04.01.2014 Views

Punishment and Personal Responsibility

Punishment and Personal Responsibility

Punishment and Personal Responsibility

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

12<br />

ment: where the right to punish came from (if it existed) <strong>and</strong> what purpose<br />

(if any) it served.<br />

The conclusion of these early reformists was that punishment indeed<br />

can be justified, because it can promote compliance with common<br />

rules <strong>and</strong> thereby uphold social peace <strong>and</strong> order. But they also concluded<br />

that punishment, taken in <strong>and</strong> of itself, is an evil. Cesare Beccaria, whose<br />

On Crime <strong>and</strong> <strong>Punishment</strong>s (1986 [1764]) was widely held to be the<br />

Enlightenment treatise on punishment, held that all punishment not deriving<br />

from absolute necessity was tyrannical. A contractarian, Beccaria<br />

understood authority as what each individual would consent to in forming<br />

a social contract. Individuals would consent to public authorities<br />

having a right to punish, Beccaria argued, since this would promote<br />

compliance with common rules, which in turn promotes happiness for<br />

all. This goal qualifies as an “absolute necessity”. But unless punishment<br />

serves this goal, <strong>and</strong> unless punishment is impersonally, reliably <strong>and</strong><br />

moderately administered, punishment cannot be justified. It would then<br />

be tyrannical, <strong>and</strong> the contracting parties would not consent to it (ibid. 7-<br />

17).<br />

The idea of punishment as a prima facie evil was most succinctly put<br />

by Jeremy Bentham in The Principles of Morals <strong>and</strong> Legislations (1988<br />

[1781]). “All punishment”, Bentham stated, “is mischief: all punishment<br />

in itself is evil. Upon the principle of utility, if it ought at all to be admitted,<br />

it ought only to be admitted as far as it promises to exclude some<br />

greater evil.” (ibid. 170) The principle of utility referred to by Bentham is<br />

the idea that the rightness or wrongness of every action or practice is<br />

determined by its consequences for general utility. If it leads to more<br />

utility than disutility than feasible alternatives, the action or practice is<br />

right. 10 But Bentham saw no justification in excluding the people being<br />

punished from the calculus of utility. Their suffering would also have to<br />

be taken into account. This meant that without compensating gains in<br />

utility, punishment would only leave a negative mark in the balance of<br />

utility. In imposing pain or deprivation on the person being punished, it<br />

10 An action or institution is right if <strong>and</strong> only if there are no (feasible) alternative<br />

which would generate better consequences. It thus does not suffice to show that<br />

punishment generates more utility than disutility – unless punishment generates<br />

better consequences than, say, a system where every rule breaker is pardoned,<br />

punishment would not be right (<strong>and</strong> hence not justified). See e.g. Tännsjö 1998.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!