22.01.2013 Views

A Critique of Pure (Genetic) Information

A Critique of Pure (Genetic) Information

A Critique of Pure (Genetic) Information

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

4 Chapter 1<br />

The Phylogenetic Turn and the History <strong>of</strong> Ontogeny<br />

Although continuous with one long-standing tradition, the rise <strong>of</strong> the<br />

gene concept marks a radical break with another. For over 2000 years,<br />

from Aristotle through the nineteenth century, the living organism within<br />

the confines <strong>of</strong> its own life span had been at the center <strong>of</strong> naturalistic<br />

understanding and explanation. I will refer to a radical shift <strong>of</strong> perspective,<br />

which begins neither with Darwin nor with Mendel (although the<br />

work <strong>of</strong> both are contributing factors) but very early in the twentieth<br />

century, as the “phylogenetic turn.” The intent <strong>of</strong> this phrase is to highlight<br />

the idea that as the gene and genetic program became understood<br />

to be the principal means by which adapted form is acquired, the theater<br />

<strong>of</strong> adaptation changed from that <strong>of</strong> individual life histories, that is,<br />

ontogenies, to that <strong>of</strong> populations over multiple generations, that is,<br />

phylogenies. As the genetic program moved to the explanatory center<br />

stage, the individual organism, with its own adaptive capacities, began<br />

to recede from view.<br />

To adequately clarify and critically consider current usage <strong>of</strong> the word<br />

the “gene” we must locate it, as well as the associated assumptions <strong>of</strong><br />

the phylogenetic turn in this larger context <strong>of</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> western<br />

efforts to reconcile the tension between the experiences <strong>of</strong> nature as<br />

simple physical matter and as organized life-forms. And to begin to<br />

do this we must start by exposing a shibboleth <strong>of</strong> recent philosophy <strong>of</strong><br />

biology. 1 The shibboleth I have in mind is one that evokes the menace <strong>of</strong><br />

creationism and insinuates that there have been only two basic organizing<br />

principles in the study <strong>of</strong> life: that <strong>of</strong> Darwinian evolution and that<br />

<strong>of</strong> creationism. Espousals <strong>of</strong> this sort continue to be ubiquitous in the<br />

philosophy <strong>of</strong> biological literature. A recent article concerned with the<br />

concepts <strong>of</strong> function and adaptation suggested that “originally, teleology<br />

was controversial because it was associated with pre-Darwinian<br />

creationist views about organisms” (Allen and Bek<strong>of</strong>f 1998). Now, in<br />

fact, the teleology <strong>of</strong> Aristotle as well as that <strong>of</strong> Immanuel Kant have<br />

both played extremely important roles in the history and advancement<br />

<strong>of</strong> our understanding <strong>of</strong> life, and dismissing them with the label “creationism”<br />

is not only misguided but also markedly misleading. It serves<br />

to create an arbitrary boundary beyond which many good neo-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!