27.03.2013 Views

Revenge, Justice, and the Law

Revenge, Justice, and the Law

Revenge, Justice, and the Law

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

REVENGE, JUSTICE AND LAW: RECOGNIZING THE<br />

VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE AS A JUSTIFICATION<br />

FOR PUNISHMENT<br />

STEVEN EISENSTAT †<br />

I. INTRODUCTION: THE RAPE OF DINAH .......................1<br />

II. DEFINITIONS ........................................5<br />

A. <strong>Revenge</strong> .........................................6<br />

B. Legal ...........................................7<br />

C. Morality .........................................8<br />

D. <strong>Justice</strong> ......................................... 10<br />

III. THE MORALITY AND JUSTICE OF STATE IMPOSED<br />

PUNISHMENTS WHICH CAUSE SUFFERING ................. 11<br />

A. The <strong>Justice</strong> of Punishments Which Cause Suffering .......... 12<br />

B. The Morality of Punishments Which Seek To Cause<br />

Suffering<br />

............................................. 18<br />

IV. THE MORALITY OF REVENGE ........................... 22<br />

V. RECOGNIZING THE VICTIM AS A WRONGED PARTY ........... 29<br />

VI. REVENGE AS A SOURCE OF VICTIM EMPOWERMENT .......... 34<br />

VII. THE LIMITATIONS OF ALTERNATIVES TO REVENGE .......... 43<br />

A. Forgiveness as Mode of Victim Healing .................. 43<br />

B. Tort <strong>Law</strong> as A Model for Victim Healing ................. 47<br />

VIII. PLACING REVENGE WITHIN THE UTILITARIAN AND<br />

RETRIBUTIVE MODELS ............................... 49<br />

† Professor of <strong>Law</strong>, Suffolk University <strong>Law</strong> School. B.A. 1972, State University of<br />

New York at Buffalo; M.Ed. 1974, State University of New York at Buffalo; J.D. 1980,<br />

Nor<strong>the</strong>astern University <strong>Law</strong> School.<br />

I would like to express my gratitude to Dean Robert Smith, Suffolk University <strong>Law</strong><br />

School, for his valued support of this Essay. I am also grateful to Dr. Vivien Perge, <strong>and</strong><br />

Professors Russell Murphy, Marin Scordato, Ilene Seidman, <strong>and</strong> David Yamada, for <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

valued <strong>and</strong> insightful comments, which were often contrary to <strong>the</strong> conclusions which I have<br />

drawn in this Essay, <strong>and</strong> thus forced me to reconsider <strong>and</strong> clarify my own thoughts on <strong>the</strong>se<br />

issues. Lastly, I would like to thank my research assistants, Jennifer Stam <strong>and</strong> Richard<br />

Buckingham, as well as a former student, Jason Bielagus, for <strong>the</strong>ir help in locating <strong>and</strong><br />

identifying many of <strong>the</strong> source materials which I have relied upon in <strong>the</strong> writing of this<br />

Essay.<br />

1


2 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

IX. HOW TO INCORPORATE REVENGE INTO THE CRIMINAL JUSTICE<br />

SYSTEM .......................................... 52<br />

X. CONCLUSION ....................................... 57<br />

I. INTRODUCTION: THE RAPE OF DINAH<br />

In <strong>the</strong> Book of Genesis, <strong>the</strong> Bible relates <strong>the</strong> story of Jacob, one of <strong>the</strong><br />

founders of Judaism, <strong>and</strong> his daughter Dinah. Dinah was raped by<br />

Shechem, <strong>the</strong> son of Hamor <strong>the</strong> Hivite, <strong>the</strong> ruler of a neighboring city. After<br />

raping Dinah, Shechem fell in love with her, <strong>and</strong> sought to marry her. He<br />

beseeched his fa<strong>the</strong>r to help “Get me this damsel to wife.” 1<br />

Hamor visited Jacob <strong>and</strong> his sons, <strong>and</strong> conveyed to <strong>the</strong> Hebrews his<br />

son’s desire to wed Dinah. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, he promised that if Jacob agreed to <strong>the</strong><br />

marriage, that <strong>the</strong> Hebrews could intermarry with Hamor’s people, <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

<strong>the</strong> two tribes could be one. The Hebrews would be allowed to own l<strong>and</strong>,<br />

<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rwise prosper. 2 Speaking on his own behalf, Shechem offered even<br />

more than his fa<strong>the</strong>r, offering to pay any price so long as <strong>the</strong>y permitted him<br />

to marry Dinah. 3<br />

Dinah’s bro<strong>the</strong>rs responded to Shechem’s offer by stating that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

could never agree to <strong>the</strong>ir sister marrying a man who was not ‘one of<br />

<strong>the</strong>m,’ <strong>and</strong> that under Jewish law, that meant that Shechem, as well as all<br />

<strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r males of Shechem’s tribe, would have to agree to be<br />

circumcised. 4<br />

Shechem, his fa<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> males of <strong>the</strong> village agreed to <strong>the</strong> proposal.<br />

Accordingly all of <strong>the</strong> males were circumcised. 5 As one can imagine, given<br />

<strong>the</strong> ordeal of <strong>the</strong> circumcisions, <strong>the</strong> men were, to say <strong>the</strong> least,<br />

incapacitated. At that point, two of Jacob’s sons, Levi <strong>and</strong> Simeon entered<br />

<strong>the</strong> city. With weapons drawn, <strong>the</strong>y killed every male. They <strong>the</strong>n looted <strong>the</strong><br />

city. Thus was Dinah’s rape revenged. 6<br />

Jacob was unaware of his sons’ plans. When he learned of <strong>the</strong>ir acts,<br />

1. Genesis 34:1-5 (King James).<br />

2. Id. at 34:6-10.<br />

3. Id. at 34:11-12.<br />

4. Id. at 34:13-17. Male circumcision represented among <strong>the</strong> Biblical Hebrews, as it<br />

does today among most traditional Jews, a ritual which must be preformed if <strong>the</strong> male is to<br />

be considered Jewish.<br />

5. Id. at 34:17-24.<br />

6. Id. at 34:25-29.


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 3<br />

<strong>the</strong> Bible says that he rebuked <strong>the</strong>m, warning that <strong>the</strong>y now needed to be<br />

wary that o<strong>the</strong>r neighboring tribes would attack <strong>the</strong> Hebrews in retaliation<br />

for <strong>the</strong> killing <strong>and</strong> looting of <strong>the</strong> Shechemites. 7 To this, Simeon <strong>and</strong> Levi<br />

merely responded: “Should he [Shechem] deal with our sister as with an<br />

harlot?” 8<br />

The rape of Dinah <strong>and</strong> her family’s reaction to it, graphically illustrates<br />

both <strong>the</strong> allures <strong>and</strong> dangers inherent within revenge. Certainly, one can<br />

sympathize, <strong>and</strong> perhaps even applaud <strong>the</strong> motivation behind Dinah’s<br />

bro<strong>the</strong>rs’ act of revenge. 9 Their desire to see that <strong>the</strong> man who raped <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

sister is punished is underst<strong>and</strong>able, <strong>and</strong> arguably commendable as well.<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> consequences of <strong>the</strong>ir revenge raise very serious issues<br />

regarding both <strong>the</strong> justness of <strong>the</strong>ir punishment, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> repercussions of<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir acts.<br />

On a substantive level, <strong>the</strong> punishments were clearly unjust. The fact<br />

that <strong>the</strong> tribe’s entire male population was punished for <strong>the</strong> acts of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

prince, while recognized under <strong>the</strong> principle of collective responsibility as<br />

justice under many earlier legal systems, 10 clearly no longer is an acceptable<br />

basis for imposing criminal punishment. 11 Moreover, in <strong>the</strong> United States,<br />

<strong>the</strong> punishment of death for <strong>the</strong> crime of rape of an adult woman is no<br />

longer recognized as proportional in severity. 12 Thus, at least in hindsight,<br />

one would question both <strong>the</strong> scope <strong>and</strong> degree of punishment . And on a<br />

procedural level, <strong>the</strong> sons’ actions violated every modern tenet <strong>and</strong><br />

constitutional requirements of procedural due process. There was no arrest,<br />

7. Id. at 34:30.<br />

8. Id. at 34:31. Interestingly, <strong>the</strong> Bible appears to take no explicit position regarding<br />

Jacob’s sons’ actions. In contrast to Jacob, God nei<strong>the</strong>r scolds nor punishes Levi or Simeon.<br />

Perhaps one can even draw <strong>the</strong> conclusion that given God’s lack of any rebuke, such silence<br />

evinces God’s tacit, if not express, approval of Simeon’s <strong>and</strong> Levi’s acts.<br />

9. Apparently, <strong>the</strong> Bible is also silent regarding what measures of vengeance, if any,<br />

were desired by Dinah, <strong>the</strong> victim of <strong>the</strong> rape.<br />

10. WILLIAM IAN MILLER, BLOODTAKING AND PEACEMAKING: FEUD, LAW, AND<br />

SOCIETY IN SAGA ICELAND 180 (1990).<br />

11. SUSAN JACOBY, WILD JUSTICE: THE EVOLUTION OF REVENGE 139 (1983); Robert<br />

C. Solomon, <strong>Justice</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Passion for Vengeance, in WHAT IS JUSTICE? 253 (Robert C.<br />

Solomon & Mark C. Murphy eds., Oxford University Press 2d ed. 2000) (1990).<br />

12. See Coker v. Georgia, 433 U.S. 584, 592 (1977) (holding that a sentence of death<br />

was “grossly disproportionate <strong>and</strong> excessive punishment” for <strong>the</strong> crime of rape of an adult<br />

woman, <strong>and</strong> thus violated <strong>the</strong> Eight Amendment’s prohibition against cruel <strong>and</strong> unusual<br />

punishment).


4 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

trial, or right to counsel. 13 The sons served, in every sense of <strong>the</strong> term, as<br />

<strong>the</strong> judge, jury, <strong>and</strong> executioners of Shechem, his fa<strong>the</strong>r <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> men of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

city.<br />

Moreover, <strong>the</strong> repercussions of <strong>the</strong> revenge act concern society today,<br />

much as it did Jacob thous<strong>and</strong>s of years ago. Upon learning of <strong>the</strong> actions<br />

of his sons, Jacob responds “Ye have troubled me to make me to stink<br />

among <strong>the</strong> inhabitants of <strong>the</strong> l<strong>and</strong>, among <strong>the</strong> Canaanites <strong>and</strong> Perizzites: <strong>and</strong><br />

I being few in number, <strong>the</strong>y shall ga<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>mselves toge<strong>the</strong>r against me,<br />

<strong>and</strong> slay me; <strong>and</strong> I shall be destroyed, I <strong>and</strong> my house.” 14 Thus, Jacob’s<br />

admonition reflects <strong>the</strong> concern that revenge simply creates an increasing<br />

cycle of violence. 15<br />

Such was actually <strong>the</strong> case in many early civilizations which premised<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir system of justice upon revenge. “Blood feuds” often resulted after one<br />

family, seeking justice for an alleged wrong, sought revenge upon <strong>the</strong><br />

suspected wrong doer. 16 Even if <strong>the</strong> revenging tribe punished <strong>the</strong> actual<br />

wrong doer, <strong>and</strong> meted out a proportional punishment, <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong>se<br />

decisions were made by an interested party, <strong>and</strong> not by an impartial body,<br />

would often cast doubt upon <strong>the</strong> justness of <strong>the</strong> punishment. And with good<br />

reason. Given <strong>the</strong> emotional involvement of <strong>the</strong> revenger, it was entirely<br />

possible, if not likely, that <strong>the</strong> wrong person would be punished for <strong>the</strong><br />

crime. 17 In addition, ano<strong>the</strong>r concern would be that even if <strong>the</strong> correct<br />

person was identified by <strong>the</strong> revenger, that <strong>the</strong> punishment meted out by <strong>the</strong><br />

revengers, due to <strong>the</strong>ir emotional involvement, would likely be<br />

disproportionately severe for <strong>the</strong> crime which was committed. 18 Certainly,<br />

both of <strong>the</strong>se concerns presented <strong>the</strong>mselves in Simeon’s <strong>and</strong> Levi’s<br />

revenge of <strong>the</strong>ir sister’s rape. Thus <strong>the</strong> revenge act, as was feared by<br />

Jacob, ra<strong>the</strong>r than ending <strong>the</strong> matter, would simply perpetuate <strong>and</strong> escalate<br />

<strong>the</strong> disputes.<br />

Primarily for <strong>the</strong>se reasons, 19 we have come to realize that <strong>the</strong>re are<br />

13. See, e.g., U.S. CONST. amends. V, XIV.<br />

14. Genesis 34:30 (King James).<br />

15. JACOBY, supra note 11, at 67; MARTHA MINOW, BETWEEN VENGEANCE AND<br />

FORGIVENESS: FACING HISTORY AFTER GENOCIDE AND MASS VIOLENCE 11 (1998).<br />

16. Lynne N. Henderson, The Wrongs of Victim’s Rights, 37 STAN. L. REV. 937, 939<br />

(1984-85); MARVIN HENBERG, RETRIBUTION: EVIL FOR EVIL IN ETHICS, LAW, AND<br />

LITERATURE 60-61 (1990).<br />

17. JACOBY, supra note 11, at 118.<br />

18. MINOW, supra note 15, at 10; HENBURG, supra note 16, at 60.<br />

19. Solomon, supra note 11, at 253 (“It is because of <strong>the</strong> likelihood of escalation as well


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 5<br />

compelling reasons for <strong>the</strong> law to prohibit victims from exacting revenge.<br />

As a consequence, we have moved away from revenge cultures to societies<br />

where <strong>the</strong> state, as an impartial body, adjudicates guilt or innocence <strong>and</strong><br />

pronounces sentence. 20 Yet as a result of this evolution, <strong>the</strong> law has<br />

significantly, if not entirely, removed <strong>the</strong> victim from any involvement in<br />

adjudicating guilt <strong>and</strong> determining punishment. 21 Victims are not considered<br />

to be a party to <strong>the</strong> action. Indeed, with few exceptions, 22 <strong>the</strong> status of<br />

victims in <strong>the</strong> criminal justice system is indistinguishable from that of any<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r potential witness.<br />

This Essay will address whe<strong>the</strong>r revenge is immoral, per se. In so<br />

doing, it will differentiate between <strong>the</strong> morality <strong>and</strong> justice of revenge,<br />

suggesting that <strong>the</strong> former relates to <strong>the</strong> motivation of <strong>the</strong> revenger, while<br />

<strong>the</strong> latter deals with fairness of <strong>the</strong> punishment itself. 23<br />

I will next argue that it is not immoral for a victim to want to punish his<br />

offender so as to cause his offender to suffer; <strong>and</strong> that punishment which<br />

causes suffering is also just, so long as it is inflicted upon <strong>the</strong> party guilty of<br />

<strong>the</strong> offense, <strong>and</strong> is proportional to <strong>the</strong> level of harm suffered by <strong>the</strong> victim. 24<br />

I will next examine <strong>the</strong> reasons why revenge has been replaced by state<br />

controlled punishment. I will conclude that <strong>the</strong> shift was necessitated by <strong>the</strong><br />

need to ensure justice, <strong>and</strong> to prevent bloody <strong>and</strong> endless vendettas, <strong>and</strong> not<br />

because of any inherent immorality of revenge. However, fueled by<br />

religious doctrine <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> state’s desire to exp<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> centralize its power,<br />

as <strong>the</strong> possibilities of mistakes on a purely personal level...that <strong>the</strong> limitation of revenge<br />

through institutionalization becomes necessary.”).<br />

O<strong>the</strong>r purposes were served by replacing revenge with public retribution. Having <strong>the</strong><br />

State serve as <strong>the</strong> arbiter of criminal matters fur<strong>the</strong>red <strong>the</strong> shifting of power from local lords<br />

to a centralized monarchy. Henderson, supra note 16, at 940, citing 2 F. POLLACK & F.<br />

MAITLAND, THE HISTORY OF ENGLISH LAW BEFORE THE TIME OF EDWARD I 460-461<br />

(2d. ed. 1899) (1895). It also provided victims, who were too weak to exact vengeance on<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir wrongdoers, with <strong>the</strong> means to enlist <strong>the</strong> assistance of <strong>the</strong> governing authority to<br />

compel <strong>the</strong> appearance of <strong>the</strong> alleged wrongdoers. HEINRICH OPPENHEIMER, T HE<br />

RATIONALE OF PUNISHMENT 12 (1975).<br />

20. William F. McDonald, Towards a Bicentennial Revolution in Criminal <strong>Justice</strong>: The<br />

Return of <strong>the</strong> Victim, 13 AM. CRIM. L.REV. 649, 650 (1976).<br />

21. Id.<br />

22. See, e.g., infra notes 183, 241-43 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text (discussing victim impact<br />

statements).<br />

23. See infra notes 44-46, 50-51 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

24. See infra notes 52-89 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.


6 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

revenge has been deemed as an evil emotion, thus justifying <strong>the</strong> law’s<br />

marginalization of victims in <strong>the</strong> criminal justice system. 25<br />

I will <strong>the</strong>n argue that because of <strong>the</strong>ir status, victims deserve <strong>the</strong> right<br />

to be actively involved in decisions regarding punishment, even if <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

motivated by revenge, so long as <strong>the</strong>ir involvement does not jeopardize <strong>the</strong><br />

accuracy of <strong>the</strong> adjudication of guilt, or <strong>the</strong> fairness of <strong>the</strong> punishment. Such<br />

involvement may aid some victims to heal emotionally, <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> process,<br />

perhaps help rehabilitate <strong>the</strong> offender, thus satisfying <strong>the</strong> societal goals of<br />

Utilitarian <strong>the</strong>ory. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, I will suggest that such involvement can be<br />

justified under an exp<strong>and</strong>ed <strong>the</strong>ory of Retribution; one that recognizes <strong>the</strong><br />

victim’s, as well as society’s, interest in ensuring that wrongdoers are<br />

punished. 26 I will also argue that alternatives to revenge, such as victim<br />

forgiveness of his offender, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> filing of tort law suits, are often<br />

inadequate to meet victim needs. 27 I will <strong>the</strong>n conclude by offering a<br />

number of procedural mechanisms by which victim involvement in<br />

sentencing decisions can be enhanced. 28<br />

II. DEFINITIONS<br />

This Essay will evaluate whe<strong>the</strong>r revenge should be recognized as a<br />

legitimate reason for inflicting punishment by examining <strong>the</strong> legality,<br />

morality, <strong>and</strong> justice of a criminal justice system which countenances such<br />

a value system. Thus, I will begin by setting out how I will be defining <strong>the</strong>se<br />

concepts.<br />

A. <strong>Revenge</strong><br />

Webster’s Dictionary defines revenge as “to inflict damage, injury or<br />

punishment in return for (an injury, insult, etc.).” 29 In this Essay, I will refine<br />

that definition so that for act to be an act of revenge, <strong>the</strong> force used must<br />

25. See infra notes 90-126 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

26. See infra notes 127-89, 218-28 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

27. See infra notes 190-217 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

28. See infra notes 229-44 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

29. WEBSTER’S NEW WORLD DICTIONARY 1245 (Coll. ed. 1964) [hereinafter<br />

WEBSTER’S]. Interestingly, <strong>the</strong> word “revenge” is not defined in Black’s <strong>Law</strong> Dictionary,<br />

perhaps revealing <strong>the</strong> disfavor (or at least <strong>the</strong> perceived irrelevance) which even <strong>the</strong> word<br />

itself has under <strong>the</strong> law.


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 7<br />

be exercised by <strong>the</strong> victim or a close family member, to punish ano<strong>the</strong>r for<br />

his actions against <strong>the</strong> victim. 30<br />

A number of points should be noted about this definition. First, is <strong>the</strong><br />

lack of any requirement that <strong>the</strong> revenge be justified, or that <strong>the</strong> level of<br />

force used is reasonable. 31 The word, in <strong>and</strong> of itself, will be value neutral.<br />

Thus, an act of minimal violence (for example, a slap in <strong>the</strong> face), taken by<br />

a person who has been raped against <strong>the</strong> actual rapist, <strong>and</strong> an act of<br />

extreme violence (shooting with a gun), taken by a driver against ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

driver who has cut in front of him without properly signaling, would both be<br />

acts of revenge. Distinctions, <strong>and</strong> thus value judgements, will naturally be<br />

drawn between <strong>the</strong> morality <strong>and</strong> justice of <strong>the</strong> two acts, but both will be<br />

considered as acts of revenge. All that is required is <strong>the</strong> state of mind that<br />

<strong>the</strong> act is “pay back” for <strong>the</strong> injury subjectively felt by <strong>the</strong> victim.<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r point regarding state of mind. The revenger may be motivated<br />

primarily by hatred of <strong>the</strong> perceived wrong doer, a wish to see him suffer,<br />

or any o<strong>the</strong>r form of malice or ill will. 32 Indeed, such emotions may be <strong>the</strong><br />

sole reason for <strong>the</strong> revenge act. The reasons which motivate <strong>the</strong> act of<br />

revenge will be relevant to <strong>the</strong> morality of <strong>the</strong> desire to seek revenge; not<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> act is an act of vengeance. <strong>Revenge</strong> need not be motivated by<br />

any o<strong>the</strong>r “higher” ideal such as acting because one believes that all wrong<br />

doers should be punished, or any of <strong>the</strong> Utilitarian reasons such as<br />

deterrence or rehabilitation.<br />

Also of note, is <strong>the</strong> personal nature of <strong>the</strong> revenge. The punishment<br />

must be meted out by <strong>the</strong> victim, or at least someone with a close familial<br />

or friendship bond to <strong>the</strong> victim. 33 If such acts are committed by o<strong>the</strong>rs,<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r condoned or prohibited under law, <strong>the</strong>y will not be defined as<br />

revenge. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, I will refer to such acts by third parties, be <strong>the</strong>y vigilante<br />

30. CHARLES K.B. BARTON, GETTING EVEN: REVENGE AS A FORM OF JUSTICE 52<br />

(1999); ROBERT NOZICK, PHILOSOPHICAL EXPLANATIONS 367 (1981).<br />

31. BARTON, supra note 30, at 32.<br />

32. Webster’s offers <strong>the</strong> fur<strong>the</strong>r definition of ‘revenge’ by contrasting it with <strong>the</strong> word<br />

‘avenge’: “revenge implies <strong>the</strong> infliction of punishment as an act of retaliation, usually for<br />

an injury against oneself, <strong>and</strong> connotes personal malice, bitter resentment, etc. as <strong>the</strong> moving<br />

force,” whereas “avenge implies <strong>the</strong> infliction of deserved or just punishment for wrongs<br />

or oppressions.” WEBSTER’S, supra note 29, at 101, 1245 (emphases added).<br />

33. See BARTON, supra note 30, at 54. The term “avenge” has also been used to<br />

distinguish between <strong>the</strong> actual victim of <strong>the</strong> crime seeking vengeance against <strong>the</strong> wrongdoer<br />

(i.e. revenge), <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> taking of vengeance on behalf of <strong>the</strong> wronged party (i.e. avenge). See,<br />

e.g., WEBSTER’S, supra note 29, at 101.


8 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

groups or legally constituted governmental bodies, as motivated by a desire<br />

to seek retribution. 34<br />

B. Legal<br />

Black’s <strong>Law</strong> Dictionary defines <strong>the</strong> term “legal” as “conforming to <strong>the</strong><br />

law; according to law; required or permitted by law...” 35 My use of <strong>the</strong> term<br />

will comport with that definition. Notably absent from that definition is any<br />

judgement as to <strong>the</strong> morality or justice of <strong>the</strong> law. To answer whe<strong>the</strong>r a<br />

particular act is legal, I will simply refer to <strong>the</strong> positive, 36 written law of <strong>the</strong><br />

34. See generally BARTON, supra note 30, at 52-69; NOZICK, supra note 30, at 366-68.<br />

Barton, however, does view revenge as a form of retribution. See BARTON, supra note 30,<br />

at 54 (“While it is true that historically revenge has been <strong>the</strong> most prevalent form of<br />

retribution, it has not been <strong>the</strong> only one.”) (emphasis added). He refers to acts of revenge<br />

taken by <strong>the</strong> victim or those in personal relationship to <strong>the</strong> victim as “personal retribution,”<br />

<strong>and</strong> acts taken by o<strong>the</strong>rs such as vigilante groups or legally constituted governmental bodies<br />

as “non-personal retribution.” Id. at 79. In so doing, he attempts to illustrate <strong>the</strong><br />

commonalities between revenge <strong>and</strong> retribution, (most notably <strong>the</strong> concept of punishment<br />

per se), <strong>and</strong> thus disabuse <strong>the</strong> notion that revenge is an inherently immoral motivation, while<br />

retribution is not. Id. at 56-69. Yet while acknowledging that <strong>the</strong> two terms have such<br />

commonalities, he also stresses <strong>the</strong> intrinsic difference between two; that is <strong>the</strong> sense of<br />

personal involvement which is at <strong>the</strong> very essence of <strong>the</strong> revenge act. Id. at 52-56.<br />

This distinction, however, is not universally accepted, as <strong>the</strong> two terms are often used<br />

synonymously. See, e.g., Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 343 (1972) (Marshall, J.,<br />

concurring) (“Retaliation, vengeance, <strong>and</strong> retribution have been roundly condemned as<br />

intolerable aspirations for a government in a free society.”); JACOBY, supra note 11, at 4<br />

(“The very word ‘revenge’ has pejorative connotations. Advocates of draconian punishment<br />

for crime invariably prefer ‘retribution’—a word that affords <strong>the</strong> comfort of euphemism<br />

although it is virtually synonymous with ‘revenge.’”) (emphasis added).<br />

I believe Barton’s definition to be more precise <strong>and</strong> useful, regardless of whe<strong>the</strong>r he<br />

uses <strong>the</strong> term revenge or personal retribution, because it draws particular attention to <strong>the</strong><br />

personal nature which motivates <strong>the</strong> revenge act. After all, it is that very characteristic—that<br />

it is <strong>the</strong> one who has been victimized who seeks to punish <strong>the</strong> wrong doer—which<br />

constitutes <strong>the</strong> underlying <strong>and</strong> compelling justification for <strong>the</strong> act. Moreover, it is clear that<br />

legal <strong>the</strong>ory itself draws such a distinction, since it accepts retribution, that is public<br />

retribution, as a recognized motivation <strong>and</strong> goal for punishment, while it rejects revenge, or<br />

private retribution as a justification. See infra note 93 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

35. BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 803 (5th ed. 1979) [hereinafter BLACK’S].<br />

36. Id. at 1046 (“Positive law: <strong>Law</strong> actually <strong>and</strong> specifically enacted or adopted by<br />

proper authority for <strong>the</strong> government of an organized jural society.”).


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 9<br />

relevant jurisdiction. Any discussion of notions of natural law 37 will be<br />

framed within <strong>the</strong> context of <strong>the</strong> morality <strong>and</strong> justice of what <strong>the</strong> positive<br />

law declares to be a legal act.<br />

In assessing <strong>the</strong> legality of a particular act, I will refer to both <strong>the</strong><br />

procedural <strong>and</strong> substantive qualities of <strong>the</strong> act. For example, all procedural<br />

safeguards required by law must be complied with, such as <strong>the</strong> right to<br />

counsel <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> right to a jury of one’s peers. Also, <strong>the</strong> adjudication of<br />

innocence or guilt must comport with <strong>the</strong> substantive elements of <strong>the</strong> crime,<br />

such as demonstrating intent <strong>and</strong> harm inflicted upon <strong>the</strong> victim.<br />

C. Morality<br />

The first two definitions of <strong>the</strong> term offered by Black’s are:<br />

1. Pertaining or relating to <strong>the</strong> conscience or moral sense or to<br />

<strong>the</strong> general principles of right conduct.<br />

2. Cognizable or enforceable only by <strong>the</strong> conscience or by <strong>the</strong><br />

principles of right conduct, as distinguished from positive law. 38<br />

Thus, as compared to what is a legal act, which refers to written or<br />

positive law, an analysis of <strong>the</strong> morality of an act refers to natural law, or<br />

“general principles” of what is considered to be <strong>the</strong> “right” thing to do. 39<br />

Quite obviously, questions of morality raise many o<strong>the</strong>r issues, most notably<br />

whose st<strong>and</strong>ards of “right conduct” are to be used. As one of my students<br />

succinctly observed: “These questions of morality open up a whole can of<br />

worms.” Do we judge moral behavior society to society, so what may be<br />

acceptable as moral under one society’s moral code may be deemed as<br />

immoral under ano<strong>the</strong>r’s code? Do we judge moral behavior within <strong>the</strong><br />

context of <strong>the</strong> times, <strong>and</strong> thus excuse <strong>the</strong> institution of slavery if it was a<br />

commonly acceptable practice? Or are <strong>the</strong>re certain universal moral truths,<br />

37. Id. at 925 (“Natural law: This expression. . . . was intended to denote a system of<br />

rules <strong>and</strong> principles for <strong>the</strong> guidance of human conduct which, independently of enacted law<br />

or of <strong>the</strong> systems peculiar to any one people, might be discovered by <strong>the</strong> rational intelligence<br />

of man, <strong>and</strong> would be found to grow out of <strong>and</strong> conform to . . . . his whole mental, moral,<br />

<strong>and</strong> physical constitution.”) (emphasis added).<br />

38. Id. at 909 (emphasis added).<br />

39. See supra note 37.


10 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

which apply regardless of society or historical period? 40<br />

It is certainly outside <strong>the</strong> scope of this Essay to even attempt to resolve<br />

<strong>the</strong>se weighty issues. However, in examining <strong>the</strong> morality of revenge, I will<br />

be operating under certain assumptions regarding <strong>the</strong>se issues. First, I will<br />

view revenge through <strong>the</strong> lens of contemporary times. That is not to state<br />

that what has occurred previously has no bearing. Quite <strong>the</strong> opposite, as <strong>the</strong><br />

Essay will explore <strong>the</strong> his tory of revenge, from its acceptance as <strong>the</strong><br />

governing rule of punishment under blood feud societies, to present day. 41<br />

Indeed, it is a premise of <strong>the</strong> Essay that such an historical analysis supports<br />

<strong>the</strong> proposition that revenge has a rightful place within contemporary<br />

criminal justice systems. 42<br />

Second, my analysis will focus on <strong>the</strong> morality of revenge within<br />

contemporary American society. It will thus draw predominantly upon<br />

Western religious <strong>and</strong> cultural norms which have formed <strong>the</strong> basis for our<br />

current sense of morality. 43 As such, it is not <strong>the</strong> intent of this Essay to<br />

engage in a comparative study of revenge. That is certainly not to suggest<br />

that such studies are without merit; but ra<strong>the</strong>r only to acknowledge <strong>the</strong><br />

scope of this Essay.<br />

Third, <strong>and</strong> perhaps of greatest relevance, I will assess <strong>the</strong> morality of<br />

revenge in a very specific sense: I will focus on <strong>the</strong> reasons which motivate<br />

<strong>the</strong> desire for revenge, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n explore <strong>the</strong> morality of <strong>the</strong> motivation. 44 For<br />

example, individuals seeking revenge will likely be motivated by <strong>the</strong> desire<br />

to have <strong>the</strong> wrong doer suffer for her crime. 45 Motivation may also arise out<br />

of hatred for <strong>the</strong> victimizer, or a desire to set an example so as to deter<br />

future criminal acts. 46 Indeed, a revenger may be motivated by a number<br />

of <strong>the</strong>se reasons. The task <strong>the</strong>n will be to identify <strong>the</strong>se motives, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n<br />

40. See Monroe H. Freedman, Atticus Finch - Right <strong>and</strong> Wrong, 45 ALA. L. REV. 473,<br />

477 (1994). In this article, Professor Freedman analyzes <strong>the</strong> moral character of Atticus<br />

Finch, <strong>the</strong> lawyer who, in Harper Lee’s Pulitzer Prize winning novel To Kill a Mockingbird,<br />

defends an African American accused of raping a white woman in <strong>the</strong> 1930's in Alabama.<br />

The question he raises is whe<strong>the</strong>r it is “unfair to hold someone in an earlier time to moral<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ards that we recognize today. . . .[or is] morality...equated with <strong>the</strong> notions of right <strong>and</strong><br />

wrong that are recognized in <strong>the</strong> culture of a particular time <strong>and</strong> place.” Id.<br />

41. See infra notes 100-25 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

42. See infra note 126 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

43. See supra notes 1-8, infra notes 70-89, <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

44. See infra notes 90-99 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

45. See infra notes 62-69 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

46. See infra notes 57, 64, <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 11<br />

by reference to historical, religious, <strong>and</strong> cultural norms, evaluate <strong>the</strong> morality<br />

of <strong>the</strong> motives.<br />

D. <strong>Justice</strong><br />

Black’s defines “justice,” in a general sense, as <strong>the</strong> “[p]roper<br />

administration of law.” 47 In my discussion of justice, I will be differentiating<br />

between substantive <strong>and</strong> procedural justice. By substantive justice, I will be<br />

referring to what Professor K.B. Barton defines as “deserved punishment,”<br />

which will mean a punishment which is meted out to an individual who is,<br />

in fact, guilty of <strong>the</strong> accused crime, <strong>and</strong> a level of punishment which is<br />

proportional to <strong>the</strong> crime committed. 48 In some cases, to answer whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

a punishment is just will lead to an examination of some of <strong>the</strong> same issues<br />

which will be examined when discussing <strong>the</strong> morality of <strong>the</strong> revenge wish.<br />

For instance, is justice a universal concept, or is it also relative to society<br />

<strong>and</strong> time.<br />

47. See BLACK’S, supra note 35, at 776.<br />

48. BARTON, supra note 30, at 45. “In this sense, <strong>the</strong> justice or injustice of punishment<br />

imposed on a wrongdoer consists essentially in <strong>the</strong> observance or non-violation of certain<br />

basic principles, such as not punishing <strong>the</strong> innocent <strong>and</strong> not overdoing <strong>the</strong> punishment - by<br />

keeping it in proportion to <strong>the</strong> moral <strong>and</strong> legal gravity of <strong>the</strong> offense.” Id. These dual justice<br />

concerns regarding <strong>the</strong> accuracy of <strong>the</strong> adjudication of guilt, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> fairness of sentences, are<br />

basic tenets of our criminal justice system.<br />

To minimize <strong>the</strong> risk of wrongful conviction, <strong>the</strong> criminal law requires that <strong>the</strong> state<br />

prove its case beyond a reasonable doubt. See, e.g., WAYNE LAFAVE, CRIMINAL LAW 18<br />

(4th ed. 2003) (“[T]he law has always been concerned with <strong>the</strong> risk of innocent persons<br />

being subjected to criminal proceedings, <strong>and</strong> thus certain evidentiary tests must be met at<br />

several points in <strong>the</strong> criminal process. The strictest test, that which requires evidence<br />

‘beyond a reasonable doubt’ for conviction clearly rests upon <strong>the</strong> notion that it is better to<br />

allow some of <strong>the</strong> guilty to escape conviction than to risk conviction of an innocent<br />

person.”).<br />

Similarly, <strong>the</strong> requirement of proportional sentences is recognized as basic to our sense<br />

of justice. See infra notes 69-76 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text; see also MODEL PENAL CODE<br />

§ 1.02(1)(e) (“The general purposes of <strong>the</strong> provisions governing <strong>the</strong> definition of offenses<br />

are . . . . to differentiate on reasonable grounds between serious <strong>and</strong> minor offenses.”);<br />

§ 1.02(2)(c) (“The general purposes of <strong>the</strong> provisions governing <strong>the</strong> sentencing <strong>and</strong> treatment<br />

of offenders are. . . . to safeguard offenders against excessive, disproportionate or arbitrary<br />

punishment.”); § 1.2(2)(e) (“The general purposes of <strong>the</strong> provisions governing <strong>the</strong> sentencing<br />

<strong>and</strong> treatment of offenders are . . . . to differentiate among offenders with a view to a just<br />

individualization in <strong>the</strong>ir treatment.”).


12 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

When I refer to procedural justice, I will mean those procedural rights<br />

guaranteed under <strong>the</strong> United States Constitution, which are intrinsic to our<br />

sense that a party has had a “fair day in court.” Such rights would include<br />

<strong>the</strong> right to counsel, to be tried by an impartial jury of one’s peers, <strong>and</strong> to<br />

confront one’s accusers. 49<br />

There will be a crucial distinction between how I will use <strong>the</strong> terms<br />

justice <strong>and</strong> morality in evaluating revenge. While morality will be <strong>the</strong><br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard by which I will assess <strong>the</strong> motivation of those who wish to invoke<br />

revenge as a justification for punishment, 50 justice will be <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard by<br />

which I will measure <strong>the</strong> consequences or results of <strong>the</strong> revenge act. 51<br />

Thus, even if <strong>the</strong> victim acts out of a desire for revenge, were <strong>the</strong><br />

consequences just? In o<strong>the</strong>r words, did she act upon <strong>the</strong> person who<br />

actually committed <strong>the</strong> crime, <strong>and</strong> was <strong>the</strong> level of punishment fair? If so,<br />

<strong>the</strong> punishment would be just.<br />

This is not to suggest that foreseeable consequences of an act are<br />

irrelevant to <strong>the</strong> morality of that act. For instance, inflicting a punishment<br />

upon a party who one knows to be innocent of <strong>the</strong> crime would certainly be<br />

relevant to <strong>the</strong> morality of <strong>the</strong> motivation behind such an act. Similarly,<br />

inflicting a punishment which clearly is in excess to a proportional response<br />

to <strong>the</strong> crime would also reflect upon <strong>the</strong> morality of <strong>the</strong> motivation. In both<br />

cases, purposefully intending such consequences would be relevant to<br />

judging <strong>the</strong> morality of wanting to impose such unjust consequences.<br />

III. THE MORALITY AND JUSTICE OF STATE IMPOSED PUNISHMENTS<br />

WHICH CAUSE SUFFERING<br />

An argument raised against victim involvement in sentencing decisions<br />

is <strong>the</strong> concern that given <strong>the</strong>ir position, victims will be primarily concerned<br />

with revenge, <strong>and</strong> that such concerns should not be recognized as a goal of<br />

<strong>the</strong> criminal justice system. 52 If indeed one accepts this underlying<br />

49. See, e.g., U.S. CONST. amends. V, XIV.<br />

50. See supra notes 44-46; infra notes 57, 62-69, 90-99; <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

51. See BARTON, supra note 30, at 44-46; infra notes 56-69 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

52. See, e.g., Kent A. Wilson, Vengeance <strong>and</strong> Mercy: Implications of Psychoanalytical<br />

Theory for <strong>the</strong> Retributive Theory of Punishment, 60 NEB. L. REV. 276, 283 (1981) (“It is<br />

<strong>the</strong> duty of <strong>the</strong> state ra<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> individual victim to seek retribution from <strong>the</strong> offender.<br />

The victim of a crime is felt to be too subjectively <strong>and</strong> emotionally involved to exact a fitting<br />

punishment. Were <strong>the</strong> victim to exact punishment, such would be an act of vengeance ra<strong>the</strong>r


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 13<br />

assumption, (which for <strong>the</strong> purposes of argument, I will) that victims’<br />

interests in sentencing are motivated primarily to see that <strong>the</strong>ir victimizers<br />

“pay for <strong>the</strong>ir crimes,” <strong>the</strong>n we must determine whe<strong>the</strong>r such a goal is a<br />

legitimate reason for imposing criminal punishment. To resolve that issue,<br />

I suggest requires an examination of two propositions:<br />

1. That it is just <strong>and</strong> moral for society, through its criminal<br />

justice system, to seek retribution against those who violate its<br />

laws; <strong>and</strong>, if so,<br />

2. That it is also moral for society to permit its criminal justice<br />

system to be used as a means by which victims can satisfy <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

desire for revenge. 53<br />

A. The <strong>Justice</strong> of Punishments Which Cause Suffering<br />

In order to address this question, I will create a hypo<strong>the</strong>tical based upon<br />

<strong>the</strong> actual recent crisis concerning <strong>the</strong> sexual abuse of minors by priests<br />

within <strong>the</strong> Catholic Church. 54 For purposes of this discussion, I will change<br />

<strong>the</strong> actual facts in <strong>the</strong> following manner: The Church announces that it has<br />

than an act of punishment.”) (emphasis added); Jon Elster, Norms of <strong>Revenge</strong>, 100 ETHICS<br />

862 (July 1990) (“Prima facie, this motivation [for rational behavior] is incompatible with<br />

revenge behavior. The very definition of revenge. . . . shows that it involves only costs <strong>and</strong><br />

risks, no benefits.”) (emphasis added); C.S. LEWIS, THE PROBLEM OF PAIN 82 (1957) cited<br />

in BARTON, supra note 30, at 12 (“On yet a third level we get vindictive passion-<strong>the</strong> thirst<br />

for revenge. This, of course, is evil <strong>and</strong> expressly forbidden to Christians.”) (emphasis<br />

added). Of interest is that C.S. Lewis was a Retributivist, <strong>and</strong> thus believed that punishment<br />

per se, by <strong>the</strong> state was entirely justified. See infra note 63.<br />

53. See supra notes 33-34 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text (distinguishing between retribution<br />

<strong>and</strong> revenge).<br />

54. On February 27, 2004, <strong>the</strong> Archdiocese of Boston released <strong>the</strong> results of its report<br />

regarding <strong>the</strong> incidence of sexual abuse by priests within its archdiocese from 1950-2003.<br />

The report indicated that 162 priests, or roughly seven percent of <strong>the</strong> 2,324 priests in <strong>the</strong><br />

archdiocese, were accused of abusing 815 minors over <strong>the</strong> 53 year period. Michael Paulson,<br />

Diocese Gives Abuse Data, BOSTON GLOBE, Feb. 27, 2004, at A1. These figures have been<br />

challenged by some as lower than <strong>the</strong> actual number of cases. Id.<br />

On a national level, a report commissioned by <strong>the</strong> Catholic Church concluded that over<br />

<strong>the</strong> same 53 year period, 4,392 priests allegedly sexually abused 10,667 minors. Since 2001,<br />

approximately 700 priests accused of sexual abusive have been removed. Michael Paulson,<br />

Church Hierarchy Faulted by Lay Panel on Abuse: 700 Priests Removed by Bishops in 2<br />

Years, BOSTON GLOBE, Feb. 28, 2004, at A1.


14 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

identified a number of its priests who have confessed to Church officials of<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir abuse. However, <strong>the</strong> Church refuses to publically identify <strong>the</strong> priests,<br />

but ra<strong>the</strong>r assures state officials that it has “punished” <strong>the</strong> priests by taking<br />

<strong>the</strong> following measures: removing <strong>the</strong>m to a retreat where <strong>the</strong>y will never<br />

come into contact with minors, until <strong>and</strong> unless, through religious <strong>and</strong><br />

psychological counseling, <strong>the</strong>y are“cured” of <strong>the</strong>ir pedophilia. Let us also<br />

assume, contrary to studies, 55 that such counseling would cure <strong>the</strong> disease.<br />

The Church also promises to inflict more draconian measures upon any<br />

priests who abuse minors in <strong>the</strong> future, including reporting such priests to<br />

state officials for criminal prosecution.<br />

Have <strong>the</strong>se priests been punished? Certainly, in that <strong>the</strong>ir freedom (at<br />

least temporarily) has been curtailed, <strong>the</strong> priests would have been punished.<br />

But should <strong>the</strong> state, based upon that level of punishment, approve of this<br />

arrangement, <strong>and</strong> agree not to pursue any criminal action against <strong>the</strong><br />

priests?<br />

To resolve that question, entails an examination of why we punish those<br />

who break our laws. Under <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory of Utilitarianism, 56 developed in <strong>the</strong><br />

early 19th century, <strong>the</strong> purpose of criminal punishment is to effectuate<br />

positive social changes such as:<br />

1. Rehabilitating <strong>the</strong> criminal so that he will not commit <strong>the</strong><br />

crime again,<br />

2. Deterring <strong>the</strong> criminal (specific deterrence) <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>rs<br />

(general deterrence) from engaging in similar criminal behavior, <strong>and</strong><br />

3. Incapacitating (imprisoning) <strong>the</strong> criminal so as to protect<br />

society from his future wrong doing. 57<br />

55. Pedophilia is considered to be a non-curable, chronic disorder. It is unclear whe<strong>the</strong>r,<br />

<strong>and</strong> to what extent it is a treatable disorder. See generally Peter J. Fagan et al., Pedophilia,<br />

288 JAMA 2458, 2462 (Nov. 20, 2002).<br />

56. The 19th century philosopher Jeremy Bentham is considered one of <strong>the</strong> principal<br />

founders of Utilitarianism. See, e.g., Jeremy Bentham, The Rationale of Punishment, in THE<br />

WORKS OF JEREMY BENTHAM (C.J. Browning ed., 1962) (1838-1843) [hereinafter<br />

Punishment]; JEREMY BENTHAM, THE THEORY OF LEGISLATION 55-59 (C.K. Ogden ed.,<br />

Richard Hildreth trans., 1987) (1931) [hereinafter LEGISLATION].<br />

57. See generally RICHARD J. BONNIE ET AL., CRIMINAL LAW 11-30 (1997); Michele<br />

Cotton, Back With a Vengeance: The Resilience of Retribution as an Articulated Purpose of<br />

Criminal Punishment, 37 AM. CRIM. L. REV. 1313, 1316-17 (2000); see also MODEL PENAL<br />

CODE §§ 1.02(1) & 1.02(2) (explicitly incorporating many of <strong>the</strong> Utilitarian goals of<br />

incapacitation <strong>and</strong> deterrence <strong>and</strong> rehabilitation, respectively).


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 15<br />

Under <strong>the</strong> Utilitarian <strong>the</strong>ory, only if punishment fur<strong>the</strong>red such goals<br />

was it warranted. Accordingly, it would seem that <strong>the</strong> Church’s plan would<br />

effectuate <strong>the</strong>se policies, <strong>and</strong> thus meet <strong>the</strong> requirements of Utilitarianism.<br />

The goal of rehabilitation would be met since it has been stipulated that <strong>the</strong><br />

Church’s counseling efforts would be effective. Similarly, <strong>the</strong> goal of<br />

incapacitation would be met since <strong>the</strong> priests would be confined to <strong>the</strong><br />

retreat <strong>and</strong> not be permitted to have contact with children, until through <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

treatment, <strong>the</strong>y no longer posed a threat to children. Lastly, <strong>the</strong> deterrence<br />

goal would be addressed since, through its promise of harsher treatment of<br />

abusive priests in <strong>the</strong> future, <strong>the</strong> plan seeks to diminish <strong>the</strong> chances of future<br />

criminal behavior. 58<br />

But is this level of punishment just? Or, as a society, would we have <strong>the</strong><br />

right to dem<strong>and</strong> that <strong>the</strong> guilty parties’ punishment be greater? I suggest that<br />

<strong>the</strong> Church’s plan, even if it would satisfy all of <strong>the</strong> Utilitarian goals, would<br />

none<strong>the</strong>less, constitute an unjust punishment. Unjust, not as is usually<br />

assumed, because of its harshness; but ra<strong>the</strong>r due to its unjustified<br />

leniency. 59 In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> punishment would not be proportional to <strong>the</strong><br />

offense. Admittedly, <strong>the</strong> utilitarian social goals would be met, but where<br />

would <strong>the</strong>re be a sense that <strong>the</strong> victimizer has “paid” for his wrong doing?<br />

This concept of payment finds support under <strong>the</strong> Retributive <strong>the</strong>ory of<br />

criminal punishment. 60 As espoused by <strong>the</strong> 18th century philosopher<br />

Immanuel Kant, under this doctrine, society has <strong>the</strong> right to dem<strong>and</strong> that<br />

wrong doers must be punished, for no o<strong>the</strong>r reason than <strong>the</strong>y are wrong<br />

doers, <strong>and</strong> thus deserve punishment. 61 Indeed, I would argue that inherent<br />

58. Id.<br />

59. See, e.g., JACOBY, supra note 11, at 295 (“[P]roportionality has no meaning as a<br />

barrier to cruelty if it does not also place some restrictions on compassion.”); see also<br />

H.L.A. HART, Punishment <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Elimination of Responsibility, in PUNISHMENT AND<br />

RESPONSIBILITY 162 (1968) (“Trivial offenses causing little harm must not be punished as<br />

severely as offenses causing great harm; causing harm intentionally must be punished more<br />

severely than causing <strong>the</strong> same harm unintentionally.”) (emphasis added).<br />

60. See generally GRAEME NEWMAN, THE PUNISHMENT RESPONSE 190-200 (1978).<br />

61. IMMANUEL KANT, THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 195 (August M. Kelly Publishers,<br />

1974) (W. Hastie trans., 1887) (“Juridical Punishment can never be administered merely as<br />

a means for promoting ano<strong>the</strong>r Good ei<strong>the</strong>r with regard to <strong>the</strong> Criminal himself or to Civil<br />

Society, but must in all cases be imposed only because <strong>the</strong> individual on whom it is inflicted<br />

has committed a Crime.”) (emphasis in original).<br />

The United States Supreme Court, in upholding <strong>the</strong> constitutionality of <strong>the</strong> death<br />

penalty, recognized a societal right to retribution:


16 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

under Retribution <strong>the</strong>ory, for <strong>the</strong>re to be just punishment, <strong>the</strong> victimizer must<br />

experience a sense of suffering, 62 <strong>and</strong> that such suffering must not be<br />

disproportionally less severe than <strong>the</strong> suffering which was experienced by<br />

<strong>the</strong> victim.<br />

Without requiring an adequate level of suffering, a wrongdoer would not<br />

pay for his wrongful act. 63 Suffering may take many forms. It may consist<br />

of loss of freedom through incarceration, loss of financial assets through<br />

fines, <strong>and</strong> perhaps even loss of life. Suffering need not be a distinct <strong>and</strong><br />

separate element of punishment. For example, by imposing <strong>the</strong> punishment<br />

of incarceration, <strong>the</strong> dual goals of incapacity <strong>and</strong> suffering could be<br />

The instinct for retribution is part of <strong>the</strong> nature of man, <strong>and</strong> channeling that<br />

instinct in <strong>the</strong> administration of criminal justice serves an important purpose in<br />

promoting <strong>the</strong> stability of a society governed by law. When people begin to<br />

believe that organized society is unwilling or unable to impose upon criminal<br />

offenders <strong>the</strong> punishment <strong>the</strong>y “deserve,” <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong>re are sown <strong>the</strong> seeds of<br />

anarchy of self- help, vigilante justice, <strong>and</strong> lynch law.<br />

Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153, 183 (1976), citing Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 308<br />

(1972) (Stewart, J., concurring).<br />

One criticism of Retribution is that its justification relies upon its own assertion that<br />

a “wrongful act must be punished.” See, e.g., Wilson, supra note 52, at 281 (“To justify<br />

punishment on <strong>the</strong> grounds that punishment is ‘just’ or ‘morally good’ is circular.”). In<br />

response to this criticism, Graeme Newman argues that it is possible for a statement to be<br />

inherently right, <strong>and</strong> so argues that “<strong>the</strong> statement ‘A wrongful act must be punished’ is not<br />

just an assertion, it is a statement of fact. There has never been a time in history when<br />

wrongful acts (that were perceived as wrongful acts) were rewarded. In fact, such a<br />

possibility is plainly ridiculous.” Id. at 191.<br />

62. See, e.g., HART, Prolegomenon to <strong>the</strong> Principles of Punishment, 4 (xxxx) (“It<br />

[Punishment] must involve pain or o<strong>the</strong>r consequences normally considered unpleasant.”);<br />

HART, Postscript: Responsibility <strong>and</strong> Retribution, supra note 59, at 231 (“The justification<br />

for punishing men under such conditions is that <strong>the</strong> return of suffering for moral evil<br />

voluntary done, is itself just or morally good.”).<br />

63. Barton also argues that retribution recognizes <strong>the</strong> wrongdoer as a mature <strong>and</strong><br />

competent individual by holding him accountable for his wrongful acts. BARTON, supra note<br />

30, at 97. C.S. Lewis argued similarly, <strong>and</strong> in so doing criticized <strong>the</strong> Utilitarians:<br />

Their very kindness stings with intolerable insult. To be “cured” against one’s will<br />

. . . ..is to be put on a level with those who have not yet reached <strong>the</strong> age of reason or<br />

those who never will. . . ...But to be punished, however severely, because we have<br />

deserved it, because we “ought to have known better” is to be treated as a human<br />

person made in God’s image.<br />

C.S. Lewis, The Humanitarian Theory of Punishment, in 6 RES JUDICATAE 224, 228 (1953).


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 17<br />

effectuated. 64 For <strong>the</strong> length of <strong>the</strong> sentence, society is protected by <strong>the</strong><br />

incarceration, while at <strong>the</strong> same time, through <strong>the</strong> loss of personal liberty,<br />

<strong>the</strong> punishment contains <strong>the</strong> element of suffering.<br />

Failure to include suffering as an essential element of punishment, <strong>and</strong><br />

relying solely upon <strong>the</strong> Utilitarian goals for justifying punishment, could lead<br />

to inordinately lenient, <strong>and</strong> I would argue, unjust punishments. For example,<br />

returning to <strong>the</strong> Church hypo<strong>the</strong>tical discussed above, suppose that <strong>the</strong><br />

abusive priests did not object, but ra<strong>the</strong>r welcomed <strong>the</strong>ir reassignments to<br />

<strong>the</strong> pastoral retreat. One could thus argue that <strong>the</strong>y would experience no<br />

suffering at all from <strong>the</strong>ir “punishment” of temporary exile. And yet, since<br />

<strong>the</strong> Utilitarian goals of incapacity, deterrence, <strong>and</strong> rehabilitation would still<br />

be met, one could still characterize that plan as a just punishment. It is only<br />

when we include <strong>the</strong> requirement that <strong>the</strong> victimizer must pay for his<br />

wrongs through his suffering, that we give real meaning to <strong>the</strong> concept of<br />

punishment, <strong>and</strong> thus construct a st<strong>and</strong>ard by which we can weigh whe<strong>the</strong>r<br />

a plan such as proposed above for punishing <strong>the</strong> abusive priests is adequate<br />

<strong>and</strong> just.<br />

The need to include within punishment a sense of suffering can be<br />

illustrated by <strong>the</strong> following: Pedophilia is recognized by <strong>the</strong> medical<br />

profession as an incurable mental disease. 65 There is also disagreement<br />

within <strong>the</strong> medical community regarding whe<strong>the</strong>r treatment is effective in<br />

reducing <strong>the</strong> recidivism of sexual offenses. 66 Thus it is unclear whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

goal of rehabilitation can be fur<strong>the</strong>red through punishment of <strong>the</strong> offender.<br />

Moreover, it is also unlikely that <strong>the</strong> threat of imprisonment or o<strong>the</strong>r criminal<br />

sanctions would be sufficient so as to deter future acts of sexual abuse. 67<br />

Therefore, due to <strong>the</strong>se medical realities, two of <strong>the</strong> primary justifications<br />

for punishment under Utilitarianism, rehabilitation <strong>and</strong> deterrence, would<br />

probably not be met by imprisoning those found guilty of child sexual abuse.<br />

This leaves incapacity as <strong>the</strong> remaining Utilitarian justification for<br />

incarceration. Yet it is also questionable whe<strong>the</strong>r using incapacity as <strong>the</strong><br />

64. BARTON, supra note 30, at 89 (“Retributivists need not deny, of course, that good<br />

consequences, such as deterrence . . . . <strong>and</strong> desirable functions . . . . are highly relevant to<br />

justifying punishment in instrumental <strong>and</strong> functional ways.”).<br />

65. See supra note 55.<br />

66. See, e.g., Linda S. Grossman et al., Are Sex Offenders Treatable? A Research<br />

Overview, 50 PSYCHIATRIC SERVICES 356-58 (Mar. 1999).<br />

67. See, e.g., Bhagwan A. Bahroo, Pedophilia: Psychiatric Insights, 41 FAM. CT. REV.<br />

497 (2003).


18 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

sole justification for imprisonment would suffice, since one could argue that<br />

if all we are concerned with is that society be protected, that end could be<br />

met by less drastic, <strong>and</strong> less costly sanctions. For instance, <strong>the</strong> offender<br />

could be fitted with an electronic bracelet which would monitor his travels,<br />

be placed in a secure half-way house, <strong>and</strong> prohibited any contact with<br />

minors. If such a plan, or any o<strong>the</strong>r one, would be found to adequately<br />

protect society, <strong>the</strong> goal of incapacity would be met.<br />

But would such a plan be an adequate, <strong>and</strong> thus just punishment? I<br />

would argue that it would not, because of <strong>the</strong> lack of proportionality<br />

between <strong>the</strong> crime <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> punishment. Society, through its laws has<br />

recognized that for <strong>the</strong> crime of sexual abuse on a minor, a proportional<br />

punishment must include more than a relatively slight abridgement of one’s<br />

freedom of travel. 68 And yet, electronic monitoring would only fail <strong>the</strong><br />

proportionality test if we include within <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard of measuring<br />

proportionality <strong>the</strong> requirement of suffering.<br />

Indeed, <strong>the</strong> whole concept of proportionality of punishment is based<br />

upon <strong>the</strong> assumption that punishment includes suffering. Proportionality<br />

weighs <strong>the</strong> seriousness of <strong>the</strong> crime to <strong>the</strong> severity of <strong>the</strong> punishment. 69<br />

68. See, e.g., TEX. PENAL CODE ANN. § 12.32 (Vernon 2005) (punishing first degree<br />

felonies, which includes aggravated assault of a child pursuant to section 22.021, with no less<br />

than five years <strong>and</strong> not more than life imprisonment); VA. CODE ANN. § 18.2-61(C) (Michie<br />

2005) (punishing rape with no less than five years <strong>and</strong> no more than life imprisonment); LA.<br />

REV. STAT. § 14:42(D)(2) (punishing aggravated rape of a victim under twelve years old<br />

with life imprisonment or death).<br />

69. See generally HART, supra note 59, at 160-70; Wilson, supra note 52, at 284-87.<br />

Some critics of Retribution fault <strong>the</strong> imprecision of proportionality as one of <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>ory’s<br />

flaws:<br />

Retributivists very commonly direct us to make punishments ‘proportional’ to<br />

crimes. . . . Unfortunately this prescription by itself cannot tell us what punishment<br />

any particular crime deserves even if we could rank every crime in a single scale from<br />

least to most serious. For <strong>the</strong> prescription requires only that we assign greater penalties<br />

as we ascend <strong>the</strong> scale of crimes, without ei<strong>the</strong>r supplying a starting point (<strong>the</strong> penalty<br />

for <strong>the</strong> least serious offense) or telling us by how much to increase <strong>the</strong> penalty as we<br />

move from one crime to <strong>the</strong> next in <strong>the</strong> scale.<br />

David Dolinko, Three Mistakes of Retributivism, 39 UCLA L. REV. 1623, 1636 (1992)<br />

(emphasis added). See also Wilson, supra note 52, at 284 (“Although balancing <strong>the</strong><br />

punishment <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> injury is conceptually simple, determining <strong>the</strong> specific nature of <strong>the</strong><br />

punishment to be inflicted presents a more difficult issue.”).<br />

Generally, I find such arguments against proportionality not to be very persuasive.<br />

Once a criminal justice system moves away from a strict “eye for an eye” approach to


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 19<br />

Without requiring <strong>the</strong> wrong doer’s suffering as an essential element of<br />

punishment, what would <strong>the</strong> seriousness of <strong>the</strong> crime be balanced with? The<br />

level of rehabilitation, deterrence, incapacity? It is only when <strong>the</strong> guilty<br />

suffers through his punishment, can we engage in <strong>the</strong> calculus of<br />

proportionality.<br />

One could, I suppose, argue that suffering is irrelevant to punis hment;<br />

that any suffering caused by punishment is unintentional <strong>and</strong> merely<br />

incidental to <strong>the</strong> attainment of one or more of <strong>the</strong> Utilitarian goals. If so,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n it would follow that any level of punishment would be permissible in<br />

order to achieve <strong>the</strong> goals. For example, why not inflict <strong>the</strong> death penalty<br />

for driving while intoxicated? Such a penalty would probably significantly<br />

reduce highway fatalities. But clearly, such a level of punishment would be<br />

unjust (<strong>and</strong> unconstitutional), because <strong>the</strong> severity of suffering would be<br />

deemed to be disproportionate to <strong>the</strong> crime. Thus, level of suffering is<br />

always relevant to <strong>the</strong> extent of punishment. In addition, one would have to<br />

question a legal system which would permit punishment to cause suffering,<br />

but would not accept <strong>the</strong> morality of allowing such suffering.<br />

B. The Morality of Punishments Which Seek To Cause Suffering<br />

A common response to <strong>the</strong> proposition that for a punishment to be just,<br />

punishment, <strong>and</strong> thus no longer requires <strong>the</strong> identical punishment for <strong>the</strong> wrong committed,<br />

it must, of necessity engage in relative comparisons, unless it opts for eliminating<br />

punishment altoge<strong>the</strong>r. Exact precision <strong>and</strong> uniformity are no longer possible.<br />

However, some seem to be too forgiving when <strong>the</strong>y argue that <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of<br />

proportionality is only dependant upon what “society at that time considers proportional<br />

to <strong>the</strong> seriousness of <strong>the</strong> offense.” Stephen J. Morse, <strong>Justice</strong>, Mercy <strong>and</strong> Craziness, 36<br />

STAN. L. REV. 1485, 1493-94 (1984) (reviewing NORVAL MORRIS, MADNESS AND THE<br />

CRIMINAL LAW (1982)). (“This is <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> deserved punishment at that time <strong>and</strong> in that<br />

place.”) Id. Such a blanket defense would appear to countenance any level of punishment,<br />

so long as society, at that time considers it to be proportional to <strong>the</strong> crime. Putting aside<br />

those instances where society has, with no moral basis, criminalized behavior, such as<br />

torturing <strong>and</strong> killing of individuals based purely upon <strong>the</strong>ir religious beliefs, affording such<br />

deference to societal st<strong>and</strong>ards could also result in unjust punishments for behavior which<br />

could morally be defined as criminal. For instance, what of a society, which through its legal<br />

system, permits extreme physical punishment for very slight offenses. Even while<br />

recognizing <strong>the</strong> problem of defining what is a “slight”offense, I question a definition of<br />

proportionality which rejects <strong>the</strong> setting of any limitation upon what any society, at any<br />

given time, may consider just punishment.


20 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

it must include proportional suffering for <strong>the</strong> wrong doer, is that such a<br />

requirement represents nothing more than seeking, in <strong>the</strong> words of <strong>the</strong><br />

famous Biblical passage: “an eye for an eye,” 70 ( also referred to as lex<br />

talionis ) 71 <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore, ipso facto, is immoral. 72 While I agree that<br />

requiring a measure of suffering by <strong>the</strong> wrong doer does include elements<br />

of an “eye for an eye” mentality, for a number of reasons, I do not agree<br />

with <strong>the</strong> resulting conclusion which would thus invalidate <strong>the</strong> requirement<br />

as immoral.<br />

First, it has been noted by numerous scholars that <strong>the</strong> passage actually<br />

imposed a proportionality requirement on <strong>the</strong> level of punishment; that it<br />

really was meant to limit <strong>the</strong> harshness of punishment. 73 In Biblical times,<br />

punishment could often far exceed <strong>the</strong> crime itself. Thus, <strong>the</strong> eye for eye<br />

70. Exodus 21:23-25 (King James) (“And if any mischief follow, <strong>the</strong>n thou shalt give<br />

life for life, eye for eye, tooth for tooth, h<strong>and</strong> for h<strong>and</strong>, foot for foot, burning for burning,<br />

wound for wound, stripe for stripe.”). Read in <strong>the</strong>ir entirety, Chapters 21 <strong>and</strong> 22 of <strong>the</strong><br />

Book of Exodus, in fact set forth God’s pronouncements of justice regarding proportionality<br />

of punishment to offense.<br />

71. The term lex talionis denotes a system of justice “which requires <strong>the</strong> infliction upon<br />

a wrongdoer of <strong>the</strong> same injury which he has caused to ano<strong>the</strong>r.” BLACK’S, supra note 35,<br />

at 822. See, e.g., OPPENHEIMER, supra note 19, at 9; NEWMAN, supra note 60, at 29. Of<br />

course, <strong>the</strong>re are some problems with judging just what constitutes <strong>the</strong> “same punishment.”<br />

For example, Lord Blackstone posed <strong>the</strong> problem “what is <strong>the</strong> equivalent harm when a twoeye’d<br />

man knocks out <strong>the</strong> eye of a one-eye’d man?” Solomon, supra note 11, at 257.<br />

Perhaps <strong>the</strong> best that can be said for proportionality is that we recognize <strong>the</strong> lack of it, when<br />

<strong>the</strong> punishment clearly exceeds <strong>the</strong> crime. Id.<br />

72. For example, Utilitarians explicitly reject lex talionis as a basis for punishment, even<br />

if <strong>the</strong> concept is employed as a means to limit <strong>the</strong> level of punishment. For Utilitarians,<br />

punishment can only be justified if it serves to fur<strong>the</strong>r one or more of <strong>the</strong> positive social<br />

goals set out earlier. See supra notes 56-57 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text. See also Punishment,<br />

supra note 56, at 397 (“If we consider an offense which has been committed as an isolated<br />

fact, <strong>the</strong> like of which would never recur, punishment would be useless. . . . .[A]ll<br />

punishment being in itself evil, upon <strong>the</strong> principle of utility, if it ought at all to be admitted,<br />

it ought only to be admitted in as far as it promises to exclude some greater evil.”).<br />

73. See, e.g., JACOBY, supra note 11, at 132 (“It [an eye for an eye] is a statement of<br />

legal proportionality as a limitation on ra<strong>the</strong>r than a blueprint for penalties so brutal in <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

reciprocity. . . . [as to] be regarded as criminal acts ra<strong>the</strong>r than instruments of just<br />

retribution.”); OPPENHEIMER, supra note 19, at 8-9 (“It is at this epoch, too, that vengeance,<br />

at first boundless, has its wings clipped <strong>and</strong> is reduced to <strong>the</strong> proportions prescribed by <strong>the</strong><br />

ubiquitous lex talionis.”); see generally HEMBERG, supra note 16, at 59-76 (detailing <strong>the</strong><br />

evolution of <strong>the</strong> doctrine of lex talionis as <strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard for determining <strong>the</strong> level of just<br />

punishment).


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 21<br />

requirement was set so as to limit punishments to a level that could be no<br />

greater than <strong>the</strong> level of <strong>the</strong> crime, <strong>and</strong> thus is a limitation regarding <strong>the</strong><br />

justness of <strong>the</strong> punishment, not whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> desire for such a punishment<br />

is moral. Under that interpretation, I take no issue with <strong>the</strong> passage, sinc e<br />

it would only impose a proportionality requirement which, I would agree, is<br />

intrinsic to any concept of just punishment. 74 It would not, however, prohibit<br />

suffering as an essential requirement for punishment, so long as such<br />

suffering was proportional to <strong>the</strong> harm suffered by <strong>the</strong> victim.<br />

Second, it is difficult for me to comprehend <strong>the</strong> basis for arguments<br />

which maintain <strong>the</strong> moral unacceptability of punishment which causes<br />

suffering, when, at least under Western religions, we are taught of a God,<br />

who repeatedly metes out punishments which include a great deal of<br />

suffering. The Bible is replete with such examples. For instance, when God<br />

destroys <strong>the</strong> towns of Sodom <strong>and</strong> Gomorrah because of <strong>the</strong>ir inhabitants’<br />

failure to adhere to God’s moral st<strong>and</strong>ards, 75 or when he visits <strong>the</strong> Ten<br />

Plagues upon <strong>the</strong> Egyptians for Pharaoh’s refusal to accede to his orders<br />

to let <strong>the</strong> Hebrew people leave Egypt, 76 he certainly causes a great deal of<br />

suffering.<br />

God when exacting <strong>the</strong>se punishments is not doing so as an impartial,<br />

disinterested, third party, seeking only to remedy past human errors. He is<br />

angry because those whom he has punished have acted against him; <strong>the</strong>y<br />

have violated his laws <strong>and</strong> comm<strong>and</strong>ments, <strong>the</strong>y have defied his orders, <strong>and</strong><br />

because of <strong>the</strong>ir insolence <strong>and</strong> hubris, God intentionally makes <strong>the</strong>m suffer<br />

through his punishments of <strong>the</strong>m. 77 He is acting in <strong>the</strong> role of <strong>the</strong> revenger,<br />

exacting punishment (<strong>and</strong> suffering) upon those who have wronged him. 78<br />

74. See supra note 69 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

75. Genesis 19:24-25 (King James).<br />

76. Exodus 7-11 (King James).<br />

77. One could certainly argue that God, when destroying <strong>the</strong> cities of Sodom <strong>and</strong><br />

Gomorrah, <strong>and</strong> visiting <strong>the</strong> plagues upon <strong>the</strong> Egyptians, was acting both as a Retributivist<br />

by punishing those who had dared to defy his laws, as well as a Utilitarian, by seeking to<br />

deter future disobedience. However, one would have to question whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> levels of<br />

punishments exacted by God comported with his own proportionality requirements . See<br />

supra note 70.<br />

78. See, e.g., JACOBY, supra note 11, at 82 (“Whatever restraints <strong>the</strong> Scriptures place<br />

on vengeance committed by God’s creatures, <strong>the</strong>y accord <strong>the</strong> unlimited <strong>and</strong> unquestionable<br />

right of vengeance to <strong>the</strong> creator of <strong>the</strong> universe.”); see also DAN JACOBSON, THE STORY<br />

OF THE STORIES: THE CHOSEN PEOPLE AND ITS GOD 84 (1982) (“On her [Israel] he [God]<br />

had to take a boundless revenge for any infidelity or wrongdoing.”).


22 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

Is God acting immorally when he inflicts such suffering? I doubt that is <strong>the</strong><br />

lesson which <strong>the</strong> Bible seeks to teach. 79<br />

Indeed, <strong>the</strong> Bible does not reserve only unto God <strong>the</strong> right to revenge.<br />

Dinah’s bro<strong>the</strong>rs’ revenge for <strong>the</strong> rape of <strong>the</strong>ir sister, 80 is but one example<br />

of where <strong>the</strong> act, if not expressly countenanced by God, is nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

subject of rebuke. Indeed, <strong>the</strong> Bible tells of God comm<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> Hebrews<br />

to create three “cities of refuge” to which those accused of crimes could<br />

receive sanctuary from those seeking to avenge <strong>the</strong> alleged wrongful acts.<br />

If <strong>the</strong> accused was innocent of <strong>the</strong> crime, for example, if he killed ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

person by accident, he could remain, unsca<strong>the</strong>d <strong>and</strong> protected in <strong>the</strong> cities. 81<br />

However, if <strong>the</strong> killing was without excuse, “<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> elders of his city shall<br />

send <strong>and</strong> fetch him <strong>the</strong>nce, <strong>and</strong> deliver him into <strong>the</strong> h<strong>and</strong>s of <strong>the</strong> avenger of<br />

blood, that he may die.” 82 Thus, while <strong>the</strong> ancient Hebrews recognized <strong>the</strong><br />

danger that a revenger who acted while his “heart [was] hot” 83 risked <strong>the</strong><br />

shedding of innocent blood, <strong>the</strong>y also recognized <strong>the</strong> legitimate right of <strong>the</strong><br />

avenger to exact <strong>the</strong> punishment once cooler heads had determined <strong>the</strong> guilt<br />

of <strong>the</strong> accused. 84<br />

In response, one might argue that even if <strong>the</strong> Bible permits suffering as<br />

part of punishment, requiring it as part of punishment is none<strong>the</strong>less<br />

79. Admittedly, all of <strong>the</strong> Biblical references cited so far in this Essay have come from<br />

<strong>the</strong> Old Testament. In contrast, <strong>the</strong> New Testament, particularly when retelling <strong>the</strong> story<br />

of Jesus, is often cited for its emphasis on mercy <strong>and</strong> forgiveness. For instance, Jesus’s<br />

admonition in John 8:7 to those who wished to stone to death a suspected adulteress that<br />

“He that is without sin among you, let him first cast a stone at her” is often cited as<br />

representative of <strong>the</strong> New Testament’s turning away from <strong>the</strong> often harsh justice of <strong>the</strong> Old<br />

Testament, towards a more forgiving social order. See JACOBY, supra note 11, at 89. While<br />

such an absolute differentiation between <strong>the</strong> two Testaments is probably overly simplistic,<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is some merit to <strong>the</strong> distinction. See generally JEFFRIE G. MURPHY, GETTING EVEN:<br />

FORGIVENESS AND ITS LIMITATIONS 87-93 (2003). Such an admission, however, does not<br />

invalidate <strong>the</strong> references to <strong>the</strong> Old Testament. Indeed, it is not <strong>the</strong> position of this Essay<br />

that vengeance should be <strong>the</strong> sole st<strong>and</strong>ard for determining justice. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, I would argue that<br />

just as <strong>the</strong> Bible, when read in its entirety, recognizes <strong>the</strong> virtues of vengeance <strong>and</strong><br />

compassion, so too, should <strong>the</strong> law recognize <strong>the</strong> value of both desires when deciding levels<br />

of fair <strong>and</strong> just punishment. See infra notes 202-04 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

80. See supra notes 1-8 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

81. Deuteronomy 19:2-6 (King James).<br />

82. Id. at 19:11-12.<br />

83. Id. at 19:6.<br />

84. But see infra notes 112-14 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text (discussing <strong>the</strong> New Testament’s<br />

prohibition against mortal’s exacting revenge in Romans 12:19).


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 23<br />

immoral, especially if <strong>the</strong> Utilitarian goals could be satisfied without<br />

imposing <strong>the</strong> additional, punitive requirement of suffering. Not surprisingly,<br />

this is <strong>the</strong> position of classical Utilitarianism. 85 To that, I offer <strong>the</strong> traditional<br />

Retributive response: that <strong>the</strong> very purpose of punishment is to punish <strong>the</strong><br />

wrong doer for what he has done. 86 It matters not that o<strong>the</strong>r, non-punitive<br />

sanctions (such as placing <strong>the</strong> priests in retreats), could accomplish <strong>the</strong><br />

goals of deterrence, rehabilitation, <strong>and</strong> incapacity. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, under <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

of “deserts,” 87 <strong>the</strong> wrong doer is forced to suffer under punishment simply<br />

“because [he] deserved it, because [he] ‘ought to have known better.’” 88<br />

His actions have caused pain <strong>and</strong> harm to ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore, he must<br />

pay for it. Even if through <strong>the</strong> punishment, none of <strong>the</strong> Utilitarian goals were<br />

met; even <strong>the</strong>n, punishment which causes <strong>the</strong> victimizer to suffer would be<br />

warranted <strong>and</strong> just as payment for his wrong.<br />

Lastly, if, as I have argued above, in order for a punishment to be just,<br />

it must contain an element of suffering, how can we characterize society’s<br />

desire for such suffering as immoral? Would not such a motivation simply<br />

reflect a desire for justice? As one commentator notes, “Punishment may<br />

or may not teach right <strong>and</strong> wrong. The important fact is that it supports <strong>the</strong><br />

morality of social order.” 89 Certainly, <strong>the</strong> actual punishment would have to<br />

be proportional, but once again, that relates to <strong>the</strong> justness of <strong>the</strong><br />

punishment, not whe<strong>the</strong>r it is moral or not to desire suffering as an element<br />

of punishment.<br />

IV. THE MORALITY OF REVENGE<br />

“To <strong>the</strong> dangers of vengeance unlimited, it must be countered that if<br />

punishment no longer satisfies vengeance, if it ignores not only <strong>the</strong> rights but<br />

85. See, e.g., Punishment, supra note 56.<br />

86. See generally KANT, supra note 61.<br />

87. Lewis, supra note 63, at 225.<br />

88. Id. at 228. Lewis’ contempt for utilitarianism is even more profound, specifically<br />

when it is used as a justification for supposedly imposing punishment for <strong>the</strong> benefit of <strong>the</strong><br />

wrongdoer. “To be ‘cured’ against one’s will. . . . is to be put on a level with those who have<br />

not yet reached <strong>the</strong> age of reason or those who never will . . . .” Id. It is a “kindness [which]<br />

stings with intolerable insult.” Id.<br />

89. NEWMAN, supra note 61, at 290 n9. See also BARTON, supra note 30, at 19<br />

(“. . .[E]ven if. . . <strong>the</strong> emotional tone accompanying most cases of revenge was in fact<br />

pleasure in <strong>the</strong> suffering of those who have harmed <strong>and</strong> wronged one, it is not so obvious<br />

that <strong>the</strong>se cases of revenge would be morally reprehensible on that account.”).


24 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

<strong>the</strong> emotional needs of <strong>the</strong> victims of crime, <strong>the</strong>n punishment no longer<br />

serves its primary purpose.” Professor Robert Solomon. 90<br />

So far in this Essay, I have concluded that punishments which include<br />

an element of suffering are just, <strong>and</strong> that it is also moral for a society to<br />

mete out criminal punishment for <strong>the</strong> purpose of causing <strong>the</strong> wrong doer to<br />

experience suffering. The remainder of this Essay extends that argument<br />

from society to <strong>the</strong> victim, <strong>and</strong> examines whe<strong>the</strong>r it is moral for society,<br />

through its legal system, to allow its punishment of <strong>the</strong> criminal to be<br />

influenced by <strong>the</strong> victim’s desire for revenge.<br />

To address this issue, first requires an examination of <strong>the</strong> morality of a<br />

victim’s desire for revenge, for if <strong>the</strong> desire for revenge is itself immoral,<br />

any legal system which recognizes such a desire as a basis for punishment,<br />

would be acting immorally as well.<br />

Many 20 th century philosophers characterize <strong>the</strong> desire for revenge as<br />

immoral per se, because <strong>the</strong>y view <strong>the</strong> desire as motivated by hatred.<br />

Representative of this belief, Robert Nozick notes that “revenge involves a<br />

particular emotional tone, pleasure in <strong>the</strong> suffering of ano<strong>the</strong>r.” 91 Similarly,<br />

Jonathan Glover rejects revenge because “[H]atred <strong>and</strong> pleasure . . .<br />

combine . . . unpleasantly in revenge.” 92<br />

90. Solomon, supra note 11, at 253.<br />

91. Nozick, supra note 30, at 367.<br />

92. Jonathan Glover, Responsibility 145 (1970). Not surprisingly, most of <strong>the</strong>se<br />

criticisms have come Utilitarians. But even classical <strong>and</strong> contemporary Retributivits have<br />

warned against punishments which are motivated by revenge. See, e.g., Lewis, supra note<br />

52, at 82; Michael Moore, The Moral Worth of Retribution, in Responsibility, Character <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Emotions 212 (Ferdin<strong>and</strong> Schoeman ed., 1987); Solomon, supra note 11, at 256<br />

(“Virtually all retributivits in fact, insist on separating retribution from vengeance.”)<br />

Solomon however seems to differ with <strong>the</strong> almost universal condemnation of revenge, as he<br />

acknowledges that “[v]engeance is our natural sense of retribution”, <strong>and</strong> that “even if it<br />

requires careful correction <strong>and</strong> containment under <strong>the</strong> auspices of reason <strong>and</strong> tradition, <strong>and</strong><br />

through <strong>the</strong> machinery of law- [it] already gives us good grounds for punishment. . . .” Id.<br />

This is not to suggest that victims might not be motivated by o<strong>the</strong>r emotions as well.<br />

For example, some victims may wish to see <strong>the</strong>ir victimizers punished through lengthy<br />

incarceration in order to allay <strong>the</strong>ir fear of future criminal attacks from <strong>the</strong>ir offender. See,<br />

e.g., Lynne Henderson, Co-opting Compassion: The Federal Victim’s Right Amendment, 10<br />

ST. THOMAS L. REV. 579, 591 (1998). Interestingly, Professor Henderson, while<br />

acknowledging that victims may experience terror <strong>and</strong> fear of <strong>the</strong>ir offender, seemingly<br />

discounts those emotions as valid reasons to justify a victim’s desire to want <strong>the</strong>ir attacker<br />

incapacitated through preventive detention <strong>and</strong> continued custody. Id. at 591 n.95. Instead<br />

she asserts, seemingly without any substantiation, that such proposals for incarceration are


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 25<br />

Yet, <strong>the</strong>re are those who defend <strong>the</strong> morality of <strong>the</strong> desire for revenge,<br />

despite its roots in hatred. For example, Professor Solomon notes that “[T]o<br />

seek vengeance for a grievous wrong, to revenge oneself against evil- that<br />

seems to lie at <strong>the</strong> very foundation of our sense of justice, indeed, of our<br />

very sense of ourselves, our dignity, <strong>and</strong> our sense of right <strong>and</strong> wrong”. 93<br />

In a similar vein, Professor Minow writes “Vengeance is also <strong>the</strong> wellspring<br />

of a notion that animates justice. Recompense, getting satisfaction, matching<br />

like with like, giving what’s coming to <strong>the</strong> wrongdoer, equalizing crime <strong>and</strong><br />

punishment, an eye for an eye; each of <strong>the</strong>se synonyms for revenge implies<br />

<strong>the</strong> proportionality of <strong>the</strong> scales of justice.” 94<br />

Three assumptions seem to underscore <strong>the</strong> position of those who<br />

dismiss, out of h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>the</strong> morality of <strong>the</strong> revenge desire, <strong>and</strong> thus reject <strong>the</strong><br />

notion that it can serve as a legitimate basis for <strong>the</strong> state to impose<br />

punishment. The first, is <strong>the</strong> assumption that whenever a victim is motivated<br />

by revenge, that motive will necessarily result in <strong>the</strong> victim dem<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong><br />

harshest possible penalty for his offender. However, often that is often not<br />

<strong>the</strong> case. 95 For example, in a number of recent murder cases, families of <strong>the</strong><br />

murdered victims have argued against sentencing <strong>the</strong> convic ted killers to<br />

death. 96<br />

motivated only “in terms of revenge <strong>and</strong> an image of offenders as monsters who will commit<br />

horrible crimes if released”. Id.<br />

93. Solomon, supra note 11, at 252.<br />

94. MINOW, supra note 15, at 10. One can also argue that revenge can be moral if it<br />

serves to help some victims heal from <strong>the</strong> emotional traumas associated with <strong>the</strong>ir attacks.<br />

See infra notes 167-177 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

95. See, e.g., Barton, supra note 30, at xvi (“While victims are by no means<br />

disinterested in <strong>the</strong> outcome of <strong>the</strong>ir cases, <strong>the</strong> notion that <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>the</strong>y can not maintain<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir own impartiality <strong>and</strong> fairness vis a vis <strong>the</strong>ir offenders is a myth. Empirical evidence<br />

consistently shows victims not to be more punitive than o<strong>the</strong>rs...”); Id. at 125 n.9 (citing to<br />

studies which demonstrate that victims are not more punitive than <strong>the</strong> general public).<br />

96. See, e.g., Julie Cart, Killer of Gay Student Spared Death Penalty, L.A. TIMES,<br />

Nov. 5, 1999, at A1 (noting that parents of Ma<strong>the</strong>w Sheppard opposed death penalty for<br />

son’s killer); Brian MacQuarrie, US Mulls Seeking of Death of Convict, BOSTON GLOBE,<br />

Sept. 23, 2003, at A1 (reporting that fa<strong>the</strong>r of murdered 10 year old son opposed federal<br />

prosecutors seeking death penalty for one of son’s murderers); Stephen Dove, Byrd Son<br />

Fighting for Life of Killer, HOUSTON CHRONICLE, July 4, 2002, at A1 (writing that <strong>the</strong> man<br />

whose African American fa<strong>the</strong>r was killed by three white men who had chained <strong>and</strong> dragged<br />

him behind a pickup truck until he was dismembered <strong>and</strong> decapitated opposed death penalty<br />

for fa<strong>the</strong>r’s killers).


26 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

The next assumption is that <strong>the</strong>re is something intrinsically immoral<br />

when a crime victim, motivated by hate <strong>and</strong> revenge, does seek <strong>the</strong> harshest<br />

allowable sentence. But why is that an immoral response? This is <strong>the</strong><br />

person who has, after all, actually suffered <strong>the</strong> greatest harm. 97 Moreover,<br />

even if <strong>the</strong> victim is seeking <strong>the</strong> harshest penalty allowable under <strong>the</strong> law,<br />

she is only asking for a level of punishment which we, as a society, have<br />

already judged to be within <strong>the</strong> parameters of proportionality, 98 <strong>and</strong> thus, if<br />

rendered, would constitute justice. 99<br />

The third, <strong>and</strong> most basic assumption which seems to underlie <strong>the</strong><br />

argument that revenge is inherently immoral, is that any desire so grounded<br />

in hatred, must be evil, <strong>and</strong> thus immoral. While I do not question <strong>the</strong><br />

genuineness of those who share that belief, I do question <strong>the</strong>ir assumption<br />

that <strong>the</strong>ir beliefs should set <strong>the</strong> moral st<strong>and</strong>ard upon which we all should be<br />

judged. The desire for revenge, more than simply being an “underst<strong>and</strong>able”<br />

reaction to wrong doing, is grounded upon a rational <strong>and</strong> legitimate set of<br />

beliefs : That those who perform good deeds deserve gratitude <strong>and</strong><br />

kindness; while those who perform evil ones deserve enmity <strong>and</strong><br />

punishment.<br />

Perhaps this sentiment was best captured by <strong>the</strong> English jurist <strong>and</strong><br />

historian Sir James Fitzjames Stephens, who, in 1883 wrote:<br />

The criminal law thus proceeds upon <strong>the</strong> principle that it is<br />

morally right to hate criminals, <strong>and</strong> it confirms <strong>and</strong> justifies<br />

that sentiment by inflicting upon criminal punishments which<br />

express it. . . . These views are regarded by many persons as<br />

being wicked, because it is supposed that we never ought to hate,<br />

or wish to be revenged upon, any one. The doctrine that hatred<br />

<strong>and</strong> vengeance are wicked in <strong>the</strong>mselves appears to me to<br />

contradict plain facts, <strong>and</strong> to be unsupported by any<br />

arguments deserving of attention. Love <strong>and</strong> hatred, gratitude for<br />

benefits, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> desire of vengeance for injuries, imply each o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

as much as convex <strong>and</strong> concave. 100<br />

97. See infra notes 127-156 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text (recognizing <strong>the</strong> victim as <strong>the</strong><br />

wronged party).<br />

98. See supra notes 69-76 ( defining proportionality of punishment to crime).<br />

99. See supra note 48 (discussing proportionality within <strong>the</strong> definition of justice).<br />

100. 2 SIR JAMES FITZJAMES STEPHENS, A HISTORY OF THE CRIMINAL LAW OF<br />

ENGLAND 81-82 (1883) (emphasis added). See also BARTON, supra note 30, at 13 (“[I]t is


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 27<br />

Stephens’s observations also point out a recurring flaw in many<br />

commentators’ analyses of <strong>the</strong> reasons for society’s evolution from revenge<br />

to State imposed punishment. As discussed previously, <strong>the</strong> reasons for this<br />

evolution relate not to <strong>the</strong> inherent immorality of a victim’s desire to revenge<br />

a wrongful act, but ra<strong>the</strong>r to <strong>the</strong> great probability that <strong>the</strong> consequences of<br />

acting upon <strong>the</strong> desire would ei<strong>the</strong>r result in an injustice, or at least in an<br />

endless <strong>and</strong> increasing cycle of violence. 101 For example, <strong>the</strong>re was nothing<br />

immoral about Jacob <strong>and</strong> his sons wishing to see Dinah’s rapist punished.<br />

It was just that by acting upon <strong>the</strong>ir desire for revenge, unjust punishments<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibility of fur<strong>the</strong>r bloodshed resulted. 102<br />

The Ancient Greeks shared this concern. They feared revenge, <strong>and</strong><br />

with good reason. As one 20th century historian noted when describing <strong>the</strong><br />

revenge culture in Ancient Greece, “a single deed of blood provokes an<br />

endless series of retaliations: a hideous orgy of revenge... an orgy which no<br />

one may escape; for old men <strong>and</strong> women <strong>and</strong> children perish, whe<strong>the</strong>r one<br />

by one, or in a general massacre.” 103<br />

We see <strong>the</strong>se very same fears of revenger justice appearing in <strong>the</strong><br />

Ancient Greek myths, which often featured a blood feud which resulted in<br />

<strong>the</strong> innocent descendants of those who may have wronged ano<strong>the</strong>r, being<br />

punished for <strong>the</strong>ir ancestor’s act. For instance, in <strong>the</strong> myth of Orestes, <strong>the</strong><br />

Greek king, Agamemnon, is murdered by his wife, Clytemnestra, for<br />

sacrificing <strong>the</strong>ir daughter’s life to <strong>the</strong> Gods. Clytemnestra, in turn, is slain by<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir son, Orestes, to avenge his fa<strong>the</strong>r’s death. The cause for this family’s<br />

tragedy is traced back to a curse placed upon <strong>the</strong> descendant’s of<br />

Agamemnon’s fa<strong>the</strong>r’s, Atreus, by his bro<strong>the</strong>r Thyestes, because Atreus<br />

murdered Thyestes’s children. 104<br />

Similarly, <strong>the</strong> myth of Medea concerns a princess, Medea, who saves<br />

<strong>the</strong> life of Jason, <strong>and</strong> enables him to gain <strong>the</strong> Golden Fleece, thus ensuring<br />

Jason great fame <strong>and</strong> wealth. To achieve <strong>the</strong>se ends for Jason, she betrays<br />

questionable whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong>re is anything wrong with hating an unjust act, or even an unjust<br />

person who, on top of <strong>the</strong> wrongdoing, refuses to make amends <strong>and</strong> remains defiant <strong>and</strong><br />

unapologetic.”); Id. at 19 (“[I]f. . . . <strong>the</strong> emotional tone accompanying most cases of revenge<br />

was in fact pleasure in <strong>the</strong> suffering of those who have harmed <strong>and</strong> wronged one, it is not so<br />

obvious that <strong>the</strong>se cases of revenge would be morally reprehensible on that account.”).<br />

101. See supra notes 11-18 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

102. See supra notes 1- 8 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

103. HUBERT J. TRESTON, POINE: A STUDY IN GREEK BLOOD REVENGE 1 (1923).<br />

104. EDITH HAMILTON, MYTHOLOGY 250-59 (Penguin Books 1969) (1942).


28 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

her family <strong>and</strong> country, <strong>and</strong> is forced to live <strong>the</strong> remainder of her life in<br />

exile. Jason has two sons with Medea, but <strong>the</strong>n ab<strong>and</strong>ons her in order to<br />

marry <strong>the</strong> daughter of <strong>the</strong> king of his native l<strong>and</strong>. In revenge, Medea kills<br />

Jason’s bride, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir two sons. 105<br />

Of note, is that <strong>the</strong>se myths do not raise an issue of whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

revengers’ desire for revenge is justified. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it is <strong>the</strong> consequences of<br />

<strong>the</strong> revenge with which <strong>the</strong> Ancient Greeks were concerned. For example,<br />

in Orestes, would we fault Thyestes for wishing to slay his bro<strong>the</strong>r, Atreus,<br />

for killing his children, particularly since Atreus serves <strong>the</strong> slain children to<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir unsuspecting fa<strong>the</strong>r at a banquet! 106 It is certainly not Thyestes’ desire<br />

for revenge with which we take exception, but ra<strong>the</strong>r with <strong>the</strong> justness of<br />

his decision to avenge <strong>the</strong>ir deaths, not by punishing Arteus directly, but<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r by cursing his bro<strong>the</strong>r’s descendants.<br />

So too do we, <strong>and</strong> one would assume <strong>the</strong> Greeks as well, sympathize<br />

with Medea’s plight. She has sacrificed everything for Jason, <strong>and</strong> he<br />

rewards her by leaving her for a younger woman, who can fur<strong>the</strong>r his<br />

career plans. (Not an uncommon <strong>the</strong>me even today). Do we question <strong>the</strong><br />

morality of her desire for revenge? If she would have concocted a plan<br />

which would have caused Jason to suffer a loss equivalent to which she<br />

105. Id. at 128-35.<br />

106. Id. at 250. For his crime of matricide, Orestes is pursued by The Furies, who in<br />

Greek myths, represent <strong>Revenge</strong>. The god Apollo intervenes on Orestes’ behalf, <strong>and</strong><br />

convinces Orestes to seek <strong>the</strong> counsel of <strong>the</strong> goddess A<strong>the</strong>na. A<strong>the</strong>na convenes a court of<br />

law, which st<strong>and</strong>s in contrast to <strong>the</strong> sui generis justice represented by <strong>the</strong> blood feud. The<br />

trial is public, <strong>the</strong> decision maker is an impartial, disinterested party; <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> process is<br />

orderly, fact finding <strong>and</strong> rule rendering. Id. at 251-59.<br />

In analyzing <strong>the</strong> Oresteia, <strong>and</strong> how it reflects <strong>the</strong> legal world of <strong>the</strong> Ancient Greeks,<br />

Professor Paul Gewirtz notes how <strong>the</strong> play illuminates <strong>the</strong> need which <strong>the</strong> Greeks had to<br />

introduce “both a court <strong>and</strong> trial process to replace <strong>the</strong> endless cycle of blood feuds <strong>and</strong><br />

revenge.” Paul Gerwitz, Aeschylus’ <strong>Law</strong>, 101 HARV. L. REV. 1043, 1045 (1987-1988). Also<br />

of note is <strong>the</strong> role which A<strong>the</strong>na grants to <strong>the</strong> Furies under her new system of law. Ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than rejecting <strong>the</strong>m altoge<strong>the</strong>r, A<strong>the</strong>na underst<strong>and</strong>s that <strong>the</strong> passions which motivate revenge<br />

have a place in her new legal system. As Gewirtz notes, “<strong>the</strong> Furies will be<br />

‘honored’...because <strong>the</strong>y actually contribute to <strong>the</strong> system A<strong>the</strong>na is establishing. What <strong>the</strong><br />

Furies most clearly represent– call it fear, conscience, vengeance– is not a threat to law in<br />

<strong>the</strong> Oresteia’s scheme. Ra<strong>the</strong>r Fury is law’s partner. It reinforces a respect for legal rights.”<br />

Id. at 1047 (emphasis added). Gewirtsz <strong>the</strong>n concludes: “[T]hus <strong>the</strong> Oresteia st<strong>and</strong>s behind<br />

those in contemporary debates who insist that retribution must play a central role in a<br />

system of criminal justice <strong>and</strong> who warn that if retributive emotions are ignored, <strong>the</strong>y will<br />

be unleashed in less acceptable ways. Id. at 1047-48.


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 29<br />

suffered, would we condemn Medea? But once again, revenge is not sought<br />

against <strong>the</strong> guilty party directly, but ra<strong>the</strong>r against Jason’s innocent sons <strong>and</strong><br />

bride. Thus, while Medea’s punishment was unjust, her desire to get back<br />

at Jason was not immoral.<br />

As a means to curtail <strong>the</strong>se excesses of revenge, <strong>the</strong> state interceded<br />

into what had heretofore been essentially private matters. 107 Tribal leaders<br />

<strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r heads of state interjected <strong>the</strong>mselves into <strong>the</strong> disputes, <strong>and</strong><br />

pronounced guilt or innocence <strong>and</strong> punishment. But what gave <strong>the</strong>m <strong>the</strong><br />

right to do so? As a practical matter, <strong>the</strong> survival of <strong>the</strong>ir state required it. 108<br />

As a corollary to that fact, what evolved was a sense that murder was not<br />

a private matter, but ra<strong>the</strong>r affected everyone; <strong>the</strong> crime “polluted” <strong>the</strong><br />

entire social fabric, <strong>and</strong> thus, society, through <strong>the</strong> state, had <strong>the</strong> right to<br />

intercede. 109<br />

Religion played a major role in justifying <strong>the</strong> evolution from revenge to<br />

state regulated justice. As Susan Jacoby notes, “ in <strong>the</strong> long transition from<br />

tribal vendetta to measured legal retribution, it is impossible to overestimate<br />

<strong>the</strong> importance of <strong>the</strong> religious concept of murder as a stain upon a l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

its entire people <strong>and</strong> an offense against its gods.” 110 Thus <strong>the</strong> pollution<br />

doctrine was afforded a religious justification.<br />

Religion served ano<strong>the</strong>r important function. It provided a basis to equate<br />

public retribution with divine vengeance, <strong>and</strong> revenge with sinful<br />

behavior. 111 The Bible, particularly in <strong>the</strong> New Testament, prohibits mortals<br />

from exacting revenge. In Romans 12:19, God declares “Dearly beloved,<br />

avenge not yourselves, but ra<strong>the</strong>r give place unto wrath: for it is written,<br />

Vengeance is mine; I will repay, saith <strong>the</strong> Lord.” 112 Thus, only God, (<strong>and</strong><br />

those state officials such as priests <strong>and</strong> kings, acting on his behalf), was<br />

authorized to exact punishment. All o<strong>the</strong>rs would be acting in contravention<br />

of <strong>the</strong> Lord’s prohibition. Thus revenge became a sin.<br />

107. See supra notes 16-18 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

108. See JACOBY, supra note 11, at 67 (“Because bloodshed posed such a grave threat<br />

to social order, nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> state nor its religious arbiters could continue to treat murder as<br />

a family affair.”). But see Solomon, supra note 11, at 255 (“Moral objections against<br />

vengeance <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> desire for public order seem to me to have far less to do with this [state<br />

involvement in punishment of wrongdoers] than <strong>the</strong> usual arrogance of <strong>the</strong> state in abrogating<br />

individual rights <strong>and</strong> its desire for control.”).<br />

109. JACOBY, supra note 11, at 71-76.<br />

110. Id at 67.<br />

111. Id. at 68.<br />

112. Romans 12:19 (King James) (emphasis added).


30 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

Yet, even <strong>the</strong> New Testament, I would submit, does not condemn<br />

revenge, per se, for after all, its admonition is only that mortals should not<br />

exact revenge. God, it is clear, will continue to avenge, <strong>and</strong> thus “repay” <strong>the</strong><br />

wrong doer. Thus <strong>the</strong> idea of repayment <strong>and</strong> deserts is not forbidden, it is<br />

only reserved for God, alone. 113 I would fur<strong>the</strong>r submit that in this way,<br />

Romans 12:19 merely echoes <strong>the</strong> concerns of those civilizations which<br />

predated Christianity; that victims, unregulated in <strong>the</strong>ir quest for revenge,<br />

were ill suited to be dispensers of justice. 114<br />

It was not until <strong>the</strong> Post-Enlightenment Period, 115 that <strong>the</strong> legitimacy of<br />

state imposed punishment required more than simply a claim to be acting as<br />

God’s agent. Instead, <strong>the</strong> secular concepts of proportionality of punishment,<br />

<strong>and</strong> individual, ra<strong>the</strong>r than collective responsibility for criminal acts, arose<br />

as <strong>the</strong> basic concepts of criminal law. 116 Underlying <strong>the</strong>se changes was a<br />

shift away from viewing <strong>the</strong> criminal justice system as a vehicle for<br />

enforcing religion- based morality, replacing it with <strong>the</strong> belief that <strong>the</strong><br />

criminal law should operate to fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> good of a more secular society.<br />

These beliefs were exemplified by <strong>the</strong> writings of <strong>the</strong> 18th century<br />

philosopher, Cesare Beccaria, particularly his work entitled Essay on<br />

Crimes <strong>and</strong> Punishment. 117 Beccaria, a member of <strong>the</strong> Enlightenment,<br />

believed in <strong>the</strong> social contract <strong>the</strong>ory of society, under which citizens agreed<br />

to forego certain individual liberties <strong>and</strong> rights, in exchange for <strong>the</strong><br />

government’s promise to act on <strong>the</strong>ir behalf to safeguard <strong>the</strong>ir lives <strong>and</strong> well<br />

being. 118 Becarria also challenged <strong>the</strong> notion that <strong>the</strong> criminal law was an<br />

113. See MURPHY, supra note 79, at 88.<br />

114. However, if by equating revenge with sin, <strong>the</strong> goal was to eradicate revenge, one<br />

can only conclude that <strong>the</strong> attempt was not very successful. Indeed, as Jacoby notes, what<br />

may in fact be <strong>the</strong> longest revenge cycle in history, <strong>the</strong> persecution of <strong>the</strong> Jews for <strong>the</strong><br />

crucifixion of Jesus, remained a fixed <strong>and</strong> countenanced policy of <strong>the</strong> Church for almost 2000<br />

years. JACOBY, supra note 11, at 68. Fur<strong>the</strong>rmore, having religion as <strong>the</strong> justification for<br />

imposing criminal punishment, led to a system of proportionality that based punishment<br />

upon <strong>the</strong> level of deviance from <strong>the</strong> teachings of <strong>the</strong> Church, ra<strong>the</strong>r than upon <strong>the</strong> level of<br />

harm. McDonald, supra note 20, at 655.<br />

115. The Enlightenment was an 18th century philosophical movement characterized by<br />

rationalism, skepticism, <strong>and</strong> empiricism in social <strong>and</strong> political thought. WEBSTER’S, supra<br />

note 29, at 482.<br />

116. JACOBY, supra note 11, at 139.<br />

117. CESARE BECCARRIA, ESSAY ON CRIMES AND PUNISHMENTS (Edward D.<br />

Ingraham trans., 1819) (1764).<br />

118. Id. at 20.


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 31<br />

extension of God’s laws on earth, administered by those serving as God’s<br />

agents. 119 Instead, he posited that <strong>the</strong> purpose of law was to serve as a<br />

means to ensure <strong>the</strong> safety <strong>and</strong> harmony of society. 120 As a corollary to that<br />

position, he rebuked <strong>the</strong> notion that <strong>the</strong> level of punishment should be based<br />

upon <strong>the</strong> level which <strong>the</strong> wrong constituted an offense to God. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, he<br />

argued that <strong>the</strong> extent of criminal punishment should be determined in<br />

reference to <strong>the</strong> level of <strong>the</strong> harm which <strong>the</strong> wrongful act posed to<br />

society. 121<br />

Becarria’s <strong>the</strong>ories, as well as those of o<strong>the</strong>r Enlightenment<br />

philosophers, ultimately supplanted <strong>the</strong> religious underpinnings of <strong>the</strong><br />

criminal justice system in Western Europe <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> United States. 122<br />

However Enlightenment <strong>the</strong>ories retained its predecessors’ prohibition<br />

against revenge. As Beccarria noted: “The right of punishing belongs not to<br />

any individual in particular, but to society in general, or <strong>the</strong> sovereign.” 123<br />

While <strong>the</strong> philosophical basis for that conclusion differed between <strong>the</strong><br />

religious <strong>and</strong> secular <strong>the</strong>ories, 124 both were driven by <strong>the</strong> same practical<br />

concerns; that being to establish a system of laws which would<br />

“counterbalance <strong>the</strong> effects of <strong>the</strong> passions of <strong>the</strong> individual which oppose<br />

<strong>the</strong> general good. 125<br />

Indeed, I would argue, <strong>the</strong> practical reasons for rejecting revenge have<br />

remained constant since Jacob rebuked his sons for exacting revenge upon<br />

<strong>the</strong> inhabitants of Hamor’s city. These reasons have not concerned <strong>the</strong><br />

morality of <strong>the</strong> desire to exact revenge, nor even with <strong>the</strong> morality of <strong>the</strong> act<br />

itself. 126 Ra<strong>the</strong>r, our fears have always been with <strong>the</strong> consequences which<br />

119. Id. at 19.<br />

120. Id.<br />

121. Id. at 28.<br />

122. JACOBY, supra note 11, at 116.<br />

123. BECCARRIA, supra note 117, at 159.<br />

124. For <strong>the</strong> religious based <strong>the</strong>ory, allowing only state sanctioned punishment rested<br />

upon <strong>the</strong> sinfulness of acting in contravention of God’s prohibition against mortal revenge.<br />

See supra note 111 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text. For <strong>the</strong> secularized enlightenment <strong>the</strong>ory, it<br />

rested upon <strong>the</strong> belief that <strong>the</strong> individual, through his social contract with his sovereign,<br />

relinquished his right to revenge. See supra note 118 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

125. BECCARRIA, supra note 117, at 16.<br />

126. This is not to suggest that <strong>the</strong> desire for revenge is always justified, <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

moral. People are motivated to exact revenge upon o<strong>the</strong>rs for countless reasons. While it is<br />

true that <strong>the</strong> desire is almost always motivated by hate, often <strong>the</strong>re is no justified basis for<br />

<strong>the</strong> hatred, <strong>and</strong> thus in those cases, I would argue, even <strong>the</strong> desire to revenge is immoral.


32 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

<strong>the</strong> desire, if acted upon, would have upon society. Based upon that<br />

proposition, it is my contention that history does not condemn as immoral<br />

society’s recognition of revenge as a justification for state imposed<br />

punishment. It merely cautions against permitting <strong>the</strong> revenger himself, to<br />

serve as judge, jury, <strong>and</strong> executioner.<br />

V. RECOGNIZING THE VICTIM AS A WRONGED PARTY<br />

Because <strong>the</strong> offense was committed . . . against <strong>the</strong> community as<br />

a whole. . . . only <strong>the</strong> community, speaking through <strong>the</strong> jury, has <strong>the</strong> right<br />

to determine what punishment should be administered. 127 Robison v.<br />

Maynard (10th Cir.)<br />

“[T]o hell with people saying society is <strong>the</strong> victim: it was me, not<br />

society, that got hurt.” 128 Statement of crime victim.<br />

The above statement by <strong>the</strong> Tenth Circuit clearly reflects <strong>the</strong><br />

predominant <strong>the</strong>ory regarding criminal punishment: that it is <strong>the</strong> community,<br />

not <strong>the</strong> victim, against whom <strong>the</strong> wrongful act was committed. In <strong>the</strong><br />

previous section, I discussed why <strong>the</strong> “pollution” <strong>the</strong>ory evolved. 129<br />

However, putting aside legal rhetoric <strong>and</strong> rationalizations, let us examine just<br />

who has truly been wronged when one inflicts a criminal act upon ano<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

Of course one can argue that under <strong>the</strong> pollution <strong>the</strong>ory, society at large is<br />

contaminated when one of us is harmed . But specifically, how so? On an<br />

existential level, it can be argued that we all suffer when one of us is<br />

injured. 130 And, on a practical level, we do have a right, if not a<br />

responsibility, to be alert to <strong>the</strong> possibility of a society where criminals<br />

realize <strong>the</strong>y can act with impunity, thus exposing ourselves, our families, <strong>and</strong><br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs to <strong>the</strong> potential of rampant criminal mayhem. 131<br />

Yet, who could reasonably argue that <strong>the</strong> person who has actually been<br />

mugged, robbed, raped, or beaten, has not suffered at least as great, if not<br />

a greater harm. He is suffering now. His injury is not purely philosophical,<br />

127. Robison v. Maynard, 829 F.2d 1501, 1505 (10th Cir. 1987) (emphasis added).<br />

128. BARTON, supra note 30 at 103, citing J. CONSEDINE, RESTORATIVE JUSTICE:<br />

HEALING THE EFFECTS OF CRIME 82 (1995).<br />

129. See supra notes 107-10 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

130. See supra note 109 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

131. This reason, of course, is dependant upon accepting <strong>the</strong> Utilitarian belief that<br />

punishment of wrongdoers has a deterrent effect upon <strong>the</strong> commission of future criminal<br />

acts. See supra note 57 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 33<br />

nor is it a matter of conjecture. It has happened, <strong>and</strong> in many cases, <strong>the</strong><br />

victim <strong>and</strong> those close to him must live with <strong>the</strong> repercussions of <strong>the</strong> act for<br />

years, if not for <strong>the</strong> remainder of <strong>the</strong>ir lives. 132 The rest of us, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

h<strong>and</strong>, will likely continue to go about our business, relatively, if not<br />

completely unaffected within a day or two after reading or hearing about<br />

<strong>the</strong> victim of ano<strong>the</strong>r crime.<br />

It is that acknowledgment; that <strong>the</strong> wronged party in a criminal matter<br />

is first <strong>and</strong> foremost <strong>the</strong> actual victim of <strong>the</strong> crime, which, I believe,<br />

m<strong>and</strong>ates that <strong>the</strong> law recognize <strong>the</strong> right of <strong>the</strong> victim to seek redress. The<br />

fact that <strong>the</strong> victim is not a party to <strong>the</strong> criminal suit, <strong>and</strong> thus has no<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ing to question rulings of law, or pronouncements of sentences, has far<br />

reaching implications for <strong>the</strong> victim. Decisions made by <strong>the</strong> district<br />

attorney’s office in trying <strong>the</strong> case, which may result in acquittals or<br />

dismissal of charges, are binding upon <strong>the</strong> victim. Errors made by law<br />

enforcement officers which cause incriminating evidence to be excluded<br />

from trial, <strong>and</strong> which also may lead to a subsequent acquittal of a wrong<br />

doer, are similarly binding upon <strong>the</strong> victim. Thus, actions taken by parties<br />

over whom <strong>the</strong> victim has no control, bind <strong>the</strong> victim, 133 leaving him without<br />

any legal recourse, o<strong>the</strong>r than seeking tort remedies. 134<br />

Victims are thus placed in a unique legal status. In one sense, <strong>the</strong> state,<br />

serves as an agent of <strong>the</strong> victim, in that its actions are binding upon its<br />

“principal,” <strong>the</strong> victim. 135 If unhappy with <strong>the</strong> result of <strong>the</strong> criminal matter,<br />

victims have no st<strong>and</strong>ing to dispute it. They can not appeal <strong>the</strong> decision, nor<br />

can <strong>the</strong>y file <strong>the</strong>ir own criminal suit.<br />

132. See generally Fran H. Norris & Krzysztof Kaniasty, Psychological Distress<br />

Following Criminal Victimization in <strong>the</strong> General Population: Cross-Sectional, Longitudanal,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Prospective Analyses, 62 J. CONSULTING & CLINICAL PSYCH. 111-23 (1994).<br />

There are also “victimless” crimes; those where <strong>the</strong> state imposes criminal penalty for<br />

an act which has caused no actual harm to anyone. For example, a driver of a motor vehicle<br />

is convicted of driving while intoxicated. Prior to his arrest, he did not cause any property<br />

or personal injury to anyone due to his intoxication. Thus, since no one has actually been<br />

victimized by <strong>the</strong> driver’s illegal behavior, <strong>the</strong> issue of revenge is irrelevant. In such cases,<br />

<strong>the</strong> criminal punishment is imposed primarily for <strong>the</strong> utilitarian purposes of deterrence,<br />

rehabilitation <strong>and</strong> incapacity.<br />

133. U.S. CONST. amend V (barring <strong>the</strong> State, under <strong>the</strong> Double Jeopardy Clause, from<br />

re-trying <strong>the</strong> defendant for <strong>the</strong> same crime).<br />

134. See infra notes 206-17 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text (discussing <strong>the</strong> viability of tort<br />

remedies for most victims of violent crimes).<br />

135. See generally W. EDWARD SELL, SELL ON AGENCY 1-6 (1975).


34 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

However, <strong>the</strong> victim shares none of <strong>the</strong> benefits which <strong>the</strong> principals in<br />

an agency relationship ordinarily possess. They have no control over<br />

choosing who <strong>the</strong>ir agent will be, nor do <strong>the</strong>y have any power to control<br />

how <strong>the</strong>ir “agent” pursues “<strong>the</strong>ir” case. 136 This is of course due to <strong>the</strong> fact<br />

that <strong>the</strong> state is not really acting as <strong>the</strong>ir agent at all, but ra<strong>the</strong>r is<br />

representing <strong>the</strong> interests of <strong>the</strong> community.<br />

This conflict can be illustrated by visiting <strong>the</strong> case of Salvatore (Sammy<br />

The Bull) Gravano. Gravano was a hitman for <strong>the</strong> Mafia, <strong>and</strong> was<br />

responsible for <strong>the</strong> killing of at least 19 people. 137 In prosecuting Gravano<br />

for <strong>the</strong> murders, <strong>the</strong> government decided to offer him a significantly reduced<br />

sentence, <strong>and</strong> subsequent placement in <strong>the</strong> Federal Witness Protection<br />

Program, in exchange for his cooperation with <strong>the</strong> government’s case<br />

against his boss, John Gotti, <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r members of Gotti’s crime family. 138<br />

Federal District Court Judge I. Leo Glasser sentenced Gravano to five<br />

years in prison, which after deducting <strong>the</strong> nearly four years Gravano had<br />

already served in detention, required him to serve only one additional<br />

year. 139 In support of his sentence, <strong>the</strong> judge held that for <strong>the</strong> greater good<br />

of society, it was less important that Gravano be proportionally punished for<br />

his crimes than it was to incarcerate Gotti <strong>and</strong> his criminal associates. 140<br />

Given <strong>the</strong> list of those crime members who ei<strong>the</strong>r were convicted largely on<br />

<strong>the</strong> basis of Gravano’s testimony, or agreed to plead guilty when faced with<br />

<strong>the</strong> prospect of Gravano’s testimony, 141 one can certainly find a credible<br />

basis for Judge Glasser’s reasoning.<br />

And yet, throughout <strong>the</strong> entire proceedings, no one spoke on behalf of<br />

<strong>the</strong> families of <strong>the</strong> nineteen men “whacked” by Gravano. As might have<br />

been expected, many of <strong>the</strong> families of <strong>the</strong> murdered victims wished to see<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir sons,’ fa<strong>the</strong>rs’ <strong>and</strong> husb<strong>and</strong>s’ murderer receive a much harsher<br />

sentence. 142 Also, given that many of <strong>the</strong> victims’ family members had<br />

personal, first h<strong>and</strong> knowledge of Gravano’s proclivity for crime <strong>and</strong><br />

136. Id.<br />

137. SENTENCING MEMORANDUM OF JUDGE I. LEO GLASSER 3-6.<br />

138. Andy Newman, Mafia Turncoat Gets 20 Years For Running Ecstasy Ring, N.Y.<br />

TIMES, Sept. 7, 2002, at B3.<br />

139. Dorothy Weiss, One Tough Judge, in BROOKLYN STATE OF MIND 110 (Michael<br />

Robbins ed., 2001).<br />

140. SENTENCING MEMORANDUM, supra note 137, at 16-17.<br />

141. Id. at 8-9.<br />

142. Dennis Wagner, Give The Bull ‘ Life’ 4 Say: His Victims’ Kin Press for <strong>Justice</strong>,<br />

THE ARIZONA REPUBLIC/GAZETTE, Mar. 9, 2000, at B1.


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 35<br />

violence, one can surely argue that <strong>the</strong>y had relevant testimony to offer<br />

Judge Glasser before he h<strong>and</strong>ed down his sentence.<br />

But <strong>the</strong> judge never heard those voices. Instead, <strong>the</strong> judge found<br />

Gravano to have made “<strong>the</strong> seemingly impossible decision to become a<br />

different person <strong>and</strong> to live by a different set of values from those that<br />

ordered his life until <strong>the</strong>n.” 143 He believed <strong>the</strong> prosecutors <strong>and</strong> federal<br />

agents, who, having spent “hundreds <strong>and</strong> hundreds of hours with him<br />

[Gravano] over <strong>the</strong> past three years [were] unanimous in <strong>the</strong>ir belief that<br />

he no longer poses a threat to this or any o<strong>the</strong>r community” <strong>and</strong> that<br />

Gravano had “irrevocably broken with his past.” 144 Judge Glasser also<br />

believed <strong>the</strong> characterization “by a very sophisticated <strong>and</strong> experienced law<br />

enforcement officer” that Gravano’s decision to cooperate with <strong>the</strong><br />

government was “<strong>the</strong> bravest thing he had ever seen.” 145 Based on <strong>the</strong>se<br />

representations by federal prosecutors <strong>and</strong> law enforcement officers, Judge<br />

Glasser’s sentence of five years 146 for 19 murders perhaps becomes a bit<br />

more comprehensible. But one must question whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> same sentence<br />

would have been h<strong>and</strong>ed down had <strong>the</strong> victims of Gravano’s crimes not<br />

been so completely ignored <strong>and</strong> marginalized while <strong>the</strong> fate of <strong>the</strong> murderer<br />

of <strong>the</strong>ir sons, fa<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>and</strong> bro<strong>the</strong>rs was being decided.<br />

The absence of victim involvement in Gravano’s sentencing takes on<br />

additional significance when examining Gravano’s behavior subsequent to<br />

his sentencing. After serving his additional one year prison sentence,<br />

Gravano was placed in <strong>the</strong> Federal Witness Protection Program. He <strong>and</strong> his<br />

family were moved to Arizona, where he set up a construction company. In<br />

February 2000, Gravano, as well as his wife, son <strong>and</strong> daughter were<br />

arrested, <strong>and</strong> subsequently pled guilty to having operated a multi-million<br />

dollar drug ring. He is currently serving a sentence of twenty years. 147<br />

Again, one can not help but wonder whe<strong>the</strong>r victim testimony would have<br />

alerted Judge Glasser to question <strong>the</strong> plausibility of <strong>the</strong> government’s<br />

assurances that Gravano had “irrevocably broken with his past.”<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r case illustrative of how victims of crime <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir families are<br />

143. Weiss, supra note 139, at 110.<br />

144. SENTENCING MEMORANDUM, supra note 137, at 17.<br />

145. Id. at 15.<br />

146. Pursuant to his deal with <strong>the</strong> federal prosecutors, Gravano could have been<br />

sentenced to up to 20 years for <strong>the</strong> 19 murders. Larry McShane, Salvatore Gravano Is<br />

FBI’s Favorite Songbird, L.A. TIMES, June 5, 1994, at ___.<br />

147. Newman, supra note 138.


36 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

marginalized by <strong>the</strong> criminal justice system is <strong>the</strong> Massachusetts case of<br />

Hagen v. Commonwealth. 148 In October 1987, James Kelley was<br />

convicted of two counts of rape <strong>and</strong> one charge of indecent assault <strong>and</strong><br />

battery of Debra Hagen. In April 1988, he was sentenced to two concurrent<br />

ten year sentences on <strong>the</strong> rape convictions, <strong>and</strong> one concurrent five year<br />

sentence on <strong>the</strong> indecent assault <strong>and</strong> battery conviction. On April 26, 1988,<br />

Kelley filed a motion to stay execution of his sentence, <strong>and</strong> a motion for a<br />

new trial, alleging ineffective assistance of trial counsel. The motion for stay<br />

of execution was granted in July 1988. 149<br />

Four years later, in May 1992, Kelley’s motion for a new trial was<br />

denied. Kelley <strong>the</strong>n appealed <strong>the</strong> judgments of conviction <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> denial of<br />

his motion for a new trial. Eight years later, due to administrative mishaps<br />

<strong>and</strong> oversights, Kelley’s appeal was still pending. 150 Thus thirteen years<br />

after his conviction for rape <strong>and</strong> assault, Mr. Kelley had still not served any<br />

time for his commission of those crimes.<br />

In May 2001, Ms. Hagen filed a motion requesting <strong>the</strong> court to revoke<br />

<strong>the</strong> stay of execution of sentence. 151 In upholding <strong>the</strong> lower court’s<br />

dismissal of her motion, <strong>the</strong> Supreme Judicial Court held that as victim of<br />

<strong>the</strong> crime, she did not have st<strong>and</strong>ing to seek <strong>the</strong> revocation of Kelley’s<br />

stay. 152 In so holding, <strong>the</strong> court cited a litany of cases, each of which clearly<br />

illustrate <strong>the</strong> extent to which <strong>the</strong> law has rendered <strong>the</strong> victim impotent in<br />

seeking to ensure that her wrongdoer is punished. 153<br />

Reviewing <strong>the</strong>se two cases, one is led to question how our law has<br />

[d]evolved from <strong>the</strong> laudable purpose of seeking to eliminate <strong>the</strong> ravages of<br />

revenge, to where today, <strong>the</strong> law denies victims st<strong>and</strong>ing to even petition<br />

courts to enforce punishments which have been lawfully imposed upon <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

convicted wrong doers. Certainly such a result is nei<strong>the</strong>r morally compelled,<br />

148. Hagen v. Commonwealth, 772 N.E.2d 32 (Mass. 2002).<br />

149. Id. at 34.<br />

150. Id. at 35.<br />

151. Id.<br />

152. Id. at 37.<br />

153. Id., citing Taylor v. Newton Div. of <strong>the</strong> Dist. Court Dep’t, 622 N.E.2d 261, 262<br />

(Mass. 1993) (“The rights which <strong>the</strong> victim seeks to enforce criminally are not private but<br />

in fact are lodged in <strong>the</strong> Commonwealth.”); see Hagen, 772 N.E.2d at 37 (“A prosecution<br />

is conducted in <strong>the</strong> interests of <strong>the</strong> Commonwealth, not on behalf of <strong>the</strong> victim.”); Tarabolski<br />

v. Williams, 642 N.E.2d 574, 575 (Mass. 1994), quoting Linda R.S. v. Richard D., 410 U.S.<br />

614, 619 (1973) (“[I]n American jurisprudence . . . . a private citizen lacks a judicially<br />

cognizable interest in <strong>the</strong> prosecution or nonprosecution of ano<strong>the</strong>r.”).


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 37<br />

nor required as a matter of fundamental justice. In fact, <strong>the</strong> Massachusetts<br />

Supreme Judicial Court in Hagen admitted as much, when it held that <strong>the</strong><br />

state legislature, if it wished, could enact legislation whic h would extend<br />

party status to victims seeking remedies like those requested by Ms.<br />

Hagen. 154 Indeed, historically, victims of crimes in America <strong>and</strong> Engl<strong>and</strong><br />

actually had such st<strong>and</strong>ing, since <strong>the</strong>y had <strong>the</strong> responsibility of capturing<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir suspected offenders, <strong>and</strong> prosecuting <strong>the</strong>m in court. The state’s<br />

function was to serve only as judge <strong>and</strong> sentencing body. 155 It was not until<br />

<strong>the</strong> 19th century, that <strong>the</strong> police <strong>and</strong> prosecutorial systems assumed <strong>the</strong><br />

roles which <strong>the</strong>y currently hold; changes which were necessitated by <strong>the</strong><br />

practical difficulties which victims encountered in attempting to apprehend<br />

<strong>and</strong> convict <strong>the</strong>ir alleged wrongdoers. 156<br />

In sum, I believe <strong>the</strong> statement that <strong>the</strong> community at large, <strong>and</strong> not <strong>the</strong><br />

victim of <strong>the</strong> crime, is <strong>the</strong> wronged party of a criminal act, is intellectually<br />

disingenuous, factually mistaken, <strong>and</strong> emotionally demeaning to victims. It<br />

is an example of legal formalism distorting reality, <strong>and</strong> ought to be<br />

recognized as such.<br />

VI. REVENGE AS A SOURCE OF VICTIM EMPOWERMENT<br />

<strong>Revenge</strong>–<strong>the</strong> attempt at some cost or risk to ourselves, to impose<br />

suffering upon those who have made one suffer, because <strong>the</strong>y have<br />

made one suffer—is a universal phenomenon. . . . [This] very<br />

definition of revenge shows that it involves only costs <strong>and</strong><br />

risks, no benefits. 157 Jon Elster<br />

To seek vengeance for a grievous wrong, to revenge oneself<br />

against evil–that seems to lie at <strong>the</strong> very foundation of our sense of<br />

justice, indeed, of our very sense of ourselves, our dignity <strong>and</strong> our<br />

sense of right <strong>and</strong> wrong. 158 Professor Robert Solomon<br />

In his novel The Amateur, 159 Robert Littell, writes of a young man,<br />

Heller, whose fiancee is murdered by terrorists. At his fiancee’s burial,<br />

154. Hagen, supra note 153, at 37.<br />

155. McDonald, supra note 20, at 651-52.<br />

156. Id. at 653-54.<br />

157. Elster, supra note 52, at 362.<br />

158. Solomon, supra note 11, at 252.<br />

159. ROBERT LITTELL, THE AMATEUR (1981).


38 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

Heller meets her fa<strong>the</strong>r, who he discovers is a survivor of <strong>the</strong> Holocaust.<br />

The fa<strong>the</strong>r tells Heller that <strong>the</strong> Nazis killed his first wife <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir two<br />

daughters. To avenge <strong>the</strong>ir deaths, he spent three years after <strong>the</strong> war,<br />

searching for <strong>the</strong> doctor who had ordered <strong>the</strong>ir deaths, <strong>and</strong> when he found<br />

him, he tells Heller, “with <strong>the</strong>se h<strong>and</strong>s, I strangled him.” Heller, struggling<br />

with his own desire for revenge, points out to <strong>the</strong> fa<strong>the</strong>r that <strong>the</strong> killing of<br />

<strong>the</strong> doctor had not brought back to life his dead wife <strong>and</strong> children. The<br />

fa<strong>the</strong>r, upset that <strong>the</strong> young man had not understood <strong>the</strong> point of his story,<br />

responds that “it brought me back.” 160<br />

In that brief exchange, Littell captures <strong>the</strong> essence of revenge. The<br />

Nazis had done more than enslave, torture <strong>and</strong> kill <strong>the</strong> fa<strong>the</strong>r’s family. They<br />

also robbed him of his dignity, forcing him to accept <strong>the</strong> reality of his<br />

powerlessness to do anything to protect his family from <strong>the</strong>ir fate. By<br />

tracking down <strong>and</strong> personally punishing at least one of <strong>the</strong> individuals<br />

responsible for <strong>the</strong>se atrocities, <strong>the</strong> fa<strong>the</strong>r was able to reclaim some of what<br />

had been taken from him. True, he could not recover his dead family, but<br />

he was able to reclaim his human dignity <strong>and</strong> power, <strong>and</strong> thus return to <strong>the</strong><br />

world of <strong>the</strong> living.<br />

In that sense, revenge can be an ennobling, as well as an enabling,<br />

concept. While <strong>the</strong> dangers of revenge systems of justice have been<br />

extensively discussed in this Essay, 161 revenge cultures also contained<br />

positive elements; elements which are missing in our current system of<br />

justice. Most notably, revenge cultures provided a mechanism by which<br />

victims could regain <strong>the</strong>ir sense of power <strong>and</strong> honor. <strong>Revenge</strong>rs could<br />

personally “get even” with <strong>the</strong>ir victimizers, <strong>and</strong> thus reassert <strong>the</strong>ir status<br />

within <strong>the</strong>ir society. <strong>Revenge</strong> cultures encompassed a sense of self worth;<br />

that is, <strong>the</strong> recognition that no one had <strong>the</strong> right to inflict unprovoked harm<br />

upon ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong> that when ano<strong>the</strong>r did so, it was <strong>the</strong> victim, <strong>and</strong> not <strong>the</strong><br />

community at large, who had primarily been wronged. As such, <strong>the</strong> victim<br />

had <strong>the</strong> right (or in some cultures <strong>the</strong> duty), to personally recapture his<br />

respect <strong>and</strong> honor. In effect, cultures which permitted revenge, allowed<br />

160. Id. at 49-50. At <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> novel, Heller avenges his fiancé’s murder by killing<br />

Schiller, her murderer. He is assisted in his quest by a Professor Lako, who, unbeknownst<br />

to Heller, also had a revenge motive to kill Schiller. Heller asks <strong>the</strong> Professor whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

revenge was worth it, to which <strong>the</strong> Professor responds “It was . . . . very satisfying. And<br />

you?” Heller confesses that he would not do it again but “it was just as advertised. It<br />

brought me back from <strong>the</strong> dead.” Id. at 246-47.<br />

161. See supra notes 10-18, 100-26 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 39<br />

those victims strong enough (or from families with sufficient strength) to<br />

erase <strong>the</strong> psychological stigma of <strong>the</strong>ir victimhood. 162<br />

And yet, as illustrated by <strong>the</strong> excerpt by Jon Elster cited at <strong>the</strong><br />

beginning of this section, many philosophers believe that revenge serves no<br />

benefit, to ei<strong>the</strong>r society as a whole, or to individual members of society<br />

who have been victimized by violent crime. Elster regards revenge as<br />

irrational, since “Rational individuals follow <strong>the</strong> principles of letting bygones<br />

be bygones, cutting <strong>the</strong>ir losses <strong>and</strong> ignoring sunk costs, whereas <strong>the</strong><br />

avenger typically refuses to forget an affront or harm to which he has been<br />

exposed.” 163<br />

O<strong>the</strong>rs go even fur<strong>the</strong>r in decrying revenge, for while conceding that<br />

such emotions are “underst<strong>and</strong>able” <strong>and</strong> “entirely human,” 164 <strong>the</strong>y believe<br />

that revenge is per se immoral because it is motivated by <strong>the</strong> victim’ s<br />

taking “pleasure in <strong>the</strong> suffering of ano<strong>the</strong>r.” 165 One reads that revenge is<br />

considered to be evil because “[H]atred <strong>and</strong> pleasure. . . . combine so<br />

unpleasantly,” 166 or hears, as I did at a recent faculty colloquium, that<br />

desires to punish for retributive purposes are simply “craven,” <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

should be dismissed out of h<strong>and</strong>.<br />

162. BARTON, supra note 30, at 39-40.<br />

163. Elster, supra note 52, at 362.<br />

164. Seymour Halleck, Vengeance <strong>and</strong> Victimization, 5 VICTIMOLOGY: AN<br />

INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL 99 (1980) [AUTHOR PROVIDE SOURCE]. Admittedly,<br />

Professor Halleck does recognize <strong>the</strong> need for victims to “get in touch with <strong>the</strong>ir feelings of<br />

rage,” in order to avoid “excessive psychological suffering.” However, he implicitly rejects<br />

any acting out of <strong>the</strong> revenge desire, since “just deserts is responsive to limited social needs<br />

<strong>and</strong> it directly <strong>and</strong> indirectly leads to neglect of <strong>the</strong> victim.” Id. at 99. More recent<br />

commentators have expressed <strong>the</strong> same concern. For example, Professor Lynne Henderson,<br />

in her article Co-opting Compassion: The Federal Victim’s Rights Amendment, expresses her<br />

concern that <strong>the</strong> victim rights movement, in general, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Amendment in specific, have<br />

stressed retribution as <strong>the</strong> sole remedy for victims, at <strong>the</strong> cost of fur<strong>the</strong>r emotionally<br />

damaging <strong>the</strong> victim. Henderson, supra note 92, at 606.<br />

To some degree, I concur with both Professors’ reservations. This Essay does not argue<br />

that <strong>the</strong> acting out of revenge is <strong>the</strong> only, best, or even appropriate response for all victims.<br />

What it does suggest, however, is that state regulated revenge- where <strong>the</strong> victim is<br />

empowered, under law, to partake in <strong>the</strong> punishment rendering decision- may, for some<br />

victims, be <strong>the</strong> only, best, or at least a helpful means to effectuate <strong>the</strong>ir recovery. It is just<br />

with <strong>the</strong> supposition that revenge can never perform such a service that I take exception.<br />

165. NOZICK, supra note 30, at 367. See also MURPHY, supra note 79, at 89 (equating<br />

vengeance with “a hatred that seems to take delight in <strong>the</strong>ir [wrongdoers] suffering.”).<br />

166. GLOVER, supra note 93, at 145.


40 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

While seemingly separate criticisms, <strong>the</strong> two are really dependant upon<br />

<strong>the</strong> validity of one ano<strong>the</strong>r, since under this argument, what makes revenge<br />

immoral on its face, is that it affords no true benefit to society or <strong>the</strong> victim.<br />

If, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, one could point to actual benefits which could arise<br />

from vengeance seeking, one could consequently argue <strong>the</strong> efficacy <strong>and</strong><br />

thus argue, on balance, <strong>the</strong> morality of <strong>the</strong> act. Charles Barton, in his book<br />

Getting Even: <strong>Revenge</strong> as a Form of <strong>Justice</strong>, 167 attempts to do just that.<br />

He takes issue with both assertions, maintaining that <strong>the</strong>re are positive<br />

emotional benefits which may accrue to <strong>the</strong> victim who exacts revenge, <strong>and</strong><br />

that as such, revenge when it fur<strong>the</strong>rs <strong>the</strong> attainment of those benefits, is a<br />

moral response.<br />

For instance, Barton notes that some victims may experience a sense<br />

of relief after exacting <strong>the</strong>ir vengeance. 168 This relief may manifest itself in<br />

a number of ways. First, noting that victims often experience feelings of<br />

humiliation, resentment, <strong>and</strong> anger, he postulates that upon meting out<br />

vengeance, victims can experience a diminution of <strong>the</strong>se “intense <strong>and</strong> taxing<br />

emotions,” <strong>and</strong> thus experience relief since <strong>the</strong>y are no longer burdened by<br />

<strong>the</strong>m. 169 Also, he suggests that a successful act of revenge can offer <strong>the</strong><br />

victim a sense of security; a belief that he will be able to cope , if, sometime<br />

in <strong>the</strong> future, he is once again <strong>the</strong> victim of a crime. Thus one may<br />

experience relief in realizing that he will be able to defend himself, <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

survive, fur<strong>the</strong>r victimization. 170<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r emotion which Barton suggests that a revenger may<br />

experience is <strong>the</strong> sense of satisfaction; not in a sadistic sense of<br />

experiencing pleasure from his victimizer’s suffering, 171 but ra<strong>the</strong>r as<br />

experienced by <strong>the</strong> avengers in Littell’s novel, 172 in <strong>the</strong> sense of regaining<br />

one’s sense of self-worth <strong>and</strong> identity. 173 In a similar vein, Professor Robert<br />

167. BARTON, supra note 30.<br />

168. Id. at 17-18.<br />

169. Id.<br />

170. Id.<br />

171. Id. at 18.<br />

172. See supra notes 159-60 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text; see also BARTON, supra note 30,<br />

at 106 (“A very important aspect of this empowerment would be that <strong>the</strong>y [victims] would<br />

be able to establish a relationship of equality vis a vis <strong>the</strong>ir wrongdoers, which would spare<br />

<strong>the</strong>m from <strong>the</strong> role of being helpless victims.”).<br />

173. BARTON, supra note 30, at 18; see also Tamar Frankel, Lessons From <strong>the</strong> Past:<br />

<strong>Revenge</strong> Yesterday <strong>and</strong> Today, 76 B.U. L. REV. 89, 100 (1996) (“Crimes can be viewed as<br />

inflicting a ‘moral injury’ that devalues <strong>the</strong> victims. <strong>Revenge</strong>-like remedies can restore <strong>the</strong>


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 41<br />

Solomon suggests that victims can also experience a sense of satisfaction<br />

by realizing that through <strong>the</strong>ir act of vengeance <strong>the</strong>y have helped to achieve<br />

a sense of justice, <strong>and</strong> thus put “<strong>the</strong> world back in balance.” 174<br />

A related psychological benefit of revenge is that it permits <strong>the</strong> victim<br />

to express, not only in word, but in deed, <strong>the</strong> sense of outrage <strong>and</strong><br />

resentment which she experiences as a result of <strong>the</strong> offender’s actions. As<br />

a result of expressing such resentment, <strong>the</strong> victim acknowledges one’s own<br />

self-respect. 175 This relationship between vengeance, resentment <strong>and</strong> selfesteem<br />

is set out by <strong>the</strong> philosopher Jean Hampton, who writes that “<strong>the</strong><br />

ability to feel resentment following a wrongdoing depends upon one’s having<br />

enough sense of one’s own worth to believe that <strong>the</strong> treatment is<br />

inappropriate <strong>and</strong> worthy of protest.” 176 Indeed, as Solomon writes, “<strong>the</strong><br />

wholesale denial of vengeance as a legitimate motive may be a<br />

psychological disaster.” 177<br />

Yet, even if one agrees that vengeance can provide a measure of<br />

solace <strong>and</strong> comfort to victims, does not necessarily lead to <strong>the</strong> conclusion<br />

that it is <strong>the</strong> function of <strong>the</strong> law to provide such comfort. Apart from arguing<br />

that any victim satisfaction which comes from <strong>the</strong> suffering of her offender<br />

is per se, immoral, (an argument which has been rejected earlier), 178 one<br />

can still legitimately raise <strong>the</strong> question whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> law should be concerned<br />

with <strong>the</strong> well being of <strong>the</strong> victim. For instance, Professor Susan B<strong>and</strong>es<br />

calls upon. “. . . us [to] be careful to distinguish <strong>the</strong> question of what victims<br />

need from <strong>the</strong> question of what <strong>the</strong> legal system ought to provide.” 179 She<br />

notes that some of <strong>the</strong> emotional benefits which victims need are available<br />

through o<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>and</strong> one could argue, more appropriate, sources, such as<br />

religion, psychological counseling, <strong>and</strong> family. 180<br />

There is certainly merit to Professor B<strong>and</strong>es’ position. Obviously, <strong>the</strong><br />

law cannot provide to every victim, all that <strong>the</strong>y need to recover. In fact,<br />

it is doubtful whe<strong>the</strong>r any one source is capable of fulfilling such an<br />

victims’ value in <strong>the</strong>ir own eyes <strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> eyes of o<strong>the</strong>rs. . . .[T]hus, revenge-like<br />

punishment can in some sense repair <strong>the</strong> violation of personal integrity that crime creates.”).<br />

174. Solomon, supra note 11, at 252-53.<br />

175. BARTON, supra note 30, at 28.<br />

176. JEFFRIE G. MURPHY & JEAN HAMPTON, FORGIVENESS AND MERCY 55 (1988).<br />

177. Solomon, supra note 11, at 253.<br />

178. See generally supra notes 70-125 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

179. Susan B<strong>and</strong>es, When Victims Seek Closure: Forgiveness, Vengeance <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Role<br />

of Government, 27 FORDHAM URB. L.J. 1599, 1605 (2000).<br />

180. Id. at 1605-06.


42 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

enormous undertaking. However, <strong>the</strong> law is <strong>the</strong> only venue which can<br />

provide victims with one source of <strong>the</strong>ir recovery; that is, <strong>the</strong> knowledge<br />

that <strong>the</strong>ir offender has been adequately punished. If <strong>the</strong> law fails to perform<br />

that function, <strong>the</strong>n society faces <strong>the</strong> very perils which forced <strong>the</strong> state to<br />

first interject itself into resolving disputes between its citizens; that<br />

individuals will seek revenge on <strong>the</strong>ir own, thus leading us back to <strong>the</strong> days<br />

of <strong>the</strong> blood feud.<br />

What I believe is Professor B<strong>and</strong>es’ underlying premise is that <strong>the</strong> law<br />

cannot simply base <strong>the</strong> harshness of punishment upon <strong>the</strong> level which<br />

victims believe <strong>the</strong>y need for closure. 181 For example, assuming that a<br />

victim of an assault could demonstrate that her emotional healing depended<br />

upon <strong>the</strong> execution of her assailant, such a level of punishment could not be<br />

justified since <strong>the</strong> penalty would clearly be disproportionate to <strong>the</strong> crime.<br />

However, as argued earlier, <strong>the</strong> calculations of proportionality are not<br />

capable of exactitude. 182 There are ranges of punishments which could be<br />

deemed to be proportional <strong>and</strong> just. All that I am suggesting is that given <strong>the</strong><br />

emotional healing which vengeance may provide to victims, 183 it is a<br />

181. Id. at 1606 (“Sometimes <strong>the</strong> legal system may be able to provide a punishment,<br />

or a result, that meets <strong>the</strong> individual’s needs for vengeance, forgiveness, closure . . . . But <strong>the</strong><br />

legal system cannot <strong>and</strong> ought not meet such needs on a case by case basis.”).<br />

182. See supra note 69.<br />

183. Professor B<strong>and</strong>es, in her article, Reply to Paul Cassell, What We Know About<br />

Victim Impact Statements, 1999 UTAH L. REV. 545, 551 (1999) [hereinafter Reply to Paul<br />

Cassell], notes that <strong>the</strong> empirical evidence is inconclusive regarding whe<strong>the</strong>r victim impact<br />

statements increase victim satisfaction with <strong>the</strong> criminal justice system. This argument has<br />

been raised by o<strong>the</strong>r commentators when arguing against victim involvement. See, e.g.,<br />

Henderson, supra note 16, at 964-66.<br />

I would respond to <strong>the</strong>se comments with <strong>the</strong> following points. First, I must confess a<br />

certain skepticism regarding such studies, or at least <strong>the</strong> way <strong>the</strong>y are used by some to argue<br />

against victim involvement based upon revenge. For instance, it would appear that those<br />

studies cited by Professors B<strong>and</strong>es <strong>and</strong> Henderson deal primarily with <strong>the</strong> efficacy of victim<br />

impact statements to assist in <strong>the</strong> healing process. See, e.g., Edna Erez, Who’s Afraid of <strong>the</strong><br />

Big Bad Victim? Victim Impact Statements as Victim Empowerment <strong>and</strong> Enhancement of<br />

<strong>Justice</strong>, 1999 CRIM. L. REV. 545, cited in Reply to Paul Cassell, supra note 183, at 552 n.31.<br />

It might well be that <strong>the</strong> reason victim impact statements do not significantly help victims<br />

is because <strong>the</strong>y do not give victims enough of a voice in <strong>the</strong> decision making process. In that<br />

event, I would suggest that <strong>the</strong> remedy would be to provide greater victim participation,<br />

ra<strong>the</strong>r than less. See infra note 244 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text (discussing possible alternatives<br />

to victim impact statements).<br />

Next, while <strong>the</strong> studies may be inconclusive, <strong>the</strong>y do not prove <strong>the</strong> ineffectiveness of


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 43<br />

legitimate function of <strong>the</strong> law to permit victims’ desire for revenge to<br />

influence what are, by <strong>the</strong>ir very nature, discretionary judgments regarding<br />

punishment.<br />

If <strong>the</strong>n, vengeance can have an ameliorative effect for some victims, 184<br />

victim impact statements. While some studies showed a decrease in victim satisfaction,<br />

o<strong>the</strong>rs demonstrated some increase in satisfaction. See, e.g., Edna Erez, Victim Participation<br />

in Sentencing: And <strong>the</strong> Debate Goes On. . . . , 3 INT’L REV. VICTIMOLOGY 17, 24 (1994),<br />

cited in Reply to Paul Cassell, supra note 183, at 552 n.33. In fact, such findings should not<br />

be unexpected, for as Professor B<strong>and</strong>es herself notes, it is “<strong>the</strong> intuitively obvious view that<br />

different victims have different needs.” B<strong>and</strong>es, supra note 179, at 1602. Consistent with<br />

that observation, one would expect such studies to be “inconclusive,” in <strong>the</strong> sense that <strong>the</strong>y<br />

would indicate that while victim involvement may not be ameliorative in all cases, such<br />

participation does provide benefits for some victims.<br />

Moreover, Professors B<strong>and</strong>es <strong>and</strong> Henderson do not consider <strong>the</strong> reasons why victim<br />

impact statements have not proven to be as effective as one may wish. One article, authored<br />

by Edna Erez, who also authored <strong>the</strong> two studies cited above by Professor B<strong>and</strong>es, suggests<br />

that <strong>the</strong> reason why victim statements have had such little effect on criminal justice<br />

proceedings is “<strong>the</strong> legal professionals’ strong resistance against accepting victims as a<br />

legitimate party in <strong>the</strong> proceedings <strong>and</strong> practitioners’ reluctance to recognize any value in<br />

victim input.” Edna Erez, Integrating A Victim Perspective Through Victim Impact<br />

Statements, in INTEGRATING A VICTIM PERSPECTIVE WITHIN CRIMINAL JUSTICE 178-79<br />

(Adam Crawford & Jo Goodey eds., 2000). In fact, she believes that affording victims such<br />

rights can empower <strong>the</strong>m by increasing <strong>the</strong>ir sense of control over <strong>the</strong> process, <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

concludes “that <strong>the</strong>re is every reason to include, <strong>and</strong> no reason to fear, integrating a victim<br />

voice through victim impact statements.” Id.<br />

Lastly, even if no emotional benefits accrue to victims as a result of increasing <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

opportunity for involvement, I would still argue in favor of affording victims such options,<br />

simply based on <strong>the</strong> fact that as victims, <strong>the</strong>y have earned that right, regardless of any<br />

Utilitarian benefits which might or might not result. I would base this right under an<br />

exp<strong>and</strong>ed <strong>the</strong>ory of classical Retribution, which is discussed in Section VIII. See infra note<br />

228 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

184. A victim need not actually choose to become involved in <strong>the</strong> criminal law process<br />

in order to experience a sense of empowerment. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, simply being given <strong>the</strong> option of<br />

participation, <strong>and</strong> knowing that should she desire, she could have an influence upon<br />

punishment, could satisfy <strong>the</strong> need for revenge. See, e.g., MURPHY, supra note 79, at 25<br />

(“Just getting <strong>the</strong> person in a position where one has <strong>the</strong> power to inflict harm may be<br />

satisfying enough, <strong>and</strong> that may itself be <strong>the</strong> revenge.”) (emphasis in original).<br />

Indeed, perhaps in part, <strong>the</strong> Biblical story of Joseph, ano<strong>the</strong>r son of Jacob, who was<br />

sold by his bro<strong>the</strong>rs into slavery, can be explained under such reasoning. See supra notes 1-8<br />

<strong>and</strong> accompanying text (providing additional background). As a slave, Joseph impresses <strong>the</strong><br />

Pharaoh, <strong>and</strong> is subsequently granted great power <strong>and</strong> wealth. Years later, his bro<strong>the</strong>rs are<br />

brought before him. Clearly he holds <strong>the</strong> power to severely punish his bro<strong>the</strong>rs. Yet, he


44 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

<strong>and</strong> if it is agreed that within <strong>the</strong> bounds of proportionality, it is a function of<br />

<strong>the</strong> law to effectuate that effect, <strong>the</strong> next task is to determine whe<strong>the</strong>r our<br />

criminal justice system, in fact, performs that function. I would argue, that<br />

it does not. Under our current criminal justice system, <strong>the</strong> state decides<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r to bring criminal charges, what those charges will be, whe<strong>the</strong>r to<br />

accept a plea bargain, whe<strong>the</strong>r to go to trial, <strong>and</strong> what <strong>the</strong> strategy at trial<br />

will be, including whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> victim will even testify against <strong>the</strong> accused.<br />

The state, through <strong>the</strong> judge, decides matters of law. And only those<br />

disinterested citizens, who, by definition, can not qualify as a revenger,<br />

decide <strong>the</strong> innocence or guilt of <strong>the</strong> accused. If convicted, <strong>the</strong> state decides<br />

what penalty it will seek, <strong>and</strong> ei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> jury or judge decides sentence.<br />

Notably absent from any prescribed role in <strong>the</strong>se proceedings is <strong>the</strong><br />

victim. He has no power to regain by himself, that which his victimizer has<br />

taken from him, but ra<strong>the</strong>r must rely on someone else to do it for him.<br />

Consequently, under our current system, <strong>the</strong> victim is once again<br />

disempowered. He can not dem<strong>and</strong> punishment, he may only request it; he<br />

cannot dem<strong>and</strong> restitution, he may only plea for it; he cannot dem<strong>and</strong><br />

atonement, he can only hope for it. The potential for a victim to regain his<br />

loss of honor <strong>and</strong> respect under our current system, is thus far less likely<br />

than under a system which allows revenge. Indeed, while a revenge system<br />

is designed precisely to create that possibility; our system, whe<strong>the</strong>r by<br />

design or merely effect, is not.<br />

Our justice system devalues victims of crime in ano<strong>the</strong>r way. By<br />

marginalizing victims <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir desires for justice, <strong>the</strong> system validates <strong>the</strong><br />

victimizers’ perceptions of <strong>the</strong>ir victims. Most criminals, particularly those<br />

convicted of violent crimes, devalue <strong>the</strong>ir victims as a predicate to <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

activity. 185 It is, after all, much easier to abuse a person for whom you have<br />

little or no regard, than one for whom you respect <strong>and</strong> honor.<br />

A worthy goal of <strong>the</strong> criminal justice system (at least under a utilitarian<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory) should be to reverse that perception; that as a means of his<br />

rehabilitation, <strong>the</strong> criminal needs to acknowledge <strong>and</strong> accept responsibility<br />

for <strong>the</strong> harm which he has caused to ano<strong>the</strong>r. Recognizing <strong>the</strong> humanity of<br />

forgives <strong>the</strong>m. Genesis 39-45 (King James).<br />

185. See, e.g., Jo-Ann Tsang, Moral Rationalization <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> Integration of Situational<br />

Factors <strong>and</strong> Psychological Processes in Immoral Behavior, in 6 REV. OF GEN.<br />

PSYCHOLOGY 25, 41 (Mar. 1, 2002) (“Ano<strong>the</strong>r way to preserve one’s sense of morality<br />

while still behaving immorally is by dehumanizing victims.”).


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 45<br />

his victim is often a step in that direction. 186 This rehabilitation could lead to<br />

remorse, apology, <strong>and</strong> a plea for forgiveness from <strong>the</strong> victim. Such<br />

expressions have also been found to help victims recover from <strong>the</strong> trauma<br />

of <strong>the</strong> crimes. 187<br />

But instead, our criminal justice system reinforces <strong>the</strong> invisibility <strong>and</strong><br />

powerlessness of <strong>the</strong> victim, <strong>and</strong> thus perpetuates <strong>the</strong> criminal’s perception<br />

of <strong>the</strong> victim. Just as when <strong>the</strong>y were originally victimized, victims at trial<br />

are once again prevented from st<strong>and</strong>ing up for <strong>the</strong>mselves. Their needs <strong>and</strong><br />

desires are largely irrelevant. They are byst<strong>and</strong>ers in <strong>the</strong> process; 188 <strong>the</strong><br />

criminal need not address nor even acknowledge <strong>the</strong> victim, since it is <strong>the</strong><br />

district attorney’s office, <strong>the</strong> judge <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> jury, who hold all <strong>the</strong> power.<br />

Once again, <strong>the</strong> process has little or nothing to do with who <strong>the</strong> victim is, or<br />

186. See, e.g., Albert W. Dzur & Alan Wer<strong>the</strong>imer, Forgiveness <strong>and</strong> Public<br />

Deliberation: The Practice of Restorative <strong>Justice</strong>, 21 CRIM. JUST. ETHICS 3, 3-4 (2002)<br />

(noting that for offenders to successfully be reintegrated back into society, requires <strong>the</strong>m to<br />

“start to take responsibility for what <strong>the</strong>y did <strong>and</strong> erode whatever stereotypes <strong>and</strong><br />

rationalizations [regarding <strong>the</strong>ir victims] <strong>the</strong>y have constructed. . . . [<strong>and</strong>] admit <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

wrongful degradation of <strong>the</strong>ir victims.”).<br />

Dzur <strong>and</strong> Werheimer support <strong>the</strong> use of restorative justice to achieve <strong>the</strong>se goals, <strong>and</strong><br />

in <strong>the</strong>ir article, describe how restorative justice operates to <strong>the</strong> benefit of victim, wrongdoer,<br />

<strong>and</strong> society. See generally id. at 1-15. Of note is that similar to this Essay, <strong>the</strong> premise of<br />

restorative justice is that it is <strong>the</strong> individual harmed by <strong>the</strong> wrongdoer, <strong>and</strong> not <strong>the</strong> state, who<br />

is <strong>the</strong> true victim of <strong>the</strong> crime. See Mark S. Umbreit, Crime Victims Seeking Fairness, Not<br />

<strong>Revenge</strong>: Towards Restorative <strong>Justice</strong>, in FEDERAL PROBATION 52 (Sept. 1989). While<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is much to recommend about restorative justice, it has at least one inherent limitation;<br />

that being its inability to fashion punishments which entail incarceration of <strong>the</strong> wrong doer,<br />

since only <strong>the</strong> state can authorize such punishments. Thus, restorative programs stress<br />

restitution <strong>and</strong> repentance by <strong>the</strong> wrong doer to <strong>the</strong> victim, as <strong>the</strong> means to redress <strong>the</strong><br />

harms suffered by <strong>the</strong> victim. Id. Such a remedy may suffice in property crime cases, but<br />

would seem to fall short when dealing with crimes of violence. See infra notes 206-17 <strong>and</strong><br />

accompanying text (discussing <strong>the</strong> inadequacies of financial payments to victims under tort<br />

law).<br />

187. See, e.g., Cheryl Regehr & Thomas Gu<strong>the</strong>il, Apology, <strong>Justice</strong>, <strong>and</strong> Trauma<br />

Recovery, 30 J. AM. ACAD. PSYCHIATRY LAW 425, 430 (2002) (acknowledging that<br />

apologies may aid in victim recovery but cautions against viewing such acts of contrition as<br />

“a panacea leading to <strong>the</strong> healing of trauma under all circumstances”).<br />

188. See, e.g., Steve Baker, <strong>Justice</strong> Not <strong>Revenge</strong>: A Crime Victim’s Perspective on<br />

Capital Punishment, 40 UCLA L. REV. 339 (1992). Detective Baker, <strong>the</strong> fa<strong>the</strong>r of murdered<br />

teenage son, noted that “A good deal of my frustration stemmed from <strong>the</strong> feeling that, as a<br />

crime victim, I was an outsider to <strong>the</strong> criminal justice system.” Id. at 340.


46 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

what he wants.<br />

By recognizing <strong>the</strong> empowering features of revenge, I do not mean to<br />

suggest that we should revert back to <strong>the</strong> revenge cultures of thous<strong>and</strong>s of<br />

years ago. The dangers of such a legal system are just too profound <strong>and</strong><br />

enormous to even seriously consider such an option. But I do maintain that<br />

we need to recognize <strong>the</strong> sense of empowerment which revenge offered to<br />

victims, <strong>and</strong> also acknowledge that our current system fails to offer victims<br />

such opportunities to regain <strong>the</strong>ir self respect. For as Professor Solomon<br />

notes:<br />

When current criminal law reduces <strong>the</strong> victim of such crimes to a<br />

mere byst<strong>and</strong>er, . . . . <strong>the</strong> problem is not that in vengeance we take<br />

<strong>the</strong> law “into our own h<strong>and</strong>s” but ra<strong>the</strong>r that without vengeance<br />

justice seems not only to be taken out of our h<strong>and</strong>s but eliminated<br />

as a consideration all toge<strong>the</strong>r. 189<br />

VII. THE LIMITATIONS OF ALTERNATIVES TO REVENGE<br />

A. Forgiveness as Mode of Victim Healing<br />

Then came Peter to him <strong>and</strong> said, Lord, how oft shall my bro<strong>the</strong>r sin<br />

against me, <strong>and</strong> I forgive him? Till seven times? Jesus saith unto him, I say<br />

not unto <strong>the</strong>e, Until seven times: but until seventy times seven. Book of<br />

Mat<strong>the</strong>w 190<br />

What do you say concerning <strong>the</strong> principle that injury should be<br />

recompensed with kindness?”<br />

The Master said, “With what <strong>the</strong>n will you recompense kindness?<br />

Recompense injury with justice, <strong>and</strong> recompense kindness with<br />

kindness. Confucius 191<br />

In response to <strong>the</strong> argument that victims deserve a greater voice in<br />

deciding <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong>ir victimizers, some have argued that such<br />

189. Solomon, supra note 11, at 255.<br />

190. Mat<strong>the</strong>w 18:21-22 (King James).<br />

191. BARTON, supra note 30, at 99, citing 1 H. SPENCER, THE PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS<br />

366 (1966).


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 47<br />

measures are not really in <strong>the</strong> victims’ best interests. 192 Instead, as<br />

expressed by Professor Martha Minow in her book, Between Vengeance<br />

<strong>and</strong> Forgiveness, it is posited that <strong>the</strong> interests of victims, as well as <strong>the</strong><br />

interests of victimizers <strong>and</strong> society, are better served through processes<br />

which encourage victims to forgive <strong>the</strong>ir assailants because:<br />

Through forgiveness, we can renounce resentment, <strong>and</strong> avoid <strong>the</strong><br />

self destructive effects of holding on to pain, grudges <strong>and</strong><br />

victimhood. The act of forgiving can reconnect <strong>the</strong> offender <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> victim <strong>and</strong> establish or renew a relationship; it can heal grief;<br />

forge new, constructive alliances; <strong>and</strong> break cycles of violence. 193<br />

Programs which attempt to facilitate forgiveness vary in scope <strong>and</strong><br />

design. In some cases, nations, attempting to deal with a former regime’s<br />

use of torture <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r forms of mass atrocities, have established programs<br />

such as Truth Commissions, which encourage wrongdoers to come forth<br />

<strong>and</strong> confess <strong>the</strong>ir crimes, in exc hange for partial or complete amnesty. 194<br />

192. See generally Henderson, supra note 16, at 968-1021. Ano<strong>the</strong>r argument against<br />

vengeance, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> role it would play in allowing greater victim involvement, is based upon<br />

Jesus’ admonition that “He that is without sin among you, let him first cast a stone at her.”<br />

John 8:7 (King James). It is posited by some that this requires those who would punish<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r, to first look into <strong>the</strong>ir own souls <strong>and</strong> at <strong>the</strong>ir own behavior before judging <strong>and</strong><br />

punishing ano<strong>the</strong>r; <strong>the</strong> assump tion being that all mortals have sinned, <strong>and</strong> thus none are<br />

qualified to judge <strong>the</strong> behavior of o<strong>the</strong>rs. See MURPHY, supra note 79, at 89. I am more<br />

persuaded by Michael Moore, who, in his essay, The Moral Worth of Retribution, writes:<br />

It is true that all of us are guilty of some immoralities, probably on a daily basis.<br />

Yet for most people reading this essay, <strong>the</strong> immoralities in question are for things<br />

like manipulating o<strong>the</strong>rs unfairly; not caring deeply enough about ano<strong>the</strong>r’s<br />

suffering. . . . .<strong>and</strong> so forth. Few of us have raped <strong>and</strong> murdered a woman,<br />

drowned her three small children, <strong>and</strong> felt no remorse about it.<br />

MICHAEL MOORE, THE MORAL WORTH OF RETRIBUTION, cited in MURPHY, supra note<br />

79, at 90.<br />

193. MINOW, supra note 15, at 14.<br />

194. For example, soon after apar<strong>the</strong>id was abolished in South Africa, that nation’s first<br />

democratically elected Parliament created <strong>the</strong> Truth <strong>and</strong> Reconciliation Committee (TRC).<br />

See generally MINOW, supra note 15, at 52- 90. Generally, <strong>the</strong> purposes of such<br />

commissions are more to bring about national reconciliation than to address <strong>the</strong> individual<br />

needs of <strong>the</strong> victims of <strong>the</strong> earlier government’s atrocities. Indicative of that distinction is<br />

that under <strong>the</strong> South African TRC, abusers are granted amnesty merely for <strong>the</strong>ir truthful<br />

confessions of wrong doing. MURPHY, supra note 79, at 37. There is no requirement that


48 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

In cases of individual acts of violence, programs set up under restorative<br />

justice models, seek to bring victim <strong>and</strong> victimizer toge<strong>the</strong>r, where, with <strong>the</strong><br />

aid of facilitators, an attempt is made to help heal <strong>the</strong> victim <strong>and</strong> reform <strong>the</strong><br />

wrongdoer. 195<br />

In practice, however, <strong>the</strong> salutary effects of forgiveness are dependant<br />

upon a number of variables. First, <strong>the</strong> victim should not be made to feel that<br />

he must forgive, for “to expect survivors to forgive is to heap yet ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

burden on <strong>the</strong>m.” 196 Thus, a victim’s participation in <strong>the</strong> process must be<br />

voluntary . Compelling participation usurps <strong>the</strong> victim’s right to determine<br />

what is in his best interests, <strong>and</strong> in a sense, once again forces <strong>the</strong> victim to<br />

be subject to <strong>the</strong> will of ano<strong>the</strong>r; albeit in this case, under <strong>the</strong> paternalistic<br />

guise of forcing <strong>the</strong> victim to do so for his “own good.”<br />

Indeed, forgiveness may not, in fact, serve <strong>the</strong> interests of all victims,<br />

or society, for that matter. 197 For whatever reason, victims may not want to<br />

forgive, <strong>and</strong> may need, or merely choose, to resolve <strong>the</strong>ir psychological<br />

difficulties through o<strong>the</strong>r venues, such as victim rights support groups <strong>and</strong><br />

individual <strong>the</strong>rapy. Or, victims may choose to channel <strong>the</strong>ir anger into<br />

actions which are aimed at preventing future acts of similar violence. For<br />

instance, one can argue that Simeon Wiesenthal, a Holocaust survivor who<br />

has dedicated his life to bringing ex-Nazis to justice, <strong>and</strong> John Walsh, fa<strong>the</strong>r<br />

of a kidnaped <strong>and</strong> murdered son, who has helped increase public awareness<br />

regarding <strong>the</strong> plight of missing children, have both chosen to direct <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

anger as victims towards positive social goals. As Professor Minow writes:<br />

Learning to manage or extinguish pain <strong>and</strong> resentment, becoming<br />

<strong>the</strong> abusers exhibit a sincere sense of repentance; a characteristic which is recognized as<br />

intrinsic to individual victim healing. Id. at 35.<br />

195. See generally Dzur & Wer<strong>the</strong>imer, supra note 186, at 2-4. Given <strong>the</strong> scope of this<br />

Essay, forgiveness will be examined within <strong>the</strong> context of individual victims of crime, ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than groups who are victimized due to governmental sponsored atrocities.<br />

Though sometimes viewed as such, <strong>the</strong> concepts of retribution <strong>and</strong> restorative justice<br />

are not inherently inconsistent with one ano<strong>the</strong>r. Indeed, a victim may, as a condition of, or<br />

a prerequisite to “restoration,” need to know that his victimizer will be punished for his acts.<br />

BARTON, supra note 30, at 7. See also infra notes 199-201.<br />

196. MINOW, supra note 15, at 17.<br />

197. For instance, a victim of rape may wish to forgive her rapist, <strong>and</strong> impose no<br />

criminal punishment. However, forgiveness in this context would likely run contrary to<br />

society’s retributive <strong>and</strong> utilitarian interests in dem<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> rapist’s punishment. See<br />

BARTON, supra note 30, at 99.


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 49<br />

able to sleep <strong>and</strong> get on with life, to co-exist with former enemies<br />

are valuable goals; but <strong>the</strong>y do not require, entail, nor<br />

necessarily accompany grants of forgiveness.<br />

Fundamentally, forgiveness cannot be comm<strong>and</strong>ed. [I]ndividual<br />

human beings are just that, individual human beings, both before<br />

<strong>and</strong> after anyone is victimized <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>n labeled as a victim.<br />

Individuals respond uniquely <strong>and</strong> differently to horror. At least <strong>the</strong><br />

responses are <strong>the</strong>ir own. To dem<strong>and</strong> different ones may yet be<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r form of degradation <strong>and</strong> denial of <strong>the</strong>ir very being. 198<br />

A second reservation concerns <strong>the</strong> victimizer’s motivation for agreeing<br />

to participate in <strong>the</strong> process. Participation can not primarily be motivated by<br />

an expectation of leniency of punishment, for if that be <strong>the</strong> case, one would<br />

certainly have to question <strong>the</strong> sincerity of <strong>the</strong> victimizer’s acceptance of<br />

responsibility <strong>and</strong> remorse. The criminal must engage in <strong>the</strong> process not<br />

merely because it might reduce his sentence, but also with a sincere desire<br />

<strong>and</strong> willingness to acknowledge his fault. 199 Without such an honest<br />

approach by <strong>the</strong> victimizer, any realistic hope for victim healing <strong>and</strong><br />

victimizer rehabilitation is lost.<br />

Thus, both victim <strong>and</strong> victimizer must enter <strong>the</strong> process willingly, <strong>and</strong><br />

with a sincerity of purpose. In light of <strong>the</strong>se prerequisites to participation,<br />

one can readily conclude that forgiveness is not a viable option for all<br />

victims <strong>and</strong> victimizers.<br />

A third caveat to forgiveness is <strong>the</strong> recognition that forgiveness should<br />

not be seen as an alternative to punishment. As I have argued previously,<br />

victims <strong>and</strong> society have <strong>the</strong> moral right to dem<strong>and</strong> that wrongdoers be<br />

punished, <strong>and</strong> suffer for <strong>the</strong>ir wrongful acts. To allow victimizers to dem<strong>and</strong><br />

complete amnesty in return for <strong>the</strong>ir participation in <strong>the</strong> process would<br />

unduly reward <strong>the</strong>m for <strong>the</strong>ir cooperation, as well as cast doubt upon <strong>the</strong><br />

sincerity of <strong>the</strong>ir participation. 200 While victimizer participation could be<br />

acknowledged through some reduction in sentence, it should not be allowed<br />

to be used as a substitute to punishment. 201<br />

198. MINOW, supra note 15, at 20 (emphasis added).<br />

199. See MINOW, supra note 15, at 18; see also MURPHY, supra note 79, at 39 (arguing<br />

that sincere repentance should be made a condition for forgiveness).<br />

200. In this manner, individual forgiveness models differ from <strong>the</strong> national forgiveness<br />

models such as <strong>the</strong> TRC in South Africa. See supra note 194 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

201. Under such a scenario, victimizer participation would permit <strong>the</strong> sentencing body


50 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

With <strong>the</strong>se reservations, a criminal justice system which in some<br />

manner encourages forgiveness certainly can fur<strong>the</strong>r worthwhile societal<br />

goals. For <strong>the</strong> purposes of this Essay, however, ano<strong>the</strong>r issue must be<br />

discussed: Is a criminal justice system which recognizes forgiveness<br />

compatible with one that also recognizes <strong>the</strong> victim’s desire for revenge?<br />

In o<strong>the</strong>r words, can a system offer victims both <strong>the</strong> right to have a<br />

meaningful role in deciding punishment, <strong>and</strong> also provide <strong>the</strong> same victims<br />

<strong>the</strong> opportunity to engage in processes which may lead to forgiveness?<br />

I believe both goals, revenge <strong>and</strong> forgiveness, can co-exist within <strong>the</strong><br />

same legal system. Indeed our cultural <strong>and</strong> religious norms reflect our<br />

acceptance of both values. For example, <strong>the</strong> concepts of justice <strong>and</strong><br />

retribution are recognized in <strong>the</strong> Old Testament of <strong>the</strong> Bible, while in <strong>the</strong><br />

New Testament, <strong>the</strong> virtues of redemption <strong>and</strong> forgiveness are extolled. 202<br />

I would argue that such duality of purposes is as much at place in <strong>the</strong> law<br />

as in religion. 203<br />

I recognize this duality, despite <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> two emotions are, in a<br />

very real sense, inapposite to one ano<strong>the</strong>r; for while “forgiveness is to let go<br />

of vengeance, to avenge is to resist forgiving.” 204 Thus, it is probably true<br />

to demonstrate mercy, but not forgiveness. It is in this context where <strong>the</strong> related concepts<br />

of mercy <strong>and</strong> forgiveness are sometimes confused. The act of mercy is demonstrated by<br />

choosing to punish a wrongdoer less than what <strong>the</strong> law would allow, <strong>and</strong> while perhaps<br />

influenced by <strong>the</strong> victim’s forgiveness, is granted by someone o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> victim, such as<br />

<strong>the</strong> sentencing judge or jury. Forgiveness of a wrongdoer, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, is an internal<br />

process which is felt by <strong>the</strong> victim, <strong>and</strong> can only be granted by <strong>the</strong> victim. Forgiveness can<br />

also exist even without any outward demonstration of forgiveness by <strong>the</strong> victim. See<br />

MURPHY, supra note 79, at 13-14.<br />

202. See supra notes 75-82, 112-114 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

203. See, e.g., Solomon, supra note 11, at 256 (“A creature endowed only with<br />

compassion, who would ‘underst<strong>and</strong>’ <strong>the</strong> motives of <strong>the</strong> criminal in every case, would be<br />

just as much an evolutionary failure as a creature who did nothing but watch out for his or<br />

her own advantage <strong>and</strong> cheated every time.”).<br />

204. MINOW, supra note 11, at 21. But see JACOBY, supra note 11, at 79 (“The phrase<br />

‘Old Testament vengeance’ has frequently been used as pejorative by Christian<br />

proselytizers to emphasis what <strong>the</strong>y regard as <strong>the</strong> fundamental distinction between Judaism<br />

<strong>and</strong> Christianity; i.e. Christ’s emphasis on forgiveness as opposed to strict Mosaic<br />

retribution. This mistaken view of Judaic revenge is partly attributable to <strong>the</strong> conviction that<br />

Christianity is <strong>the</strong> fulfilment of Hebrew prophesy, <strong>and</strong> is, as such, <strong>the</strong> divinely ordained<br />

successor to Judaism.”).<br />

An illuminating example of this perception is portrayed in <strong>the</strong> movie Dead Man<br />

Walking. In <strong>the</strong> film, Susan Sar<strong>and</strong>on plays Sister Helen Prejean, a nun who is counseling


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 51<br />

that one cannot forgive while at <strong>the</strong> same time, seek revenge. However, this<br />

conflict presupposes that both emotions must be acted upon simultaneously.<br />

I would propose, instead, that in many cases, victims may be capable of<br />

forgiveness, only after <strong>the</strong>y have experienced a sense of empowerment by<br />

having a meaningful role in <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong>ir victimizers. Under that<br />

scenario, forgiveness may not become an option until <strong>the</strong> criminal has been<br />

imprisoned for years. Indeed, one can argue that until after <strong>the</strong> victimizer<br />

has been punished for his wrong, he has not earned <strong>the</strong> right to even seek<br />

<strong>the</strong> forgiveness of his victim. 205<br />

B. Tort <strong>Law</strong> as A Model for Victim Healing<br />

A tort is not <strong>the</strong> same thing as a crime. . . .So far as <strong>the</strong> criminal law is<br />

concerned, <strong>the</strong> victim will leave <strong>the</strong> courtroom empty-h<strong>and</strong>ed. The civil<br />

action for a tort, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, is commenced <strong>and</strong> maintained by <strong>the</strong><br />

injured person, <strong>and</strong> its primary purpose is to compensate for <strong>the</strong> damage<br />

suffered, at <strong>the</strong> expense of <strong>the</strong> wrongdoer. 206 Prosser <strong>and</strong> Keaton on Torts.<br />

Her disdain for blood money was not unusual. Some Holocaust<br />

survivors refused to accept German reparations. So did some Korean<br />

women who were offered compensation by <strong>the</strong> Japanese for being forced<br />

into prostitution during World War II. They claimed that blood money<br />

commodicized <strong>the</strong>ir pain. Ra<strong>the</strong>r than restoring honor, it humiliated <strong>the</strong>m<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>r. Not only were <strong>the</strong>y hurt, but that hurt could be bought. The<br />

infinity of anguish could be measured; owned. 207 Laura Blumenfeld.<br />

Sean Penn’s character, a convicted rapist <strong>and</strong> murderer, who is soon to be executed for his<br />

crimes. She engages in a debate with <strong>the</strong> minister of <strong>the</strong> prison regarding <strong>the</strong> morality of<br />

capital punishment. The Sister, who is opposed to capital punishment, continually cites to<br />

<strong>the</strong> New Testament to support her argument for mercy <strong>and</strong> forgiveness. The prison minister,<br />

in favor of <strong>the</strong> execution, continually cites to <strong>the</strong> Old Testament, to support his argument<br />

for retribution. DEAD MAN WALKING (Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer 1995).<br />

205. In this respect, I would exp<strong>and</strong> upon a point raised by Professor Murphy. He<br />

writes that it would be inconsistent for a victim who claims that she has forgiven her<br />

offender, to none<strong>the</strong>less favor punishing <strong>the</strong> offender out of a sense of vengeance. MURPHY,<br />

supra note 79, at 14. Yet, a victim could choose to punish out of vengeance, <strong>and</strong> subsequent<br />

to <strong>the</strong> wrongdoer’s punishment, still forgive. Only when one presumes that both forgiveness<br />

<strong>and</strong> punishment must occur simultaneously, are <strong>the</strong> two necessarily inconsistent with one<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r.<br />

206. PROSSER AND KEATON ON TORTS 7 (5th ed. 1984).<br />

207. LAURA BLUMENFELD, REVENGE: A STORY OF HOPE 87 (2002) (emphasis added).


52 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r argument raised against affording victims a greater opportunity<br />

for involvement in <strong>the</strong> criminal justice system is that <strong>the</strong>y are already<br />

afforded <strong>the</strong>ir day in court under civil tort law. Tort law provides victims<br />

with <strong>the</strong> opportunity to file <strong>the</strong>ir own law suits, hire <strong>the</strong>ir own lawyers,<br />

decide trial strategy, <strong>and</strong> appeal decisions. If successful, <strong>the</strong>y can recover<br />

monetary damages from <strong>the</strong> defendant designed to “make <strong>the</strong>m whole,” 208<br />

<strong>and</strong> in most states, if <strong>the</strong> defendant’s act is particularly egregious, <strong>the</strong>y can<br />

receive punitive monetary damages as well. 209 For physical attacks <strong>the</strong>y can<br />

recover under <strong>the</strong> torts of assault <strong>and</strong> battery. 210 For <strong>the</strong>ft <strong>the</strong>y can recover<br />

under <strong>the</strong> tort of conversion. 211 They can also recover for <strong>the</strong>ir emotional 212<br />

as well as <strong>the</strong>ir physical injuries. Thus, in <strong>the</strong>ory, victims as plaintiffs in civil<br />

tort law suits can seek <strong>and</strong> receive <strong>the</strong>ir individual justice. 213<br />

However, in practice, this is frequently an illusory option. The<br />

availability of monetary damages is only as real as <strong>the</strong> defendant’s financial<br />

resources. For example, almost 90% of all inmates in state prisons<br />

convicted of violent crimes have only a high school education or less, <strong>and</strong><br />

almost 40% have less than a high school education. 214 Such defendants are<br />

thus unlikely to be able to satisfy judgments which award substantial<br />

monetary damages to <strong>the</strong> victim-plaintiff . Consequently, if a victim is<br />

unfortunate enough to have been assaulted by a poor defendant, <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

little chance that she will ever recover monetary damages.<br />

On a more profound level, one must question <strong>the</strong> level of satisfaction<br />

which tort suits can bring to victims, even if <strong>the</strong>y do result in monetary<br />

awards which are recoverable. The primary purpose of a civil law suit is not<br />

to punish <strong>the</strong> victimizer or to make him suffer. There is no incarceration of<br />

<strong>the</strong> defendant who is found liable in tort. At <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> trial, <strong>the</strong><br />

defendant, regardless of <strong>the</strong> outcome, is free to go home. All <strong>the</strong> defendant<br />

is required to do is to pay <strong>the</strong> victim money.<br />

And what does that money represent? Under tort law, payment by <strong>the</strong><br />

208. See generally PROSSER, supra note 206, at 7.<br />

209. Id. at 9-10.<br />

210. See generally id. at 39-46.<br />

211. See generally id. at 88-107.<br />

212. Id. at 57.<br />

213. See OPPENHEIMER, supra note 19, 24-35 (providing a historical analysis of <strong>the</strong><br />

intersection of tort <strong>and</strong> criminal law).<br />

214. CAROLINE W. HARLOW, BUREAU OF JUSTICE STATISTICS, U.S. DEP’T OF<br />

JUSTICE, EDUCATION AND CORRECTIONAL POPULATIONS 10 (Jan. 2003, rev’d April 15,<br />

2003).


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 53<br />

defendant (wrongdoer) to <strong>the</strong> plaintiff (victim) represents “satisfaction” 215<br />

of <strong>the</strong> plaintiff’s claim. Thus, in a very real sense, <strong>the</strong> victim’s acceptance<br />

of <strong>the</strong> payment is her acknowledgment that <strong>the</strong> harm she suffered was<br />

reducible to a monetary figure. Such acceptance also represents her<br />

acknowledgment that <strong>the</strong> monetary award constitutes all that is owed to her<br />

by <strong>the</strong> wrongdoer for <strong>the</strong> harms he inflicted upon her.<br />

No wonder, not all victims are willing to accept such “blood money,”<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>reby let <strong>the</strong>ir victimizers off so easily. Be it survivors of <strong>the</strong><br />

Holocaust, Korean women forced into prostitution by <strong>the</strong> Japanese during<br />

World War II, 216 or children who were sexually abused by Catholic<br />

priests, 217 some victims view financial restitution as a derogation, ra<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

as a recognition of <strong>the</strong> harms which <strong>the</strong>y were forced to suffer, <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

refuse to accept such money.<br />

VIII. PLACING REVENGE WITHIN THE UTILITARIAN AND RETRIBUTIVE<br />

MODELS<br />

How does accepting that revenge has a place in deciding punishment<br />

fit within <strong>the</strong> traditional <strong>the</strong>ories which support punishing those found guilty<br />

of committing a crime? As discussed earlier, two <strong>the</strong>ories have generally<br />

been advanced for justifying <strong>the</strong> state’s imposing of punishment. One<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory, Utilitarianism, proposes that punishment is justified only if o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

societal interests are fur<strong>the</strong>red, such as <strong>the</strong> deterring of future criminal<br />

behavior, <strong>the</strong> rehabilitation of <strong>the</strong> criminal, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> incapacitation of <strong>the</strong><br />

criminal so as to protect society from his future criminal acts. 218 The second<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory, Retribution, rejects <strong>the</strong> rationale that punishment is only justified if<br />

those societal goals are fur<strong>the</strong>red. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, it is deontological in nature; its<br />

underlying justification is that a wrongful act must be repaid simply because<br />

<strong>the</strong> act is wrong. 219<br />

Both <strong>the</strong>ories denounce revenge as a justification for punishment.<br />

215. BLACK’S, supra note 35, at 1204. (“Satisfaction: The discharge of an obligation<br />

by paying a party what is due to him. . . . or what is awarded to him, by <strong>the</strong> judgment of a<br />

court or o<strong>the</strong>rwise.”).<br />

216. BLUMENFIELD, supra note 207, at___.<br />

217. Ralph Ranalli, Victims Agonize Over Church Deal; Struggle With Moral, Legal<br />

Questions About Accepting Settlement, BOSTON GLOBE, Oct. 8, 2003, at B1.<br />

218. See supra notes 56-58 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

219. See supra notes 60-64 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.


54 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

Retributivists acknowledge punishment per se, but view <strong>the</strong> source of <strong>the</strong><br />

retribution as societal in nature. They justify punishment upon society’s right<br />

to dem<strong>and</strong> that wrongdoers be punished, not because of an inherent right of<br />

victims to see <strong>the</strong>ir victimizers punished. Thus, most advocates of retributive<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory are careful to distinguish <strong>the</strong>ir beliefs from <strong>the</strong> “wicked” emotion of<br />

revenge. 220<br />

Utilitarian <strong>the</strong>ory, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, denounces punishment if it does not<br />

advance socially acceptable goals. Utilitarians are forward looking; <strong>the</strong>y<br />

countenance punishment only if a social good will come from it. Since<br />

revenge is not invoked in order to deter future crimes, rehabilitate <strong>the</strong><br />

criminal, or incapacitate <strong>the</strong> wrongdoer ( though it might indeed have such<br />

an effect), under classical Utilitarian <strong>the</strong>ory, it can never be an acceptable<br />

reason to punish. 221<br />

Yet, with some tweaking, both <strong>the</strong>ories could support allowing revenge<br />

to justify punishment. For instance, it is interesting, though not surprising ,<br />

that none of <strong>the</strong> goals of Utilitarianism directly address <strong>the</strong> needs of <strong>the</strong><br />

victim. They deal instead with how society can benefit from punishing <strong>the</strong><br />

wrong doer. I would argue that in addition to <strong>the</strong> goals of deterrence,<br />

rehabilitation <strong>and</strong> incapacitation, a valid <strong>and</strong> morally acceptable goal of<br />

punishing wrong is to facilitate <strong>the</strong> victim’s recovery from <strong>the</strong> trauma of <strong>the</strong><br />

crime. I would fur<strong>the</strong>r argue that such a goal would not only fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

interests of <strong>the</strong> victim, but by doing so, would also benefit society as well.<br />

This Essay has previously discussed <strong>the</strong> emotional <strong>and</strong> psychological<br />

benefits which victims may gain when, under a right of revenge, <strong>the</strong>y are<br />

afforded a meaningful voice in <strong>the</strong> setting of punishment. 222 These benefits<br />

include a sense of empowerment; that after having <strong>the</strong>ir honor <strong>and</strong> dignity<br />

stolen from <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>the</strong>y are given <strong>the</strong> opportunity to dem<strong>and</strong>, by <strong>the</strong>mselves,<br />

satisfaction, for <strong>the</strong>mselves. 223 Ano<strong>the</strong>r benefit may also include an<br />

increased likelihood that <strong>the</strong> wrongdoer, upon being forced to directly<br />

address his victim, will come to recognize <strong>the</strong> humanity of <strong>the</strong> victim,<br />

assume responsibility for his actions, <strong>and</strong> as a result, express remorse to his<br />

victim for his acts. 224<br />

These benefits are not limited to <strong>the</strong> victim. Surely on an existential as<br />

220. See supra notes 52 <strong>and</strong> 93.<br />

221. Id.<br />

222. See supra notes 158-83 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

223. See supra notes 167-77 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

224. See supra notes 185-89.


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 55<br />

well as a practical level, society benefits when victims of crime are not left<br />

at <strong>the</strong> end of <strong>the</strong> process broken, tormented, <strong>and</strong> vengeful, but ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

emerge from <strong>the</strong>ir ordeals with some satisfaction <strong>and</strong> closure. Moreover,<br />

to <strong>the</strong> extent that <strong>the</strong> wrongdoer accepts responsibility for his acts, so too<br />

are <strong>the</strong> chances increased for his rehabilitation, thus lessening <strong>the</strong> chances<br />

that he will commit future criminal acts. 225<br />

Thus, simply by exp<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>the</strong> list of Utilitarian goals to include a desire<br />

to assist in victim recovery; a goal which is entirely consistent with <strong>the</strong><br />

underlying premise of Utilitarianism to fur<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> good of society, one can<br />

argue that allowing revenge to motivate punishment can be justified under<br />

Utilitarian principles.<br />

However, I would be wary of relying solely upon Utilitarianism as <strong>the</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>oretical underpinning for justifying revenge, because it relies upon <strong>the</strong><br />

actual attainment of its goals for its justification. If punishment does not (or<br />

at least, does not sufficiently) deter, rehabilitate, incapacitate, (or under my<br />

analysis, empower), <strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> punishment is unwarranted. Indeed, many<br />

contemporary critics of Utilitarianism have raised that very argument: that<br />

since <strong>the</strong>re is no evidence that incarceration rehabilitates or deters, <strong>and</strong> in<br />

fact, may indeed have an opposite effect, such punishment cannot be<br />

justified, even if it does result in incapacitation. 226 Under a pure Utilitarian<br />

approach, if <strong>the</strong>se underlying assumptions are correct, such conclusions are<br />

valid. Similarly, Utilitarianism would warrant accepting revenge as a<br />

justification, only if <strong>the</strong> nexus between revenge <strong>and</strong> empowerment could be<br />

proven. Given <strong>the</strong> admittedly difficult task of empirically proving such a<br />

relationship, 227 traditional Utilitarianism would provide an uncertain<br />

foundation upon which to secure a justification for revenge.<br />

Fur<strong>the</strong>r, it can be argued that Utilitarianism allows only that level of<br />

punishment which is necessary to effectuate <strong>the</strong> realization of <strong>the</strong> goals. 228<br />

For instance, if in a given case, deterrence could be achieved through a<br />

suspended sentence, actually incarcerating <strong>the</strong> wrong doer would be<br />

unjustified. Similarly, if it could be demonstrated that victim empowerment<br />

also could be achieved without permitting revenge, for instance, through a<br />

225. See supra note 186 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

226. See, e.g., Marie Ashe, Prison-House of Prison-Houses: Incarceration in Theory<br />

<strong>and</strong> in Practice, 53 RUTGERS L. REV. 437, 449 (2001).<br />

227. For example, witness <strong>the</strong> difficulty in empirically proving whe<strong>the</strong>r victim impact<br />

statements enhance <strong>the</strong> empowerment of victims. See supra note 183.<br />

228. See supra note 56 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.


56 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

restorative justice model, one could argue that <strong>the</strong> justification for<br />

punishment based upon revenge would disappear.<br />

These reservations underlie <strong>the</strong> basic flaw with Utilitarianism, in that<br />

punishment is dependent upon <strong>the</strong> attainment of external goals. Retributive<br />

<strong>the</strong>ory, on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r h<strong>and</strong>, avoids that flaw, since it justifies punishment<br />

simply as a rational response to wrongful harm. The underlying <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

which supports Retribution is almost a tautology: Punishment is justified<br />

simply because a wrong was committed. One flows from <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r. No<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r reason is necessary.<br />

In this way, Retribution offers a safer harbor than does Utilitarianism.<br />

However, classic Retribution <strong>the</strong>ory does not allow for retribution as a<br />

means to avenge a wrong to <strong>the</strong> victim; it only permits <strong>the</strong> state to exact<br />

punishment as a payment for <strong>the</strong> wrong visited upon society. It is in this<br />

manner that I would argue Retribution <strong>the</strong>ory is overly restrictive, <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

should be exp<strong>and</strong>ed so as to include not only society’s, but also <strong>the</strong> victim’s<br />

interest in securing <strong>the</strong> punishment of wrongdoers. After all, <strong>the</strong> state’s right<br />

to exact retribution derives its justification from <strong>the</strong> wrong initially, <strong>and</strong> more<br />

grievously, exacted upon <strong>the</strong> victim. If society has <strong>the</strong> right to exact<br />

retribution for <strong>the</strong> indirect harm caused to it, certainly <strong>the</strong> victim should have<br />

no less of a right to do so. And that right should not depend upon any<br />

external benefit which may accrue. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, under Retributive <strong>the</strong>ory, it<br />

would exist simply because punishment is <strong>the</strong> just deserts for <strong>the</strong> wrong<br />

done.<br />

IX. HOW TO INCORPORATE REVENGE INTO THE CRIMINAL JUSTICE<br />

229. BARTON, supra note 30, at 85-86.<br />

SYSTEM<br />

Taking victim rights <strong>and</strong> victim justice seriously requires, among<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r things, . . . legal institutionalized forums where victims can<br />

express <strong>the</strong>ir legitimate feelings of resentment <strong>and</strong> anger, forums<br />

where <strong>the</strong>y can dem<strong>and</strong> satisfaction in terms of adequate<br />

restoration, apologies, or retributive justice in a controlled <strong>and</strong><br />

civilized manner for <strong>the</strong> wrongs committed against <strong>the</strong>m, without<br />

<strong>the</strong>ir being trivialized, moralized, or patronized on account of suc h<br />

needs <strong>and</strong> feelings. . . .Without according such substantial rights<br />

<strong>and</strong> powers to victims, notions of victim justice <strong>and</strong> victim<br />

empowerment ring hollow. 229 Professor Barton.


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 57<br />

It is one thing to propose new <strong>the</strong>oretical principles of law. It is quite<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r to attempt to adapt <strong>the</strong>m into actual practice. The challenge thus<br />

becomes how to incorporate into <strong>the</strong> criminal justice system <strong>the</strong> concept<br />

that victims have rights which extend to having <strong>the</strong>ir desires for revenge<br />

recognized as a legitimate basis for punishment, without exposing ourselves<br />

to <strong>the</strong> dangerous consequences which revenge can have upon a society.<br />

In order to accomplish both of <strong>the</strong>se goals, first requires distinguishing<br />

between <strong>the</strong> guilt phase <strong>and</strong> sentencing phase of a criminal trial. The guilt<br />

phase of a trial is where <strong>the</strong> guilt or innocence of <strong>the</strong> accused is<br />

determined. 230 Typically, this decision is made by <strong>the</strong> jury unless <strong>the</strong><br />

defendant waives a jury trial. 231<br />

It is here where <strong>the</strong> interests of <strong>the</strong> state <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> defendant are <strong>the</strong><br />

greatest. The state’s interests are to ensure to <strong>the</strong> extent that is reasonably<br />

possible, that <strong>the</strong> defendant receives a fair trial, <strong>and</strong> that only those who are<br />

actually guilty of <strong>the</strong> crime are so convicted. 232 The state has <strong>the</strong> interest of<br />

ensuring this result not only on behalf of <strong>the</strong> accused, but also for society,<br />

since if <strong>the</strong> wrong person is convicted, <strong>the</strong> actual perpetrator is still free to<br />

commit fur<strong>the</strong>r crimes. Whatever merit attaches to <strong>the</strong> principles of<br />

Utilitarianism <strong>and</strong> Retribution are completely defeated when <strong>the</strong> innocent<br />

is convicted, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> guilty remain free.<br />

It is thus of paramount importance that a legal system be devised so that<br />

chances of error are minimized, in order for <strong>the</strong> system’s verdicts to<br />

achieve credibility <strong>and</strong> finality. Without this credibility, trust in <strong>the</strong> verdicts<br />

would disappear, <strong>and</strong> society would face <strong>the</strong> prospect of a return to<br />

vendettas <strong>and</strong> blood feuds. 233 As such, any measure which would increase<br />

<strong>the</strong> possibility of incorrect verdicts <strong>and</strong> thus cast doubt upon <strong>the</strong> accuracy<br />

of findings of guilt needs to be avoided.<br />

230. See ANDRE MOENSSENS ET AL., CRIMINAL LAW CASES AND COMMENTS 9 (7th<br />

ed. 2003).<br />

231. Id. In fact, according to <strong>the</strong> Bureau of <strong>Justice</strong> Statistics, over 90% of all criminal<br />

convictions in state courts in 1996 were attained pursuant to a plea agreement between <strong>the</strong><br />

prosecutor <strong>and</strong> defendant, without <strong>the</strong> case ever going to trial. OFFICE FOR VICTIMS OF<br />

CRIME, U.S. DEP’T OF JUSTICE, VICTIM INPUT INTO PLEA AGREEMENTS, LEGAL SERIES<br />

BULLETIN #7, 1 (Nov. 2002). This statistic obviously relates to <strong>the</strong> issue of victim<br />

participation, since any program which seeks to enhance victim participation would need<br />

to ensure that such participation was available not only at trial, but also during <strong>the</strong> plea<br />

agreement process. See infra notes 242-44 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

232. See supra note 48 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

233. See supra notes 16-18 <strong>and</strong> 101-10.


58 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

To that end, <strong>the</strong>re can be no victim involvement in <strong>the</strong> guilt phase o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than as a witness with relevant testimony regarding <strong>the</strong> innocence or guilt<br />

of <strong>the</strong> accused. Findings of guilt or innocence must be a completely<br />

impartial <strong>and</strong> dispassionate process. Weighing of evidence <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

credibility of witnesses are functions which can only be permitted by<br />

citizens who have no direct involvement with any of <strong>the</strong> individuals involved<br />

in <strong>the</strong> suit. It is difficult to conceive of a just criminal justice system which<br />

does not insist upon this level of impartiality at <strong>the</strong> guilt phase of <strong>the</strong> trial.<br />

Once this phase of <strong>the</strong> trial has been completed, <strong>and</strong> if it has resulted<br />

in a finding of guilt, <strong>the</strong> system must <strong>the</strong>n decide what sentence to place<br />

upon <strong>the</strong> defendant. At this stage, <strong>the</strong> sentencing body (usually <strong>the</strong> judge<br />

unless a capital murder case) is permitted to exercise some discretion when<br />

deciding what level of punishment to set. 234 Accordingly, <strong>the</strong>re no longer<br />

exists <strong>the</strong> need for <strong>the</strong> same level of dispassionate analysis which existed<br />

during <strong>the</strong> adjudication of guilt. I would <strong>the</strong>refore suggest that it is here, in<br />

<strong>the</strong> sentencing phase, where <strong>the</strong> victim’s desire for revenge (or leniency)<br />

has a right to be heard.<br />

The question thus becomes just how loud should <strong>the</strong> victim’s voice be?<br />

Given <strong>the</strong> victim’s status as <strong>the</strong> individual who has suffered <strong>the</strong> greatest<br />

wrong, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> fact that <strong>the</strong> criminal trial may very well afford <strong>the</strong> victim<br />

<strong>the</strong> only opportunity to see his victimizer punished, 235 that voice should be<br />

as loud as possible, so long as it does not impermissibly defeat legitimate<br />

countervailing state interests.<br />

However, before exploring <strong>the</strong> possible mechanisms by which to<br />

increase victim participation in <strong>the</strong> setting of punishment, it must be asked<br />

whe<strong>the</strong>r any measure, short of having <strong>the</strong> victim actually decide <strong>and</strong> render<br />

punishment, can actually satisfy <strong>the</strong> desire for revenge. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, to<br />

qualify as revenge, <strong>and</strong> more importantly, to bring <strong>the</strong> type of relief which<br />

it has been argued revenge can bestow upon some victims, must such<br />

victims be personally involved in delivering <strong>the</strong> punishment? Or can victims<br />

retain <strong>the</strong> benefits of revenge even if <strong>the</strong> state serves as <strong>the</strong>ir proxy in<br />

deciding <strong>and</strong> meting out <strong>the</strong> actual punishment?<br />

234. See 21A AM. JUR. 2D Criminal <strong>Law</strong> § 794 (“It is <strong>the</strong> sentencing judge alone who<br />

determines <strong>the</strong> appropriate sentence or o<strong>the</strong>r disposition of a case, <strong>and</strong> who does so by<br />

exercising his or her best judgment, common sense, <strong>and</strong> judicial discretion after considering<br />

all of <strong>the</strong> reports, <strong>the</strong> defendant’s background, <strong>the</strong> facts of <strong>the</strong> case, <strong>and</strong> public safety.”).<br />

235. See supra notes 206-17 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text (discussing <strong>the</strong> limitations victims<br />

face when bringing <strong>the</strong>ir own civil law suits based on tort law).


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 59<br />

Under a perfect revenge system, (one which would maximize victim<br />

benefits), <strong>the</strong> victim would serve as prosecutor, judge, jury, <strong>and</strong> sentencer.<br />

The revenger would only punish those who actually committed <strong>the</strong> wrongful<br />

act, <strong>and</strong> would only inflict proportional punishments. However, history <strong>and</strong><br />

human nature renders such a possibility as pure fantasy. Thus, we are<br />

“stuck” with a system that requires state intervention; thus negating <strong>the</strong><br />

potential maximization of personal revenge.<br />

As such, “revenge by proxy”—having <strong>the</strong> state exact <strong>the</strong> revenge on<br />

behalf of <strong>the</strong> victim- is <strong>the</strong> only realistic alternative. But I still return to <strong>the</strong><br />

question of whe<strong>the</strong>r such a system can provide revenge-like benefits to <strong>the</strong><br />

victim. Berel Lang questions whe<strong>the</strong>r revenge by proxy can satisfy such<br />

needs, noting “ [I]t is ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> fact that I or someone (or some group) with<br />

whom I associate myself has been <strong>the</strong> victim of <strong>the</strong> offense. In this respect,<br />

even if a legally constituted court should punish a malefactor, <strong>the</strong> person<br />

who has been harmed might still feel that he did not have his revenge.” 236<br />

Professor Solomon seems to believe o<strong>the</strong>rwise, arguing that vengeance<br />

does not have to be violent, at least in <strong>the</strong> sense that <strong>the</strong> victim must<br />

personally physically assault his offender. Ra<strong>the</strong>r he focuses on <strong>the</strong><br />

requirement that <strong>the</strong> punishment must simply “harm” <strong>the</strong> offender, (similar<br />

to my earlier point that just punishment must include a measure of suffering<br />

for <strong>the</strong> offender) 237 <strong>and</strong> notes that it would be difficult to “[I]nsist for long<br />

that sending a man to prison is not in fact actually harming him.” He thus<br />

concludes that “<strong>the</strong>re is much that counts as punishment <strong>and</strong> consequently<br />

s atisfies <strong>the</strong> desire for revenge which need not be violence.” 238 Professor<br />

Barton similarly writes that “if <strong>the</strong> victims <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir relatives retained <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

involvement, if <strong>the</strong>y had a say or a h<strong>and</strong> in <strong>the</strong> punishment of <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

wrongdoers, <strong>the</strong> imposed punishment would quite appropriately be called<br />

institutionalized or sanitized revenge.” 239<br />

I agree with Professors Solomon <strong>and</strong> Barton, so long as <strong>the</strong> victim can<br />

sincerely believe that through her participation she will, at least in part, be<br />

responsible for <strong>the</strong> punishment <strong>and</strong> harm which her offender will suffer. To<br />

that end, I will propose a number of procedural mechanisms which could<br />

possibly offer such a sense of participation. First, is <strong>the</strong> use of Victim<br />

236. See Berel Lang, Holocaust, Memory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Revenge</strong>: The Presence of <strong>the</strong> Past, 2<br />

Jewish Social Studies 2, 14 (1966).<br />

237. See supra notes 62-89 <strong>and</strong> accompanying text.<br />

238. Solomon, supra note 11, at 255.<br />

239. BARTON, supra note 30, at 54.


60 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

Impact Statements (VIS), where victims are afforded <strong>the</strong> opportunity to<br />

express <strong>the</strong>mselves regarding <strong>the</strong> sentencing of <strong>the</strong> defendant after <strong>the</strong><br />

defendant has been found or has pled guilty. 240 Currently, all 50 states allow<br />

victims to speak at sentencing, in some form or ano<strong>the</strong>r. 241 VIS testimony<br />

typically concerns three different subjects: <strong>the</strong> effect of <strong>the</strong> crime on <strong>the</strong><br />

victim (<strong>and</strong> her family), <strong>the</strong> character of <strong>the</strong> victim (usually allowed when<br />

victim is deceased), <strong>and</strong> recommendations regarding sentencing. Most<br />

jurisdictions permit <strong>the</strong> first two forms of VIS; a few permit <strong>the</strong> third. 242<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r option could be to permit victims, after an adjudication of guilt,<br />

to intervene as a party regarding <strong>the</strong> sentencing phase of <strong>the</strong> trial. Victims,<br />

along with <strong>the</strong> state <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> defendant, would thus have party status, <strong>and</strong><br />

would enjoy <strong>the</strong> same rights as <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r parties. The actual sentencing<br />

decisions would still be rendered by <strong>the</strong> judge or jury.<br />

A third option could be to allow <strong>the</strong> victim to actually serve as <strong>the</strong><br />

sentencing body, once <strong>the</strong> defendant was adjudicated as guilty. Here, <strong>the</strong><br />

victim would decide <strong>the</strong> actual sentence. Clearly, this alternative would be<br />

<strong>the</strong> most radical. However, given <strong>the</strong> ra<strong>the</strong>r narrow level of discretion<br />

which many judges currently possess under <strong>the</strong> federal 243 , <strong>and</strong> many state,<br />

sentencing guidelines, if similar restraints were placed upon <strong>the</strong><br />

victim/sentencer, <strong>the</strong> dangers of wide disparity in sentences would be<br />

greatly obviated.<br />

These are but a few of <strong>the</strong> possible procedural mechanisms for<br />

increasing victim participation. Admittedly, <strong>the</strong>y all present varying degrees<br />

of practical <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>oretical concerns, which will be dealt with in a future<br />

piece. 244 For now, I am simply suggesting that given <strong>the</strong> current<br />

240. See generally DOUGLAS E. BELOOF, VICTIMS IN CRIMINAL PROCEDURE 621-22<br />

(1999).<br />

241. Douglas E. Beloof, Constitutional Implications of Crime Victims as Participants,<br />

88 CORNELL L. REV. 282, 286 (2003); Id. at 299-305 (analyzing state by state <strong>the</strong> extent of<br />

victims’ rights to speak at sentencing).<br />

242. Beloof, supra note 241, at 621; see Payne v. Tennessee, 501 U.S. 808, 827, 830<br />

n.2 (1991) (upholding <strong>the</strong> constitutionality of VIS for <strong>the</strong> first two categories in capital<br />

murder cases, but seemingly let st<strong>and</strong> its earlier rulings which found victim testimony<br />

regarding recommendation of sentences to violate <strong>the</strong> 8th Amendment’s prohibition against<br />

cruel <strong>and</strong> unusual punishment).<br />

243. See, e.g., ROGER HAINES, JR., FRANK BOWMAN III, & JENNIFER C. WOLL,<br />

FEDERAL SENTENCING GUIDELINES HANDBOOK (2003).<br />

244. For instance, if victims were granted party status, would <strong>the</strong>y also have <strong>the</strong> right<br />

to have an attorney represent <strong>the</strong>ir interests if <strong>the</strong>y could not afford one on <strong>the</strong>ir own; would


2005] VICTIM’S DESIRE FOR VENGEANCE 61<br />

marginalization of victims, <strong>the</strong>se <strong>and</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r options need to be actively<br />

considered.<br />

X. CONCLUSION<br />

This Essay has attempted to rehabilitate <strong>the</strong> concept of revenge, by<br />

demonstrating that a victim’s desire to revenge <strong>the</strong> wrong done to him, is<br />

not inherently immoral. To prove this point, I have attempted to distinguish<br />

between <strong>the</strong> morality <strong>and</strong> justice of revenge; focusing on <strong>the</strong> motivation of<br />

<strong>the</strong> victim when discussing morality, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> consequences of <strong>the</strong> revenge<br />

act when discussing justice. Next, I have argued that when society seeks<br />

to punish wrongdoers under its retribution powers, such punishment requires<br />

an element of suffering for it to be a just punishment, <strong>and</strong> moreover, that<br />

when society purposely intends that <strong>the</strong> punishment cause suffering, that it<br />

is acting morally as well.<br />

I have <strong>the</strong>n suggested that society would be acting morally were it to<br />

allow <strong>the</strong> victim’s desire for revenge to be considered as a factor when<br />

deciding level of punishment. While recognizing <strong>the</strong> legitimate concerns<br />

which society has with revenge, I have sought to differentiate between<br />

those concerns having to do with <strong>the</strong> justness <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> repercussions of <strong>the</strong><br />

revenge act itself, <strong>and</strong> those having to do with <strong>the</strong> desire for revenge.<br />

The societal concerns with victims exacting revenge upon <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

victimizers stem from a well founded, historically supported belief that <strong>the</strong><br />

underlying emotions (primarily hatred of <strong>the</strong> victimizer) which motivate<br />

revenge, while justified <strong>and</strong> moral, would none<strong>the</strong>less have an unacceptable<br />

effect upon <strong>the</strong> consequences of <strong>the</strong> act. Specifically, such strong emotional<br />

involvement could impair <strong>the</strong> victim’s judgment regarding whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

accused is actually guilty; <strong>and</strong> if guilty, what should be <strong>the</strong> fair <strong>and</strong><br />

proportional judgment for <strong>the</strong> crime. Fur<strong>the</strong>r, without having an impartial<br />

third party involved in deciding <strong>the</strong>se issues, <strong>the</strong> credibility <strong>and</strong> impartiality<br />

of such decisions would be open to question, <strong>and</strong> thus impact on <strong>the</strong> societal<br />

acceptance of <strong>the</strong> verdict <strong>and</strong> sentence.<br />

To meet <strong>the</strong>se concerns, ancient civilizations moved away from revenge<br />

party status be given to victims of all crimes, only felonies, or only violent <strong>and</strong> serious<br />

crimes; would any of <strong>the</strong> proposed measures violate constitutional protections to due<br />

process or cruel <strong>and</strong> unusual punishment; would party status be afforded at sentencing<br />

hearings for plea agreements <strong>and</strong> probation <strong>and</strong> parole hearings, as well as at <strong>the</strong> sentencing<br />

phase subsequent to a guilty verdict?


62 THE WAYNE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 50:4<br />

based, blood feud systems to one where <strong>the</strong> state became increasingly<br />

involved in <strong>the</strong> adjudication <strong>and</strong> sentencing of <strong>the</strong> wrong doer. At first,<br />

merely acting as arbiter <strong>and</strong> enforcer of <strong>the</strong> law, <strong>the</strong> role of <strong>the</strong> state has<br />

now come to eclipse that of <strong>the</strong> victim. All of <strong>the</strong> justifications for imposing<br />

criminal punishment under traditional Utilitarian <strong>and</strong> Retributive <strong>the</strong>ory rely<br />

not upon <strong>the</strong> victim’s interests, but instead upon fur<strong>the</strong>ring <strong>the</strong> goals of<br />

society.<br />

By prohibiting victim involvement in any of <strong>the</strong> decision making<br />

functions, <strong>the</strong> state has usurped <strong>the</strong> rights of victims to have a meaningful<br />

voice in determining punishment of <strong>the</strong>ir victimizers, even if that voice is<br />

laced with a desire for revenge <strong>and</strong> hate. We must recognize <strong>and</strong> remember<br />

that it is <strong>the</strong> victim of <strong>the</strong> crime who has primarily been harmed, <strong>and</strong> thus,<br />

that his wrong must also be redressed. Accordingly, his interests deserve<br />

to be honored <strong>and</strong> legitimized under our criminal justice system.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!