04.01.2014 Views

Punishment and Personal Responsibility

Punishment and Personal Responsibility

Punishment and Personal Responsibility

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

142<br />

is “one of the devices of social order” (ibid. 22). Faced with two plausible<br />

but conflicting theories, Rawls attempts to reconcile them.<br />

The solution to the conflict between retributivism <strong>and</strong> utilitarianism,<br />

Rawls argues, consists in making a distinction between what justifies<br />

punishment as a general practice, <strong>and</strong> what justifies a particular action<br />

under this practice. He illustrates how this distinction works in the case<br />

of punishment by a very compelling hypothetical discussion about the<br />

practice of punishment between a father <strong>and</strong> his son. The son asks his<br />

father why a particular criminal, F, was put in jail yesterday. The father<br />

replies that F has robbed a bank <strong>and</strong> that F was duly tried <strong>and</strong> found<br />

guilty. But if the son were to proceed to ask why people are put in jail,<br />

his father would reply “to protect good people from bad people” or the<br />

like. Rawls argues that these are different questions:<br />

“There are two very different questions here. One emphasizes the<br />

proper name: it asks why F was punished rather than someone else, or<br />

it asks what he was punished for. The other question asks why we<br />

have the institution of punishment: why do people punish one another<br />

rather than, say, always forgiving one another?” (ibid. 22)<br />

Rawls contends that the first question is answered by retributivism <strong>and</strong><br />

the second question by utilitarianism. Retributivism governs actions falling<br />

under the practice of punishment, such as why F <strong>and</strong> no one else<br />

went to jail. Utilitarian considerations answer the question what the practice<br />

as such aims to do, <strong>and</strong> why it is justified in the first place. In this<br />

sense, utilitarianism is the more fundamental theory of the two, for it<br />

answers the question about the very point of having an institution of punishment.<br />

152 The two questions furthermore address different institutional<br />

levels, Rawls argues. Legislators, who are interested in social protection<br />

<strong>and</strong> overall welfare, pass laws in order to control crime, but are not concerned<br />

with the everyday workings of the criminal justice system. That is<br />

the responsibility of the courts. But the courts are ruled by retributivist<br />

ideas about desert <strong>and</strong> proportionality, not utilitarian considerations. The<br />

conflict between retributivism <strong>and</strong> utilitarianism is therefore a superficial<br />

152 Speaking with Hart, we could say that utility provides the “general justifying<br />

aim” of punishment (Hart 1968). Speaking with Dolinko, we could say that utility<br />

provides its “rational justification” (Dolinko 1991).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!