talked over and photographing things that<br />

stimulated my imagination around Paris. The premise on which we decided to make<br />

the film was based on a belief that surprise of image and rhythm would make a pure<br />

film without drawing on any of the other arts, such as writing, acting, painting. In<br />

other words, we were going to make a pure film. Our project was called Ballet Mecanique.<br />

I saw an old washerwoman climbing a flight of stone stairs. When she reached the<br />

top, she was tired and made a futile gesture. The scene in itself was banal, but by<br />

printing it 20 times and connecting the end of the scene with the beginning of her<br />

climb, it expressed the futility of life because she never got there. This scene in the<br />

editing followed a very intricate piece of shiny machinery, somehow correlated in<br />

movement and rhythm to that of hers.<br />

Another scene showed a tremendous piston, brilliant and shiny, plunging up and<br />

down in a very phallic movement. This was followed by the bulging stomach of<br />

Katherine [Hawley, Murphy's wife], who was now pregnant.<br />

I was intrigued to do something with the artificial legs that exhibit silk stockings and<br />

decided to do a stop motion dance with these legs around a clock. In bringing the<br />

legs to the studio, I drove through Paris in an open cab, with a leg over each<br />

shoulder, screaming. 10<br />

Dudley Murphy began his film career at Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer (MGM) in<br />

the late 1910s under the tutelage of eminent Hollywood art director Cedric<br />

Gibbons. From there, he moved into art directing positions at assorted<br />

Hollywood studios. He made several poetically inspired films, starring his<br />

first and second wives, and attempted to distribute them commercially.<br />

With the help of an investor he then formed in the early 1920s a company<br />

called "Visual Symphonies," the goal of which was to identify a method to<br />

establish a frame-by-frame correspondence with a musical composition. 11<br />

The first film to emerge from these efforts was Danse macabre, a dance film<br />

choreographed to and therefore necessarily performed with Saint-Saens's<br />

music. Ballet Mecanique followed two years later; by this time, Murphy had<br />

31


accumulated considerable experience in shooting and editing him. Moreover,<br />

he considered the film to be an extension of his "visual symphonies." 12<br />

Murphy's account helps to explain how Leger, an artist without specific<br />

technical expertise in cinema, actually made a film. Yet the story of the<br />

project's origins conflicts with the account of another contributor, Man Ray:<br />

One day a tall young man appeared with his beautiful blond wife, and introduced<br />

himself as a cameraman from Hollywood. . . . Dudley Murphy said some very flattering<br />

things about my work and suggested that we do a him together. He had all the<br />

professional material, he said; with my ideas and his technique something new<br />

could be produced. We became quite friendly, spent a few days together discussing<br />

subject matter —I insisted on my Dada approach if we were to work together, to<br />

which he readily agreed . . . We took some walks together, I bringing my little<br />

camera and shooting a few scenes without any attempt at careful choice of people or<br />

setting, emphasizing the idea of improvisation. For the more tricky effects we<br />

planned indoors, Dudley set up an old Pathe camera on its tripod, the kind used in<br />

the comic shorts of the day. He showed me some complicated lenses that could<br />

deform and multiply images, which we'd use for portraits and close-ups. The camera<br />

remained standing in my studio for a few days, which annoyed me, as I never like to<br />

have my instruments in view . . . When Dudley appeared again, he announced that<br />

he was ready to go to work and would I purchase the him. I was surprised, thinking<br />

this was included with his technical equipment - that I was to supply the ideas only.<br />

He packed up his camera, took it over to the painter Leger's studio, explaining that<br />

he himself had no money and that the painter had agreed to finance the film. I made<br />

no objection, was glad to see the black box go, and relieved that I hadn't gotten involved<br />

in a co-operative enterprise. And that is how Dudley realized the Ballet Mecanique,<br />

which had a certain success, with Leger's name. 13<br />

The goal of the Dadaists, according to Man Ray, was to "try the spectators'<br />

patience." 14 And clearly that concept was incorporated into the final form of<br />

the film in the repetition of the washerwoman climbing the stairs and in the<br />

fracturing of repeated forms, such as that of his mistress's, Kiki of Montparnasse's,<br />

face toward the end of the film. 15<br />

Man Ray's description curiously is not corroborated in the other accounts<br />

of the making of Ballet Mecanique. While the film clearly bears the imprint<br />

of Leger's predominantly machine aesthetic in the first half of the 1920s, it<br />

also contains Man Ray's distinctive treatment of people in his photographs<br />

and other films. It is worth noting that in 1926, when Man Ray embarked on<br />

the making of Emak Bakia, he envisioned the film in terms similar to Leger's<br />

stated intentions for Ballet Mecanique:<br />

A series of fragments, a cine-poem with a certain optical sequence make up a whole<br />

that still remains a fragment. Just as one can much better appreciate the abstract<br />

beauty in a fragment of a classical work than in its entirety, so this film tries to indicate<br />

the essentials in its contemporary cinematography. 16<br />

Man Ray's involvement with Ballet Mecanique, nevertheless, was restricted<br />

to the shooting of imagery in the earliest phases of the project.<br />

Ezra Pound's role in the film's production was also limited, in this case to<br />

the introduction of the various makers of the film to one another. In a letter<br />

of July 1923 to his parents, Pound noted, "Dudley Murphy, whom I met in<br />

Venice in 1908, he being then eleven; turned up a few days ago ... he is try-<br />

32<br />

ing to make cinema into art." 17 By September, he stated "We [Pound and<br />

George Antheil] have a new Leger 'projet' waiting to be framed." 18 In November,<br />

Murphy wrote "I have practically completed the film with Ezra<br />

Pound and it looks quite interesting ... it is quite abstract-no people-only<br />

interesting forms." 19 It is clear by January 1924 that the three collaborators,<br />

Pound, Murphy, and Leger, were at work on the film; "Also work on vorticist<br />

film-experiment interesting, but probably Murphy hasn't brain<br />

enough to finish the job in my absence or without pushing." 20<br />

Pound had very much become, in the early 1920s, the key sponsor of aspiring<br />

composer Antheil. 21 While Pound himself was deeply interested in<br />

music and was in fact composing his own compositions and operas, he encouraged<br />

Antheil to embark on a performing tour of Europe, with Pound's<br />

mistress, pianist Olga Rudge. In 1923, Antheil gave a Paris concert with<br />

music so deliberately audacious that it provoked a major riot in Paris's Theatre<br />

des Champs-Elysees; the riot was caused intentionally and was filmed<br />

for use in Marcel LHerbier's 1923 film L'Inhumaine. The notoriety Antheil<br />

gained from this performance emboldened the composer to propose publicly<br />

a new project. Whether Leger's and Murphy's project predates this and<br />

whether it was Ezra Pound who encouraged Antheil to join in is unclear,<br />

given the lack of reliability characteristic in much of Antheil's writings;<br />

nevertheless, it is Antheil's account of Ballet Mecanique's origins that further<br />

confuses the issue of who made what and when:<br />

[In October 1923] I announced to the press that I was working on a new piece, to be<br />

called "Ballet Mecanique." I said that I also sought a motion-picture accompaniment<br />

to this piece. The newspapers and art magazines seemed only too happy to publish<br />

this request, which interested a young American cameraman, Dudley Murphy. He<br />

had really been flushed by Ezra Pound, who convinced him.<br />

Murphy said he would make the movie, providing the French painter Fernand Leger<br />

consented to collaborate. Leger did. 22<br />

Antheil's composition, which was scored for machines, bells, anvils, automobile<br />

horns, player pianos, and percussion and was converted into three<br />

Pleyela piano rolls, was not completed, however, until the autumn of 1925. 23<br />

Leger was eager to get it, writing to Antheil in April 1924, "Where is your<br />

composition, Ballet Mecanique? Let me know what is available to listen to<br />

. . ." 24 To Leger's dismay, the score was not completed by September 1924,<br />

when Leger first screened the film publicly at the Internationale Ausstellung<br />

fur Theatertechnik organized by Frederick Kiesler. Leger was so confident<br />

that Antheil's music would be finished and successfully merged with the film<br />

that the title card on the print screened in Vienna referred to the synchronized<br />

score. Its first known performance was, like most of its subsequent<br />

performances, independent of the film's screening; by this time, several<br />

different prints of the film were already in distribution. Leger's reaction to<br />

the music was, according to Antheil, wildly enthusiastic:<br />

• • . I hear that Leger has been simply crazy since he heard the Ballet Mecanique several<br />

days ago. He heard it for the first time, for I've been very busy with my opera and<br />

couldn't go to him. So we arranged a performance of the music several days ago, and<br />

after it was over he simply embraced me. Leger expected a great deal, but he said it<br />

was beyond his expectations and that it was as right as right can be. 25<br />

33


Figure 2<br />

In several letters to both Antheil and Ezra Pound, Leger refers to an additional<br />

collaborator on Ballet Mecamque, Charles Delacommune. 26 Delacommune's<br />

company, Synchro-Cine, is credited by the use of its logo, at the end<br />

of The Museum of Modern Art's print of the film, which Leger gave to the<br />

museum in 1935. It is clear that Leger and Murphy knew and worked with<br />

Delacommune at the time of the film's making in 1923-24 because Leger acknowledged<br />

his role in his article on the film published in Little Review in<br />

1924. 27 At the time, Delacommune founded a company called Synchronisme<br />

cinematique (known as Synchro-Cine after 1928), which served as an umbrella<br />

organization for Delacommune's research into synchronization. One<br />

of the first films he "synchronized," through the use of punched musical<br />

scores aligned to sprocket holes in nitrate films, was Murphy's La Valse de<br />

Mephisto. Murphy continued to employ him on Ballet Mecamque, paying<br />

him 300 francs on January 18, 1924 for his services on the film, 28 and Leger<br />

entrusted the distribution of his prints to him in the late twenties and early<br />

thirties.<br />

Leger was so engrossed in Delacommune's method of synchronization,<br />

which Delacommune had patented in 1922 and 1923, as well as the "cinepupitre,"<br />

the mechanical apparatus he invented, that he sketched the<br />

machinery to be used on back of notes made in relation to Ballet Mecanique<br />

(Fig. 2). 29 On the front of these pages, Leger made specific notes on ideas he<br />

34<br />

Figure 3<br />

had, perhaps with Murphy and/or the other collaborators, on the film's imagery.<br />

30 He proposed dividing the screen into nine equal sections, an idea<br />

that anticipated Gance's use of this device in the opening sequences of his<br />

1927 film Napoleon. He envisioned figures engulfed by mechanical objects,<br />

integrated into an array of constructed objects, typewriters, pendulums. The<br />

alternation of black on white and white on black was to be explored. Advertising<br />

images were to be used frequently. Above all, contrasts were intended<br />

to reign, a way of suggesting equivalences through the use of quick-fire juxtaposition.<br />

In addition to individual images Leger suggested for inclusion in the film,<br />

he also fused a previously unrealized film project into Ballet Mecanique. The<br />

painter was a passionate fan of the work of Charlie Chaplin, having been<br />

first introduced to Chaplin's films during the First World War by the poet<br />

Guillaume Apollinaire. 31 Leger was fascinated by Chaplin's control over his<br />

audience and, by extension, the potential of cinema to affect and manipulate<br />

35


audience response. 32 He illustrated an edition of Ivan Golfs book, Die Chaplinade<br />

(1920) and shortly thereafter began work on a scenario for an animated<br />

him, Chariot Cubiste. Leger's scenario was extremely detailed, chronicling<br />

every moment in a day in the life in Paris of Chariot, who was constructed<br />

as a mario<strong>net</strong>te in relief (Fig. 3). At least five lengthy drafts of the<br />

scenario were penned by Leger; however, the film appears never to have<br />

been made, probably due to the lack of financial backing. 33<br />

Leger made use of the mario<strong>net</strong>te and the idea of a disintegrating/reconstituted<br />

Chariot at the begining and end of Ballet Mecanique. He is almost<br />

always juxtaposed in his jerky choreography with the repetitive movements<br />

of the woman (Katherine Hawley Murphy) seen at the beginning of the film<br />

on the swing and seen later sniffing flowers in a garden (Fig. 4). But between<br />

Leger's involvement with his Chariot Cubiste project and the undertaking of<br />

Ballet Mecanique, his work on another film, this time for filmmaker Marcel<br />

L'Herbier, intervened and redirected Leger's attention toward the potential<br />

of mechanical imagery in his films. For L'Herbier's 1923 L'Inhumaine, Leger<br />

created the sets for the film's climactic laboratory scene (Fig. 5). Machinery<br />

in this silent film suggested, presumably with the help of a live orchestral accompaniment,<br />

whirring, buzzing, clanging, and pumping, thereby enhancing<br />

the sensory experience for the viewer. Leger incorporated the lessons<br />

from that film into the images he chose for Ballet Mecanique: swinging<br />

Christmas ornaments and saucepan covers (Fig. 6), incessantly pumping<br />

pistons, whirling gelatin molds, gyrating pieces of corrugated sheet metal. It<br />

36<br />

Figure 5<br />

appears that Léger instructed Murphy to shoot many of these images, along<br />

with other images Murphy already had shot with Man Ray or, in several in<br />

stances, chosen with Pound or on his own; many of the refracted and frac-<br />

37


Figure 6<br />

tured images, such as Kiki's face (Fig. 7), the owl, or the corrugated sheet<br />

metal resulted from Pound's ideas on film inspired by his experience with<br />

the vortographs of Alvin Langdon Coburn and from Man Ray's rayogram experiments.<br />

34<br />

When the actual fusion of the images into a final film took place, however,<br />

it was Leger's evolving vision that dominated that of Pound, Man Ray, and<br />

Murphy. While his machine aesthetic dominated much of the imagery finally<br />

selected when Leger and Murphy sat down at the editing table, the<br />

rapid montage that Leger had learned by watching Abel Gance dominated<br />

his editing style. He reflected later that the "editing gave me a lot of trouble.<br />

There are long sequences of repeated movements that had to be cut. I had to<br />

watch the smallest details very carefully because of the repetition of<br />

images." The minute and extensive frame by frame cutting that occurred is<br />

visible on the nitrate print of the first known version of the film, premiered<br />

at the Internationale Ausstellung fur Theatertechnik in Vienna and preserved<br />

by Frederick Kiesler. 35<br />

Leger declared:<br />

The particular interest of the film is centered upon the importance which we give to<br />

the 'fixed image,' to its arithmetical, automatic projection, slowed down or accelerated—additional,<br />

likeness.<br />

No scenario-Reactions of rhythmic images, that is all.<br />

38<br />

Figure 7<br />

Two coefficients of interest upon which the film is constructed:<br />

The variation of the speeds of projection:<br />

The rhythm of these speeds.<br />

We persist up to the point when the eye and spirit of the spectator will no longer accept.<br />

We drain out of it every bit of its value as a spectacle up to the moment when it<br />

becomes insupportable. 36<br />

Leger's fascination with the mechanical aspects of movement were coupled<br />

with his curiosity about the audience's response to it. His description of the<br />

editing of the washerwoman climbing the stairs, also recalled by Murphy,<br />

underscores his desire to challenge the spectator:<br />

... in "The Woman Climbing the Stairs," I wanted to amaze the audience first, then<br />

make them uneasy, and then push the adventure to the point of exasperation. In<br />

order to "time" it properly, I got together a group of workers and people in the neighborhood,<br />

and I studied the effect that was produced on them. In eight hours I learned<br />

what I wanted to know. Nearly all of them reacted at about the same time. 37<br />

The wish to challenge the spectator and to juxtapose images, speeds, and<br />

rhythms in order to establish equivalences characterize Leger's approach to<br />

his painting. In his work, he sought to apply a "law of plastic contrasts," one<br />

that allowed him to combine different forms: flat vs. modeled surfaces, fig-<br />

39


Figure 8<br />

ures vs. flat building facades, volumes of smoke vs. active architectural surfaces,<br />

pure, flat vs. gray, modulated tones. 38 Leger believed we "live in a<br />

state of frequent contrasts" and that the role of art was to be of its time. 39 He<br />

also aspired to "conquer his public":<br />

We live surrounded by beautiful objects that are slowly being revealed and perceived<br />

by man; they are occupying an increasingly important place around us, in our interior<br />

and exterior life.<br />

40<br />

Figure 9<br />

Cultivate this possibility, release it, direct it, extend its consequences. 40<br />

Increasingly, however, the imagery which Leger chose to present to his public<br />

changed. Whereas in 1923 Leger's absorption was with observed life in<br />

me machine-dominated modern era in paintings such as Le grand rémorqueur,<br />

by 1924 he returned to more abstract Elements mécaniques (Fig. 8) a<br />

theme he had previously pursued in the late 1910s. The imagery became the<br />

machine, then the machine closeup, then the closeup of everyday life. By<br />

41


1926, Leger had immersed himself almost completely in making drawings<br />

and paintings of closeup imagery (Fig. 9).<br />

What intervened was Ballet Mecanique. The effect of a hat alternating with<br />

legs, with ornaments, with shoes, triangles, alternating with circles, a pearl<br />

necklace alternating with the words "un collier des perles," single zeros alternating<br />

with multiple zeros-all of these opened up new avenues of exploration<br />

for Leger. By narrowing his vision, he could focus on the varied meanings<br />

and associations of objects. In painting, his intentions approached those<br />

of Rene Magritte and Max Ernst. Certainly Leger had not become a Surrealist;<br />

indeed he went to great pains to distance himself from the group. He<br />

had not completely abandoned Purism either, still portraying objects from<br />

daily life that belonged to the machine age as much of his imagery. But Ballet<br />

Mecanique, as a collaborative product by artists from various media, allowed<br />

Leger to see the potential of his ideas in another medium, as well as helped<br />

to redirect the values he endeavored to explore in his own favored medium<br />

of painting.<br />

Notes<br />

1. This is the case in the most recent major monographs devoted to Leger:<br />

Christopher Green, Leger and the Avant-Garde (New Haven and London: Yale University<br />

Press, 1976), and Peter de Francia, Fernand Leger (New Haven and London: Yale<br />

University Press, 1984).<br />

2. Georges Sadoul referred to the film in an article written after Leger's death in<br />

1955; see Georges Sadoul, "Fernand Leger ou la cineplastique," Cinema 59.35 (April<br />

1959:81), and Bulletin de I'ACA 4 (January-February 1959): 7.<br />

All known footage for Ballet de couleurs belonged to Nadia Leger until her death in<br />

1982 and presumably is part of the Leger estate. Nadia Leger and Georges Bauquier<br />

were collaborating with Mary Meerson, formerly of the Cinematheque francaise,<br />

Paris, to complete this film, left unfinished at Leger's death, and present it in the early<br />

1980s. To my knowledge, the film has never been publicly screened. Mary Meerson,<br />

in conversation with the author, Paris, November 1982 and Jean Mitry, in conversation<br />

with the author, Neuilly, April 1983.<br />

3. In this context I will not address the relationship of Ballet Mecanique and contemporary<br />

theorists' writings on film. In doing so, I have concluded that this context does<br />

not help to illuminate the making and meaning of the film and therefore disagree with<br />

Richard Brender, who, in a recent article devoted to Leger's cinema, assessed the film<br />

by evaluating it against these theorists' expectations. See Richard Brender, "Functions<br />

of Film: Leger's Cinema on Paper and on Cellulose, 1913-25," Cinema Journal 24.1<br />

(Fall 1984): 41-63.<br />

4. Fernand Leger, "A Critical Essay on the Plastic Quality of Abel Gance's Film The<br />

Wheel," Comoedia (1922), translated in Fernand Leger, Functions of Painting, translated<br />

by Alexandra Anderson, edited by Edward F. Fry (New York: Viking Press, 1965),<br />

pp. 20-21.<br />

5. See the extensive correspondence from Blaise Cendrars to Abel Gance on a variety<br />

of topics related to the making of La Roue (Abel Gance archives, Centre national<br />

de cinematographic, Paris, and the Abel Gance papers, Cinematheque francaise,<br />

Paris).<br />

42<br />

6. Leger already knew Epstein, having published his "La couleur dans la vie (Fragment<br />

dune etude sur les valeurs plastiques nouvelles)" in Epstein's journal Promenoir<br />

5 (1921): 66-67.<br />

7. Gance commissioned articles from Jean Epstein, Blaise Cendrars, Jacques Theve<strong>net</strong>,<br />

and Leger for various newspapers. See Abel Gance, "Dennitif La Roue," unpublished<br />

manuscript, 1 p. (Abel Gance papers, Cinematheque francaise, Paris).<br />

8. Letter from Fernand Leger to Abel Gance, 11 November 1922 (Abel Gance papers,<br />

Cinematheque francaise, Paris).<br />

9. Ibid.<br />

10. Dudley Murphy, "Murphy by Murphy," unpublished autobiographical manuscript,<br />

January 1966 (Erin Murphy O'Hara, Malibu, California). The image of<br />

Katherine's bulging pregnant stomach is not present in any of the known versions of<br />

Ballet Mecanique. However, according to Dudley Murphy's son, the filmmaker<br />

Michael Murphy, Murphy possessed a print, one he carried with him from Paris to<br />

the United States in 1926 and screened in New York theatres in that year, which contained<br />

this and other nude, particularly suggestive images. It appears that all extant<br />

copies, which appear to have been distributed only by Leger and as early as 1924, had<br />

these passages deleted. Interview with Michael Murphy and the author, Malibu,<br />

August 1982.<br />

11. "'Visual Symphonies' Find Recognition; New Short Subjects Replace Prologues,"<br />

Moving Picture World (January 28, 1922): 387.<br />

12. Letter from Dudley Murphy to Herman Dudley Murphy, July 20, 1924 (Poco<br />

Murphy, Sea Cliff, New York).<br />

13. Man Ray, Self Portrait (New York: McGraw-Hill Book Company, 1963),<br />

pp. 266-267. It is worth noting that Man Ray claimed Leger financed the film, while<br />

Dudley Murphy asserted that Ezra Pound did; see letter from Dudley Murphy to Herman<br />

Dudley Murphy, November 19, 1923 (Poco Murphy, Sea Cliff, New York).<br />

14. Ibid., p. 260.<br />

15. Man Ray in fact published and signed a number of these images as independent<br />

prints; see, for example, Kiki ofMontparnasse (1924), in: Man Ray, Photographe (Paris:<br />

Musee national d'art moderne, Centre national dart et de culture Georges Pompidou,<br />

1982), p. 104, pi. 107. Other images are currently preserved in glass negatives in the<br />

Man Ray studio in Paris.<br />

16. Frank Stauffacher, Art in Cinema (San Francisco: San Francisco Museum of Art,<br />

1947), p. 53.<br />

17. Letter from Ezra Pound to his parents, July 1923 (Ezra Pound Archives, Beinecke<br />

Rare Book and Manuscript Library, Yale University, New Haven, Connecticut).<br />

18. Letter from Ezra Pound to his parents, 12 September 1923 (Ezra Pound Archives,<br />

Beinecke Rare Book and Manuscript Library, Yale University, New Haven, Connecticut).<br />

19. Letter from Dudley Murphy to Carlene Murphy Samoileff, November 16, 1923<br />

(Poco Murphy, Sea Cliff, New York).<br />

20. Letter from Ezra Pound to his parents, 29 January 1924 (Ezra Pound Archives,<br />

Beinecke Rare Book and Manuscript Library, Yale University, New Haven, Connecticut).<br />

I am grateful to Archibald Henderson III for suggesting that I consult these letters.<br />

21. On the relationship between Antheil and Pound and especially on Pound's interest<br />

in music, see Archibald Henderson III, "Pound and Music: The Paris and Early Rapallo<br />

Years," Ph.D. dissertation, University of California at Los Angeles, 1983.<br />

43


22. George Antheil, Bad Boy of Music (New York: Garden City, New York: Doubleday,<br />

Doran and Company, Inc., 1945), pp. 134-135.<br />

23. The three piano rolls, recorded in Paris in 1925, are currently in the collection of<br />

the Archives of the History of Art, Getty Center for the History of Art and Humanities,<br />

Santa Monica, California.<br />

24. Letter from Leger to George Antheil, dated April 1924 (Ezra Pound Archives, Beinecke<br />

Rare Book and Manuscript Library, Yale University, New Haven, Connecticut).<br />

25. Letter to Ezra Pound from George Antheil, n.d. (1925), (Ezra Pound Archives, Beinecke<br />

Rare Book and Manuscript Library, Yale University, New Haven, Connecticut).<br />

26. See, for example, letters from Leger to Ezra Pound, dated 22 April, 23 November,<br />

and 14 December 1932 (Ezra Pound Archives, Beinecke Rare Book and Manuscript Library,<br />

Yale University, New Haven, Connecticut), and Leger to George Antheil, February<br />

5, 1933 (George Antheil Archives, El Cerrito, California).<br />

27. Fernand Leger, "Film by Fernand Leger and Dudley Murphy, Musical Synchronism<br />

by George Antheil," Little Review (Autumn-Winter 1924-1925) :44.<br />

28. Katherine Hawley Murphy's datebook for 1924 (Poco Murphy, Sea Cliff, New<br />

York), page for January 18, documents this payment.<br />

29. These notes were first published by Standish D. Lawder in his pioneering study,<br />

The Cubist Cinema (New York: New York University Press, 1975). Pierre Alechinsky<br />

purchased the notes on the advice of film historian Lotte Eisner, who recognized that<br />

they were notes for Leger's film. Previously they were in the possession of Robert<br />

Hessens, the Belgian filmmaker, who was making a short film on Leger analogous (in<br />

Leger's view) to personal manuscripts and notes in preparation; see letter from Leger<br />

to Robert Hessens, n.d. (1950s), (Pierre Alechinsky, Bougival, France).<br />

30. Murphy's own notes list white gloved hands moving in black spaces, nude bodies<br />

writhing in blackness, water falling through a triangle, a wheel approaching the<br />

camera, and numerous stunts. Whether these were Murphy's or Leger's ideas is unclear;<br />

the pronounced contrasts among the images listed suggest that these were<br />

mainly Leger's thoughts. Dudley Murphy, "Page of notes," Unpublished MS., 1 p.<br />

(Poco Murphy, Sea Cliff, New York).<br />

31. Leger was so taken by Chaplin that he devoted an admiring article to him, describing<br />

his first impressions of the filmmaker/actor; see Leger, "Chariot Cubiste," unpublished<br />

MS., 7 pp. (Fernand Leger Archives, formerly Musee national Fernand<br />

Leger, Biot) and Leger, "Temoignage," Les Chroniques dujour (special issue devoted to<br />

Chaplin) 73 (December 15-31, 1926).<br />

Leger also referred to Chaplin's "mechanical" possibilities in his "L'avenir du<br />

cinema," Unpublished MS., n.d. (1923), 1 p. (Fernand Leger Archives, formerly Musee<br />

national Fernand Leger, Biot).<br />

32. Leger considered both Chaplin and Buster Keaton's work to have this ability; see<br />

Leger, "Sur le cinema," Unpublished MS., 1 p. (Fernand Leger Archives, formerly<br />

Musee national Fernand Leger, Biot.<br />

33. For the five scenario manuscripts, see the unpublished documents in the Fernand<br />

Leger Archives, formerly Musee national Fernand Leger, Biot.<br />

Leger alluded to his difficulties in obtaining this backing in his letter to Jean Epstein,<br />

March 2, 1923 (Marie Epstein, Paris).<br />

34. See Lawder, p. 140, 142.<br />

44<br />

35. This print, found in 1976 by Lillian Kiesler, the artist's widow, is presently in the<br />

collection of Anthology Film Archives, New York. Its condition and important<br />

provenance and screening history makes it the definitive version of the film, to be<br />

used in evaluating the film's relationship to its score. All published studies of Ballet<br />

Mecanique to date have been based on the Museum of Modern Art's print of the film,<br />

given by Leger to the museum at the time of his retrospective in 1935. A considerable<br />

amount of material has been edited out of MOMA's version.<br />

36. Fernand Leger, "Film by Fernand Leger and Dudley Murphy, Musical Synchronism<br />

by George Antheil," Little Review (Autumn-Winter 1924-25): 42-44.<br />

37. Fernand Leger, "Ballet Mecanique," (listed as c. 1924, but most certainly not written<br />

before 1926), printed in: Fernand Leger, Functions of Painting, p. 51.<br />

38. Fernand Leger, "Notes on the Mechanical Element," 1923, published in Functions<br />

of Painting, p. 29.<br />

39. Ibid., p. 30.<br />

40. Fernand Leger, "The Spectacle: Light, Color, Moving Image, Object-Spectacle,"<br />

Bulletin de I'Effort Moderne, 1924, reprinted in: Functions of Painting, p. 44-45.<br />

List of Illustrations<br />

1. Fernand Leger, Poster Design for Abel Gance's La Roue, c. 1922. Gouache. Musee<br />

National Fernand Leger, Biot, France. Photo: Studio Jacques Mer, Antibes.<br />

2. Fernand Leger, Notes for Ballet Mecanique, c. 1923-24. Pen and ink. Collection<br />

Pierre Alechinsky, Bougival, France.<br />

3. Fernand Leger, Chariot Cubiste, c. 1922. Wood Relief. Galerie Jan Krugier,<br />

Geneva and New York.<br />

4. Katherine Hawley Murphy swinging, still from Ballet Mecanique, 1924. Photo:<br />

British Film Institute, London.<br />

5. Laboratory set from Marcel L'Herbier's film, L'Inhumaine, 1923. Photo: British<br />

Film Institute, London.<br />

6. Still from Ballet Mecanique, 1924. Photo: British Film Institute, London.<br />

7. Still from Ballet Mecanique, 1924. Photo: British Film Institute, London.<br />

8. Fernand Leger, Elements mecanimes sur fond rouge, 1924. Oil on canvas. Musee<br />

National Fernand Leger, Biot. Photo: Studio Jacques Mer, Antibes.<br />

9. Fernand Leger, Composition on Blue Background, 1928. Oil on canvas. 16Vs x 13 in.<br />

Private Collection.<br />

45


Sandy FLITTERMAN-LEWIS: Dulac in Context: French Film Production<br />

in the Twenties. In: Dies.: To Desire Differently. Feminism and the French<br />

Cinema. Univ. of Illinois Press 1990, S. 78-97. [R]<br />

Sandy FLITTERMAN-LEWIS: From Fantasy to Structure of the Fantasm:<br />

The Smiling Mme Beudet and The Seashell and the Clergyman. In: Dies.:<br />

To Desire Differently. Feminism and the French Cinema. Univ. of Illinois<br />

Press 1990, S. 98-140.


THREE<br />

Dulac in Context:<br />

French Film Production in the Twenties<br />

IN ORDER TO APPRECIATE the specifically feminist import of Germaine<br />

Dulac's work—to understand what distinguishes that work from the<br />

filmmaking of her contemporaries—it is useful to look at the economic<br />

and aesthetic contexts of French film production in the twenties.<br />

French filmmaking of that period is traced with the ambiguous and<br />

contradictory legacy of both its own pioneers and the richly innovative<br />

work of the Americans. In the search for "cinematic specificity" that<br />

preoccupied not only Dulac, but the other major directors (Louis<br />

Delluc, Jean Epstein, Marcel L'Herbier, and Abel Gance) as well, there<br />

is a simultaneous rejection of the theatrical and literary emphases of<br />

the traditional commercial cinema along with an appreciation of both<br />

the technical achievements and the purely visual conception of this<br />

same cinema. Out of this contradiction emerged some of the first<br />

attempts to subvert what came to be called the dominant "Hollywood<br />

model" and to develop the systematic alternatives associated with this<br />

first cinematic avant-garde.<br />

French filmmakers found themselves in an ambivalent situation<br />

regarding the hegemony of American production during the twenties.<br />

On the one hand, they resented the massive importation of American<br />

films that dominated the market and absorbed the film-viewing audi­<br />

ence. Before World War I, the French film industry had led the world<br />

in film production; after the war, which concurrently saw the industry's<br />

collapse, film production suffered from the diversion of capital to the<br />

reconstructed areas of northern France. During the war the two major<br />

French film companies, Pathe and Gaumont, which also controlled the<br />

Dulac in Context / 79<br />

exhibition circuits, started projecting great numbers of American films<br />

in order to draw audiences. The result was that by 1924, 85 percent<br />

of the feature-length films shown in France were American-made.1<br />

At the same time, French filmmakers were fascinated by the techni­<br />

cal innovations and artistic achievements of the American cinema.<br />

Notably, Cecil B. DeMille's 1915 film The Cheat, shown in France in<br />

late summer of 1916, was seen as something of a cinematic revelation:<br />

Dulac said simply, "The Cheat represents the beginning of human<br />

feelings in the cinema." 2<br />

The films of D. W. Griffith and Thomas Ince,<br />

actors like Pearl White, Douglas Fairbanks, and Sessue Hayakawa, and<br />

the comedies of Buster Keaton, Charlie Chaplin, and Mack Sen<strong>net</strong>t<br />

were received enthusiastically. It was American films that marked (he<br />

transition from enthusiastic viewing to actual filmmaking, and in a<br />

short time these films provided emerging filmmakers not only with<br />

inspiration, but also with cinematic models to analyze and emulate. 3<br />

Paradoxically, the attention paid to the American cinema led French<br />

filmmakers toward a national cinema grounded in experimentation,<br />

one that turned away from the commercial imperatives of the Holly­<br />

wood product toward new areas of cinematic expressivity and specifi­<br />

cally filmic construction. In addition, attempts to challenge the domi­<br />

nant cinema were characterized by a situation of double rupture in<br />

relation to commercial cinema in France. At the time, the so-called<br />

"mainstream" cinema consisted of filmmakers like Louis Feuillade and<br />

Henri Pouctal, among others, whose popular serials concentrated on<br />

an economy of action and narrative motivation, leaving little room<br />

for stylistic elaboration or technical virtuosity. In very general terms,<br />

filmmakers like Gance and L'Herbier attempted to create a quality<br />

French art cinema within the context of this popular commercial<br />

cinema by utilizing influences from literature, painting, and music in<br />

films with wide popular appeal. At the same time, Dulac, along with<br />

Delluc and Epstein, concerned herself with defining the essence of<br />

cinema, concentrating on the plastic rhythms of montage. It is in this<br />

sense that all five of these filmmakers have been called the First Avant-<br />

Garde, particularly when their work is seen in relation to the films of<br />

the Dadaists and the Surrealists (René Clair and Luis Bunuel, for<br />

example), as well as to films by those filmmakers interested in more<br />

purely formal or graphic concerns, such as Hans Richter, Vicking<br />

Eggeling, and Henri Chomette.<br />

In his highly interesting, if idiosyncratic history of the French cinematic<br />

avant-garde, En marge du cinema francais, 4<br />

Jacques B. Brunius<br />

begins his discussion with a clarification of terminology. Brunius feels<br />

that a general confusion of the terms experimental, abstract, pure, total


80 / To Desire Differently<br />

(integral), and avant-garde has allowed them to be used interchangeably<br />

while they all describe very particular—if in some sense similar—<br />

approaches to the cinema. All of these types of production, of course,<br />

are seen in a position of marginality in relation to the dominant com­<br />

mercial cinema.<br />

Experimental cinema, a term used particularly in the United States<br />

and England, refers to everything outside of ordinary commercial<br />

production and is characterized by an orientation toward research and<br />

experimentation. Brunius points out that once this kind of cinematic<br />

research is successful, it runs the risk of becoming standard fare,<br />

stereotyped and imitated by those who lack the spirit of exploration.<br />

He also specifies that this type of experimentation is primarily for<br />

those interested in it for the sake of experiment. On the other hand,<br />

pure cinema emphasizes the rhythmic possibilities of the cinema, aban­<br />

doning representational forms, actors, and decors for the pure play<br />

of light and movement. Henri Chomette's Jeux des reflets et de la vitesse<br />

(which worked with moving light reflected on a crystal, and images of<br />

the Metro and Bateau-Mouches in negative and accelerated motion)<br />

and Cinq minutes de cinéma pur are cited as examples. It is this type of<br />

filmmaking that Dulac's later "symphonic poems" represent as well.<br />

Eggeling's Symphonie diagonale and Ruttmann's Les Quatre études exem­<br />

plify the work of abstract cinema by taking the interest in nonrepresen-<br />

tation even farther in the realm of graphics.<br />

Brunius is harshest on the loose usage of the term avant-garde, which<br />

he dismisses as so many "ill-bred pedants" who populate "avant-garde<br />

boutiques." For him, the avant-garde must abandon a fascination with<br />

gratuitous novelty and the style of the day in order to seek new meth­<br />

ods for expressing truly original thoughts. In this—almost in spite of<br />

himself—he is quite close to Dulac's formulation in her 1932 article<br />

"Le Cinéma d'avant-garde." She sees the term avant-garde as applying<br />

to any film that strives to "renew the expressive possibilities of image<br />

and sound, breaking with established tradition in order to search out,<br />

in the domain which is strictly visual and auditory, new emotional<br />

chords." 5<br />

For Dulac then, the avant-garde cinema does not simply<br />

attempt to appeal to large audiences through clever artificial tricks<br />

and devices, for, in the double movement characteristic of her think­<br />

ing, this cinema is at once profoundly personal (internal) and signifi­<br />

cantly social (external). It is, in her words, both more egotistical and<br />

more altruistic than films of superficial innovation: "Egotistical because<br />

it is the personal manifestation of a pure thought; altruistic because it<br />

is only interested in progress."6 Beneath the sometimes inaccessible<br />

surface of a truly avant-garde film are the seeds of discoveries that<br />

Dulac in Context / 81<br />

suggest the cinematic form of the future. It is in this sense that the<br />

avant-garde both critiques the present and anticipates the future. As<br />

such, avant-garde cinema, in Dulac's formulation, becomes undeniably<br />

political in its suggestion of new cinematic forms to describe a new<br />

social reality. The feminist implications of this kind of thinking are<br />

far-reaching, for in positing alternative structures of seeing, Dulac<br />

implies the necessity of social transformation as well. Her "new emo­<br />

tional chords," then, can be understood as another discourse of desire,<br />

a way of conceptualizing "otherwise," for it is thus at the level of<br />

cinematic language that true social change can be conceived.<br />

Regardless of the shades of difference in the terminology used to<br />

describe various aspects of the cinematic avant-garde, the intellectual<br />

and artistic ferment of France in the twenties created a situation in<br />

which polemics about film and its modernist context thrived. This<br />

produced Impressionist. Dadaist, Cubist, and Surrealist experiments,<br />

all of which conceived of film as an art whose specific nature was visual,<br />

and all of which took various positions in relation to the narrative,<br />

fictional component of the art. This led to an emphasis on the visual<br />

image, on mise-en-scéne, on montage, and on technical devices of<br />

lighting and camerawork as opposed to what was conceived of as the<br />

narrative linearity of the literary or theatrical commercial cinema. The<br />

cinematic avant-garde thus self-consciously defined itself in opposition<br />

to mainstream narrative cinema.<br />

It is often the case that the formation of an art cinema (that is, film<br />

production-distribution-exhibition circuits on the margins of domi­<br />

nant commercial cinema, usually characterized by a high degree of<br />

experimentation, and often surrounded by polemics on the specific<br />

nature of the medium) coincides with the development of national<br />

cinemas. Traditionally, this convergence has come about in terms of<br />

a mutual response to the domination of domestic markets by foreign—<br />

primarily American—films. This is particularly true of French cinema<br />

of the twenties, whose rallying cry, as has already been noted, crystal­<br />

lized on the masthead of Delluc's journal Cinéa: "The French cinema<br />

must be cinema; the French cinema must be French." In very general<br />

terms, French film production of the twenties can be identified by an<br />

emphasis on visual style (which can be seen to highlight a personal<br />

artistic vision in reaction to the more homogenized institutional specta­<br />

cle), an exploration of subjective or internal elements of character<br />

elaboration (as opposed to the emphasis on dramatic action), and a<br />

concern with the spectator-screen relationship conceived in philosoph­<br />

ical or aesthetic terms (as opposed to a spectator-screen relationship<br />

understood simply in terms of consumption). Thus, although none of


82 / To Desire Differently<br />

these characteristics might be recognized as specifically nationalistic, a<br />

field of artistic endeavor generated in opposition to the foreign model<br />

unites both national and artistic claims of this cinema.<br />

The First Avant-Garde thus functioned in the maimer of any politi­<br />

cal opposition force—it assumed a role of critical negation. Activity<br />

crystallized around three major areas of endeavor: the creation of a<br />

field of critical inquiry and appraisal through the development of film<br />

criticism in magazines and specialized journals; the establishment of<br />

widespread viewing availability and the creation of an audience inter­<br />

ested in cinematic experimentation through the founding of art the­<br />

aters, ciné-clubs, and noncommercial distribution circuits; and the<br />

development of a cinematic avant-garde through increased filmmak­<br />

ing and theoretical activity, this often accompanied by researches in<br />

style and technique and by open forums for the theoretical elaboration<br />

of these researches.<br />

Film Journals<br />

Although there were many industry trade journals throughout the<br />

twenties, the period saw the emergence of a new kind of film journal<br />

in France, one geared to nonprofessional audiences and committed to<br />

the exploration and elaboration of the cinema's artistic possibilities.<br />

Dulac, who along with Ricciotto Canudo, Jean Tedesco, and Louis<br />

Delluc, was a major figure in the film journal movement, appraised<br />

such critical activity: "In the current state of cinematography, the work<br />

of criticism, analysis, and polemical exchange has as much productive<br />

value as the films themselves. I would even go so far as to say they<br />

have more value. . . . They direct the cinema toward a specific goal,<br />

revealing its ideal form, an image of its perfection. ..."7<br />

With a few important exceptions, such as Ricciotto Canudo's "Manifesto<br />

des sept arts," published in Paris in March of 1911, 8<br />

Abel Gance's<br />

"Qu'est-ce que le cinématographe? Un sixième art," appearing in the<br />

trade magazine Ciné-journal in 1912,9 film reviews by Maurice Raynal<br />

in the avant-garde monthly Les Soirées de Paris, and a few enthusiastic<br />

commentaries on the cinema by Guillaume Apollinaire, there was<br />

relatively little of what could be called actual film criticism before<br />

World War I. However, slowly during the course of the war, and then<br />

finally at its end, the situation changed quite radically. A body of "film<br />

criticism" in the form of columns in daily newspapers (for example,<br />

L'Oeuvre, Le Journal, Paris-Midi, L'Intransigeant) or articles written by<br />

such figures in the literary world as Guillaume Apollinaire, Blaise<br />

Cendrars, Robert Desnos, Louis Aragon, Max Jacob, Colette, Jean<br />

Dulac in Context / 83<br />

Cocteau, and Philippe Soupault began to develop. At the same time,<br />

specialized journals emerged that were concerned with theoretical and<br />

aesthetic issues.<br />

The weekly journal Le Film, founded in February of 1914 by its<br />

publisher Henri Diamant-Berger, was the first large magazine devoted<br />

entirely to the cinema. When Louis Delluc was appointed as editor-inchief<br />

in 1917, he began the work of establishing an indigenous French<br />

film culture, informing his articles on the cinema with appraisals of its<br />

aesthetic potential, encouraging polemics around the specific nature<br />

and possibilities of the medium, and supporting the work of young<br />

filmmakers like Dulac, Gance, and L'Herbier. Delluc changed the<br />

format of the magazine and began soliciting articles from scriptwriters<br />

and directors (Dulac, Gance, and L'Herbier all had articles in Le Film)<br />

along with the work of artists and poets. Apollinaire's "Avant le cinema,"<br />

as well as Aragon's first published poem, "Chariot sentimental,"<br />

and his seminal article asserting that film was the art of modern life,<br />

"Du Decor," all appeared in Le Film.<br />

The same ambivalent relation toward American film that characterized<br />

the general cultural scene in France—wild enthusiasm tempered<br />

by resistance to its dominance—was present in Le Film. Delluc's first<br />

piece for Le Film was an enthusiastic review of Thomas lnce's 1916<br />

film Home, which contained references to all of Ince's other films seen<br />

in France, along with William S. Hart's The Aryan. What impressed<br />

Delluc most about the American films was their sense of vitality, naturalness,<br />

and spontaneity. Next to the stiffness of acting and gesture of<br />

the contemporary Film d'Art productions, for example, American<br />

films virtually radiated with life, generating a surplus of realism when<br />

placed against the stale artificiality of the commercial French product.<br />

At the same time, Le Film was militantly nationalistic, encouraging<br />

the work of new French filmmakers in the face of what was recognized<br />

as the massive threat of foreign competition. In the editorial commentary<br />

that prefaced an article by Dulac entitled "Mise en scène,"10elluc<br />

notes that in France there are a handful of new directors whose work<br />

is "animated with a new vitality," concluding, in reference to Dulac's<br />

Ames de fous, that "we can expect quite a bit from French talents, when<br />

they are French in this way." In the article itself Dulac argues that<br />

the cinema can take its place among "the superior forms of artistic<br />

expression" once it is seen on its own terms and not as a poor relation<br />

of the theater. Exclaiming "Oh! The Americans have shaken us up a<br />

bit!" she confidently predicts, "When we've understood that the cinema<br />

is an artform, a French artform, . . . which can expand and affirm<br />

the great reputation of our literature in the world, reestablish the


84 / To Desire Differently<br />

uncontested superiority of our taste, and defend our culture, we'll have<br />

achieved our real goal." Although perhaps a little excessive in its<br />

chauvinism, Dulac's formulation is no<strong>net</strong>heless significant of the association<br />

of aesthetics and nationalism characteristic of film activity of<br />

the time.<br />

In 1920, Delluc and another young film critic, Léon Moussinac,<br />

started Le Journal du ciné-club as an organ of information serving the<br />

burgeoning French film culture. In addition to listings, film reviews,<br />

and articles on other forms of popular entertainment such as vaudeville<br />

and the music hall, it contained historical and biographical information,<br />

as well as articles by film stars and directors. Also during this<br />

time (starting in 1918) Delluc wrote film criticism for the daily Paris-<br />

Midi.<br />

In May of 1921, Delluc founded Cinéa (he had left Le Journal du<br />

ciné-club after sixteen issues), a major weekly film journal that he edited<br />

until December 1922. It was on the masthead of issue number 45<br />

(March 17, 1922) that Delluc placed his famous slogan calling for<br />

national and cinematic specificity. In the interests of extending theoretical<br />

and aesthetic debate around French film by removing it from its<br />

more commercial context and reinforcing the artistic and intellectual<br />

components of film writing, Delluc included articles and interviews<br />

with those whom he felt were pointing the way for French cinema of<br />

the future—actors Jacque Catelain, Ivan Mosjoukine, Eve Francis,<br />

and of course the filmmakers Dulac, Gance, L'Herbier, and Epstein.<br />

Attention was also paid to avant-garde activities in the other arts in<br />

France in the form of articles discussing such things as Cocteau's Les<br />

Mariés de la Tour Eiffel and the Ballet Suédois production of Canudo's<br />

Skating Rink.<br />

While Ciné-pour-tous (1919) came out bimonthly, Cinémagazine (begun<br />

in 1921) published complete transcripts of lectures given at the<br />

specialized theaters and ciné-clubs (in particular, Germaine Dulac's<br />

series of talks around The Smiling Mme Beudet, and her "workshops"<br />

illustrated with short fragments from individual films), and also conducted<br />

polls and inquiries with filmmakers and critics. In November<br />

1923, Cinéa and Ciné-pour-tous merged to form a new bimonthly film<br />

journal under the editorship of Jean Tedesco. Cinéa-Ciné-pour-tous<br />

then carried the banner of sophisticated and intellectual film studies<br />

through the remainder of the twenties, It aimed at a more cultured<br />

audience than either of its predecessors, focusing on such aesthetic<br />

debates as the question of a cinematic avant-garde, the issues surrounding<br />

the adequacy of the musical analogy and the necessity of<br />

intertitles, and the polemic raised by the notion of "pure cinema." This<br />

Dulac in Context / 85<br />

latter raged in a series of articles throughout 192(5, which included<br />

such titles as Pierre Porte's "Une sensation nouvelle" (number 64, July<br />

1) and "Le Cinéma, art objectif ou subjectif?" (number 69, September<br />

15), Henri Fescourt and Jean-Louis Bouquet's "Sensations ou sentiments?"<br />

(number 66, July 31), Jacques Brunius' "Musique ou cinéma?"<br />

(number 68, September 1), Henri Chomette's "Cinéma pur, art naissant,"<br />

and Paul Ramain's "A La Recherche de l'émotion vraie" (both<br />

number 71, October 15). It was a debate that carried over into the<br />

single issue of Dulac'sjournal Schémas, where many of the same authors<br />

contributed articles that further elaborated their positions.<br />

Cinéa-Ciné-pour-tous also included articles by the French filmmakers<br />

whom Delluc had championed at the outset of their careers, now firmly<br />

established as the innovators of the French cinematic avant-garde.<br />

Several important texts of Impressionist film theory by its practitioners<br />

thus appeared in this journal, among them: Dulac's "Le Cinéma, art<br />

des nuances spirituelles" (number 28, January 1, 1925), Gance's "Le<br />

Cinéma, c'est la musique de la lumière" (number 3, December 15,<br />

1923), Epstein's "Pour une avant-garde nouvelle" (number 29, January<br />

15, 1925) and "L'Objectif lui-même" (number 53, January 15, 1926),<br />

and two minor articles by L'Herbier. In an interview some forty years<br />

after this period, L'Herbier commented on the crucial nature of the<br />

activity of critical writing undertaken by these filmmakers: "Dulac,<br />

Epstein, Delluc, myself—we did not at all share the same aesthetic<br />

positions. But there was a point of communion between us: the search<br />

for that famous 'specificity.' On that point we all agreed, without any<br />

possible dissent. Another point in common was the fact that we all<br />

wrote a great deal, in magazines and journals, what we thought about<br />

the cinema: we needed to clarify, on paper, the ways in which we<br />

conceived cinematic art."11<br />

To balance this heavy emphasis on theory and aesthetics, Cinéa-Cinépour-tous<br />

published detailed weekly listings of new films, including<br />

specific production information, as well as articles explaining cinematic<br />

procedures for amateurs, and a series entitled "Les Cinéastes," which<br />

examined the work of filmmakers both foreign and domestic. The<br />

journal also ran an extensive interview with Gance after the release of<br />

La Roue, and seven production articles on Napoléon.<br />

Thus by the end of the decade, a significant body of film writing<br />

had been developed, to the extent that by 1929, Le Tout cinéma could<br />

estimate that there were thirty-eight specialized film journals, counting<br />

trade publications, in Paris. 12<br />

In addition, regular film review columns<br />

had become widespread in French daily newspapers. Therefore, a<br />

context for writing seriously and critically about the cinema had been


86 / To Desire Differently<br />

created; an ongoing awareness of contemporary film culture was established<br />

and the formulation of a specifically cinematic aesthetic was<br />

encouraged. Dulac's prolific film-writing activity is due in no small part<br />

to this productive cultural context, and the reciprocity between theory<br />

and practice so important to feminist thinking finds its specific historical<br />

roots in this critical milieu as well.<br />

Film Culture<br />

In addition to the development of a critical practice of writing about<br />

the cinema, the establishment of a serious film culture in France was<br />

also due to the creation of ciné-clubs and specialized theaters. These<br />

alternative, noncommercial viewing situations stimulated an independent<br />

film production and exhibition sector distinct from the mainstream<br />

commercial cinema. This enabled the diffusion of new ideas<br />

to a wider audience, an audience often open to experimentation and<br />

energetically interested in aesthetic issues. The ciné-clubs [film societies]<br />

promoted the same French, German, Swedish, and American<br />

films as did the journals, but they added something—they provided<br />

the element of active participation from the audience by stimulating<br />

discussions, organizing debates and forums, and coordinating lecture<br />

series. They also provided the opportunity for short, noncommercial<br />

films of an experimental nature to be viewed by an audience flexible<br />

enough to appreciate their experimental status. As previously noted,<br />

Germaine Dulac was a key figure in the ciné-club movement, in part<br />

because she felt that these film societies provided the audience most<br />

receptive to experimentation. In the educating tone characteristic of<br />

her film lectures, she used these opportunities to increase appreciation<br />

of avant-garde films: "An experimental film [film d'essai] is not necessarily<br />

a good film. Realized with haphazard means, it is often less perfect<br />

than films shown on the regular circuits, but it always contains some<br />

new principle and spirited researches worthy of being encouraged and<br />

retained."<br />

Louis Delluc initiated the idea of ciné-clubs with his publication of<br />

the Journal du ciné-club (it was also he who coined the term cinéaste), but<br />

Ricciotto Canudo, along with Henri Fescourt and Bernard Deschamps,<br />

actually founded the first regularly functioning group of this kind.<br />

The Club des Amis du Septième Art (C.A.S.A.) had its first official<br />

meeting on April 22, 1921. Dulac describes the alternative status of<br />

ciné-clubs in her precise definition: "A ciné-club is a group of spectators<br />

who, without scorning those classic or popular works offered by the<br />

official circuits in commercial theaters, are interested in learning about<br />

Dulac in Context / 87<br />

and encouraging the technical and artistic progress of avant-garde<br />

films and films of quality, by means of special screenings at irregular<br />

intervals. . . . In contrast to the audience of commercial theaters, which<br />

is careful to expect the pleasure of known quantities each evening,<br />

the audience of ciné-clubs, constantly on the watch, encourages and<br />

commends new endeavors. . . . " 14<br />

Dulac sees the ciné-club's function of encouraging critical reception<br />

of filmmakers' work as highly important, both to the evolution of the<br />

art of the cinema, and to the development of a sophisticated audience.<br />

However, she is careful to deny an elitist conception of this audience,<br />

noting the cinema's peculiar combination of aesthetic sophistication<br />

and mass popular appeal. If the ciné-club functions to proselytize and<br />

educate about the cinema, it must also be aware of the needs of the<br />

audience it seeks to "convert." "Certainly we'must not divide the<br />

cinema into an exceptional class and a commercial class. A popular art<br />

[the cinema] must reach both the general public and the elite."15<br />

Starting in the mid-twenties, specialized theaters represented another<br />

form of alternative film exhibition, and in some cases they provided<br />

an alternative financial base for experimental film production<br />

as well. Before 1924, Paris did not have a single theater exclusively<br />

showing films of special artistic interest; this was the area taken up<br />

by the independent ciné-clubs and individual special screenings. On<br />

November 14, 1924, Jean Tedesco opened the Vieux-Colombier in<br />

order to show French and foreign films of precisely this kind. Dulac<br />

points out that Tedesco was the first major exhibitor to envision the<br />

need for a specialized distribution sector in order to show films that<br />

either could not obtain commercial distribution or were not commercial<br />

enough to maintain mainstream audiences. 16<br />

Between 1913 and 1924 Jacques Copeau had made the Vieux-<br />

Colombier one of the most famous showcases in Paris for dramatic<br />

avant-garde theatrical productions. When Tedesco took it over for<br />

film exhibition, he carried this interest in the artistic avant-garde over<br />

to film (both production and exhibition). He premiered Dmitri Kirsanov's<br />

Mémlmontant (made entirely free of studio economics) and Jean<br />

Renoir's La Petite marchande d'allumettes (commissioned and partially<br />

directed by Tedesco, with interiors shot in the theater's attic). Screenings<br />

of independent films, often shorter than regular features because<br />

of the smaller amount of money invested in their production, included<br />

all of Dulac's later short "visual poems" and Jean Epstein's Photogénies—short<br />

cinematic "documents" commissioned by Tedesco and dismantled<br />

after the screening. In addition, in 1925 the theater cosponsored<br />

a series of conferences with Le Ciné-Club de France and (he


88 / To Desire Differently<br />

important literary journal Les Cahiers du mois, at which filmmakers and<br />

critics gave lectures accompanied by screenings. Dulac's "Les Esthétiques,<br />

les entraves: La Cinégraphie intégrale" is the text of one such<br />

lecture; Epstein's "Pour une avant-garde nouvelle" is another.<br />

On January 21, 192(3, Armand Tallier and Mlle L. Myrga opened<br />

the Studio des Ursulines with the following statement of purpose: "We<br />

propose to recruit our public from among the best writers, artists,<br />

and intellectuals of the Latin Quarter, and from among the growing<br />

number of people who have been driven away from the movie theaters<br />

due to the poverty of existing films. Our program will be composed of<br />

French and foreign films of quality which represent diverse tendencies<br />

and schools: everything which represents originality, value, effort will<br />

find a place on our screen." 17<br />

Some of the films shown at this theater,<br />

which had also previously served the theatrical avant-garde (Charles<br />

Dullin's "atelier" ensemble was based there), are evidence of the Ursulines'<br />

eclectic programming, which included both commercial American<br />

and foreign films with works of the cinematic avant-garde: James<br />

Cruze's Jazz, Howard Hawks's A Girl in Every Port (with Louise Brooks),<br />

Stroheim's Greed, German classics such as The Joyless Street and The Blue<br />

Angel, Man Ray's Emak Bakia and L'Etoile de mer, Epstein's La Glace à<br />

trois faces, Cavalcanti's Rien que les heures, and of course, Dulac's and<br />

Artaud's The Seashell and the Clergyman.<br />

There was a constant effort, especially on the part of Dulac, to<br />

integrate this particularized audience into the larger context of the<br />

general cinema-viewing public. Continually maintaining that the goal<br />

of the avant-garde was to seek out new modes of expression that could<br />

expand the parameters of cinematic thought, she worked consistently<br />

to bring the audience into a relation of discovery compatible with her<br />

own excitement for the possibilities of the cinema. Avant-garde film<br />

work thus had a dual aim: to enrich the visual language and style of the<br />

cinema while at the same time educating mass tastes. Dulac therefore<br />

insisted on the educational function of agitational work: "To bring<br />

together those works of the screen possessing an intrinsic cinematographic<br />

value, in order to study them and to make them appreciated<br />

by the general public which ordinarily might scorn them through lack<br />

of comprehension." 18<br />

In her emphasis on the educational function of<br />

certain types of film exhibition, then, Dulac introduces a conception of<br />

cultural production which contrasts with the notion of film as aesthetic<br />

object. Avant-garde activity is seen in a social context rather than as<br />

the product of ivory-tower experimentation, and it is in this sense that<br />

the ciné-club and alternative screening activities intersect with the<br />

Dulac in Context / 89<br />

works themselves in a reciprocal meshwork which can be understood<br />

as the "text" of culture.<br />

Film Practice<br />

The creation of a film culture in France in the twenties, attuned<br />

to aesthetic issues and enthusiastically receptive to experimentation,<br />

provided a fertile context for the theoretical and practical explorations<br />

of Dulac and her contemporaries, Gance, L'Herbier, Delluc, and Epstein.<br />

These filmmakers are often designated as Impressionists because<br />

of their common interest in the cinematic rendering of subjectivity<br />

through the exploitation of the expressive possibilities of film. While<br />

serious debate about the accuracy of such a title continues, it is no<strong>net</strong>heless<br />

true that there exist between these filmmakers certain similarities<br />

in their work and aesthetic formulations. In addition, they all<br />

conceived of their work as being in opposition to established film<br />

practice of the time, and all were mutually supportive in encouraging<br />

the aesthetic advancement of the cinema as an autonomous art form.<br />

Dulac employs the term and provides a description in an essay<br />

written for L´Art cinématographique in 1927; she repeats her definition,<br />

in slightly modified form, five years later in "Le Cinéma d'avantgarde."<br />

Then came the period of the psychological and impressionist film. It seemed<br />

frivolous to place a character in a given situation without pe<strong>net</strong>rating the<br />

secret domain of his [or her] interior life, and the actor's playing became<br />

complemented by the play of his [or her] thoughts, of visualized feelings.'19<br />

Once the description of the multiple and contradictory interior impressions<br />

(which occur in the course of an action) was joined to the specific facts of<br />

the drama—the facts no longer existing in themselves, but becoming the<br />

consequence of a moral state—a duality imperceptibly intervened which, in<br />

order to remain harmonious, adapted itself to the rhythmic cadence, to the<br />

dynamism, and to the tempo of the images. 20<br />

Toward this end of cinematically rendering the life of the mind and<br />

psychological states of the characters, the Impressionist filmmakers<br />

employed a wide variety of cinematic devices. From camera techniques<br />

(prisms, distorting lenses, masks, unusual camera angles and focal<br />

lengths), through technical devices (dissolves, punctuating fades, softfocus,<br />

multiple superimpositions, and double exposures), to experiments<br />

with rhythm and motion (both fast and slow motion, accelerated<br />

montage, and multiple repetitions) and the exploitation of other pa-


90 / To Desire Differently<br />

rameters in film (large grain film stocks, dramatic lighting effects, and<br />

new techniques of make-up and gesture), a battery of experimental<br />

techniques was devised that became the stylistic hallmark of Impressionist<br />

filmmaking.<br />

The "duality" that was "adapted ... to the rhythmic cadence ... of<br />

the image" enables Dulac to see this work as a prelude to abstract<br />

filmmaking, a practice of cinema which rejects referentiality (and the<br />

potential surplus realism of the filmed image) in favor of the more<br />

cinematically "pure" properites of light, rhythm, and movement. "Imperceptibly,<br />

narrative storytelling and the actor's performance lost<br />

their isolated value in favor of a broad orchestration of shots, rhythms,<br />

framings, angles, lighting, proportions, contrasts and harmonies of<br />

the images." 21<br />

She expands on this by means of the musical analogy,<br />

equating the filmmaker and composer in their artistic efforts: "Just as<br />

the musician works with the rhythm and sonorities of the musical<br />

phrase, the cinéaste began to work with the rhythm and sonorities of<br />

the image." 22<br />

In this formulation, cinematic images take on an "emotive<br />

value" in some way related to their plastic composition and the rhythmic<br />

relations between them; meaning is generated by the properties<br />

of the images themselves, "without the aid of the [written] text."<br />

For Dulac, however, this cinematic abstraction does not necessarily<br />

mean the total denial of humanistic concerns. Rather, in a pre-semiotic<br />

grasp of the interrelations of form and signification, she posits an early<br />

formulation of the cinematic signifier. "In sum, the avant-garde has<br />

provided the abstract research and manifestation of pure thought and<br />

technique later applied to more clearly human films. It not only posited<br />

the foundations of screen dramaturgy, but discovered and disseminated<br />

all of the expressive possibilities contained within the camera<br />

lens." 23<br />

In other words, Dulac sees all of the work of experimentation in the<br />

cinema—from the films of the Impressionists to the more abstract<br />

work of the adherents of "pure cinema"—as having a signifying function.<br />

Insisting on the aesthetic qualities inherent in the cinema at a<br />

time when the new medium was obliged to assert its difference from<br />

other forms of popular entertainment, she concludes: "Whether partisans<br />

of lyrical, poetic, psychological or pure cinema, all of these schools<br />

are valid. Cinematographic expression is not single, but multiple. Will<br />

it not be the conjunction of all these diversities of its form, carried to<br />

their extreme degree, which will make the cinema a very great art?" 24<br />

It is critical that the work of the five Impressionists, this first cinematic<br />

avant-garde, be understood as much more than stylistic renovation<br />

or technical advancement of the medium. As the film scholar<br />

Dulac in Context / 91<br />

Bernard Eisenschitz points out, each film that they made was conceived<br />

as "a struggle to define a new artistic practice" 25<br />

—a struggle that was<br />

fundamentally in opposition to the dominant commercial cinema, both<br />

French and American, of the time. In their effort to put cinema on<br />

the same level as the other arts, these filmmakers were also agitating<br />

for its status as a specific, autonomous practice with its own history,<br />

evolution, conventions, and procedures. The keynote of the dominant<br />

cinema as it emerged in Hollywood is found in the particular kind of<br />

effect produced in the cinema spectator. The impression of a continuous<br />

and homogeneous spatial unity, the centrality of the perceiving<br />

subject, and the reinforcement of the reality of depicted events all<br />

contribute to the production of this effect, which makes the spectator<br />

a credulous participant in the cinematic fiction. The research into<br />

cinematic signification carried on by the Impressionist filmmakers—<br />

whether this was on the level of the intrinsic properties of the filmic<br />

image itself or on the level of types of narrative organization through<br />

rhythmic montage constructions—represents one of the earliest attempts<br />

to develop an alternative type of meaning-production in the<br />

cinema.<br />

In these researches, the reproduction of an illusory world, irreducibly<br />

tied to its referent, ceased being of prime importance, while the<br />

status of filmic images as signs and their organization into a discursive<br />

structure became foregrounded. Eisenschitz formulates this in similar<br />

terms when he describes the work of Epstein (L'Auberge rouge. La<br />

Glace a trois faces), Gance (J'Accuse, Napoleon, La Roue), and L'Herbier<br />

(L´Argent): "One already finds in their work the destruction of the<br />

taboo of the image as a transparent, total, and inviolable reflection of<br />

the world and a construction of a filmic space-time dimension (un<br />

espace-temps du film)." 26<br />

In this light, the proliferation of visual experiments<br />

associated with Impressionist filmmaking—and often used as<br />

evidence of an aestheticizing sensibility—stands among the first serious<br />

theoretical reflections on the cinema in its history.<br />

Cast in ideological terms, this construction of a "filmic space-time<br />

dimension" indicated the way toward a radical disruption of the spatial<br />

and temporal cohesion offered by the dominant cinema. Conventionally,<br />

it is this cohesion which provides the viewer with the illusion of a<br />

unified fictional space which can be pe<strong>net</strong>rated and "experienced."<br />

Absolutely necessary for the production of this illusion is the strongest<br />

possible coincidence between narrative (diegetic) motivation for shot<br />

changes and their formal or rhythmic potentialities. Any attempt to<br />

highlight the fragmentary and constructed nature of the cinema by<br />

exploiting the plastic and rhythmic elements of composition can be


92 / To Desire Differently<br />

seen as an effort to disrupt the work of narrative unity and spatial<br />

coherence. This can operate on many different levels, and the Impressionist<br />

filmmakers, in differing ways, explored every formal permutation.<br />

In all of their experiments with camera distance and angle, with<br />

rhythmic editing, and with technical devices, it is possible to see a<br />

wedge being driven between narrative referentiality and the discursive<br />

organization of the film. Thus a new signifying dimension became<br />

part of filmic discourse, the plastic emphasis on film's fragmentary<br />

nature suggesting a multiplicity of effects instead of a single expressive<br />

meaning. Therefore, although one might interpret the Impressionists'<br />

efforts to increase the viewer's participation in the film as the imposition<br />

of a univocal meaning, the fact remains that their films have an<br />

undeniable formal and material dynamism, an explosion of signification<br />

fundamental to establishing the specificity of cinematic language.<br />

Thus in the work of the First Avant-Garde can be found an early<br />

form of cinematic writing, what Dulac refers to as "cinêgraphié" and<br />

contemporary theory calls the meaning-production process of the filmtext.<br />

Henri Langlois says as much in his critical assessment: "They<br />

were already writing films with the camera; they had already achieved<br />

a form of cinematic language. Through their research with the contrasts<br />

of black and white, through the meaning they conferred on<br />

each image according to their choice of camera angle, through their<br />

intertwining of surfaces, volumes, and temporal variations by means<br />

of montage, through an ever-increasing fragmentation of shots and<br />

their simplification, our avant-garde was leading directly to the cinematographic<br />

hieroglyph, to this ideographic language on which<br />

Eisenstein would base his work." 27<br />

Dulac is only slightly more concrete when, in an introduction to one<br />

of her illustrated lectures at the Musée Galliera, she refers to "the<br />

expressive procedures of the cinema—the role of different types of<br />

shots and angles, the fade-out, the dissolve, the superimposition, softfocus,<br />

distortions—in sum, the entire syntax of the film." 28<br />

Problems<br />

with the linguistic metaphor aside, this early formulation of the signifying<br />

possibilities of formal structures is basic to the conception of filmic<br />

writing. Going on to discuss the arrangement of individual shots<br />

through editing she says, "You will understand . . . the emotion that a<br />

logical succession of images can provoke . . . the work moves us, therefore,<br />

by means of a purely cinematographic technique." 29<br />

To the extent,<br />

then, that the filmmakers of the First Avant-Garde realized that<br />

the cinema was a "language," they began to tell stories by a sequence<br />

of images alone, an organization without recourse to verbal intertitles<br />

or literary elaboration.<br />

Dulac in Context / 93<br />

The Impressionist propensity for intimate psychological narratives<br />

which permitted the exploration of the life of the mind led to an<br />

effusion of cinematic devices and techniques capable of portraying<br />

memories, flashbacks, dreams, fantasies, and mental states. For all of<br />

the Impressionists, then, the cinema was thus put not in the service of<br />

the "realistic" reproduction of dramatic characters, but rather in the<br />

service of the expression, suggestion, translation, and representation<br />

of emotions, thoughts, and feelings. As Jean Mitry puts it, "The descriptive<br />

image, in some sense, became 'subjectivized.' " 30<br />

In addition to Dulac, both Jean Epstein and Abel Gance are credited<br />

with adding rhythmic editing to the repertoire of subjective techniques.<br />

Gance's La Roue emerged on the scene in 1923; an exciting<br />

crystallization of all of the experimental techniques that had preceded<br />

it, it demonstrated an expressive lyricism that became a hallmark of<br />

French film of the twenties. As Dulac notes, it marked a decisive<br />

turning point in the evolution of cinematographic art. Its use of accelerated<br />

montage techniques to establish a rhythmic, methodically organized<br />

structure paved the way for future experiments and further<br />

definitions of cinematic specificity as movement and rhythm. By basing<br />

his rhythmic editing of La Roue entirely on the metric relations between<br />

the shots, Gance was able to achieve a creation of "pure visual rhythm"<br />

whose "meaning was established on the value of the duration of the<br />

images." 31<br />

In other words, the filmed image's referentiality ceased to<br />

have primary importance, while other meanings, more related to the<br />

plasticity of montage, emerged.<br />

The rapidity of tempo due to shots that became increasingly shorter,<br />

for example, created the sensation of an emotional crescendo. Dulac's<br />

description of this process is fairly precise and wildly enthusiastic:<br />

Abel Gance's La Roue marked a great step forward. In this film, psychology,<br />

gestures, drama all became dependent on a cadence. The characters were<br />

no longer the only important factors in the work, hut objects, machines, the<br />

length of the shots, their composition, their contrast, their framing, their<br />

harmony all play a role. Rails, locomotive, boiler wheels, pressure-gauge,<br />

smoke, tunnels functioned—through images—along with the characters. A<br />

new drama emerged composed of feelings, of raw movements, of unfolding<br />

lines. The conception of the art of movement and of rhythmically organized<br />

images came into its own, as did the expression of "things," magnificently<br />

achieving the visual poem composed of human life-instincts, playing with<br />

both the material and the ineffable. A symphonic poem in which feeling<br />

explodes not in facts, not in acts, but in visual sonorities. 32<br />

It is easy to see how this exciting evidence of the expressive possibilities<br />

of movement and form could lead to the theories of pure cinema, so


94 / To Desire Differently<br />

dear to Dulac, based on rhythmic structures capable of signifying by<br />

themselves. The visual orchestration of signs achieved through the<br />

rapid alternation of shots thus produced a dynamic theory of cinematic<br />

articulation. Rhythmic patterns based on internal (within the shot) and<br />

external (between shots) relations became the foundation of cinematic<br />

composition.<br />

In one way or another, all of the Impressionist filmmakers took, up<br />

researches into the rhythmic potentials of accelerated montage and the<br />

aesthetics of pure movement. But it was Dulac who was to follow this<br />

more consistently toward its logical conclusion of nonreferential signification.<br />

She used a fragment of La Roue (considered the core of the<br />

film, it was entitled La Chanson du rail) for her illustrated talks, thereby<br />

removing it from extraneous narrative and diegetic material in order to<br />

concentrate on the purely aesthetic properties of its accelerated montage<br />

structure. "One can be moved without characters, therefore without<br />

theatrical means: Look at the song of the train-tracks and wheels. A<br />

theme, but no dramatic action. . . . The train-track, a railway of rigid<br />

steel, intertwined, the train-track, far removed from human life, a poem<br />

whose rhymes are moving lines, simple, then multiplied. . . . Then the<br />

wheels, a rhythm, a speed . . . aconnecting-rod whose mechanical movement<br />

follows the rhythm of a heartbeat."33<br />

Dulac used this fragment as evidence of the signifying capacity of<br />

pure form. A profoundly emotional sense of rhythm proved capable of<br />

evoking feelings, thoughts, experiences, without recourse to "the petty<br />

little stories with which the audience too often satisfies itself."34 Through<br />

this kind of formulation, Dulac was positing the metaphoric elaboration of<br />

the fragment as a form of resistance to the powerful drive of narrativity<br />

associated with dominant cinema. She was thus paving the way for the<br />

consideration of the cinema as a sign system in its own right. Arguing<br />

for the artistic autonomy of the cinema she declared: "A real film should<br />

not be capable of simply being 'told,' since it draws its active and emotive<br />

principle uniquely from visual vibrations. Can one 'narrate' a painting?<br />

Can one 'narrate' a sculpture? Certainly not!" 35<br />

This raises the issue of assessing the filmmaking practice of the First<br />

Avant-Garde. While the title "Impressionist" is perhaps reductive,<br />

linking the five filmmakers in a relationship based too much on a strict<br />

interpretation of the content of their films ("subjectivity," "interior<br />

life"), no single name covers the magnitude of their collective contribution<br />

to the history of cinematic language. Differing fundamentally<br />

from what preceded them, they endowed the cinema with a "marvellous<br />

power of formal renovation, which was linked, as well, to a very<br />

Dulac in Context / 95<br />

specific conception of their material." 36<br />

This involved a major recasting<br />

of narrative conceptions—a new formulation of the film's subject matter<br />

conceived visually, in terms of plastic or formal organization. What<br />

emerged was a fundamentally cinematic method of constructing films.<br />

This meant, among other things, that a film could move not by a<br />

linear concatenation of events, as in its literary predecessor, the novel,<br />

but by a "vertical" (to use L'Herbier's term) structure more akin to<br />

poetics. This latter could deploy all of the signifying possibilities of the<br />

cinematic image and its relations, giving filmic discourse a productive<br />

new dimension. The work of the First Avant-Garde thus situated itself<br />

in the space between narrative referentiality and discursive organization,<br />

thereby emphasizing cinema's systematicity—its particular way of<br />

producing meaning through a constant dialectical interaction between<br />

diegetic content and formal structure. No longer considering formal<br />

elements as mere stylistic devices tacked on in the service of narrative<br />

imperatives, the filmmakers of the First Avant-Garde advanced the<br />

understanding of cinematic language, whose fundamental dialectic of<br />

continuity (which bridges the transitions between shots) and discontinuity<br />

(which introduces ruptures at another, formal, level) is at the<br />

core of its meaning-production.<br />

What are the feminist implications of Dulac's contribution to film<br />

language, then, given the general aesthetic context of her time and its<br />

widespread cinematic exploration of subjectivity? Or, to put it another<br />

way, what is the resisting status of her films within a cinematic practice<br />

that had already conceived of itself as oppositional? To arrive at the<br />

precise feminist inflection of Dulac's concern with unconscious signification,<br />

it is necessary to consider her work from the perspective of<br />

feminist theory. It is possible to understand Dulac's move toward<br />

abstraction and the nonreferentiality of the image—her theorization<br />

of "pure cinema"—as an attempt to conceptualize a form of "feminine<br />

cinematic writing" in which the oppressive logic of patriarchal structures<br />

of thought would be bypassed for the more suggestive, multiple,<br />

and varied forms of signification on the connotative level. Dulac's<br />

particular emotional emphasis, her enduring belief in the evocative<br />

power of cinematic technique and the proliferation of meanings implied,<br />

suggests that against the tyranny of hierarchical meaning the<br />

filmic image could counterpose a celebration of flux. Moreover, Dulac's<br />

most incisive researches into processes of signification are cinematically<br />

worked out precisely in terms of figuring "the feminine" and<br />

the specificity of female desire. These issues will be explored in the<br />

following chapter.


96 / To Desire Differently<br />

NOTES<br />

1. Carlton J. H. Hayes, France: A Nation of Patriots (New York: Columbia<br />

University Press, 1930), p. 186. It seems probable that Hayes's (inaccurate)<br />

figure comes from Léon Moussinac, Panoramique du cinéma (Paris: Au Sans<br />

Pareil, 1929), p. 17. Again, Richard Abel's exhaustive and comprehensive<br />

study of the period, French Cinema: The First Wave, 1915-1929 (Princeton:<br />

Princeton University Press, 1984) provides a detailed background. David<br />

Bordwell's French Impressionist Cinema: Film Culture, Film Theory, and Film Style<br />

(New York: Arno Press, 1980), is also useful.<br />

2. Germaine Dulac in Colson-Malleville text (unpublished manuscript of<br />

Dulac's collected writings), chapter 2, "Historique du cinéma: Evolution vers<br />

le cinéma pur," p. 8. All translation from the French are my own unless<br />

otherwise noted.<br />

3. For a highly useful discussion of the Parisian excitement around American<br />

films, see Richard Abel's "The Contribution of the French Literary Avant-<br />

Garde to Film Theory and Criticism (1907-1924)," Cinéma Journal 14:3<br />

(Spring 1975): 18—40, and his more recent article, "On the Threshold of<br />

French Film Theory and Criticism, 1915—1919," Cinema Journal 25:1 (Fall<br />

1985): 12-33.<br />

4. Jacques B. Brunius, En marge du cinéma français (Paris: Editions Arcanes,<br />

Collection Ombres Blanches, 1954).<br />

5. Germaine Dulac, "Le Cinéma d'avant-garde," in Le Cinéma des origines<br />

à nos jours, ed. Henri Fescourt (Paris: Editions du Cygne, 1932), p. 357. An<br />

alternative translation of this article, by Robert Lamberton, can be found in<br />

The Avant-Garde Film: A Reader of Theory and Criticism, ed. P. Adams Sitney<br />

(New York: New York University Press, 1978), pp. 43-48.<br />

(i. Dulac, "Le Cinema d'avant-garde."<br />

7. Germaine Dulac, quoted in Pierre Leprohon, Histoire du cinéma (Paris:<br />

Editions du Cerf, 1961), p. 64.<br />

8. Reprinted in Ricciotto Canudo, L'Usine aux images (Geneva: Office Centrale<br />

d'Edition, 1927), pp. 5-8.<br />

9. Reprinted in Marcel L'Herbier, éd., L'Intelligence du cinématographe,<br />

(Paris: Editions Corréa, 1946), pp. 91-92.<br />

10. Germaine Dulac, "Mise en scène," Le Film, no. 87 (November 12, 1917):<br />

7-9.<br />

11. Marcel L'Herbier, "Autour du cinématographe: Entretien avec Marcel<br />

L'Herbier par Jean-André Fieschi," Les Cahiers du cinéma, no. 202 (June—July<br />

1968): 29.<br />

12. Cited by Bordwell, French Impressionist Cinema, p. 62.<br />

13. Colson-Malleville text, chapter 10, "Les ciné-clubs," p. 3.<br />

14. Colson-Malleville text, chapter 10, pp. 1, 2.<br />

15. Ibid., p. 2.<br />

16. Dulac, "Le Cinéma d'avant-garde," p. 362.<br />

17. Quoted by Dulac in "Le Cinéma d'avant-garde," p. 362.<br />

18. Colson-Malleville text, chapter 10, p. 1.<br />

Dulac in Context / 97<br />

19. Germaine Dulac, "Les Esthétiques. Les entraves: La Cinégraphie<br />

intégrale," in L'Art cinématographique, vol. 2 (Paris: Alcan, 1927); reprinted in<br />

French in The Literature of the Cinema (New York: Arno Press, 1970), p. 41,<br />

and translated by Stuart Liebman as "The Aesthetics, the Obstacles: Integral<br />

Cinegraphie" in Framework, no. 19 (1982): 6—9.<br />

20. Dulac, "Le Cinéma d'avant-garde," p. 359.<br />

21. Ibid., p. 360. A similar, but less precise, statement can be found in "Les<br />

Esthétiques," p. 45, where Dulac simply refers to "the study of images and<br />

their juxtaposition."<br />

22. Dulac, "Les Esthétiques," p. 45.<br />

23. Dulac, "Le Cinéma d'avant-garde," p. 364.<br />

24. Colson-Malleville text, chapter 10, p. 3.<br />

25. Bernard Eisenschitz:, "Histoires de l'histoire (Deux périodes du cinéma<br />

français: le muet—la génération de 58)," Défense du cinéma français, January<br />

8—March 16, 1975, Maison de la Culture de la Seine Saint-Denis, p. 28.<br />

26. Eisenschitz, "Histoires," p. 28.<br />

27. Henri Langlois, "L'Avant-garde français," Les Cahiers du cinéma, no. 202<br />

(June-July 1968): 17.<br />

28. Germaine Dulac, "Les procédés expressifs du cinématographe," Cinémagazine,<br />

no. 27 (July 4, 1924): 15.<br />

29. Dulac, "Les Procédés," p. 15.<br />

30. Jean Mitry, Le Cinéma expérimental (Histoire et perspectives) (Paris: Editions<br />

Seghers, 1974), p. 67.<br />

31. Mitry, Le Cinéma expérimental, p. 69.<br />

32. Dulac, "Le Cinéma d'avant-garde," p. 360. This passage is similar,<br />

though not identical, to what appears in "Les Esthétiques" on page 43.<br />

33. Germaine Dulac, "Conférence de Mme Germaine Dulac" Cinémagazine,<br />

no. 51 (December 19, 1924): 517. This also appears in L'Art du cinéma, ed.<br />

Pierre Lherminier (Paris: Editions Seghers, 1960), p. 65.<br />

34. Ibid.<br />

35. Germaine Dulac, "Films visuels et anti-visuels," Le Rouge et le noir (July<br />

1928): 39. This can also be found in Lherminier, L'Art du cinéma, p. 70. An<br />

alternate translation, by Stuart Lamberton, can be found in The Avant-Garde<br />

Film, ed. Sitney.<br />

36. Noel Burch and Jean-André Fieschi, "La Première vague," Les Cahiers<br />

du cinéma, no. 202 (June-July 1968): 24.


FOUR<br />

From Fantasy to Structure of the Fantasm:<br />

The Smiling Mme Beudet and The Seashell<br />

and the Clergyman<br />

[U]nconscious ideas are organized into phantasies or imaginary<br />

scenarios to which the instinct becomes fixated and which may be<br />

conceived of as true mises en scène of desire. 1<br />

The cinema is marvellously equipped to express the manifestations of<br />

our thought, of our hearts, of our memories. 2<br />

DISCUSSIONS OF DULAC'S FILMS tend to contrast what are perceived as the<br />

two poles of her work, to compare two conflicting—and consecutive—<br />

cinematic practices. The first is represented by La Souriante Mme Beudet<br />

(The Smiling Mme Beudet, 1923), frequently cited as an outstanding<br />

example of feminist filmmaking because of its exploration of what<br />

would constitute a feminine imaginary. In it, a fairly traditional narrative<br />

sequence is amplified by a whole range of suggestive poetic and<br />

cinematic techniques used to evoke the inner world of the main character,<br />

rendering her fantasies and desires through the cinematic depiction<br />

of mental processes. The other tendency, exemplified by the<br />

violent clash between the sexes depicted through a kind of antinarrative<br />

experimentation bordering on abstraction, is seen in Surrealism's<br />

first film, La Coquille et le clergyman (The Seashell and the Clergyman,<br />

1927). 3<br />

Based on a scenario by Antonin Artaud, the film demonstrates<br />

an astonishing originality in its structure, exploding all myths of character<br />

and plot in an effort to generate the fantasmatic process of<br />

dreaming itself. This use of narrative and its antithesis would seem to<br />

suggest contradictory conceptions of the cinema. However, from the<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 99<br />

standpoint of Dulac's own preoccupation with what constitutes an<br />

alternative language of desire "in the feminine," a remarkable consistency<br />

strongly connects such superficially divergent projects.<br />

Another level of debate contrasts the overt and easily interpreted<br />

feminism of Beudet with what is perceived as the stridently masculine<br />

Surrealist aesthetic of Seashell. For example, in a rather serious instance<br />

of misattribution, an article that pits Dulac-the-feminist against Artaud-the-misogynist<br />

bases its argument on the claim that Artaud had<br />

objected to the film on the grounds that Dulac has used optical tricks<br />

and had "feminized" the script. 4<br />

In fact, Artaud never actually made<br />

either assertion. More specifically, both criticisms were made some<br />

twenty-five years after the release of the film, and five years after<br />

Artaud's death. It was Jacques B. Brunius, in his 1954 book En marge<br />

du cinéma français, who criticized Dulac's film for having "drowned [the<br />

scenario] under a debauch of technical tricks" 5<br />

—a criticism which, it<br />

has been established, was first launched not by Artaud himself, but by<br />

Yvonne Allendy. For the second, infinitely more offensive, criticism,<br />

Ado Kyrou must take credit. In a 1953 assessment of the film that<br />

borders on the hysterical, he states: "The script is very beautiful; filled<br />

with eroticism and fury, it could have been a film in the same class as<br />

Bunuel's L'Age d'or, but Germaine Dulac betrayed the spirit of Artaud<br />

and made a FEMININE film." 6<br />

This misunderstanding about the nature of the debate surrounding<br />

Seashell illustrates, in a fairly graphic way, the pitfalls of a form of<br />

feminist criticism that too readily employs unexamined assumptions<br />

and notions of a "feminist aesthetic." An analysis which shifts its emphasis<br />

from a superficial reading of the content of the films to a<br />

more nuanced understanding of the place of the woman within the<br />

mechanisms of fantasy and desire in the cinema suggests a way to<br />

overcome this problem. Seen from this latter perspective, Dulac's shift<br />

in interest from the representation of fantasy (through the portrayal<br />

of the intensely active mental world of her heroine in Beudet) to the<br />

actual generation of the fantasmatic process (through the seemingly<br />

arbitrary and irrational depiction of those processes themselves in<br />

Seashell) can be understood as an entirely consistent evolution in her<br />

search for a new cinematic language capable of expressing female<br />

desire. Dulac's two films can thus be seen to crystallize certain positions<br />

within her ongoing theoretical research into cinematic language, from<br />

the more explicitly feminist content of Beudet (the dissatisfied housewife<br />

brutalized by an obnoxious husband and a repressive bourgeois<br />

system) to a concentration on the processes of cinematic meaningproduction<br />

in Seashell (the cinema's capacity to materially reproduce


100 / To Desire Differently<br />

the structure and logic of dreams and the unconscious), and eventually<br />

to her concern with pure cinema. At the heart of both films is an interest<br />

in the psychical mechanisms of the unconscious, an exploration of<br />

subjective reality which—whether determined by the specific confines<br />

of fictional characterization or liberated by the unmediated play of the<br />

logic of dreams—is capable of revealing not only productive insights<br />

into our deepest longings, but the structure and function of "femininity"<br />

in its social, psychic, and cinematic contexts, as well.<br />

The Smiling Mme Beudet<br />

The Smiling Mme Beudet depicts the imaginative life of its main character<br />

with a psychological precision previously unseen in the cinema at the<br />

time of its release in 1923. In fact, its slim plot, which concerns an<br />

aborted murder—misread as a suicide attempt—by an unhappy middle-class<br />

housewife, serves merely as a pretext for the visual orchestration<br />

of thoughts, memories, dreams, hallucinations, and fantasies that<br />

constitute Madame Beudet's internal world. The film's unsmiling protagonist,<br />

whose revolt against the stifling constraints of her bourgeois<br />

marriage is demonstrated by a desire for liberation through fantasy,<br />

provides the point of focus for both narrative articulation and spectator<br />

identification. The plot involves two days in the life of this cultured<br />

and sensitive provincial housewife (Germaine Dermoz) and her oppressively<br />

vulgar fabric merchant husband (Arquilliere). One evening,<br />

having found her piano locked by Monsieur Beudet, who is at a<br />

performance of Faust, Madame Beudet loads the gun that her husband—in<br />

a jokingly sadistic parody of suicide—often puts to his head.<br />

The next morning, overcome by guilt, fear, and remorse, she unsuccessfully<br />

tries to empty the chamber before the habitual joke's repetition,<br />

but before she can do so Beudet impulsively aims the gun at his<br />

wife instead. The film climaxes and resolves ironically, as the egotistical<br />

husband mistakenly interprets the loaded gun as his wife's suicide<br />

attempt, and his renewed appreciation of her is matched by Madame<br />

Beudet's disbelieving resignation—and the implied closing off of any<br />

future possibilities for her fertile imaginative world.<br />

Yet it is the very interiority of this world that comprises the majority<br />

of the film's forty minutes. Dulac uses a whole range of experimental<br />

cinematic techniques in order to represent Madame Beudet's dreams<br />

and desires, to render female subjectivity filmically through the metaphoric<br />

figuration of her character's fantasies. Through a battery of<br />

technical devices ranging from dissolves, punctuating fades and irises,<br />

soft-focus and superimpositions to both slowed-down and accelerated<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 101<br />

motion, distorting lenses, camera manipulations, high-contrast distortions,<br />

and unusual angles, Dulac creates a highly charged visual atmosphere<br />

for these mini-scenarios of the fantasmatic. The actual narrative<br />

action of the film, as I've noted, is relatively sparse; it is in the<br />

visual orchestration of Madame Beudet's inner world that Dulac's<br />

prime interest in cinematic experimentation can be found. In her<br />

desire to eliminate those constraints on expression implied by the logic<br />

of narrative causality and of character development through action,<br />

Dulac turned to music as a model for cinematic composition. For her,<br />

the unmediated directness of the visual image could best be conveyed<br />

through a musical form: "Shouldn't the cinema—an art of vision, as<br />

music is an art of hearing—lead us . . . toward the visual idea, made<br />

of movement and of life, toward a conception of an art of the eye<br />

composed of emotional inspiration, evolving in its continuity and attaining,<br />

just as music does, our thoughts and feelings?" 7<br />

Thus for Beudet, Dulac relied upon such musical inspiration in order<br />

to organize the flow of images constituting Madame Beudet's solitary<br />

reveries, her flights of fantasy, and her perceptions of the emotional<br />

prison that enclosed her. Images chosen for their evocative power—<br />

for their ability to suggest a state of mind or feeling—were thus filmed<br />

using technical devices meant to enhance this power or interpret its<br />

effects. These images in turn were organized according to a psychical<br />

and subjective logic rather than one based on dramatic or causal<br />

requirements of the narrative.<br />

This emphasis on feeling led Dulac to call the close-up the "psychological<br />

shot" because of its peculiar ability to materialize "the very<br />

thoughts, souls, emotions, and desires of the characters projected on<br />

the screen." 8<br />

Dulac felt that in this way she was able to bypass the<br />

logical structure of verbal language in order to more profoundly move<br />

and directly touch the spectator by means of a filmic structure based<br />

on visual rhythm.<br />

In a 1928 article entitled "La Musique du silence," Dulac affirmed<br />

the importance of correctly assessing the cinema's fundamental capacity<br />

to visualize feelings. She saw a danger in the traditional cinema's<br />

reliance on precise dramatic action for its structure: "Two actors are<br />

speaking to each other in the course of a scene. A mistake. Only the<br />

silent expressions on their faces will be visual. Alas, in ordinary dramatic<br />

cinema, facts count more than expressions." 9<br />

Dulac felt that<br />

traditional cinema was too literary because, following in the footsteps<br />

of its predecessor, the novel, it developed its action uniquely through<br />

a succession of dramatic situations. For her, the cinema was most<br />

consistent with its expressive and aesthetic potential when it was able


102 / To Desire Differently<br />

to "develop emotively through the image alone. . . . The cinema can<br />

certainly tell a story, but one mustn't forget that the story is nothing.<br />

The story is a surface. The seventh art, the art of the screen, is the<br />

palpable rendering of the depth which extends beneath this surface:<br />

the musical ineffable (l'insaisissable musical)." 10<br />

Yet, although a universalist assumption of consciousness might be<br />

inferred from these formulations, it is not simply a generalized notion<br />

of fantasy that interests Dulac here; clearly, in Beudet, she is concerned<br />

to articulate what might be called a feminine "imaginary," as she makes<br />

the exploration of female subjectivity the very core of her film. For this<br />

reason, the fantasy sequences—organized in each instance by a relay<br />

of mental associations—are anchored in the particulars of the woman<br />

character she creates, a frustrated, imprisoned housewife who longs<br />

for some sort of romantic evasion, Thus a focus on the content of<br />

the representation of fantasy is necessary as Dulac finds metaphoric<br />

equivalents and subjective distortions for each of Madame Beudet's<br />

imaginings. The most complete realization of this filmic rendering of<br />

unconscious processes is found in what can be called the "fantasysolitude"<br />

sequence of the film, a series of seven segments in which<br />

Madame Beudet's fantasies take hold and overpower her in the moments<br />

preceding her decision to load her husband's gun. However,<br />

although this sequence is virtually the longest in the entire film (comprising<br />

roughly one-fifth of its total shots) Dulac is careful to prepare<br />

this cinematic explosion of perception, fantasy, and desire by a number<br />

of shorter subjective sequences, momentary indications of the power<br />

of Madame Beudet's imaginative capacities.<br />

This "prologue" to the fantasy sequence has a trajectory of its own,<br />

for it moves from a purely mental representation of Madame Beudet's<br />

thoughts through a metaphoric image signifying her wish for escape,<br />

to an imagined scenario of desire in which a fantasm of her creation<br />

actually interacts with the space of the room in which the Beudets sit.<br />

This gradation in the type of mental or unconscious operation is<br />

matched by an increase in duration, as each of the three sequences<br />

furl hers the demonstration of Dulac's interest in combining the experimental<br />

techniques of the First Avant-Garde with a cinematic elaboration<br />

of female desire. There is in this progression a movement from<br />

a more conventionally accepted icon of feminine resistance, through<br />

a momentary display of the power of the female imagination, to a<br />

situation which locates the productive capacity to dream (and thereby<br />

enact the possibility of liberation) within the female psyche itself. In<br />

this way the prologue prepares the more extensively developed fantasy<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 103<br />

sequence, whose conclusion to the complex visual chain of associations<br />

results in the ultimate act of resistance, a fantasy of murder.<br />

The first of these "preparatory" sequences is a simple exchange of<br />

two pairs of shots, each representing the Beudets' part in a conversation.<br />

Monsieur Beudet tries to convince his wife to see Faust, and she<br />

replies with a polite shake of her head. A close-up of Beudet singing<br />

(fade to black) is followed by a shot of the opera chorus, while Madame<br />

Beudet's close-up (again, a fade to black) leads into a glowering Mephistopheles,<br />

large in the left foreground, and a resisting Marguerite,<br />

arm stretched out to fend off his intrusion. Although the first of these<br />

has been attributed to Dulac's attempt to give some small measure of<br />

subjectivity to other characters, I maintain, instead, that Dulac's chief<br />

interest is in the subjective experience of her female character and the<br />

possibilities it represents for expressing feminine desire. From this<br />

standpoint, Beudet's shot simply illustrates what he is saying (a silent<br />

film convention), while Madame Beudet's shot—a representation of<br />

her thoughts—is a first indication of the interiority that will control<br />

our identification with her throughout the film.<br />

This is an appropriate preparation for the sequence that follows,<br />

the first demonstration of Madame Beudet's ability to imaginatively<br />

call up an image of something longed-for, and thus a mark of the shift<br />

from a mental image to the representation of a wish. The five shots of<br />

this sequence cluster around a subjective inversion of the reverse-shot<br />

structure, a cinematic figure conventionally used to indicate perceptual<br />

point-of-view. Instead of the traditional alternation of character<br />

seeing/object seen, Dulac gives us a sequence of object-seen/character<br />

seeing/object-fantasized—and thus a transformation from perception to<br />

imagination as a close-up of a car advertisement (for a Sizaire-Berwick)<br />

in a magazine dissolves to a profile close-up of Madame Beudet reading,<br />

and its fade to black then opens on a shot of the miniature car<br />

gliding across a background of clouds. The sequence ends on an<br />

extreme close-up of Madame Beudet's eyes (reminiscent of a subsequent<br />

use of this ethereal and haunting shot in Seashell, to which I will<br />

return), as the frame is filled with eyes that close—in resignation or in<br />

satisfaction. This momentary insertion of two antinaturalistic shots<br />

within the context of the narrative development connects Dulac's interest<br />

in mental processes with her related belief in the close-up as a<br />

powerfully evocative expressive tool. But more important, this first<br />

indication of Madame Beudet's fantasmatic capacity to escape what<br />

she cannot leave in reality reflects Dulac's own desire to represent<br />

cinematically the psychic force of the human mind, as well as her


104 / To Desire Differently<br />

uncanny ability to designate such subtle distinctions as those between<br />

thought, imagination, and, ultimately, unconscious fantasy.<br />

The last preparatory sequence depicts precisely that latter process<br />

of the unconscious, for in it Madame Beudet advances from a picture<br />

that she imagines to a fantasmatic scenario that she directs. Having<br />

succeeded in mentally projecting an image of a vehicle for escape (if<br />

only for an instant), she is now able to envision a little mise-en-scene<br />

of action in the form of a confrontation between an imaginary lover<br />

and the oppressive husband who sits across from her. In no fewer<br />

than twenty-four shots the sequence depicts a phantom tennis player<br />

(come to life from the pages of the magazine by means of a superimposilion)<br />

who waltzes over to Beudet's desk, lifts him bodily, and carries<br />

him off. To Madame Beudet's spontaneous—and exceptional—eruption<br />

of laughter, Beudet responds in mimicked glee, taking the gun<br />

from the drawer as a title explains: "A stupid and oft-repeated joke,<br />

dear to Monsieur Beudet: The suicide-parody." A subjective shot of<br />

the blanched and contorted face of Beudet in large close-up (Dulac's<br />

cinematic distortion to suggest Madame Beudet's emotional attitude<br />

toward her husband) is matched by a profile shot of Madame Beudet<br />

wincing. The return to a more "realistic" shot of Beudet as he places<br />

the gun back in the desk and shrugs is followed by a close-up of the<br />

back of Madame Beudet's head and a subsequent alternation of similar<br />

shots and shrugs.<br />

This sequence is notable for a number of reasons. First, it is the<br />

introduction of the suicide joke that will generate the central dramatic<br />

action of the film. But, and this is the second point, this joke is not<br />

presented in the form of a simple narrative event. Rather, it is prefaced<br />

by the first example of Madame Beudet's mental ability to "create" a<br />

character of her own who performs in a fantasmatic scene enacted<br />

within the actual space of her life, a fictive character capable of representing<br />

through action her desire to rebel against her despotic: husband.<br />

And so powerful is this imaginary scene that it can accomplish<br />

what nothing else in her oppressive existence can do—it makes her<br />

laugh. A smile that explodes in one single moment of the film thus<br />

gives renewed ironic substance to its title, for it is not simply that<br />

Madame Beudet never smiles; she is, in fact, quite capable of smiling—<br />

even laughing—but only as a result of the power of her own fantasmatic:<br />

capability.<br />

Third, the conclusion of the sequence is a foreshadowing of the<br />

film's ending. The two shots of the back of Madame Beudet's head<br />

function in direct contrast to her interaction with the fantasy tennis<br />

player. In the moment when we see her face, we observe her as the<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 105<br />

sole member of an audience reacting to a scenario of her own creation,<br />

and are thus given access to her interiority. But when the back of her<br />

head is depicted, there is a sealing off of this capacity to fictively<br />

interact, and of our capacity to identify as well. Therefore, just as these<br />

last shots of the sequence represent a temporary cessation of Madame<br />

Beudet's imaginative activity, the final images of the film itself signify<br />

a similar—and this time permanent—closure. The film's ending shot<br />

depicts Monsieur and Madame Beudet in American-shot (depicting<br />

characters to the hip, that is, three quarters of the body), seen from<br />

the back, as they continue down the provincial cobblestone street<br />

toward the vanishing point of the frame. Madame Beudet's resignation<br />

to the suffocating trap of bourgeois marriage is signified by the narrative<br />

action; the impossibility of future flights of fantasy is equally<br />

emphasized by the symbolic "closed door" of the back of the head. To<br />

return to the sequence under analysis, then, the hostile sarcasm of the<br />

exchange between the couple that concludes this fantasized scene of<br />

the tennis player's triumph is a forceful indication of just how powerfully<br />

Madame Beudet's painful reality can limit and confine her imagination's<br />

play.<br />

Having thus prepared the view with these glimpses into the visual<br />

richness of Madame Beudet's interior world, Dulac now turns to her<br />

most sustained exploration of processes of the psyche (to date) by creatinga<br />

situation in which fantasy emerges from enforced solitude. Having<br />

been left alone by the boorish husband—off at the opera with two of his<br />

provincial peers—and discovering that he has locked the piano—her<br />

one objective source of pleasure—Madame Beudet paces aimlessly<br />

through the darkened parlor as her thoughts and reveries fill the screen.<br />

The very minimal situation of a woman at home alone thus becomes the<br />

simple dramatic framework (the surface) that permits the purely visual<br />

elaboration of subjectivity (its depth).<br />

For purposes of analysis, this sequence will be called the "fantasysolitude<br />

sequence." Madame Beudet's subjective vision is constructed<br />

through a series of montage units, seven smaller segments which each<br />

evoke a different emotion, and which collectively combine to create a<br />

generalized atmosphere that both objectifies her state of mind and articulates<br />

her desire. In this cinematic texture of perception, thought, and<br />

fantasy, each sub-segment portrays a different type of subjective relation<br />

of Madame Beudet to the external world. In order to render this,<br />

each smaller segment is structured by a different type of technical device,<br />

alternating montage pattern, or cinematic punctuation, allowing<br />

the full range of expressive possibilities of the cinema to come into play.<br />

I have identified the seven segments by titles that denote their


106 / To Desire Differently<br />

content: 1) "Initial Solitude" (two shots); 2) "The Poem" (fourteen<br />

shots); 3) "The Maid" (eight shots); 4) "Imprisonment" (eighteen<br />

shots); 5) "Fantasy of the Phantom Lover" (thirteen shots); 6) "Monsieur<br />

Beudet's Haunting Appearances" (ni<strong>net</strong>een shots); and 7) "The<br />

Resolution" (three shots). In each segment, an alternation that interposes<br />

shots of Madame Beudet with different types of subjective image<br />

renders the emotional and mental atmosphere of her psyche. Thus<br />

Madame Beudet "sees" optically subjective images (shots which convey<br />

her perceptual viewpoint), semi-subjective images (shots which suggest<br />

her emotional attitude toward an object), and purely mental images<br />

(memories, thoughts-, and fantasies). 12<br />

Each of these segments is thus<br />

organized on the basis of an alternation of seeing and seen, implying<br />

that Madame Beudet's vision, both perceptual and imaginary, articulates<br />

the shot-changes that compose the sequence. In this way, Madame<br />

Beudet is continually determined as the central focus of spectatoridentification<br />

and Dulac is able to achieve her stated intention: "If the<br />

opposition and succession of images are capable of creating movement,<br />

they can also perfectly depict the state of mind of a character, enabling<br />

us to enter his [or her] thoughts more readily than words can do."<br />

Initial Solitude<br />

The first segment ("Initial Solitude") simply uses its two shots to establish<br />

the situation: Madame Beudet, alone in the study, turns off the<br />

desk lamp and discovers that the piano has been locked. The soft<br />

chiaroscuro created by her first gesture can be seen to initiate the<br />

sequence, marking the transition from the brutal reality of the Beudets'<br />

marriage to the imaginative realm of the subsequent flow of<br />

images. This short segment is matched in its simplicity (and lack of<br />

technical effects) by the three shots at the end of the sequence ("The<br />

Resolution"): Madame Beudet goes over to the desk, takes out the<br />

revolver, and reaches into the drawer for the bullets. The repetitions<br />

(Madame Beudet in American-shot, the desk, the window) reinforce<br />

the framing effect of these two segments that enclose the sequence, a<br />

sequence that effectively demonstrates "the multiple and contradictory<br />

interior impressions" which characterize "the secret domain of [Madame<br />

Beudet's] inner life." 14<br />

As such, the entire sequence can be read as a microcosm of the film,<br />

for within its limits—precisely defined by the "realistic" representation<br />

of Madame Beudet in the study—the whole interplay of fantasy and<br />

desire is rendered through a visual equivalent of stream-of-consciousness<br />

narration. In the context of the film itself, Madame Beudet's<br />

imaginary reveries are her only means of escape from her suffocating<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 107<br />

bourgeois marriage. Thus the film's introductory title, "In the<br />

provinces. ..." is repeated at its end, with the additional commentary<br />

"In the quiet streets, without horizon, under the heavy sky. . . . Joined<br />

together by habit." The same dismal images of Chartres ("Notations<br />

of sadness, the empty streets, the mundane, colorless people. ..." ) 15<br />

occur after both opening and closing titles, with the important addition<br />

of the Beudet couple, firmly ensconced in the provincial environment<br />

of the film's final image, and this provincial environment now equally<br />

ensconced in the narrative legibility required by cinematic illusionism.<br />

But while the end of the "fantasy-solitude" sequence is marked by<br />

Madame Beudet's resolve to liberate herself from the tyrannical husband—an<br />

active solution that involves loading his revolver—the end<br />

of the film, as noted before, confirms her powerlessness, enclosing<br />

her extraordinarily rich fantasy world within the immutable shape of<br />

"reality," and closing off the film's expressive psychological depth with<br />

an image of stark realism.<br />

The Poem<br />

Throughout her writing, Dulac stressed the importance of conceiving<br />

a film visually, of working from a "visual idea" or a "visual theme" that<br />

she equated with feelings, emotions, or sensations. In accordance with<br />

this, the "fantasy-solitude" sequence originates with a state of mind—<br />

despair, loneliness, frustration—and evokes this by means of suggestion<br />

rather than through precise definition. The interplay of images<br />

thus takes the place of what might have been the free indirect discourse<br />

of verbal intertitles ("Madame Beudet longed to be transported by a<br />

fiery, romantic lover . . . ," for example). The spectator is appealed to<br />

directly, without recourse to rational processes of the intellect, by<br />

means of a visual language which functions, paradoxically, by indirectness.<br />

This is a process of "suggestive magic" actualized in cinematic<br />

images—the Symbolist poem visualized.<br />

Therefore, it seems quite natural that in this sequence, Madame<br />

Beudet first seeks escape through Symbolist poetry, Baudelaire's "La<br />

Mort des amants," to be precise. The fourteen shots of the next subsegment<br />

are thus patterned on an alternation that shifts between<br />

images of Madame Beudet reading and thinking, intertitles of lines<br />

from the poem, and corresponding shots of objects around the house.<br />

The implication of this logic of montage, the cinema's discursive process,<br />

is that Madame Beudet is trying to imagine the poetic images as<br />

she reads by calling to mind objects of her quotidian reality.<br />

The result, of course, is undeniably ironic, as the banality of the<br />

objects only reinforces her dissatisfaction with a loveless marriage. The


108 / To Desire Differently<br />

Baudelaire poem is in fact about a perfect union of two lovers (lines<br />

not quoted in the film): "Our two hearts will be two immense torches,/<br />

Which will reflect their double lights/In our two minds, these twin<br />

mirrors" ["Nos deux coeurs seront deux vastes llambeaux,/Qui réfléchiront<br />

leurs doubles lumières/Dans nos deux esprits, ces miroirs<br />

jumeaux"]. But what Madame Beudet "sees" in her mind's eye—each<br />

image prefaced by a fade-in and closed by a fade-to-black—are the<br />

Beudets' empty bed, their neatly stacked pillows, and the vase of<br />

flowers that has become a symbol of their confrontation. In response<br />

to the poem's invocation of spiritual doubling, then, images of her<br />

alienated life emphasize Madame Beudet's sense of isolation. The<br />

punctuating fades signify her thoughts as she tries to conjure, from<br />

her own experiences, images of "beds wafted with light scents" ["des<br />

lits pleins d'odeurs légères"], "couches deep as tombs" ["des divans<br />

profonds comme des tombeaux"], and "strange flowers" ["d'étranges<br />

fleurs"]. But the vague perfume, the suggested swoon, the exoticism<br />

of the poem are lost in the bland reality of her life's objects. She throws<br />

the book down in disgust. Thus the spectator's first entry into Madame<br />

Beudet's feelings is guided by the character's own cognitive powers of<br />

imagination and the ensuing frustration when these efforts fail.<br />

The Maid<br />

The spectator goes deeper into Madame Beudet's unconscious mind—<br />

but only for an instant—in the next sub-segment. In a conventional<br />

exchange of the reverse-shot structure, the maid enters and asks if she<br />

may go out with her fiance (the question is rendered in an intertitle).<br />

The only two shots of Madame Beudet in this segment (indicating her<br />

reply by a sad nod of the head) surround the first truly imaginary<br />

apparition of the sequence. In a single close-up of the maid, the<br />

fiance is made to appear, kiss her cheek, then disappear through a<br />

superimposition that dissolves in and out. Framed as it is by identical<br />

images of Madame Beudet in American-shot, this sequence of shots<br />

implies her own mental projection of a loving relationship. This image<br />

of desire is thus a foreshadowing of things to come: Madame Beudet<br />

will only experience the love she longs for through an imaginary<br />

scenario of her own creation.<br />

Imprisonment<br />

The sub-segment treating Madame Beudet's sensation of entrapment<br />

is marked by signifiers of imprisonment and chronological time.<br />

Clocks, associated with calculated and measurable time, and thus with<br />

the mercantile mentality of Monsieur Beudet, first seem to harass her<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 109<br />

by appearing everywhere she turns. Thus a strict alternation of closeups<br />

("psychological shots" of Madame Beudet back-lit in a shadowy<br />

halo effect, then various clock faces and clanging bells) terminates<br />

with a close-up, accentuated by a hazy iris, of Madame Beudet's eyes,<br />

another image in a paradigm of shots of this kind. In this way, the<br />

experimental flow of the subjective time of consciousness (perhaps<br />

emphasized by the "luminous halo" that surrounds Madame Beudet,<br />

and calling to mind Virginia Woolfs definition of life as "a luminous<br />

halo, a semi-transparent envelope surrounding us from the beginning<br />

of consciousness to the end") l6<br />

is cinematically contrasted with metonymies<br />

of the implacable and ordered movement of chronological time.<br />

This contrast is then condensed into one striking, emblematic image<br />

that is repeated in various avatars for three shots. Madame Beudet, in<br />

medium-close-up, stands before a mantelpiece mirror and rests her<br />

head on a glass clock cover. Where the signifying function of editing<br />

had contrasted the two types of temporality across the cut, the temporal<br />

registers are now juxtaposed by a form of internal montage that<br />

relates elements within the frame among themselves.<br />

Madame Beudet's sensation of temporal oppression is matched with<br />

one of spatial entrapment in the remaining shots of the segment.<br />

Once again, this is provided by a metonymy, this time of physical<br />

imprisonment: a penitentiary. After an intertitle that announces (a bit<br />

too literally), "Always the same horizons. ..." close-ups of Madame<br />

Beudet in profile looking out the window enclose shots of a dreary<br />

provincial doorway and its facade that reads "House of Detention<br />

and Corrections." There is perhaps a problem with this notion of an<br />

objective correlative that relies too heavily on the content of the image<br />

to convey a state of mind. Images of clocks and prisons remain too<br />

anchored in their referents to fully achieve the suggestive evocation<br />

of the Symbolists. It is conceivable that at this point Dulac would have<br />

been more successful if she had adopted a pattern of accelerated<br />

montage, for example, which might have allowed the spectator to<br />

experience the feeling of suffocation more readily. No<strong>net</strong>heless, in<br />

terms of the overall structure of the sequence, this segment largely<br />

functions as preparation for the more viable imaginary production,<br />

Madame Beudet's "Fantasy of the Phantom Lover," and thus successfully<br />

contrasts an overt referentiality with what is ultimately the most<br />

fantasmatic sequence of the film.<br />

Fantasy of the Phantom Lover<br />

Here "fantasy" refers to the fulfillment of a wish by means of the<br />

production of an imaginary scene in which the subject (in this case,


110 / To Desire Differently<br />

the character Madame Beudet) is the protagonist. It is distinguished<br />

from the world of imaginative activity in general by its profound and<br />

systematic relations of desire: "[ T]he primary function of phantasy [is]<br />

namely the mise-en-scene of desire—a mise-en-scene in which what is<br />

prohibited (l´interdit) is always present in the actual formation of the<br />

wish." 17<br />

Thus in terms of the film, Madame Beudet has engaged in<br />

imaginative activity of a conscious or subliminal kind up until this<br />

point in the sequence. Now, in order to convey the transition into the<br />

"dream-state" which makes imaginary production of a fantasmatic sort<br />

possible, Dulac has recourse to the figure of the "double."<br />

First, in American-shot, Madame Beudet slumps into a chair, recalling<br />

the habitual gesture of Emma Bovary that characteristically precedes<br />

her transports of vague desire ("She sank down into an aimchair").<br />

The next shot—an axis-match close-up of Madame Beudet<br />

which dissolves into and then fills the frame—provides us with her<br />

double, the character who will act as protagonist in her ensuing fantasy.<br />

This Madame Beudet turns her head and looks off toward left frame<br />

as the image fades to black. Suddenly, the apparition, the phantasm,<br />

the phantom lover appears in a doorway—a blurred, superimposed<br />

image, advancing on air, arms outstretched. The corresponding closeup<br />

discloses Madame Beudet's hands in a gesture of response. The<br />

following shot, rendered hazy by a sort of reverse-iris effect which<br />

frames Madame Beudet's face in a halo of light, reveals her ecstatic<br />

smile—her only genuine smile in the entire film.<br />

Whereas Madame Beudet's laughter, discussed earlier with the action<br />

of the tennis-player, had the effect of an unexpected eruption,<br />

here her smile emphatically retains something of an enigmatic quality.<br />

It is a smile of puissance, of orgasmic ecstasy, of an expressiveness not<br />

seen on Madame Beudet's face before or since. This has the effect of<br />

suggesting a kind of condensation of woman's sexuality, of undecipherability,<br />

and of pleasure in a momentary image that is as uncertain<br />

as it is fleeting. And it is in this sense that the earlier laughter (related<br />

to an imagined vision) prepares this moment, a moment which is<br />

particularly significant in that it is linked precisely to the "representation"<br />

of the fantasmatic object of desire. For this reason, it is this smile<br />

which carries the weight of the film's title. Completely enclosed in an<br />

imaginary, subjective realm which has been prepared by the entire<br />

sequence, it is this smile to which all of the action returns, this smile<br />

that signifies at the same time the desire of the character, the filmmaker,<br />

and the spectator herself.<br />

But the signifier of contradiction appears in an intertitle<br />

("But. . . . "). A close-up of Madame Beudet's eyes, framed in an iris<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 11 1<br />

and now looking toward the right of the frame, prepares the way<br />

for the following shot—a high-contrast, distorted image of Monsieur<br />

Beudet's grinning face. As if to oppose the harsh reality of the marriage<br />

evoked by this image with the possible excitement and suggestive<br />

sexuality offered by the fantasy, the shot of the phantom lover is<br />

repeated. Subsequent shots reveal Madame Beudet tossing her wedding<br />

ring until the segment's final shot irises on her hand, the ling<br />

firmly back in place.<br />

Throughout this sub-segment, then, Madame Beudet's fantasmatic<br />

projection is rendered through an alternation of shots: her "double"<br />

seeing, the imagined representations seen. Her hallucination of the<br />

phantom lover confronts the memory of her oppressive husband in a<br />

scenario that subsumes desire to the law. The figure of the double,<br />

indicating the dream-state necessary to the production of this fantasm,<br />

also functions to induce the spectator's participation in this production.<br />

It is by virtue of this double that Madame Beudet becomes a character<br />

in her own fiction. Likewise, the viewer twice removed (watching Madame<br />

Beudet watching her fantasm), becomes a credulous participant<br />

in the hallucination, spectator to the fantasy-within-a-fantasy offered<br />

by the film, and equal participant in her desire.<br />

Monsieur Beudet's Haunting Appearances<br />

The penultimate sub-segment of the "fantasy-solitude" sequence elaborates<br />

on the horrific appearance of Monsieur Beudet, as subsequent<br />

shots render him capable, even in his absence, of preventing Madame<br />

Beudet's fantasy of escape. This is the longest sub-segment in the<br />

sequence, and as such demonstrates his power, both narratively and<br />

textually, to foreclose his wife's desire. The segment opens as Madame<br />

Beudet, still seated in the armchair, jumps up, startled. The image of<br />

Monsieur Beudet, made even more grotesque through a variety of<br />

technical procedures from bizarre camera angles and distorting lenses<br />

to both fast and slow motion, appears in nine of the segment's ni<strong>net</strong>een<br />

shots, alternating (in general) with close-ups of a terrorized Madame<br />

Beudet.<br />

The effect is such that he seems to surge up wherever Madame<br />

Beudet, in increasing panic, turns. First he bounds over the balcony<br />

in slow motion. This apparition differs from that of the phantom lover<br />

in that while the latter, an imaginary creation of Madame Beudet,<br />

appeared from an imagined doorway in a barely distinguishable softfocus<br />

haze. Monsieur Beudet, a remembered figure, climbs through<br />

the window of the Beudet apartment and has some degree of corporeality.<br />

He grimaces, grins, and laughs in subsequent images, chasing


112 / To Desire Differently<br />

her in accelerated motion, pushing the flowers to the center of the<br />

table in slow motion, demanding that she adjust his collar. These<br />

last three are characteristic gestures, memories of Monsieur Beudet's<br />

behavior that now haunt Madame Beudet as she sees him before her<br />

eyes. The image of her fear thus concretized, these gestures culminate<br />

in a repetition of Monsieur Beudet's parodic suicide joke. And as he<br />

disappears from the frame in this final haunting image, leaving the<br />

empty desk, Madame Beudet's "resolution" to load the gun seems the<br />

logical conclusion.<br />

The Seashell and the Clergyman<br />

A dream on the screen—The most recent psychological research has established<br />

that the dream, far from being a formless and chaotic mass of images,<br />

always tends to organize itself according to precisely defined rules, and thus<br />

has its own—affective and symbolic—logic. Consequently, someone else's<br />

dream (if we were able to see it) would be capable of moving us as effectively<br />

as any other spectacle, by addressing not our logic and our intellectual<br />

comprehension, but this obscure and unconscious sensibility which elaborates<br />

our own dreams for us. Such is the bold attempt of poet Antonin<br />

Artaud, who has proposed a scenario made of a dream: The Seashell and the<br />

Clergyman. Madame Germaine Dulac has just finished making this film . . .<br />

and we can expect that [she] has surpassed herself in this effort of the avantgarde.<br />

It concerns a dream which is not enclosed in any kind of story and<br />

which each spectator will have to understand, or better, experience uniquely<br />

according to the resources of his own personal sensibility. 18<br />

With The Seashell and the Clergyman, Dulac extends her concern with<br />

the mechanisms of the unconscious by shifting her focus from a fantasy<br />

of which a fictional character is the subject to the fantasmatic process<br />

itself. Thus, while her interest in the processes of the psyche remains<br />

constant, one of the things that marks the difference between the two<br />

films is a modification in the type of spectatorial involvement required<br />

by each text. Whereas in Beudet, as we have seen, the spectator is made<br />

to identify with a specific character whose thoughts, dreams, and<br />

fantasies are represented within the confines of a fiction, what Seashell<br />

elicits is the spectator's actual participation, as the subject of the fantasm,<br />

in the experience of those psychic processes themselves. And it<br />

is here that the consequences for the exploration and expression of<br />

desire, and of feminine desire in particular, are most provocative. In<br />

Beudet, Dulac had conceived of her female character's unconscious<br />

desires as specific objects capable of being rendered on the screen<br />

through formal means: here, in Seashell, she uses the female figure


Beudet and Seashell / 117<br />

precisely as a representation, thematizing woman as a force of desire<br />

within the production of the filmic writing itself.<br />

In order to have a better understanding of the radical feminist<br />

potential of a film like Seashell, it is first necessary to grasp the distinction<br />

between the mobilization of spectator identification through a<br />

fictional construct and the production of a liberated and active viewing<br />

subjectivity—a distinction that characterizes the specific procedures of<br />

the two films. As discussed earlier in relation to the entire cinematic<br />

apparatus, contemporary film theory posits that the film spectator is<br />

in some sense "constructed" in and by the viewing experience, and<br />

that fictive participation in the film's events has its roots in fantasy. As<br />

is evident from the analysis of Madame Beudet's imaginings, "Even<br />

where they can be summed up in a single sentence, phantasies are still<br />

scripts . . . of organized scenes which are capable of dramatization—<br />

usually in a visual form." 19<br />

Within this framework of a wishfulfilling<br />

staging of desire, all fantasmatic production is conceived as a relation<br />

to a representation, a relation of the subject born of loss and marked<br />

by the perpetual impossibility of satisfaction. The desiring process,<br />

then, is one of infinite circulation, of endless displacement from representation<br />

to representation. And it is the intersection of film and<br />

unconscious fantasy around a concept of "dramatization" that accounts<br />

for the mobilization of the spectator's desire in the viewing<br />

situation.<br />

It is this dramatization which connects Seashell to Beudet in terms of<br />

Dulac's feminist project. Certain formulations of the Surrealist film<br />

conceived it as a textual space in which various psychic forces were<br />

made to interact—in short, they posited a notion of film as textual<br />

process. Alain and Odette Virmaux's definition of the Surrealist film<br />

as "a means of exploring the profound life of consciousness, obsessions,<br />

and fantasms in their spontaneous and irrational eruption" 20<br />

foregrounds this staging of psychic processes at the base of the Surrealist<br />

film's textuality. It can be successfully argued that Seashell, undeniably<br />

acknowledged as the first example of Surrealist cinema (both<br />

chronologically and aesthetically), represents the earliest attempt to<br />

cinematically render these unconscious forces in a way that engages<br />

the viewer in a process of identification with the film-text itself, rather<br />

than with any specific fictional construct. Once liberated from the<br />

constraints of both character and plot, these forces are thus free to<br />

circulate on the screen with all the energy of unconscious drives themselves.<br />

A film like Seashell, then, facilitates the spectator's own—and<br />

unique—participation in the meaning-production process without recourse<br />

to the traditional mechanisms of identification.


118 / To Desire Differently<br />

As noted earlier, Dulac's film is based on a script by the revolutionary<br />

poet and dramatist Antonin Artaud. This double authorship has been<br />

the source of much critical confusion, for the riot that accompanied<br />

the film's inaugural screening on February 9, 1928, has led to extensive<br />

debates concerning artistic theory, intentionality, and cinematic transcription<br />

from verbal to visual text. 21<br />

What interests me here, however,<br />

is the way that Seashell's articulation of hallucinatory dream-images is<br />

consistent with Dulac's exploration of unconscious processes throughout<br />

her career and how, in fact, this suggests possibilities for the<br />

conceptualization and representation of feminine desire. My concern<br />

is with how a concept of "femininity" is produced in the text of Seashell,<br />

and for this reason the textual markers of authorship are of more<br />

significance than the particulars of the debate between individuals. It<br />

is within this context that I consider both Dulac and Artaud as having<br />

similar conceptions of the film and compatible impulses behind its<br />

realization. For the present analysis, I thus emphasize the correspondence<br />

of authorial voices. 22<br />

To attempt to describe the "plot" of Seashell is to immediately situate<br />

oneself within its central problematic, for the film consists of a series<br />

of moments connected associatively without any regard for narrative<br />

logic or causality. It is precisely the unpredictability and confusion of<br />

dreams that Artaud sought in his scenario, a succession of images "in<br />

a film constructed according to the dark and hidden rules of the<br />

unconscious," images that would follow each other despotically, arbitrarily,<br />

relentlessly in a "poetry of the unconscious . . . which is the only<br />

poetry possible." 23<br />

This pure poetry of visual elements was intended to<br />

approximate subjectivity by recreating the impact of the dream as it is<br />

being dreamed: "[The Seashell and the Clergyman attempts] to find, in the<br />

occult birth and wanderings of feeling and thought, the deep reasons,<br />

the active and veiled impulses of our so-called lucid acts[.] [This]<br />

scenario can resemble, can be related to the mechanism of a dream without<br />

actually being a dream itself. [It seeks to] restore the pure work of<br />

thought." 24<br />

Thus a simple outline of the visual situations that follow<br />

each other for no apparent reason is the closest one can come to a<br />

narrative description, for the significance of each sequence of images<br />

comes from its suggestive relationship (its representation of thought<br />

processes) rather than from its content (its motivation through character<br />

development).<br />

A clergyman (Alex Allin) fills beakers with a black liquid from an<br />

oyster shell, then lets them shatter on the floor; a general (Lucien<br />

Bataille) arrives and brandishes his saber; the clergyman follows him<br />

through the city streets to a church, where an astonishingly beautiful<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 119<br />

woman in eighteenth-century attire (Genica Athanasiou) suddenly<br />

appears. There is a confrontation in the confessional, as the officer<br />

abruptly becomes a priest; after tossing the priest from a cliff, the<br />

clergyman takes the latter's place in the confessional, then, confronting<br />

the woman, rips off her bodice, which turns into a carapace of shellshaped<br />

armor. There is next a wildly dancing society crowd into which<br />

a royal couple (the general and the woman) arrives, followed by the<br />

clergyman brandishing first the seashell and then the carapace; as he<br />

momentarily sees another apparition of the woman, he drops the carapace,<br />

which disappears in flames. His coattails then grow and expand<br />

across the parquet floor; suddenly, he is chasing the woman down a<br />

country road, as she metamorphoses (through close-ups) into a series of<br />

facial distortions; he continues to chase her through several hallways<br />

with closing doors until, finally, he enters a room where there is a large<br />

globe on a pedestal. He beckons to the unseen woman, captures her<br />

head, and places it inside the ball; now jauntily trying his key on a number<br />

of doors, the clergyman again sees the royal couple and this time<br />

pursues them both through the hallways and on the country road.<br />

Pounding fists wake the clergyman, who is asleep on a hammock on a<br />

ship; he spies the general and the woman kissing, a sight that prompts<br />

an attempt to strangle her fantasized neck in a movement that initiates<br />

a series of dreamlike images of glittering stalactites, islands, shimmering<br />

water, a tiny sailing ship, mist. Abruptly, a corps of maids emerges into<br />

a room, busily dusting as the woman, now a governess, takes charge;<br />

there is a couple (an unseen man and the woman) with tennis rackets,<br />

then a return to the maids who clean the globe as a group of butlers<br />

arrives. A return to the tennis scene precedes the arrival in the room of<br />

the clergyman and the woman now as a wedding couple; a close-up of<br />

the clergyman's head initiates a series of dream-images which are displayed<br />

on four different portions of his face. Suddenly, the headless<br />

clergyman descends the stairs, holding the glass ball; he then arrives in<br />

the room as the servants line up; a panning shot of their eyes causes<br />

the clergyman to drop the globe, which shatters on the floor, his face<br />

emerging among the shards. He stands, now with the oyster shell in his<br />

hand, then drinks from the shell that has his head in it, and the film ends<br />

as he drinks the black liquid—and his own image—which pours from<br />

the seashell.<br />

Again it is Artaud's words that clarify this apparent narrative confusion<br />

and indicate the profound systemalicity at work beneath the film's<br />

surface disorientation. "The Seashell and the Clergyman does not tell a<br />

story, but develops a series of states of mind, just as one thought<br />

derives from another, without needing to reproduce a logical sequence


120 / To Desire Differently<br />

of events. From the clash of objects and gestures, true psychic situations<br />

are derived, and from these, rational thinking, trapped, can only seek<br />

a subtle escape." 25<br />

What is particularly illuminating for the purposes of this chapter is<br />

the manner in which an emphasis on psychic processes eliminates the<br />

distinction between internal and external necessitated by the conventional<br />

fiction film, for it is precisely this latter kind of film that must<br />

develop narrative alibis and rational explanations for the appearance<br />

of every one of its images. In the traditional film, a veneer of narrative<br />

complications acts as an explanatory frame for the arbitrariness of the<br />

subjective images, whereas in Seashell, the absence of this frame allows<br />

the spectator to actually participate in the fantasmatic process.<br />

Far from being a facile depiction of dream associations on the screen,<br />

therefore, Seashell attempts to reproduce—for the spectator's active engagement—the<br />

actual production process of desire, its perpetual metamorphoses<br />

as it circulates from representation to representation. And<br />

it is no coincidence that this is associated specifically with the representation<br />

of the female figure, for throughout the text the elusive quality<br />

of the female figure is equated with that of desire in its evanescence.<br />

The woman's image is repeatedly generated as a fantasm of vision<br />

throughout the film—femininity is thematized as desire itself. Therefore,<br />

conceptions of the "feminine" do not disappear from Seashell,<br />

but are reoriented so that they are associated more fundamentally<br />

with unconscious processes.<br />

Artaud's understanding of this is quite apparent in his description<br />

of the female character (portrayed by the woman with whom he was<br />

still passionately and desperately in love, although he was at the time<br />

in the process of ending their long and intense affair): "The woman<br />

displays her animal desire, she has the shape of her desire, the spectral<br />

shimmering of the instinct which drives her to be at the same time one<br />

and ceaselessly different in her repeated metamorphoses." 26<br />

In the<br />

film, Dulac was able to emphasize the fantasmatic quality of this female<br />

ligure through expressive lighting, through soft-focus and hazy iris<br />

effects, and through sudden appearances and disappearances that<br />

enhanced her ephemeral status as an apparition. The figure of the<br />

woman thus emerges in Seashell, repeatedly in different guises, as a<br />

concrete, visual manifestation of unconscious forces of desire. According<br />

to Artaud, again, the woman was meant to portray "a role which<br />

is entirely instinctive, one in which a very surprising sexuality takes on<br />

an air of fatality that goes beyond the character as a human being and<br />

attains the universal." 27<br />

It is clear from both Artaud's intent and Dulac's<br />

cinematic articulation of it, then, that the mediations of the subjective<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 121<br />

consciousness of a character, the rationalizations of narrative complications<br />

are not only unnecessary, they are strictly forbidden: This image<br />

of the woman is continually presented as representation. Thus rather<br />

than a figure with a referent in the actual world, a personality with<br />

depth of characterization, Génica Athanasiou's appearances materialize<br />

the actual production process of the image itself—an image of the<br />

woman as desire. However, it is extremely important to understand<br />

that both Artaud and Dulac in no way attempt to ascertain "the truth<br />

of woman" in this film, nor do they posit any social generalities of<br />

gender. Rather than suggesting an essentialist association of woman<br />

and instinct, or the particularities of personality, both scenarist and<br />

filmmaker place their emphasis on the dynamic and protean variations<br />

that the woman's form assumes. By foregrounding the fantasmatic<br />

nature of this image of the woman—as an imaginary production, with<br />

the capacity of simulacrum, of memory, of hallucinated vision—the<br />

female figure in Seashell thus provides a sustained reflection on the<br />

construction and production of femininity both in the film and within<br />

its cultural and psychic contexts.<br />

Another point to be made in relation to Artaud's positing of sexuality<br />

over personality in the construction of the female image concerns his<br />

reference to the "surprising" sexuality of the woman (in the passage<br />

just cited). Like most of Artaud's language, the term "une sexualité<br />

très curieuse" defies literal translation, for the very "curiosity" that<br />

seems self-evident in its meaning explodes in a number of allusive<br />

directions once it slides from French to English. What is peculiar to<br />

the meticulous or inquisitive investigator—attracting and retaining the<br />

attention of the pursuit—becomes almost meaningless as an attribute<br />

when used to modify "sexuality." What remains, instead, are the<br />

strange, the surprising and the singular—qualities of the rare and the<br />

extraordinary. How contradictory, then, that Artaud should choose a<br />

word designating an astonishing uniqueness in order to describe the<br />

characteristic that makes his female "universal." It is precisely within<br />

this complication that Dulac chose to situate her elaboration of "femininity"<br />

in this film, for the very elusiveness of definition is what characterizes<br />

her female form.<br />

A brief exploration of Artaud's descriptions of the feminine figure<br />

in the scenario and Dulac's cinematic actualizations of them might be<br />

useful in this light. As previously noted, at a very superficial level,<br />

none of the "characters" in Seashell conforms to traditional notions of<br />

character elaboration and development. Yet even at the outset, by<br />

virtue of her ephemeral quality and the clergyman's fascinated pursuit,<br />

the woman's image is secured as central to the cinematic fiction. This


122 / To Desire Differently<br />

"very beautiful" woman's figure, in various aspects, characterizations,<br />

and symbolic forms, constantly and unexpectedly appears throughout<br />

the film, as the clergyman, a consciousness in search of itself, pursues<br />

her.<br />

However, in order to avoid an immediate and superficial reading<br />

of the film as romantic quest, I should point out that Seashell neither<br />

begins nor concludes with this pursuit of the woman. Rather, if an<br />

interpretation must be posited (and it should be noted that Artaud<br />

had excised "everything that had a poetic or literary quality" in the<br />

decoupage he sent to Dulac), the film has as much to do with the<br />

clergyman's quest for identity as it does with romantic aspirations. The<br />

film thus both opens and closes with the clergyman alone, in a circular<br />

reiteration of images that assures the association of clergyman, liquid,<br />

seashell, and self. This equivocation of interpretations is intentional:<br />

Artaud and Dulac were less interested in the character's psychological<br />

narrative—be it of identity or of romance—than they were in dramatizing<br />

fundamental operations of the psyche. Instead of a single protagonist—male<br />

or female—used to focus and organize the identificatory<br />

processes of the spectator, then, there is a multiplicity of positions<br />

available within the fantasmatic scenario, a scenario which, in fact,<br />

comprises the entire film. It is this form of dispersed subjectivity that<br />

puts the viewer, rather than the character, in the place of the desiring<br />

producer of the fantasm, and in so doing, unfixes notions of the<br />

singular self, and of "masculinity" and "femininity" as well. Numerous<br />

relations of identification with both characters and functions make<br />

the film's "story" a series of dramatized relationships and narrative<br />

moments in a psychosexual dynamic—and the spectator perpetually<br />

slides between and among them.<br />

A form of spectatorial identification with fantasmatic activity itself<br />

thus allows the female figure to function as a representation in the<br />

dream-space of the film, a generalized social and psychic articulation<br />

of "femininity" as it is produced from situation to situation. It is in this<br />

sense that the overall "narrative" structure of both scenario and film<br />

achieves the dream-logic so important to Artaud, and thereby permits<br />

the rendering of sexuality as a process unrestricted by prior definitions.<br />

Both Dulac and Artaud agreed that a film's structural coherence<br />

should emerge from within the text itself rather than from an organizing<br />

principle external to it. In fact, Artaud was not against the notion<br />

of the dream per se, but against its use as an alibi to justify the bold<br />

technical maneuvers of the film. In his preface to Seashell, immediately<br />

after his famous disclaimer ("I will not seek to excuse its incoherence<br />

by the easy loop-hole of dreams"), Artaud is quick to point out the<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 123<br />

importance of the film's internal logic: "Dreams have a logic of their<br />

own—but more than that, they have a life of their own in which<br />

nothing but dark and intelligent truths appear. This scenario seeks<br />

out the somber truth of the mind, in images emerging uniquely from<br />

themselves, images which . . . draw their meaning . . . from a sort of<br />

powerful inner necessity which projects them in the light of a merciless<br />

obviousness (evidence sans recours)."28<br />

But although his evocation of these "somber truths" demonstrates<br />

a profound understanding of the mechanisms of the unconscious,<br />

Artaud most definitely objects to traditional notions of psychology,<br />

personality, and behavior. Thus he emphatically counterposes this<br />

self-engendering power of the image to the facile explanatory coherence<br />

of narrative or of psychology. Again in the preface he is quite<br />

explicit on this point: "In the scenario that follows I have attempted<br />

to realize this idea of a visual cinema in which even psychology is<br />

devoured by acts. No doubt this scenario does not achieve the absolute<br />

image of all that might be done in this direction; but at least it points<br />

the way. Not that the cinema must renounce all human psychology.<br />

That is not its principle. On the contrary, it must give this psychology<br />

a much more vital and active form—and this without those discursive<br />

connections which attempt to make the motives for our actions appear<br />

in an absolutely stupid light instead of exposing them to us in their<br />

original and profound barbarity." 29<br />

And it is here that the distinction critical to a feminist reading of the<br />

film emerges, for in eliminating psychology as a means of rational<br />

explanation or interpretation, the full psychic force of the unconscious<br />

as a signifying system becomes apparent. Screen images and sequences<br />

thus become violently evocative stimuli for the viewer's own intuitive<br />

and psychic processes, chosen for their powerful immediacy and capacity<br />

to move rather than for their discursive ability to delineate<br />

fictional constructs, male or female. In this context, then, the viewer<br />

is continually engaged in the activity of meaning-production through<br />

textual instances that actualize psychic forces: "characters" become<br />

generalized cultural constructs—symbolic representations of masculinity<br />

and femininity, of patriarchal authority and female sexuality in<br />

a circuit of desire. It is along these lines that the appearance of the<br />

woman's figure in the film—as spectral apparition rather than as substantial<br />

character—must be understood. Through each incarnation,<br />

through each elusive moment, the woman in Seashell achieves exactly<br />

that directness of the "purely visual situations whose dramatic action<br />

springs from a shock designed for the eyes, a shock founded . . . on<br />

the very substance of the gaze" 30<br />

that Artaud called for and that the


124 / To Desire Differently<br />

dream-work implies. It is in this sense that the images of libidinal<br />

violence, of perverse sexuality, and of passion must be understood.<br />

There is an even more important point: Artaud envisioned The<br />

Seashell and the Clergyman as the film that would tear the cinema away<br />

from its status as reflection, reproduction, and representation of the<br />

real, and in so doing demonstrate its capacity to signify the unrepresentable—the<br />

fantasmatic world of hallucinations, metamorphoses<br />

and desires. Yet it is only—and specifically—the figure of the woman<br />

that bears the full weight of this project. For while the clergyman<br />

remains clothed in his ecclesiastic frock throughout the film, the patriarchal<br />

figure likewise alternating between military uniform and<br />

priestly robes, it is the female figure alone who undergoes no fewer<br />

than ten transformations of attire. From billowing eighteenth-century<br />

gown and feathered bon<strong>net</strong> to slender black silk dress with train, from<br />

a flowing Empire-style garment to the dark high-collared outfit of a<br />

governess, from the contemporary tennis outfit of pleated skirt and<br />

sweater to the filmy simplicity of a wedding gown, the image of the<br />

woman perpetually reappears, as variable as she is elusive. Her changes<br />

of costume correspond to changes of function in the representation<br />

of the sexual dynamic, as she repeatedly forms a different couple<br />

with each of the men at different times. A closer look at her varied<br />

appearances throughout the film will demonstrate the way in which<br />

a sense of almost "physical intoxication" is achieved through these<br />

repeated metamorphoses of the visual embodied in the female ligure.<br />

The first indication of the woman in Seashell emerges unexpectedly:<br />

She is seated in a horse-drawn carriage beside the officer whom we<br />

recognize from the film's first sequence. Artaud's scenaric indications<br />

are even devoid of a verb—the officer is simply seen "with a very<br />

beautiful white-haired woman." 31 This sudden emergence of the female<br />

figure is depicted in the film by means of the first in a series of<br />

"impossible" points of view. The initial two shots of the carriage show<br />

it traversing the frame from different sides, intercut with images of<br />

the clergyman crawling in the street. As he crawls around the corner<br />

of a building, we see him suddenly lurch upward, as a close-up reveals a<br />

horrified expression on his face. The "reverse-shot" is a close-mediumshot<br />

of the woman seated in the carriage, making our first encounter<br />

with her one signalled by her status as an object of vision. As spectators,<br />

we see the woman in a way impossible for the clergyman, given both<br />

his distance from the carriage and his position behind it. Yet his<br />

reaction is vividly portrayed, and the force of the woman as haunting<br />

vision, replayed throughout the film, is secured from the start.<br />

As the scenario describes it, the officer and the woman enter a<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 125<br />

church; once they are in the confessional together, the clergyman leaps<br />

on the officer, who turns into a priest. At this point, Artaud indicates that<br />

the priest should appear differently to the clergyman and the woman.<br />

Dulac conveys this sequence in a way which emphasizes the ephemeral<br />

beauty of the woman: As the woman and the officer form a primal couple<br />

in the confessional (a shot that opens and closes the sequence, its<br />

repetition acting as a frame), shots of the clergyman begin to alternate<br />

with shots of the woman, alone in the frame. A close-up of the clergyman's<br />

eyes, framed by a soft iris, initiates a strikingly lovely shot of the<br />

woman—a frontal close-up of her face, isolated and enhanced by the<br />

hazy lighting that surrounds it. The episode in which the clergyman<br />

strangles the priest is elaborated in a separate sequence. Artaud designates<br />

a number of separate close-ups of the priest to indicate his different<br />

demeanors, "aimiable and complaisant when [his face] appears to<br />

the woman, savage, bitter, and menacing when it considers the clergyman."<br />

In a sequence of roughly twenty-five shots, Dulac utilizes a variety<br />

of technical devices, including an original and inventive use of split<br />

screen, superimpositions, a wide range of high and low angles, distorting<br />

lenses, and larger or smaller close-ups to convey the violence of the<br />

episode and the gamut of expressive attitudes evoked by the scene. At<br />

this point, the female character's face expresses love or shock, concomitant<br />

with the emotions designated by the scenario.<br />

In a subsequent episode, it is now the woman and the clergyman<br />

who are in the confessional, and as the clergyman's rage develops, the<br />

film follows the scenario's description fairly closely. Allin's anger is<br />

accompanied by pounding fists and paroxysms of gesticulation, while<br />

the image of the woman maintains its evanescent stature. Once again,<br />

a close-up of astonishing beauty, this time of Genica Athanasiou's eyes<br />

surrounded by a gauzed iris, renders the woman in all her seductive<br />

loveliness while the scenario says simply, "The woman stands before<br />

him, looking." Through the metonymy of the close-up of the eyes,<br />

Dulac thus materializes the act of looking in a provocative way, making<br />

the eyes, which look themselves, the object of the (spectator's) gaze. I<br />

will return to this shortly.<br />

The responding shot, a masked close-up of the clergyman's eyes,<br />

initiates the next sequence, one which has, because of its violence and<br />

the fairly obvious misogyny of its literal denotation, been seized upon<br />

by traditional feminist criticism. The clergyman "throws himself upon<br />

[the woman] and tears off her bodice as if he had wished to lacerate<br />

her breasts. But her breasts are replaced by a carapace of shells." Yet<br />

this can only be interpreted as an act of psychologically motivated<br />

violence within the context of a conventional narrative film; here, 1


126 / To Desire Differently<br />

maintain, both Dulac and Artaud are interested in the libidinal force<br />

of the gesture—in its function as a representable instance in the dream-<br />

work—and in these terms it is one of many "purely visual situations"<br />

that constitute the film.<br />

Therefore, the apparition of the woman, a spectral vision that<br />

freezes the clergyman in terror or incites him to violence throughout<br />

the film, must not be interpreted as a sign of Artaud's sexist fear of<br />

women. Rather, these sudden, disturbing unexpected appearances—<br />

at once horrifying and seductive—are instances of the visual shock<br />

"founded on the very substance of the gaze," images in which the<br />

woman—as a figure of desire—evokes ambivalent sexuality, passionate<br />

obsession, and libidinal violence. In a subsequent episode of the film—<br />

after another of the woman's protean transformations into a queen in<br />

a royal couple, her absorption into the air (done through a dissolve),<br />

and her reappearance in a different corner of the room (this time<br />

portrayed in hazy iris as a mythical figure in flowing white robe and<br />

long hair)—the clergyman reacts: "This apparition seems to terrify<br />

the clergyman," indicates the scenario, as he drops the carapace-breastplate<br />

he has been brandishing. This sequence, then, makes use of the<br />

cinematic reaction-shot to convey pure dynamic emotive processes,<br />

for, as Artaud maintains, "There is no hidden significance of a psychological,<br />

metaphysical, or even human[istic] kind." 32<br />

This initiates another sequence which condenses a number of the<br />

"repealed metamorphoses" intended by Artaud to convey that "fantasmatic<br />

shimmering" of desire. As the woman and the clergyman run<br />

wildly, distractedly in the night,<br />

Their flight is intercut with successive apparitions of the woman in diverse<br />

attitudes [another translation refers to this as "hallucinatory sequences with<br />

the woman in various guises. ... "]: Sometimes her cheek is enormously<br />

swollen, sometimes she slicks out her tongue, which stretches out to infinity<br />

as the clergyman clutches it as if it were a rope. Sometimes her chest swells<br />

out horribly.<br />

At the end of their course, we see the clergyman entering a hallway and<br />

the woman behind him swimming in a sort of sky. 33<br />

These words are in Artaud's description, and Dulac utilized the full<br />

extent of her skill and imagination to transform these to the screen.<br />

All of the distortions are filmed against a very black background,<br />

something that contrasts with the intense sunlight of the chase sequence<br />

with which they are interspersed; this also emphasizes the<br />

spectral and illusory quality of these varied metamorphoses. Through<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 127<br />

the use of distorting lenses, wipes, superimpositions, and rotating<br />

prisms and lenses, a number of deformations are wrought on the<br />

feminine figure. Yet in some strange way, none of these is as horrific<br />

as the images of Monsieur Beudet in the earlier film, although many<br />

of the same devices are used. This demonstrates fairly graphically,<br />

therefore, that while the effects in Beudet are aimed at conveying an<br />

interpretation of character already formulated when the film was shot,<br />

the focus here is on processes—the conditions of representability at<br />

work in both unconscious and filmic figuration which it is Seashell's<br />

project to represent.<br />

Shortly after this, a sequence of the film occurs that has lent itself<br />

to the strongest attacks by traditional feminist criticism. The clergyman<br />

"raises his arms in the air as if he were embracing the body of a<br />

woman." Then, once his hold is secured, he throws himself upon it,<br />

strangling it "with expressions of unheard-of sadism," introducing<br />

the severed head into a glass bowl. Standard interpretations of this<br />

sequence find still another instance of violence wrought on women,<br />

yet a reading of both the scenario and the film's images reveals other<br />

meanings instead. The scenario clearly indicates that what the clergyman<br />

grabs hold of is a "shadow, a sort of invisible double," thereby<br />

permitting the "elle" on which he flings himself to be interpreted as<br />

either the woman or the shadow (which is feminine in French). And<br />

although it is true that the head that gradually appears in the ball in<br />

close-up is a woman's face, throughout the film the textual work has<br />

established an association between the woman and the clergyman's<br />

identity, between his pursuit of her and his quest for self. Substantiating<br />

this is the fact that near the close of the film, it is the clergyman's<br />

head that appears amid the shards of the broken glass ball. And it is<br />

this head that is placed on the oyster shell, the clergyman's own head,<br />

which "melts" and becomes the dark liquid that he drinks in the film's<br />

final shots. Indeed, it is not a "real" female character which has been<br />

captured and subdued in the film, but an image of the woman, as<br />

phantom, as specter, as shadow of desire.<br />

As noted before, there are other transformations of the female<br />

figure in the film: she appears as a governess, as a young girl, and as<br />

a bride. Yet one additional sequence stands out in the film, for it<br />

materializes the libidinal force of the primal scene in a sequence of<br />

eight shots whose very economy seems to illustrate Artaud's belief in<br />

the powerful directness of the cinema and its ability to bypass the<br />

distortion of verbal language and rational thought. Artaud's description<br />

in the scenario is as follows:


128 / To Desire Differently<br />

The clergyman finds himself in a ship's cabin. He gets up from his bunk<br />

and goes out to the ship's bridge. The officer is there, in chains. Now the<br />

clergyman seems to meditate and pray, but when he raises his head, at the<br />

level of his eyes, two mouths which touch each other reveal to him, at the<br />

side of the officer, the presence of a woman who was not there a moment<br />

ago. The body of the woman rests horizontally in the air.<br />

Then a paroxysm shakes him. It seems as if the fingers of each of his two<br />

hands were seeking a neck. 34<br />

Dulac renders this in a sequence whose shots (one action per shot)<br />

are all connected by dissolves, contributing to the nocturnal, dreamlike<br />

quality of the episode. Six shots constitute the crux of the sequence,<br />

laying out this miniature scenario of vision in terms of positions held<br />

by its protagonists. First, the officer is seen in long-shot, standing,<br />

asleep, by a pile of boxes on the ship's deck. The clergyman enters the<br />

frame from the left foreground, and turning, assuming a position of<br />

half-wakeful spectatorship, leaning against a pillar as if in a daze or a<br />

dream. A dissolve to the next shot reveals the officer, now in mediumshot,<br />

looking up slowly (decelerated motion) toward the top right edge<br />

of the frame. A parallel movement in the next shot discloses Allin, in<br />

close-medium-shot, looking slowly down and then left. The next shot,<br />

a medium-close-up of the officer, is interrupted by the spectral appearance,<br />

through a dissolve, of the woman's head; she leans over and<br />

kisses the officer. Now, as can be anticipated, a shot discloses all three<br />

figures—the "parental" couple in the background, kissing (as the woman's<br />

leaning body appears horizontal), and the clergyman in Americanshot<br />

in the foreground, making his characteristic clutching gesture.<br />

Finally, the sequence is terminated by a close-up of Allin's head; he<br />

first looks off frame right toward the couple, then turns his head<br />

frontally, revealing a horrified expression.<br />

This scene-within-a-scene encapsulates and reiterates the fantasmatic<br />

drama of spectatorship, a drama which, in The Seashell and the<br />

Clergyman, is played out through the circulation of figures of desire,<br />

figures of generalized sexual identity whose movements are not justified<br />

by narrative peregrinations. And it is here that the cinematic<br />

image of the woman assumes its full erotic force. As spectral illusion,<br />

as hallucinated vision, she is the reappearing phantom who draws the<br />

clergyman—and the viewer—into seeing things which are not there.<br />

And precisely because of her ephemeral quality, an undecipherability<br />

as powerful as it is evasive, the feminine figure allows something of<br />

Artaud's vision of the spectator to be achieved: "The mind is affected<br />

outside of all representation. This sort of virtual power of the image<br />

finds hitherto unutilized possibilities in the very depths of the mind." 35<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 129<br />

It seems appropriate to return now, momentarily, to the scene of<br />

the confessional, for it condenses a number of the film's procedures<br />

with a kind of striking immediacy. All of Seashell's sequences, in one<br />

way or another, actualize psychic processes, and their method of doing<br />

so can be categorized as follows: 1) the representation of the dispersed<br />

subjectivity that places the viewer at the center of a generalized psychic<br />

experience; 2) the use of male and female "characters" as cultural and<br />

symbolic constructs; 3) the use of shots or sequences that foreground<br />

vision, such as the staging of the primal scene or the emphatic elaboration<br />

of the gaze; 4) the representation of a dreaming consciousness as<br />

evidenced by the apparition of metamorphosing objects and fantastic<br />

visions; and 5) the depiction of the subjectivity turned in on itself, as<br />

exemplified by the film's conclusion, which repeats its beginning in a<br />

parable of film spectatorship, the clergyman consuming his own image<br />

in an act of narcissistic absorption. One brief moment in the confessional—a<br />

simple exchange of two shots—articulates all five of these<br />

categories in such a way as to produce a microcosm of the film itself.<br />

This pair of shots is the "eyeline match" par excellence, for it is,<br />

quite simply, the alternation of two large close-ups of eyes (gauzily<br />

masked to render everything else in the image a hazy blur)—first<br />

the woman's, then the clergyman's. This exchange, embedded within<br />

sequences that dramatize religious hypocrisy and erotic violence,<br />

seems, by its very energy, to erupt from the more narrational instances<br />

that surround it. This is how Artaud's scenario describes the action:<br />

"The woman and the clergyman are praying in the confessional. The<br />

clergyman's head quivers like a leaf, and all of a sudden it seems that<br />

something begins to speak inside him. He pushes up his sleeves and<br />

gently, ironically, knocks three times on the partition of the confessional.<br />

The woman gets up. Then the clergyman bangs with his fist<br />

and opens the door like a fanatic. The woman stands before him and<br />

looks at him. He throws himself on her and tears off her bodice as if<br />

he had wanted to lacerate her breasts." 36<br />

In keeping with her usual practice, Dulac renders—in detailed images<br />

and gestures—each action described. Yet for one small moment<br />

she diverges from the written scenario to depict these eyes, and this is<br />

highly significant. For it is precisely in their capacity to act as signs<br />

that these haunting, elusive images function to evoke exactly those<br />

processes of unconscious figuration which are central to the film in its<br />

effort to create, for the spectator, the experience of the fantasm. In their<br />

isolation, their fragmentary status, they aid the dissolution of character<br />

and the redirection toward psychic processes by emphasizing vision<br />

itself. In so doing, these pairs of eyes create an ambiguous space of


130 / To Desire Differently<br />

interpretation for the viewer, a site in which character psychology is<br />

only one option among many others in determining the symbolic value<br />

of the shot. It is possible, for example, to regard this exchange of<br />

glances as one instance in the circulation throughout the film of cultural<br />

signifiers of femininity and masculinity—hers the alert and<br />

watchful eyes of a female victim, his the lustful eyes of a violent brute.<br />

This is, after all, a confrontation with an extensive representational<br />

heritage. From another standpoint, these shots can be seen to take<br />

their place in a paradigm of subjective images and dream distortions;<br />

it is generally this sort of close-up that is linked to the flow of glistening<br />

castles, shimmering water, and the like in the film.<br />

Yet there is something different about these shots as well, a difference<br />

that recalls the slide of subjectivity back into itself. Although<br />

Artaud's script specifies only the gaze of the woman (as opposed to<br />

that of the man), Dulac chose to emphasize the actual fact of looking<br />

in a reciprocity of vision that blurs the distinction between characters.<br />

This slippage is characteristic of a film that associates the clergyman's<br />

pursuit of the woman with his own quest for self. But more important<br />

than that, here Dulac is able to give both characters the privilege of<br />

visuality, and in so doing she reaffirms the psychic reality that is the<br />

mainspring of the film. There is a remarkably similar close-up of<br />

eyes in The Smiling Mme Beudet, where it was used to amplify our<br />

understanding of the character, her desperate need for escape, and<br />

her imaginative capacity to envision flight. When this type of shot<br />

reappears in Seashell, however—in what amounts to an echo of the<br />

earlier film—it reinforces the latter film's project, not of recounting<br />

the dream or the daydream, but of portraying the unconscious figural<br />

processes of dreams themselves. And this foregrounded visual exchange<br />

which slides, as it does, between the masculine and feminine<br />

configurations of the gaze, represents nothing less than the double<br />

scenario of sexuality and vision—a dramatization of desire for both<br />

"character" and spectator that plays itself out on the psyche's unconscious<br />

stage.<br />

Fantasy and/as the Woman<br />

From the foregoing analyses it should be clear that there is an undeniable<br />

feminist consistency in Dulac's film work, a plurality of intersecting<br />

concerns that links her early explorations of "female fantasy" in Beudet<br />

to the more sustained examination of the very mechanisms of unconscious<br />

desire in Seashell. Thus her preoccupations—with cinematic<br />

language and its constructions of the viewer, with structures of the<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 131<br />

fantasm, and with the possibilities for representing woman's desire—<br />

converge in her filmmaking practice, while the explicit manifestation<br />

of these interests varies from film to film. For this reason, from the<br />

more overt feminism of the earlier film to the analysis of cultural and<br />

psychic representations of femininity (through work on signification)<br />

in the later one, Dulac's entire oeuvre can be said to represent the<br />

feminist project of conceptualizing differing ways of articulating women's<br />

relation to language and the body.<br />

This is precisely the postulation of an alternative feminist cinema<br />

formulated in Mary Ann Doane's article, "Woman's Stake: Filming<br />

the Female Body," in which she asserts: "The most interesting and<br />

productive . . . films dealing with the feminist problematic are precisely<br />

those which elaborate a new syntax, thus 'speaking' the female body<br />

differently, even haltingly or inarticulately from the perspective of a<br />

classical syntax." 37<br />

Doane calls for a kind of filmmaking that will posit<br />

a complex interrelation between the female body and psychic and<br />

signifying processes, because, for her, a pathway out of the essentialist<br />

impasse lies not in the abandonment of the body altogether, but in<br />

theories that "attempt to define or construct a feminine specificity<br />

(not essence), theories which work to provide the woman with an<br />

autonomous symbolic representation."38 And one of the ways this<br />

representation can come about is to be found in the very problematization<br />

of the woman's image engendered by both Beudet and Seashell, for<br />

in each of these films Dulac is concerned—albeit in different ways—<br />

to determine new forms in which the woman's body is "spoken" by the<br />

cinematic text.<br />

Regarded in this light, each film suggests a way of thinking "femininity"<br />

in its multiple meanings, and of understanding these meanings in<br />

their relation to the signifying processes of the unconscious. As such,<br />

they represent attempts to appropriate the construction and representation<br />

of the woman's image in its social, psychic, and cinematic contexts—attempts<br />

which, for Dulac, inflect her continuing research into<br />

the language of the cinema at every point. Whereas Beudet´s early<br />

example of representing female desire can be seen as an effort to<br />

give the woman both a vision and a voice, Seashell offers an abstract<br />

meditation on the processes that produce these at the level of the<br />

unconscious. Thus in Beudet the female character thinks (or dreams)<br />

in images, while in Seashell the female character is, in fact, the image<br />

itself.<br />

In the earlier film it is possible to understand Dulac's depiction of<br />

her heroine's dreams, hallucinations, and fantasies as evidence of<br />

an assumed definition of female desire, for both Madame Beudet's


The Seashell and the Clergyman (Summary)<br />

- 3SEX<br />

The Seashell and the Clergyman (Summary, cont.)


134 / To Desire Differently<br />

phantom lover and her reveries of escape participate in the certainty<br />

of familiar meanings. Yet the very certainty with which Dulac can be<br />

said to "know" her heroine's fantasy already becomes problematized<br />

within that same film when she confronts the issue of representing her<br />

female character differently. You will remember that, as a result of<br />

her solitary thoughts, Madame Beudet loads her husband's gun and<br />

subsequently engages in a frantic attempt to remove the bullets before<br />

a tragedy occurs. Sitting in her bedroom the following morning, she<br />

contemplatively brushes her hair as she considers, in remorse and<br />

desperation, how to slip undetected into her husband's study. It is<br />

here that, for one striking moment in the film, Dulac gives us an image<br />

of arresting beauty as Madame Beudet's face, lavishly surrounded by<br />

her flowing hair, is replicated in her triple mirror. This reiteration of<br />

the woman's image, framed and enhanced as it is by the multiple<br />

borders of the mirror, suggests a considerable departure from what<br />

was already being established at the time—the conventional representation<br />

of the woman as object of spectacle and of the desiring gaze.<br />

For in contrast to an erotic image of the woman looking—offering<br />

herself to the viewer as an image of her own desire (and thus recalling<br />

the culmination of this in Marnie's fascinated, self-absorbing gaze)—<br />

Dulac here fractures the masculine mode of visual pleasure in an<br />

activity which disperses and problematizes that very image. The tripartite<br />

framing of the woman's face, then, represents a reflection on the<br />

image as a mode of representation—a refusal to simply generate an image<br />

of female beauty constructed in masculine terms. And it is just such a<br />

dislocation of the visual language used to represent the woman's body<br />

that begins the challenge to dominant articulations of femininity and<br />

their structures of the gaze.<br />

The Seashell and the Clergyman extends this work by activating the<br />

female image as representation itself, for it is here that the female<br />

body—and the very processes of desire that constitute it as "feminine"—undergo<br />

a sustained investigation throughout the film. It is<br />

therefore no accident that the him of Dulac's that most assertively<br />

takes the "language of the unconscious" as its subject should offer<br />

multiple modes of figuring the feminine, not only in terms of the<br />

different types of costuming and the positions suggested by these, but<br />

also in its use of explicit nudity and its focus on body parts. The facial<br />

close-up itself exemplifies these procedures in a highly interesting<br />

manner. In Beudet, the close-up of the heroine's face—which was for<br />

Dulac, as noted before, the psychological shot par excellence—is used<br />

to convey access to Madame Beudet's interiority and her desires. For<br />

this reason, the connection between the head and the rest of the body


136 / To Desire Differently<br />

(the face as a metonymy of the person) is not only maintained, it<br />

is reinforced. However, in Seashell it is precisely this close-up, this<br />

disembodied woman's face, which becomes the site of transformations<br />

and hallucinations, in an obsessive reworking of feminine features<br />

used to produce the psychic atmosphere of the dream. Beyond this,<br />

Seashell contains several shots of bare breasts, which would have been<br />

shocking at the time, in addition to various other erotically charged<br />

bodily fragments such as the neck, the ankle, the shoulder, and so<br />

forth. In each instance, the shot brings us closer to a reinforcing<br />

physicality. aligning femininity with the body, while at the same time<br />

creating a breach between the image and its referent. It thus obliges<br />

us to read the image as a sign circulating in the textual space of the<br />

film.<br />

In this context, it is important to note that the "characters" in the film<br />

are not simply generalized symbolic forms that interact, but, precisely,<br />

sexually differentiated figures whose very distinction comes about in relation<br />

to a concept of the body. From this perspective, Seashell is less about<br />

the narcissistic identity of its hero than it is about sexual identity in general,<br />

for it gives us not the conclusion of a solidified character to emulate,<br />

but the production processes of femininity and masculinity themselves—cultural<br />

processes which overlay psychic trajectories. In her<br />

move from the particularized representation of a female character in<br />

Beudet to the generalized social and psychic representation of "femininity"<br />

in Seashell, Dulac thus demonstrates her growing understanding of<br />

sexuality as a process rather than a content. Her interest in unconscious<br />

processes of desire is the constant between the two films, as is her exploration<br />

of the constitutive elements of "femininity." But it is in her shift<br />

from the representation of the content of the fantasy to its very operations<br />

that the consequences for thinking the woman's relation to language<br />

and the body can be found.<br />

In its foregrounding of processes of signification, then, Seashell activates<br />

that syntactic disequilibrium which challenges both fixed meanings<br />

and notions of sexual identity from the very start. The excess<br />

of meaning provoked by its random and incongruous images, the<br />

circulation of its unexpected signs, suggests the impossibility of stable<br />

comprehension, or at least implies a kind of signification exceeding<br />

the borders of established reason. In the proliferation of meanings,<br />

the film offers diverse positions of viewer subjectivity and in so doing<br />

puts into relief the complex relations of language and desire. Therefore,<br />

Doane's positing of a feminist filmmaking which "attempts to<br />

construct another syntax," one that "threatens the 'idea of language' "<br />

based on intelligibility, finds a model here. 39<br />

In Seashell, the female<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 137<br />

body is represented differently as the film reworks conventional modes<br />

of articulation, organizing its flow of images according to "other" rules.<br />

Its disrupted, disordered syntactical relations suggest .something of<br />

the dynamism of unconscious forces and in so doing evoke possible<br />

alternative constructions of the "feminine."<br />

I am arguing that this work at the limits of meaning, taken in the<br />

context of feminist concerns, can be understood as a way of circumventing<br />

established structures of thinking, a way of reinscribing desire<br />

into the process of signification itself. When analyzed in this light,<br />

Dulac's formulation—of an abstract cinema endowed with the capacity<br />

to passionately move the viewer—takes on new force: "Yes, lines,<br />

volumes, surfaces, light, envisioned in their constant metamorphoses,<br />

are capable of taking hold of us by their rhythms if we know how to<br />

organize them in a construction capable of responding to the needs<br />

of our imagination and our feelings. . . . "40 This solicitation of each<br />

spectator's potential for direct, affective access to the cinematic image<br />

suggests a reconceptualization of desire not restricted to preformulated<br />

categories of meaning, and by extension, it implies the blurring<br />

of fixed definitions of masculine and feminine as well. The liberation<br />

implicit in this reconceptualization has important consequences for<br />

feminist cinema, for in rethinking sexuality by way of a profound<br />

exploration of the deepest foundations of all meaning-production,<br />

Dulac is able to contribute to the formulation of an alternative cinema<br />

based on new articulations of the body, language, and desire. And it<br />

is in this sense that, for all their differences in emphasis, both The<br />

Smiling Mme Beudet and The Seashell and the Clergyman provide significant<br />

contributions to the development of a forceful new theory of<br />

sexual difference in cinematic representation.<br />

NOTES<br />

1. J. Laplanche and J.-B. Pontalis, The Language of Psychoanalysis (New<br />

York: W. W. Norton, 1973), p. 475.<br />

2. Germaine Dulac, "Les procédés expressifs du cinématographe," Cinémagazine,<br />

no. 28 (July 11, 1924): 68. This is a transcript of a talk Dulac gave<br />

on June 17, 1924, at the Musée Galliera. All translations from the French are<br />

my own unless otherwise noted.<br />

3. Both films are available from the Museum of Modern Art, 11 West 53d<br />

St., New York, NY 10019. It is possible that the print of Seashell, if ordered<br />

from another distributor, is in an incorrect order. See note 23 below.<br />

4. Wendy Dozoretz, "Dulac Versus Artaud," Wide Angle 3:1 (1979): 51.<br />

5. Jacques B. Brunius, En marge du cinéma français (Paris: Editions Arcanes,<br />

Collection Ombres Blanches, 1954). p. 138.


138 / To Desire Differently<br />

(6. Ado Kyrou, Le Surréalisme au cinéma (Paris: Editions Arcanes, 1953), p.<br />

186.<br />

7. Germaine Dulac, "L'Essence du cinéma: L'Idée visuelle," Les Cahiers du<br />

mois, nos. 16/17 (1925): 64. An alternative translation of this article by Robert<br />

Lamberton, can be found in The Avant-Garde Film: A Reader of Theory and<br />

Criticism, ed. P. Adams Sitney (New York: New York University Press, 1978),<br />

pp. 36-42.<br />

8. Dulac, "Les Procédés," p. 68.<br />

9. Germaine Dulac, "La Musique du silence," Cinégraphie, no. 5 (January<br />

15, 1928): 78.<br />

10. Dulac, "La Musique." The identical statement appears in Dulac's "Films<br />

visuels et anti-visuels," Le Rouge et le noir (July 1928); anthologized in L'Art du<br />

cinema, ed. Pierre Lherminier (Paris: Editions Seghers, 1960), p. 71.<br />

11. See Richard Abel's insightful discussion of the film in French Cinema:<br />

The First Wave, 1915-1929 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986), pp.<br />

340-44.<br />

12. This categorization of subjective images is proposed by Jean Mitry in<br />

Esthétique et psychologie du cinéma, vol. 2 (Paris: Editions Universitaires, 1965),<br />

pp. 61-79.<br />

13. Germaine Dulac, "Les Procédés expressifs du cinématographe," Cinémagazine,<br />

no. 27 (July 4, 1924): 17.<br />

14. Germaine Dulac, "Le cinéma d'avant-garde," in Le Cinéma des origines à<br />

nos jours, ed. Henri Fescourt (Paris: Editions du Cygne, 1932), p. 359. An<br />

alternate translation can be found in The Avant-Garde Film ed. Sitney, pp. 43—<br />

48.<br />

15. Dulac, "Les Procédés," Cinémagazine, no. 28 (July 11, 1924): 67.<br />

16. Virginia Woolf, "Modern Fiction," in The Common Reader (1925; repr.<br />

New York: Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich, 1953), p. 154. There is much suggested<br />

by the parallels between Dulac and Woolf, not the least of which are the<br />

"multiple and contradictory interior impressions" that form the cornerstone of<br />

each woman's artistic practice. The possibilities for a study along these lines<br />

are endlessly suggestive.<br />

17. Laplanche and Pontalis, The Language, p. 318.<br />

18. Anonymous, "Un rêve à l'écran," Cinégiaphie, no. 2 (October 15, 1927):<br />

32. This appears to be a press release announcing the opening of the film at<br />

the end of October, a screening that in fact never took place. There is reason<br />

to believe that this text (or portions of it) were written by Yvonne Allendy,<br />

Artaud's close friend (and, ironically, the same person who was instrumental<br />

in the subsequent attacks on Dulac for having "distorted" the scenario by,<br />

among other things, calling it a "dream").<br />

Once the initial agreement with Germaine Dulac was reached, Yvonne<br />

Allendy increased communiques to the press announcing the film; she<br />

continued to do this during the film's shooting, and once completed, in the<br />

weeks preceding its opening; the accent was always placed on the film's<br />

uniqueness in being made of a single dream. In the beginning of October<br />

Beudet and Seashell / 139<br />

1927, Yvonne Allendy wrote an advance publicity release (we do not know<br />

if it was ever published and are working from drafts [provided by Colette<br />

Allendy]) which carried the same assertion and whose prospective titles (A<br />

Dream-Scenario, A Dream in the Camera, A Dream on the Screen) are<br />

sufficiently characteristic. (Editors, Les Oeuvres completes d´Antonin Artaud,<br />

vol. 3 [Paris: Editions Gallimard, 1978], p. 327.)<br />

(Further references will be noted as OC; this volume contains all of Artaud's<br />

film scenarios, letters, and texts concerning the cinema. The edition date is<br />

important, as each edition of OC contains new material and different pagination.)<br />

A number of Artaud's scenarios and texts on the cinema, translated into<br />

English, can be found in TDR 11:1 (Fall 1966): 166-85, as well as in the Susan<br />

Sontag anthology, Antonin Artaud: Selected Writings (New York: Farrar, Straus,<br />

and Giroux, 1976).<br />

19. Laplanche and Pontalis, The Language, p. 318.<br />

20. Alain Virmaux and Odette Virmaux, Les Surréalistes et le cinéma (Paris:<br />

Editions Seghers, 1976), p. 29.<br />

21. See chapter 2, note 49.<br />

22. Although Dulac's film follows the scenario, image for image, with extreme<br />

precision, there is still a very complex relation between the two texts,<br />

and this is what I explore in detail in my article "The Image and the Spark:<br />

Dulac and Artaud Reviewed," in Dada and Surrealist Film, ed. Rudolf E. Kuenzli<br />

(New York: Willis Locker and Owens, 1987), pp. 110-27, where I discuss the<br />

Dulac-Artaud debate in terms of conflicting aesthetic theories of Symbolist<br />

poetic fusion and Surrealist juxtaposition. I trace the actual conflict between<br />

Dulac and Artaud over the production of the film in detail in my Ph.D.<br />

dissertation, "Women, Representation, and Cinematic Discourse: The Example<br />

of the French Cinema," University of California at Berkeley, 1982.<br />

23. Antonin Artaud, letter to Jean Paulhan, January 22, 1932, reprinted<br />

in OC, pp. 259-60. A translation by Helen R. Weaver can be found in Sontag,<br />

Antonin Artaud, p. 281. To further confuse matters, a very serious error exists<br />

in some American prints of the film, something that continues to be corrected,<br />

but that has already led to some critical misinterpretations. For some reason,<br />

when the film's three reels were initially spliced in the United States, the last<br />

reel found its way into the middle of the film, making American prints end<br />

with an image of the woman's severed head inside a glass ball. Both the correct<br />

version of the film and the scenario itself end with the clergyman drinking<br />

the black liquid from the shell. Within each of the three reels, however, the<br />

order of individual shots is correct, making the basic sequence structure<br />

uniform in all prints of the film. It is the order of the sequencing that is incorrect<br />

in the U.S. prints, and although the Museum of Modern Art has rectified this<br />

mistake, other distributors have failed to do so. William Van Wert's widely<br />

read article, "Germaine Dulac: First Feminist Filmmaker," for example, bases<br />

its entire argument on the incorrect sequencing and its mistaken ending.<br />

24. Artaud, "La Coquille et le clergyman," Cahiers de Belgique, no. 8 (October<br />

1928) reprinted in OC, p. 71.


140 / To Desire Differently<br />

25. Artaud, "Le cinéma et l'abstraction," Le Monde illustré, no. 3645 (October<br />

29, 1927) reprinted in OC, pp. 68—69, emphasis added.<br />

26. "Le Cinéma et l'abstraction," OC, p. 69<br />

27. Ibid.<br />

28. Artaud, "Cinéma et réalité," La Nouvelle revue française, no. 170, November<br />

1, 1927, reprinted in OC, p. 19. Artaud had wanted to clarify his position<br />

about the scenario in relation to Dulac's film, and proposed an article to Jean<br />

Paulhan, stating, "I have something to defend, and an article could help me<br />

defend my film without attacking anyone, in order to more clearly determine<br />

my position in relation to this film" (letter to Jean Paulhan, August 29, 1927,<br />

reprinted in OC, p. 127). "Cinéma et réalité" was suggested for the October<br />

issue of La NRF, but actually appeared in November, functioning as an introduction<br />

to the scenario. Alternative translations of this text are widely available.<br />

For a more thorough discussion of this particular passage in relation to the<br />

film's strategies, see my " 'Poetry of the Unconscious': Circuits of Desire in<br />

Two Films by Germaine Dulac," in French Cinema: Text and Contexts, ed. Susan<br />

Hayward and Gi<strong>net</strong>te Vincendeau (London: Methuen, 1989).<br />

29. "Cinéma et réalité," OC, p. 19; emphasis added.<br />

30. Ibid.<br />

31. The scenario for The Seashell and the Clergyman is reprinted in OC, pp.<br />

18-25. There is a translation by Victor Corti in TDR 11:1 (Fall 1966): 173-8.<br />

32. Artaud, letter to Dulac, September 25, 1927, reprinted in OC, p. 128.<br />

33. Scenario, OC, p. 22.<br />

34. Scenario, OC, p. 23.<br />

35. Artaud, "Sorcellerie et cinéma," OC, p. 66. Written at the time of the<br />

shooting of Seashell, this article does not appear to have been published until<br />

1949, when it appeared in the catalogue of the Festival du Film Maudit,<br />

Biarritz, July 29-August 5, 1949. Translations are in TDR, pp. 178-80, The<br />

Avant-Garde Film, pp. 49—50, and The Shadow and its Shadow: Surrealist Writings<br />

on Cinema, ed. Paul Hammond (London: British Film Institute, 1978), pp. 63—<br />

64.<br />

36. Scenario, OC, p. 21.<br />

37. Mary Ann Doane, "Woman's Slake: Filming the Female Body," October,<br />

no. 17 (Summer 1981): 34.<br />

38. Doane, "Woman's Stake," p. 33.<br />

39. Ibid., p. 36.<br />

40. Dulac, "Du Movement, des harmonies, et du rhythme: A la Symphonie<br />

visuelle." p. 6, chapter 8 of an unpublished manuscript of texts collected by<br />

Marie-Anne Colson-Malleville.<br />

FIVE<br />

Marie Epstein:<br />

A Woman in the Shadows<br />

MARIF. EPSTEIN'S CAREER AS A FILMMAKER offers something more of a<br />

challenge from the standpoint of an argument that seeks to establish<br />

an alternative tradition of feminist cinema, for while Germaine Dulac's<br />

filmmaking practice can be seen to demonstrate a consistent project<br />

of resistance to traditional cinematic norms—from the dual perspective<br />

of both aesthetic issues and feminist theory—Epstein's work is, in<br />

fact, fairly exemplary of French filmmaking in the thirties. All of the<br />

major directors of the period conceived of their films as efforts to<br />

establish a national cinematic identity—each in their own way posing<br />

a form of opposition to the dominant commercial cinema of Hollywood<br />

by making films "in the French manner." However, Marie Epstein's<br />

films can also be seen to resist this French standard, placing<br />

her work in the status of double-rupture in relation to the cinematic<br />

mainstreams of both Hollywood and France. For one thing, Epstein<br />

is virtually unknown to the conventional film histories, and for this<br />

reason her very specific marginalization implies a position at the borders<br />

of the cinematic activity of the time. But more important for<br />

the purposes of this study, Epstein's concerted focus on "feminine"<br />

questions—issues of the maternal, of the domestic, of female bonding—and<br />

her reworking of basic cinematic structures of point-of-view<br />

and identification along these lines, offer a form of textual resistance<br />

whose challenge to the mainstream can only be discerned in terms of<br />

sustained analysis of her films. To begin the work of elaborating<br />

Epstein's significant contribution to a feminist theorization of the cinema,<br />

then, a form of "feminist archaeology" is first necessary.


Linda WILLIAMS: Un Chien andalou. In: Dies.: Figures of Desire. A<br />

Theory and Analysis of Surrealist Film. Univ. of Calif. Press 1981, S.<br />

53-105.<br />

CHAPTER TWO<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

New images will come to follow the free bent of desire<br />

at the same time as they are vigorously repressed.<br />

Un Chien andalou (The Andalusian Dog) 1929<br />

SALVADOR DALI'<br />

Production: Luis Bunuel.<br />

Director: Luis Bunuel.<br />

Script: Luis Bunuel, Salvador Dali.<br />

Photography: Albert Duverger.<br />

Design: Pierre Schilzneck.<br />

Editor: Luis Bunuel.<br />

Music: At its first performance the film was accompanied by gramophone<br />

records, including Wagner's Tristan and Isolde and some<br />

Argentine tangos. In 1960 Bunuel advised on the compilation of<br />

a score for a synchronized version based on the 1929 musical<br />

selections.<br />

Leading Players: Pierre Batcheff (The Man); Simone Mareuil (The<br />

Woman); Jaime Miratvilles; Salvador Dali (Marist Priest). 17 minutes.<br />

Black and White.<br />

IN 1929 Luis Bunuel and Salvador Dali's short film Un Chien andalou<br />

1 burst upon the Paris scene, an instant success in Surrealist and<br />

1 Dali, "The Stinking Ass," trans. ]. Bronowsky, This Quarter 5 (September 1932): 49-54;<br />

reprinted in Lucy Lippard, ed., Surrealists on Art (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall,<br />

1970). Originally published as "L'Ane pourri," in Le Surrealisms au service de la revolution<br />

1:12.<br />

" Bunuel directed from a scenario written by himself and Dali. Much has been written<br />

about the respective contributions of each man. Although Dali was present only on the last<br />

day of shooting, Bunuel gives him equal credit for creation of the scenario: " 'The film was<br />

50% of each of us. ... I did the cutting of the eye and the ants in the hand; Dali did the<br />

garden scene and the cocktail shaker bell.'" Francisco Aranda, Luis Bunuel: A Critical Biography,<br />

trans, and ed. David Robinson (New York: Da Capo Press, 1976), p. 60. Many com-<br />

53


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

other avant-garde circles and the apparent fulfillment of the many<br />

Surrealist hopes for the cinema. Ever since, this short seventeenminute<br />

film has enjoyed a privileged position in film history, considered<br />

variously as: the primary source for the spread of a Surrealist<br />

style in the commercial cinema, the first film to assault its spectator<br />

systematically, the classic example of cinematic poetry, and an important<br />

precursor of the current American avant-garde.'<br />

In an extended article Philip Drummond shows how the above<br />

accolades have, for half a century, replaced and obscured any serious<br />

understanding of the text by so many "presumed moments of<br />

historico-aesthetic impact and effect." 4 Drummond s detailed analysis<br />

of the film is an important corrective to the kind of impressionistic<br />

rewriting to which the film has so often been subjected, and I<br />

highly recommend it on that account.<br />

The aim of my own analysis is somewhat different. If, as Artaud<br />

suggests, Surrealist film can offer the cinematic equivalent of the<br />

"mechanics of the dream" and if, as is widely recognized, Un Chien<br />

andalou is the most successfully oneiric of Surrealist films, it is important<br />

to discover what these mechanics are all about. The aim of<br />

the following section is to establish the methodological groundwork<br />

for analysis of the dreamlike rhetoric that dominates the film. With<br />

this groundwork I hope to offer: (1) a close analysis of the peculiar<br />

form of the Surrealist figure in film, (2) a subsequent analysis of the<br />

latent meaning of these figures in relation to the text as a whole, and<br />

(3) a rhetorico-psychoanalytic reading of the entire film.<br />

The Rhetoric of the Unconscious. Unconscious desire cannot be<br />

named. As Freud defines it, it is forbidden a normal mode of dis-<br />

mentators, Aranda included, tend to attribute positive credit to Buiiuel, negative credit—for<br />

snobism and avant-garde preciosity—to Dali (ibid., p. 60). This is a tempting view, since Dali<br />

had much less to do with their following "collaboration" on L'Age d'or and since he appears to<br />

have a long history of behaving irresponsibly toward Bunuel. Nevertheless, as far as the scenario<br />

goes, ir seems more reasonable to accept Bunuel's word on their equal collaboration<br />

than to allow current anti-Dali sentiment to lead us astray.<br />

'Philip Drummond cites the sources for these prevalent views in "Textual Space in Un<br />

Chien Andalou," Screen 18 (Autumn 1977): 55.<br />

4 Ibid., p. 56.<br />

54<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

course; it can only be registered by its transgressions. For the psychoanalyst<br />

these transgressions are the slips and repetitions that do violence<br />

to originally intended speech. In dreams they are memory<br />

traces divested of their original meaning by the hidden discourse of<br />

the unconscious. 5<br />

The way in which the unconscious accomplishes these transgressions<br />

is not in itself codified in the same way a linguistic system is<br />

codified. Emile Benveniste points out that it is only in the broad<br />

sense of a general linguistic capacity, as langage rather than langue<br />

(a specific system or code), that one can speak of "language" in dreams<br />

or other unconscious expressions. 6 Benveniste continues that it is<br />

really in the secondary procedures of what is commonly referred<br />

to as style that one encounters the qualities that constitute unconscious<br />

langage. He explains that the unconscious makes use of a<br />

rhetoric which, like style, has its figures. The old catalog of tropes<br />

can thus provide an inventory suitable to it.'<br />

Jacques Lacan, in his essay "The agency of the letter in the unconscious<br />

or reason since Freud" carries Benveniste's original observation<br />

a step further by drawing an analogy between the primary<br />

figures of new rhetoric—metaphor and metonymy—and the procedures<br />

of condensation and displacement in dreams. 8 Lacan suggests<br />

that condensation and displacement in dreams are primary<br />

processes that temporarily bind the psychic energy of desire in ways<br />

similar to the temporary poetic binding of meaning in metaphor<br />

and metonymy. This is not to say that metaphor and metonymy<br />

are the same as condensation and displacement. Dreams are unconscious<br />

productions, and poems are for the most part conscious<br />

productions. For this reason I prefer to retain the poetic/rhetorical<br />

terms metaphor and metonymy, but with the ultimate purpose of<br />

discovering how a specifically Surrealist use of these rhetorical procedures<br />

resembles the unconscious procedure of "dream work."<br />

5 Lacan, he Seminaire, vol. 1, Les Ecrits techniques de Freud, p. 270.<br />

6 Emile Benveniste, "Remarques sur la fonction du langage dans la decouverte freudienne,"<br />

Problemes de linguistique generate (Paris: Gallimard, 1966), p. 86.<br />

7 Ibid.<br />

Lacan, Ecrits, pp. 146-75,<br />

55


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

JAKOBSON'S METAPHOR AND METONYMY:<br />

RHETORICAL FIGURES IN FILM<br />

When Lacan first noted the resemblance between Freud's condensation<br />

and displacement and Roman Jakobson's rhetorical concept of<br />

metaphor and metonymy, he acknowledged the importance of Jakobson's<br />

reformulation of the old catalog of tropes into a more modern,<br />

restricted rhetoric.consisting of two main figures: metaphor and<br />

metonymy. 9 This restricted rhetoric 1 " was composed of two basic<br />

kinds of figures modeled on the binary oppositions of structural linguistics:<br />

paradigm and syntagm. Since the rhetorical notions of metaphor<br />

and metonymy derive from the parallel with the linguistic<br />

function of paradigm and syntagm, it is important to describe what<br />

these linguistic functions are.<br />

The structural linguistics of Ferdinand Saussure show that language<br />

has two fundamental axes. The first, a paradigmatic axis,<br />

functions to select the elements of any given utterance according to<br />

certain rules or paradigms. A paradigm is the theoretical reconstruction<br />

of the linguistic choices made by every speaker of a language.<br />

These choices are made among similar things. "'Did you say pig or<br />

fig,' said the cat. i said pig,' replied Alice." Thus Jakobson explains<br />

that phonologically the cat was attempting to recapture a linguistic<br />

choice made by Alice. "In the common code of the cat and Alice<br />

. . . the difference between a stop and a continuant, other things<br />

being equal, may change the meaning of the message."" Alice has<br />

made a paradigmatic selection from similar—phonological—elements.<br />

The second, a syntagmatic axis, refers to the way in which<br />

the elements actually present in the verbal chain are arranged. Here<br />

the key function is the combination of contiguous elements along<br />

Roman Jakobson has written several articles on aphasia, all of which are reprinted in<br />

volume 2 of his Selected Writings, 2 vols. (The Hague: Mouton, 1971). The most famous of<br />

these, the one to which I refer, is the 1956 article "Two Aspects of Language and Two Types of<br />

Aphasic Disturbances," pp. 239-59. For a brief history and description of the "old catalogue<br />

of tropes" that Jakobson is reformulating, see Roland Barthes, "L'Ancienne rhetorique: Aidememoire,"<br />

Communications 16 (1970): 172-230.<br />

10 The term restricted rhetoric is Gerard Ge<strong>net</strong>te's. See his "La rhetorique restreinte,"<br />

Communications 16 (1970): 158-71.<br />

"jakobson, Selected Writings, 2:241.<br />

56<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

the chain of discourse: how Alice put together the contiguous phonological,<br />

morphological, and syntactical elements she has already<br />

chosen. Every speech act, Saussure shows, encompasses both these<br />

functions.<br />

Jakobson's article on language and aphasic disturbances shows<br />

how this binary division of structural linguistics applies to two very<br />

similar divisions in aphasic speech disorders. Jakobson suggests that<br />

two rhetorical figures selected from the catalogs of classical rhetoricians<br />

can be used to simplify and revitalize rhetorical analyses<br />

in literature and the visual arts. Thus, he proposes that metaphor<br />

and metonymy are the two quintessential rhetorical figures, because<br />

they have polar axes similar to those of paradigm and syntagm. 12<br />

Jakobson explains that the one thing (linguistic) paradigms, (rhetorical)<br />

metaphors, and the so-called aphasic "contiguity disorder"<br />

have in common is similarity: all derive from the selection of features<br />

from among similar things. On the other hand, syntagms, metonymies,<br />

and the aphasic "similarity disorder" are all marked by the<br />

function of contiguity, the combination of contiguous and present<br />

elements. Aphasic similarity disorder affects a speaker's ability to select<br />

words or phrases from the paradigmatic language code that<br />

is organized according to similar categories. Contiguity disorder affects<br />

a speaker's ability to arrange these elements contiguously. The<br />

speaker with a contiguity disorder will therefore rely heavily on the<br />

other pole of language, choosing similar or "metaphoric" formulations<br />

from the paradigm. In response to the word microscope, such<br />

an aphasic might substitute the similar word spyglass, but he or she<br />

would have difficulty providing the linguistic context for the word in<br />

a full sentence. On the contrary, a speaker with a similarity disorder<br />

would find it difficult to select similar terms from a paradigm. Such<br />

speakers would find it hard to name, provide synonyms for, or metalinguistically<br />

define a given term. For example, when shown a pencil,<br />

an aphasic with similarity disorder would not be able to name it<br />

but would, instead, veer off to a contiguous quality or function and<br />

say something like "to write." 1 '<br />

Jakobson applies the underlying linguistic categories of similarity<br />

"Ibid., pp. 244-56.<br />

'Ibid., p. 247.<br />

57


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

and contiguity (or selection and combination) to larger stylistic (or<br />

aphasic) idiosyncrasies of metaphor and metonymy. 14 In so doing he<br />

draws the important lesson that similarities that underlie metaphor<br />

have been given much attention in stylistic analyses, while contiguities<br />

that underlie metonymy have been rather ignored. We<br />

hardly notice, for example, that Anna Karenina's handbag becomes<br />

a metonymic figure for the heroine herself in her famous suicide<br />

scene in Tolstoy's novel. Jakobson's point is that we tend not to<br />

notice that metonymies are figures, because the fact that they are<br />

based on real or virtual spatial contiguities makes them seem so<br />

much more realistic than metaphoric associations based upon similarity<br />

alone.<br />

At the end of his article Jakobson suggests that metaphoric and<br />

metonymic poles of stylistic expression occur in film. But he does<br />

not say how this is so other than that the work of Griffith is predominantly<br />

metonymic, while the work of Chaplin and Eisenstein is<br />

predominantly metaphoric. ' 5 Although this statement is extremely<br />

suggestive, Jakobson does not tackle the very difficult problem of<br />

tracing the differences between verbal and visual figurations. Yet,<br />

often when we talk about metaphors in film, we really think of the<br />

model of verbal metaphors. Verbal metaphors are built out of the<br />

transgression of coded linguistic meanings. On the purely denotative,<br />

linguistic level, the phrase my love is a flame makes no sense,<br />

because love is not a flame. On the connotative, rhetorical level,<br />

however, the word flame has undergone a change of meaning. A<br />

figural meaning arises out of the discrepancy between the coded,<br />

literal meanings of the two parts of the statement. This discrepancy<br />

between what I. A. Richards 16 calls tenor (the underlying idea of<br />

love) and vehicle (the flame with which love is compared) forges the<br />

discovery of a new meaning that is based upon the ground of their<br />

14 Jakobson himself does not always keep these linguistic and rhetorical levels separate.<br />

Christian Metz, in "Metaphore/Metonymie, ou le referent imaginarie" (Le Signifiant imaginaire,<br />

pp. 224-29), clarifies Jakobson by stressing the difference between the coded linguistic<br />

level of the discourse and the uncoded rhetorical level of the referent. I mention this now to<br />

avoid confusion later.<br />

15 Jakobson, Selected Writings, 2:256.<br />

16 1. A. Richards, Philosophy of Rhetoric (New York; Oxford University Press, 1936, 197 r),<br />

p. 96.<br />

58<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

shared characteristic of heat. The metaphor is composed of both<br />

halves of the statement.<br />

But in film, the image of a flame is not an arbitrarily coded link<br />

between a sound and a concept. If a filmmaker uses the image of a<br />

flame as a metaphor for love, this visual flame rather stubbornly remains<br />

a flame, at least more stubbornly than the word. (If one<br />

thinks of all the love scenes in films that take place adjacent to fireplaces,<br />

it is clear that such "figures" are only loose approximations<br />

of the love-flame equation in the verbal metaphor. In fact, they are<br />

very often partial metonymies owing to the fact that the fireplace<br />

and its flame are contiguously related to the lovers.)<br />

One result of Jakobson's reformulation of old rhetoric into two<br />

binary figures has been to encourage a great many studies in film<br />

(and literary) metonymy. 1 Rather than the loose application of the<br />

poetic term metaphor, film analysis now tends to focus on metonymy<br />

to the extent that film has often been defined as an essentially<br />

metonymic art. Film metaphors have been pushed aside, as if to<br />

make up for all the years metaphor reigned supreme.<br />

An extreme but typical instance of this antimetaphoric tendency<br />

is film historian and aesthetician Jean Mitry's insistence that film<br />

metaphors do not actually exist. Mitry argues that most of what are<br />

called film metaphors are not true metaphors at all but rather at<br />

least partial metonymies. He cites as an example a famous close-up<br />

of the pince-nez of the ship's doctor caught in the ropes of the ship<br />

in Eisenstein's Potemkin, after the doctor himself had been thrown<br />

overboard. Mitry argues that the pince-nez is not so much a metaphor<br />

founded on similarity between the upperclass doctor and his<br />

glasses as a metonymy based upon the fact that the glasses and the<br />

doctor have been contiguously associated with each other previously<br />

in the film. 18<br />

Here Mitry simply gives a more elaborate theoretical basis to the<br />

general notion mentioned above—that in film metaphor the flame<br />

and pince-nez, unlike the words for these things, seem to be really<br />

' One of the best analyses of metonymy in literature is Gerard Ge<strong>net</strong>te's "Metonvmie<br />

chez Proust." Figures III (Paris: Seuil, 1972), pp. 41-66.<br />

Jean Mitry, Esthetique et psychologic du cinema, 2 vols. (Paris: Editions universitaires,<br />

1963), 1:120-22.<br />

59


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

there. If they don't have a reason to be there, Mitry argues, they<br />

disrupt what is often felt to be the film's primary function of narration.<br />

Mitry generalizes this notion to proclaim that film, unlike verbal<br />

language, cannot accommodate metaphors that do not arise<br />

from the given space or imaginary world of the narrative—from<br />

what he and other French critics refer to as its diegesis. 19 In other<br />

words, since film must use images to create its diegetic illusion of a<br />

world, any figural connotation that comes from outside this world<br />

goes against the grain of filmic creation; it is a conceptual intrusion<br />

appropriate to verbal language but not to film.<br />

Mitry's pronouncements are important because they articulate<br />

narrative norms that are often implied in analyses of films. But although<br />

Mitry is correct to show that many so-called film metaphors<br />

are in fact partial metonymies, he is wrong to deny the existence of<br />

"pure" filmic metaphor. Such a denial leads him to dismiss such<br />

metaphors as the two shots that open Chaplin's Modern Times. This<br />

famous metaphor—a shot of a crowd of sheep herded to the slaughter<br />

followed by a similar crowd of workers pressing into a subway<br />

entrance—points out the function of workers in a machine-dominated,<br />

depersonalized society. Metaphoric similarity between the<br />

herd of sheep and the "herd" of workers suggests that workers are as<br />

faceless and submissive as sheep herded to the slaughter. Mitry<br />

would claim that, since the sheep don't belong to the modern urban<br />

world of the diegesis (they are extradiegetic), the metaphor defeats<br />

the realistic thrust of all filmic discourse and thus weakens Chaplin's<br />

film. He adds that even this metaphor is not entirely pure, since the<br />

sheep are present in the image chain along with the workers; they<br />

have not taken their place. Thus Mitry also defines metaphor substitutional^:<br />

as only that instance where, in a verbal metaphor, the<br />

word flame replaces the word love (my flame burns) and, in a film<br />

Diegesis is an important term in the analyses of Un Chien andalou and L'Age d'or that<br />

follow. The term was first coined by Etienne Souriau to indicate the denotative material of a<br />

film. Christian Metz explains that the term is derived from the Greek St^Acri? meaning narration<br />

but also relating to the represented instance—the ficitonal space and time dimension<br />

implied in and by the narrative. It is thus contrasted with the aesthetic instance of the film, its<br />

connotative or figural level, which, according to Metz, comes later, building upon the diegesis.<br />

Christian Metz, Film Language, trans. Michael Taylor, (New York: Oxford University<br />

Press, 1974), p. 97.<br />

60<br />

«•«<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

metaphor, where the shot of the sheep replaces the shot of the<br />

workers.<br />

But if Jakobson's binary rhetorical division is to be useful as a way<br />

of talking about filmic or any other kind of figures, these divisions<br />

must be able to accommodate all existing practices. It is no solution<br />

to disallow metaphor in film, when the films of Chaplin, Eisenstein,<br />

and Bunuel all contain such metaphors. The real question is<br />

how these figures operate.<br />

In this connection I would like to mention a very helpful elaboration<br />

of Jakobson's rhetoric proposed by Christian Metz. 2 " Metz<br />

shows that, in spite of jakobson's expansion of verbal rhetoric to include<br />

visual figures, there is a persistent tendency, even in Jakobson's<br />

work, to define film rhetoric in terms of verbal tropes. When<br />

Mitry says the Modern Times metaphor is not a metaphor because it<br />

lacks substitution, he is thinking in terms of the verbal definition of<br />

a trope—one word or expression used for another. Metz suggests,<br />

however, that both in language and in film there are really two ways<br />

in which a figure can be deployed, and only one of them is an actual<br />

substitution. The first and more common way is for a metaphor<br />

(or metonymy) to be arranged syntagmatically in the verbal or image<br />

chain. The second, less common way, is for the figure to be arranged<br />

paradigmatically—condensed in such a way that the given<br />

element of the figure implies the part that is not given. 21<br />

With this distinction, Metz suggests that we must be careful not<br />

to confuse the referential axis of rhetoric with the discursive axis of<br />

linguistics. What has often happened in past rhetorical analyses<br />

is that, since the phenomenon of contiguity is common to both<br />

metonymy and syntagm, contiguity of the discourse (syntagm) is<br />

confused with contiguity of the referent (metonymy). In like manner,<br />

since similarity or contrast is common to both metaphor and<br />

paradigm, it is easy to confuse similarity or contrast of the discourse<br />

(paradigm) with that of the referent (metaphor). In critical practice<br />

this commonly means that the observations made about metonymy<br />

are actually pertinent to a discussion of syntagm, while the observations<br />

about metaphor are pertinent to paradigm. Proof of this con-<br />

" Metz, "Metaphore/Metonymie," pp. 177-371.<br />

21 Ibid., pp. 224-29.<br />

61


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

fusion is often provided in the tacit assumption that metonymies,<br />

like syntagms, are always spread out along the horizontal axis of the<br />

discourse, while metaphors, like paradigms, can only appear vertically,<br />

as implied but absent terms.<br />

Metz preserves the primary rhetorical categories of metaphor and<br />

metonymy while providing a secondary stipulation as to how the<br />

figure is deployed on the linguistic level of the discourse. Out of<br />

Jakobson's original binary division, Metz develops a four-part classification<br />

consisting of: (1) Metaphors placed in syntagm (similarity—<br />

or comparability—on the level of the referent plus contiguity on the<br />

level of the discourse). Such metaphors can either be pure, as in the<br />

extradiegetic example of sheep plus workers from Modern Times, or<br />

diegetic, as in the shot of Clive Brook and Marlene Dietrich's kiss<br />

on a train followed by the train whistle blowing in the film Shanghai<br />

Express. (2) Metaphors placed in paradigm (similarity—or comparability—on<br />

the level of the referent plus comparability on the<br />

level of the discourse). Here, a single comparable element of an<br />

originally two-part metaphor placed in a syntagm comes to stand for<br />

the thing being compared. Thus (in a diegetic example) in a love<br />

scene that takes place before a fire, the fire can come to stand for<br />

(and replace) the passion of the embracing couple. (3) Metonymies<br />

placed in paradigm (contiguity on the level of the referent plus comparability<br />

on the level of the discourse). Here, as above, one element<br />

replaces another, but in this case the original association of<br />

elements is based on metonymic contiguity rather than similarity or<br />

contrast. A classic example cited by Metz is the moment in Fritz<br />

Lang's M when a balloon, which had earlier been contiguously associated<br />

with a little girl, is shown all alone, caught in a web of telephone<br />

wires. The balloon replaces the murdered body of the girl<br />

herself in much the same way Anna Karenina's handbag comes to<br />

stand for Anna's crushed body. (4) Metonymies placed in syntagm<br />

(contiguity of the referents plus contiguity of the discourse). This is<br />

similar to (3), except that both elements of the metonymy are present<br />

in the image chain as, for example, the earlier moments in M<br />

when both balloon and girl appear together. n<br />

What happens most often in narrative films is that a metaphor or<br />

metonymy first placed in syntagm will at some later point be placed<br />

22 Ibid.<br />

62<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

in paradigm. Metz's elaboration allows us to keep the rhetorical and<br />

linguistic levels separate so that we can more completely describe<br />

the operations of the figure and the way it is deployed in the actual<br />

discourse. The usefulness of this distinction will, I hope, become<br />

evident in the analysis of the prologue to Un Chien andalou that<br />

follows.<br />

THE PROLOGUE TO UN CHIEN ANDALOU:<br />

A SURREALIST FILM METAPHOR<br />

The famous metaphor of moon and eye that concludes the prologue<br />

to Un Chien andalou is perhaps the most often cited example of<br />

filmic Surrealism—to the extent that audiences usually remember<br />

it and forget the rest of the film. The image of a woman's eye cut<br />

open by a razor has been isolated as a still in countless posters, film<br />

histories, and anthologies, to become the very emblem of surreality<br />

in film in much the same way as Dalfs melting watches have functioned<br />

in painting. But this image has not been sufficiently studied<br />

as a metaphor. It is, after all, the bizarre similarity between the eye<br />

cut by a razor and the moon cut by a horizontal sliver of a cloud that<br />

is so striking in this episode. In this section I propose to concentrate<br />

exclusively on the peculiar form of this most famous Surrealist<br />

metaphor.<br />

Description of the Prologue. The prologue is composed of what appears<br />

to be an entire scene played out in the space on and near a<br />

balcony bathed in moonlight. It begins with the title, "Once upon a<br />

time." Apart from this title the sequence has only twelve shots. The<br />

following is a numbered description of each shot, including a camera-distance<br />

scale.<br />

Title: "Once upon a time . . ."<br />

SHOT DESCRIPTION SCALE<br />

1 Fade-in on two hands sharpening a long razor on a Close-up<br />

strop attached to the door-handle of a French-window.<br />

Hands are viewed from above and behind. A<br />

watch is on the left wrist. Four strokes of the razor.<br />

63


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

2 Head and shoulders of man, cigarette in mouth, eyes Close-up<br />

lowered, in three-quarter right profile. The man is<br />

wearing a striped, collarless shirt. A curtained window<br />

is visible to right of frame.<br />

3 As in l. Razor blade is tested for sharpness on the Close-up<br />

thumbnail of the left hand.<br />

4 As in 2. Close-up<br />

5 Man in left profile standing before window-door with Medium<br />

curtains. He looks at strop, razor, then opens Frenchwindow<br />

to go outside.<br />

6 Reverse frontal of balcony and man walking out onto Medium<br />

it. He looks out across balcony (in general direction<br />

of spectator) and walks to edge where he leans on<br />

railing, razor still in hand.<br />

7 Head and shoulders of man in three-quarter right Close-up<br />

profile. He raises head to look up.<br />

8 Dark sky with moon on screen left. A horizontal Long shot<br />

sliver of cloud approaches from the right.<br />

9 As in 7. Close-up<br />

10 Direct frontal view of woman's face staring at specta- Close-up<br />

tor. To left and slightly behind is torso of man wearing<br />

striped shirt, a diagonally striped tie, and no<br />

watch. As his left hand holds open her left eye his<br />

right hand moves in front of the lower part of her<br />

face, as if preparing to draw razor across the round<br />

exposed eye.<br />

11 As in 8. The cloud now passes before the moon. Long shot<br />

12 The eye with thumb and forefinger holding it open. Extreme<br />

The razor slices it open. A jellylike substance spills close-up<br />

out.<br />

Shots 1-4. The prologue opens on a high-angle close-up of a man's<br />

hands sharpening a long razor on a strop. The four strokes of this<br />

sharpening correspond to the four-shot alternating syntagm (1-4) of<br />

the entire sharpening action. In shot 2 (close-up of the man's head<br />

and shoulders, cigarette in mouth), it is only by the downward direction<br />

of the man's glance that we infer the diegetic contiguity of<br />

shots 1 and 2, e.g., that these hands and arms are connected to the<br />

64<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

head and shoulders which follow. Shots 3 and 4 repeat this same<br />

procedure with the slight difference in shot 4 that the razor is now<br />

tested for sharpness on the thumbnail of the left hand—the first instance<br />

of a horizontal line bisecting a circular shape. Though shots<br />

1 and 3 (looking down on the razor and hands) are not viewed from<br />

precisely the same angle at which the man would see them, the<br />

downward angle of the shot, from above and behind the hands and<br />

a little to the left, does approximate the subjective viewpoint of his<br />

glance.<br />

So far the diegetic action of a man sharpening a razor has been<br />

placed in an alternating syntagm characterized by the organization<br />

of isolated fragments of space leading to the inference of their connection<br />

in a larger whole. But already there are problems in this<br />

inference. If we look closely at the relation of the arms and hands to<br />

the French door and curtain in shots r and 3, we see that the man's<br />

position in relation to the curtained window close behind this head<br />

in shots 2 and 4 is spatially different in relation to what is presumably<br />

the same (now curtainless) window-door in shots 1 and 3.<br />

Shots 5 and 6. The repetition of close-ups in shots 1-4 gives way in<br />

the middle of the prologue to two medium shots. These shots reinforce<br />

the spectator's previous inference as to the contiguity of hands<br />

and arms (1 and 3) to head and shoulders (2 and 4) by showing the<br />

whole person and the general scene through which he moves. In<br />

shot 6 the French doors behind the man form a horizontal line that<br />

runs into his head at precisely eye level. This is the second instance<br />

of a horizontal line that bisects a round shape.<br />

Shots 7-12. Shots 7, 8, and 9 seem about to repeat the alternating<br />

syntagm of shots 1-4 in which the man's glance is alternated with<br />

the object he sees in a four-shot series. But there are two important<br />

differences. In the first series the order is object-seen + glance,<br />

while here it is the more usual glance (man looks upward at night<br />

sky) + object (insert of moon). In the second series, just at the point<br />

where the pattern glance + moon, glance + . . . creates anticipation<br />

of a return to the moon to continue the already begun movement<br />

of the cloud across the moon, an entirely new element is introduced,<br />

a close-up of a woman's face (shot 10). The seated woman<br />

65


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

66<br />

67


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

is staring directly at the camera; the torso of a (or is it the?) man<br />

stands beside her preparing to cut open her eye. Thus, instead of the<br />

anticipated completion of one diegetic action—the movement of<br />

the cloud across the moon—another, formally similar, action is introduced.<br />

This new action, like the movement of the clouds before<br />

the moon finally completed in shot 11, is also divided into two alternating<br />

shots, culminating in the final shot of the extreme close-up<br />

of the eye cutting. (The movements of cloud across moon and razor<br />

across eyeball are the third and fourth instances of round shapes<br />

bisected by horizontal lines.)<br />

Because it is an action divided into the same kind of alternating<br />

two-shot syntagm as the movement of the clouds across the moon,<br />

this new element of the eye cutting at first seems consistent with the<br />

diegesis in the rest of the prologue. In other words, we tend to read<br />

this action as taking place in the continuous diegetic space of the<br />

balcony and night sky. But at the same time there is no real indication<br />

that this woman whose eye is about to be cut is placed in this<br />

space. We only infer it on the basis of the general contiguity of the<br />

previous syntagms. We tend to assume, for example, that the torso<br />

of the man standing beside her in shot 10 holding a razor and wearing<br />

a striped shirt is the same man we have viewed throughout the<br />

prologue. But, if it is the same man, he has suddenly lost his watch<br />

and acquired a striped tie. And, after solitarily gazing at the sky in<br />

shot g, he is suddenly in an entirely new position as well as in modified<br />

dress in the very next shot. Our tendency to want to absorb a<br />

nondiegetic element that ultimately cannot be absorbed into the diegesis<br />

is an important feature of both this prologue and the film in<br />

general. The result is a subtle tension that seems to emanate from<br />

within the diegesis without allowing us to point to clear-cut instances<br />

of a total rupture with its apparent realism.<br />

This initially subtle spatial discrepancy of the man's position in<br />

shots 1-4 becomes more apparent in shots 8-12, but only as a tension<br />

within a dominant pattern of alternating syntagms that describe<br />

two connected sets of actions: the sharpening and test cutting in<br />

shots 1-5, and the final bisecting (of both moon and eye) in shots<br />

8-12. Both of these actions proceed via the division of what at first<br />

appear to be contiguous fragments of space and time in a conventional<br />

diegetic manner. But on closer examination (almost im-<br />

68<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

perceptibly in the first, and more noticeably in the second) both<br />

subvert the very same assumptions about diegetic space and time<br />

they seem to want us to accept.<br />

The Figure: Metaphor or Metonymy. The rupture in the diegesis<br />

that occurs in the second half of the prologue is a rhetorical figure.<br />

The only apparent motivation for the interruption of the movement<br />

of the cloud across the moon is the formal similarity between the<br />

round shape of the moon and eye, and the thin shape of the cloud<br />

and razor, which "cut" them. Since the motive is similarity of the<br />

(shapes of the) referents rather than an association of contiguity, this<br />

figure is metaphoric rather than metonymic.<br />

Using Christian Metz's four-part division of filmic figuration, we<br />

can see that this is a metapor placed in syntagm. It is a metaphor in<br />

which similarities between the referents—moon and eye, cloud and<br />

razor, and the similar horizontal movements of the latter—are arranged<br />

contiguously (syntagmatically) in the image chain.<br />

To reach an understanding of what is special about this particular<br />

metaphor, it may be helpful to compare it with the much more typical<br />

function of a similar figure in another more typically diegetic<br />

film. In the example from Josef von Sternberg's Shanghai Express<br />

cited above, Glive Brook and Marlene Dietrich's first kiss is followed<br />

by an exterior shot of the train's whistle blowing. These two elements,<br />

kiss (the tenor) and whistle (the vehicle) constitute a diegetic<br />

metaphor placed in syntagm, in which the vehicle "comments"<br />

upon the tenor. The usual procedure in reading such a metaphor is<br />

to construct a connotative system of the referents that can encompass<br />

both elements. Differences between kiss and whistle are minimized,<br />

while their similarities (heat, excitement, pressure) emerge<br />

in a comment upon the sexual excitement of the Dietrich-Brook's<br />

relationship.<br />

This particular metaphor observes a structure typical of many diegetic<br />

metaphors in film: a contiguous background element, the<br />

whistle that is on the same train, is brought momentarily to the foreground<br />

as a comment upon the dominant narrative action of the<br />

kiss. The figure preserves a hierarchy of the tenor belonging to the<br />

diegesis over the vehicle brought into the diegesis momentarily.<br />

Thus the vehicle (the more properly figural element of the meta-<br />

69


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

phor, brought in for purposes of comparison) rarely takes on more<br />

than momentary importance before restoring us to the main action<br />

of the tenor. In the classical metaphor this hierarchy is usually<br />

maintained by the order of appearance of the two parts of the metaphor<br />

placed in syntagm: most often, diegetic action of the tenor is<br />

followed by the comparison of the vehicle commenting upon it.<br />

The whistle emerges as connotatively significant only after the kiss;<br />

the reverse would be less effective. But if this order is reversed, as<br />

for example in the extradiegetic pure metaphor of the herd of sheep<br />

from the opening of Modern Times, in which the shot of the sheep<br />

preceeds the shot of the workers, there is a second way in which the<br />

dominance of the diegesis is assured." The vehicle, whether present<br />

in the diegesis or not, usually belongs to natural, architectural, or<br />

otherwise nonhuman material (in this case the sheep) that seems a<br />

secondary or background element, again maintaining a hierarchy of<br />

diegesis over figure.<br />

In the prologue metaphor, precisely this hierarchy is disturbed.<br />

The distinctive feature of this metaphor is that what would commonly<br />

constitute the tenor or comparing element of the figure—in<br />

this case the moon—is given first. But, not only is it given first, its<br />

entire function builds upon the viewer's expectation of the more<br />

common metaphoric process—of a metaphor that serves the diegesis—while<br />

actually giving a diegesis that serves the metaphor.<br />

Everything happens in this metaphor as if the formal resemblance<br />

between the moon that is "sliced" by cloud and the woman's round<br />

eye elicits the human action of slicing the eye. In other words, there<br />

is a reversal of the usual metaphoric process in which the tenor half<br />

of the metaphor belongs to the action of the diegesis and the vehicle<br />

half belongs to a part of the decor or, in the case of the pure metaphor,<br />

to an entirely extraneous element brought in from outside the<br />

narrative. Instead, the moon and cloud are precisely the kind of extraneous<br />

or background material that would usually come second<br />

and belong to the vehicle, while the eye and the razor, which here<br />

belong to the compared element of the figure, are the kind of<br />

3 The Modern Times metaphor is somewhat of an exception in that the vehicle part of this<br />

metaphor—the sheep—precedes the tenor part—the workers. But this unusual order is because<br />

the metaphor opens the film; it does not disturb the usual hierarchy of diegesis over<br />

figure.<br />

70<br />

Un Chicn andalou<br />

human activity that would usually appear first and belong to the<br />

tenor.<br />

So it is impossible to say that the vehicle element of this metaphor<br />

(moon and cloud) comments on another hierarchically more significant<br />

tenor element belonging to the diegesis (eye and razor). For<br />

here it is precisely the vehicle—the element that usually appears to<br />

be the artificial or consciously constructed part of the figure (the<br />

moon and clouds)—that constitutes the "action" of this sequence.<br />

In other words, the action has shifted to the vehicle part of the figure,<br />

which usually comes second and in which we notice the hand<br />

of the artist at work forging connotative meanings. Within the original<br />

denotative signifiers—the round shape of the eye and moon, the<br />

thinness of the cloud and razor, and the similar speeds with which<br />

both move across their respective objects, there is a remarkable formal<br />

similarity of the signifiers alone motivating the comparison; yet<br />

there is no immediate connotative "explanation" on the level of the<br />

signifieds.<br />

But not only does the first part of this figure seem to create the<br />

diegesis, it also becomes a self-reflecting comment on the very process<br />

of making metaphors. In describing the first part, we tend to say<br />

that the clouds slice or cut the moon, which they do not really do—<br />

it is already a figure of speech to say so. But we say so precisely because<br />

the film has been building up to this final cutting through a<br />

proliferation of motifs emphasizing the bisection of circular shapes<br />

by horizontal lines. The first cutting of the thumbnail with the razor<br />

prepares us for the later—figural—cutting of the moon by the<br />

cloud. This figural cutting is in turn a prefiguration of the literal<br />

cutting of the eye which follows. What is so radically disturbing in<br />

this figure then is, not only the audacity of comparing one violent<br />

and sadistic image with another that is innocuous and natural, but<br />

also the fact that such a rigorous formal control exercised by the operation<br />

of the figure dictates the development of the sadistic and violent<br />

content.<br />

To summarize the differences between the Chien andalou prologue<br />

metaphor and the structurally similar, and more typical, metaphor<br />

in Shanghai Express, we find that: (1) in the prologue metaphor<br />

a disturbed hierarchy of background and foreground creates a<br />

situation in which the figural or vehicle half of the metaphor comes<br />

71


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

first and appears to generate the diegesis; and (2) in the Chien figure<br />

is a deviation from the more typical semantic basis for association of<br />

the elements of the metaphor—form rather than content dictates<br />

the ground of the association. Such a figure, though formally modeled<br />

on the typical metaphor, actually functions as a deconstruction<br />

of the anticipated metaphoric process in which the denotative content<br />

of the eye-cutting refuses to be absorbed immediately into a<br />

connotative expression.<br />

Unlike the classical figure, this seemingly autonomous figure refuses<br />

to be read as mere embellishment upon a discourse. It demands<br />

to be seen as the very cause of this discourse. The figure,<br />

which in its more usual manifestation can be dismissed as superfluous,<br />

here becomes essential. In Un Chien andalou this means<br />

that none of the events related by the prologue can be read as the<br />

illusion of past events, but only as configurations arising out of the<br />

act of writing, out of the desire expressed by the figure itself. Yet,<br />

what is so striking about this particular metaphor is the way the meticulous<br />

building of an apparently realistic diegesis culminates in an<br />

outrageous and metaphoric act of violence, which unlike most film<br />

violence subverts the very realism of its discourse.<br />

The Hand and the Eye." If, as we have seen, this figure does not<br />

permit the kind of connotative interpretation that comments on the<br />

diegesis, there is another sense in which it can be seen as a general<br />

symbol of the entire act of filmic creation. It is certainly no accident<br />

that the first shot of this prologue is a close-up of a hand sharpening<br />

a razor, while the last shot combines the elements of hand, razor,<br />

and eye. Even to a viewer unaware of the identity of the man who<br />

wields this razor—he is played by Luis Bunuel himself—and whose<br />

gaze we constantly follow, it is clear that his function in this prologue<br />

resembles that of the filmmaker. This function is double: it<br />

consists of vision and cutting, two processes that are repeated several<br />

times in the short twelve shots of this sequence.<br />

Each new element introduced after the first shot is first viewed by<br />

the man on the balcony. We watch him looking—twice this look is<br />

24 In this section I am only making more explicit what Pascal Bonitzer ("Le Gros orteil:<br />

'Realite de la denotation," Cahiers du cinema 232 [October 1971]: 15) and Joel Farges ("L'lmage<br />

d'un corps," Communications 23 [May 1975]: 88) have already implied.<br />

72<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

followed by the razor, once by the moon. The final look of outward<br />

regard that precedes the sudden appearance of the woman develops<br />

out of the pattern created by this vision. It is a progression to envision,<br />

which the diegetically contradictory elements of the tie and<br />

the absence of the watch seem to affirm. The cutting that follows<br />

this envision is nothing less than its implementation, an ironic symbol<br />

of the hand of the artist at work cutting up the continuous fabric<br />

of "reality" into newly significant combinations.<br />

This prologue has yet another kind of vision, that of the woman.<br />

Hers is an eye that sees nothing, an eye that stares straight ahead,<br />

passive and unblinking at the approach of the razor. It is an eye that<br />

is put there to be seen, whose vacant stare, as Joel Farges has<br />

noted," connects with our own passive voyeuristic stare, which<br />

through this connection feels the violence of the razor as a blinding<br />

assault on its own vision. But blindness, as every poet knows, can<br />

also be a figure for a different kind of sight. For, as the Surrealist<br />

poet Paul Eluard writes, "he doux fer rouge de I'aurorelKend la vue<br />

aux aveugles" (The gentle red iron of dawn/Restores sight to the<br />

blind). 26 And, just as Eluard employs the iron that blinds as a metaphoric<br />

figure for sight, so Bunuel and Dali draw their razor across<br />

our eye in such a way that, by blinding us to the possibility of seeing<br />

through the figure, they force us to look at the work of the figure<br />

itself.<br />

LATENT MEANING<br />

The above analysis of the formal attributes of the prologue metaphor<br />

is in no sense exhaustive. But at this point it will be more fruitful<br />

to proceed with the analysis of the rest of the film before venturing<br />

an interpretation of its latent significance.<br />

Since metaphor and condensation, unlike metonymy and displacement,<br />

make associations between elements that may never be<br />

brought together outside the particular textual space of the metaphor,<br />

it is reasonable to ask, especially in the case of Surrealist meta-<br />

Farges, "L'Image d'un corps," p. 93.<br />

Paul Eluard, "Le Baillon sur la table," La Vie immediate (Paris: Editions des cahiers<br />

libres, 1932). The translation is mine.<br />

73


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

phors like that of the prologue, just what is the motive for these<br />

combinations: why are the moon and eye, like the umbrella and<br />

sewing machine in Lautreament's famous image, brought together?<br />

(In fact, the parallel between Lautreamont's famous comparison<br />

from Maldoror, "as handsome ... as the fortuitous encounter<br />

upon a dissection table of a sewing machine and an umbrella" 2 and<br />

the filmic figure under question is itself fortuitous. In both examples<br />

male and female symbols combine with cutting motifs. Just as Andre<br />

Breton has noted the sexual import of Lautreamont's poetic image,<br />

28 we will eventually see a similarly latent sexual import in the<br />

prologue metaphor.)<br />

On the microlevel of a single metaphor, it is not possible to point<br />

to a consensus of meaning with the same facility with which we<br />

would translate the classical metaphoric formula My love is a flame.<br />

In the preceding analysis of the prologue metaphor, we have only<br />

seen that a self-referential figure seems to generate the diegesis. Although<br />

there is a latent meaning to this metaphor, it cannot be discovered<br />

through the kind of translation that the classical equation<br />

love = flame has accomplished in the past. Once again this is partly<br />

due to the absence in film, as well as in the unconscious productions<br />

of the Imaginary, of a fixed code analogous to that of language.<br />

As we have seen, the figural meaning of verbal rhetoric arises out<br />

of the discrepancy between the accepted literal meanings of the<br />

two parts of a statement. This discrepancy between the conventional<br />

coded meanings of tenor (love) and vehicle (flame) forces the discovery<br />

of a new meaning based on the ground of a shared characteristic<br />

(heat). But film does not possess such a fixed denotative code except<br />

insofar as rhetorical figures themselves have hardened into codelike<br />

forms.<br />

Christian Metz's work in film semiology has shown that the narrative<br />

procedures of film have tended to develop out of connotative<br />

effects that have later become absorbed into short-lived and only<br />

partial kinds of systems: what Metz prefers to call a grande syntagmatique,<br />

rather than a full-fledged paradigmatique. This grande<br />

syntagmatique is a level of codification that exists only in the larger<br />

2/ Lautreamont, Maldoror, p. 263.<br />

28 Breton, Les Vases communicants (Paris: Gallimard, 1955). P- 67. Breton suggests that<br />

the umbrella represents man, the sewing machine woman, the dissection table the bed.<br />

74<br />

1<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

organizational units of sequences and not in the minimum unit of<br />

the shot. Unlike language, the film does not begin with a code that<br />

connotation then transgresses. Instead the filmmaker begins with<br />

the raw material of the photographic registration, which connotative<br />

effect eventually shapes into a denotative code. (For example,<br />

Metz explains how an alternating montage originates as a way of<br />

making the denotation more lively and later becomes codified as<br />

one of the signifiers of simultaneity. 29 ) In other words, the separation<br />

between grammar and rhetoric is not as sharp as it is in the verbal<br />

arts, although certainly even the verbal arts present problems<br />

enough on this score.<br />

Similarly, in the dream the basic units of discourse are images<br />

that, unlike words, in themselves have no codified meanings. As<br />

seen in chapter 1, it is a common mistake in dream analysis to assume<br />

that the unconscious is a preexisting storehouse of meaning<br />

which the dream symbols simply represent. Laplanche and<br />

Leclaire, in their psychoanalytic study of the unconscious, explain<br />

that it is a misuse of the Freudian understanding of the unconscious<br />

to see dream images as the fixed symbolization of certain unconscious<br />

thoughts rather than as the production and creation of meaning.<br />

30 This is not to say that there is not a latent meaning in every<br />

dream, but simply that this latent meaning is not an already existing<br />

entity that can be reached through mechanistic decoding.<br />

Insofar as Un Chien andalou imitates the procedures of the unconscious,<br />

its figures too have a latent meaning, not just the usual<br />

connotation of most filmic figuration, like the kiss and whistle in<br />

Shanghai Express that can be interpreted in an instant, but a truly<br />

latent meaning that can be discovered only through a close analysis<br />

of the entire text. In the prologue metaphor we saw the peculiar way<br />

in which a figure becomes a part of the denotative diegesis through a<br />

reversal of the more typical hierarchy of diegesis and figure. The<br />

disturbance of this hierarchy is an indication that a desire simultaneously<br />

seeks to find expression and through censorship to cover<br />

this expression. On the basis of the prologue alone, we cannot yet<br />

determine what this latent meaning is. We have only been cued to<br />

Metz, "Problems of Denotation in the Fiction Film," in Film Language, pp. 118-19.<br />

Jean Laplanche and Serge Leclaire, "L'Inconscient: Une Etude psychanalytic," Les<br />

Temps Modemes 183 (July 1961)183.<br />

'


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

the presence of an enigma by the unconventionally and self-referentiality<br />

of the metaphoric process.<br />

As a result, we are forced to hold the process of interpretation in<br />

suspense, to look at the figure and the discourse it generates more<br />

closely, until on the macrolevel of the whole text we begin to see a<br />

pattern of overdetermination. Throughout the film these include a<br />

fascination with body parts that are never quite as they should be<br />

and the often related activity of cutting or mutilation—mutilation<br />

that always occurs in the context of male and female relations. The<br />

following close description and analysis of the rest of the film attempts<br />

to understand the metaphorical "statement" of the prologue<br />

in light of the figural complex of the entire film.<br />

The prologue is followed by a second time-reference, the specificity<br />

of which, "eight years later," contradicts the earlier fairy-tale<br />

time-reference ("once upon a time") that began the film. A cyclist<br />

appears on a deserted Paris street. (I will refer to this man as the cyclist<br />

through the rest of the analysis to distinguish him from other<br />

nameless male figures.) In addition to a dark suit, he is wearing<br />

incongruous lacy-white frills on his head, shoulders, and waist.<br />

Around his neck, attached by a strap, is a wooden box covered with<br />

diagonal stripes. When the cyclist rides directly toward the camera<br />

the box becomes the center of the shot. The following shot is a lapdissolve<br />

to a close-up of the same box. The diagonal stripes on the<br />

box are a visual echo (or rhyme) of the vertical stripes on the tie the<br />

razor-wielding man suddenly acquired during the eye-cutting.<br />

The scene changes to a full view of a bed and sitting room, in<br />

which the woman of the prologue sits at a table reading a book. She<br />

is wearing the same dress but her eye is uncut. Suddenly she looks<br />

up as if startled. A shot of the cyclist outside leads us to infer that his<br />

presence must somehow be what startled her. The woman throws<br />

her book shut onto the table. In a close-up it unnaturally reopens<br />

to a reproduction of Vermeer's The Lacemaker, showing a seated<br />

woman intently working a piece of lace. The woman goes to the<br />

window and looks down on the cyclist. From this high perspective<br />

we watch the cyclist slowly come to a stop and, without putting out<br />

a hand or leg to break his fall, keel over onto his side in the street.<br />

There he remains motionless, one wheel of the bicycle still spin-<br />

76<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

ning, his box still around his neck. In reaction shots, the woman<br />

has been alternately repelled and intensely interested. She now runs<br />

downstairs, where in a great show of protective emotion she kneels<br />

beside him, holds his head, and kisses his face repeatedly. Dissolve<br />

to a close-up of a box showing a hand opening it with a key. An<br />

object wrapped in diagonally striped paper is removed. A medium<br />

shot reveals that the woman, who is now back in the room, is the<br />

person opening the box with the key, removing from it a diagonally<br />

striped necktie wrapped in vertically striped paper.<br />

From the bed beside her, the woman picks up a white collar with<br />

a black tie attached. She removes the black tie and replaces it with<br />

the diagonally striped one from the box. A shot of the bed shows<br />

that the cyclist's frills have been carefully laid out in the position<br />

they would occupy if the cyclist were himself on the bed. The<br />

woman puts the collar with the new tie in its proper place but without<br />

tying the tie. She carefully arranges the whole effigy as the camera<br />

pulls back to reveal that the box too is in its proper place around<br />

the "neck" of the "cyclist." The woman then sits beside the bed as if<br />

watching over a sick person. Two separate shots show the bed and<br />

frills over which she watches. In each of them the untied striped tie<br />

magically ties itself—first quickly, then slowly.<br />

This ritualized arrangement of the cyclists bizarre garments on<br />

the bed in the woman's apartment has an unmistakable fetishistic<br />

function, which we shall examine later. For the moment it is sufficient<br />

to note that these garments evoke the absent cyclist in the form<br />

of a metonymy-placed-in-paradigm, a figural association based<br />

upon the previous contiguity of the cyclist and these garments (as<br />

the pince-nez of the ship's doctor in Potemkin evoked its recently<br />

drowned former owner). But, in this case, the extremely unlikely<br />

combination of these particular garments with a male cyclist on a<br />

Parisian street lends to this metonymy (unlike the more typical<br />

metonymic association of doctor and pince-nez) a good deal of the<br />

sense of artificial construction common to metaphor. This sense of<br />

artifice tends to encourage us to discover an underlying metaphoric<br />

similarity between the cyclist himself and the confused signs of gender—tie,<br />

collar, box, and frills—which evoke him.<br />

Suddenly, the woman starts, as if sensing something. She turns<br />

her head away from the bed to see the cyclist on the other side of the<br />

77


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

room now without the frills and box. He stares with fascination at<br />

his right hand. The woman approaches, looks at the hand with<br />

him, and then recoils fearfully. The man continues to stare at his<br />

hand, glancing at her only briefly to check if she sees it too.<br />

A Metaphoric Series. At this point an intricate series of similar<br />

shapes forms a transition between the space of the apartment and<br />

the street below. The metaphoric series begins by revealing the mystery<br />

of the cyclist's hand:<br />

Shot 1. Close-up of the man's hand with a circular hole in the<br />

palm, out of which ants swarm. Dissolve.<br />

Shot 2. Close-up of the torso of a female sunbather lying on her<br />

back with arms crossed behind her head. The shot is centered on a<br />

round patch of dark underarm hair. Dissolve.<br />

Shot 3. Close-up of a round sea urchin, whose stiffblack spines are<br />

slowly moving. Dissolve.<br />

Shot 4. A round, iris-framed, long shot from a high angle centered<br />

on the round close-cropped head of an androgynous-looking woman<br />

holding a long stick. With the stick she pokes at a round severed hand<br />

lying in the street. The iris opens out to reveal a crowd that has<br />

formed a circle around the androgyne.<br />

This is the end of the figure proper, although the action begun in<br />

the final shot of the androgyne continues with a close-up of the severed<br />

hand as it is prodded by the stick, a low-angle shot of the crowd<br />

as it sways slightly, and a policeman who pushes the crowd away<br />

from the androgyne. As an interior shot reveals the cyclist and<br />

woman standing before a window looking down on the scene in the<br />

street, we realize that the high-angle shot that first presented the androgyne<br />

(shot 2) was in fact the perspective from the woman's apartment<br />

and that she and the cyclist have overseen the drama of the<br />

severed hand taking place in the street below. While the cyclist and<br />

woman continue to watch from above, the androgyne places the severed<br />

hand in a ubiquitous, diagonally-striped box identical to the<br />

cyclist's box and clasps it sadly to her breast. Soon afterward she is<br />

struck by a car. The cyclist's reaction to all these events is one of<br />

mounting sexual excitement.<br />

Like the metaphor of the prologue, the metaphoric series proper<br />

is motivated by the formal similarity of round shapes emphasized by<br />

78<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

the dissolves between shots. The round shape of the hole in the<br />

cyclist's hand and the swarming movement of the ants resemble the<br />

similar round shape of the sunbather's armpit and its tuft of hair.<br />

Thus far similarity of the referents (hollow in hand and armpit)<br />

combine with contiguity of the discourse to form a metaphor placed<br />

in syntagm.<br />

In shot 3 the round shape of the sea urchin and its protruding<br />

spines echoes the round hole and swarm of ants in shot 1 and the<br />

round underarm and tuft of hair in shot 2. But, whereas in shots 1<br />

and 2 the round shapes were concave holes or vacuums from which<br />

ants and hair emerged, the round shape of the sea urchin in shot 3 is<br />

a convex volume from which black spines protrude.<br />

With shot 4 (beginning with the iris on the androgyne), the round<br />

shapes of the preceding three shots are repeated in a different way.<br />

Here the iris frame of the shot itself is round. This roundness is<br />

echoed by the round shape of the androgyne's head within the shot.<br />

Then, as the iris opens out, its shape is replaced by the round shape<br />

of the crowd encircling the androgyne and is echoed by the severed<br />

round hand with which she plays.<br />

Comparing these images, we discover a marked development<br />

from the round concave hole of the hand (shot 1) and the equally<br />

concave round cup of the sunbather's armpit (shot 2) with the convex<br />

roundness of the sea urchin (shot 3) and the equally convex<br />

roundness of the androgyne's head and severed hand (shot 4). In this<br />

progression, the metaphor begins within the diegesis; it continues its<br />

development extradiegetically in the shots of the armpit and sea<br />

urchin. Then, in the final shot of the series, the androgyne and severed<br />

hand lead back into the diegesis through the subsequent revelation<br />

that the androgyne has been observed by the cyclist, whose<br />

own mutilated hand began the series. Thus a progression of similar<br />

shapes deviously links the contiguous space of apartment and street,<br />

leading first away from and then back to the diegesis.<br />

THE MEANING OF THE FIGURES<br />

Each of these enigmatic figures—the prologue metaphor of moon<br />

and eye, the metonymy of the garments placed on the bed, and the<br />

79


The cyclist and woman stare at his<br />

hand. The metaphoric series begins<br />

with<br />

Shot 1. The cyclist's hand with ants<br />

swarming out of a hole.<br />

Dissolve between the hole in the hand<br />

and<br />

Shot 2. The underarm of a female sunbather.<br />

Dissolve between the underarm of the<br />

sunbather and<br />

Shot 3. A spiny sea urchin.<br />

Dissolve between the sea urchin and<br />

Shot 4. The androgyne who pokes at a<br />

severed hand with a long stick.


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

metaphoric series beginning with the hole in the hand—repeat<br />

motifs of cut or mutilated flesh and/or signs of male and female<br />

gender.<br />

The cutting motif begins with the trial cut of the thumbnail before<br />

the eye-cutting of the prologue and continues with the mutilated<br />

hand and completely severed hand of the metaphoric series.<br />

The opposing signs of male and female gender appear first in the<br />

diegesis in the combination of male cyclist dressed in feminine<br />

frills, then in the metonymic manipulation of male collar and tie<br />

combined with these same frills; they continue in the more abstract<br />

concave hollows and convex protrusions of the metaphoric series,<br />

and finally culminate in the person of the androgyne "herself."<br />

Mutilation by cutting frequently leads to the combination of the<br />

signs of male and female gender. For example, the initial mutilation<br />

of the eye-cutting in the prologue is followed by the male-female<br />

cyclist and then by the fetishized signs of his contradictory gender<br />

alone in the metonymies of the garments placed on the bed. In the<br />

metaphoric series this pattern is repeated within a single figure: the<br />

initial mutilation of the hole in the hand is followed by a shift from<br />

concave to convex roundness that culminates in the appearance of<br />

the androgyne, who combines in one person the same contradictory<br />

gender traits as the cyclist.<br />

Most commentators have viewed the prologue metaphor variously<br />

as a symbol of sexual pe<strong>net</strong>ration of the female body, 31 as an<br />

assault on the viewer's own vision and a movement toward inner vision,"<br />

and finally, as in my own preceding analysis, as some<br />

form of metaphor for the act of cinematic construction itself. My<br />

further view does not deny any of these meanings but, rather, adds<br />

the notion that the latent meaning of the metaphor can only be castration.<br />

The significant point about this meaning is that it emerges<br />

only in the light of the other figures, as they respond to the initial<br />

metaphor of the prologue. But what these subsequent figures do,<br />

paradoxically, is attempt to deny the meaning of castration, even<br />

"See Raymond Durgnat, Luis Bunuel (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1968),<br />

p. 24.<br />

"See Ken Kelman, "The Other Side of Realism," The Essential Cinema: Essays on the<br />

i'ilms in the Collection of Anthology Film Archives, 2 vols., ed. P. Adams Sitney (New York:<br />

Anthology Film Archives and New York University Press, 1975), 1:113.<br />

82<br />

Un Chicn andalou<br />

though this very denial becomes itself the confirmation of the fear it<br />

is intended to allay.<br />

The woman whose eye is cut by the razor in the prologue becomes<br />

a sexual object of the cyclist's desire in the subsequent diegesis.<br />

It is thus reasonable to interpret the woman's split eye as a<br />

metaphor for the vagina and the razor as a substitute penis. But if<br />

this is so, the metaphor of male desire is peculiarly condensed. The<br />

fact that pe<strong>net</strong>ration occurs through cutting opens up the possibility<br />

that it is the result of cutting—the result, that is, of castration. This<br />

only becomes apparent in the movement of the following figures to<br />

deny the consequences of this castration: to deny sexual difference.<br />

In a 1927 article" Freud shows how the function of the fetish<br />

arises from the fear of castration. In the male fantasy, a woman's<br />

difference (and desirability) is the result of castration. If the fear of<br />

castration becomes a fixation, the tendency on the part of the male<br />

unconscious is to replace female love objects with fetish objects that<br />

will forever disavow the feared castration. Thus Freud shows that<br />

the function of the fetish is to be a substitute for the mother's "penis<br />

that the little boy once believed in." 54 He calls this substitute a Verleugnung<br />

or "disavowal" of the terrifying fact that women have no<br />

penis:<br />

In the conflict between the weight of the unwelcome perception and<br />

the force of his counter-wish, a compromise has been reached, as<br />

is only possible under the dominance of the unconscious laws of<br />

thought. . . . the woman has got a penis; but this penis is no longer<br />

the same as it was before. Something else has taken its place, has been<br />

appointed its substitute. ... the horror of castration has set up a memorial<br />

to itself in the creation of this substitute. ... It remains a<br />

token of triumph over the threat of castration and a protection against<br />

it. 55<br />

Frequently these substitutes—feet, shoes, underpants—are contiguous<br />

substitutes metonymically associated with the hidden and<br />

feared lack. They either cover or stop short of the part of the body<br />

that may have undergone castration. Thus the fetish allows the<br />

"Fetishism," in Freud, Complete Psychological Works, 21:153.<br />

Ibid., p. 154.<br />

"Ibid.<br />

83


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

fetishist to preserve the illusion of the female phallus. Yet, as Freud<br />

points out and as others after him have stressed even more, 35 the<br />

fetish is an object that, in its denial of what is most feared, cannot<br />

help but assert that very fear.<br />

The feminine frills the woman lays out on the bed, to which the<br />

diagonally striped tie is significantly added, are fetishistic figures of<br />

the cyclist himself that wishfully present him as a sexually undifferentiated<br />

being, as both male and female. But this fetishistic<br />

assertion of the absence of sexual difference simultaneously asserts<br />

the fear that the fetish is created to deny. 3 ' This process of denial is<br />

repeated in the following figure of the metaphoric series. But here<br />

the metaphor also reasserts the initial fear of castration in the beginning<br />

shot of the wounded hand. Just as the wound of the eye-cutting<br />

is followed in a subsequent scene by the disavowal of the fetish<br />

garments, so here the metaphoric assertion of castration is directly<br />

followed by a progression of increasingly convex shapes that attempts<br />

to disavow the initial concave wound.<br />

But, again, the more the text tries to disavow and cover an initial<br />

lack, the more it asserts that lack. For in the final image of the<br />

series—the shot of the androgyne on the street—the forms are<br />

convex; but the content of the convex form is, most disturbingly,<br />

a severed hand—a cut-off organ. Not only does this process of disavowal<br />

call attention to the fear of castration, it also ironically points<br />

out the double nature of the sexual symbols involved: concave and<br />

convex are two sides of the same bowl. One side is absence (the concave<br />

wound, the vagina), the other side is presence (the convex protrusion,<br />

the penis). When the convex protrusion turns out to be a<br />

severed organ, it becomes a presence that insidiously evokes an absence.<br />

Thus even a phallic protrusion becomes an ironic metaphor<br />

for the fear it is intended to allay.<br />

The paradoxical structure of all these figures reflects the ambiguous<br />

logic of dreams, in which the assertion of any thought can be<br />

' 6 Octave Manonni, "Je sais bien mais quand merae," Clefs pour I'imaginaire (Paris: Seuil,<br />

1969), p. 2.<br />

57 A variant and even complementary interpretation of the placing of these garments on<br />

the bed could see it as an expression of the woman's desire that the sexually undifferentiated<br />

child not develop into a sexual being, thus her own disavowal would seem to be less oriented<br />

toward a specific fear of castration and more toward keeping the child a neuter (and unthreatening)<br />

object of her motherly affections.<br />

84<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

both positive and negative in a perpetual movement between the<br />

opposing poles of signification. Contraries act in this film as they do<br />

in dreams, where, as Freud has observed, the concept no seems not<br />

to exist. 38 Causality in general seems to operate throughout the film<br />

in a particularly dreamlike way. Freud has observed that dreams can<br />

represent causal connection by the introduction of the dream equivalent<br />

of a "dependent clause." In certain kinds of dreams a clearly<br />

separate beginning section—the dependent clause—posits an initial<br />

condition or state of affairs, which the rest of the dream—the<br />

"principal clause"—then develops. Freud's point is that the seemingly<br />

disjointed segments of a dream can nevertheless exhibit the<br />

logic of causality. In Un Chien andalou the prologue metaphor acts<br />

as such a dependent clause positing the initial condition of castration-division-absence<br />

that the principal clause of the subsequent figures—and<br />

the diegesis that flows out of these figures—attempts to<br />

deny.<br />

Still more may be said about the principal clause of the final metaphoric<br />

series ending with the androgyne. The androgyne herself is<br />

a dominantly feminine version of the contradictory gender traits of<br />

the dominantly masculine cyclist. Her feminine skirt is countered<br />

by short hair, angular body, and tailored jacket, just as the cyclist's<br />

suit and tie are countered by feminine frills. The cyclist and androgyne<br />

are also linked by their mutual possession of the diagonally<br />

striped box, which in one instance contains a necktie and in another<br />

becomes the receptacle for the severed hand. In the first instance<br />

the box appears to let out its secret: the necktie as substitute phallus<br />

and fetish working to deny a feared castration. In the second instance<br />

it functions as the container for the countersecret: the receptacle<br />

for the severed hand, which because it is once again a reminder<br />

of castration must be hidden away.<br />

Taken together these figures establish a symmetrical pattern of assertion<br />

and denial, the basic terms of which are presence and absence.<br />

The prologue metaphor of cutting posits a gap-split-absence,<br />

which the metonymy of the fetish garments attempts to disavow.<br />

"'No' seems not to exist so far as dreams are concerned. . . . Dreams represent any element<br />

by its wishful contrary so there is no way of deciding at a first glance whether any element<br />

that admits of a contrary is present in the dream-thoughts as a positive or a negative.<br />

Interpretation of Dreams, p. 353.<br />

85


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

The hole in the hand posits a similar gap-split-absence, which the<br />

following series of metaphorically similar shapes even less successfully<br />

disavows. The desire of the text thus mirrors the desire of<br />

the (male) subject. It seeks perpetually and impossibly to fill in,<br />

cover over, and to otherwise deny an original loss. If castration is<br />

one meaning of the prologue metaphor, it is itself, as Lacan has<br />

said, also a metaphor for difference, for the fundamental lack-inbeing<br />

that marks the entrance into the Symbolic and structures<br />

desire.<br />

Thus the intense figural activity of this first part of the film offers a<br />

conscious imitation of the rhetorical form of the discourse of the<br />

unconscious. The dream work carried out by condensation and displacement<br />

in actual dreams is closely imitated in Un Chien andalou<br />

by the Surrealist use of metaphor and metonymy in which the<br />

meaning of the'text is generated entirely through its figures. Only<br />

by putting off the initial impulse to interpret these figures on the<br />

micro-level of their relation to the immediate diegetic situation<br />

have we been able to discover the latent text consisting of the repeated<br />

assertion-denial of castration in the context of awakening<br />

sexual desire. These Surrealist figures intentionally frustrate our attempts<br />

at interpretation based on the relation of the figure to the<br />

diegesis that surrounds it, because the discourse of this film is carried<br />

out by and large on the level of its figures. This is the final reason<br />

for the disturbed hierarchy between diegesis and figure noted<br />

earlier. The desire expressed by this film cannot be directly named<br />

or diegetically presented: it can only be generated by a hidden discourse,<br />

which like the discourse of the unconscious in dreams,<br />

Freudian slips, or bungled actions disturbs and rearranges the memory<br />

traces, logical speech, and action of our daily lives.<br />

Sexual Pursuit. When the cyclist observes the death of the androgyne<br />

on the street below, his response is mounting excitement<br />

(captured beautifully by his breath fogging the window through<br />

which he gazes). This excitement immediately becomes overt sexual<br />

desire for the woman who has been observing the scene below<br />

with him. Until this point his relations with her have been mostly<br />

filial and passive. Suddenly, in direct response to the death of the<br />

androgyne, he is on the verge of raping her. One interpretation of<br />

86<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

his reaction would be to see the death of the androgyne as at least a<br />

temporary resolution of the castration fear and the fetishistic impulses<br />

this fear engenders. This resolution allows a progression toward<br />

desire for the opposite sex. From this point on, the woman is<br />

no longer a mother substitute, whose absence of a penis is a source<br />

of disturbance to the male child; now she has become a woman,<br />

whose difference becomes the object of his desire—his first act is to<br />

grab for her breasts.<br />

In the second half of this film, the intensely Surrealistic figurations<br />

examined above give way to more conventional symbols. Desire<br />

here becomes a conscious pursuit of a concrete love-object. But<br />

it should be clear from the preceding analysis that this love-object is<br />

herself nothing but another substitute for the fundamental lack-inbeing<br />

posited by the castration metaphor of the prologue.<br />

Turning from the window from which he has witnessed the death<br />

of the androgyne, the cyclist begins a comic cat-and-mouse pursuit<br />

of the woman. On the sound track a jaunty Argentine tango alternates<br />

with the ponderous and passionate Liebestod from Wagner's<br />

Tristan und Isolde.<br />

Momentarily catching the woman, the cyclist caresses her breasts<br />

over her clothes. A dissolve reveals the same hands caressing entirely<br />

nude breasts. A close-up of the cyclist's face shows that he,<br />

too, has undergone a transformation. His face is contorted, his eyes<br />

roll up so that the pupils are no longer visible, and from the side of<br />

his mouth drips a bloody drool. This transformation begins a pattern<br />

of association linking passion with the paroxysms of violence<br />

and death. This is a frequent association in a great many of Bunuel's<br />

films, in which sexual desire is never beautiful but always that<br />

which dirties, mutilates, or profanes its object and subject. In most<br />

cases this excessive passion represents the pursuit of an impossible<br />

and absolute union that death alone can finally offer.<br />

In the love-death scene in question, when the cyclist begins to<br />

caress the woman's breasts, his passion immediately evokes a reaction<br />

that approximates death: his eyes roll up into his head and drool<br />

drips from his mouth. Love and death are inextricably connected,<br />

because only the transgression and separation of death can accomplish<br />

the ultimate union of love. Bataille points out that in French<br />

orgasm is often referred to as a petite mort (little death), a brief<br />

87


1. The cyclist caresses the woman's breasts over<br />

her dress.<br />

2. The breasts are suddenly nude.<br />

3. The breasts become buttocks.<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

moment in which an individual transgresses the separate discontinuities<br />

of daily life to dissolve into continuity with the rest of the<br />

universe. He also notes that such eroticism can place the very existence<br />

of human consciousness in question. 39 Un Chien andalou is<br />

precisely such a questioning of the self and of the illusion of the<br />

unity of the self through eroticism. Unlike the Wagnerian Liebestod,<br />

this love-death is not a romantic affirmation of the transcendent<br />

power of love that finds its ultimate fulfillment in death. The<br />

Wagnerian references, like the similar references in L'Age d'or, are<br />

ironic, as the musical alternation between the ponderous and passionate<br />

Liebestod and the jaunty Argentine tango suggests. 40 Where<br />

Wagner's Liebestod is a transcendent unity, Bunuel and Dali emphasize<br />

the impossibility of ultimate consummation. Just as masculine<br />

signifiers evoke feminine signifiers, so also desire evokes<br />

death. For Bunuel and Dali it is the process of the movement between<br />

these poles that holds our attention, not their transcendent<br />

merging.<br />

The cyclist's passion begins when he caresses the woman's breasts<br />

through her clothes. On a dissolve the breasts are suddenly nude;<br />

then they are clothed again. In a repeat of this sequence, when the<br />

hands caress the alternately clothed and nude breasts, the mounds<br />

of flesh turn out to be not breasts but buttocks. The switch from<br />

breasts to buttocks comprises a movement from sexual orthodoxy to<br />

relative perversion—a transgression that obviously heightens the<br />

cyclist's passion. It is also a transgression that presents a similar flux<br />

of male and female signifiers observed in the first part of the film.<br />

The breasts belong to the woman's body and the buttocks seem to<br />

also. But in the context of being caressed and substituted for breasts,<br />

these buttocks tend to suggest the perversion of a normal male desire<br />

for different body parts (breasts or vagina) into an abnormal male<br />

desire for similar body parts (buttocks or penis). Whether the buttocks<br />

are male or female, we tend to read them as yet another variation<br />

on the frequent assertion-denial of sexual difference begun by<br />

the figural castration of the prologue.<br />

At this point the woman runs away. The cyclist chases her around<br />

George S. Bataille, Erotisme (Paris: Editions de minuit, 1957), p. 34.<br />

At the film's first public screening, Bunuel stood behind the screen with a record player.<br />

In i960 this same music was placed on the soundtrack of the film.<br />

89


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

the room and across the bed. Grabbing a tennis racket that is hanging<br />

on the wall, she fends the cyclist off. Against such resistance the<br />

cyclist has recourse to more subtle stratagems, sublimating his energetic<br />

desire into a more socially acceptable form. Retreating a bit he<br />

casts about for some alternative. Finding two ropes on the floor he<br />

grabs them and resumes his movement toward the woman pulling a<br />

rope over each shoulder, evidently pleased to have found "the solution."<br />

The frame does not immediately reveal just what is attached<br />

to the ropes, although it is clear that the weight must be enormous.<br />

Even before we know what the cyclist is pulling, the action of<br />

pulling alone is a fairly clear imitation of the process of sublimation.<br />

The energy for one (sexual) purpose is channeled into another; direct<br />

movement toward the woman is balanced by the weight on the<br />

other end of the ropes. Subsequent shots of what he pulls reveal the<br />

various forms taken by his sublimation: ropes and corks at the beginning<br />

suggest the accoutrements of fishing and the notion of entrapment.<br />

Next the two Marist brothers dragged along by the ropes<br />

seem to represent the smug piety of religious sanctions, the religious<br />

weight and authority that impedes and transforms the cyclist's initial<br />

desire. The same can be said of the two grand pianos which follow,<br />

except that this sublimation is cultural. On top of it all, mocking<br />

these religious and cultural pretensions is the dead, rotting flesh of<br />

two asses, one on top of each piano. Their exposed teeth are an<br />

echo of the pianos' keyboards, and their blinded, oozing eye-sockets<br />

are a reminder of the prologue eye-cutting as well as a prefiguration<br />

of the gouged eye-sockets of both man and woman in the final tableau.<br />

The rotting asses are a reminder that the ultimate end of all<br />

desire can only be death and decay. Thus the castration of the prologue<br />

blinding gives way in these later blindings to the general symbolic<br />

meaning of death. Here sex and death begin to approach each<br />

other in a different way. The asses' blinded eyes signify an absence of<br />

desire. Associated with death, they are an ironic mockery of the<br />

cyclist's sexual energy, and their dead weight slows him down to the<br />

extent that the woman manages to slip away into the next room.<br />

The next room is exactly the same as the one she has just left,<br />

down to the last detail of a tennis racket and sailor hat hanging on<br />

the wall. Indeed, everything that takes place in this scene is a kind of<br />

repetition or doubling of what has come before, from the repetition<br />

90


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

of the room itself to the repetition of the hole-wifh-ants in the hand,<br />

to the appearance of an actual double who knocks on the door. As<br />

the woman escapes into the next room and closes the door against<br />

her pursuer, his wrist is caught in the door. In a prolonged and agonizing<br />

struggle, the pressure of the door grotesquely squeezes the<br />

ants out of the hole that has suddenly reappeared in his hand. The<br />

cyclist on the other side of the door reacts in agony. The escape to<br />

another identical room, along with the return of the previous image<br />

of ants-and-hole in hand suggests a regression to a former state, as<br />

the subsequent rediscovery of the cyclist dressed in his frills on the<br />

bed seems to affirm.<br />

Certainly the trauma of a hand caught in a door is analogous to<br />

the vulnerability to castration of an erect penis. This is especially so<br />

in the context of the earlier metaphoric series begun by the same<br />

image of the hole in the hand. But while the first appearance of the<br />

hole and ants emphasized the fear that women have undergone castration,<br />

the excruciation of this same hand caught in a door emphasizes<br />

the more present and direct agony of undergoing dismemberment.<br />

From the apparent danger of this aggressive acting-out of<br />

sexual desire, the cyclist regresses back to a fear of castration, resulting<br />

in a return to the fetish-attachments of the beginning of the<br />

film. As the woman is still engaged in her struggle to close the door<br />

against her pursuer, she glances around and sees that "he" is now<br />

lying on the bed in his former frills, the striped box around his neck.<br />

Once again the cyclist resorts to the infantile attempt to cover over<br />

the possibility of sexual difference through disavowal by the fetish.<br />

At this juncture a stranger wearing a hat rings the doorbell. The<br />

stranger quickly enters the room, imperiously orders the cyclist off<br />

the bed, roughly pulls off his frills and box. Then, going to the window,<br />

he throws them all out one by one. During this entire sequence<br />

the stranger's back is to the camera; we never see his face.<br />

He places the cyclist face-to-the-wall with hands out to form a cross.<br />

Thus far the stranger's actions have indicated an authoritarian<br />

role—either father or teacher. These functions correspond with<br />

Freud's concept of the super-ego, a censuring agent of self-observation<br />

that measures the self against a social ideal.<br />

As the stranger turns around, we discover that he is the cyclist's<br />

double. This resemblance confirms the interpretation of the dou-<br />

92


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

ble's function as super-ego—another, idealized, aspect of the self. 41<br />

But the stranger is something else as well. When he rips off the<br />

fetish garments and throws the box and its cord out the window, he<br />

becomes a threat to the cyclist's tenuous sexual equilibrium. It is as<br />

if the cyclist has retreated to this infantile stage to protect himself<br />

against the stranger's feared punishment: castration.<br />

But immediately the stranger's aspect changes. When he turns to<br />

face the camera for the first time in a slow-motion shot with a<br />

gauze-effect, his assertive manner gives way to a gentle sadness, as if<br />

overwhelmed and dismayed by the spectacle of what, by virtue of<br />

his resemblance to the cyclist, we now see to be his own youth. He<br />

walks over to a school child's desk that has suddenly appeared in the<br />

center of the room, picks up two books, and clasps them to his chest<br />

in a manner reminiscent of the way in which the androgyne clasped<br />

the box to her chest just before she was hit by a car. He puts a book<br />

in each of the cyclist's hands and moves away.<br />

Suddenly the books become revolvers. 42 Now it is the super-ego's<br />

turn to raise his hands, a tremendously hurt and martyred expression<br />

on his face. When the cyclist shoots, the super-ego begins his<br />

slow-motion fall in the room and ends it outside in the meadow. As<br />

he completes his fall, his hand grazes the length of the naked back<br />

of a woman seated in the meadow. Again a moment of extreme agony<br />

coincides with a moment of sensual bliss. The lyrical beauty of<br />

the nude woman seated in the meadow, whose image slowly disappears<br />

after the super-ego has fallen, combines with the paroxysm of<br />

his death and the final gesture of grasping for,,but never possessing,<br />

a fleeting image of desire: another instance of the interdependence<br />

of passion and death.<br />

The death of the- super-ego double marks an important phase in<br />

the successive stages of psycho-sexual development thus far portrayed.<br />

With this death and the funeral procession that follows it,<br />

the film for once lets a passion play itself out. In the only restful<br />

moment in the entire film, the claustrophobic and intense enigmas<br />

41 Kelman refers to the super-ego function of this personage in "The Other Side of Realism,"<br />

p. 115. Durgnat refers to the stranger as an authority figure in Luis Bufiuel, p. 35.<br />

4 The books-into-revolver theme is typical of Surrealist images. Andre Breton, in his second<br />

manifesto (Manifestoes of Surrealism, p. 125), had written that the simplest Surrealist act<br />

would be to go out on the street and shoot at random at a crowd.<br />

94<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

of the male-female sexual games give way here to a kind of irrelevant<br />

denouement—a man dies in a field, and a group of strangers<br />

discover and carry off his body in a series of increasingly "epic"<br />

long shots, at the end of which they all disappear. The funereal<br />

commemoration this death receives marks it as a significant loss.<br />

Though the death of the super-ego frees the cyclist from the social<br />

forces that have attempted to sublimate his sexual energy, it also<br />

leaves him insufficiently socialized and, as far as the woman is concerned,<br />

irrelevant. At this point the focus of the film begins to move<br />

away from the desires and fantasies of the male and increasingly toward<br />

those of the female.<br />

After the funeral procession we return once again to the room.<br />

The woman enters slowly, leans against the door, and looks intently<br />

at the opposite wall. The wall is blank. A second shot of the same<br />

wall reveals a small black spot. A closer shot reveals that the spot is<br />

actually a moth with a death's head on its back. A close-up of the<br />

death's head alone completes the series. As in many of the previous<br />

instances of metaphoric formulation, the death's head is an extremely<br />

formal variation of round shapes evolving out of a character's<br />

subjective glance. This, however, is not a metaphor but, rather,<br />

a conventional symbol of death.<br />

Suddenly the cyclist appears in the room as well. In a rapid<br />

movement he puts his hand over his mouth and takes it away. His<br />

mouth has disappeared. The woman looks at him disdainfully. As if<br />

to assert her own possession of an oral orifice, she rouges her lips<br />

defiantly. In the next shot of the man, a tuft of hair "grows" where<br />

his mouth once was. This last outrage seems to have a desired shock<br />

effect upon the woman, who, looking with surprise at her underarm,<br />

discovers that the hair is gone; it has moved to the cyclist's face.<br />

Scornfully she sticks out her tongue at the man—a second assertion<br />

of her possession of an oral orifice—and leaves the room forever.<br />

This particularly enigmatic scene can be understood only in relation<br />

to all the slicings, dismemberments, and holes that have preceded<br />

it and of which it is a direct reversal. Up until this point,<br />

physical mutilation has functioned as, among other things, a symbol<br />

of psychic interiority. Pe<strong>net</strong>ration of the flesh has corresponded<br />

to an analogous pe<strong>net</strong>ration of ordinarily repressed realms of the unconscious.<br />

Now, however, this final appearance of the cyclist closes<br />

95


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

1. The cyclist.<br />

2. The cyclist places his hand over his<br />

mouth.<br />

3. His mouth disappears.<br />

4. A tuft of hair appears where his<br />

mouth was.<br />

5. The woman discovers her underarm<br />

hair missing.<br />

96<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

and seals the flesh, not the grotesque wounds generated throughout<br />

the film, but a perfectly natural orifice: the mouth. It then covers<br />

this newly closed orifice with alien underarm hair.<br />

Thus the last moments of the film seal and cover the inferiority<br />

that the beginning of the film so grotesquely opened. Unnatural<br />

cutting is followed by equally unnatural closing. Though an epilogue<br />

follows, this final scene between the cyclist and the woman<br />

truly ends the revelation of psychic inferiority begun by the prologue.<br />

Once the literal and figural openings have been sealed,<br />

nothing more can pass between them.<br />

This reversal of cutting images also brings an end to the accompanying<br />

castration theme, but it does so in a peculiar way. When<br />

the underarm hair appears on the space that was once the cyclist's<br />

mouth, the effect of this triangular patch of hair is rather startlingly<br />

that of a misplaced patch of pubic hair. 43 Since the hair has<br />

sprouted over a sealed orifice, we know that it cannot conceal female<br />

genitalia. But neither does it cover male genitalia, for there is<br />

no protruding phallus. This particular displacement of body parts<br />

contradicts all previous instances of the assertion of masculine<br />

and/or feminine sexual traits. It represents the decidedly neutral absence<br />

of any sexual signifiers, even through it provides their natural<br />

context (pubic hair). In other words, displaced hair sets up an expectation<br />

for the signifiers of sexuality, which the sealed mouth denies.<br />

In this context the protrusion of the woman's tongue connotes a bit<br />

more than the usual disdain. Like her previous lip rouging it asserts<br />

her own possession of orifices (and thus of gender) and the man's<br />

pathetic lack (of gender, virility). Her tongue is a phallic protrusion<br />

that he can no longer emulate.<br />

The woman now leaves the cyclist. The role of the woman,<br />

which began passively, now becomes active. Up until this point,<br />

events have tended to happen to her. Her role has been that of an<br />

object responding to the cyclist's initiatives: maternally to his bicycle<br />

fall and fearfully to his sexual advances. Now, in the face of his lack<br />

of initiative, she asserts her own desire to pursue the new man on<br />

43 In a 1934 canvas that later appeared on the cover of Andre Breton's Qu'est-ce que le<br />

Surrealisme? (Brussels: R. Henriquez, 1934), Rene Magritte created a similar figure. Entitled<br />

Le Viol, it is a portrait of a woman in which breasts take the place of eyes, a navel is the nose,<br />

and a triangle of pubic hair is the mouth.<br />

97


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

the beach. But, although the woman's own desires now come into<br />

focus for the first time, these desires are not of the repressed, unconscious<br />

variety that have dominated the rest of the film. Even when<br />

she does find and win over the new man, this new relationship<br />

serves only as a comment on the deterioration of the former. This<br />

happens in the following way.<br />

Before the woman leaves the room, she opens the door and waves<br />

to someone off-screen while a breeze blows her hair. In the next<br />

shot a new man in golf clothes turns around to face her. From the<br />

Parisian apartment she steps immediately onto the beach. The man<br />

in golf clothes at first shows her his watch as if to reproach her for<br />

tardiness, but he soon succumbs to her charms. In a close-up we see<br />

the side of the woman's face on the left of the frame, and the man's<br />

hand and watch horizontally on the right. This shot echoes the first<br />

part of the prologue in which a close-up of the woman's face and<br />

another male hand figured prominently. Smiling, the woman puts<br />

her hand over the watch and pulls the man's hand down out of the<br />

frame. When she does this, a horizontal white fence in the background<br />

bisects her face at exactly eye level, recalling the same visual<br />

motifs that culminated in the prologue's eye-cutting. But this man's<br />

hand holds no razor and the fence that bisects the eye leads to no<br />

cutting. Here the latent meanings that underlay the initial cutting<br />

metaphor—castration, fear, and denial; psychic interiority; filmic<br />

creation—have been exhausted.<br />

The subsequent discovery on the beach of the broken and abandoned<br />

box, cord, and frills functions similarly; but here it is through<br />

a metonymy placed in paradigm, much like the pince-nez in Potemkin.<br />

The single image of the box and frills evokes the cyclist with<br />

whom it was associated earlier. But the added feature of deterioration<br />

of the box and frills comments metaphorically on the reduced<br />

status of the cyclist in the woman's affections, on the present absence<br />

of any desire. The useless box is kicked away by the new man,<br />

while the woman picks up the frills and cord. She laughingly gives<br />

them to the man, who throws them away one by one, in a manner<br />

that recalls the similar gesture of the super-ego double when he<br />

threw these objects out the window.<br />

These paradigmatic evocations of previous metaphors and metonymies<br />

function much more traditionally than their initial for-<br />

98<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

mulation in earlier parts of the film. Unlike these earlier figures,<br />

they do not generate the diegesis but only comment contrastingly<br />

upon previous developments, primarily upon the wearing down of<br />

desire that once generated so much of the discourse. As the new<br />

man walks along the beach with the woman, the banality of the<br />

final "happy ending" of united lovers rings false. It has no traditional<br />

integrating effect because the rest of the film has not functioned on<br />

this level.<br />

The final tableau, with the words "in the springtime" written at<br />

the top of the frame and the new man and woman buried up to their<br />

chests in sand, blinded and devoured by insects, further mocks the<br />

happy ending. This frozen image of the putrefying carcasses of the<br />

two characters is one of final exhaustion, a remarkable precursor of<br />

Beckett's similar stage image fifty years later in Happy Days." But<br />

here it is the unnatural stillness of the image that is significant. The<br />

effect is of a painted tableau with real people stuck in the sand like<br />

dead flowers. The tableau effect gives none of the violence of the<br />

previous surreal images in spite of the fact that the two figures have<br />

hollowed eye-sockets and are eaten by insects. 45 Rather, it is a worndown,<br />

exhausted image of death that includes the previous element<br />

of blindness/castration as well as a new suggestion of return to the<br />

womb in the half burial 46 that resembles the corpse planted in a garden<br />

in Eliot's Waste Land.' 17<br />

The title "in the springtime" is also an ironic mockery of rebirth,<br />

fertility, and energy (another resemblance to Eliot's Waste Land).<br />

What purports to be a beginning is really an end. Just as the beginning<br />

images (preceded by the fairy-tale "once upon a time") opened<br />

the semantic paradigm "romance" through the insistence of moon,<br />

balcony, man, and woman and then subverted this paradigm<br />

Samuel Beckett, Oh, les beaux jours (Paris: Editions de minuit, 1963); id., Happy Days<br />

(London: Faber & Faber, 1962).<br />

I should add that, although these details are indicated in the scenario, 1 have yet to see a<br />

print in which they are very noticeable. The eyes simply look dark and hollow. Neither is it<br />

very clear that the man in the tableau is the man from the beach, although the scenario so<br />

indicates.<br />

In his essay "The Uncanny," Freud notes that dreams of burial often express a desire to<br />

return to the womb. Complete Psychological Works, 17:217-52.<br />

' "Stetson! You sho were with me in the ships of Mylae / That corpse you planted last<br />

year in your garden, / Has it begun to sprout? Will it bloom this year?" T. S. Eliot, Selected<br />

Poems (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1964), p. 53.<br />

99


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

through the metaphor of the eye-cutting, so the final image of the<br />

man and woman united on the beach opens up a similar semantic<br />

paradigm of "happy ending to romance," which the content of the<br />

final tableau disrupts. Such are the tensions that structure the entire<br />

film. From a metaphoric blindness that is also a figure for a new<br />

kind of sight, the film moves to the final blindness of death, from<br />

which no further vision ensues.<br />

Secondary Revision. Throughout much of Un Chien andalou there<br />

is rather scrupulous attention to the classic rules of film editing and<br />

mise en scene. Early in the film, when the woman leaves her apartment<br />

to run downstairs, the filmic transition is careful to show a<br />

sample of every step of her journey, across the room, down the<br />

steps, and out the door to the street. But these details are established<br />

only so that, at a later point in the film, when she leaves the apartment<br />

for good, the abruptness of the transition from Parisian apartment<br />

to seaside will be felt.<br />

These transgressions of filmic conventions modeled on the distortions<br />

of the unconscious in dreams or fantasies register as such only<br />

if the laws transgressed are first established. In other words, a process<br />

at work in this film tries to satisfy our conscious expectations of<br />

intelligibility. But this intelligibility is only a semblance analogous<br />

to another agency of dream formation, which Freud has described<br />

as secondary revision. 48<br />

As Freud defines it, secondary revision is contemporaneous with<br />

the process of dream formation. It is a form of censorship that covers<br />

up the illogicality of dreams. Freud compares it with the false<br />

semblance of coherence encountered in the enigmatic inscriptions<br />

that entertained the readers of a popular journal of his day. These<br />

inscriptions were "intended to make the reader believe that a certain<br />

sentence—for the sake of contrast, a sentence in dialect and as<br />

scurilous as possible—is a Latin inscription. For this purpose the<br />

letters contained in the words are torn out of their combination into<br />

syllables and arranged in a new order. Here and there a genuine<br />

Latin word appears." 49 To read the real text the reader must actually<br />

48 Freud, Interpretation of Dreams, p. 539.<br />

49 Ibid.<br />

100<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

disregard the semblance of Latin, looking only at the letters and not<br />

at their ostensible arrangement. In a similar way Un Chien andalou<br />

creates the illusion of obeying the codes of filmic narrativity. But,<br />

like the spurious Latin text of Freud's example, it does so only to<br />

transgress them.<br />

This process is a further refinement of the way Surrealist film imitates<br />

what Artaud calls the "mechanics" of the dream—its textual<br />

procedures. As in the early screenplays of Apollinaire, Desnos, and<br />

Artaud, the quality of surreality is not achieved by the "liberation"<br />

of pure imagination. It is achieved rather through the tension between<br />

the categories of the Imaginary and Symbolic. Thus," if the<br />

transgressions of the Imaginary are to be felt, it is necessary for the<br />

film to first set up certain diegetic expectations, which the intrusion<br />

of the Imaginary then transgresses. Secondary revision is thus ultimately<br />

a set-up for an eventual rupture of the very codes it pretends<br />

to obey. This rupture occurs either through the eventual nonobservance<br />

of the diegetic code itself (as when the woman exits from<br />

Parisian apartment to the seashore with no transition) or through the<br />

disturbed hierarchy between diegesis and figure occurring at significant<br />

points throughout the film.<br />

Physical Violence/Textual Violence. I have already shown the very<br />

subtle ways in which the relations between figure and diegesis are<br />

transgressed in this film, but I have not yet commented on the way<br />

in which this textual violence is also connected with a very physical<br />

violence. Violence is not as gratuitous an element in this film as at<br />

first appears. Physical violence is used as a catalyst for even more<br />

radical forms of textual violence, to cue a textual progression to a<br />

greater inferiority of vision (or envision). This envision could be<br />

more usefully rechristened Mindscreen after Bruce Kawin's book of<br />

the same name. 50 Mindscreen is a filmic visual field that presents<br />

itself as the product of a mind. Often associated with self-reflexive<br />

works, it is a concept developed to explain a general textual subjectivity<br />

that is not confined to the more limited notion of subjective<br />

camera and point of view (which imitate the activity of a character's<br />

physical eye). Mindscreen can thus be used to describe the visual<br />

50 Bruce Kawin, Mindscreen (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1978).<br />

101


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

workings of film texts in which there is no fictionalized character<br />

whose mind is visualized—works in which the text itself projects the<br />

workings of a mind. This occurs in films as diverse as The Cabi<strong>net</strong><br />

of Dr. Caligari, Persona, and Un Chien andalou.<br />

We have seen how the physical violence of the eye-cutting of the<br />

prologue opens up a literal and figural gap out of which the rest of<br />

the film's exploration of unconscious sexual fantasy spills, just as the<br />

gelatinous fluid spills out of the eye. This is the first pattern-setting<br />

instance of an act of physical violence that triggers the textual violence<br />

of mindscreen. In this initial instance the mindscreen is the<br />

whole balance of the film considered as an unconscious reaction to<br />

the fear of castration.<br />

But within this basic structure are many smaller repetitions of the<br />

progression from physical violence to mindscreen. If the overwhelming<br />

violence of the prologue triggers the mindscreen of the<br />

rest of the film, subsequent moments of violence trigger localized<br />

progressions to mindscreen that can be read as the subjective fantasies<br />

and unconscious projections of individuals within the initial<br />

mindscreen: mindscreens within mindscreens.' 1 Thus the violence<br />

of the mutilated hand (another gap) leads to a metaphoric progression<br />

that is a mindscreen for the flux of male and female signifiers.<br />

Or a violence to eyes and face in the breast-caressing scene triggers<br />

another mindscreen of the nude breasts that become buttocks. And,<br />

finally, the more conventional murder of the super-ego leads to another<br />

mindscreen in the image of the nude woman seated in the<br />

field.<br />

Physical violence on the Symbolic level of the diegesis consistently<br />

leads to a new level of textual violence—the rupture of the<br />

diegesis and a progression to Imaginary fantasy. Thus, even when<br />

physical violence does not lead to a specifically metaphoric elaboration<br />

as it does in the prologue metaphor or the mutilated-hand series<br />

of metaphors, the effect is quite similar: physical violence on the<br />

diegetic level triggers a textual violence that moves the film to a different<br />

level of discourse altogether. Each of these new levels or<br />

mindscreens entails a visual elaboration of the opposition between<br />

male and female signifiers. Both the violence in the diegesis and the<br />

51 Bunuel develops this procedure extensively in his later films—Belle de jour. The Dis­<br />

creet Charm of the Bourgeoisie.<br />

102<br />

Un Chien andalou<br />

violent rupture of the diegesis are ways in which the film overcomes<br />

the censorship usually imposed on sexual obsessions. It is therefore<br />

another way in which the diegetic codes (and sexual taboos) of the<br />

Symbolic are transformed by the workings of the Imaginary.<br />

But if, as we have seen, Un Chien andalou is about sexual desire<br />

(and the accompanying fear of castration), it is not about a love affair<br />

whose consummation is thwarted by the intervention of society.<br />

I state this because, even though some critics who have dealt with<br />

the film proclaim the enigmatic presence of unconscious meanings,<br />

they still tend to read it in terms of a love affair that is never consummated<br />

due to moral and social circumstances.5 2 In fact, to speak of<br />

sexual consummation at all in this film is misleading. Un Chien<br />

andalou focuses on the unconscious oppositions that structure sexual<br />

desire rather than on a psychological love affair that either is, or<br />

is not, consummated.<br />

The principal oppositions that structure sexual desire in the film<br />

are, in their most abstract and schematic form, male-female, lovedeath,<br />

and sight-blindness. These oppositions are in continual flux<br />

in many different and complex ways throughout the film, finally<br />

coming to rest in complete stasis at the end. For example, the assertion<br />

of passion in the scene in which the cyclist caresses the<br />

woman's breasts leads directly to an apparent contradiction of this<br />

passion in the death throes that follows. A similar, though reverse<br />

order, pattern occurs during the love-death of the super-ego. In this<br />

instance murder leads to a passionate caress as his dying hand grazes<br />

the naked woman's back. Finally, in the frozen tableau of the<br />

two dead lovers buried up to their chests in sand, love and death<br />

coincide.<br />

Sexual desire manifests itself in this context as an energy that<br />

transgresses and dissolves the constituted forms of social life. But<br />

only insofar as these forms are constituted can transgression have<br />

value. Because transgression is forbidden, it is by definition a violence<br />

to the established order. This quality of violent transgression<br />

marks Bunuel's portrayal of sexual desire in all his most Surrealist<br />

films. These transgressions are the search for an impossible unity<br />

that only death can finally offer. Thus death, violations, and mutila-<br />

"Man is not free to approach the woman he loves. He carries around with him a whole<br />

load of moral and social circumstances." Buache, Cinema of Luis Bunuel, p. 12.<br />

103


FIGURES OF DESIRE<br />

tion express a complicity with the very law that forbids them. Love<br />

evokes death and death evokes love in a fascinating structure of opposition.<br />

Sight and blindness are opposed in similar ways.<br />

If Un Chien andalou pushes these transgressions to their limit, it<br />

does not do so to negate one or the other pole. Death does not<br />

negate love, neither does blindness negate sight. As in a dream,<br />

negation and contradiction do not exist. As Freud observed above,<br />

there is no "no" in dreams.5 3 The film does not assert or deny any<br />

one truth about desire; it simply reveals the opposing elements that<br />

structure it and the rhetorical figures that enact it.<br />

"' Freud, Interpretation of Dreams, p. 353.<br />

1. A cyclist appears on a deserted<br />

Paris street.<br />

2. The woman places the cyclist's frills<br />

on the bed and adds the box.<br />

104<br />

3. The severed hand is prodded with<br />

the stick.<br />

4. The cyclist and woman observe the<br />

scene in the street below.<br />

5. The policeman puts the hand in the<br />

box.<br />

6. The policeman admonishes the an<br />

drogyne.


BLOCK 3<br />

SOWJETUNION – KINO DER MONTAGE


Chapter 13<br />

The Soviet montage cinema of the 1920s<br />

Mark Joyce<br />

• Introduction: why study the Soviet cinema? 418<br />

• Historical background 418<br />

• Pre-revolutionary Russian cinema 419<br />

• Soviet cinema and ideology: film as agent of<br />

change 420<br />

• Economics of the Soviet film industry 421<br />

• Form: montage 422<br />

• Other features of the Soviet montage cinema 425<br />

• The key Soviet montage film-makers of the 1920s 425<br />

• Case study 1: Lev Kuleshov, The Extraordinary Adventures<br />

of Mr West in the Land of the Bolsheviks (1924) 426<br />

• Case study 2: Sergei Eisenstein, Strike (1924); Battleship<br />

Potemkin (1925); October (1927); Old and New (1929) 428<br />

• Case study 3: Vsevolod Pudovkin, The Mother (1926);<br />

The End of St Petersburg (1927) 437<br />

• Case study 4: Alexander Dovzhenko, Arsenal (1929);<br />

Earth (1930) 441<br />

• Case study 5: Esfir Shub, The Fall of the Romanov Dynasty<br />

(1927) 443<br />

• Audience response 443<br />

• Theoretical debates: montage versus realism 444<br />

• Postscript to the 1920s 445<br />

• Notes and references 446<br />

• Further reading 448<br />

• Further viewing 449<br />

• Resource centres 450


N A T I O N A L<br />

The Soviet montage cinema of the 1920s<br />

See Chapter 4 for further<br />

discussion of film form.<br />

Soviet cinema<br />

This will refer to films<br />

made in the Soviet Union<br />

between October 1920<br />

and 1991, although for<br />

the purposes of this<br />

chapter most Soviet<br />

films discussed will be<br />

confined to the 1920s.<br />

ideology<br />

There are two key definitions<br />

of this term, one<br />

provided by the ni<strong>net</strong>eenth-century<br />

German<br />

philosopher, Karl Marx,<br />

the other by the twentieth-century<br />

French<br />

Marxist philosopher,<br />

Louis Althusser, drawing<br />

on Marx's original ideas.<br />

For Marx, ideology was<br />

the dominant set of<br />

beliefs and values existent<br />

within society, which<br />

sustained power relations.<br />

For Althusser,<br />

ideology consisted of the<br />

representations and<br />

images which reflect<br />

society's view of'reality'.<br />

Ideology thus refers to<br />

'the myths that a society<br />

lives by'.<br />

See Chapter 5 for<br />

discussion of ideology in<br />

relation to spectatorship.<br />

INTRODUCTION: WHY STUDY THE SOVIET CINEMA?<br />

As the lights went up at the end an emotion-charged silence reigned, broken<br />

only when Lunacharsky [the Soviet Union's Commissar for Education] jumped<br />

on his chair and began an enthusiastic speech: 'We've been witnesses at an<br />

historic cultural event. A new art has been born....' 1<br />

Anatoli Lunacharsky's response to Sergei Eisenstein's 1925 film Battleship Potemkin<br />

acknowledges the importance of a new wave of film-making. The films made by the<br />

Soviet directors of the 1920s are considered by many as the most innovative and<br />

exciting to have been produced in the history of the cinema. The names of these filmmakers,<br />

such as Eisenstein, Pudovkin, Vertov and Kuleshov, are far from forgotten and<br />

a number of the films and directors from this period consistently score highly in Sight<br />

and Sound's critics'/directors' choice of the best ten films and directors.<br />

This decade of intensive experimentation with film form produced techniques that<br />

have subsequently been widely emulated. In addition, the theoretical debates formulated<br />

by these film-makers are still relevant today. For these reasons the Soviet cinema<br />

of the 1920s merits detailed analysis.<br />

HISTORICAL BACKGROUND<br />

The Soviet film-makers of the 1920s reflect the ideology (the values and beliefs) and<br />

politics of the society in which they were produced. The early 1920s marked the end of<br />

a period of civil unrest, the causes of which lay in the great divide that separated<br />

wealthy land-owning Russians from the peasants and workers. 2 For centuries Russia<br />

had been governed by the single figure of the Tsar who had absolute powers. The<br />

Russian serfs were not granted freedom from slavery until 1861; this liberation, however,<br />

did not mean improved conditions, as they continued to live an existence of appalling<br />

poverty. Attempts had been made prior to the revolution of October 1917 by various<br />

factions to undermine the Tsarist regime, all of which were unsuccessful. A wave of<br />

revolutionary activity in 1905 included a mutiny by Russian sailors at Odessa which<br />

formed the basis for Sergei Eisenstein's 1925 film Battleship Potemkin.<br />

The First World War (1914-18) eventually proved to be disastrous for Tsar Nicholas II,<br />

as it consumed vast amounts of money and resources that were sorely needed at<br />

home. It was also unpopular with the Russian people as the reasons for fighting were<br />

unclear. The peasants and the workers were the worst hit by the impact of the war,<br />

either being killed on the front or starving at home as supplies became depleted. The<br />

land-owning rich were protected by their wealth and were able to continue in their<br />

existing lifestyle.<br />

These conditions provided the catalyst for the revolution of 25 February 1917 which<br />

resulted in the formation of a liberal provisional government led by Alexander Kerensky<br />

and later supported by Menshevik and Socialist Revolutionary factions. This caused<br />

Nicholas II to abdicate on 4 March. The provisional government decided to continue the<br />

war, and for many (especially V.I. Lenin who was in hiding in Zurich) it appeared that the<br />

new government was in effect continuing the policies of the Tsarist order.<br />

On 25 October 1917 the Bolsheviks, taking advantage of a situation of confusion<br />

and competition between the various factions, seized power by storming the Winter<br />

Palace. 3 The new Bolshevik government agreed to Germany's demands for control of


areas of land previously under Russian administration, and pulled out of the war.<br />

Almost immediately, however, a fierce civil war broke out between the Bolsheviks<br />

(known as the Reds) and those still loyal to the Tsarist regime (known as the<br />

Whites). 4<br />

By 1920 it was clear that the Bolsheviks had seized ultimate control of the country.<br />

The new Soviet government under the leadership of V.I. Lenin was faced with the task<br />

of convincing the population of Russia of the evils of the Tsarist regime and the positive<br />

points of the new Communist one.<br />

Selected historical dates<br />

1905, Jan. First revolution (abortive)<br />

1914, July<br />

1917, Feb.<br />

1917, Oct.<br />

1918-21<br />

1922-8<br />

1922-3<br />

1924<br />

1927<br />

Provides the backdrop for Eisenstein's Battleship Potemkin<br />

General strike organised by the Bolsheviks<br />

Outbreak of war and the crushing of the political unrest<br />

The war was a general disaster for the Russians; low morale and<br />

food shortages in the following years led to uprisings in 1917<br />

Popular uprisings culminating in the overthrow of the Tsar, and the<br />

setting up of a provisional government<br />

The Bolsheviks overthrow the provisional government and seize<br />

political power<br />

Civil war between White and Red factions, as well as fighting of<br />

hostile troops sent from abroad in an attempt to restore the power<br />

of the Tsar. The continued fighting led to the destruction of trade,<br />

agriculture, industry and film production<br />

NEP (New Economic Policy) adopted by Lenin. A brief return to<br />

controlled forms of capitalism to help to rebuild the shattered<br />

economy<br />

Soviet feature film production resumes<br />

Sergei Eisenstein's Strike completed<br />

The tenth anniversary of the October Revolution. A number of films<br />

are made to mark the occasion including:<br />

October (Eisenstein)<br />

The End of St Petersburg (Vsevolod Pudovkin)<br />

The Fall of the Romanov Dynasty (Esfir Shub)<br />

PRE-REVOLUTIONARY RUSSIAN CINEMA<br />

The nature of the Russian cinema<br />

When discussing the Soviet cinema it is important to have at least an outline of the form<br />

and content of its antecedent, for although the majority of the Soviet directors had not<br />

made films prior to 1919, they would certainly have been familiar with the conventions<br />

of the pre-revolutionary cinema. Significantly, for a number of the Soviet directors, this<br />

cinema was the antithesis of their new approach to film-making. The Russian cinema<br />

1907-17 was in fact markedly different from the Soviet cinema of the 1920s. The<br />

majority of the films that are available for viewing today 5 are between thirty-five and<br />

seventy minutes long and deal predominantly with the lives of the upper classes, quite<br />

frequently centring on their relationship with servants and/or the working class. Their<br />

subject matter, plot and preoccupations are often melodramatic; unfaithful husbands<br />

and wives, psychological states of mind and death predominate. The form of the films is<br />

also different, comprising slow-moving scenes containing a limited number of shots,<br />

with an emphasis on the mise en scene and in particular the expressions of the actors.<br />

Russian cinema<br />

This will refer to the<br />

body of films made in<br />

Tsarist Russia between<br />

1907 and 1919.<br />

mise en scene<br />

This literally means<br />

'placed in the scene',<br />

and it includes all<br />

elements that are placed<br />

before the camera such<br />

as props, actors,<br />

costume, movement and<br />

position of actors, etc.


See Chapter 4 for further<br />

discussion of mise en<br />

scéne.<br />

montage<br />

From the French word<br />

meaning 'to edit',<br />

montage means the<br />

assembling of bits of<br />

footage to form a whole.<br />

In film studies it usually<br />

refers to the style of fast<br />

editing adopted by the<br />

Soviet film-makers of<br />

the 1920s.<br />

N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S<br />

A key director working in this period is Evgeny Bauer, who produced a large number of<br />

films including After Death (1915), A Life for a Life (1916) and The King of Paris (1917). 6<br />

The Russian Revolution of October 1917 and the civil war that followed had a devastating<br />

effect on the Russian film industry, which was almost completely destroyed. Very<br />

few of the Russian directors and stars remained in Russia after 1919, the majority<br />

having fled to Paris where they continued production. 7 Initially it would seem that the<br />

Russian cinema had little in common with the Soviet cinema that followed, and there<br />

appears to have been a clear break in terms of style between the two cinemas after the<br />

revolution. The figure of Yakov Protazanov, however, provides an interesting example of<br />

a film-maker who made films between 1911-43. 8 His key films from the pre-revolutionary<br />

era include, The Queen of Spades (1916) and Satan Triumphant (1917); these<br />

conform to the conventions of the Russian cinema outlined earlier. His best-known film<br />

of the 1920s is Aelita (1924), a fantasy concerning a revolution on Mars. Protazanov was<br />

more concerned with mise en scene than with creating new meanings by juxtaposing<br />

images. A study of his films reveals that the Tsarist cinema continued into the Soviet<br />

montage era and was by all accounts successful with the public. 9<br />

Russian cinema audiences and imported films<br />

That Russian films had moderate success with native audiences is not surprising. What<br />

is significant, however, is that before the revolution the most popular films with Russian<br />

audiences were imported from America, France and Germany. The first Russian film<br />

studio was not set up until 1907 10 and this can partly account for the success of these<br />

foreign films as audiences had grown accustomed to watching them. In the 1910s when<br />

native films vied for audiences with imported films, foreign ones were clearly the more<br />

successful and were perceived by Russian audiences as being more entertaining and<br />

having higher production values than Russian films.<br />

SOVIET CINEMA AND<br />

CHANGE 11<br />

IDEOLOGY: FILM AS AGENT OF<br />

The October Revolution was the first successful revolution made in the name of Karl<br />

Marx (1818-83). For Marx, the key fact about any society was how it produced its livelihood.<br />

He saw capitalism as an economic system, which, just like every other previous<br />

economic system, was based on exploitation. In capitalism the class with power was<br />

the bourgeoisie, the owners of the means of production, and the class subject to their<br />

power was the proletariat or working class. In addition, the bourgeoisie's economic<br />

strength was protected by the state and sustained by ideology. However, as capitalism<br />

developed, the workers, who survived by selling their labour for wages, would be<br />

squeezed more and more as competition between capitalists intensified. At the same<br />

time they would become aware that they would have everything to gain by replacing an<br />

economic system based on the ownership of private property with one based on the<br />

non-exploitative communal ownership of productive property. This awareness, or classconsciousness,<br />

would eventually produce a revolution. The October Revolution was<br />

seen as such a proletarian revolution in Russia and was celebrated as such by the films<br />

of the key Soviet film-makers of the 1920s.<br />

The revolution, however, was only the beginning of a process of radical social<br />

change, called the era of 'the dictatorship of the proletariat' because it involved the<br />

proletariat, or in this case its representatives, the Bolshevik Party, establishing its dominance.<br />

V.I. Lenin writing in Pravda outlined the situation:<br />

Theoretically, there can be no doubt that between capitalism and communism there lies a definite<br />

EC


S O V I E T M O N T A G E C I N E M A M A R K J O Y C E<br />

transition period which must combine the features and properties of both these forms of social<br />

economy. This transition period has to be a period of struggle between dying capitalism and<br />

nascent communism - or, in other words, between capitalism which has been defeated but not<br />

destroyed and communism which has been born but is still very feeble. 12<br />

The transition to communism referred to by Lenin would have been a monumental task<br />

at the best of times, but the Bolsheviks had seized control of a country whose industry<br />

and agriculture were relatively underdeveloped. Also they had to confront internal and<br />

external opposition, civil war and famine. In such a situation artists and film-makers<br />

were perceived as having a special role as proponents of propaganda cinema. Lenin<br />

declared in 1922 that 'of all the arts, for us the cinema is the most important'. 13 Prior to<br />

this, trains highly decorated with Soviet flags and paintings had been sent into the<br />

countryside in an attempt to educate and inform the peasants. 14 Short agitational films<br />

called agitki were made. Pre-revolutionary newsreels and foreign fiction films were also<br />

shown, with a Soviet commentator giving a 'new' reading to the material. Later most of<br />

the energy went into the making of new feature films that reflected the ideals of the new<br />

regime. Anatoli Lunacharsky (the People's Commissar for Education) had stated in<br />

1924:<br />

There is no doubt that cinema art is a first-class and perhaps even an incomparable instrument for<br />

the dissemination of all sorts of ideas. Cinema's strength lies in the fact that, like any art, it imbues<br />

an idea with feeling and with captivating form but, unlike the other arts, cinema is actually cheap,<br />

portable and unusually graphic. Its effects reach where even the book cannot reach and it is, of<br />

course, more powerful than any kind of narrow propaganda. The Russian Revolution, which is<br />

extremely interested in exercising the broadest possible influence on the masses, should long since<br />

have turned its attention to cinema as its natural instrument. 15<br />

The enthusiastic, young, educated film-makers, who attempted to fulfil<br />

Lunacharsky's ideal of revolutionary cinema, responded by making innovative films,<br />

revolutionary both in content and in form.<br />

ECONOMICS OF THE SOVIET FILM INDUSTRY<br />

The pre-revolutionary Russian film industry had previously imported its film stock from<br />

abroad, and during the civil war most of the Russian film-makers had fled to White-held<br />

areas (or abroad) taking their equipment with them. The reality facing the film-makers of<br />

the newly formed state was that there was little in the way of film stock or equipment. 16<br />

The Soviet government initially attempted to ban the showing of all American and<br />

European films, as they were concerned about the public being exposed to films that<br />

reflected the values of capitalist societies. The Soviets had little option, however, but to<br />

show these films as they had no native film industry to produce their own. The cinema<br />

was seen by the new government as a means of keeping the public entertained at a<br />

time of hardship and general civil unrest.<br />

From a western perspective it is easy to underestimate the importance of imported<br />

films in the Soviet Union in the 1920s. Denise Youngblood (1992: 944-71), in Movies for<br />

the Masses, states that 'Foreign films accounted for almost two-thirds of the titles<br />

screened in the twenties.... Nearly as many American as Soviet films were shown in this<br />

period'. She continues: 'Sovkino's head, K.M. Shvedchikov, claimed in 1927 that<br />

Sovkino would be bankrupt were it not for the success of its import policy.' 17<br />

The 1920s could be characterised as a period in which American and European<br />

propaganda cinema<br />

A terms used pejoratively<br />

with reference to<br />

any film that consciously<br />

attempts to persuade an<br />

audience towards<br />

certain beliefs and<br />

values.<br />

See Chapter 7,<br />

pp. 219-24 for discussion<br />

of propaganda and<br />

British cinema during the<br />

Second World War.


422 N A T I O N A L CI N E M A S<br />

See Chapter 4,<br />

pp. 110-13, for reference<br />

to Kuleshov's<br />

experiments with<br />

editing, and for discussion<br />

of editing in<br />

mainstream narrative<br />

cinema.<br />

narrative films were in effect directly subsidising the dramatic experimentation with film<br />

form undertaken by the Soviet film-makers.<br />

Innovation and experimentation frequently come from a lack. In the Soviet Union the<br />

lack of film stock (and even film cameras) meant that certain groups of film-makers<br />

worked on re-editing existing films (often European/American films and old Russian<br />

newsreels) to make them conform to the values of the Soviet state. Other film-makers<br />

experimented with creating films from the small amount of negative available, which<br />

often only came in short lengths. Out of this experimentation came Soviet montage<br />

cinema.<br />

FORM: MONTAGE<br />

The roots of Soviet montage<br />

The innovative use of montage in film by the Soviet film-makers had its roots in art<br />

forms such as painting, literature and music from pre-revolutionary Russia. David<br />

Bordwell, in The Idea of Montage in Soviet Art and Film', states that by 1910 a group of<br />

Russian painters had already experimented extensively with 'montage': 'the Russian<br />

futurists declared that conventional art must be destroyed and that a new art, appropriate<br />

to the machine age, must be created. Hence the futurists took their subjects from<br />

modern life and exploited a technique of shocking juxtapositions.' 18 Poetry, in particular<br />

that of Mayakovsky, 19 was also 'shattering words and reassembling them into brutal<br />

images'.<br />

The question needs to be asked: why didn't the Russian film-makers of the 1910s<br />

experiment with montage earlier? This lack of explicit montage experiment in the<br />

Russian cinema compared to that taking place in other art forms can perhaps be attributed<br />

to economics. The crucial difference between film and- many of the other arts at<br />

the time was that the small groups of experimental artists, writers and musicians were<br />

often privately funded by rich patrons. The film industry, however, was not. 20 The revolution<br />

of October 1917 provided the right conditions for experimentation with film to take<br />

place. It is ironic that this experimentation had its roots in the elitist art forms of prerevolutionary<br />

Russia.<br />

The Kuleshov effect and its consequences<br />

The montage technique is based on the theory that when two pieces of film are placed<br />

side by side the audience immediately draws the conclusion that the two shots must be<br />

directly related in some way. In other words, the audience try to create meaning by<br />

combining the two separate images. The experimentation along these lines by Lev<br />

Kuleshov, a young Soviet film-maker, culminated in what became known as the<br />

Kuleshov effect. Vsevolod Pudovkin outlined the experiment in a lecture given at the<br />

London Film Society in February 1929:<br />

Kuleshov and I made an interesting experiment. We took from some film or other several close-ups<br />

of the well-known Russian actor Mosjukhin. We chose close-ups which were static and which did<br />

not express any feeling at all - quiet close-ups. We joined these close-ups, which were all similar,<br />

with other bits of film in three different combinations. In the first combination the close-up of<br />

Mosjukhin was immediately followed by a shot of a plate of soup standing on a table. It was<br />

obvious and certain that Mosjukhin was looking at this soup. In the second combination the face of<br />

Mosjukhin was joined to shots showing a coffin in which lay a dead woman. In the third the closeup<br />

was followed by a shot of a little girl playing with a funny toy bear. When we showed the three<br />

combinations to an audience which had not been let into the secret the result was terrific. The<br />

public raved abut the acting of the artist. They pointed out the heavy pensiveness of his mood over


S O V I E T M O N T A G E C I N E M A M A R K J O Y C E<br />

the forgotten soup, were touched and moved by the deep sorrow with which he looked on the dead<br />

woman, and admired the light, happy smile with which he surveyed the girl at play. But we knew<br />

that in all three cases the face was exactly the same. 21<br />

Kuleshov carried out further experiments using editing in which he cut together<br />

separate shots of a walking man, a waiting woman, a gate, a staircase and a mansion. 22<br />

When the shots were combined the audience assumed that the different elements were<br />

present at the same location. Kuleshov had discovered the cinema's ability to link<br />

entirely unrelated material into coherent sequences. He termed the technique 'creative<br />

geography'.<br />

Kuleshov's discoveries about the nature of the cinema medium provided a number<br />

of film-makers with a new set of ideas about how film could manipulate and deceive an<br />

audience. Perhaps the most vital consequence of the Kuleshov effect, however, for later<br />

directors, was its recognition that the audience were not merely passive recipients.<br />

Soviet montage cinema<br />

In the 1920s a number of the film-makers carried out further experiments with editing<br />

techniques along the same lines as Kuleshov. It was discovered that when two shots<br />

were joined together meaning could be made by emphasising the difference between<br />

shots, that is, instead of trying to cover up graphic dissimilarities between shots, as in<br />

the Hollywood cinema, the difference could be emphasised and indeed become the<br />

main way in which meaning could be created. This 'montage' cinema which demanded<br />

that audiences continually searched for the meanings created by the juxtaposition of<br />

two shots can thus be seen as alternative to the continuity editing-based Hollywood<br />

cinema. One of the Soviet film-makers who developed this idea into both a theory and a<br />

practice of film-making was Sergei Eisenstein.<br />

Eisenstein believed that maximum impact could be achieved if shots in a scene were<br />

in conflict. This belief was based on the general philosophical idea that 'existence' can<br />

only continue by constant change. In other words, everything surrounding us in the<br />

world is as a result of a 'collision' of opposite elements. The existing world is itself only<br />

in a temporary state until the next collision of elements produces a completely new<br />

state. It is only through this 'collision' that change can be effected. This method of<br />

creating meaning from such collision of opposites is termed dialectical. When applying<br />

this idea to film, Eisenstein proposed the view that when two shots are combined a<br />

completely new meaning is formed. For example, shot A combined with shot B does<br />

not produce AB but the new meaning C. The formulation can also be presented as:<br />

thesis + anti-thesis = synthesis.<br />

Vsevolod Pudovkin, another key Soviet film-maker, was opposed to the theoretical<br />

ideas of Eisenstein, although they both used innovative forms of montage in their films.<br />

Pudovkin, like Kuleshov, believed that shots could be likened to bricks in the sense that<br />

they could be used as building blocks to construct a scene. Pudovkin then did not see<br />

his shots as being in conflict. In Pudovkin's formulae shot A + shot B = AB rather than<br />

C. Pudovkin aimed at linkage rather than conflict in his scenes.<br />

The montage technique was not only confined to fiction film-making. Soviet<br />

documentary film-makers such as Dziga Vertov and Esfir Shub used montage<br />

extensively in a range of films in the 1920s, including Vertov's well-known The<br />

Man with a Movie Camera (1929). For Vertov much of the power of cinema came<br />

from its ability to mechanically record events that took place before the camera,<br />

but he also ensured that the audience was made aware of the constructed nature<br />

of his films. His films are a whirlwind of conflicting shots which disavow conventional<br />

ideas of narrative.<br />

Hollywood cinema<br />

In classical Hollywood<br />

cinema, the editing is<br />

designed to be Invisible'.<br />

It is intended to<br />

allow the audience<br />

closer views and to see<br />

the point of view of<br />

different characters. The<br />

editing is used essentially<br />

to clarify what is<br />

taking place in the<br />

narrative. This type of<br />

editing had become<br />

dominant in Hollywood<br />

film-making by approximately<br />

1920.<br />

juxtaposition<br />

In film studies, this<br />

usually refers to two<br />

different shots that have<br />

been joined together to<br />

make a contrast.<br />

alternative<br />

Alternative cinema is<br />

defined with reference to<br />

dominant: it is an alternative<br />

(both<br />

economically and<br />

formally) to the dominant<br />

form. In any study<br />

concerning an 'alternative'<br />

cinema, the films<br />

would not only have to<br />

be examined in their<br />

own right, but also<br />

compared to contemporary<br />

dominant Hollywood<br />

cinema.<br />

A number of questions<br />

might have to be posed<br />

when analysing these<br />

alternative films: In what<br />

ways is this group of<br />

films different to the<br />

dominant cinema of the<br />

time? What are the<br />

possible reasons for the<br />

difference: cultural?<br />

economic? social? political?<br />

Could this<br />

'alternative' way of<br />

making films, given the<br />

right conditions, have<br />

itself turned into the<br />

dominant cinema?<br />

The Soviet cinema of<br />

the 1920s, when<br />

compared to the Hollywood<br />

cinema of the same<br />

era, certainly could be<br />

regarded as alternative.


In other words, it offered<br />

a style of film-making<br />

that was radically<br />

different to the mass of<br />

films that was being<br />

produced in America.<br />

See Chapter 4 for<br />

discussion of continuity<br />

editing, conventional<br />

narrative and alternative<br />

narratives.<br />

dialectical<br />

A difficult term to define,<br />

as it has many different<br />

meanings. The Collins<br />

English Dictionary (2nd<br />

edn., 1986), for example,<br />

defines it a 'disputation<br />

or debate, esp. intended<br />

to resolve differences<br />

between two views<br />

rather than to establish<br />

one of them as true'. The<br />

crucial factor to grasp in<br />

the context of<br />

Eisenstein's thinking,<br />

however, is the notion of<br />

change and the creation<br />

of a new order.<br />

Eisenstein would have<br />

defined dialectic with<br />

reference to Marxist<br />

philosophy, which<br />

believed that society was<br />

contradictory and in<br />

need of change.<br />

See Chapter 7,<br />

pp. 215-16, for further<br />

discussion of Vertov and<br />

his contribution to documentary<br />

film.<br />

non-diegetic<br />

Refers to any element<br />

that remains outside the<br />

world of the film, such as<br />

voiceovers, credits and<br />

mood-setting music, that<br />

does not originate from<br />

the world of the film.<br />

N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S<br />

The montage technique for the majority of the Soviet film-makers could also provide<br />

sequences with a sense of rhythm and momentum, which could be used to increase or<br />

decrease the speed of the action. Eisenstein, for example, frequently increases his rate<br />

of cutting prior to the climax of a scene. Violent actions couid also be emphasised by<br />

using a succession of short conflicting shots from different viewpoints. Montage, the<br />

film-makers discovered, could further be used to either compress or expand time,<br />

which could heighten the effect of certain actions or events.<br />

Four different types of film montage 23<br />

The first two categories of montage outlined below are frequently, although not exclusively, used in Soviet film; the last<br />

two categories deal with montage techniques that are often to be found in mainstream films:<br />

• Intellectual montage (also called dialectical montage or discontinuity editing)<br />

• Linkage editing (also known as constructive editing)<br />

• Hollywood montage<br />

• Fast cutting<br />

Intellectual montage<br />

In this type of editing, shots are placed together to emphasise their difference. They are in 'collision' with each other. For<br />

example, in October a shot of a mechanical golden peacock is placed next to a shot of a man (the peacock does not<br />

form part of the world of the film, that is, it is non-diegetic). The audience draw the conclusion that the man is vain. In<br />

this type of editing the audience are not passive as they play an active part in producing meaning from the film.<br />

Linkage editing<br />

Mainly used by Pudovkin, who proposed a theory of montage based on this principle. In linkage editing individual shots<br />

are used to build up scenes. The shots are not in collision with each other, but are used as fragments or parts of a whole<br />

scene. The technique can be seen in The Mother and The End of St Petersburg.<br />

Hollywood montage<br />

Often used to show a quick succession of events over a period of time. For example, in Raging Bull (1980) Martin<br />

Scorsese shows the successful career of the boxer Jack La Motta by combining shots (mostly still photographs) taken<br />

from a number of different fights interspersed with home movie footage of La Motta's home life. The shots are clearly<br />

intended to flow into each other rather than to be in conflict. The music played on the soundtrack over the images rein­<br />

forces the sense of continuity.<br />

Fast cutting<br />

In which editing is used primarily to build suspense or tension. For example, in the gunfight at the climax of The Good,<br />

the Bad and the Ugly (1966), Sergio Leone creates a dramatic effect by using a combination of music, tighter and tighter<br />

close-ups of the three characters and a shortening of shot length.<br />

Statistical analysis of Soviet films<br />

Soviet films, because of the use of the montage technique, contain many more shots<br />

than Hollywood films of the same period. David Bordwell 24 claims that the Soviet films<br />

of the 1920s contain on average between 600-2,000 shots, whereas the films made in<br />

Hollywood between 1917 and 1928 contain on average 500-1,000 shots. He further<br />

suggests that Hollywood films had an average shot length of five to six seconds and the<br />

Soviet films had an average shot length of two to four seconds. The comparison<br />

provides concrete evidence of the unique nature of the editing used in the Soviet films<br />

in this period.


OTHER FEATURES OF THE SOVIET MONTAGE CINEMA<br />

Aside from editing, these films have other features which separate them from the dominant<br />

Hollywood cinema. In keeping with a Marxist analysis of society, plots frequently<br />

do not centre on the individual; for example, in Eisenstein's Strike, October and<br />

Battleship Potemkin, individual heroes are replaced by a mass of people. The only characters<br />

that are individuated are those that wield power or have wealth. Events in the<br />

narrative therefore are not motivated by individuals. Films such as Pudovkin's The<br />

Mother and The End of St Petersburg and Dovzhenko's Earth do have central characters,<br />

but it is made clear that these characters are representative of the masses. The<br />

audience is not interested in the details of the heroes, only what they represent. A<br />

number of the Soviet film-makers (including Eisenstein and Pudovkin) also used nonactors<br />

to play key parts, believing that the external appearance of the character was<br />

vital to the performance. This idea is termed 'typage'.<br />

The montage style also means that Soviet cinema relies more heavily on the use of<br />

the close-up than Hollywood cinema. Not only are there more shots overall in a scene,<br />

but a greater proportion of them are close-ups. A number of Soviet films also rely on<br />

high levels of symbolism to achieve their aims. The audience must be culturally and<br />

politically aware to be able to decode the messages that are being presented. In<br />

Eisenstein's October, for example, great demands are made on the audience to create a<br />

'reading' of the film which does justice to Eisenstein's political thinking. It may seem<br />

that many of the film-makers ran the risk of making films that were not understood by<br />

their audience.<br />

Several of the montage film-makers combined the montage principle with other<br />

techniques that they believed would revitalise the cinema. Lev Kuleshov, for example,<br />

placed great emphasis on the gestures and movement of actors. FEKS (Factory of the<br />

Eccentric Actor), formed by film-makers Grigori Kozintsev and Leonid Trauberg, had<br />

similar concerns about the role of the actor, but also paid great attention to mise en<br />

scene.<br />

THE KEY SOVIET MONTAGE Fl LM-MAKERS OF THE<br />

1920s<br />

Fiction<br />

Lev Kuleshov<br />

Sergei Eisenstein<br />

Vsevolod Pudovkin<br />

FEKS (Kozintsev and Trauberg)<br />

Alexander Dovzhenko<br />

Documentary<br />

Dziga Vertov<br />

Esfir Shub<br />

A film directed by Eisenstein probably provided most viewers' first experience of Soviet<br />

montage. The history of the Soviet cinema of the 1920s, however, involves more than<br />

the work of this one director. In this section, although the work of Eisenstein is<br />

discussed in detail, the vital importance of Eisenstein's contemporaries is recognised by<br />

analysing the work of such directors as Kuleshov, Pudovkin, Kozintsev and Trauberg,<br />

Dovzhenko, Vertov and Shub.<br />

Lev Kuleshov (1899-1970)<br />

Shortly after the revolution, Kuleshov was recruited as a teacher by the State Film<br />

dominant<br />

Refers to both economic<br />

strength and also to the<br />

dominant form or<br />

convention, which is<br />

realism: dominant<br />

cinema in film studies is<br />

assumed to be<br />

Hollywood.<br />

symbolism<br />

The means by which a<br />

film-maker can assign<br />

additional meanings to<br />

objects/characters in a<br />

film. For example, in<br />

Dovzhenko's Earth and<br />

Eisenstein's Old and<br />

New, the tractor is a<br />

symbol of progress.


Key films<br />

Engineer Prite's Project<br />

(1918)<br />

The Extraordinary<br />

Adventures of Mr West in<br />

the Land of the<br />

Bolsheviks (1924)<br />

The Death Ray (1925)<br />

By the Law (1926)<br />

For comparison and<br />

contrast see Chapter 6<br />

for a discussion of the<br />

star in Hollywood<br />

cinema.<br />

N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S<br />

School where he set up an experimental film workshop. Kuleshov and his students<br />

carried out a number of experiments related to editing, partly inspired by a lack of<br />

raw film stock. One of these experiments included re-editing D.W. Griffith's<br />

Intolerance (1916), a film that had impressed Kuleshov because of its innovative use<br />

of editing. The experiments resulted in the formation of a number of principles of<br />

film-making that the group adopted. The underlying belief for Kuleshov was that<br />

'Film-art begins from the moment when the director begins to combine and join<br />

together the various pieces of film'. 25 Kuleshov's ideas about how editing should<br />

work are similar to those of Pudovkin in that his shots, rather than being in conflict,<br />

can be seen as blocks out of which a scene can be constructed. Significantly,<br />

Kuleshov's students included Vsevolod Pudovkin and for a brief time Sergei<br />

Eisenstein. In Eisenstein's films and theoretical writing the influence of Kuleshov can<br />

clearly be seen.<br />

Kuleshov's experimentation was not confined to editing, however, but also involved<br />

acting. He believed that theatre-trained actors, in particular those from the Moscow Arts<br />

Theatre 26 were not suitable for the cinema. He also rejected the idea of using nonactors<br />

or 'types' chosen for their visual suitability for a role. He set up an acting<br />

laboratory dedicated to developing a style of acting tailored specifically to the requirements<br />

of the cinema and he carefully recruited would-be film actors who were<br />

'endowed with natural beauty, good health, and the ability to show expediency and<br />

purpose on the screen without "acting" or "recreating", unaided by makeup, wigs, and<br />

props, of course'. 27<br />

The techniques that Kuleshov adopted emphasised gesture and movement, the<br />

exact nature and timing of which had been practised rigorously in rehearsals. This style<br />

of acting was combined with great attention to the composition and framing of each<br />

shot to give maximum impact to the action. Kuleshov's opportunity to apply the principles<br />

that he had developed came in 1924 when he was assigned valuable imported film<br />

stock to direct the first feature film of the film school: The Extraordinary Adventures of<br />

Mr West in the Land of the Bolsheviks.<br />

• CASE STUDY 1: LEV KULESHOV, THE<br />

EXTRAORDINARY ADVENTURES OF MR WEST IN THE<br />

LAND OF THE BOLSHEVIKS (1924)<br />

The film is an action-comedy which uses satire to expose the false attitudes and beliefs<br />

about the Soviet Union that many in the West held. The action is centred on the fate of<br />

Mr West, an American visitor to the USSR, whose view of the Bolsheviks as savages is<br />

formed by reading the New York Times. Mr West falls into the hands of a group of petty<br />

criminals who frighten him into parting with his dollars by dressing up to look like the<br />

Bolsheviks that Mr West had seen in his paper. At the climax he is rescued by a 'real'<br />

Bolshevik who uncovers the deception. Mr West's stereotypical views of the Bolsheviks<br />

are dismantled and he sends a radio message to his wife telling her to hang Lenin's<br />

picture in the study.<br />

The montage technique used in Mr West is largely based on a system of closeups<br />

of the actors that emphasise facial expressions. Kuleshov frequently cuts from<br />

an action to a close-up reaction shot of a character's face. He starts the film with a<br />

separate shot of Mr West juxtaposed with another of his wife; it is only later that we<br />

see them together. Later in the film Kuleshov cuts between a shot of the 'real'<br />

Bolshevik and Mr West standing on a balcony and another shot of marching Soviet<br />

troops taken at a different place and time (the film stock is markedly different).


S O V I E T M O N T A G E C I N E M A • M A R K J O Y C E<br />

Kuleshov is here using his technique of creative geography to make the audience<br />

construct a location in their minds that does not actually exist. The film also fulfils<br />

Kuleshov's ideas concerning acting. The movements of the actors are stylised and<br />

precise and it is clear that attention has been paid to even the smallest action. The<br />

comical nature of the action and a plot based on individual characters meant that<br />

the film was popular with audiences. 28<br />

Sergei Eisenstein (1898-1948) 29<br />

Eisenstein, as his age might indicate (he was just 26 when he completed Strike),<br />

did not emerge from the context of the pre-revolutionary Russian cinema. Prior to<br />

his film-making career, he had experimented with a number of different art forms,<br />

including the theatre. In this experimentation, the principles of his work in film<br />

may be found. In 1923 Eisenstein produced a version of a play by Alexander<br />

Ostrovky, 30 in which he attempted to communicate the messages of the play to<br />

the audience using a series of shocks which Eisenstein termed 'attractions':<br />

'Emotions were expressed through flamboyant physical stunts ... at the finale, firecrackers<br />

exploded under spectators' seats... [he] explained that the theatre could<br />

engage its audience through a calculated assembly of "strong moments" of shock<br />

or surprise.' 31<br />

Eisenstein quickly abandoned experimentation with the theatre and turned to the<br />

more popular and accessible medium of film, to which he rigorously applied his<br />

theatrical principle of 'montage of attractions'.<br />

• Plate 13.1 The<br />

Extraordinary<br />

Adventures of Mr West<br />

in the Land of the<br />

Bolsheviks (1924)<br />

Mr West is duped by the<br />

false Bolsheviks.<br />

key films<br />

Sfrfte(1924)<br />

Battleship Potemkin<br />

(1925)<br />

October (1927)<br />

Old and New (1929)


• Plate 13.2 Sergei<br />

Eisenstein (1898-1948)<br />

N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S<br />

• CASE STUDY 2: SERGEI EISENSTEIN, STRIKE (1924);<br />

BATTLESHIP POTEMKIN (1925); OCTOBER (1927);<br />

OLD AND NEW (1929)<br />

Strike (192 4)<br />

Strike was the first of a proposed series of eight films 32 made by the Moscow Theatre of<br />

the Proletkult, under the general subheading 'Towards the Dictatorship of the<br />

Proletariat'. Strike is about the repression of a group of factory workers involved in an<br />

industrial dispute, which ends with the massacre of the strikers and their families by<br />

government forces. The six-part structure of 'Strike' - (1) 'All Quiet at the Factory', (2)<br />

'The Immediate Cause of Strike', (3) The Factory Stands Idle', (4) 'The Strike is<br />

Protracted', (5) 'Engineering a Massacre', (6) 'Slaughter' - is partly due to Eisenstein's<br />

theatrical background, but it would also have been vital for the film to be contained on<br />

single reels as many cinemas had only one projector.<br />

The plot of Strike, as in Eisenstein's later films Battleship Potemkin (1925) and<br />

October (1927), is not told using individual characters as heroes. Instead, any character<br />

that is individuated is deemed to be 'bad' or corrupt. The grotesque factory-owner, for<br />

example, is shown completely isolated in a vast office. The workers themselves,<br />

however, are seen usually as a group with no one individual standing out to play the role<br />

of leader. In Part 3 these ideas are combined. The scenes depicting the four stockholders<br />

of the factory carelessly deciding the future of the strikers are intercut with


S O V I E T M O N T A G E C I N E M A • M A R K J O Y C E<br />

images of strikers being attacked by mounted police; the individual concern of the capitalists<br />

contrasts with the collective concern of the masses. The effect of this montage is<br />

dramatic, as parallels can immediately be drawn by the viewer between, for example,<br />

the dishonesty, greed, deviousness and wealth of the management and the poverty and<br />

honesty of the workers. The political implications of this are obvious. Eisenstein,<br />

through montage, is seeking to persuade his audience towards a certain view.<br />

The methods applied by Eisenstein in Strike axe derived in part from a rebellion<br />

against what Eisenstein termed the 'Bourgeois Cinema' that was still the main form of<br />

entertainment in post-revolutionary cinemas. Eisenstein explains how this cinema was<br />

rejected in favour of his own approach: 'We brought collective and mass action onto the<br />

screen ... our films in this period made an abrupt deviation - insisting on an understanding<br />

of the masses as hero.' 33<br />

In terms of the Hollywood cinema it is not difficult to imagine how the plot of Strike<br />

could have been adapted into a mainstream film: the story of one individual's fight<br />

against authority. The comparison may be trite, but it does emphasise the difference in<br />

approach and purpose between the two different modes of representation. Eisenstein's<br />

decision not to use individual heroes is of course deliberate; the film registers a political<br />

ideology that enshrines the notion of collective strength.<br />

In Strike Eisenstein applies his principle of 'montage of attractions' to the editing. He<br />

believed that by creating visual 'jolts' between each cut, the viewer would be 'shocked'<br />

into new awarenesses. In most sequences this approach involves juxtaposing shots<br />

that are in conflict with each other in some way, either cutting between different actions<br />

taking place in a scene or emphasising the importance of certain actions or events by<br />

fragmenting them into a number of shots taken from different viewpoints. At various<br />

points in Strike Eisenstein juxtaposes shots which need to be interpreted by the audience.<br />

One of the best examples of this type of 'intellectual montage' is in the last part of<br />

the film ('Slaughter'), in which Eisenstein juxtaposes a non-diegetic image of a bull<br />

being slaughtered with the shots of the factory workers being systematically butchered<br />

by government forces. The formula mentioned earlier can be applied: shot A (massacre<br />

| • Plate 13.3 Strike<br />

(1924)<br />

Mounted police enter<br />

the factory district.


N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S


S O V I E T M O N T A G E C I N E M A • M A R K J O Y C E<br />

• Plate 13.4 This sequence from Strike (lasting 25 seconds) illustrates<br />

Eisenstein's use of intellectual montage. An inter-title ('Rout')<br />

is inserted between shots 2 and 3.


432 N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S<br />

• Plate 13.5 Battleship<br />

Potemkin (1925)<br />

Drama on the quarterdeck<br />

(the firing squad).<br />

of the workers) + shot B (bull being slaughtered) = NEW MEANING C (that the workers<br />

are being killed cold-bloodedly like animals in a slaughterhouse). It is the audience that<br />

is creating meaning here from the juxtaposition of the shots, thus becoming active political<br />

interpreters.<br />

Battleship Potemkin (1925)<br />

Eisenstein's second film Battleship Potemkin is based on the true story of a mutiny that<br />

took place on board the Potemkin in 1905. 34 As in Strike, Battleship Potemkin is split<br />

into a number of distinct parts: (1) 'Men and Maggots', (2) 'Drama on the Quarter Deck',<br />

(3) 'Appeal from the Dead', (4) 'The Odessa Steps', (5) 'Meeting the Squadron'.<br />

The central scene of the film, 'The Odessa Steps', consisting of parallel lines of<br />

soldiers marching down the steps leading to the harbour systematically shooting the<br />

onlookers, provides a vivid example of the effectiveness of Eisenstein's montage technique.<br />

35 A close examination of the sequence reveals that Eisenstein, by using montage<br />

to repeat certain key events, has expanded time. 36 The effect is to heighten the horrific<br />

nature of the slaughter as well as to hold the audience in suspense as the pram finally<br />

begins its descent. The furious and shocking climax to the scene demonstrates how<br />

Eisenstein is able to use montage to manipulate audience expectations and to shock<br />

with violent juxtapositions and graphic images.<br />

In the last part of the film in which the sailors aboard the Potemkin are nervously anticipating<br />

an attack by the rest of the Russian Fleet, Eisenstein builds up tension by increasing<br />

the number of cuts in a montage finale that maintains a consistently high rate of shots per<br />

minute. The scene provides an excellent example of the way in which montage could be<br />

used to create an event that did not exist as a whole, as according to Eisenstein the shots of<br />

the 'Russian' squadron were taken from 'old newsreels of naval manoeuvres - not even of<br />

the Russian Fleet'. 37 It also reveals how montage can be used for rhythmic effect, as the<br />

fast cutting between the different elements gives the scene a sense of urgency which<br />

would be impossible to achieve using any other method.<br />

The opposition of critics at the time ironically stressed the difficulties of understanding<br />

Potemkin's experimental form; ironic because it was through film form that<br />

Eisenstein hoped to make his political points. It was also declared that Potemkin was<br />

pitched far above the intellectual level of most peasants, a damning indictment for any<br />

propaganda/revolutionary piece. However, although Potemkin was not successful as a


• Plates 13.7,13.8 and 13.9<br />

Battleship Potemkin (1925)<br />

Immediately after the massacre on the Odessa Steps, the sailors on the battleship take their revenge by shelling the<br />

headquarters of the generals. As part of this sequence, Eisenstein juxtaposes three images of stone lions in<br />

different stages of awakening as a symbol of the awakening of the Russian people to political ideas and action.<br />

piece of popular propaganda, it did, like Strike before it, mark a major step in the<br />

progress of revolutionary cinema. It also represented the first film that gave recognition<br />

and acclaim to Soviet cinema. The claim that the experimental nature of Potemkin was<br />

not solely to blame for its unpopularity, and that it was badly let down 'by Sovkino's<br />

methods of distribution, is a view that should certainly be considered.<br />

October (1927)<br />

October, made for the Tenth Anniversary celebrations of the Russian Revolution, depicts<br />

the build-up to the October Revolution, ending with the storming of the Winter Palace by<br />

the Bolsheviks. It is considered the most experimental of Eisenstein's films, especially in its<br />

increased use of 'intellectual montage', which demands that the audience think critically<br />

and constructively about important political issues. A demonstration of this type of<br />

montage can be found in the scene in which both Kerensky and General Kornilov are<br />

depicted as Napoleons. By intercutting between the two men and the plaster cast figures<br />

of Napoleon, Eisenstein effectively exposes both the vanity and essentially the lack of any<br />

• Plate 13.6 Battleship<br />

Potemkin (1925)<br />

The Odessa Steps.


diegetic<br />

The elements of a film<br />

that originate from<br />

directly within the film's<br />

narrative. For example, a<br />

popular song that is<br />

being played on the<br />

soundtrack would be<br />

diegetic if it was clear<br />

that it was coming from<br />

a source within the<br />

world of the film such as<br />

a car radio.<br />

• Plate 13.10 October<br />

(1927)<br />

Lenin's arrival at the<br />

Finland Railway Station.<br />

N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S<br />

power within the characters themselves to form a separate identity. 38 Eisenstein's 'intellectual<br />

montage' also involves diegetic material. For example, early in the film, shots of a<br />

soldier cowering in a trench are juxtaposed with low-angle shots of a vast cannon being<br />

unloaded elsewhere. The combination of shots initially points to the soldier being physically<br />

crushed, but then swiftly the assumption is reached that the war is oppressive,<br />

degrading and without purpose for the ordinary troops.<br />

Eisenstein also combines montage techniques with visual puns and symbolism for<br />

political effect. At one point, in order to degrade the power of the church, he swiftly cuts<br />

from the image of one deity to another, starting with a magnificent statue of Christ, and<br />

ending up with a primitive wooden idol, demonstrating that all religions essentially<br />

worship crude man-made objects. Eisenstein's use of such techniques was considered<br />

by many to be obscure, inaccessible in meaning and elitist. Victor Shklovsky, writing in<br />

Novyi Lef in 1927, records the responses of a man connected with the cinema:<br />

After viewing some Eisenstein sequences a man who is intelligent and conversant with cinema said


S O V I E T M O N T A G E C I N E M A • M A R K J O Y C E<br />

to me, That is very good. I like that a lot but what will the masses say? What will the people we are<br />

working for say?' What can you say to that? 39<br />

Indeed, an examination of contemporary criticism of October reveals that far from being<br />

popular among Soviet audiences, the film was met with derision and apprehension.<br />

Old and New (1929)<br />

The adverse reaction to October prompted Eisenstein to produce Old and New, a film<br />

more readily understood by audiences. Despite employing a number of the techniques<br />

• Plate 13.11 October<br />

(1927)<br />

• Plate 13.12 Old and<br />

New (1929)<br />

The new tractor is eventually<br />

delivered to<br />

Martha's co-operative.


key films<br />

The Mof/ier(1926)<br />

The End of St Petersburg<br />

(1927)<br />

Storm Over Asia (1928)<br />

N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S<br />

used in October, Eisenstein presents them in a simplified form. Juxtapositions, for<br />

example, are more obvious and on a less symbolic level.<br />

The narrative of Old and New, concerned with the collectivisation of agriculture, is,<br />

unlike Eisenstein's previous films, bound together by a central character or heroine<br />

'Martha'. Despite its more conventional narrative form, the film contains one of<br />

Eisenstein's most effective montage sequences in which a cream separator is delivered<br />

to the collective farm. The new machine is eyed suspiciously by the peasants as milk is<br />

poured into it. In an ever-quickening flow of images, Eisenstein cuts between the glittering,<br />

spinning parts of the machine, the changing faces of the peasants and<br />

non-diegetic shots of fountains of water which symbolise the future flow of cream from<br />

the separator. The film is fascinating to study in the context of Eisenstein's earlier work<br />

and marks an attempt to address problems of understanding associated with October.<br />

Vsevolod Pudovkin (1893-1953)<br />

Editing is the language of the film director. Just as in living speech, so, one<br />

may say, in editing: there is a word - the piece of exposed film, the image; a<br />

phrase - the combination of these pieces.<br />

(Pudovkin) 40<br />

Pudovkin believed that the power of cinema comes from editing. In the above quotation<br />

he claims that a 'shot' (or image) which is the equivalent of the single word in language<br />

has very limited meaning. However, when a number of words are combined together<br />

they form a 'phrase' which is dense with meaning. Pudovkin's equivalent of a 'phrase'<br />

was a number of shots edited together. He went further to support his claim by<br />

contending that:<br />

every object, taken from a given viewpoint and shown on the screen to spectators, is a dead object,<br />

even though it has moved before the camera.... Only if the object be placed together among a<br />

number of separate objects, only if it be presented as part of a synthesis of different separate visual<br />

images, is it endowed with filmic life. 41<br />

It would seem initially that Pudovkin's theoretical position regarding the effectiveness<br />

of editing was in tandem with his contemporary Eisenstein. There are, however, important<br />

differences in the specific way each director thought editing should be used. 42<br />

Pudovkin did not agree with Eisenstein's system of montage, which created visual 'jolts'<br />

between cuts. Instead, Pudovkin believed greater impact could be made by linking<br />

shots in a constructive way. Shots were to be used as individual building blocks, made<br />

to fit together exactly. Though seemingly theoretically opposed to Eisensteinian<br />

montage, Pudovkin made extensive use of devices such as 'intellectual montage' in The<br />

Mother and The End of St Petersburg. Pudovkin's juxtapositions, however, are much<br />

less symbolic, more clearly related to the diegetic world of the film and less intent on<br />

creating conflict than those of Eisenstein. Leon Moussinac, a French historian, summed<br />

up the differences between the two directors: 'An Eisenstein film resembles a shout, a<br />

Pudovkin film evokes a song.' 43<br />

Pudovkin, like Eisenstein, cast according to 'type' and was concerned about the<br />

problem of 'stagey acting'. He stated:<br />

I want to work only with real material - this is my principle. I maintain that to show, alongside real<br />

water and real trees and grass, a property beard pasted on the actor's face, wrinkles traced by


S O V I E T M O N T A G E C I N E M A M A R K J O Y C E<br />

means of paint, or stagey acting is impossible. It is opposed to the most elementary ideas of<br />

style. 44<br />

Unlike Eisenstein, however, Pudovkin uses individual characters that are cast in the role<br />

of hero or heroine to carry the narrative, and although he discouraged the use of professional<br />

actors some of his lead parts were played by professional actors of the Moscow<br />

Arts Theatre. 45<br />

• CASE STUDY 3: VSEVOLOD PUDOVKIN, THE MOTHER<br />

(1926); THE END OF ST PETERSBURG (1927)<br />

The Mother (1926)<br />

The scenario for Pudovkin's The Mother is based on the earlier play by Gorky of the<br />

same name. The plot is concerned with the political awakening of a mother after she<br />

betrays her son to the police, in the belief that he will be dealt with justly. The action is<br />

set (as in Battleship Potemkin) in the revolutionary context of 1905, with strikes, mass<br />

protests and a final brutal massacre of the workers.<br />

With its focus on individuals, the film offers an interesting contrast to Eisenstein's<br />

approach to revolutionary cinema. In The Mother, the role of the individual is reinstated<br />

and emphasised. The mass struggle is thus registered through the lives and fates of<br />

separate characters involved in that struggle. It is important to note that the individual<br />

characters are not highlighted in such a way that the general struggle itself becomes<br />

obscured. The audience is encouraged to make connections between individual fate<br />

and the fate of the masses. Pudovkin is thus using individual characters to make his<br />

political points, believing that the audience would be able to relate better to separate<br />

identities than to an anonymous mass.<br />

Pudovkin's use of 'linkage' editing (shot A + shot B = AB) can be illustrated in the<br />

trial scene at the mid-point of the film. The scene is composed of a large number of<br />

shots which tend to centre on single characters or pairs of characters. The fragmentation<br />

allows Pudovkin to draw direct comparisons between, for example, the<br />

uninterested and uncaring attitude of the judges, the accused Pavel, his mother and<br />

several of the gossiping onlookers. Close shots of the soldiers guarding the courthouse<br />

are also inserted in order to demonstrate that 'justice' is being upheld by a substantial<br />

force. Pudovkin clearly reveals the judges to be vain and self-interested by highlighting<br />

their overriding concern with attire and pictures of horses, rather than the proceedings<br />

of the trial. If the same scene had been shot by Eisenstein the vanity of the judges might<br />

have been indicated in a similar way to that of Kerensky in October (that is, juxtaposing<br />

him with a shot of a peacock).<br />

The End of St Petersburg (1927)<br />

Made to celebrate the Tenth Anniversary of the October Revolution, The End of St<br />

Petersburg, based on Andre Bely's 1916 symbolist novel Petersburg, 48 also uses individual<br />

characters to deal with the events preceding the revolution. One is a young<br />

peasant boy who has come to St Petersburg to seek work, as his family can no longer<br />

support him at home. Despite initial involvement with strikebreakers, the boy quickly<br />

becomes aware of the corruption and injustice of the Tsarist regime. His political awakening,<br />

however, lands him in prison and then he is forced to volunteer into the Tsar's<br />

army, where he is exposed to the horrors of trench warfare.<br />

Using montage, Pudovkin draws a contrast between the suffering of the soldiers<br />

who are fighting for the Tsar and the greed of those who are benefiting financially from<br />

the war. Horrific images of dying soldiers in mud at the front-line trenches are intercut


• Plate 13.13 The End<br />

of St Petersburg (1927)<br />

One of Pudovkin's<br />

central characters, a<br />

young peasant boy, is<br />

seen here demanding<br />

justice from the authorities.<br />

Key films<br />

The Adventures of<br />

Oktyabrina (1924)<br />

The Cloak (1926)<br />

The New Babylon (1929)<br />

N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S<br />

with scenes at the St Petersburg stock market. As the fighting gets worse and worse at<br />

the front, the higher the value of the shares becomes - thereby enforcing the point that<br />

people are making money out of suffering. The old order, by supporting and being<br />

supported by the stock market, is seen to be inhumane and preoccupied with the<br />

wrong values - the acquisition of wealth at whatever cost. Pudovkin at one point intercuts<br />

between the image of a soldier slashing ferociously at an opponent with his<br />

bayo<strong>net</strong> and the image of a stock market figure fre<strong>net</strong>ically dealing at the stock<br />

exchange. He thus likens the barbarities of war to the barbarity inherent in the centre of<br />

the capitalist structure. Earlier Pudovkin intercut between the images of death at the<br />

front and the words 'In the name of the Tsar, the fatherland, and the capital'. This is<br />

clearly ironic as the soldiers have no idea what they are fighting for - certainly not for<br />

the Tsar.<br />

In the final part of The End of St Petersburg, in the storming of the Winter Palace<br />

sequences, Pudovkin intercuts the images of the advancing Bolsheviks with both fastmoving<br />

clouds and crashing waves. This emphasises the power and inevitability of the<br />

revolution - revolution is unstoppable. Earlier in a Bolshevik's speech at the Lebedev<br />

factory, images of slowing down machinery are intercut with the speaker to point to the<br />

power of his words upon the workers.<br />

Eccentrism of the FEKS: Grigori Kozintsev and Leonid<br />

Trauberg<br />

FEKS (Factory of the Eccentric Actor), formed in December 1921 by a small group of<br />

theatre actors and directors, shared the common aim of reforming the traditional theatre<br />

and incorporating into their experimental work elements of the circus, music hall and<br />

puppet theatre. On 9 July 1922 FEKS published a manifesto which stated their aims as<br />

a group. 47 The poster shown on page 439 shows just a small sample of the material<br />

contained within the manifesto.


S O V I E T M O N T A G E C I N E M A • M A R K J O Y C E


440 N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S<br />

• Plate 13.14 The New Babylon (1929)<br />

The extract makes it clear that FEKS valued the bold, dynamic and popular elements<br />

of circus and cinema posters. It was with these elements that they proposed to revitalise<br />

the theatre. Two of the founding members of the group, Grigori Kozintsev and<br />

Leonid Trauberg, became interested in the cinema, making a number of short experimental<br />

films between 1924 and 1927, including The Adventures of Oktyabrina (1924)<br />

and The Cloak (1926). The films primarily emphasised the artificial nature of the mise en<br />

scene and the stylised nature of the acting rather than the editing.<br />

Kozintsev and Trauberg are perhaps best known for their 1929 film, The New<br />

Babylon, based on the events building up to the Paris Commune of 1871. As in their<br />

previous films, artificial mise en scene combined with stylised acting were employed,<br />

but also extensive use was made of camera movement. At one point in the film the<br />

camera moves swiftly enough to blur the image, thus conveying the sense of confusion<br />

present in the scene. The response to the film was unfavourable, as audiences failed to<br />

understand its form.


S O V I E T M O N T A G E C I N E M A • M A R K J O Y C E<br />

• CASE STUDY 4: ALEXANDER DOVZHENKO, ARSENAL<br />

(1929); EARTH (1930) 48<br />

Inspired by the creative and political possibilities of film, Dovzhenko had approached<br />

the Odessa film studio in 1926. At this point he had little knowledge of cinema, but<br />

within a few years he had made an outstanding contribution to Soviet revolutionary<br />

cinema with such films as Arsenal and Earth which, in addition to revolutionary fervour,<br />

displayed poetic qualities and provided a demonstration of his love for the Ukraine and<br />

its people.<br />

Arsenal surveys the devastating impact of the First World War and the political struggles<br />

between the Social Democrats and the Bolsheviks during 1917. The opening<br />

sequences of Arsenal exemplify Dovzhenko's approach to film-making. There is little<br />

camera movement or use of establishing shots and, overall, there is less concern with a<br />

conventional rendering of space and time than with the emotional impact of the flow of<br />

images. In these opening and further sequences Dovzhenko reveals the loss and<br />

impoverishment of the people, as well as the unthinking callousness of the social order.<br />

Arsenal shows that Dovzhenko is not concerned with personalised conflict between<br />

individuals, but with the ongoing struggle between opposing social forces. This concern<br />

is pursued further in Earth which deals with class struggle in the countryside, although<br />

like Arsenal it features a strong attractive male hero, Vasil. The latter is the operator of<br />

the tractor which will allow the collective farm to effectively rid the village of the selfseeking<br />

and more prosperous peasants, the kulaks. In the end Vasil is shot by Khoma,<br />

the son of a kulak, although what he stands for will not be defeated. Vasil's father, hitherto<br />

hostile to the young revolutionaries of the village, commits himself to the cause of<br />

collectivisation and rejects a religious burial in favour of the village youth singing songs<br />

about the new life to come. The film, then, presents a strong case for the recently instigated<br />

policy of the collectivisation of agriculture. Commentators on the film, however,<br />

• Plate 13.15 Earth<br />

(1930)


442 N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S<br />

Key films<br />

Film Truth (Kino-Pravda)<br />

(1922)<br />

Kino_Eye (1924)<br />

A Sixth of the World<br />

(1926)<br />

The Man with a Movie<br />

Camera (1929)<br />

Enthusiasm (1931)<br />

See Chapter 7, pages<br />

215-for further<br />

discussion of Vertov's<br />

contribution to documentary<br />

film.<br />

have argued that the formal and poetic qualities of the film actually undermine the political<br />

message. Denise J. Youngblood, for example, states that:<br />

Dovzhenko's Earth (1930) is a much more curious example of the collectivisation film - the politically<br />

correct story of a handsome young village Party activist murdered by an evil and dissolute<br />

kulak opposed to collectivisation is undercut by a deeply subversive subtext related to its form. The<br />

lyrical imagery and slow rhythms of this film, totally unlike Ejsenstein's, belie the purported theme<br />

and in effect serve as a paean to a way of life soon to be no more. 49<br />

The opening sequence in which Vasil's grandfather dies would certainly seem to<br />

bear out this interpretation. He dies contented, his last act being to enjoy a pear, a<br />

product of the fruitful Ukrainian earth. Next to him a baby plays and a boy eats an<br />

apple, while the adult members of the family await the inevitable. This portrait of<br />

pastoral abundance and peacefulness with its allusions to the cycle of life and death<br />

seem to undermine the necessity for revolutionary change, but it is made clear by the<br />

old man's friend Petro that his has been a life of hard work - 'Seventy-five years behind<br />

a plough'.<br />

Dziga Vertov (1896-1954)<br />

Dziga Vertov 50 (pseudonym of Denis Kaufman) was interested in the idea that the film<br />

camera had the potential to capture 'truth'; the camera could be seen simply as a<br />

mechanical device that was capable of recording the world without human intervention.<br />

Vertov led a group of film-makers called Kinoki ('cinema-eye') who stated in their 1923<br />

manifesto:<br />

I am the Cine-Eye. I am the mechanical eye.<br />

I the machine show you the world as only I can see it.<br />

I emancipate myself henceforth and forever from human immobility. / am in constant motion. I<br />

approach objects and move away from them, I creep up on them, I clamber over them, I move<br />

alongside the muzzle of a running horse, I tear into a crowd at full tilt, I flee before fleeing<br />

soldiers, I turn over on my back, I rise up with aeroplanes, I fall and rise with falling and rising<br />

bodies. 51<br />

Vertov believed that the fiction film could not be used to reveal the 'truth' about a<br />

society. His films were based on documenting events around him; nothing should be<br />

artificially set up or staged for the camera. In 1922 Vertov had stated: 'WE declare the<br />

old films, the romantic, the theatricalised etc., to be leprous.' 52<br />

Vertov's techniques were based on experimentation caused by the general scarcity<br />

of film stock and also, when available, the short lengths of the negative film. His experiments<br />

included using old newsreels as part of his films, and he found that new<br />

meanings could be created by the conflict produced by the old material and the new.<br />

Vertov soon discovered that the conflicts produced by montage were a vital element in<br />

the construction of meaning in his films.<br />

Perhaps one of the most interesting features of Vertov's films is that great effort is<br />

taken to ensure that the audience is made aware of cameraman, editor and the whole<br />

process of producing a film. In The Man with a Movie Camera, for example, Vertov<br />

shows the cameraman shooting the scenes that we see before us, and later we see


S O V I E T M O N T A G E C I N E M A • M A R K J O Y C E<br />

shots of this same film being edited. This technique of acknowledging the nature of the<br />

film-making process can be linked to documentary film-making practice in the 1970s<br />

and 1980s (in the films of Emile de Antonio and Jean-Pierre Gorin, for example) which<br />

went against the fly-on-the-wall practice and attempted to show the presence of the<br />

film-crew and camera and the fact that the audience are watching a manufactured film<br />

rather than 'reality'. This style of film-making which draws attention to its own process<br />

is often termed 'self-reflexive'.<br />

Esfir Shub (1894-1959)<br />

Esfir Shub is an interesting female figure in a period of film-making dominated by<br />

men. She was initially employed by the Soviet government to re-edit foreign films<br />

to make them conform to the ideology of communism. Shub also re-edited old<br />

Tsarist newsreels to show the corrupt nature of the old order. Shub's practice of<br />

reassembling parts of existing films culminated in the adoption of the montage<br />

technique.<br />

• CASE STUDY 5: ESFIR SHUB, THE FALL OF THE<br />

ROMANOV DYNASTY (1927)<br />

Shub's first feature-length film, The Fall of the Romanov Dynasty, constructed entirely<br />

from old newsreels, was made to celebrate the Tenth Anniversary of the October<br />

Revolution and it is claimed that 60,000 metres of film had to be examined in order to<br />

finish the project. 53 Shub provides new commentary on existing material by inserting<br />

intertitles between shots. By juxtaposing sequences of shots from different newsreels<br />

she also makes the audience draw new conclusions about the material. For example,<br />

she contrasts shots of an aristocratic gathering with shots of workers digging ditches.<br />

The intertitle reads 'by the sweat of your brow'. The intertitles and the juxtaposition of<br />

the images encourage the audience to assign an aberrant decoding to the original<br />

shots. In other words, the audience can deliberately 'misread' the images. Shub uses<br />

images which emphasise the pomp and splendour of Tsarist Russia, which in the<br />

context of the film look absurd and out of place; the audience is forced to be critical of<br />

this obvious display of wealth.<br />

Although the film in principle uses montage in a similar way to Eisenstein or<br />

Pudovkin (in particular the way in which the audience are placed as active participants<br />

in the text), Shub does not make use of its rhythmic possibilities. Although the pace of<br />

the film is on the whole sedate it does put its political messages across in a powerful<br />

and convincing way. Recently, there has been a call for a re-evaluation of Esfir Shub by<br />

Graham Roberts, who claims that Shub's contribution to the Soviet cinema has been<br />

undervalued. 54<br />

AUDIENCE RESPONSE<br />

Viewers in the West may possibly already have an idea of the nature of the Soviet<br />

cinema after seeing extracts from films discussed previously such as Sergei Eisenstein's<br />

Battleship Potemkin or October. They may have wondered how many films such as<br />

these were made and how they were received by Soviet audiences that had only a few<br />

years previously gone through the upheaval of civil war. They may have pitied or even<br />

envied the Soviet cinema-goer - were these the only films that the Soviet cinema-goer<br />

fly-on-the-wall<br />

A term associated with a<br />

style of documentary<br />

film-making which<br />

attempts to present<br />

events as though the<br />

presence of the camera<br />

and film crew had not<br />

influenced them in any<br />

way.<br />

Key films<br />

The Fall of the Romanov<br />

Dynasty (1927)<br />

The Great Road (1927)<br />

The Russia of Nicholas II<br />

and Lev Tolstoy (1928)


For further discussion of<br />

realism and Bazin, see<br />

Chapter 4, p. 106-7.<br />

N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S<br />

could see on a Friday night? How could a largely uneducated population have coped<br />

with sophisticated material like this?<br />

Recent research into the Soviet cinema of the 1920s has encouraged new ideas. In<br />

the past, attention has focused on a number of key directors such as Pudovkin,<br />

Eisenstein and Vertov, whose films in the Soviet Union and later in the West were<br />

received with critical acclaim. We must examine, however, new evidence that points to<br />

the fact that Russian audiences were far more likely to be watching the Soviet 1920s<br />

equivalent of Jurassic Park than the likes of Battleship Potemkin, Strike and October.<br />

Richard Stites, in Russian Popular Culture: Entertainment and Society since 1900,<br />

reveals that the majority of Soviet directors were making mainstream films that were<br />

conventional in form and content. The montage film was the exception rather than the<br />

rule:<br />

The most popular movie genres of the revolutionary period were the same as the foreign and prerevolutionary<br />

Russian ones: costume drama, action and adventure, literary works adapted for the<br />

screen, melodramas, and comedy. Those who patronized them were not merely the nepmanskaya<br />

auditoriya, that is the bourgeoisie, alleged to be addicted to lurid sex films. Working-class clubs<br />

sponsored by the Communist Party also had to show some entertainment films or risk losing their<br />

audience. 55<br />

Soviet audiences also favoured foreign films which were imported in large numbers<br />

throughout the 1920s.<br />

But why were the Soviet propaganda films relatively less successful? Why would<br />

audiences rather see foreign and conventional Soviet genre films? Were foreign films<br />

perceived as being more exciting or exotic? Denise Youngblood, in Movies for the<br />

Masses, cites an interview conducted in 1929 with a Soviet cinema manager that<br />

recorded audience response:<br />

He noted that 'the public watched [Dovzhenko's Arsenal] with great difficulty,' and that attendance<br />

dropped to 50 percent of normal when his theatre screened New Babylon, Kozintsev and Trauberg's<br />

famous picture about the Paris Commune. Asked about the reaction to Vertov's The Man with the<br />

Movie Camera, he replied sarcastically, 'One hardly need say that if New Babylon didn't satisfy the<br />

spectator's requirements and 'lost' him, then The Man with the Movie Camera didn't satisfy him<br />

either.' 56<br />

The problem is clear. The Soviet propaganda films that were intended for the<br />

masses, from the illiterate peasant upwards, simply were not being understood by<br />

Soviet audiences, whereas the clear hero-led narrative structure of the foreign and<br />

Soviet genre films were far more straightforward and appealing. It is well documented<br />

that the American version of Robin Hood proved more successful in Soviet cinemas on<br />

all counts. The film-makers involved in Soviet propaganda production, although<br />

committed to the ideals of communism, were also committed to experimenting with film<br />

form. The experimentation in this case clearly did not culminate in a popular cinema<br />

that appealed to the masses.<br />

THEORETICAL DEBATES: MONTAGE VERSUS REALISM<br />

The montage technique has been widely acknowledged as a powerful means of expression<br />

and to many cinema theorists montage is the essence of cinema. The technique,<br />

however, does have its opponents, among them the French film critic and theorist<br />

Andre Bazin. 57 Bazin was concerned with the cinema's ability to record 'reality'. He saw


in cinema a means of capturing a record of events before the camera with minimum<br />

mediation. Bazin regarded the montage cinema of the Soviets (among others) as essentially<br />

non-realist because scenes could be manipulated and altered in many different<br />

ways. He claimed that the audience of montage cinema was essentially passive, 58 as<br />

the director forced the audience towards certain meanings.<br />

Bazin saw montage cinema as being in direct opposition to a style of film-making<br />

associated with realism. Realism is a term often associated with the Hollywood cinema,<br />

but Bazin used it to refer to a style of film-making adopted by certain film-makers such<br />

as Jean Renoir, a French director, who felt that the power of cinema came not from<br />

editing, but from mise en scene. The realists, unlike the montage film-makers, took<br />

great pains to hide the artificial constructed nature of film. The long take, for example,<br />

was frequently used as it made editing unnecessary. The use of the long take supported<br />

the claim that what was being watched was unmediated and therefore more 'realistic'.<br />

Bazin cited further devices that could enhance the 'reality' of a scene, such as the use<br />

of deep-focus, wide-angle lenses, the long shot and a highly mobile camera which all<br />

meant that the film-maker could preserve real time and space in individual scenes.<br />

POSTSCRIPT TO THE 1930s<br />

The 1930s and after: the decline of experimentation in<br />

the Soviet cinema<br />

In the 1930s the Soviet authorities, under the guidance of Stalin, reacted to the unpopularity<br />

of many of the Soviet films by issuing strict guidelines on how films should be<br />

made. This set of 'rules', essentially demanding hero-led narratives and concerned with<br />

realistic subject matter, was termed 'Socialist Realism'. The head of the Soviet film<br />

industry outlined why such a policy was necessary in 1933: 'A film and its success are<br />

directly linked to the degree of entertainment in the plot... that is why we are obliged to<br />

require our masters [the film-makers] to produce works that have strong plots and are<br />

organised around a story-line.' 59<br />

The policy of 'Socialist Realism' was combined with a complete ban on imported<br />

foreign films. By removing these positive representations of capitalism Stalin had also<br />

effectively made the Soviet film industry a monopoly; audiences could either see Soviet<br />

films or not see any films at all.<br />

The direct interest that the Soviet state took in the film industry reveals its perceived<br />

importance, but also had drastic consequences for many of the directors. It was noted<br />

by the authorities, for example, that several of these directors were not actually<br />

Communist Party members. (This might explain perhaps why they were more interested<br />

in form or technique than making positive films about communism that were easy to<br />

comprehend.) The film-makers of the 1920s discussed in this chapter were mostly not<br />

successful in the 1930s and 1940s. Eisenstein, for example, continued to make films,<br />

but the majority were either suppressed or had their funding withdrawn.<br />

However, the decline of montage cinema could possibly be the consequence of<br />

another factor: technology. In October 1929 the first Soviet sound films were released<br />

and with this advance in cinema technology came the almost immediate downfall of<br />

film-making practices that relied on either complex camera movement or rapid editing,<br />

as sound cinema initially required non-movable cameras and fixed microphones in<br />

order to record dialogue.<br />

The legacy of the Soviet cinema: its influence on<br />

modern cinema 60<br />

The impact of the Soviet films of the 1920s on the analysis of film and film-making itself<br />

For further discussion of<br />

realism and documentary<br />

film, see Chapter 7,<br />

pp. 212-15.


was immediate and continues to this day. The films, however, have not so much<br />

provided a model for successive film-makers as been an inspiration for their work. The<br />

British Documentary Movement of the 1930s, for example, was influenced by Soviet<br />

montage as well as impressed by the idea that films could be a force for education. The<br />

film-makers in this movement, however, did not conceive of films having a revolutionary<br />

role or even the rale of questioning contemporary inequalities. Other film-makers have<br />

been inspired by the Soviet cinema because of its rejection of the forms and conventions<br />

of the dominant Hollywood entertainment cinema. Jean-Luc Godard, for example,<br />

demanded that audiences participate in the construction of meaning in his films and so<br />

engage directly with social and political questions. The achievements of Eisenstein<br />

continue to impress film editors as well as contemporary film directors. The editor,<br />

Ralph Rosenblum, for example, states in his discussion of Battleship Potemkin that<br />

'[although the movie is filled with stunning moments, the massacre on the Odessa<br />

steps outweighs them all; it remains for editors everywhere the single most intimidating<br />

piece of film ever assembled.' 61<br />

Direct references to Eisenstein's films are numerous, ranging from Bernardo<br />

Bertolucci's subtle allusions to Strike in his Tragedy of a Ridiculous Man (Italy/US 1981)<br />

through Brian de Palma's opportunistic reworking of the Odessa Steps sequence in The<br />

Untouchables (US 1987) 62 to Zbiginiew Rybczynski's use of the same sequence in<br />

Steps (US/UK/Poland 1987) 63 in order to satirise cultural attitudes including the veneration<br />

of Battleship Potemkin as a work of art. 64 Dovzhenko's influence has not been a<br />

direct political one, but the films of Andrei Tarkovsky, at one time a pupil of Dovzhenko,<br />

and a film like My Childhood by the Scottish film-maker Bill Douglas, exhibit a similar<br />

emotional intensity.<br />

1 Quoted in Yon Barna, Eisenstein (Seeker & Warburg,<br />

London, 1973) p. 102.<br />

2 The term peasants is used to describe those who worked<br />

on the land in the country, and the term workers describes<br />

those who worked within cities.<br />

3 This was a planned attack by a relatively small force, not a<br />

mass uprising as chronicled by Eisenstein in his 1927 film<br />

October.<br />

4 An unusual account of this period told from the point of<br />

view of the White side can be found in Mikhail Bulgakov's<br />

1926 novel, The White Guard (available in the UK as a<br />

Flamingo paperback).<br />

5 The British Film Institute has released a number of early<br />

Russian films on video (in ten volumes).<br />

6 See list of selected Russian films in Further viewing.<br />

7 The history of what happened to the migrant Russian filmmakers<br />

and stars is an area worthy of study in its own right.<br />

8 Protazanov was not in the Soviet Union for the full duration<br />

of this period; he emigrated briefly to Paris in 1920-3.<br />

9 For more information on Protazanov, see Ian Christie and<br />

Julian Graffy (eds), Yakov Protazanov and the Continuity of<br />

Russian Cinema (British Film Institute/NFT, London, 1993).<br />

For more information on the Russian cinema, see Jay<br />

Leyda, Kino, 3rd edn (George Allen & Unwin, London,<br />

1983); and Paolo Usai, Lorenzo Codelli, Carlo Montanaro<br />

and David Robinson (eds), Silent Witnesses (British Film<br />

Institute, London, 1989).<br />

10 The first Russian studio was set up by Drankov in 1907.<br />

11 The first half of 'Soviet Cinema and Ideology: Film as Agent<br />

of Change' is by Danny Rivers (Film Studies Lecturer, West<br />

Kent College).<br />

12 V.I. Lenin, in Pravda (No. 250, 7 November 1919), reprinted<br />

in Lenin: Economics and Politics in the era of the<br />

Dictatorship of the Proletariat (Progress Publishers,<br />

Moscow, 1978) p. 3.<br />

13 The context of this remark can be found in Leyda, Kino, p.<br />

161.<br />

14 The Museum of the Moving Image (MOMI) has recreated<br />

the cinema carriage of an Agit Train complete with<br />

commentator, although the Soviet films being shown are<br />

from the period 1924-30.<br />

15 Richard Taylor and Ian Christie (eds), The Film Factory:<br />

Russian and Soviet Cinema in Documents, 1896-1939<br />

(Routledge, London, 1988) p. 109.<br />

16 The civil war also resulted in trade barriers being set up<br />

which prevented the importation of film stock and cinema<br />

equipment into the Soviet Union. This had a dramatic effect<br />

on the film industry as the Soviet Union initially had no<br />

means of producing its own film stock and lenses.


S O V I E T M O N T A G E C I N E M A • M A R K J O Y C E 447<br />

17 Denise Youngblood, Movies for the Masses (Cambridge<br />

University Press, Cambridge, 1992) p. 51.<br />

18 Cinema Journal (Vol. 11, No. 2, 1972).<br />

19 Vladimir Vladimirovich Mayakovsky (1893-1930).<br />

20 The team effort involved in the production of a feature film<br />

would clearly cost a great deal more than an individual<br />

artist producing a painting. The Russian film industry,<br />

although economically successful, needed to produce films<br />

that would appeal to a wide audience. The desire to experiment<br />

with film form, when the existing genres were popular,<br />

was therefore limited.<br />

21 From Vsevolod Pudovkin, 'Types instead of Actors', in his<br />

Film Technique and Film Acting (Gollancz, London, 1929).<br />

22 The mansion was in fact the White House.<br />

23 Adapted from Bruce Kawin, How Movies Work (Collier<br />

Macmillan, London, 1987) pp. 99-101.<br />

24 David Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film (Routledge,<br />

London, 1986). Bordwell uses a technique pioneered by<br />

Barry Salt in his article 'Statistical Style Analysis of Motion<br />

Pictures', Film Quarterly (Vol. 28, No. 2, Winter 1974-5).<br />

25 Quoted by Pudovkin at a lecture given at the London Film<br />

School in 1929.<br />

26 The Moscow Arts Theatre under the direction of Konstantin<br />

Stanislavski developed a method of acting which required<br />

the actor to attempt to 'become' the character.<br />

27 Quoted in Neya Zorkaya, The Illustrated History of Soviet<br />

Cinema (Hippocrene Books, New York, 1989) p. 52.<br />

28 This can be inferred from the fact that Goskino made thirtytwo<br />

prints of the film.<br />

29 For fuller details and a chronology of the life of Eisenstein<br />

see Bordwell 1993.<br />

30 A well-known Russian playwright (1823-86).<br />

31 David Bordwell, The Cinema of Eisenstein, p. 6.<br />

32 The other seven films were never made.<br />

33 Quoted at further length in Leyda's Kino, p. 181.<br />

34 Eisenstein bends historical fact in the film as the sailors on<br />

board the Potemkin, instead of persuading the Russian<br />

Fleet to join the struggle, were captured and the mutiny<br />

suppressed.<br />

35 The scene has been much copied by recent film-makers:<br />

see the section on the 'Legacy of the Soviet cinema: its<br />

influence on modern cinema', on pp. 445-6.<br />

36 See Bordwell, The Cinema of Eisenstein, p. 74, for an<br />

excellent analysis of the sequence.<br />

37 Quotation cited by Leyda in Kino, 1983, p. 195. Leyda also<br />

points out that the same sequence caused 'an anxious<br />

debate in the German Reichstag on the size of the Soviet<br />

Navy'.<br />

38 Bordwell, in The Cinema of Eisenstein, p. 85, claims that<br />

the peacock could be seen as a diegetic image as it forms<br />

part of the treasures contained within the Winter Palace.<br />

Yuri Tsivian, in 'Eisenstein's October and Russian Symbolist<br />

Culture' (Christie and Taylor 1993), puts forward the view<br />

that 'Eisenstein was hoping to attain the effect of Kerensky<br />

entering the peacock's asshole'.<br />

39 Taylor and Christie (eds), The Film Factory, p. 182.<br />

40 Quoted in V. Perkins, Film as Film (Penguin, London, 1972)<br />

p. 21.<br />

41 Ibid., p. 22.<br />

42 Pudovkin's films, like those of Eisenstein, were based on a<br />

body of theoretical writing.<br />

43 Quoted by Richard Taylor, The Politics of the Soviet<br />

Cinema, 1917-1929 (Cambridge University Press,<br />

Cambridge, 1979) p. 142.<br />

44 Lecture given by Pudovkin at the London Film Society,<br />

1929.<br />

45 The theatre was founded in 1898 by Konstantin<br />

Stanislavski and Vladimir Nemirovich-Danchenko.<br />

46 Published in the UK by Penguin (London, 1983).<br />

47 The manifesto was reprinted in 1992 in a limited edition of<br />

500 copies by Aldgate Press, London.<br />

48 Section on Dovzhenko written by Danny Rivers (West Kent<br />

College).<br />

49 Youngblood, Movies for the Masses, p. 169.<br />

50 Vertov in Russian is derived from the Russian word for<br />

'rotation' and was thus a reflection of his approach to the<br />

arts.<br />

51 Quoted in Taylor and Christie (eds), The Film Factory, p. 93.<br />

52 Ibid., p. 69.<br />

53 Soviet montage cinema tended to put the stress on the<br />

importance of the director (auteur) and work in postproduction,<br />

rather than scriptwriting and the screenplay.<br />

This became a source of dispute in the 1920s when there<br />

was greater concern with efficiency and a more elaborate<br />

division of labour. See Thompson's 'Early Alternatives to<br />

the Hollywood Mode of Production', Film History: An<br />

International Journal (Vol. 5, No. 4, December 1993).<br />

54 See 'Esfir Shub: A Suitable Case For Treatment', Historical<br />

Journal of Film, Radio and Television (Vol. 11, No. 2, 1991).<br />

55 Richard Stites, Russian Popular Culture: Entertainment and<br />

Society Since 1900 (Cambridge, Cambridge University<br />

Press, 1992) p. 56.<br />

56 Youngblood, Mow'es for the Masses, pp. 18-19.<br />

57 Bazin was also editor of the French film journal Cahiers du<br />

Cinema.<br />

58 Eisenstein rigorously opposed this view claiming that the<br />

audience for his films played an active part in the text.<br />

59 The head of Sovkino at this time was Boris Shumyatsky.<br />

The quotation is taken from Richard Taylor, 'Boris<br />

Shumyatsky and the Soviet Cinema in the 1930s: Ideology<br />

as Mass Entertainment', Historical Journal of Film, Radio<br />

and Television (Vol. 6, No.1, 1986) p. 43.<br />

60 This section was written by Danny Rivers (West Kent<br />

College).<br />

61 From Ralph Rosenblum and Robert Karen, When the<br />

Shooting Stops... the Cutting Begins: A Film Editor's Story<br />

(Da Capo Press, New York, 1979).<br />

62 A statistical analysis of both scenes in terms of shot<br />

length/shot type reveals that they are also very similiar in<br />

form.<br />

63 A co-production of KTCA-TV Minneapolis and ZBIG Vision<br />

Ltd in association with Channel Four, London.<br />

64 Woody Allen in Love and Death (US 1975), also makes<br />

reference to this sequence.


Key texts<br />

Aumont, J. Montage Eisenstein (British Film Institute, London,<br />

1987)<br />

Bordwell, D. The Cinema of Eisenstein (Harvard University<br />

Press, Cambridge, MA, 1993)<br />

Christie, I. and Taylor, R. (eds) Eisenstein Rediscovered<br />

(Routledge, London, 1993)<br />

Eisenstein, S. A/ofes of a Film Director (Dover Publications, New<br />

York, 1970)<br />

The Film Sense (Faber & Faber, London, 1986)<br />

(Film scripts of The Mother, Earth and Battleship Potemkin have<br />

been published by Simon & Schuster, New York, 1973.)<br />

Kepley, V., Jr In the Service of the State: The Cinema of<br />

Alexander Dovzhenko (University of Wisconsin Press,<br />

Madison, 1986)<br />

Leyda, J. Kino: A History of the Russian and Soviet Film, 3rd edn<br />

(George Allen & Unwin, London, 1983)<br />

Michelson, A. (ed.) Kino Eye: The Writings of Dziga Vertov<br />

(University of California Press, Berkeley, 1984)<br />

Taylor, R. Film Propaganda: Soviet Russia and Nazi Germany<br />

(Croom Helm, London, 1979)<br />

The Politics of the Soviet Cinema, 1917-1929 (Cambridge<br />

University Press, Cambridge, 1979)<br />

Taylor, R. and Christie, I. (eds) The Film Factory: Russian and<br />

Soviet Cinema in Documents, 1896-1939 (Routledge,<br />

London, 1988)<br />

(eds) Inside the Film Factory: New Approaches to Russian<br />

and Soviet Cinema (Routledge, London, 1991)<br />

Youngblood, D. Movies for the Masses: Popular Cinema and<br />

Soviet Society in the 1920s (Cambridge University Press,<br />

Cambridge, 1992)<br />

Books<br />

Barna, Y. Eisenstein (Seeker & Warburg, London, 1973)<br />

Barron, S. and Tuchman, M. (eds) The Avant-Garde in Russia,<br />

1910-1930: New Perspectives (Los Angeles County<br />

Museum of Art, Los Angeles, 1980)<br />

Birkos, A. Soviet Cinema: Directors and Films (Archon, Hamden,<br />

CT, 1976)<br />

Bordwell, D. Narration in the Fiction Film (Routledge & Kegan<br />

Paul, London, 1986)<br />

Christie, I. and Giliett, J. (eds) Futurism/Formalism/FEKS:<br />

'Eccentrism' and Soviet Cinema 1918-1936 (British Film<br />

Institute (Film Availability Services), London, 1978)<br />

Christie, I. and Graffy, J. (eds) Yakov Protazanov and the<br />

Continuity of Russian Cinema (British Film Institute/NFT,<br />

London, 1993)<br />

Dickinson, T. and de la Roche, C. Soviet Cinema (The Falcon<br />

Press, London, 1948)<br />

Goodwin, J. Eisenstein, Cinema and History (University of Illinois<br />

Press, Urbana and Chicago, 1993)<br />

Kenez, P. Cinema and Soviet Society, 1917-1953 (Cambridge<br />

University Press, Cambridge, 1992)<br />

Lawton, A. The Red Screen: Politics, Society, Art in Soviet<br />

Cinema (Routledge, London, 1992)<br />

Marshall, H. Masters of the Soviet Cinema (Routledge & Kegan<br />

Paul, London, 1983)<br />

NATIONAL CINEMAS<br />

Petric, V. Constructivism in Film: The Man with the Movie<br />

Camera - A Cinematic Analysis (Cambridge University<br />

Press, Cambridge, 1987)<br />

Rosenblum, R. and Karen, R. When the Shooting Stops...the<br />

Cutting Begins: A Film Editor's Story (Da Capo Press, New<br />

York, 1979)<br />

Schnitzer, J., Schnitzer, L. and Martin, M. (eds) Cinema in<br />

Revolution, trans. D. Robinson (Seeker & Warburg, London,<br />

1973; reprinted by Da Capo Press, New York, 1987)<br />

Stites, R. Russian Popular Culture: Entertainment and Society<br />

Since 1900 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1992)<br />

Taylor, R. (ed.) S.M. Eisenstein: Writings 1922-1934 - Selected<br />

Works vol. 1 (British Film Institute, London, 1988)<br />

(ed.) Beyond the Stars: The Memoirs of Sergei Eisenstein -<br />

Selected Works vol. 4 (British Film Institute, London, 1995)<br />

Taylor, R. and Glenny, M. (eds) S.M. Eisenstein: Towards a<br />

Theory of Montage - Selected Works vol. 2 (British Film<br />

Institute, London, 1994)<br />

Tsivian, Y. Early Cinema in Russia and its Cultural Reception<br />

(Routledge, London, 1994)<br />

Usai, P., Codelli, L., Montanaro, C. and Robinson, D. (eds) Silent<br />

Witnesses: Russian Films 1908-1919 (British Film Institute,<br />

London, 1989)<br />

Youngblood, D. Soviet Cinema in the Silent Era, 1918-1935<br />

(UMI Research Press, Ann Arbor, Ml, 1985)<br />

Zorkaya, N. The Illustrated History of Soviet Cinema (Hippocrene<br />

Books, New York, 1989)<br />

Chapters in books<br />

Bordwell, D. Narration in the Fiction Film (Routledge, London,<br />

1990) pp. 234-73.<br />

Cook, P. (ed.) The Cinema Book (British Film Institute, London,<br />

1985) pp. 34-6 and 218-19.<br />

Dudley, A. The Major Film Theories: An Introduction (Oxford<br />

University Press, Oxford, 1976) Chs 3 and 4, pp. 42-101.<br />

Gian<strong>net</strong>ti, L. Understanding Movies, 6th edn (Prentice Hall,<br />

Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1993) pp. 135-47 and 373-83.<br />

Gian<strong>net</strong>ti, L. and Eyman, S. Flashback: A Brief History of Film,<br />

2nd edn (Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1991) pp.<br />

82-90.<br />

Gomery, D. Movie History: A Survey (Wadsworth, Belmont, CA,<br />

1991) pp. 135-60.<br />

Henderson, B. Toward a Non-Bourgeois Camera Style', in B.<br />

Nichols (ed.) Movies and Methods (University of California<br />

Press, Berkeley, 1976) pp. 422-38.<br />

Kawin, B. How Movies Work (Collier Macmillan, London, 1987)<br />

pp. 264-75.<br />

Kenez, P. The Birth of the Propaganda State: Soviet Methods of<br />

Mass Mobilization 1917-1929 (Cambridge University Press,<br />

Cambridge, 1985) Ch. 9, pp. 195-219.<br />

Perkins, V. Film as Film (Penguin, London, 1972) p. 21.<br />

Robinson, D. World Cinema 1895-1980 (Methuen, London,<br />

1981) pp. 123-42.<br />

Thompson, K. and Bordwell, D. Film Art: An Introduction, 4th<br />

edn (McGraw-Hill, New York, 1993) pp. 466-9.<br />

Film History: An Introduction (McGraw-Hill, New York,<br />

1994) pp. 128-55.


S O V I E T M O N T A G E C I N E M A M A R K J O Y C E<br />

Tudor, A. Theories of Film (Viking Press and Seeker & Warburg,<br />

London, 1973) pp. 25-58.<br />

Articles<br />

Bordwell, D. 'The Idea of Montage in Soviet Art and Film',<br />

Cinema Journal (Vol. 11, No. 2, 1972)<br />

Christie, I. 'From the Kingdom of Shadows', in the catalogue to<br />

Twilight of the Tsars (Hayward Gallery, London, 1991)<br />

Hartsough, D. 'Soviet Film Distribution and Exhibition in<br />

Germany, 1S21-1933', Historical Journal of Film, Radio and<br />

Television (Vol. 5, No. 2, 1985)<br />

Historical Journal of Film, Radio and Television (Vol. 11, No. 2,<br />

1991) - a special issue centred on new research into Soviet<br />

cinema including: Tsivian, Yuri, 'Early Russian Cinema and<br />

its Public'; Yangirov, Rashit, 'Soviet Cinema in the Twenties:<br />

National Alternatives'; Youngblood, Denise, "'History' on<br />

Film'; Yampolsky, Mikhail, 'Reality at Second Hand'; Listov,<br />

Viktor, 'Early Soviet Cinema: The Spontaneous and the<br />

Planned, 1917-1924'; Roberts, Graham, 'Esfir Shub: A<br />

Suitable Case for Treatment'.<br />

V = available on video<br />

16mm = available to hire on 16mm<br />

Where neither symbol is listed, the film is not available to buy or<br />

rent<br />

Selected Russian films of the 1910s<br />

1908 Sken'ka Razin, Drankov (V)<br />

1909 A Sixteenth-century Russian Wedding, Goncharov (V)<br />

1910 The Queen of Spades, Petr Chardynin (V)<br />

Rusalka/The Mermaid, Goncharov (V)<br />

The House in Kolomna, Petr Chardynin (V)<br />

1912 The Brigand Brothers, Goncharov (V)<br />

The Peasants' Lot, Vasilii Goncharov (V)<br />

1913 Twilight of A Woman's Soul, Evgeny Bauer<br />

Merchant Bashkirov's Daughter, Larin (V)<br />

1914 The Child of the Big City, Evgeny Bauer (V)<br />

Silent Witnesses, Evgeny Bauer (V)<br />

1915 After Death, Evgeny Bauer<br />

Daydreams, Evgeny Bauer (V)<br />

Happiness of Eternal Night, Evgeny Bauer<br />

Children of the Age, Evgeny Bauer<br />

1916 The 1002nd Ruse, Evgeny Bauer (V)<br />

The Queen of Spades, Yakov Protazanov (V)<br />

Antosha Ruined by a Corset, Eduard Puchal'ski (V)<br />

A Life for a Life, Evgeny Bauer (V)<br />

1917 Safari Triumphant, Yakov Protazanov<br />

The King of Paris, Evgeny Bauer<br />

Grandmother of the Revolution, Svetlov<br />

The Revolutionary, Evgeny Bauer<br />

For Luck, Evgeny Bauer (V)<br />

1918 Jenny the Maid, Yakov Protazanov<br />

Still, Sadness, Still, Petr Chardynin<br />

Little Ellie, Yakov Protazanov<br />

Kepley, V, Jr 'The Origins of Soviet Cinema: A Study in Industry<br />

Development', Quarterly Review of Film Studies (Vol. 10, No.<br />

1, 1985)<br />

Kepley, V, Jr and Kepley, B. 'Foreign Films on Soviet Screens<br />

1922-1931', Quarterly Review of Film Studies (Fall 1979)<br />

Screen (Vol. 12, No. 4, Winter 1971-2) - a special issue centred<br />

on Soviet film of the 1920s including translations from: LEF,<br />

Novy LEF, Brik, Kuleshov, Shklovsky, Vertov, Mayakovsky<br />

Film Scenarios.<br />

Stites, R. 'Soviet Movies for the Masses and Historians',<br />

Historical Journal of Film, Radio and Television (Vol. 11, No.<br />

3, 1991)<br />

Taylor, R. 'Boris Shumyatsky and the Soviet Cinema in the<br />

1930s: Ideology as Mass Entertainment', Historical Journal<br />

of Film, Radio and Television (Vol. 6, No.1, 1986) p. 43.<br />

Thompson, K. 'Early Alternatives to the Hollywood Mode of<br />

Production', Film History: An International Journal (Vol. 5,<br />

No. 4, December 1993)<br />

Selected Soviet films of the 1920s-40s<br />

1922-5 Film-Truth, Dziga Vertov (a series of newsreels)<br />

1924 The Extraordinary Adventures of Mr West in the Land of<br />

the Bolsheviks, Lev Kuleshov (16mm)<br />

Strike, Sergei Eisenstein (V, 16mm)<br />

Aelita, Yakov Protazanov (16mm)<br />

Kino-eye, Dziga Vertov<br />

Cigarette-Girl from Mosselprom, Yuri Zhelyabuzhsky<br />

1925 Battleship Potemkin, Sergei Eisenstein (V, 16mm)<br />

The Death Ray, Lev Kuleshov<br />

1926 The Mother, Vsevolod Pudovkin (V, 16mm)<br />

A Sixth of the World, Dziga Vertov (16mm)<br />

1927 The End of St. Petersburg, Vsevolod Pudovkin (V, 16mm)<br />

October, Sergei Eisenstein (V, 16mm)<br />

The Fall of the Romanov Dynasty, Esfir Shub (V, 16mm)<br />

The Great Road, Esfir Shub<br />

1928 Storm Over Asia, Vsevolod Pudovkin (V, 16mm)<br />

The Russia of Nicholas II and Lev Tolstoy, Esfir Shub<br />

1929 The New Babylon, Grigori Kozintsev and Leonid<br />

Trauberg (V)<br />

1930<br />

1934<br />

1935<br />

1936<br />

1945<br />

1946<br />

Old and New or The General Line, Sergei Eisenstein (V,<br />

16mm)<br />

The Man with a Movie Camera, Dziga Vertov (16mm)<br />

Arsenal, Alexander Dovzhenko (V, 16mm)<br />

Turksib, Victor Turin<br />

Ranks and People, Yakov Protazanov<br />

Earth, Alexander Dovzhenko (V, 16mm)<br />

Enthusiasm, Dziga Vertov (16mm)<br />

Chapayev, Sergei and Georgy Vasiliev (V)<br />

The Youth of Maxim, Grigori Kozintsev, and Leonid<br />

Trauberg (16mm)<br />

Aerograd, Alexander Dovzhenko<br />

We from Krondstadt, Yefim Dzigan (V)<br />

Alexander Nevsky, Sergei Eisenstein (16mm)<br />

Ivan the Terrible: Part I, Sergei Eisenstein (V, 16mm)<br />

Ivan the Terrible: Part II, Sergei Eisenstein (V, 16mm)


Availability of Russian/Soviet<br />

films<br />

Soviet/Russian films are easily obtained both on video and for<br />

hire on 16mm. Most of the key 1920s Soviet films have been<br />

released on video by Hendring and can also be hired on 16mm<br />

from the BFl at a relatively low cost (on average £25.00 plus<br />

delivery). For more information about hiring films see the BFI's<br />

films for hire catalogue, Films on Offer. A large number of the<br />

Russian films of the 1910s are also available (released by the<br />

BFl) as a set of ten videos.<br />

N A T I O N A L C I N E M A S<br />

http://us.imdb.com/Sections/Countries/SovietUnion<br />

This is the Inter<strong>net</strong> Movie Data Base (US) with a listing of 2,380<br />

Russian films including details of producers, distributors, directors,<br />

genres, casts, writers, composers of music, and other titles<br />

by which the film is known.<br />

http://www.nd.edu/astrouni/zhiwriter/movies.htm<br />

A Russian cinema/movies website with films, directors, artists,<br />

critics, distributors, history, historians and Russian Cinema<br />

WWW Server.


Sergej M. EISENSTEIN: Über die Reinheit der Filmsprache (1934). In:<br />

Ders.: Schriften 2, Hans-Joachim Schlegel (Hg.). München: Hanser<br />

1973, S. 141-150.<br />

Über die Reinheit der Filmsprache<br />

Es ist bezeichnend, daß man sich inzwischen angewöhnt hat,<br />

von Filmen als von »Ton«-Filmen zu sprechen. Soll das etwa<br />

bedeuten, daß das, was man sieht, keinerlei Beachtung verdient?<br />

Darauf läuft es aber schließlich hinaus.<br />

141


An dieser Stelle wird man natürlich giftig einwerfen: »Aha,<br />

alter Teufel, willst uns wieder mit Montage kommen!«<br />

Ja sicher, mit Montage.<br />

Für viele sind Montage und »linke«, formalistische Übertreibung<br />

1 synonym.<br />

Inzwischen aber...<br />

Mit all dem hat Montage aber gar nichts gemein.<br />

Für diejenigen, die etwas davon verstehen: Montage ist das<br />

stärkste Kompositionsmittel für die künstlerische Realisierung<br />

eines Sujets.<br />

Für diejenigen, die von Komposition keine Ahnung haben:<br />

Montage ist die Syntax des richtigen Aufbaus aller Einzelfragmente<br />

eines künstlerischen Films.<br />

Und schließlich für diejenigen, die Filmstücke irrigerweise so<br />

zusammenfügen, wie man nach gebrauchsfertigen Rezepten<br />

Medizin zusammenbraut, Gurken einlegt, Pflaumen einmacht<br />

oder aber Äpfel mit Preiselbeeren einkocht: Montage<br />

ist schlicht und einfach eine elementare Regel filmischer Orthographie.<br />

Wenn Knopf, Gürtel und Hosenträger auch mal zum Selbstzweck<br />

würden, so gäbe das ein ganz schönes Durcheinander.<br />

Und ich möchte mal die Freiheit der ausdrucksvollen Handbewegungen<br />

eines Menschen sehen, der im unteren Teil seiner<br />

festlichen Garderobe dieser Hilfsaggregate entbehren<br />

müßte.<br />

Es gibt Filme, in denen man auf einzelne gutgemachte Einstellungen<br />

stößt, wobei es aber in den jeweiligen Kontexten<br />

zu einem regelrechten Widerspruch zwischen den verselbständigten<br />

bildlichen Qualitäten und dem Stellenwert einer Einstellung<br />

kommt. Einstellungen ohne Verbindung mit einem<br />

Montagegedanken und der Komposition werden zu ästhetischen<br />

Spielereien und Selbstzweck. Je besser sie gemacht<br />

sind, umso mehr läuft der Film Gefahr, zu einer Sammlung<br />

schöner Phrasen, einem Schaufenster voller bunt zusammengewürfelter<br />

Dinge oder einem Album schönbebilderter Briefmarken<br />

zu werden.<br />

Wir sind keine Verfechter einer »Hegemonie« der Montage<br />

mehr. Die Zeit ist vorbei, als man aus pädagogischen und<br />

erzieherischen Gründen taktische und polemische Manöver<br />

für die allgemeine Etablierung der Montage als eines Aus-<br />

142<br />

drucksmittels führen mußte. Es ist aber unsere verdammte<br />

Pflicht und Schuldigkeit, die Frage nach dem Bildungsgrad<br />

einer Filmdiktion zu stellen. Es genügt nicht, zu fordern, daß<br />

die Qualität der Montage, der Filmsyntax und Filmsprache<br />

nicht hinter der Qualität früherer Arbeiten zurückbleiben<br />

dürfe. Es gilt vielmehr, über diese hinauszugehen, sie zu<br />

überflügeln. Das fordert der Kampf für eine hohe Qualität<br />

der Filmkultur von uns.<br />

Die Literatur hat es leichter. Wenn man sie kritisiert, so kann<br />

man ihr Beispiel der Klassiker entgegenhalten. Ihr Erbe und<br />

ihre Leistungen sind in vielen Fragen bis zu den detailliertesten<br />

Einzelheiten mit mikroskopischer Akribie erforscht worden.<br />

Obwohl Andrej Belyj gestorben ist, so steht dennoch<br />

seine Analyse des Gogolschen Kompositions- und Bildaufbaus<br />

2 wie ein lebendiger Vorwurf vor jeder Form literarischer<br />

Leichtfertigkeit.<br />

[...]<br />

Kehren wir noch einmal zur Frage nach der Reinheit der<br />

Filmsprache zurück. Es fällt mir keineswegs schwer, den<br />

Einwand, die Meisterschaft der Filmdiktion und -ausdruckskraft<br />

sei noch zu jung und ohne klassische Vorbilder in der<br />

klassischen Tradition, in der Luft zu zerreißen. Ebenso die Behauptung,<br />

ich würde jene mißachten und - ohne ihnen positive<br />

Vorbilder gegenüberzustellen - mich einfach an literarischen<br />

Analogien orientieren. Viele zweifeln sogar daran, daß<br />

es in dieser »Halbkunst« (das ist die Filmkunst immer noch<br />

für viele) überhaupt so etwas geben könne. In einer bestimmten<br />

Epoche kannte aber unsere Filmkunst immerhin schon<br />

einmal ein ebenso strenges Verantwortungsgefühl gegenüber<br />

jeder Einstellung, wie die Dichtkunst gegenüber jeder Strophe<br />

eines Poems oder die Musik für den gesetzmäßigen Verlauf<br />

einer Fuge.<br />

Hierfür könnten genügend Beispiele aus der Praxis unseres<br />

Stummfilms angeführt werden. Da ich aber keine Zeit habe<br />

jetzt speziell hierfür andere Beispiele zu untersuchen, erlaube<br />

ich mir, an dieser Stelle ein Analysebeispiel aus meiner eigenen<br />

Arbeit anzuführen. Es ist den Materialien meines noch<br />

nicht fertig gestellten Buches >Regiekunst< 3 entnommen.<br />

(Teil II: >Mise-en-cadresPotemkin


gen zu können, wähle ich bewußt keine besonders akzentuierte<br />

Szene, sondern die erstbeste Stelle, auf die ich gerade<br />

stoße: Vierzehn aufeinander folgende Filmstücke aus der<br />

Szene, die der Schießerei auf der »Odessaer Treppe« vorangeht.<br />

Es handelt sich um die Szenen, als die »Herren<br />

Odessaer« (so titulierten die »Potemkin«-Matrosen die Einwohner<br />

von Odessa in ihrer Ansprache) Jollen mit Proviant<br />

zum meuternden Panzerkreuzer schickten.<br />

Die Begrüßung des »Potemkin« ist aus der deutlichen Überschneidung<br />

zweier Themen aufgebaut:<br />

1. Die Jollen eilen auf den Panzerkreuzer zu.<br />

2. Die Einwohner von Odessa winken.<br />

Am Schluß verschmelzen die beiden Themen miteinander.<br />

Im wesentlichen handelt es sich um eine Komposition auf<br />

zwei Ebenen: Tiefe und Vordergrund. Abwechselnd schieben<br />

sich diese Themen nach oben, treten in den Vordergrund<br />

oder schieben sich gegenseitig in den Hintergrund.<br />

Die Komposition ist folgendermaßen aufgebaut:<br />

1) auf einer plastischen Wechselwirkung der beiden Ebenen<br />

(innerhalb der Einstellung) und 2) auf dem Wechsel der Linien<br />

und Formen von Einstellung zu Einstellung - und zwar<br />

in jeder der beiden Ebenen (in Montageform). Im zweiten<br />

Fall wird das Kompositionsspiel durch ein kollidierendes<br />

oder aber innerlich zusammenhängendes Ineinandergreifen<br />

des plastischen Eindrucks einer vorhergegangenen und einer<br />

darauf folgenden Einstellung gestaltet. /(Hierbei handelt es<br />

sich um eine an rein räumlichen und linearen Merkmalen<br />

orientierte Analyse. Die rhythmisch-zeitliche Beziehung wird<br />

an anderer Stelle untersucht).<br />

Die Kompositionsbeweguhg nimmt folgenden Verlauf (vgl.<br />

die beigefügte graphische Analyse, Abb., S. 268.<br />

I. Die Jollen in Bewegung. Gleichmäßige Bewegung, parallel<br />

zum horizontalen Schnitt dieser Einstellung. Das ganze<br />

Blickfeld ist vom ersten Thema bestimmt: Ein Spiel kleiner,<br />

vertikaler Segel.<br />

II. Intensivere Bewegung der Jollen aus dem ersten Thema<br />

(das wird auch durch das Aufkommen des zweiten Themas<br />

bewirkt). Mit dem strengen Rhythmus der vertikalen,<br />

unbeweglichen Säulen tritt das zweite Thema in den Vordergrund.<br />

Vertikallinien künden die plastische Verteilung der<br />

nun folgenden Figuren an (IV, V usw.). Im unteren Teil der<br />

144<br />

Einstellung erscheint das plastische Thema des Brückenbogens.<br />

III. Das plastische Thema des Brückenbogens wächst in<br />

die ganze Einstellung hinein. Das Spiel der wechselnden Einstellungsfolge<br />

besteht im Übergang der Vertikallinien in eine<br />

bogenförmige Struktur. Das Thema der Vertikalen ist in der<br />

Bewegung der Menschen bewahrt worden, die sich ohne<br />

heftigere Bewegung von der Kamera wegbegeben. Das Jollenthema<br />

ist endgültig in die Tiefe verdrängt.<br />

IV. Das plastische Bogenthema rückt endgültig in den<br />

Vordergrund. Die Bogenformation geht in eine entgegengesetzte<br />

Lösung über, die von der kreisförmig zusammengetretenen<br />

Gruppe angekündigt wird (die Komposition wird<br />

durch den Sonnenschirm vorausgedeutet). Derselbe Übergang<br />

in ein Gegenstück findet auch innerhalb des Vertikalaufbaus<br />

statt: Die Rücken der sich ohne heftigere Bewegung<br />

in die Tiefe begebenden Menschen werden von unbeweglichen<br />

und von vorn aufgenommenen Figuren abgelöst. Das<br />

Thema der Jollenbewegung wird dabei durch deren Augenausdruck<br />

und ihre horizontale Bewegung in gespiegelter<br />

Form beibehalten.<br />

V. Im Vordergrund gibt es eine allgemein übliche Kompositionsvariation:<br />

Eine gerade Anzahl von Gesichtern wird<br />

durch eine ungerade ersetzt. Zwei ersetzt durch drei. Diese<br />

»goldene Regel« eines Mise-en-scene-Wechsels hat ihre Tradition,<br />

die bis zur italienischen »Comedia dell'arte« (hier<br />

kreuzen sich noch die Blickrichtungen) zurückreicht. Das<br />

Bogenmotiv wird erneut gespannt, diesmal aber in umgekehrter<br />

Biegung: Es wird vom Hintergrund, von der Balustrade<br />

wiederholt und unterstützt. Das Thema der Jollen: Sie<br />

sind in Bewegung. Das Thema der Augen: Sie spähen in der<br />

ganzen Breite der Einstellung in horizontaler Richtung.<br />

VI. Die Einstellungen I-V bilden den Übergang vom Jollenthema<br />

zum Thema der Beobachter, das in fünf Montagestücken<br />

entwickelt wird. Das Intervall von V zu VI bringt in<br />

abrupter Rückwärtswendung einen Übergang von den Beobachtern<br />

zurück zu den Jollen. Die Komposition, die sich<br />

streng an den Inhalt hält, verkehrt alle bezeichnenden Elemente<br />

abrupt in ihr Gegenteil. Die Balustradenlinie wird aus<br />

der Tiefe schnell in den Vordergrund gerückt, d. h. durch die<br />

Bordlinie des Bootes wiederholt. Darüberhinaus wird sie<br />

145


durch die Berührungslinien von Boot und Wasseroberfläche<br />

verdoppelt. Die grundlegende kompositionelle Anordnung<br />

bleibt zwar gleich, ihre konkrete Ausarbeitung aber ist kontrovers.<br />

V ist statisch. VI wird von der Dynamik der Bootsbewegung<br />

bestimmt. Die vertikale »Dreiteilung« wird in beiden<br />

Einstellungen beibehalten. Das jeweilige Zentralelement<br />

(Frauenbluse, bzw. Segeltuch) ist strukturell verwandt. Die<br />

jeweiligen Seitenelemente stehen in scharfem Gegensatz: Die<br />

schwarzen Flecken der beiden Männer neben der Frau und<br />

die weißen Zwischenräume neben dem Segel. Ebenso konträr<br />

ist auch die vertikale Aufgliederung: Die drei - durch<br />

den unteren Rand des Bildes abgeschnittenen - Figuren gehen<br />

in ein vertikales Segel über, das vom oberen Bildrand<br />

abgeschnitten wird. Im Hintergrund taucht ein neues Thema<br />

auf: Der Panzerkreuzer, dessen Bord sichtbar wird, und der<br />

von oben her abgeschnitten ist (Vorbereitung auf VII).<br />

VII. Eine erneute scharfe thematische Wendung. Das<br />

Hintergrundthema - der Panzerkreuzer - wird in den Vordergrund<br />

gerückt (der Sprung des Themenwechsels von V<br />

auf VI hat gleichsam die Funktion eines musikalischen Vorschlags<br />

4 für den Sprung von VI auf VII). Der Blickwinkel<br />

wird um 180 ° gedreht und ist vom Panzerkreuzer aufs Meer,<br />

d. h. zurück auf VI gerichtet. Diesmal befindet sich also der<br />

Panzerkreuzer im Vordergrund, wobei er vom unteren BUdrand<br />

abgeschnitten wird. In der Tiefe wird das Segelthema<br />

mit Vertikalen entwickelt. Und auch die Matrosen bilden<br />

eine Vertikale. Der statische Geschützlauf setzt die Bewegungslinie<br />

aus der vorhergehenden Einstellung fort. Der<br />

Schiffsbord erscheint als ein in die Gerade übergehender Bogen.<br />

VIII. Hier wird VI mit erhöhter Intensivität wiederholt.<br />

Das horizontale Augenspiel wird in vertikal winkende Hände<br />

umgesetzt. Und das Vertikalthema rückt aus der Tiefe heraus<br />

in den Vordergrund, wobei es in verdoppelter Wiederholung<br />

das Sujet auf die aufmerksamen Beobachter hinüberlenkt.<br />

IX. Zwei Gesichter aus der Nähe. Übrigens eine unglückliche<br />

Zusammenstellung mit der vorangegangenen Einstellung.<br />

Es wäre besser gewesen, eine Einstellung mit drei Gesichtern<br />

dazwischenzuschalten, etwa Einstellung V mit erhöhter<br />

Intensivität zu wiederholen.<br />

146<br />

Dabei wäre die Bauform 2:3:2 herausgekommen. Darüberhinaus<br />

hätte die Wiederholung der vertrauten Gruppe aus<br />

IV und V mit dem neuen Abschluß in IX den Eindruck der<br />

vorangehenden Einstellung verstärkt. Die Situation wird einzig<br />

durch eine gewisse Stärkung der Ebene gerettet.<br />

X. Die beiden Gesichter gehen in ein einziges über. Der<br />

voller Energie hochgerissene Arm befindet sich außerhalb<br />

der Einstellung. Es findet ein richtiger Wechsel der Gesichter<br />

im Verhältnis 2:3:2:1 statt (natürlich unter der angemerkten<br />

Verbesserung in der Folge VIII auf IX). Das zweite<br />

Paar wird in bezug auf das erste Paar in der richtigen Dimensionserweiterung<br />

gezeigt (= richtige Wiederholung mit<br />

qualitativer Variation). Die Linie der Ungeraden ist quantitativ<br />

und qualitativ unterschiedlich (bei Beibehaltung des allgemeinen<br />

Kennzeichens der Ungeraden sind Ausmaße und<br />

Anzahl der Gesichter verschieden).<br />

XI. Neuer abrupter Themenwechsel. Ein Sprung, der den<br />

von V auf VI mit erhöhter Intensivität wiederholt. Das vertikale<br />

Hochreißen der Hände in der vorangegangenen Einstellung<br />

wird von dem vertikalen Segel aufgenommen und fortgesetzt.<br />

Dabei bewegt sich die Vertikale dieses Segels auf der<br />

Horizontalen. Das Thema von VI wird mit erhöhter Intensität<br />

wiederholt. Ebenso auch die Komposition von II, allerdings<br />

mit dem Unterschied, daß das Horizontalthema der<br />

sich bewegenden Jollen und die Vertikalen der unbeweglichen<br />

Säulen hier in einer einzigen horizontalen Verschiebung<br />

des vertikalen Segels zusammenfließen. Die Komposition<br />

nimmt erneut die Sujetlinie von der Einheit und Zusammengehörigkeit<br />

der Jollen und der am Ufer stehenden Menschen<br />

auf (und dies bevor zum Thema der endgültigen, abschließenden<br />

Vereinigungsthematik übergegangen wird: Zur Vereinigung<br />

von Ufer und Panzerkreuzer über die Mittlerrolle der<br />

Jollen).<br />

XII. Das Segel von XI löst sich in einer Menge vertikaler<br />

Segel auf, die sich wiederum auf der Horizontalen bewegen<br />

(= Wiederholung von I mit erhöhter Intensität). Die kleinen<br />

Segel bewegen sich in entgegengesetzter Bewegung wie das<br />

große Segel.<br />

XIII. Nachdem das große Segel in viele kleine aufgelöst<br />

worden ist, wird es jetzt wiederum zusammengesetzt. Nunmehr<br />

aber nicht als Segel sondern als Flagge, die über der<br />

147


»Potemkin« weht. Diese Einstellung besitzt eine neue Qualität:<br />

Sie ist zugleich statisch und bewegt - der Mast ist vertikal<br />

und unbeweglich, die Flagge dagegen flattert im Wind.<br />

In formaler Hinsicht wird XI von XII wiederholt. Gleichzeitig<br />

aber übersetzt der Segel-Flagge-Wechsel das Prinzip der<br />

plastischen Vereinigung in eine Verschmelzung von Thema<br />

und Idee. Es handelt sich hierbei schon nicht mehr nur<br />

um eine Vertikale, die einzelne Kompositionselemente in<br />

plastischer Weise vereinigt, sondern um das Banner der<br />

Revolution, das den Panzerkreuzer, die Jollen und das Ufer<br />

vereinigt.<br />

XIV. Von hier aus findet eine natürliche Rückkehr von<br />

der Flagge zum Panzerkreuzer statt. XIV wiederholt VII.<br />

Und dies natürlich wiederum mit erhöhter Intensität.<br />

Diese Einstellung führt eine neue Kompositionsgruppe ein:<br />

Die Wechselbeziehungen von Jollen und Panzerkreuzer gegenüber<br />

der ersten Bezugsgruppe Jollen - Ufer. Die erste<br />

Gruppe drückte das Thema aus: »Die Jollen bringen dem<br />

Panzerkreuzer Grüße und Geschenke des Ufers«. Die zweite<br />

Gruppe wird die Verbrüderung von Jollen und Panzerkreuzer<br />

ausdrücken.<br />

Der Schiffsmast mit der Revolutionsflagge dient gleichzeitig<br />

als kompositionelle Wasserscheide und als ideologisches<br />

Vereinigungsinstrument dieser beiden Kompositionsgruppen.<br />

Einstellung VII - von XIV, der ersten Einstellung der zweiten<br />

Gruppe wiederholt - ist eine Art musikalischer Vorschlag<br />

der zweiten Gruppe und ein bestimmtes Verbindungselement<br />

dieser beiden Gruppen, so als hätte die zweite<br />

Gruppe einen »Aufklärertrupp« in die erste Gruppe geschickt.<br />

In der zweiten Gruppe spielen die Einstellungen mit<br />

den winkenden Figuren, die zwischen die Verbrüderungsszenen<br />

von Jollen und Panzerkreuzer eingeblendet wurden, diese<br />

Rolle.<br />

Natürlich soll man nicht glauben, daß Aufnahme und Montage<br />

dieser Einstellungen nach einer solchen - schon a priori<br />

vorgefertigten - graphischen Tabelle gemacht wurden. Natürlich<br />

war das nicht so! Aber die Sammlung und zusammenhangbezogene<br />

Plazierung dieser Filmstücke auf dem Schneidetisch<br />

war dann schon von den kompositionellen Erfordernissen<br />

der Filmform streng vorgeschrieben. Diese Erforder-<br />

148<br />

nisse diktierten die Auswahl der Filmstücke aus dem gesamten<br />

zur Verfügung stehenden Material und legten gleichzeitig<br />

die Gesetzmäßigkeit ihres Wechsels fest. Wenn diese<br />

Filmstücke natürlich nur unter anekdotischem oder sujetbezogenem<br />

Aspekt betrachtet werden, können sie freilich in jeder<br />

beliebigen Anordnung vorgestellt werden. Aber die<br />

durch sie hindurchlaufende Kompositionslinie würde sich in<br />

diesem Fall kaum als regelmäßig erweisen.<br />

Man sollte deshalb nicht gar zu sehr über die Kompliziertheit<br />

dieser Analyse schimpfen. Im Vergleich mit den Analysen<br />

literarischer und musikalischer Formen ist unsere Analyse<br />

noch verhältnismäßig eingängig und leicht verständlich 5 .<br />

Obwohl wir die Fragen der rhythmischen Abfolge bisher beiseite<br />

gelassen haben, stellt unsere Analyse irgendwie auch<br />

eine Analyse des Wechsels von Klang- und Wortkombinationen<br />

dar. -—<br />

Eine Analyse der Aufnahmeobjekte selbst sowie ihrer künstlerischen<br />

Gestaltung durch die perspektivische Verkürzung<br />

der Kamera- und Lichtbewegungen, die von den Forderungen<br />

des Stils und des inhaltlichen Charakters eines Filmes<br />

bestimmt werden, entspräche einer Ausdrucksanalyse der<br />

sprachlichen Wendungen, Wörter und pho<strong>net</strong>ischen Merkmale<br />

in einem literarischen Werk.<br />

Wir sind davon überzeugt, daß die Anforderungen, die die<br />

Filmkomposition an sich selbst stellt, in keinem Punkt hinter<br />

den Anforderungen der entsprechenden literarischen und<br />

musikalischen Disziplinen zurückstehen.<br />

Am allerwenigsten vermag natürlich ein Zuschauer die Baugesetze<br />

montierter, aufeinanderfolgender Einstellungen in<br />

ihrem ganzen Umfang zu erfassen. In seiner Wahrnehmung<br />

der gesetzmäßigen Montagekomposition wirken aber dieselben<br />

Elemente, die eine Passage gepflegter Prosa von den Passagen<br />

eines Grafen Amori, einer Verbickaja oder eines<br />

Bresko-Breskovskij stilistisch unterscheiden 6 .<br />

Gegenwärtig reiht sich die sowjetische Filmkunst in den historisch<br />

richtigen Feldzug für das Sujet ein. Auf diesem Wege<br />

liegen aber noch eine Menge Schwierigkeiten und das große<br />

Risiko, die Prinzipien des Sujethaften falsch zu verstehen.<br />

Das Schlimmste dabei ist die Mißachtung jener Möglichkeiten,<br />

die uns der zeitweise Bruch mit den alten Sujettraditionen<br />

eröff<strong>net</strong>e:<br />

149


Gemeint ist die Chance, die Grundlagen und Probleme des<br />

Filmsujets auf neue Weise zu überdenken,<br />

ferner die Chance, in einer kinematografischen Vorwärtsbewegung<br />

nicht »zurück« zum Sujet, sondern »vorwärts zum<br />

Sujet« zu gelangen.<br />

Obwohl sich schon einige positive Erscheinungen abzeichnen,<br />

befinden wir uns bislang noch nicht auf den Wegen einer<br />

strengen künstlerischen Orientierung.<br />

Aber was auch immer geschieht: In dem Moment, in dem<br />

wir die exakt erkannten Prinzipien der sowjetischen Sujet-<br />

Filmkunst beherrschen, müssen wir ihr in der vollen Rüstung<br />

einer makellosen Reinheit und Kultiviertheit von Filmsprache<br />

und -rede 7 entgegengehen.<br />

Unsere großen Meister der Literatur - von Puskin und<br />

Gogol' bis zu Majakovskij und Gor'kij schätzen wir nicht<br />

nur als Meister des Sujets. Wir schätzen in ihnen auch die<br />

Kultur von Meistern der Sprache und des Wortes.<br />

Es ist an der Zeit, die Frage nach der Kultur der Filmsprache<br />

wieder in aller Schärfe zu stellen.<br />

Es ist wichtig, daß hierzu alle Filmschaffenden Stellung<br />

beziehen.<br />

Und dies vor allem in der Sprache der Montage und der Einstellungen<br />

ihrer Filme.<br />

1934<br />

Das Organische und das Pathos in der Komposition<br />

des Filmes >PanzerkreuzerPotemkin<<br />

Wenn vom >Panzerkreuzer Potemkin< die Rede ist, werden<br />

gewöhnlich zwei Merkmale hervorgehoben: Die organische<br />

Harmonie seiner Komposition als Gesamtwerk. Und<br />

das Pathos des Films.<br />

150<br />

Das Organische und das Pathos<br />

Wir werden diese zwei markantesten Züge des >Panzerkreuzers<<br />

betrachten und herauszufinden versuchen, mit welchen<br />

Mitteln sie erreicht worden sind - vor allem auf dem Gebiet<br />

der Komposition. Den ersten Zug, das Organische, werden<br />

wir an der Komposition des Films als Gesamtwerk untersuchen;<br />

den zweiten, das Pathos, an der »Hafentreppen«-Episode,<br />

wo das Pathos seine größte dramatische Konzentration<br />

erreicht.<br />

Unsere Analyse wird sich mit der Frage beschäftigen, wie das<br />

Organische und das Pathos des Themas speziell mit kompositorischen<br />

Mitteln erzielt worden sind, so wie wir ja zum<br />

Beispiel auch untersuchen könnten, wie diese zwei Züge im<br />

Spiel der Schauspieler, in der Behandlung des Sujets, in der<br />

Licht- und Farbgebung, in der Darstellung von Massenszenen<br />

und Landschaft und so weiter realisiert worden sind.<br />

Das heißt also, wir werden es mit einem begrenzten, speziellen<br />

Problem der Struktur des Werkes zu tun haben, das natürlich<br />

keinesfalls eine gründliche Analyse aller Seiten des<br />

Films beanspruchen kann.<br />

Nichtsdestoweniger durchdringen gerade in einem organischen<br />

Kunstwerk diejenigen Elemente, die dem ganzen Werk<br />

zugrunde liegen, jeden einzelnen Zug des Werkes. Eine einzige,<br />

einheitliche Gesetzmäßigkeit durchdringt nicht nur das<br />

allgemeine Ganze und jedes seiner Einzelteile, sondern auch<br />

jedes Gebiet, das an der Schaffung des Ganzen teilzunehmen<br />

hat. Ein und dieselben Prinzipien speisen jedes Gebiet, dergestalt,<br />

daß sie in jedem von ihnen in ihren eigenen qualitativen<br />

Unterschieden in Erscheinung treten. Und nur wenn diese<br />

Voraussetzungen erfüllt sind, kann man vom Organischen<br />

eines Kunstwerkes reden, denn wir verstehen den Begriff Organismus<br />

hier so, wie ihn Engels in seiner »Dialektik der Natur«<br />

definiert: »Denn der Organismus ist allerdings die höhere<br />

Einheit.. .« 1<br />

Diese Überlegungen führen uns zugleich zum ersten Gegenstand<br />

unserer Analyse: Zur Frage nach dem »Organischen«<br />

im Aufbau des >Panzerkreuzer Potemkin


Aber dem Bildinhalt nach scheinen sie alle Herzen ihnen entgegenzutragen.<br />

In diesem leichtem, beschwingtem Flug von hundert<br />

geschwellten Segeln erscheint im Bild eine Gruppengebärde, die<br />

mehr Jubel, Liebe, Seligkeit, Hoffnung ausdrückt, als es das Gesicht<br />

des größten Schauspielers ausdrücken könnte. Diese Aufnahme<br />

- eben die Aufnahme und nicht das Motiv! - ist zum Übergehen<br />

erfüllt von einer überschwenglichen Lyrik, von einer Gleichniskraft,<br />

von einer Poesie, der kaum eine geschriebene Dichtung<br />

zu vergleichen ist.<br />

In dieser verborgenen Gleichniskraft der Bilder - die nichts mit<br />

»dekorativer Schönheit« zu tun hat - liegt die poetisch-schöpferische<br />

Möglichkeit des Kameramannes.<br />

Die Segelboote sehen wir dann vom Schiffsdeck aus. Alle, wie auf<br />

ein Kommando, lassen gleichzeitig die Segel herunter. Der rationelle<br />

»Inhalt« der Begebenheit ist, daß die Boote eben stehen bleiben<br />

vor dem Schiff. Aber die Bildwirkung ist: als wenn die hundert<br />

Segel, hundert Fahnen, zum Gruß sich neigen würden vor<br />

dem Helden. In dieser Gleichniskraft der Bilder liegt ihre eigene<br />

Poesie, jene, die erst im Bild durch die Aufnahme entsteht.«<br />

23<br />

Eisenstein attakiert hier Baläzs' Unterscheidung von »Fabelinhalt«<br />

und »Bildinhalt«, mit der Baläzs praktisch eine Ressortaufteilung<br />

zwischen Drehbuchautor und Kameramann vornimmt.<br />

!<br />

24<br />

Mit diesem Satz reagiert Eisenstein auf Baläzs' abschließende<br />

These, a.a.O., S. 235b: »Freilich wird man mir sagen: Die beiden<br />

Bildeinstellungen in >PotemkinPotemkin< - die Ermordung Vakulincuks<br />

durch Giljarovskij nach dem Ausbruch des Aufstands - von der<br />

zeitgenössischen Kritik moniert. Vgl. V. Sklovskij, »Cetvertyi<br />

242<br />

fel'eton ob Ejzenstejne«, in: >Za sorok letVersuch einer Psychologie des FilmsDOK 50The Birth of a Nation. (1915) gilt als Paradebeispiel<br />

der »amerikanischen Montage«. Eisenstein setzt sich mit<br />

Griffith wiederholt auseinander; vgl. besonders >Dickens, Griffith<br />

und wirThe ten commandments« (1923), Regie: Cecil de Mill.<br />

>Über die Reinheit der Filmsprache<<br />

Erstdruck: >E! O cistote kinojazyka«, in »Sovetskoe kino< 1934/5,<br />

S. 25-31; jetzt in: >Izbr. proizv.«, Bd. II, S. 81-92. Auszug. Auf die<br />

Verwendung der zum Teil recht problematischen Übersetzung aus<br />

dem Amerikanischen unter dem Titel >Filmsprache< wurde verzichtet,<br />

in: >Vom Theater zum Film«, Deutsch von Marlies Pörtner,<br />

Zürich 1960, S. 55-70. Übersetzung: Hans-Joachim Schlegel.<br />

1 Eisenstein setzt sich hiermit von seinen rigorosen Thesen aus<br />

der LEF-Zeit ab; die LEF stand in enger theoretischer und personeller<br />

Beziehung zur russischen Formalen Schule und dem russischen<br />

Futurismus. Vgl. »Montage 1938«, in: »Schriften« 4, »Aleksandr<br />

Nevskij« (in Vorbereitung). Dort heißt es: »Es gab in unserer<br />

Filmkunst eine Periode, in der Montage »alles« war. Jetzt geht<br />

eine Periode zu Ende, in der Montage »nichts« galt.«<br />

2 Bezieht sich auf die theoretische Arbeit des russischen symbolistischen<br />

Prosaikers Andrej Belyj (d.i. Boris Nikolevic Bugaev;<br />

1880-1934): »Masterstvo Gogolja« (»Gogols Meisterschaft«), Moskau<br />

1934. Eisenstein hatte Belyj im Januar 1933 persönlich kennengelernt.<br />

3 An dem unvollendeten Lehrbuch »Rezissura« (»Regie«) arbeitete<br />

Eisenstein von 1933 bis zu seinem Tod. Fertiggestellt wurde<br />

nur der erste Teil »Iskusstvo mizansceny« (»Die Kunst der mise-enscene«).<br />

Der hier erwähnte zweite Teil »Iskusstvo mizankadra«<br />

(»Die Kunst der mise-en-cadre


5 Bezieht sich vor allem auf die literaturwissenschaftlichen<br />

Analysen der Formalen Schule: J. Tynjanov, B. Ejchenbaum,<br />

V. Sklovskij, u. a.<br />

6 Graf Amori (d. i. I. P. Rapgof), A. A. Verbickaja und N. N.<br />

Bresko-Breskovskij waren russische Boulevardschriftsteller der<br />

Jahrhundertwende.<br />

7 s. »Bela vergißt die Schere«, Anm. 19.<br />

>Das Organische und das Pathos in der Komposition des Filmes<br />

>Panzerkreuzer Potemkin0 stroenii vescej«<br />

(>Über den Bau der DingeIskusstvo kinoIzbr. proi'zv.Vom Theater zum FilmDialektik der NaturMEWZur Frage der Dialektik«, in: Lenin a.a.O.,<br />

Bd. 36, 1962, S. 347.<br />

3 >Platons Timaios, Kritias, Gesetze XProporcional'nost' v architekture< (»Proportionalität<br />

in der Architektur«), Moskau 1935, S. 33.<br />

5 Hegel, >Sämtliche Werke«, Hrsg. von H. Glockner, Bd. 8,<br />

Stuttgart 1929, S. 294: >System der Philosophie«, in: »Encyklopädie<br />

der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse«.<br />

6 Ebda, S. 308.<br />

7 E. K. Rozenov, russischer Musikwissenschaftler, aus dessen<br />

Werk >J.-S. Bach i ego rod< (>J.-S. Bach und seine GenerationEugen Onegin und andere VerserzählungenVystavka peredviznikov« (»Ausstellung der Pe-<br />

244<br />

redvizniki«), in: »Izbrannye socinenija« (»Ausgewählte Werke«),<br />

Bd. 3, Moskau 1952, S. 59.<br />

11 Zitiert nach V. Nikolskij, »Tvorceskije processy V. I. Surikova


Dziga VERTOV: Wir. Variante eines Manifestes (1922). In: Franz-Josef<br />

Albersmeier (Hg.): Texte zur Theorie des Films. Stuttgart 1979, S. 19-<br />

23.<br />

DZIGA VERTOV<br />

Wir. Variante eines Manifestes<br />

1922<br />

Wir nennen uns »Kinoki« im Unterschied zu den »Kinematographisten«<br />

- der Herde von Trödlern, die nicht übel mit ihren<br />

Lappen handelt.<br />

Wir sehen keine Bindung zwischen der Gerissenheit und Berechnung<br />

des Handels und der echten Filmsache.<br />

In unseren Augen ist das von der Sicht und den Erinnerungen<br />

der Kindheit belastete psychologische russo-deutsche Kinodrama<br />

Humbug.<br />

Dem amerikanischen Abenteuerfilm, dem Film des optischen<br />

Dynamismus, den Inszenierungen der amerikanischen Pinkertonovscina<br />

- das Danke des Kinoks für die Schnelligkeit des<br />

Bildwechsels und für die Großaufnahmen! Gut, aber regellos,<br />

nicht auf das genaue Studium der Bewegung gegründet. Eine<br />

Stufe höher als das psychologische Drama, aber dennoch ohne<br />

Fundament. Schablone. Eine Kopie der Kopie.<br />

Wir erklären die alten Kinofilme, die romantizistischen, theatralisierten<br />

u. a. für aussätzig.<br />

— Nicht nahekommen!<br />

— Nicht anschauen!<br />

- Lebensgefährlich!<br />

- Ansteckend!<br />

Wir bekräftigen die Zukunft der Filmkunst durch die Ablehnung<br />

ihrer Gegenwart.<br />

Der Tod des »Kinematographen« ist notwendig für das Leben<br />

der Filmkunst.<br />

Wir rufen dazu auf, seinen Tod zu beschleunigen.<br />

Wir protestieren gegen die Ineinanderschiebung der Künste, die<br />

viele eine Synthese nennen. Die Mischung schlechter Farben ergibt,<br />

auch wenn sie im Idealfall nach dem Farbenspektrum ausgewählt<br />

worden sind, keine weiße Farbe, sondern Dreck.


20 D. Vertov<br />

Zur Synthese im Zenit der Errungenschaften jeder Kunstgattung<br />

— aber nicht früher.<br />

Wir säubern die Filmsache von allem, was sich einschleicht, von<br />

der Musik, der Literatur und dem Theater; wir suchen ihren nirgendwo<br />

gestohlenen Rhythmus und finden ihn in den Bewegungen<br />

der Dinge.<br />

Wir fordern auf:<br />

Weg<br />

von den süßdurchfeuchteten Romanzen,<br />

vom Gift des psychologischen Romans,<br />

aus den Fängen des Liebhabertheaters,<br />

mit dem Rücken zur Musik!<br />

Weg<br />

ins reine Feld, in den Raum der vier Dimensionen (drei + Zeit)!<br />

Auf zur Suche nach ihrem Material, ihrem Jambus, ihrem<br />

Rhythmus!<br />

Das »Psychologische« stört den Menschen, so genau wie eine<br />

Stoppuhr zu sein, es hindert ihn in seinem Bestreben, sich mit<br />

der Maschine zu verschwägern.<br />

Wir sehen keinen Grund, in der Kunst der Bewegung dem heutigen<br />

Menschen das Hauptaugenmerk zu widmen.<br />

Die Unfähigkeit des Menschen, sich zu beherrschen, ist vor den<br />

Maschinen beschämend; aber was tun, wenn uns die fehlerlosen<br />

Funktionsweisen der Elektrizität mehr erregen als die regellose<br />

Hetze aktiver und die zersetzende Schlaffheit passiver Leute.<br />

Uns ist die Freude tanzender Sägen einer Sägemaschine verständlicher<br />

und vertrauter als die Freude menschlicher Tanzvergnügen.<br />

Wir schließen den Menschen als Objekt der Filmaufnahme deshalb<br />

zeitweise aus, weil er unfähig ist, sich von seinen Bewegungen<br />

leiten zu lassen.<br />

Unser Weg — vom sich herumwälzenden Bürger über die Poesie<br />

der Maschinen zum vollendeten elektrischen Menschen.<br />

Die Seele der Maschine enthüllen, den Arbeiter in die Werkbank<br />

verlieben, den Bauern in den Traktor, den Maschinisten in<br />

die Lokomotive!<br />

Wir. Variante eines Manifestes 21<br />

Wir tragen die schöpferische Freude in jede mechanische Arbeit.<br />

Wir verbinden den Menschen mit der Maschine.<br />

Wir erziehen neue Menschen.<br />

Der neue Mensch, befreit von Schwerfälligkeit und linkischem<br />

Wesen, wird mit den genauen und leichten Bewegungen der<br />

Maschinen ein dankbares Objekt für die Filmaufnahme sein.<br />

Mit offenen Augen, des maschinellen Rhythmus bewußt, begeistert<br />

von der mechanischen Arbeit, die Schönheit chemischer<br />

Prozesse erkennend, komponieren wir das Filmpoem aus<br />

Flammen und Elektrizitätswerken, begeistern wir uns an der<br />

Bewegung der Kometen und Meteoriten und den Strahlen der<br />

Scheinwerfer, die die Gestirne blenden.<br />

Jeder, der seine Kunst liebt, sucht das Wesen ihrer Technik zu<br />

erfahren.<br />

Die erlahmten Nerven der Kinematographie brauchen das<br />

strenge System genauer Bewegungen.<br />

Der Jambus, das Tempo, die Bewegungsart, ihre genaue Disposition<br />

im Hinblick auf die Achsen der Einstellungskoordinaten,<br />

vielleicht aber auch zu den Weltachsen der Koordinaten (drei<br />

Dimensionen + die vierte - Zeit) müssen vom Filmschöpfer berücksichtigt<br />

und untersucht werden.<br />

Notwendigkeit, Präzision und Geschwindigkeit — drei Forderungen<br />

an die Bewegung, die der Aufnahme und Wiedergabe<br />

wert ist.<br />

Der geometrische Extrakt der Bewegung, gepackt vom Wechsel<br />

der Darstellungen, ist die Forderung an die Montage.<br />

Die Filmsache ist die Kunst der Organisation der notwendigen<br />

Bewegungen der Dinge im Raum und — angewandt — das rhythmische<br />

künstlerische Ganze, entsprechend den Eigenschaften des<br />

Stoffes und dem inneren Rhythmus jeder Sache.<br />

Der Stoff— die Elemente der Bewegungskunst - sind die Intervalle<br />

(die Übergänge von einer Bewegung zu anderen) und keinesfalls<br />

die Bewegungen selbst. Sie (die Intervalle) geben auch<br />

der Handlung die ki<strong>net</strong>ische Lösung.<br />

Die Organisation der Bewegung ist die Organisation ihrer Elemente,<br />

d. h. der Intervalle in Sätzen.


22 D. Vertov<br />

In jedem Satz gibt es einen Aufschwung, Errungenschaft und<br />

Fall der Bewegung (eine Enthüllung auf dieser oder jener Stufe).<br />

Das Werk baut sich ebenso aus Sätzen auf wie der Satz aus<br />

Intervallen.<br />

Um ein Kinopoem oder eine Sequenz in sich reifen zu lassen,<br />

muß der Kinok sie genau aufzeichnen können, um ihnen unter<br />

günstigen technischen Bedingungen das Leben auf der Leinwand<br />

geben zu können.<br />

Das vollendetste Szenarium kann diese Aufzeichnung nicht ersetzen,<br />

ebensowenig, wie das Libretto die Pantomime ersetzen<br />

kann, ebensowenig, wie die literarischen Erläuterungen zum<br />

Werk Skrjabins eine Vorstellung von seiner Musik vermitteln<br />

können. Um auf einem Blatt Papier eine dynamische Studie zu<br />

entwerfen, bedarf es graphischer Zeichen der Bewegung.<br />

Wir sind auf der Suche nach dem Filmalphabet.<br />

Wir fallen und wachsen hoch im Rhythmus der Bewegung verlangsamter<br />

und beschleunigter Dinge,<br />

die sich von uns entfernen, neben uns sind, über uns,<br />

um uns, sich gerade oder in Ellipsenform bewegen, .<br />

von rechts und links, versehen mit einem Plus und Minus: die<br />

Bewegungen verkrümmen, korrigieren, teilen, zerschroten,<br />

multiplizieren sich miteinander, durchschießen geräuschlos den<br />

Raum.<br />

Das Kino ist ebenso die Kunst der Erfindung der Bewegung der<br />

Dinge im Raum, die den Forderungen der Wissenschaft entsprechen,<br />

die Erfüllung des Traums des Entdeckers, sei dies ein<br />

Gelehrter, Künstler, Ingenieur oder Zimmermann, die Verwirklichung<br />

des im Leben nicht zu Verwirklichenden durch die<br />

Filmsache.<br />

Zeichnungen in Bewegung. Konstruktionsentwürfe in Bewegung.<br />

Projekte der Zukunft. Die Relativitätstheorie auf der<br />

Leinwand.<br />

Wir begrüßen die gesetzmäßige Phantastik der Bewegungen.<br />

Auf den Flügeln der Hypothesen stürmen unsere durch Propeller<br />

angetriebenen Augen in die Zukunft.<br />

Wir glauben, daß der Augenblick nicht fern ist, da wir Orkane<br />

Wir. Variante eines Manifestes 23<br />

von Bewegungen in den Raum schleudern können, die am Lasso<br />

unserer Taktik hängen.<br />

Es lebe die dynamische Geometrie, es leben die Abläufe der<br />

Punkte, Linien, Flächen, Volumina!<br />

Es lebe die Poesie der bewegenden und sich bewegenden Maschinen,<br />

die Poesie der Hebel, Räder und stählernen Flügel, der<br />

eiserne Schrei der Bewegung, die verblendeten Grimassen glühender<br />

Strahlen.<br />

Im Namen der ersten konstituierenden Versammlung der<br />

Kinoki.


Dziga VERTOV: Kinoglaz (1924). In: Franz-Josef Albersmeier (Hg.):<br />

Texte zur Theorie des Films. Stuttgart: Reclam 1979, S. 39-41.<br />

DZIGA VERTOV<br />

»Kinoglaz«<br />

1924<br />

Unsere Richtung nennt sich »Kinoglaz« (»Filmauge«). Wir, die<br />

wir für die Idee des Kinoglaz kämpfen, nennen uns »Kinoki«.<br />

Den Terminus »Filmkunst« gebrauchen wir möglichst nicht<br />

ebenso wie jede gebräuchliche oder zufällige Wortzusammensetzung.<br />

Deshalb benutzen unsere Gegner sie so gern.<br />

Und wir haben viele Feinde. Anders geht es nicht. Das stört natürlich<br />

bei der Verwirklichung unserer Ideen, aber dafür stärkt<br />

es uns im Kampf und schärft die Gedanken.<br />

Wir treten der künstlerischen Kinematographie entgegen, aber<br />

sie erweist sich uns hundertmal überlegen. Mit den Geld-Krümeln,<br />

die vom Tisch der künstlerischen Kinematographie fallen,<br />

aber manchmal auch gänzlich ohne Mittel, bauen wir unsere bescheidenen<br />

Filmchen zusammen.<br />

Der Kinoprawda wurden die Filmtheater verschlossen, aber sie<br />

konnte nicht aus dem öffentlichen Bewußtsein und aus dem Bewußtsein<br />

der unabhängigen Presse vertrieben werden. Die Kinoprawda<br />

erscheint unzweideutig als Wendepunkt in der Geschichte<br />

der russischen Kinematographie.<br />

Erfolg oder Mißerfolg dieses oder jenes unserer Filmwerke hat<br />

nur kommerzielle Bedeutung und ist nur wichtig für die Durchschlagskraft<br />

unserer Bestrebungen; einen Einfluß auf unsere<br />

Ideen werden sie nicht nehmen. Für uns sind unsere Filmarbeiten<br />

- ob sie nun gelungen sind oder nicht - gleich wertvoll, insofern<br />

sie die Idee des Kinoglaz weiterführen und insofern alle 100<br />

bis 200 Meter mißlungener Aufnahmen für die nächsten - gelungenen<br />

- 200 Meter eine Lehre sind.<br />

Die erste Serie von Kinoglaz ist deshalb von den Kinoki sehr<br />

richtig Kinoglaz tastet sich vorwärts genannt worden. Damit ist<br />

die Behutsamkeit der Filmkamera bei der Erkundung des Lebens<br />

gemeint, denn ihre Hauptaufgabe ist es nicht, sich im


40 D. Vertov<br />

Chaos des Lebens zu verlieren, sondern sich in der Umgebung<br />

zurechtzufinden, in die sie geraten ist.<br />

Die Aufgabe der folgenden Serien wird es sein, diese Erkundung<br />

des Lebens bis zu einem möglichen Maximum zu steigern<br />

und die Aufmerksamkeit ununterbrochen im technischen Sinne<br />

zu vertiefen.<br />

Alle Menschen sind in einem mehr oder weniger strengen Maße<br />

- Dichter, Maler, Musiker.<br />

Oder es gibt überhaupt keine Dichter, Maler oder Musiker.<br />

Schon der millionste Teil der Erfindungen, die jeder Mensch bei<br />

seiner alltäglichen Arbeit macht, schließt in sich bereits ein<br />

Element der Kunst ein, wenn es auch nicht mit diesem Namen<br />

belegt zu werden pflegt.<br />

Wir ziehen die trockene Chronik dem konstruierten Szenarium<br />

vor, wenn wir über die Lebensgewohnheiten und die Arbeit der<br />

Menschen berichten. Wir mischen uns niemals in das Leben ein.<br />

Wir nehmen Fakten auf, organisieren sie und bringen sie über<br />

die Filmleinwand in das Bewußtsein der Arbeitenden. Wir berücksichtigen,<br />

was die Welt erklärt, was uns klar macht, wie sie<br />

ist — das ist unsere Hauptaufgabe.<br />

Kinoglaz stellte sich die Aufgabe, den ausgedehnten Kampf mit<br />

der bürgerlichen Kinematographie aufzunehmen, und wir bezweifeln<br />

sehr, daß es in der Folgezeit möglich sein wird, — ungeachtet<br />

der neuen weltpolitischen Situation - unserem revolutionären<br />

Ansturm ernsthaften Widerstand entgegenzusetzen.<br />

Eine andere Gefahr. Die Gefahr der Entstellung unserer Ideen.<br />

Gefährliche Surrogate und Gegenströmungen, die wie Seifenblasen<br />

aufquellen, bis sie, wie Seifenblasen, platzen.<br />

Das ist die Aufgabe aller Arbeitenden — wachsam den einmal<br />

begonnenen Kampf fortzusetzen, sich immer von Betrug fernzuhalten<br />

und nie die süßlichen Kopien mit den harten Originalen<br />

zu verwechseln.<br />

Aus dem Reglement der Kinoki<br />

»Kinoglaz« 41<br />

Allgemeine Hinweise für alle Aufnahmen: die Kamera ist unsichtbar.<br />

1. Schnappschuß - alte Kriegsregel: Augenmaß, Geschwindigkeit,<br />

Abdrücken.<br />

2. Aufnahme von einem öffentlichen Beobachtungsposten aus,<br />

der von Kinok-Beobachtern vorbereitet wurde. Geduld, absolute<br />

Stille, im geeig<strong>net</strong>en Moment — sofortiger Angriff.<br />

3. Aufnahme vom verborgenen Beobachtungsposten aus. Geduld<br />

und absolute Aufmerksamkeit.<br />

4. Aufnahme ohne naturalistische Gesichtspunkte.<br />

5. Aufnahme ohne künstlerische Gesichtspunkte.<br />

6. Aufnahme auf Entfernung.<br />

7. Aufnahme von Bewegung.<br />

8. Aufnahme von oben.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!