29.01.2013 Views

Kant and the Power of Imagination (CUP 2007 - Additional Information

Kant and the Power of Imagination (CUP 2007 - Additional Information

Kant and the Power of Imagination (CUP 2007 - Additional Information

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

KANT AND THE POWER OF IMAGINATION<br />

In this book Jane Kneller focusses on <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> imagination as a<br />

creative power in <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> in his overall philosophical<br />

enterprise. She analyzes <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> relation between imaginative free play <strong>and</strong> human social <strong>and</strong><br />

moral development, showing various ways in which his aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>of</strong><br />

disinterested reflection explains moral interests. She situates <strong>the</strong>se<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory within <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> German<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> eighteenth century, arguing that his contribution is<br />

a bridge between early <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic moral education <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

early Romanticism <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> last decade <strong>of</strong> that century. In so doing,<br />

her book brings <strong>the</strong> two most important German philosophers <strong>of</strong><br />

Enlightenment <strong>and</strong> Romanticism, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Novalis, into dialog.<br />

The book will be <strong>of</strong> interest to a wide range <strong>of</strong> readers in both <strong>Kant</strong><br />

studies <strong>and</strong> German philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> eighteenth <strong>and</strong> nineteenth<br />

centuries.<br />

Jane Kneller is Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> Philosophy at Colorado State<br />

University. She is editor <strong>and</strong> translator <strong>of</strong> Novalis: Fichte Studies<br />

(2003) in <strong>the</strong> Cambridge Texts in <strong>the</strong> History <strong>of</strong> Philosophy series.


KANT AND THE POWER OF<br />

IMAGINATION<br />

JANE KNELLER<br />

Colorado State University


CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS<br />

Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo<br />

Cambridge University Press<br />

The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8RU, UK<br />

Published in <strong>the</strong> United States <strong>of</strong> America by Cambridge University Press, New York<br />

www.cambridge.org<br />

<strong>Information</strong> on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521851435<br />

© Jane Kneller <strong>2007</strong><br />

This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> provision <strong>of</strong><br />

relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction <strong>of</strong> any part may take place<br />

without <strong>the</strong> written permission <strong>of</strong> Cambridge University Press.<br />

First published in print format <strong>2007</strong><br />

ISBN-13 978-0-511-27455-8 eBook (MyiLibrary)<br />

ISBN-10 0-511-27455-6 eBook (MyiLibrary)<br />

ISBN-13 978-0-521-85143-5 hardback<br />

ISBN-10 0-521-85143-2 hardback<br />

Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for <strong>the</strong> persistence or accuracy <strong>of</strong> urls<br />

for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication, <strong>and</strong> does not<br />

guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.


Contents<br />

Preface <strong>and</strong> acknowledgments page vii<br />

Introduction 1<br />

1 <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism 20<br />

2 The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom 38<br />

3 The interests <strong>of</strong> disinterest 60<br />

4 Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical 72<br />

5 The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 95<br />

6 Imaginative reflections <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self in Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin 122<br />

7 Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism 139<br />

Bibliography 161<br />

Index 168<br />

v


Preface <strong>and</strong> acknowledgments<br />

This book contains work that has been in process for over fifteen years,<br />

<strong>and</strong> during that time I was greatly aided by <strong>the</strong> encouragement <strong>and</strong> advice<br />

<strong>of</strong> wonderful colleagues <strong>and</strong> students in many places: philosophers <strong>and</strong><br />

scholars too numerous to mention here, but some <strong>of</strong> whom will perhaps<br />

recognize <strong>the</strong>ir influence in parts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> book that follow. Let this serve as<br />

a gesture <strong>of</strong> my thanks <strong>and</strong> deep appreciation for <strong>the</strong>ir time <strong>and</strong><br />

thoughtful discussions. Three constellations <strong>of</strong> scholars deserve mention<br />

in connection with this book, all tied in one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r to <strong>the</strong><br />

National Endowment for <strong>the</strong> Humanities (NEH): The NEH Summer<br />

Seminar ‘‘What is Enlightenment?’’ conducted by James Schmidt at<br />

Boston University during <strong>the</strong> bicentenary <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> French Revolution, <strong>the</strong><br />

NEH Workshop ‘‘Figuring <strong>the</strong> Self ’’ conducted by David Klemm <strong>and</strong><br />

Günter Zöller at <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> Iowa over <strong>the</strong> Spring semester <strong>of</strong> 1992,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> NEH Summer Institute for College Teachers on ‘‘Nature, Art<br />

<strong>and</strong> Politics after <strong>Kant</strong>: Reevaluating Early German Idealism’’ directed by<br />

Karl Ameriks <strong>and</strong> myself at Colorado State University in 2001. The<br />

participants at <strong>the</strong>se NEH venues were truly inspired <strong>and</strong> inspiring, <strong>and</strong><br />

without <strong>the</strong>m much <strong>of</strong> this book would have remained unwritten, even<br />

unconceived.<br />

I owe a special debt <strong>of</strong> gratitude to <strong>the</strong> faculty at <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong><br />

Cincinnati’s Department <strong>of</strong> Germanic Languages <strong>and</strong> Literatures for <strong>the</strong><br />

very formative time I spent <strong>the</strong>re doing MA studies in German literature<br />

<strong>and</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tics. They were amazingly tolerant <strong>of</strong> an Ausländerin from<br />

Philosophy, a new PhD in <strong>Kant</strong>ian aes<strong>the</strong>tics who insisted on turning<br />

every term paper into ano<strong>the</strong>r philosophy essay. I want to thank especially<br />

Richard Schade for introducing me to <strong>the</strong> beauty <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> German<br />

Baroque, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> humor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> German Enlightenment, <strong>and</strong> for<br />

entrusting me with a stint on <strong>the</strong> Lessing Yearbook as assistant editor. I<br />

hope he has forgiven me for returning to <strong>the</strong> philosophical fold. The<br />

romanticism <strong>of</strong> this book was pr<strong>of</strong>oundly influenced by <strong>the</strong> instruction <strong>of</strong><br />

vii


viii<br />

Preface <strong>and</strong> acknowledgments<br />

Hans-Georg Richert <strong>and</strong> Helga Slessarev, <strong>and</strong> (since <strong>the</strong>y were not<br />

particularly fond <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>) I dedicate <strong>the</strong> Novalis sections <strong>of</strong> this work to<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir memory.<br />

Several <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> chapters in this book contain material published earlier.<br />

I would like to thank <strong>the</strong> following publishers for granting permission to<br />

reprint parts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> following: ‘‘Imaginative Freedom <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> German<br />

Enlightenment,’’ Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> History <strong>of</strong> Ideas, 51, 1990; Marquette<br />

University Press, for ‘‘The Interests <strong>of</strong> Disinterest,’’ from Proceedings <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Eighth International <strong>Kant</strong> Congress, ed. Hoke Robinson, Marquette<br />

University Press, ª 1995, Marquette University Press Reprinted with<br />

permission <strong>of</strong> Marquette University Press; ‘‘The Failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

<strong>Imagination</strong>,’’ in ‘‘What is Enlightenment?’’: Texts <strong>and</strong> Interpretations, ed.<br />

James Schmidt, The Regents <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> University <strong>of</strong> California, University<br />

<strong>of</strong> California Press, 1996 ª 1996, University <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1996;<br />

‘‘Romantic Conceptions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Self in Hölderlin <strong>and</strong> Novalis,’’ reprinted<br />

by permission from Figuring <strong>the</strong> Self: Subject, Individual, <strong>and</strong> Spirit in<br />

Classical German Philosophy, ed. by David E. Klemm <strong>and</strong> Günter Zöller,<br />

The State University <strong>of</strong> New York Press, ª 1997, State University <strong>of</strong> New<br />

York, all rights reserved; ‘‘Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Value <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Practical in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Philosophy,’’ Journal <strong>of</strong> Value Inquiry, 36, 2002 <strong>and</strong><br />

‘‘Novalis’ O<strong>the</strong>r Way Out,’’ in Philosophical Romanticism, ed. Nikolas<br />

Kompridis, Routledge, 2006.<br />

I owe a special debt <strong>of</strong> gratitude once again to Hilary Gaskin at<br />

Cambridge University Press for her ever-helpful advice <strong>and</strong> guidance<br />

throughout <strong>the</strong> publishing process, <strong>and</strong> to Jackie Warren for her able<br />

h<strong>and</strong>ling <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> final stages <strong>of</strong> production. Barbara Docherty’s keen eye<br />

for detail was absolutely invaluable in <strong>the</strong> copy-editing <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> book <strong>and</strong> I<br />

want to thank her in particular for <strong>the</strong> time <strong>and</strong> care she took with it.<br />

Finally, to <strong>the</strong> three philosophers closest to me – Michael, Miroslav,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Rosavera: thank you, respectively, for your healthy skepticism about<br />

claims to objectivity, your critical attitude towards all established<br />

doctrine, <strong>and</strong> your ability to make ordinary things magical. I hope I’ve<br />

captured some <strong>of</strong> that, at least in <strong>the</strong>ory, here.


Introduction<br />

This book situates <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory within <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> his overall<br />

philosophical enterprise <strong>and</strong> also within German aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

eighteenth century. Although <strong>the</strong> aim <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> book is not primarily historical,<br />

I have found it useful to frame <strong>the</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong><br />

imagination historically, by locating his views within a line <strong>of</strong> German<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>ticians from <strong>the</strong> early German Enlightenment through early German<br />

Romanticism. <strong>Kant</strong> is not <strong>of</strong>ten viewed as an advocate <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

didactic value <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tics nor as a precursor to early German Romanticism,<br />

but <strong>the</strong> chapters at <strong>the</strong> beginning <strong>and</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> book (chapters 1<br />

<strong>and</strong> 7) argue that <strong>the</strong>se are important aspects <strong>of</strong> his aes<strong>the</strong>tic project. In so<br />

doing <strong>the</strong>y situate <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory between rationalist aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

pedagogy <strong>and</strong> early German romantic aes<strong>the</strong>tics in a way that brings into<br />

relief certain commonalities <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se o<strong>the</strong>rwise very different <strong>the</strong>ories.<br />

Given a prevailing attitude that casts Romanticism as an irrationalist<br />

mysticism with sinister inheritors, connecting it to rationalist philosophies<br />

at all may sound implausible. This book aims to show that by<br />

focussing on certain important but neglected aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory, a window is opened on <strong>the</strong> common link between both perspectives<br />

in German aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> eighteenth century. That link<br />

is <strong>the</strong> recognition <strong>and</strong> gradual elevation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination.<br />

Rationalist aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> art criticism in Germany prior to <strong>Kant</strong> was<br />

principle-bound <strong>and</strong> rigid in many ways, so that Alfred Bauemler could<br />

say <strong>of</strong> Gottsched <strong>and</strong> Bodmer <strong>and</strong> Breitinger <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir circles that <strong>the</strong><br />

concept <strong>of</strong> criticism (Kritik), which Shaftesbury ‘‘h<strong>and</strong>les with a fine sense<br />

<strong>of</strong> humanity, becomes in Leipzig <strong>and</strong> Zurich an instrument <strong>of</strong> punishment<br />

for poetical sinners.’’ 1 Yet Enlightenment concern for education<br />

required a reconciliation, if not an overcoming, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> divide between <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘higher’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘lower’’ cognitive faculties <strong>of</strong> reason <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> sensation,<br />

1 Alfred Bauemler, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Kritik der Urteilskraft (Halle: Max Niemeyer Verlag, 1923), pp. 97–98.<br />

1


2<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

perception, <strong>and</strong> inner feeling. The role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination gradually took<br />

on great significance as a mental power that interfaces with <strong>the</strong>se aspects<br />

<strong>of</strong> human experience. 2 Thus we find <strong>the</strong> imagination playing an especially<br />

crucial role in <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> cognition, <strong>and</strong> that role in turn being<br />

adapted <strong>and</strong> incorporated into his <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> beauty. Dieter Henrich<br />

points out that, since <strong>Kant</strong> regularly taught Baumgarten’s Metaphysics<br />

text, <strong>and</strong> in his Anthropology course worked directly from <strong>the</strong> section <strong>of</strong><br />

that text that dealt with empirical psychology, including <strong>the</strong> doctrine <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> lower cognitive faculties including <strong>the</strong> imagination: ‘‘Therefore it is<br />

no surprise that <strong>Kant</strong> had developed his own aes<strong>the</strong>tics before he came to<br />

terms with <strong>the</strong> problems he intended to solve in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure<br />

Reason.’’ 3 Although for a time after writing <strong>the</strong> first Critique, <strong>Kant</strong> denied<br />

<strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> a critique <strong>of</strong> taste – i.e. a critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong><br />

imagination in judgments about beauty – he changed his mind once he<br />

realized that he could provide an account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> universal elements <strong>of</strong><br />

such judgments, specifically <strong>the</strong> generic relation <strong>of</strong> harmonious play<br />

between <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing, without appeal<br />

to determinate empirical or a priori rules. Henrich argues for a certain<br />

continuity in <strong>Kant</strong>’s view <strong>of</strong> imagination between his pre-critical <strong>and</strong> final<br />

critical view that taste could claim justification a priori:<br />

When he rethought <strong>the</strong> epistemology <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason he quickly<br />

saw that his epistemological <strong>the</strong>orems about <strong>the</strong> relationship between imagination<br />

<strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing would allow him to produce an explanation <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

judgment whose sources would not be empirical throughout but ra<strong>the</strong>r derived<br />

from <strong>the</strong> explanation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> our knowledge <strong>of</strong> objects. Hence <strong>the</strong><br />

new explanation would have <strong>the</strong> ‘‘a priori’’ status <strong>of</strong> a transcendental insight. We<br />

can now underst<strong>and</strong> why <strong>Kant</strong> felt he could carry out his plan, once conceived,<br />

with little trouble. Most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> content <strong>of</strong> his aes<strong>the</strong>tics had been available to him<br />

for a long time. Its views <strong>and</strong> its conceptual apparatus <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cognitive activities<br />

had only to be transferred to a new context. 4<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> did not invent or change rationalist notions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> faculties involved<br />

so much as make <strong>the</strong>m more precise, Henrich argues. Thus in <strong>the</strong><br />

2<br />

This becomes apparent in Baumgarten’s attempt to discover a special ‘‘logic’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> lower cognitive<br />

faculty, which included imagination. Bauemler points out that Wolff already prepared <strong>the</strong> way for<br />

this move in his discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘expectation <strong>of</strong> similar cases’’ (‘‘Erwartung ähnlicher Fälle’’) asa<br />

function <strong>of</strong> inference (induction) based in <strong>the</strong> lower cognitive faculties. Ibid., pp. 188–197. See also<br />

Bauemler’s Das Irrationalitätsproblem im äs<strong>the</strong>tischen Denken des 18. Jahrhunderts (Halle, 1923;<br />

republished Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1967) for an account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ascendency<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination in this period.<br />

3<br />

Henrich, Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Moral Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> World (Stanford: Stanford University Press,<br />

1992), p. 33.<br />

4<br />

Ibid., pp. 34–35.


Introduction 3<br />

first Critique <strong>Kant</strong> carefully delineates <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> operation <strong>of</strong><br />

imagination in cognition: it operates subconsciously, at least in part, <strong>and</strong><br />

is <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> all combinations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sensible manifold, but not <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

rules that prescribe its combinatorial activity. 5<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory in its final form still utilizes <strong>the</strong> apparatus <strong>of</strong><br />

rationalist psychology, but in a more articulated way. One can also add to<br />

Henrich’s point, however, that this refinement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong><br />

psychology had dramatic consequences for German aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory:<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s new articulation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> functions <strong>of</strong> imagination undermined <strong>the</strong><br />

hierarchical structuring <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> older rationalist approaches. In <strong>the</strong> third<br />

Critique <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>the</strong>orizes a new sort <strong>of</strong> relationship between imagination<br />

<strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing, one in which <strong>the</strong> former is ‘‘freed’’ from <strong>the</strong> latter –<br />

in o<strong>the</strong>r words, in which <strong>the</strong> imagination is seen as capable <strong>of</strong> operating<br />

independently <strong>of</strong> its function <strong>of</strong> processing <strong>the</strong> material <strong>of</strong> sensation into<br />

<strong>the</strong> products <strong>of</strong> experience via concepts a priori. It does not follow that<br />

imaginative freedom in this sense operates free <strong>of</strong> experiential backdrop,<br />

but simply that within <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> an already syn<strong>the</strong>sized experience,<br />

imagination can function in a different capacity so as to reflect upon a<br />

sensory manifold without ‘‘determining’’ an object. The result is, instead,<br />

a certain kind <strong>of</strong> feeling. 6 One important result <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s more complex<br />

account <strong>of</strong> imaginative functioning is a new appreciation for <strong>the</strong> way in<br />

which imaginative freedom contributes to an overall awareness in us, as<br />

individual subjects, <strong>of</strong> our own cognitive (including moral) operations.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory, that is, highlights <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

produces a ‘‘feeling <strong>of</strong> life,’’ making us aware <strong>of</strong> ourselves via pleasure that<br />

‘‘forms <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> a very special power <strong>of</strong> discriminating <strong>and</strong> judging’’(V:<br />

204, 277). This complex notion <strong>of</strong> imagination’s functioning is<br />

<strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> reflective aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment, <strong>and</strong> takes as its object (which<br />

is to say, it determines a priori) <strong>the</strong> feeling <strong>of</strong> pleasure <strong>and</strong> pain (XX: 208).<br />

5 Ibid., p. 37.<br />

6 An important issue emerges here involving <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cognitive role <strong>of</strong> reflection. Henrich,<br />

on historical grounds, distinguishes reflection from reflective judgment. The former is a<br />

‘‘primitive’’ capacity <strong>of</strong> unconscious ideation, that concurs with <strong>the</strong> operations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind,<br />

keeping <strong>the</strong>m distinct, <strong>and</strong> allowing an ‘‘awareness’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> operations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind. This process is<br />

discussed in <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> genius <strong>and</strong> fantasy in chapter 7 <strong>of</strong> this volume, but <strong>the</strong> overall role <strong>of</strong><br />

such processes <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir relationship to cognitive <strong>and</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgments must be postponed here.<br />

Important work on <strong>the</strong> prior function <strong>of</strong> reflection has been done by Beatrice Longueness, in <strong>Kant</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Capacity to Judge: Sensibility <strong>and</strong> Discursivity in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason, trans. Charles<br />

T. Wolfe (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998). See also Henry Allison’s discussion <strong>of</strong><br />

Longueness’ views on reflection with respect to reflective judgment, in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Taste<br />

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), chapter 1 , pp. 14ff.


4<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

As such, <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination takes on a central role in <strong>the</strong> mediation<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical a priori (XX: 206–208).<br />

Giving <strong>the</strong> imagination a lead role is not to say it is <strong>the</strong> only star <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

human show, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> never contended that it was. But it certainly<br />

opens <strong>the</strong> way for a philosophical turn towards viewing imagination as<br />

<strong>the</strong> main player on <strong>the</strong> human mental stage. This is <strong>the</strong> connection to<br />

Romanticism that <strong>Kant</strong>’s refinement <strong>of</strong> rationalist faculty psychology<br />

makes possible. The early Romantic <strong>the</strong>orists in Germany took <strong>the</strong><br />

complex imaginative function as <strong>the</strong>ir central explanatory concept in<br />

analyzing human subjectivity. Charles Larmore, in The Romantic Legacy,<br />

suggests that <strong>Kant</strong>’s primary influence on Romanticism was <strong>the</strong> view that<br />

<strong>the</strong> mind actively determines human experience. Yet it was not simply<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s ‘‘Copernican’’ insight that had such an influence on Romanticism.<br />

Romanticism also took its cue more specifically from <strong>Kant</strong>’s recognition<br />

<strong>of</strong> a special mental activity that (somehow) connects with <strong>the</strong> ‘‘matter <strong>of</strong><br />

sensation’’ (<strong>the</strong> given), <strong>and</strong> is itself nei<strong>the</strong>r pure underst<strong>and</strong>ing nor pure<br />

practical reason. Charles Larmore points out that, for <strong>the</strong> Romantics,<br />

imagination came to mean more than a faculty <strong>of</strong> imaging <strong>and</strong> association,<br />

but was centrally ‘‘<strong>the</strong> enrichment <strong>of</strong> experience through expression.’’<br />

But this formulation also nicely captures <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

imaginative ‘‘free play’’ in reflective aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment resulting in a<br />

special, ‘‘disinterested’’ pleasure that is universally communicable <strong>and</strong><br />

expressed in judgments <strong>of</strong> taste <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> sublime. Larmore goes on to<br />

point out that ‘‘Typically <strong>the</strong> Romantics considered <strong>the</strong> imagination, so<br />

understood, not as one mental faculty among o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>and</strong> certainly not as<br />

a mere organ <strong>of</strong> make-believe, but ra<strong>the</strong>r as <strong>the</strong> very essence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind.’’<br />

The arguments <strong>of</strong> this book make <strong>the</strong> case that <strong>the</strong> move from <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

third Critique account <strong>of</strong> imagination as a central, mediating faculty to<br />

<strong>the</strong> early Romantic view <strong>of</strong> it as <strong>the</strong> primary faculty is a logical next step,<br />

not an irrational leap, in <strong>the</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> human subjectivity.<br />

In her account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> Darstellung (literally: a ‘‘placing<br />

before,’’ usually translated as ‘‘representation’’ or ‘‘presentation’’) Martha<br />

Helfer sketches <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> this notion in <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy as ‘‘a<br />

technical term that designates <strong>the</strong> mediation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination between<br />

sensibility <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing.’’ She argues that this <strong>Kant</strong>ian notion <strong>of</strong><br />

imaginative mediation is <strong>of</strong> great significance to subsequent philosophical<br />

<strong>and</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic thought:<br />

Thus Darstellung constitutes an essential point <strong>of</strong> tangency for German Idealism<br />

<strong>and</strong> Romanticism, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> critical exposition <strong>of</strong> this <strong>Kant</strong>ian notion <strong>of</strong> representation<br />

in various disciplines results in a tremendously productive interplay <strong>of</strong>


Introduction 5<br />

philosophy, aes<strong>the</strong>tics, literature <strong>and</strong> linguistic <strong>the</strong>ory in German critical<br />

discourse around 1800. 7<br />

Helfer argues that <strong>Kant</strong>’s notion <strong>of</strong> Darstellung creates problems for him<br />

in three related ways, <strong>the</strong> first <strong>of</strong> which is <strong>the</strong> heart <strong>of</strong> his problem, <strong>and</strong><br />

results from <strong>the</strong> fact that imaginative syn<strong>the</strong>sis in cognition for <strong>Kant</strong> is ‘‘a<br />

hidden art in <strong>the</strong> depths <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human soul’’:<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is a breakdown at a crucial juncture in <strong>Kant</strong>’s argument for <strong>the</strong> underlying<br />

syn<strong>the</strong>tic unity <strong>of</strong> intuition <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing in cognition ... Because <strong>the</strong><br />

syn<strong>the</strong>tic unity <strong>of</strong> apperception falls beyond <strong>the</strong> limits <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> transcendental<br />

Critique, <strong>the</strong> sensible subject cannot represent itself to itself as it really is, as a<br />

moral subject <strong>of</strong> reason. The fact that reason imposes <strong>the</strong>se limits on <strong>the</strong> scope <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophical investigation points to <strong>the</strong> third problem that <strong>Kant</strong> encounters, <strong>the</strong><br />

problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rhetorical presentation or representation <strong>of</strong> his philosophical<br />

system. 8<br />

I shall explore <strong>the</strong> degree to which <strong>Kant</strong> himself saw <strong>the</strong>se aspects <strong>of</strong> his<br />

account <strong>of</strong> imaginative mediation, or reflection as ‘‘breakdowns’’ in his<br />

system in chapter 5. Helfer is quite right to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s notion <strong>of</strong><br />

(re)presentation as imaginative mediation, but it is not clear that <strong>Kant</strong><br />

was concerned to give an account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underlying source or foundation<br />

<strong>of</strong> this faculty, nor that he felt it necessary to provide a unified <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong><br />

subjectivity in a strong sense. If imaginative reflection, as I argue in<br />

chapter 4, is to be seen as performing <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> mediation in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong><br />

providing an interface or bridge between sensibility <strong>and</strong> reason such that<br />

human beings can move from one aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir selves to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, it<br />

may not necessarily be <strong>the</strong> case that in <strong>Kant</strong>’s mind, at least, <strong>the</strong>se aporiae<br />

are so thoroughly problematic as <strong>the</strong> Romantics <strong>the</strong>mselves came to<br />

believe. Lacoue-Labar<strong>the</strong> <strong>and</strong> Nancy, as well as Andrew Bowie <strong>and</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs who see <strong>Kant</strong> as a catalyst for Romanticism, also tend to emphasize<br />

<strong>the</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> a thoroughgoing account <strong>of</strong> unity between subject <strong>and</strong> object,<br />

moral dem<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> natural laws, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical as<br />

<strong>the</strong> jumping <strong>of</strong>f point for Romantic philosophy. Thus Bowie, like Helfer,<br />

argues that <strong>Kant</strong> left a major problem for his own <strong>the</strong>ory unsolved<br />

thanks to his inability to give an account <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> freedom<br />

while simultaneously dem<strong>and</strong>ing that we must act in accordance with a<br />

belief in it: ‘‘In both <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical parts <strong>of</strong> his philosophy,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n, <strong>Kant</strong> leaves a gaping hole where <strong>the</strong> highest principle is<br />

7 Martha Helfer, The Retreat <strong>of</strong> Representation: The Concept <strong>of</strong> Darstellung in German Critical<br />

Discourse (Albany: State University <strong>of</strong> New York Press, 1996), p. 10<br />

8 Ibid., p. 11.


6<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

located.’’ 9 Lacoue-Labar<strong>the</strong> <strong>and</strong> Nancy explain <strong>the</strong> Romantic debt to<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>, along similar lines, as <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> what <strong>the</strong>y refer to as <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘weakening <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject’’ as a result <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s denying <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

an ‘‘original Intuition’’ – i.e., an intuition that produces its own ‘‘given’’:<br />

As a result, all that remains <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject is <strong>the</strong> ‘‘I’’ as an ‘‘empty form’’ ... that<br />

‘‘accompanies my representations.’’ This is so because <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> time, which is<br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘‘form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> internal sense’’ permits no substantial presentation. As is well<br />

known, <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian ‘‘cogito’’ is empty. 10<br />

Lacoue-Labar<strong>the</strong> <strong>and</strong> Nancy view <strong>Kant</strong>’s valorizing <strong>of</strong> morality as a sort<br />

<strong>of</strong> compensation for <strong>the</strong> weakened cognitive subject, but here again <strong>the</strong><br />

problem becomes one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> reality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject: ‘‘As a moral subject, in<br />

sum, <strong>the</strong> subject recovers none <strong>of</strong> its substance. Quite to <strong>the</strong> contrary, <strong>the</strong><br />

question <strong>of</strong> its unity, <strong>and</strong> thus <strong>of</strong> its very ‘being-subject’, is brought to a<br />

pitch <strong>of</strong> high tension.’’ This tension is also referred to more dramatically<br />

by <strong>the</strong>m as <strong>the</strong> ‘‘crisis’’ that Romanticism takes as its starting point. 11<br />

All <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se scholars are surely right to point to precisely <strong>the</strong>se issues as<br />

catalysts to Romanticism, <strong>and</strong> yet by dramatizing <strong>the</strong> problem as a<br />

‘‘gaping hole’’ or ‘‘crisis,’’ <strong>the</strong>y tend to downplay <strong>the</strong> degree to which <strong>the</strong><br />

younger generation <strong>of</strong> poetic philosophers adapted <strong>and</strong> developed some<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s best attempts to solve <strong>the</strong>se very problems. Lacoue-Labar<strong>the</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

Nancy grant <strong>the</strong> point that <strong>Kant</strong> did try to solve <strong>the</strong> problem in <strong>the</strong> third<br />

Critique, but <strong>the</strong>y view that solution as failed, thanks to <strong>the</strong> merely<br />

regulative nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> principles <strong>Kant</strong> relies on in his attempt to unify<br />

subjectivity. Yet in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> Novalis, at least, <strong>the</strong> regulative nature <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophy was precisely all that philosophy could be <strong>and</strong>, for him, this<br />

was not in itself a problem. Helfer herself, commenting on <strong>the</strong> fact that<br />

Novalis sees philosophy resolved in ‘‘poesy,’’ points out that ‘‘Poesy,<br />

however, does not supplant philosophy in Novalis aes<strong>the</strong>tic program:<br />

‘‘Without philosophy <strong>the</strong> poet is incomplete ... (II: 531, #29).’’ 12 An<br />

important aim <strong>of</strong> this book is to show that <strong>Kant</strong>’s own solutions went a<br />

long way in <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> Novalis’ <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> early Romantics’ views:<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory enabled entertaining <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> creative, reflective<br />

imagination in general as a possible source for <strong>the</strong> realization <strong>of</strong><br />

substantive changes in <strong>the</strong> world.<br />

9<br />

Andrew Bowie, Aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> Subjectivity: From <strong>Kant</strong> to Nietzsche (Manchester: Manchester<br />

University Press, 1990), p. 22.<br />

10<br />

Philippe Lacoue-Labar<strong>the</strong> <strong>and</strong> Jean-Luc Nancy, trans. Philip Barnard <strong>and</strong> Cheryl Lester, The<br />

Literary Absolute: The Theory <strong>of</strong> Literature in German Romanticism (Albany: State University <strong>of</strong><br />

New York Press, 1988), p. 30.<br />

11 12<br />

Ibid., pp. 31–32. Helfer, The Retreat <strong>of</strong> Representation, p.88.


Introduction 7<br />

Making that case requires not only a careful look at <strong>Kant</strong>’s views on <strong>the</strong><br />

power <strong>of</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> its roles beyond judgments <strong>of</strong> taste, but also a<br />

less one-sided view <strong>of</strong> Romanticism. Much <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> argument <strong>of</strong> this book<br />

hinges on viewing early German Romanticism as a philosophical position –<br />

<strong>and</strong>, moreover, one that is close enough in spirit to <strong>the</strong> anti-speculative<br />

position <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ianism to be able to easily connect with it. Recent work<br />

has established this view on solid scholarly ground. Philosophers <strong>and</strong><br />

literary critical <strong>the</strong>orists have gone a long way toward correcting <strong>the</strong> caricature<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> early German Romantics as mystical irrationalists, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

case has been made for some time now that philosophically <strong>the</strong> early <strong>and</strong><br />

late period <strong>of</strong> Romanticism in <strong>the</strong> German tradition are quite distinct. 13<br />

At <strong>the</strong> same time <strong>the</strong>re has been a flowering <strong>of</strong> new studies in <strong>the</strong> past<br />

twenty-five years or so dealing with <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy in a multitude <strong>of</strong><br />

ways that go beyond <strong>the</strong> first Critique <strong>and</strong> his moral <strong>the</strong>ory as famously, if<br />

also misleadingly at times, summarized in <strong>the</strong> Groundwork <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Metaphysics<br />

<strong>of</strong> Morals. 14 <strong>Kant</strong>’s political <strong>the</strong>ory, his social <strong>and</strong> anthropological<br />

13 The most influential work in this regard is Manfred Frank’s Einführung in die Frühromantische<br />

Äs<strong>the</strong>tik (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1989), trans. Elizabeth Millán-Zaibert as The<br />

Foundations <strong>of</strong> Early German Romanticism (Albany: SUNY Press, 2004). See also Karl Ameriks’<br />

introduction to The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism (Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 2000), p. 13: ‘‘The greatest problem for <strong>the</strong> philosophical appreciation <strong>of</strong><br />

German Romanticism may be simply <strong>the</strong> word romanticism itself.’’ Part III on ‘‘Idealism <strong>and</strong><br />

romanticism’’ is a very useful summary introduction to <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Frühromantik.’’ Several newly<br />

translated texts <strong>of</strong> philosophical writings <strong>of</strong> early German Romanticism have appeared, including<br />

my own Novalis: Fichte Studies (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003) <strong>and</strong> an English<br />

edition <strong>of</strong> Novalis’ Allgemeine Brouillon, ed. David Wood, is forthcoming from SUNY Press<br />

(<strong>2007</strong>). Jay Bernstein’s edition <strong>of</strong> Classic <strong>and</strong> Romantic German Aes<strong>the</strong>tics (Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press, 2003) includes selections from earlier German <strong>the</strong>orists <strong>of</strong> art<br />

(Lessing, Moritz) <strong>and</strong> devotes large sections to works from Hölderlin <strong>and</strong> Novalis as well as<br />

Schiller <strong>and</strong> Friedrich Schlegel. Frederick Beiser’s edition <strong>of</strong> works from this tradition, The Early<br />

Political Writings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> German Romantics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), as<br />

well as his important contribution to <strong>the</strong> politico-philosophical history <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> era in<br />

Enlightenment, Revolution <strong>and</strong> Romanticism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992)<br />

bear witness to a growing philosophical interest in <strong>the</strong> early German Romantics. At <strong>the</strong> same<br />

time, literary philosophical interest in <strong>the</strong>se thinkers is growing, with works like Azade Seyhan’s<br />

Representation <strong>and</strong> Its Discontents: The Critical Legacy <strong>of</strong> German Romanticism (Berkeley:<br />

University <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1992) <strong>and</strong> Andrew Bowie’s From Romanticism to Critical Theory:<br />

The Philosophy <strong>of</strong> German Literary Theory (London: Routledge, 1997) being two fine studies in<br />

this area.<br />

14 Enormous recent interest in <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tics is reflected in new translations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third Critique,<br />

(including even a new translation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> title <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> book itself) <strong>and</strong> several major new Englishlanguage<br />

interpretive works on <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment that pay equal attention to <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory (John Zammito’s The Genesis <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, Chicago: University <strong>of</strong><br />

Chicago Press, 1992, is a fine example). English-language studies <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory tend to<br />

focus primarily on <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> taste in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment,’’ <strong>the</strong> first half <strong>of</strong><br />

his Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment. Paul Guyer’s l<strong>and</strong>mark earlier treatment, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Claims <strong>of</strong> Taste<br />

(Harvard University Press, 1979) along with o<strong>the</strong>r, less comprehensive accounts, were typical in<br />

this regard. More recent work has paid attention to <strong>the</strong> connection <strong>of</strong> morality <strong>and</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tics,


8<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

studies, his <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> history, <strong>and</strong> his overall methodological approach<br />

have been <strong>the</strong> subjects <strong>of</strong> interesting <strong>and</strong> close textual analytic research in<br />

several languages <strong>and</strong> scholarly traditions. 15 Focus on <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophically<br />

‘‘lesser’’ works that were never<strong>the</strong>less written during <strong>the</strong> critical<br />

period has proved enormously helpful in filling in gaps, accounting for<br />

inconsistencies; <strong>and</strong>, perhaps most important, <strong>the</strong> new focus has in many<br />

cases corrected common caricatures by disclosing <strong>the</strong> complexity <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ories. Allen Wood has perhaps gone as far as any scholar in this<br />

regard. 16 Focussing especially on <strong>Kant</strong>’s writings on religion <strong>and</strong> history,<br />

he has been able to counter many st<strong>and</strong>ard criticisms <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> by showing<br />

<strong>the</strong> compatibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s moral <strong>the</strong>ory with naturalist <strong>and</strong> materialist<br />

accounts <strong>of</strong> human development, progress, <strong>and</strong> culture. By carefully<br />

explicating <strong>the</strong> details <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s teleological conception <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong><br />

humanity, <strong>and</strong> by reconstructing <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> coordination <strong>of</strong><br />

‘‘ends <strong>of</strong> nature’’ with human rational ends in promoting culture, Wood<br />

debunks criticisms <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s moral <strong>the</strong>ory that see it as oriented towards a<br />

noumenal realm outside nature, individualistic in its prescriptions, <strong>and</strong><br />

insensitive to material human conditions in its rigorism. A complete<br />

summary <strong>of</strong> Wood’s comprehensive account is beyond <strong>the</strong> scope <strong>of</strong> this<br />

introduction, but in skeletal outline, <strong>the</strong> argument hinges on natural<br />

mechanism as <strong>the</strong> initial catalyst <strong>of</strong> human cultural development. <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

especially Guyer’s <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Experience <strong>of</strong> Freedom: Essays on Aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> Morality<br />

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993). Henry Allison’s <strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Taste (see n. 6)<br />

devotes a section to <strong>the</strong> link between morality <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> taste in <strong>Kant</strong>. Hannah Ginsborg’s<br />

The Role <strong>of</strong> Taste in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Cognition (New York: Garl<strong>and</strong> Press, 1990) looks at <strong>the</strong><br />

connection between aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> knowledge, as does Christel Fricke’s <strong>Kant</strong>s Theorie des reinen<br />

Geschmacksurteils (<strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Pure Judgment <strong>of</strong> Taste, Berlin: de Gruyter, 1990).<br />

15 John Zammito’s excellent book on <strong>the</strong> genesis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third Critique (see n. 14) links it to his<br />

Anthropology as well as to <strong>the</strong> younger generation <strong>of</strong> ‘‘aes<strong>the</strong>tic idealists.’’ English-language works<br />

dealing with <strong>Kant</strong>’s political writings <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir connection to issues <strong>of</strong> teleology include Patrick<br />

Riley, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Political Philosophy (Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield, 1983), Yirmiahu Yovel, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Philosophy <strong>of</strong> History (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980), <strong>and</strong> Thomas Auxter,<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s Moral Teleology (Macon, GA: Mercer University Press, 1982). Important studies on <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

anthropological writings include work, in addition to Allen Wood, by Holly Wilson, Robert B.<br />

Louden, Patrick R. Frierson, among o<strong>the</strong>rs. Representative samples <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir work is<br />

included in B. Jacobs <strong>and</strong> P. Kain, Essays in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Anthropology (Cambridge: Cambridge Unversity<br />

Press, 2003). John Zammito traces <strong>the</strong> historical development <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

conflicting views <strong>of</strong> Herder <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>, in <strong>Kant</strong>, Herder <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Birth <strong>of</strong> Anthropology (Chicago:<br />

University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 2002). Reinhard Br<strong>and</strong>t <strong>and</strong> Werner Stark have both published<br />

important work on <strong>Kant</strong>’s Anthropology <strong>and</strong> have been largely responsible for <strong>the</strong> rise <strong>of</strong> interest in<br />

this area thanks to <strong>the</strong>ir painstaking work in compiling <strong>and</strong> editing, at <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> Archiv at <strong>the</strong><br />

Philips-Universität, Marburg, <strong>the</strong> lecture notes <strong>of</strong> students in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Anthropology classes. Hannah<br />

Arendt’s Lectures on <strong>Kant</strong>’s Political Philosophy is one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most well-known attempts to link<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory to political <strong>the</strong>ory (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1982).<br />

16 See his <strong>Kant</strong>’s Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).


Introduction 9<br />

well-known notion <strong>of</strong> ‘‘unsocial sociability’’ captures <strong>the</strong> drive <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

species towards greater <strong>and</strong> greater freedom, equality <strong>and</strong> community<br />

arising out <strong>of</strong> natural self-interested inclinations <strong>and</strong> resulting social<br />

struggle. Human social progress is to be interpreted (regulatively) as a<br />

purpose <strong>of</strong> nature: ‘‘Nature’s own purposes require that human beings<br />

should emerge at a certain point from <strong>the</strong> tutelage <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> begin to<br />

set rational collective ends’’ (p. 298). Wood gives a compelling account <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> connection <strong>Kant</strong> sees between nature <strong>and</strong> human reason in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ir ends:<br />

Because human beings are <strong>the</strong> only beings in nature that can set a final end, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

may be considered as <strong>the</strong> ultimate end <strong>of</strong> nature ins<strong>of</strong>ar as <strong>the</strong>y do set a final end.<br />

Nature has no ultimate end except through human beings; or, what comes to <strong>the</strong><br />

same thing, it has no ultimate end at all until human beings give it one by setting a<br />

final end . . . <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy <strong>of</strong> history can be regarded as a <strong>the</strong>odicy or <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

<strong>of</strong> divine providence, as he himself also regularly regards it. But if so, it is a<br />

highly novel <strong>and</strong> perhaps unorthodox one. For in <strong>Kant</strong>’s view, <strong>the</strong> plan <strong>of</strong><br />

providence remains incomplete until we human beings complete it. (p. 311).<br />

The problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> institution <strong>of</strong> a just social order – <strong>the</strong> ‘‘highest good’’<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong> says is a direct comm<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> morality – involves <strong>the</strong> impossiblesounding<br />

dem<strong>and</strong> that we ourselves coordinate natural ends with moral<br />

ones, so that, simply put, moral goodness <strong>and</strong> happiness are systematically<br />

proportional. Wood points out that this dem<strong>and</strong> for systematic proportionality<br />

<strong>of</strong> natural <strong>and</strong> rational ends is not just a baroque, ‘‘architectonic’’<br />

feature <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory, but is fundamental to his ethics. <strong>Kant</strong><br />

insists that <strong>the</strong> moral law comm<strong>and</strong>s that humans in concert, as a species,<br />

attempt to create this system as <strong>the</strong> only means <strong>of</strong> guaranteeing systematic<br />

progress towards morality. Drawing on <strong>the</strong> Religion within <strong>the</strong> Limits <strong>of</strong><br />

Reason Alone, Wood argues that for <strong>Kant</strong> ‘‘The pursuit <strong>of</strong> my own<br />

morality can be distinguished from <strong>the</strong> moral progress <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human race,<br />

but [<strong>Kant</strong> argues that] <strong>the</strong> two ends are necessarily linked in <strong>the</strong>ir pursuit.<br />

Human beings must join in free community to accomplish <strong>the</strong> task.’’ And<br />

he adds, ‘‘The moral progress <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human race, in <strong>Kant</strong>’s view is<br />

possible only through <strong>the</strong> progressive extension <strong>of</strong> such a free moral<br />

community to more <strong>and</strong> more people, until it eventually encompasses <strong>the</strong><br />

entire human race’’ (p. 315). The problem with this dem<strong>and</strong> is that it asks<br />

<strong>the</strong> individual to commit to a project only <strong>the</strong> species as a whole can<br />

fulfill. This leads, in <strong>Kant</strong>’s moral <strong>the</strong>ory (V: 114ff.) to <strong>the</strong> (in)famous<br />

postulates <strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> immortality, belief in which is a necessary condition<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rational hope each individual requires to shoulder his or her<br />

part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> burden <strong>of</strong> this enormous comm<strong>and</strong>. This issue is examined


10<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

in more detail in chapter 2, but here I will simply point out that Wood<br />

explains <strong>Kant</strong>’s appeal to <strong>the</strong> postulates <strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> immortality as ways<br />

<strong>of</strong> turning, not to <strong>the</strong> ‘‘beyond’’ for hope, but to an enlightened human<br />

community <strong>of</strong> free believers that is not associated with <strong>the</strong> coercion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

state.<br />

Wood rightly points out that <strong>the</strong> community <strong>of</strong> rational faith that<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> envisioned is so far removed from <strong>the</strong> social reality <strong>of</strong> our own time<br />

that it is nearly impossible to see how one could take heart <strong>and</strong> carry on<br />

social reform in any ‘‘really existing’’ religious community. Wood pleads<br />

for historical underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s case: In an era <strong>of</strong> guarded<br />

Enlightenment optimism, <strong>Kant</strong> had reason to hope for <strong>the</strong> formation <strong>of</strong> a<br />

freely affirmed, rational religious community. Interpreting <strong>Kant</strong> in this<br />

way might suggest a kind <strong>of</strong> socialist ideal, <strong>and</strong> such a suggestion is not<br />

<strong>of</strong>f target, Wood argues, if it does not expect cataclysmic change:<br />

such a view would be <strong>Kant</strong>ian in holding that if we are to fulfill our collective<br />

historical vocation, we will need to find (or invent) a form <strong>of</strong> ethical community<br />

that is capable <strong>of</strong> gradually reshaping our deeply corrupt social life by revolutionizing<br />

<strong>and</strong> uniting <strong>the</strong> hearts <strong>of</strong> individuals through <strong>the</strong> free power <strong>of</strong> reason.<br />

For <strong>Kant</strong> himself, however, <strong>the</strong> human race can no more expect to fulfill this<br />

moral vocation apart from organized religion than it can expect to achieve justice<br />

through anarchy. (p. 320)<br />

What Wood’s account shows, I believe, is how problematic <strong>the</strong> religious<br />

‘‘postulate’’ has become, <strong>and</strong> thus how unlikely it is for people to b<strong>and</strong><br />

toge<strong>the</strong>r in heart <strong>and</strong> mind to effect change in contemporary societies. If<br />

religion, even a ‘‘socialist’’ version, is <strong>the</strong> only alternative community, <strong>and</strong><br />

a rational public can no longer envision belonging to it, <strong>the</strong>n a new vision<br />

must be possible or moral progress is doomed. But if it is <strong>the</strong> case that we<br />

cannot hope for apocalyptic change, is it not equally impossible, after<br />

decades <strong>and</strong> centuries <strong>of</strong> possibilities closed <strong>and</strong> social reforms laid waste,<br />

rationally to hold on to hope for gradual change in <strong>the</strong> long term? I want<br />

to propose, in <strong>the</strong> chapters that follow, that <strong>Kant</strong>’s natural teleology<br />

provides a ‘‘fallback’’ option when moral vision becomes clouded. The<br />

contingently available experience <strong>of</strong> beauty <strong>and</strong> its attendant interests,<br />

produced via a creative imagination, might also make it possible for<br />

despairing individuals to join with o<strong>the</strong>rs in communities aimed at<br />

change. If no model is available at a given point in time, it is at least<br />

possible to model a new community in imagination, <strong>and</strong> like artists <strong>of</strong><br />

any medium, to find ways to ‘express’ this community in concrete<br />

experience. That it seems to me, is <strong>the</strong> moral promise <strong>of</strong> imaginative<br />

freedom, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> real power <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination in <strong>Kant</strong>.


Introduction 11<br />

Turning to <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory is a useful <strong>and</strong> interesting way to<br />

solve some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> difficulties his moral <strong>the</strong>ory generates for social progress<br />

<strong>the</strong>ories. Interest in <strong>the</strong> relevance <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory to <strong>the</strong> rest <strong>of</strong><br />

his system is certainly growing, yet much <strong>of</strong> this work to date has focused<br />

predominately on <strong>the</strong> pure judgment <strong>of</strong> taste <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> sublime. 17 By<br />

contrast, <strong>the</strong> chapters in this volume foreground <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong><br />

imagination as a creative activity <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> interests to which that activity<br />

gives rise. Hence, although this volume discusses <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘pure’’<br />

disinterested judgment <strong>of</strong> taste in some detail in various sections, I pay<br />

special attention to <strong>Kant</strong>’s third Critique account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> interested judgments<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong> says aes<strong>the</strong>tic disinterest may produce, <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> imagination in such judgments. I concentrate on <strong>Kant</strong>’s elevation <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> function <strong>of</strong> imagination to <strong>the</strong> status <strong>of</strong> creative faculty, <strong>and</strong> to his<br />

account in ‘‘lesser’’ texts (<strong>the</strong> Anthropology, <strong>and</strong> ‘‘occasional’’ essays) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

dangers <strong>and</strong> potential <strong>of</strong> this power. The chapters that follow thus do not<br />

dispute <strong>the</strong> autonomy claim <strong>of</strong> pure judgments <strong>of</strong> taste, a claim that <strong>Kant</strong><br />

is quite insistent upon. Indeed, focussing on interested judgments <strong>of</strong><br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection depends on seeing ‘‘pure’’ aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective judgments<br />

that comprise a realm <strong>of</strong> human experience independent <strong>of</strong> moral<br />

cognitive judgment as a condition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> interests involved. These chapters<br />

represent a sustained focus on <strong>the</strong> specific ways in which <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong><br />

imaginative independence serves <strong>Kant</strong>’s larger purpose <strong>of</strong> describing a<br />

mediating faculty between <strong>the</strong> ‘‘is’’ <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘ought to be’’ <strong>of</strong><br />

morality. In this respect <strong>the</strong>y elaborate a <strong>the</strong>me argued for in great detail in<br />

Rudolf Makkreel’s <strong>Imagination</strong> <strong>and</strong> Interpretation in <strong>Kant</strong>, that ‘‘imagination<br />

is a power that both exhibits <strong>and</strong> overcomes <strong>the</strong> limits <strong>of</strong> experience.’’<br />

18 This book was in many ways pathbreaking in studies <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tics for its breadth <strong>and</strong> depth <strong>of</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> imagination,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>sis that reflective judgment is interpretive judgment. Makkreel’s<br />

reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> as a proto-hermeneuticist brought to light aspects <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment that were previously ignored, <strong>and</strong> his<br />

17 Felicitas Munzel’s detailed work showing how moral character is chosen, developed, <strong>and</strong> sustained<br />

via complex interaction with morality, pedagogy, <strong>and</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tics come closest to <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> point I<br />

am making here. However, her focus is primarily on moral character formation in <strong>the</strong> individual,<br />

<strong>and</strong> her analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tics in this formation rests on <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> taste <strong>and</strong> sublimity in<br />

moral education <strong>and</strong> does not rely on an account <strong>of</strong> imagination, but ra<strong>the</strong>r on <strong>the</strong> feeling. The<br />

chapters in this book focus more on <strong>the</strong> role imagination plays in <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> that feeling,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> role that feeling (<strong>of</strong> hope) plays in supporting social morality. Felicitas Munzel, <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

Conception <strong>of</strong> Moral Character: The ‘‘Critical’’ Link <strong>of</strong> Morality, Anthropology, <strong>and</strong> Reflective<br />

Judgment (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1999).<br />

18 Rudolf A. Makkreel, <strong>Imagination</strong> <strong>and</strong> Interpretation in <strong>Kant</strong>: The Hermeneutical Import <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1990).


12<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

work connects <strong>Kant</strong> scholarship that focuses on <strong>the</strong>oretical aspects <strong>of</strong> his<br />

social <strong>and</strong> cultural views with o<strong>the</strong>r philosophical accounts <strong>of</strong> its connection<br />

to Romanticism. A problem for such a view, however, is that <strong>Kant</strong><br />

seems to want to give a kind <strong>of</strong> systematic privilege to practical reason over<br />

all o<strong>the</strong>r kinds <strong>of</strong> experience. The chapters in this book defend <strong>the</strong> view<br />

that <strong>the</strong> imagination in reflective judgment serves as an equally important<br />

power (<strong>of</strong> mediation), arguing explicitly against influential views that<br />

presume <strong>the</strong> ‘‘primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical’’ in <strong>Kant</strong>.<br />

Finally, <strong>the</strong> work that follows takes into account <strong>and</strong> responds to<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r problem for <strong>the</strong> view that imagination can be understood as a<br />

central faculty in <strong>Kant</strong>’s account: <strong>the</strong> accusation <strong>of</strong> some postmodernist<br />

or post-Enlightenment positions, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> some feminists, 19 that <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

philosophy could not truly value imagination given his philosophical <strong>and</strong><br />

even cultural <strong>and</strong> personal antipathy towards sensibility <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong><br />

emotion <strong>and</strong> feeling. This issue has most recently been underscored by<br />

texts such as <strong>the</strong> anthology edited by James Schmidt, ‘‘What is Enlightenment?’’<br />

Eighteenth Century Answers <strong>and</strong> Twentieth Century Questions. 20 I<br />

take <strong>the</strong>se arguments seriously, arguing in <strong>the</strong> end that <strong>Kant</strong> is never<strong>the</strong>less<br />

far less hostile to <strong>the</strong> significance <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom than he<br />

sometimes appears to be.<br />

Thus I find <strong>Kant</strong>’s compatibility with early German Romanticism to<br />

lie not only in his actual philosophical innovations with respect to <strong>the</strong><br />

nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> its freedom, but also, to a certain extent, I<br />

find <strong>the</strong>ir aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ories temperamentally compatible. In o<strong>the</strong>r words,<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> was not as far removed from <strong>the</strong> ironic sensitivities <strong>of</strong> early<br />

Romanticism as one might think, based on st<strong>and</strong>ard ‘‘one-sided’’<br />

accounts <strong>of</strong> both <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Early German Romanticism.<br />

general overview<br />

The book is composed <strong>of</strong> a series <strong>of</strong> chapters, each <strong>of</strong> which reads <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory as mediating between his moral <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> his account <strong>of</strong><br />

19 For a sustained feminist critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> along <strong>the</strong>se lines, see Robin May Schott’s Cognition <strong>and</strong><br />

Eros: A Critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian Paradigm (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press,<br />

1988), <strong>and</strong> also ‘‘The Gender <strong>of</strong> Enlightenment,’’ in Feminist Interpretations <strong>of</strong> Immanuel <strong>Kant</strong>, ed.<br />

Robin May Schott (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1997), pp. 319–37.<br />

My ‘‘The Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Dimension <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian Autonomy’’ (pp. 173–189) inFeminist Interpretations<br />

attempts to adjudicate some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se issues in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> by contrast to<br />

Onora O’Neill’s response to such criticisms, in Constructions <strong>of</strong> Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1989).<br />

20 Riverside: University <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1996.


Introduction 13<br />

human knowledge. The key to this reading is <strong>Kant</strong>’s conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

power <strong>of</strong> imagination, <strong>and</strong> especially <strong>of</strong> what I will call <strong>the</strong> ‘‘transformative’’<br />

power <strong>of</strong> imagination that <strong>Kant</strong> first develops only in <strong>the</strong> third<br />

Critique. Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective judgment, I argue, extends beyond <strong>the</strong><br />

narrower goals <strong>of</strong> deduction <strong>and</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> judgments <strong>of</strong> taste in <strong>the</strong><br />

third Critique. <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tics argues for interests that attach to aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

reflective judgment that surpass <strong>the</strong>ir purely aes<strong>the</strong>tic value.<br />

However, reading <strong>Kant</strong>ian aes<strong>the</strong>tics as part <strong>of</strong> a larger moral project<br />

runs into certain difficulties, one might even say ‘‘hostilities,’’ within<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> imagination. <strong>Kant</strong> frequently expresses a dim view <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>of</strong> imagination that may perhaps be diagnosed as extraphilosophical,<br />

but which never<strong>the</strong>less militates against taking human<br />

imaginative capacities to be central to <strong>Kant</strong>ian moral <strong>and</strong> social concerns.<br />

In chapter 5 I address criticisms <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s motivation in characterizing <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination as subordinate faculty, or as mysterious <strong>and</strong> even dangerous.<br />

This chapter argues that, in <strong>the</strong> end, such criticisms may be countered by<br />

<strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>Kant</strong>’s attitude toward ‘‘undisciplined’’ creative imaginative<br />

power was not uniformly negative. His defense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘enthusiast’’ <strong>and</strong><br />

his self-avowed love affair with metaphysics have a continued influence<br />

on his philosophy that re-emerge, I argue, in scattered attempts to find a<br />

secure place for speculative metaphysical imaginings in his finished philosophical<br />

system.<br />

Finally, given this reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory, I argue for <strong>the</strong><br />

claim (made on historical grounds in chapter 2) that <strong>the</strong>re is substantive<br />

continuity between <strong>the</strong> Enlightenment values <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s critical enterprise<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> values <strong>of</strong> early German Romanticism. The main focus here is<br />

upon <strong>the</strong> paradigmatic central figure <strong>of</strong> that movement, Friedrich von<br />

Hardenberg, known as Novalis. Novalis was a student <strong>and</strong> friend <strong>of</strong><br />

Schiller’s in Jena <strong>and</strong>, along with <strong>the</strong> rest <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> so-called ‘‘Jena Romantic<br />

circle,’’ was party to <strong>the</strong> lively debate surrounding Fichte’s revision <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>ianism. Moreover, it was in Jena that <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy became a<br />

centerpiece <strong>of</strong> philosophical discussion, thanks to Reinhold’s enormously<br />

successful popularizing work in <strong>the</strong> late 1780s <strong>and</strong> early 1790s at <strong>the</strong><br />

university <strong>the</strong>re. Recent work has underscored <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> Jena as<br />

<strong>the</strong> first site <strong>of</strong> sustained study <strong>and</strong> argument over <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy, <strong>and</strong><br />

to <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> Fichtean <strong>and</strong> later German idealism (see Karl<br />

Ameriks, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Fate <strong>of</strong> Autonomy: Problems in <strong>the</strong> Appropriation <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Critical Philosophy). 21 Yet little has been written on <strong>the</strong> relation <strong>of</strong><br />

21 Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.


14<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s work to <strong>the</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> early German Romantics who were<br />

central to <strong>the</strong> debate over <strong>Kant</strong>ianism in Jena at <strong>the</strong> time. Chapters 6 <strong>and</strong><br />

7 in this book brings <strong>the</strong>se two remarkable philosophies into dialog by<br />

exploring Novalis’ reception <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> toge<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>Kant</strong>’s own interest in<br />

questions about <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> imagination in uniting nature <strong>and</strong> morality in<br />

<strong>the</strong> human subject. These questions, <strong>and</strong> some <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s answers, I<br />

contend, became central to <strong>the</strong> Romantic project.<br />

ov erview o f <strong>the</strong> book<br />

Chapter 1, ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism,’’ introduces <strong>the</strong> overall <strong>the</strong>me <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

book, that <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> imagination is not so far removed from<br />

Novalis’ definition <strong>of</strong> ‘‘romanticizing.’’ By showing what Novalis means<br />

by this term, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> extent to which his meaning is at odds with stereotypical<br />

distortions <strong>of</strong> Romanticism as mystical <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rworldly, I set<br />

<strong>the</strong> stage for looking at <strong>Kant</strong>’s views on such ‘‘mystical’’-sounding ideas as<br />

that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘supersensible.’’ In <strong>the</strong> same way that ‘‘romanticizing’’ for<br />

Novalis is a process <strong>of</strong> both recognizing <strong>the</strong> ordinary in <strong>the</strong> mysterious,<br />

<strong>and</strong> demystifying <strong>the</strong> extraordinary, I argue, <strong>Kant</strong>’s views also involve this<br />

tw<strong>of</strong>old procedure. <strong>Kant</strong>’s commitment to <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> exp<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

<strong>and</strong> developing our mental powers <strong>the</strong>mselves is discussed, along with <strong>the</strong><br />

influence <strong>of</strong> Rousseau on his overall view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> re-creating<br />

ourselves <strong>and</strong> our world.<br />

Chapters 2– 4 place <strong>Kant</strong>’s views on aes<strong>the</strong>tics in historical context <strong>and</strong><br />

situate <strong>the</strong>m also within <strong>the</strong> larger context <strong>of</strong> his philosophy as a whole.<br />

chapter 2, ‘‘The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom,’’ sets <strong>the</strong> stage with an<br />

examination <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> freedom in <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> Germany<br />

beginning with Baumgarten. In particular it looks at three early <strong>and</strong><br />

mid-eighteenth-century German accounts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

that may be seen as precursors to <strong>Kant</strong>’s: those <strong>of</strong> Baumgarten, Bodmer<br />

<strong>and</strong> Breitinger, <strong>and</strong> Lessing. I argue that <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory provides a link<br />

between <strong>the</strong>se earlier more didactic <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> visionary aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>of</strong><br />

Schiller <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r early Romantic poets. The argument is based on <strong>the</strong><br />

new role that <strong>Kant</strong> assigns <strong>the</strong> imagination in <strong>the</strong> third Critique, where he<br />

argues that it is capable <strong>of</strong> transforming nature <strong>and</strong> exhibiting human<br />

ideals in concrete form. Given that such exhibitions would provide a basis<br />

for rational hope when directed towards social ideals, I argue that it is<br />

possible in <strong>Kant</strong>’s later thought to ground a rational hope for bringing<br />

about a just world in such imaginative visions. This move would obviate<br />

<strong>the</strong> need for <strong>the</strong> questionable reintroduction <strong>of</strong> metaphysics in <strong>the</strong> form


Introduction 15<br />

<strong>of</strong> postulates <strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> immortality which have proven to be so<br />

problematic for <strong>Kant</strong>, <strong>and</strong> it also suggests <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> a <strong>Kant</strong>ian<br />

ethics less hostile to imagination <strong>and</strong> sensibility.<br />

Chapter 3, ‘‘The interests <strong>of</strong> disinterest,’’ <strong>the</strong>n moves from <strong>the</strong> historical<br />

framework <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tics to <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory itself. Here I deal with<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pure judgment <strong>of</strong> taste, or <strong>the</strong> judgment about <strong>the</strong><br />

beautiful, in light <strong>of</strong> his claim that <strong>the</strong> central element <strong>of</strong> his justification<br />

<strong>of</strong> such judgments – <strong>the</strong> universal communicability <strong>of</strong> ‘‘disinterested’’<br />

feelings <strong>of</strong> pleasure – ‘‘must already carry with it an interest’’ for human<br />

beings. This chapter examines <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se<br />

interests <strong>and</strong> follows <strong>the</strong> thread <strong>of</strong> his argument to show its potential for<br />

establishing a link between morality <strong>and</strong> sensibility. Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as <strong>Kant</strong> is<br />

able to make a case for a close analogy between aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>and</strong> moral<br />

interest, he may argue for a psychological transition from <strong>the</strong> former to<br />

<strong>the</strong> latter. Hence he could make ‘‘love <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> beautiful,’’ <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> fashioning<br />

<strong>of</strong> conditions where it may be experienced by all, a kind <strong>of</strong> moral<br />

imperative. This chapter <strong>the</strong>n explores <strong>the</strong> ways in which <strong>Kant</strong>’s conception<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> interests <strong>of</strong> disinterested reflection on <strong>the</strong> beautiful <strong>and</strong> his<br />

views on genius might lead to a higher valuation <strong>of</strong> art <strong>and</strong> even human<br />

embodiment than <strong>Kant</strong> himself seems to allow.<br />

Chapter 4, ‘‘Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical,’’<br />

refocusses <strong>the</strong> discussion from <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> beauty to <strong>the</strong> larger role<br />

that his aes<strong>the</strong>tics plays within his <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> value. Having argued for a<br />

larger systematic role for aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment on historical <strong>and</strong> textual<br />

grounds, I here address <strong>the</strong> largest challenge to such a reading – <strong>the</strong> fact<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong>’s critical philosophy turns on <strong>the</strong> ‘‘primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical,’’<br />

<strong>and</strong> should be interpreted as a system within which all value ultimately<br />

derives from practical reasoning. Onora O’Neill <strong>and</strong> Christine Korsgaard<br />

have given powerful <strong>and</strong> influential accounts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> methodological primacy<br />

<strong>of</strong> practical reason in <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy, <strong>and</strong> I look at each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se<br />

in turn <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>fer criticisms. Yet, even if methodological primacy accounts<br />

are inadequate, it is possible that practical reason is primary for <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

overall account <strong>of</strong> human valuation in some o<strong>the</strong>r sense. I <strong>the</strong>n address<br />

Karl Ameriks’ account <strong>of</strong> what I label <strong>the</strong> ‘‘metaphysical’’ primacy <strong>of</strong><br />

practical reason, as well as Richard Velkley’s <strong>and</strong> Susan Neiman’s different<br />

approaches to <strong>the</strong> issue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unification <strong>of</strong> reason. Finally I argue<br />

for an alternative underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy that<br />

is nei<strong>the</strong>r founded upon nor ordered ‘‘under’’ a principle <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy<br />

<strong>of</strong> practical judgment. This chapter claims that <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy is<br />

better understood as an attempt at a comprehensive account <strong>of</strong> nature (as


16<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

known by rational, embodied beings) <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> morality (as practiced by<br />

rational agents) mediated by a freely reflecting imagination. The unification<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se accounts, I argue, is accomplished not by placing one<br />

under <strong>the</strong> jurisdiction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r, as is suggested by primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

practical accounts. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> two domains are mediated <strong>and</strong>, in this<br />

sense only, ‘‘united,’’ by reflective aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong><br />

hope to which it gives rise.<br />

In chapter 5, ‘‘The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination’’ I address a challenge<br />

to any interpretation that would try to center an account <strong>of</strong> human<br />

experience in <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory around <strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>of</strong> imagination. The<br />

challenge was famously laid down by Heidegger, <strong>and</strong> taken up again in<br />

recent times by Gernot <strong>and</strong> Hartmut Böhme <strong>and</strong> by some feminist<br />

philosophers as well. It consists, in a nutshell, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> claim that <strong>Kant</strong> was<br />

constitutionally incapable <strong>of</strong> granting so much importance to <strong>the</strong> faculty<br />

<strong>of</strong> imagination. Heidegger reads <strong>the</strong> second edition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Deduction <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Categories, wherein <strong>Kant</strong> subsumes <strong>the</strong> imaginative capacity under <strong>the</strong><br />

faculty <strong>of</strong> Underst<strong>and</strong>ing, as pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> this. The Böhmes agree, <strong>and</strong> take<br />

<strong>the</strong> argument from <strong>the</strong> first Critique to <strong>the</strong> third, by arguing that even<br />

here, in his <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> taste, <strong>Kant</strong> relegates <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> imagination to mere<br />

‘‘play.’’ Chapter 5 examines <strong>the</strong>se criticisms <strong>and</strong> responds by arguing that<br />

<strong>the</strong> third Critique account <strong>of</strong> imagination goes well beyond a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong><br />

taste <strong>and</strong> fine arts criticism. I argue that <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Ideal <strong>of</strong><br />

beauty <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas suggests an important role for imagination<br />

in moral development, as do his comments on <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> moral<br />

enthusiasm, made in his lectures on Anthropology <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> late essay<br />

‘‘An old question raised again: is <strong>the</strong> human race constantly progressing?’’<br />

This chapter concludes with a discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> extent to which <strong>Kant</strong><br />

himself opposed <strong>the</strong> metaphysical attitude in philosophizing. It argues<br />

that in fact, <strong>Kant</strong> was not unsympa<strong>the</strong>tic to <strong>the</strong> desire for a unified<br />

account <strong>of</strong> subjectivity – <strong>and</strong>, indeed, found a place for it in his aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory.<br />

Chapter 6, ‘‘Imaginative reflections <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self in Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin,’’<br />

takes up <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> subjectivity in <strong>the</strong><br />

philosophical <strong>and</strong> poetic work <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> early German Romantics, arguing<br />

for a continuity between <strong>the</strong> latter <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s third Critique views on<br />

imaginative power. It lays out <strong>the</strong> departure <strong>of</strong> Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin<br />

from Fichte’s attempt to give an account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self that claims to present<br />

an ultimate ground or foundational account <strong>of</strong> its unity. It argues that<br />

Novalis’ <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin’s accounts bear a closer affinity to <strong>Kant</strong>’s views<br />

than to those <strong>of</strong> Fichte’s idealism inasmuch as <strong>the</strong>y reject <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong>


Introduction 17<br />

giving a positive account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> subjectivity. Instead, both<br />

embrace a fundamentally negative account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural <strong>and</strong><br />

‘‘absolute’’ in <strong>the</strong> subject: in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> Novalis, <strong>the</strong> resemblance to<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sublime is striking. In Hölderlin<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is an explicit reversion to an account <strong>of</strong> non-conceptual aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

experience <strong>of</strong> beauty that owes much to <strong>Kant</strong>’s, <strong>and</strong> that in <strong>the</strong> end, like<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s, remains skeptical about <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> knowing our absolute<br />

nature.<br />

Finally, in chapter 7, ‘‘Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism,’’<br />

I return to discuss in more detail <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> unified subjectivity in<br />

<strong>the</strong> philosophical work <strong>of</strong> Novalis, examining <strong>the</strong> influence <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

philosophy on it. I argue that although Novalis, like o<strong>the</strong>r early<br />

Romantics, is apparently more disturbed by <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> unified<br />

subjectivity than <strong>Kant</strong>, his metaphysical position is not in <strong>the</strong> end much<br />

different from <strong>Kant</strong>’s. Novalis upholds <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

unknowability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolute self <strong>and</strong> is hence nei<strong>the</strong>r an idealist nor an<br />

irrationalist. What both share is a commitment to <strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>of</strong> creative<br />

imagination as link between <strong>the</strong> inner world <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> outer<br />

world <strong>of</strong> nature in <strong>the</strong> human subject. The second part <strong>of</strong> this chapter<br />

picks up on Novalis’ notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘genius <strong>of</strong> genius’’ to inquire more<br />

deeply into <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> role such an underst<strong>and</strong>ing might play in<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory. <strong>Kant</strong>’s views on <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> genius are explored<br />

first in terms <strong>of</strong> his account <strong>of</strong> unconscious ideation discussed in <strong>the</strong><br />

Anthropology, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s mention <strong>the</strong>re <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> performer <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘‘free fantasia.’’ The phenomenon <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘free fantasia’’ in <strong>Kant</strong>’s time<br />

is discussed, along with <strong>Kant</strong>’s analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mental state <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> musical<br />

performer <strong>of</strong> this genre <strong>and</strong> its relationship to ordinary cognitive activity<br />

<strong>and</strong> genius. This chapter concludes that once one-sided characterizations<br />

<strong>of</strong> both <strong>the</strong>se thinkers are corrected, <strong>the</strong>ir views can no longer be seen as<br />

anti<strong>the</strong>tical to each o<strong>the</strong>r. The differences, in o<strong>the</strong>r words, are more<br />

differences in attitude than in method <strong>and</strong> substance.<br />

For all its importance in <strong>the</strong> history <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> art, <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tics is far more than a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> art <strong>and</strong> beauty. This book presents<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r aspects <strong>of</strong> his aes<strong>the</strong>tics, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> creative imagination<br />

upon which it is based, as both a central, integrating component <strong>of</strong> his<br />

larger philosophical enterprise <strong>and</strong> as a keystone in <strong>the</strong> bridge between<br />

eighteenth- <strong>and</strong> early nineteenth-century moral aes<strong>the</strong>tics in German<br />

philosophy. It is a reading <strong>Kant</strong> himself suggested, when in <strong>the</strong> introductions<br />

to <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment he argued that both his aes<strong>the</strong>tics<br />

<strong>and</strong> his account <strong>of</strong> teleological judgment would help close <strong>the</strong> great


18<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

chasm between <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> morality <strong>and</strong> cognition established in <strong>the</strong><br />

first two Critiques. Certainly a bridge between human need <strong>and</strong> human<br />

obligation was central to German Enlightenment aes<strong>the</strong>tics, beginning<br />

with Gottsched <strong>and</strong> carried forward by Lessing’s work, <strong>and</strong> it became<br />

even more crucial (<strong>and</strong> more politicized) in <strong>the</strong> early German Romantics.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tics is not typically associated with his thoughts on<br />

Enlightenment, but it is <strong>the</strong> point <strong>of</strong> this book to show how <strong>the</strong>y enabled<br />

<strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> German tradition <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic education <strong>the</strong>ory,<br />

transforming it in <strong>the</strong> process into a critical <strong>the</strong>oretical enterprise.<br />

Historical periods are difficult, arguably impossible, to delineate <strong>and</strong><br />

define, <strong>and</strong> although <strong>the</strong> Enlightenment has been a remarkably resilient<br />

historical category (perhaps because, as Foucault emphasized, it named<br />

itself) <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> what truly characterizes this period is still a matter<br />

<strong>of</strong> contention. Broadly speaking, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> this book is to grasp <strong>the</strong><br />

shape <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Enlightenment <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> Romanticism by, as it were, studying<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir interface. If <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy is taken as an exemplar (many would<br />

say <strong>the</strong> exemplar) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> late German Enlightenment <strong>and</strong> Novalis’ philosophy<br />

as paradigm <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> early German Romantic movement, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong><br />

interface <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two is <strong>of</strong> real historical significance. It is all <strong>the</strong> more<br />

important since <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se two positions sets <strong>the</strong>m up as<br />

diametrically opposed. In examining <strong>the</strong> historical <strong>and</strong> conceptual connections<br />

between, on <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>, a philosophy <strong>of</strong>ten viewed as rigidly<br />

rationalist <strong>and</strong> formalist in its overall contours <strong>and</strong>, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>,<br />

one that is <strong>of</strong>ten taken to be so inchoate <strong>and</strong> fantastical as to be no<br />

philosophy at all, I hope to bring into relief important dimensions <strong>of</strong><br />

both. I have long been convinced that if one looks closely at <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>of</strong> imagination, especially as foregrounded, developed,<br />

<strong>and</strong> exp<strong>and</strong>ed in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment,’’ a good deal<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> criticism <strong>of</strong> his ethics <strong>and</strong> anthropology becomes moot. During <strong>the</strong><br />

course <strong>of</strong> study <strong>of</strong> Novalis <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> immediate post-<strong>Kant</strong>ian philosophical<br />

context in Germany, I have come to appreciate <strong>the</strong> continuities <strong>of</strong> early<br />

German Romanticism with <strong>Kant</strong>’s work <strong>and</strong> to see <strong>the</strong> distortion <strong>and</strong><br />

tired caricatures <strong>of</strong> that movement as an impediment to underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

important aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tics. Looking at <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy<br />

from <strong>the</strong> perspective <strong>of</strong> his view <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom is surprisingly<br />

disruptive <strong>of</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard views <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ianism, but it also undermines stereotypical<br />

accounts <strong>of</strong> Romanticism. On philosophical turf, an important<br />

recent debate has centered around <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r Romanticism<br />

is to be characterized as a continuation <strong>of</strong> German Idealism or as


Introduction 19<br />

Idealism’s most ‘‘decisive’’ opponent. 22 This book skirts that issue, in part<br />

because <strong>the</strong>re are any number <strong>of</strong> questions about what constitutes<br />

‘‘German Idealism’’ in general, <strong>and</strong> more specifically because <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

equally many questions raised by calling <strong>Kant</strong> an ‘‘idealist.’’ 23 My aim is<br />

simply to look at <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r Romanticism, as characterized<br />

by one <strong>of</strong> its leading exponents, is to be found at all in <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong><br />

Immanuel <strong>Kant</strong>, <strong>and</strong> if so, what aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s enlightenment thought<br />

might be seen as partially constitutive <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> early Romantic point <strong>of</strong><br />

view. At stake is <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> enlivening <strong>and</strong> enriching enlightenment<br />

commitments to human equality <strong>and</strong> freedom with <strong>the</strong> early Romantic<br />

emphasis on community <strong>and</strong> creativity. The chapters that follow trace a<br />

path from <strong>Kant</strong>’s views on imaginative creativity <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> connection<br />

between aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> morality to late eighteenth-century<br />

Romanticism in Germany. In so doing <strong>the</strong> book suggests an alternative<br />

trajectory to <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tics that will, I hope, bring attention to its<br />

continuing relevance for <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> social transformation.<br />

22 Ernst Behler, Review <strong>of</strong> Manfred Frank’s Einführung in die Frühromantische Äs<strong>the</strong>tik, A<strong>the</strong>näum, 3,<br />

1993. Also see Karl Ameriks’ Introduction to The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism (see n.<br />

13), esp. pp. 10–13, ‘‘Idealism <strong>and</strong> Romanticism.’’<br />

23 Ameriks, Introduction, pp. 1–10.


chapter 1<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism<br />

The very idea <strong>of</strong> connecting <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism has raised <strong>and</strong> no<br />

doubt will continue to raise hackles among some <strong>Kant</strong> scholars. These<br />

critics typically view <strong>Kant</strong> as <strong>the</strong> last great defender <strong>of</strong> Enlightenment<br />

values in <strong>the</strong> modern era <strong>of</strong> philosophy, while viewing Romanticism as a<br />

reactionary, counterenlightenment development expressing irrationalist<br />

tendencies <strong>and</strong> forces whose aims are ana<strong>the</strong>ma to <strong>the</strong> spirit <strong>of</strong> liberty <strong>and</strong><br />

equality. This view continues to prevail in <strong>the</strong> face <strong>of</strong> much new scholarship<br />

documenting <strong>the</strong> broad spectrum <strong>of</strong> Enlightenment positions <strong>and</strong><br />

controversies, 1 <strong>and</strong> in spite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>Kant</strong> himself was a great<br />

admirer, <strong>and</strong> in some cases friend, <strong>of</strong> several major counterenlightenment<br />

figures. 2 <strong>Kant</strong> did not directly engage <strong>the</strong> so-called ‘‘Jena school <strong>of</strong><br />

Romantics’’ that included <strong>the</strong> Schlegels, Schelling, <strong>and</strong> Novalis. Yet his<br />

philosophy loomed so large in <strong>the</strong> German academic context that <strong>the</strong>re<br />

can be no question <strong>of</strong> his influence on <strong>the</strong>m. Indeed one could argue that<br />

it is in <strong>the</strong> claim to be <strong>Kant</strong>’s successor <strong>and</strong> remediator that Fichte<br />

attracted <strong>and</strong> fascinated <strong>the</strong> early Romantics. <strong>Kant</strong> repudiated Fichte’s<br />

appropriation <strong>of</strong> his philosophy, 3 <strong>and</strong> Fichte’s Doctrine <strong>of</strong> Scientific<br />

Knowledge was criticized by <strong>the</strong> early Romantics. 4 They quickly came<br />

to reject Fichte’s basic assumptions. It is a major contention <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter<br />

part <strong>of</strong> this book that this rejection, most forcefully stated in Novalis’<br />

Fichte Studies, is fundamentally a rejection on <strong>Kant</strong>ian grounds <strong>and</strong> bears<br />

<strong>the</strong> mark <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory. This chapter will serve to introduce<br />

1<br />

See for instance James Schmidt, ed., What is Enlightenment? Eighteenth Century Answers <strong>and</strong><br />

Twentieth Century Questions (Riverside: University <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1996).<br />

2<br />

Most notable here is <strong>Kant</strong>’s great admiration <strong>of</strong> Rousseau, but he was also on friendly terms at one<br />

time or ano<strong>the</strong>r with Hamann <strong>and</strong> Jacobi.<br />

3<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s ‘‘Open Letter on Fichte’s Wissenschaftslehre’’ (August 7, 1799), in Arnulf Zweig, <strong>Kant</strong>:<br />

Philosophical Correspondence 1759–99 (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1967), pp. 253–254 is<br />

decisive, if also somewhat peevish.<br />

4<br />

Most famously by Novalis (Novalis: Fichte Studies, ed. Jane Kneller, Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 2003).<br />

20


<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism 21<br />

this argument, along with some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> book’s o<strong>the</strong>r major <strong>the</strong>mes, by<br />

juxtapositing Novalis’ definition <strong>of</strong> Romanticism with key aspects <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy.<br />

kant <strong>and</strong> novalis<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Novalis both gave shape to <strong>the</strong>ir philosophical programs <strong>of</strong><br />

Enlightenment <strong>and</strong> Romanticism, respectively, in <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> dicta that<br />

became mottoes for <strong>the</strong>se movements. <strong>Kant</strong>’s ‘‘Sapere aude!’’ – ‘‘Think for<br />

yourself !’’ – was a call to arms for Enlightenment <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> practice,<br />

<strong>and</strong> so, in its own way, was Novalis’ dem<strong>and</strong> that: ‘‘The world must be<br />

romanticized.’’ Controversial as it may sound, in many ways early<br />

German Romantic philosophy carried <strong>Kant</strong>’s Enlightenment banner<br />

longer <strong>and</strong> higher than those who named <strong>the</strong>mselves heir to <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

philosophy. Even more controversial, but equally plausible, is that <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

own philosophy moved in <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> carrying out a program <strong>of</strong><br />

‘‘romanticization’’ in accordance with Novalis’ dictum. To make this last<br />

claim is sure to upset <strong>Kant</strong> scholars, especially those in <strong>the</strong> Anglo-<br />

American tradition who for decades have labored hard to reconstruct an<br />

analytic, empiricist-friendly reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> as primarily responding to<br />

Humean skepticism. Certainly, to associate <strong>Kant</strong> with mysticism, irrationalism,<br />

<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rworldly utopianism is false, <strong>and</strong> would be ana<strong>the</strong>ma<br />

to <strong>the</strong> no-nonsense humanism <strong>of</strong> ‘‘<strong>the</strong> Prussian Hume.’’ 5 Yet characterizing<br />

early German Romanticism in <strong>the</strong>se terms is itself a gross misrepresentation<br />

<strong>of</strong> its most lively <strong>and</strong> central tendencies. Moreover, in <strong>the</strong><br />

mid-twentieth century rush to make <strong>Kant</strong> palatable to Anglo-American<br />

analytic philosophers, much that was central to <strong>Kant</strong>’s own work was<br />

initially ignored, down-played, or simply dismissed. No one denies that<br />

<strong>the</strong> so-called ‘‘Copernican revolution’’ <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ethics founded on a<br />

Categorical Imperative remained basic to all his most important work,<br />

but it is equally true that <strong>Kant</strong> wrote about far more than <strong>the</strong> conditions<br />

<strong>of</strong> cognitive knowledge <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> foundations <strong>of</strong> moral obligation. Recent<br />

scholarship on <strong>Kant</strong>’s ‘‘impure’’ ethics, 6 aes<strong>the</strong>tics, anthropology, methodology,<br />

politics, <strong>and</strong> social <strong>the</strong>ory has virtually exploded, <strong>and</strong> our ability<br />

to bring <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy into sharper historical focus has increased<br />

proportionally.<br />

5 Lewis White Beck’s term in ‘‘A Prussian Hume <strong>and</strong> a Scottish <strong>Kant</strong>?’’ in Essays on <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Hume<br />

(New Haven: Yale University Press, 1978).<br />

6 The term is due to Robert Louden <strong>and</strong> is <strong>the</strong> title <strong>of</strong> his book on <strong>Kant</strong>’s Anthropology: <strong>Kant</strong>’s Impure<br />

Ethics: From Rational Beings to Human Beings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000).


22<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

Let us begin by looking at what Novalis means when he defines <strong>the</strong><br />

movement known as Romanticism in terms <strong>of</strong> ‘‘romanticizing.’’ As it<br />

turns out, he has in mind something quite specific: to romanticize is to<br />

convert what is ordinary <strong>and</strong> mundane into something extraordinary <strong>and</strong><br />

mysterious, <strong>and</strong> conversely, to make what is unknown, known:<br />

The world must be romanticized. In this way one rediscovers <strong>the</strong> original<br />

meaning. Romanticizing is nothing but a qualitative raising to a higher power<br />

[Potenzirung]. The lower self becomes identified with a better self. Just as we<br />

ourselves are such a qualitative exponential series. This operation is still quite<br />

unknown. Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as I give <strong>the</strong> commonplace a higher meaning, <strong>the</strong> ordinary a<br />

mysterious countenance, <strong>the</strong> known <strong>the</strong> dignity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unknown, <strong>the</strong> finite an<br />

appearance <strong>of</strong> infinity, I romanticize it. The operation is precisely <strong>the</strong> opposite<br />

for <strong>the</strong> higher, unknown, mystical <strong>and</strong> infinite – <strong>the</strong>se are logarithmized by this<br />

connection – <strong>the</strong>y become common expressions. Romantic philosophy. Lingua<br />

romana. Alternating elevation <strong>and</strong> lowering. (II: 545, #105)<br />

Novalis characterizes romanticizing as a two-part process. As Ernst Behler<br />

explains it, it is ‘‘a dual, counteractive movement ... in which romanticizing<br />

constitutes <strong>the</strong> expansion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind into <strong>the</strong> mysterious <strong>and</strong><br />

unknown, yet eventually reverses itself into a return into <strong>the</strong> ordinary <strong>and</strong><br />

familiar.’’ 7<br />

The first part <strong>of</strong> this process – giving <strong>the</strong> commonplace a higher<br />

meaning, mystifying <strong>the</strong> ordinary – is stereotypically associated with<br />

Romanticism. But it is equally important in underst<strong>and</strong>ing Novalis <strong>and</strong><br />

early German Romanticism that equal weight be placed on <strong>the</strong> second<br />

part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> process – lowering or ‘‘logarhythmizing’’ [‘‘logarythmisirt’’] <strong>the</strong><br />

mystical. Andrew Bowie points out that<br />

The neologism ‘‘logorhythmised’’, which combines <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> rational ordering,<br />

verbalisation <strong>and</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical progression with <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> music<br />

inherent in <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> everyday language, epitomises <strong>the</strong> Romantic position. 8<br />

Bowie goes on to argue that for Novalis, as for Friedrich Schlegel,<br />

romanticizing by no means meant a ‘‘surrender to indeterminacy.’’ 9 While<br />

Novalis certainly sympathized with <strong>the</strong> urge to idealize, he was insistent<br />

that although a ‘‘tendency to seek <strong>the</strong> universal’’ [Universaltendenz] is<br />

essential to <strong>the</strong> scholar,<br />

7 Ernst Behler, German Romantic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 207.<br />

8 Andrew Bowie, From Romanticism to Critical Theory: The Philosophy <strong>of</strong> German Literary Theory<br />

(London <strong>and</strong> New York: Routledge, 1997), p. 80.<br />

9 Ibid., pp. 78ff <strong>and</strong> p. 313, n.19.


<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism 23<br />

one must never, like a phantast, seek <strong>the</strong> undetermined – a child <strong>of</strong> fantasy – an<br />

ideal. One proceeds from determinate task to determinate task. An unknown<br />

lover <strong>of</strong> course has a magical charm. Striving for <strong>the</strong> unknown, <strong>the</strong> undetermined,<br />

is extremely dangerous <strong>and</strong> disadvantageous. Revelation must not be<br />

forced. (3: 601, #291)<br />

This fragment may serve to remind contemporary eighteenth-century<br />

scholars that a genuine appreciation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘practical, technical <strong>and</strong> real’’<br />

(Novalis, 3: 600, #291) in science was not <strong>the</strong> sole property <strong>of</strong> Enlighteners.<br />

In fact, on Novalis’ account <strong>of</strong> romanticizing, a reductionist<br />

approach in <strong>the</strong> sciences can be viewed as a legitimate <strong>and</strong> integral part <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> romantic program.<br />

Recognizing <strong>the</strong> ‘‘naturalizing’’ side <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> romanticizing<br />

helps to correct <strong>the</strong> misreading <strong>of</strong> Novalis’ program as irrationalist, but it<br />

is just as important to emphasize that even <strong>the</strong> expansive side <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

process is not a call for mystification. To make <strong>the</strong> familiar unfamiliar is<br />

not to seek cognitive oblivion, but simply to learn to look at <strong>the</strong> world<br />

again with wonder. Understood in this way, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong>re is certainly a very<br />

general sense in which <strong>Kant</strong>, along with o<strong>the</strong>r great philosophers before<br />

him, ‘‘romanticized’’ in both <strong>the</strong>se senses <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term. The very procedure<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian ‘‘critique’’ is one <strong>of</strong> painstaking analysis <strong>and</strong> ordering <strong>of</strong><br />

mental phenomena that had previously been considered ‘‘unknown’’ or<br />

mystical. For example, one could say without exaggeration that, in <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

view, he was demystifying Hume’s h<strong>and</strong>-waving conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> causal<br />

connection as a ‘‘gentle force’’ or Descartes’ mystical ‘‘stamp <strong>of</strong> God’’<br />

view <strong>of</strong> innate ideas, or Locke’s substance – a ‘‘somewhat, I know not<br />

what.’’ One might very well characterize <strong>the</strong> analytic <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong><br />

Pure Reason as a process <strong>of</strong> demystification <strong>of</strong> formerly metaphysical<br />

notions like substance, causal connection, possibility, <strong>and</strong> necessity, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> very notion <strong>of</strong> ideas knowable a priori. Certainly in <strong>Kant</strong>’s own time,<br />

<strong>the</strong> depressingly deflationary nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s transcendental move was<br />

clear, as was attested to in <strong>the</strong> famous case <strong>of</strong> Kleist’s ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong> crisis.’’ Even<br />

where it seemed impossible to reduce phenomena to functions <strong>of</strong> human<br />

cognition – for instance, in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> uniformity <strong>of</strong> natural<br />

appearances <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> systematic regularity <strong>of</strong> nature, as in <strong>the</strong> appearance<br />

<strong>of</strong> systematic interconnectedness <strong>of</strong> nature according to empirical laws, or<br />

in <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> natural organisms (entities with purposes) – <strong>Kant</strong><br />

pushed <strong>the</strong> critical philosophy to its limits, introducing ‘‘regulative’’<br />

principles, or principles <strong>of</strong> reflection (in <strong>the</strong> third Critique) as necessary<br />

conditions <strong>of</strong> our recognition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se contingencies.


24<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

Even <strong>the</strong> human tendency to ‘‘surrender’’ to <strong>the</strong> infinite is analyzed as a<br />

psychological phenomenon by <strong>Kant</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Dialectic <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first Critique,<br />

<strong>and</strong> can thus be viewed as a ‘‘logarythmizing’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unknowable in <strong>the</strong><br />

various forms in which Reason seeks it. <strong>Kant</strong> does not deny <strong>the</strong> existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason’s irrepressible desire to strive to know <strong>the</strong> unknown <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

infinite. But by carefully cataloguing <strong>the</strong> various specific traps <strong>and</strong> pitfalls<br />

that human reason is liable to, he systematically reduces <strong>the</strong> search for <strong>the</strong><br />

unknown itself to a part <strong>of</strong> human cognitive functioning. Where this<br />

desire to surrender to <strong>the</strong> infinite is aes<strong>the</strong>ticized, as in our fascination<br />

with that in nature which appears infinitely large or powerful, <strong>Kant</strong> also<br />

gives a detailed analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cognitive functions involved. He assures his<br />

readers that <strong>the</strong> sublime is really not to be located in natural objects<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves, but ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

all we are entitled to say is that <strong>the</strong> object is suitable for exhibiting a sublimity<br />

that can be found in <strong>the</strong> mind. For what is sublime, in <strong>the</strong> proper meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

term, cannot be contained in any sensible form but concerns only ideas <strong>of</strong><br />

reason, which ... can be exhibited in sensibility. (V: 245–246).<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> goes on to explain in great detail <strong>the</strong> way in which <strong>the</strong> imagination<br />

attempts to estimate in intuition <strong>the</strong> magnitude <strong>and</strong> power <strong>of</strong> vast, even<br />

infinite nature, <strong>and</strong> how this striving eventuates in a feeling (<strong>of</strong> inadequacy<br />

or fear) that refers us to an aspect <strong>of</strong> ourselves that is ‘‘independent<br />

<strong>of</strong> nature.’’ This reference itself gives rise to a second feeling <strong>of</strong> overcoming<br />

<strong>the</strong> inadequacies <strong>of</strong> our imagination. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

pr<strong>of</strong>fers a highly nuanced <strong>and</strong> complex psychological account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

origins <strong>of</strong> our feeling <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mysteries <strong>and</strong> majesty <strong>of</strong> nature. And, beyond<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sublime, as Rudolf Makkreel points out, <strong>Kant</strong>’s account<br />

<strong>of</strong> reflective judgment <strong>and</strong> imagination in <strong>the</strong> third Critique also attempts<br />

to analyze <strong>and</strong> explain ‘‘one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> greatest metaphysical mysteries – <strong>the</strong><br />

fact that matter can at times partake <strong>of</strong> life’’ by way <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic pleasure. 10<br />

To be sure, as Behler (echoing Friedrich Schlegel) points out, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

recognized a ‘‘dark’’ <strong>and</strong> mysterious element <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human psyche in <strong>the</strong><br />

guise <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>of</strong> imagination. 11 It was for him <strong>the</strong> ‘‘blind but<br />

indispensable function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul without which we would have no<br />

10 Rudolf A. Makkreel, <strong>Imagination</strong> <strong>and</strong> Interpretation in <strong>Kant</strong>: The Hermeneutical Import <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1990). This book is an excellent<br />

account <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s developed <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> severely undermines any argument that<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> had an impoverished account <strong>of</strong> imagination that placed it at <strong>the</strong> very lowest level <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophical inquiry, as suggested by, e.g., ‘‘Ernst Behler über Manfred Frank,’’ Buchbesprechung,<br />

A<strong>the</strong>näum, 1 (1991).<br />

11 Behler, Review <strong>of</strong> Manfred Frank’s Einführung, p.249.


<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism 25<br />

knowledge but <strong>of</strong> which we are scarcely ever conscious’’ (Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure<br />

Reason A78/B103). Yet it does not follow even from this characterization<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong> was unwilling to admit <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> scientific study <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘‘dark’’ side <strong>of</strong> imagination, e.g. in unconscious ideation, or what he<br />

called ‘‘obscure ideas.’’ When he talks about unconscious ideas in <strong>the</strong><br />

Anthropology he says that ‘‘<strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> obscure ideas belongs only to<br />

physiological ... anthropology’’ (VII: 136), suggesting that although<br />

<strong>the</strong>se may be inaccessible to investigation a priori, <strong>and</strong> hence beyond <strong>the</strong><br />

reach <strong>of</strong> critique, still <strong>the</strong>re is room for empirical study <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se phenomena.<br />

12 This view is completely compatible with transcendental idealism<br />

<strong>and</strong> also in keeping with <strong>the</strong> naturalist side <strong>of</strong> Novalis’<br />

Romanticizing program.<br />

That <strong>Kant</strong>’s work could be seen as deflationary, a bringing down to<br />

earth, or naturalizing <strong>of</strong> metaphysical <strong>and</strong> previously mysterious notions,<br />

ought not to be too surprising, <strong>of</strong> course. More strange, <strong>and</strong> certainly<br />

more likely to <strong>of</strong>fend traditional <strong>Kant</strong>-scholarly sensibilities, is <strong>the</strong> suggestion<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong> performed <strong>the</strong> ‘‘romantic operation’’ in <strong>the</strong> first sense<br />

outlined by Novalis. Can it plausibly be maintained that <strong>Kant</strong> ‘‘made <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> ordinary <strong>and</strong> commonplace something mystical <strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ound?’’ We<br />

have only to consider, for a start, <strong>the</strong> extent to which <strong>Kant</strong>’s project<br />

involved ‘‘denying knowledge to make room for faith.’’ I argue in chapter 4<br />

that contemporary <strong>Kant</strong>ians who take <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> practical reason to<br />

be <strong>the</strong> absolute center <strong>and</strong> determining focus <strong>of</strong> his philosophy go too far,<br />

but it is undeniable that <strong>Kant</strong>’s concern for this ‘‘unknowable’’ side <strong>of</strong><br />

human experience was a central concern. <strong>Kant</strong> devotes a great deal <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>oretical energy to explaining <strong>and</strong> analyzing moral judgment, yet he<br />

explicitly states that, morally speaking, <strong>the</strong> foundation <strong>of</strong> that investigation<br />

lies in <strong>the</strong> dignity <strong>and</strong> absolute worth <strong>of</strong> humanity as an end in itself.<br />

This is not to say that <strong>the</strong> recognition <strong>of</strong> individual human dignity is a<br />

mystical experience, but ra<strong>the</strong>r that, in <strong>the</strong> tradition <strong>of</strong> making what is<br />

most familiar into something that appears fresh <strong>and</strong> new, <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy<br />

‘‘re-enchants’’ our humanity, makes us marvel in awe at <strong>the</strong> ‘‘moral<br />

law within.’’<br />

Similarly <strong>Kant</strong>’s notorious ‘‘fact <strong>of</strong> reason,’’ ultimately allows <strong>of</strong> no<br />

explanation, practical or <strong>the</strong>oretical:<br />

12 I have examined this aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> creativity in two papers, ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

Apology for Sensibility,’’ delivered at <strong>the</strong> APA Pacific Division in New Orleans in 1999, <strong>and</strong> also in<br />

‘‘Fantasts <strong>and</strong> Fantasias: A <strong>Kant</strong>ian Theory <strong>of</strong> Imaginative Free Play,’’ delivered at <strong>the</strong> Evelyn<br />

Dunbar Early Music Festival Symposium, Northwestern University (February 2003). A discussion<br />

also appears in chapter 7 <strong>of</strong> this volume.


26<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

The consciousness <strong>of</strong> this fundamental law [<strong>the</strong> Categorical Imperative, <strong>the</strong><br />

moral law] may be called a fact <strong>of</strong> reason, since one cannot ferret it out from<br />

antecedent data <strong>of</strong> reason such as <strong>the</strong> consciousness <strong>of</strong> reason (for this is not<br />

antecedently given), <strong>and</strong> since it forces itself on us as a syn<strong>the</strong>tic proposition ‘‘a<br />

priori’’ based on no pure or empirical intuition. It would be analytic if <strong>the</strong><br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> will were presupposed, but for this, as a positive concept, an<br />

intellectual intuition would be needed, <strong>and</strong> here we cannot assume it. In order to<br />

regard this law without any misinterpretation as given, one must note that it is<br />

not an empirical fact, but <strong>the</strong> sole fact <strong>of</strong> reason, which by it proclaims itself as<br />

originating law (sic volo, sic iubeo)[This is my will <strong>and</strong> my comm<strong>and</strong>, from<br />

Juvenal: Satire]. (Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason, V:31)<br />

In o<strong>the</strong>r words, consciousness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> law is a given, <strong>and</strong> no account,<br />

transcendental or empirical, can suffice to explain it. <strong>Kant</strong> was no poet,<br />

but <strong>the</strong> few passages that come close to poetry in his work are those that<br />

refer to <strong>the</strong> dignity, <strong>the</strong> ‘‘jewel-like’’ radiance, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> good will in<br />

humanity. And although in contemplating <strong>the</strong> ‘‘moral law within,’’ <strong>Kant</strong><br />

allows his mind to ‘‘exp<strong>and</strong> into <strong>the</strong> mysterious reaches <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unknown,’’<br />

it is an expansion that any ordinary human being can accomplish, consciousness<br />

<strong>of</strong> which is a given.<br />

So even though in his <strong>the</strong>oretical work <strong>Kant</strong> clearly exemplifies <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘logorythmizing’’ or reductionist tendency <strong>of</strong> ‘‘natural philosophy,’’ his<br />

moral philosophy provides <strong>the</strong> complementary enlargement that completes<br />

<strong>the</strong> tw<strong>of</strong>old contraction – expansion dynamic <strong>of</strong> Romanticism<br />

described by Novalis. Properly understood, Novalis’ dictum covers <strong>the</strong><br />

critical philosophy in spirit <strong>and</strong> in letter: <strong>Kant</strong> made <strong>the</strong> unknown<br />

known, reducing cognition to functions <strong>of</strong> judgment discoverable to<br />

philosophical inquiry; <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> very process <strong>of</strong> humanizing <strong>the</strong> cosmos,<br />

he transformed <strong>the</strong> most intimate aspects <strong>of</strong> human nature into an<br />

unknowable but awesome thought: a ‘‘thing-in-itself.’’<br />

Of course, it may be objected that <strong>the</strong>re is a perfectly good sense in<br />

which all pathbreaking philosophy will qualify for <strong>the</strong> label ‘‘Romantic’’<br />

if taken in <strong>the</strong> sense just outlined, since all progress in philosophy may be<br />

understood as a kind <strong>of</strong> elevation <strong>of</strong> certain fundamental assumptions to<br />

‘‘foundational,’’ ‘‘original,’’ or ‘‘primitive’’ notions that remain unquestioned,<br />

while at <strong>the</strong> same time reducing <strong>and</strong> making ‘‘mundane’’ o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

phenomena that <strong>the</strong>n are explained by <strong>the</strong>se assumptions. In this sense,<br />

one could say that Descartes, Plato, even Hume, also ‘‘romanticized.’’ 13<br />

In response it may first <strong>of</strong> all be pointed out that indeed, on Novalis’<br />

13 I thank Michael Losonsky for first raising this objection, <strong>and</strong> also an anonymous reviewer at<br />

Cambridge University Press for making <strong>the</strong> same point.


<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism 27<br />

account, <strong>the</strong>y did. For Novalis, philosophizing is a variety <strong>of</strong> romanticizing,<br />

wherein we search for a ground, for an absolute:<br />

Philosophizing must be a unique kind <strong>of</strong> thinking. What do I do when I<br />

philosophize? I reflect upon a ground. The ground <strong>of</strong> philosophizing is thus a<br />

striving after <strong>the</strong> thought <strong>of</strong> a ground ... All philosophizing must <strong>the</strong>refore end<br />

in an absolute ground. Now if this were not given, if this concept contained an<br />

impossibility – <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> drive to philosophize would be an unending activity –<br />

<strong>and</strong> without end because <strong>the</strong>re would be an eternal urge for an absolute ground<br />

that can be satisfied only relatively <strong>and</strong> that would <strong>the</strong>refore never cease.<br />

Unending free activity in us arises through <strong>the</strong> free renunciation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolute –<br />

<strong>the</strong> only possible absolute that can be given us <strong>and</strong> that we only find through our<br />

inability to attain <strong>and</strong> know an absolute. This absolute that is given to us thus<br />

can only be known negatively, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as we act <strong>and</strong> find that what we<br />

seek cannot be attained through action ... This could be called an absolute<br />

postulate. All searching for a single principle would be like <strong>the</strong> attempt to square<br />

<strong>the</strong> circle. (#566)<br />

Novalis goes on to distinguish <strong>the</strong> activity <strong>of</strong> doing philosophy from<br />

Philosophy as product <strong>of</strong> that activity:<br />

Philosophy, <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> philosophizing, arises accordingly through interruption<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> drive towards knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ground – through st<strong>and</strong>ing still at <strong>the</strong><br />

point where one is. (#566)<br />

Hence all true philosophers are indeed driven by <strong>the</strong> same motive force,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir work will be characterizable as <strong>the</strong> attempt to reduce previously<br />

inflated notions to simple ones while at <strong>the</strong> same time simply assuming as<br />

given an ‘extraordinary’ point towards which that reduction is aimed, <strong>and</strong><br />

which itself cannot be proven or fur<strong>the</strong>r explained. Philosophizing is itself<br />

a conceptual version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> expansion <strong>and</strong> contraction process <strong>of</strong><br />

romanticizing. At least, it is until it becomes ‘‘Philosophy’’ – i.e. <strong>the</strong> point<br />

at which <strong>the</strong> philosopher ‘‘interrupts’’ herself, <strong>and</strong> claims to have finally<br />

found ‘‘<strong>the</strong> answer’’ <strong>and</strong>, in so doing, quits <strong>the</strong> activity.<br />

Thus, although in one interesting sense for Novalis, philosophers<br />

always ‘romanticize’ in <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir thought, <strong>the</strong>y also cease to do<br />

so at that point where <strong>the</strong>y declare that <strong>the</strong>y have uncovered or produced<br />

a systematic solution. <strong>Kant</strong>, like most philosophers, claimed to have<br />

found ‘‘<strong>the</strong> answer’’ in his Copernican turn <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> systems <strong>of</strong> cognitive<br />

<strong>and</strong> moral experience that eventuate from that turn, <strong>and</strong> perhaps to that<br />

extent he too ceased ‘‘romanticizing’’ in favor <strong>of</strong> ‘‘st<strong>and</strong>ing still at <strong>the</strong><br />

point where he was.’’ What is unique about <strong>Kant</strong>, <strong>and</strong> what connects him<br />

directly to Novalis <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> system-eschewing early Romantics in a way<br />

that o<strong>the</strong>r philosophers are not so connected, is that <strong>the</strong> revolution in


28<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

philosophizing that his approach articulated involved <strong>the</strong> self-conscious,<br />

methodical recognition <strong>of</strong> both <strong>the</strong> limitations <strong>of</strong> human knowledge (our<br />

inability to know ei<strong>the</strong>r nature or ourselves in <strong>the</strong>ir entirety), <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong><br />

same time <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ineliminable, natural human drive to surpass those<br />

limitations. In <strong>the</strong> third Critique, <strong>Kant</strong> explicitly takes on <strong>the</strong> project <strong>of</strong><br />

bringing <strong>the</strong>se two aspects <strong>of</strong> human nature toge<strong>the</strong>r in a coherent<br />

account. A particularly good example <strong>of</strong> his ‘‘romanticizing’’ here is <strong>the</strong><br />

use that he makes <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘supersensible’’ (das Übersinnliche)<br />

14 or what he earlier called <strong>the</strong> ‘‘noumenal.’’ In <strong>the</strong> third Critique <strong>the</strong><br />

idea <strong>of</strong> a substrate that underlies <strong>and</strong> makes possible objects <strong>of</strong> knowledge<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘‘good-willed’’ action is problematized, since, <strong>Kant</strong> worries,<br />

an immense gulf is fixed between <strong>the</strong> domain <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> nature, <strong>the</strong><br />

sensible, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> domain <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> freedom, <strong>the</strong> supersensible, so that no<br />

transition from <strong>the</strong> sensible to <strong>the</strong> supersensible ... is possible, just as if <strong>the</strong>y<br />

were two different worlds, <strong>the</strong> first <strong>of</strong> which is to have no influence on <strong>the</strong><br />

second; <strong>and</strong> yet <strong>the</strong> second is to have an influence on <strong>the</strong> first, i.e., <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom is to actualize in <strong>the</strong> world <strong>of</strong> sense <strong>the</strong> purpose enjoined by its<br />

laws. (V: 175–176)<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> goes on to argue that it must <strong>the</strong>refore be possible to think <strong>of</strong><br />

nature as amenable to our moral purposes,<br />

So <strong>the</strong>re must after all be a basis uniting <strong>the</strong> supersensible that underlies nature<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> supersensible that <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> freedom contains practically, even<br />

though <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> this basis does not reach cognition ... though it does<br />

make possible <strong>the</strong> transition from our way <strong>of</strong> thinking in terms <strong>of</strong> principles <strong>of</strong><br />

nature to our way <strong>of</strong> thinking in terms <strong>of</strong> principles <strong>of</strong> freedom. (V: 176)<br />

Odd as this language may sound, 15 <strong>the</strong> talk <strong>of</strong> a noumenal ‘‘realm that<br />

is unbounded but that is also inaccessible to our entire cognitive power’’<br />

should be understood, as <strong>Kant</strong> himself suggests, as simply an assumption<br />

which serves as a necessary basis for our ‘‘way <strong>of</strong> thinking [Denkungsart].’’<br />

We can think ‘‘in terms <strong>of</strong> principles <strong>of</strong> nature’’ (based on <strong>the</strong> assumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> something that is first given to experience that we can never know in<br />

itself) <strong>and</strong> ‘‘in terms <strong>of</strong> principles <strong>of</strong> freedom’’ (based on <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom, which we must postulate in order to act). The question posed<br />

14 Again, I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer at Cambridge University Press for this point.<br />

15 Werner Pluhar, in his Introduction to his edition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment makes <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> supersensible <strong>and</strong> its determinability into a Leitfaden (guiding thread) for interpreting <strong>the</strong> whole<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> book <strong>and</strong> its place in <strong>the</strong> Critical project. He begins with <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

reflective judgment in this regard, <strong>and</strong> points out that although <strong>Kant</strong> appears to be introducing three<br />

‘‘supersensibles’’ (whatever that could mean!) in this passage, he is suggesting ra<strong>the</strong>r three ideas <strong>of</strong> one<br />

supersensible (Pluhar, Translator’s Introduction, p. lxiii).


<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism 29<br />

by <strong>the</strong> third Critique is: ‘‘On what basis, can we move seamlessly in<br />

thought from one way <strong>of</strong> thinking to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r; from thinking in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

nature to thinking in terms <strong>of</strong> freedom?’’ Or, more accurately, how do we<br />

combine both ways <strong>of</strong> thinking to effect moral improvement in nature,<br />

including in our ‘‘natural’’ selves? 16<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s answer is complicated, indeed, ‘‘obscure’’ even by his own<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ards, as he admits in his Preface (V: 170). The ability to transition<br />

from one way <strong>of</strong> thinking to ano<strong>the</strong>r rests upon an experience <strong>of</strong> what<br />

appears to be nature’s purposiveness for <strong>the</strong> human mind, an experience<br />

that is itself nei<strong>the</strong>r cognitive nor moral, but contains elements <strong>of</strong> both. It<br />

is an experience that involves perception <strong>of</strong> nature, but that goes beyond<br />

immediate sensory input to linger over <strong>and</strong> play with <strong>the</strong>se perceptions in<br />

imagination. Such ‘‘play’’ makes no claims to know <strong>and</strong> no dem<strong>and</strong>s to<br />

act, but simply eventuates in a judgment that <strong>the</strong> object is beautiful, a<br />

claim that at its core expresses a feeling <strong>of</strong> pleasure that we derive from<br />

contemplating nature’s harmonious forms. This is a special pleasure, an<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective pleasure that for <strong>Kant</strong>, might be rooted in noumenal<br />

ground: ‘‘<strong>the</strong> basis that determines <strong>the</strong> judgment lies, perhaps, in <strong>the</strong><br />

concept <strong>of</strong> what may be considered <strong>the</strong> supersensible substrate <strong>of</strong><br />

humanity’’(V: 340). The supersensible ‘‘substrate,’’ or basis, is <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

counterpart to <strong>the</strong> cognitive <strong>and</strong> moral notions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thing-in-itself<br />

<strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> postulate <strong>of</strong> freedom. It is in essence tw<strong>of</strong>old, befitting its role<br />

as mediating ‘‘principle’’: It involves feeling that is disinterested (i.e. not<br />

self-interested), similar to <strong>the</strong> feeling <strong>of</strong> respect that <strong>the</strong> moral law elicits<br />

in us, <strong>and</strong> it also refers to nature, both in ourselves (pleasure is after all an<br />

animal sensation) <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> world around us.<br />

Details <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> connection between <strong>the</strong> moral <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

beautiful will be discussed in <strong>the</strong> chapters that follow. What is important<br />

here is <strong>the</strong> way in which <strong>Kant</strong> both demystifies <strong>the</strong> human being’s ‘‘two<br />

world split’’ by reference to a way <strong>of</strong> adjudicating reflectively, while<br />

recognizing at <strong>the</strong> same time <strong>the</strong> ultimate inscrutability <strong>of</strong> this process:<br />

As for <strong>the</strong> subjective principle – i.e., <strong>the</strong> indeterminable idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> supersensible<br />

in us – as <strong>the</strong> sole key for solving <strong>the</strong> mystery <strong>of</strong> this ability [<strong>the</strong> capacity to<br />

16 Felicitas Munzel’s book <strong>Kant</strong>’s Conception <strong>of</strong> Moral Character: The ‘‘Critical’’ Link <strong>of</strong> Morality,<br />

Anthropology, <strong>and</strong> Reflective Judgment (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1999) deals with <strong>the</strong><br />

issue <strong>of</strong> a ‘‘moral Denkungsart’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘moral Gesinnung’’ – <strong>the</strong> rational <strong>and</strong> sensible sides <strong>of</strong> human<br />

character – in great detail. Her focus is upon <strong>the</strong> positing <strong>and</strong> development <strong>of</strong> moral character in <strong>the</strong><br />

individual, but much <strong>of</strong> her discussion, some <strong>of</strong> which will be noted later in <strong>the</strong> book, is relevant to<br />

issues <strong>of</strong> reason’s unity with itself. Since her focus is on <strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> character in <strong>the</strong> individual, <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘external’’ problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human being with <strong>the</strong> world is not taken up in <strong>the</strong> same detail.


30<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

experience <strong>the</strong> beautiful <strong>and</strong> express it in a judgment <strong>of</strong> taste] concealed from us<br />

even as to its sources, we can do no more than point to it; but <strong>the</strong>re is nothing we<br />

can do that would allow us to grasp it any fur<strong>the</strong>r. (V: 341, emphasis added)<br />

Or, as Novalis would later say, such an idea is ‘‘just a little connecting<br />

hook used for hanging things on pro forma – it only appears [to connect<br />

things] – it just grasps a h<strong>and</strong>ful <strong>of</strong> darkness’’ (FS: #3, 6). It may be<br />

useful to recall a claim that <strong>Kant</strong> made much earlier, in discussing <strong>the</strong><br />

nature <strong>of</strong> human cognition in <strong>the</strong> deduction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> categories in <strong>the</strong><br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason. <strong>Kant</strong> here admits that his analysis must simply<br />

assume <strong>the</strong> independence, or ‘‘givenness,’’ <strong>of</strong> that which is intuited <strong>and</strong><br />

syn<strong>the</strong>sized by cognition:<br />

This peculiarity <strong>of</strong> our underst<strong>and</strong>ing, that it can produce ‘‘a priori’’ unity <strong>of</strong><br />

apperception solely by means <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> categories, <strong>and</strong> only by such <strong>and</strong> so many, is<br />

as little capable <strong>of</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r explanation as why we have just <strong>the</strong>se <strong>and</strong> no o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

functions <strong>of</strong> judgment, or why space <strong>and</strong> time are <strong>the</strong> only forms <strong>of</strong> our possible<br />

intuition. (B: 145–146)<br />

It is a given that we have an underst<strong>and</strong>ing that structures but is not <strong>the</strong><br />

original, controlling source <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sensible world. It is similarly a given ‘‘fact<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason’’ that we have a will that imparts to <strong>the</strong> sensible world <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong><br />

a supersensible rational-moral system (V: 43). What <strong>the</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> taste <strong>and</strong><br />

beauty add to <strong>the</strong>se unquestionable claims is a third ‘‘given’’ that mediates<br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r two: We are capable <strong>of</strong> sensible feelings, shareable with o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

human beings, <strong>of</strong> nature’s possible attunement to a supersensible rational –<br />

moral system. <strong>Kant</strong> assumes, ironically <strong>and</strong> (early) romantically, an<br />

extraordinary, unknowable purpose that is grasped in ordinary human<br />

feeling (a sensus communis aes<strong>the</strong>ticus). This feeling is <strong>the</strong> natural<br />

expression <strong>of</strong> supersensibility – <strong>and</strong> is <strong>the</strong> vehicle for our human ability to<br />

think from nature to morality <strong>and</strong> back again: It is at once both elevated<br />

<strong>and</strong> everyday.<br />

kant <strong>and</strong> rousseau<br />

Considerations <strong>of</strong> this sort will serve as an initial argument for <strong>the</strong> claim<br />

put forward in what follows: that aes<strong>the</strong>tic considerations shape <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

overall philosophical program, a program that is proto-romantic in many<br />

respects. Novalis’ philosophical insights are deeply indebted to <strong>Kant</strong>. The<br />

former’s romantic imperative, like <strong>the</strong> latter’s Enlightenment one, issued<br />

a challenge to philosophy to self-consciously present <strong>and</strong> carry out a<br />

new program. Precisely this self-consciousness characterizes <strong>the</strong> critical<br />

philosophical project, which was in <strong>Kant</strong>’s own mind, epoch-making. His


<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism 31<br />

‘‘mission,’’ stated explicitly, was to dethrone <strong>the</strong> queen <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sciences,<br />

metaphysics, <strong>and</strong> set up in her place a more humble ruling body, namely,<br />

<strong>the</strong> principles <strong>of</strong> human cognition in general. 17 At <strong>the</strong> same time <strong>Kant</strong><br />

recognized <strong>the</strong> inevitability <strong>of</strong> human striving for <strong>the</strong> absolute, for a final<br />

unification <strong>of</strong> knowledge under a single principle, <strong>and</strong> as we shall shortly<br />

see, embraced this striving to a far greater degree than Novalis himself<br />

would have allowed, if we take Novalis’ fragment from <strong>the</strong> observations<br />

on medicine <strong>and</strong> physics seriously.<br />

For all his anti-metaphysical posturing, <strong>Kant</strong> embraced <strong>the</strong> view that<br />

metaphysical ‘‘Schwä rmerei’’ has an important role to play in <strong>the</strong> development<br />

<strong>of</strong> human cognitive faculties <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> progressively better social<br />

institutions. We shall examine <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> enthusiasm <strong>and</strong> imagination in<br />

transforming society in what follows, especially in chapter 5. The first<br />

claim, that imaginative speculation might itself develop our abilities, is<br />

made in <strong>the</strong> First Introduction to <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, in a footnote to a<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> a transcendental definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> feeling <strong>of</strong> pleasure. The<br />

note will serve as something <strong>of</strong> a guiding thread in <strong>the</strong> chapters that follow.<br />

It deals with <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> why, in <strong>Kant</strong>’s words, ‘‘nature has given us <strong>the</strong><br />

predisposition to such fruitless expenditure <strong>of</strong> our forces as we see in<br />

empty wishes <strong>and</strong> longings (which certainly play a large role in human<br />

life).’’ <strong>Kant</strong> recognizes that human beings in fact <strong>of</strong>ten long for <strong>the</strong><br />

absolutely impossible. Such dangerous longings ‘‘are <strong>of</strong>ten nourished by<br />

novels <strong>and</strong> sometimes also by mystical presentations, similar to novels, <strong>of</strong><br />

superhuman perfections <strong>and</strong> fanatical bliss.’’ But even as he is attacking <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘Roman’’ (<strong>the</strong> novel, one <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s own cherished pastimes was reading<br />

<strong>the</strong>m) <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r devices <strong>of</strong> mystification, he is suggesting that such projects<br />

have a natural role to play in human intellectual development:<br />

It seem s to me that here, as in all else, nature has made wise provisions . For if we<br />

had to assure ou rselves that we can in fact produce <strong>the</strong> object, b efore <strong>the</strong><br />

present ation <strong>of</strong> it could determin e us to apply our force s, our forces woul d<br />

presuma bly remain largely unu sed. For usually we do not come to know what<br />

force s we have except by tryin g <strong>the</strong>m out. So nature has provided for <strong>the</strong><br />

connec tions betw een <strong>the</strong> determ ination <strong>of</strong> our force s an d <strong>the</strong> presentati on <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

object [to be <strong>the</strong>re] even before we know what ability we have, <strong>and</strong> it is <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

precisely this effort which to that very mind seemed at first an empty wish, that<br />

produces that ability in <strong>the</strong> first place. Now wisdom is obligated to set limits to<br />

17 See Frederick Beiser’s description <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s attack on metaphysics in ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s Intellectual<br />

Development: 1746–1781,’’ chapter I <strong>of</strong> The Cambridge Companion to <strong>Kant</strong> (New York: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1992).


32<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

that instinct, but wisdom will never succeed in eradicating it, or [ra<strong>the</strong>r] it will<br />

never even dem<strong>and</strong> its eradication. (XX: 231)<br />

This passage will be referred to again, <strong>and</strong> it is crucial to <strong>the</strong> arguments<br />

that follow in this book. <strong>Kant</strong> suggests here, first, that natural,<br />

‘‘instinctive’’ forces – forces not identified as rational – drive creativity<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> our cognitive capacities. The ‘‘power <strong>of</strong> imagination,<br />

that blind but indispensable function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul, without which<br />

we should have no knowledge whatsoever, but <strong>of</strong> which we are scarcely<br />

ever conscious’’ (A78/B103), is <strong>the</strong> force that makes human intellectual<br />

development possible. Imaginative striving – we might call it a kind <strong>of</strong><br />

‘‘straining to underst<strong>and</strong>’’ what appears impossible – allows us to<br />

recognize in <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n possibly to realize in practice what ‘‘seemed<br />

at first an empty wish.’’ Without this natural impulse surely no progress<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason is possible. It is this impulse that is also at <strong>the</strong> heart <strong>of</strong> Novalis’<br />

program, <strong>and</strong> constitutes <strong>the</strong> Romantic debt to <strong>Kant</strong>.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> was pr<strong>of</strong>oundly aware <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role that nature plays in human<br />

experience <strong>and</strong> progress. 18 Considering <strong>the</strong> source for <strong>Kant</strong>’s revolutionary<br />

turn in ethics, <strong>the</strong> Urromantic Rousseau, this should come as no<br />

real surprise. <strong>Kant</strong>’s Rousseauistic turn is well known, especially his<br />

famous claim in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Remarks’’ on <strong>the</strong> Observations on <strong>the</strong> Beautiful <strong>and</strong><br />

Sublime that reading Rousseau ‘‘set him straight’’ <strong>and</strong> taught him to<br />

honor humanity above all else. 19 Richard Velkley has made a strong case<br />

for <strong>the</strong> pervasive influence <strong>of</strong> Rousseau not only on <strong>Kant</strong>’s moral <strong>and</strong><br />

political views, but for his view <strong>of</strong> reason in general. 20 Velkley takes <strong>the</strong><br />

defining moment <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s project to arise from Rousseau’s characterization<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> reason as <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> relationship <strong>of</strong><br />

human reason to human happiness. If, as Rousseau so forcefully argues,<br />

becoming progressively more rational only makes us progressively more<br />

miserable (<strong>the</strong> more we know, <strong>the</strong> more we desire), <strong>the</strong>n how can <strong>the</strong><br />

development <strong>of</strong> reason as humanity’s ‘‘vocation’’ or destiny be asserted?<br />

Recognition <strong>of</strong> Rousseau’s problem with reason, Velkley argues, forces<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> to attempt a ‘‘<strong>the</strong>odicy <strong>of</strong> reason.’’ He argues that <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy<br />

is driven by <strong>the</strong> need for an account <strong>of</strong> Reason’s final purpose, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

18 No one, in my opinion, has argued more persuasively for this awareness, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> systematic<br />

connection <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s naturalism with his ethics than Allen Wood, in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Ethical Thought<br />

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).<br />

19 Ak XX: p. 44.<br />

20 Richard Velkley, Freedom <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> End <strong>of</strong> Reason: on <strong>the</strong> Moral Foundations <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critical<br />

Philosophy, (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1989)


<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism 33<br />

<strong>the</strong> need to articulate that purpose leads <strong>Kant</strong> on a quest for what Velkley<br />

calls ‘‘<strong>the</strong> teleological consummation <strong>of</strong> reason in a new legislation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

order <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul’’: an order that ‘‘proceeds in <strong>the</strong> direction’’ <strong>of</strong> ‘‘one form<br />

<strong>of</strong> human perfection’’ <strong>and</strong> that ‘‘can be achieved only through a certain<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> willing’’(p. 66). The need for a <strong>the</strong>odicy <strong>of</strong> reason, according to<br />

Velkley, leads <strong>Kant</strong> to assert <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> practical reason in <strong>the</strong>se<br />

terms: ‘‘The moral foundation <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s critical philosophy can be<br />

uncovered in <strong>the</strong> manner in which this ‘primacy’ determines <strong>the</strong><br />

content <strong>and</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> all inquiries belonging to <strong>the</strong> ‘criticism’ <strong>of</strong><br />

reason’’ (p. 2).<br />

This is a dramatic claim, to which I will return in chapters 2 <strong>and</strong> 4. At<br />

<strong>the</strong> very least, Velkley’s argument shows that <strong>Kant</strong>’s sense <strong>of</strong> urgency about<br />

<strong>the</strong> need for philosophy to justify reason as <strong>the</strong> final arbiter <strong>of</strong> truth owes as<br />

much to Rousseau as to Hume, <strong>and</strong> it is persuasive in making its case that,<br />

in important respects, <strong>the</strong> Rousseauian turn in his thinking was even more<br />

definitive <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s overal critical program. Rousseau’s worry about vindicating<br />

Reason as a final moral court <strong>of</strong> appeal was certainly a wakeup call<br />

for <strong>Kant</strong>, who had no intention <strong>of</strong> ab<strong>and</strong>oning <strong>the</strong> tribunal <strong>of</strong> reason as <strong>the</strong><br />

moral final court <strong>of</strong> appeal. On Velkley’s account, <strong>Kant</strong>’s moral philosophy<br />

takes on epic, (if not Quixotic) proportions consistent with a<br />

romanticizing <strong>of</strong> philosophy in <strong>the</strong> expansive direction. However, it does<br />

not follow from <strong>the</strong> centrality <strong>of</strong> this issue that <strong>Kant</strong>’s expansion <strong>of</strong> reason<br />

beyond <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical can be billed as <strong>the</strong> saga <strong>of</strong> his quest for <strong>the</strong> Holy<br />

Grail <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> reason, nor even as a quest to unify Reason under <strong>the</strong><br />

conception <strong>of</strong> an ideal <strong>of</strong> practical willing, as Velkley argues. In chapters<br />

that follow, I argue against reading <strong>Kant</strong> as identifying <strong>the</strong> ‘‘philosophic<br />

life’’ with ‘‘seeking <strong>the</strong> perfection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> will’’ (p. 66). In o<strong>the</strong>r words, it is a<br />

very different tendency in <strong>Kant</strong>’s later philosophical work that this book<br />

explores. <strong>Kant</strong>’s views on aes<strong>the</strong>tic (imaginative) reflection <strong>and</strong> its role in<br />

morality undermine single-focus, idealist readings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort Velkley<br />

advocates – i.e. readings that situate <strong>Kant</strong> at <strong>the</strong> foundation <strong>of</strong> Germanic<br />

philosophical system-building beginning with Fichte. Of course <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

conceptual <strong>and</strong> historic continuities, but <strong>Kant</strong> himself disowned <strong>the</strong><br />

Fichtean system <strong>and</strong>, I am convinced, would have disavowed <strong>the</strong> view<br />

<strong>of</strong> philosophy as an epic quest for <strong>the</strong> Holy Grail <strong>of</strong> a single, unifying<br />

teleological account <strong>of</strong> human nature. As Allen Wood puts it:<br />

For <strong>Kant</strong>, <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> philosophy is not (as it is for Hegel) to reconcile us to <strong>the</strong><br />

human condition. <strong>Kant</strong> thinks that as rational creatures our condition must be<br />

one <strong>of</strong> dissatisfaction, self-alienation, <strong>and</strong> endless striving. Philosophy should not


34<br />

try to transcend that condition but only to help us live with its inevitability, <strong>and</strong><br />

more important, to make progress in <strong>the</strong> painful tasks it sets us. 21<br />

This does not preclude that for <strong>Kant</strong>, as Wood also claims, <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophy ‘‘in an age <strong>of</strong> enlightenment is to make [rational collective<br />

ends] explicit <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n to look for social institutions <strong>and</strong> historical tendencies<br />

that promote <strong>the</strong>m.’’ 22 But <strong>Kant</strong>’s insistence on <strong>the</strong> regulative<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> all such accounts, <strong>and</strong> his increasing attention in <strong>the</strong> later<br />

Critical philosophy to <strong>the</strong> sensible <strong>and</strong> contingent conditions <strong>of</strong> moral<br />

judgment <strong>and</strong> human creativity is continuous, not with idealist systembuilding,<br />

but with <strong>the</strong> more modest <strong>and</strong> ironic approach <strong>of</strong> early German<br />

Romanticism. For all its insight into <strong>the</strong> connection <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy<br />

to Rousseau, I would disagree with Velkley’s central claim. A final<br />

<strong>the</strong>odicy <strong>of</strong> reason for <strong>Kant</strong> was never fully worked out, <strong>and</strong> for a very<br />

good reason: it could not be accomplished on <strong>Kant</strong>’s own terms. No<br />

concrete, ‘‘substantive’’ notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> Reason could ever be<br />

delivered solely by reason to itself. Reason can regulate but never, by<br />

itself, create <strong>the</strong>se ends.<br />

Although Velkley claims that <strong>the</strong> principle <strong>of</strong> reason’s final end, to be<br />

realized historically, is a regulative one not in conflict with individual<br />

choice (p. 162), <strong>the</strong>re are several places in <strong>the</strong> book that suggest that he has<br />

something more substantive in mind. He claims that ‘‘In light <strong>of</strong> this<br />

ideal,’’ all <strong>of</strong> reason comes under <strong>the</strong> legislation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> critical philosopher<br />

so as to secure <strong>the</strong> grounds for humanity’s unobstructed progress toward a<br />

final practical goal – <strong>the</strong> achievement <strong>of</strong> a definitive ‘‘culture’’ that<br />

embodies <strong>the</strong> ideal (p. 15), <strong>and</strong> he speaks <strong>of</strong> ‘‘<strong>the</strong> practical advance <strong>of</strong><br />

humanity toward a consummate ‘‘culture’’(p. 43). Towards <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

book (p. 161) he argues that, for <strong>Kant</strong>, reason must reshape human<br />

happiness itself: ‘‘<strong>the</strong> individual’s conception <strong>of</strong> happiness has not kept<br />

pace with reason’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘<strong>the</strong> individual is in great measure himself to<br />

blame if he is at odds with <strong>the</strong> species’ rational advance.’’ ‘‘Moral obligation<br />

taken in a very wide fashion, thus includes <strong>the</strong> effort to refine <strong>the</strong><br />

concept <strong>of</strong> happiness’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘The final system <strong>of</strong> culture must rest on a<br />

plan that dictates <strong>the</strong> mode <strong>of</strong> pursuing happiness if not its content ... A<br />

culture organized on a moral plan requires that happiness be grounded in<br />

rational self-activity <strong>and</strong> not in passive enjoyment.’’ There is certainly<br />

textual evidence in <strong>Kant</strong> to support this view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Highest Good, but it<br />

also ignores <strong>Kant</strong>’s views on <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> contemplative, aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

(passive?) pleasures – moments <strong>of</strong> happiness that are not ‘‘dictated’’ by<br />

21 Wood, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Ethical Thought, p.334.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

22 Wood, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Ethical Thought, p.309.


<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism 35<br />

pure reason, but partake in <strong>the</strong> contingencies <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world outside human<br />

control.<br />

Hence in <strong>the</strong> second Critique, at <strong>the</strong> very place where he also describes<br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘‘primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical,’’ <strong>Kant</strong> also feels obliged to resort to <strong>the</strong><br />

postulation <strong>of</strong> a higher power to lend hope to reason’s dem<strong>and</strong> that we<br />

strive for individual virtue <strong>and</strong> community justice. The chapters that<br />

follow explore <strong>the</strong> possibility that it was <strong>the</strong> inadequacy <strong>of</strong> this <strong>the</strong>ological<br />

turn as a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> motivation for human moral behavior that motivated<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s attempts in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment’’ to uncover,<br />

among <strong>the</strong> contingencies <strong>of</strong> human feeling <strong>and</strong> imagination, a more<br />

human ‘‘bridge’’ to <strong>the</strong> moral.<br />

I do not want to argue that <strong>Kant</strong> actually built <strong>the</strong> bridge, nor that an<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> moral development can be entirely successful. Whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

<strong>the</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> beauty in all its manifestations<br />

can indeed resolve <strong>the</strong> crisis is a matter for debate. It may be that<br />

in <strong>the</strong> attempted resolution to <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> making reason accountable<br />

to human nature <strong>and</strong> happiness, in <strong>the</strong> words <strong>of</strong> Lacoue-Labar<strong>the</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

Nancy, ‘‘an abyss opens where a bridge should have been built’’(p. 30). 23<br />

The point, however, is that <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy, especially as articulated in<br />

<strong>the</strong> third <strong>and</strong> final Critique, becomes a signpost pointing away from<br />

Fichte <strong>and</strong> rationalist–idealist resolutions to <strong>the</strong> problem. As Lacoue-<br />

Labar<strong>the</strong> <strong>and</strong> Nancy put it:<br />

in <strong>the</strong> absence <strong>of</strong> a subject whose self-presence is guaranteed by originary<br />

intuition <strong>and</strong> whose ma<strong>the</strong>sis <strong>of</strong> this first evidence organizes <strong>the</strong> totality <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> world more geometrico, <strong>the</strong> system as such, although it is<br />

deeply desired by <strong>Kant</strong> ... is continually lacking precisely where it is in greatest<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>. (p. 32)<br />

Their point is that <strong>Kant</strong>ian practical reason requires (‘‘desires’’) a systematic<br />

connection between nature <strong>and</strong> intellect if <strong>the</strong> human moral<br />

agent is to have an effect on <strong>the</strong> world (including upon her own character).<br />

But knowledge <strong>of</strong> a natural moral system (hence also, knowledge<br />

<strong>of</strong> our ‘‘moral substance’’) is impossible on <strong>Kant</strong>’s account. Denying<br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> this unified moral natural realm famously cleared a space<br />

for belief in it (since <strong>the</strong> denial also includes denial <strong>of</strong> knowing its<br />

nonexistence), but at <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong> rendering <strong>the</strong> moral furniture <strong>of</strong> this<br />

23 Philippe Lacoue-Labar<strong>the</strong> <strong>and</strong> Jean-Luc Nancy, trans. Philip Barnard <strong>and</strong> Cheryl Lester, The<br />

Literary Absolute: The Theory <strong>of</strong> Literature in German Romanticism (Albany: State University <strong>of</strong><br />

New York Press, 1988).


36<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

space intangible. <strong>Kant</strong> thus created a tension that is not resolved by <strong>the</strong><br />

postulation <strong>of</strong> freedom, God, <strong>and</strong> immortality. In explaining <strong>the</strong> link<br />

between <strong>the</strong> third Critique <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> early German Romantics, Lacoue-<br />

Labar<strong>the</strong> <strong>and</strong> Nancy continue:<br />

this ‘‘subject’’ <strong>of</strong> morality can only be defined negatively, as a subject that is not<br />

<strong>the</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> knowledge ... as a subject without ma<strong>the</strong>sis, even <strong>of</strong> itself. It is<br />

indeed posited as freedom, <strong>and</strong> freedom is <strong>the</strong> locus <strong>of</strong> ‘‘self-consciousness.’’ But<br />

this does not imply that <strong>the</strong>re is any cognition – or even consciousness – <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom, for freedom in turn is posited only as ratio essendi <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral law<br />

within us, which, because it is only a fact ... can provide only a ratio cognoscendi<br />

<strong>of</strong> freedom, which produces no cognition. This fact (<strong>the</strong> imperative, <strong>the</strong> universality<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> law) is nei<strong>the</strong>r an intuition nor a concept. As a moral subject, in<br />

sum, <strong>the</strong> subject recovers none <strong>of</strong> its substance. (p. 31)<br />

In o<strong>the</strong>r words, early Romantic doubts about <strong>the</strong> analyzability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘I’’ –<br />

that is, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human subject, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir concomitant skepticism about a<br />

final, total system within which it resides, are continuations <strong>of</strong> a trajectory<br />

set by <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy, not a break with it. Interpretations that fix <strong>Kant</strong><br />

within <strong>the</strong> Idealist tradition ignore this trajectory.<br />

Never<strong>the</strong>less, focussing as Velkley does on Rousseau’s problematizing<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason <strong>and</strong> its impact on <strong>Kant</strong> helps make sense <strong>of</strong> aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory that formalist readings ignore. 24 <strong>Kant</strong>’s acknowledged<br />

<strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ound debt to that earliest <strong>of</strong> early romantics is certainly a driving<br />

force, but not, I argue, behind an attempt to unify reason in a single<br />

teleological principle. Rousseau’s insight, I would suggest, spurred him to<br />

exp<strong>and</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tics beyond <strong>the</strong> conventional <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> ‘‘taste’’ towards a<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> imagination as a creative force in human motivation <strong>and</strong> in<br />

nature. Whatever o<strong>the</strong>r influences it had on his contemporaries <strong>and</strong><br />

successors in German philosophy, <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy, especially his aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory with its pathbreaking new view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination,<br />

contained <strong>the</strong> seeds <strong>of</strong> early German Romanticism. As such it continued<br />

to propagate a strain <strong>of</strong> German moral philosophizing that had been<br />

developed throughout <strong>the</strong> century by philosophers <strong>and</strong> literary <strong>the</strong>orists<br />

24 Reception <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tics in <strong>the</strong> mid-twentieth century focussed on <strong>Kant</strong>’s arguments for a<br />

disinterested attitude on <strong>the</strong> part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> judging subject, <strong>and</strong> on definition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic object<br />

purely in terms <strong>of</strong> its formal characteristics (design, figure, etc.). It tended to ignore or dismiss<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> text that struggled to connect aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection with moral interest <strong>and</strong><br />

feeling. Donald Crawford’s work, as well as that <strong>of</strong> Paul Guyer, began to move analytic approaches<br />

to <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tics towards a more serious analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se sections <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third Critique. Donald<br />

Crawford, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Theory (Madison: University <strong>of</strong> Wisconsin Press, 1974); Paul Guyer,<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> claims <strong>of</strong> Taste (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1979).


<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Romanticism 37<br />

who saw <strong>the</strong> potential for enlightening <strong>the</strong> populace through art. In<br />

chapter 2, I examine aspects <strong>of</strong> this pre-history in Germany, <strong>and</strong> argue for<br />

reading <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom as being <strong>of</strong> a piece with his<br />

German predecessors. Their concerns for human emancipation through<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic education were certainly an important influence, like that <strong>of</strong><br />

Rousseau, on <strong>Kant</strong>’s own views <strong>of</strong> human nature <strong>and</strong> morality.


chapter 2<br />

The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom<br />

Just as <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> freedom is central to <strong>the</strong> political <strong>and</strong> moral<br />

philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Enlightenment, it is also important to <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> this period. This is clearly true <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> German Enlightenment.<br />

Beginning with Baumgarten, <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> autonomy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination<br />

in aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment <strong>and</strong> artistic production becomes an<br />

essential feature <strong>of</strong> German aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory, culminating in <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

detailed account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free activity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination in judgments<br />

about <strong>the</strong> beautiful.<br />

A study <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s notion <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom also reveals a continuity<br />

in German philosophy from Lessing to Schiller that is not apparent in o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

approaches to his aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory. That is, in spite <strong>of</strong> an apparent break with<br />

<strong>the</strong> German enlightenment tradition created by <strong>Kant</strong>’s insistence that<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tics is essentially irrelevant to morality, his account <strong>of</strong> imaginative<br />

freedom suggests <strong>the</strong> possibility that political <strong>and</strong> moral progress may be<br />

intimately connected with our ability to make universally valid aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

judgments. This in turn suggests that <strong>Kant</strong>’s system left room for an<br />

‘‘enlightened’’ commitment to <strong>the</strong> view that our experience <strong>of</strong> beauty <strong>and</strong><br />

art may have an indispensable role to play in our moral improvement.<br />

In what follows, I first briefly trace <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong><br />

imaginative freedom from Baumgarten to Lessing <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n go on to outline<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> this concept. In <strong>the</strong> last section I argue that <strong>Kant</strong>’s account<br />

<strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom provides a solution to <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> how reason<br />

can comm<strong>and</strong> us to strive to bring about <strong>the</strong> highest good – that is, a moral<br />

world – on earth. I conclude by suggesting that in view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibilities<br />

that his notion <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom hold out to morality, <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory may be seen as a ‘‘missing link’’ between Lessing’s views on <strong>the</strong><br />

didactic nature <strong>of</strong> art <strong>and</strong> Schiller’s views on aes<strong>the</strong>tic education. 1<br />

1 Lewis White Beck first suggested <strong>the</strong> phrase <strong>and</strong> provided much helpful advice in improving earlier<br />

drafts <strong>of</strong> this chapter. I am also grateful to members <strong>of</strong> James Schmidt’s NEH 1989 summer seminar<br />

38


The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom 39<br />

imaginative freedom from baumgarten to kant<br />

Aes<strong>the</strong>tics as a distinct philosophical discipline was first developed, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> term ‘‘aes<strong>the</strong>tics’’ first coined, by Alex<strong>and</strong>er Gottlieb Baumgarten, a<br />

student <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rationalist philosopher Christian Wolff. Although Baumgarten<br />

was a loyal disciple <strong>of</strong> Wolff <strong>and</strong> a committed rationalist, he<br />

never<strong>the</strong>less argued that <strong>the</strong>re was a need within this tradition for an<br />

account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> logic <strong>of</strong> judgments about sensation. For Wolff’s philosophical<br />

predecessor, Leibniz, sense perception was too unclear <strong>and</strong> indistinct<br />

to give rise to a systematic structure <strong>of</strong> its own. In Leibniz’s words:<br />

‘‘Taste as distinguished from underst<strong>and</strong>ing consists <strong>of</strong> confused perceptions,<br />

for which one cannot give an adequate reason. It is something<br />

like an instinct.’’ 2 For Wolff, too, sensation is only confused perception<br />

<strong>and</strong> hence belongs to <strong>the</strong> ‘‘lower’’ cognitive faculties. To <strong>the</strong> extent that<br />

sense perception exhibits order, it is for <strong>the</strong>se philosophers imposed from<br />

‘‘above’’ by reason. The problem, as Baumgarten saw it, was that sensory<br />

knowledge in <strong>the</strong> rationalist tradition is thus ei<strong>the</strong>r equated with something<br />

like instinct (<strong>and</strong> is not knowledge at all) or is seen as an inferior<br />

species <strong>of</strong> knowledge.<br />

Baumgarten was a poet as well as a philosopher, <strong>and</strong> he wanted to<br />

secure for art an objective validity <strong>and</strong> a claim to truth that was equal to<br />

that <strong>of</strong> cognition. In his Meditationes Philosophicae ... (Reflections on<br />

Poetry), published in 1735, Baumgarten claimed that <strong>the</strong> so-called lower<br />

faculties <strong>of</strong> sensation, memory, <strong>and</strong> imagination had a logic <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir own<br />

analogous to, but not identical with, that <strong>of</strong> reason. 3 Reason’s method<br />

involves making sensations clear <strong>and</strong> distinct through abstraction, definition,<br />

<strong>and</strong> demonstration. But beauty is destroyed by <strong>the</strong> tools <strong>of</strong> reason<br />

precisely because <strong>the</strong>se processes minimize <strong>the</strong> sensuous, concrete, <strong>and</strong><br />

individual nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> beautiful. The ‘‘analogon <strong>of</strong> reason,’’ as Baumgarten<br />

called <strong>the</strong> combined faculties <strong>of</strong> sensation, memory, <strong>and</strong> imagination,<br />

has a logic <strong>of</strong> its own specific to judgments <strong>of</strong> beauty <strong>and</strong> free<br />

‘‘What is Enlightenment?’’ for fur<strong>the</strong>r commenting on <strong>the</strong> chapter <strong>and</strong> encouraging me to pursue<br />

<strong>the</strong> argument outlined here. Finally, I am grateful to John Fisher <strong>and</strong> Rudolf Makkreel for valuable<br />

criticisms <strong>and</strong> suggestions.<br />

2 ‘‘Le goût distingué de l’entendement consiste dans les perceptions confusés, dont on ne saurait assez<br />

rendre raison. C’est quelque chose d’approchant de l’instinct’’ (Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz,<br />

Philosophische Schriften, ed. C. I. Gerhardt [Berlin, 1875–90], III, 420); trans. from Philosophical<br />

Papers <strong>and</strong> Letters, ed. <strong>and</strong> trans. Leroy Loemker (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1956), II,<br />

1031.<br />

3 Alex<strong>and</strong>er G. Baumgarten, Meditationes Philosophicae de Nonnullis ad Poema Pertinentibus (Halle,<br />

1735), trans. K. Aschenbrenner <strong>and</strong> ed. W. B. Hol<strong>the</strong>r as Reflections on Poetry (Berkeley: University<br />

<strong>of</strong> California Press, 1954).


40<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

from <strong>the</strong> laws <strong>of</strong> abstraction, definition, <strong>and</strong> demonstration that reason<br />

imposes on cognition. 4 Thus <strong>the</strong> birth <strong>of</strong> rationalist aes<strong>the</strong>tics in<br />

Baumgarten’s philosophy clears <strong>the</strong> way for a philosophical account <strong>of</strong><br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment in which exemption from <strong>the</strong> constraints <strong>of</strong> cognitive<br />

judgment is a dominant <strong>the</strong>me.<br />

The movement in German philosophy for <strong>the</strong> emancipation <strong>of</strong> beauty<br />

from cognition was an echo <strong>of</strong> what had begun earlier in German literary<br />

circles. Bodmer <strong>and</strong> Breitinger, <strong>the</strong> so-called ‘‘Swiss Critics <strong>of</strong> Zurich,’’<br />

had been critical <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rule-fetishism <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ruling rationalist literary <strong>and</strong><br />

dramatic <strong>the</strong>ory associated especially with J. C. Gottsched. Gottsched<br />

took his task to be <strong>the</strong> improvement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> German literary niveau, <strong>and</strong><br />

to that end he rigidly applied rules originally laid down by Horace <strong>and</strong><br />

Aristotle <strong>and</strong> adapted by recent French aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>orists such as Boileau.<br />

Gottsched’s insistence on a literal application <strong>of</strong> classicist rules led to such<br />

absurd prescriptions as, for instance, banning monologues (‘‘‘Intelligent<br />

people are careful not to speak aloud when <strong>the</strong>y are alone’’) <strong>and</strong> asides<br />

(‘‘It is <strong>the</strong>n as if those present had lost <strong>the</strong>ir hearing for this short time’’)<br />

on <strong>the</strong> grounds that <strong>the</strong>y were ‘‘unnatural’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘improbable.’’ 5 Exclusive<br />

emphasis on ‘‘reasonableness’’ (Vernünftigkeit) <strong>and</strong> insistence on following<br />

specific rules was taken by Gottsched’s critics to be a denial <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

importance <strong>of</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> artistic creativity. Bodmer <strong>and</strong> Breitinger,<br />

like Baumgarten, remained rationalists. That is, <strong>the</strong>y did not deny<br />

<strong>the</strong> need for rulegovernedness in aes<strong>the</strong>tic experience <strong>and</strong> creation, but<br />

<strong>the</strong>y believed that <strong>the</strong> imagination <strong>of</strong> both artist <strong>and</strong> critic could <strong>and</strong><br />

should be free to play a greater role in art <strong>and</strong> criticism. 6<br />

By far <strong>the</strong> greatest exponent <strong>of</strong> artistic freedom in Germany, however,<br />

was Gotthold Ephraim Lessing. He is perhaps better known for his<br />

advocacy <strong>of</strong> religious freedom <strong>and</strong> tolerance in such works as Die<br />

Erziehung des Menschengeschlechts <strong>and</strong> Nathan der Weise, but aes<strong>the</strong>tic as<br />

well as religious freedom was extremely important to him. In terms <strong>of</strong> his<br />

personal philosophical development, <strong>the</strong> literary arguments came first<br />

4 Alex<strong>and</strong>er G. Baumgarten, Aes<strong>the</strong>tica (Hildesheim, 1961), Sect. I <strong>and</strong> 555–565. Cf. also Lewis White<br />

Beck, Early German Philosophy: <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> his Predecessors (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press <strong>of</strong><br />

Harvard University Press, 1969), pp. 279–280.<br />

5 ‘‘Kluge Leute aber pflegen nicht laut zu reden, wenn sie allein sind’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘es wäre denn, dass die<br />

anwesende Person auf eine so kurze Zeit ihr Gehör verloren hatte’’ (J. C. Gottsched, Versuch einer<br />

Critischen Dichtkunst: Ausgewählte Werke, eds. Joachim Birke <strong>and</strong> Birgitte Birke [New York, 1973],<br />

p. 353).<br />

6 Cf. J. J. Bodmer <strong>and</strong> J. J. Breitinger, Von dem Einfluss und Gebrauche der Einbildungs-Kraft; Zur<br />

Ausbesserung des Geschmackes; Genaue Untersuchung Aller Arten Beschreibungen, Worinne die<br />

ausserlesenste Stellen der berühmtesten Poeten dieser Zeit mit gründtlicher Freyheit beur<strong>the</strong>ilt werden<br />

(Frankfurt, 1727).


The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom 41<br />

<strong>and</strong>, I would argue, helped shape his later works on religion. Lessing, like<br />

Bodmer <strong>and</strong> Breitinger before him, reacted sharply to <strong>the</strong> excessive<br />

rationalism <strong>of</strong> German literary <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>and</strong> his polemics against Gottsched<br />

are well known. Great art, Lessing argues, is <strong>the</strong> result not <strong>of</strong><br />

following recipes but <strong>of</strong> genius, <strong>and</strong> genius is its own rule. In his famous<br />

‘‘Seventeenth Letter on Literature’’ published in a series that ran from<br />

1759 to 1760, Lessing argues that <strong>the</strong> Germans, ra<strong>the</strong>r than looking to <strong>the</strong><br />

overly ‘‘delicate’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘polite’’ drama <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> French, would do better to<br />

turn <strong>the</strong>ir attention to British drama, especially to Shakespeare, whose<br />

genius lay in his ability to excite passion in his audience. 7<br />

Thus Lessing entered <strong>the</strong> fray in <strong>the</strong> debate over <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> rules in<br />

artistic production <strong>and</strong> criticism, <strong>and</strong> he went far beyond Baumgarten<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Swiss critics in urging <strong>the</strong> centrality <strong>of</strong> feeling to art <strong>and</strong> insisting<br />

on <strong>the</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> artist to arouse feeling in whatever manner was<br />

most effective. 8 In <strong>the</strong> Laokoon, published in 1766, Lessing argues that <strong>the</strong><br />

poet ought to evoke feelings by whatever would require <strong>the</strong> reader to use<br />

his or her imagination. The means available to <strong>the</strong> painter are different<br />

from those <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> poet; <strong>the</strong> painter works with bodies in space, <strong>the</strong> poet<br />

with events in time. But <strong>the</strong> end goal <strong>of</strong> both painter <strong>and</strong> poet is to<br />

produce in <strong>the</strong> audience an imaginative response. ‘‘That alone is fruitful,’’<br />

Lessing says, ‘‘which allows <strong>the</strong> imagination free play.’’ 9 For Lessing,<br />

imaginative freedom is important because it allows for <strong>the</strong> strongest<br />

possible emotional response to a work <strong>of</strong> art. Since for Lessing imaginative<br />

freedom is also <strong>the</strong> key to <strong>the</strong> success <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> artist, to insist on<br />

mechanical application <strong>of</strong> rules in art is not to improve it but to guarantee<br />

its continued mediocrity. And yet Lessing does not go so far as to say that<br />

artistic genius is subject to no rule, but ra<strong>the</strong>r that genius has its own<br />

inner logic. He says: ‘‘Not every critic is a genius, but every genius is a<br />

born critic. Genius has <strong>the</strong> pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> all rules within itself.’’ 10 Genius<br />

demonstrates its autonomy not by ignoring all rules, but by deriving <strong>the</strong><br />

rules from itself. Sensation (Empfindung) <strong>and</strong> intuitive knowledge must<br />

be capable <strong>of</strong> being expressed in words – <strong>of</strong> being generalized – if genius<br />

7 Gotthold Ephraim Lessing, Briefe. Die neueste Literatur betreffend (1759), Werke, ed. Herbart G.<br />

Göpfert (Munich, 1973), V: 71ff.<br />

8 Indeed, <strong>the</strong> Laokoon may be read as primarily a plea for <strong>the</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> poet from <strong>the</strong><br />

emotional constraints <strong>of</strong> Winckelmann’s neo-classicism.<br />

9 Lessing, Laokoon, Werke, ed. Herbart G. Göpfert (Munich: x, 1973), VI, 25–26, Sect. III: ‘‘Das<br />

jenige aber nur allein ist fruchtbar, was der Einbildungskraft freies Spiel lässt.’’<br />

10 Lessing, Hamburgische Dramaturgie, Werke, ed. Herbart G. Göpfert (Munich: x, xxxx), IV, no. 96,<br />

673. ‘‘Nicht jeder Kunstrichter ist Genie; aber jedes Genie ist ein geborner Kunstrichter. Es hat die<br />

Probe aller Regeln in sich.’’


42<br />

is to improve on its own first attempts: ‘‘Who reasons correctly also<br />

invents, <strong>and</strong> who wishes to invent must be able to reason.’’ 11 Thus Lessing<br />

by no means rejects rationalist aes<strong>the</strong>tics altoge<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong> for Lessing as<br />

much as for <strong>the</strong> rationalists <strong>the</strong> final purpose <strong>of</strong> art is education.<br />

Lessing’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> autonomy <strong>of</strong> genius bears some resemblance to<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> moral freedom, according to which <strong>the</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

individual consists not in ignoring law but in giving <strong>the</strong> law to oneself as a<br />

rational being <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby to all rational creatures generally. On Lessing’s<br />

account, genius follows its own law but in such a way as to be able to<br />

communicate its inventions with its audience. Given Lessing’s strong<br />

conviction that art should educate, one might expect to find in his <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

some sort <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic counterpart to <strong>Kant</strong>’s categorical imperative for<br />

morals. Nothing <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> kind, however, is to be discovered. Lessing’s<br />

famous dictum, ‘‘The most sympa<strong>the</strong>tic person is <strong>the</strong> best person,’’ 12<br />

comes closest to giving generalized expression to his own first principle <strong>of</strong><br />

dramatic invention – that <strong>the</strong> writer should attempt to produce sympathy<br />

in <strong>the</strong> audience. Yet it is not stated explicitly as a formula universally valid<br />

for all artistic production; nor is this surprising, since Lessing was not<br />

concerned to produce a systematic aes<strong>the</strong>tic. 13 Although he believed that<br />

<strong>the</strong> goal <strong>of</strong> all art was to fur<strong>the</strong>r human moral progress, his more specific<br />

interests in dramatic <strong>the</strong>ory no doubt made <strong>the</strong> need for a detailed<br />

account <strong>of</strong> artistic imagination seem less urgent. Yet Lessing’s essentially<br />

rationalist belief in <strong>the</strong> didactic nature <strong>of</strong> art would seem to require that<br />

some such account be possible if <strong>the</strong> precise role <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tics in <strong>the</strong><br />

education <strong>of</strong> human beings is to be described. It is <strong>the</strong>refore somewhat<br />

surprising that this account first appears in <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>,<br />

where <strong>the</strong> view that art <strong>and</strong> beauty should serve <strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong> moral<br />

perfection is ab<strong>and</strong>oned. Never<strong>the</strong>less, it is not until <strong>Kant</strong> that <strong>the</strong><br />

creative possibilities <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom first receive detailed<br />

systematic treatment in German aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory.<br />

11<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

‘‘Wer richtig räsoniert, erfindet auch; und wer erfinden will, muss räsonieren können’’ (Werke, ed.<br />

Herbart G. Göpfert, IV, no. 96, 675).<br />

12 ‘‘Der mitleidigste Mensch ist der beste Mensch, zu allen gesellschaftlichen Tugenden, zu allen<br />

Arten der Grossmutt der aufgelegteste’’ (letter to Nicolai, November 1756, Werke, ed. Herbart G.<br />

Göpfert, IV, 163).<br />

13 Cf. a typical statement in <strong>the</strong> Hamburgische Dramaturgie Werke, ed. Herbart G. Göpfert, no. 95,<br />

670: ‘‘Ich erinnere hier meine Leser, dass diese Blätter nichts weniger als ein dramatisches System<br />

enthalten sollen. Ich bin also nicht verpflichtet, alle die Schwierigkeiten aufzulösen, die ich<br />

mache.’’ (Here I remind my reader that <strong>the</strong> last thing that I intend <strong>the</strong>se pages to contain is a<br />

dramatic system. I am <strong>the</strong>refore not obliged to solve all <strong>the</strong> difficulties that I create.)


The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom 43<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> moral freedom is well known. In <strong>the</strong> Foundations <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Morals <strong>Kant</strong> gives what he calls a negative <strong>and</strong> a positive<br />

account <strong>of</strong> this concept. On <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong> it means freedom from causation<br />

by <strong>the</strong> lower, sensuous desires; on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r it means freedom to<br />

act according to a law <strong>of</strong> practical reason that we give to ourselves as<br />

rational beings. 14 In <strong>the</strong> circle <strong>of</strong> concepts that make up <strong>the</strong> core <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

moral <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>the</strong> moral law st<strong>and</strong>s at <strong>the</strong> very center. However, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

says, aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective judgment has its own ‘‘territory,’’ within which,<br />

although not sovereign, it still enjoys freedom from <strong>the</strong> constraint <strong>of</strong><br />

administering laws <strong>of</strong> cognition <strong>and</strong> morality. 15 That is, in aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

reflection, judgment is not immediately subject to <strong>the</strong> legislation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing (i.e. to <strong>the</strong> categories). It is free <strong>of</strong> cognitive determination –<br />

it does not involve predicating empirical concepts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> object. Nor is<br />

judgment concerned directly with applying <strong>the</strong> Categorical Imperative in<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection. It is <strong>the</strong>refore free <strong>of</strong> moral determination: we may<br />

not ask, in <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> a purely aes<strong>the</strong>tic experience, whe<strong>the</strong>r or not<br />

this object is virtuous or promotes virtue. So although judgments about<br />

beauty must always be ‘‘directed to cognition in general’’ 16 <strong>and</strong> no activity<br />

based on aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment may violate <strong>the</strong> Categorical Imperative,<br />

judgment in its reflective capacity is not compelled to apply a rule <strong>of</strong><br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r cognitive or moral judgment. Moreover, aes<strong>the</strong>tic experience <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

beautiful is also free from what <strong>Kant</strong> calls ‘‘mere’’ subjectivity – that is,<br />

<strong>the</strong> desires <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> senses for immediate pleasurable response are not<br />

determining factors in <strong>the</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> beauty. Thus aes<strong>the</strong>tic freedom,<br />

like moral freedom, is characterized by a lack <strong>of</strong> determination by<br />

sensuous <strong>and</strong> selfish desires.<br />

The foregoing may be called <strong>Kant</strong>’s ‘‘negative account’’ <strong>of</strong> imaginative<br />

freedom. But <strong>Kant</strong> also has a positive account <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom,<br />

<strong>and</strong> it is here that <strong>the</strong> radical nature <strong>of</strong> this sort <strong>of</strong> freedom can be seen.<br />

For within <strong>the</strong> territory <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tics judgment takes a holiday from moral<br />

<strong>and</strong> cognitive work; no concepts must be applied, no comm<strong>and</strong>s must be<br />

followed. Our judgments about <strong>the</strong> beautiful are not determined by <strong>the</strong>se<br />

laws. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> an aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective judgment is determined<br />

solely by <strong>the</strong> ‘‘mental state in which we are when <strong>the</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

14<br />

Immanuel <strong>Kant</strong>, Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten. 4: 446; Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, V:<br />

28–29.<br />

15<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>, Kritik der Urteilskraft, V:177.<br />

16<br />

Cf. Section 9,V:217, <strong>and</strong> also Section 22,V:240–241, where <strong>Kant</strong> speaks <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘free lawfulness <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> imagination’’ (freie Gesätzmässigkeit der Einbildungskraft), <strong>and</strong> argues that imagination in pure<br />

judgments <strong>of</strong> taste is free from any compulsion to ‘‘proceed according to determinate law’’ but is<br />

not <strong>the</strong>reby self-legislating (autonomous).


44<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing are in free play.’’ 17 Imaginative free play may occur ei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

in ‘‘merely judging’’ <strong>the</strong> object in a wholly disinterested way, allowing my<br />

imagination to play freely with <strong>the</strong> forms that <strong>the</strong> object presents to<br />

perception; or it may occur in ‘‘productive’’ form in <strong>the</strong> artist, where it is<br />

used to produce <strong>and</strong> exhibit ‘‘aes<strong>the</strong>tic Ideas’’ – indeterminate ‘‘inner<br />

intuitions’’ that ‘‘prompt much thought’’ but cannot be grasped discursively.<br />

18 In both cases judgment determines its object in accordance<br />

with feeling ra<strong>the</strong>r than objective law. 19<br />

But what is <strong>the</strong> ultimate value <strong>of</strong> this radical freedom – this lack <strong>of</strong><br />

constraint described by <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tics? It is quite clear that moral<br />

freedom is priceless, as <strong>Kant</strong> would say. It has an absolute value as a<br />

necessary condition <strong>of</strong> virtuous behavior. But <strong>the</strong> time <strong>of</strong>f for free play<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong> grants <strong>the</strong> imagination within <strong>the</strong> carefully circumscribed territory<br />

<strong>of</strong> reflective judgment at <strong>the</strong> same time suggests a certain immaturity<br />

<strong>and</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> importance relative to those realms <strong>of</strong> human endeavor<br />

that are capable <strong>of</strong> self-governance <strong>and</strong> autonomy.<br />

To be fair, <strong>Kant</strong>, like Lessing, allows that beautiful art is valuable as a<br />

means to civilizing human beings (V: 433–434). Moreover, <strong>Kant</strong> believes<br />

that our experience <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> beautiful is social – that is, our interest in <strong>the</strong><br />

beautiful actually arises only in society, where <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> communicating<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic feelings exists (V: 296ff, V: 205n.). And although<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> argues that aes<strong>the</strong>tic experience does not make us more virtuous, he<br />

holds that respect for objects in nature may facilitate respect for our<br />

fellow human beings (V: 354). Never<strong>the</strong>less, at best it seems that for <strong>Kant</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> exercise <strong>of</strong> our imagination in aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> beautiful may<br />

socialize us by producing in us a sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> worth <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r human<br />

beings as part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural world. 20<br />

But it can <strong>and</strong> should be objected at this point that a feeling <strong>of</strong><br />

harmony produced in us by imagination’s freely reflecting upon <strong>the</strong><br />

beautiful <strong>and</strong> actually being free <strong>and</strong> in harmony with <strong>the</strong> world around<br />

17<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>, Section 9, V:217–218.: ‘‘der Gemüthszust<strong>and</strong> in dem freien Spiele der Einbildungskraft und<br />

des Verst<strong>and</strong>es.’’<br />

18<br />

Cf. Section 48, V:313 for <strong>the</strong> distinction between taste <strong>and</strong> artistic production, <strong>and</strong> Section 49,<br />

V: 313–314 for <strong>the</strong> introduction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic Ideas.<br />

19<br />

The sense in which feeling can be <strong>the</strong> determining ground <strong>of</strong> a judgment <strong>of</strong> taste is discussed in my<br />

article ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s Concept <strong>of</strong> Beauty,’’ History <strong>of</strong> Philosophy Quarterly 3 (1986): pp. 311–324.<br />

20<br />

In ‘‘<strong>Imagination</strong> <strong>and</strong> Temporality in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Sublime’’ ( Journal <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> Art<br />

Criticism 42 [1984], pp. 303–315) Rudolf Makkreel argues quite convincingly that <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> imagination’s judgments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sublime may play an important role in <strong>the</strong> integration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

faculties in <strong>Kant</strong>’s overall <strong>the</strong>ory. If I am correct, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> imagination’s function in making<br />

judgments about beauty must also have a key role to play in reintegrating imagination.<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing, <strong>and</strong> practical reason.


The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom 45<br />

us are two different things. Moral freedom is no illusion because it is<br />

based on a requirement <strong>of</strong> practical reason – it is necessary for <strong>the</strong> possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> any moral action whatsoever. But freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination<br />

on <strong>Kant</strong>’s account is <strong>the</strong> precondition only <strong>of</strong> our being able to look at<br />

<strong>the</strong> world as if it were orderly <strong>and</strong> in harmony with our underst<strong>and</strong>ing.<br />

Imaginative freedom does not constitute this order <strong>and</strong> harmony. In fact,<br />

as moral agents we are constantly faced with evidence that <strong>the</strong> natural<br />

world is not well ordered with respect to our best efforts. That is, we are<br />

regularly faced with <strong>the</strong> sight <strong>of</strong> moral virtue going unrewarded. It seems<br />

<strong>the</strong> best thing an imagination ‘‘at play’’ can <strong>of</strong>fer is a way <strong>of</strong> forgetting<br />

this fact for <strong>the</strong> time it takes us to judge an object in a wholly disinterested,<br />

‘‘playful’’ manner, since during <strong>the</strong> time in which we are contemplating<br />

<strong>the</strong> beauty <strong>of</strong> an object we are free from all interest. The<br />

judgment that something is beautiful is not made for <strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong><br />

producing an interest (V: 205n.). <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory is unique in <strong>the</strong><br />

Enlightenment ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it gives up <strong>the</strong> rationalist view that <strong>the</strong> ultimate<br />

purpose <strong>of</strong> art is <strong>the</strong> perfection <strong>of</strong> humanity. So <strong>the</strong> challenge for <strong>Kant</strong><br />

remains: Does <strong>the</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination have any value beyond<br />

providing a temporary respite from a morally hostile world?<br />

imagining <strong>the</strong> highest good<br />

Already in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason <strong>Kant</strong> shows some discomfort over<br />

<strong>the</strong> apparently unbridgeable gap that his philosophy creates between <strong>the</strong><br />

human being as a causally determined member <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sensible world <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> human being as a free member <strong>of</strong> an intelligible world or ‘‘realm <strong>of</strong><br />

ends.’’ The problem emerges here in <strong>the</strong> following form: practical reason<br />

tells me what I ought to do – i.e., what is moral – in <strong>the</strong> comm<strong>and</strong>: ‘‘Do<br />

that through which you become worthy <strong>of</strong> happiness.’’ But if I do so act,<br />

may I <strong>the</strong>refore hope to obtain happiness in this world? The answer must<br />

be ‘‘yes,’’ <strong>Kant</strong> says, for in our thinking about morality it is necessary ‘‘to<br />

assume that everyone has reason to hope for happiness to <strong>the</strong> extent to<br />

which <strong>the</strong>y have, through <strong>the</strong>ir conduct, become worthy <strong>of</strong> it ... The<br />

system <strong>of</strong> morality is <strong>the</strong>refore inseparably ... bound up with that <strong>of</strong><br />

happiness.’’ 21 In <strong>the</strong> intelligible world – a world <strong>of</strong> purely rational creatures<br />

– happiness would necessarily be proportionate with morality, since<br />

in such a world our only desire would be a rational one – namely, <strong>the</strong><br />

21 <strong>Kant</strong>, Kritik der reinen Vernunft A809/B837.


46<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

desire to be reasonable. In such a world moral freedom would itself be <strong>the</strong><br />

cause <strong>of</strong> happiness.<br />

But <strong>Kant</strong> immediately qualifies his claim that <strong>the</strong> hope for happiness in<br />

proportion to virtue is a necessary assumption with <strong>the</strong> reminder that<br />

‘‘such a system <strong>of</strong> self-rewarding morality is only an Idea, <strong>the</strong> carrying out<br />

<strong>of</strong> which rests on <strong>the</strong> condition that everyone do what <strong>the</strong>y ought’’ (A801/<br />

B838). Our moral obligations remain binding, however, even if o<strong>the</strong>rs do<br />

not behave morally; <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> natural world, where motives <strong>and</strong> forces<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r than reverence for <strong>the</strong> moral law are at work, <strong>the</strong>re is no guarantee<br />

that <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> our moral actions will be happy ones. So, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

concludes here, ‘‘The alleged necessary connection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> hope <strong>of</strong> happiness<br />

with <strong>the</strong> necessary endeavor to render <strong>the</strong> self worthy <strong>of</strong> happiness<br />

cannot, <strong>the</strong>refore, be known through reason.’’<br />

The existence <strong>of</strong> a moral world cannot be known, <strong>and</strong> yet in <strong>the</strong><br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason <strong>Kant</strong> tells us that obedience to <strong>the</strong> moral law<br />

requires that we adopt <strong>the</strong> highest good (summum bonum) as our goal,<br />

where <strong>the</strong> highest good is interpreted as ‘‘<strong>the</strong> systematic connection <strong>of</strong><br />

morality as <strong>the</strong> supreme good [bonum supremum] with <strong>the</strong> totality <strong>of</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r goods (summed up as ‘happiness’).’’ 22 In o<strong>the</strong>r words reason<br />

comm<strong>and</strong>s us to try to create <strong>the</strong> moral world on earth even though this is<br />

an end whose practical possibility cannot be known. If morality requires<br />

that we strive to bring about <strong>the</strong> highest good, <strong>and</strong> yet we cannot know<br />

<strong>the</strong> present or future existence <strong>of</strong> such a world, <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>Kant</strong> says, we must<br />

at least be able to believe it is possible to bring it about, for o<strong>the</strong>rwise <strong>the</strong><br />

moral law itself would be illusory: ‘‘If, <strong>the</strong>refore, <strong>the</strong> highest good is<br />

impossible according to practical rules, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> moral law which comm<strong>and</strong>s<br />

that it be fur<strong>the</strong>red must be fantastic, directed to empty imaginary<br />

ends, <strong>and</strong> consequently inherently false’’ (V: 114).<br />

Our hope to bring about <strong>the</strong> highest good can be founded only on a<br />

rational belief in its possibility; <strong>and</strong> this in turn is possible, <strong>Kant</strong> argues,<br />

only if we postulate <strong>the</strong> immortality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul (so that, since <strong>the</strong> highest<br />

good is conditional on <strong>the</strong> moral perfection <strong>of</strong> individuals, something<br />

that can be completed only in an ‘‘infinite progress’’ can be rendered<br />

practicable) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> a supreme being capable <strong>of</strong> seeing to it<br />

that <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> ends is actualized in a life hereafter (V: 122, 124).<br />

22 Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason, V:110–111. Allen Wood’s explanation (in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Ethical Thought,<br />

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> summum bonum in <strong>the</strong> second Critique is<br />

exceptionally clear <strong>and</strong> helpful in laying out <strong>the</strong> relationship <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept’s component parts. See<br />

chapter 9 Sect. 4.2, ‘‘The highest good,’’ pp. 311–313.


The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom 47<br />

This move is highly problematic within <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critical<br />

philosophy, however. First <strong>of</strong> all, it reintroduces into <strong>the</strong> heart <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

ethics fundamental concepts <strong>of</strong> speculative metaphysics that had been<br />

discredited by critical reason, a deeply inconsistent move on <strong>the</strong> surface <strong>of</strong><br />

it. We shall return to this issue in chapter 5. Lewis White Beck argues that<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> does loosen <strong>the</strong> strictures <strong>of</strong> critique at this point, allowing <strong>the</strong> truth<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> postulates a role in <strong>the</strong>oretical reasoning, if only a very small role:<br />

‘‘I think <strong>the</strong>re can be no doubt that he regarded his argument as an<br />

argument for that which was posited in this way <strong>and</strong> not merely as an<br />

argument for <strong>the</strong> necessity <strong>of</strong> this positing’’(p. 264), although Beck also<br />

points out that ‘‘all that <strong>Kant</strong>’s argument, if o<strong>the</strong>rwise valid, entails is <strong>the</strong><br />

necessity <strong>of</strong> making certain postulations as acts, <strong>and</strong> not <strong>the</strong> truth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

postulates thus made’’ (p. 263).<br />

Ra<strong>the</strong>r than accept this methodological inconsistency on <strong>Kant</strong>’s part, it<br />

is tempting to see <strong>the</strong> introduction <strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> immortality as strategically<br />

placating <strong>the</strong> reactionary forces coming to power in Prussia at that<br />

time. Thus, Frederick Beiser suggests that at a juncture in <strong>the</strong> Critical<br />

philosophy where <strong>the</strong>y might be seen as doing least ‘‘harm,’’ religious<br />

doctrines are used in a way calculated to put <strong>the</strong> censors <strong>of</strong>f <strong>and</strong> allow<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> to make <strong>the</strong> more pressing argument for freedom <strong>of</strong> speech. 23<br />

Certainly, as Beiser points out, <strong>the</strong> introduction <strong>of</strong> a supernatural power<br />

to hold out <strong>the</strong> promise <strong>of</strong> accomplishing what ought to be a human task<br />

constitutes a deep betrayal <strong>of</strong> his political values, suggesting that a just<br />

state can be accomplished only with <strong>the</strong> help <strong>of</strong> God, in <strong>the</strong> hereafter.<br />

Susan Neiman agrees that <strong>Kant</strong>’s postulation <strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> immortality<br />

amounts to an admission <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> impossibility <strong>of</strong> accomplishing <strong>the</strong><br />

comm<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral law to create a moral state within nature. She<br />

takes issue with claims, made by Velkley <strong>and</strong> Yovel, that <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

highest good is intended by <strong>Kant</strong> to be realizable in this world, even if<br />

only in <strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong> a long history towards progress. Neiman sees <strong>Kant</strong> as<br />

pr<strong>of</strong>oundly skeptical about <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> this realization. Even if<br />

human beings could manage to perfect <strong>the</strong>mselves as moral agents <strong>and</strong> do<br />

everything right, <strong>the</strong> cosmic injustice <strong>of</strong> natural evil remains to thwart our<br />

plans <strong>and</strong> dash our moral hopes <strong>of</strong> instituting <strong>the</strong> highest good within <strong>the</strong><br />

world <strong>of</strong> nature. At <strong>the</strong> same time, <strong>Kant</strong> recognizes that ‘‘restructuring<br />

human affairs according to [reason’s] laws would go a long way toward<br />

23 Frederick Beiser, Enlightenment, Revolution <strong>and</strong> Romanticism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard<br />

University Press, 1992). He calls it, <strong>and</strong> not without some justice, ‘‘a compromise with <strong>the</strong><br />

status quo’’ on <strong>Kant</strong>’s part, p. 53.


48<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

achieving it’’ <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore, she says, <strong>Kant</strong> ‘‘emphasizes’’ it. 24 Thus she<br />

argues that <strong>the</strong>re is simply an irresolvable tension in <strong>Kant</strong>’s critical<br />

philosophy that <strong>the</strong> invocation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ideal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest<br />

good <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> postulation <strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> immortality does not alleviate. The<br />

adoption <strong>of</strong> postulates <strong>of</strong> progress might serve better, Neiman argues, to<br />

solve <strong>the</strong> needs <strong>of</strong> practical reason for rational hope by ‘‘substituting faith<br />

in human progress for faith in God’’:<br />

Since rational faith does not concern <strong>the</strong> objects <strong>the</strong>mselves but our moral needs<br />

<strong>and</strong> capacities, <strong>Kant</strong> might well allow that <strong>the</strong> content <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> postulates could<br />

change while <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> argument for <strong>the</strong>ir necessity remained <strong>the</strong> same.<br />

Thus it might be <strong>the</strong> case that reason’s needs have changed to <strong>the</strong> point that we<br />

do not, two hundred years after <strong>Kant</strong>, need to represent to ourselves a personal<br />

God to sustain our moral convictions but can make do with some more general<br />

assumption. The extreme indeterminacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s postulate <strong>of</strong> God’s existence<br />

lends weight to this idea ... Might this very minimal postulation <strong>of</strong> God’s<br />

existence be replaced by <strong>the</strong> postulate that <strong>the</strong> world as a whole is progressing<br />

toward <strong>the</strong> best? There is some reason to think so. <strong>Kant</strong> connects <strong>the</strong> latter<br />

postulate with <strong>the</strong> former one <strong>and</strong> holds its assertion to be a need <strong>of</strong> practical<br />

reason. (p. 179)<br />

In o<strong>the</strong>r words, what matters to morality is not what we postulate so<br />

much as how we postulate it. Neiman argues that <strong>the</strong> postulates’ function<br />

is not to make truth claims about <strong>the</strong> world, but to regulate our attitude<br />

<strong>and</strong> consequent behavior. What matters is not that we assert <strong>the</strong> existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> some particular object (although, as Beck points out, in fact we do) but<br />

that we adopt an attitude or ‘‘Denkungsart’’ – a way <strong>of</strong> thinking – that<br />

involves trust or confidence in our own abilities. <strong>Kant</strong>’s definition <strong>of</strong><br />

rational faith in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Teleological Judgment’’ lends support to<br />

this interpretation:<br />

‘‘Faith (as habitus, not as actus [as attitude, not as an act]) is reason’s moral way <strong>of</strong><br />

thinking in assenting to what is not accessible to <strong>the</strong>oretical cognition. It is <strong>the</strong><br />

mind’s steadfast principle to assume as true what we must necessarily presuppose<br />

as a condition for <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> achieving <strong>the</strong> highest moral final purpose,<br />

<strong>and</strong> to assume this because <strong>of</strong> our obligation to this final purpose <strong>and</strong> despite <strong>the</strong><br />

fact that we have no insight into whe<strong>the</strong>r achieving it is possible (nor consequently,<br />

into whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> conditions are possible under which alone we can<br />

conceive <strong>of</strong> achieving that aim). (V: 471–472)<br />

24<br />

Susan Neiman, The Unity <strong>of</strong> Reason: Rereading <strong>Kant</strong> (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994),<br />

p. 178.


The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom 49<br />

Felicitas Munzel makes <strong>the</strong> parallel argument with respect to <strong>the</strong> conditions<br />

required for <strong>the</strong> perfection <strong>of</strong> character <strong>and</strong> rational faith, namely<br />

that character development requires putting our trust in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘promises’’<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason. In <strong>Kant</strong>’s Conception <strong>of</strong> Moral Character, she argues that <strong>the</strong> aim<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> postulates is steadfastness <strong>of</strong> character such that we may fulfill our<br />

duties to ourselves <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> world around us without faltering. Arguing<br />

that feeling will not do, Munzel defends <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong> rational faith <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> postulates is just <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> reflective principles <strong>of</strong> judgment<br />

– i.e., adopting belief in God’s existence or in our own immortality<br />

are simply applications <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> maxim <strong>of</strong> rational faith that <strong>Kant</strong> defines in<br />

<strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment. As she puts it:<br />

In view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral task, practical reason in a reflective mode <strong>of</strong> judgment avails<br />

itself, against <strong>the</strong> doubts raised through <strong>the</strong> failure <strong>of</strong> speculative attempts at<br />

demonstration, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subjective principle <strong>of</strong> ‘‘regarding as true what is inaccessible<br />

to <strong>the</strong>oretical cognition,’’ but necessary from a moral point <strong>of</strong> view. To<br />

do so is just what it means to have rational faith. (pp. 206–207)<br />

Munzel’s account skirts <strong>the</strong> issue <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> postulates make an<br />

existence claim <strong>and</strong> its attendant difficulties. Like Neiman, she sees <strong>the</strong><br />

issue as one <strong>of</strong> adopting an attitude or ‘‘conduct <strong>of</strong> thought’’: Adoption <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> postulates, on Munzel’s account, is <strong>the</strong> adoption <strong>of</strong> a ‘‘moral Denkungsart,’’<br />

or way <strong>of</strong> thinking in which <strong>the</strong> ‘‘human subject’’ makes a<br />

decision about how to think, not about <strong>the</strong> world, but about herself. In<br />

Munzel’s words, ‘‘she invokes <strong>the</strong> maxim <strong>of</strong> rational faith’’ <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

‘‘reconfirms’’ her moral resolve:<br />

What this renewed steadfastness consists in, what judgment has brought about, is<br />

a relationship <strong>of</strong> inner trust between practical reason <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> human agent, a<br />

trust that undergirds <strong>the</strong> proactive working toward <strong>the</strong> good by <strong>the</strong> morally good<br />

character in <strong>the</strong> world. (p. 213)<br />

The judgment made by <strong>the</strong> individual subject is, on Munzel’s account, a<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> contract or ‘‘promise’’ with her own practical reason: ‘‘it is an<br />

inner promissory note’’ with reason promising <strong>the</strong> realizability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

good in nature, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject accepting <strong>and</strong> responding to <strong>the</strong> promise<br />

by striving ‘‘steadfastly’’ to fulfill it. In essence, Munzel’s account sees <strong>the</strong><br />

postulates as <strong>the</strong> subject’s morally motivated leap <strong>of</strong> faith into <strong>the</strong> abyss <strong>of</strong><br />

human reason, an act <strong>of</strong> trust that energizes <strong>the</strong> mind for <strong>the</strong> long trudge<br />

down <strong>the</strong> road <strong>of</strong> moral rectitude.<br />

There is much to be said for this de-ontologized account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

doctrine <strong>of</strong> rational faith <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> postulates. It avoids <strong>the</strong> issue <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s


50<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

‘‘betrayal’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critical view <strong>of</strong> metaphysical speculation, <strong>and</strong><br />

emphasizes what was surely an important point for <strong>Kant</strong>, namely that if<br />

<strong>the</strong> moral law comm<strong>and</strong>s us to do something, we are necessitated to act,<br />

<strong>and</strong> that means adopting whatever conditions are <strong>the</strong>mselves necessary for<br />

that action. It is easy to move from Neiman <strong>and</strong> Munzel’s insight that <strong>the</strong><br />

conditions <strong>the</strong>mselves are not <strong>Kant</strong>’s concern so much as <strong>the</strong> attitude <strong>of</strong><br />

steadfastness that <strong>the</strong>y make possible, to <strong>the</strong> conclusion that <strong>the</strong> conditions<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves are internal: They involve setting up a relationship <strong>of</strong><br />

trust with one’s own reason. Faith in God on <strong>the</strong>se accounts becomes just<br />

one version <strong>of</strong> what is at bottom a faith in reason.<br />

As appealing as this move is, I think it misses one crucial aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

problem: <strong>the</strong> postulates, in order to work, must connect us to <strong>the</strong> world<br />

in all its contingent variability. It is after all this world that causes <strong>the</strong><br />

problem for reason, both with respect to developing our moral character<br />

over a lifetime <strong>and</strong> to developing a more just social environment over <strong>the</strong><br />

course <strong>of</strong> history. Whe<strong>the</strong>r in this world or <strong>the</strong> next, it is hard to see how<br />

any mere postulate <strong>of</strong> reason, whe<strong>the</strong>r as a belief in God <strong>and</strong> immortality,<br />

or in human progress in history, or as a pact with reason itself, really<br />

solves <strong>the</strong> problem for <strong>Kant</strong>, because <strong>the</strong> problem is not just one <strong>of</strong><br />

attitude, but <strong>of</strong> rational motivation: It is a matter <strong>of</strong> having good reason to<br />

imagine ourselves achieving what reason dem<strong>and</strong>s, <strong>of</strong> feeling that possibly<br />

we ourselves can accomplish a just world. I might decide to believe in<br />

God, try to believe in God, but if I don’t really feel or can’t imagine that<br />

God exists, <strong>the</strong>re is, on this view, no hope for me. It may be true that<br />

some people do feel God exists, <strong>and</strong> imagine that <strong>the</strong>y know God, but<br />

one person’s revelation is ano<strong>the</strong>r’s delusion, <strong>and</strong> no amount <strong>of</strong> moral<br />

comm<strong>and</strong>ing can force a feeling on <strong>the</strong> unbeliever. What is needed is<br />

really tw<strong>of</strong>old: First, some concrete, natural evidence that <strong>the</strong> world is<br />

rational <strong>and</strong> amenable to our moral projects, <strong>and</strong> second, evidence that<br />

we can, ourselves, accomplish <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> was painfully aware <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> such evidence in most <strong>of</strong><br />

human experience. Neiman correctly points out that <strong>Kant</strong> was no optimist,<br />

arguing that none<strong>the</strong>less for him ‘‘optimism becomes ... a moral<br />

obligation’’ (p. 181). But hope is not a purely rational attitude – it is an<br />

incentive, <strong>and</strong> incentives involve feelings. 25 Feelings cannot simply be<br />

adopted at will, much less rightfully comm<strong>and</strong>ed. True, <strong>the</strong> moral law<br />

25 That is, with one notable exception: <strong>the</strong> moral law can be an incentive, although ‘‘why it supplies<br />

an incentive’’ is an ‘‘insoluble problem for human reason.’’ But <strong>the</strong> moral laws’ effects can be felt<br />

<strong>and</strong> hence can be motivating in a negative way, since <strong>the</strong> suppression or eradication <strong>of</strong> feeling is<br />

also felt – as pain (V: 72–73).


The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom 51<br />

dem<strong>and</strong>s that we mortals strive to bring about <strong>the</strong> highest good, <strong>and</strong><br />

consequently our hope to achieve this end must rest on a belief in our own<br />

ability to do so. But it will not do merely to ‘‘postulate’’ that a God exists<br />

who will complete <strong>the</strong> task for us, or that we have an infinite amount <strong>of</strong><br />

time in which to accomplish our goal, since such a position amounts to<br />

admitting <strong>the</strong> hopelessness <strong>of</strong> our quest as mere mortals. 26 Finally, even<br />

(following Neiman’s suggestion) postulating as a regulative idea that ‘‘<strong>the</strong><br />

world as a whole is progressing toward <strong>the</strong> best,’’ remains a hopeless belief<br />

if we do not really feel that it is true. Reason’s comm<strong>and</strong>, <strong>Kant</strong> says, is that<br />

we strive to bring about <strong>the</strong> highest good here, in <strong>the</strong> world <strong>and</strong> on our<br />

own power. Unless we can imagine ourselves accomplishing progress for<br />

ourselves, sooner or later we will be overcome with despair over <strong>the</strong> Sisyphian<br />

dimension <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> task reason has set for us to accomplish. Lewis W.<br />

Beck’s somewhat dismissive position would thus appear to be <strong>the</strong> only<br />

friendly interpretative option: <strong>Kant</strong>’s claim that reason comm<strong>and</strong>s us to<br />

seek <strong>the</strong> highest good could amount to no more than a reiteration <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

comm<strong>and</strong> to obey <strong>the</strong> Categorical Imperative, <strong>and</strong> ‘‘[<strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

highest good] is not important in <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy for any practical<br />

consequences it might have.’’ 27<br />

It may be argued that postulating God’s existence does not relieve<br />

human beings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir duty to work for a better world here <strong>and</strong> now,<br />

because God is only postulated as <strong>the</strong> necessary ground <strong>and</strong> guarantor <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> our eventual success. Yirmiyahu Yovel argues this way in<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Philosophy <strong>of</strong> History: ‘‘At most, God helps us to help<br />

ourselves. The solution that <strong>Kant</strong> suggests to <strong>the</strong> antinomy is to be found<br />

in <strong>the</strong> ability not <strong>of</strong> God but <strong>of</strong> man, although man’s ability presupposes<br />

<strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> cannot be deduced from his own immanent<br />

characteristics.’’ 28 But, again, this is a solution to <strong>the</strong> antinomy only if we<br />

can give a plausible, genuinely motivating account <strong>of</strong> how it is possible<br />

that we ‘‘help ourselves’’ create a moral world. I want to suggest that<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment<br />

provides <strong>the</strong> material for such an account.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s purpose in introducing <strong>the</strong> postulates <strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> immortality<br />

was to provide a rational ground for our hope for <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

26<br />

John R. Silber, ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s Conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Highest Good as Immanent <strong>and</strong> Transcendent,’’<br />

Philosophical Review 68 (1959), pp. 474–475, makes a similar criticism <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s argument. See<br />

Allen Wood’s response to this article in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Ethical Thought, p.407, n34.<br />

27<br />

Lewis White Beck, Commentary on <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong><br />

Chicago Press, 1996), p. 245.<br />

28<br />

Yirmiyahu Yovel, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Philosophy <strong>of</strong> History (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980),<br />

p. 96.


52<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

bringing about <strong>the</strong> highest good, so that it is not, in Yovel’s words, ‘‘just a<br />

delusion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>of</strong> desire.’’ 29 But in <strong>the</strong> third<br />

Critique imagination is not treated as a faculty <strong>of</strong> illusion, but as a<br />

powerful creative faculty, a capacity to reform nature:<br />

For <strong>the</strong> imagination (as a productive cognitive power) is very mighty when it<br />

creates, as it were, ano<strong>the</strong>r nature out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> material that actual nature gives<br />

it ... In this process we feel our freedom from <strong>the</strong> law <strong>of</strong> association ... for<br />

although it is under that law that nature lends us material, yet we can process<br />

that material into something quite different, namely, into something that surpasses<br />

nature. (V: 314)<br />

Through imagination we are capable, in thought at least, <strong>of</strong> taking what<br />

nature gives us <strong>and</strong> working it up into ‘‘ano<strong>the</strong>r nature.’’ As natural<br />

physical beings we are bound by <strong>the</strong> laws <strong>of</strong> nature, as moral agents by <strong>the</strong><br />

law <strong>of</strong> practical reason, but as imaginative creatures we are constrained by<br />

nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> thus have creative power.<br />

This suggests that <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom in <strong>the</strong> third<br />

Critique <strong>of</strong>fers a solution to <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> grounding our belief in <strong>the</strong><br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> bringing about <strong>the</strong> highest good. The existence <strong>of</strong> a moral<br />

world presupposes agency that can bring it about, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> comm<strong>and</strong> to<br />

seek it presupposes that we can believe it possible through our own<br />

agency. Our ability to represent such a world in imagination would allow<br />

us to believe in <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> a moral world on earth <strong>and</strong> in ourselves<br />

as creators <strong>of</strong> that world. 30 Human beings as members <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural<br />

realm are in a position, to some extent at least, to rearrange <strong>the</strong> physical<br />

<strong>and</strong> social order <strong>of</strong> which <strong>the</strong>y are a part. Moreover, as beings capable <strong>of</strong><br />

reflective sensuous response to that world – that is, as beings with imaginations<br />

– it is open to us to represent intuitively a natural world in<br />

which individual human needs are met to such a degree that we all behave<br />

rationally <strong>and</strong> are happy. 31 Such a world would be <strong>the</strong> highest good – a<br />

perfectly moral world.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> grants that we are able to think <strong>the</strong> highest good as a rational Idea<br />

<strong>and</strong> to represent in imagination a world that ‘‘surpasses nature.’’ But this<br />

29 Yovel, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Philosophy <strong>of</strong> History, p.59.<br />

30 Here I am in agreement with Yovel’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest<br />

good in <strong>Kant</strong>: It is with <strong>the</strong> third Critique that this concept takes on great practical significance for<br />

human action <strong>and</strong> becomes ‘‘<strong>the</strong> summit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> historical enterprise.’’ Yovel, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Philosophy <strong>of</strong> History, p.75.<br />

31 Allen Wood, in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Ethical Thought, pp. 314 ff., points out that achieving a moral world for<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> necessarily requires acting in concert with o<strong>the</strong>rs. This <strong>the</strong>n would become part <strong>of</strong> any<br />

imaginative construction <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest good: that it is carried out with o<strong>the</strong>rs in community.


The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom 53<br />

is all that is needed for <strong>the</strong> activity <strong>of</strong> trying to bring it about: <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

(in this case <strong>the</strong> Idea) <strong>of</strong> what we want, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> motivation to act on it.<br />

All <strong>Kant</strong> needs in order to claim that <strong>the</strong> Idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest good is a<br />

necessary condition <strong>of</strong> morality is that we can believe it to be possible. To<br />

reword Lewis W. Beck’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> postulate <strong>of</strong> God’s existence:<br />

‘‘acknowledgment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral law ... requires only that I believe in <strong>the</strong><br />

highest good’s [possible future] existence. Even if it does not exist <strong>and</strong> will<br />

not exist, <strong>the</strong> practical consequences for obedience to <strong>the</strong> moral law are<br />

<strong>the</strong> same.’’ 32 A major contribution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third Critique is <strong>the</strong> argument<br />

that feelings <strong>of</strong> a special sort – aes<strong>the</strong>tic ones resulting from <strong>the</strong> free play<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination – can be universally communicable <strong>and</strong> valid for all.<br />

Thus <strong>the</strong> felt possibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest good in imagining it may be all<br />

that is required to justify reason’s comm<strong>and</strong> that we try to bring it about.<br />

To make <strong>the</strong> point in yet ano<strong>the</strong>r way, <strong>the</strong> ‘‘productive’’ imagination,<br />

in <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> empirical knowledge, serves <strong>the</strong> function <strong>of</strong> providing<br />

schemata for concepts – that is, <strong>of</strong> taking purely intellectual<br />

concepts <strong>and</strong> fitting <strong>the</strong>m to intuitions. Why not suppose, <strong>the</strong>n, that <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination, when allowed freedom in aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection to produce<br />

what <strong>Kant</strong> calls aes<strong>the</strong>tic Ideas, ‘‘inner intuitions’’ (V: 314), may <strong>the</strong>reby<br />

be capable <strong>of</strong> ‘‘schematizing’’ rational ideas like that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest good?<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> himself points out that <strong>the</strong> two are counterparts. Aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas<br />

have no adequate concept, rational ideas no adequate intuition – both<br />

point beyond <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> nature (V: 314). In <strong>Kant</strong>’s own language <strong>of</strong><br />

schematism, <strong>the</strong> one ‘‘fits’’ <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

In his discussion <strong>of</strong> genius <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> beautiful art <strong>Kant</strong><br />

says that poetry ‘‘lets <strong>the</strong> mind feel its ability to use nature on behalf <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong>, as it were, as a schema <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> supersensible’’ (i.e. <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> intelligible or<br />

rational) (V: 326). He also says that aes<strong>the</strong>tic Ideas lend a ‘‘semblance <strong>of</strong><br />

reality to rational ideas’’ (V: 314). Moreover, as we saw, <strong>Kant</strong> believes that<br />

<strong>the</strong> human imagination is powerful enough to envision new worlds. He<br />

says that imagination in poetry, for instance, ‘‘ventures to give sensible<br />

expression to rational ideas <strong>of</strong> invisible beings, <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> blessed, <strong>the</strong><br />

realm <strong>of</strong> hell, eternity, creation, <strong>and</strong> so on’’ (V: 314, emphasis mine). But<br />

if <strong>the</strong> imagination can represent <strong>the</strong>se exalted ideas, why not also <strong>the</strong><br />

realm <strong>of</strong> ends existing on earth?<br />

At this point, however, a problem arises. In <strong>the</strong> penultimate section <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment’’ (§ §59) <strong>Kant</strong> talks <strong>of</strong> beauty as a<br />

symbol <strong>of</strong> morality. Reflective aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment may symbolize<br />

32 Beck, Commentary, p.262.


54<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

morality, he says, inasmuch as it presents morality by analogy to beautiful<br />

natural forms. But, he continues, it cannot schematize morality; it cannot<br />

provide <strong>the</strong> sensible representations adequate to <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> representing a<br />

natural world that is also moral. A state, <strong>Kant</strong> tells us, can only be<br />

represented (vorgestellt) symbolically – for instance, as an animate body if<br />

it is ruled by constitutional law, or by a h<strong>and</strong>mill if it is despotic – thus<br />

suggesting that no portrait – that is, no concrete representation – <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

moral condition <strong>of</strong> society is possible.<br />

Yet it is difficult to see why <strong>Kant</strong> insists on <strong>the</strong> complete inability <strong>of</strong><br />

imagination in free play to portray moral Ideas, given what he has already<br />

said about its creative power in reflective judgment. Part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem<br />

may lie with his definition <strong>of</strong> schemata as provided by imagination only<br />

for concepts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing (Categories), toge<strong>the</strong>r with his claim<br />

that ‘‘all intuitions supplied for concepts a priori are ei<strong>the</strong>r schemata or<br />

symbols. Schemata contain direct, symbols indirect, exhibitions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

concept.’’ 33 Thus <strong>Kant</strong> quite emphatically precludes <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> any<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r type <strong>of</strong> schematization than that discussed in <strong>the</strong> first Critique. Yet<br />

at section 17 <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third Critique he suggests that a judgment is possible<br />

in which <strong>the</strong> imagination is in free play <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> same time directed to<br />

representing something in a non-symbolic way:<br />

Idea properly means a rational concept, <strong>and</strong> ideal <strong>the</strong> representation [Vorstellung]<br />

<strong>of</strong> an idea. Hence that archetype <strong>of</strong> taste, which does indeed rest on reason’s<br />

indeterminate Idea <strong>of</strong> a maximum, but which still can be represented [vorgestellt]<br />

not through concepts but only in an individual exhibition [Darstellung], may<br />

more appropriately be called <strong>the</strong> Ideal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> beautiful. Though we do not have<br />

such an Ideal in our possession, we do strive to produce it within us. But it will<br />

be merely an ideal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination, precisely because it does not rest on<br />

concepts but rests on an exhibition, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> exhibition is <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination. (V: 232)<br />

Later in this same section <strong>Kant</strong> suggests that some degree <strong>of</strong> success in<br />

exhibiting <strong>the</strong> Ideal <strong>of</strong> beauty is possible if ‘‘pure ideas <strong>of</strong> reason are<br />

united with a very strong imagination’’ in <strong>the</strong> viewer or <strong>the</strong> artist. Here<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> does not seem to have in mind mere symbolic representation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

beautiful. The Ideal <strong>of</strong> beauty has two components (Stucke): <strong>the</strong> rational<br />

Idea <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘aes<strong>the</strong>tic normal idea’’ (Normalidee, V:233). In explicating<br />

<strong>the</strong> empirical component <strong>of</strong> normalcy, <strong>Kant</strong> is quite clear that here <strong>the</strong>re<br />

33 V: 352–359: ‘‘Alle Anschauungen, die man Begriffen a priori unterlegt, sind also entweder Schemate,<br />

oder Symbole, wovon die erstern directe, die zweiten indirecte Darstellungen des Begriffs<br />

enthalten.’’


The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom 55<br />

will be definite (non-symbolic) characteristics to represent although <strong>the</strong>se<br />

will vary relative to <strong>the</strong> collective experiences <strong>of</strong> particular groups <strong>of</strong><br />

people. His discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> ‘‘making visible’’ moral<br />

attributes like ‘‘goodness <strong>of</strong> soul, or purity, or fortitude, or serenity etc.’’<br />

<strong>and</strong> an earlier footnote in <strong>the</strong> same section (V: 235) make it quite clear<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong> has ordinary portraiture, not symbolism, in mind. Granted,<br />

here he argues that only humanity in <strong>the</strong> individual can be an Ideal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination. But if <strong>the</strong> moral law requires us not only to be virtuous as<br />

individuals but also to attempt to bring about a moral society, <strong>the</strong>n we<br />

must add social virtues to <strong>the</strong> list <strong>of</strong> human virtues that can be portrayed<br />

in imagination. Portraits <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> truly moral human being must <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

also somehow convey <strong>the</strong> context within which individual morality can<br />

become effective: that is, such an art work would portray, if only<br />

implicitly, a moral world. At <strong>the</strong> very least it would seem that if <strong>the</strong> ideal<br />

<strong>of</strong> beauty can embody morality in individual human beings, <strong>the</strong>n it<br />

should be equally possible (if not equally easy) to portray <strong>the</strong> social<br />

dimension <strong>of</strong> morality in <strong>the</strong> human community. If this is <strong>the</strong> case, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

<strong>the</strong> imagination in its free reflection may be ‘‘applied’’ in <strong>the</strong> service <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> ideal <strong>of</strong> beauty to enable us to believe in <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest<br />

good as a result <strong>of</strong> human agency alone.<br />

Thus <strong>Kant</strong> could have used his account <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom to<br />

reintegrate <strong>the</strong> sensuous <strong>and</strong> moral aspects <strong>of</strong> human nature. He does not<br />

do so, however, <strong>and</strong> it is important to ask why. It seems to me that <strong>Kant</strong><br />

shrinks from <strong>the</strong> implications <strong>of</strong> his <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom for at<br />

least two reasons. 34 One is that his concern in <strong>the</strong> third Critique is<br />

primarily with contemplation <strong>of</strong> natural beauty, while it is in <strong>the</strong> creative<br />

power <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination that its possible value for <strong>the</strong> moral realm first<br />

becomes evident. Of <strong>the</strong> sixty sections that make up <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong><br />

34 There are, <strong>of</strong> course. many possible accounts <strong>of</strong> why <strong>Kant</strong> relies solely on <strong>the</strong> postulate <strong>of</strong> a<br />

supernatural being as ground <strong>of</strong> our hope to bring about <strong>the</strong> highest good. Yovel points to <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

determination to make <strong>the</strong> finite nature <strong>of</strong> human reason <strong>the</strong> Leitmotif <strong>of</strong> his philosophy (<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Philosophy <strong>of</strong> History, p.24) . It may also be argued that <strong>Kant</strong> intended to combat enthusiasm<br />

(Schwärmerei) not only in such irrationalists as Jacobi but also even in ‘‘rationalist’’ philosophers<br />

like his friend Mendelssohn, who relied on <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> an unexplained <strong>and</strong> apparently<br />

inexplicable ‘‘common sense’’ as <strong>the</strong> only check on <strong>the</strong> speculative flights <strong>of</strong> reason. To <strong>the</strong> extent<br />

that imagination is for <strong>Kant</strong> bound up with <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> a common aes<strong>the</strong>tic sense <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong><br />

extent that imagination remains for him a ‘‘blind but indispensable function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul’’ (CPR<br />

A781B1O3), it may be argued that <strong>Kant</strong> feared letting enthusiasm into philosophy through <strong>the</strong><br />

door <strong>of</strong> imaginative fiction masquerading as ‘‘common sense.’’ Cf. <strong>Kant</strong>’s essay ‘‘Was heisst. Sich<br />

im Denken orientiren?’’ VIII: 133–147. ‘‘What is Orientation in Thinking?,’’ in Critique <strong>of</strong><br />

Practical Reason <strong>and</strong> O<strong>the</strong>r Writings in Moral Philosophy, Lewis White Beck, ed. (Chicago:<br />

University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1949), pp. 293–305. Thanks to James Schmidt for suggesting this last<br />

explanation.


56<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment’’ only eleven are given over to a discussion <strong>of</strong> art <strong>and</strong><br />

genius. Moreover, <strong>Kant</strong> believes that ‘‘a direct interest in <strong>the</strong> beauty <strong>of</strong><br />

nature is always a mark <strong>of</strong> a good soul’’ since it involves respect for<br />

nature’s products. Interest in beautiful art, he states flatly, is no pro<strong>of</strong> at<br />

all that someone is inclined to be moral. But he gives no argument for <strong>the</strong><br />

last claim <strong>and</strong> he exhibits a general lack <strong>of</strong> appreciation for <strong>the</strong> fine arts.<br />

So his failure to draw out <strong>the</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> reflective<br />

imagination may be due simply to bias. What <strong>Kant</strong> could have said about<br />

art’s possible contribution to morality will be taken up in chapter 3.<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r possible explanation for <strong>Kant</strong>’s failure to develop <strong>the</strong> implications<br />

<strong>of</strong> his <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom for social change is by<br />

reference to his problematic views on obedience to <strong>the</strong> authority <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

state <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> legitimate social change. Although he sympathized<br />

with bourgeois revolution in <strong>the</strong> American colonies <strong>and</strong> in France, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

remained a vocal supporter <strong>of</strong> Frederick <strong>the</strong> Great <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Prussian state<br />

under that king. And although what is most egalitarian <strong>and</strong> humanistic in<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s ethics is due to Rousseau ra<strong>the</strong>r than Frederick, <strong>the</strong> Prussian leader<br />

exercised a strong influence on <strong>the</strong> intellectuals <strong>of</strong> his time, including<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>. 35 In ‘‘On <strong>the</strong> Common Saying, ‘That may be right in Theory, but<br />

it doesn’t work in Practice’ ’’ he argues that <strong>the</strong> claim that <strong>the</strong>re is a right<br />

<strong>of</strong> public resistance would involve a contradiction inasmuch as no<br />

institutionalized power can provide for its own destruction, <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘Metaphysical Elements <strong>of</strong> Justice’’ he argues for <strong>the</strong> same reason that ‘‘it<br />

is <strong>the</strong> people’s duty to endure even <strong>the</strong> most intolerable abuse <strong>of</strong> supreme<br />

authority.’’ 36 <strong>Kant</strong>’s ‘‘Rousseauistic revolution’’ 37 in morals thus appears<br />

to be followed by a ‘‘restoration’’ in his political thought, where respect<br />

for outside authority seems to win out on both moral <strong>and</strong> legalistic<br />

grounds. A number <strong>of</strong> biographical explanations are possible, <strong>of</strong> course.<br />

In Enlightenment, Revolution <strong>and</strong> Romanticism, Frederick Beiser argues<br />

that political conditions in Prussia at <strong>the</strong> time forced <strong>Kant</strong> to prioritize<br />

his political values, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> strategy he opted (or in Beiser’s view,<br />

coopted) for in <strong>the</strong> end was to call for freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> press at <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong><br />

35 In <strong>the</strong> third Critique <strong>Kant</strong> even quotes one <strong>of</strong> Frederick’s poems to illustrate a point about <strong>the</strong> way<br />

in which genius animates rational ideas (Section 49, V:315–314 [184]).<br />

36 ‘‘Uber den Gemeinspruch: Das mag in der Theorie richtig sein. taugt aber nicht für die Praxis’’<br />

VIII: 303; <strong>the</strong> Rechtslehre <strong>of</strong> Metaphysik der Sitten. VI: 319 (trans. John Ladd as The Metaphysical<br />

Elements <strong>of</strong> Justice [Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press 1965], p. 85); <strong>and</strong> Ak. VI: 372 (140–141).<br />

37 Cf. Lewis White Beck, ‘‘Was haben wir von <strong>Kant</strong> gelernt?,’’ in 5. Intemationaler <strong>Kant</strong> Kongress,<br />

Akten II (Bonn, 1982), p. 8 <strong>and</strong> ‘‘What Have We Learned from <strong>Kant</strong>?,’’ in Self <strong>and</strong> Nature in <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

Philosophy, ed. Allen W. Wood (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1984), p. 22.


The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom 57<br />

suppressing his support for revolution. 38 Manfred Kuehn suggests that in<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s own mind, <strong>the</strong>re was a distinction to be made between a right to<br />

rebellion <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> French revolution, which technically was not<br />

a rebellion <strong>and</strong> hence permissible on legal grounds. 39<br />

But however we explain <strong>Kant</strong>’s failure to attribute a ‘‘visionary’’ role to<br />

imaginative freedom – <strong>and</strong> this question will be taken up fur<strong>the</strong>r in<br />

chapter 5 – we can never<strong>the</strong>less carry one step fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> view, put forth<br />

by Beck <strong>and</strong> more recently by Allen Wood, Richard Velkley, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs,<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong>’s sympa<strong>the</strong>tic attitude toward those revolutions that had<br />

already occurred was consistent with his teleological account <strong>of</strong> history. 40<br />

If <strong>Kant</strong> can argue that it is part <strong>of</strong> nature’s plan that humanity progress<br />

morally even through such ‘‘evils’’ as revolution, it would be plausible for<br />

him to hold that human imagination in its aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective role is<br />

equipped literally to envision this progress – that is, to exhibit it in <strong>the</strong><br />

imaginative Ideal <strong>of</strong> a moral human community. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, Susan<br />

Neiman’s suggestion that <strong>the</strong> highest good could rest on a secular postulation<br />

<strong>of</strong> human progress could actually become a vehicle for hope, but<br />

only once it is ‘‘embodied’’ in an imaginative <strong>and</strong> concrete vision <strong>of</strong> this<br />

society. 41 That <strong>Kant</strong> did not propound this solution need not be attributed<br />

to <strong>the</strong> requirements <strong>of</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r his moral or aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory but, in <strong>the</strong><br />

end, may be due to <strong>the</strong> problematic nature <strong>of</strong> his views on political<br />

authority. Too much imaginative freedom can threaten <strong>the</strong> established<br />

order, <strong>and</strong> good Bü rger that he was, <strong>Kant</strong> could applaud Frederick <strong>the</strong><br />

Great’s imperative ‘‘Think for yourself!’’ <strong>and</strong> yet comfortably follow up<br />

with ‘‘But do as you are told.’’ 42 Still, <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> steadfast obedience<br />

to authority come what may was by no means <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophical view,<br />

<strong>and</strong> such attitudes were already suspect in <strong>Kant</strong>’s time. A younger generation<br />

<strong>of</strong> poets <strong>and</strong> visionary reformers, both within Germany <strong>and</strong><br />

outside its borders, was relying on <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory to provide <strong>the</strong><br />

groundwork for a metaphysics <strong>of</strong> social change. I hope to have shown that<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir use <strong>of</strong> that aes<strong>the</strong>tics was based on a consistent application <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

38 Beiser, Enlightenment, Revolution, <strong>and</strong> Romanticism, chapter 2, p.53.<br />

39 Manfred Kuehn, <strong>Kant</strong>: A Biography (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), p. 375.<br />

40 Lewis White Beck. ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Right <strong>of</strong> Revolution,’’ Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> History <strong>of</strong> ldeas x 32 (1971),<br />

pp. 417ff.; Richard Velkley, Freedom <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> End <strong>of</strong> Reason: On <strong>the</strong> Moral Foundations <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

Critical Philosophy (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1989).<br />

41 Neiman, The Unity <strong>of</strong> Reason.<br />

42 Cf. <strong>Kant</strong>. ‘‘Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufkläirung?’’ (Ak. VIII: 33–42) <strong>and</strong> in Lewis White<br />

Beck, Foundations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Morals (pp. 85–92). For an interpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> as<br />

somewhat less <strong>of</strong> a conservative, see John Christian Laursen, ‘‘The Subversive <strong>Kant</strong>: The<br />

Vocabulary <strong>of</strong> ‘Public’ <strong>and</strong> ‘Publicity,’ ’’ Political Theory 14 (1986), pp. 584–603.


58<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

account <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic freedom to his moral <strong>the</strong>ory, whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>Kant</strong><br />

himself would have condoned this application.<br />

I began by suggesting that <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic freedom provides<br />

an important link between Lessing <strong>and</strong> Schiller, <strong>and</strong> it should now be<br />

easier to see how this could be so. Schiller was among <strong>the</strong> earliest <strong>and</strong><br />

most important artist–philosophers to be influenced by <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> to<br />

advocate <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tics to <strong>the</strong> moral progress <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human<br />

race. Although Schiller’s letters On <strong>the</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Education <strong>of</strong> Man are<br />

typically viewed as <strong>the</strong> mature philosophical result <strong>of</strong> his coming to terms<br />

with <strong>Kant</strong>’s moral philosophy, Schiller was first introduced to <strong>Kant</strong><br />

through <strong>the</strong> latter’s philosophy <strong>of</strong> history, <strong>and</strong> it was through it that<br />

Schiller first came to know <strong>Kant</strong>’s moral <strong>the</strong>ory. 43 Moreover, his serious<br />

study <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> began with <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, <strong>and</strong> it was <strong>Kant</strong>’s long<br />

first introduction to this work that served as his introduction to <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>ian edifice as a whole. 44 It is thus plausible, in light <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong><br />

his <strong>Kant</strong> study alone, to read Schiller’s views on aes<strong>the</strong>tic education as a<br />

working out <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s teleological notion <strong>of</strong> historical progress in terms<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ories advanced in <strong>the</strong> third Critique. Although <strong>the</strong> letters On <strong>the</strong><br />

Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Education <strong>of</strong> Man involve a rejection <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s emphasis on <strong>the</strong><br />

absolute autonomy <strong>of</strong> moral experience in favor <strong>of</strong> a more integrated<br />

account <strong>of</strong> human nature, this is not necessarily an outright rejection <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s views on morality. As we have seen, <strong>Kant</strong> himself brings <strong>the</strong><br />

process <strong>of</strong> repatriating citizens <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral world into <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> nature<br />

by claiming in <strong>the</strong> second Critique that reason comm<strong>and</strong>s us to seek <strong>the</strong><br />

highest good. Moreover, he provides <strong>the</strong> means according to which this<br />

repatriation may be carried out by outlining an extremely powerful<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> imaginative creativity as a human faculty capable <strong>of</strong> transcending<br />

nature without separation from nature.<br />

In light <strong>of</strong> this aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy, <strong>the</strong> Letters may be seen as a<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r development <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom first given life<br />

by Lessing <strong>and</strong> philosophical depth by <strong>Kant</strong>. Schiller’s analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

formal <strong>and</strong> sensuous aspects <strong>of</strong> human life, <strong>and</strong> his account <strong>of</strong> a mediating<br />

<strong>and</strong> humanizing drive to ‘‘play’’ (der Spieltrieb) would have been<br />

impossible without <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free play <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> disinterested nature <strong>of</strong> judgments <strong>of</strong> taste. The crucial difference<br />

between <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Schiller lies in <strong>the</strong> latter’s claim that reconciling<br />

43 Reinhard Buchwald, Schiller (Wiesbaden: Insel Verlag, 1954), II, p. 173.<br />

44 Buchwald, Schiller, p.174.


The power <strong>of</strong> imaginative freedom 59<br />

<strong>the</strong> rational <strong>and</strong> natural aspects <strong>of</strong> human nature is a requirement <strong>of</strong><br />

reason:<br />

Reason must make this dem<strong>and</strong> because it is reason – because it is its nature to<br />

insist on perfection <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> abolition <strong>of</strong> all limitation, <strong>and</strong> because any<br />

exclusive activity on <strong>the</strong> part <strong>of</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> one drive or <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r leaves human<br />

nature incomplete <strong>and</strong> gives rise to some limitation within it. Consequently, as<br />

soon as reason utters <strong>the</strong> pronouncement: Let humanity exist, it has by that very<br />

pronouncement also promulgated <strong>the</strong> law: Let <strong>the</strong>re be beauty. 45<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> argues only that taste may enable us ‘‘to make <strong>the</strong> transition from<br />

sensible charm to a habitual moral interest without making too violent a<br />

leap’’ (V: 354). Yet <strong>the</strong> requirement <strong>of</strong> reason that we strive to attain <strong>the</strong><br />

highest good, being a comm<strong>and</strong> both to strive for moral perfection <strong>and</strong> to<br />

try to reward that perfection with material happiness, really amounts to no<br />

more or less than <strong>the</strong> comm<strong>and</strong> that we strive to be fully human; or in<br />

Schiller’s words, it amounts to <strong>the</strong> pronouncement, ‘‘Let humanity exist.’’ If,<br />

as I have argued, <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> perfected humanity rests on <strong>the</strong> ability to<br />

represent this perfection in imagination, <strong>the</strong>n Schiller simply gives voice to a<br />

view implicit in <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy – that reason requires <strong>the</strong> imaginative free<br />

play typical <strong>of</strong> our contemplation <strong>of</strong> beauty to fulfill its comm<strong>and</strong>.<br />

In concluding, it should be noted that On <strong>the</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Education <strong>of</strong><br />

Man, in a Series <strong>of</strong> Letters (hereafter, Letters) is more than an explicit<br />

working out <strong>of</strong> a line <strong>of</strong> reasoning available to <strong>Kant</strong> in <strong>the</strong> third Critique.<br />

It is also an instantiation <strong>of</strong> an imaginative portrayal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest good.<br />

More <strong>of</strong>ten than not, Schiller’s Letters is read as a work <strong>of</strong> visionary<br />

literature, <strong>and</strong> rightly so. Even though by 1793, when <strong>the</strong> original letters<br />

were written, Schiller was thoroughly suspicious <strong>of</strong> artists with revolutionary<br />

intentions, still <strong>the</strong> Letters is clearly meant to be a portrait <strong>of</strong> a<br />

possible human community dominated by nei<strong>the</strong>r physical nor moral<br />

force. 46 Schiller’s ‘‘Aes<strong>the</strong>tic State’’ is an attempt to portray in <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

terms an ‘‘Ideal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination.’’ 47 In so doing he embodies a position<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong> appeared unwilling to work out fully: ‘‘The human being has<br />

no need to flee <strong>the</strong> material world in order to prove himself as spiritual<br />

being.’’ 48 It would be left to one <strong>of</strong> Schiller’s most brilliant students,<br />

Friedrich von Hardenberg, later known as Novalis, <strong>and</strong> his Jena cohort to<br />

turn this insight into a poetic philosophical program.<br />

45<br />

Friedrich Schiller. On <strong>the</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Education <strong>of</strong> Man, in a Series <strong>of</strong> Letters, trans. Elizabeth M.<br />

Wilkinson <strong>and</strong> L. A. Willoughby (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967), 15th letter, para. 4,<br />

p. 103.<br />

46<br />

Cf. Letters, p.197 <strong>and</strong> commentary, pp. 286–287.<br />

47 48<br />

Letters, p.219. Letters, p.189.


chapter 3<br />

The interests <strong>of</strong> disinterest<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s deduction <strong>of</strong> our ‘‘peculiar ability’’ (sonderbares Vermögen, V:281)<br />

to make universally valid judgments about particulars without <strong>the</strong> aid <strong>of</strong><br />

concepts <strong>and</strong> based solely on a feeling is as well known as his ‘‘deduction<br />

<strong>of</strong> judgments <strong>of</strong> taste’’ in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment. Less familiar is his<br />

contention that this aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective capacity involves certain dem<strong>and</strong>s<br />

on how we value <strong>the</strong> world around us. Having just presented his<br />

deduction, <strong>Kant</strong> claims that we can more readily underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> judgment<br />

<strong>of</strong> taste’s dem<strong>and</strong> for agreement if we see that <strong>the</strong> mere ‘‘universal<br />

communicability as such <strong>of</strong> our feeling must already carry with it an<br />

interest for us’’ (V: 296). 1 That is, judgments <strong>of</strong> taste make dem<strong>and</strong>s on<br />

us analogous to <strong>the</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> morality, because, like moral interest in<br />

<strong>the</strong> good, aes<strong>the</strong>tic interests are bound up with a kind <strong>of</strong> duty. However,<br />

<strong>the</strong>se interests <strong>of</strong> disinterest are more important to <strong>Kant</strong> than just as<br />

vehicles for explaining why taste can comm<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> assent <strong>of</strong> everyone,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y clearly have implications beyond <strong>the</strong> justification <strong>of</strong> judgments<br />

<strong>of</strong> taste. In what follows, I want to suggest that <strong>Kant</strong>’s discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

interests <strong>of</strong> disinterest has significance for his views on art <strong>and</strong> morality, as<br />

well as for his position on how we ought to value nature.<br />

moral interest <strong>and</strong> intellectual interest<br />

in <strong>the</strong> beautiful<br />

Before looking at <strong>the</strong> broader implications <strong>of</strong> his views, it is necessary to<br />

discuss briefly <strong>Kant</strong>’s doctrine <strong>of</strong> ‘‘interest’’ <strong>and</strong> also to look closely at his<br />

arguments in Sections 41 <strong>and</strong> 42 to <strong>the</strong> effect that beauty gives rise to<br />

interests in us.<br />

1 This interest, <strong>Kant</strong> says, helps us to underst<strong>and</strong> why we dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs that <strong>the</strong>y feel <strong>the</strong> pleasure we<br />

do in <strong>the</strong> beautiful. That is, we underst<strong>and</strong> that reason has an interest in <strong>the</strong> morally good, <strong>and</strong> that this<br />

interest is bound up in certain ways with our duty to be moral. Similarly, our interest in <strong>the</strong> beautiful<br />

will be bound up with an analogous duty to be ‘‘aes<strong>the</strong>tic’’ (sensitive to beauty) (V: 296).<br />

60


The interests <strong>of</strong> disinterest 61<br />

‘‘[A]ll interest consists in pleasure in <strong>the</strong> existence [ ein Lust an der<br />

Existenz] <strong>of</strong> an object’’ (V: 296). Interest, <strong>the</strong>refore, is aes<strong>the</strong>tic in character.<br />

As we know already from <strong>Kant</strong>’s moral <strong>the</strong>ory, interest is ‘‘that<br />

through which reason becomes practical’’ (reason becomes ‘‘a cause<br />

determining <strong>the</strong> will’’) (IV: 459). Thus an interest is practical <strong>and</strong> volitional<br />

in nature: ‘‘To will something <strong>and</strong> to have a liking for its existence,<br />

i.e., to take an interest in it, are identical’’ (V: 209). Here <strong>Kant</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r<br />

identifies <strong>the</strong> will with ‘‘<strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> desire determined by reason,’’ so<br />

that it follows that to take an interest in something is rationally to desire<br />

<strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> thing, or, to phrase it in such a way as to preserve its<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic aspect, to take an interest in something is to feel <strong>the</strong> need for <strong>the</strong><br />

existence <strong>of</strong> something, where this feeling is itself determined by reason.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, <strong>Kant</strong> defines ‘‘interest’’ to include a desire for<br />

<strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> something that is conditioned ‘‘pathologically’’ – that is,<br />

determined directly by some positive stimulus ra<strong>the</strong>r than by reason.<br />

Here, a sensation arouses a desire for <strong>the</strong> object, as in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> spicy<br />

dish that <strong>Kant</strong> is inclined to eat even though he knows, ‘‘by reason’’ that<br />

it will lead to bad consequences for his digestion (V: 207, 208 ). 2<br />

An interest can be ei<strong>the</strong>r ‘‘direct’’ or ‘‘indirect [mittelbar, unmittelbar]’’<br />

(IV: 459, V: 208). That is, something is desired for its own sake, or for its<br />

usefulness to some o<strong>the</strong>r desired end. The pathological (sensuous) kind <strong>of</strong><br />

interest is ‘‘direct’’ – we like <strong>the</strong> thing as ‘‘good in itself [ an sich gut ]’’ –<br />

but, being conditioned by contingent factors, it is not capable <strong>of</strong> being<br />

universal. O<strong>the</strong>r interests may be ‘‘indirect’’ – when we like something<br />

because it is useful to us – that is, when we consider it ‘‘instrumentally<br />

good.’’ But <strong>the</strong>re are two kinds <strong>of</strong> interest which are both direct <strong>and</strong><br />

capable <strong>of</strong> universalization: <strong>the</strong> morally good, which <strong>Kant</strong> says, ‘‘carries<br />

with it <strong>the</strong> highest interest’’ (V: 209), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> beautiful (V: 208: ‘‘What<br />

we call beautiful is also liked directly’’). A great deal has been written on<br />

<strong>the</strong> interest in <strong>the</strong> morally good that in <strong>the</strong> Foundations <strong>Kant</strong> says is <strong>the</strong><br />

only pure (non-empirical) interest. 3 It is <strong>the</strong> notoriously difficult notion <strong>of</strong><br />

a moral feeling <strong>of</strong> respect, a sensuous feeling itself conditioned only by ‘‘a<br />

mere thought containing nothing sensuous’’ (IV: 460) that motivates<br />

<strong>the</strong> truly moral action. In what follows, I will bracket <strong>the</strong> problems<br />

surrounding this doctrine in <strong>Kant</strong>’s moral <strong>the</strong>ory in order to look more<br />

closely at <strong>the</strong> noteworthy fact that in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment <strong>Kant</strong> no<br />

2<br />

In <strong>the</strong> Foundations he called <strong>the</strong>se mere ‘‘sensuous impulses’’ (sinnliche Antriebe), not interests at all<br />

(IV: 459).<br />

3<br />

A very helpful summary <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s ‘‘phenomenology <strong>of</strong> respect’’ is given in Henry E. Allison, <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

Theory <strong>of</strong> Freedom (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990 , chapter 6 , especially pp. 123 ff.).


62<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

longer holds that <strong>the</strong> moral feeling <strong>of</strong> respect is <strong>the</strong> only direct nonempirical<br />

interest <strong>of</strong> which we are capable.<br />

For <strong>Kant</strong>, our pleasure in <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> judgment <strong>of</strong> taste is not<br />

bound up with <strong>the</strong> desire for <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> object. This is what it<br />

means to say that we take a disinterested pleasure in <strong>the</strong> beautiful. ‘‘But,’’<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> says, ‘‘it does not follow from this that, after <strong>the</strong> judgment has been<br />

made as a pure aes<strong>the</strong>tic one, an interest cannot be connected with it.’’<br />

He continues somewhat cryptically:<br />

This connection, however, must always be indirect. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, we must<br />

think <strong>of</strong> taste as first <strong>of</strong> all connected with something else, so that with <strong>the</strong> liking<br />

<strong>of</strong> mere reflection on an object <strong>the</strong>re can [<strong>the</strong>n] be connected, in addition, a<br />

pleasure in <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> an object ... For what we say in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> cognitive<br />

judgments (about things in general) also holds for aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgments: a posse ad<br />

esse non valet consequentia [An inference from possible to actual is not valid].<br />

(V: 296)<br />

This may be glossed as follows: In order for <strong>the</strong>re to be an interest, <strong>the</strong>re<br />

has to be an object whose existence is desired, but <strong>the</strong> ‘‘object’’ <strong>of</strong> a<br />

judgment <strong>of</strong> taste is <strong>the</strong> mere form <strong>of</strong> an actually existing object. This<br />

form may or may not really exist (I could be having a beautiful hallucination).<br />

Thus <strong>the</strong> disinterested pleasure (Wohlgefallen) in <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> object (judgment <strong>of</strong> taste) must give rise to (be ‘‘connected’’ (verknüpft)<br />

with) <strong>the</strong> interested pleasure (Lust) 4 in <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> that object<br />

via something o<strong>the</strong>r than this mere formal presentation. <strong>Kant</strong> allows two<br />

possibilities for this mediating connection <strong>of</strong> disinterest to interest: one<br />

‘‘empirical’’ <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r ‘‘intellectual.’’ In <strong>the</strong> first case, <strong>the</strong> pleasure in<br />

<strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> object arises because <strong>of</strong> an ‘‘inclination inherent in<br />

human nature’’ to ‘‘sociability.’’ Because taste allows us to communicate<br />

even a feeling, it naturally fur<strong>the</strong>rs this inclination that all human beings<br />

have, <strong>and</strong> thus we are naturally interested in <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> judgment <strong>of</strong><br />

taste on <strong>the</strong>se grounds. <strong>Kant</strong> uses contractarian metaphors (‘‘<strong>the</strong> concern<br />

for universal communicability is something everyone expects <strong>and</strong><br />

dem<strong>and</strong>s from everyone else on <strong>the</strong> basis, as it were, <strong>of</strong> an original<br />

contract dictated by our very humanity’’ (V: 297)), but <strong>the</strong> ‘‘empirical<br />

interest in <strong>the</strong> beautiful’’ may be understood as a natural social urge that<br />

we have to share our delight in <strong>the</strong> beautiful object with o<strong>the</strong>rs. This urge<br />

runs so deep that, <strong>Kant</strong> argues, we would cease to seek <strong>the</strong> beautiful in <strong>the</strong><br />

4 All pleasures are in <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>the</strong> same for <strong>Kant</strong>, <strong>and</strong> can be distinguished only by <strong>the</strong> conditions<br />

that give rise to <strong>the</strong>m. Thus <strong>the</strong> terminology is somewhat arbitrary (cf. Werner Pluhar,<br />

‘‘Introduction to <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment,’’ trans. Werner Pluhar, Indianapolis <strong>and</strong> Cambridge:<br />

Hackett, 1987, p.49n.).


The interests <strong>of</strong> disinterest 63<br />

absence <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs with whom to share it. He does not argue that we<br />

would cease to be capable <strong>of</strong> experiencing beauty altoge<strong>the</strong>r, however. It<br />

is simply that my disinterested delight in <strong>the</strong> formal features <strong>of</strong> an object<br />

naturally gives rise to a pleasure in its existence because I want to bring<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs to it to share in my initial aes<strong>the</strong>tic pleasure.<br />

Having introduced <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> an empirical interest in <strong>the</strong> beautiful,<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> divulges that he is now turning away from <strong>the</strong> deduction <strong>of</strong> taste to<br />

ask whe<strong>the</strong>r taste can be used ‘‘purposively’’ as a ‘‘transition from sense<br />

enjoyment to moral feeling’’ (V: 297–298). Because <strong>the</strong> empirical interest<br />

is just an inclination, albeit a very deeply rooted one, it is easily confused<br />

with o<strong>the</strong>r social inclinations <strong>and</strong> passions, <strong>and</strong> ‘‘can provide only a very<br />

ambiguous transition from <strong>the</strong> agreeable to <strong>the</strong> good.’’ So, in Section 42,<br />

he turns his attention to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r possibility available for connecting <strong>the</strong><br />

pleasure <strong>of</strong> taste with a pleasure in <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> beautiful object:<br />

namely, a non-empirical connection. This connection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two sorts <strong>of</strong><br />

pleasure is intellectual, made a priori via ‘‘<strong>the</strong> will’s property <strong>of</strong> being<br />

determinable a priori by reason’’ (V: 296).<br />

The argument at Section 42 is one <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s more fascinating ones, <strong>and</strong> is<br />

far-reaching in its implications if it succeeds. A great deal actually hangs on it,<br />

not only for his account <strong>of</strong> moral development but also for <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> human subjectivity. As <strong>Kant</strong> himself says, if taste can be used<br />

purposively, ‘‘we would also be showing that judgment is <strong>the</strong> mediating link in<br />

<strong>the</strong> chain <strong>of</strong> humanity’s a priori powers’’ (V: 298). What <strong>Kant</strong> wants to do here<br />

is to show that <strong>the</strong> interest connected with <strong>the</strong> beautiful is sufficiently like<br />

that <strong>of</strong> moral interest to allow a kind <strong>of</strong> psychological transition-throughclose-association<br />

from aes<strong>the</strong>tic values to moral values. He wants to do this<br />

by showing that a direct (non-instrumental) interest in <strong>the</strong> beautiful ‘‘is<br />

always a mark <strong>of</strong> a good soul’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘indicates at least a mental attunement<br />

favorable to moral feeling.’’ (That he limits this to <strong>the</strong> beautiful in nature,<br />

excluding art, is a point that I shall return to shortly.) He does not want to<br />

show that interest in <strong>the</strong> beautiful, even an a priori interest, is identical to<br />

moral interest: ‘‘<strong>the</strong> feeling for <strong>the</strong> beautiful is distinct in kind from moral<br />

feeling’’ (V: 298). The similarity is that, like aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective judgment,<br />

moral judgment is not based on an interest.<br />

We know from <strong>Kant</strong>’s ethical <strong>the</strong>ory that moral judgment gives rise to<br />

an interest that we call ‘‘moral feeling’’: an interest in obeying <strong>the</strong> moral<br />

law or, <strong>Kant</strong> says ‘‘respect for <strong>the</strong> moral law itself’’ (V: 75ff., 80):<br />

But [this feeling <strong>of</strong> respect] is a feeling which is directed only to <strong>the</strong> practical <strong>and</strong><br />

which depends on <strong>the</strong> representation <strong>of</strong> a law only as to its form <strong>and</strong> not on


64<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

account <strong>of</strong> any object <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> law; thus it cannot be reckoned ei<strong>the</strong>r as enjoyment<br />

or as pain, <strong>and</strong> yet it produces an interest in compliance with <strong>the</strong> law which we<br />

call moral interest, just as <strong>the</strong> capacity to take such an interest in <strong>the</strong> law (or<br />

respect for <strong>the</strong> moral law itself) is <strong>the</strong> moral feeling properly speaking. (V: 80)<br />

This practical interest <strong>of</strong> reason in <strong>the</strong> moral law is also an interest in<br />

fulfilling it: that is, in doing what <strong>the</strong> law comm<strong>and</strong>s. Although pure<br />

practical moral interest – respect for <strong>the</strong> law – is not a feeling <strong>of</strong> pleasure<br />

or pain in <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> ‘‘<strong>the</strong> object’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> law, it does depend on <strong>the</strong>re<br />

being at least a possibility <strong>of</strong> our being able to bring about that which <strong>the</strong><br />

law dem<strong>and</strong>s. As we saw in chapter 2, in <strong>the</strong> Antinomy <strong>of</strong> Pure Practical<br />

Reason (V: 113ff.), <strong>Kant</strong> insists that reason requires us to strive to bring<br />

about <strong>the</strong> highest good, understood by him as <strong>the</strong> greatest possible<br />

connection <strong>of</strong> moral virtue with happiness in this world. Reason has an<br />

interest, as <strong>Kant</strong> puts it, in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘objective reality’’ <strong>of</strong> its moral ideas. <strong>Kant</strong><br />

returns to this issue in his aes<strong>the</strong>tics, arguing at Section 42 that when we<br />

contemplate <strong>the</strong> beautiful it cannot be a matter <strong>of</strong> complete indifference<br />

to us that nature here ‘‘shows a trace or gives a hint that it contains some<br />

basis or o<strong>the</strong>r for us to assume’’ an orderliness that may be conducive to<br />

<strong>the</strong> state <strong>of</strong> justice we morally desire. ‘‘Hence,’’ <strong>Kant</strong> says, ‘‘if someone is<br />

directly interested in <strong>the</strong> beauty <strong>of</strong> nature, we have cause to suppose that<br />

he has at least a predisposition to a good moral attitude’’ (V: 300–301).<br />

Thus a direct interest in natural beauty is akin to, but not identical<br />

with, moral interest in <strong>the</strong> good. Caring for beauty in nature suggests that<br />

a person is moved by <strong>the</strong> possibility that she belongs <strong>the</strong>re, too. The<br />

difference is that intellectual interest in <strong>the</strong> beautiful is ‘‘free’’ while<br />

intellectual interest in <strong>the</strong> moral is based immediately upon ‘‘objective<br />

laws’’ (V: 301). Indeed, this difference is precisely why we can call our<br />

interest in <strong>the</strong> beautiful a direct interest: we do not care about <strong>the</strong> existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> object because <strong>of</strong> its instrumental link to our own moral<br />

interests (e.g. <strong>the</strong> moral idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest good), but ra<strong>the</strong>r we care for it<br />

just for what it contingently is. <strong>Kant</strong> says here that what we are (directly)<br />

interested in is ‘‘ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> beauty’s characteristic in itself <strong>of</strong> qualifying for<br />

such a link, which <strong>the</strong>refore belongs to it intrinsically [die ihr innerlich<br />

zukommt].’’<br />

This can be illustrated in <strong>the</strong> following way: In <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> making<br />

an aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective judgment about <strong>the</strong> beauty <strong>of</strong> an object I am also<br />

(concurrently, as a moral being) feeling <strong>the</strong> need for <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> this<br />

object for its own sake. This direct interest in <strong>the</strong> object is possible<br />

because I am charged by my own reason with <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> bringing<br />

moral order into <strong>the</strong> natural world – a severe dem<strong>and</strong> on my nature


The interests <strong>of</strong> disinterest 65<br />

that hardly seems possible. As such I am ‘‘morally’’ interested in finding<br />

that nature outside me, because <strong>of</strong> what appears to be <strong>the</strong> rational<br />

orderliness <strong>and</strong> purposiveness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> object I am contemplating, may be<br />

suited to beings like myself. Thus my disinterested aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection<br />

upon <strong>the</strong> object also gives rise to my caring about <strong>the</strong> object, wanting it to<br />

exist, for its own sake, even though it may be <strong>of</strong> no use to me, or<br />

may even cause me harm. I take a direct interest in it. <strong>Kant</strong> explains as<br />

follows:<br />

Cons ider som eone who is all b y himse lf (<strong>and</strong> has no intention <strong>of</strong> communi cating<br />

his observ ations to oth ers) <strong>and</strong> who contem plates <strong>the</strong> bea utiful shape <strong>of</strong> a wild<br />

flower, a bird , an insect, etc., out <strong>of</strong> admi ratio n <strong>and</strong> love for <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>and</strong> woul d<br />

not want nature to be entirely witho ut <strong>the</strong>m even if th ey provid ed him no<br />

prospec t <strong>of</strong> benefit but instead perha ps even som e harm . Such a person is takin g<br />

a dire ct inte rest in <strong>the</strong> beauty <strong>of</strong> na ture, <strong>and</strong> this interes t is inte llectual. That is,<br />

not only does he like nature ’s product for its form, but he also likes its existe nce,<br />

even tho ugh no cha rm <strong>of</strong> sen se is involve d; <strong>and</strong> he also does not connec t that<br />

existenc e with any purpose whatever. (V: 299 )<br />

The reason I am capable <strong>of</strong> desiring <strong>the</strong> natural object for its own sake,<br />

however, has to do with my intellectual/moral need to find at least a<br />

‘‘hint’’ in nature that my moral actions will not be in vain. My interest in<br />

<strong>the</strong> object is direct – it is not for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> morality that I admire <strong>and</strong> love<br />

it <strong>and</strong> desire its existence – ra<strong>the</strong>r that direct interest that <strong>Kant</strong> also calls<br />

‘‘admiration’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘love’’ is ‘‘at least an attunement favorable to moral<br />

feeling.’’ 5 Love <strong>of</strong> nature, in o<strong>the</strong>r words, is a climate <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> spirit within<br />

which respect for our duty flourishes. 6<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> ends this section with <strong>the</strong> remarkable claim (for him) that we can<br />

<strong>and</strong> do require this admiration <strong>and</strong> love for nature <strong>of</strong> everyone:<br />

for we conside r som eone’s way <strong>of</strong> thinking to be coa rse <strong>and</strong> ignoble if he has no<br />

feeling for bea utiful nature ... <strong>and</strong> sticks to <strong>the</strong> enjoyments <strong>of</strong> me re sense that he<br />

gets from meals or <strong>the</strong> bottle. (V: 302–303)<br />

5 See Karl Ameriks, ‘‘On Paul Guyer’s <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Experience <strong>of</strong> Freedom,’’ Philosophy <strong>and</strong><br />

Phenomenological Research, 60 (2) (1995), 361–367.<br />

6 See Felicitas Munzel, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Conception <strong>of</strong> Moral Character: The ‘‘Critical’’ Link <strong>of</strong> Morality,<br />

Anthropology, <strong>and</strong> Reflective Judgment (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1999 , chapter 5 ,<br />

‘‘Moral Spiritedness <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Relation <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>and</strong> Moral Cultivation’’). Munzel’s account still<br />

insists on <strong>the</strong> ‘‘hierarchical’’ nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic response (feeling) to moral reason. She does not<br />

see love <strong>of</strong> nature – i.e., this climate <strong>of</strong> spirit – as a source for moral heartiness <strong>and</strong> cheerfulness –<br />

i.e., for moral hope. (See, esp., p. 305.)


66<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

intellectual interests in nature, art,<br />

<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r people<br />

To summarize so far: I have tried to unravel <strong>and</strong> make somewhat more<br />

intuitive <strong>Kant</strong>’s distinction between moral interest <strong>and</strong> intellectual<br />

interest in <strong>the</strong> beautiful. In <strong>the</strong> remainder <strong>of</strong> this chapter, I want to focus<br />

on this last claim that we ‘‘can’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘do’’ require a feeling <strong>of</strong> love for<br />

nature. I use <strong>the</strong> term ‘‘love’’ here intentionally, for, as we saw, it is <strong>the</strong><br />

term <strong>Kant</strong> himself uses, following Burke (V: 277) for <strong>the</strong> feeling we have<br />

for nature when we value it for its own sake. 7 The claim that love can be<br />

required is a startling one in light <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s sharp division between<br />

pathological <strong>and</strong> practical love:<br />

for love as an inclination cannot be comm<strong>and</strong>ed. But beneficence from duty,<br />

even when no inclination impels it <strong>and</strong> even when it is opposed by a natural <strong>and</strong><br />

unconquerable aversion, is practical love, not pathological love; it resides in <strong>the</strong><br />

will <strong>and</strong> not in <strong>the</strong> propensities <strong>of</strong> feeling, in principles <strong>of</strong> action <strong>and</strong> not in<br />

tender sympathy [in schmelzender Teilnehmung]; <strong>and</strong> it alone can be comm<strong>and</strong>ed.<br />

(Foundations IV: 399)<br />

Where does <strong>the</strong> love for nature that we can <strong>and</strong> do require <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs fit<br />

into this division? It cannot be an inclination. That much we already<br />

know from what <strong>Kant</strong> tells us about <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> an interest in <strong>the</strong><br />

beautiful, which is based on contemplative pleasure <strong>and</strong> not mere sense<br />

stimulation. Hence it is not pathological. Yet it is based on feeling – a<br />

disinterested feeling, to be sure, not tender sympathy – but a pleasure<br />

none<strong>the</strong>less. And although it is an interest that involves <strong>the</strong> will – that is,<br />

it is a desire determined by reason – still it cannot be called practical or be<br />

said to lie in ‘‘principles <strong>of</strong> action.’’ The love <strong>of</strong> nature (<strong>the</strong> direct interest<br />

based on disinterested pleasure) is not practical love (although <strong>the</strong><br />

capacity for practical love may be a necessary condition for it), but is itself<br />

based ra<strong>the</strong>r on contemplation. It seems as if <strong>Kant</strong> has made <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

room for a third kind <strong>of</strong> love, nei<strong>the</strong>r practical nor pathological: a kind <strong>of</strong><br />

‘‘reflective’’ love for nature.<br />

Given that <strong>Kant</strong> has already argued that we may ‘‘dem<strong>and</strong> agreement’’<br />

for judgments <strong>of</strong> taste based on <strong>the</strong>ir reflective nature, it is not surprising<br />

that he would argue that reflective as well as practical love can be comm<strong>and</strong>ed.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> seems to suggest as much when he claims that we require<br />

that o<strong>the</strong>rs take a direct interest in beautiful nature. But this comm<strong>and</strong><br />

cannot be a categorical imperative, because <strong>the</strong> conditions under which<br />

7 See also V: 267: ‘‘The beautiful prepares us for loving something, even nature, without interest.’’<br />

Here <strong>Kant</strong> should be read as meaning ‘‘indirect’’ or instrumental interest. See also V: 380.


The interests <strong>of</strong> disinterest 67<br />

such an interest are first made possible are contingent on our experience<br />

<strong>of</strong> beautiful nature. <strong>Kant</strong> tells us that ‘‘<strong>the</strong> mind cannot meditate about<br />

<strong>the</strong> beauty <strong>of</strong> nature without at <strong>the</strong> same time finding its interest aroused’’<br />

(V: 300). But that ‘‘<strong>the</strong> mind’’ finds itself in <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> beautiful<br />

nature in <strong>the</strong> first place, or has <strong>the</strong> leisure to meditate upon it when in its<br />

presence, is not entirely within our control. Growing up in a povertystricken<br />

urban environment might very well preclude <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

contact with beautiful nature. Whereas <strong>Kant</strong> would argue that even <strong>the</strong><br />

most deprived human being, so long as she retains her ability to reason at<br />

all, can always turn inward for <strong>the</strong> motivation necessary to be moral, <strong>the</strong>re<br />

may well be situations where natural beauty is simply not accessible. If<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is a comm<strong>and</strong>, it would, like <strong>the</strong> interest itself, have to be <strong>of</strong> a<br />

different type than any <strong>Kant</strong> has so far distinguished: it would have to be<br />

comm<strong>and</strong>ed on <strong>the</strong> condition that beautiful nature exists <strong>and</strong> is accessible<br />

for contemplation.<br />

Given <strong>Kant</strong>’s view that a direct intellectual interest in <strong>the</strong> beautiful<br />

explains <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> ‘‘a transition from sense enjoyment to moral<br />

feeling’’ (V: 297), it might also follow that we have a moral obligation to<br />

develop a love for nature in ourselves. 8 It may also follow that, if love <strong>of</strong><br />

nature fur<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>and</strong> develops moral feeling, <strong>and</strong> if, as <strong>Kant</strong> suggests in <strong>the</strong><br />

Groundwork (IV: 417), ‘‘Whoever wills <strong>the</strong> end ... wills also <strong>the</strong> indispensably<br />

necessary steps to it,’’ <strong>the</strong>n we may have an obligation to bring<br />

about <strong>the</strong> conditions under which reflective judgment <strong>of</strong> beautiful nature is<br />

possible for o<strong>the</strong>rs as well as for ourselves. All <strong>of</strong> which suggests interesting<br />

refutations <strong>of</strong> those who malign <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy as inimical to a serious<br />

environmental ethic because <strong>Kant</strong> has no room for intrinsic value in nature.<br />

9 But <strong>Kant</strong>’s notions <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective interest have implications for<br />

two o<strong>the</strong>r areas where <strong>Kant</strong> is <strong>of</strong>ten criticized, namely his views on <strong>the</strong><br />

value <strong>of</strong> art relative to nature <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> human embodiment.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s claim that an intellectual love for nature is associated with a<br />

moral attitude came to have a certain intuitive value in <strong>the</strong> early twentieth<br />

century, when baser human instincts put wilderness so seriously at risk all<br />

over <strong>the</strong> globe. (Although, had <strong>Kant</strong> had occasion to speak with some<br />

twentieth-century proponents <strong>of</strong> ‘‘deep ecology’’ he might have seen that<br />

love <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> respect for humanity are not necessarily conjoined.)<br />

What does not make sense is his insistence, in <strong>the</strong> same passage, that love<br />

8 See Paul Guyer’s argument in <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Experience <strong>of</strong> Freedom: Essays on Aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> Morality<br />

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993).<br />

9 I discuss <strong>the</strong>se issues at length in ‘‘Beauty, Autonomy <strong>and</strong> Respect for Nature,’’ L’Esthétique de<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>/<strong>Kant</strong>s Äs<strong>the</strong>tik/<strong>Kant</strong>’s Aes<strong>the</strong>tics (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1995).


68<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

for art is no indication whatsoever <strong>of</strong> a ‘‘beautiful soul.’’ Of course, even<br />

among philosophers <strong>Kant</strong> is accused <strong>of</strong> being something <strong>of</strong> a Philistine<br />

when it came to art. Certainly he maintained a certain contempt for <strong>the</strong><br />

bourgeois man <strong>of</strong> taste:<br />

virtuosi <strong>of</strong> taste, who not just occasionally but apparently as a rule are vain,<br />

obstinate, <strong>and</strong> given to ruinous passions, can perhaps even less than o<strong>the</strong>r people<br />

claim <strong>the</strong> distinction <strong>of</strong> being attached to moral principles. (V: 298)<br />

By ‘‘taste’’ in this context, however, <strong>Kant</strong> is not referring to pure judgments<br />

<strong>of</strong> taste, but ra<strong>the</strong>r to <strong>the</strong> ability to ‘‘judge <strong>the</strong> products <strong>of</strong> fine art<br />

with <strong>the</strong> greatest correctness <strong>and</strong> refinement.’’ Such connoisseurship is <strong>of</strong><br />

course not <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> simple aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection, but requires a great<br />

deal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical knowledge <strong>of</strong> art, <strong>and</strong> finesse in applying it. For <strong>Kant</strong>,<br />

such knowledge apparently taints <strong>the</strong> connoisseur’s interest in <strong>the</strong> object<br />

so that it is never valued purely for its own sake, but always for its use<br />

only. The sheer bias <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s position is apparent when his view <strong>of</strong> artists<br />

is contrasted with his view <strong>of</strong> scientists. The parallel case <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> scientist’s<br />

<strong>the</strong>oretical knowledge does not, it seems, interfere with his ability to<br />

admire <strong>and</strong> love <strong>the</strong> object being studied for its own sake. In <strong>the</strong> Critique<br />

<strong>of</strong> Practical Reason (V: 160) he recounts approvingly <strong>the</strong> tale <strong>of</strong> Leibniz<br />

carefully replacing <strong>the</strong> insect upon its leaf after studying it as pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> how<br />

an ‘‘observer <strong>of</strong> nature finally comes to like objects that at first <strong>of</strong>fended<br />

his senses.’’<br />

Perhaps <strong>Kant</strong>’s views were occasioned by his own lack <strong>of</strong> interest. He<br />

does give an argument for why we may require o<strong>the</strong>rs to take a direct<br />

interest in nature, but no such requirement holds for a direct interest in<br />

art. This is so, he says, for one <strong>of</strong> two reasons: Ei<strong>the</strong>r because art is such a<br />

good imitation that it is deceptive – it fools us into taking it to be nature,<br />

so that our liking for it is really a (deluded) direct interest in nature; or we<br />

are aware <strong>of</strong> it as art <strong>and</strong> hence aware <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> intention to please that went<br />

into its making. In <strong>the</strong> latter case, he concludes, our interest is only<br />

indirect – we desire <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> object not for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

object in itself, but for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> intentions (to please) that brought<br />

it into existence. What is missing from <strong>the</strong> art object, he asks, that makes<br />

us value it so differently from <strong>the</strong> natural object? In o<strong>the</strong>r words, why is it<br />

not possible to value an art object for its own sake? His answer is that <strong>the</strong><br />

regularity in nature which we crave as moral agents seeking to be effective<br />

in nature is ‘‘hinted’’ at by beautiful natural objects, but not by art<br />

objects. Art objects are <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> ‘‘art’’ after all, <strong>and</strong> so cannot<br />

provide a clue <strong>of</strong> any sort about <strong>the</strong> world <strong>of</strong> nature in which we must


The interests <strong>of</strong> disinterest 69<br />

operate. They can tell us only about human intentions (when <strong>the</strong>y are not<br />

altoge<strong>the</strong>r deceiving us). Thus <strong>the</strong>y may ‘‘minister to vanity <strong>and</strong> perhaps<br />

to social joys,’’ but <strong>the</strong>y cannot interest in a direct way.<br />

What is truly odd about this position is that <strong>Kant</strong> follows it almost<br />

immediately with a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> fine art that defines it as ‘‘<strong>the</strong> art <strong>of</strong> genius,<br />

<strong>and</strong> genius as ‘‘<strong>the</strong> innate mental predisposition [he also calls it a ‘‘natural<br />

endowment’’ eine Naturgabe] through which nature gives <strong>the</strong> rule to art’’<br />

(V: 307). Shortly <strong>the</strong>reafter he repeats that ‘‘nature in <strong>the</strong> subject gives <strong>the</strong><br />

rule to art’’ (V: 307). So, fine art is <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> a gift from ‘‘<strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

nature’’ (V: 309) through which nature gives <strong>the</strong> rule to art. That practically<br />

makes <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> fine art a natural object; at least as much as a<br />

beautiful waterfall obeying laws <strong>of</strong> physical nature. It certainly mitigates<br />

<strong>the</strong> sharp division between natural <strong>and</strong> art objects, thus also mitigating<br />

<strong>the</strong> distinction between kinds <strong>of</strong> possible interest. After all, a beautiful<br />

artifact that cannot be explained by <strong>the</strong> artificer’s intentions, being <strong>the</strong><br />

result <strong>of</strong> her natural inspiration, might be just as worthy <strong>of</strong> our interest on<br />

<strong>the</strong> grounds that some intrinsic natural order is manifested by it. That is,<br />

a work <strong>of</strong> natural genius ought to suggest ‘‘a trace or give a hint that<br />

[nature] contains some basis or o<strong>the</strong>r for us to assume in its products a<br />

lawful harmony with [our moral feeling]’’ (V: 300). In that case, however,<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> could conclude that fine art should be interesting (loved by us) for<br />

its own sake, <strong>and</strong> that a feeling for beautiful art would after all indicate<br />

‘‘at least a mental attunement favorable to moral feeling.’’<br />

Finally, on moral grounds <strong>Kant</strong> may be able to conclude that love <strong>of</strong><br />

art could be ‘‘required’’ <strong>of</strong> everyone in <strong>the</strong> same sort <strong>of</strong> way that love <strong>of</strong><br />

nature is required, as a kind <strong>of</strong> duty that we have if <strong>and</strong> when we are<br />

exposed to <strong>the</strong> arts. It might <strong>the</strong>n follow, as in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> natural beauty,<br />

that we have obligations to ourselves <strong>and</strong> to o<strong>the</strong>rs to cultivate <strong>the</strong> conditions<br />

necessary for aes<strong>the</strong>tic, artistic experiences. Reflective exposure to<br />

<strong>the</strong> arts, like reflective exposure to nature, might <strong>the</strong>n turn out to be a<br />

dem<strong>and</strong> made upon us by our moral nature.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>, as we saw, called reflective interest in nature ‘‘love’’ for nature for<br />

its own sake. This sort <strong>of</strong> love, though not pathological, is also not what<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> labels practical love, because it is not determined by ‘‘principles <strong>of</strong><br />

action.’’ It is, as I said earlier ‘‘reflective love,’’ <strong>and</strong> I have suggested that<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s own <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> fine art allowed extension <strong>of</strong> this sort <strong>of</strong> interest in<br />

nature to one in art. But when <strong>Kant</strong> speaks <strong>of</strong> ‘‘love’’ in <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong><br />

obligations, as when he insists that love as an inclination cannot be<br />

comm<strong>and</strong>ed, he is typically thinking <strong>of</strong> love <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs. Thus he speaks <strong>of</strong><br />

‘‘tender sympathy,’’ ‘‘sympathy with <strong>the</strong> lot <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs,’’ as ‘‘pathological.’’


70<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> also speaks <strong>of</strong> duties <strong>of</strong> mutual aid <strong>and</strong> beneificence, but <strong>the</strong>se are<br />

dictated by <strong>the</strong> Categorical Imperative – that is, <strong>the</strong>y are purely practical,<br />

<strong>and</strong> need not involve any sympa<strong>the</strong>tic feelings towards o<strong>the</strong>rs. And <strong>of</strong><br />

course, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as <strong>Kant</strong> assumes that sympa<strong>the</strong>tic love is a mere inclination,<br />

<strong>the</strong>re can be no requirement <strong>of</strong> feeling for o<strong>the</strong>rs.<br />

What I want to suggest, in closing, is that <strong>the</strong> argument in Section 42<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third Critique, which ends by asserting a requirement <strong>of</strong> everyone<br />

that <strong>the</strong>y have some feeling for beautiful nature, suggests <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> an analogous requirement for a feeling (<strong>of</strong> love) for o<strong>the</strong>rs.<br />

In ‘‘Radical Virtue Ethics’’ Kurt Baier suggests in passing that it may be<br />

that for <strong>Kant</strong> a third kind <strong>of</strong> duty is in order, a duty ‘‘to cultivate or<br />

develop or preserve such feelings [<strong>of</strong> pathological love] to <strong>the</strong> extent we<br />

can do so.’’ 10 I think something like this might fall naturally out <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

argument at Section 42. By analogy it would go as follows. Reason has an<br />

interest in finding a trace or hint <strong>of</strong> order in nature that would suggest<br />

that our efforts to create a more moral world are not necessarily in vain.<br />

The ‘‘starry heavens above’’ provide such a hint, but so, too, does <strong>the</strong><br />

moral law embodied within myself <strong>and</strong> my fellow human beings. The<br />

latter may arouse pure practical interest, but it also may be contemplated<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tically by reflecting on <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘objects’’ involved. Here it is<br />

important to recall <strong>Kant</strong>’s position, stated in Section 17 <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique<br />

<strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment,’’ on <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic contemplation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human<br />

figure: ‘‘It is <strong>the</strong> human being [der Mensch], alone among all objects in <strong>the</strong><br />

world, who admits <strong>of</strong> an ideal <strong>of</strong> beauty’’ (V: 233):<br />

we must still distinguish <strong>the</strong> ideal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> beautiful, which for reasons already<br />

stated must be expected solely in <strong>the</strong> human figure. Now <strong>the</strong> ideal in this figure<br />

consists in <strong>the</strong> expression <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral; apart from <strong>the</strong> moral <strong>the</strong> object would<br />

not be liked universally <strong>and</strong> in a positive way [nicht allgemeine <strong>and</strong> dazu positiv<br />

gefallen würde]. (V: 235)<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> believes that it is not possible to make a purely disinterested aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

judgment about human forms. (Which is not to suggest that <strong>the</strong> quality<br />

or ‘‘correctness’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> presentation – e.g. in a portrait or sculpture –<br />

cannot be appreciated, as he says, ‘‘negatively’’ (by ‘‘virtuosi <strong>of</strong> taste’’).)<br />

But an aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective response ‘‘taken from experience’’ <strong>of</strong> a concrete<br />

visible human form is possible in which a ‘‘great’’ intellectual interest is<br />

produced.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> drops <strong>the</strong> discussion to go on with <strong>the</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> judgments <strong>of</strong><br />

taste, <strong>and</strong> does not elaborate on <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> interest involved in aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

10 Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13 (1988), pp. 126–135.


The interests <strong>of</strong> disinterest 71<br />

reflection on human forms. But it is clearly an intellectual interest, <strong>and</strong> it<br />

is similar to that sort <strong>of</strong> interest <strong>of</strong> reason that we are required to take in<br />

all beautiful objects <strong>of</strong> nature. It is a kind <strong>of</strong> reflective ‘‘love <strong>and</strong><br />

admiration’’ for <strong>the</strong> natural embodiment <strong>of</strong> moral order. It should follow<br />

that for <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>the</strong> same sort <strong>of</strong> (conditioned) requirement holds: Given<br />

<strong>the</strong> chance <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> leisure to contemplate ‘‘beautiful humanity’’ aes<strong>the</strong>tically,<br />

we ought to take a direct interest in it: ‘‘we consider someone’s<br />

way <strong>of</strong> thinking to be coarse <strong>and</strong> ignoble if he has no such feeling for<br />

human beings.’’ This is not ‘‘tender sympathy’’ or sentimentality, still less<br />

a prurient interest. But it is also not merely moral respect for <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r as<br />

a rational end. It is a ‘‘positive’’ feeling, a desire for <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘object,’’ this beautiful embodiment <strong>of</strong> human virtue, for its own sake.<br />

Again, as with natural beauty, <strong>Kant</strong> could conclude that an intrinsic<br />

valuing (a rational desire for <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong>, a direct interest in) human<br />

beings, even if <strong>the</strong>y ‘‘provide ... no prospect <strong>of</strong> benefit but instead<br />

perhaps even some harm’’ is required, but only on <strong>the</strong> condition that we<br />

have opportunities to see humanity portrayed in beautiful ways. And<br />

again, it might follow, as in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> natural beauty, that we have<br />

obligations to ourselves <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs to cultivate <strong>the</strong> conditions necessary<br />

for aes<strong>the</strong>tic appreciation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> beauty <strong>of</strong> human beings in various stages<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> various types, ages, etc. The cultivation <strong>of</strong> this sort <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic/<br />

intellectual love for o<strong>the</strong>rs might <strong>the</strong>n turn out to be a dem<strong>and</strong> made<br />

upon us by our moral nature.<br />

Of course, <strong>the</strong> last two arguments for a requirement that we take a<br />

direct intellectual interest in both art <strong>and</strong> in human beings qua physical<br />

beings, go well beyond what <strong>Kant</strong> himself said. In <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> art I doubt<br />

he would ever concede such an interest, in spite <strong>of</strong> his proto-Romantic<br />

account <strong>of</strong> genius. But I am inclined to think that in his account <strong>of</strong> an<br />

Ideal <strong>of</strong> beauty <strong>Kant</strong> was moving, perhaps in spite <strong>of</strong> himself, towards<br />

finding a place in his philosophy for a reflective love for human beings,<br />

bodies <strong>and</strong> all.


chapter 4<br />

Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical<br />

Chapter 3 argued that aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection produces interests, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

those interests might well issue in obligations on how we value ourselves<br />

<strong>and</strong> our world. This sort <strong>of</strong> claim poses a certain challenge to interpretations<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> that reduce his account <strong>of</strong> value to moral or purely<br />

practical value. Since in recent years this view has had some very persuasive<br />

<strong>and</strong> powerful advocates, this chapter engages <strong>the</strong> topic <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective imagination might play in underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> ‘‘primacy<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical’’ in <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy. The notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong><br />

practical reason, which <strong>Kant</strong> introduces explicitly in <strong>the</strong> second Critique,<br />

has been adopted by a number <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ians as <strong>the</strong> correct lens for viewing<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy as a whole. This development has in many respects<br />

been a much-needed pendant to what might be called ‘‘second-wave’’<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>ianism in <strong>the</strong> US, when mid-twentieth-century analytic philosophers<br />

began a serious re-evaluation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first Critique for developments in <strong>the</strong><br />

history <strong>of</strong> modern <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> metaphysics. The turn<br />

towards interpretive strategies that prioritize <strong>the</strong> practical philosophy, due<br />

in large part to Rawls, 1 has allowed scholars to put <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge in context, <strong>and</strong> has provided <strong>the</strong> motivation <strong>and</strong> basis for<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r important developments in contemporary <strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> moral<br />

constructivism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian-type ethics.<br />

While acknowledging <strong>the</strong> enormous contribution to ethical <strong>and</strong> political<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory that <strong>the</strong>se interpreters have made, <strong>the</strong> tendency to read <strong>Kant</strong><br />

as primarily an ethical <strong>the</strong>orist who subsumed all <strong>the</strong>ory to practice is<br />

misleading. Exclusive emphasis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral dimensions <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

thought may in fact lead scholars away from much that is fascinating<br />

<strong>and</strong> philosophically innovative in his <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> value, including in his<br />

1 See in particular A Theory <strong>of</strong> Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971).<br />

72


Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical 73<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> moral value. In particular, <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic value has<br />

been ignored or subordinated by <strong>the</strong> recent stress on <strong>the</strong> ‘‘primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

practical’’ in his system. In what follows, I make a case for closer consideration<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s incorporation <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection into <strong>the</strong> critical<br />

edifice. In doing so, I hope to undercut to a certain extent <strong>the</strong> view that<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> practical reason has absolute pride <strong>of</strong> place in his philosophy.<br />

<strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical: methodological<br />

In an essay entitled ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>, Fichte, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Radical Primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Practical,’’<br />

Karl Ameriks suggests three ways <strong>of</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> primacy<br />

attributed to <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> practical reason by various interpretors. He<br />

argues that pure practical reason may be understood as primary for <strong>Kant</strong> in<br />

<strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> having special significance because it is <strong>the</strong> sole source <strong>of</strong><br />

revelation to us <strong>of</strong> ‘‘what is <strong>of</strong> unconditional interest <strong>and</strong> value, <strong>the</strong> moral<br />

will.’’ It may also be primary in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> revealing, through <strong>the</strong> postulates<br />

<strong>of</strong> pure practical reason, a ‘‘positive <strong>and</strong> relatively ‘filled in’ version<br />

<strong>of</strong> our ultimate destiny.’’ Ameriks goes on to reject a third possible sense <strong>of</strong><br />

primacy – namely, what he calls a ‘‘methodological primacy’’ that attributes<br />

to practical reason <strong>the</strong> ability to ‘‘set <strong>the</strong> fundamental conditions <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophical argument.’’ 2 I shall return to Ameriks’ first two senses <strong>of</strong><br />

primacy in <strong>the</strong> next section, but want first to look at two important recent<br />

interpretations <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian practical reason that attribute what Ameriks calls<br />

‘‘methodological primacy’’ to practical reason in <strong>Kant</strong>.<br />

Some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> strongest arguments that <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy must be seen<br />

as fundamentally practical have come in recent years from <strong>the</strong> camp <strong>of</strong><br />

neo-<strong>Kant</strong>ian constructivists following more or less in <strong>the</strong> footsteps <strong>of</strong><br />

John Rawls. Of <strong>the</strong> many important contributions, Onora O’Neill, in<br />

particular, has argued most strenuously that <strong>Kant</strong>’s entire philosophy<br />

must be understood as procedurally practical to its very core. She argues<br />

that since <strong>Kant</strong> has repudiated Cartesian introspective procedures, he<br />

must launch his entire project in a novel way:<br />

Where does <strong>Kant</strong> start? If he can’t begin by vindicating philosophical method,<br />

where can he begin? The motto <strong>of</strong>fers <strong>the</strong> clue that we must see <strong>the</strong> enterprise as<br />

practical: It is a task, not a body <strong>of</strong> opinions, <strong>and</strong> moreover a task that has to be<br />

2 Karl Ameriks, ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>, Fichte, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Radical Primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Practical,’’ in <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Fate <strong>of</strong><br />

Autonomy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), p. 190.


74<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

shared. The first move must <strong>the</strong>n presumably be to recruit those o<strong>the</strong>rs who will<br />

form <strong>the</strong> task force. 3<br />

O’Neill argues later that ‘‘The central point that <strong>Kant</strong> makes with <strong>the</strong>se<br />

analogies is that reason’s authority must (since it receives no antecedent or<br />

transcendent vindication) be seen as a practical <strong>and</strong> collective task, like that<br />

<strong>of</strong> constituting political authority.’’ 4 Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> reason is<br />

possible only if we think <strong>of</strong> critique as recursive <strong>and</strong> reason as constructed<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than imposed.’’ 5<br />

Reason’s method is essentially practical, <strong>the</strong> exercise <strong>of</strong> autonomous<br />

agency, <strong>and</strong> this autonomy is also its vindication, according to O’Neill.<br />

The Copernican revolution is not itself a method but a preliminary<br />

‘‘trial.’’ It is a hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that leads to an ‘‘estimate or inventory’’ or<br />

assembling <strong>of</strong> materials available for use in <strong>the</strong> actual ‘‘tasks’’ <strong>of</strong> reason.<br />

The real unveiling <strong>of</strong> methodology comes only later, after <strong>the</strong> preliminary<br />

assemblage <strong>of</strong> materials:<br />

At <strong>the</strong> beginning we had no ‘‘material’’ to discipline; now a hypo<strong>the</strong>sis about<br />

how we might embark on <strong>the</strong> tasks <strong>of</strong> reason has supplied some material, but has<br />

not shown how this material is to be combined into <strong>the</strong> edifice <strong>of</strong> knowledge. It<br />

has, however, provided a vantage point for a reflexive task, which could not be<br />

undertaken initially, but only retrospectively, reflectively, toward <strong>the</strong> end. 6<br />

Because <strong>the</strong> Doctrine <strong>of</strong> Elements <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason inventories<br />

materials but does not provide ‘‘a determinate account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

integrated deployment,’’ O’Neill argues, in <strong>the</strong> end that, ‘‘maxims to<br />

regulate <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se capacities in thinking <strong>and</strong> acting’’ must be<br />

adopted. The supreme principle <strong>of</strong> reason is identified with that <strong>of</strong><br />

practical reason. It is, in fact<br />

<strong>the</strong> requirement that any fundamental principles <strong>of</strong> thought <strong>and</strong> action we<br />

deploy be ones that it is not impossible for all to follow ... Here we begin to<br />

underst<strong>and</strong> why <strong>Kant</strong> held that <strong>the</strong> Categorical Imperative was <strong>the</strong> supreme<br />

principle not just <strong>of</strong> practical but <strong>of</strong> all reasoning. 7<br />

O’Neill proposes interpreting <strong>Kant</strong>’s critical philosophy as a generalized<br />

version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> social contract <strong>the</strong>ory for all aspects <strong>of</strong> human experience<br />

<strong>and</strong> valuing. In this dramatic reconstruction <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s project, <strong>the</strong> critical<br />

edifice is seen as a sort <strong>of</strong> all-encompassing compact drawn up by rational<br />

individuals who take <strong>the</strong> Categorical Imperative as <strong>the</strong>ir sole procedural<br />

principle. This is a bold interpretive move <strong>and</strong>, not surprisingly, it suggests<br />

3<br />

Onora O’Neill, Constructions <strong>of</strong> Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), p. 8.<br />

4<br />

Ibid., p. 18.<br />

5<br />

Ibid., p. 27.<br />

6<br />

Ibid., pp. 13–14.<br />

7<br />

Ibid., pp. 19–20.


Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical 75<br />

some novel interpretive results. The analogy to social contract <strong>the</strong>ory,<br />

some versions <strong>of</strong> which view social <strong>and</strong> moral values as only first becoming<br />

possible upon agreement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> parties to <strong>the</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> contract, raises<br />

questions. Does it <strong>the</strong>n follow that <strong>the</strong> values <strong>of</strong> all rationality, expressed<br />

generally by <strong>the</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> rational contract as autonomy in thought <strong>and</strong><br />

action, but including cognitive <strong>and</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic value, must likewise wait<br />

upon <strong>the</strong> contract itself? O’Neill’s reading seems to suggest that all rational<br />

value is socially constructed, including even <strong>the</strong> ‘‘truth value’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

categories, principles, etc. ‘‘inventoried’’ in <strong>the</strong> first Critique , ins<strong>of</strong>ar as<br />

reason itself is vindicated only later, in <strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> constructive<br />

process.<br />

In general, it is an odd feature <strong>of</strong> this reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> priority <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

practical that it relegates <strong>the</strong> Copernican turn in <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> knowledge<br />

to <strong>the</strong> status <strong>of</strong> a mere hypo<strong>the</strong>sis in <strong>Kant</strong>’s overall philosophical enterprise,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> results <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Deduction <strong>and</strong> Principles to an ‘‘inventory’’<br />

<strong>of</strong> materials for knowledge, ra<strong>the</strong>r than granting that <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory is a<br />

relatively free-st<strong>and</strong>ing account <strong>of</strong> empirical knowledge. The subordination<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> cognition to <strong>the</strong> project <strong>of</strong> practical reason also<br />

seems to pull <strong>the</strong> rug out from under <strong>Kant</strong>’s stance that he has ‘‘had to<br />

deny knowledge to make room for faith’’ (including autonomous freedom).<br />

The ‘‘denial’’ <strong>of</strong> knowledge is <strong>of</strong> course not a repudiation or<br />

subordination <strong>of</strong> cognition, but an explicit claim that <strong>the</strong> method <strong>and</strong><br />

purposes <strong>of</strong> a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> cognition are in an important sense external to<br />

<strong>the</strong>ories <strong>of</strong> human moral practice. A prior <strong>and</strong> independent account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

conditions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> cognition, most <strong>of</strong> which take place in us<br />

without our explicit awareness, is <strong>the</strong> very locus from which <strong>Kant</strong> discovers<br />

a space outside or beyond those conditions where practical reason<br />

might operate. To interpret <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Analytic as mere hypo<strong>the</strong>sis<br />

<strong>and</strong> inventory on <strong>the</strong> way to an account in which knowledge is defined as<br />

reflexive social practice undermines <strong>the</strong> self-st<strong>and</strong>ing nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

account <strong>of</strong> empirical knowledge, <strong>and</strong> with it <strong>the</strong> stance from which to<br />

‘‘deny’’ that knowledge. In sum, it is hard to square O’Neill’s claims for<br />

<strong>the</strong> methodological primacy <strong>of</strong> practical reason with <strong>Kant</strong>’s stated need to<br />

establish separate domains for <strong>the</strong> various applications <strong>of</strong> reason. 8<br />

For <strong>Kant</strong>, vindicating reason not only requires a methodological distinction<br />

between principles <strong>of</strong> thought (knowledge) <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> action<br />

8 See Karl Ameriks, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Fate <strong>of</strong> Autonomy: Problems in <strong>the</strong> Appropriation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critical<br />

Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), chapter 4 , for a general criticism along<br />

<strong>the</strong>se lines <strong>of</strong> all claims for methodological primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical. Ameriks argues convincingly<br />

that <strong>the</strong>se approaches follow in <strong>the</strong> footsteps <strong>of</strong> Fichte’s idealism ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy.


76<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

(morality), but <strong>the</strong> introduction <strong>of</strong> a third ‘‘faculty,’’ (Vermögen des<br />

Gemuths), namely feeling, along with its own principle [<strong>of</strong> judgment]. 9 Far<br />

from identifying <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> practice under a single principle, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

reiterates <strong>the</strong>ir separation, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n seeks to show how <strong>the</strong>y can possibly be<br />

reunited in <strong>the</strong> human subject through <strong>the</strong> mediation <strong>of</strong> a reflective<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> purpose <strong>and</strong> its human manifestation in a universally communicable<br />

feeling. 10 Because O’Neill sees <strong>the</strong> problem for reason as that <strong>of</strong><br />

uniting thought <strong>and</strong> action under a single principle, she tends to neglect<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s own characterization <strong>of</strong> his third <strong>and</strong> final Critique as ‘‘mediating<br />

<strong>the</strong> connection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two parts <strong>of</strong> philosophy to [form] a whole’’(V: 176)–<br />

i.e. that <strong>of</strong> finding a mediating principle to negotiate <strong>and</strong> harmonize, not<br />

under which to subsume, <strong>the</strong> two capacities <strong>of</strong> reason.<br />

O’Neill’s interpretation is motivated by a commitment to <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

Enlightenment political values <strong>and</strong> especially to <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> non-coercive<br />

public discourse. 11 She assumes that ‘‘critique <strong>of</strong> reason is only possible if<br />

we think <strong>of</strong> critique as recursive [reflexive] <strong>and</strong> reason as constructed<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than imposed.’’ 12 She repeatedly poses <strong>the</strong> following dilemma:<br />

Reason must be <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> a ‘‘never passive’’ constructive enterprise<br />

carried out in accordance with <strong>the</strong> generalized Categorical Imperative (all<br />

principles employed must be ones that all can follow), or it is tyranny. On<br />

this account, if rationality is not actively constructed by us, it is imposed on<br />

us. There is no alternative. 13<br />

9 ‘‘Introduction to <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment,’’ trans. Werner Pluhar (Indianapolis <strong>and</strong><br />

Cambridge: Hackett, 1987), V: 198.<br />

10 Cf. ‘‘Introduction to <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment,’’ <strong>and</strong> also <strong>the</strong> First Introduction to <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong><br />

Judgment (published separately as vol. XI <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> collected works, <strong>and</strong> included as an appendix in<br />

Pluhar’s translation).<br />

11 Cf. O’Neill, ‘‘Vindication Reason,’’ chapter 9 <strong>of</strong> The Cambridge Companion to <strong>Kant</strong>, ed. Paul<br />

Guyer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), p. 293.<br />

12 O’Neill, Constructions <strong>of</strong> Reason, p.27.<br />

13 Even if we agree that this contract, or procedural model <strong>of</strong> reason is appropriate, it may still be<br />

objected that, as with any contract <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> who is to be party to <strong>the</strong> original<br />

contract is not irrelevant: to whom do we refer when we say that ‘‘all’’ must be able to follow <strong>the</strong><br />

principles <strong>of</strong> reason adopted? O’Neill argues that <strong>the</strong> political analogy should not be pressed too<br />

far, that <strong>the</strong> contract ‘‘need not be taken literally, or as referring to historical events’’(Constructions<br />

<strong>of</strong> Reason, p.18). But <strong>the</strong> many <strong>and</strong> varied postmodern attacks on <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> tribunal <strong>of</strong><br />

reason <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> Enlightenment optimism in general have underscored <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

question <strong>of</strong> origins. Who will be admitted to <strong>the</strong> all-important team constructing reason? Who will<br />

be excluded? What about questions <strong>of</strong> development? How will <strong>the</strong> rationally immature be<br />

distinguished from <strong>the</strong> mature thinker, <strong>and</strong> who will train <strong>the</strong>m for maturity? What methods will<br />

be used by <strong>the</strong> trainers to ensure that <strong>the</strong>ir trainees become autonomous? Those who cannot or<br />

will not submit to <strong>the</strong> discipline <strong>of</strong> reason as already constructed at any given historical<br />

moment will presumably never be party to <strong>the</strong> process. For a collection <strong>of</strong> essays expressing <strong>the</strong>se<br />

sorts <strong>of</strong> criticisms, from both <strong>Kant</strong>’s own time <strong>and</strong> from contemporary authors, see What is<br />

Enlightenment? Eighteenth Century Answers <strong>and</strong> Twentieth Century Questions, James Schmidt, ed.


Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical 77<br />

I want to suggest in what follows that for <strong>Kant</strong>, at any rate, this<br />

formulation harbors a false dilemma. If ‘‘construction’’ is understood as<br />

any activity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind that in any way shapes our experience it may be<br />

true for <strong>Kant</strong>, but as O’Neill appears to underst<strong>and</strong> him, active construction<br />

involves self-legislation, self-legislation means giving <strong>the</strong> law to<br />

oneself, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter involves <strong>the</strong> ‘‘willful’’ activity <strong>of</strong> reason. The picture<br />

is one <strong>of</strong> a struggle for rational self-definition against external,<br />

‘‘alien’’ forces, an image that <strong>Kant</strong> himself surely encourages in many<br />

places. Yet in <strong>the</strong> third Critique, especially in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

Judgment,’’ <strong>Kant</strong>’s concern is with a less interventionist, less defensive<br />

mode <strong>of</strong> rational engagement with <strong>the</strong> world <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> with o<strong>the</strong>rs.<br />

His account <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic contemplation is certainly about mental activity.<br />

Reflecting on beauty, however, is not willful activity, nor <strong>the</strong> imposition<br />

<strong>of</strong> form on nature. It is mere imaginative ‘‘play’’ with natural forms, <strong>and</strong><br />

in this sense, at least, might be considered more passive. Still, <strong>Kant</strong> takes<br />

this activity to be <strong>the</strong> connecting link between reason in its cognitive/<br />

<strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> in its moral capacities. Interpretations that unify reason<br />

under practical reason <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> autonomy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> will fail to account for <strong>the</strong><br />

centrality <strong>of</strong> reflection in <strong>Kant</strong>’s overall account <strong>of</strong> human reason. The<br />

sense in which reflective judgment defines rationality will be explored<br />

later. First, however, it will be useful to turn briefly to ano<strong>the</strong>r important<br />

recent argument for <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> practical reason that does take<br />

account explicitly <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> contemplation in relation to practical<br />

reason.<br />

Christine Korsgaard also interprets <strong>Kant</strong>’s overall account <strong>of</strong> rationality<br />

in terms ultimately <strong>of</strong> practical reasoning, <strong>the</strong> spirit <strong>of</strong> which she traces to<br />

his humanism. That is, she argues, for <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> all value is<br />

ultimately humanity itself – or, to be more precise, humanity ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it<br />

is capable <strong>of</strong> ‘‘full rational autonomy’’(p. 241). Like O’Neill, she, too, sees<br />

practical reason as <strong>the</strong> fundamental source <strong>of</strong> all values <strong>and</strong>, like O’Neill,<br />

she believes that choices, to be truly human, can be determined only by<br />

practical reason, <strong>and</strong> not inclination <strong>and</strong> pleasures:<br />

In <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason, <strong>Kant</strong> claims that good is a rational concept.<br />

This means that if ends are to be good, <strong>the</strong>y must be determined by reason, not<br />

merely inclination or pleasantness ... Behind <strong>the</strong> assumption that if every<br />

rational being could acknowledge something to be good ... <strong>the</strong>n it is indeed<br />

(Riverside: University <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1996). For a feminist version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se sorts <strong>of</strong> criticisms<br />

<strong>and</strong> a suggestion for reconstructing <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tics as a part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> solution, see my ‘‘The<br />

Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Dimension <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian Autonomy,’’ in Feminist Interpretations <strong>of</strong> Immanuel <strong>Kant</strong>, ed.<br />

Robin May Schott (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1997), pp. 173–190.


78<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

good ... is <strong>the</strong> idea that it is rational beings who determine what is good;<br />

rational nature confers value on <strong>the</strong> objects <strong>of</strong> its choices <strong>and</strong> is itself <strong>the</strong> source<br />

<strong>of</strong> all value. 14<br />

Korsgaard <strong>the</strong>n argues that rational nature for <strong>Kant</strong> must be understood<br />

as fundamentally practical. Theoretical knowledge is limited to <strong>the</strong><br />

mechanism <strong>and</strong> not <strong>the</strong> ends <strong>of</strong> nature, while speculation about final<br />

causes is also banished from <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> knowledge. Thus Korsgaard<br />

argues, <strong>the</strong>oretical reflection relinquishes any claim to being <strong>the</strong> source –<br />

i.e. ultimate justification – <strong>of</strong> human values. For this reason, she says,<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s rationalism, unlike Aristotle’s, values agency over contemplation,<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘‘Morality replaces metaphysics as <strong>the</strong> highest expression <strong>of</strong> our<br />

rational nature.’’ 15<br />

Since Korsgaard’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s subordination <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> contemplative<br />

side <strong>of</strong> human nature to <strong>the</strong> practical dovetails with O’Neill’s<br />

view that practical reason unites all aspects <strong>of</strong> reason under a single<br />

principle, a response to Korsgaard’s arguments against contemplation also<br />

raises questions for O’Neill. Korsgaard outlines two <strong>Kant</strong>ian arguments<br />

against contemplation as <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> value. The first she takes from <strong>the</strong><br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, Section 86 ‘‘On Ethico<strong>the</strong>ology,’’ in which <strong>Kant</strong><br />

states that<br />

it is not by reference to man’s cognitive power (<strong>the</strong>oretical reason) that <strong>the</strong><br />

existence <strong>of</strong> everything else in <strong>the</strong> world first gets its value, i.e., it is not [because]<br />

(say) <strong>the</strong>re is someone to contemplate <strong>the</strong> world. For if all this contemplation<br />

<strong>of</strong>fered to man’s presentation nothing but things without a final purpose, <strong>the</strong>n<br />

<strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> world is cognized cannot make its existence valuable; only if we<br />

presupposed that <strong>the</strong> world has a final purpose, could its contemplation itself<br />

have a value by reference to that purpose. 16<br />

Korsgaard reads this as follows:<br />

while speculative reason hopes vainly to discover or prove that this ideal <strong>of</strong> reason<br />

is already realized in <strong>the</strong> world, practical reason – or morality – is <strong>the</strong> attempt to<br />

impose this ideal on action <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong> world ins<strong>of</strong>ar as action shapes <strong>the</strong> world.<br />

The argument against contemplation as a source <strong>of</strong> value she summarizes<br />

concisely as<br />

The world must have a final purpose in order to be worth contemplating, so<br />

contemplation cannot be that final purpose. 17<br />

14<br />

Christine M. Korsgaard, ‘‘Aristotle <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> on <strong>the</strong> Source <strong>of</strong> Value’’, in Creating <strong>the</strong> Kingdom <strong>of</strong><br />

Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 241.<br />

15 16<br />

Ibid., p. 246. <strong>Kant</strong>, Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, (V: 442).<br />

17<br />

Korsgaard, ‘‘Aristotle <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>,’’ p. 241.


Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical 79<br />

This is a good summary <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s point, but it does not follow from <strong>the</strong><br />

claim that contemplation cannot be <strong>the</strong> final purpose <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world that it<br />

also cannot be a source <strong>of</strong> value. Contemplation, like moral judgment, is<br />

an activity. Final purposes or ends are objects <strong>of</strong> desire. It may well be<br />

that <strong>the</strong> highest end or final purpose <strong>of</strong> humanity is essentially moral<br />

without it following that our method <strong>of</strong> creating or producing it be<br />

essentially practical. In fact, in this section <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Teleological<br />

Judgment’’ <strong>Kant</strong> is speaking about <strong>the</strong> way in which even <strong>the</strong><br />

most ordinary mind meditates (nachdenkt) about <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> things.<br />

The citation Korsgaard uses occurs in a context in which <strong>Kant</strong> is concerned<br />

to explain teleological reflection upon <strong>the</strong> universe, <strong>and</strong> to argue,<br />

as Korsgaard points out, that <strong>the</strong>re is a moral component to this reflection.<br />

The reflective product, <strong>the</strong> judgment itself, however, does not rest<br />

on determinant principles <strong>of</strong> judgment, ei<strong>the</strong>r cognitive or moral, but on<br />

a principle <strong>of</strong> reflective judgment that, as <strong>Kant</strong> has already argued, is<br />

independent <strong>of</strong> both:<br />

The effect [at which we are to aim] according to <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> freedom is <strong>the</strong><br />

final purpose which (or <strong>the</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> which in <strong>the</strong> world <strong>of</strong> sense) ought to<br />

exist; <strong>and</strong> we [must] presuppose <strong>the</strong> condition under which it is possible [to<br />

achieve] this final purpose in nature (in <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject as a being <strong>of</strong><br />

sense, namely, as a human being). It is judgment that presupposes this condition<br />

‘‘a priori,’’ <strong>and</strong> without regard to <strong>the</strong> practical, [so that] this power provides us<br />

with <strong>the</strong> concept that mediates beween <strong>the</strong> concepts <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom: <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> a purposiveness <strong>of</strong> nature, which makes possible <strong>the</strong><br />

transition from pure <strong>the</strong>oretical to pure practical lawfulness, from lawfulness in<br />

terms <strong>of</strong> nature to <strong>the</strong> final purpose set by <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> freedom. For it is<br />

through this concept [<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> purposiveness <strong>of</strong> nature] that we cognize [erkennen]<br />

<strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> [achieving] <strong>the</strong> final purpose, which can be actualized only in<br />

nature <strong>and</strong> in accordance with its laws. 18<br />

Korsgaard argues that <strong>Kant</strong> rejects contemplation as <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> value,<br />

but in fact all he really rejects is <strong>the</strong> claim to know anything through<br />

contemplation, in <strong>the</strong> very limited sense <strong>of</strong> knowledge characterized by<br />

him in <strong>the</strong> first half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason. She claims that ‘‘for<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> ... teleological thinking is not knowledge, <strong>and</strong> such grounding as it<br />

has lies in practical religious faith <strong>and</strong> so in ethics.’’ 19 But as we have just<br />

seen, teleological thinking is grounded in a concept <strong>of</strong> reason that is<br />

nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>oretical nor practical, but that belongs none<strong>the</strong>less to <strong>the</strong><br />

18 <strong>Kant</strong>, Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, V:195–196.<br />

19 Korsgaard, ‘‘Aristotle <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>,’’ p. 245.


80<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

system <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> faculties <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind a priori. It is grounded in reflective<br />

judgment.<br />

Korsgaard <strong>the</strong>n goes on to conclude that ‘‘we cannot, through <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

thinking, participate in <strong>the</strong> final purpose <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world. We can only<br />

do this in practice.’’ 20 Here she presents her own version <strong>of</strong> what I have<br />

suggested is <strong>the</strong> false dichotomy in O’Neill’s constructivism: ei<strong>the</strong>r we<br />

think <strong>the</strong>oretically, or we act according to <strong>the</strong> principles <strong>of</strong> practical<br />

reason. There is no alternative. <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> relatively independent<br />

mediating activity <strong>of</strong> reflection on both thinking <strong>and</strong> acting is<br />

simply ignored. 21<br />

Korsgaard’s second argument for <strong>the</strong> devaluation <strong>of</strong> contemplative<br />

activity in <strong>Kant</strong> is taken from <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason. <strong>Kant</strong> claims<br />

that intellectual pleasures are no different in kind from physical pleasures,<br />

since <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> both rests on feeling, <strong>and</strong> feeling, being a mere<br />

passive susceptibility to causes, is ‘‘firmly divorced’’ from autonomy. 22 It<br />

is certainly undeniable that <strong>Kant</strong> tends to belittle <strong>the</strong> contribution <strong>of</strong><br />

feeling to rationality, but it ought to be noted immediately that charges <strong>of</strong><br />

‘‘passivity’’ will apply equally to all sorts <strong>of</strong> feeling, including not only<br />

pleasures <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>and</strong> intellect, but also to <strong>the</strong> satisfaction we take in<br />

<strong>the</strong> moral. The latter type <strong>of</strong> feeling is one that <strong>Kant</strong> certainly nei<strong>the</strong>r<br />

wants to deny nor belittle. <strong>Kant</strong>’s tendency to characterize pleasure always<br />

as a kind <strong>of</strong> contingent a posteriori feeling vanishes with <strong>the</strong> advent <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> reflective judgment. In <strong>the</strong> third Critique, <strong>Kant</strong>’s claim is that<br />

‘‘<strong>the</strong> feeling <strong>of</strong> pleasure <strong>and</strong> displeasure is only <strong>the</strong> subject’s receptivity to a<br />

[ certain] state.’’ 23 Pleasure in itself is only receptivity, indeed, but always a<br />

reception <strong>of</strong> a certain state <strong>of</strong> mental activity. Thus, for <strong>Kant</strong> pleasures are<br />

not all created equal: <strong>the</strong>y are to be distinguished in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conditions<br />

which give rise to <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> important new contribution <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment’’ is to introduce <strong>and</strong> argue for<br />

pleasures <strong>of</strong> reflection whose conditions are universal <strong>and</strong> a priori. Such<br />

pleasures are <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conditions that hold a priori <strong>of</strong> a form <strong>of</strong><br />

contemplation, albeit not an intellectual one: aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective judgment.<br />

The argument from passivity does not in <strong>the</strong> end constitute an<br />

20 Ibid.<br />

21 <strong>Kant</strong> refers to this relative independence as <strong>the</strong> ‘‘heautonomy’’ <strong>of</strong> judgment, in which it gives <strong>the</strong><br />

law only to itself, not to nature or freedom, for reflection upon nature. Cf. Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment,V:<br />

185, <strong>and</strong> First Introduction to <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, XI: 225.<br />

22 V: 185–186, XI: 225.<br />

23 First Introduction to <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment (XX: 208). See also <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason<br />

(V: 75) where <strong>Kant</strong> has already made this point about <strong>the</strong> origins <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> feeling <strong>of</strong> respect for <strong>the</strong><br />

moral law.


Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical 81<br />

argument against <strong>the</strong> pleasures <strong>of</strong> contemplation as a source <strong>of</strong> value,<br />

since some pleasures are ‘‘conditioned’’ only by activities <strong>of</strong> judgment<br />

that are universal <strong>and</strong> a priori. In part, Korsgaard’s arguments against<br />

contemplative reason as a source <strong>of</strong> value rest on a conflation <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical reason <strong>and</strong> speculative metaphysics with contemplation.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>, however, has a more fine-tuned account <strong>of</strong> reason’s<br />

activities. Theoretical reason needs to speculate upon <strong>the</strong> unconditioned,<br />

<strong>and</strong> this need, for <strong>Kant</strong>, should, for <strong>the</strong> most part, be sublimated to<br />

practical reason. But <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> contemplative thought, or<br />

‘‘reflective judgment,’’ is a different sort <strong>of</strong> thinking altoge<strong>the</strong>r, whose<br />

function is not to subordinate <strong>the</strong>oretical to practical reason, but to<br />

negotiate <strong>the</strong> rift between <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

Korsgaard’s <strong>and</strong> O’Neill’s readings <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s overall <strong>the</strong>ory are in many<br />

respects inspired, <strong>and</strong> st<strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong>ir own right as important <strong>Kant</strong>ian<br />

reconstructions. Still, based on <strong>the</strong> arguments just presented, I believe<br />

that any accounts that locate <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> all value, <strong>and</strong> define rationality<br />

itself, primarily in terms <strong>of</strong> practical reason fail to do justice to one <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s greatest insights, namely, that reason is a system <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> interplay <strong>of</strong><br />

both thinking <strong>and</strong> acting. A fully developed critique <strong>of</strong> reason must<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore provide an account <strong>of</strong> this connection – <strong>the</strong> interface as it were –<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> practical reason. 24 The third Critique, where <strong>Kant</strong><br />

argues that this interface is just <strong>the</strong> mediation <strong>of</strong> reflective judgment,<br />

must be taken seriously. Whatever else reflective judgment is – <strong>and</strong> it has<br />

many aspects <strong>and</strong> various applications both practical <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical, it is<br />

not <strong>of</strong> itself practical or ‘‘constructive.’’ It is contemplative, where this<br />

always presupposes a reflective principle <strong>of</strong> purposiveness ‘‘without regard<br />

to <strong>the</strong> practical.’’<br />

<strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> practical reason: metaphysical<br />

To argue that practical reason is not primary or prior in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> being<br />

<strong>the</strong> origin or justificatory source <strong>of</strong> all value is not to suggest that <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

no sense in which practical reason <strong>and</strong> agency are primary for <strong>Kant</strong>. In his<br />

comparative study <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Fichte, Karl Ameriks argues that <strong>the</strong><br />

values <strong>of</strong> practical reason are primary in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> having somehow<br />

more significance for human beings than ei<strong>the</strong>r cognitive or aes<strong>the</strong>tic or<br />

24 This is in no way to deny that in some sense reason is a unity for <strong>Kant</strong>. But I would argue for <strong>the</strong><br />

position that Dieter Henrich <strong>and</strong> many o<strong>the</strong>rs have advocated, that it is crucial to <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

philosophy that <strong>the</strong> unifying basis <strong>of</strong> reason itself cannot be known.


82<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r values. Ameriks suggests that pure practical reason ‘‘in <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

philosophy has a kind <strong>of</strong> preeminence because it discloses <strong>the</strong> basic<br />

sources <strong>and</strong> goals <strong>of</strong> what is valuable’’ <strong>and</strong> he argues that <strong>the</strong> moral law<br />

for <strong>Kant</strong> is<br />

<strong>the</strong> most significant object <strong>of</strong> our attention in <strong>the</strong> sense that it alone reveals what<br />

is <strong>of</strong> unconditional interest <strong>and</strong> value, <strong>the</strong> moral will. Although <strong>Kant</strong> recognized<br />

that mere <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> prudential activities also have considerable positive<br />

value, he insists that by <strong>the</strong>mselves <strong>the</strong>y are rooted in secondary interest that<br />

[has] nothing like <strong>the</strong> incomparable worth <strong>of</strong> morality. 25<br />

The language <strong>of</strong> revelation <strong>and</strong> disclosure is important here. Ameriks’<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical depends on a metaphysical<br />

interpretation <strong>of</strong> transcendental idealism that is <strong>the</strong> polar opposite <strong>of</strong><br />

O’Neill’s constructivism. For Ameriks, <strong>the</strong> Copernican turn <strong>and</strong> its<br />

‘‘denial <strong>of</strong> knowledge to make room for faith’’ is not <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> metaphysics<br />

but simply its redirection from <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical to <strong>the</strong> practical<br />

realm. The transcendental idealist account <strong>of</strong> nature is <strong>the</strong> methodological<br />

condition <strong>of</strong> our discovery, as moral agents, <strong>of</strong> a new practical<br />

metaphysics. It provides our ticket out <strong>of</strong> determined nature into ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

realm:<br />

<strong>the</strong> spatiotemporal laws covering all <strong>the</strong> ordinary appearances <strong>of</strong> our life need not<br />

constrain our inner or noumenal reality, <strong>and</strong> so, ra<strong>the</strong>r than having to give up<br />

morality in <strong>the</strong> face <strong>of</strong> a law-governed nature, we can <strong>and</strong> should accept morality<br />

as <strong>the</strong> guide to a nonspatiotemporal realm that exists <strong>and</strong> is more fundamental<br />

than nature. 26<br />

Ameriks goes on to argue that transcendental idealism has thus provided<br />

for ‘‘<strong>the</strong> only escape from ‘nature’ ... .’’ So that, on this reading, our<br />

noumenal being is revealed to us as a result <strong>of</strong> our denial <strong>of</strong> knowledge, in<br />

a sort <strong>of</strong> Critical reversal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fall from grace. The details <strong>of</strong> this new<br />

moral l<strong>and</strong>scape are a fur<strong>the</strong>r disclosure <strong>of</strong> practical reason, given in <strong>the</strong><br />

form <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> postulates <strong>of</strong> God, freedom, <strong>and</strong> immortality. 27<br />

Ameriks is correct in pointing to <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>Kant</strong>ian practical reason<br />

depends on his account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> limitations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical reason <strong>and</strong>, hence,<br />

in <strong>the</strong> overall structure <strong>of</strong> his philosophy, cannot be methodologically or<br />

logically prior. Yet Amerik’s unrepentant metaphysical account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

practical leaves it open to a criticism that <strong>Kant</strong> himself wanted very much<br />

25 Ameriks, ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>, Fichte,’’ p. 190.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

26 Ibid., p. 191.<br />

27 Ameriks, ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>, Fichte,’’ pp. 190–91.


Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical 83<br />

to avoid. That is, it portrays human beings as hopelessly alienated from<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves – if not at war with <strong>the</strong>ir own physicality, <strong>the</strong>n at least seriously<br />

alienated from <strong>the</strong>ir own basic nature as embodied ‘‘beings <strong>of</strong><br />

need.’’ 28 There can be no doubt that recognition <strong>of</strong> this concern in <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

philosophical enterprise is key to underst<strong>and</strong>ing him. Both versions <strong>of</strong> his<br />

introduction to his third <strong>and</strong> final Critique mention <strong>the</strong> need to reconnect<br />

nature <strong>and</strong> reason <strong>and</strong>, as we have already seen, <strong>the</strong> need to connect<br />

<strong>the</strong> rational/ethical <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> nature is urgent on moral grounds.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> last section <strong>of</strong> this chapter, I shall argue that <strong>Kant</strong> is also concerned<br />

about <strong>the</strong>oretical reason’s stake in this reconnection.<br />

As we saw earlier, <strong>Kant</strong> was painfully aware <strong>of</strong> this potential problem<br />

in Chapter III <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> second Critique, when he assumes that <strong>the</strong> moral law<br />

must have an effect on <strong>the</strong> will <strong>of</strong> human beings through some natural,<br />

subjective path – that is, through some sensuous impulse. Here, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

allows for such a feeling, albeit a ra<strong>the</strong>r tortured one caused by <strong>the</strong><br />

frustration by reason <strong>of</strong> sensuous inclination:<br />

For all inclination <strong>and</strong> every sensuous impulse is based on feeling, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

negative effect on feeling (through <strong>the</strong> check on <strong>the</strong> inclinations) is itself feeling.<br />

Consequently, we can see a priori that <strong>the</strong> moral law as a ground <strong>of</strong> determination<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> will, by thwarting all our inclinations, must produce a feeling<br />

which can be called pain. Here we have <strong>the</strong> first <strong>and</strong> perhaps <strong>the</strong> only case<br />

wherein we can determine from a priori concepts <strong>the</strong> relation <strong>of</strong> a cognition<br />

(here a cognition <strong>of</strong> pure practical reason) to <strong>the</strong> feeling <strong>of</strong> pleasure or<br />

displeasure. 29<br />

Assuming <strong>the</strong> plausibility <strong>of</strong> this move, it is still not much <strong>of</strong> an answer to<br />

<strong>the</strong> criticism that a bifurcated account <strong>of</strong> reason leads <strong>Kant</strong> inevitably to a<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> moral being that is essentially alienated from its natural self.<br />

Humiliation, even when rechristened as a feeling for <strong>the</strong> majesty <strong>of</strong> duty,<br />

as <strong>Kant</strong> himself puts it, ‘‘has nothing to do with <strong>the</strong> enjoyment <strong>of</strong> life.’’ 30<br />

Even with <strong>the</strong> addition <strong>of</strong> an account <strong>of</strong> moral feeling, <strong>the</strong> doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical interpreted as resting on a metaphysical ‘‘escape’’<br />

from nature, as Ameriks claims it does, leaves us with a ra<strong>the</strong>r disintegrated<br />

<strong>and</strong> desolate picture <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human condition. It is surely to avoid<br />

that portrait that <strong>Kant</strong>, even already at <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> second Critique,<br />

begins to move towards <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical incorporation <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r sorts <strong>of</strong><br />

28<br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason, trans. Lewis White Beck (Macmillan: 1988), V: 61.<br />

29 30<br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason, V:72–73. Ameriks, ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>, Fichte,’’ p. 88.


84<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

‘‘case[s] wherein we can determine from a priori concepts <strong>the</strong> relation <strong>of</strong> a<br />

cognition to <strong>the</strong> feeling <strong>of</strong> pleasure or displeasure.’’ 31<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> metaphysical primacy <strong>of</strong> practical reason that<br />

explicitly recognizes <strong>the</strong> depth <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> alienation problem for <strong>Kant</strong>, is<br />

Richard Velkley’s teleological reading in Freedom <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> End <strong>of</strong> Reason.<br />

Velkley argues that <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> reason was first<br />

apparent to <strong>Kant</strong> after his reading <strong>of</strong> Rousseau’s account <strong>of</strong> humanity’s<br />

progressive alienation from its own nature:<br />

The difficulties are subsumed under <strong>the</strong> heading <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘teleological problem’’ in<br />

<strong>the</strong> modern ‘‘individualistic’’ emancipation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> passions. If reason has no<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r end than to serve <strong>the</strong> passions aiming at freedom <strong>and</strong> mastery, what<br />

prevents reason, as a modifiable <strong>and</strong> exp<strong>and</strong>ing power, from unfolding in ways<br />

that exacerbated <strong>the</strong> passions <strong>and</strong> that increase human servitude to socially<br />

generated <strong>and</strong> factitious desires? By suggesting that <strong>the</strong> whole modern emancipatory<br />

effort may be self-defeating, Rousseau initiates <strong>the</strong> later modern criticism<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> modern world as <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> ‘‘alienation’’ in which man is subjugated by<br />

his own creations. 32<br />

In Velkley’s view, <strong>Kant</strong> solves <strong>the</strong> problem by asserting <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong><br />

practical reason, which Velkley interprets as <strong>the</strong> position that <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

philosophy has an ‘‘overarching moral project’’ that is actually a continuation<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> modern project <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> emancipation from nature:<br />

<strong>the</strong> modern critique <strong>of</strong> speculation is not neutral to all human purposes or human<br />

finality. The rejection <strong>of</strong> metaphysical first causes is to make room for <strong>the</strong><br />

supremacy <strong>of</strong> human final causes. The order <strong>of</strong> cosmic final causes is replaced by<br />

<strong>the</strong> legislated order or by <strong>the</strong> ideal construct supported only by human volition –<br />

<strong>the</strong> establishment <strong>of</strong> a new universal nomos that promotes <strong>the</strong> maximum <strong>of</strong> human<br />

freedom from <strong>the</strong> evils <strong>and</strong> unwelcome constraints <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural order ... <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

own critique is quite clearly a continuation <strong>of</strong> this emancipatory project. 33<br />

Whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> characterization <strong>of</strong> replacing cosmic order with ‘‘<strong>the</strong><br />

legislated order or ... <strong>the</strong> ideal construct supported only by human<br />

volition’’ is true to <strong>the</strong> intentions <strong>of</strong> modern philosophy prior to <strong>Kant</strong>, it<br />

is certainly true that <strong>Kant</strong> follows Rousseau in foregrounding <strong>the</strong> problem<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason, <strong>and</strong> as a result is moved by <strong>the</strong> need for a ‘‘<strong>the</strong>odicy <strong>of</strong> reason’’<br />

31 In <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Methodology <strong>of</strong> Pure Practical Reason,’’ <strong>Kant</strong> outlines two ‘‘exercises’’ for enabling moral<br />

cultivation that are rough sketches <strong>of</strong> his account <strong>of</strong> judgments <strong>of</strong> taste <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> sublime. Cf.<br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason, V:160–161.<br />

32 Velkley, Freedom <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> End <strong>of</strong> Reason: On <strong>the</strong> Moral Foundations <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critical Philosophy<br />

(Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1989), pp. 13–14.<br />

33 Ibid., pp. 18–19.


Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical 85<br />

to establish that ‘‘reason is a beneficent force in human life’’ (p. 2).<br />

According to Velkley, <strong>Kant</strong> ultimately finds that justification in <strong>the</strong><br />

view that ‘‘reason is governed by a single organizing principle or telos’’(pp.<br />

17–18), <strong>and</strong> already in <strong>the</strong> 1760s <strong>Kant</strong> was beginning to see <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘subjective need that human reason has <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> metaphysical concepts <strong>of</strong><br />

substance, force <strong>and</strong> causality, which is above all a moral need – <strong>the</strong><br />

inexorable concerns with <strong>the</strong> fate <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul, God <strong>and</strong> freedom ...’’<br />

(pp. 119–120). Velkley thus sees ‘‘<strong>the</strong> ‘core’ <strong>of</strong> metaphysics shift[ing] to its<br />

practical‘telos-giving part <strong>and</strong> away from <strong>the</strong>oretical inquiry’ in <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

philosophy’’(p. 119). Ultimately, Velkley claims, <strong>Kant</strong> developed a<br />

‘‘practical metaphysics’’ that has been revived in recent twentieth-century<br />

idealisms:<br />

One can say <strong>Kant</strong>’s idealism marks <strong>the</strong> high point <strong>of</strong> a certain effort that has<br />

been renewed, but not surpassed, by later phenomenological <strong>and</strong> hermeneutical<br />

definitions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘horizon’’ <strong>of</strong> experience. It would confine <strong>the</strong> reflection on <strong>the</strong><br />

absolute (whose meaning <strong>and</strong> content are ultimately moral), within <strong>the</strong> sphere <strong>of</strong><br />

human freedom <strong>and</strong> practice ... that is kept distinct from <strong>the</strong> speculative<br />

noumenal realm <strong>of</strong> modern idealism. (p. 135).<br />

The primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral end, for <strong>Kant</strong>, limits ‘‘<strong>the</strong> true metaphysical<br />

whole’’ (pp. 112–113) <strong>and</strong> since philosophy is only critique, not discovery,<br />

‘‘<strong>the</strong>oretical inquiry is primarily self knowledge’’ so that ‘‘<strong>the</strong> true calling<br />

<strong>of</strong> humanity is to legislate unity where disunity reigns’’ (p. 116). Of<br />

course, it is in nature that disunity appears to reign. Thus Velkley<br />

characterizes <strong>Kant</strong>’s solution as a triumph <strong>of</strong> reason – i.e., <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> will –<br />

over nature: Rousseau’s emphasis on <strong>the</strong> ‘‘unnaturalness’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> will<br />

(p. 74), <strong>of</strong> its increasingly greater separation from nature, posed <strong>the</strong><br />

problem <strong>of</strong> reason, but also set forth its solution: <strong>the</strong> will can be free <strong>of</strong><br />

natural impulses, hence ‘‘autonomous’’ <strong>and</strong> hence capable <strong>of</strong> acting as a<br />

‘‘restorative’’ for <strong>the</strong> ordering <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human soul: ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong> tends toward<br />

a single form <strong>of</strong> perfection in <strong>the</strong> teleological consummation <strong>of</strong> reason in<br />

a new legislation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> order <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul’’ (p. 66).<br />

For all its historical insight, Velkley’s interpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> is, in my<br />

view, flawed in two important ways. First, he presents a version <strong>of</strong> a flight<br />

from nature in <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy that ignores <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

judgments about natural beauty in <strong>Kant</strong>’s notion <strong>of</strong> teleology. These are<br />

not less important than his account <strong>of</strong> teleology in <strong>the</strong> second half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

third Critique, <strong>and</strong> indeed, <strong>Kant</strong> suggests that methodologically <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

more fundamental to his account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> connection <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> reason,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> practical <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical aspects <strong>of</strong> human functioning. The


86<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

Preface to <strong>the</strong> second Introduction to <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment ends with<br />

a short paragraph in which <strong>Kant</strong> says ‘‘With this I conclude my entire<br />

critical enterprise.’’ The directly preceding paragraphs are devoted to<br />

explaining why a transcendental account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘aes<strong>the</strong>tic power <strong>of</strong><br />

judgment’’ is necessary, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> role this power plays in solving <strong>the</strong> riddle<br />

<strong>of</strong> finding a principle for <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> judgment. <strong>Kant</strong>’s ‘‘entire critical<br />

enterprise,’’ in o<strong>the</strong>r words, comes to an end with an account <strong>of</strong> how<br />

judgment ‘‘whose correct use is so necessary <strong>and</strong> universally required that<br />

this power is just what we mean by sound underst<strong>and</strong>ing’’ (V: 169) itself<br />

relies on an account <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic – i.e, feeling-based – reflection. To insist<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong>’s enterprise was intended ultimately to overcome or transcend<br />

nature ignores <strong>the</strong> mediating role that imagination, disinterestedness, <strong>and</strong><br />

pleasure play in his critical enterprise. Certainly in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong><br />

Teleological Judgment’’ <strong>Kant</strong> is concerned with human culture <strong>and</strong><br />

progress, <strong>and</strong> is aware <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ever-increasing artificial desires that technical<br />

development brings. But precisely this concern sends him ‘‘back to nature’’<br />

in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment,’’ where he focuses on <strong>the</strong><br />

need to reconnect directly (non-instrumentally, but also non-morally)<br />

with nature, in such a way that we come to feel, via <strong>the</strong> pleasure <strong>of</strong><br />

reflection on perceptual forms, <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> nature’s conforming to<br />

our moral calling. Velkley’s reading leaves no room for this direct connection<br />

to nature, privileging instead <strong>the</strong> rational projection <strong>of</strong> a unitary<br />

ideal <strong>of</strong> human freedom that not only elides but in fact ‘‘overcomes’’<br />

nature in human subjectivity. It is exceedingly difficult, <strong>the</strong>n, to see how<br />

<strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> alienation <strong>of</strong> reason from nature that Velkley so<br />

carefully traces from <strong>Kant</strong> back to Rousseau, is solved on this reading.<br />

A second problem with this interpretation, in my opinion, is that it<br />

places extraordinary power in <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> philosopher. On Velkley’s<br />

reading, it is that elite group that plans a global ‘‘revolution in <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

<strong>and</strong> moral foundations’’:<br />

According to <strong>Kant</strong>, <strong>the</strong> philosopher is to be defined as a legislator, not as a mere<br />

<strong>the</strong>oretician. His legislation establishes <strong>the</strong> architectonic order <strong>of</strong> reason wherein<br />

<strong>the</strong> various investigations <strong>of</strong> philosophy <strong>and</strong> science are to take <strong>the</strong>ir places <strong>and</strong><br />

in which <strong>the</strong>y are to be viewed as collectively fur<strong>the</strong>ring <strong>the</strong> ultimate end that <strong>the</strong><br />

philosopher defines. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> philosopher legislates <strong>the</strong> systematic<br />

unity <strong>of</strong> reason as governed by a single organizing principle or telos. The revolution<br />

taking place in <strong>the</strong> foundational inquiries <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> moral philosophy<br />

has a principal architect – <strong>the</strong> philosophy as legislator. That is to say that<br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘‘local’’ revolutions in <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> moral foundations are reflecting a<br />

larger, more comprehensive revolution planned <strong>and</strong> initiated by <strong>the</strong> legislative<br />

activity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> critical philosopher. (p. 18)


Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical 87<br />

Philosophy takes on far more importance, on Velkley’s reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>,<br />

than <strong>the</strong> limiting function <strong>Kant</strong> claims for it in <strong>the</strong> first Critique. For<br />

Velkley, this is part <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s response to Rousseau, who questioned<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r ‘‘modern philosophy [can] maintain its position as <strong>the</strong> dominant<br />

force in human affairs <strong>and</strong> continue to promote <strong>the</strong> emancipation <strong>and</strong><br />

enlightenment <strong>of</strong> humanity’’ (p. 13). An ideal ‘‘definitive culture’’ is to be<br />

determined by philosophy as part <strong>of</strong> this answer, which according to<br />

Velkley involves an overwhelming commitment to practical concerns over<br />

<strong>the</strong>oretical ones: ‘‘all supersensible realities <strong>and</strong> causes are understood as<br />

subordinated to freedom’s essential projects ... <strong>Kant</strong> could not state<br />

more directly <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical in <strong>the</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>oundest sense in<br />

which he intends it; <strong>the</strong> practical determines <strong>the</strong> direction <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> even <strong>the</strong><br />

content <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical inquiry’’ (p. 144).<br />

Velkley’s notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical is not to be accused <strong>of</strong><br />

escapism, as Ameriks’ might, but it is all <strong>the</strong> more worrisome for that very<br />

reason. Freedom <strong>of</strong> inquiry <strong>and</strong> belief <strong>the</strong>mselves seem to disappear in <strong>the</strong><br />

all-encompassing quest for unity <strong>of</strong> reason. This is surely too high a price<br />

to pay for conquering alienation, <strong>and</strong> it is hard to believe that <strong>Kant</strong><br />

himself would entertain, let alone subscribe to, such a vision. Indeed, <strong>the</strong><br />

very spirit <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Rousseauistic revolution’’ in his way <strong>of</strong> thinking about<br />

ordinary humanity appears to give way, on this account, to an extreme<br />

paternalism that is precisely <strong>the</strong> wrong answer to <strong>the</strong> question ‘‘What is<br />

Enlightenment?’’ Paradoxically, on this account <strong>the</strong> elevation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

practical over <strong>the</strong>ory opens <strong>the</strong> door to <strong>the</strong> very authoritarianism it was<br />

supposed to combat. As we shall see shortly, <strong>Kant</strong> was aware <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> danger<br />

<strong>of</strong> letting practical reason take over all aspects <strong>of</strong> human experience, <strong>and</strong><br />

wanted to block <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> its dictating content to <strong>the</strong>ory.<br />

Richard Eldridge, in The Persistence <strong>of</strong> Romanticism, also sees <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

philosophy as centrally engaging <strong>the</strong> alienation problem, but he is less<br />

inclined to read <strong>Kant</strong> as assigning <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> instituting a higher moral<br />

culture on earth to <strong>the</strong> philosopher:<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> regards his own philosophical writing as advancing this work, helping to<br />

free us from tutelage or service to our animal nature so as to achieve collective<br />

rational freedom. His articulation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> principle <strong>of</strong> morality is to help to move<br />

us first to found a liberal state <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n fur<strong>the</strong>r, through culture, to bring our<br />

ends into rational harmony with one ano<strong>the</strong>r. This advance toward freedom first<br />

through politics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n through culture is not however, <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> philosophy<br />

alone. Art has a crucial role to play in this development. 34<br />

34 Richard Eldridge, The Persistence <strong>of</strong> Romanticism: Essays in Philosophy <strong>and</strong> Literature (Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press, 2001), p. 38.


88<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

Eldridge takes <strong>the</strong> separation <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> freedom problematized in <strong>the</strong><br />

third Critique to be an expression <strong>of</strong> a latent ‘‘deep anxiety’’ in <strong>Kant</strong><br />

about <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> actually manifesting our freedom in <strong>the</strong> world<br />

(p. 36). <strong>Kant</strong>’s ‘‘imaginative narratives’’ about <strong>the</strong> (possible) progress <strong>of</strong><br />

human history are ways <strong>of</strong> dealing with that angst, <strong>and</strong> perhaps even <strong>of</strong><br />

combatting <strong>the</strong> miserable human conditions that cause it. Moreover, he<br />

points out, <strong>the</strong> artist’s imaginative <strong>and</strong> communicable work might do <strong>the</strong><br />

same. In ‘‘How is <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian Moral Criticism <strong>of</strong> Literature possible?,’’<br />

he discusses <strong>Kant</strong>’s characterization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> domain <strong>of</strong> philosophy – i.e. <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> overall human condition – in <strong>the</strong> second introduction to <strong>the</strong> third<br />

Critique. 35 Eldridge glosses <strong>Kant</strong>’s worry as follows: ‘‘we will not rest<br />

content with an empty, speculative freedom that is not intelligibly<br />

actualizable <strong>and</strong> we must somehow come to see <strong>the</strong> world as supporting<br />

<strong>the</strong> actualization <strong>of</strong> freedom’’ (p. 75). Eldridge recognizes, in o<strong>the</strong>r words,<br />

that <strong>the</strong> third Critique takes up <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> alienation, <strong>and</strong> presents a<br />

third way between metaphysical accounts <strong>of</strong> morality (whe<strong>the</strong>r noumenal<br />

or politically ideal) <strong>and</strong> first-person practical reasoning approaches, both<br />

<strong>of</strong> which only perpetuate <strong>the</strong> alienation <strong>of</strong> human freedom from human<br />

nature. ‘‘It is too little recognized,’’ Eldridge writes, ‘‘that <strong>Kant</strong> began in<br />

his last writings, particularly in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, to rethink <strong>the</strong><br />

problem <strong>of</strong> how <strong>the</strong>re can be morality <strong>and</strong> freedom in <strong>the</strong> sensible world’’<br />

(p. 75).<br />

Eldridge is particularly interested in <strong>the</strong> role that genius plays in<br />

actualizing freedom through art, <strong>and</strong> I shall return to this point in later<br />

chapters. For now, his point about <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third Critique is well<br />

taken: By <strong>the</strong> time he wrote his final critical work, <strong>Kant</strong> had changed his<br />

views about <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sensible, <strong>of</strong> feeling, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> imagination with<br />

respect to morality. What he had declared impossible in <strong>the</strong> first Critique<br />

<strong>and</strong> unlikely in <strong>the</strong> second, became <strong>the</strong> focus <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> entire first half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

third Critique: <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> pleasures – not painful humiliations –<br />

based on conditions that were universal <strong>and</strong> a priori. There he argues that<br />

reflection gives rise in aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment to a feeling whose universal<br />

validity depends upon its independence from practical <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

determination. Since aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection itself involves <strong>the</strong> conditions <strong>of</strong><br />

cognition in general (imagination <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing in free play) <strong>the</strong><br />

resulting feelings have a pedigree every bit as pure as that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> humbled<br />

feeling <strong>of</strong> respect for <strong>the</strong> moral law. Some reflective feelings, like <strong>the</strong><br />

35 Ibid., pp. 71–84.


Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical 89<br />

feeling <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sublime, involve <strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>of</strong> pure practical reason <strong>and</strong> our<br />

recognition <strong>of</strong> our moral autonomy in <strong>the</strong> face <strong>of</strong> purposeless nature. But<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>and</strong> indeed <strong>the</strong> paradigm case <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic feeling – namely, our<br />

feelings for <strong>the</strong> beautiful – depend entirely on conditions <strong>of</strong> cognition in<br />

general. Such feelings not only are independent <strong>of</strong> practical reason, but<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir very right to claim universal validity depends on this independence.<br />

36<br />

<strong>the</strong> mediated primacy <strong>of</strong> practical reason<br />

I want now to return to <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> alienation raised by what I have<br />

been calling metaphysical readings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> priority <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s initial attempt to bring <strong>the</strong> practical back into <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> nature.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> went on to address <strong>the</strong> issue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> causal efficacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral in <strong>the</strong><br />

Dialectic <strong>of</strong> Pure Practical Reason, by introducing <strong>the</strong> conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Highest Good as <strong>the</strong> necessary objective <strong>of</strong> practical reason. The moral<br />

law, <strong>Kant</strong> argues, dem<strong>and</strong>s that we strive to produce, in nature, a state in<br />

which ‘‘happiness [is] in exact proportion to morality.’’ 37 But if we are<br />

incapable <strong>of</strong> so doing, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> moral law itself must be ‘‘fantastic,<br />

directed toward imaginary ends, <strong>and</strong> consequently inherently false.’’ 38<br />

The famous solution to this problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> potentially debilitating moral<br />

alienation from our natural selves was <strong>of</strong> course <strong>the</strong> postulates <strong>of</strong> practical<br />

reason – <strong>of</strong> immortality <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> God. It is as a springboard for this<br />

dangerous leap <strong>of</strong> reason, which in effect involves breaching <strong>the</strong><br />

boundaries <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical reason for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> practice, that <strong>Kant</strong><br />

explicitly argues for <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> practical reason. Having looked at<br />

several interpretations <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s doctrine, it is perhaps time to examine<br />

his own account.<br />

Unfortunately, <strong>Kant</strong>’s own statement <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical<br />

turns out to be far from transparent. To begin, as already mentioned, its<br />

placement in <strong>the</strong> Critique is clearly strategic, if not ad hoc. To preserve<br />

<strong>the</strong> doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest good, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> need for a more integrated<br />

account <strong>of</strong> morality that motivates it, <strong>Kant</strong> has taken up a precarious<br />

position. He has allowed reason to suspend <strong>the</strong> Copernican turn in order,<br />

36<br />

Cf. Paul Guyer, ‘‘Feeling <strong>and</strong> Freedom: <strong>Kant</strong> on Aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> Morality,’’ in <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Experience <strong>of</strong> Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 1–47, esp. pp. 46–47.<br />

Guyer sees this independence as ultimately serving pure practical reason. The argument <strong>of</strong> this<br />

chapter is slightly different – namely, that this independence does also serve pure practical reason.<br />

It is not, however, independence for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> morality.<br />

37 38<br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason, V:110. Ibid., V: 114.


90<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> practice, to make <strong>the</strong> bald metaphysical claims <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

postulates. 39 To prepare <strong>the</strong> ground for this un-Critical move, he argues<br />

that under certain circumstances speculative reason ought to<br />

take up <strong>the</strong>se principles [<strong>of</strong> practical reason] <strong>and</strong> seek to integrate <strong>the</strong>m, even<br />

though <strong>the</strong>y transcend it, with its own concepts, as a foreign possession h<strong>and</strong>ed<br />

over to it ... It must assume <strong>the</strong>m indeed as something <strong>of</strong>fered from <strong>the</strong> outside<br />

<strong>and</strong> not grown in its own soil, <strong>and</strong> it must seek to compare <strong>and</strong> connect <strong>the</strong>m<br />

with everything which it has in its power as speculative reason. It must remember<br />

that <strong>the</strong>y are not its own insights but extensions <strong>of</strong> its use in some o<strong>the</strong>r respect,<br />

viz., <strong>the</strong> practical; that this is not in <strong>the</strong> least opposed to its interest, which lies in<br />

<strong>the</strong> restriction <strong>of</strong> speculative folly. 40<br />

The interests <strong>of</strong> practical reason, where <strong>the</strong>y are ‘‘inseparably bound’’ to<br />

it, trump <strong>the</strong> interests <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical reason, but only because <strong>the</strong> former’s<br />

interests are not ‘‘in <strong>the</strong> least’’ opposed to <strong>the</strong> latter’s. They are just<br />

different from <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> says, ‘‘It is not a question <strong>of</strong> which must<br />

yield, for one does not necessarily conflict with <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.’’ 41 Yet practical<br />

reason’s ability to trump speculation is not as powerful as it might seem.<br />

Although he claims that ‘‘if <strong>the</strong> speculative <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical were<br />

arranged merely side by side (coordinated),’’ a conflict would arise, his<br />

argument for <strong>the</strong> need to give preference to practical ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

needs is based on a worry that, without a specified hierarchy <strong>of</strong><br />

interests, ei<strong>the</strong>r side might take over:<br />

<strong>the</strong> first [speculative reason] would close its borders <strong>and</strong> admit into its domain<br />

nothing from <strong>the</strong> latter [practical reason], while [practical reason] would extend<br />

its boundaries over everything <strong>and</strong>, when its needs required, would seek to<br />

comprehend [speculative reason] within <strong>the</strong>m. Nor could we reverse <strong>the</strong> order<br />

<strong>and</strong> expect practical reason to submit to speculative reason. 42<br />

The point here seems to be that giving certain interests <strong>of</strong> practical reason<br />

primacy is legitimate to <strong>the</strong> extent that it maintains a reasonable balance<br />

<strong>and</strong> harmony between <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> practical reason, including keeping<br />

practical reason itself under control. <strong>Kant</strong>’s own account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical is thus a far more mitigated sort <strong>of</strong> preference than many<br />

commentators, including both O’Neill <strong>and</strong> Korsgaard, <strong>and</strong> even Ameriks,<br />

seem to want to attribute to <strong>Kant</strong>. Moreover, it suggests that <strong>Kant</strong> is<br />

39<br />

Yirmiyahu Yovel, in <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Philosophy <strong>of</strong> History (Princeton: Princeton University Press,<br />

1980), pp. 287ff, makes a strong case for <strong>the</strong> untenability <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s incorporation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> postulates<br />

in his system.<br />

40 41 42<br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason, V:120ff. Ibid. Ibid., V: 121.


Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical 91<br />

already groping for <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> mediating faculty that he would soon<br />

suggest in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment as a way <strong>of</strong> coordinating without<br />

subordinating ei<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

It is worth looking more closely at what <strong>Kant</strong> seems to want at this<br />

point in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason, <strong>and</strong> in particular to note his<br />

concern that practical reason ‘‘would extend its boundaries over everything<br />

<strong>and</strong>, when its needs required, would seek to comprehend<br />

[speculative reason] within <strong>the</strong>m.’’ His worries about placing speculation<br />

over pure practical reason – moral autonomy – are well known. They date<br />

back to his first awakening, thanks to Rousseau, to <strong>the</strong> incomparable<br />

value <strong>of</strong> humanity, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> concern that a dogmatic preference for <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>oretical could render one blind to that value. Here, however, he<br />

expresses a parallel concern that if practical reason is not suitably<br />

restrained it will become ideological, bending <strong>the</strong>ory to suit its purposes.<br />

This is an important insight that is unfortunately obscured by his call for<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory to borrow <strong>the</strong> principles <strong>of</strong> practical reason ‘‘<strong>and</strong> seek to integrate<br />

<strong>the</strong>m ... as a foreign possession’’ to be compared <strong>and</strong> connected with<br />

everything that it can, for <strong>the</strong> purposes <strong>of</strong> lending support to morality. To<br />

be sure, this is permitted only if <strong>and</strong> when <strong>the</strong> ‘‘borrowed’’ principle is<br />

shown to be inseparably bound up with <strong>the</strong> needs <strong>of</strong> pure practical<br />

reason, so that no mere ‘‘pathological interest,’’ or (we might say)<br />

ideology, is at its root.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s intention at this point in <strong>the</strong> second Critique is to set <strong>the</strong> stage<br />

for <strong>the</strong> postulates <strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> immortality, which ‘‘reason holds out to us<br />

as <strong>the</strong> supplement to our impotence to [realize] <strong>the</strong> highest good.’’ The<br />

problem with <strong>Kant</strong>’s explanation <strong>of</strong> how postulating metaphysical<br />

notions will provide <strong>the</strong> rational hope necessary to fulfill our moral<br />

obligations has already been examined in chapter 2: How could <strong>Kant</strong><br />

suspend <strong>the</strong> entire critical apparatus for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> bringing back <strong>the</strong>ological<br />

metaphysics? 43 And even if he could get away with that on<br />

practical grounds, does <strong>the</strong> introduction <strong>of</strong> supernatural aids really solve<br />

<strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> how we can rationally hope to bring about <strong>the</strong> highest<br />

good in nature, as <strong>the</strong> moral law comm<strong>and</strong>s that we do? 44 Moreover, if<br />

<strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> practical reason was introduced as a doctrine in order to<br />

make sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> arguments for <strong>the</strong> postulates, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter fail, <strong>of</strong> what<br />

systematic use is <strong>the</strong> primacy claim?<br />

Again, <strong>the</strong> third Critique, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> independence <strong>of</strong><br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic value, are crucial to <strong>the</strong> final story. There is indeed a sense in<br />

43 Yovel, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Philosophy <strong>of</strong> History.<br />

44 See chapter 2 in this volume.


92<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

which for <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical is primary, but it has to do nei<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong><br />

claim that all values are ultimately constructed by us, nor with <strong>the</strong> need<br />

for a practical procedure that serves as guide for all such construction.<br />

Nei<strong>the</strong>r does this primacy have to do with discovering <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> all<br />

value in an inner world transcending nature, nor in a unifying definitive<br />

telos <strong>of</strong> human reason. What appears to be motivating <strong>the</strong> primacy claim<br />

in <strong>the</strong> second Critique is <strong>the</strong> need to link morality in its pure rational<br />

form to <strong>the</strong> fact <strong>of</strong> human beings’ finitude <strong>and</strong> embodiment. <strong>Kant</strong> was<br />

keenly aware in <strong>the</strong> second Critique that his moral <strong>the</strong>ory required <strong>of</strong><br />

human beings a feeling <strong>of</strong> hope if it was to provide a plausible account <strong>of</strong><br />

how we could possibly be required to implement its dem<strong>and</strong>s in <strong>the</strong><br />

natural world. But humiliation, God, <strong>and</strong> immortality were not enough.<br />

In The Unity <strong>of</strong> Reason: Rereading <strong>Kant</strong>, Susan Neiman argues that, for<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>, <strong>the</strong> alienation human beings feel as moral beings in <strong>the</strong> world <strong>of</strong><br />

nature is ‘‘so fundamental that it can never be fully overcome.’’ She<br />

claims that ‘‘If philosophy involves coming <strong>of</strong> age [as <strong>Kant</strong> claims in<br />

‘‘What is Enlightenment?’’], it also involves an acceptance <strong>of</strong> loss <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

unreflective sense <strong>of</strong> unity that children feel toward <strong>the</strong>ir world.’’ 45 I think<br />

she is right to recall <strong>the</strong> depth <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s realization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pervasive<br />

disharmony <strong>and</strong> unease between human reason <strong>and</strong> its embodiment. At<br />

<strong>the</strong> same time, however, it is <strong>the</strong> case that <strong>Kant</strong> sought some kind <strong>of</strong><br />

connection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two, <strong>and</strong> clearly intended his analysis <strong>of</strong> judgment <strong>of</strong><br />

beauty to help serve that purpose. A naive, unreflective sense <strong>of</strong> unity had<br />

to be outgrown, as Neiman rightly points out, but in fact <strong>Kant</strong> found a<br />

mature version <strong>of</strong> that unity in <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> a reflective aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

sense for nature’s objects. That it is also contingent, as we saw in chapter<br />

3, on human beings having <strong>the</strong> access to nature <strong>and</strong> leisure to reflect upon<br />

it does not make it any less important as a remedy for alienation, <strong>and</strong> as I<br />

have already suggested, may make <strong>the</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> beauty a crucial<br />

part <strong>of</strong> moral development. At <strong>the</strong> very least it reintroduces human<br />

45 Susan Neiman, The Unity <strong>of</strong> Reason: Rereading <strong>Kant</strong> (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994),<br />

p. 202. Neiman’s view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical is that it comes down to a primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

moral world in terms <strong>of</strong> its power <strong>and</strong> application relative to that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical reason. She equates<br />

<strong>the</strong>oretical reason with science, <strong>and</strong> argues that <strong>the</strong>oretical reason is crucially dependent on <strong>the</strong><br />

cooperation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world. Practical reason, by contrast, can achieve its ends alone. She goes on to<br />

argue that <strong>the</strong> objects <strong>of</strong> practical reason, because <strong>the</strong>y are our own ends, are breathtakingly simple<br />

to realize (pp. 128–129). Of course, if <strong>the</strong> Highest Good is an end <strong>of</strong> reason, <strong>and</strong> we are indeed<br />

required to try to make it real in <strong>the</strong> world in <strong>the</strong> face <strong>of</strong> an utter lack <strong>of</strong> reason to think that is<br />

even possible for us, <strong>the</strong>n developing <strong>the</strong> right internal attitude towards our duty becomes a real<br />

problem for reason. (See chapter 2 for fur<strong>the</strong>r discussion <strong>of</strong> Neiman’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest good<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> postulates.)


Aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical 93<br />

imaginative, creative capacities into our navigation between <strong>the</strong> two<br />

aspects <strong>of</strong> our human selves.<br />

We have seen that several sections <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

Judgment’’ may be read as an account <strong>of</strong> how reflective aes<strong>the</strong>tic valuing<br />

can serve <strong>the</strong> purposes <strong>of</strong> moral judgment in precisely <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> way that<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> needed, by embodying values <strong>of</strong> practical reason. A passage quoted<br />

earlier from Section 42 <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment’’ is worth<br />

looking at again, because it <strong>of</strong>fers <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> an aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective<br />

approach to <strong>the</strong> alienation problem that was never really solved by <strong>the</strong><br />

postulation <strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> immortality. If we were somehow to be able to<br />

sense or feel that nature had a place for moral beings – that beings with<br />

purpose belonged <strong>the</strong>re, <strong>and</strong> that nature itself had a purpose – <strong>the</strong>n we<br />

would have something <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> feeling <strong>of</strong> hope that we need to make<br />

following its strict law possible <strong>and</strong> even natural:<br />

reason also has an interest in <strong>the</strong> objective reality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ideas (for which, in<br />

moral feeling, it brings about a direct interest), i.e., an interest that nature should<br />

at least show a trace or give a hint that it contains some basis or o<strong>the</strong>r for us to<br />

assume in its products a lawful harmony with that liking <strong>of</strong> ours which is<br />

independent <strong>of</strong> all interest (a liking we recognize ‘‘a priori’’ as a law for everyone,<br />

thus we cannot base this law on pro<strong>of</strong>s). Hence reason must take an interest in<br />

any manifestation in nature <strong>of</strong> a harmony that resembles <strong>the</strong> mentioned harmony,<br />

<strong>and</strong> hence <strong>the</strong> mind cannot meditate about <strong>the</strong> beauty <strong>of</strong> nature without<br />

at <strong>the</strong> same time finding its interest aroused. 46<br />

But that is something that we can achieve only indirectly through moral<br />

ideas. That is, in order for <strong>the</strong> connection <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> moral interest to<br />

occur, our attention <strong>and</strong> our feeling must be directly connected with<br />

nature itself, apart from any moral interest. It is only disinterested,<br />

contemplative, non-practical but direct interest in nature’s forms that<br />

makes possible <strong>the</strong> indirect link to morality:<br />

it is not this link [between nature’s beauty <strong>and</strong> moral ideas] that interests us<br />

directly, but ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> beauty’s own characteristic <strong>of</strong> qualifying for such a link,<br />

which <strong>the</strong>refore belongs to it intrinsically. 47<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s insight is in a way quite simple: If we want pro<strong>of</strong> that our moral<br />

nature is compatible with ourselves as embodied finite creatures – that<br />

rationality <strong>and</strong> animality belong naturally toge<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong> that we can<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore hope to achieve our highest moral goals in this world – <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong><br />

world must present us with at least a ‘‘hint’’ that it is possible that our<br />

moral purposes have a place in it. Disinterested contemplation <strong>and</strong> a<br />

46 Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, V:300.<br />

47 Ibid., V: 302.


94<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

consequent direct interest in nature gives us an independent reason,<br />

however tentative, to believe in our capacity to bring morality to <strong>the</strong><br />

world. <strong>Kant</strong>’s solution to <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gulf between <strong>the</strong> two uses <strong>of</strong><br />

reason here amounts to a suspension <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

moral. Aes<strong>the</strong>tic values are not fundamental conditions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral law,<br />

nor <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> all value, but <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong> source <strong>of</strong> an independent <strong>and</strong><br />

very special value, without which fulfilling our moral duty would be a<br />

grim <strong>and</strong> desperate undertaking. It is this insight that is buried by<br />

overemphasizing <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical in <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy. Such<br />

emphasis amounts to neglecting a fundamental aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

humanism: its focus on ‘‘<strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject as a being <strong>of</strong> sense,<br />

namely, as a human being.’’ 48<br />

48 Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason, V:196. I would like to thank Henry Allison for comments on my<br />

reading <strong>of</strong> Section 42 ‘‘On <strong>the</strong> Intellectual Interest in <strong>the</strong> Beautiful,’’ that helped me clarify <strong>the</strong><br />

relationship <strong>of</strong> moral to aes<strong>the</strong>tic value <strong>the</strong>re. For a sustained account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> independence <strong>of</strong><br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic value from moral value, but <strong>the</strong> ultimate subordination <strong>of</strong> this independence to morality,<br />

<strong>the</strong> reader is referred to Guyer’s introduction <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> essays collected in <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Experience <strong>of</strong><br />

Freedom. Guyer’s book, (<strong>Kant</strong> on Freedom, Law, <strong>and</strong> Happiness, Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 2000), however, is less centrally concerned with aes<strong>the</strong>tic value, <strong>and</strong> indeed, in<br />

arguing for a normative conception <strong>of</strong> freedom as ‘‘our fundamental value’’ Guyer seems to be<br />

moving away from his earlier emphasis on <strong>the</strong> independence <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic value in its relation to<br />

moral value.


chapter 5<br />

The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination<br />

In a well-known account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> transcendental imagination in<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy, Martin Heidegger practically accused <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>of</strong> intellectual<br />

cowardice. Heidegger argued that <strong>Kant</strong>’s refusal in <strong>the</strong> second<br />

edition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason to grant that <strong>the</strong> imagination was a<br />

fundamental faculty was a result <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s having originally identified <strong>the</strong><br />

transcendental imagination with <strong>the</strong> ‘‘common root’’ <strong>of</strong> sensibility <strong>and</strong><br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> his subsequently being unwilling to grant such<br />

basic status to a faculty whose obscure nature frightened him: ‘‘He saw<br />

<strong>the</strong> unknown,’’ Heidegger says, <strong>and</strong> ‘‘he had to draw back.’’ 1<br />

In what has become a classic critique <strong>of</strong> Heidegger’s <strong>Kant</strong> interpretation,<br />

Dieter Henrich’s ‘‘Die Einheit der Subjektivität’’ (‘‘On <strong>the</strong> Unity <strong>of</strong><br />

Subjectivity’’) 2 takes up his challenge to <strong>the</strong> integrity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian<br />

enterprise <strong>and</strong> defends <strong>Kant</strong> on <strong>the</strong> grounds that his refusal to explore <strong>the</strong><br />

common root <strong>of</strong> both sensibility <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing really has nothing to<br />

do with <strong>Kant</strong>’s attitude toward <strong>the</strong> imagination, but ra<strong>the</strong>r represents his<br />

adoption <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> view, already promulgated against Christian Wolff by<br />

Christian August Crusius, that subjectivity cannot be traced to a single<br />

basic faculty or principle. Far from suggesting <strong>the</strong> need to identify any<br />

common root <strong>of</strong> human subjectivity, Henrich argues, <strong>Kant</strong> denies outright<br />

<strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> ever knowing such a basic power <strong>and</strong> is agnostic<br />

about <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> such a power even apart from <strong>the</strong> conditions <strong>of</strong><br />

1 See Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason (CPR), trans. Norman Kemp Smith (New York, 1929), Introduction,<br />

A15/B 29: ‘‘<strong>the</strong>re are two stems <strong>of</strong> human knowledge, namely, sensibility <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing, which<br />

perhaps spring from a common, but to us unknown, root.’’ And see also Heidegger, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Problem <strong>of</strong> Metaphysics (KPM), trans. James S. Churchill (Bloomington: University <strong>of</strong> Indiana<br />

Press, 1962), pp. 41–42, 173.<br />

2 Dieter Henrich, ‘‘Die Einheit der Subjektivität,’’ Philosophische Rundschau 3 (1955), pp. 28–69.<br />

Trans. Gunter Zöeller as ‘‘On <strong>the</strong> Unity <strong>of</strong> Subjectivity,’’ in Dieter Henrich, The Unity <strong>of</strong> Reason:<br />

Essays on <strong>Kant</strong>’s Philosophy, ed. Richard Velkley (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994).<br />

The translations in this chapter are Zöeller’s.<br />

95


96<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

human knowledge. 3 Since <strong>Kant</strong> ultimately ‘‘renounces’’ a positive answer<br />

to <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> what conditions <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> human subjectivity,<br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘‘unknown’’ common root that <strong>Kant</strong> refers to in <strong>the</strong> introduction to<br />

<strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason cannot be any known faculty <strong>and</strong> hence<br />

cannot be <strong>the</strong> imagination. 4 The imagination is not suppressed or ‘‘displaced’’<br />

in <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy, but is simply not central.<br />

Historically, <strong>the</strong> notion that human subjectivity must be unified on <strong>the</strong><br />

basis <strong>of</strong> its stemming from a common source in that which mediates<br />

sensibility <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing was a <strong>the</strong>me worked out in Johann Gottlieb<br />

Fichte, F. W. J. Schelling, <strong>and</strong> G. W. F. Hegel <strong>and</strong> voiced again, Henrich<br />

argues, in Heidegger. But for critical philosophy such unity was<br />

unknowable <strong>and</strong> could be explained regulatively only in terms <strong>of</strong> some<br />

sort <strong>of</strong> ‘‘intrasubjective’’ purposiveness: 5<br />

The unity <strong>of</strong> subjectivity, in <strong>Kant</strong>’s final construction <strong>of</strong> it, is conceived as<br />

teleological. <strong>Kant</strong> feels compelled to look beyond what is immediately given in<br />

consciousness, ‘‘to look beyond <strong>the</strong> sensible to <strong>the</strong> supersensible as <strong>the</strong> point<br />

where all our a priori powers are reconciled, since that is <strong>the</strong> only alternative left<br />

to us for bringing reason into harmony with itself.’’ 6<br />

But so far as knowledge is concerned, <strong>the</strong> structural unity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> faculties<br />

is contingent. If this is <strong>Kant</strong>’s view, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>of</strong> course no account could be<br />

established for <strong>the</strong> primacy <strong>of</strong> imagination as <strong>the</strong> original source <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge. The imagination is only one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> faculties <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind, all<br />

<strong>of</strong> which can only be encountered ‘‘derivatively’’ through experience. 7<br />

This, Henrich argues, explains <strong>Kant</strong>’s turn away from any attempt to<br />

‘‘deduce’’ <strong>the</strong> faculties in <strong>the</strong> first edition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critique to a ‘‘logical<br />

analysis’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conditions <strong>of</strong> knowledge in <strong>the</strong> revised second edition.<br />

Not a fear <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unknown source <strong>of</strong> reason, but ra<strong>the</strong>r a recognition <strong>of</strong> its<br />

unavailability, led <strong>Kant</strong> to focus on <strong>the</strong> conditions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing,<br />

whose structures – <strong>the</strong> logical forms <strong>of</strong> judgment – unlike imagination or<br />

sensibility, he was convinced were available for examination. Hence,<br />

according to Henrich, <strong>Kant</strong> became increasingly cautious about any<br />

3 Henrich, ‘‘Die Einheit der Subjektivität,’’ pp. 32–39.<br />

4 If any faculty is to be viewed as most fundamental to <strong>the</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> human subjectivity, Henrich<br />

argues, it is ‘‘apperception <strong>and</strong> its categories’’ (p. 44). Henrich does admit that this renunciation <strong>of</strong><br />

hope for grounding subjectivity did not come easily to <strong>Kant</strong> (p. 46).<br />

5 Henrich, ‘‘Die Einheit der Subjektivität,’’ pp. 44–45. The search for a unifying principle is seen by<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> to be a necessary subjective condition <strong>of</strong> reason, <strong>and</strong> hence <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> a fundamental faculty<br />

or power is a regulative idea.<br />

6 Ibid., p. 46. The quotation from <strong>Kant</strong> is from <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, trans. Werner Pluhar<br />

(Indianapolis <strong>and</strong> Cambridge: Hackett, 1987) V:341.<br />

7 Ibid., p. 50.


The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 97<br />

attempt to explain <strong>the</strong> exact nature <strong>of</strong> sensibility or <strong>the</strong> relationship <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination to <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing. Since <strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> faculties in any<br />

absolute sense is unknown to human beings, <strong>the</strong> mediating role <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination must be understood as merely ‘‘<strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> activities that are<br />

required in addition to <strong>the</strong> objective principles <strong>of</strong> knowledge in order to<br />

render intelligible <strong>the</strong> actuality <strong>of</strong> knowledge.’’ 8 Viewing <strong>the</strong> imagination<br />

in this operational sense explains <strong>Kant</strong>’s move, in <strong>the</strong> second edition <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Critique, to assimilate it to <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing as one <strong>of</strong> its functions.<br />

Henrich’s argument seems historically correct. Few would argue<br />

against <strong>the</strong> claim that <strong>the</strong> idealists’ move to extend knowledge to an<br />

account <strong>of</strong> its ultimate origins constituted a decisive break with <strong>Kant</strong>ian<br />

philosophy, even if not all its proponents saw it as such at <strong>the</strong> time. Yet<br />

<strong>the</strong> success <strong>of</strong> Henrich’s ‘‘epistemological’’ approach has had <strong>the</strong> effect <strong>of</strong><br />

pushing interesting aspects <strong>of</strong> Heidegger’s reading into a corner to ga<strong>the</strong>r<br />

dust. In particular, <strong>Kant</strong> scholars have tended to neglect what Heidegger,<br />

on his reading, was able to appreciate – namely, <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>Kant</strong> was<br />

unusually struck by what he took to be <strong>the</strong> mysterious nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination <strong>and</strong> that, even in <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> cognition (not to mention<br />

human action <strong>and</strong> motivation) <strong>Kant</strong> did appear suspicious <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination’s<br />

inscrutability. 9<br />

Yet a third wrinkle has been added to <strong>the</strong> fabric <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> debate by<br />

Hartmut Böhme <strong>and</strong> Gernot Böhme, in <strong>the</strong>ir book Das Andere der<br />

Vernunft. They agree with Henrich that <strong>the</strong> critical turn in some sense<br />

necessitated <strong>Kant</strong>’s move away from viewing <strong>the</strong> imagination as a separate<br />

faculty, but take this shift to be grounds for criticizing <strong>the</strong> entire <strong>Kant</strong>ian<br />

enterprise. 10 They argue that, whatever his philosophical reasons, <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

unwillingness to grant <strong>the</strong> imagination any sort <strong>of</strong> autonomous status was<br />

rooted in psychological misapprehensions <strong>of</strong> phobic proportions. And<br />

while subconscious fears <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> its close association with<br />

feeling <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> body were typical <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Enlightenment psyche, <strong>the</strong>y were<br />

by no means ‘‘healthy.’’ After some very illuminating <strong>and</strong> entertaining<br />

textual analysis, <strong>the</strong> Böhmes conclude that <strong>the</strong> critical turn was an<br />

8 Ibid., p. 54.<br />

9 See, e.g., CPR, A78/B103: ‘‘Syn<strong>the</strong>sis in general ... is <strong>the</strong> mere result <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination,<br />

a blind but indispensable function <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul, without which we should have no knowledge<br />

whatsoever, but <strong>of</strong> which we are scarcely ever conscious.’’ And A123: ‘‘That <strong>the</strong> affinity <strong>of</strong><br />

appearances ... <strong>and</strong> so experience itself, should only be possible by means <strong>of</strong> this transcendental<br />

function <strong>of</strong> imagination, is indeed strange, but is none<strong>the</strong>less an obvious consequence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

preceding argument.’’<br />

10 Hartmut Böhme <strong>and</strong> Gernot Böhme, Das Andere der Vernunft: Zur Entwicklung von<br />

Rationalitätsstrukturen am Beispiel <strong>Kant</strong>s (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1996).


98<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

anxiety-driven swerve away from philosophical engagement with creative<br />

<strong>and</strong> enriching aspects <strong>of</strong> human experience. On a more sinister note, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

suggest that <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy sealed <strong>the</strong> fate <strong>of</strong> any such philosophizing<br />

in <strong>the</strong> future:<br />

Although <strong>the</strong> imagination had always been met with caution ... even into <strong>the</strong><br />

seventeenth century it still had its ancestral place among <strong>the</strong> faculties <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge. It lost this position with <strong>Kant</strong> – once <strong>and</strong> for all, one might say, if<br />

one views <strong>the</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Romantics as an intermezzo. 11<br />

The Böhmes see <strong>the</strong> critical turn as symptomatic not simply <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

‘‘angst’’ as a typical eighteenth-century man <strong>of</strong> reason but <strong>of</strong> much that<br />

ails contemporary ‘‘modern’’ thought generally. In what follows, I would<br />

like to make an initial attempt at adjudicating <strong>the</strong> debate between those<br />

who, like <strong>the</strong> Böhmes, 12 believe that critical philosophy’s antipathy to<br />

imagination <strong>and</strong> sensibility in general ought to undermine its significance<br />

<strong>and</strong> those (typically <strong>Kant</strong> scholars) who view such critiques as misplaced<br />

psychologizing that misses <strong>the</strong> point <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> critical enterprise. 13<br />

Henrich argues that <strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> faculties for <strong>Kant</strong> can be understood<br />

only ‘‘teleologically,’’ hence <strong>the</strong> move to <strong>the</strong> imagination as<br />

transcendental origin is ruled out, <strong>and</strong> any attempts to rewrite <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

account <strong>of</strong> subjectivity in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination could only be misguided.<br />

The Böhmes argue that <strong>Kant</strong> was pathologically averse to giving<br />

<strong>the</strong> imagination any genuine status next to <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> reason<br />

<strong>and</strong> hence could not find a proper place for it in his account <strong>of</strong> knowledge.<br />

Henrich’s account is a methodological explanation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘displacement’’<br />

<strong>of</strong> imagination in <strong>Kant</strong>’s critical philosophy, <strong>the</strong> Böhmes’ is a<br />

psycho-social one. Both may contain elements <strong>of</strong> truth – <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y are by<br />

no means mutually exclusive – but, I believe, nei<strong>the</strong>r view can be <strong>the</strong> last<br />

word on <strong>the</strong> subject. For, as I will argue in what follows, it is not clear<br />

that, in <strong>the</strong> final analysis, <strong>the</strong> imagination was entirely displaced in <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

philosophy, nor is it clear that he continued to hold that all functioning<br />

<strong>of</strong> imagination a priori must be subsumed under <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing.<br />

Two considerations support <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> imagination was<br />

not displaced in <strong>Kant</strong>’s overall <strong>the</strong>ory. First, <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> teleological<br />

11 Ibid., p. 231.<br />

12 Robin May Schott’s book, Cognition <strong>and</strong> Eros: A Critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian Paradigm (Boston: Beacon<br />

Press, 1988), presents ano<strong>the</strong>r statement <strong>of</strong> this position from a feminist perspective.<br />

13 The three-way debate between <strong>the</strong> Böhmes, Henrichians, <strong>and</strong> Heideggerians must be waived for<br />

<strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> space here. It is hinted at, however, in <strong>the</strong> insert to <strong>the</strong> Böhmes’ chapter on <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination in Das Andere der Vernunft (see n. 10), ‘‘Heideggers Philosophische Rehabilitierung<br />

der Einbildungskraft,’’ pp. 243–245.


The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 99<br />

judgment came to have significance as a transcendental condition <strong>of</strong><br />

human judgment for <strong>Kant</strong>, <strong>and</strong> his concern with it eventually resulted in<br />

<strong>the</strong> capstone <strong>of</strong> critical philosophy with <strong>the</strong> publication <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong><br />

Judgment. Here, in <strong>the</strong> final phases <strong>of</strong> his mature philosophy, <strong>the</strong> imagination<br />

plays a pivotal role in <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> human<br />

experience reflectively (teleologically) organized. Second, <strong>Kant</strong> was not<br />

uniformly negative in his view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination, even <strong>of</strong> what he perceived<br />

to be its excesses. And at least one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se excesses – viz.<br />

enthusiasm – plays an important role in his later social <strong>the</strong>ory.<br />

A third consideration is also important in evaluating <strong>the</strong> extent to<br />

which <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy was tainted by problematic motivations.<br />

Scholars have argued that a crucial motivating force behind <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

‘‘rejection’’ <strong>of</strong> metaphysics was his reading <strong>of</strong> Rousseau <strong>and</strong> his consequent<br />

radical revision <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> prevailing instrumentalist conception <strong>of</strong><br />

reason. 14 To <strong>the</strong> extent that this interpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> critical turn rests on<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s deeply felt conviction that metaphysical speculation led to an<br />

‘‘elitist’’ picture <strong>of</strong> morality, it clearly represents an additional element for<br />

consideration in any complete analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> motives underlying <strong>the</strong><br />

critical philosophy. I look at each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se considerations in turn <strong>and</strong><br />

conclude with an assessment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Bö hmes’ contribution to <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

interpretation in <strong>the</strong> light <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

im aginative reflection <strong>and</strong> taste<br />

The Bö hmes’ claim that <strong>the</strong> imagination lost its place as one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

faculties <strong>of</strong> knowledge in <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy is relatively uncontroversial,<br />

if one considers <strong>the</strong> fate <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> second edition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critique , <strong>Kant</strong> defines <strong>the</strong> imagination as<br />

‘‘<strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>of</strong> presenting [vorstellen] in intuition an object that is not itself<br />

present ’’ (B151). 15 Such an activity may involve <strong>the</strong> representing <strong>of</strong> an<br />

object in accordance with laws <strong>of</strong> association, so that <strong>the</strong> images involved<br />

14 See Richard Velkley, Freedom <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> End <strong>of</strong> Reason: On <strong>the</strong> Moral Foundations <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critical<br />

Philosophy (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1989), <strong>and</strong> Frederick C. Beiser, ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

Intellectual Development: 1746–1781,’’ chapter I <strong>of</strong> The Cambridge Companion to <strong>Kant</strong> (New York:<br />

Cambridge University Press, 1992), pp. 26–61.<br />

15 I have purposely avoided <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> ‘‘represent’’ to translate vorstellen. This is to avoid any<br />

misleading literal reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> English term, which would suggest that whatever <strong>the</strong> imagination<br />

is presenting in intuition must have been present before (literally, is being ‘‘re-presented’’). The<br />

German word vorstellen when read also in literal fashion does not carry <strong>the</strong> same meaning<br />

(but means literally, to ‘‘place in front <strong>of</strong>’’). See also, Pluhar, translator’s note in Critique <strong>of</strong><br />

Judgment, p.14.


100<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

depend on what is, or was, given to <strong>the</strong> senses. Or, alternatively, <strong>the</strong><br />

subject, apart from any particular experience, represents <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong><br />

intuition in accordance with <strong>the</strong> categories a priori. In <strong>the</strong> former case,<br />

imagination is an effect determined empirically <strong>and</strong> is thus contingent in<br />

a way that renders it opaque to transcendental analysis. In <strong>Kant</strong>’s words,<br />

this empirical manner <strong>of</strong> representing intuitions is ‘‘reproductive’’ <strong>and</strong><br />

‘‘contributes nothing to <strong>the</strong> explanation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> a priori<br />

knowledge’’ (B152). This sort <strong>of</strong> imaginative activity, <strong>Kant</strong> says here, falls<br />

within <strong>the</strong> domain <strong>of</strong> psychology, but not transcendental (i.e., critical)<br />

philosophy.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> latter case, where, in <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> intuitively presenting an<br />

object <strong>the</strong> mind is active, <strong>Kant</strong> calls <strong>the</strong> activity ‘‘productive.’’ It is <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘first application’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing to objects <strong>of</strong> possible intuition.<br />

Here <strong>the</strong> mind is creative in that it spontaneously presents an object in<br />

intuition; that is, <strong>the</strong> mind presents <strong>the</strong> object independently <strong>of</strong> empirical<br />

conditions. <strong>Kant</strong> holds that <strong>the</strong> only avenue for this sort <strong>of</strong> spontaneous<br />

‘‘production’’ (syn<strong>the</strong>sis) is via <strong>the</strong> categories <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing. Hence<br />

this sort <strong>of</strong> imaginative production is seen as ‘‘an action [Wirkung] <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing on <strong>the</strong> sensibility’’ (B152), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘transcendental act <strong>of</strong><br />

imagination’’ is identified with <strong>the</strong> ‘‘syn<strong>the</strong>tic influence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

upon inner sense’’ (B154). Since <strong>Kant</strong> has already declared <strong>the</strong><br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing to be <strong>the</strong> sole source <strong>of</strong> all acts <strong>of</strong> combination (‘‘syn<strong>the</strong>sis,’’<br />

B130), <strong>the</strong> condition <strong>of</strong> all syn<strong>the</strong>tic knowledge a priori can only be<br />

<strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing, one <strong>of</strong> whose tasks is to be productively imaginative.<br />

The imagination simply has no independent status here.<br />

For <strong>Kant</strong>, as already mentioned, all acts <strong>of</strong> syn<strong>the</strong>sis are acts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing. Moreover, he claims that all acts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing are<br />

judgments (A69/B94) <strong>and</strong> labels <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> ‘‘faculty <strong>of</strong><br />

judgment’’ (A69/B94), as if to suggest that no o<strong>the</strong>r judgment is possible<br />

except judgments syn<strong>the</strong>sizing representations in accordance with categories<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing. But, strictly speaking, it does not follow that<br />

all acts <strong>of</strong> judgment are acts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing, or <strong>of</strong> syn<strong>the</strong>sis. All that<br />

follows from <strong>the</strong> claims mentioned (at A69/B94) is that all acts <strong>of</strong><br />

syn<strong>the</strong>sis are judgments. True, <strong>Kant</strong>’s claim in <strong>the</strong> second (B) edition <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘‘Transcendental Deduction’’ is a strong one: ‘‘All possible perceptions,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore everything that can come to empirical consciousness,<br />

that is, all appearances <strong>of</strong> nature, must, so far as <strong>the</strong>ir connection is<br />

concerned, be subject to <strong>the</strong> categories’’ (B164–165). But even this strong<br />

claim does not rule out that human beings have a fur<strong>the</strong>r capacity for<br />

non-syn<strong>the</strong>tic judgment involving <strong>the</strong> imagination. Obviously human


eings are capable <strong>of</strong> analytic judgments but, apart from this, we may also<br />

contemplate our (already syn<strong>the</strong>sized) experience. We are capable <strong>of</strong><br />

making judgments about judgments <strong>of</strong> experience – that is, about already<br />

categorized experience. There is no need to suppose that such ‘‘higherorder’’<br />

judgments <strong>the</strong>mselves involve application <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> categories just<br />

because <strong>the</strong>y take syn<strong>the</strong>tic judgments for <strong>the</strong>ir material. If such judgments<br />

are possible, as it were, ‘‘upon’’ syn<strong>the</strong>tic judgments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing, it may be that imagination is required by this o<strong>the</strong>r sort <strong>of</strong><br />

non-syn<strong>the</strong>tic judgment, 16 in which case imagination could not be<br />

assimilated to <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing. If such judgments are taken to be <strong>of</strong> any<br />

importance in <strong>the</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> human experience, <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re may be a<br />

place, after all, for <strong>the</strong> imagination as an independent faculty in <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

philosophy.<br />

Of course, this is precisely what happens in <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> reflective<br />

judgment. In <strong>the</strong> First Introduction to <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

allows that ‘‘judgment is not merely an ability to subsume <strong>the</strong> particular<br />

under <strong>the</strong> universal (whose concept is given), but also, <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way<br />

round, an ability to find <strong>the</strong> universal for <strong>the</strong> particular,’’ 17 <strong>and</strong> he goes on<br />

to argue that <strong>the</strong> principle for performing <strong>the</strong> latter task cannot come<br />

from <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing. The task <strong>of</strong> finding universals for particulars is<br />

<strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> ‘‘reflective judgment’’: ‘‘To reflect (or consider [belegen]) is to<br />

hold given presentations [Vorstellungen] up to, <strong>and</strong> compare <strong>the</strong>m with,<br />

ei<strong>the</strong>r o<strong>the</strong>r presentations or one’s cognitive power [itself], in reference to<br />

a concept that this [comparison] makes possible’’ (X: 211). <strong>Imagination</strong>,<br />

‘‘<strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>of</strong> presenting in intuition an object that is not itself present’’<br />

(B151), obviously will have a role to play here ins<strong>of</strong>ar as given presentations<br />

are to be compared to (but not combined with) ‘‘o<strong>the</strong>r presentations’’<br />

not <strong>the</strong>mselves present. What <strong>the</strong>se ‘‘o<strong>the</strong>r’’ presentations might be<br />

will be discussed in what follows, but it is clear that, whatever <strong>the</strong>y are,<br />

<strong>the</strong> imagination, as <strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>of</strong> ‘‘presenting’’ what is not present, will<br />

have to be involved.<br />

Moreover, <strong>the</strong> ‘‘object’’ <strong>of</strong> reflective judgment is not an object <strong>of</strong><br />

experience but ra<strong>the</strong>r a ‘‘purposive arrangement <strong>of</strong> nature in a system’’<br />

(XX: 214), so that this purposiveness is not <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong><br />

a category. In <strong>Kant</strong>’s words, it has ‘‘no basis ... in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> universal<br />

laws <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing’’ (XX: 216). Whatever work <strong>Kant</strong> holds that <strong>the</strong><br />

16 On <strong>Kant</strong>’s definition, analytic judgments require no imagination since <strong>the</strong>ir ‘‘objects’’ are already<br />

<strong>the</strong>re, as it were, in <strong>the</strong> concept being analyzed, <strong>and</strong>, in any case, intuition is not involved.<br />

17 First Introduction to <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment (Ak XX), trans. Werner Pluhar, in Critique <strong>of</strong><br />

Judgment, XX: 210.<br />

The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 101


102<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

imagination performs in such judgments, he does not want to say that<br />

reflective imagination is merely a task <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing. For this<br />

reason, reflective judgment cannot be constitutive <strong>of</strong> knowledge. It does<br />

not determine cognition but deals with appearances in an entirely different<br />

manner:<br />

So when reflective judgment tries to bring given appearances under empirical<br />

concepts <strong>of</strong> determinate natural things, it deals with <strong>the</strong>m technically ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

schematically. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, it does not deal with <strong>the</strong>m mechanically, as it<br />

were, like an instrument, guided by <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> senses; it<br />

deals with <strong>the</strong>m artistically, in terms <strong>of</strong> a principle that is universal but also<br />

indeterminate: <strong>the</strong> principle <strong>of</strong> a purposive arrangement <strong>of</strong> nature in a system.<br />

(XX: 213–214)<br />

This sort <strong>of</strong> judging, for <strong>Kant</strong>, is more holistic than <strong>the</strong> ‘‘determining’’<br />

judgments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing, <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> same time more tentative. Its<br />

principle is ‘‘only a necessary presupposition’’ while that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

is ‘‘law’’ (XX: 215). To borrow Rudolf Makkreel’s terminology<br />

in <strong>Imagination</strong> <strong>and</strong> Interpretation in <strong>Kant</strong>, reflective judgment may be<br />

called interpretive. 18 It involves technique <strong>and</strong> is an ‘‘art,’’ while <strong>the</strong> syn<strong>the</strong>sizing<br />

activity <strong>of</strong> cognitive judgment proceeds ‘‘schematically’’ <strong>and</strong> is<br />

thus more ‘‘mechanical’’ in nature. In light <strong>of</strong> all this, it is reasonable to<br />

wonder if <strong>the</strong> Böhmes’ claim that <strong>Kant</strong>’s is a philosophy <strong>of</strong> suppressed<br />

imagination is not a bit too hasty. Their point can perhaps be made for<br />

<strong>the</strong> second edition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason, <strong>and</strong> even more plausibly<br />

made for <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason, for that matter. 19 But in writing<br />

about reflection in <strong>the</strong> third Critique <strong>Kant</strong> demonstrates a willingness to<br />

consider a far more ‘‘imaginative’’ sort <strong>of</strong> judgment.<br />

The Böhmes are <strong>of</strong> course aware <strong>of</strong> this defense <strong>and</strong> do consider <strong>the</strong><br />

importance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination in one kind <strong>of</strong> reflection – namely, in<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective judgments <strong>of</strong> taste. They argue that although in <strong>the</strong>se<br />

judgments <strong>the</strong> imagination is given a more independent role, still, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

in effect finds in taste a ‘‘safe,’’ segregated arena for <strong>the</strong> imagination,<br />

where <strong>the</strong> creative work <strong>of</strong> this faculty is reduced to mere ‘‘play’’:<br />

But it can still be established, that also here, where <strong>the</strong> independence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination is at least accepted as play, <strong>the</strong> joy taken in this play occurs precisely<br />

where it is well mannered, that is, where it conforms to <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing.<br />

Classicism delights in <strong>the</strong> allegorized <strong>and</strong> domesticated figures <strong>of</strong> Greek<br />

mythology-figures that once were gripping <strong>and</strong> overwhelming powers. The<br />

18 Rudolf A. Makkreel, <strong>Imagination</strong> <strong>and</strong> Interpretation in <strong>Kant</strong>: The Hermeneutical Import <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1990).<br />

19 Cf. Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason, V:69.


The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 103<br />

imagination itself is turned from Eros into Cupid (Putto), into a child that one<br />

delights in because it does <strong>of</strong> its own accord what one would o<strong>the</strong>rwise ask <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

(Das Andere der Vernunft, pp. 238–239)<br />

With respect to <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> taste, <strong>the</strong> Böhmes’ assessment is apt –<br />

<strong>and</strong>, indeed, <strong>the</strong>y could have said a good deal more. Taste, for <strong>Kant</strong>,<br />

although he hints at a substantive connection with morality, is closely<br />

associated with culture, <strong>and</strong> serves (at best) to tame <strong>and</strong> discipline people<br />

by cloaking <strong>the</strong>m in <strong>the</strong> appearance <strong>of</strong> morality. 20 <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> taste<br />

is heavily invested in eighteenth-century British accounts, <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong><br />

extent that he departs from <strong>the</strong>se <strong>the</strong>ories in an attempt to find an a priori<br />

grounding for judgments <strong>of</strong> taste, he does so by insisting that in <strong>the</strong>se<br />

judgments <strong>the</strong> ‘‘harmonious’’ activity <strong>of</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

‘‘belongs to cognition in general’’ (‘‘zu einem Erkenntnis uberhauptgehört’’<br />

(V: 219)). <strong>Imagination</strong> is not absolutely free, but ra<strong>the</strong>r is ‘‘freely lawful,’’<br />

21 with <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing setting its limits: ‘‘And yet to say that <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination is free <strong>and</strong> yet lawful <strong>of</strong> itself, i.e., that it carries autonomy with<br />

it, is a contradiction. The underst<strong>and</strong>ing alone gives <strong>the</strong> law’’ (V: 241).<br />

At Section 50 in <strong>the</strong> third Critique, <strong>Kant</strong> sets up a dichotomy between<br />

genius/spirit/imagination, on <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> discipline/taste/underst<strong>and</strong>ing,<br />

on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. In judgments <strong>of</strong> taste, although <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

is not <strong>the</strong> only operative faculty, it clearly is <strong>the</strong> defining one:<br />

In order for a work to be beautiful, it is not necessary that it be rich <strong>and</strong> original<br />

in ideas, but it is necessary that <strong>the</strong> imagination in its freedom be commensurate<br />

with <strong>the</strong> lawfulness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing. For if <strong>the</strong> imagination is left in lawless<br />

freedom, all its riches produce nothing but nonsense, <strong>and</strong> it is judgment that<br />

adapts <strong>the</strong> imagination to <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing. (V: 319)<br />

Here <strong>Kant</strong> disassociates imagination from judgment, implicitly defining<br />

<strong>the</strong> latter as <strong>the</strong> ability to subject <strong>the</strong> imaginative faculty to <strong>the</strong><br />

20<br />

E.g. see Anthropology (Anthr.) (Ak VII), trans. Mary J. Gregor (The Hague: Nijh<strong>of</strong>f, 1974), 11–12/<br />

244: ‘‘Ideal taste has a tendency to promote morality in an external way. Making a man [Mensch]<br />

well-mannered as a social being falls short <strong>of</strong> forming a morally good man, but it still prepares him<br />

for it by <strong>the</strong> effort he makes, in society, to please o<strong>the</strong>rs (to make <strong>the</strong>m love or admire him).’’ And<br />

also V: 210: ‘‘To show taste in our conduct (or in judging o<strong>the</strong>r people’s conduct) is very different<br />

from expressing our moral way <strong>of</strong> thinking. For this contains a comm<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> gives rise to a need,<br />

whereas moral taste only plays with <strong>the</strong> objects <strong>of</strong> liking without committing itself to any <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>m.’’ For a discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> parallels between <strong>Kant</strong>’s views on taste <strong>and</strong> femininity, see Kneller,<br />

‘‘Discipline <strong>and</strong> Silence: Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>Imagination</strong> in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Taste,’’ in Aes<strong>the</strong>tics in<br />

Feminist Perspective, eds. Hilde Hein <strong>and</strong> Carolyn Korsmeyer (Bloomington: University <strong>of</strong><br />

Indiana Press, 1993), pp. 179–192.<br />

21<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> speaks <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘freie Gesetzmüßigkeit der Einbildungskraft’’ (free lawfulness <strong>of</strong> imagination)<br />

(V: 240).


104<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing. ‘‘Judgment ... will sooner permit <strong>the</strong> imagination’s<br />

freedom <strong>and</strong> wealth to be impaired than that <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing be<br />

impaired’’ (V: 320). Thus, <strong>Kant</strong> argues, fine art requires ‘‘imagination,<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing, spirit, <strong>and</strong> taste,’’ <strong>and</strong> it is <strong>the</strong> fourth condition – namely,<br />

taste – that sees to it that <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r three elements are so ordered that<br />

imagination never gets <strong>the</strong> upper h<strong>and</strong> (V: 320 n. 55). Thus it would<br />

appear that <strong>the</strong> Böhmes are correct in saying that ‘‘<strong>the</strong> freedom <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination in art is also only apparent.’’ 22<br />

imaginative excess <strong>and</strong> moral progress<br />

To view <strong>the</strong>se aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> taste as a sort <strong>of</strong> final critical<br />

blow to <strong>the</strong> imagination would, however, be to overlook <strong>the</strong> fact that even<br />

if <strong>Kant</strong> wanted <strong>the</strong> imagination to be ‘‘tamed’’ by taste, he also seemed<br />

willing to permit <strong>the</strong> imagination’s enthusiastic overflow in some<br />

instances. <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory involves more than just a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> taste,<br />

as I have already argued. 23 And, as we have already seen, in Section 17 <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, <strong>Kant</strong> also defends <strong>the</strong> view, albeit briefly, that ‘‘a<br />

very strong imagination’’ (later in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment’’<br />

he speaks <strong>of</strong> ‘‘spirit’’ or ‘‘genius’’) may form a partnership <strong>of</strong> sorts with<br />

reason. <strong>Kant</strong> argues for <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> artistic genius exhibiting <strong>the</strong><br />

rational idea <strong>of</strong> humanity ‘‘as an aes<strong>the</strong>tic idea fully in concreto (in a<br />

model image)’’ (V: 233), <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> last paragraph <strong>of</strong> this section <strong>Kant</strong><br />

argues unequivocally for <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> ‘‘<strong>the</strong> visible expression <strong>of</strong> moral<br />

ideas’’ through imagination, in a manner that, while ‘‘taken only from<br />

experience,’’ never<strong>the</strong>less transforms that experience into a presentation <strong>of</strong><br />

something new:<br />

These moral ideas must be connected, in <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest purposiveness,<br />

with everything that our reason links with <strong>the</strong> morally good: goodness <strong>of</strong> soul, or<br />

purity, fortitude, or serenity, etc.; <strong>and</strong> in order for this connection to be made<br />

visible, as it were, in bodily expression (as an effect <strong>of</strong> what is inward), pure ideas<br />

22 Das Andere der Vernunft, p.329 (see n. 10).<br />

23 I am here setting aside <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sublime, which I have discussed in ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s Immature<br />

<strong>Imagination</strong>,’’ in Modern Engendering: Critical Feminist Readings in Modern Western Philosophy, ed.<br />

Bat Ami Bar-on (Albany: SUNY Press, 1994). Although in it <strong>the</strong> imagination is allowed to ‘‘run<br />

wild,’’ <strong>the</strong> role assigned to imagination vis-à-vis reason is no less problematic than that assigned to<br />

it vis-à-vis <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing in judgments <strong>of</strong> taste. In <strong>the</strong> end it must be ‘‘humiliated’’ by reason,<br />

as <strong>the</strong> Böhmes argue in Das Andere der Vernunft, pp. 215–223 (see n. 10). I have also given a critique<br />

along feminist lines in ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s Immature <strong>Imagination</strong>,’’ in Modern Engendering: Critical Feminist<br />

Readings in Modern Western Philosophy, ed. Bat Ami Bar-on (Albany: SUNY Press, 1994),<br />

pp. 141–153.


The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 105<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason must be united with a very strong imagination in someone who seeks<br />

so much as to judge, let alone exhibit, it. (V: 235)<br />

Moral considerations <strong>and</strong> a ‘‘mighty’’ (mächtige) imagination are also<br />

introduced into aes<strong>the</strong>tic experience in <strong>Kant</strong>’s discussion <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

ideas – that is, <strong>of</strong> intuitive presentations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination that ‘‘prompt<br />

much thought, but to which no determinate thought whatsoever ... can<br />

be adequate’’ (V: 314). And as we saw earlier, aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas are said to<br />

complement rational ideas since <strong>the</strong> latter are ‘‘concepts to which no<br />

intuition (presentation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination) can be adequate’’ (V: 314).<br />

Aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas are imaginative ‘‘excesses’’ that<br />

prompt ... so much thought as can never be comprehended within a determinate<br />

concept <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby <strong>the</strong> presentation aes<strong>the</strong>tically exp<strong>and</strong>s <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

itself <strong>and</strong> sets <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> intellectual ideas (i.e., <strong>of</strong> reason) in motion: it makes<br />

reason think more ... than what can be apprehended <strong>and</strong> made distinct in <strong>the</strong><br />

presentation. (V: 315)<br />

Thus aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas can be said to express a rational idea in sensible form.<br />

In Makkreel’s formulation, <strong>the</strong> imagination, through aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas,<br />

complements reason by striving to complete reason’s ideas in experience.<br />

‘‘Thought, which is a function <strong>of</strong> reason, is here [in <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> an<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic idea] occasioned by an excess <strong>of</strong> intuitive content that cannot be<br />

contained within <strong>the</strong> concepts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing.’’ 24 <strong>Kant</strong> says that<br />

such creative imaginative presentations ‘‘make us add to a concept <strong>the</strong><br />

thoughts <strong>of</strong> much that is ineffable, but <strong>the</strong> feeling <strong>of</strong> which quickens our<br />

cognitive powers <strong>and</strong> connects language, which o<strong>the</strong>rwise would be mere<br />

letters, with spirit’’ (V: 316). That <strong>the</strong> expression <strong>of</strong> imaginative ‘‘excess’’<br />

might have important implications for human life <strong>and</strong> creativity is an<br />

idea that is new to <strong>Kant</strong> in <strong>the</strong> third Critique, where he grants <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination a ‘‘transformative’’ (umbildende) power. It is certainly an<br />

argument for <strong>the</strong> claim that imagination had not lost its place in <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

critical philosophy. We need only recall <strong>Kant</strong>’s claim at V: 314:<br />

For <strong>the</strong> imagination ([in its role] as a productive cognitive power) is very mighty<br />

when it creates, as it were, ano<strong>the</strong>r nature out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> material that actual nature<br />

gives it. We use it to entertain ourselves when experience strikes us as overly<br />

routine. We may even restructure [umbilden] experience; <strong>and</strong> though in doing so<br />

we continue to follow analogical laws, yet we also follow principles which reside<br />

higher up, namely, in reason (<strong>and</strong> which are just as natural to us as those which<br />

24 Makkreel, <strong>Imagination</strong> <strong>and</strong> Interpretation, pp. 118, 121.


106<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

<strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing follows in apprehending empirical nature) for although it is<br />

under that law [<strong>of</strong> association] that nature lends us material, yet we can process<br />

that material into something quite different, namely, into something that surpasses<br />

nature. (V: 314)<br />

Here <strong>Kant</strong> is describing a kind <strong>of</strong> ‘‘judging’’ – in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> ideas <strong>of</strong><br />

reason, one might call it ‘‘moral daydreaming’’ – in which imagination<br />

constructs presentations that ‘‘surpass’’ (übertreffen) without transcending,<br />

nature. In commenting on this passage, Makkreel puts it as follows:<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term ‘‘surpass’’ points to a significant difference in <strong>the</strong> way<br />

rational <strong>and</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas may be said to go ‘‘beyond’’ <strong>the</strong> limits <strong>of</strong> experience.<br />

Rational ideas transcend nature, <strong>and</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas surpass it by transforming<br />

<strong>and</strong> enriching experience. 25<br />

The result <strong>of</strong> such presentations is that <strong>the</strong> imagination ‘‘enlivens’’ <strong>the</strong> idea<br />

<strong>of</strong> reason by making it present in intuition – that is, imagination is capable<br />

<strong>of</strong> making <strong>the</strong> rational idea ‘‘feel real.’’ Whenever such presentations are<br />

expressed in concrete form, in a way that communicates itself to o<strong>the</strong>rs, a<br />

‘‘mixed-mode’’ experience <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sort discussed in <strong>the</strong> ideal <strong>of</strong> beauty occurs.<br />

That is, an experience that permits <strong>the</strong> subject to feel what in <strong>the</strong> rational<br />

(moral) ideal alone could only be thought takes place.<br />

The elevated role <strong>of</strong> imagination in <strong>the</strong>se cases suggests, if not a unity<br />

<strong>of</strong> sensibility <strong>and</strong> reason in <strong>the</strong> human subject <strong>the</strong>n at least a higher place<br />

for <strong>the</strong> latter in human moral experience. In <strong>the</strong> (mixed-mode) aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

experiences that <strong>Kant</strong> allows for beyond taste, rationality <strong>and</strong> sensibility<br />

(via <strong>the</strong> imagination) are both involved. But, unlike in <strong>the</strong> judgment <strong>of</strong><br />

taste, <strong>the</strong> imagination is not restrained <strong>and</strong> ‘‘disciplined.’’ In fact, it is<br />

precisely imaginative excess, in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘multiplicity <strong>of</strong> partial presentations’’<br />

(V: 316), that meets a need on <strong>the</strong> side <strong>of</strong> reason. This pr<strong>of</strong>ligate presentation<br />

prompts in <strong>the</strong> subject a ‘‘lively interest’’ in reason’s ideas, <strong>and</strong><br />

as we saw in chapter 4, an interest in <strong>the</strong>ir being actualized.<br />

For <strong>Kant</strong>, judgments involving what might be called ‘‘idealistic’’<br />

imagination connect intuitive presentations with a moral idea, giving rise<br />

to a concrete, sensible ideal <strong>and</strong> to a kind <strong>of</strong> moral liveliness or interest<br />

that does not result from <strong>the</strong> intellectual idea alone. As we have already<br />

seen, such moral ‘‘imaginings’’ might arguably serve as a subjective basis<br />

for a rational hope for moral progress; that is, <strong>the</strong>y may enable belief<br />

in <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> realizing moral ideas. In <strong>the</strong> exhibition <strong>of</strong> its<br />

object, imagination makes <strong>the</strong> realization <strong>of</strong> that object subjectively<br />

25 Makkreel makes this point in his comment on this passage, ibid., p. 120.


The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 107<br />

possible – ‘‘imaginable.’’ Perfect human virtue may be an unattainable<br />

ideal, but ‘‘a very strong imagination’’ can give this intellectual notion a<br />

flesh <strong>and</strong> blood quality that it did not have before, bringing it down to<br />

earth, as it were, <strong>and</strong> enabling human beings to envision actually attaining<br />

that which moral reason requires <strong>the</strong>m to strive for.<br />

We saw in chapter 2 that imagination’s capacity to enliven morality is<br />

especially relevant in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Highest Good –<br />

that is, <strong>of</strong> a moral ‘‘world in which virtue <strong>and</strong> happiness are commensurate,<br />

or at least in which human beings make every effort to maximize<br />

<strong>the</strong> correspondence <strong>of</strong> happiness to virtue.’’ 26 I argued <strong>the</strong>re that, given<br />

<strong>the</strong> difficulties attendant on what has been called <strong>the</strong> ‘‘<strong>the</strong>ological’’<br />

doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Highest Good in <strong>Kant</strong>, which requires postulation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

existence <strong>of</strong> God to ground such hope, it is worth looking at <strong>the</strong> accounts<br />

<strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic moral experiences in <strong>Kant</strong>’s third Critique as a possible<br />

alternative to this metaphysical leap <strong>of</strong> faith in <strong>the</strong> second Critique. 27<br />

That is, if, as <strong>Kant</strong> argues in <strong>the</strong> third Critique, we have <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

reflective capacity to literally ‘‘make sense’’ <strong>of</strong> rational ideas like <strong>the</strong><br />

Highest Good, why could not this capacity itself serve to ground our hope<br />

(not our certainty) that we ourselves could bring it about? In light <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s very strong claims for <strong>the</strong> imagination’s creative <strong>and</strong> enlivening<br />

powers in <strong>the</strong> third Critique, <strong>the</strong> question seems reasonable, <strong>and</strong> yet <strong>Kant</strong><br />

does not go so far, in ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ideal <strong>of</strong> beauty or <strong>of</strong><br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas, as to suggest that <strong>the</strong>se are necessary ingredients in human<br />

efforts to moral improvement. 28<br />

26 Scholars have debated whe<strong>the</strong>r or not <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest good involves, in Harry van der<br />

Linden’s words, ‘‘<strong>the</strong> union <strong>of</strong> universal virtue <strong>and</strong> universal happiness’’ or <strong>the</strong> far more modest<br />

‘‘moral society in which human agents attempt to make one ano<strong>the</strong>r happy, but do not necessarily<br />

succeed’’ (<strong>Kant</strong>ian Ethics <strong>and</strong> Socialism, Indianapolis: Hackett, (1988, pp. 42ff.). Also see Andrews<br />

Reath, ‘‘Two Conceptions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Highest Good in <strong>Kant</strong>,’’ Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> History <strong>of</strong> Philosophy 26<br />

(4) (1988), pp. 593–619. Van der Linden distinguishes between a teleological conception (<strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘highest good desirable’’) <strong>and</strong> a moral conception (<strong>the</strong> ‘‘highest moral good’’). Reath makes a<br />

similar distinction between a ‘‘<strong>the</strong>ological’’ <strong>and</strong> a ‘‘secular (or political)’’ conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest<br />

good (pp. 594ff.).<br />

27 The term is Andrews Reath’s (see n. 26). Although I find both <strong>the</strong>ir accounts extremely useful in<br />

sorting out <strong>the</strong> different str<strong>and</strong>s in <strong>Kant</strong>’s thought, both Reath <strong>and</strong> van der Linden are inclined to<br />

dismiss <strong>the</strong> ‘‘spiritualized’’ account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Highest Good in <strong>Kant</strong>. This, it seems to me, has <strong>the</strong><br />

unfortunate effect <strong>of</strong> disconnecting <strong>Kant</strong>’s notion from <strong>the</strong> felt response that is part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

happiness component <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Highest Good. In <strong>Kant</strong>’s account, <strong>the</strong> postulate <strong>of</strong> God’s existence on<br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘‘<strong>the</strong>ological’’ reading served to do more than ground rational belief in a future paradise. It also<br />

channeled desire for such a state <strong>of</strong> affairs into faith in God. The virtue <strong>of</strong> finding a role for <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination in grounding efforts to bring about <strong>the</strong> ‘‘highest good desirable’’ is that it provides a<br />

this-worldly channel, <strong>and</strong> hence a justification, for <strong>the</strong> desire to do so.<br />

28 <strong>Kant</strong> does suggest that beauty might serve as a symbol <strong>of</strong> morality <strong>and</strong> thus act as a sort <strong>of</strong> bridge<br />

to <strong>the</strong> moral from taste, because <strong>the</strong> beautiful arouses sensations that are ‘‘somehow analogous’’ to


108<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

There is a parallel here to <strong>Kant</strong>’s essay ‘‘An Old Question Raised<br />

Again: Is <strong>the</strong> Human Race Constantly Progressing?’’ where <strong>Kant</strong> raises<br />

much <strong>the</strong> same question for rational hope in human social institutions<br />

<strong>and</strong> moral progress:<br />

There must be some experience in <strong>the</strong> human race which, as an event, points to<br />

<strong>the</strong> disposition <strong>and</strong> capacity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human race to be <strong>the</strong> cause <strong>of</strong> its own advance<br />

toward <strong>the</strong> better, <strong>and</strong> ... toward <strong>the</strong> human race as being <strong>the</strong> author <strong>of</strong> this<br />

advance. 29<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> uses <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> moral progress to take <strong>the</strong> opportunity to<br />

express his own support for <strong>the</strong> goals <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> French Revolution. Yet <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘event’’ that indicates <strong>the</strong> human capacity for moral progress is not<br />

<strong>the</strong> Revolution itself, but ra<strong>the</strong>r ‘‘<strong>the</strong> mode <strong>of</strong> thinking [Denkungsart] <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> spectators.’’ That is, <strong>the</strong> event that indicates human ability to be <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘author’’ <strong>of</strong> a moral society is <strong>the</strong> publicly expressed, non-opportunistic<br />

(uneigenützig) sympathy for those who participate in struggles to end<br />

human oppression. The glimmer <strong>of</strong> hope that history holds out to those<br />

seeking reason to believe in moral progress is <strong>the</strong> spectators’ ‘‘wishful<br />

participation that borders on enthusiasm’’ (VII: 85), an enthusiasm that<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> identifies as a ‘‘passionate participation in <strong>the</strong> good’’ (VII: 86).<br />

Felicitas Munzel’s work on <strong>Kant</strong>’s notion <strong>of</strong> moral character <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘revolution in Denkungsart’’ that precipitates it underscores <strong>the</strong> centrality<br />

<strong>of</strong> a kind <strong>of</strong> unconditional ‘‘adoption <strong>of</strong> resolve’’ to do what is right come<br />

what may that lies at <strong>the</strong> heart <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> enthusiasm that <strong>Kant</strong> admires<br />

here. 30 On this reading, <strong>the</strong> spectator’s response could itself be an indication<br />

that humanity may possess <strong>the</strong> means to accomplish moral progress.<br />

But what exactly is this mode <strong>of</strong> thinking that ‘‘borders on<br />

enthusiasm’’ <strong>and</strong> is a ‘‘passionate participation in <strong>the</strong> good’’?<br />

<strong>the</strong> feeling present when we make moral judgments (CJ, 230/354). But even apart from <strong>the</strong><br />

vagueness <strong>of</strong> his arguments, <strong>the</strong> point here is that <strong>Kant</strong> fails to follow up on <strong>the</strong> much more<br />

intimate relationships between morality <strong>and</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic experience suggested in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘ideal’’ <strong>and</strong> in<br />

his account <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas. For a different reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> connection between taste <strong>and</strong> morality,<br />

see Paul Guyer, ‘‘Feeling <strong>and</strong> Freedom: <strong>Kant</strong> on Aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> Morality,’’ Journal <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong><br />

Art Criticism 48 (2) (1990), pp. 137–146.<br />

29 The essay, although complete in its own right, was included as <strong>the</strong> second part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1798<br />

publication entitled Streit der Fakultäten. The translation here is from <strong>Kant</strong> on History, ed. Lewis<br />

White Beck (New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1986), pp. 137–154. The citation is from VII: 84.<br />

30 See Felicitas Munzel, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Conception <strong>of</strong> Moral Character: The ‘‘Critical’’ link <strong>of</strong> Morality,<br />

Anthropology, <strong>and</strong> Reflective Judgment, (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1999), p. 330.<br />

Munzel’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> voluntary nature, <strong>the</strong> positing, as it were, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral self in an act <strong>of</strong><br />

resolve followed by <strong>the</strong> development <strong>and</strong> maintenance <strong>of</strong> character, is insightful. Emphasizing this<br />

aspect <strong>of</strong> moral character helps make clear why, for <strong>Kant</strong>, moral enthusiasts were so valuable: <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are flamboyant, visible examples <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> radical choice <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral. Like fictional characters,<br />

however, <strong>the</strong>y could also be dangerous for <strong>the</strong> same reason (see CPR: A570/B598).


The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 109<br />

In this same passage (VII: 85) <strong>Kant</strong> makes an anthropological point<br />

that he repeatedly made in his lectures on <strong>the</strong> subject: ‘‘Genuine<br />

enthusiasm always moves only toward what is ideal <strong>and</strong>, indeed, to what<br />

is purely moral, such as <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> right.’’ In student notes from his<br />

anthropology lectures taken during <strong>the</strong> 1770s, we find <strong>Kant</strong> telling his<br />

students that ‘‘an enthusiast is always a noble Fantast, full <strong>of</strong> life <strong>and</strong><br />

strength, <strong>and</strong> so, in addition, inclined to virtue. Indeed, much that is good<br />

disappears from <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong> where <strong>the</strong>y are purged.’’ 31 In <strong>the</strong> published<br />

anthropology lectures, he defines an enthusiast as a visionary or fantast<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter as a person who ‘‘fails to collate his imaginings with laws <strong>of</strong><br />

experience.’’ In <strong>the</strong> same place he adds that, when accompanied by<br />

‘‘passion’’ (Affect), fanaticism becomes enthusiasm (VII: 202). That is,<br />

enthusiasm is <strong>the</strong> condition <strong>of</strong> passionate participation in moral ‘‘imaginings’’<br />

that fail to ‘‘harmonize with concepts’’ (VII: 48/172) but are<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r bound up with rational ideals. In <strong>the</strong> Reflections on Anthropology<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> identifies two kinds <strong>of</strong> ‘‘fantasts’’: those <strong>of</strong> sensibility <strong>and</strong> those <strong>of</strong><br />

reason. The former are people who mistake <strong>the</strong>ir own ideas for actual<br />

perceptions (XV.1: R#498: as in hallucinations, presumably). They are<br />

wahnsinnig: taking what is merely in one’s thoughts to be perceived<br />

through <strong>the</strong> bodily senses. Fantasts <strong>of</strong> reason are ‘‘visionaries’’ who<br />

mistake <strong>the</strong>ir own ideas for reality (even if not perceptual; also at R #499;<br />

Schwärmer: taking what is sensed ‘‘mentally/spiritually’’ (geistig) for real).<br />

Fantasts <strong>of</strong> both sorts confuse what is in <strong>the</strong>ir imagination with <strong>the</strong> things<br />

<strong>the</strong>mselves (R #499). <strong>Kant</strong> claims that both Plato <strong>and</strong> Rousseau were<br />

enthusiasts <strong>of</strong> reason. Arguably <strong>the</strong>n, <strong>the</strong> spectators <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Revolution,<br />

whose sympa<strong>the</strong>tic fervor ‘‘borders’’ on enthusiasm, are experiencing<br />

something like <strong>the</strong> ‘‘noble fantast’’ experiences in <strong>the</strong>ir ability to imagine<br />

<strong>and</strong> desire a rational ideal. These spectators are a source <strong>of</strong> hope precisely<br />

because <strong>the</strong>ir own moral way <strong>of</strong> thinking is embodied in passion <strong>and</strong><br />

imagined participation in great social ideals. They imbue abstract conceptions<br />

<strong>of</strong> justice with a desire <strong>and</strong> longing that is palpable. The creative<br />

imagination <strong>and</strong> its play <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas in <strong>the</strong> third Critique discussion<br />

31 Brauer notes, MS p. 88. Based on <strong>the</strong> notes taken by a student, Theodor Friederich Brauer, dated<br />

1779, taken from transcripts at <strong>the</strong> Philips-Universität, Marburg. I would like to thank Werner<br />

Stark for assistance in <strong>the</strong> use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se materials <strong>and</strong> for helpful information about <strong>the</strong> historical<br />

context in which <strong>the</strong>y were written. Although <strong>the</strong>se sources are from student transcriptions <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s lectures <strong>and</strong> are <strong>the</strong>refore not <strong>the</strong> final word on any disputed question in <strong>Kant</strong><br />

interpretation, nothing that I rely on here is essentially new to <strong>Kant</strong>, but ra<strong>the</strong>r corroborates views<br />

on enthusiasm expressed elsewhere. I have relied only on passages from Brauer that also appear in<br />

notes taken down by o<strong>the</strong>r students during that time.


110<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

<strong>of</strong> genius comes to mind: spectators whose own moral character finds<br />

expression in an excess <strong>of</strong> imaginative participation resemble <strong>the</strong> artistic<br />

genius who embodies an excess <strong>of</strong> thought in a single physical expression<br />

<strong>of</strong> it.<br />

Yet <strong>Kant</strong> was not unequivocal in his praise <strong>of</strong> moral enthusiasm. In<br />

connection with his comments from <strong>the</strong> anthropology lectures <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

late comment from <strong>the</strong> ‘‘An Old Question,’’ it is interesting to note his<br />

position expressed in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason: <strong>Kant</strong> argues that <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘typic’’ <strong>of</strong> pure practical judgment guards against ‘‘<strong>the</strong> mysticism <strong>of</strong><br />

practical reason, which makes into a schema that which should serve only<br />

as a symbol, i.e., proposes to supply real yet nonsensuous intuitions (<strong>of</strong> an<br />

invisible kingdom <strong>of</strong> God) for <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral law <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

plunges into <strong>the</strong> transcendent’’ (V: 70–71). Never<strong>the</strong>less, he contrasts this<br />

mystic plunge with <strong>the</strong> ‘‘empiricism <strong>of</strong> practical reason’’ to <strong>the</strong> benefit <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> former:<br />

The protest against empiricism <strong>of</strong> practical reason is much more important <strong>and</strong><br />

commendable, because mysticism is compatible with <strong>the</strong> purity <strong>and</strong> sublimity <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> moral law; <strong>and</strong> as it is not natural to ordinary ways <strong>of</strong> thinking [Denkungsart]<br />

to stretch its imagination to supersensuous intuitions, <strong>the</strong> danger from this side<br />

is not so general ... [E]mpiricism [<strong>of</strong> practical reason] is far more dangerous<br />

than all mystical enthusiasm, which can never be a lasting condition for any great<br />

number <strong>of</strong> persons. (V: 70–71)<br />

Here <strong>Kant</strong> expresses a thoroughly ambivalent attitude to <strong>the</strong> imagination<br />

when used to present ideas <strong>of</strong> reason. Whereas he is quite clear that<br />

practical reason based on empirical principles is degrading because it is<br />

generally allied with (sensuous) inclination, he is tolerant <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

‘‘stretched’’ to <strong>the</strong> supersensuous only because it is less likely to occur.<br />

The ‘‘rationalism <strong>of</strong> practical reason’’ is a safer bet, if one had to choose.<br />

Thus, in one brief passage in <strong>the</strong> heart <strong>of</strong> his mature moral <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

manages to both criticize <strong>and</strong> defend <strong>the</strong> enthusiast (e.g., Swedenborg)<br />

<strong>and</strong>, at <strong>the</strong> same time, <strong>Kant</strong>’s own rationalist forefa<strong>the</strong>rs. So far as moral<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory is concerned, passionate rationalist speculation about <strong>the</strong> good is<br />

less dangerous than dwelling on ‘‘empirical interest, with which inclinations<br />

generally are secretly in league’’ (V: 71). Mystical enthusiasm will<br />

only ever be ‘‘a lasting condition’’ for a small number <strong>of</strong> persons, <strong>and</strong><br />

even <strong>the</strong>n is compatible with <strong>the</strong> purity <strong>and</strong> sublimity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral law<br />

because it involves imaginative transcendence <strong>of</strong> inclinations <strong>and</strong> sensibility.<br />

On balance, <strong>and</strong> in conjunction with <strong>Kant</strong>’s o<strong>the</strong>r claims about <strong>the</strong><br />

positive moral value <strong>of</strong> enthusiasm, it appears that he always maintained<br />

a certain regard for visionaries that went beyond simply enlightened


tolerance. His rejection <strong>of</strong> Swedenborg, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> metaphysics, was more<br />

nuanced than <strong>the</strong> Böhmes suggest. 32<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> held that attempts at imaginative transcendence by ordinary<br />

people are bound to fail, <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> third Critique he argues that this very<br />

failure <strong>of</strong> imagination may give rise to an appreciation <strong>of</strong> reason’s<br />

superiority to imagination (<strong>and</strong> sensibility). This appreciation is, <strong>of</strong><br />

course, <strong>the</strong> feeling <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sublime: At Section 29, ‘‘On <strong>the</strong> Modality <strong>of</strong> a<br />

Judgment about <strong>the</strong> Sublime in Nature,’’ <strong>Kant</strong> says that<br />

The [sublime] is what genuinely characterizes man’s morality, where reason must<br />

exert its dominance over sensibility, except that in an aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment about<br />

<strong>the</strong> sublime we present this dominance as being exerted by <strong>the</strong> imagination itself,<br />

as an instrument <strong>of</strong> reason. (V: 268–269)<br />

And also:<br />

The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 111<br />

<strong>the</strong> [imagination], acting in accordance with principles <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> schematism <strong>of</strong><br />

judgment[,] ... is an instrument <strong>of</strong> reason <strong>and</strong> its ideas ... In this reflection <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic power <strong>of</strong> judgment [i.e., <strong>of</strong> imagination], by which it seeks to<br />

elevate itself to <strong>the</strong> point <strong>of</strong> being adequate to reason ... we present <strong>the</strong> object<br />

itself as subjectively purposive, precisely because objectively <strong>the</strong> imagination,<br />

[even] in its greatest expansion, is inadequate to reason. (V: 269)<br />

Here <strong>the</strong> imagination appears to be grasping <strong>the</strong> transcendent, only to be<br />

humiliated <strong>and</strong> give way to <strong>the</strong> higher moral calling <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject. In a<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> moral bait-<strong>and</strong>-switch, <strong>the</strong> promise <strong>of</strong> metaphysical insight is held<br />

out as <strong>the</strong> goal that imagination attempts to reach (in contemplation <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> overwhelming might or size <strong>of</strong> natural objects), only to be replaced by<br />

<strong>the</strong> feeling <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> transcendence <strong>of</strong> reason.<br />

So we find <strong>Kant</strong> on <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong> admiring <strong>and</strong> defending <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘enthusiast <strong>of</strong> reason’’ who takes his imagined moral visions to be reality<br />

<strong>and</strong> also, in his aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory, propounding a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

that suggests that such visions could have significant moral worth. At <strong>the</strong><br />

same time, he conspicuously refrains from making a strong, explicit<br />

argument for <strong>the</strong> need for such an imagination to support moral judgment<br />

<strong>and</strong> action. Once again we must ask why.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s hesitancy to embrace a natural consequence <strong>of</strong> his own views<br />

about <strong>the</strong> imagination may be traced, I believe, to two quite different<br />

32 For a defense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>Kant</strong> never fully rejected rationalist metaphysics, see Karl Ameriks,<br />

‘‘The Critique <strong>of</strong> Metaphysics: <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Traditional Ontology,’’ in The Cambridge Companion to<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 249–279.


112<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

motivations, one <strong>of</strong> which has historical <strong>and</strong> (if <strong>the</strong> Böhmes are correct)<br />

personal psychological roots in his concerns about <strong>the</strong> dangers <strong>of</strong><br />

imaginative distractions. The o<strong>the</strong>r motivation is not so obviously<br />

lamentable. <strong>Kant</strong>’s aversion to moral elitism led him to reject <strong>the</strong><br />

notion <strong>of</strong> any sort <strong>of</strong> intuitive access to <strong>the</strong> rational (moral), even if he<br />

did not totally reject those who claimed to have it. <strong>Kant</strong> was convinced<br />

that morality itself proscribed taking oneself to be better equipped to<br />

grasp moral principles <strong>and</strong> hence to set oneself up as a moral authority<br />

over o<strong>the</strong>rs. The very heart <strong>of</strong> his moral <strong>the</strong>ory requires knowing oneself<br />

(honestly evaluating one’s maxims) so as to prevent self-deception from<br />

paving <strong>the</strong> way to making an exception for oneself morally. 33 Whatever<br />

else it is, such self-knowledge ought not to be ‘‘creative.’’ Moreover,<br />

imagination, <strong>Kant</strong> felt, is not given to all in <strong>the</strong> same measure (although<br />

everyone has some potential for developing it). Genius is a gift <strong>of</strong><br />

nature, ‘‘an innate mental predisposition’’ (V: 308) that belongs to<br />

artists whose ideas are ‘‘rich in fancy <strong>and</strong> yet also in thought’’ (V: 309).<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> was willing to allow that certain enthusiasts (notably Plato <strong>and</strong><br />

Rousseau) were able to combine <strong>the</strong>ir gift for fantasy with an equally<br />

great gift for philosophical thought. But nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>y nor any o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

genius could claim, just on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir genius, to be more or less<br />

moral than any o<strong>the</strong>r person. The reason for this is that <strong>the</strong> distinguishing<br />

mark <strong>of</strong> genius is its inability to be shared – literally communicated<br />

– with o<strong>the</strong>rs. For this reason, <strong>Kant</strong> argues that a great<br />

discoverer like Newton was not, in his scientific work, exhibiting genius,<br />

since Newton could ‘‘show how he took every one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> steps he had<br />

to take in order to get from <strong>the</strong> first elements <strong>of</strong> geometry to his great<br />

<strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ound discoveries ...to everyone else as well ...allowing o<strong>the</strong>rs<br />

to follow.’’ On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong> a Homer or a Wiel<strong>and</strong> did exhibit<br />

genius precisely because <strong>the</strong>ir work, based in <strong>the</strong>ir own rich fantasy, was<br />

inexplicable even to <strong>the</strong>mselves, let alone communicable to o<strong>the</strong>rs. They<br />

could not lay out rules for o<strong>the</strong>rs to follow in order to accomplish what<br />

<strong>the</strong>y <strong>the</strong>mselves accomplished.<br />

In chapter 7 I shall argue that, on <strong>Kant</strong>’s own account <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

reflection, genius may be seen as more common among human beings<br />

33 See Immanuel <strong>Kant</strong>, The Metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Morals, trans. Mary J. Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1991), VI: 441. Andrews Reath argues convincingly for <strong>the</strong> centrality <strong>of</strong> this aspect<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s ethics in ‘‘Two Conceptions,’’ <strong>and</strong> more recently Jeanine Grenberg has written<br />

extensively on <strong>Kant</strong>’s conception <strong>of</strong> humility <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> role it plays in his moral <strong>the</strong>ory (<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Ethics <strong>of</strong> Humility: A Story <strong>of</strong> Dependence, Corruption <strong>and</strong> Virtue, Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 2005).


The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 113<br />

than his distinction between Newton <strong>and</strong> Homer suggests. Here <strong>the</strong><br />

point to be made is simply that <strong>Kant</strong> did present this distinction as<br />

unproblematic. In this respect, he is simply reiterating <strong>the</strong> trend in<br />

German aes<strong>the</strong>tics, culminating in Lessing’s work, discussed in chapter 2.<br />

That is, Lessing argued for granting <strong>the</strong> artist greater artistic freedom<br />

<strong>and</strong> less constraint by rules <strong>of</strong> criticism, on <strong>the</strong> ground that genius is a<br />

rule unto itself. And, as we saw in chapter 3, <strong>the</strong> artistic imagination for<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>, as for Lessing, is itself a product <strong>of</strong> nature. But for that very reason<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> felt it could not be a necessary condition <strong>of</strong> human moral experience;<br />

hence <strong>Kant</strong>’s suspicion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> claims <strong>of</strong> metaphysical visionaries.<br />

These ‘‘artists <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolute,’’ as we might call <strong>the</strong>m, could never<br />

provide rules for o<strong>the</strong>rs to follow in order to duplicate <strong>the</strong>ir own<br />

experiences. Their fantasies are not universally communicable, in o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

words. 34<br />

<strong>the</strong> imaginative dimension <strong>of</strong> metaphysical<br />

speculation<br />

In Enlightenment, Revolution <strong>and</strong> Romanticism, <strong>and</strong> his article ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

Intellectual Development 1746–1781’’ for The Cambridge Companion to<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>, Frederick Beiser emphasizes <strong>Kant</strong>’s ambivalent feelings toward<br />

metaphysics throughout his life <strong>and</strong> writings. Beiser points to <strong>Kant</strong>’s own<br />

metaphor <strong>of</strong> metaphysics as his (<strong>Kant</strong>’s) seductive mistress, 35 mapping<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s intellectual development through several stages, including infatuation,<br />

disillusionment, partial reconciliation, <strong>and</strong> divorce. He argues<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong>’s view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> philosophical enterprise, <strong>and</strong> consequently <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

importance <strong>of</strong> metaphysics, had changed in 1765 after his reading <strong>of</strong><br />

Rousseau. <strong>Kant</strong> famously claimed that from <strong>the</strong>n on he was to be<br />

committed to practical concerns:<br />

I am myself by inclination a seeker after truth. I feel a consuming thirst for<br />

knowledge <strong>and</strong> a restless desire to advance in it, as well as a satisfaction in every<br />

step I take. There was a time when I thought that this alone could constitute <strong>the</strong><br />

34 Neiman points out ano<strong>the</strong>r problem with visionaries, for <strong>Kant</strong>, namely <strong>the</strong>ir tendency to force<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir views on o<strong>the</strong>rs, (The Unity <strong>of</strong> Reason: Rereading <strong>Kant</strong>, Oxford: Oxford University Press,<br />

1994, p.169).<br />

35 Dreams <strong>of</strong> a Spirit-Seer, Ak II: 367: ‘‘Die Metaphysik, in welche ich das Schicksal habe verliebt zu<br />

sein, ob ich mich gleich von ihr nur selten einiger Gunstbezeugungen ruehmen kann, leistet<br />

zweierlei vorteile.’’


114<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

honor <strong>of</strong> mankind, <strong>and</strong> I despised <strong>the</strong> common man who knows nothing.<br />

Rousseau set me right. This pretended superiority vanished <strong>and</strong> I learned to<br />

respect humanity. I should consider myself far more useless than <strong>the</strong> common<br />

laborer if I did not believe that one consideration alone gives worth to all o<strong>the</strong>rs,<br />

namely, to establish <strong>the</strong> rights <strong>of</strong> man. (Remarks on <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Observations on <strong>the</strong><br />

Beautiful <strong>and</strong> Sublime’’ XX: 44)<br />

In Enlightenment, Revolution <strong>and</strong> Romanticism, Beiser sees <strong>the</strong> concern<br />

expressed by <strong>Kant</strong> that his philosophizing be ‘‘useful’’ as a concern shared<br />

generally by later Enlighteners in Germany:<br />

The Aufklärung was a practical movement ins<strong>of</strong>ar as its purpose was not to<br />

discover <strong>the</strong> first principles <strong>of</strong> reason – most Aufklärer believed that this task had<br />

already been achieved by thinkers such as Leibniz, Wolff, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> – but to<br />

bring <strong>the</strong>m into daily life. In short, its aim was to surmount <strong>the</strong> gap between<br />

reason <strong>and</strong> life, <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> practice, speculation <strong>and</strong> action ...Most thinkers <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> late eighteenth century saw <strong>the</strong>mselves as Aufklärer, not only older figures<br />

such as <strong>Kant</strong>, Herder, <strong>and</strong> Wiel<strong>and</strong>, but also younger ones such as Schlegel,<br />

Hölderlin, <strong>and</strong> Novalis.<br />

This turn to <strong>the</strong> practical explains, according to Beiser, why <strong>Kant</strong><br />

comes to manifest a ‘‘complete skepticism toward metaphysics.’’ It is so<br />

deep, Beiser says, that in Dreams <strong>of</strong> a Spirit-Seer, ‘‘he likens metaphysics<br />

to <strong>the</strong> dreams <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> visionary or spirit-seer’’(‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s Intellectual<br />

Development,’’ p. 45) <strong>and</strong> (in ‘‘The Politics <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critical Philosophy’’)<br />

he also claims that for <strong>Kant</strong> ‘‘Both metaphysicians <strong>and</strong> spirit<br />

seers live in a private fantasy world <strong>and</strong> chase after illusory abstractions<br />

...<strong>the</strong> aim <strong>of</strong> [<strong>Kant</strong>’s] skepticism [about metaphysics] is to expose<br />

<strong>the</strong> vanity <strong>of</strong> speculation, so that we direct our efforts toward finding<br />

what is truly useful for human life’’(Enlightenment, Revolution <strong>and</strong><br />

Romanticism, p.28). With this favoring <strong>of</strong> practical over <strong>the</strong>oretical<br />

reason, Beiser suggests, <strong>the</strong> honeymoon with metaphysics is over for<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>.<br />

I have argued in chapter 4 that in fact <strong>Kant</strong> did not ‘‘prefer’’ practical<br />

to <strong>the</strong>oretical reason, but saw <strong>the</strong> two as intertwined, connected by<br />

reflective judgment. Beiser himself maintains, I believe quite correctly,<br />

that <strong>the</strong> supposed ‘‘divorce’’ with speculative <strong>the</strong>ory was never fully<br />

carried out, <strong>and</strong> that ‘‘<strong>the</strong> flames <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> old love affair burnt to <strong>the</strong> bitter<br />

end’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s life (‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s Intellectual Development,’’ p. 57). Beiser<br />

finds <strong>the</strong> old flame burning most strongly in <strong>Kant</strong>’s hypostatization in <strong>the</strong><br />

second Critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> conditions under which human beings could hope<br />

to bring about a just world – <strong>the</strong> highest good (Enlightenment, Revolution


The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 115<br />

<strong>and</strong> Romanticism, p.55), that is, in <strong>the</strong> postulates <strong>of</strong> metaphysical notions<br />

<strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> immortality. As we saw earlier, Beiser argues that this return<br />

to metaphysics constitutes a ‘‘deep betrayal’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> radical spirit <strong>of</strong> his<br />

republican politics, <strong>and</strong> an inconsistency in his philosophy (p. 55).<br />

Although Beiser is surely correct to point to <strong>Kant</strong>’s disillusionment with<br />

metaphysics in 1765, <strong>and</strong> even before, I believe that, like <strong>the</strong> Böhmes, he<br />

overstates <strong>the</strong> situation in labeling <strong>Kant</strong>’s view <strong>of</strong> speculative metaphysics<br />

one <strong>of</strong> ‘‘complete skepticism.’’ While it is true that <strong>Kant</strong> castigates<br />

metaphysics for being schwärmerisch, <strong>and</strong> prone to fanaticism, as we have<br />

just seen, <strong>Kant</strong> was not himself immune to ‘‘enthusiasm,’’ nor was he<br />

ashamed to admit that fact. The <strong>of</strong>t-cited passage from <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Remarks’’ is<br />

certainly indicative <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s own susceptibility to Schwärmerei, for both<br />

knowledge <strong>and</strong> morality: he confesses to a ‘‘consuming thirst for<br />

knowledge <strong>and</strong> a restless desire to advance it’’ that only gave way after<br />

reading Rousseau to an even more consuming desire ‘‘to establish <strong>the</strong><br />

rights <strong>of</strong> man.’’ 36<br />

As we saw, in certain cases, <strong>Kant</strong> actually embraced metaphysical<br />

Schwärmerei in <strong>the</strong> service <strong>of</strong> morality <strong>and</strong> eventually even found a<br />

limited place for this enthusiasm in <strong>the</strong> critical system. I want to conclude<br />

this chapter by arguing that <strong>Kant</strong> did intend to return metaphysics to <strong>the</strong><br />

Critical Philosophy, <strong>and</strong> that he did so in an interesting <strong>and</strong> defensible way<br />

that would not require recourse to <strong>the</strong> postulates. The postulates were, I<br />

would agree, a failed reintroduction <strong>of</strong> metaphysical entities that did not,<br />

<strong>and</strong> were not in any case intended to, preserve <strong>the</strong> autonomy <strong>of</strong> metaphysical<br />

speculation. But skeptical as <strong>Kant</strong> was about ‘‘enthusiasts,’’ he<br />

also believed that <strong>the</strong> pleasure <strong>of</strong> disinterested metaphysical speculation –<br />

i.e., <strong>the</strong> pleasure <strong>of</strong> doing metaphysics not in <strong>the</strong> service <strong>of</strong> morals or politics –<br />

is a natural <strong>and</strong> perhaps even necessary mechanism for <strong>the</strong> advancement<br />

<strong>of</strong> humanity. The arguments <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> previous section suggest that <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r dimension to <strong>Kant</strong>’s relationship to metaphysics – an aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

dimension.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> associates Rousseau with imaginative enthusiasm for moral ideas:<br />

And yet it was Rousseau who awakened him from his dogmatic metaphysical<br />

slumbers <strong>and</strong> caused him to divorce himself from ‘‘elitist’’<br />

metaphysical speculation in favor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> practical. There is a certain irony<br />

in this that may have prompted <strong>Kant</strong> to find a systematic place for <strong>the</strong><br />

36 See Velkley, Freedom <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> End <strong>of</strong> Reason, pp. 6–8, 32–43 <strong>and</strong> Beiser, ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s Intellectual<br />

Development,’’ pp. 43–46, <strong>and</strong> also Dieter Henrich, ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong> und Hegel,’’ in Selbstverhältnisse<br />

(Stuttgart: Reclam, 1982), pp. 183–184, on Rousseau’s influence on <strong>the</strong> ‘‘emotional <strong>and</strong> imaginative<br />

side’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s thought.


116<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

‘‘noble fantast’’ who strives for perfection <strong>and</strong> ideals that lie at <strong>the</strong> heart <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> rationalist metaphysics <strong>Kant</strong> sought to ab<strong>and</strong>on. In this regard it is<br />

worth recalling our earlier discussion (chapter 3) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third Critique at<br />

Section 17 (‘‘On <strong>the</strong> Ideal <strong>of</strong> Beauty’’). <strong>Kant</strong> here describes a kind <strong>of</strong><br />

judging that involves <strong>the</strong> connecting <strong>of</strong> intuitive presentations with a<br />

moral idea, producing a concrete presentation <strong>of</strong> what is merely a rational<br />

idea. In chapter 2 I argued that such moral ‘‘imaginings’’ might even serve<br />

as a subjective basis <strong>of</strong> rational hope for moral progress – that is, <strong>the</strong>y may<br />

enable belief in <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> realizing moral ideas, supplanting <strong>the</strong><br />

hypostatisizations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> postulates. In <strong>the</strong> exhibition <strong>of</strong> this idea <strong>of</strong>reason,<br />

imagination makes <strong>the</strong> realization <strong>of</strong> that idea subjectively possible –<br />

‘‘imaginable.’’ Interestingly enough, <strong>Kant</strong> hints that this will not be<br />

found in all people:<br />

in order for this connection to be made visible, as it were, in bodily expression<br />

(as an effect <strong>of</strong> what is inward), pure ideas <strong>of</strong> reason must be united with a very<br />

strong imagination in someone who seeks so much as to judge, let alone exhibit<br />

it (V: 235)<br />

The similarities in this section <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> third Critique to <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘pathological’’ state <strong>of</strong> Schwärmerei are clear: <strong>the</strong> person judging according<br />

to an ideal <strong>of</strong> beauty is seeing genuine reality in his/her idea. And yet here<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> is in no way suggesting that taking ideas for reality is deranged. It is<br />

simply a way <strong>of</strong> putting aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment to moral use, although presumably<br />

only a few will have <strong>the</strong> requisite powers <strong>of</strong> imagination to literally<br />

produce this ideal. In all <strong>the</strong>se cases, <strong>Kant</strong>’s ab<strong>and</strong>oned metaphysical<br />

longings seem to have found a new home on <strong>the</strong> borders <strong>of</strong> his practical<br />

philosophy; <strong>and</strong> it is far less alienated than <strong>the</strong> postulation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘fact’’ <strong>of</strong> human immortality.<br />

In addition to embracing <strong>and</strong> even incorporating metaphysical longings<br />

into his practical philosophy, <strong>Kant</strong> also finds a way to value metaphysical<br />

urges even where <strong>the</strong>y are not directly connected with moral<br />

concerns. The judgment that involves <strong>the</strong> ideal <strong>of</strong> beauty involves an<br />

interest <strong>of</strong> reason, <strong>and</strong> hence is not itself a purely aes<strong>the</strong>tic judgment, but<br />

what I called earlier a kind <strong>of</strong> ‘‘mixed mode’’ that involves practical as<br />

well as aes<strong>the</strong>tic elements (V: 236). This distinguishes it from <strong>the</strong> pure<br />

judgments <strong>of</strong> taste, which are by definition impractical – <strong>the</strong>y involve<br />

disinterested pleasure. As we saw in chapter 3, however, <strong>Kant</strong> believes that<br />

we can become interested in <strong>the</strong> objects <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective judgment<br />

‘‘after <strong>the</strong> judgment has been made as a pure aes<strong>the</strong>tic one’’ (V: 296). <strong>Kant</strong><br />

allows two possibilities: one ‘‘empirical’’ <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r ‘‘intellectual.’’ In


The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 117<br />

chapter 4 I argued that <strong>the</strong> intellectual interest in <strong>the</strong> beautiful is an<br />

interest in <strong>the</strong> embodiment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> a world that is fitted to our<br />

moral needs, <strong>and</strong> here again <strong>Kant</strong>’s repressed desire for metaphysics<br />

emerges: Since reason has an interest, as <strong>Kant</strong> puts it, in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘objective<br />

reality’’ <strong>of</strong> its moral ideas it cannot be a matter <strong>of</strong> complete indifference<br />

to us, when contemplating <strong>the</strong> beautiful, that nature here ‘‘shows a trace or<br />

gives a hint that it contains some basis or o<strong>the</strong>r for us to assume’’ an<br />

orderliness that may be conducive to, or at least not out <strong>of</strong> sync with, our<br />

moral desires. As we saw, <strong>Kant</strong> is suggesting that in <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> making<br />

an aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective judgment about <strong>the</strong> beauty <strong>of</strong> an object we may come<br />

to care for <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> which it is but a part, <strong>and</strong> we may come to value <strong>the</strong><br />

whole <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> natural world for its own sake. As moral beings we are charged<br />

with <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> bringing moral order into <strong>the</strong> natural world – a dem<strong>and</strong> on<br />

human nature that hardly seems possible. Thus we are intellectually<br />

interested in finding evidence that nature outside us, in what appears to be<br />

<strong>the</strong> rational orderliness <strong>and</strong> purposiveness <strong>of</strong> her beauty, may be suited to<br />

<strong>the</strong> nature ‘‘within.’’ But never<strong>the</strong>less, for <strong>Kant</strong> this desire/interest/pleasure<br />

in <strong>the</strong> orderliness <strong>of</strong> nature manifested in beauty is not itself a moral<br />

interest. It is intellectual, a kind <strong>of</strong> Platonic love, as it were. Contemplation<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> beautiful may give rise to a ‘‘love’’ or admiration for nature in itself,<br />

apart from any connection to our moral nature.<br />

But what is this pleasure in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘hint’’ <strong>of</strong> transcendent rational order<br />

but a sort <strong>of</strong> metaphysical enthusiasm, suitably distanced by aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

reflection? The person who comes to love <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>of</strong> nature based on<br />

disinterested contemplation <strong>of</strong> nature’s formal properties bears a close<br />

resemblance to <strong>the</strong> ‘‘noble fantast’’ – to Plato’s philosopher gazing out <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> cave, or Rousseau surveying <strong>the</strong> state <strong>of</strong> nature, or even <strong>Kant</strong> himself,<br />

awed by <strong>the</strong> starry heavens above. Taking an intellectual interest in <strong>the</strong><br />

beautiful is a deeply ‘‘metaphysical’’ feeling.<br />

That <strong>the</strong> desire for metaphysical speculation is inevitable <strong>and</strong> unavoidable<br />

is, <strong>of</strong> course, a recurring <strong>the</strong>me in <strong>the</strong> first Critique. Reason seeks<br />

<strong>the</strong> unconditioned by its very nature. The danger is believing that one<br />

has found it. Tough-minded resistance <strong>and</strong> staying close to home (staying<br />

close to <strong>the</strong> rocky shores <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenomenal <strong>and</strong> avoiding <strong>the</strong> open sea<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> noumenal) are <strong>the</strong> only ways to avoid <strong>the</strong> lures <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> threat <strong>of</strong> fanaticism. But I hope to have shown that <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

attitude toward fanaticism is not uniformly negative. Chapter 1 already<br />

introduced <strong>the</strong> idea that, for <strong>Kant</strong>, <strong>the</strong> mental powers are capable<br />

<strong>of</strong> imaginative development <strong>and</strong> growth – <strong>of</strong> progress, we might say. It is<br />

worth quoting in full <strong>the</strong> passage mentioned <strong>the</strong>re in passing. In a


118<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

footnote in <strong>the</strong> First Introduction to <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment (Section<br />

XIII, ‘‘On <strong>the</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Power</strong> <strong>of</strong> Judging, Comment’’ (in reference<br />

to finding a definition <strong>of</strong> a feeling <strong>of</strong> pleasure that is tied to sources a<br />

priori)) <strong>Kant</strong> makes <strong>the</strong> following surprising admission:<br />

In fact man can desire something most fervently <strong>and</strong> persistently even though<br />

he is convinced that he cannot achieve it, or that it is perhaps even<br />

[something] absolutely impossible ... <strong>and</strong> it is indeed an important article for<br />

morality to warn us emphatically against such empty <strong>and</strong> fanciful desires,<br />

which are <strong>of</strong>ten nourished by novels <strong>and</strong> sometimes also by mystical<br />

presentations, similar to novels, <strong>of</strong> superhuman perfections <strong>and</strong> fanatical<br />

bliss. But some empty desires <strong>and</strong> longings ...do have <strong>the</strong>ir effect on <strong>the</strong><br />

mind ...It is indeed a not unimportant problem for anthropology to<br />

investigate why it is that nature has given us <strong>the</strong> predisposition to such<br />

fruitless expenditure <strong>of</strong> our forces as [we see in] empty wishes <strong>and</strong> longings<br />

(which certainly play a large role in human life). It seems to me that here, as in<br />

all else, nature has made wise provisions. For if we had to assure ourselves that<br />

we can in fact produce <strong>the</strong> object, before <strong>the</strong> presentation <strong>of</strong> it could<br />

determine us to apply our forces, our forces would presumably remain largely<br />

unused. For usually we do not come to know what forces we have except by<br />

trying <strong>the</strong>m out. So nature has provided for <strong>the</strong> connection between <strong>the</strong><br />

determination <strong>of</strong> our forces <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> presentation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> object [to be <strong>the</strong>re]<br />

even before we know what ability we have, <strong>and</strong> it is <strong>of</strong>ten precisely this effort,<br />

which to that very mind seemed at first an empty wish, that produces that<br />

ability in <strong>the</strong> first place. Now wisdom is obligated to set limits to that instinct,<br />

but wisdom will never succeed in eradicating it, or [ra<strong>the</strong>r] it will never even<br />

dem<strong>and</strong> its eradication.<br />

A ‘‘predisposition’’ to ‘‘empty wishes <strong>and</strong> longings’’ that appears to be a<br />

‘‘fruitless expenditure <strong>of</strong> our forces’’ could in fact be an enabling<br />

mechanism – part <strong>of</strong> nature’s plan for advancing human capacities<br />

unbeknownst to <strong>the</strong>m. Something akin to <strong>the</strong> historical progress enabled<br />

by nature via unsocial sociability is at work on <strong>the</strong> microlevel in individuals,<br />

with <strong>the</strong> imagination goading reason into a development that<br />

rational critique would itself only stymie. Here too nature’s mechanism, a<br />

kind <strong>of</strong> ‘‘unrational rationality’’ perhaps, is something <strong>Kant</strong> not only<br />

tolerates but to a certain extent applauds. Consider <strong>the</strong> following passage<br />

from <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Teleological Judgment,’’ in which <strong>Kant</strong> illustrates<br />

what he calls ‘‘intellectual purposiveness’’ <strong>and</strong> describes <strong>the</strong> way in which<br />

it can naturally lead to ‘‘Schwärmerei’’:<br />

It is a true joy to see how eagerly <strong>the</strong> ancient geometers investigated <strong>the</strong>se<br />

properties <strong>of</strong> such lines, not letting <strong>the</strong>mselves be disconcerted if asked by


The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 119<br />

narrow minds <strong>of</strong> what use such knowledge might be ...While <strong>the</strong>se geometers<br />

were thus unwittingly working for posterity, <strong>the</strong>y took delight in a purposiveness<br />

which, though it belonged to <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> things, could still be exhibited<br />

completely ‘‘a priori’’ in its necessity. Plato, himself a master <strong>of</strong> this science, was<br />

overcome by enthusiasm [Begeisterung] [when he saw] that <strong>the</strong> original character<br />

<strong>of</strong> things is such that it can be discovered without any experience whatever, <strong>and</strong><br />

that <strong>the</strong> mind is able to derive <strong>the</strong> harmony <strong>of</strong> beings from <strong>the</strong>ir supersensible<br />

principle ...It was this enthusiasm that lifted Plato above empirical concepts to<br />

ideas that he thought could be explained only by an intellectual community<br />

[between ourselves <strong>and</strong>] <strong>the</strong> origin <strong>of</strong> all beings ... Surely it is pardonable if, as<br />

<strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> a misunderst<strong>and</strong>ing this admiration gradually increased to <strong>the</strong> point<br />

<strong>of</strong> fanaticism [Schwärmerei].<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> seems to have finally settled on <strong>the</strong> view that <strong>the</strong> desire for metaphysics<br />

is useful, <strong>and</strong> may be embraced by Enlightenment, even if<br />

metaphysics – <strong>the</strong> Absolute itself – is <strong>of</strong>f limits. At <strong>the</strong> same time, this<br />

desire is not an interest in morals, politics, or utility (<strong>Kant</strong> also mentions<br />

‘‘<strong>the</strong> properties <strong>of</strong> numbers, with which <strong>the</strong> mind plays in music’’ in this<br />

passage). It is, in o<strong>the</strong>r words, a disinterested desire for knowledge for its<br />

own sake that leads us to discover apparent purposiveness which in turn<br />

‘‘exp<strong>and</strong>s <strong>the</strong> mind’’ <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> says, ‘‘makes us suspect ...that <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

something else above <strong>and</strong> beyond those presentations <strong>of</strong> sense, something<br />

which, although we do not know it, might hold <strong>the</strong> ultimate basis for that<br />

harmony [between <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> sensible intuition <strong>and</strong> our power <strong>of</strong><br />

concepts].’’<br />

In both <strong>the</strong>se passages <strong>Kant</strong> again is advocating, or at least ‘‘apologizing’’<br />

for, a kind <strong>of</strong> intellectual disinterested pleasure, that is a complete<br />

absorption, ‘‘love,’’ or ‘‘delight’’ taken in <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> object<br />

studied, <strong>and</strong> a lack <strong>of</strong> concern for <strong>the</strong> usefulness, gratification, or even<br />

goodness <strong>the</strong> object might bring. Even where that pleasure leads to<br />

fanaticism, <strong>Kant</strong> is willing to be tolerant. It is difficult not to see<br />

something autobiographical in <strong>the</strong>se passages, some latent reference to <strong>the</strong><br />

self-avowed infatuation with metaphysics in <strong>the</strong> remarks <strong>of</strong> 1765. Certainly<br />

it does not represent a return to his former love, if that meant<br />

embracing <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> objects that transcend experience. Although he<br />

flirts with it in <strong>the</strong> postulates <strong>of</strong> God <strong>and</strong> immortality in <strong>the</strong> second<br />

Critique, what <strong>Kant</strong> does in <strong>the</strong> third Critique is far more subtle. What<br />

returns here is not <strong>the</strong> substance <strong>of</strong> metaphysical speculation but <strong>the</strong><br />

recognition <strong>and</strong> repositioning <strong>of</strong> a legitimate desire for it.<br />

Thus <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination did not fail, but ra<strong>the</strong>r returned as a real force<br />

in <strong>the</strong> final chapters <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critical opus. In this respect <strong>the</strong> Böhmes’


120<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

critique is too strong. And, to <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>Kant</strong> did not develop his<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory fur<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> motivation is not entirely bad: Intuitive access to <strong>the</strong><br />

moral may indeed be creative <strong>and</strong> important, but it is not unproblematic.<br />

<strong>Imagination</strong> may accompany all sorts <strong>of</strong> ‘‘undesirable’’ characteristics, just<br />

as may underst<strong>and</strong>ing. Enormously creative persons may also be perfectly<br />

self-centered, <strong>and</strong> genius can be evil. Certainly <strong>Kant</strong> was correct, for <strong>the</strong>se<br />

reasons, to hold that <strong>the</strong> way in which imagination functioned in conjunction<br />

with o<strong>the</strong>r capacities was central to deciding its value.<br />

It is in answering <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> just how <strong>Kant</strong> characterizes <strong>the</strong><br />

possible ‘‘conjunctions’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r faculties that <strong>the</strong><br />

Böhmes’ critique cannot be ignored. They are right to point out that<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> never seemed entirely comfortable with <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> an ‘‘equal’’<br />

relation between imagination <strong>and</strong> reason, even though in his critical<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory he had worked out an account <strong>of</strong> imaginative creativity<br />

compatible with such a relation. The question arises yet again: Why did<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> not push <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ideal <strong>of</strong> beauty, or <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas,<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r? Why did he not find a more pronounced place for <strong>the</strong> imagination<br />

in <strong>the</strong> moral? The role enthusiasm plays in <strong>Kant</strong>’s social <strong>the</strong>ory, as<br />

a glimmer <strong>of</strong> hope in <strong>the</strong> human quest for moral progress, is a way <strong>of</strong><br />

doing precisely this, but <strong>Kant</strong> himself never seems fully convinced. 37 It is<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore quite possible that part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> answer lies in <strong>the</strong> Böhmes’<br />

hypo<strong>the</strong>sis. In laying out <strong>the</strong> motivation for <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>oretical development,<br />

we should not dismiss <strong>the</strong> possibility that, for subconscious reasons<br />

that are all too transparent two centuries later, <strong>Kant</strong> simply may not have<br />

been able to bring himself to unequivocally grant <strong>the</strong> imagination a status<br />

equal to that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘law-governed’’ branches <strong>of</strong> human experience. It<br />

was, after all, a faculty associated on <strong>the</strong> transcendental level with ‘‘lawlessness’’<br />

<strong>and</strong>, on <strong>the</strong> empirical level, with <strong>the</strong> contaminating influences <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> body, its feelings, <strong>and</strong> desires. There may well be a sense in which<br />

Heidegger was after all right about one thing: It was not <strong>the</strong> failure <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination that prevented his finally embracing <strong>the</strong> ‘‘lower’’<br />

faculty, but ra<strong>the</strong>r a failure <strong>of</strong> nerve.<br />

In sum, <strong>Kant</strong> was tempted by, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore perhaps extremely cautious<br />

about, enthusiastic, imaginative excess – it was ‘‘not to be wholly esteemed,<br />

since passion as such deserves censure’’ (VII: 86) <strong>and</strong> was one <strong>of</strong><br />

37 The Böhmes’ claim that Romanticism is an ‘‘intermezzo’’ is thus not entirely accurate. See ‘‘The<br />

‘Earliest System-Programme <strong>of</strong> German Idealism’ (Berne, 1796): an Ethics,’’ trans. H. S. Harris, in<br />

Hegel’s Development: Toward <strong>the</strong> Sunlight 1770–1801 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972), pp. 510–513.<br />

On pp. 249ff., Harris also discusses <strong>the</strong> fragment’s origin, proposing his own view that it was<br />

authored by Hegel.


The failure <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s imagination 121<br />

‘‘two rocks’’ between which critical philosophy must navigate (in <strong>the</strong> first<br />

Critique (B128)). Such caution was not shared by <strong>Kant</strong>’s ‘‘enthusiastic’’<br />

followers. The ‘‘System-Programme’’ fragment (attributed by various<br />

scholars to ei<strong>the</strong>r Hegel or Hölderlin or Schelling, or to all three, or to<br />

some combination <strong>the</strong>re<strong>of</strong>) is a good example <strong>of</strong> an attempt to carry out in<br />

practice some <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s views on <strong>the</strong> modeling <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ideal in art: ‘‘I am<br />

now convinced,’’ says its author(s), ‘‘that <strong>the</strong> highest act <strong>of</strong> Reason, <strong>the</strong> one<br />

through which it encompasses all Ideas, is an aes<strong>the</strong>tic act.’’ 38 Although its<br />

authorship is uncertain, seen in light <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s views on <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong><br />

imagination, <strong>the</strong> early Romantic period for which this fragment is a kind <strong>of</strong><br />

manifesto is easily seen as an extension <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory.<br />

38 In Friedrich Hölderlin: Essays <strong>and</strong> Letters on Theory, trans. <strong>and</strong> ed. Thomas Pfau (Albany: State<br />

University <strong>of</strong> New York Press, 1988), pp. 154–156.


chapter 6<br />

Imaginative reflections <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self in<br />

Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin<br />

The early ( Jena) period <strong>of</strong> German Romanticism is closely identified with<br />

early German Idealism, <strong>and</strong> with <strong>the</strong> philosophy <strong>of</strong> Johann Gottlieb<br />

Fichte. The reason for this is obvious enough. Fichte began lecturing at<br />

<strong>the</strong> university in Jena in <strong>the</strong> spring (Summer semester) <strong>of</strong> 1794, <strong>and</strong> work<br />

preliminary to his major work, <strong>the</strong> Wissenschaftslehre, appeared in that<br />

same year. 1 His arrival at Jena was anticipated with great excitement, <strong>and</strong><br />

among <strong>the</strong> Jena cohort <strong>of</strong> scholars <strong>and</strong> students who were inspired by his<br />

forceful presence were some whose names were to become inseparably<br />

bound up with German Romanticism. The Schlegels, Schelling, Tiek,<br />

Novalis, <strong>and</strong> also Hölderlin 2 all were part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Jena milieu in which<br />

Fichte’s work was avidly studied <strong>and</strong> discussed.<br />

Fichte’s philosophy was <strong>of</strong> course very much influenced by <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

Critical philosophy (he was hired at <strong>the</strong> University at Jena as a ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>ian’’<br />

1 Über den Begriff der Wissenschaftslehre, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Foundation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Entire Wissenschaftslehre, Parts I<br />

<strong>and</strong> II, were published in September 1794. Concerning <strong>the</strong> Concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Wissenschaftslehre had<br />

already been completed <strong>and</strong> was published in May 1794. Cf. Daniel Breazeale, trans. <strong>and</strong> ed., Fichte:<br />

Early Philosophical Writings (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988), pp. 47–49 for a list <strong>of</strong><br />

Fichte’s publications <strong>and</strong> lectures during <strong>the</strong> Jena period.<br />

2 The question <strong>of</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r to consider Hölderlin a ‘‘Romantic’’ is somewhat difficult to answer. On<br />

<strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong>, he is typically classified in German literature schoolbook texts as part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> late<br />

‘‘Klassik,’’ <strong>and</strong> many scholars would resist labeling him a Romantic. Cf., for example, Manfred<br />

Frank: ‘‘Hölderlin ... gehört aber nach der gewöhnlichen Meinung nicht in den Rahmen der<br />

Frühromantik; und ich will ihn auch nicht durch einen hermeneutischen coup de force zu einem<br />

geistigen Mitbewohner der Jenaer Wohngemeinschaft machen, der er nicht war.’’ In Einführung in<br />

die Frühromantische Äs<strong>the</strong>tik: Vorlesungen (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1989), p. 249. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>,<br />

he is characterized by Ricarda Huch in Die Romantik: Blütezeit, Ausbreitung und Verfall (Hamburg:<br />

Rowholt, 1985 [1951]) as a Romantic by disposition (pp. 484ff.). In Die Romantische Schule (Berlin:<br />

Gaertner, 1870), Rudolf Haym sees <strong>the</strong> germ <strong>of</strong> Romantic philosophy in Hölderlin’s ideas, <strong>and</strong><br />

argues that he belongs for this reason in a history <strong>of</strong> Romanticism (p. 305) although Hölderlin is<br />

called ‘‘eine Seitenlinie der Romantik’’ (an <strong>of</strong>fshoot <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Romantic), in contrast to Novalis’<br />

‘‘Hauptlinie’’ (p. 324).<br />

122


Imaginative reflections in Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin 123<br />

to replace Reinhold 3 ), <strong>and</strong> by Fichte’s concern that a stronger defense <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> practical reason was needed than <strong>Kant</strong> himself gave. 4<br />

The need for such a move is suggested by <strong>Kant</strong> himself in <strong>the</strong> third<br />

Critique, where he speaks <strong>of</strong> a ‘‘gulf’’ separating nature <strong>and</strong> freedom, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> need for a ‘‘principle <strong>of</strong> purposiveness’’ if a causality <strong>of</strong> freedom is to<br />

be seen as effective in <strong>the</strong> natural realm. 5 As we have seen, this principle<br />

for <strong>Kant</strong> is never more than regulative, however, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> a<br />

common principle uniting <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> practical reason in a single<br />

system necessarily remains open for <strong>Kant</strong>. But for Fichte, a defense <strong>of</strong><br />

freedom required more. The discovery <strong>of</strong> a unitary account <strong>of</strong> subjectivity –<br />

that is, an account founded upon a single ‘‘constitutive’’ principle –<br />

appeared necessary so that practical reason might be firmly situated<br />

within <strong>the</strong> constitution <strong>of</strong> an overarching system. 6<br />

To <strong>the</strong> extent that Hö lderlin’s <strong>and</strong> Novalis’ projects are taken to be<br />

searches for an account <strong>of</strong> how human desire <strong>and</strong> feeling may be united<br />

with reflection <strong>and</strong> reason – that is, to <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>the</strong>y are instances <strong>of</strong><br />

what Dieter Henrich calls ‘‘ Vereinigungsphilosophie’’ 7 – it is plausible to<br />

see both authors as part <strong>of</strong> a post-<strong>Kant</strong>ian attempt to ‘‘repair’’ difficulties<br />

raised by <strong>Kant</strong>’s view that subjectivity is irreducibly dual-natured – that<br />

is, part nature <strong>and</strong> part freedom. It may also be plausible to claim for<br />

<strong>the</strong>se writers a decisive influence on <strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong> German idealism. 8<br />

Certainly in <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> both Hö lderlin <strong>and</strong> Novalis, <strong>the</strong> ‘‘reunification’’<br />

<strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> self was an important <strong>the</strong>me. And yet, this longing for a<br />

unification <strong>of</strong> self <strong>and</strong> nature ought not to be confused with <strong>the</strong> project <strong>of</strong><br />

giving a unified systematic account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self based on a single basic<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> consciousness. The latter was Fichte’s project, <strong>and</strong> one to<br />

which, I will argue, nei<strong>the</strong>r Novalis nor Hö lderlin were committed.<br />

3<br />

Dieter Henrich points out that even though <strong>Kant</strong> was still teaching at Kö nigsberg, by 1792 it was<br />

<strong>the</strong> University at Jena that was <strong>the</strong> center <strong>of</strong> ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>ian’’ philosophy (Konstellationen: Probleme und<br />

Debatten am Ursprung der idealistischen Philosophie (1789–1795) (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1991), p. 229.<br />

4<br />

Cf. Frederick Neuhouser, Fichte’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Subjectivity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,<br />

1990 ), chapter 1.<br />

5<br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, V:175–176.<br />

6<br />

That is, Fichte was not content with ei<strong>the</strong>r a mere regulative principle, or an alleged ‘‘fact’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

consciousness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> moral law. Fichte’s concern was also rooted in his discontent with <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

doctrine <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘fact <strong>of</strong> reason’’ in <strong>the</strong> second Critique. See Neuhouser, Fichte’s Theory, pp. 21–29.<br />

7<br />

Cf. Dieter Henrich, ‘‘Hegel und Hölderlin,’’ in Hegel im Kontext (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp,<br />

1987), pp. 12ff. ‘‘Vereinigungsphilosophie’’ is <strong>the</strong> term Henrich uses to refer to <strong>the</strong> str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> thought<br />

exemplified in modern times by neoplatonism – for instance, by Shaftesbury in Engl<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> by<br />

Hemsterhuis <strong>and</strong> Herder in Germany.<br />

8<br />

As Henrich does with Hölderlin, ‘‘Hegel und Hölderlin,’’ pp. 21–22, inKonstellationen, <strong>and</strong> most<br />

fully in Der Grund im Beweßtsein: Hölderlins Denken in Jena (1794–95) (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta,<br />

1992).


124<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

If this were not <strong>the</strong> case – that is, if it were assumed that Hölderlin <strong>and</strong><br />

Novalis are at one with Fichte in attempting a unified account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

self – <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>y do not do so can only be seen as a philosophical<br />

failure. Moreover, identifying <strong>the</strong>se writers’ goals with Fichte’s<br />

obscures <strong>the</strong> very close affinity between <strong>Kant</strong>’s later writings on morality<br />

<strong>and</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> an important str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> Romanticism. In what follows,<br />

I shall argue that both Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin developed conceptions <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> self that were in fact far more in <strong>the</strong> spirit <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> than <strong>of</strong> Fichte, <strong>and</strong><br />

that <strong>the</strong>ir criticisms <strong>of</strong> Fichte ought to be read as a sort <strong>of</strong> poetic <strong>Kant</strong>ian<br />

response to Fichte’s revisionism. 9 Both Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin, I shall<br />

argue, adopted positions that are best seen as espousing an essentially<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>ian agnosticism about <strong>the</strong> ability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human self to know <strong>the</strong><br />

ultimate ground <strong>of</strong> its own unity. 10<br />

In <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Doctrine <strong>of</strong> Virtue’’ <strong>Kant</strong> claims that ‘‘Only <strong>the</strong> descent into <strong>the</strong><br />

hell <strong>of</strong> self-knowledge can pave <strong>the</strong> way to godliness’’ 11 :‘‘Erforsche, ergründe<br />

dich selbst!’’ (‘‘Explore, fathom yourself!’’). The self-knowledge that <strong>Kant</strong> is<br />

speaking <strong>of</strong> here is self-cognition (Selbsterkenntnis), but in this context it is<br />

not, or not simply, a <strong>the</strong>oretical knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self that <strong>Kant</strong> is prescribing.<br />

It is ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> sort <strong>of</strong> knowledge that would answer <strong>the</strong> questions:<br />

‘‘What am I, by nature?’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘What do I really want?’’ ‘‘What is really<br />

9 Charles Larmore, in ‘‘Hölderlin <strong>and</strong> Novalis,’’ also points out that both <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se poet–<br />

philosophers were critical <strong>of</strong> Fichte’s account <strong>of</strong> self-knowledge <strong>and</strong> its original ground in an<br />

intellectual intuition, but stops short <strong>of</strong> labeling this a <strong>Kant</strong>ian insight. He sees <strong>the</strong> influence <strong>of</strong><br />

Niethammer at work on both philosophers, especially in <strong>the</strong>ir view <strong>of</strong> philosophical method as an<br />

unending task. This may be true, but it is also a very <strong>Kant</strong>ian notion <strong>of</strong> philosophy, as I have<br />

argued in chapter 1. Larmore sees <strong>Kant</strong>’s main contribution to early Romanticism to be via his<br />

moral <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ideal <strong>of</strong> freedom, by contrast with Schiller’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> ideal <strong>of</strong><br />

unity. <strong>Kant</strong>’s ultimately rigorist rejection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> feeling (‘‘Hölderlin <strong>and</strong> Novalis,’’ p. 143)<br />

sets up <strong>the</strong> tension that early Romantics addressed <strong>and</strong> attempted to ease. He does not consider<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective imagination, which this book argues constitutes an important<br />

conceptual connection between <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> early Romantics (in The Cambridge Companion to<br />

German Idealism, ed. Karl Ameriks, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000, pp. 141–160).<br />

Richard Eldridge, in The Persistence <strong>of</strong> Romanticism: Essays in Philosophy <strong>and</strong> Literature<br />

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), does see a conceptual continuity between<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s insistence on both <strong>the</strong> fact <strong>of</strong> human freedom <strong>and</strong> our inability to know it, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Romantic enactment <strong>of</strong> this ‘‘impossible aspiration to freedom’’ (p. 19). In ‘‘The <strong>Kant</strong>ian Moral<br />

Criticism <strong>of</strong> Literature,’’ he explicates <strong>Kant</strong>’s views <strong>of</strong> genius <strong>and</strong> moral hope by reference to<br />

literature in ways that are fully compatible with early Romantic accounts <strong>of</strong> bridging <strong>the</strong> gap<br />

between freedom <strong>and</strong> nature.<br />

10 As we saw in chapter 5, <strong>the</strong> classic discussion <strong>of</strong> this problem in <strong>Kant</strong>, worked out against<br />

Heidegger’s reading, is to be found in Dieter Henrich, ‘‘The Unity <strong>of</strong> Subjectivity,’’ first published<br />

in Philosophische Rundschau 3 (1955), pp. 28–69 as ‘‘Über die Einheit der Subjektivität’’ <strong>and</strong> trans.<br />

G. Zöller in Henrich, The Unity <strong>of</strong> Reason, ed. R. Velkley (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University<br />

Press, 1994), pp. 17–54.<br />

11 Immanuel <strong>Kant</strong>, The Metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Morals, trans. Mary J. Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1991), VI: 441.


Imaginative reflections in Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin 125<br />

motivating me?’’ These are <strong>the</strong> questions that for <strong>Kant</strong> are fundamental to<br />

<strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> becoming moral <strong>and</strong>, hence, fully human. Answering <strong>the</strong>m is<br />

<strong>the</strong> project that all human beings are obliged to set for <strong>the</strong>mselves. In this<br />

same passage, <strong>Kant</strong> says that all human wisdom (Weisheit) ultimately<br />

consists in <strong>the</strong> agreement <strong>of</strong> wants <strong>and</strong> desires with <strong>the</strong> human being’s final<br />

purpose, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> path to this final end requires descent into <strong>the</strong> murky<br />

depths <strong>of</strong> human nature <strong>and</strong> motivation. Human wisdom for <strong>Kant</strong><br />

involves both <strong>the</strong>oretical (including empirical) <strong>and</strong> practical knowledge:<br />

knowledge <strong>of</strong> what we are, <strong>and</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> what we should be. 12 Fichte’s<br />

revision <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian project <strong>of</strong> ‘‘fathoming’’ <strong>the</strong> self was an important<br />

driving force behind Hölderlin’s <strong>and</strong> Novalis’ philosophical conceptions <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> self. It is, <strong>the</strong>refore, important to sketch Fichte’s account <strong>of</strong> selfknowledge<br />

before going on to assess <strong>the</strong> link between <strong>the</strong> project as <strong>Kant</strong><br />

conceived it, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Romantic response to Fichte.<br />

fichte’s project<br />

Although <strong>Kant</strong> showed concern in <strong>the</strong> third Critique for bridging <strong>the</strong> gap<br />

between <strong>the</strong>oretical <strong>and</strong> practical reason in his own philosophy, he never<br />

rescinded <strong>the</strong> separate accounts <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se two sides <strong>of</strong> reason given in <strong>the</strong><br />

first two Critiques. His call for self-knowledge in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Doctrine <strong>of</strong> Virtue’’<br />

is intended as a call for individuals to come to know <strong>the</strong>mselves for <strong>the</strong><br />

purposes <strong>of</strong> a practical reason whose necessary systematic connection to<br />

<strong>the</strong>oretical reason has not been demonstrated. But Fichte, setting about to<br />

redeem <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian project for morality, was determined to give a unitary<br />

account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> underlying structure <strong>of</strong> all consciousness. Thus, what was<br />

for <strong>Kant</strong> a call to ‘‘know thyself’’ for <strong>the</strong> purposes <strong>of</strong> practical reason<br />

involved, for Fichte, giving an account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> very structure <strong>of</strong> all selfconsciousness.<br />

An important motivation for Fichte’s account was<br />

prompted by criticism <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> view attributed to <strong>Kant</strong> by Reinhold that all<br />

consciousness is representational. 13 On this view, self-consciousness is to be<br />

understood as a representing <strong>of</strong> ourselves to ourselves, <strong>and</strong> it <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

12 The distinction has a contemporary counterpart in Ernst Tugendhat’s distinction between<br />

Selbstbewußtsein <strong>and</strong> Selbstbestimmung. Cf. his Self-Consciousness <strong>and</strong> Self-Determination, trans.<br />

Paul Stern (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986), pp. 18–38.<br />

13 Cf. Neuhouser Fichte’s Theory, pp.70ff. Neuhouser characterizes <strong>the</strong> difficulty as an infinite regress <strong>of</strong><br />

knowing subjects. Also see Dieter Henrich ‘‘Fichte’s Original Insight’’ (in Contemporary German<br />

Philosophy, University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1982, pp. 15–53), where it is argued<br />

that ‘‘reflection <strong>the</strong>ory’’ was seen by Fichte to be untenable because it led to circularity <strong>and</strong> was<br />

question-begging. Fichte responded to <strong>the</strong> charges directed against Reinhold’s version <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

by G. E. Schulze in Aenesidemus, in a review published in 1794 (in Breazeale, Fichte, pp.59–77).


126<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

comes to be seen on <strong>the</strong> model <strong>of</strong> a subject examining an object, in this case<br />

itself. But this, so <strong>the</strong> criticism went, appears to involve a vicious regress <strong>of</strong><br />

subjects. That is, <strong>the</strong> representational account assumes that self-awareness<br />

requires that I view myself not only as <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> my examination but also<br />

as subject, as examiner. And <strong>the</strong> question arises: ‘‘What is <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> this<br />

examining subject?’’ At this point, <strong>the</strong> subject conducting <strong>the</strong> examination<br />

becomes <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> examination <strong>and</strong> so on ad infinitum. It follows,<br />

according to <strong>the</strong> criticism, that if we model self-awareness on our awareness<br />

<strong>of</strong> tables <strong>and</strong> chairs <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r objects in our world, an account <strong>of</strong> our own<br />

subjectivity is literally always just beyond reach.<br />

Whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>Kant</strong> himself held such a view, <strong>and</strong> whe<strong>the</strong>r a representational<br />

account must lead to vicious infinite regress may be questioned. What is<br />

important, however, is that Fichte took <strong>the</strong>se problems seriously. His<br />

response was to maintain, first <strong>of</strong> all, that self-consciousness is not a<br />

matter <strong>of</strong> representing <strong>the</strong> self to <strong>the</strong> self – it is not a case <strong>of</strong> consciousness<br />

<strong>of</strong> an object. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong> ‘‘I’’ <strong>of</strong> self-consciousness, what I discover when I<br />

examine my own consciousness, is an activity that is at <strong>the</strong> same time an<br />

accomplishment, eine Tath<strong>and</strong>lung. This ‘‘fact-act’’ 14 <strong>of</strong> immediate, nonrepresentational<br />

self-awareness, this intellectual intuition, is what Fichte<br />

calls ‘‘self-positing.’’ The subject capable <strong>of</strong> representational knowledge is<br />

not itself a representation but ra<strong>the</strong>r just is, in Fichte’s words ‘‘that act<br />

which does not <strong>and</strong> cannot appear among <strong>the</strong> empirical states <strong>of</strong> our<br />

consciousness, but ra<strong>the</strong>r lies at <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> all consciousness <strong>and</strong> alone<br />

makes it possible.’’ 15 The task <strong>of</strong> philosophy is to ‘‘reflect on what one<br />

might at first sight take it to be, <strong>and</strong> to abstract from everything that does<br />

not really belong to it.’’ 16<br />

The result <strong>of</strong> this process <strong>of</strong> reflection <strong>and</strong> abstraction is an account <strong>of</strong><br />

self-consciousness outlined by Fichte in three ‘‘principles.’’ First, <strong>the</strong> self<br />

posits itself absolutely, <strong>and</strong> this positing is its existence. 17 For Fichte, <strong>the</strong><br />

activity <strong>of</strong> self-positing does not produce an effect that is distinct from its<br />

activity. 18 Ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> self is to be understood as essentially identical with<br />

14<br />

This is Neuhouser’s rendering <strong>of</strong> Tath<strong>and</strong>lung, Fichte’s Theory, p.106.<br />

15<br />

Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge, ed. <strong>and</strong> trans. by Peter Heath <strong>and</strong> John Lachs (New York: Meredith, 1970),<br />

p. 93.<br />

16<br />

Heath <strong>and</strong> Lachs, Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge, ibid.<br />

17<br />

Heath <strong>and</strong> Lachs, Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge, p.98: The word ‘‘I’’ is to be understood as ‘‘<strong>the</strong> self as<br />

absolute subject. That whose being or essence consists simply in <strong>the</strong> fact that it posits itself as<br />

existing ... As it posits itself, so it is; <strong>and</strong> as it is, soitposits itself.’’<br />

18<br />

‘‘It is at once agent <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong> action; <strong>the</strong> active, <strong>and</strong> what <strong>the</strong> activity brings about; action<br />

<strong>and</strong> deed are one <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> same, <strong>and</strong> hence <strong>the</strong> ‘I am’ expresses an Act (Tath<strong>and</strong>lung)’’ (Heath <strong>and</strong><br />

Lachs, Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge, p.97).


Imaginative reflections in Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin 127<br />

this activity. Second ‘‘opposition in general is posited absolutely by <strong>the</strong><br />

self.’’ 19 This means that <strong>the</strong> self, in addition to positing itself posits ‘‘<strong>the</strong><br />

not-self ’’ that is opposed to itself. 20 Third, ‘‘Both self <strong>and</strong> not-self<br />

are posited as divisible.’’ Both self <strong>and</strong> not-self are posited as partial<br />

negations <strong>of</strong> each o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>the</strong>y are thus limited by each o<strong>the</strong>r, but not<br />

annihilated. These principles exhaust what can be accomplished by philosophical<br />

investigation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self, Fichte says. The outcome <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

investigation, in Fichte’s words, is that ‘‘In <strong>the</strong> self I oppose a divisible<br />

not-self to <strong>the</strong> divisible self.’’ 21 The first moment expresses an immediate<br />

consciousness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self, an intellectual intuition, a self-positing. The<br />

second <strong>and</strong> third occur as two aspects <strong>of</strong> one act: <strong>the</strong> act <strong>of</strong> division (or<br />

‘‘limitation’’) ‘‘occurs immediately, within <strong>and</strong> alongside <strong>the</strong> act <strong>of</strong><br />

opposition, both are one <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> same, <strong>and</strong> are distinguished only in<br />

reflection.’’ 22 For Fichte,<br />

The self is to be equated with, <strong>and</strong> yet opposed to, itself. It is all one consciousness,<br />

but a consciousness that involves an absolute self, on one h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

divisible limited self on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. 23<br />

This, in very rough outline, is how <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> self-consciousness stood<br />

with Fichte in Jena in 1795. Fichte’s own later revisions need not concern<br />

us here. Hölderlin attended Fichte’s lectures in <strong>the</strong> last months <strong>of</strong> 1794,<br />

<strong>and</strong> resumed attendance in <strong>the</strong> following January, during which time he<br />

‘‘engaged in a thorough <strong>and</strong> critical study <strong>of</strong> his [Fichte’s] philosophy.’’ 24<br />

During this time Hölderlin was hard at work on his novel Hyperion, <strong>and</strong><br />

also produced his only philosophical work, four essay-fragments including<br />

one implicitly critical <strong>of</strong> Fichte’s conception <strong>of</strong> absolute being,<br />

‘‘Urteil und Sein.’’ 25 At <strong>the</strong> same time (early in 1795) that Hölderlin was<br />

writing this piece, Novalis was preparing his Fichte-Studien, a large collection<br />

<strong>of</strong> observations <strong>and</strong> commentary that is, in <strong>the</strong> words <strong>of</strong> Manfred<br />

Frank, ‘‘<strong>the</strong> most important philosophical contribution <strong>of</strong> early<br />

Romanticism.’’ 26<br />

19<br />

Heath <strong>and</strong> Lachs, Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge, p.103.<br />

20<br />

Cf. Heath <strong>and</strong> Lachs, Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge, p.104.<br />

21<br />

Heath <strong>and</strong> Lachs, Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge, p.110.<br />

22<br />

Heath <strong>and</strong> Lachs, Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge, p.108.<br />

23<br />

Heath <strong>and</strong> Lachs, Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge, p.109.<br />

24<br />

David Constantine, Hölderlin (Oxford: Clarendon, 1988), p. 48.<br />

25<br />

See Henrich, Konstellationen, pp. 59–63, for a discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> dating <strong>of</strong> this important fragment<br />

(‘‘Judgment <strong>and</strong> Being’’), <strong>and</strong> for an argument that it dates from Hölderlin’s Jena period (1794–5).<br />

26<br />

Manfred Frank, Einführung in der Frühromantische Äs<strong>the</strong>tik: Vorlesungen (Frankfurt am Main:<br />

Suhrkamp, 1989), p. 248.


128<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

Central to both Hölderlin’s <strong>and</strong> Novalis’ reception <strong>of</strong> Fichte was<br />

dissatisfaction with Fichte’s claim that self-consciousness must be<br />

understood as originating in an act <strong>of</strong> self-positing, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

that is created <strong>and</strong> maintained by this act is not knowable reflectively via a<br />

representation, but is ra<strong>the</strong>r identified as an immediate consciousness, an<br />

‘‘intellectual intuition.’’ In o<strong>the</strong>r words, both took issue with Fichte’s<br />

‘‘First, Absolutely Unconditioned Principle.’’ As Manfred Frank points<br />

out, both Hölderlin <strong>and</strong> Novalis found <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> absolute selfpositing<br />

inadequate to <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> explaining a genuine unity <strong>of</strong><br />

subjectivity, since <strong>the</strong> very notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘self-positing itself’’ would seem<br />

to involve a fur<strong>the</strong>r reflexive act. That is, in Frank’s terms ‘‘immediacy<br />

<strong>and</strong> self-reference are incompatible notions.’’ 27 An account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

immediately present self cannot be a self-referential account. This disagreement<br />

led, in <strong>the</strong> works <strong>of</strong> Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin, to doubts about<br />

<strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> a unified account <strong>of</strong> subjectivity, <strong>and</strong> to challenges to<br />

Fichte’s attempt at such an account. I want now to examine each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se<br />

challenges in turn.<br />

Novalis<br />

In May 1795, Novalis spent an evening in Jena with Fichte <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin at <strong>the</strong><br />

house <strong>of</strong> Friedrich Niethammer, publisher <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> influential Philosophisches<br />

Journal. Niethammer noted in his diary that <strong>the</strong>y talked much about religion <strong>and</strong><br />

revelation <strong>and</strong> concluded that philosophy faced many unanswered questions. 28<br />

This meeting apparently convinced Novalis <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> need to come to terms<br />

with Fichte’s philosophy, a conviction which resulted in over 500<br />

manuscript pages <strong>of</strong> notes, his Fichte-Studien, begun during <strong>the</strong> fall <strong>of</strong><br />

1795 <strong>and</strong> finished <strong>the</strong> following summer. But although <strong>the</strong>se studies<br />

certainly do represent a kind <strong>of</strong> homage to <strong>the</strong> dynamic pr<strong>of</strong>essor, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

also contain a strong critique <strong>of</strong> a central aspect <strong>of</strong> Fichte’s work.<br />

Novalis’ problem with Fichte’s account <strong>of</strong> self-consciousness depends<br />

on <strong>the</strong> view that, in his words, ‘‘The I must posit itself as representing<br />

[darstellend].’’ 29 That is, in a very important sense, for Novalis, selfconsciousness<br />

must be representational. Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as self-consciousness is a<br />

reflection on consciousness, it involves thought, <strong>and</strong> thought can only<br />

grasp an object. But Fichte’s ‘‘I’’ is supposed to be non-representing, an<br />

original fact-act that can only be described as immediate consciousness, or<br />

27 28<br />

Frank, Einführung, p.250. John Neubauer, Novalis (Boston: Twayne, 1980), p. 22.<br />

29<br />

Fichte-Studien,inNovalis Schriften, ed. Paul Kluckhohn <strong>and</strong> Richard Samuel (Stuttgart: Verlag W.<br />

Kohlhammer, 1969), II: 282, # 633: ‘‘Das Ich muß sich, als darstellend setzen.’’


Imaginative reflections in Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin 129<br />

‘‘intellectual intuition.’’ In his discussion <strong>of</strong> Novalis, Frank argues that<br />

<strong>the</strong> very term ‘‘intellectual intuition’’ suggests that, whatever else it may<br />

be, this way <strong>of</strong> characterizing ‘‘absolute’’ unity cannot truly be absolute,<br />

because it involves two distinct components, one intuitive <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

intellectual or conceptual. So for Novalis, intellectual intuition is viewed<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r as a reflection that is directed toward an intuition, or what for<br />

Novalis is <strong>the</strong> same, a feeling. 30 Because it is only an attempt to reach an<br />

intuition (feeling) in thought, <strong>the</strong> best it can accomplish is still only a<br />

reflection <strong>of</strong> this intuition (feeling). But this is not identical to <strong>the</strong> feeling<br />

itself.<br />

With Fichte’s complex account <strong>of</strong> a unitary self-consciousness that<br />

contains a divided self in mind, Novalis speaks <strong>of</strong> ‘‘<strong>the</strong> famous struggle<br />

within <strong>the</strong> I.’’ 31 It is found already in <strong>the</strong> (allegedly) ‘‘absolute Urh<strong>and</strong>lung’’<br />

<strong>of</strong> self-positing, which is, Novalis argues, nothing more than a<br />

necessary deception <strong>of</strong> a mediated I that is attempting to be absolute –<br />

that is, unmediated – <strong>and</strong> thus comes into conflict with itself. Hence,<br />

what Fichte takes to be an immediate act <strong>of</strong> self-positing is in fact a<br />

mediated act. Manfred Frank takes Novalis’ metaphor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘mirror <strong>of</strong><br />

reflection’’ (Fichte Studies, #11) <strong>and</strong> his talk <strong>of</strong> reversal (#36) to heart <strong>and</strong><br />

explains <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory as an account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind’s attempt to grasp itself<br />

through an act <strong>of</strong> mirroring :<br />

‘‘Reflection’’ indeed, means mirroring, <strong>and</strong> all mirror images are laterally<br />

reversed. If I hold an object in front <strong>of</strong> a mirror, right is reflected to me as left<br />

<strong>and</strong> left as right. Also <strong>the</strong> light rays that approach <strong>the</strong> glass appear to move into<br />

<strong>the</strong> distance <strong>and</strong> head <strong>of</strong>f in <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r direction. Should it be any different with<br />

<strong>the</strong> reflection with which we recognize our self-consciousness? Novalis asks.<br />

This is an interesting counter to <strong>the</strong> interpretation <strong>of</strong> Romanticism made<br />

canonical by Meyer H. Abrams in The Mirror <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Lamp, wherein it is<br />

argued that <strong>the</strong> Romantic conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind is that <strong>of</strong> a lamp that<br />

shines upon <strong>and</strong> transforms its object. 32 In The Romantic Legacy, Charles<br />

Larmore balks at this reading <strong>of</strong> Romanticism for reasons similar to those<br />

I outlined in chapter 1 for Novalis’ definition <strong>of</strong> romanticizing. In Larmore’s<br />

view, <strong>the</strong> role played by <strong>the</strong> mind – or, more specifically, by <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination – is both reflective <strong>and</strong> transformative on <strong>the</strong> Romantic view.<br />

30 31<br />

Frank, Einführung, p.253. Fichte-Studien, II: 127, #32.<br />

32<br />

The Mirror <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Lamp (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1953). See also Abrams’ Natural<br />

Supernaturalism Tradition <strong>and</strong> Revolution in Romantic Literature (New York: W. W. Norton,<br />

1973), esp. chapter 7.2, ‘‘Freshness <strong>of</strong> Sensation,’’ where he points to Novalis’ notion <strong>of</strong> what<br />

Abrams calls ‘‘an unlocalized irradiation <strong>of</strong> consciousness <strong>and</strong> an inc<strong>and</strong>escent item <strong>of</strong> sense<br />

perception’’ (p. 387).


130<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

In his words, it has a ‘‘dual, creative-responsive function’’ that operates<br />

‘‘at one <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> same time.’’ 33 Although his argument is intended to hold<br />

for Romanticism generally, it is especially true <strong>of</strong> Novalis who, as we<br />

should recall, defined ‘‘romanticizing’’ as a two-pronged movement from<br />

<strong>the</strong> ordinary to <strong>the</strong> extraordinary (corresponding to Larmore’s ‘‘creative’’<br />

function) <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> same time from <strong>the</strong> extraordinary <strong>and</strong> mysterious to<br />

<strong>the</strong> ordinary (Larmore’s ‘‘responsive’’ function).<br />

Since <strong>the</strong> latter move is rarely attributed to Romanticism, Frank’s<br />

account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind as ‘‘mirroring’’ ourselves in Novalis is particularly<br />

insightful. For Novalis, he argues, we ‘‘see’’ self-intuition (‘‘Selbstgefühl ’’)<br />

reflected in <strong>the</strong> mirror <strong>of</strong> thought <strong>and</strong> conclude that we have reached it.<br />

But, in fact, we are fooled: We have only <strong>the</strong> ‘‘mirror image’’ <strong>of</strong> selfintuition,<br />

not that intuition itself. Like any mirroring, self-reflection<br />

presents us with an illusion <strong>of</strong> ourselves that, Novalis says, requires a<br />

second act <strong>of</strong> reflection if we are not to be misled into thinking we have<br />

attained objective knowledge <strong>of</strong> what is essentially non-objective. This<br />

second reflective act ‘‘corrects’’ <strong>the</strong> illusion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first act that we had <strong>of</strong><br />

ourselves, <strong>and</strong> shows us, not <strong>the</strong> self, but our ignorance <strong>of</strong> it. Novalis’<br />

romantic–philosophic conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self holds that we are incapable<br />

<strong>of</strong> grasping <strong>the</strong> absolute ground <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self. Since Novalis believes that<br />

‘‘striving after <strong>the</strong> thought <strong>of</strong> a ground is <strong>the</strong> ground <strong>of</strong> philosophy’’ <strong>and</strong><br />

‘‘all philosophizing must end in an absolute ground,’’ 34 this would seem<br />

to spell <strong>the</strong> end <strong>of</strong> all philosophizing, <strong>and</strong> for Novalis, in one sense this is<br />

true: ‘‘The borders <strong>of</strong> feeling are <strong>the</strong> borders <strong>of</strong> philosophy.’’<br />

But in ano<strong>the</strong>r sense, he argues, philosophy may recognize its own<br />

absolute when it recognizes that no absolute ground is given. Even in <strong>the</strong><br />

face <strong>of</strong> giving up <strong>the</strong> search for <strong>the</strong> absolute – or ra<strong>the</strong>r, precisely because<br />

<strong>of</strong> giving it up – <strong>the</strong> ‘‘drive to philosophize’’ can never be satisfied, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>re arises an ‘‘unending free activity.’’ This ‘‘unending free activity in<br />

us,’’ Novalis says, is ‘‘<strong>the</strong> only possible absolute that can be given us.’’ 35<br />

Thus philosophy can only ever provide a negative account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self: The<br />

drive to unify feeling <strong>and</strong> thought is <strong>the</strong> only unifying characteristic <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

self. 36 But since this negative characteristic is indeed one aspect <strong>of</strong> our<br />

nature, it is at least not a falsified account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human self. Where<br />

philosophy must stop, however, poetry may begin.<br />

There is no definitive answer to whe<strong>the</strong>r or not Novalis believed that<br />

poetry could do what philosophy could not – that is, unveil <strong>the</strong> absolute,<br />

33<br />

Charles Larmore, The Romantic Legacy (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), pp. 21, 31.<br />

34<br />

Fichte-Studien, II: 269, #566.<br />

35<br />

Ibid.<br />

36<br />

Cf. Fichte-Studien, II: 126–127, #32.


Imaginative reflections in Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin 131<br />

<strong>and</strong> portray its very essence. 37 It seems unlikely that he intended to<br />

accomplish so much in his own work. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, Novalis’ poetic achievement<br />

is his ability to portray artistically what he believed followed from<br />

his views on <strong>the</strong> essentially negative nature <strong>of</strong> self-consciousness. That is,<br />

his literary work is not an ‘‘unveiling’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolute, but ra<strong>the</strong>r an<br />

attempt to do ‘‘poetic philosophy’’ 38 – to underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> self <strong>and</strong> its<br />

world not in abstractions but by romanticizing <strong>the</strong>m. ‘‘Romanticizing’’<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘‘Romantic philosophy,’’ on Novalis’ definition, is <strong>the</strong> ‘‘operation’’ <strong>of</strong><br />

portraying <strong>the</strong> unexpected, <strong>of</strong> ‘‘interrupting’’ ordinary life by ‘‘potentializing’’<br />

<strong>the</strong> objects <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world, showing <strong>the</strong>m not for what <strong>the</strong>y are but<br />

for what <strong>the</strong>y are not – what <strong>the</strong>y are only potentially. On this approach,<br />

<strong>the</strong> ordinary is always seen in <strong>the</strong> light <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘unending’’ <strong>and</strong>, by <strong>the</strong><br />

same token, <strong>the</strong> unknown, mysterious, <strong>and</strong> unending, are portrayed as<br />

ordinary. 39 Such a world is a ‘‘Verkehrung,’’ an inversion, but it is also a<br />

setting right, just as <strong>the</strong> second reflection <strong>of</strong> self-consciousness sets right<br />

<strong>the</strong> illusion <strong>of</strong> self-recognition.<br />

‘‘Die Welt muß romantisirt werden,’’ ‘‘The world must be romanticized,’’<br />

says Novalis. 40 Romanticizing, because it portrays what is merely<br />

potential, <strong>and</strong> hence in effect portrays what it is not, is an illusion or<br />

inversion that sets right <strong>the</strong> original illusion <strong>of</strong> being at home in <strong>the</strong><br />

world.<br />

Heinrich von Ofterdingen, with its simple straightforward narrative style<br />

used to depict a free-floating, kaleidoscopic set <strong>of</strong> illusion, dream, <strong>and</strong><br />

symbols, is a perfect example <strong>of</strong> Novalis’ doctrine <strong>of</strong> corrective inversion.<br />

Perhaps because it is quite literally a model <strong>of</strong> Novalis’ idea <strong>of</strong> romantic<br />

philosophizing, <strong>and</strong> hence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory in practice, <strong>the</strong> secondary literature<br />

on this novel is voluminous. 41 Here I will simply suggest how Heinrich,<br />

<strong>the</strong> protagonist <strong>of</strong> this piece, can be said to ‘‘figure’’ Novalis’ conception<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self. Heinrich is no ordinary protagonist, in spite <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that he<br />

is indeed <strong>the</strong> central figure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> novel. Heinrich’s ‘‘development’’ is<br />

almost entirely an internal, subjective one, <strong>and</strong> he is passive to <strong>the</strong> point<br />

<strong>of</strong> near absence in many <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> chapters. Much, if not most, <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> action<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> novel does not involve him – or, perhaps it is better to say, it<br />

involves him only as <strong>the</strong> blank screen on which <strong>the</strong> fables, allegories, <strong>and</strong><br />

magical images that constitute <strong>the</strong> bulk <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> work are played out.<br />

37<br />

Cf. Herbert Uerlings, Friedrich von Hardenberg, genannt Novalis: Werk und Forschung (Stuttgart:<br />

Metzler, 1991), p. 118.<br />

38 39<br />

Ibid. Cf. Frank, Einführung, pp. 272ff., <strong>and</strong> Fichte-Studien, II: 545, #105.<br />

40 41<br />

Fichte-Studien, ibid. See Uerlings, Friedrich von Hardenberg, pp. 389ff.


132<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

Indeed, Heinrich has practically no ‘‘psychological pr<strong>of</strong>ile’’ – he is<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r a world unto himself in which dream, fantasy, <strong>and</strong> reality blur – or,<br />

better, in which it makes no difference which is which. Heinrich is a<br />

vessel whose only anchor, if it can even be called that, is his own passive<br />

subjectivity. But if Novalis’ Heinrich is a romanticized, unanchored, <strong>and</strong><br />

even alienated self-consciousness compared to <strong>the</strong> full-blooded <strong>and</strong><br />

many-faceted character one comes to expect in novels, still Heinrich’s is a<br />

‘‘pleasantly’’ alienated self-consciousness. 42<br />

It includes occasional<br />

moments <strong>of</strong> ecstatic feeling that occur most <strong>of</strong>ten in dreams, or in love,<br />

when <strong>the</strong> self (not always Heinrich) recognizes something ‘‘unending’’ in<br />

itself. These moments, for Novalis, are <strong>the</strong> result <strong>of</strong> a reinversion <strong>of</strong> our<br />

inverted sense <strong>of</strong> self <strong>and</strong> as such <strong>the</strong>y are moments (‘‘Augenblick’’ )<strong>of</strong><br />

insight into <strong>the</strong> absolute. The self, in <strong>the</strong>se felicitous moments <strong>of</strong><br />

‘‘renunciation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Absolute,’’ when it recognizes its own inability to<br />

attain transcendence through reflection, produces in itself<br />

<strong>the</strong> unending free activity ... <strong>the</strong> only possible absolute that can be given to us,<br />

<strong>and</strong> which we find only through our inability to attain <strong>and</strong> to recognize an<br />

Absolute. 43<br />

This pleasurable negative experience <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolute bears little resemblance<br />

to Fichte’s original Tath<strong>and</strong>lung. It does, however very closely<br />

resemble <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian sublime:<br />

For what is sublime in <strong>the</strong> proper meaning <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> term, cannot be contained in<br />

any sensible form but concerns only ideas <strong>of</strong> reason, which though <strong>the</strong>y cannot be<br />

exhibited (dargestellt) adequately, are aroused <strong>and</strong> call to mind this very inadequacy,<br />

which can be exhibited in sensibility. 44<br />

A little fur<strong>the</strong>r on, <strong>Kant</strong> emphasizes that <strong>the</strong> sublime is an experience <strong>of</strong><br />

what is absolutely great in us. Our inability to represent to ourselves <strong>the</strong><br />

absolutely great outside us is <strong>the</strong> condition <strong>of</strong> this recognition:<br />

Yet this inadequacy is <strong>the</strong> arousal in us <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> feeling that we have within us a<br />

supersensible power, <strong>and</strong> what is absolutely great is not an object <strong>of</strong> sense, but is<br />

<strong>the</strong> use that judgment makes naturally <strong>of</strong> a certain object so as to [arouse] this<br />

(feeling). 45<br />

One might say that Novalis’ Ofterdingen is full <strong>of</strong> just <strong>the</strong>se sorts <strong>of</strong><br />

‘‘negative’’ epiphanies – momentarily transcendent experiences that<br />

amount to ‘‘sublimations’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self.<br />

42<br />

III: 685–688: ‘‘Die Kunst, auf eine angenehme Weise zu befremden, einen Gegenst<strong>and</strong> fremd zu<br />

machen und doch bekannt und anziehend, das ist die romantische Poetik.’’<br />

43 44<br />

Fichte-Studien, II: 269, #566. Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, p.245 (emphasis added).<br />

45<br />

Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, V:250.


Imaginative reflections in Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin 133<br />

hölderlin<br />

At <strong>the</strong> time <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir meeting at Niethammer’s home, Hölderlin was on<br />

<strong>the</strong> verge <strong>of</strong> departure from Jena, had already attended Fichte’s lectures in<br />

<strong>the</strong> Winter semester, <strong>and</strong> had almost certainly already developed his<br />

influential critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter in <strong>the</strong> fragment ‘‘Judgment <strong>and</strong> Being.’’<br />

Hölderlin came to his study <strong>of</strong> Fichte immersed in questions <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tics<br />

from his recent engagement with <strong>Kant</strong>’s third Critique <strong>and</strong> Plato’s<br />

Phaedrus, <strong>and</strong> Schiller’s ‘‘Über Anmuth und Würde.’’ 46 In one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

philosophical fragments dating from this time, he is concerned to account<br />

for <strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong> ‘‘necessity <strong>and</strong> freedom, <strong>the</strong> restricted <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> unrestricted,<br />

<strong>the</strong> sensuous <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> sacred’’ in <strong>the</strong> faculty <strong>of</strong> desire. 47 Here he<br />

speaks longingly <strong>of</strong> a ‘‘morality <strong>of</strong> instinct’’ that resembles a kind <strong>of</strong><br />

intellectual intuition, an attunement <strong>of</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> desire that<br />

naturally conforms to <strong>the</strong> moral law, uncoerced. But, he also admits, such<br />

‘‘attunement would <strong>the</strong>n be merely contingent, a matter <strong>of</strong> fortune.’’ The<br />

longed-for unity, though possible contingently, is for that very reason<br />

unfit for systemic development. At least at this period in his philosophical<br />

development, Hölderlin seems at once driven by what Henrich called<br />

‘‘Vereinigungsphilosophie’’ <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong> same time by skeptical doubts about<br />

its possibility.<br />

Doubts about <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> a systematic account <strong>of</strong> a ‘‘morality <strong>of</strong><br />

instinct’’ underlie Hölderlin’s disagreement with Fichte. But <strong>the</strong>se doubts<br />

must be seen in light <strong>of</strong> his explication <strong>of</strong> ‘‘Being’’ in <strong>the</strong> fragmentary<br />

essay ‘‘Judgment <strong>and</strong> Being’’:<br />

Being – expresses <strong>the</strong> connection between subject <strong>and</strong> object. Where subject <strong>and</strong><br />

object are united altoge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> not only in part, that is, united in such a manner<br />

that no separation can be performed without violating <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> what is to<br />

be separated, <strong>the</strong>re <strong>and</strong> nowhere else can be spoken <strong>of</strong> Being proper, as is <strong>the</strong> case<br />

with intellectual intuition. 48<br />

From this, it follows that Fichte’s account <strong>of</strong> intellectual intuition must<br />

be incorrect, because it refers not to a primordial, essentially indivisible<br />

consciousness <strong>of</strong> Being, but only to a self-positing activity that involves an<br />

act <strong>of</strong> opposition <strong>and</strong> reunification through a concept <strong>of</strong> limitation or<br />

divisibility. 49 The unity <strong>of</strong> Fichte’s is thus, for Hölderlin, a derivative<br />

unity: an identity, but not an absolute unity.<br />

46<br />

Cf. Friedrich Hölderlin, Essays <strong>and</strong> Letters on Theory, trans. Thomas Pfau (Albany: State University<br />

<strong>of</strong> New York Press, 1988), p. 11, <strong>and</strong> Haym, Die Romantische Schule, pp. 301–302.<br />

47<br />

‘‘On <strong>the</strong> Law <strong>of</strong> Freedom,’’ in Hölderlin, Essays, pp. 33–34.<br />

48 49<br />

Hölderlin, Essays, p.37. Cf. Heath <strong>and</strong> Lachs, Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge, p.110.


134<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

The fact that Fichte did not intend to suggest this sort <strong>of</strong> ‘‘primordial<br />

coherence’’ 50 is <strong>of</strong> less importance here than is <strong>the</strong> fact that Hölderlin felt<br />

that such primordial coherence was necessary to ground <strong>the</strong> conception <strong>of</strong><br />

a unified self, <strong>and</strong> that without it <strong>the</strong> self was, quite literally, lost. Given<br />

such constraints on what can count as an integrated self, 51 it is no surprise<br />

that for Hölderlin it is not clear that <strong>the</strong> self can ever come to know itself.<br />

To <strong>the</strong> extent that self-knowledge is possible, it must involve that which<br />

‘‘antedates any structure <strong>of</strong> syn<strong>the</strong>sis, identity <strong>and</strong> consciousness.’’ 52 That<br />

means, for Hölderlin, that self-knowledge must be aes<strong>the</strong>tic. Influenced<br />

by his reading <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> beauty, <strong>and</strong> by his friendships with<br />

Schiller <strong>and</strong> Schelling, Hölderlin developed a ‘‘doctrine <strong>of</strong> beauty’’ that<br />

made <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong> unifying principle <strong>of</strong> human experience. Beauty,<br />

for Hölderlin, is <strong>the</strong> ideal – <strong>the</strong> visible model <strong>of</strong> perfected humanity. In<br />

<strong>the</strong> Hyperion he speaks <strong>of</strong> ‘‘beings <strong>of</strong> beauty, or what is <strong>the</strong> same thing,<br />

human beings.’’ 53 Beauty bespeaks <strong>the</strong> divinity in <strong>the</strong> human being: ‘‘The<br />

human being is a god as soon as he is human. And once he is a god, he is<br />

beautiful.’’ 54 For Hölderlin, <strong>the</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> beautiful is <strong>the</strong> only<br />

integrating experience for <strong>the</strong> self at odds with itself.<br />

This doctrine does not set Hölderlin apart from Schiller or Schelling.<br />

What is distinctive to Hölderlin is his emphasis on <strong>the</strong> attainment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

beautiful being only a contingent matter, depending as it does on nature<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> degree <strong>of</strong> sensitivity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> individual:<br />

Beauty forsakes <strong>the</strong> life <strong>of</strong> men, flees upward into Spirit; <strong>the</strong> Ideal becomes what<br />

Nature was ... By this, by <strong>the</strong> Ideal, this rejuvenated divinity, <strong>the</strong> few recognize<br />

one ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> are one.’’ 55<br />

Unity <strong>of</strong> subjectivity is not granted everyone, by any means. The ‘‘few’’ <strong>of</strong><br />

whom Hölderlin speaks here, <strong>of</strong> course, are artists – <strong>the</strong>y are <strong>the</strong> most<br />

deeply sensitive <strong>of</strong> souls. ‘‘The first child <strong>of</strong> divine beauty is art.’’ 56 And<br />

though in Hyperion <strong>the</strong> hope is expressed that <strong>the</strong>se few great souls will<br />

inaugurate a ‘‘second age,’’ this utopian enthusiasm is edged throughout<br />

50<br />

Hölderlin, Essays, pp. 20ff.<br />

51<br />

This aspect <strong>of</strong> Hölderlin’s thought, Henrich points out, probably owes much to his ‘‘projection <strong>of</strong><br />

Spinoza onto <strong>the</strong> Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge’’ (Konstellationen, p.74).<br />

52<br />

Hölderlin, Essays, p.26.<br />

53<br />

Friedrich Hölderlin, Hyperion or <strong>the</strong> Hermit in Greece, trans. W. R. Trask (New York: Ungar,<br />

1965), p. 90.<br />

54 55<br />

Hyperion, p.91. Hyperion, p.76.<br />

56<br />

Hyperion, p.91.


Imaginative reflections in Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin 135<br />

with a sense <strong>of</strong> disillusionment. In a remarkable chapter early in <strong>the</strong><br />

novel, Hyperion writes to Bellarmin, ‘‘What is man?’’:<br />

How does it happen that <strong>the</strong> world contains such a thing, which ferments like a<br />

chaos or moulders like a rotten tree, <strong>and</strong> never grows to ripeness? ... To <strong>the</strong><br />

plants he says: I, too, was once like you! And to <strong>the</strong> pure stars: I shall become like<br />

you in ano<strong>the</strong>r world! – meanwhile he falls to pieces <strong>and</strong> keeps practicing his arts<br />

on himself, as if, once it had come apart, he could put a living thing toge<strong>the</strong>r<br />

again like a piece <strong>of</strong> masonry ... yet what he does will always be artifice. 57<br />

Even <strong>the</strong> artistic self – or, ra<strong>the</strong>r, especially <strong>the</strong> artistic self, who has ‘‘feasted<br />

at <strong>the</strong> table <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> gods’’ <strong>and</strong> felt ‘‘full, pure beauty’’ must face <strong>the</strong> inescapable<br />

fact <strong>of</strong> its own fragmented condition. The poet is bound to be<br />

disillusioned, Hyperion tells his friends, because, having known <strong>the</strong> feeling<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> beautiful, that which is thought is revealed to be disharmonious, full<br />

<strong>of</strong> contradiction <strong>and</strong> imperfection. Beauty is never thought. 58<br />

Hölderlin did not see beauty as a consolation, nor, like Novalis, as<br />

something to be attained in moments <strong>of</strong> poetic exaltation; a gift that,<br />

when received lends a feeling <strong>of</strong> coherence to <strong>the</strong> self, redeeming it in<br />

moments <strong>of</strong> poetic magic: ‘‘Overall [<strong>the</strong> poet] must accustom himself not<br />

to try to attain within individual moments <strong>the</strong> totality that he strives for<br />

<strong>and</strong> to bear <strong>the</strong> momentarily incomplete.’’ 59 For Hölderlin, unlike<br />

Novalis, <strong>the</strong> poetic can never be a purely pleasant alienation because it<br />

rests on feeling, <strong>and</strong> feeling is suffering as well as pleasure. Indeed, in <strong>the</strong><br />

novel, <strong>the</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> suffering seems to be assigned to Hyperion, if not<br />

as a duty, <strong>the</strong>n as a matter <strong>of</strong> necessity for his romantic spirit. In <strong>the</strong><br />

second part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> novel, Hyperion asks his correspondent: ‘‘Why do I<br />

recount my grief to you, renew it ... ?’’ 60<br />

The entire novel is a narrative <strong>of</strong> alternating suffering <strong>and</strong> rejoicing, an<br />

attempt to portray <strong>the</strong> depths <strong>and</strong> heights that human feeling can attain.<br />

Feeling, Hölderlin says, is <strong>the</strong> poet’s ‘‘bridle <strong>and</strong> spur.’’ 61 Thus it is<br />

tempting to conclude that feeling is what redeems <strong>the</strong> self, for Hölderlin,<br />

<strong>and</strong> that even if <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic is not always a consolation to <strong>the</strong> divided self<br />

it may still, in a more heroic sense, save it. But this, too, would fail to<br />

capture Hölderlin’s stance. Although elevated, intense feeling may give<br />

<strong>the</strong> artistic spirit glimpses <strong>of</strong> absolute Being, it is ultimately unable to<br />

unify <strong>the</strong> individual self, <strong>and</strong> in this very important sense cannot be<br />

57 58<br />

Hyperion, p.57. Cf. Hyperion, p.93.<br />

59<br />

‘‘Reflection,’’ in Hölderlin, Essays, p.46<br />

61<br />

‘‘Reflection,’’ in Hölderlin, Essays, p.45.<br />

60 Hyperion, p.114.


136<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

redemptive. In his sketch ‘‘The Ground for ‘Empedocles,’’’ he says <strong>of</strong> his<br />

hero’s fate:<br />

In order to organize life, he had to strive seizing it with his being at its innermost;<br />

with his spirit he had to try to master <strong>the</strong> human element, all tendencies <strong>and</strong><br />

drives, <strong>the</strong>ir soul, <strong>the</strong> inconceivable, <strong>the</strong> unconscious, <strong>the</strong> involuntary in <strong>the</strong>m;<br />

precisely in so far as his will, his consciousness, his spirit, transcended <strong>the</strong> ordinary<br />

<strong>and</strong> human boundaries <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> effectiveness, it had to lose itself <strong>and</strong><br />

become objective ... <strong>the</strong> objective resounded <strong>the</strong> more purely <strong>and</strong> deeply within<br />

him <strong>the</strong> more open his soul lay, precisely because <strong>the</strong> spiritually active man had<br />

given himself away, <strong>and</strong> this in <strong>the</strong> particular as well as in <strong>the</strong> universal. 62<br />

The experience <strong>of</strong> unified consciousness, in those rare moments when it<br />

occurs, for Hölderlin is also tragic because it forces <strong>the</strong> individual to <strong>the</strong><br />

universal, <strong>and</strong> hence beyond what <strong>the</strong> individual can ever be. To paraphrase<br />

Cassirer, <strong>the</strong> vessel through which <strong>the</strong> self announces itself must,<br />

because it is singular <strong>and</strong> limited, itself be broken. 63 Unified consciousness<br />

is also <strong>the</strong> death <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> individual. If Hölderlin’s project is <strong>the</strong> quest<br />

for such unity, <strong>the</strong>n its success would appear to be <strong>the</strong> death <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self.<br />

One feels this in <strong>the</strong> protagonist Hyperion, who in <strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

entire novel never becomes a fully fledged character. He is a heroic<br />

struggling ‘‘figure’’ but never an integrated personality. The only<br />

redemption may lie, for Hölderlin, in <strong>the</strong> poetic process itself. Here at<br />

least, <strong>the</strong> artist may create, in Eric L. Santner’s words, ‘‘<strong>the</strong> possibilities <strong>of</strong><br />

new modes <strong>of</strong> discoursing <strong>and</strong> being, new modes <strong>of</strong> fortifying <strong>the</strong> self for<br />

its dialog with <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r.’’ 64<br />

conclusion<br />

Almost as if he had Hölderlin <strong>and</strong> Novalis in mind (in fact, he was <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

thinking <strong>of</strong> Klopstock), <strong>Kant</strong> proclaimed time <strong>and</strong> again <strong>the</strong> dangers <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> novel, <strong>the</strong> Roman. Too much <strong>of</strong> this sort <strong>of</strong> reading, he warns, loosens<br />

one’s grip on reality, <strong>and</strong> leads to fantasizing, which is closely related to<br />

enthusiasm <strong>and</strong> even madness. As we have already seen, <strong>Kant</strong> advocated a<br />

guarded attitude towards ‘‘empty <strong>and</strong> fanciful desires, which are <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

nourished by novels <strong>and</strong> sometimes also by mystical presentations, similar<br />

62 ‘‘The Ground for ‘Empedocles,’ ’’ in Thomas Pfau, Friedrich Hölderlin: Essays <strong>and</strong> Letters on<br />

Theory (Albany: State University <strong>of</strong> New York Press, 1988), p. 60.<br />

63 Cf. Ernst Cassirer, ‘‘Hölderlin und der deutsche Idealismus,’’ in Hölderlin: Beiträge zu seinem<br />

Verständnis in unserm Jahrhundert, Alfred Kelletat, ed. (Tübingen: Mohr, 1961), p. 115.<br />

64 Eric L. Santner, Introduction to Friedrich Hölderlin: Hyperion <strong>and</strong> Selected Poems (New York:<br />

Continuum, 1990), pp. xxxv–xxxvi. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer at Cambridge University<br />

Press for suggesting this way <strong>of</strong> interpreting Hölderlin’s project in a less dismal light.


to novels, or superhuman perfections <strong>and</strong> fanatical bliss.’’ 65 But <strong>the</strong>n,<br />

almost as if he knew <strong>the</strong>re would be no holding back <strong>the</strong> Romantic quest<br />

for a unified consciousness, he added <strong>the</strong> claim already examined in<br />

chapter 5 – namely, that it is important ‘‘to investigate why it is that<br />

nature has given us <strong>the</strong> predisposition to such fruitless expenditure <strong>of</strong> our<br />

forces as [we see in] empty wishes <strong>and</strong> longings (which certainly play a<br />

large role in human life).’’ His hypo<strong>the</strong>sis was that if we had to be sure<br />

that attaining an object was within our power before we let ourselves<br />

desire it, many powers we in fact have would remain unused. Thus,<br />

nature wisely provides us with desires that call forth great effort ‘‘even<br />

before we know what ability we have, <strong>and</strong> it is <strong>of</strong>ten precisely this effort,<br />

which to that very mind seems at first an empty wish, that produces<br />

that ability in <strong>the</strong> first place.’’ It is wise to be on guard, but equally<br />

wise to recognize that nature’s provisions should be respected, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

concludes.<br />

It is natural to conclude from this that ‘‘wisdom’’ will desire what<br />

Novalis would later call <strong>the</strong> ‘‘drive to be an ‘I.’ ’’ 66 Since <strong>Kant</strong> believed, as<br />

we saw at <strong>the</strong> outset, that wisdom also requires that we fathom ourselves,<br />

it is a very good thing for him that we also have <strong>the</strong> drive to do so. The<br />

works <strong>of</strong> both Hölderlin <strong>and</strong> Novalis embody this tendency to strive for<br />

what is not, to overstep, ‘‘in a fruitless expenditure <strong>of</strong> forces,’’ <strong>the</strong> bounds<br />

<strong>of</strong> what may be reasonably desired. Hence, for this very reason <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

Romantic contributions appear to be a step along <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian path to<br />

self-knowledge, <strong>and</strong> a natural <strong>and</strong> important continuation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian<br />

project.<br />

These poet-philosophers may be seen as following <strong>the</strong> injunction to<br />

fathom <strong>the</strong> self, to determine what <strong>the</strong> self is not, but could be, in order<br />

to fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian project <strong>of</strong> determining what <strong>the</strong> self should be. But<br />

as <strong>Kant</strong> was acutely aware, this drive to self-knowledge has its costs.<br />

Hölderlin’s <strong>and</strong> Novalis’ Romanticism holds out <strong>the</strong> promise <strong>of</strong> discovering<br />

new forms <strong>of</strong> consciousness, <strong>and</strong> hence <strong>of</strong> ‘‘refiguring’’ <strong>the</strong> self,<br />

but where it is not suitably tempered by a sense <strong>of</strong> its own limitations it<br />

risks <strong>the</strong> erasure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> very ‘‘self’’ it attempts to fathom. Novalis’ insistence<br />

on <strong>the</strong> momentary nature <strong>of</strong> imaginative epiphanies, <strong>and</strong> on <strong>the</strong><br />

corresponding recognition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ordinary, was one approach to <strong>the</strong><br />

problem that vexed <strong>Kant</strong>. In <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> Hölderlin, <strong>the</strong> solution was to be<br />

65 Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, p.420.<br />

Imaginative reflections in Novalis <strong>and</strong> Hölderlin 137<br />

66 Fichte-Studien, II: 126–127, #32.


138<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

found in art, in his case in <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong> poetry. It was a solution that<br />

depended on artistic genius, <strong>and</strong> as his own final tragedy suggests, was<br />

only partially successful. In <strong>the</strong> concluding chapter 7 we shall examine <strong>the</strong><br />

degree to which Novalis’ <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s views on imaginative genius converge<br />

<strong>and</strong> finally gesture towards a new underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> philosophy itself<br />

in early German Romanticism.


chapter 7<br />

Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism<br />

Doch das Paradies is verriegelt und der Cherub hinter uns; wir<br />

müssen die Reise um die Welt machen, und sehen, ob es vielleicht<br />

von hinten irgendwo wieder <strong>of</strong>fen ist.<br />

(Kleist, ‘‘Über das Marionetten Theater’’ (On <strong>the</strong> Marionette Theater))<br />

(Paradise is barred <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> cherub behind us; we must travel around <strong>the</strong><br />

world, <strong>and</strong> see if maybe somewhere it is open again from <strong>the</strong> back.) 1<br />

Kleist summed up <strong>the</strong> mix <strong>of</strong> awe <strong>and</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ound disappointment that<br />

many intellectuals in <strong>the</strong> 1780s <strong>and</strong> 1790s must have felt in <strong>the</strong> wake <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy. For although in it human cognitive activity takes on<br />

new constitutive powers that define <strong>the</strong> boundaries <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> real, <strong>the</strong> cost <strong>of</strong><br />

shifting this constitutive power to human subjectivity was high: loss <strong>of</strong><br />

access to a world beyond appearances. In spite <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s claim to have<br />

made ‘‘room for faith,’’ knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world <strong>of</strong> things ‘‘in <strong>the</strong>mselves’’<br />

was barred, so it seemed, once <strong>and</strong> for all. In his fictional essay ‘‘On <strong>the</strong><br />

Marionette Theater,’’ Kleist frames <strong>the</strong> philosophical problem <strong>of</strong><br />

knowledge as a problem within <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> performance art. His<br />

narrator interviews a renowned dancer who aims to move with absolute<br />

grace across <strong>the</strong> floor, freely <strong>and</strong> without alienation, but recognizes that<br />

<strong>the</strong> impossibility <strong>of</strong> achieving his goal is rooted in self-consciousness. The<br />

great dancer tells Kleist’s narrator that <strong>the</strong> artist should look to <strong>the</strong><br />

marionette as a model <strong>of</strong> unselfconscious expression <strong>of</strong> absolute, unalienated<br />

movement.<br />

The dancer’s remarks are, <strong>of</strong> course, a metaphor for human striving<br />

after that which is beyond <strong>the</strong> pale <strong>of</strong> possible human experience: absolute<br />

knowledge <strong>and</strong> perfect self-expression. Kleist’s essay captures <strong>the</strong> problem<br />

that seemed almost without exception to plague philosophers in <strong>the</strong><br />

immediate wake <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s relativization <strong>of</strong> knowledge to <strong>the</strong> human<br />

capacity for it. Kleist is not typically classified as a Romantic, but his call<br />

1 Heinrich von Kleist: Werke in einem B<strong>and</strong> (Munich: Karl Hanser Verlag, 1966), pp. 802–807.<br />

139


140<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

for a ‘‘back-door’’ strategy is characteristic <strong>of</strong> much <strong>of</strong> Early German<br />

Romanticism, <strong>and</strong> describes <strong>the</strong> major project <strong>of</strong> this movement’s most<br />

fascinating figure, Friedrich von Hardenberg, known as Novalis. <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

philosophy was a fact <strong>of</strong> life for Novalis <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> philosophers <strong>and</strong> poets <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> famous Jena circle. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Copernican’’ paradigm in philosophy<br />

was so well entrenched that in his encyclopedic ‘‘Allgemeine Brouillon’’<br />

Novalis could speak <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Copernican turn as established fact:<br />

Here <strong>Kant</strong> played <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> Copernicus <strong>and</strong> explained <strong>the</strong> empirical I along<br />

with its outer world as a planet, <strong>and</strong> placed <strong>the</strong> moral law or <strong>the</strong> moral I at <strong>the</strong><br />

center <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> system – <strong>and</strong> Fichte has become <strong>the</strong> Newton – <strong>the</strong> second<br />

Copernicus – <strong>the</strong> inventor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> laws <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> system <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> inner world (III: 335). 2<br />

Novalis was as convinced as was <strong>Kant</strong> that <strong>the</strong> latter’s new philosophy <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> subject had dissolved past errors in philosophy once <strong>and</strong> for all. Along<br />

with most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> intellectuals <strong>of</strong> his circle, Novalis ab<strong>and</strong>oned <strong>the</strong><br />

vaulting structures <strong>of</strong> Leibnizian <strong>and</strong> Wolffian rationalism for shelter in<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian alternative account <strong>of</strong> what <strong>the</strong> human mind can know. <strong>Kant</strong><br />

himself recognized that human beings would forever be tempted to strive<br />

after <strong>the</strong> absolute, or ‘‘unconditioned,’’ but in <strong>the</strong> end his tendency was to<br />

be ra<strong>the</strong>r sanguine about <strong>the</strong> fact that everyday cognition, science, <strong>and</strong><br />

even ethics, would have to do without final metaphysical answers. At <strong>the</strong><br />

same time, as we saw in chapter 5, this great purveyor <strong>of</strong> rationalist<br />

humanism betrayed a fondness, even sympathy for metaphysical fantasizing<br />

that has been almost wholly ignored by commentators on his<br />

work. 3 In <strong>the</strong> last section <strong>of</strong> this chapter I shall return to <strong>Kant</strong> to examine<br />

<strong>the</strong> place that metaphysical speculation retains in his system, <strong>and</strong> to<br />

conclude <strong>the</strong> argument <strong>of</strong> this book for <strong>the</strong> continuity between his system<br />

<strong>and</strong> early German Romanticism.<br />

It has become a cliché that German idealism with its pyrotechnical<br />

metaphysics jettisoned <strong>Kant</strong>ian limits on knowledge. Early German<br />

Romanticism is typically cast in this same unflattering role, with <strong>the</strong><br />

additional <strong>of</strong>fense <strong>of</strong> ‘‘irrationalism <strong>and</strong> mysticism’’ added to <strong>the</strong><br />

indictment. In fact, however, many if not all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> early German<br />

Romantics associated with <strong>the</strong> Jena circle renounced metaphysical<br />

2 All references to Novalis’ works are to Novalis Schriften: Die Werke Friedrich von Hardenbergs eds.<br />

Paul Kluckhohn <strong>and</strong> Richard Samuel (Stuttgart: Verlag W. Kohlhammer, 1965). The second <strong>and</strong><br />

third volumes, ed. Richard Samuel toge<strong>the</strong>r with Hans-Joachim Mähl <strong>and</strong> Gerhard Schulz, contain<br />

Novalis’ philosophical writings, published in 1981 <strong>and</strong> 1983, respectively.<br />

3 <strong>Kant</strong> was not always comfortable with this attitude; throughout his life he was fascinated by<br />

apparently ‘‘supernatural’’ phenomena. See Hartmut Böhme <strong>and</strong> Gernot Böhme’s Das Andere der<br />

Vernunft (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1996), <strong>and</strong> chapter 5 <strong>of</strong> this book.


Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism 141<br />

knowledge claims <strong>and</strong> speculative thinking in harsher terms than did<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> himself. 4 No one better exemplifies this strict adherence to <strong>the</strong><br />

Copernican turn than does Novalis, whose philosophical efforts culminate<br />

in <strong>the</strong> elevation <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> practice <strong>of</strong> art as <strong>the</strong> embodiment<br />

<strong>of</strong> human freedom. I will begin, <strong>the</strong>n, with a look at <strong>the</strong><br />

surprisingly modest metaphysical underpinnings <strong>of</strong> this great Romantic<br />

poet <strong>and</strong> philosopher. In so doing I hope to exonerate Novalis, <strong>and</strong> by<br />

extension <strong>the</strong> early German Romantic circle, <strong>of</strong> charges <strong>of</strong> metaphysical<br />

excess <strong>and</strong> irrationalism. In <strong>the</strong> second part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> chapter I look at <strong>the</strong><br />

consequences <strong>of</strong> Novalis’ views for an account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> ordinary<br />

cognition.<br />

novalis’ kantianism<br />

As we saw in chapter 6, in1795–96 Novalis undertook a serious study <strong>of</strong><br />

Fichte’s Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge (Wissenschaftslehre) after having met Fichte,<br />

along with Hölderlin, in <strong>the</strong> home <strong>of</strong> a mutual friend in Jena. The set <strong>of</strong><br />

notes on Fichte which comprised <strong>the</strong> bulk <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> large h<strong>and</strong>written<br />

manuscript produced by Novalis has been called ‘‘<strong>the</strong> most significant<br />

philosophical work <strong>of</strong> early Romanticism.’’ 5 In it, Novalis comes to grips<br />

with <strong>the</strong> early philosophy <strong>of</strong> this thinker who had claimed ascendancy to<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s throne in German philosophy. There is no doubt that Fichte’s<br />

philosophy was <strong>of</strong> great importance to Novalis, yet what emerges in <strong>the</strong><br />

Fichte Studies is not a student’s reworking <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> master’s ideas, but ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

a persistent criticism <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fundamental assumption <strong>of</strong> Fichte’s major<br />

work. Whereas Fichte had argued that <strong>the</strong> inner world <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self may be<br />

accessed initially via an intellectual intuition <strong>of</strong> self-activity, in his Fichte<br />

Studies Novalis repeatedly insists that no immediate knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

self, as it is in itself, is possible. Chapter 6 discussed Novalis’ metaphor <strong>of</strong><br />

mirroring as an account <strong>of</strong> human self-knowledge, but he also argues that<br />

self-observation is a kind <strong>of</strong> ‘‘eavesdropping on <strong>the</strong> self’’ in order to learn<br />

about it. By ‘‘learning,’’ he says,<br />

4 In this book I deal only with Novalis <strong>and</strong> his circle <strong>of</strong> early German Romantics. The later<br />

Romantics, especially those associated with Heidelberg, but even including Schlegel <strong>and</strong> Tieck in<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir later period are not under discussion here.<br />

5 Manfred Frank, in Einführung in die Frühromantische Äs<strong>the</strong>tik (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp,<br />

1989), p. 248. Novalis’ work, which included <strong>the</strong> so-called ‘‘Fichte Studies’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong> Studies’’<br />

comprised about 500 pages <strong>of</strong> h<strong>and</strong>written notes that were left unpublished until 1901, when Ernst<br />

Heilborn brought out a substantial selection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> notes. The entire set, however, remained<br />

unpublished <strong>and</strong> was lost to scholarship for thirty years between 1930 <strong>and</strong> 1960, when it resurfaced<br />

at an auction in New York.


142<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

we mean absolutely nothing but intuiting an object <strong>and</strong> impressing it along with<br />

its characteristics upon ourselves. It [<strong>the</strong> self] would thus become an object again.<br />

No, philosophy cannot be self-observation, because it would not <strong>the</strong>n be what<br />

we are after [i.e., it would not be immediately known as subject: JK]. It is<br />

perhaps self-feeling. What <strong>the</strong>n is feeling? ... It can only be observed in<br />

reflection – <strong>the</strong> spirit <strong>of</strong> feeling is <strong>the</strong>n gone. The producer can be inferred from<br />

<strong>the</strong> product in accordance with <strong>the</strong> schema <strong>of</strong> reflection.(II: 113–114, #15)<br />

Novalis goes on to argue that since feeling cannot represent itself, <strong>and</strong><br />

reflection can only represent feeling in thought, our intuition <strong>of</strong> our Self is<br />

never <strong>of</strong> a thing as it is ‘‘in itself.’’ It is necessarily always mediated or<br />

‘‘inferred,’’ a syn<strong>the</strong>tic product <strong>of</strong> feeling <strong>and</strong> reflection (II: 114, #16).<br />

Novalis may have honored Fichte with <strong>the</strong> title <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘second Copernicus,’’<br />

but this did not prevent his rejecting <strong>the</strong> Fichtean central assumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> inner world <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self, namely that <strong>the</strong> ‘‘absolute’’ self can be known.<br />

Not only does Novalis reject claims <strong>of</strong> access to <strong>the</strong> ‘‘absolute I,’’ his<br />

‘‘positive’’ account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self resembles <strong>Kant</strong>’s notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> noumenal, or<br />

thing in itself, as a limiting notion. As von Molnár points out, Novalis<br />

typically refers to <strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘I’’ as a regulative one: 6<br />

I – has, perhaps, like all ideas <strong>of</strong> reason merely regulative, classificatory use –<br />

Nothing at all in relation to reality. (II: 258, #502)<br />

Referring to Fichte’s notion <strong>of</strong> a Tath<strong>and</strong>lung, <strong>the</strong> originary intuitive act<br />

<strong>of</strong> positing <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self, Novalis says,<br />

Every state, every fact-act [Tath<strong>and</strong>lung] presupposes an o<strong>the</strong>r ... all quest for a<br />

First [genus] is nonsense – it is a regulative idea. (II: 254, #472)<br />

Novalis’ reaction to Fichte places limitations on <strong>the</strong> power <strong>and</strong> reach <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> intellect that are essentially <strong>Kant</strong>ian in spirit. Especially as a student <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> natural sciences, Novalis was critical <strong>of</strong> metaphysical speculation, <strong>and</strong><br />

as we saw in chapter 1, he insisted that although a ‘‘tendency to seek <strong>the</strong><br />

universal’’ [Universaltendenz] is essential to <strong>the</strong> scholar,<br />

One must never, like a phantast, seek <strong>the</strong> undetermined – a child <strong>of</strong> fantasy – an<br />

ideal. One proceeds from determinate task to determinate task. An unknown<br />

lover <strong>of</strong> course has a magical charm. Striving for <strong>the</strong> unknown, <strong>the</strong> undetermined,<br />

is extremely dangerous <strong>and</strong> disadvantageous. Revelation must not<br />

be forced. (III: 601, #291)<br />

Given <strong>the</strong>se strong views on <strong>the</strong> unknowability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self as it is in itself,<br />

it is not surprising that Novalis’ intense study <strong>of</strong> Fichte led him back<br />

6 Geza von Molnár argues for this point in Novalis’ ‘‘Fichte Studies’’: The Foundations <strong>of</strong> His Aes<strong>the</strong>tics<br />

(The Hague: Mouton, 1970), pp. 41–42.


Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism 143<br />

again to a study <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>. The very short collection <strong>of</strong> notes <strong>and</strong> commentary<br />

now collected under <strong>the</strong> title <strong>the</strong> ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong> Studien’’ (1797) was<br />

found toge<strong>the</strong>r with a group <strong>of</strong> notes on <strong>the</strong> Dutch philosopher Hemsterhuis<br />

(1721–90). 7 Probably his renewed interest in <strong>Kant</strong>’s views on <strong>the</strong><br />

natural sciences was piqued by Hemsterhuis’ frequent reference to <strong>the</strong><br />

Metaphysical Foundations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Natural Sciences in Hemsterhuis’<br />

‘‘Metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Nature,’’ but given his abrupt turn away from Fichtean<br />

idealism it is likely that he turned to <strong>Kant</strong>’s works to support his<br />

developing views on <strong>the</strong> limits <strong>of</strong> philosophizing about metaphysical<br />

matters. 8<br />

However, a set <strong>of</strong> very brief notes in this collection suggests that it<br />

could also have been ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>Kant</strong>ian text, <strong>and</strong> a far more obscure one,<br />

that may have provided Novalis with impetus for <strong>the</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r development<br />

<strong>of</strong> his philosophy as well as his artistic enterprise. Amidst <strong>the</strong> notes<br />

on <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy were also found notes on <strong>Kant</strong>’s reply to Samuel<br />

Thomas Sömmerring, a well-known medical doctor <strong>and</strong> physiologist<br />

from Frankfurt. Sömmerring’s book ‘‘Über das Organ der Seele’’ raised<br />

<strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘seat <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul [der Sitz der Seele],’’ or <strong>the</strong> location <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> mind in <strong>the</strong> body. The book was published with a short appendix<br />

written by <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> sent to Sömmerring specifically for <strong>the</strong> book: 9<br />

If I am supposed to make <strong>the</strong> place <strong>of</strong> my soul, that is, <strong>of</strong> my absolute self,<br />

intuitable somewhere in space, <strong>the</strong>n I must perceive myself through that very<br />

same [spatial intuition] through which I also perceive <strong>the</strong> matter right around<br />

me ... Now <strong>the</strong> soul can only perceive via inner sense, but <strong>the</strong> body (whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

internal or outer) can only perceive through outer sense; hence it can determine<br />

absolutely no place for itself, because in order to do this it would make itself <strong>the</strong><br />

object <strong>of</strong> its own outer intuition <strong>and</strong> would have to transpose [versetzen] itself<br />

outside itself – which is a contradiction. So <strong>the</strong> desired solution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> seat <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul which is dem<strong>and</strong>ed <strong>of</strong> metaphysics leads into an impossible<br />

dimension ...; <strong>and</strong> one can, with Terence, call to those who would undertake<br />

it: ‘‘You wouldn’t succeed any more than if you were to try to be rationally<br />

insane’’ [‘‘Nihilo plus agas, quam si des opera ut cum ratione insanias’’]. (<strong>Kant</strong>, letter<br />

to Sömmerring, 1796)<br />

7<br />

See Hans-Joachim Mähl’s introduction to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Eschenmeyer Studies, Novalis Schriften II:<br />

334. According to Mähl, based on <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>writing <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> type <strong>and</strong> format <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> paper, <strong>the</strong>se<br />

notes <strong>and</strong> commentary were probably written during or immediately following his work on<br />

Hemsterhuis, <strong>and</strong> within a year after finishing <strong>the</strong> Fichte Studies in 1796.<br />

8<br />

Mähl, p. 332. The fact that his focus <strong>of</strong> study seems to have been primarily <strong>the</strong> Preface <strong>and</strong><br />

Introduction to <strong>the</strong> first Critique as well as <strong>the</strong> Metaphysical Foundations <strong>of</strong> Natural Science also<br />

supports this view.<br />

9<br />

See <strong>the</strong> letter to Sömmerring dated August 10, 1795, <strong>Kant</strong>s gesammelte Schriften, Prussian Academy<br />

edition, XII.3: 30–35.


144<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

To Sömmerring’s question, <strong>Kant</strong> replies that <strong>the</strong> spatial location [der Ort]<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul, where ‘‘soul’’ is understood as ‘‘my absolute self’’ would have<br />

to be perceived in <strong>the</strong> same way we perceive matter around us, namely<br />

through outer sense (this includes our physical ‘‘insides’’ as well). But <strong>the</strong><br />

absolute self can perceive itself only through inner sense, non-spatially,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore cannot determine a spatial place for itself. For <strong>the</strong> soul to<br />

make itself <strong>the</strong> object <strong>of</strong> its own outer intuition would mean that it would<br />

have to set [versetzen] its non-spatial being ‘‘outside’’ itself in space – <strong>and</strong><br />

that is a contradiction, <strong>Kant</strong> says. The dem<strong>and</strong> that metaphysics solve <strong>the</strong><br />

problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> seat <strong>of</strong> consciousness leads it into incoherence, <strong>Kant</strong><br />

continues, <strong>and</strong> he admonishes would-be metaphysical speculators with a<br />

quotation from Terence, <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> which involves advice to a<br />

spurned lover to give up on <strong>the</strong> idea <strong>of</strong> winning <strong>the</strong> heartless object <strong>of</strong> his<br />

desire through reasoning.<br />

The question <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘seat’’ <strong>of</strong> consciousness raised by Sömmerring, as<br />

well as an apparent dissatisfaction with <strong>Kant</strong>’s deflationary response,<br />

might well be explained by Novalis’ strong emphasis on <strong>the</strong> importance<br />

<strong>of</strong> feeling as a central aspect <strong>of</strong> self-knowledge. Although Novalis makes<br />

no independent comment in his notes on <strong>the</strong> Sömmerring passage, later<br />

in his notes on <strong>the</strong> first Critique <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘seat’’ <strong>of</strong> consciousness<br />

is addressed obliquely:<br />

The concept <strong>of</strong> sense. According to <strong>Kant</strong>, pure ma<strong>the</strong>matics <strong>and</strong> pure natural<br />

science refer to <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong> outer sensibility – What science refers to <strong>the</strong> form <strong>of</strong><br />

inner sensibility? Is <strong>the</strong>re yet extra-sensible knowledge? Is <strong>the</strong>re still ano<strong>the</strong>r way<br />

open for getting outside oneself <strong>and</strong> to get to o<strong>the</strong>rs, or to be affected by <strong>the</strong>m?<br />

(II: 46)<br />

This getting ‘‘outside ourselves’’ is in all probability a reference to <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

claim in <strong>the</strong> reply to Sömmerring, that <strong>the</strong> self cannot without contradiction<br />

be said to set itself outside itself. Later, in his well-known work Pollen<br />

[Blütenstaub], Novalis picks up this thought in <strong>the</strong> following fragment:<br />

The seat <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul is <strong>the</strong>re, where <strong>the</strong> inner world <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> outer world touch<br />

[sich berühren]. Where <strong>the</strong>y permeate – it is in every point <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> permeating.<br />

(Novalis, II: 418, #20)<br />

The ‘‘inner world’’ is <strong>the</strong> world that Fichte tries to elucidate by recourse<br />

to intellectual intuition <strong>of</strong> an original act <strong>of</strong> self-consciousness, an<br />

account that, as we saw, Novalis rejected on <strong>Kant</strong>ian grounds. 10 At <strong>the</strong><br />

10 Although Novalis appeared to believe that some sort <strong>of</strong> phenomenology, a science <strong>of</strong> inner sense, is<br />

possible. As we saw, he also took Fichte to be <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Newton’’ <strong>of</strong> this science. See Allgemeine<br />

Brouillon, Novalis Schriften, III: 335 (#460).


Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism 145<br />

same time, Novalis is unhappy with <strong>Kant</strong>’s refusal to countenance any<br />

possibility for ‘‘externalizing’’ <strong>the</strong> inner world <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self. What Novalis<br />

seems to suggest here is a third option involving <strong>the</strong> redefining <strong>of</strong> selfconsciousness<br />

as <strong>the</strong> interface between <strong>the</strong> inner world <strong>of</strong> self-feeling <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> outer world <strong>of</strong> objective self-consciousness. This redefinition, he<br />

suggests, might also involve a way <strong>of</strong> reaching o<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>and</strong> in turn being<br />

affected by <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

Novalis’ insistence on <strong>the</strong> centrality <strong>of</strong> feeling to self-consciousness <strong>and</strong><br />

hence to philosophy in general was very likely due in part to <strong>the</strong> influence<br />

<strong>of</strong> Hemsterhuis’ philosophy. The latter’s emphasis on desire, feeling, <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> poesy in underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> sciences must have<br />

appealed greatly to <strong>the</strong> poet. 11 A strong commitment to <strong>the</strong> importance <strong>of</strong><br />

feeling to knowledge certainly helps explain <strong>the</strong> following exasperated<br />

comment in <strong>the</strong> midst <strong>of</strong> Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong> Studies:<br />

The whole <strong>Kant</strong>ian method – <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>Kant</strong>ian way <strong>of</strong> philosophizing is onesided.<br />

And it could with some justice be called Scholasticism. (II: 392 #50) 12<br />

In ano<strong>the</strong>r fragmentary note just prior to his pondering <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong><br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r way <strong>of</strong> getting ‘‘outside ourselves,’’ Novalis suggests that <strong>the</strong><br />

practice <strong>of</strong> philosophy itself, <strong>and</strong> practical reason, must move into a new,<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic dimension:<br />

Philosophizing is just scientizing [wissenschaften], thinking through thought,<br />

knowing knowledge – treating <strong>the</strong> sciences scientifically <strong>and</strong> poetically. Should <strong>the</strong><br />

practical <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> poetic be one – <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> latter simply signifies absolute practice<br />

made specific? (II: 390, #45)<br />

Now, whatever it would mean to find ano<strong>the</strong>r way, an extra-sensible<br />

knowledge, for Novalis, cannot involve ab<strong>and</strong>oning <strong>the</strong> real world or<br />

embracing some noumenal thing in itself as known:<br />

Everything absolute must be ostracized from <strong>the</strong> world. In <strong>the</strong> world one must<br />

live with <strong>the</strong> world. 13<br />

11 Cf. Mähl’s introduction, II: 314ff.<br />

12 The reference to <strong>Kant</strong>’s scholasticism also appears in <strong>Kant</strong>’s ‘‘Open letter on Fichte’s<br />

Wissenschaftslehre,’’ where <strong>Kant</strong> quotes from Fichte’s earlier correspondence with him. <strong>Kant</strong> had<br />

written to Fichte that he (Fichte) would do better to devote his energies to applying <strong>the</strong> teachings<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason ra<strong>the</strong>r than attempting to rewrite <strong>the</strong>m. Fichte’s reply ‘‘politely’’<br />

assures <strong>Kant</strong> that he will not ‘‘make light <strong>of</strong> scholasticism.’’ See Arnulf Zweig, <strong>Kant</strong>: Philosophical<br />

Correspondence – 1759–99 (Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1967) (XII: 370–371).<br />

13 This is taken from <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Fragmentblatt’’ found along with <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> notes (Schriften, II: 395, #55).<br />

It follows a remarkable passage in which Novalis suggests, presumably in opposition to Fichte’s<br />

notion <strong>of</strong> an originary self-postulation or Tath<strong>and</strong>lung, that ‘‘<strong>the</strong> true philosophical act is<br />

suicide ... only this act corresponds to all <strong>the</strong> conditions <strong>and</strong> characteristics <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> transcendental<br />

act’’ – i.e., we can’t bring ourselves into being, but we can take ourselves out.


146<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

Beneath all Novalis’ comments <strong>and</strong> criticisms <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>, his underlying<br />

metaphysical assumption remains <strong>Kant</strong>ian: <strong>the</strong> unknowability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

thing-in-itself is no longer up for debate. In fact, he makes <strong>the</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

condescending claim that <strong>Kant</strong>’s belaboring <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> issue can appear too<br />

obvious, ‘‘superfluous <strong>and</strong> wearisome’’ to thinkers <strong>of</strong> Novalis’ generation,<br />

unless <strong>the</strong>y keep in mind <strong>the</strong> historical context within which <strong>Kant</strong><br />

worked. 14 <strong>Kant</strong>’s anti-speculation doctrine had become ‘‘scholasticism’’<br />

for Novalis <strong>and</strong> his cohort. So when Novalis speaks <strong>of</strong> discovering an<br />

extra-sensible knowledge, he is by no means taking issue with <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

circumscription <strong>of</strong> cognitive experience. For Novalis, finding a way to get<br />

‘‘outside’’ ourselves is not a matter <strong>of</strong> conflating <strong>the</strong> spheres <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cognitive<br />

<strong>and</strong> moral self that <strong>Kant</strong> had so carefully separated. 15 The path<br />

outside <strong>the</strong> self is an altoge<strong>the</strong>r different approach, <strong>and</strong> is already<br />

becoming apparent to <strong>the</strong> young philosopher–poet as he finishes <strong>the</strong><br />

Fichte Studies <strong>and</strong> works on <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Hemsterhuis. It is <strong>the</strong> path <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

artist, <strong>and</strong> requires making concrete <strong>and</strong> tangible in art that inner world<br />

based on immediate self-feeling that is impossible to capture purely<br />

reflectively. Novalis’ ‘‘o<strong>the</strong>r way’’ <strong>of</strong> locating <strong>the</strong> seat <strong>of</strong> consciousness in<br />

<strong>the</strong> world is through its embodiment in art.<br />

I suggest that what Novalis finds lacking in <strong>Kant</strong> is not metaphysical,<br />

but imaginative commitment. As we saw in chapter 5, <strong>Kant</strong> was deeply<br />

ambivalent about <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> attempts to realize ideals<br />

through it. The transposition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self that Novalis seeks <strong>and</strong> fails to<br />

find in <strong>Kant</strong>’s one-sided approach is, for Novalis, an imaginative transformation.<br />

Novalis’ impatience with <strong>Kant</strong> appears to stem from his view<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong> fails to see <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> poeticizing <strong>the</strong> world – or, as he<br />

would soon come to say – <strong>of</strong> ‘‘romanticizing’’ it, as discussed in chapter 1:<br />

The world must be romanticized. In this way one rediscovers <strong>the</strong> original<br />

meaning. Romanticizing is nothing but a qualitative raising to a higher power<br />

[Potenzirung]. The lower self becomes identified with a better self. Just as we<br />

ourselves are such a qualitative exponential series. This operation is still quite<br />

unknown. Ins<strong>of</strong>ar as I give <strong>the</strong> commonplace a higher meaning, <strong>the</strong> ordinary a<br />

mysterious countenance, <strong>the</strong> known <strong>the</strong> dignity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unknown, <strong>the</strong> finite an<br />

appearance <strong>of</strong> infinity, I romanticize it. The operation is precisely <strong>the</strong> opposite<br />

for <strong>the</strong> higher, unknown, mystical <strong>and</strong> infinite – <strong>the</strong>se are logarithmized by this<br />

14 ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>-Studien,’’ II: 392, #49.<br />

15 See Fichte Studies #649: ‘‘we are also in a sphere outside time’’ – Novalis retains <strong>Kant</strong>’s view that<br />

to be human means to be able to ‘‘transport’’ oneself into a realm <strong>of</strong> intellect.


Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism 147<br />

connection – <strong>the</strong>y become common expressions. Romantic philosophy. Lingua<br />

romana. Alternating elevation <strong>and</strong> lowering. 16<br />

This activity was, for Novalis, something <strong>Kant</strong> failed to <strong>the</strong>orize in his<br />

‘‘one-sided’’ attempt to explain human knowledge in terms <strong>of</strong> ‘‘pure<br />

reason.’’ Novalis did not reject <strong>Kant</strong>’s most pr<strong>of</strong>ound insights, but ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

complemented <strong>and</strong> tried to complete <strong>the</strong> Critical turn through his notion<br />

<strong>of</strong> romanticizing. In this sense, Novalis saw himself as opposing <strong>Kant</strong>,<br />

who could certainly come <strong>of</strong>f as an old Scholastic in <strong>the</strong> mind <strong>of</strong> a<br />

twenty-four-year-old poet, by wanting to give free rein to <strong>the</strong> imagination<br />

as a vehicle for externalizing <strong>and</strong> hence realizing what could only be felt.<br />

<strong>Imagination</strong>, Novalis believed, would produce poetry that would be literally<br />

<strong>the</strong> embodiment <strong>and</strong> external vehicle for taking <strong>the</strong> self where it<br />

needed to be – outside itself <strong>and</strong> into <strong>the</strong> world. Therein lay Novalis’<br />

philosophical solution to Kleist’s <strong>Kant</strong>-induced dilemma: The key to <strong>the</strong><br />

back door to paradise would be aes<strong>the</strong>tic.<br />

I have argued that Novalis’ position in no way betrays <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

‘‘Copernican’’ revolution <strong>and</strong> does not embrace a metaphysical noumenal.<br />

Novalis is not an idealist in this sense. But <strong>the</strong> view that art is a<br />

supersession <strong>of</strong> philosophy appears to lend credence to ano<strong>the</strong>r common<br />

criticism <strong>of</strong> Romanticism – namely, that it embraces irrationalism <strong>and</strong><br />

mysticism. Yet this, too, is an unfair characterization <strong>of</strong> Novalis’ own<br />

views. To see why, it is important to begin with Novalis’ characterization<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> philosophy itself.<br />

Given Novalis’ views on <strong>the</strong> regulative nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘I’’ <strong>and</strong> his<br />

renunciation <strong>of</strong> an ‘‘absolute’’ in any but a negative sense, one might<br />

expect him to read <strong>Kant</strong>’s letter to Sömmerring with approval. However,<br />

as we just saw, <strong>the</strong> ‘‘seat <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul’’ discussion appears to have sent<br />

him in ano<strong>the</strong>r direction, one that marks a departure from <strong>Kant</strong>’s views<br />

on self-knowledge. Novalis’ philosophical account <strong>of</strong> self-knowledge<br />

depends crucially on <strong>the</strong> view that our ‘‘inner’’ sense <strong>of</strong> ourself – selffeeling<br />

– is absolute <strong>and</strong> immediate, but that our knowledge <strong>of</strong> it, being<br />

reflective, is never absolute <strong>and</strong> immediate. For Novalis, <strong>the</strong> intellectual<br />

intuition that Fichte postulated as <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> knowledge is replaced by<br />

what could be called ‘‘reflected self-feeling.’’ Novalis argues that thinking<br />

about our self-feeling does not give us direct access to this immediate selfexperience,<br />

but it does gesture in <strong>the</strong> right direction, reminding us <strong>of</strong> it in<br />

an image: ‘‘Consciousness is an image <strong>of</strong> being within being’’ (II: 106, #2).<br />

As Manfred Frank puts it, for Novalis, reflected self-feeling becomes<br />

16 2: 545, #105.


148<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

<strong>the</strong> ‘‘orientation towards, or better, <strong>the</strong> longing for, <strong>the</strong> absolute.’’ 17 In <strong>the</strong><br />

Fichte Studies, this longing is taken by Novalis to be <strong>the</strong> very heart <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophy, or ra<strong>the</strong>r philosophizing – <strong>the</strong> ‘‘unique kind <strong>of</strong> thinking’’<br />

that is <strong>the</strong> activity <strong>of</strong> doing philosophy. We should recall Novalis’ own<br />

account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> activity <strong>of</strong> philosophizing:<br />

What do I do when I philosophize? I reflect upon a ground. The ground <strong>of</strong><br />

philosophizing is thus a striving after <strong>the</strong> thought <strong>of</strong> a ground ... All philosophizing<br />

must <strong>the</strong>refore end in an absolute ground. Now if this were not given, if<br />

this concept contained an impossibility – <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> drive to philosophize would<br />

be an unending activity ... Unending free activity in us arises through <strong>the</strong> free<br />

renunciation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolute – <strong>the</strong> only possible absolute that can be given us <strong>and</strong><br />

that we can only find through our inability to attain <strong>and</strong> know an absolute. This<br />

absolute that is given to us can only be known negatively, ins<strong>of</strong>ar as we act <strong>and</strong><br />

find that what we seek cannot be attained through action. ( II: 269, #566)<br />

Novalis’ view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> activity <strong>of</strong> philosophy is that it involves a conscious<br />

recognition that it ‘‘absolutely’’ cannot attain its goal. But he also suggests<br />

that human consciousness cannot ultimately live with this paradoxical<br />

situation. Towards <strong>the</strong> very end <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Fichte Studies he calls for a free<br />

creative response to <strong>the</strong> limitations philosophy recognizes in reason:<br />

Objects must not do violence to us – They must not hem us in, not determine<br />

[bestimmen] beyond <strong>the</strong> borders ... We must seek to create an inner world that is<br />

an actual pendant to <strong>the</strong> outer world – that ins<strong>of</strong>ar as it is in direct opposition to<br />

[<strong>the</strong> outer world] at every point, constantly increases our freedom ... All<br />

determinations proceed outward from us – we create a world out <strong>of</strong> ourselves<br />

... The more we determine, <strong>the</strong> more we lay out what is in us – <strong>the</strong> freer –<br />

more substantial – we become – we set aside, as it were, more <strong>and</strong> more that<br />

which is inessential <strong>and</strong> approach <strong>the</strong> thoroughly pure, simple essence <strong>of</strong> our I.<br />

Our creative power gets as much free play as it has world under it. But since our<br />

nature, or <strong>the</strong> fullness <strong>of</strong> our being, is unending, we can never reach this goal in<br />

time – But since we are also in a sphere outside time, we must reach it <strong>the</strong>re in<br />

every moment, or better, if we want, in this sphere we are able to be pure simple<br />

substance. Here is morality <strong>and</strong> peace <strong>of</strong> mind, because an endless striving after<br />

what hovers ever out <strong>of</strong> reach before us seems unbearable. (II: 287–288, #647)<br />

These musings recall <strong>Kant</strong>’s view that <strong>the</strong> human being has a higher<br />

vocation, a ‘‘st<strong>and</strong>point’’ in an intellectual realm where it is possible at<br />

any time to transport oneself. 18 But whereas <strong>Kant</strong> says that we can only<br />

think ourselves into this world, or at best postulate <strong>the</strong> time <strong>and</strong> power to<br />

create it, Novalis argues that <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination can create a<br />

17 Cf. Frank, Einführung, p.253.<br />

18 E.g. in <strong>the</strong> Groundwork <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Morals, IV: 452ff.


Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism 149<br />

‘‘sphere outside time.’’ Moreover, he claims that it is in this imaginative<br />

world that we first ‘‘approach <strong>the</strong> ... pure simple essence <strong>of</strong> our ‘I’.’’ The<br />

passage is cryptic, leaving <strong>the</strong> reader to speculate fur<strong>the</strong>r on <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong><br />

this world. But Novalis’ notes seem to suggest a kind <strong>of</strong> moral oppositional<br />

consciousness – a utopian vision – a world <strong>of</strong> what ought to be as<br />

opposed to what is. It is ‘‘unreal’’ <strong>and</strong> unattainable, but we never<strong>the</strong>less<br />

can dwell in it because we are its imaginative architects. It is a sphere to be<br />

accessed ‘‘in every moment’’ precisely because it is ‘‘outside’’ time <strong>and</strong><br />

place, in our imagination.<br />

Two points need to be made about this matter <strong>of</strong> ‘‘world-making’’ in<br />

Novalis. First, it is not a mystical or transcendent account. Novalis is<br />

quite clear that <strong>the</strong> ‘‘inner’’ imaginative world is a ‘‘pendant’’ to <strong>the</strong> outer.<br />

It is oppositional <strong>and</strong> for that very reason dependent upon <strong>the</strong> world <strong>of</strong><br />

objects, as any part depends on its counterpart. There is thus nothing<br />

ineffable about it. In Pollen, he writes:<br />

It is <strong>the</strong> most arbitrary prejudice that it is denied to human beings to be able to<br />

be outside <strong>the</strong>mselves, to have consciousness beyond <strong>the</strong> senses. Humans may at<br />

any moment be supersensible beings. Without this ability <strong>the</strong>y could not be<br />

citizens <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world, <strong>the</strong>y would be animals. Of course <strong>the</strong> composure <strong>and</strong> selfdiscovery<br />

in this state is very difficult since it is so perpetually, so necessarily,<br />

bound up in <strong>the</strong> alternation <strong>of</strong> our o<strong>the</strong>r states. The more we are able to become<br />

conscious <strong>of</strong> this state, <strong>the</strong> livelier, more powerful <strong>and</strong> enjoyable is <strong>the</strong> conviction<br />

that arises from it; <strong>the</strong> belief in genuine spiritual revelation. (II : 421, #22)<br />

Novalis goes on to describe this ‘‘appearance’’ as a kind <strong>of</strong> emergent<br />

experience rooted in ordinary life, <strong>the</strong> ‘‘inc<strong>and</strong>escence’’ referred to by<br />

Abrams in his account <strong>of</strong> ‘‘moments’’ in Romanticism: 19 Novalis claims:<br />

It is not a sight, a sound or feeling; it is all three toge<strong>the</strong>r, more than all three: a<br />

sensation <strong>of</strong> immediate certainty, an insight into my truest, most characteristic<br />

life ... <strong>the</strong> appearance [Erscheinung] strikes us particularly at <strong>the</strong> sight <strong>of</strong> many<br />

human forms <strong>and</strong> faces, especially in a glimpse <strong>of</strong> some eyes, some demeanors,<br />

some movements, or at <strong>the</strong> hearing <strong>of</strong> certain words, <strong>the</strong> reading <strong>of</strong> certain<br />

passages, certain perspectives on life, <strong>the</strong> world <strong>and</strong> fate. Very many coincidences,<br />

many events in nature, especially times <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> year <strong>and</strong> day, deliver such<br />

experiences to us. Certain voices are particularly well-suited to producing such<br />

revelations. Most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m [revelations] are momentary, a few last awhile, a very few<br />

endure. (II: 421, #22)<br />

19 Meyer H. Abrams, Natural Supernaturalism: Tradition <strong>and</strong> Revolution in Romantic Literature<br />

(New York: W.W. Norton, 1973).


150<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

Novalis <strong>the</strong>n says that different people will have different experiences <strong>of</strong><br />

‘‘revelation,’’ depending on <strong>the</strong>ir propensities towards sensibility or<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing, <strong>and</strong> he also allows that this ability to ‘‘get outside oneself’’<br />

is capable <strong>of</strong> becoming pathological when a person’s senses <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

are out <strong>of</strong> balance. Romanticism’s detractors may or may not<br />

agree that this is a case <strong>of</strong> being ‘‘outside’’ oneself, but it is what Novalis<br />

means by <strong>the</strong> phrase, <strong>and</strong> it is a far cry from an irrationalist mystic’s<br />

description <strong>of</strong> consciousness.<br />

This leads to a second observation about Novalis’ doctrine <strong>of</strong> imaginative<br />

world-making: It is an account <strong>of</strong> at least one important aspect <strong>of</strong><br />

ordinary human cognition. Very typically his work, along with that <strong>of</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r romantics, is characterized as obsessed by <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> individual<br />

genius. Novalis speaks as if he is characterizing ordinary human consciousness,<br />

<strong>the</strong> objection might proceed, but if self-discovery <strong>of</strong> what he<br />

called <strong>the</strong> ‘‘pure, simple I’’ depends so heavily on imagination, <strong>and</strong> an<br />

artistic one at that, can this account be true for ordinary people? Or is it a<br />

description <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> elite domain <strong>of</strong> artistic consciousness?<br />

There is no doubt that in this section <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Fichte Studies Novalis was<br />

working out <strong>the</strong> rudiments <strong>of</strong> a <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> artistic process for himself. But<br />

in this connection it is important to keep in mind his subsequent views<br />

on artistic genius <strong>and</strong> talent, since <strong>the</strong>y are far more liberal than is generally<br />

attributed to Romanticism. In his Mixed Remarks, for instance, he<br />

advances <strong>the</strong> view that genius is a universal human faculty. He argues that<br />

genius is <strong>the</strong> ability to treat imagined objects as real <strong>and</strong> that it should be<br />

distinguished from <strong>the</strong> talent for presentation <strong>and</strong> precise observation<br />

that is necessary for <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> genius. He <strong>the</strong>n quite explicitly<br />

states:<br />

Without geniality, none <strong>of</strong> us would exist at all. Genius is necessary for everything.<br />

What is usually meant by genius however, is <strong>the</strong> genius <strong>of</strong> genius. 20<br />

This is unequivocal. For Novalis, as for Fichte <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> as well, imagination<br />

is a universal, necessary condition <strong>of</strong> human cognitive experience.<br />

It is precisely <strong>the</strong> naturalness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> capacity that he finds significant<br />

for self-knowledge. Revelation itself is natural, <strong>and</strong> ‘‘must not be forced.’’<br />

It is this capacity for momentary, everyday transcendence (as in reverie)<br />

that defines <strong>the</strong> human: a being to be found ‘‘<strong>the</strong>re, where <strong>the</strong> inner<br />

world <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> outer world touch.’’<br />

20 II: 420, #22.


Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism 151<br />

kant’s romanticism<br />

In seeking to connect <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory with Romanticism, I have<br />

mostly been swimming against <strong>the</strong> current in <strong>Kant</strong> scholarship. However,<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is one aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s philosophy that most scholars would agree is<br />

a precursor <strong>of</strong> Romanticism, <strong>and</strong> that is his notion <strong>of</strong> genius. It is also<br />

seen as something <strong>of</strong> a side issue for <strong>Kant</strong>, given <strong>the</strong> way it is positioned<br />

after his extensive account <strong>of</strong> taste in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Critique <strong>of</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment.’’<br />

21 I want to end this chapter by looking more closely at <strong>the</strong> way in<br />

which this is <strong>and</strong> is not true. I shall do so by juxtaposing <strong>Kant</strong>’s notion <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> creative process with Novalis’ views.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> is ra<strong>the</strong>r notorious for <strong>the</strong> view, discussed in chapter 3, that<br />

artistic products are secondarily or derivatively beautiful, since all art<br />

objects are produced with a concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> final product in mind. 22 That,<br />

by definition for <strong>Kant</strong>, was what it means to create art, <strong>and</strong> artistic<br />

creativity, by extension it would seem, must be understood as only<br />

derivatively creative since <strong>the</strong> artist has a purpose or concept in mind. In<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic experience <strong>of</strong> beauty in nature, however, we do not look for a<br />

specific purpose or rule according to which <strong>the</strong> object was constructed.<br />

There is no purpose in nature, at least none that we can ever know. So we<br />

simply ‘‘play’’ in our minds with <strong>the</strong> sights or sounds nature presents,<br />

letting <strong>the</strong>m take us fleetingly from one thought to <strong>the</strong> next, never<br />

stopping to ‘‘finish’’ <strong>the</strong> job by labeling what we are seeing or hearing.<br />

The point is not to categorize, or apply rules, but ra<strong>the</strong>r to enjoy <strong>the</strong><br />

sustained feeling <strong>of</strong> our mental powers in ‘‘playful’’ harmony with each<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r. Or, as <strong>Kant</strong> also says, it is to experience <strong>the</strong> pleasurable ‘‘quickening’’<br />

or ‘‘enlivening’’ <strong>of</strong> our cognitive forces (Section 9). On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

h<strong>and</strong>, art, which by definition is purposive, can only imitate nature in this<br />

respect. It can at best ‘‘come <strong>of</strong>f’’ as if it were purposeless <strong>and</strong> ‘‘artless.’’<br />

Still, superimposed, as it were, on <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tics is a remarkable<br />

account <strong>of</strong> artistic genius <strong>and</strong> ‘‘originality’’ that became enormously<br />

influential for <strong>the</strong> late eighteenth- <strong>and</strong> early nineteenth-century <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong><br />

21 See Henry Allison’s discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> genius in <strong>the</strong> third Critique. Looked<br />

at closely, he argues, <strong>Kant</strong>’s conception really amounts to two conceptions: one ‘‘thick’’ notion that<br />

is a special talent that no rule can capture, but that instead gives <strong>the</strong> rule to nature <strong>and</strong> that is able<br />

to actually produce beautiful objects <strong>of</strong> art. The o<strong>the</strong>r is a ‘‘thin’’ conception <strong>of</strong> genius that ‘‘seems<br />

to be limited merely to an imaginative capacity <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore does not itself involve underst<strong>and</strong>ing,<br />

judgment or taste.’’ This distinction, appears to be <strong>the</strong> very same that Novalis uses when he speaks<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘genius <strong>of</strong> genius.’’ In Henry E. Allison, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Taste (Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 2001), chapter 12, ‘‘Fine Art <strong>and</strong> Genius,’’ p. 301. Allison’s analysis suggests that<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s conception <strong>of</strong> genius is completely distinct from that <strong>of</strong> taste only in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘thin’’ case.<br />

22 Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment, Section 46 (V: 307–308).


152<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

art. As we saw in chapter 1, this account bears <strong>the</strong> mark <strong>of</strong> earlier German<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory, in particular Lessing’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> imaginative<br />

freedom in artistic genius. This account identifies creative genius as a<br />

phenomenon <strong>of</strong> nature, thus rendering <strong>the</strong> activity <strong>and</strong> product <strong>of</strong> genius<br />

as ‘‘original’’ as <strong>the</strong> beauty in natural objects. In Section 49, ‘‘On <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>Power</strong>s <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Mind that Constitute Genius,’’ <strong>Kant</strong> distinguishes between<br />

tastefulness on <strong>the</strong> one h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> spirit on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. Tastefulness involves<br />

order <strong>and</strong> agreeableness but does not, by itself, move us. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

h<strong>and</strong>, spirit ‘‘in an aes<strong>the</strong>tic sense, is <strong>the</strong> animating principle in <strong>the</strong><br />

mind’’(V: 313). <strong>Kant</strong> identifies genius with ‘‘spirit’’ or <strong>the</strong> power to animate<br />

or enliven <strong>the</strong> soul. Genius is, in his words, <strong>the</strong> power to ‘‘impart to<br />

[<strong>the</strong> mental powers] a purposive momentum, i.e., to impart to <strong>the</strong> mental<br />

powers a play which ... sustains itself on its own <strong>and</strong> even streng<strong>the</strong>ns<br />

<strong>the</strong>m for such play’’ (V: 313). Genius animates <strong>the</strong> mind <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> listener by<br />

drawing on <strong>and</strong> communicating what <strong>Kant</strong> calls ‘‘aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas’’:<br />

‘‘presentations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination which prompt much thought’’ but that<br />

cannot be conceptually represented (i.e., <strong>the</strong>y do not follow rules).<br />

There is no rule for <strong>the</strong> creation <strong>and</strong> communication <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas.<br />

The animating power <strong>of</strong> genius cannot be learned by following formulae,<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> says. At best it can be imitated, just as a (non-genius) artist imitates<br />

<strong>the</strong> spontaneous productions <strong>of</strong> nature. Artistic genius proceeds ‘‘naturally’’<br />

– without ‘‘distinctly known rules that determine <strong>the</strong> procedure’’<br />

although it has in mind some idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> art <strong>and</strong><br />

also some idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> way that is to be manifested in a sensory medium.<br />

(V: 310, 318). Training is <strong>of</strong> course necessary, but it is not sufficient for<br />

genius. ‘‘Genius is <strong>the</strong> innate mental predisposition (ingenium) through<br />

which nature gives <strong>the</strong> rule to art,’’ but this rule is ‘‘indeterminate’’:<br />

Genius is a [natural endowment] for producing something for which no<br />

determinate rule can be given, not a predisposition consisting <strong>of</strong> a skill for<br />

something that can be learned by following some rule or o<strong>the</strong>r; hence <strong>the</strong><br />

foremost property <strong>of</strong> genius must be originality. (V: 307–308)<br />

This notion <strong>of</strong> genius, what Allison in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Taste calls <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

‘‘thin’’ notion <strong>of</strong> genius, is imaginative freedom or simply creative<br />

thought. 23 Creativity for <strong>Kant</strong> is not rule-governed, <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> Anthropology,<br />

23 Allison, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Taste. Brigitte Sassen in ‘‘Artistic Genius <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Question <strong>of</strong> Creativity’’<br />

in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Power</strong> <strong>of</strong> Judgment, ed. Paul Guyer (New York: Rowman & Littlefield,<br />

2003), argues that <strong>the</strong> free play <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination is not creativity properly so called: ‘‘For <strong>the</strong><br />

creative process centers on how those ideas can be brought to presence.’’ Sassen, like Allison, is<br />

identifying <strong>Kant</strong>’s conception <strong>of</strong> genius with a ‘‘thick’’ sense that Novalis would call <strong>the</strong> ‘‘genius <strong>of</strong><br />

genius.’’


Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism 153<br />

his description <strong>of</strong> genius sounds very much like <strong>the</strong> descriptions <strong>of</strong> primary<br />

process regression used by contemporary cognitive scientists. 24 There <strong>Kant</strong><br />

discusses <strong>the</strong> natural process <strong>of</strong> artistic creation as a kind <strong>of</strong> immediate,<br />

non-conceptual awareness <strong>of</strong> ideas that we have without being conscious <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>m. He has, that is to say, a notion <strong>of</strong> unconscious ideation, that<br />

resembles closely contemporary discussions <strong>of</strong> primary process. In his lectures<br />

to his Anthropology class, which he taught for over twenty years at <strong>the</strong><br />

University in Königsberg, <strong>Kant</strong> always included a session on what he called<br />

‘‘obscure representations’’ – ideas that we have unconsciously. To illustrate<br />

this phenomenon to his students, he chose <strong>the</strong> example <strong>of</strong> an organist<br />

playing a free fantasia.<br />

Before looking at <strong>Kant</strong>’s own comment, it will be useful to make a few<br />

preliminary historical remarks. The free fantasia was an art form that<br />

gained great popularity in <strong>Kant</strong>’s time <strong>and</strong> one <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> few musical forms<br />

that <strong>Kant</strong> mentions anywhere. <strong>Kant</strong>, like every educated man <strong>and</strong> woman<br />

<strong>of</strong> his time, was well aware <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenomenon <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free fantasia, which<br />

was at <strong>the</strong> height <strong>of</strong> its popularity during <strong>the</strong> period <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s mature<br />

scholarship in <strong>the</strong> latter half <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> eighteenth century. <strong>Kant</strong> was not<br />

particularly well versed in <strong>the</strong> fine arts, <strong>and</strong> knew little about music<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>and</strong> so <strong>the</strong> fact that he refers to <strong>the</strong> fantasia at all speaks to <strong>the</strong><br />

ubiquity <strong>and</strong> importance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> genre to <strong>the</strong> general educated public <strong>of</strong><br />

eighteenth-century Germany. The free fantasia, according to Peter<br />

Schleuning’s The Fantasia, is a peculiarly eighteenth-century phenomenon,<br />

<strong>and</strong> moreover, ‘‘a purely German phenomenon for <strong>the</strong> entire<br />

period <strong>of</strong> its existence – until about 1800.’’ 25 It finds its prototype in<br />

J. S. Bach’s Chromatic Fantasia <strong>and</strong> Fugue, which combined elements <strong>of</strong><br />

seventeenth-century genres (such as <strong>the</strong> prelude, toccata, <strong>and</strong> capriccio)<br />

that had <strong>the</strong>mselves inherited <strong>the</strong> compositional freedoms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fantasia<br />

<strong>of</strong> an earlier period. Johann Mat<strong>the</strong>son (a Hamburg music scholar)<br />

defined it fur<strong>the</strong>r, when he argued that music in <strong>the</strong> ‘‘fantastic style’’<br />

24 The creative process has received a great deal <strong>of</strong> attention recently from cognitive psychologists,<br />

<strong>and</strong> one view, espoused by Colin Martindale among o<strong>the</strong>rs, argues that artistic originality can be<br />

understood in terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> artist’s ability to ‘‘regress’’ to ‘‘primary process cognition,’’ or what<br />

Martindale prefers to call ‘‘primordial’’ cognition. That is, on this account <strong>the</strong> creative artist<br />

temporarily ab<strong>and</strong>ons conceptual cognition which is ‘‘abstract, rational <strong>and</strong> reality-oriented’’ to<br />

regress to cognition that is ‘‘concrete, irrational, <strong>and</strong> autistic’’ – to ‘‘<strong>the</strong> thought <strong>of</strong> dreams <strong>and</strong><br />

reveries.’’ Martindale says that ‘‘Primordial cognition is free-associative. It thus increases <strong>the</strong> novel<br />

combinations <strong>of</strong> mental elements, which form <strong>the</strong> raw material for a work <strong>of</strong> art. This raw material<br />

must <strong>the</strong>n be put into final form in a rational or conceptual state <strong>of</strong> mind.’’ (‘‘How Can we<br />

Measure a Society’s Creativity?,’’ in Dimensions <strong>of</strong> Creativity, ed. Margaret A. Boden, Cambridge,<br />

MA: MIT Press, 1996), pp. 163–164.)<br />

25 The Fantasia I: 16th to 18th Centuries, trans. A. C. Howie (Cologne: Arno Volk Verlag, 1971), p. 17.


154<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

(Stylus Phantasticus) should have ‘‘no <strong>the</strong>me <strong>and</strong> subject to be worked ...<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is nothing so opposed to it as order <strong>and</strong> restraint’’ (p. 15). One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se<br />

problematic restraints was <strong>the</strong> juxtaposition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fantasia with <strong>the</strong> fugue as<br />

a sort <strong>of</strong> ‘‘corrective’’ to <strong>the</strong> fantasia’s anarchic character. Ano<strong>the</strong>r constraint<br />

thatwastobeoverthrownwas<strong>the</strong>imposition<strong>of</strong>aunity<strong>of</strong>feeling,<strong>of</strong><br />

a single emotive <strong>the</strong>me, throughout a movement. By mid-century<br />

C. P. E. Bach had refined Mat<strong>the</strong>son’s principle <strong>of</strong> freedom for <strong>the</strong> fantasia<br />

to include <strong>the</strong> freedom from <strong>the</strong>matic emotional constraints; <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

musician was ‘‘to excite <strong>and</strong> to calm many affections in close succession’’<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘‘to effect <strong>the</strong> sudden unexpected change from one affection to <strong>the</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>r’’ so as ‘‘to master <strong>the</strong> emotions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> audience’’ (p. 16).<br />

Given <strong>the</strong> development <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fantasia towards ever greater freedom<br />

from formal constraints, it thus st<strong>and</strong>s to reason, as Schleuning points<br />

out, that ‘‘<strong>the</strong> extempore performance was <strong>the</strong> essential medium <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free<br />

fantasia’’ (p. 17). If <strong>the</strong> free fantasia is defined as improvisational, notating<br />

<strong>the</strong>se pieces would <strong>of</strong> necessity alter <strong>the</strong> very nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> piece:<br />

It is to be observed from an examination <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> formal structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free<br />

fantasia that a free, r<strong>and</strong>om, erratic <strong>and</strong> ‘‘capricious’’ structure such as would<br />

have been <strong>the</strong> case in <strong>the</strong> improvised, hour-long fantasias could not have been<br />

effected to <strong>the</strong> same extent in <strong>the</strong> pieces which were written down. On <strong>the</strong><br />

contrary, <strong>the</strong> necessity to reach a conclusion after a relatively short time compelled<br />

<strong>the</strong> composer to sacrifice a part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> pleasant <strong>and</strong> continual dreamlike<br />

character <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fantasia ... for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> some kind <strong>of</strong> symmetry, so that <strong>the</strong><br />

ending could have a meaningful effect. (p. 20)<br />

There are strong similarities between <strong>Kant</strong>’s account <strong>of</strong> genius <strong>and</strong> what<br />

is dem<strong>and</strong>ed <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> performer <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free fantasia by Mat<strong>the</strong>son <strong>and</strong><br />

C. P. E. Bach. Like <strong>Kant</strong>’s genius, <strong>the</strong> performer proceeds ‘‘naturally’’ <strong>and</strong><br />

through inspiration without ‘‘distinctly known rules that determine <strong>the</strong><br />

procedure’’ moving easily <strong>and</strong> artlessly from one musical idea or<br />

expression to <strong>the</strong> next without end goal or purpose. Just as nature exhibits<br />

purposive purposelessness, so too does <strong>the</strong> performer <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> fantasia. At<br />

<strong>the</strong> keyboard she is a kind <strong>of</strong> natural phenomenon. For <strong>Kant</strong>, <strong>the</strong> problem<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> composed fantasia might be understood, <strong>the</strong>n, as <strong>the</strong> problem<br />

<strong>of</strong> how to retain <strong>the</strong> ‘‘h<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> nature’’ (V: 309) in <strong>the</strong> writing down <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

free fantasia, since <strong>the</strong> free fantasia, with its utter freedom <strong>of</strong> expression<br />

<strong>and</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> predictable outcome – indeed with its lack <strong>of</strong> outcome at all –<br />

would be ra<strong>the</strong>r more like a natural phenomenon than it is like a ‘‘work’’<br />

<strong>of</strong> art. As we have already seen, <strong>Kant</strong> has a ‘‘natural’’ account <strong>of</strong> what<br />

artistic genius involves. One way to deal with <strong>the</strong> musician who sits down


Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism 155<br />

to play <strong>the</strong> fantasia might be to regard her, too, as a natural phenomenon,<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> does say something very much along <strong>the</strong>se lines:<br />

In man (<strong>and</strong> so in beasts too) <strong>the</strong>re is an immense field <strong>of</strong> sensuous intuitions<br />

<strong>and</strong> sensations we are not conscious <strong>of</strong>, though we can conclude with certainty<br />

that we have <strong>the</strong>m ... If a musician plays a fantasia on <strong>the</strong> organ with ten fingers<br />

<strong>and</strong> both feet, while talking with someone nearby, in a matter <strong>of</strong> seconds a host<br />

<strong>of</strong> ideas is awakened in his soul; <strong>and</strong> in selecting each <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m he must make a<br />

particular judgment about its appropriateness, since a single stroke <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> finger<br />

out <strong>of</strong> keeping with <strong>the</strong> harmony would at once be perceived as discord. And<br />

yet <strong>the</strong> whole turns out so well that a musician, when he improvises freely,<br />

would <strong>of</strong>ten like to transcribe some <strong>of</strong> his happy improvisations, which he<br />

might o<strong>the</strong>rwise never hope to bring <strong>of</strong>f so well, no matter how hard he tried.<br />

[<strong>Kant</strong>: Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point <strong>of</strong> View, Section 1, Bk. 1, ‘‘On <strong>the</strong><br />

representations that we have without being conscious <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m’’]<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s point was that this example illustrates that <strong>the</strong>re is a ‘‘wide field’’<br />

<strong>of</strong> representations in <strong>the</strong> mind <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> musician (<strong>and</strong> in all <strong>of</strong> us, for that<br />

matter), that although very much part <strong>of</strong> cognition, are never<strong>the</strong>less not<br />

clearly <strong>and</strong> distinctly present to consciousness. What is special in <strong>the</strong> case<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> musician is that she has <strong>the</strong> requisite technical skills to express <strong>the</strong>se<br />

ideas behaviorally, as it were, in her impromptu but never<strong>the</strong>less nonr<strong>and</strong>om<br />

harmonic choices. That <strong>the</strong>se choices are <strong>the</strong> product <strong>of</strong><br />

unconscious processes is shown by <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> musician could only<br />

come up with <strong>the</strong>se combinations by somehow being able to shortcut <strong>the</strong><br />

conscious, deliberative process <strong>of</strong> rule-governed composition. In fact,<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> suggests, <strong>the</strong> more diligently <strong>and</strong> attentively (i.e. self-consciously)<br />

she tried to reproduce <strong>the</strong>se afterwards on paper (‘‘with real diligence <strong>and</strong><br />

attention (‘‘mit allem Fleiß,’’)), <strong>the</strong> less likely she would be to capture <strong>the</strong><br />

free fantasy. And yet at <strong>the</strong> same time, he characterizes this process as one<br />

involving discriminations: every stroke <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> keyboard or pedal involves<br />

judgments about its appropriateness, <strong>Kant</strong> says, <strong>and</strong> one bad choice<br />

would produce discord. 26<br />

Though he knew little about music <strong>the</strong>ory, <strong>Kant</strong> is obviously intrigued<br />

by <strong>the</strong> cognitive state that underlies <strong>the</strong> free fantasia. Interestingly, he<br />

does not seem particularly bo<strong>the</strong>red by <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> ‘‘happy<br />

26 <strong>Kant</strong>’s characterization <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> cognitive state <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> musician playing <strong>the</strong> free fantasia <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

subsequent attempt to recapture it in notation is an early version <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> dilemma or paradox that<br />

Schleuning describes. (The musician while improvising is working with musical ideas that, while<br />

not r<strong>and</strong>om or arbitrary, are also nei<strong>the</strong>r predictable nor purposive. A composition, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

h<strong>and</strong>, must have some coherent structure (at least a beginning, middle, <strong>and</strong> end) <strong>and</strong> in this sense,<br />

a purpose. To stay true to <strong>the</strong> essence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> original this structure must be put toge<strong>the</strong>r in a way<br />

that is nei<strong>the</strong>r predictable nor reproducible.)


156<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

improvisations’’ are by his definition not really works <strong>of</strong> art. He is more<br />

concerned to characterize <strong>the</strong> nature <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> process by which an artistic<br />

virtuoso creates beautiful music. The organist who improvises is a kind <strong>of</strong><br />

phenomenon <strong>of</strong> nature, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> improvised piece is thus itself more <strong>of</strong> a<br />

natural than an artificial object whose aes<strong>the</strong>tic value can be explained<br />

along <strong>the</strong> lines <strong>of</strong> natural beauty: it results from <strong>the</strong> interplay <strong>of</strong> musical<br />

forms <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> free play <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imaginations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> listeners for whom <strong>the</strong><br />

improvisor plays. And so far as <strong>the</strong> musician is concerned, a naturalistic<br />

account <strong>of</strong> her role is also available. Just as a beautiful natural object can<br />

be explained scientifically, <strong>the</strong> causal story <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> organist’s inner state can<br />

be told by reference to a kind <strong>of</strong> ‘‘regression’’ or dreamlike access to ideas<br />

that are not immediately present to consciousness.<br />

This causal story as <strong>Kant</strong> tells it, is <strong>the</strong> story <strong>of</strong> ‘‘fantasy,’’ <strong>the</strong> term<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> prefers to use instead <strong>of</strong> imagination when referring to ‘‘images<br />

produced involuntarily’’ or what he has called ‘‘unconscious ideas’’:<br />

Before an artist can present a physical form (tangibly, as it were), he must have<br />

already made it in his imagination; <strong>and</strong> this form is <strong>the</strong>n called invention. If it is<br />

produced involuntarily (as in dreaming) it is called fantasy <strong>and</strong> lies outside <strong>the</strong><br />

artist’s proper realm; but if it is governed by choice it is called composition,<br />

fabrication. (VII: 174ff.)<br />

The ‘‘proper realm’’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> artist for <strong>Kant</strong> is by definition a realm <strong>of</strong><br />

purpose <strong>and</strong> technique for implementing <strong>and</strong> realizing it in a medium.<br />

The free fantasia is not <strong>of</strong> course a mere dream, but it is a case <strong>of</strong> what<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> sees as fantasizing none<strong>the</strong>less, because it involves loss <strong>of</strong> control –<br />

or, as he puts it, it involves <strong>the</strong> imagination ‘‘playing with us.’’ He says,<br />

‘‘we like to play with our imagination <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>ten do; but imagination (in<br />

its role <strong>of</strong> fantasy) plays with us just as <strong>of</strong>ten.’’ The difference between <strong>the</strong><br />

fantasia performer <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> daydreamer for <strong>Kant</strong> is <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong><br />

organist has developed great technical skills to such a level that <strong>the</strong>y can<br />

be accessed kines<strong>the</strong>tically, i.e. nearly unconsciously. There is <strong>the</strong>n a sense<br />

in which <strong>the</strong> improvising musician is not a ‘‘conscious’’ artist. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, she<br />

is an artist who has consciously chosen a dream-like state in order to let<br />

her imagination ‘‘play’’ with her decisions about what musical ideas to<br />

express. The result is a natural, not a ‘‘composed,’’ object.<br />

Something along <strong>the</strong>se lines holds for philosophical creativity, for<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>, as well. <strong>Kant</strong> has more to say about <strong>the</strong> free play <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination<br />

with natural objects like fire <strong>and</strong> babbling brooks, <strong>and</strong> it seems to me <strong>the</strong><br />

reverie he describes on <strong>the</strong>se occasions is precisely <strong>the</strong> reverie that<br />

C. P. E. Bach hoped to induce in himself <strong>and</strong> his listeners in <strong>the</strong>


Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism 157<br />

performance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free fantasia. Here is a an excerpt from <strong>Kant</strong>’s<br />

Anthropology, where he speaks <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> free play <strong>of</strong> imagination with ‘‘<strong>the</strong><br />

changing, moving forms’’ <strong>of</strong> flickering flames or a babbling brook;<br />

imagination plays with ‘‘a host <strong>of</strong> ideas <strong>of</strong> a quite different kind (than<br />

those <strong>of</strong> sight) [or <strong>of</strong> hearing]’’ <strong>and</strong> ‘‘becomes lost in reverie’’:<br />

Even music can fulfill this function, provided we do not listen to it as connoisseurs;<br />

it can put a poet or a philosopher into a frame <strong>of</strong> mind such that he<br />

can snatch <strong>and</strong> even master thought relevant to his business or his fancy, which<br />

he would not have caught so luckily had he sat down alone in his room [<strong>and</strong><br />

tried to come up with <strong>the</strong>m]. (V: 173–174)<br />

Thought is facilitated <strong>and</strong> ‘‘animated’’ by <strong>the</strong> focus <strong>of</strong> our attention on a<br />

single str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> sensation to <strong>the</strong> exclusion <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r sensations, because <strong>the</strong><br />

imagination is <strong>the</strong>n conserved for <strong>the</strong> purpose <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘strenuous <strong>and</strong><br />

persistent activity ... <strong>of</strong> providing material for its intellectual ideas.’’ (In<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r words, it is conserved for <strong>the</strong> production <strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas.) The<br />

imaginative power is able to focus on its work by fixating: zeroing in on<br />

one set <strong>of</strong> sensations that occupy, even transfix, our outward perception.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s account helps make sense <strong>of</strong> how artistic creativity works, at its<br />

best: By eschewing predictability, it renders <strong>the</strong> artist (<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> audiences,<br />

even <strong>the</strong> connoisseur) an amateur again, a ‘‘natural’’ as it were. The<br />

element <strong>of</strong> surprise <strong>and</strong> unruliness will pleasantly disorient <strong>the</strong> savant so<br />

that he or she can see or hear it with ‘‘fresh’’ eyes <strong>and</strong> ears, as it were, <strong>and</strong><br />

restore <strong>the</strong> kind <strong>of</strong> originality that <strong>the</strong> amateur enjoys. Like <strong>the</strong> play <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

flames in fire, works like <strong>the</strong> free fantasia level <strong>the</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic playing field<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir audience.<br />

Before turning to Novalis, I want to go back to something <strong>Kant</strong> says<br />

about <strong>the</strong> imagination in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

powers <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> mind that constitute genius that fits h<strong>and</strong> in glove with his<br />

discussion <strong>of</strong> unconscious ideation in <strong>the</strong> Anthropology:<br />

<strong>the</strong> imagination ([in its role] as a productive cognitive power) is very mighty<br />

when it creates, as it were, ano<strong>the</strong>r nature out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> material that actual nature<br />

gives it. We use it to entertain ourselves when experience strikes us as overly<br />

routine. We may even restructure [umbilden] experience; <strong>and</strong> though in doing so<br />

we continue to follow analogical laws, yet we also follow principles which reside<br />

higher up, namely, in reason (<strong>and</strong> which are just as natural to us as those which<br />

<strong>the</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing follows in apprehending empirical nature). In this process we<br />

feel our freedom from <strong>the</strong> law <strong>of</strong> association (which attaches to <strong>the</strong> empirical use<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination); for although it is under that law that nature lends us<br />

material yet we can process that material into something quite different, namely,<br />

into something that surpasses nature. (V: 314)


158<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

Let us return to Novalis, keeping in mind some <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> points just made<br />

about <strong>Kant</strong>’s view <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> creative process. First, <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> creativity<br />

involves a central reference to non-rational, or sub-rational processing.<br />

This is not altoge<strong>the</strong>r clear in <strong>the</strong> third Critique, but when read in<br />

conjunction with <strong>the</strong> passage from his Anthropology on unconscious<br />

ideation <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> free fantasia, it seems obvious that this is what he has in<br />

mind when he speaks <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> creative power <strong>of</strong> imagination to create<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r nature out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> one that is actually given, doing so to relieve<br />

boredom ‘‘when experience strikes us as overly routine.’’ Second,<br />

although it occurs within <strong>the</strong> context <strong>of</strong> his characterization <strong>of</strong> genius, in<br />

this particular passage he refers to everyone’s power <strong>of</strong> imagination ‘‘when<br />

experience strikes us as overly routine.’’ This suggests that he is thinking<br />

<strong>of</strong> ordinary daydreaming or reverie, wherein it is possible for ‘‘us’’<br />

(humans, presumably) to creatively ‘‘process’’ <strong>the</strong> materials <strong>of</strong> nature into<br />

something ‘‘that surpasses nature’’ <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby feel our freedom from <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘empirical use <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> imagination.’’ In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>Kant</strong> intimates here<br />

that genius is a capacity common to all, <strong>the</strong> ability to produce aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

ideas – ‘‘inner intuitions to which no concept can be completely adequate.’’<br />

But he <strong>the</strong>n goes on, somewhat confusingly, to say that genius is<br />

<strong>the</strong> special capacity to find ideas that prompt so much thought that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

exp<strong>and</strong> a concept ‘‘in an unlimited way’’ (V: 315). 27 <strong>Kant</strong> leaves unclear<br />

<strong>the</strong> relationship between ordinary consciousness <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> creative process<br />

<strong>of</strong> genius, perhaps because, for him <strong>the</strong> two are not so easily separated in<br />

<strong>the</strong> first place.<br />

And, finally, we should notice that in this section (V: 314) <strong>Kant</strong> makes<br />

<strong>the</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r surprising claim that in ‘‘productive’’ imaginative reflection, we<br />

are capable <strong>of</strong> surpassing nature. For <strong>Kant</strong>, to surpass (übertreffen) nature,<br />

<strong>of</strong> course, suggests entering <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> supersensible, or <strong>the</strong> moral,<br />

not in any metaphysical sense, but in <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> entering a realm <strong>of</strong> what<br />

ought to be as opposed to what is. I have already argued that this little<br />

paragraph gestures towards a view that <strong>Kant</strong> himself didn’t adopt, but<br />

perhaps should have. It opens <strong>the</strong> possibility that morality is directly<br />

linked to aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection ins<strong>of</strong>ar as moral law requires us to project<br />

<strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> creating <strong>the</strong> highest good – happiness commensurate<br />

27<br />

And <strong>the</strong>n in concluding he says:<br />

Hence genius actually consists in <strong>the</strong> happy relation ... allowing us, first, to discover ideas for a given<br />

concept, <strong>and</strong> second, to hit upon a way <strong>of</strong> expressing <strong>the</strong>se ideas that enables us to communicate to<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs ... <strong>the</strong> mental attunement that those ideas produce. (V: 317)<br />

suggesting that it is <strong>the</strong> ability to communicate that makes for genius, since originality alone can<br />

amount to ‘‘original nonsense.’’


Novalis’ <strong>Kant</strong>ianism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Romanticism 159<br />

with virtue on earth. <strong>Kant</strong> didn’t follow through to say that aes<strong>the</strong>tic<br />

creativity is needed for just this sort <strong>of</strong> projection, but Novalis, along with<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r early Romantics, did.<br />

In a sense, Novalis’ entire philosophical <strong>and</strong> poetic project is intended<br />

to both embody <strong>and</strong> explain <strong>the</strong> creative process. Given his view that<br />

‘‘Without geniality, none <strong>of</strong> us would exist at all. Genius is necessary for<br />

everything,’’ it is no wonder. Genius for Novalis, as we saw, is ‘‘<strong>the</strong> ability<br />

to treat imagined objects as real,’’ <strong>and</strong> thought <strong>of</strong> in this way, his claim<br />

that it is ‘‘necessary for everything’’ is not all that exaggerated. Does <strong>Kant</strong><br />

also subscribe to this notion <strong>of</strong> ‘‘ordinary’’ genius? I think in his discussion<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> primordial cognition that is involved in improvisational art –<br />

that is, in art that is closest to nature <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore genuinely original – he<br />

came close to expounding <strong>the</strong> ubiquity <strong>of</strong> genius. But he placed restrictions<br />

on <strong>the</strong> notion in <strong>the</strong> third Critique account that reserves <strong>the</strong> term<br />

‘‘genius’’ to refer only to <strong>the</strong> ability to successfully communicate primordial<br />

or ‘‘unconscious’’ ideas. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, although he came very<br />

close to an underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> creativity as a necessary part <strong>of</strong> human<br />

cognitive functioning, he ended up discussing only what Novalis calls <strong>the</strong><br />

‘‘genius <strong>of</strong> genius.’’ It is not entirely clear why. Perhaps he believed that<br />

<strong>the</strong> extraordinary power <strong>of</strong> imagination <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ‘‘genius <strong>of</strong> genius’’ was so<br />

much fur<strong>the</strong>r developed than <strong>the</strong> ordinary person’s that <strong>the</strong>y become<br />

qualitatively different – belonging to a class by <strong>the</strong>mselves. Or perhaps he<br />

was afraid to defend <strong>the</strong> virtues <strong>of</strong> daydreaming.<br />

Novalis had no such worries. He recognizes <strong>the</strong> ordinariness <strong>of</strong> genius,<br />

or <strong>the</strong> genius <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ordinary, we might say. Revelations, he said, are<br />

natural, <strong>and</strong> ‘‘cannot be forced.’’ 28 Surely <strong>the</strong>re is truth in this position: It<br />

is this capacity for momentary, everyday transcendence – <strong>the</strong> ability to<br />

daydream – that develops our powers. Our propensity for ordinary, if not<br />

always productive, creativity is what allows us to transpose ourselves<br />

outside ourselves, <strong>and</strong> meet each o<strong>the</strong>r, as Novalis says, ‘‘<strong>the</strong>re, where <strong>the</strong><br />

inner world <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> outer world touch.’’<br />

conclusion<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>, like Novalis, firmly believed that longing <strong>and</strong> striving for <strong>the</strong><br />

absolute, <strong>the</strong> unconditioned, was an essential characteristic <strong>of</strong> human<br />

28 ‘‘One must never, like a phantast, seek <strong>the</strong> undetermined – a child <strong>of</strong> fantasy – an ideal. One<br />

proceeds from determinate task to determinate task. An unknown lover <strong>of</strong> course has a magical<br />

charm. Striving for <strong>the</strong> unknown, <strong>the</strong> undetermined, is extremely dangerous <strong>and</strong> disadvantageous.<br />

Revelations cannot be forced’’ (3: 601, #291, Observations on <strong>the</strong> Physical).


160<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> power <strong>of</strong> imagination<br />

reason that nei<strong>the</strong>r could nor should be entirely suppressed. Both also<br />

agreed that no knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> absolute could ever be attained, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

claims to have done so were necessarily in error. The difference between<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Novalis was thus not a difference over <strong>the</strong> value <strong>of</strong> unattainable<br />

rational ideals or <strong>the</strong> need to avoid transcendent delusions. Throughout<br />

this book I have argued that <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Novalis were closer philosophically<br />

than is canonically assumed. And assuming Novalis to be a central<br />

spokesman for <strong>the</strong> early German Romantics, <strong>Kant</strong> is in many ways closer<br />

to this movement than to <strong>the</strong> Idealism with which he is so <strong>of</strong>ten associated.<br />

But <strong>the</strong> two are certainly not identical. What really separates <strong>Kant</strong><br />

from Novalis <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> early German Romantic movement, I believe, is his<br />

relatively sanguine acceptance <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> limitations <strong>of</strong> human reason <strong>and</strong><br />

hence <strong>of</strong> philosophy. Novalis took this resignation to be a kind <strong>of</strong><br />

‘‘scholasticism’’ – a ‘‘one-sided’’ approach that assigned philosophy to <strong>the</strong><br />

domain <strong>of</strong> reason alone. Novalis’ innovation, <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong> his cohort in<br />

Jena, was to redefine philosophy itself as an ‘‘unending, free activity’’ that<br />

at its limits becomes an aes<strong>the</strong>tic, creative endeavor, driven by an<br />

exp<strong>and</strong>ed power <strong>of</strong> imagination first described by <strong>Kant</strong> in <strong>the</strong> third<br />

Critique.


Bibliography<br />

References to <strong>Kant</strong>’s work in this book (except references to <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure<br />

Reason, which following long practice are to <strong>the</strong> pagination <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> original<br />

German editions) are to <strong>Kant</strong>s Gesammelte Schriften edited by <strong>the</strong> Königliche<br />

Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, <strong>the</strong> ‘‘Academie edition,’’ by volume<br />

<strong>and</strong> page number. English translations <strong>of</strong> most <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se exist in a st<strong>and</strong>ard format<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Cambridge Edition <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Works <strong>of</strong> Immanuel <strong>Kant</strong>. The Akademie pagination<br />

is provided in all <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>se.<br />

Except where o<strong>the</strong>rwise noted, references to Novalis’ works are to Novalis<br />

Schriften: Die Werke Friedrich von Hardenbergs, eds. Paul Kluckhohn <strong>and</strong><br />

Richard Samuel (Stuttgart: Verlag W. Kohlhammer, 1965). References are to<br />

volume, page, <strong>and</strong>, when applicable, to paragraph number <strong>of</strong> that edition. The<br />

second <strong>and</strong> third volumes, edited by Richard Samuel toge<strong>the</strong>r with Hans-<br />

Joachim Mähl <strong>and</strong> Gerhard Schulz, contain Novalis’ philosophical writings,<br />

published in 1981 <strong>and</strong> 1983, respectively. English editions now available include <strong>the</strong><br />

Notes for a Romantic Encyclopaedia: The Universal Brouillon, trans. David Wood<br />

(Albany: SUNY Press, <strong>2007</strong>); Novalis: Fichte Studies, ed. Jane Kneller (Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press, 2003); Novalis: Philosophical Writings, trans. Margaret<br />

Mahoney Stoljar (Albany: State University <strong>of</strong> New York Press, 1997).<br />

kant works cited (followed by akademie<br />

edition number)<br />

Kritik der praktischen Vernunft/Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason (V) (also ‘‘Second<br />

Critique’’); Kritik der reinen Vernunft/Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason (also ‘‘First Critique’’)<br />

(A & B editions); Kritik der Urteilskraft/Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment (V) (also<br />

‘‘Third Critique’’); Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht/Anthropology from a<br />

Pragmatic Point <strong>of</strong> View (VII); Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufklärung?/An<br />

Answer to <strong>the</strong> Question: What is Enlightenment? (XIII); Bemerkungen zu den<br />

Beobachtungen über das Gefühl des Schönen und Erhabenen/Remarks on <strong>the</strong> Observations<br />

on <strong>the</strong> Beautiful <strong>and</strong> Sublime (XX); Briefwechsel/Correspondence (XII);<br />

Erste Einleitung in der Kritik der Urteilskraft/First Introduction to <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong><br />

Judgment (XX); Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten/Groundwork <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Morals (also Foundations <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Metaphysics <strong>of</strong> Morals) (IV);<br />

161


162<br />

Bibliography<br />

H<strong>and</strong>schriftlicher Nachlass/Reflections (Anthropology) (XV); Streit der Fakultäten/<br />

Conflict <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Faculties (VII); Träume eines Geistersehers, erläutert durch Träume<br />

der Metaphysik/Dreams <strong>of</strong> a Spirit-Seer, Illustrated by <strong>the</strong> Dreams <strong>of</strong> Metaphysics<br />

(II); Vorlesungen über Anthropologie/Lectures on Anthropology (XXV).<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r books <strong>and</strong> articles<br />

Abrams, Meyer H., The Mirror <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Lamp. Oxford: Oxford University Press,<br />

1953.<br />

Natural Supernaturalism: Tradition <strong>and</strong> Revolution in Romantic Literature.<br />

New York: W. W. Norton, 1973.<br />

Allison, Henry E., <strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Freedom. New York: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 1990.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Taste. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.<br />

Ameriks, Karl, The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism. Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press, 2000.<br />

‘‘The Critique <strong>of</strong> Metaphysics: <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Traditional Ontology,’’ in The<br />

Cambridge Companion to <strong>Kant</strong>. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,<br />

2000.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Fate <strong>of</strong> Autonomy: Problems in <strong>the</strong> Appropriation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critical<br />

Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.<br />

‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>, Fichte, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Radical Primacy <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Practical,’’ in <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Fate<br />

<strong>of</strong> Autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.<br />

‘‘On Paul Guyer’s <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Experience <strong>of</strong> Freedom,’’ Philosophy <strong>and</strong><br />

Phenomenological Research, 60(2) (1995).<br />

Arendt, Hannah, Lectures on <strong>Kant</strong>’s Political Philosophy. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong><br />

Chicago Press, 1982.<br />

Auxter, Thomas, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Moral Teleology. Macon, GA: Mercer University Press,<br />

1982.<br />

Baier, Kurt, ‘‘Radical Virtue Ethics,’’ Midwest Studies in Philosophy 13 (1988),<br />

pp. 126–135.<br />

Bauemler, Alfred, Das Irrationalitätsproblem im äs<strong>the</strong>tischen Denken des 18.<br />

Jahrhunderts. Halle, 1923; republished Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche<br />

Buchgesellschaft, 1967.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s Kritik der Urteilskraft. Halle: Max Niemeyer Verlag, 1923.<br />

Baumgarten, Alex<strong>and</strong>er G., Aes<strong>the</strong>tica. Hildesheim, 1961.<br />

Meditationes Philosophicae de Nonnullis ad Poema Pertinentibus. Halle, 1735,<br />

trans. Karl Aschenbrenner <strong>and</strong> ed. William B. Hol<strong>the</strong>r as Reflections on<br />

Poetry. Berkeley: University <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1954.<br />

Beck, Lewis W., Commentary on <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason. Chicago:<br />

University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1996.<br />

ed., Critique <strong>of</strong> Practical Reason <strong>and</strong> O<strong>the</strong>r Writings in Moral Philosophy.<br />

Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1949.<br />

Early German Philosophy: <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> His Predecessors. Cambridge, MA: Belknap<br />

Press <strong>of</strong> Harvard University Press, 1969.


Bibliography 163<br />

Essays on <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> Hum e. New Have n: Yale Universi ty Pres s, 1978 .<br />

‘‘<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Right <strong>of</strong> Revolut ion,’’ Journ al <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> His tory <strong>of</strong> Ideas 32 , 1971<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> on History . Indiana polis: Bobb s-Merril l, 1963 .<br />

‘‘Wha t have we learn ed from <strong>Kant</strong>?,’ ’ in Self <strong>and</strong> Nature in <strong>Kant</strong> ’s philosoph y,<br />

ed. Allen W. Wood. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Unive rsity Pres s, 1984 .<br />

Behle r, Ern st, German Roma ntic Theory . Cambridg e: Cambridg e Universit y<br />

Pres s, 1993 .<br />

‘‘Revie w <strong>of</strong> Manfred Fran k’s Einfü hrung in die Frü hroma ntische Ä s<strong>the</strong>tik ,<br />

Ath enä um ’’ 3, Pade rborn: F. Schohn ingh 1993<br />

Beiser, Frede rick C., Th e Ear ly Politica l Writings <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> German Roma ntics .<br />

Cambr idge: Cambridg e Unive rsity Press, 1996 .<br />

Enlightenment, Revolution <strong>and</strong> Romanticism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard<br />

University Press, 1992.<br />

‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s Intellectua l De velopme nt: 1746 –1781 ,’’ chapte r I <strong>of</strong> The Camb ridge<br />

Companion to <strong>Kant</strong>, ed. Paul Guyer. New York: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 1992.<br />

Bernstein, Jay, Classic <strong>and</strong> Romantic German Aes<strong>the</strong>tics. Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 2003.<br />

Bodmer, J. J. <strong>and</strong> J. J. Breitinger, Von dem Einfluss und Gebrauche der<br />

Einbildungs-Krafft; Zur Ausbesserung des Geschmackes; Genaue Untersuchung<br />

Aller Arten Beschreibungen, Worinne die ausserlesenste Stellen der<br />

berühmtesten Poeten dieser Zeit mit gründtlicher Freyheit beur<strong>the</strong>ilt werden.<br />

Frankfurt 1727.<br />

Böhme, Hartmut <strong>and</strong> Böhme, Gernot, Das Andere der Vernunft: Zur<br />

Entwicklung von Rationalitätsstrukturen am Beispiel <strong>Kant</strong>s. Frankfurt am<br />

Main: Suhrkamp, 1996.<br />

Aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> Subjectivity: From <strong>Kant</strong> to Nietzsche. Manchester: Manchester<br />

University Press, 1990.<br />

Bowie, Andrew, Aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> Subjectivity: From <strong>Kant</strong> to Nietzsche. Manchester:<br />

Manchester University Press, 1990.<br />

From Romanticism to Critical Theory: The Philosophy <strong>of</strong> German Literary<br />

Theory. London: Routledge, 1997.<br />

Breazeale, Daniel, Fichte: Early Philosophical Writings. Ithaca, NY: Cornell<br />

University Press, 1988.<br />

Buchwald, Reinhard, Schiller. Wiesbaden, 1954.<br />

Cassirer, Ernst, ‘‘Hölderlin und der deutsche Idealismus,’’ in Hölderlin: Beiträge<br />

zu seinem Verständnis in unserm Jahrhundert, Alfred Kelletat, ed. Tübingen:<br />

Mohr, 1961.<br />

Constantine, David, Hölderlin. Oxford: Clarendon, 1988.<br />

Crawford, Donald, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Theory. Madison: University <strong>of</strong> Wisconsin<br />

Press, 1974.<br />

Eldridge, Richard, The Persistence <strong>of</strong> Romanticism: Essays in Philosophy <strong>and</strong><br />

Literature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.<br />

Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, Early Philosophical Writings, Daniel Breazeale, trans.<br />

<strong>and</strong> ed. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988.


164<br />

Bibliography<br />

Science <strong>of</strong> Knowledge, Peter Heath <strong>and</strong> John Lachs, ed. <strong>and</strong> trans. New York:<br />

Meredith, 1970.<br />

Einführung in die Frühromantische Äs<strong>the</strong>tik: Vorlesungen. Frankfurt am Main:<br />

Suhrkamp, 1989, English trans. Elizabeth Millán-Zaibert, The Foundations<br />

<strong>of</strong> Early German Romanticism. Albany: SUNY Press, 2004.<br />

Fricke, Christel, <strong>Kant</strong>s Theorie des reinen Geschmacksurteils. Berlin: de Gruyter,<br />

1990.<br />

Frierson, Patrick R., Freedom <strong>and</strong> Anthropology in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Moral Philosophy.<br />

Cambridge <strong>and</strong> New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003.<br />

Ginsborg, Hannah, The Role <strong>of</strong> Taste in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Cognition. New York:<br />

Garl<strong>and</strong> Press, 1990.<br />

Gottsched, J. C., Versuch einer Critischen Dichtkunst: Ausgewählte Werke, eds.<br />

Joachim Birke <strong>and</strong> Birgitte Birke. New York, 1973.<br />

Gregor, Mary J., Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point <strong>of</strong> View. The Hague:<br />

Nijh<strong>of</strong>f, 1974.<br />

Grenberg, Jeanine, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Ethics <strong>of</strong> Humility: A Story <strong>of</strong> Dependence,<br />

Corruption <strong>and</strong> Virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005.<br />

Guyer, Paul, ‘‘Feeling <strong>and</strong> Freedom: <strong>Kant</strong> on Aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> Morality,’’ in <strong>Kant</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Experience <strong>of</strong> Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,<br />

1993.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Claims <strong>of</strong> Taste. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,<br />

1979.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Experience <strong>of</strong> Freedom: Essays on Aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> Morality.<br />

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> on Freedom, Law, <strong>and</strong> Happiness. Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 2000.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s Critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Power</strong> <strong>of</strong> Judgment, ed. New York: Rowman &<br />

Littlefield, 2003.<br />

Harris, H. S., Hegel’s Development: Toward <strong>the</strong> Sunlight 1770–1801. Oxford:<br />

Clarendon Press, 1972.<br />

Haym, Rudolf, Die Romantische Schule. Berlin: Gaertner, 1870.<br />

Heidegger, Martin, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Problem <strong>of</strong> Metaphysics, trans. James S.<br />

Churchill. Bloomington: University <strong>of</strong> Indiana Press, 1962.<br />

Helfer, Martha, The Retreat <strong>of</strong> Representation: The Concept <strong>of</strong> Darstellung in<br />

German Critical Discourse. Albany: State University <strong>of</strong> New York Press,<br />

1996.<br />

Henrich, Dieter, Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Judgment <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Moral Image <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> World. Stanford:<br />

Stanford University Press, 1992.<br />

‘‘Die Einheit der Subjektivität,’’ Philosophische Rundschau 3 (1955), ‘‘On <strong>the</strong><br />

Unity <strong>of</strong> Subjectivity,’’ trans. G. Zöller, in The Unity <strong>of</strong> Reason: Essays on<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s Philosophy, ed. Richard Velkley, Cambridge, MA: Harvard<br />

University Press, 1994.<br />

‘‘Fichte’s Original Insight’’ (in Contemporary German Philosophy, ed. Darrell<br />

E. Christensen et al. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University<br />

Press, 1982, pp. 15–53).


Bibliography 165<br />

Der Grund im Bewußtstein: Hölderlins Denken in Jena (1794–95). Stuttgart:<br />

Klett-Cotta, 1992.<br />

‘‘Hegel und Hölderlin,’’ in Hegel im Kontext. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp,<br />

1987.<br />

‘‘<strong>Kant</strong> und Hegel,’’ in Selbstverhältnisse. Stuttgart: Reclam, 1982.<br />

Konstellationen: Probleme und Debatten am Ursprung der idealistischen<br />

Philosophie (1789–1795). Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1991.<br />

Hölderlin, Friedrich, Essays <strong>and</strong> Letters on Theory, trans. <strong>and</strong> ed. Thomas Pfau.<br />

Albany: State University <strong>of</strong> New York Press, 1988.<br />

‘‘The Ground for ‘Empedocles,’ ’’ in Thomas Pfau, Friedrich Hölderlin: Essays<br />

<strong>and</strong> Letters on Theory. Albany: State University <strong>of</strong> New York Press, 1988.<br />

Hyperion or <strong>the</strong> Hermit in Greece, trans. W. R. Trask. New York: Ungar, 1965.<br />

On <strong>the</strong> Law <strong>of</strong> Freedom, pp. 33–34.<br />

Huch, Ricarda, Die Romantik: Blütezeit, Ausbreitung und Verfall. Hamburg:<br />

Rowholt, 1985 [1951].<br />

Jacobs, B. <strong>and</strong> P. Kain, Essays in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Anthropology. Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 2003.<br />

Kleist, Heinrich von, Werke in einem B<strong>and</strong>. Munich: Karl Hanser Verlag, 1966.<br />

Kneller, Jane, ‘‘The Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Dimension <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian Autonomy’’, in Feminist<br />

Interpretations <strong>of</strong> Immanuel <strong>Kant</strong>, ed. Robin May Schott. University Park,<br />

PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1997, pp. 173–189.<br />

‘‘Beauty, Autonomy <strong>and</strong> Respect for Nature,’’ L’Esthétique de <strong>Kant</strong>/<strong>Kant</strong>s<br />

Äs<strong>the</strong>tik/<strong>Kant</strong>’s Aes<strong>the</strong>tics. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1995.<br />

‘‘Discipline <strong>and</strong> Silence: Women <strong>and</strong> <strong>Imagination</strong> in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong><br />

Taste,’’ in Aes<strong>the</strong>tics in Feminist Perspective, eds. Hilde Hein <strong>and</strong> Carolyn<br />

Korsmeyer. Bloomington: University <strong>of</strong> Indiana Press, 1993.<br />

‘‘Fantasts <strong>and</strong> Fantasias: A <strong>Kant</strong>ian Theory <strong>of</strong> Imaginative Free Play,’’ Evelyn<br />

Dunbar Early Music Festival Symposium, Northwestern University,<br />

February 2003.<br />

‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s Concept <strong>of</strong> Beauty,’’ History <strong>of</strong> Philosophy Quarterly 3 (1986).<br />

‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s Immature <strong>Imagination</strong>,’’ in Modern Engendering: Critical Feminist<br />

Readings in Modern Western Philosophy, ed. Bat Ami Bar-on. Albany: SUNY<br />

Press, 1994.<br />

ed., Novalis: Fichte Studies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003.<br />

Korsgaard, Christine M., ‘‘Aristotle <strong>and</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> on <strong>the</strong> Source <strong>of</strong> Value,’’ in<br />

Creating <strong>the</strong> Kingdom <strong>of</strong> Ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,<br />

1996.<br />

Kuehn, Manfred, <strong>Kant</strong>: A Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,<br />

2001.<br />

Lacoue-Labar<strong>the</strong>, Philippe <strong>and</strong> Jean-Luc Nancy, trans. Philip Barnard <strong>and</strong><br />

Cheryl Lester, The Literary Absolute: The Theory <strong>of</strong> Literature in German<br />

Romanticism. Albany: State University <strong>of</strong> New York Press, 1988.<br />

Ladd, John, The Metaphysical Elements <strong>of</strong> Justice. New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965.<br />

Larmore, Charles, The Romantic Legacy. New York: Columbia University Press,<br />

1996.


166<br />

Bibliography<br />

Laursen, John Christian, ‘‘The Subversive <strong>Kant</strong>: The Vocabulary <strong>of</strong> ‘Public’ <strong>and</strong><br />

‘Publicity’,’’ Political Theory 14 (1986).<br />

Leibniz, Gottfried Willhelm, Philosophische Schriften, ed. C. I. Gerhardt. Berlin,<br />

1875–90, trans. Leroy Loemker, Philosophical Papers <strong>and</strong> Letters. Chicago:<br />

University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1956.<br />

Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim, Briefe, die neueste Literatur betreffend, 1759, Werke,<br />

ed. Herbart C. Göpfert. Munich, 1973, V.<br />

Hamburgische Dramaturgie, Werke, ed. Herbart C. Göpfert. Munich, 1973, IV.<br />

Laokoon, 1766, Werke, ed. Herbart C. Göpfert. Munich, 1973, VI.<br />

Longueness, Beatrice, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Capacity to Judge: Sensibility <strong>and</strong> Discursivity<br />

in <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998.<br />

Louden, Robert B., <strong>Kant</strong>’s Impure Ethics: From Rational Beings to Human Beings.<br />

New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.<br />

Makkreel, Rudolf A., <strong>Imagination</strong> <strong>and</strong> Interpretation in <strong>Kant</strong>: The Hermeneutical<br />

Import <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press,<br />

1990.<br />

‘‘<strong>Imagination</strong> <strong>and</strong> Temporality in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Sublime,’’ Journal <strong>of</strong><br />

Aes<strong>the</strong>tics <strong>and</strong> Art Criticism 42 [1984], pp. 303–315.<br />

Martindale, Colin, ‘‘How Can we Measure a Society’s Creativity,?’’ in<br />

Dimensions <strong>of</strong> Creativity, ed. Margaret A. Boden. Cambridge, MA: MIT<br />

Press, 1996.<br />

Molnár, Geza von, Novalis’ ‘‘Fichte Studies’’: The Foundations <strong>of</strong> His Aes<strong>the</strong>tics.<br />

The Hague: Mouton, 1970.<br />

Munzel, Felicitas, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Conception <strong>of</strong> Moral Character: The ‘‘Critical’’ Link <strong>of</strong><br />

Morality, Anthropology, <strong>and</strong> Reflective Judgment. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong><br />

Chicago Press, 1999.<br />

Neiman, Susan, The Unity <strong>of</strong> Reason: Rereading <strong>Kant</strong>. Oxford: Oxford University<br />

Press, 1994.<br />

Neubauer, John, Novalis. Boston: Twayne, 1980.<br />

Neuhouser, Frederick, Fichte’s Theory <strong>of</strong> Subjectivity. Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press, 1990.<br />

O’Neill, Onora, Constructions <strong>of</strong> Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University<br />

Press, 1989.<br />

‘‘Vindicating Reason,’’ chapter 9 <strong>of</strong> The Cambridge Companion to <strong>Kant</strong>, ed.<br />

Paul Guyer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.<br />

Pluhar, Werner, ‘‘Introduction to <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment,’’ trans. Werner<br />

Pluhar. Indianapolis <strong>and</strong> Cambridge: Hackett, 1987.<br />

Rawls, John, A Theory <strong>of</strong> Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,<br />

1971.<br />

Reath, Andrews, ‘‘Two Conceptions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Highest Good in <strong>Kant</strong>,’’ Journal <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> History <strong>of</strong> Philosophy 26 (4) (1988).<br />

Riley, Patrick, <strong>Kant</strong>’s Political Philosophy. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield,<br />

1983.<br />

Santner, Eric L., Friedrich Hölderlin: Hyperion <strong>and</strong> Selected Poems. New York:<br />

Continuum, 1990.


Bibliography 167<br />

Schiller, Friedrich, On <strong>the</strong> Aes<strong>the</strong>tic Education <strong>of</strong> Man, in a Series <strong>of</strong> Letters, trans.<br />

Elizabeth M. Wilkinson <strong>and</strong> L. A. Willonghby. Oxford: Oxford University<br />

Press, 1967.<br />

Schleuning, Peter, The Fantasia: 16th to 18th Centuries (I), trans. A. C. Howie.<br />

Cologne: Arno Volk Verlag, 1971.<br />

Schmidt, James, ed., What is Enlightenment? Eighteenth Century Answers <strong>and</strong><br />

Twentieth Century Questions. Riverside: University <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1996.<br />

Schott, Robin May, Cognition <strong>and</strong> Eros: A Critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian Paradigm.<br />

Boston: Beacon Press, 1988.<br />

‘‘The Gender <strong>of</strong> Enlightenment,’’ in Feminist Interpretations <strong>of</strong> Immanuel<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1997.<br />

Schulz, Gerhard, Fichte-Studien, in Novalis Werke. Munich: Beck, 1969.<br />

Seyhan, Azade, Representation <strong>and</strong> Its Discontents: The Critical Legacy <strong>of</strong> German<br />

Romanticism. Berkeley: University <strong>of</strong> California Press, 1992.<br />

Silber, John R., ‘‘<strong>Kant</strong>’s Conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Highest Good as Immanent <strong>and</strong><br />

Transcendent,’’ Philosophical Review 68 (1959).<br />

Smith, Norman Kemp, Critique <strong>of</strong> Pure Reason. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1929.<br />

Tugendhat, Ernst, Self-Consciousness <strong>and</strong> Self-Determination, trans. Paul Stern.<br />

Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986.<br />

Uerlings, Herbert, Friedrich von Hardenberg, genannt Novalis: Werk und<br />

Forschung. Stuttgart: Metzler, 1991.<br />

Van der Linden, Harry, <strong>Kant</strong>ian Ethics <strong>and</strong> Socialism, Trans. Paul Sten.<br />

Indianapolis: Hackett, 1988.<br />

Velkley, Richard, Freedom <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> End <strong>of</strong> Reason: On <strong>the</strong> Moral Foundations <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s Critical Philosophy. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1989.<br />

ed. The Unity <strong>of</strong> Reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994.<br />

Wilson, Holly L., ‘‘A Gap in American <strong>Kant</strong> Scholarship: Pragmatic<br />

Anthropology as <strong>the</strong> Application <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>ian Moral Theory,’’ in Akten des<br />

Siebten Internationalen <strong>Kant</strong>-Kongresses, ed. G. Funke. Bonn: Bouvier, 1991.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s Pragmatic Anthropology. Albany, NY: State University New York Press,<br />

2006.<br />

Wood, Allen, Self <strong>and</strong> Nature in <strong>Kant</strong>’s Philosophy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell<br />

University Press, 1984.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.<br />

Wood, David, Notes for a Romantic Encyclopedia: The Universal Brouillon.<br />

Albany: State University <strong>of</strong> New York Press, <strong>2007</strong>.<br />

Yovel, Yirmiyahu, <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Philosophy <strong>of</strong> History. Princeton: Princeton<br />

University Press, 1980.<br />

Zammito, John, The Genesis <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong>’s Critique <strong>of</strong> Judgment. Chicago: University<br />

<strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1992.<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>, Herder <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Birth <strong>of</strong> Anthropology. Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago<br />

Press, 2002.<br />

Zweig, Arnulf, <strong>Kant</strong>: Philosophical Correspondence 1759–99. Chicago: University<br />

<strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1967.


Abrams, M. H. 129, 149<br />

absolute, <strong>the</strong> (<strong>the</strong> unconditional) 140, 148<br />

tendency to seek 119 42, 159<br />

see also self-knowledge<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic ideas 16, 44, 53, 104, 105 7, 108,<br />

109, 120, 152<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflection see reflection<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tics<br />

German 1 3, 113, 152<br />

German Enlightenment 1, 1 6, 18, 38 45<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s see <strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

<strong>and</strong> rationalism in (Germany) 1, 2 3, 40,<br />

41, 42<br />

rules for 40 1, 152 3, 155, 157<br />

alienation 83, 84 6, 87 9, 89 94, 116, 139<br />

Allison, Henry 3, 8, 61, 94, 151, 152<br />

Ameriks, Karl 7, 13, 19, 73, 75, 81 4, 87, 90,<br />

111<br />

Arendt, Hannah 8<br />

art 44, 53, 56, 134, 151<br />

<strong>and</strong> nature 56, 67 9, 151, 154, 156<br />

as superseding philosophy (Novalis)<br />

autonomy, rational 74, 77, 80, 85<br />

Auxter, Thomas 8<br />

Bach, C. P. E. 154, 156<br />

Bach, Johann Sebastian 156<br />

Baier, Kurt 70<br />

Bauemler, Alfred 1, 2, 7<br />

Baumgarten, Alex<strong>and</strong>er G. 2, 14, 38 40<br />

beauty, <strong>the</strong> beautiful 15, 17 19, 35, 39, 44<br />

‘‘doctrine <strong>of</strong>’’ see Hölderlin<br />

ideal <strong>of</strong> 16, 70 1, 107, 108, 116, 120<br />

judgments <strong>of</strong> 15<br />

see judgments <strong>of</strong> taste<br />

natural (<strong>of</strong> nature) 64<br />

as symbol <strong>of</strong> morality 53, 107<br />

Beck, Lewis White 21, 38 58, 47, 51, 57<br />

Behler, Ernst 19, 22, 24<br />

Beiser, Frederick 7, 31, 47, 56, 113 15, 120<br />

Bernstein, Jay 7<br />

Index<br />

168<br />

Bodmer <strong>and</strong> Breitinger 1, 14, 40<br />

Böhme, Gernot <strong>and</strong> Hartmut 16, 97 104, 98,<br />

115, 120<br />

Bowie, Andrew 5, 7, 22, 28<br />

Br<strong>and</strong>t, Reinhard 8<br />

Burke, Edmond 66<br />

Cassirer, Ernst 136<br />

common sense/sensus communis 44<br />

common aes<strong>the</strong>tic sense/sensus communis<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>ticus 44<br />

communicability, universal 44, 53, 60<br />

community 10, 19, 35<br />

consciousness<br />

primary process accounts 153 8<br />

see also unconscious ideas/ideation 125,<br />

128<br />

self-consciousness 125 38, 145<br />

see also self-knowledge<br />

unconscious ideas/ideation 153 8<br />

contemplation see reflection<br />

creativity 19, 92<br />

see also imagination<br />

Crusius, Christian August 95<br />

Darstellung 4<br />

daydreaming 156, 158, 159<br />

disinterest/disinterested pleasure 4, 15, 24, 45,<br />

58 9, 60 71, 93 4, 116<br />

in metaphysical speculation 115, 119<br />

Earliest System-Programme <strong>of</strong> German Idealism<br />

120, 121<br />

Eldridge, Richard 87 8, 124<br />

elitism (moral, philosophical) 87, 112,<br />

115<br />

embodiment 70 1, 92, 117<br />

end(s), see purpose<br />

enlightenment, German 1, 18, 21, 38, 114<br />

enthusiasm/enthusiast 13, 16, 55, 99, 108 13,<br />

136, 119 42


Fantast see enthusiasm<br />

fantasy 156, 157<br />

see also imagination<br />

feelings 50, 53, 61, 80, 83, 86, 129<br />

in art 41, 135 6<br />

for beautiful nature 65, 66 7<br />

for belonging in nature/nature’s<br />

purposiveness 93<br />

as central to self-knowledge (Novalis) 144,<br />

145 6<br />

faculty <strong>of</strong> 76<br />

in Hölderlin 135 6<br />

<strong>and</strong> imagination 44, 53<br />

as an intuition 129<br />

metaphysical 117<br />

moral 63 4, 65, 66 7, 83<br />

in Novalis, defined 142<br />

universal communicability <strong>of</strong> 76, 88<br />

feminist critiques <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> 12<br />

Fichte, Johann Gottlieb 13 17, 20, 33, 35, 96,<br />

122 8, 140, 141, 145, 150<br />

Frank, Manfred 7, 122, 127 8, 129 30<br />

Frederick <strong>the</strong> Great 56, 57<br />

free fantasia 17, 153 7<br />

freedom<br />

<strong>of</strong> imagination see imagination<br />

moral/practical 45, 123<br />

Fricke, Christel 8<br />

Frierson, Patrick 8<br />

genius 13 17, 53<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s view <strong>of</strong> 13, 69, 104, 109, 112 13, 124,<br />

151, 154<br />

Lessing’s view <strong>of</strong> 41 2, 152<br />

Novalis’ view <strong>of</strong> 150<br />

see also Novalis<br />

Ginsborg, Hannah 8<br />

Gottsched, J. C. 1, 18<br />

Grenberg, Jeanine 112<br />

Guyer, Paul 7, 67, 89, 94, 108<br />

Hardenberg, Friedrich von 13<br />

see also Novalis<br />

Haym, Rudolf 122<br />

Hegel, G. W. F. 96, 120, 121<br />

Heidegger, Martin 16, 95 7, 120, 124<br />

Helfer, Martha 4<br />

Hemsterhuis, Frans 123, 143, 145<br />

Henrich, Dieter 2, 3, 7, 81, 95 8, 115, 123, 124,<br />

125, 127, 133, 134<br />

Herder, Johann Gottfried 114<br />

highest good/summum bonum 9, 38, 64, 66 7,<br />

89, 107, 114<br />

Index 169<br />

reason’s comm<strong>and</strong> to bring about 46 59, 64,<br />

89, 117<br />

supreme good (distinguished from highest<br />

good) 46<br />

Hölderlin 7, 16 17, 114, 121, 122 38, 141<br />

doctrine <strong>of</strong> beauty 134<br />

Hyperion 127, 134<br />

Homer 112<br />

hope, rational 9, 14, 46, 92, 106 8, 116, 120, 124<br />

feeling <strong>of</strong> 92, 93<br />

Huch, Ricarda 122<br />

Idealism, German 19, 33 6, 97, 122, 143<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> as idealist 33 6<br />

imagination, <strong>Kant</strong>’s <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>of</strong> 1 6, 14<br />

association with feeling <strong>and</strong> embodiment 97,<br />

120<br />

as common root <strong>of</strong> sensibility <strong>and</strong><br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing 95 8<br />

creative 19, 52, 92, 105, 109, 120, 151 60<br />

as dangerous 13, 112, 120<br />

distinguished from fantasy (involuntary<br />

invention) 156<br />

free play <strong>of</strong> imagination <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing 2,<br />

29, 44, 58 9<br />

freedom <strong>of</strong> (imaginative freedom) 35, 37,<br />

38 59, 103<br />

as inscrutable 13, 25, 29, 97, 149<br />

as mediating faculty 4, 15 16, 29, 92<br />

<strong>and</strong> metaphysics 13, 31 2<br />

productive 53, 100, 158<br />

reproductive 99<br />

role in cognition 2, 3, 99 100, 105, 150, 151<br />

schema/schemata/schematism 53 5<br />

as subordinate 13, 16, 95<br />

as transformative/reforming power/visionary<br />

13, 14 15, 57, 104, 105 7, 129, 148 9<br />

improvisation 154<br />

interest 15, 116<br />

<strong>of</strong> aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective judgments (judgments <strong>of</strong><br />

taste, judgments <strong>of</strong> beauty) 44, 60 71, 63<br />

direct 61, 63, 64 5, 68, 71, 75 93<br />

doctrine <strong>of</strong> 60 2<br />

empirical 62 3, 116<br />

indirect 61, 93<br />

intellectual 62, 63 5, 116<br />

moral 60, 61, 63 4,<br />

in nature 64, 76 93<br />

<strong>of</strong> universal communicability 60<br />

intuition 6<br />

as feeling (Novalis) 129, 147<br />

inner, outer perception (nonspatial, spatial)<br />

143, 147


170<br />

intuition (cont.)<br />

original/intellectual 6, 26, 112, 126, 127,<br />

128 30, 133, 141, 144, 147<br />

moral 120<br />

Jacobi 55<br />

Jena Circle see romanticism<br />

judgments <strong>of</strong> taste see taste<br />

<strong>Kant</strong><br />

anthropology 8<br />

as Copernicus 140<br />

<strong>and</strong> metaphysics 31 2, 47, 50, 82, 99, 113 19, 140<br />

‘‘<strong>the</strong>odicy <strong>of</strong> reason’’ 32<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s aes<strong>the</strong>tic <strong>the</strong>ory 1 4, 7, 17 19<br />

<strong>and</strong> environmentalism 67 9<br />

influence on romanticism<br />

see romanticism <strong>and</strong> metaphysics 16<br />

as ‘‘missing link’’ in German eighteenthcentury<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory 38<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s romanticism 23 6<br />

see also romanticism<br />

Kleist, Heinrich von 139 40, 147<br />

Klopstock, Friedrich Gottlieb 136<br />

Korsgaard, Christine 77, 90<br />

Kühn, Manfred 57<br />

Lacou-Labar<strong>the</strong>, Philippe <strong>and</strong> Nancy, Jean-Luc<br />

5, 6, 35 6<br />

Larmore, Charles 4, 124, 129<br />

Laursen, John Christian 57<br />

Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm 39, 114, 140<br />

Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim 14, 18, 38, 40 2, 58,<br />

113, 152<br />

see also genius<br />

Longueness, Beatrice 3<br />

Louden, Robert B. 8, 21<br />

love 66<br />

for nature 66 7, 117<br />

pathological 66, 69<br />

practical 66, 69<br />

reflective 66, 69, 71, 117<br />

Mähl, Hans-Joachim 143<br />

Makkreel, Rudolf 11, 24, 39, 44, 102, 105 6<br />

Martindale, Colin 153<br />

Mat<strong>the</strong>son, Johannes 153<br />

Mendelssohn, Moses 55<br />

metaphysics<br />

see <strong>Kant</strong> <strong>and</strong> metaphysics<br />

see Novalis <strong>and</strong> metaphysics<br />

Millán-Zaibert, Elizabeth 32<br />

Munzel, Felicitas 11, 29, 49 50, 65, 108<br />

mysticism <strong>of</strong> practical reason 108 10<br />

see also enthusiasm<br />

Index<br />

nature<br />

<strong>and</strong> freedom 123<br />

see also nature <strong>and</strong> reason<br />

<strong>and</strong> reason, unity <strong>of</strong> 83, 84 6, 88 9,<br />

123<br />

see also alienation<br />

Neiman, Susan 15 16, 47 8, 57, 92, 113<br />

Newton, Sir Isaac 112<br />

Niethammer, Friedrich 124, 128, 133<br />

Novalis 7, 13 14, 16 17, 20, 58 9, 114,<br />

122 38, 140 60<br />

critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>Kant</strong> 145, 146 9, 160<br />

Fichte Studies 127, 128 31, 141, 148<br />

genius 16 17, 150, 151, 152, 159<br />

Heinrich von Ofterdingen 131 2<br />

<strong>Kant</strong> Studies 143<br />

logarythmizing 22, 24 6<br />

<strong>and</strong> metaphysics 142 3, 146<br />

philosophy (distinguished from<br />

philosophizing) 27<br />

philosophizing 27<br />

potentializing (Potenzierung) 131, 146<br />

romanticizing 14, 21, 22 3, 146<br />

suicide 145n<br />

novel, <strong>the</strong> (der Roman) 31, 136 7<br />

O’Neill, Onora 12, 73 7, 76 93, 90<br />

philosophy<br />

distinguished from philosophizing (Novalis)<br />

27<br />

for Fichte 126<br />

for Novalis 130 1, 145, 148<br />

philosophical creativity (<strong>Kant</strong>) 148<br />

as ‘‘poetic’’ 131, 140 1, 145<br />

systematic 27<br />

Plato 109, 117, 119, 133<br />

pleasure 24, 29, 80 1, 88<br />

see also disinterest, interest<br />

Pluhar, Werner 28<br />

postulates <strong>of</strong> practical reason 9, 10, 15, 35,<br />

46 52, 82, 89 90, 91, 115, 116, 119<br />

practical reason 25, 72 94<br />

comm<strong>and</strong> to implement highest good<br />

see highest good/summum bonum<br />

metaphysical 15<br />

methodological 15, 73, 75<br />

primacy <strong>of</strong> 12, 15 16, 33, 35, 72 94<br />

progress, moral <strong>and</strong> social 9, 10, 32, 38, 42, 48,<br />

57, 106 8, 116, 120<br />

imagination 117 19<br />

purpose/purposiveness<br />

final 78 80, 84, 125<br />

principle <strong>of</strong> 79 80, 81, 86, 123, 155


purposiveness <strong>of</strong> nature 117<br />

purposiveness without purpose 154<br />

Rationalism 110, 116, 140<br />

see also aes<strong>the</strong>tics<br />

Rawls, John 72, 73<br />

reason<br />

fact <strong>of</strong> 25, 123<br />

practical see practical reason<br />

problem <strong>of</strong> reason 32, 45 6<br />

unity <strong>of</strong> see unity <strong>of</strong> reason<br />

Reath, Andrews 107<br />

reflection, reflective judgment 11, 23, 81, 101 2<br />

aes<strong>the</strong>tic; aes<strong>the</strong>tic reflective judgment 15 16,<br />

33, 43 4, 86, 107, 116 17<br />

as mirroring (Novalis) 129 30<br />

as source <strong>of</strong> value 78<br />

see principle <strong>of</strong> purposiveness<br />

technic/technique 102<br />

regulative principle(s) 6, 23, 34, 123, 142, 147<br />

Reinhold, Karl 13, 123, 125<br />

Riley, Patrick 8<br />

romanticism, German 1, 98, 121, 122, 140<br />

as irrationalist 1, 14, 16 19, 20, 23, 140, 147,<br />

150<br />

Jena Circle (early German romanticism) 13,<br />

20, 58 9, 122, 140 1, 160<br />

<strong>Kant</strong>’s influence on 4 7, 16 19, 20 36<br />

late romanticism (Heidelberg School) 141<br />

as naturalizing 22 3, 25<br />

romantic conception <strong>of</strong> mind 129<br />

Romanticizing 14, 22 3, 129 30, 131<br />

see also Novalis<br />

Rousseau, Jean-Jacques 14, 32 6, 109 117<br />

influence on <strong>Kant</strong> 32 3, 56, 99, 113 14, 115<br />

‘‘Rousseauistic’’ revolution 87 8, 91<br />

revolution 56 7<br />

French Revolution 57, 108 10<br />

‘‘Rousseaustic’’ see Rousseau<br />

Santner, Eric 136<br />

Sassen, Brigitte 152<br />

Schelling, F. W. J. 20, 96, 121, 134<br />

schema/schemata/schematism see imagination<br />

Schiller, Friedrich 7, 13, 14, 38, 58 9,<br />

128 34<br />

Schlegel, Friedrich 7, 20, 24, 114<br />

Schleuning, Peter 153, 155<br />

Schmidt, James 12, 20, 38, 55<br />

Schott, Robin May 12, 98<br />

Schulze, G. E. 125<br />

Schwärmerei see enthusiasm<br />

self-deception 112<br />

self-knowledge 124<br />

Index 171<br />

absolute self (knowledge) 127, 129, 130, 141,<br />

143<br />

in Fichte 125 7<br />

self-positing (Tath<strong>and</strong>lung, ‘‘fact-act’’) 126,<br />

142, 144, 145<br />

see also Fichte; intellectual<br />

intuition<br />

three principles <strong>of</strong> 126 7<br />

in Hölderlin 134<br />

in <strong>Kant</strong> 124 5, 142<br />

in Novalis 128 34, 141, 142, 144<br />

<strong>the</strong> seat (location) <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> soul (Sitz der Seele)<br />

143 5, 147<br />

self as regulative concept 142<br />

see also consciousness<br />

Seyhan, Azade 7<br />

Shaftesbury, Earl <strong>of</strong> (Anthony Ashley Cooper) 1,<br />

123<br />

Silber, John R. 51<br />

sociability 62<br />

Sömmerring, Samuel Thomas 143 4<br />

Spinoza, Benedict de 134<br />

spirit see genius<br />

Stark, Werner 8, 109<br />

sublime, <strong>the</strong> 17, 24, 111, 132<br />

supersensible, <strong>the</strong> 14, 28 30, 96, 149, 158<br />

Swedenborg, Emanuel 110 11<br />

taste 2, 60, 103 4, 106<br />

as discipline 103<br />

distinguished from genius (spirit) 152<br />

pure judgments <strong>of</strong> taste 15, 60, 116<br />

autonomy 11<br />

teleology/teleological judgment 8, 10, 98<br />

see also purpose<br />

Tugendhat, Ernst 125<br />

unconscious ideas/ideation 25<br />

unity <strong>of</strong> reason 15, 33, 76, 86<br />

see also unity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

unity <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject/subjectivity 5, 14, 35 6,<br />

38 58, 63, 95, 96 119, 123, 124 38,<br />

130<br />

contingency <strong>of</strong> 96, 133<br />

distinguished from unity <strong>of</strong> self <strong>and</strong> nature 123<br />

regress <strong>of</strong> subjects 126<br />

‘‘weakening <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject’’ 6<br />

Vereinigungsphilosophie 123, 133<br />

unsocial sociability 9, 118<br />

van der Linden, Harry 107<br />

Velkley, Richard 15 16, 32 6, 47, 57, 84 7, 115<br />

von Molnár, Geza 142


172<br />

Wiel<strong>and</strong>, Christoph Martin 112, 114<br />

Wilson, Holly 8<br />

Winckelmann, Johann Joachim 41<br />

Wolff, Christian 2, 39, 95, 114, 140 59<br />

Wood, Allen 8, 32, 35, 46, 52, 57<br />

Index<br />

Wood, David 7<br />

Yovel, Yirmiyahu 8, 47, 51 2, 55, 90<br />

Zammito, John 7, 8

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!