23.07.2013 Views

lexical class, particle-verbs and telicity Cale Johnson - UCLA

lexical class, particle-verbs and telicity Cale Johnson - UCLA

lexical class, particle-verbs and telicity Cale Johnson - UCLA

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

AOS2004 / San Diego, March 13, 2004 / <strong>Johnson</strong><br />

[1] Introduction<br />

Decomposing <strong>lexical</strong> aspect in Sumerian:<br />

BNBV(inalienable) <strong>lexical</strong> <strong>class</strong>, <strong>particle</strong>-<strong>verbs</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>telicity</strong><br />

<strong>Cale</strong> <strong>Johnson</strong> (cale@ucla.edu)<br />

(i) In this presentation I redescribe <strong>and</strong> extend one part of what is, in my view, the most<br />

important ongoing work on Sumerian morphosyntax: the directive case hypothesis<br />

emerging from work by Krecher, Jagersma <strong>and</strong> Zólyomi (see Zólyomi 1999 for<br />

orientation <strong>and</strong> background). At the same time, I attempt to bring at least part of the<br />

directive case hypothesis into productive dialogue with the aspectual <strong>class</strong>es identified by<br />

Yoshikawa (1993).<br />

(ii) In the following I argue that the compound verb is not a homogeneous <strong>class</strong> <strong>and</strong> that<br />

distributional tests can be used to identify <strong>lexical</strong> <strong>class</strong>es within the set of compound<br />

<strong>verbs</strong>. One of these <strong>class</strong>es is defined by the inanimate directive case [bi-√] in<br />

configuration with a bare, inalienable noun (hereafter BNBV inalienable) <strong>and</strong> the balance of<br />

this paper attempts to characterize the <strong>lexical</strong> aspectual (Aktionsart) properties of this<br />

distributional <strong>class</strong> as well as its interaction with certain oblique case-marking patterns<br />

known in the literature as the oblique object. These <strong>lexical</strong> <strong>class</strong>es also exhibit distinct<br />

sets of quantificational properties, but these are dealt with in a forthcoming paper (to be<br />

presented at the Sprache-Aegyptologie Roundtable, Basel, April 23-24, 2004; see Borer<br />

2004; Filip 2000, 2004 for background).<br />

[2] Identifying the compound verb<br />

(i) At the most basic level, there is a <strong>lexical</strong> <strong>class</strong> whose members do not form compound<br />

<strong>verbs</strong>: unergative, Activity predicates ([+ agentive, – punctate, + durative]) such as gin /<br />

du / e.re 7 / su 8.b ‘to go’, tuß / dur 2 / durun ‘to sit’ or gub / su 8.g ‘to st<strong>and</strong>’ do not as a<br />

rule form compound <strong>verbs</strong> unless they are—in a certain sense—causative such the<br />

1


AOS2004 / San Diego, March 13, 2004 / <strong>Johnson</strong><br />

“object-governed” plural <strong>verbs</strong> (Yoshikawa 1993, 310, cf. Edzard 2003, 74-81 <strong>and</strong><br />

references therein).<br />

(ii) This reflects the fact that [+ agentive, – punctate, + durative] <strong>verbs</strong> lack a direct<br />

object <strong>and</strong> that, at some level of syntactic representation, the nominal component of the<br />

compound verb is the direct object (hence the exclusion of [+ agentive, – punctate]<br />

<strong>verbs</strong>).<br />

(iii) Instead of negative evidence (such as [+ agentive, – punctate, + durative] <strong>verbs</strong> do<br />

not form compounds), one might ask for a positive criterion of compound verb formation.<br />

The best evidence is that possessors of the nominal component of a compound verb<br />

regularly undergo possessor raising (Zólyomi 1999, 231-237), resulting in either a bare<br />

nominal or, at most, a resumptive pronoun <strong>and</strong> a case-marking postposition following the<br />

noun. Other criteria based, above all, on the degree to which the nominal component of a<br />

compound verb refers to an entity in the world are interesting <strong>and</strong> valuable, but difficult<br />

to use in evaluating a language with no living speakers (the nominal component is<br />

described as, for example, (semantically) incorporated (Attinger 1993), non-referential<br />

(Zólyomi 1996a: 99-102; 1999: 216, n. 2), or part of an idiomatic construction (Karahashi<br />

2003) in recent work).<br />

[3] The BNBV diagnostic<br />

(i) As an initial distributional test, I propose that the occurrence of a bare nominal<br />

immediately preceding a [bi-√] conjugation prefix constitutes a distinctive <strong>lexical</strong> <strong>class</strong>:<br />

the Bare Noun Bi-Verb [BNBV] <strong>class</strong>.<br />

(1a) lu 2 izi.la 2 igi bi 2.du 8.am 3 (GEN 302; Karahashi 2000: 121, ex. 25)<br />

lu izi-√la-r igi [b] 5/6-[i] 10-√du-am<br />

person fire-hang-DatH eye NH-Dir-hold-Cop<br />

Did you see a man who had burned (to death)?<br />

2


AOS2004 / San Diego, March 13, 2004 / <strong>Johnson</strong><br />

(1b)<br />

d en.lil2.le igi.ni ki kur 2.ra ba.ab.œar.ra.a.ba (LSU 23; Karahashi 2000: 124)<br />

enlil-e igi-ni ki kur-a [b] 5/6-[a] 7-[b] 11-√œar-a-bi-a<br />

PN-Erg eye-3Poss place oppose-Loc NH-Dat-ProNH-place-Nmz-DistAdv-Loc<br />

When Enlil looked at the enemy l<strong>and</strong>, …<br />

(2a) a.ra 2 na.me.ka ka.tar.ra.a.du 11.du 11 œiß li.bi 2.tuku.am 3<br />

(EdB 117; Karahashi 2000: 87, ex. 8)<br />

ara name-k-a katara-du-du œiß li [b] 5/6-[i] 10-tuku-am<br />

time any-Gen-Loc praise-say-Redup “ear” Neg NH-Dir-“have”-Cop<br />

I have never heard any praise<br />

(2b) mußen.e œeßtu 2 mu.un.ßi.in.ak / mu.un.ßi.in.œa 2.ar (L2 160; PSD A/3: 85)<br />

mußen-e œeßtu [mu] 2-[n] 5/6-[ßi] 9-[n] 11-√ak/œar<br />

bird-Erg ear Vent-ProH-All-ProH-do/place<br />

The bird listened to him<br />

(ii) Whereas Examples (1a) <strong>and</strong> (1b) obviously differ according to the basic BNBV<br />

criteria, so in (1b) the nominal component of the compound verb bears a possessive<br />

pronoun <strong>and</strong> does not immediately precede the verb. Example (2b) differs from example<br />

(2a) in that an allative (terminative) directional element [ßi] 9 occurs in the verbal prefix,<br />

moving the perceived entity from an allative case to a zero-marked case<br />

(absolutive/nominative) so that it can be pronominalized <strong>and</strong> subsequently deleted under<br />

relevance. As a rule, the [bi-√] verbal prefix excludes such directional elements—this is<br />

in fact the intuition behind the most widely accepted reconstruction of the verbal prefix<br />

under the directive case hypothesis: the [bi-√] prefix is made up of [b] 5/6 <strong>and</strong> [i] 10,<br />

excluding the directional elements in slots [ ] 7, [ ] 8 <strong>and</strong> [ ] 9 (see Zólyomi 1999 <strong>and</strong><br />

references therein).<br />

(iii) Based on Karahashi’s work on compound <strong>verbs</strong> in which the nominal component is a<br />

part of the body (Karahashi 2000) <strong>and</strong> assuming that parts of the body form the core of<br />

any (in)alienability opposition in Sumerian, the set of compound verb lexemes defined by<br />

3


AOS2004 / San Diego, March 13, 2004 / <strong>Johnson</strong><br />

the BNBV diagnostic can be further subdivided into two distinct sets on the basis of the<br />

(in)alienability of the nominal component of the compound verb: where the nominal<br />

component of a BNBV lexeme is inalienable, the ergative-case marked nominal can be<br />

<strong>class</strong>ified as a perceptual Experiencer or positively affected participant (as opposed to a<br />

dative perceived object or negatively affected entity), but when the nominal component<br />

of the BNBV is alienable, the ergative-case marked nominal is a Causer (as opposed to a<br />

dative Causee). This conforms to both the description of the inchoative/causative nature<br />

of <strong>verbs</strong> bearing the directive case in the theory of Krecher, Jagersma <strong>and</strong> Zólyomi<br />

(Zólyomi 1999) as well as the description of inchoative/causative alternation <strong>and</strong> its<br />

correlation with Experiencer <strong>and</strong> Causer thematic roles as described by Pesetsky (1995).<br />

The following is a small, contrastive sample of verbal lexemes <strong>and</strong> their meaning in<br />

BNBV constructions (verba dicendi <strong>and</strong> denominative <strong>verbs</strong> in œar are excluded):<br />

BNBV inalienable<br />

BNBV alienable<br />

ßu-√dag “to ab<strong>and</strong>on” ˙i-li-√ak “to make attractive”<br />

a2-√dar “to cheat someone” eß 3-√du 3 “to have a shrine built”<br />

gu2-√du3 “to neglect” pa-√e3 “to make something extend, ramify”<br />

igi-√du8 “to see” kiœ 2-√gi 4 “to send a message”<br />

ni2-√te “to fear” ni2-√gur3 “to imbue with fear”<br />

[4] Low source applicative<br />

(i) The (de)privative semantics of the BNBV inalienable set in conjunction with a bare<br />

nominal whose syntactic role is filled by an oblique, postpositional phrase (the Oblique<br />

Object of the Krecher, Jagersma, <strong>and</strong> Zólyomi school) is strongly reminiscent of what has<br />

recently been described as a low source applicative [LoAppl] (Pylkkänen 2002). In<br />

general terms, an applicative morpheme allows an nominal phrase that would otherwise<br />

have appeared in an adpositional phrase to appear in a syntactic position that is more<br />

4


AOS2004 / San Diego, March 13, 2004 / <strong>Johnson</strong><br />

closely related to the verbal predicate: the double object construction in English is a good<br />

example:<br />

(3a) Julien bought a cake for Billy.<br />

(3b) Julien bought Billy a cake.<br />

(ii) In the example, (3a) is an ordinary ditransitive clause with the Recipient in a<br />

prepositional phrase that is equivalent to an oblique case, for Billy, but in (3b) the<br />

Recipient appears immediately after the verb <strong>and</strong> is no longer in an oblique case or its<br />

equivalent. Besides applicatives that involve a Goal or Recipient argument such as (3b),<br />

there are also applicatives that involve a Source such as the following Korean examples<br />

((4a) from Pylkkänen 2002, 21; (4b) provided by Grace Park):<br />

(4a) totuk-i Mary-hanthey panci-lul humchi-ess-ta<br />

thief-Nom Mary-Dat ring-Acc steal-Past-Plain<br />

The thief stole a ring from Mary (<strong>and</strong> it was in her possession when he stole it)<br />

(4b) totuk-i Mary-ui panci-lul humchi-ess-ta<br />

thief-Nom Mary-Gen ring-Acc steal-Past-Plain<br />

The thief stole Mary’s ring (with no implication as to the presence of Mary at the theft)<br />

(iii) In (4a) the dative postposition following Mary shows that Mary was the possessor of<br />

the ring, but the possessive relation is coded at the clausal level by an independent<br />

postpositional phrase rather than the ordinary genitive construction in (4b). This<br />

phenomenon is known as possessor raising <strong>and</strong> the resulting construction is often termed<br />

a possessor dative construction. Pylkkänen names several criteria useful in identifying a<br />

low source applicative that are also true of the BNBV <strong>class</strong>: (a) low applicatives do not<br />

combine with unergative <strong>verbs</strong>, (b) they cannot appear in a structure that lacks a direct<br />

object, (c) they cannot appear with <strong>verbs</strong> that are completely static since they imply a<br />

transfer of possession (Pylkkänen 2002, 23; on Japanese gapped adversity passives <strong>and</strong><br />

their similarity to (4a), see Kubo 1992 <strong>and</strong> Pylkkänen 2002, 59-68).<br />

5


AOS2004 / San Diego, March 13, 2004 / <strong>Johnson</strong><br />

[5] LoAppl with inalienable bare nominal<br />

(i) One the most well-known semantic effects of the constructions such as (4a) <strong>and</strong> the<br />

corresponding form in Japanese (gapped adversity passives) is that the event described by<br />

the predicate affects the dative possessor in a negative way: this clearly results from the<br />

Source argument implicit in LoAppl constructions <strong>and</strong> is apparent in examples of the<br />

BNBV inalienable <strong>class</strong>.<br />

(5) gu 4.da.ni gu 4.œu 10.da ≠lirum± im.da.ab.zi gu 4 unug ki .ga.ke 4 a 2 bi 2.ib.œar<br />

(Enmerkar <strong>and</strong> Ensu˙girana: 123 <strong>and</strong> 125; Karahashi 2000, 77)<br />

gud unug-ak-e a bi-b-œar<br />

ox GN-Gen-Dat2 arm LoAppl-ProNH-put<br />

His ox fought with my ox <strong>and</strong> the ox of Uruk was defeated<br />

(6) niœ 2.bun 2.na saœ.ki.œu 10 umbin bi 2.in.la 2 (Heron <strong>and</strong> Turtle 104; Karahashi 2000, 174)<br />

niœbuna saœki-œu-e/ø ?<br />

6<br />

umbin bi-n-la<br />

turtle forehead-1Poss-Dat2 claw LoAppl-ProH-hang<br />

The turtle scratched my forehead with its claw<br />

(7) en aratta ki .ke 4 gig.e igi bi 2.in.du 8<br />

(Enmerkar <strong>and</strong> the Lord of Aratta 554; Karahashi 2000, 119)<br />

en aratta-k-e gig-e igi bi-n-dur<br />

lord GN-Gen-Erg wheat-Dat2 eye LoAppl-ProH-hold<br />

The lord of Aratta saw the grain<br />

(8) [mußen.e an].ta igi mi.ni.in.il 2 erin 2.e igi bi 2.in.du 8.ru<br />

(Lugalb<strong>and</strong>a II 207; Karahashi 2000, 119)<br />

mußen-e an-ta mini-n-il erin-e igi bi-n-dur-eß<br />

bird-Erg above-Abl MINI-ProH-lift troops-Dat2 eye LoAppl-ProH-hold-Pl<br />

The bird looked (down) from above <strong>and</strong> saw the troops


AOS2004 / San Diego, March 13, 2004 / <strong>Johnson</strong><br />

(ii) In the four preceding examples, the Dat2 argument (this is equivalent to the non-<br />

human dative proposed by Zólyomi, traditionally the locative-terminative case) refers to a<br />

entity that is a Source (as opposed to a Goal) in spite of the fact that it bears a dative, or<br />

more generally Goal-oriented, postposition. The Dat2 argument in (5) <strong>and</strong> (6) is also<br />

negatively affected, but as in the case of the adversity passives dealt with above, this is a<br />

secondary semantic effect of the Source argument involved in the construction. Although<br />

alienable BNBV constructions are not dealt with herein, one might imagine that the<br />

semantics of the Causee argument in LoAppl constructions with alienable bare noun,<br />

likewise, derive from the negative affect of a Source argument, but this is probably not<br />

the case: the Source thematic role implicit in the LoAppl construction seems to serve as<br />

an Instrument in certain kinds of causative constructions (BNBV alienable) just like the<br />

instrumental use of the ablative postposition (On the privative semantics of <strong>verbs</strong> of<br />

perception <strong>and</strong> its relation to the choice of instrumental—instead of agentive—case-<br />

marking for a Causee argument, see Pylkkänen 2002, 47-50, for the most part a<br />

commentary on data presented in L<strong>and</strong>au 1999).<br />

[6] LoAppl constituent as <strong>particle</strong> in <strong>particle</strong>-verb construction<br />

(i) At this point someone might reasonably ask what any of this has to do with <strong>telicity</strong>. It<br />

has long been recognized that in English, for example, <strong>particle</strong>s—prepositions that lack a<br />

nominal complement—are often used to control the <strong>telicity</strong> of <strong>verbs</strong>.<br />

(9) He hammered it ø for three hours / *in three hours.<br />

(10) He hammered it out for three hours / in three hours.<br />

(ii) In these examples, as is st<strong>and</strong>ard practice, a temporal adverb can be used to<br />

differentiate a telic event from an atelic one: in (9), an atelic verb can only occur with an<br />

unbounded temporal adverb, for three hours, whereas the telic verb in (10), which is<br />

followed by the <strong>particle</strong> out, can also occur with a bounded temporal adverb, in three<br />

hours. Since Sumerian is strictly verb-final, the possibility of a <strong>particle</strong>-based system for<br />

controlling the <strong>telicity</strong> of a verb seems out of reach. But recent work on the formation of<br />

7


AOS2004 / San Diego, March 13, 2004 / <strong>Johnson</strong><br />

verbal complexes (Kayne 1994; Koopman <strong>and</strong> Szabolcsi 2000) has argued that they are<br />

regularly derived through movement of phrases that appear to the right of the verb in<br />

languages like English into positions on the left of the verb as in the following three stage<br />

process.<br />

(11a) [ XP Xº [ YP Yº [ ZP ZP]]<br />

(11b) [ XP Xº [ YP [ ZP ZP] Yº t ZP ]<br />

(11c) [ XP [ YP [ ZP ZP] Yº t ZP ] Xº t YP ]<br />

(iii) Where ZP is the Dat2 argument, Yº is the bare nominal <strong>and</strong> Xº is the LoAppl head,<br />

namely, the [bi-√] prefix. Kayne has argued, in fact, that this process is the primary<br />

reason why so-called agglutinative languages behave the way they do (see Kayne 1994,<br />

53). But more to the point, one of the effects of the formation of a BNBV inalienable<br />

construction with a Dat2 possessor instead of a Gen possessor is that the Dat2 argument<br />

can form a Goal with respect to the bare noun in a possessive construction: this provides<br />

a bounded telic point for the verb along the lines of the verb-<strong>particle</strong> construction in<br />

English. The primary difference between a low goal applicative as in the English double<br />

object construction (3b) <strong>and</strong> a low source applicative as in the Korean example (4a) is<br />

that the possessive relation between direct object <strong>and</strong> dative possessor is the situation at<br />

the beginning of an event described by a low source applicative but the end point of an<br />

event described by a low goal applicative (see L<strong>and</strong>au 1999; Pylkkänen 2002, Borer 2004<br />

for elaboration).<br />

[7] Restrictions on <strong>lexical</strong> aspectual <strong>class</strong> of LoAppl <strong>verbs</strong> (˙amt¬u-reduplication)<br />

(i) The most peculiar fact about BNBVs—at least in the corpora that I have been able to<br />

examine—is that they do not seem to form the continuative (marû) aspect at all: the vast<br />

majority of the cases show the simple ˙amt¬u verbal root, a small subset show what I take<br />

to be ˙amt¬u-reduplication (of Yoshikawa’s “distributive plurality” type (Yoshikawa<br />

1993, 312)) <strong>and</strong> an even smaller set are followed by nominal postpositions of one kind or<br />

8


AOS2004 / San Diego, March 13, 2004 / <strong>Johnson</strong><br />

another. This seems to conform to the <strong>telicity</strong> inherent in the low source applicative<br />

construction as well as what Vendler would have called an Achievement verb<br />

([+ punctate, + durative, – segmentable change of state]), a verb that describes an event in<br />

which there is both inherent duration <strong>and</strong> an inherent telos, but with little or no gradual or<br />

cumulative development of the resultant state. This is why, for example, <strong>verbs</strong> of<br />

perception such as igi-√du 8 ‘to see’ or œiß-√tug 2 ‘to hear’ do seem to occur in the BNBV<br />

<strong>class</strong>, but other <strong>verbs</strong> of looking <strong>and</strong> hearing without perceiving do not.<br />

(ii) The dative possessor / oblique object (Dat2) can only function as a Source if the<br />

continuative (marû) aspect is blocked <strong>and</strong> inactive, since if it were to occur with a<br />

continuative (marû) aspect, it would presumably revert to its original function as a Goal<br />

argument as in the cases that are prototypical in the secondary literature in descriptions of<br />

the locative-terminative case: e 2.e (house-Dat2) im.ma.œen (Cyl. A 18: 8-9; Zólyomi<br />

1999, 253) ‘he (= Gudea) went up to the temple’. On the assumption that restriction of<br />

the verbal root to a ˙amt¬u form blocks any aspectual interaction between the Dat2<br />

argument <strong>and</strong> the verb, it is probably best to think of the possessor raising construction as<br />

a constituent such as [[NP 1-Dat2 Goal NP 2] Source bi]-√ so that with respect to the possessive<br />

relation between the two NPs, NP 1 functions as a Goal/Possessor, but with respect to the<br />

event described by the main verb, the entire constituent [NP 1-Dat2 NP 2] functions as a<br />

Source for a higher Goal/Possessor.<br />

(iii) Due to the peculiar interaction of <strong>telicity</strong> <strong>and</strong> oblique case-marking in<br />

BNBV/LoAppl constructions, the BNBV/LoAppl construction must be located very low<br />

on, for example, Cinque’s universal hierarchy of adverbial positions, presumably the<br />

simple ˙amt¬u form at 37 AspSingCompletive2 <strong>and</strong> the ˙amt¬u-reduplication form at<br />

38 AspFrequentitive2, although I cannot exclude the possibility that they are in fact at a<br />

slightly higher position such as 31 AspSingCompletive1 <strong>and</strong> 32 AspPlCompletive (Cinque<br />

1999, 100-106). These kinds of issues are at the forefront of ongoing work in syntactic<br />

theory (Cinque 1999) <strong>and</strong> Yoshikawa’s discussion of verbal reduplication <strong>and</strong> plural<br />

<strong>verbs</strong> (1993, 287-322) speaks directly to these questions.<br />

9


AOS2004 / San Diego, March 13, 2004 / <strong>Johnson</strong><br />

References<br />

Agha, Asif. 1993. Structural form <strong>and</strong> Utterance Context in Lhasa Tibetan. Peter Lang.<br />

Attinger, Pascal. 1993. Eléments de linguistique sumérienne. V<strong>and</strong>enhoeck <strong>and</strong> Ruprecht.<br />

Borer, Hagit. 2004. Structuring Sense. Oxford University Press.<br />

Cinque, Guglielmo. 1999. Ad<strong>verbs</strong> <strong>and</strong> Functional Heads. Oxford University Press.<br />

Edzard, Dietz Otto. 2003. Sumerian Grammar. Brill.<br />

Filip, Hana. 2000. The Quantization Puzzle. In J. Pustejovsky <strong>and</strong> C. Tenny (eds.) Events as<br />

grammatical objects, pp. 3-60. CSLI Press.<br />

––––––. 2004. Prefixes <strong>and</strong> the delimitation of events. Journal of Slavic Linguistics 12(1-2).<br />

Karahashi, Fumi. 2000. Sumerian Compound Verbs with Body-Part Terms. PhD dissertation,<br />

University of Chicago.<br />

––––––. 2003. Towards a Typology of Compound Verbs. Paper presented at AOS.<br />

Kayne, Richard S. 1994. The Antisymmetry of Syntax. MIT Press.<br />

Koopman, Hilda, <strong>and</strong> Anna Szabolcsi. 2000. Verbal Complexes. MIT Press.<br />

Kubo. 1992. Japanese Passives. Working Papers of the Department of Languages <strong>and</strong> Cultures<br />

23. University of Hokkaido.<br />

L<strong>and</strong>au, I. 1999. Possessor raising <strong>and</strong> the structure of the VP. Lingua 107: 1-37.<br />

Pesetsky, David. 1995. Zero Syntax: Experiencers <strong>and</strong> Cascades. MIT Press<br />

Pylkkänen, Mariliina. 2002. Introducing Arguments. PhD Thesis, MIT.<br />

Thomsen, Marie-Louise. 2001. The Sumerian Language. Akademisk Forlag.<br />

Vendler, Zeno. 1967. Linguistics in Philosophy. Cornell University Press.<br />

Yoshikawa, Mamoru. 1993. Studies in the Sumerian Verbal System. Acta Sumerologica<br />

Supplementary Series 1. Middle Eastern Culture Center in Japan.<br />

Zólyomi, Gábor. 1996. Review of Attinger 1993. Bibliotheca Orientalis 53(1/2): 95-107.<br />

––––––. 1999. Directive infix <strong>and</strong> oblique object in Sumerian: An account of the history of their<br />

relationship. Orientalia 68: 215-253.<br />

10

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!