20.06.2013 Views

Chapter 2 Matter as a Mirror: Marsilio Ficino and Renaissance ...

Chapter 2 Matter as a Mirror: Marsilio Ficino and Renaissance ...

Chapter 2 Matter as a Mirror: Marsilio Ficino and Renaissance ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Matter</strong> <strong>as</strong> a <strong>Mirror</strong> 95<br />

The idea that humans themselves not only look into mirrors or skilfully<br />

manipulate them, but can also turn themselves into mirrors becomes<br />

even more obvious in the De amore, where <strong>Ficino</strong> underscores the emotional<br />

<strong>as</strong>pect of this exchange of images. The accomplished lover, again a sort of magus,<br />

must first turn himself into a mirror that reflects the beloved, whereupon<br />

the latter acknowledges his own beauty in the person opposite. <strong>Ficino</strong> maintains<br />

that, ultimately, one falls in love with a person in whom one recognizes<br />

one’s own image; the beloved becomes a magical, living mirror, the object<br />

of desire to which the lover eventually falls prey, converting himself from<br />

agent into p<strong>as</strong>sive subject. 148 The idea that a person could <strong>as</strong>sume the form<br />

of a mirror is also encountered later, perhaps most prominently, in Shakespeare’s<br />

Winter’s Tale when Polixenes says: “Good Camillo, Your changed<br />

complexions are to me a mirror, which shows me mine, too.” (I, 2, 380–2)<br />

Ultimately, these words relate to a p<strong>as</strong>sage in Plato’s Phaedrus (253D–255D)<br />

<strong>as</strong> well <strong>as</strong> to Aristotle’s concept of friendship, which is valuable because it<br />

imparts self-consciousness by acknowledging the friend <strong>as</strong> alter ego. 149 The<br />

idea that the friend serves <strong>as</strong> the mirror image for the self is in accordance<br />

with the broader Aristotelian concept that “in both sensation <strong>and</strong> thought,<br />

in different ways, knowledge involves an identity of some kind of the knower<br />

with the object known.” 150<br />

So why did the concept of mirrors which embody the images they<br />

reflect become so attractive to <strong>Ficino</strong>? The idea is absent in Plotinus, who<br />

is all too keen to ward off the idea that mirrors may have the capacity to<br />

retain images, because to him matter is — paradoxically — “a receptacle that<br />

148 The idea that the lover is actually transformed into the beloved object h<strong>as</strong> interesting<br />

consequences, especially if applied to God himself: does the supreme creator actually<br />

want to be transformed into his creation? Leone Ebreo <strong>and</strong>, to a much greater extent,<br />

Giordano Bruno would later address this question.<br />

149 On this, see Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 1170b 6–8; Eudemian Ethics 1244b<br />

24–26, Magna moralia 1313a; Frontisi-Ducroix (1998) 122–123; Kenny (1978) 229; Kenny<br />

(1992) 46–48. To my knowledge, the relationship between <strong>Ficino</strong>’s ide<strong>as</strong> about friendship<br />

<strong>and</strong> Aristotle’s Eudemian ethics, with its Platonic undertone, h<strong>as</strong> never been investigated;<br />

the concept of the will to knowledge, which is inextricably linked to Aristotle’s theory of<br />

friendship, is particularly f<strong>as</strong>cinating. Kenny (1992) 50 summarises Aristotle’s complex<br />

argument in the Eudemian Ethics 1245a 5–10 <strong>as</strong> follows: “We wish to go on living because<br />

we wish to go on knowing; <strong>and</strong> that amounts to wishing that one should be in some sense<br />

identical with the object of knowledge.”<br />

150 Kenny (1992) 50, commenting on De anima; 418a 13–16.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!