04.01.2014 Views

Punishment and Personal Responsibility

Punishment and Personal Responsibility

Punishment and Personal Responsibility

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

desert as such which does the justificatory work. But this is the price one<br />

must pay for not settling for intrinsic-good retributivism.<br />

A third thing to note is that it may seem as if I am confusing different<br />

levels of analysis here. Whereas Dolinko wondered why desert<br />

should count as a reason for the act of punishment, I have argued that<br />

desert gives birth to a penal regime which is superior to other regimes.<br />

Does this mean that I do not have anything to say about the most fundamental<br />

question of all in the philosophy of punishment: what, if anything,<br />

justifies punishment? No. While the institutional reason is obviously<br />

not an argument for punishment as such – it is only an argument<br />

for a particular kind of penal regime once we have one - the symbolic<br />

reason is a direct argument for punishment. It states, as we have just<br />

seen, that the act of retribution respects rule breakers as persons, which is<br />

a good thing. This, then, counts in favour of a singular act of retributive<br />

punishment just as it underscores the claim that a retributive penal regime<br />

is symbolically superior to rival regimes.<br />

Suppose that the institutional <strong>and</strong> symbolic reasons are sound, <strong>and</strong><br />

that they count in favour of a retributive answer to (Q). A final thing to<br />

note is that it is unclear what the ultimate justification of that answer is.<br />

Retributivism has of course traditionally been understood as a deontological<br />

theory (Dolinko 1997). If my argument is read as a deontological<br />

one, we would say that a retributive penal regime is good because it<br />

treats people fairly <strong>and</strong> with respect, <strong>and</strong> thereby adheres to obligations<br />

we have to each other. But this interpretation seems to be silent on a fundamental<br />

question: why we have a practice of punishment in the first<br />

place. It is one thing to argue that the institutional <strong>and</strong> symbolic reason<br />

count in favour of preferring a retributive penal regime over ones based<br />

on deterrence <strong>and</strong> rehabilitation. But can fair <strong>and</strong> respectful treatment<br />

really explain why we are right in punishing rule breakers in the first<br />

place? This not only questions whether retributivism can supply us with<br />

an answer as to why we have a practice of punishment. More to the<br />

point, it also questions whether the reasons in favour of a retributive<br />

penal regime are really deontological. It might just as well be that they<br />

are of a consequentialist, indeed even straightforwardly utilitarian sort: it<br />

might be that we have reason to prefer a regime which gives us what we<br />

deserve because it would leave us on aggregate better off than other regimes.<br />

I will return to these difficult questions concerning the ultimate justification<br />

of a retributive penal regime in the concluding chapter. Here it<br />

195

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!