13.07.2014 Views

Applying wildlife welfare principles to individual animals

Applying wildlife welfare principles to individual animals

Applying wildlife welfare principles to individual animals

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

8. DUTY OF CARE FOR WILDLIFE SPECIES<br />

8.1 Is our responsibility context dependent?<br />

Much of the literature (and many of the <strong>principles</strong>) established thus far have been developed<br />

for <strong>animals</strong> which are closely managed by humans such as production farm <strong>animals</strong>,<br />

companion <strong>animals</strong> or labora<strong>to</strong>ry <strong>animals</strong>. Before considering how we may assess and<br />

respond <strong>to</strong> the <strong>welfare</strong> status of <strong>wildlife</strong> it is important <strong>to</strong> question <strong>to</strong> what extent our<br />

responsibility may be in some sense context dependent (see also Ohl and Putman, 2013d).<br />

There has been much debate in the more philosophical literature about human<br />

responsibilities <strong>to</strong> <strong>animals</strong> and about the moral value of animal life. A significant part of this<br />

literature recognizes <strong>animals</strong> as having moral status: that is, <strong>to</strong> be an entity (a being)<br />

<strong>to</strong>wards which we can have moral duties (Warren, 1997), acknowledging that <strong>animals</strong> that<br />

fall under our responsibility are also part of our moral circle, and whether these <strong>animals</strong><br />

flourish is also our concern. In the past, perhaps, many philosophers, following a Kantian<br />

approach, presumed that such moral status derived as a consequence of their relationship<br />

with humans, as an extension of human-centred morality, but a significant number of<br />

ethicists now concede that <strong>animals</strong> have some moral value that is independent of their use<br />

by humans.<br />

According <strong>to</strong> Regan (1983), <strong>animals</strong> are, like humans, subjects-of-a-life. They have<br />

subjective experiences, can experience the quality of their lives, and enter in<strong>to</strong> and maintain<br />

relationships with others. Taylor (1986) argues that all organisms have ‘inherent worth’<br />

because, as ‘teleological centres of life’, they have a good of their own, while Rollin (2011)<br />

ascribes an intrinsic value <strong>to</strong> <strong>animals</strong> because “what happens <strong>to</strong> an entity matters <strong>to</strong> it even<br />

if it does not matter <strong>to</strong> anyone or anything else. Because it is capable of valuing what<br />

happens <strong>to</strong> it, either in a positive or negative way, such valuing is inherent in it.”<br />

In effect, although the basis for the belief may differ, many western philosophies now accept<br />

that all <strong>animals</strong> have moral status and that in consequence, and without exception, they<br />

merit moral consideration. This broad acknowledgement of <strong>animals</strong> as having moral status,<br />

however, appears not <strong>to</strong> result in one broadly shared view on how we should treat them.<br />

This is clearly reflected in current legislative provisions for consideration of <strong>animals</strong>’ <strong>welfare</strong><br />

which are in general largely context-dependent, such that there may be a clear legal<br />

distinction between responsibilities <strong>to</strong>wards farm <strong>animals</strong>, lab <strong>animals</strong>, companion <strong>animals</strong>,<br />

closely managed <strong>wildlife</strong>, and truly wild <strong>animals</strong> experiencing little management input (see<br />

for example review by Vapnek and Chapman, 2010).<br />

Partly as a reflection of that legal distinction, some authors (as, for example, Swart, 2005<br />

and Swart & Keulartz, 2011) suggest a similar distinction in relation <strong>to</strong> context (kept and nonkept),<br />

in terms of our responsibilities for <strong>animals</strong> and the way those responsibilities might be<br />

discharged. If we wish <strong>to</strong> try <strong>to</strong> claim for a wider duty of care, we may argue that at least<br />

within a European context, all <strong>animals</strong> (whatever their status as kept or non-kept) are <strong>to</strong><br />

some degree influenced by human activity – whether <strong>to</strong> a greater or lesser extent, and<br />

whether deliberate or incidental. Closely managed <strong>animals</strong> in whatever context (farm<br />

<strong>animals</strong>, labora<strong>to</strong>ry <strong>animals</strong>, companion <strong>animals</strong>) have their whole environment controlled by<br />

human agency; but even for free-ranging or apparently wild <strong>animals</strong>, their habitat and<br />

movement patterns are affected by human land-use and land-management and many<br />

populations are directly controlled by culling.<br />

Thus even in terms of those philosophical traditions which base responsibilities for <strong>animals</strong><br />

on their relationship with humans, some duty of care might be expected. In practice however<br />

such separate ‘justification’ is unnecessary if we accept the moral premise above that all<br />

22

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!