26.03.2013 Views

Terada - Looking Away (Selections).pdf - Townsend Humanities Lab

Terada - Looking Away (Selections).pdf - Townsend Humanities Lab

Terada - Looking Away (Selections).pdf - Townsend Humanities Lab

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

2 looking away<br />

ine would happen if these philosophers spoke more openly? Who, indeed,<br />

is hating whom?<br />

We hardly need Nietzsche’s indignation to remind us how thoroughly<br />

the language of appearance is taken personally, in actual exchanges and in<br />

philosophers’ fantasies of them. Stanley Cavell’s work has made the psychology<br />

of this strain a philosophical subject, focusing especially on one<br />

figure, the person usually referred to in the lonely singular as “the skeptic,”<br />

who seems to care inordinately about appearance and reality. Interpreting<br />

the mutually irritable conversation between the skeptic and her or<br />

his—almost always, his—interlocutors, Cavell explains that the skeptic is<br />

perceived as wanting something fundamentally unreasonable, something<br />

more than conditions on our planet can provide. Cavell interprets the<br />

skeptic’s language as a request for social acknowledgment in the guise of a<br />

failed epistemic statement. In his account, skeptical scruples about appearance<br />

and reality transmit fears and desires about interpersonal understanding:<br />

“acceptance in relation to objects” corresponds to “acknowledgment in<br />

relation to others.” 1 I’ll return to Cavell, since I share his emphasis on the<br />

infusion of the problem of appearance and reality with value judgments<br />

and psychological needs. Like Cavell in The Claim of Reason, I am interested<br />

in how one might feel about aspects of existence that, in their exigency<br />

and impersonality, transcend feelings. Such exigencies are often<br />

called “facts.” The notion of the “given” in the Kantian sense, meaning appearances<br />

that present themselves and the laws and limits that produce<br />

them, is another such figure of exigency, and the “given world” can function<br />

as a figure of the largest fact—not directly perceivable, but knowable<br />

through Kantian critique. 2 Nietzsche is outraged that anyone could imagine<br />

liking or disliking a necessity as powerful as “this world.” That he can<br />

be suggests that fact perceptions are normative, not only of actions, but of<br />

likes and dislikes, thoughts and feelings. We must not only take fact perceptions<br />

into account when navigating reality, but our feelings about them<br />

1. The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy (Oxford: Oxford<br />

UP, 1979), 454; Cavell refers as well here to his own “Avoidance of Love: A Reading of<br />

King Lear,” inMust We Mean What We Say? A Book of Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

UP, 1969), 267–353, p. 324.<br />

2. I’ll always use “given” in this sense, not the pre-Kantian one of the surfaces of<br />

things.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!