26.03.2013 Views

Terada - Looking Away (Selections).pdf - Townsend Humanities Lab

Terada - Looking Away (Selections).pdf - Townsend Humanities Lab

Terada - Looking Away (Selections).pdf - Townsend Humanities Lab

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

6 looking away<br />

Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, I’ll argue, sets up structures whose unfore-<br />

seen consequences Coleridge lives out. Coleridge becomes enamored of<br />

optical illusions and other visual ephemera (which he calls “spectra”) because<br />

they make no claim on his endorsement, over and against obsessive<br />

thoughts and memories, which he experiences as immutable internal facts<br />

(“spectres”). Although Coleridge considered himself a Kantian, his psychic<br />

life reads like an involuntary flight from critical philosophy, with its inexorable<br />

inner laws from which he seeks respite in the most transient and<br />

merely apparent phenomena he can find.<br />

In Chapter 2, I explain how Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason triggers the<br />

interest in offbeat perception in which Coleridge participates. By normalizing<br />

appearance (Erscheinung) and requiring its acceptance, Kant unwittingly<br />

encourages fantasies of aberrant perception that might escape his<br />

strictures and hence his recommended path to world-acceptance. To understand<br />

the resistance Kant inspires, it helps to understand that the First<br />

Critique proposes a kind of therapeutics: by establishing narrow limits for<br />

knowledge, the Critique of Pure Reason isolates minimal responsibilities of<br />

acceptance. What’s radical about the First Critique is how minimal Kant is<br />

willing to be: Kant would make accepting the world bearable by miniaturizing<br />

the endorsement due to it. Kant wants his readers to realize the given<br />

world’s limits—in the pejorative sense of liabilities as well as boundaries—<br />

in order to realize, secondarily, that the amount of respect we have already<br />

paid it in this very apprehension is all we owe. What Kant succeeds in conveying,<br />

however, is mostly that the world “as is” is necessarily appearance.<br />

So, in the new circumstances of replete appearance that Kant furnishes, to<br />

anyone who is not ready to accept Kant’s world aberrant appearance becomes<br />

suddenly indispensable. This result also bears implications for post-<br />

Kantian aesthetics. The Critique of Judgment excludes the most ephemeral<br />

and indefinite perceptions from aesthetic experience because they cannot<br />

sustain the thought of commonality that Kant wishes to affirm; from the<br />

phenomenophilic point of view, however, that’s exactly the appeal of these<br />

perceptions. Because no one can be imagined to share them, no one can be<br />

imagined to appropriate, benefit from, or push one to endorse them. They<br />

offer a glimpse, not of spontaneous accord but of freedom from the demand<br />

for agreement. Of course, spontaneous accord is itself a figure of<br />

freedom from the obligation to agree. But while Kant’s aesthetic is posi-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!