08.09.2014 Views

A comparative study of models for predation and parasitism

A comparative study of models for predation and parasitism

A comparative study of models for predation and parasitism

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

A COMPARATIVE STUDY OF MODELS FOR PREDATION<br />

AND<br />

PARASITISM<br />

by<br />

T. ROYAMA<br />

Canadian Forestry Service, P. O. Box 4000,<br />

Fredericton, New Brunswick, Canada<br />

TABLE OF CONTENTS<br />

Page<br />

1. Introduction 1<br />

2. A brief inquiry into the role <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>models</strong> in scientific inference 2<br />

3. A background theory <strong>of</strong> the<br />

structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> 9<br />

4. The existing <strong>models</strong> 20<br />

a) The LOTKA-VOLTERRA model 21<br />

b) The NICHOLSON-BAILEY model 24<br />

c) HOLLiNG'S disc equation 31<br />

d) The IVLEV-GAusE equation 35<br />

e) ROYAMA'S model <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om<br />

searching <strong>and</strong> probability <strong>of</strong><br />

r<strong>and</strong>om encounters 42<br />

f) WATT'S equation 55<br />

g) The T~o~esoN-SwoY equations<br />

<strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> 61<br />

h) The HASSELL-VARLSY model <strong>of</strong><br />

social interference in parasites 66<br />

i) A geometric model <strong>for</strong> social<br />

interaction among parasites<br />

(this <strong>study</strong>) 70<br />

Appendix to w 4i. Is the concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery' useful in<br />

studies <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>parasitism</strong> ? 74<br />

j) HOLLING'S hunger model 76<br />

5. Discussion <strong>and</strong> conclusions 78<br />

6. Summary 84<br />

7. Acknowledgements 85<br />

8. References 85<br />

Appendix 1. The pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> LI=I/2RX 88<br />

Appendix 2. The pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

Lz- ~ (I/2~-,XR)/UX - Re- ~rR~'X 88<br />

I_e-~R~X<br />

Appendix 3. The pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> eq. (4i. 6) 89<br />

Appendix 4. List <strong>of</strong> symbols 90<br />

1. INTRODUCTION<br />

ELTON (1935), in his review <strong>of</strong> the works <strong>of</strong> the great biomathematician, the late<br />

ALFRED J. LOTKA, wrote:<br />

"When LOTKA published his first notes on this subject in 1920, animal ecology<br />

had entered on a new phase, though we are probably only now beginning to see the<br />

importance <strong>of</strong> it." However, "like most mathematicians, he takes the hopeful biologist<br />

to the edge <strong>of</strong> a pond, points out that a good swim will help his work, <strong>and</strong> then<br />

pushes him in <strong>and</strong> leaves him to drown."<br />

When NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY (1935) published their theoretical paper, SMITH<br />

(1939) predicted that "in that admirable work by NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY, 'The<br />

Balance <strong>of</strong> Animal Populations', will be found enough population problems to keep<br />

several laboratories busy <strong>for</strong> the next twenty years."<br />

Shortly after the publication <strong>of</strong> these theoretical works, there arose among ecolo-


gists a storm <strong>of</strong> controversy which has lasted <strong>for</strong> more than 20 years ~nd hss not<br />

yet subsided. Much <strong>of</strong> the dispute has been based on varying degrees <strong>of</strong> mutual<br />

misunderst<strong>and</strong>ing, <strong>and</strong> many innocent students <strong>of</strong> natural history have perhaps been<br />

drowned. Nevertheless, theoretical approaches <strong>and</strong> mathematical concepts still play<br />

an important role in animal population ecology, chiefly <strong>for</strong> the following reason. In<br />

the <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> population processes, what we can observe is an integrated complex <strong>of</strong><br />

factors. But the elemental components <strong>and</strong> their interactions are not always apparent<br />

<strong>and</strong> indeed may even be impossible to detect by ordinary observation. Wherever<br />

unobservables are involved, they must be detected through reasoning by analogy.<br />

For the past decade, biomathematics <strong>and</strong> statistics have become increasingly more<br />

sophisticated, while the students <strong>of</strong> natural history have by observation accumulated<br />

a vast amount <strong>of</strong> in<strong>for</strong>mation on animal behaviour. Yet, there seems to be an increasing<br />

gap between the two approaches. My aim is to bridge this gap, <strong>and</strong> the scope<br />

<strong>of</strong> this paper is to show what the existing theories on <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> really<br />

mean, <strong>and</strong> what role these theories would, or would not, play in leading to an underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> processes in relation to population dynamics.<br />

Be<strong>for</strong>e the existing theories are critically reviewed, I shall discuss the role <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>models</strong> in general terms <strong>and</strong> then consider some basic attributes <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>parasitism</strong>. In fact, these two sections are the result <strong>of</strong> my <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> the<br />

existing <strong>models</strong> rather than a starting point. Nevertheless, this part <strong>of</strong> the conclusion<br />

is presented first because the argument can then be more readily followed.<br />

2. A BRIEF INQUIRY INTO THE ROLE OF MODELS IN SCIENTIFIC INFERENCE<br />

To make a critical <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> existing <strong>predation</strong> (<strong>parasitism</strong>) <strong>models</strong>, we need to<br />

have a clear idea <strong>of</strong> what a 'model' is. However, the concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>models</strong> in science<br />

varies from one case to another, depending on what is aimed at in each individual<br />

case. Thus it is perhaps better to examine the past use <strong>of</strong> the word rather than to<br />

begin with an attempt to define it.<br />

The word 'model' has been used more or less synonymously with: an assumption;<br />

a hypothesis; a proposition; a theory; a law; or even a mere mathematical equation.<br />

A typical example <strong>and</strong> positive justification <strong>for</strong> this broad usage <strong>of</strong> the word is found<br />

in WALKER (1963, p. 4) :<br />

"The word model in a particular sentence may refer to one or more <strong>of</strong> many<br />

related aspects <strong>of</strong> the general notion. Thus cortical model refers to the model as it<br />

is recorded in the structure <strong>and</strong> arrangement <strong>of</strong> molecules in the memory banks <strong>of</strong><br />

the brain. Conceptual model refers to the mental picture <strong>of</strong> the model that is intro-<br />

spectively present when one thinks about the model. This picture probably corresponds<br />

to some scanning process over the appropriate memory banks. The verbal model<br />

consists <strong>of</strong> the spoken or written description <strong>of</strong> the model. The postulational model<br />

is a certain type <strong>of</strong> verbal model that consists <strong>of</strong> a list <strong>of</strong> the postulates <strong>of</strong> the model.<br />

The geometrical model refers to the diagrams or drawings that are used to describe


the model. The mathematical model refers to the equations or other relationships<br />

that provide the quantitative predictions <strong>of</strong> the model. The material model is the<br />

arrangement <strong>and</strong> interactions <strong>of</strong> fundamental particles, their fields <strong>and</strong> aggregates.<br />

When a writer refers to the 'Bohr model <strong>of</strong> the hydrogen atom', he may have in<br />

mind any or all <strong>of</strong> these aspects; the reader must select the aspects appropriate to<br />

the context."<br />

WALKER'S broad usage <strong>of</strong> the word includes, in later chapters <strong>of</strong> his book, the<br />

MENDELIAN law <strong>of</strong> inheritance <strong>and</strong> the DARWINIAN theory <strong>of</strong> natural selection as<br />

<strong>models</strong>. Clearly, the word 'model' in WALKER'S sense is used to categorize similar,<br />

but distinctly different notions in a single, convenient, descriptive term. This catego.<br />

rization may at times be needed in scientific communication, but I would rather use<br />

the word in a much restricted sense in this paper, in order to emphasize the role <strong>of</strong><br />

a certain type <strong>of</strong> model that distinguishes itself from other similar notions, e.g.<br />

'assumptions', 'hypotheses', 'theories', or 'descriptions' <strong>of</strong> laws <strong>and</strong> rules.<br />

A dictionary (e. g. The WEBSTER's Third International Dictionary, 1968) treats<br />

the word as a synonym <strong>for</strong> : Example, Pattern, Exemplar, Paradigm, Ideal, etc.; or it<br />

is something perfect <strong>of</strong> its kind. The dictionary also states that a model is: a thing<br />

that serves as a pattern or source <strong>of</strong> inspiration <strong>for</strong> an artist or writer; or an analogy<br />

used to help visualize, <strong>of</strong>ten in a simplified way, something that cannot be observed<br />

directly. The last definition is particularly important <strong>and</strong> most relevant to my investigation.<br />

WALKER further stated that "the main purpose <strong>of</strong> a model is to make predictions",<br />

<strong>and</strong> that "if a mathematical model predicts future events accurately, there is no necessity<br />

<strong>for</strong> any interpretation or visualization <strong>of</strong> the process described by the equation."<br />

These statements should be interpreted with caution, however. If they are taken<br />

literally, it might be concluded that the purpose <strong>of</strong> an assumption, hypothesis, theory,<br />

etc. is to predict but not to aid underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> natural order: that is to say,<br />

WALKER'S statement might be taken erroneously as synonymous with 'the aim <strong>of</strong><br />

science is predictions'. TOULMIN (1961) pointed out that the ancient Babylonian<br />

astronomers who predicted the motion <strong>of</strong> stars amazingly accurately by arithmetic<br />

means failed to underst<strong>and</strong> underlying mechanisms, while the Ionian philosophers'<br />

crude model <strong>of</strong> the universe eventually led to 20 th-century physics.<br />

The underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> natural order is achieved through the <strong>for</strong>mation <strong>of</strong> new<br />

concepts. SCHON (1967) emphasized the role <strong>of</strong> metaphor in the <strong>for</strong>mation <strong>of</strong> a new<br />

concept, through which a novel idea or discovery was made. He maintained that the<br />

new concept would emerge by shifting already existing concepts to a new situation<br />

by metaphor. That is to say, the old concepts, shifted to the new situation by metaphor,<br />

are <strong>models</strong> <strong>for</strong> the new concept. If we use the word 'model' in a similar way,<br />

<strong>and</strong> I am inclined to do so here, then some <strong>of</strong> WALKER'S examples should be excluded.<br />

For example, the DARWINIAN theory can be a model if its principle is shifted


<strong>and</strong> applied, say, to social phenomena, but as long as the theory remains in the domain<br />

<strong>of</strong> organic evolution I do not call it a model. Similarly, while the MENDELIAN law<br />

itself is by the same token not a model <strong>of</strong> M~NDELIAN inheritance, its principle can<br />

be demonstrated by a model in which equal numbers <strong>of</strong> red <strong>and</strong> white balls in a jar<br />

are sampled at r<strong>and</strong>om, two balls at a time. The statistical expectation <strong>of</strong> the propor-<br />

tion <strong>of</strong> white-white pairs is one-quarter <strong>of</strong> the total number <strong>of</strong> pairs drawn. This<br />

model can be stated by a simple mathematical equation, <strong>and</strong> the equation is just the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> statement. The equation as a statement <strong>of</strong> the model can at the same time<br />

be a statement <strong>of</strong> the law, since the symbolic expression <strong>for</strong> both the model <strong>and</strong> the<br />

law takes the same <strong>for</strong>m. By means <strong>of</strong> the balls-in-a-jar model, however, the empirical<br />

law found by MENDEL becomes underst<strong>and</strong>able <strong>and</strong> intelligible, <strong>and</strong> the model leads<br />

to the postulation <strong>of</strong> particulate inheritance--a hypothesis; the reliability <strong>of</strong> this hypo-<br />

thesis is tested in an organized way against further observations until it emerges as<br />

a biological theory <strong>and</strong> principle.<br />

We should distinguish, however, between an equation as a general, symbolic<br />

method <strong>of</strong> statement, <strong>and</strong> one as a mathematical operation as a means <strong>of</strong> reasoning. In<br />

a model as simple as the balls-in-a-jar example, the mathematical probability <strong>of</strong> a pair<br />

<strong>of</strong> one kind, say white-white, may be obtained intuitively <strong>and</strong> correctly (i. e. a priori),<br />

whereas <strong>of</strong>ten a more complicated mathematical operation is required to draw a con-<br />

clusion. An equation that states a result <strong>of</strong> inferences should there<strong>for</strong>e be distinguished<br />

from an equation which is adopted as a convenient description <strong>of</strong> an empirical law,<br />

such as a polynomial equation obtained in curve-fitting by the least squares method.<br />

The latter is generally not the statement <strong>of</strong> a model nor a hypothesis;it is merely<br />

one casual <strong>and</strong> tentative way, among many others, <strong>of</strong> describing what has been<br />

observed, although it may at times play a certain role in the <strong>for</strong>mulation <strong>of</strong> ideas,<br />

as a tentative part <strong>of</strong> a model.<br />

In a very few cases, an empirical law can be stated accurately by a simple math-<br />

ematical equation in which the value <strong>of</strong> every coefficient involved is clearly defined,<br />

but without underst<strong>and</strong>ing. A typical example <strong>of</strong> this is NEWTON'S gravitational law,<br />

i.e. the <strong>for</strong>ce <strong>of</strong> gravitational interaction is proportional to the product <strong>of</strong> the masses<br />

<strong>of</strong> two interacting bodies <strong>and</strong> inversely proportional to the square <strong>of</strong> the distance<br />

between them. This is an accurate statement.<br />

It should be noticed, however, that<br />

even this accurate statement <strong>of</strong> the universal law had no rational explanatory model<br />

behind it until the early 20 th century when EINSTEIN explained it in his relativistic<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> gravity (GAMoW 1962).<br />

A similar example is seen in the logistic law in demography first <strong>for</strong>mulated by<br />

VERHURST (1838), which was later generalized to population growth in other animal<br />

species by PEARL (1927). The VERHURST-PEARL logistic law assumes that the instantaneous<br />

rate <strong>of</strong> increase per animal is proportional to the still unutilized opportunity<br />

<strong>for</strong> growth, <strong>and</strong> is expressed in the well-known mathematical equation. But no positive<br />

rationalization <strong>of</strong> the assumption has been made;there is no rational relationship


etween the assumption (CHAPMAN's (1931) concept <strong>of</strong> 'environmental resistance')<br />

<strong>and</strong> the attributes <strong>of</strong> the subject (population growth), so the latter remain unknown.<br />

The logistic equation was derived through metaphoric inferences rather than through<br />

comparisons between the attributes <strong>of</strong> the subject <strong>and</strong> those <strong>of</strong> a model in which<br />

factors involved are known.<br />

Thus, we can see that differences between (a) a deductive model (deduced only<br />

by reasoning) <strong>and</strong> (b) a descriptive equation like that <strong>of</strong> the logistic law, lie in<br />

differences between (a) a comparison <strong>of</strong> components in the subject with equivalent<br />

parts <strong>of</strong> the model <strong>and</strong> (b) a metaphoric juxtaposition <strong>of</strong> the observed trend <strong>of</strong> the<br />

subject with that <strong>of</strong> some known concepts.<br />

While the importance <strong>of</strong> metaphor, as SCHON (1967) emphasized, is appreciated,<br />

it should be borne in mind that metaphor alone does not necessarily lead to explanations<br />

<strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ings. Quoting one <strong>of</strong> SCHON'S examples, the original concept <strong>of</strong><br />

'foot', restricted to an animal's foot, can be shifted to a much broader concept including<br />

'the foot <strong>of</strong> a mountain'. Although this example certainly shows the importance<br />

<strong>of</strong> metaphor in, say, the evolution <strong>of</strong> languages, such juxtaposition does not immediately<br />

imply the underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong> the foot <strong>of</strong> mountains. In other words,<br />

metaphor, playing its important role in one situation, or in a certain part <strong>of</strong> the process<br />

in the <strong>for</strong>mation <strong>of</strong> ideas, can be too vague to be useful in another. In the<br />

example <strong>of</strong> the logistic law, metaphor led to the <strong>for</strong>mulation <strong>of</strong> the equation that can<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten describe observed relationships satisfactorily, but such success <strong>of</strong>ten depends<br />

on how the observed relationships are described deterministically.<br />

Normally, in the field <strong>of</strong> population ecology, a deterministic description <strong>of</strong> phenomena<br />

is <strong>of</strong>ten so difficult that a descriptive, empirical equation can be adopted only<br />

casually. Such casual equations <strong>of</strong>ten involve some coefficients whose nature is not<br />

known. The equation is then hard to rationalize as there can be some other <strong>for</strong>ms<br />

<strong>of</strong> equations which fit the same observation equally well. Also, the coefficients must<br />

be estimated from a limited set <strong>of</strong> observed data (our observations are, at any rate,<br />

limited), <strong>and</strong> the more limited the number <strong>of</strong> observations, the less generalized the<br />

estimate will be. Further, the more coefficients that are involved <strong>and</strong> that need to be<br />

estimated, the more flexible the equation becomes since the degrees <strong>of</strong> freedom <strong>for</strong><br />

fitting increase. The above statement simply suggests that a good fit does not imply<br />

that the equation concerned explains the mechanism.<br />

Conversely, if an equation, derived from metaphoric inference, did not fit observed<br />

relationships, it would have to be rejected. The rejection, however, involves a risk<br />

<strong>of</strong> rejecting a correct assemblage <strong>of</strong> right components. This is because the disagreement<br />

could be due to some other components or conditions which were missed, <strong>and</strong><br />

not due to inappropriate metaphor; if this is so, the equation need not be rejected<br />

but only improved by further search <strong>for</strong> these overlooked factors. The difficulty is,<br />

however, that there is no systematic way to know whether the disagreement is due<br />

to the inadequate assemblage <strong>of</strong> factors or to inappropriate metaphor.


Hence, the fitting <strong>of</strong> an empirical equation to observed relationships in certain<br />

subjects, <strong>and</strong> I imply that animal <strong>predation</strong> is one such subject, has a limited value<br />

theoretically. In the following, another method, i.e. analogies by attributes, will be<br />

explored.<br />

Normally, reasoning starts from a set <strong>of</strong> tentative propositions. This set <strong>of</strong><br />

propositions is one kind <strong>of</strong> hypothesis. Because it is only tentatively assumed, it does<br />

not necessarilly <strong>and</strong> immediately postulate mechanisms underlying the subject.<br />

Often, an early, tentative hypothesis is a mere collection <strong>of</strong> all the factors that<br />

can be conceived, whereas what one can observe is the integrated complex <strong>of</strong> factors<br />

interacting with each other. It is, however, difficult in many cases to extract each<br />

component <strong>of</strong> the subject to compare with an assumed one purely by the observational<br />

method. It is possible, instead, to integrate the assumed components on a theoretical<br />

basis so that the assumption-system can be compared with the observed whole. The<br />

difficulty is that a mere list <strong>of</strong> components will not necessarily provide the method<br />

<strong>of</strong> integration. By some means, we have to assume the structure as well. It is at<br />

this stage that analogies can play a role, <strong>and</strong> it is the structure thus derived from<br />

analogies (or some known examples) that I call a 'model' here. When the model to<br />

adopt is determined, a method <strong>of</strong> calculating the model's attributes will follow. An<br />

analytic (i. e. mathematical) method can be used <strong>for</strong> the calculation, or the method<br />

commonly called 'Monte Carlo simulation' may be useful. Here, mathematics is used<br />

not as a convenient means <strong>of</strong> description, but as a means <strong>of</strong> inference.<br />

Now, we recognize two early stages <strong>of</strong> inferences; the collection <strong>of</strong> components,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the arrangement <strong>and</strong> integration <strong>of</strong> them by a tentative model. The tentative<br />

model may be called a hypothesis, but it should be borne in mind that it is only<br />

tentative <strong>and</strong> not more than a convenient assumption. Such tentative hypotheses do<br />

not enable us to postulate the mechanism <strong>of</strong> the subject. The tentative hypothesis,<br />

however, is now compared with observation <strong>and</strong> will in general need refinement, as<br />

it <strong>of</strong>ten does not agree with the facts with a desirable degree <strong>of</strong> precision. A refinement<br />

will be made through alteration <strong>of</strong> the arrangement, adding some more components<br />

which have previously been missed, etc. As the stage <strong>of</strong> refinement advances,<br />

the hypothesis would enable one to postulate more confidently. Finally, as the degree<br />

<strong>of</strong> agreement with the facts increases, the postulational hypothesis would eventually<br />

emerge as a theory or even a principle.<br />

There are three important points in the gradual process <strong>of</strong> inferences mentioned<br />

above; they will be discussed more in detail below. First is the <strong>for</strong>mulation <strong>of</strong> a<br />

tentative hypothesis; second, the evaluation <strong>of</strong> agreement ~nd disagreement between<br />

the theoretical <strong>and</strong> the observed; third, the fact-observation relationship. The third<br />

one is a question <strong>of</strong> whether an observation can be accepted as fact.<br />

For the following discussion, some symbols will be used as defined below:<br />

0 : the result <strong>of</strong> observation,<br />

Ko :the set <strong>of</strong> all major components involved (not particularly known) in the


observed system,<br />

So : the structure <strong>of</strong> the observed system,<br />

KA : the set <strong>of</strong> all assumed components in the model system,<br />

S~ : the structure <strong>of</strong> the model system,<br />

E : theoretical expectation deduced from KA <strong>and</strong> S.x.<br />

When E <strong>and</strong> 0 are compared, we will get either an agreement or a disagreement,<br />

i.e. E=O or Er respectively, to which various conditions (causes) contribute as<br />

below:<br />

Conditions<br />

C1. K~ <strong>and</strong> S~ are involved in Ka <strong>and</strong> So respectively (so that both K~4 <strong>and</strong> S~<br />

are, at least, not false).<br />

cu. if KA <strong>and</strong> S~ are both sufficient, then E=O.<br />

c~2. if either KA or S:~ is inadequate, then E~ O.<br />

c~a. if O is false or inadequate under c~I, then E:~O.<br />

Cz. Ko does not involve the whole <strong>of</strong> K~, <strong>and</strong>/or So does not involve the whole<br />

<strong>of</strong> S.~ (so that KA <strong>and</strong>/or S.n are/is, at least partly, false),<br />

c21. if false parts <strong>of</strong> Ka <strong>and</strong> Sn, or false parts <strong>of</strong> O <strong>and</strong> K~, (or S:,z), are<br />

adjusted so that they cancel out each other, then E-O.<br />

c~2. if not c21, then Er<br />

Now, one can claim that his hypothesis is right only when c, under C~ holds.<br />

However, the fact that an agreement (E~O) exists is not sufficient to establish the<br />

hypothesis, since E=O also occurs when c~1 under C2 is involved. There<strong>for</strong>e, if a<br />

comparison between E <strong>and</strong> O is the only available method, we have to be contented<br />

with an assessment <strong>of</strong> the relative credibility <strong>of</strong> these causes. The assessment can<br />

be done much the same way as <strong>for</strong> the calculation <strong>of</strong> the LAPLACIAN probability (see<br />

BURNSIDE 1928 ; POL~CA 1955).<br />

Let Pr {E=O} be the probability <strong>of</strong> event (E=O) taking place. As it takes place<br />

either when cu or when C~l is involved (the probability <strong>of</strong> which will be written as<br />

Pr {(E=O) ]c~} <strong>and</strong> Pr {(E=O) Icy} respectively), we get<br />

Pr{E=O} =Pr{(E=O) i c~} +Pr{(E=O) !c2~.<br />

Also, as C~l is dependent on C~,<br />

Pr{(E=O) [c,} =Pr~c,}Pr{C~}<br />

<strong>and</strong> similarly,<br />

Pr { (E= O) I ce~} =Pr {c~x} Pr {C~}.<br />

From these <strong>for</strong>mulae, the following conclusions are drawn. If Ka is comprised<br />

<strong>of</strong> only those components which are either axiomatic, a priori (known to be true<br />

without appeal to the particular facts <strong>of</strong> evidence), or can be deduced from concepts<br />

already known to be true, Ka must be involved in Ko. In other words, Pr {C~} is<br />

high but Pr {C2~ is low. There<strong>for</strong>e. if an agreement (E=O) was observed under<br />

these circumstances, Pr{(E-O) [cH[ is high as compared with Pr {(E=O) lc2~} ; i. e.<br />

the credibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> reasoning that the agreement is due to a right hypothesis is com-


paratively high. However, the more axiomatic K~ is, the lower Pr {cn} will be, <strong>and</strong><br />

so the less likely is event (E=O) to occur.<br />

For the above reason, a simple, deductive model <strong>of</strong>ten fails to agree with obser-<br />

vation. But such failures in deductive <strong>models</strong> are more likely to be caused either<br />

by c~2 or c~3 than by c2z. If so, there is no reason to reject the hypothesis ; it only<br />

needs further elaboration. The only case in which at least a part <strong>of</strong> the components<br />

or the structure should be rejected, is C~. Here, a careful observation <strong>of</strong> the disagree-<br />

ment is <strong>of</strong> paramount importance.<br />

There are, broadly speaking, two possible kinds <strong>of</strong> alterations when a disagree-<br />

ment is observed. A method frequently seen in the literature is to adjust the structure<br />

<strong>of</strong> the model or to add some more components to obtain E=O. Here, Pr{E=O}<br />

certainly increases, but at the same time there is a risk <strong>of</strong> getting a high Pr{C2},<br />

<strong>and</strong> hence Prl(E=O)[c21}. The risk is greater if the added components are those<br />

whose trend is not fully understood. The estimation <strong>of</strong> coefficients involved in the<br />

empirical equation could amount to this kind <strong>of</strong> adjustment, as the coefficients <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

have to be estimated by comparing E with O. The recent <strong>predation</strong> <strong>models</strong> in fact<br />

involve such a risk, as will be shown later. The worst thing is to obtain E=O by<br />

adjustment when the first disagreement was in fact caused by c22 ; it only increases<br />

Prl(E=O)]c21} <strong>and</strong> has no meaning at all.<br />

The second type <strong>of</strong> improvement is to look <strong>for</strong> more <strong>of</strong> the axiomatic components,<br />

or <strong>of</strong> those which are known to be true <strong>for</strong> any reason, without making a particular<br />

ef<strong>for</strong>t to obtain E=O. This keeps Pr {C2} to a low level, <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e the improve-<br />

ment, if any, increases, though only gradually, Pr {c1~}.<br />

Although the second method will provide a steady approach to the goal, a question<br />

arises whether a collection <strong>of</strong> axiomatic assumptions can eventually produce a suffi-<br />

cient model. WALKER (1963) argued that "it is a common misconception that new<br />

<strong>models</strong> are constructed by strict logical deduction from observed facts <strong>and</strong> from<br />

previous <strong>models</strong>". Certainly, nothing new will come from mere accumulations <strong>of</strong><br />

known concepts. However, a model is not a mere collection <strong>of</strong> already known com-<br />

ponents but involves a positive recombination <strong>of</strong> them which is applied to a new<br />

situation. And the role <strong>of</strong> the model is to produce a useful recombination by analogy.<br />

The efficiency <strong>of</strong> finding a useful model depends on the efficiency in selecting<br />

axiomatic components <strong>and</strong> recombining them. A model is there<strong>for</strong>e required to have<br />

room <strong>for</strong> accommodating added components <strong>and</strong> recombining them. This calls <strong>for</strong><br />

a general <strong>and</strong> idealized model to start with: too specific a model has to be rejected<br />

upon finding a disagreement because <strong>of</strong> its limited capacity <strong>for</strong> modification, or it<br />

could involve a high value <strong>of</strong> Pr{(E=O)Ic2~}, particularly when some coefficients<br />

involved have to be estimated rather than determined by independent <strong>and</strong> direct<br />

observations <strong>of</strong> what these coefficients' represent.<br />

The role <strong>of</strong> idealization is again seen in the history <strong>of</strong> the physical sciences,<br />

which should be understood in the context <strong>of</strong> fact-observation relationships <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>


the notions 'realistic' <strong>and</strong> 'unrealistic'. In the ARISTOTELIAN doctrine, certain natural<br />

phenomena as observed were taken <strong>for</strong> granted as axioms. Thus, a cart pulled by a horse<br />

(a constant <strong>for</strong>ce) moves at a constant speed, but comes to a stop (a natural state<br />

<strong>of</strong> rest) when the <strong>for</strong>ce is removed. Inorganic chemical processes were explained by<br />

analogy with physiological processes, such as seeds becoming ripe, which were accepted<br />

as natural, axiomatic, <strong>and</strong> were not questioned.<br />

A significant change in the way that natural order was regarded came at the<br />

time <strong>of</strong> the Renaissance when BURIDAN (OPPENHEIMER 1956), <strong>and</strong> later GALILEI,<br />

made the earliest announcement <strong>of</strong> the principle <strong>of</strong> physical inertia. In 1612, GALILEI<br />

wrote to a pupil <strong>of</strong> his:<br />

"For I seem to have observed that physical bodies have physical inclination to<br />

some motion ...... through an intrinsic property ...... And there<strong>for</strong>e, all external impediments<br />

removed,. ..... it will maintain itself in that state in which it has once been<br />

placed" (translation by DRAKE 1957).<br />

The recognition <strong>of</strong> the "physical inclination through an intrinsic property" is<br />

important, in the context <strong>of</strong> the present discussion, as GALILEI could not have been<br />

able to observe a ship floating on a perfectly calm, smooth, resistanceless water <strong>and</strong>,<br />

once pushed, moving at a constant speed without the faintest sign <strong>of</strong> slowing down.<br />

The discovery, or recognition, <strong>of</strong> inertia must there<strong>for</strong>e have been made with only<br />

an idealized situation in mind, a situation which to other natural philosophers <strong>of</strong> the<br />

period must have been 'unrealistic'. A similar example is found in the history <strong>of</strong><br />

chemistry, when the existence <strong>of</strong> chemically pure substances was recognized only<br />

under idealized, artificial, <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e unnatural conditions (TouLMIN 1961).<br />

These examples illustrate the point that a fact as observed in a natural state is<br />

not ultimate, <strong>for</strong> it is only the visible part <strong>of</strong> the whole. Inferences by <strong>models</strong> can<br />

only help one to generalize an observation, <strong>and</strong>, as POINCAR~ (1952) pointed out,<br />

"without generalization, prediction is impossible". It is perhaps particularly true with<br />

ecological studies that generalization is possible, not in a thing in itself which we<br />

observe under natural conditions, but in an idealized situation. Here, analogies by<br />

<strong>models</strong> play an important role.<br />

3. A BACKGROUND THEORY OF THE STRUCTURE OF PREDATION AND PARASITISM<br />

In the first place, it will be made clear that what I mean by 'background' in this<br />

section involves only those components <strong>and</strong> conditions which, under each idealized<br />

assumption, are known a priori; that is, they are known to be involved in the idealized<br />

process <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> without any need <strong>of</strong> confirmation by observation.<br />

The need <strong>for</strong> such theories is undeniable since, as already pointed out in w 2,<br />

they are the starting point <strong>for</strong> gradual inferences. It should be borne in mind that a<br />

direct comparison <strong>of</strong> this background theory with any observation might result in<br />

disagreement; but such disagreement, unlike that caused by condition c~2, will not<br />

invalidate the theory.


10<br />

The structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> is considered first. Suppose that there are x prey <strong>and</strong><br />

y predator individuals per unit area, <strong>and</strong> that each individual predator consumes, on<br />

the average, f(x) prey individuals per unit time. For the moment, the analytic <strong>for</strong>m<br />

<strong>of</strong> f(x) is not specified, but it is an assumed, increasing function <strong>of</strong> x.<br />

It is also<br />

assumed <strong>for</strong> the moment that the prey <strong>and</strong> predator numbers are fixed at X <strong>and</strong> Y<br />

respectively throughout one observation period t, i.e. that during t the prey population<br />

is replenished as fast as it is reduced by <strong>predation</strong>, <strong>and</strong> no increase or decrease<br />

occurs among the predators. Under these assumptions, the following will hold :<br />

n-~f(X) Yt (3.1)<br />

where n is the total number <strong>of</strong> prey killed by predators per unit area during t.<br />

capital letters <strong>for</strong> x <strong>and</strong> y indicate that these values are fixed during an observation<br />

period t.) At this stage, neither the effect <strong>of</strong> changes in the predator's psycho-physio-<br />

logical state nor the effect <strong>of</strong> social interaction is considered.<br />

(The<br />

Equation (3.1) is shown graphically in Fig. 1 where hypothetical values <strong>of</strong> n are<br />

plotted against X; note that Y <strong>and</strong> t are both fixed <strong>for</strong> all X's. The evaluation <strong>of</strong> n is<br />

nl when X is X~ <strong>and</strong> n2 when X is Xz. Of course, the measurements <strong>of</strong> n~ <strong>and</strong> n~<br />

must be made in two separate observations to meet the condition under which eq.<br />

(3.1) holds. It should also be noticed that eq. (3.1) does not provide any means <strong>of</strong><br />

evaluating the effect <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> upon the prey density because the latter is fixed in<br />

each observation period.<br />

rl<br />

n~<br />

N<br />

y<br />

X2<br />

Fig. 1. A hypothetical example <strong>of</strong> curves <strong>for</strong> eq. (3. 1) The prey density,<br />

fixed at X during time-interval t, is plotted on the horizontal axis,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the total number (n) preyed upon <strong>for</strong> t, when the predator density<br />

y is fixed at Y, is plotted on the vertical axis.<br />

Now, suppose a new situation in which the prey population is not replenished so<br />

that the prey density is gradually depleted while the predators are hunting in one<br />

observation period, i.e.t.<br />

Xl<br />

As the prey density decreases during the period, the number<br />

that the predators can kill per unit time per unit area must also decrease. This<br />

>•


11<br />

situation is easily seen from Fig. 1. Suppose XI, is the initial prey density. At this<br />

moment, the prey are killed at the rate <strong>of</strong> nJYt. But if the prey density is depleted<br />

to X2, the rate <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> is decreased to n~/Yt. Hence, the overall rate <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong><br />

must be something between nl/Yt <strong>and</strong> n2/Yt. To evaluate the overall rate <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong>,<br />

we must use calculus.<br />

As mentioned be<strong>for</strong>e, eq. (3.1) holds only when the prey density does not change<br />

during t. In our new situation in which the density x decreases as t increases, eq.<br />

(3. 1) holds only <strong>for</strong> such a short period that a reduction in x at this moment can<br />

practically be ignored. Let us denote this short period by `it <strong>and</strong> an accordingly small<br />

fraction <strong>of</strong> number killed by `in. Substituting x, `it, <strong>and</strong> `in <strong>for</strong> X, t, <strong>and</strong> n respectively<br />

in eq. (3.1), we have<br />

`in =f(x) Yztt, or `in/dt =f(x) Y (3.2)<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong> `it->0, we have<br />

dn/dt :f(x) Y (3.3).<br />

Clearly, the derivative dn/dt is the rate <strong>of</strong> capturing prey, <strong>and</strong> so it is a positive<br />

function <strong>of</strong> x. If, however, the rate <strong>of</strong> depletion in prey density, i.e. dx/dt, is considered,<br />

it is a negative function <strong>of</strong> x, but its absolute value must be equal to dn/dt,<br />

because the prey population is reduced according to the number consumed. So, we<br />

have<br />

dx/dt = -f(x) Y (3.4).<br />

Let xo be the initial prey density (when t=0) which is reduced to x over a period<br />

<strong>of</strong> time, i.e. t, <strong>and</strong> integrating eq. (3.4), we have<br />

dx<br />

fx (3.5).<br />

=- xo fCxi-<br />

Now, I shall explain in more detail the reason why the differential equation <strong>and</strong><br />

the integration (i. e. eqs. (3.4) <strong>and</strong> (3.5) respectively) are used as a means <strong>of</strong> deduction,<br />

because this means <strong>of</strong> deduction should be understood thoroughly so that my criticism<br />

<strong>of</strong> various <strong>models</strong> in later sections will be followed readily.<br />

Suppose that the initial prey density was xo when t=0, <strong>and</strong> that it took `ito to<br />

reduce the prey density by ,Ix. Assuming that `ito <strong>and</strong> so `ix were sufficiently small,<br />

<strong>and</strong> substituting xo, -`ix, <strong>and</strong> `it0 <strong>for</strong> x, `in, <strong>and</strong> `it in eq. (3.2), we have<br />

Ydto = - `ix/f (xo) .<br />

At this moment, the prey density is reduced to Xo-`ix. Suppose, <strong>for</strong> further reduc-<br />

tion in the prey density by as much as `ix, it took `itl. Then <strong>for</strong> the same reason as<br />

above, we get<br />

Y`it~ = - `ix/f (xo- dX) .<br />

In general, at the i th interval, it takes `its to reduce the density by another `ix. As<br />

the prey density has been reduced to xo-i`ix by this time, the evaluation <strong>of</strong> `it~ is<br />

given by


12<br />

Y Jr, = -Jx/f(xo-iJx).<br />

Thus we have the following summation :<br />

YJto = - Jx/f(xo)<br />

YJt, Jx/f(xo - ,fx)<br />

Y~at~ = - Jx/f (xo - 2Jx)<br />

+) YJt,=-Jx/f(xo-iJx)<br />

i<br />

i<br />

Y ZJt, = - ~ {Jx/f(xo- iJx) }.<br />

i=0 i=0<br />

Now, let t be the total time taken to the i th interval. Then t is the summation <strong>of</strong><br />

all Jt's to the i th interval, i.e.<br />

so that<br />

i<br />

t=~dt,<br />

i=0<br />

i<br />

Y ~,ft, = Yt.<br />

i-O<br />

Similarly, let x be the prey density at the i th interval, which is the difference between<br />

the initial density xo <strong>and</strong> the total number <strong>of</strong> prey taken per unit area, i.e. iJx. So,<br />

X=Xo-iJx.<br />

As x is a continuous variable, we can make Jx infinitesimally small, which is now<br />

written as dx. Also, under these circumstances, the summation sign ~ is replaced by<br />

the integral sign ~. Further, it is clear that x varies from xo to x when i varies from<br />

0 to i. Thus<br />

i fx dx<br />

lim ~ {Jx/f(xo- lax) } : f(x)"<br />

Jx~O i~O<br />

xo<br />

Hence, yt=_<br />

f; ~ dx f(X)' <strong>and</strong> we have eq. (3.5).<br />

For further discussion, the integral in the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq. (3.5) must be<br />

evaluated. As the <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> f(x) has not been specified, a few <strong>for</strong>ms will be assumed<br />

below <strong>for</strong> convenience.<br />

Let us assume first that f(x) is a linear function <strong>of</strong> x ; that is, the prey are killed<br />

in proportion to their density. Then,<br />

f(x) =ax (3.6)<br />

where a is any positive constant. As will be seen later, eq. (3.6) is the basis <strong>of</strong> the<br />

classical <strong>models</strong> by LOTKA (!925), VOLTERRA (1926), <strong>and</strong> NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY<br />

(1935), but I shall not discuss its ecological meaning as this is not needed at the<br />

moment. Substituting the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq. (3.6) <strong>for</strong> f(x) in eq. (3.5), we have<br />

which yields<br />

a Yt = - (x<br />

d xo<br />

dx<br />

X<br />

a Yt = - In x (3. 7).<br />

Xo


As the prey density is reduced from Xo to x during time t, the difference (xo-x) is<br />

the number <strong>of</strong> prey individuals killed per unit area during t. So, removing the 'ln'<br />

sign <strong>and</strong> rearranging, eq. (3. ,7) will be solved with respect to xo-x as below,<br />

Xo - x = Xo (1 - e- ~')<br />

or, setting z equal to Xo--X,<br />

z =Xo (1 - e -art) (3.8).<br />

This is in fact the familiar NICHOLSON-BAILEY 'Competition equation' (see w<br />

Now we have three variables in eq.<br />

13<br />

(3.8), z being the dependent variable <strong>and</strong><br />

x0 <strong>and</strong> Yt independent ones. In this particular example, the predator density Y <strong>and</strong><br />

the time t (<strong>for</strong> which the prey population is exposed to <strong>predation</strong>) are mutually com-<br />

plementary. That is to say, the effect <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> upon prey density exerted by twice<br />

as many predators <strong>for</strong> half the time, is exactly the same as the effect by half as many<br />

predators <strong>for</strong> twice the time since<br />

(2 Y) (t/2) = (Y/2) (2 t).<br />

This holds only because neither social interference (or social facilitation) among pred-<br />

ators nor changes in physiological state are considered: they have been ignored,<br />

<strong>for</strong> the time being, <strong>for</strong> simplicity.<br />

Under the above circumstances, eq.<br />

(3. 8) represents a surface in a three-dimen-<br />

sional coordinate system, i.e. the z-, x0-, <strong>and</strong> Yt-axes, in which z is the only<br />

dependent variable, <strong>and</strong> x0 <strong>and</strong> Yt are mutually independent.<br />

This does not mean<br />

that Yt is ecologically independent <strong>of</strong> x0, particularly in a closed system in which the<br />

predator density in one generation is determined by the prey density in the preceding<br />

generation. But, within a generation, Yt <strong>and</strong> xo are mathematically independent <strong>of</strong><br />

each other, in the sense that we can think <strong>of</strong> any Yt-value <strong>for</strong> a given x0-value.<br />

Figure 2a shows a surface generated by eq. (3.8), the surface being determined<br />

primarily <strong>for</strong> a given value <strong>of</strong> the constant a.<br />

In this figure, any cross-section <strong>of</strong> the surface parallel to the Z-Xo plane is linear,<br />

which suggests that <strong>for</strong> any fixed value <strong>of</strong> YL the number <strong>of</strong> prey killed per unit<br />

area increases linearly with the initial prey density. However, the cross-section parallel<br />

to the z-Yt plane is exponential, suggesting that <strong>for</strong> any fixed value <strong>of</strong> x0, the share<br />

<strong>of</strong> food <strong>for</strong> each predator decreases progressively as the predator density increases,<br />

or it becomes progressively harder <strong>for</strong> each individual to find its food as the time<br />

spent hunting increases. This is in fact the 'law <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns' when the<br />

predators put more ef<strong>for</strong>t (or predator-hours, i.e. Yt) into hunting.<br />

If both sides <strong>of</strong> eq. (3. 8) are divided by x0, then<br />

Z/Xo: (1-e -~') (3. 9).<br />

The right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq.<br />

(3. 9) does not involve x0, <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e z/xo is uninflu-<br />

enced by changes in x0. Graphically, the surface on the Z/Xo-Xo Yt coordinate system<br />

is perfectly parallel to the xo-Yt plane so that the cross-sections parallel to the z/xo<br />

-Yt plane maintain a constant shape along the x0-axis (Fig. 2b). Under these<br />

circumstances, we do not need a three-dimensional coordinate system but a simple


14<br />

Z-Xo PLANE ~ ...'~<br />

0 Xll ~<br />

Fig. 2a. An example <strong>of</strong> surfaces generated by eq. (3.8). x0 is the initial<br />

prey density, Yt the hunting ef<strong>for</strong>t (i.e. predator-hours), <strong>and</strong> z<br />

the reduction <strong>of</strong> the prey density at the end <strong>of</strong> the interval t.<br />

A<br />

zl~-x, PLANE<br />

,*'"'i<br />

Fig. 2b. Same as Fig. 2a, but the proportion <strong>of</strong> the prey density reduced<br />

from the initial density, i.e. Z/Xo, is plotted on the vertical axis, cf.<br />

eq. (3. 9).<br />

two-dimensional one, i.e. a Z/Xo-Yt system. This is in fact the method <strong>of</strong> presenta-<br />

tion originally used by N[CHOLSON (1933) who called the curve the 'competition curve'.<br />

This simple method <strong>of</strong> presentation is possible, however, only under the particular


15<br />

assumption that f(x) is a linear function <strong>of</strong> x. If f(x) is not a linear function, gener-<br />

ally speaking, the x0-axis is still required since the ratio z/xo again changes as x0<br />

changes, This will be shown in the following example.<br />

Observations by various authors have shown that the function f(x) is not normally<br />

linear, <strong>and</strong> there is a good reason to believe that it should not be so (see w 4c).<br />

fact, f(x) is more like the curve shown in Fig. 1, which increases as x increases but<br />

gradually approaches a plateau. This type <strong>of</strong> curve can be generated by various<br />

equations.<br />

For convenience, however, we shall assume the following function used<br />

extensively in IVLEV'S (1955) <strong>study</strong> on fish <strong>predation</strong> (see w 4d):<br />

f(x) -~ b (1 - e- a,~) (3.10)<br />

where b <strong>and</strong> a are any positive constants.<br />

Although the biological meaning <strong>of</strong> this<br />

equation is as open to criticism as the NICHOLSON-BAILEu one, this is not important<br />

at the present stage <strong>of</strong> the argument.<br />

Substituting the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq. (3. 10) <strong>for</strong> f(x) in eq. (3.5), we have<br />

In<br />

which yields<br />

Yt=- fx dx (3.11),<br />

xo 1 -- e -~<br />

Z--<br />

a 1 ln{(l_e_axo)e_~br~+e_~,, } (3.12)<br />

where z = x0- x.<br />

Equation (3. 12) generates a surface on the z-xo-Yt coordinate system (Fig. 3a)<br />

which has a more complex shape than that generated by eq. (3.8) or Fig. 2a.<br />

Although the cross-sections parallel to the z-Yt plane are very similar to those in<br />

Fig. 2a, as they also represent the law <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns, those parallel to z-xo<br />

Z<br />

9 -,.. \ ",, :~<br />

9 ., \ -,. :<br />

0 x~<br />

Fig 3a.<br />

Same as Fig. 2a, but the surface is generated by eq. (3. 12).


16<br />

z/x, T x o PLANE<br />

/// ,' !"--r , j,<br />

Fig. 3b.<br />

0 • ~<br />

Same as Fig. aa, but proportion z/xo is plotted on the vertical axis.<br />

plane are also curvilinear <strong>and</strong> similar to the curve generated by eq. (3. 10), Clearly,<br />

we cannot present eq. (3. 12) in a two-dimensional coordinate system showing the<br />

relationship between Z/Xo <strong>and</strong> Yt, since the relationship changes as Xo changes (Fig.<br />

3b).<br />

These two examples show that, though no ecological reality is attached to them<br />

at the moment, the number <strong>of</strong> prey killed by predators per unit area, i.e. z, is expressed<br />

as a function <strong>of</strong> two independent variables (x0 <strong>and</strong> Yt). So we can write this rela-<br />

tionship in a general <strong>for</strong>m using a functional symbol F as<br />

z=F (Xo, Yt) (3.13).<br />

Equation (3. 13) will be called an 'overall hunting equation' i<strong>and</strong> the function F<br />

an 'overall hunting function' as opposed to eq. (3.1), or (3.4), which is called an<br />

'instantaneous hunting equation' <strong>and</strong> the function f an 'instantaneous hunting function'.<br />

(The instantaneous hunting function may be a function <strong>of</strong> x, y, <strong>and</strong> t as a general<br />

case ; see later. )<br />

The essential difference between the overall <strong>and</strong> the instantaneous<br />

equations is that the <strong>for</strong>mer involves the effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns whereas the<br />

latter holds only at an instant <strong>and</strong> so does not involve this effect. If one intends to<br />

build a model to <strong>study</strong> a predator-prey interacting system, what is needed, from a<br />

theoretical point <strong>of</strong> view, is the overall hunting equation, since this is the equation<br />

which provides the estimates <strong>of</strong> the number <strong>of</strong> prey killed <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> the final density<br />

<strong>of</strong> prey at the end <strong>of</strong> a hunting period. The <strong>for</strong>mer estimate gives a basis <strong>for</strong> calculat-<br />

ing the number <strong>of</strong> predators' progeny <strong>and</strong> the latter the number <strong>of</strong> prey's progeny.<br />

Equation (3. 13), however, does not take into consideration a number <strong>of</strong> other<br />

factors which are likely to be involved in an actual <strong>predation</strong> process, e.g. the effect


17<br />

<strong>of</strong> social interactions among predators <strong>and</strong> the effect <strong>of</strong> hunger. One way to incorpo-<br />

rate these factors <strong>and</strong>~ their influence on the <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> an overall hunting equation will<br />

be shown in the following paragraphs.<br />

Social interactions among predators may be classified into two major categories,<br />

social interference <strong>and</strong> facilitation. These cause a reduction or increase, respectively,<br />

in the instantaneous hunting efficiency <strong>of</strong> each predator as compared to what it would<br />

potentially exhibit if these factors were not operating (<strong>for</strong> a detailed discussion, see<br />

w 4i). Let S be the factor by which f(x) is reduced or increased. Then an effective<br />

instantaneous hunting function will be Sf(x). Also the effect <strong>of</strong> social interaction<br />

must vary as the densities <strong>of</strong> both predators <strong>and</strong> prey vary. For instance, too many<br />

predators hunting too few prey would experience more intense interference, than other-<br />

wise, among the predators. There<strong>for</strong>e, S must at least be a function <strong>of</strong> both Y <strong>and</strong> x,<br />

which will be written as S (Y, x). Incorporating the factor S (Y, x) into eq. (3.4),<br />

we have<br />

<strong>and</strong> so<br />

dx/dt= -S(Y, x)f(x) Y (3. 14),<br />

Yt = _ ~,jx dx (3.15).<br />

xo S (Y, x)f(x)<br />

However, the intensity <strong>of</strong> social interaction might change with time, in which case, S<br />

may also be a function <strong>of</strong> t. The complex function Sf in eq. (3.14) is a generalized<br />

instantaneous hunting function <strong>and</strong> can be written as f(x, Y), <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong> further gener-<br />

alization as above it may be written as f(x, Y, t). But I shall avoid such complica-<br />

tions at the moment.<br />

The integral on the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq. (3.15) generally involves Y but not<br />

t. This suggests that if z(=xo-x) is evaluated in eq. (3. 15), it would be a function<br />

<strong>of</strong> xo, Y, <strong>and</strong> t, rather than one <strong>of</strong> x0 <strong>and</strong> Yr. Here, Y <strong>and</strong> t no longer <strong>for</strong>m a single<br />

complex variable. Thus the overall hunting equation becomes<br />

z =F(x0, Y, t) (3.16).<br />

Equation (3. 16) has three independent variables, <strong>and</strong> so it can be presented only<br />

in a four-dimensional coordinate system, or more practically in a series <strong>of</strong> three-dimen-<br />

sional coordinate systems;if, <strong>for</strong> instance, z, x0, <strong>and</strong> Y <strong>for</strong>med the three axes <strong>of</strong> a<br />

graph, separate graphs would be needed <strong>for</strong> each l. This means that if any social<br />

interaction is involved, different results should be expected between observations with<br />

different values <strong>of</strong> t.<br />

The effect <strong>of</strong> hunger can be incorporated in much the same way as is that <strong>of</strong><br />

social interactions. Suppose f(x) is an instantaneous hunting function <strong>of</strong> an individual<br />

predator when it can potentially exert its maximum output in hunting. If the predator<br />

is partially satiated, the maximum per<strong>for</strong>mance will only be partially realized.<br />

partial realization will be expressed by a factor H, which is an index <strong>of</strong> the hunger<br />

level <strong>and</strong> is naturally defined between 0 <strong>and</strong> 1 ; H may also be less than unity when<br />

the animal has been so starved that it cannot exert its full potential ef<strong>for</strong>t. Under<br />

This


18<br />

these circumstances, the effective instantaneous hunting function is Hf(x) instead <strong>of</strong><br />

f(x), so that we have, from eq. (3.4),<br />

dx/dt =--Hf(x) Y (3.17).<br />

Naturally, H is dependent on the net food intake into the stomach <strong>and</strong> the speed<br />

<strong>of</strong> digestion. No doubt, the net food intake depends on the density <strong>of</strong> food, the density<br />

<strong>of</strong> predators, <strong>and</strong> the time spent in hunting; 3nd the speed <strong>of</strong> digestion is also a<br />

function <strong>of</strong> time, at least. There<strong>for</strong>e, an argument similar to that in social interaction<br />

applies here too. One essential difference between the effect <strong>of</strong> social interaction <strong>and</strong><br />

hunger is that the latter involves the effect <strong>of</strong> initial state ; i. e. the factor H is<br />

influenced by the level <strong>of</strong> satiation or hunger just be<strong>for</strong>e the start <strong>of</strong> the observation.<br />

So if this initial state is denoted by the symbol I0, we can write the factor H as<br />

H(x, Y, t]I0), <strong>and</strong> so the instantaneous hunting equation will be <strong>of</strong> the <strong>for</strong>m<br />

dx/dt=-H(x, Y, t! Io)f(x) Y (3.18).<br />

Both functions S <strong>and</strong> H in the above examples are indices <strong>of</strong> the partial realization<br />

<strong>of</strong> the potential per<strong>for</strong>mance that an individual predator could exert if the influence<br />

<strong>of</strong> social interaction or hunger did not exist. Of course, this index method <strong>of</strong> building<br />

a model may not toke account <strong>of</strong> the actual <strong>and</strong> detailed processes <strong>of</strong> such psycho-<br />

logical <strong>and</strong> physiological states, although these states must actually have influences on<br />

particular components <strong>of</strong> the hunting activity ; e.g. the threshold at which searching<br />

or catching action is triggered must be reflected in, say, the effective speed <strong>of</strong> search-<br />

ing or the distance at which a predator reacts to a prey. Nevertheless, the index<br />

method has the advantage <strong>of</strong> illustrating some basic properties that a model must<br />

have, without going into too minute <strong>and</strong> unnecessary details <strong>of</strong> the structure, <strong>and</strong><br />

provides a criterion <strong>for</strong> evaluating some <strong>of</strong> the <strong>models</strong> reviewed in later sections.<br />

For instance, it shows that all the components that one wants to incorporate into a<br />

model have to be considered in the <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> an instantaneous hunting equation from<br />

which the overall equation will be derived. To incorporate new components directly<br />

into the overall function that had been derived be<strong>for</strong>e these components were dis-<br />

covered is not valid, unless the new components are known to have no influence on the<br />

effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns.<br />

treatment will be reviewed later.<br />

Some examples <strong>of</strong> <strong>models</strong> containing such erroneous<br />

A model <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> has a different structure than that <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong>, <strong>and</strong> a<br />

brief account <strong>of</strong> it will be given below.<br />

In <strong>predation</strong>, prey individuals normally disappear from the hunting area one after<br />

another as they ~re preyed upon, <strong>and</strong> so these "already eaten" prey are no longer<br />

available to the predators. This process is described by a differential equation, e.g.<br />

eq. (3. 4), which is the basis <strong>of</strong> a <strong>predation</strong> model. In <strong>parasitism</strong>, however, host<br />

individuals do not necessarily disappear <strong>and</strong> are still available to parasites during the<br />

course <strong>of</strong> hunting. Under these circumstances, the approach based on a differential<br />

equation loses its logical basis. Also, the availability <strong>of</strong> already parasitized hosts has<br />

different influences on those parasites that do not discriminate between parasitized


19<br />

<strong>and</strong> unparasitized hosts <strong>and</strong> on those that do.<br />

A typical, idealized parasite <strong>of</strong> the indiscriminate type can be defined as one<br />

which parasitizes fresh host individuals <strong>and</strong> already parasitized ones with equal prob-<br />

ability. In the following, <strong>for</strong> simplicity, it is assumed ideally that a parasite individual<br />

lays only one egg at a time.<br />

Suppose the host density is X<br />

(the capital letter indicates, as be<strong>for</strong>e, that the<br />

density is not subject to change during the course <strong>of</strong> attack) <strong>and</strong> n eggs are laid by<br />

Y parasites per unit area <strong>for</strong> time interval t. Then eq.<br />

(3.1) holds here too. As the<br />

parasites do not recognize already parasitized hosts, some hosts receive more than<br />

one parasite egg. Then our task is to find the total number <strong>of</strong> hosts receiving at<br />

least one egg, since those hosts receiving at least one egg are assumed to be killed<br />

eventually.<br />

Let Pr{i} be the probability <strong>of</strong> one host individual receiving i eggs. Then XPr{i}<br />

is the number <strong>of</strong> hosts per unit area, each <strong>of</strong> which receives i parasite eggs. There-<br />

<strong>for</strong>e, the total number <strong>of</strong> hosts parasitized, i.e. z, will be<br />

Clearly, since<br />

n<br />

z =X~ Pr{i} (3. 19).<br />

i=l<br />

Pr {i} = 1- Pr {0},<br />

i~l<br />

the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> the above equation is substituted <strong>for</strong> that in eq.<br />

we have<br />

z = X(1 - Pr ~0} ) (3.20).<br />

(3. 19), <strong>and</strong><br />

Normally, the frequency distribution <strong>of</strong> a probability is determined by its mean <strong>and</strong><br />

variance about the mean. Since n eggs are laid in X hosts per unit area, the mean<br />

number <strong>of</strong> eggs laid in each host is n/X, <strong>and</strong> so, if the variance V is known, we can<br />

write<br />

Pr{O~ =r V) (3.21)<br />

where ff is a functional symbol. Since n is given by eq. (3. 1), we have<br />

Pr{0} =r<br />

Yt/X, V).<br />

Substituting the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> the above equation <strong>for</strong> Pr{O} in eq. (3. 20), we get<br />

z=X[1-O(f(Y) Yt/X, V)] (3. 22).<br />

Equation (3. 22) is an overall hunting equation <strong>for</strong> an indiscriminate parasite comparable<br />

to eq. (3. 13) <strong>for</strong> predators. If social interaction is involved among the parasites<br />

concerned, the same argument as in <strong>predation</strong> applies here too ; the function f is then<br />

S(Y, X)f (X), or in general f(X, Y, t).<br />

Generally, eqs. (3. 13) <strong>and</strong> (3. 22) differ from each other, even if they have the same<br />

f(X), Y, <strong>and</strong> t. Only under a few special circumstances will these two turn out to<br />

be <strong>of</strong> the same <strong>for</strong>m. For instance, if the parasites are assumed to distribute their<br />

eggs at r<strong>and</strong>om over the host individuals, <strong>and</strong> if the number <strong>of</strong> hosts is sufficiently<br />

large so that the probability <strong>of</strong> a given host individual being found by each parasite


20<br />

individual is sufficiently small, the number <strong>of</strong> hosts receiving no egg, i.e. Pr {0}, will<br />

be the first term (or the 0 term) <strong>of</strong> a POISSON series, i.e.<br />

Pr{O} =e -~/x<br />

So if we assume f(X)=aX, we have from eq. (3. 1),<br />

n =aXYt<br />

so that<br />

Pr {0} = e -~r~<br />

<strong>and</strong> substituting the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> the above equation <strong>for</strong> Pr{O} in eq. (3.20),<br />

we get<br />

z=X(1-e -art) (3.23).<br />

Since X is equivalent to x0 in the case <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong>, the above equation is identical<br />

in <strong>for</strong>m to eq. (3. 8).<br />

If, however, we assume that eq. (3.10) holds instead <strong>of</strong> eq. (3. 6) <strong>for</strong> f(x), other<br />

things being equal, we have <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong><br />

z =X(1-e -b(1-e-ax) Yt/X) (3.24),<br />

which is not the same as eq. (3.12). Obviously, a predator does not find 'already<br />

eaten' prey individuals nor spend any time eating such imaginary prey, <strong>and</strong> this<br />

makes the difference. In the first example <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>, no account is taken <strong>of</strong> the<br />

time that the parasite has to spend laying eggs, so that it becomes the same as in a<br />

<strong>predation</strong> model in which the time spent eating prey is not considered. Also, as will<br />

be discussed in detail later, we cannot assume without contradiction that the instantaneous<br />

hunting function is the same <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>. This implies that<br />

<strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> <strong>models</strong> cannot logically be considered to have the same <strong>for</strong>m.<br />

As far as I know, this point has been entirely overlooked in population theories.<br />

If the parasite concerned has the ability to detect a host already carrying one or<br />

more eggs, then one assumption set <strong>for</strong>th in the above indiscriminate <strong>parasitism</strong><br />

model breaks down. That is, discriminate parasites would not spend the same amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> time on already parasitized hosts as on fresh hosts, since in the <strong>for</strong>mer case only<br />

the time spent in examination would be involved whereas, in the latter, the time<br />

spent laying eggs is also involved. Even their paths <strong>of</strong> search may be influenced if<br />

they can detect an already parasitized host from some distance by scent <strong>and</strong> do not<br />

approach <strong>for</strong> a close examination. The situation is then halfway between <strong>predation</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> indiscriminate <strong>parasitism</strong>.<br />

Bearing these background theories in mind, we can now take a close look at the<br />

existing <strong>models</strong>.<br />

4. THE EXISTING MODELS<br />

The <strong>models</strong> to be studied here are those by LOTKA (1925)-VoLTERRA (1926),<br />

NICHOLSON-BAILEY (1935), HOLLING (1959b), IVLEV (1955)-GAosE (1934), ROYAMA<br />

(1966), WATT (1959), THOMPSON (1924)-SToY (1932), HASSELL-VARLnY (1969), <strong>and</strong>


21<br />

HOLLING (1966). In order to maintain consistency throughout this <strong>study</strong>, an ef<strong>for</strong>t<br />

will be made, as far as possible, to use the same symbols denoting the same factors,<br />

parameters, etc. For example, x st<strong>and</strong>s <strong>for</strong> the density <strong>of</strong> a prey (host) species as<br />

against y <strong>for</strong> the predator (parasite) density, <strong>and</strong> t <strong>for</strong> a time-interval during which<br />

the prey (host) species are exposed to <strong>predation</strong> (<strong>parasitism</strong>). Symbols used extensively<br />

are listed <strong>and</strong> defined in Appendix 4. The consistency <strong>of</strong> using the same symbols<br />

<strong>for</strong> the same meaning in different <strong>models</strong> makes it difficult to use those <strong>of</strong> the<br />

original authors.<br />

Each subsection begins with the presentation <strong>of</strong> the model concerned, more or<br />

less in the manner that the original author presented it, so that the way he reasoned<br />

can be studied easily.<br />

a). The LOTKA-VOLTERRA model<br />

LOTKA (1925) <strong>and</strong> VOLTERRA (1926) independently proposed equations which<br />

are essentially the same. Both authors' methods are largely analytical (i. e. by mathematical<br />

analysis), though considering to some extent analogies from kinetics. VOLTE-<br />

RRA was thinking <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> whereas it was explicitly stated by LOTKA that his<br />

equations were <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>.<br />

Their first assumption is the geometric increase <strong>of</strong> a population; in the case <strong>of</strong><br />

the prey population, its instantaneous rate <strong>of</strong> increase per individual, i.e. (dx/dt)/x, is<br />

assumed to be constant in the absence <strong>of</strong> predators. Thus we have dx/dt-rx where<br />

r is a coefficient <strong>of</strong> increase (or <strong>of</strong> net birth -= birth minus death due to factors other<br />

than <strong>predation</strong>). Similarly, <strong>for</strong> the predator population, we have dy/dt=-r'y where<br />

-r' is a coefficient <strong>of</strong> decrease in the absence <strong>of</strong> the prey population, as predators<br />

will die if no food is available. However, if the two populations are put together,<br />

the prey population will now diminish as much as it is preyed upon. That is to say,<br />

in the presence <strong>of</strong> predators, the coefficient <strong>of</strong> increase must be equal to the difference<br />

between the net birth in the absence <strong>of</strong> predators <strong>and</strong> the death due to <strong>predation</strong>.<br />

It is assumed secondly that the number preyed upon is proportional to the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> encounters between prey <strong>and</strong> predator individuals, <strong>and</strong> so the rate <strong>of</strong> loss due to<br />

<strong>predation</strong> is equal to the rate at which an individual prey is encountered by predators,<br />

i.e. ax where a is a proportionality factor <strong>of</strong> encounters. Then r, under these circumstances,<br />

should be replaced by the expression (r-ay). Similarly, the predator population<br />

can now increase because food is available, <strong>and</strong> its rate <strong>of</strong> increase per predator<br />

must be equal to the difference between the death rate <strong>and</strong> the birth rate due to the<br />

intake <strong>of</strong> food. So, under the assumption that the birth rate is proportional to the<br />

amount <strong>of</strong> food eaten, which in the above assumption is proportional to the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> encounters with prey, the coefficient <strong>of</strong> the net increase in the predator population<br />

is equal to the expression (-r'+a'x), where a' is a positive constant. Thus we have,<br />

dx/dt = (r- ay) x<br />

=rx-ayx<br />

(4a. la)


22<br />

dy/dt: (-r' +a'x)y<br />

= -r'y+a'xy (4a. lb).<br />

Both LOTKA <strong>and</strong> VOLTERRA, assuming that all the coeffients involved were constant,<br />

solved the above two equations simultaneously, from which emerged the familiar<br />

'LOTKA-VoLTERRA oscillation' in a predator-prey interacting system. Both LOTKA <strong>and</strong><br />

VOLTERRA were aware that the assumption that the coefficients a <strong>and</strong> a' were cons-<br />

tant was too simple, but VOLTERRA justified his assumption by stating that the<br />

frequency <strong>of</strong> encounters between the prey <strong>and</strong> the predators<br />

proportion to the densities.<br />

must be in linear<br />

For LOTKA, however, the justification <strong>of</strong> the constant<br />

coefficients seemed to be purely <strong>for</strong> operational convenience, that is, to solve the<br />

simultaneous equations. LOTKA carefully stated that factor a can, in a broad assump-<br />

tion, be exp<strong>and</strong>ed as power series in x <strong>and</strong> y, i.e.<br />

a:oz+~x +ry + ............<br />

<strong>and</strong> a=oz can be an approximation if ~, r, etc. are sufficiently small <strong>for</strong> values <strong>of</strong><br />

both x <strong>and</strong> y not too large.<br />

Some unreasonable aspects can be pointed out in the LOTKA-VoLTERRA equations<br />

from a theoretical point <strong>of</strong> view.<br />

First, LOTKA stated that the model is primarily<br />

<strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>, although he did not exclude <strong>predation</strong> explicitly. As I have pointed<br />

out in w 3, however, the instantaneous hunting equation <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> would not take<br />

the <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> a differential equation as in eq. (4a. la). There<strong>for</strong>e, LOTKA was mistaken<br />

in this respect. Secondly, because VOLTERRA was thinking <strong>of</strong> a <strong>predation</strong> process,<br />

the way he reasoned to get eq. (4a. lb) is not acceptable. First, it is obviously<br />

incorrect to assume that predators die <strong>of</strong> starvation at the same rate when prey is<br />

available as when no prey is available. In other words, the presence <strong>of</strong> the prey<br />

population causes not only the rise <strong>of</strong> predator population by reproduction but also a<br />

decrease in the death rate, because the predators are not as starved as when no prey<br />

was given. This suggests that the first term in the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq. (4a. lb)<br />

must also involve x, the prey density. It is acceptable, however, to assume that, in<br />

eq.<br />

(4a. la), the coefficient <strong>of</strong> increase <strong>for</strong> the prey population is equal to the<br />

difference between r, the rate <strong>of</strong> net increase in the absence <strong>of</strong> enemies, <strong>and</strong> ay, the<br />

rate <strong>of</strong> death due to <strong>predation</strong> when the predator population is added to the system<br />

concerned. This is because it can be assumed that r is not influenced directly by<br />

the presence <strong>of</strong> predators; its influence, if any, operating only through changes in<br />

the prey numbers due to <strong>predation</strong>.<br />

At this stage, let us rewrite eqs. (4a. la) <strong>and</strong> (4a. lb) in general <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>for</strong> further<br />

discussion, i. e.<br />

dx/dt=g~(x) -f(x, y) (4a. 2a)<br />

dy/dt=g2(x, y) (4a. 2b)<br />

where gl, ge, <strong>and</strong> f are functional symbols. Note that the linear term <strong>for</strong> x in the<br />

second equation is now excluded <strong>for</strong> the reason given above.<br />

The second function, i.e.<br />

f(x, y), on the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq. (4a. 2a) is <strong>of</strong>


course an instantaneous hunting function which has been referred to in w 3 as f(x) Y.<br />

The expression f(x, y) is a general one, <strong>and</strong> f(x) Y more specific. Whichever expression<br />

is convenient will be used in this paper.<br />

The above <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> presentation was in fact used by GAUSE (1934) in his explana-<br />

tion <strong>of</strong> VOLTERRA'S theory, though GAUSE did not explicitly explain why the linear<br />

term <strong>for</strong> x in the second equation was excluded.<br />

The following two points were raised by GAUSE (1934). First, the assumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> a geometric increase in the prey population in the absence <strong>of</strong> predators is not<br />

correct, since the population growth in any animal species, in the absence <strong>of</strong> natural<br />

enemies, would normally follow the logistic law, <strong>and</strong> so a population would not grow<br />

indefinitely. That is to say, function g~(x) in eq.<br />

23<br />

(4a. 2a) would not be a linear<br />

function <strong>of</strong> x but should be an instantaneous <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> the logistic law, <strong>and</strong> this sugges-<br />

tion sounds reasonable. GAUSE'S second point is that in the predator population the<br />

rate <strong>of</strong> increase per predator at different densities <strong>of</strong> prey would not be a linear<br />

function <strong>of</strong> the prey density either ; i.e. (dy/dt)/y is not a linear function <strong>of</strong> x.<br />

This conclusion <strong>of</strong> GAUSE'S was based on an observation by SMIRNOV <strong>and</strong> WLADIMI-<br />

gOW (see GAUSE 1934, p. 139), which showed that the rate <strong>of</strong> increase <strong>of</strong> a parasite<br />

population, Morrnoniella vitripennis, in relation to the density <strong>of</strong> its host, Phorrnia<br />

groenlaudica, was not linear, <strong>and</strong> an exponential function <strong>of</strong> x was more appropriate<br />

<strong>for</strong> gs(x, y). This suggestion, however, is not immediately acceptable <strong>for</strong> reasons<br />

discussed in detail in w 4d.<br />

My last point is concerned with the interpretation <strong>of</strong> t. If g~ is a non-zero positive<br />

function <strong>for</strong> all x's~0, (x <strong>of</strong> course is never negative), it means that progeny are<br />

produced in the prey population, <strong>and</strong> at the same time these progeny are susceptible<br />

to <strong>predation</strong> during t. Similarly, if g2 takes at times a positive value, it means that<br />

the predator population must also produce their progeny which attack the prey during<br />

t. Hence, there is no clear distinction between generations ; generations are continuous<br />

as in protozoa.<br />

<strong>and</strong> (4a. lb)<br />

Under these circumstances, the solution <strong>of</strong> simultaneous eqs. (4a. la)<br />

generates the predator-prey oscillations that were actually shown by<br />

both LOTKA <strong>and</strong> VOLTERRA.<br />

However, generations can be discrete, as in many insect species, in which case<br />

the progeny <strong>of</strong> prey produced during the time vulnerable to <strong>predation</strong> in the present<br />

generation may be attacked only in the following generation. Also, the progeny <strong>of</strong><br />

predators produced in the present generation may not attack the prey in this generation.<br />

The populations in the present generation are then only subject to decrease during t<br />

(within the generation), in which case both functions g~ <strong>and</strong> g2 will never become<br />

positive. Under these circumstances, a solution <strong>of</strong> the two simultaneous equations<br />

gives changes in numbers in both populations <strong>of</strong> the present generation, only during<br />

the period <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> within the generation (see w 4b). Hence, in this case, separate<br />

equations are required to compute the number <strong>of</strong> progeny to be produced to <strong>for</strong>m<br />

the next generation by the survivors <strong>of</strong> each population in the previous generation (s).


24<br />

This problem will not be discussed any further in this paper.<br />

The solution <strong>of</strong> simultaneous eqs. (4a. la) <strong>and</strong> (4a. lb) under the assumption <strong>of</strong> discrete<br />

generations was not considered by the original authors. The solution, as I will<br />

show in the next section, is in fact possible <strong>and</strong> is related to the NICHOLSON-BAILEY<br />

model.<br />

b).<br />

The NICHOLSON-BAILEY model<br />

This model is known as the 'Competition model'. It is, primarily, constructed <strong>for</strong><br />

the purpose <strong>of</strong> demonstrating NICHOLSON'S hypothesis that animal populations are in<br />

the state <strong>of</strong> balance fluctuating around a steady density <strong>of</strong> each species concerned,<br />

<strong>and</strong> that this steady density (or steady state) is brought about by competition among<br />

the members <strong>of</strong> the parasite species (NICHOLSON 1933). NICHOLSON with the collabo-<br />

ration <strong>of</strong> a mathematician, BAILEY (NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY 1935), intended to con-<br />

struct a model on the assumption <strong>of</strong> a very simple, idealized situation, concerning a<br />

theoretical relationship in densities between host <strong>and</strong> parasite species. By altering<br />

conditions in this simple model, they drew numerous conclusions about the mode <strong>of</strong><br />

existence <strong>of</strong> steady states.<br />

Whether or not NICHOLSON'S basic philosophy that animal populations are in the<br />

state <strong>of</strong> balance is a useful one, is not <strong>of</strong> concern here.<br />

It is more important to<br />

determine whether the basic premises in the NICHOLSON-BAILEY theory can produce<br />

a reasonable model <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>, so that a comparison between the model <strong>and</strong><br />

observation can provide any useful direction.<br />

original authors.<br />

The following is the reasoning by the<br />

Let x0 be the number <strong>of</strong> objects (hosts) originally present in a unit area, <strong>and</strong> let<br />

x be the number left undiscovered after an area s has been traversed (by all parasites<br />

concerned). Then the number <strong>of</strong> previously undiscovered objects discovered in a<br />

fraction <strong>of</strong> area traversed, i.e. ds, is xds. This must be equal to the decrease, -dx,<br />

<strong>of</strong> the number <strong>of</strong> undiscovered objects per unit area, i.e.<br />

-dx--xds (4b. 1),<br />

<strong>and</strong> since x=xo when s=0, integrating eq. (4b. 1) <strong>for</strong> the range (0, s), <strong>and</strong> hence<br />

(x0, x), we obtain<br />

X ~Xoe-*<br />

from which we have<br />

z/xo: 1- e-' (4b. 2)<br />

where z=xo-x. Factor s is called by the authors the 'area traversed', which is the<br />

area that is searched effectively by all parasites involved <strong>and</strong> includes possible overlaps.<br />

In passing, the average area traversed by each individual parasite is called the 'area <strong>of</strong><br />

discovery'. As against the area traversed, the net total area searched by all parasites<br />

concerned is called the 'area covered', which excludes areas already searched. Thus,<br />

the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq.<br />

(4b. 2) shows that the proportion <strong>of</strong> the 'area covered'<br />

increases only asymptotically as the 'area traversed' increases, <strong>and</strong> that there<strong>for</strong>e the


number <strong>of</strong> hosts attacked in terms <strong>of</strong> a proportion <strong>of</strong> the initial number present per<br />

unit area, i.e. Z/Xo, increases only asymptotically. Hence, the equation shows a simple<br />

example <strong>of</strong> the law <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns.<br />

25<br />

As it is important to underst<strong>and</strong> the<br />

geometric meaning <strong>of</strong> the above equation in order to see if the assumptions involved<br />

are reasonable, an illustration will be given.<br />

Be<strong>for</strong>e doing so, however, it should be pointed out that NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY<br />

failed to recognize the distinction between the <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> processes.<br />

For the reason already given in w 3, the differential equation as in eq. (4b. 1) is a<br />

starting point <strong>of</strong> deduction in the <strong>predation</strong> process, whereas NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY<br />

were aiming at constructing a <strong>parasitism</strong> model. Since I am examining the reasoning<br />

<strong>of</strong> NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY, their differential equation as a means <strong>of</strong> deduction has to<br />

be taken seriously. Since their reasoning is based on this differential equation, it is<br />

unreasonable to use the word 'parasite', <strong>and</strong> hence, <strong>for</strong> the remaining part <strong>of</strong> this<br />

section, I shall use the word 'predator' instead.<br />

Although the NICHOLSON-BAILEY<br />

equation can be regarded as one <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> because, as pointed out in w 3, an<br />

equation <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong> can take the same <strong>for</strong>m as one <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> under a particular<br />

assumption, the maintenance <strong>of</strong> consistency between terminology <strong>and</strong> reasoning is<br />

more important here. The case in which the NICHOLSON-BAILEY equation is considered<br />

to be a <strong>parasitism</strong> model will be discussed in w 4g.<br />

Suppose a number <strong>of</strong> prey individuals are scattered at r<strong>and</strong>om over a plane where<br />

one predator searches with an average speed V, completely independently <strong>of</strong> the<br />

distribution <strong>of</strong> the prey individuals, from point A to B (see Fig. 4). The path <strong>of</strong> the<br />

predator between A <strong>and</strong> B is assumed to be rectilinear, <strong>and</strong> all the prey individuals<br />

in the plane remain stationary. (It can be shown that an irregular path may be as-<br />

sumed without influencing the conclusion, or that there is no need to assume a stationary<br />

distribution <strong>of</strong> prey individuals.) As in Fig. 4a, each prey individual has an area around<br />

it within, <strong>and</strong> only within, which the predator can recognize the prey. To simplify<br />

[" 9<br />

9 .<br />

(a)<br />

(b)<br />

Fig. 4. A geometric interpretation <strong>of</strong> the NICHOLSON-BAILEY (1935) model.<br />

For explanation see text.


26<br />

the situation again, though it is not quite necessary, the area around each prey is<br />

assumed to be a circle <strong>of</strong> radius R. Then, as the predator moves from A to B, it<br />

sees those prey individuals with hatched circles (Fig. 4a) ;or if, alternatively, the<br />

predator, rather than the prey, is given a circle <strong>of</strong> radius R as in Fig. 4b, then those<br />

prey within the hatched belt along the predator's path will be recognized.<br />

To calculate the number <strong>of</strong> prey found by the predator along its path <strong>of</strong> search,<br />

Fig. 4b will be used. First, if the predator can see a prey anywhere in the circle,<br />

the size <strong>of</strong> the effective area in which prey are found between A <strong>and</strong> B must be the<br />

size <strong>of</strong> the hatched area plus the circle at A. If, however, the distance between A<br />

<strong>and</strong> B is sufficiently large as compared with radius R, the area covered with the<br />

circle around A can be neglected as compared with the size <strong>of</strong> the hatched area.<br />

Second, <strong>and</strong> alternatively, if the path between A <strong>and</strong> B is considered to be a given<br />

fraction <strong>of</strong> a path <strong>of</strong> search, point A is the last point reached in the preceding section<br />

<strong>of</strong> search, <strong>and</strong> so the circle at A is the area already searched. Thus, it is sufficient<br />

to know the size <strong>of</strong> the hatched area in order to calculate the number <strong>of</strong> prey found<br />

between A <strong>and</strong> B. The size <strong>of</strong> the hatched area is clearly the product <strong>of</strong> the width<br />

2R <strong>and</strong> the length Vt, so that the number <strong>of</strong> prey found in the area is 2RVXt, where<br />

X is the density <strong>of</strong> prey fixed during t in each observation.<br />

If there are Y predator individuals searching at the same time, their paths being<br />

entirely independent <strong>of</strong> each other, the total number <strong>of</strong> prey found by these Y predators<br />

<strong>for</strong> time t, i. e. n, will be<br />

n-:2RVXYt (4b. 3).<br />

Equation (4b. 3) is clearly equivalent to eq. (3.1). That is, expression 2RVX is the<br />

instantaneous function f(X) in eq. (3.1), i.e.<br />

f(x) :2 RVX.<br />

Consequently, if R <strong>and</strong> V are assumed to be independent <strong>of</strong> X, i.e. changes or variation<br />

in both R <strong>and</strong> V are independent <strong>of</strong> X, we can replace the complex factor 2RV<br />

by a single factor, say, a, which can conveniently be treated as a constant. Thus we<br />

have in this model<br />

f(X) -aX (4b. 4)<br />

or<br />

n =aXYt. (4b. 5).<br />

Clearly, the complex factor aYt(=-2RVYt) is the area traversed by all the predators<br />

<strong>for</strong> time t, <strong>and</strong> is there<strong>for</strong>e equal to the NICHOLSON-BAILEY factor s. Also, if t is the<br />

whole length <strong>of</strong> time that each predator spends hunting in the generation concerned,<br />

the expression at is the whole area effectively searched by each individual predator<br />

hunting <strong>for</strong> the generation. So, this factor at is the 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery' <strong>and</strong> is assumed<br />

in NICHOLSON-BAILEY'S argument to be constant <strong>for</strong> a given species. (It should be<br />

mentioned here that NICHOLSON-BAILEY did not find any reason to separate <strong>parasitism</strong><br />

from <strong>predation</strong>, <strong>and</strong> so the above factor was in fact called the area <strong>of</strong> discovery <strong>of</strong><br />

a parasite species <strong>for</strong> its life time which usually ends at the end <strong>of</strong> a generation.)


Now, if the prey density in the present model is subject to decrease because <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>predation</strong>, X should be replaced by variable x. Then eq. (4b. 4) becomes .f(x)=ax,<br />

which is identical to eq. (3.6) in every respect. Thus in conclusion we have eq. (3.8)<br />

which is identical to eq. (4b. 2). The above discussion will be summarized below.<br />

If the predator's paths are independent <strong>of</strong> each other as well as <strong>of</strong> the distribution<br />

<strong>of</strong> prey individuals, <strong>and</strong> also if the paths are deflected every now <strong>and</strong> then, predators<br />

will sooner or later cross those paths already traversed by themselves or by others,<br />

where the probability <strong>of</strong> finding still-undiscovered prey will be effectively nil, provided<br />

that all the prey discovered are eaten. (If a proportion <strong>of</strong> prey in the area traversed<br />

is not discovered, the predator's effectiveness is reduced by lessening the effective<br />

area <strong>of</strong> discovery by that proportion. If, however, this proportion is independent <strong>of</strong><br />

prey density, it does not influence the end conclusion.) Now, the paths intersect each<br />

other more frequently as either the time spent hunting by each predator or the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> predators hunting increases, <strong>and</strong> so the efficiency <strong>of</strong> finding prey drops<br />

progressively.<br />

This is the geometric meaning <strong>of</strong> 'competition' in NICHOLSON'S concept <strong>and</strong> is, as<br />

already mentioned, synonymous with the 'law <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns'. The effect <strong>of</strong><br />

diminishing returns still exists even when only an individual predator is hunting.<br />

The effect can still be called 'competition' since the predator is competing with itself,<br />

so to speak. In this respect, the NICHOLSONIAN competition should be distinguished<br />

from competition caused by social interference.<br />

As already mentioned, the NICHOLSON-BAILEY model assumes animals with discrete<br />

generations. Let us introduce this condition into the LOTKA-VOLTERRA eqs. (4a. la)<br />

<strong>and</strong> (4a. lb). As generations are discrete, no birth will take place during t in both<br />

populations; the coefficient <strong>of</strong> increase <strong>for</strong> the prey species will never exceed zero,<br />

i.e. r


28<br />

since<br />

z =Xo (1 - e-ay~<br />

lira (1 - e-,'t)/r': t.<br />

r~-~O<br />

Clearly, y0 corresponds to my previous notation Y, <strong>and</strong> so we obtain the NICHOLSON-<br />

BAILEY eq. (3. 8).<br />

Now it is very clear that the NICHOLSON-BAILEY model is only a special case <strong>of</strong><br />

the new solution <strong>of</strong> the LOTKA-VOLTERRA model, i.e. eq. (4b. 6), in which r, r', <strong>and</strong><br />

a' are all zero. The above conclusion is contradictory to a statement by NICHOLSON<br />

<strong>and</strong> BAILEY (1935, second paragraph, p. 551) :<br />

"... , we have not been able to derive our theory from LOTKA'S fundamental<br />

equations. Competition does not appear explicitly in any <strong>of</strong> his equations, <strong>and</strong> few,<br />

if any, indicate the existence <strong>of</strong> this factor."<br />

It should be mentoned that NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY appeared to refer to 'LOTKA'S<br />

fundamental equations' as those in chapter VI <strong>of</strong> LOTKA'S book, but that those which<br />

are relevant to the NICHOLSON-BAILEY treatise, i.e. eqs.<br />

(4a. la) <strong>and</strong> (4a. lb) in the<br />

present paper, appear in chapter VIII. However, LOTKA called the equations in chapter<br />

VIII a 'special case' <strong>and</strong> those in chapter VI, a 'general case'. Since a general case<br />

involves a special case, the NICHOLSON-BAILEY criticism quoted above must be meant<br />

to apply also to eqs. (4a. la) <strong>and</strong> (4a. lb), <strong>and</strong> such a criticism cannot be taken seriously.<br />

Contrary to the NICHOLSON-BAILEY view, the LOTKA-VOLTERRA equations are<br />

<strong>comparative</strong>ly more general <strong>and</strong> detailed than the NICHOLSON-BAILEY one. Obviously,<br />

the only necessary condition which makes the LOTKA-VOLTERRA equations match the<br />

condition <strong>of</strong> discrete generations is that a'-0.<br />

And r <strong>and</strong> r' are, unlike the simpler<br />

assumption by NICHOLSON-BAILEY, not generally zero. That is to say, the whole <strong>of</strong><br />

the NICHOLSON-BAILEY model is covered by the LOTKA-VOLTERRA one, <strong>and</strong> so we<br />

do not need the <strong>for</strong>mer. However, some specific assumptions tentatively adopted by<br />

LOTKA are not satisfactory from an ecologist's point <strong>of</strong> view. What is needed is the<br />

generalized LOTKA-VOLTERRA eqs. (4a. 2a) <strong>and</strong> (4a. 2b), which have both necessary <strong>and</strong><br />

sufficient conditions <strong>for</strong> computation <strong>of</strong> the final densities <strong>of</strong> both populations, if<br />

appropriate functions <strong>for</strong> f, gl, <strong>and</strong> gz are found. As animals with discrete generations<br />

are assumed here, we need separate equations to evaluate the initial densities in the<br />

following generation. If, however, generations are not discrete, eqs. (4a. 2a) <strong>and</strong> (4a. 2b)<br />

are sufficiently comprehensive.<br />

Although TINBERGEN <strong>and</strong> KLOMP (1960) introduced into the NICHOLSON-BAILEY<br />

model the effect <strong>of</strong> mortality in both populations (the authors considered <strong>parasitism</strong><br />

rather than <strong>predation</strong> as they did not think that a distinction was needed), it was<br />

assumed that their mortality factors acted only after the period <strong>of</strong> attack had ended,<br />

but not during the attack. This was perhaps because the arithmetic method used by<br />

TINBERGEN <strong>and</strong> KLOMP was not quite capable <strong>of</strong> incorporating the effect <strong>of</strong> mortality<br />

during the attack period. An analysis <strong>of</strong> the process in which death takes place during


29<br />

the attack period is now possible with the aid <strong>of</strong> the generalized LOTKA-VOLTERRA<br />

eqs. (4a. 2a) <strong>and</strong> (4a. 2b).<br />

The final point <strong>of</strong> investigation in this section will be concerned with the real<br />

meaning <strong>of</strong> the 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery' in the NICHOLSON-BAILEY terminology, i.e. at, or<br />

2RVt in my notation.<br />

In the dynamics <strong>of</strong> gas molecules, the movement <strong>of</strong> a molecule can be regarded<br />

as ideally haphazard <strong>and</strong> independent <strong>of</strong> other molecules be<strong>for</strong>e it collides with another.<br />

Then the number <strong>of</strong> collisions that will occur during time interval At will be<br />

2RVxAt in which R is the effective radius, V the average speed <strong>of</strong> each molecule,<br />

<strong>and</strong> x the population density <strong>of</strong> the molecules. Clearly, the NICHOLSON-BAILEY model,<br />

as well as the second term in LOTKA-VOLTERRA eq. (4a. la), is an analogy to the<br />

'law <strong>of</strong> mass-action' in physical chemistry. (This was perhaps the reason by which<br />

VOLTERRA justified his assumption <strong>of</strong> the linear relationship between the frequency<br />

<strong>of</strong> encounters <strong>and</strong> the densities <strong>of</strong> prey <strong>and</strong> predator species.) The competition equation<br />

as expressed in eq. (3.8) is in fact identical to what is called in chemistry<br />

the 'velocity equation <strong>for</strong> a unimolecular reaction'.<br />

It is not difficult to visualize what the effective radius <strong>of</strong> a gas molecule is,<br />

since it is the radius in which an effective contact with another molecule is made so<br />

that a reaction takes place. However, what is the effective radius <strong>for</strong> a predator ?<br />

NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY assumed that this was the radius within which a predator<br />

could recognize the prey. However, <strong>for</strong> the competition equation to be an exact analogy<br />

to the velocity equation, as the <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> the NICHOLSON-BAILEY equation implies, the<br />

path <strong>of</strong> a predator (a molecule) has to be completely independent <strong>of</strong> the position <strong>of</strong><br />

the prey (other molecules) immediately be<strong>for</strong>e the collision. In other words, the<br />

predator's recognition <strong>of</strong> a prey has to be made, strictly speaking, by bodily contact.<br />

If, however, recognition was made well away from the prey, the predator would have<br />

to approach it, <strong>and</strong> this immediately means a digression from a free path. The problem<br />

now is, how much deviation from the competition equation would be expected by<br />

the digression from a free path. This degression can be serious under certain circumstances<br />

as will be discussed in w 4e.<br />

Also, if it is assumed that recognition occurs at some distance from the prey,<br />

the predator may see more than one prey individual at a time. Unless the predator<br />

can catch the prey in a sweeping action, each prey must be h<strong>and</strong>led individually.<br />

Under these circumstances, recognition will not result in immediate capture. In other<br />

words, the number <strong>of</strong> prey that a predator can capture would not increase as fast as<br />

the number <strong>of</strong> recognitions increases with increasing density <strong>of</strong> prey population.<br />

This problem will be discussed in ~ 4d.<br />

The last point, which is more important than any other, is the effect <strong>of</strong> the time<br />

spent catching, killing, digesting, etc., <strong>for</strong> each victim. In the analogy <strong>of</strong> unimolecular<br />

reaction, there is no need to think about the time involved in actions taking place<br />

after a collision is made since each molecule ceases to capture more. In the <strong>predation</strong>


30<br />

<strong>models</strong>, each predator continues to catch a number <strong>of</strong> prey during the period concerned.<br />

While it is h<strong>and</strong>ling the victim, the predator temporarily stops searching, <strong>and</strong> this<br />

h<strong>and</strong>ling time should be separated from effective searching time. No doubt, as the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> captures increases within a given period, the smaller is the proportion <strong>of</strong><br />

the period available <strong>for</strong> searching, <strong>and</strong> hence the number <strong>of</strong> captures increases only<br />

asymptotically as the prey density increases (<strong>for</strong> details see w 4c).<br />

It is clear that because <strong>of</strong> their neglect <strong>of</strong> some unavoidable physical properties<br />

the NICHOLSON-BAILEY concept <strong>of</strong> the 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery' is quite unsatisfactory as a<br />

basis <strong>of</strong> calculating the number <strong>of</strong> captures. The term may be used as one denoting<br />

the efficiency <strong>of</strong> a predator's catching activity now <strong>for</strong> a historical reason, but if so it<br />

should be borne in mind that the term loses its geometric implication <strong>and</strong> becomes<br />

only metaphorical.<br />

The usage <strong>of</strong> the term 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery', widely seen in the literature <strong>of</strong> popu-<br />

lation dynamics, is in fact <strong>of</strong> this metaphorical nature, because it is not an 'area'<br />

measurable in physical dimensions. It is a value to be calculated from eq. (3. 7),<br />

i.e. in the NICHOLSON-BAILEY model <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong>,<br />

at= 1 in Xo (4b. 7)<br />

X0 -- z<br />

(note that X=Xo-Z), <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong> a special case <strong>of</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>, i.e. in eq. (3. 23),<br />

at =+In X (4b. 8).<br />

X-z<br />

If we accept this metaphorical implication <strong>of</strong> the term, <strong>for</strong> historical reasons,<br />

<strong>and</strong> redefine it as a calculated value in the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eqs. (4b. 7) or (4b. 8), the<br />

concept <strong>of</strong> 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery' becomes one way <strong>of</strong> expressing the hunting efficiency<br />

(though not necessarily a useful one: see the appendix to w 4i), completely emanci-<br />

pated from its original implication as a geometric measure <strong>of</strong> the effective area <strong>of</strong><br />

recognition (or catching) as in Fig. 4. Naturally, the value under the logarithmic<br />

sign in eqs. (4b. 7) <strong>and</strong> (4b. 8) involves various factors which are <strong>of</strong> no geometric<br />

significance, e.g. the time spent in activities other than searching, mortality in both<br />

hunting <strong>and</strong> hunted species, <strong>and</strong> social interactions among the hunters.<br />

In order to make a clear distinction between the two concepts : (1) 'the area <strong>of</strong><br />

discovery' as a measure <strong>of</strong> hunting efficiency, defined by the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eqs.<br />

(4b. 7) <strong>and</strong> (4b. 8), <strong>and</strong> (2) 'the effective area <strong>of</strong> recognition' as truly a geometric measure<br />

in <strong>models</strong> appearing in this paper, I shall use, throughout this paper, a symbol /~ <strong>for</strong><br />

the <strong>for</strong>mer measure as distinguished from a plain symbol a <strong>for</strong> the latter. Thus, the<br />

/~ <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong> is :<br />

<strong>and</strong> the /~ <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> is :<br />

i~=1 In Xo (4b. 9),<br />

X0 --Z<br />

i~ =~ln X (4b. 10).<br />

. [ X-z


31<br />

In this scheme, the NICHOLSON-BAILEY model is a particular case in which ii=-at<br />

(constant). However, as will be shown in later sections (also summarized in the<br />

appendix to w 4i), the value /~ cannot normally be constant but a function (<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

a decreasing function) <strong>of</strong> both predator <strong>and</strong> prey (or parasite <strong>and</strong> host) densities.<br />

It should be recalled again here that the NICHOLSON-BAILEY model, although in<br />

their paper used extensively as a model <strong>of</strong> para~<br />

is essentially a <strong>predation</strong> model,<br />

a special case <strong>of</strong> the LOTKA-VOLTERRA model. For the reason given in w 3, it turns<br />

out to be <strong>of</strong> the same <strong>for</strong>m as a parasite model only because the instantaneous hunting<br />

function is assumed to be linear. This assumption is no longer reasonable, however.<br />

c). HOLLING'S disc equation<br />

HOLLING (1959b) per<strong>for</strong>med the following simulation experiment.<br />

A number <strong>of</strong><br />

cardboard discs were placed on a table in a casual way. A blind-folded subject tapped<br />

the table with a finger to discover discs, again in a casual manner. When a disc was<br />

found, it was picked up <strong>and</strong> carried to a corner <strong>of</strong> the table, then a new series <strong>of</strong><br />

taps was per<strong>for</strong>med to find another disc, <strong>and</strong> so on. After a series <strong>of</strong> experiments at<br />

various disc densities, the number <strong>of</strong> discs h<strong>and</strong>led in a given time was plotted against<br />

the density <strong>of</strong> the discs. The curve thus obtained looked like that in Fig. 1, i.e. the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> discs taken increased as the disc density increased but gradually leveled<br />

<strong>of</strong>f.<br />

HOLLING'S explanation <strong>for</strong> this trend was as follows. It was assumed that the<br />

probability <strong>of</strong> finding a disc with a tap was proportional to the density <strong>of</strong> the discs.<br />

Thus, letting a be the proportionality factor, which HOLLING called the 'instantaneous<br />

rate <strong>of</strong> discovery', <strong>and</strong> t, be the time spent tapping, the number <strong>of</strong> discs touched<br />

(i.e. n) <strong>for</strong> t, would be<br />

n=aXt, (4c. 1)<br />

where X is the density <strong>of</strong> the discs. This evaluation is reasonable provided that the<br />

disc density is kept constant during each experiment ; thus capital letter X is used<br />

above. HOLLING, however, did not explicitly mention that X was kept constant to<br />

meet this condition.<br />

Now if an average time h was spent h<strong>and</strong>ling a disc each time one was found,<br />

the total time spent h<strong>and</strong>ling n discs must be hn. Thus the total hunting time t (i. e.<br />

total time tapping+total time h<strong>and</strong>ling) must be<br />

t=t,+hn (4c. 2).<br />

Eliminating t~ from eqs. (4c. 1) <strong>and</strong> (4c. 2) we have<br />

n =aXt/(1 +ahX) (4c. 3).<br />

This is HOLLING'S disc equation <strong>and</strong> describes his experiments very well. HOLLING<br />

showed that this equation also fitted observed relationships in experiments with<br />

various living predator <strong>and</strong> parasite species very well. Equation (4c. 3) clearly shows<br />

that, because <strong>of</strong> the involvement <strong>of</strong> factor h, the number <strong>of</strong> prey captured by a<br />

predator <strong>for</strong> a given time is limited, <strong>and</strong> under no circumstances can exceed l/h, since


32<br />

lim n/t=l/h.<br />

X~co<br />

(It should be mentioned in passing, however, that there is a logical jump from the<br />

assumption <strong>of</strong> the disc model to the above conclusion (see w 4d).)<br />

Although this model is excellent to demonstrate the effect <strong>of</strong> the h<strong>and</strong>ling time<br />

upon the number <strong>of</strong> captures, the application <strong>of</strong> this model to various observations<br />

with actual animals, by HOLLING himself <strong>and</strong> by others, is open to criticism. Let us<br />

examine the disc experiment more critically below.<br />

First, the assumption that the probability <strong>of</strong> finding a disc is proportional to the<br />

density <strong>of</strong> discs is justified only when the discs do not overlap <strong>and</strong> only <strong>for</strong> as long<br />

as the disc density is kept constant. Clearly, the mathematical probability <strong>of</strong> touching<br />

a disc at a tap must, under these circumstances, be equal to the proportion <strong>of</strong> the<br />

total area covered with the discs to the area <strong>of</strong> the table, provided that every part<br />

<strong>of</strong> the table has an equal probability <strong>of</strong> being tapped. Hence, letting R, S, <strong>and</strong> X be<br />

the radius <strong>of</strong> each disc, the size <strong>of</strong> the table, <strong>and</strong> the density <strong>of</strong> discs (fixed during<br />

t in each set <strong>of</strong> experiment), respectively, the probability <strong>of</strong> discovery, P, at each tap<br />

will be P=1rR~SX/S-TrR2X. As the frequency with which discs are touched (i. e. n)<br />

<strong>for</strong> tapping time to must be the product <strong>of</strong> P, t~, <strong>and</strong> the frequency <strong>of</strong> tapping per<br />

unit time (i. e. k), we have<br />

Comparing eq.<br />

n =Pkts<br />

= ~R~Xkts (4c. 4).<br />

(4c. 4) with eq. (4c. 1), we find that HOLLING'S factor a, his instanta-<br />

neous rate <strong>of</strong> discovery, is in fact ~R2k. As zc, R, <strong>and</strong> k can all be assumed to be<br />

constant, factor a can also be constant.<br />

Now, if eq. (4c. 1) is compared with eq. (4b. 5), it is clear that the <strong>for</strong>mer is a<br />

special case <strong>of</strong> the latter; that is, t in eq.<br />

(4b. 5) is replaced by t~, <strong>and</strong> Y is set equal<br />

to 1. Hence, HOLLING'S disc equation also applies to the NICHOLSON-BAILEY geometric<br />

model as in Fig. 4. This means that HOLLING'S model seems reasonable if, <strong>and</strong><br />

perhaps only if, the predator is either a sweep-feeder or tap-feeder (such as plankton-<br />

feeders or shore birds probing their beaks into the s<strong>and</strong>), but in either case discovery<br />

<strong>of</strong> prey should be made by bodily contact. This implies that the size <strong>of</strong> the disc is<br />

either the size <strong>of</strong> the body <strong>of</strong> the prey in the case <strong>of</strong> a tap-feeder, or the ambit <strong>of</strong><br />

the catching apparatus in the case <strong>of</strong> a sweep-feeder. Although both NICHOLSON-BAILEY<br />

<strong>and</strong> HOLLING assumed that the factor s or a involves the distance at which the<br />

predator perceives a prey (HOLLING 1961), the distance should be restricted, <strong>for</strong> the<br />

reason raised above, only to a very limited area around the prey or the predator. If<br />

this limitation is removed, the size <strong>of</strong> the disc should, in the case <strong>of</strong> the tap-feeder,<br />

set the upper limit <strong>of</strong> the disc density, because the probability <strong>of</strong> discovery is zcR2X,<br />

which should not exceed unity. This is somewhat artificial, <strong>and</strong> the problem will be<br />

discussed in w 4d <strong>and</strong> e.<br />

In HOLLING'S disc eq. (4c. 3), the number <strong>of</strong> predators searching does not explicitly


33<br />

appear. This is perhaps because HOLLING used only one finger <strong>and</strong> also because n is<br />

the number <strong>of</strong> discs removed per table. If, however, there are two fingers tapping<br />

independently, the frequency <strong>of</strong> tapping, k in eq. (4c. 4), will be doubled provided<br />

that there is no interference. In general, if there are Y fingers tapping per unit<br />

area <strong>of</strong> the table we have, in place <strong>of</strong> eq. (4c. 1),<br />

n =aXYG (4c. 5)<br />

in which n is the number <strong>of</strong> discs removed per unit area rather than per table.<br />

This generalization would not influence eq. (4c. 2), <strong>and</strong> so, eliminating t~, we get<br />

n = aXYt/(1 + ahX) (4c. 6).<br />

As the disc density has been fixed in the above model situation, eq. (4c. 6) is obviouslY<br />

an instantaneous equation comparable to eq. (3.1), in which<br />

f(X) =aX/ (l +ahX) (4c. 7).<br />

Hence the overall hunting equation <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong>, i.e. eq. (3.13), will be evaluated<br />

by integrating<br />

dx/dt = -ax Y/ (1 + ahx) (4c. 8).<br />

Thus we have<br />

z =x0 (1 - e -~(rt-7~)) (4c. 9).<br />

Equation (4c. 9) is an overall <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> HOLLINC'S disc equation, taking account <strong>of</strong> the<br />

effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns, <strong>and</strong> is thus comparable with the LOTKA-VOLTERRA <strong>and</strong><br />

the NICHOLSON-BAILEY equations. It is at once clear that the equation is a generalized<br />

NICHOLSON-BAILEY model, or that the latter is a special case <strong>of</strong> the <strong>for</strong>mer in which<br />

factor h-0 (cf. eq. (3.8)). Equation (4c. 9) represents a surface in a Z-Xo-Yt coordinate<br />

system, the shape <strong>of</strong> which is very much like that in Fig. 3a. A cross-section<br />

parallel to the z-Yt plane shows the effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns similar to the<br />

cross-section in the NmHOLSON-BAILEY competition surface (Fig. 2). The shape <strong>of</strong><br />

a cross-section parallel to the Z-Xo plane in HOLLING'S surface is, however, curvilinear,<br />

unlike the NICHOLSON-BAILEY one which is rectilinear (see Fig. 2a). (It is difficult to<br />

make the variable z in eq. (4c. 9) perfectly dependent : nevertheless the surface can<br />

be drawn by assuming that Xo is the dependent variable <strong>and</strong> z <strong>and</strong> Yt independent<br />

ones.)<br />

If the disc model is applied to <strong>parasitism</strong> <strong>of</strong> the indiscriminate type, the righth<strong>and</strong><br />

side <strong>of</strong> eq. (4c. 7) should be substituted <strong>for</strong> f(x) in eq. (3. 22). Hence, if the<br />

fingers tap, <strong>for</strong> example, entirely at r<strong>and</strong>om, the function r will be the zero-term <strong>of</strong><br />

a POISSON series, <strong>and</strong> so we have<br />

z=X(1-e -a~/(l+ahz~) (4c. 10).<br />

This also generates a surface similar to that in Fig. 3a.<br />

My intention in generalizing HOLLING'S disc equation is in fact to point out three<br />

mistakes commonly seen in the scattered publications in which the original disc equation<br />

was applied directly to observed data (see e.g. HOLLING 1959). First, the<br />

density <strong>of</strong> the predators is not always 1. If eq. (4c. 3) is fitted to observed data in<br />

which Yr the estimates <strong>of</strong> the factor a <strong>and</strong> h in the equation inevitably involve


34<br />

the effect <strong>of</strong> Y. In order to show the point, let us assume that a <strong>and</strong> h in eq. (4c. 6)<br />

are the true estimates <strong>of</strong> the factors originally defined, whereas those in eq. (4c. 3)<br />

are superficial <strong>and</strong> are written a' <strong>and</strong> h' respectively. Then the fit <strong>of</strong> eq. (4c. 3) to<br />

data, which should be correctly fitted by eq. (4c. 6), means that<br />

a'Xt/ (1 + a'h'X) = aXYt/ (1 + ahX)<br />

<strong>and</strong> transposing we get<br />

h'=h/Y+ (a'-aY)/aa'XY<br />

or<br />

a'=aY/ (l +aX(h- h'Y) ).<br />

Thus, estimates a' <strong>and</strong> h' not only change as the predator density changes but also<br />

they are a decreasing function <strong>of</strong> the prey density, unless a'=aY <strong>and</strong> h'=h/Y. Fur-<br />

ther, they are not independent <strong>of</strong> the units in which the densities <strong>of</strong> both populations<br />

are measured. Hence, such estimates have no universal value.<br />

Secondly, the depletion <strong>of</strong> prey or, in the case <strong>of</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>, super<strong>parasitism</strong>,<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten occurred in the observations. If eq. (4c. 3) is applied to such data, it is the<br />

same as fitting the instantaneous equation to one <strong>of</strong> the cross-sections parallel to the<br />

Z-Xo plane <strong>of</strong> the surface generated by eq. (4c. 9) in the case <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong>, or eq.<br />

(4c. 10) in the case <strong>of</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>. Obviously, the curve <strong>of</strong> a cross-section parallel to<br />

the Z-Xo plane, as in Fig. 3a, changes as Y or t changes, <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e the estimates<br />

<strong>for</strong> factors a <strong>and</strong> h should change accordingly. Again such estimates have no univer-<br />

sal value.<br />

The third point is concerned with a precaution that should be taken when prey<br />

density is changed by changing the size <strong>of</strong> the experimental universe, a method <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

adopted to obtain an extremely high prey density with relatively few individuals (e. g.<br />

MORRIS 1963; HAYNES <strong>and</strong> SISOJEVIC 1966).<br />

If this is done, however, it should<br />

be noticed that the predator density changes too. To assess z in this method, we<br />

measure a cross-section <strong>of</strong> the surface which goes diagonally across the xo-Yt plane.<br />

As far as I know, all the published literature in which HOLLING'S disc equation<br />

is applied, involves at least one <strong>of</strong> the above three misapplications. Yet, the goodness<br />

<strong>of</strong> fit is, in many cases, remarkably high. This is because the equation involves two<br />

factors that are normally estimated from the observed relationships between z <strong>and</strong><br />

x0. That is to say, the nature <strong>of</strong> the estimation ensures that the resultant curve fits<br />

the observation well. Hence, a good fit does not constitute verification <strong>of</strong> the theory.<br />

In my opinion, the significance <strong>of</strong> HOLLING'S simulation experiment with discs<br />

<strong>and</strong> tapping is to show the importance <strong>of</strong> the factor h, <strong>and</strong> this simple model is<br />

sufficient to show that "the area <strong>of</strong> discovery", i.e. /i, cannot be independent <strong>of</strong> prey<br />

or host density, as clearly deduced from eqs. (4c. 9) or (4c. 10). However, an application<br />

<strong>of</strong> the original model as in eq. (4c. 3) to a situation in which the effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing<br />

returns is obviously involved, is incorrect.


35<br />

d).<br />

The IVLEV-GAusE equation<br />

IVLEV (1955), in his <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> the feeding ecology <strong>of</strong> fish, proposed an equation<br />

<strong>and</strong> used it rather extensively <strong>for</strong> the analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> processes. One <strong>of</strong> IVLEV'S<br />

fundamental ideas which led him to the <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> feeding ecology appears to have<br />

emerged from his dissatisfaction with one <strong>of</strong> VOLTERRA'S assumptions that the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> prey taken by predators is a linear function <strong>of</strong> the prey density.<br />

his book (pp. 20-21, English edition, 1961):<br />

IVLEV wrote in<br />

"... , according to VOLTERRA'S position, in the case <strong>of</strong> an unlimited increase in<br />

the concentration <strong>of</strong> the food material, there must also be an unlimited increase in<br />

the amount <strong>of</strong> the food taken. This 'unlimited' increase is a biological absurdity,<br />

since each individual is only capable <strong>of</strong> consuming a strictly limited quantity <strong>of</strong><br />

food in each unit time."<br />

This criticism led IVLEV to propose a new hunting equation in the following quota-<br />

tion:<br />

"... the actual ration <strong>of</strong> food eaten by the predator over a certain period <strong>of</strong> time<br />

will, under favorable feeding conditions, tend to approach a certain definite size,<br />

above which it cannot under any circumstances increase <strong>and</strong> which also corresponds<br />

to the physiological condition <strong>of</strong> full saturation. Hence the mathematical interpret-<br />

ation <strong>of</strong> the given law takes a <strong>for</strong>m which has been used fairly widely in quanti-<br />

tative biology <strong>and</strong> physical chemistry. If the amount <strong>of</strong> the maximal ration is taken<br />

as b, then the relation between the size <strong>of</strong> the actual ration u <strong>and</strong> the density <strong>of</strong><br />

the prey population v must be proportional to the difference between the actual <strong>and</strong><br />

maximal rations <strong>and</strong> can be expressed by<br />

du/dv =a (b- u), (4d. 1)<br />

where a represents the coefficient <strong>of</strong> proportionality. Integrating this equation, we<br />

get<br />

u =b (1 - e -~') ." (4d. 2)<br />

(The symbols are mine).<br />

Although IVLEV'S criticism <strong>of</strong> VOLTERRA is a correct one, there appear to be some<br />

ambiguities <strong>and</strong> confusions in the second statement quoted above. It is not clear<br />

what IVLEV was aiming at in these equations, because <strong>of</strong> inadequate definition <strong>of</strong> the<br />

symbols in the equations. As far as I know, it is not explicitly mentioned anywhere<br />

in his book, whether eq. (4d. 2) represents an overall hunting equation or an instan-<br />

taneous relationship.<br />

IVLEV'S treatise covers a wide range <strong>of</strong> problems in feeding ecology, which<br />

includes problems in natural population <strong>and</strong> competition between species feeding on<br />

the same food resources. Needless to say, these problems cannot be solved unless<br />

the depletion <strong>of</strong> the resources is considered ; the notion <strong>of</strong> 'competition' in the VOL-<br />

TERRA-GAusE (as well as in the NICHOLSON-BA1LEY) line <strong>of</strong> thought would not have<br />

emerged without this fundamental phenomenon, the depletion <strong>of</strong> some essential requi-


36<br />

site, e.g. space <strong>and</strong> food. It should have there<strong>for</strong>e<br />

been <strong>of</strong> fundamental importance<br />

<strong>for</strong> IVLEV to make his position absolutely clear; whether he was aiming at an overall<br />

relationship, which includes the effect <strong>of</strong> depletion, or an instantaneous relationship,<br />

in which the effect is not considered.<br />

Having studied IVLEV's inference critically, I reached the conclusion that eq.<br />

(4d. 2) is not an overall hunting equation. This conclusion would seriously influence<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> IVLEV'S treatise, <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e I should present the pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> this conclu-<br />

sion in order to eliminate the possibility that my remarks are too critical.<br />

In order to prove my point, let us assume firstly that eq. (4d. 2) is an overall<br />

hunting equation equivalent to z=F(xo, Y, t) in my system presented in w 3. Thus,<br />

under this hypothesis, IVLEV'S symbol u is equivalent to my z, <strong>and</strong> obviously v cannot<br />

be x. it follows that v=xo, the initial prey density. Then eqs. (4d. 1) <strong>and</strong> (4d. 2)<br />

become respectively<br />

<strong>and</strong><br />

dz/dxo = a (b- z)<br />

z ~ b (1 - e- aXo )<br />

(4d. 1')<br />

(4d. 2').<br />

Now, according to IVLEV, Z approaches, over a certain period <strong>of</strong> time, the maximal<br />

ration b. In the meantime, b must be a positive value, <strong>and</strong> it has to be independent<br />

<strong>of</strong> x0, since otherwise eq. (4d. 2') will not be yielded by eq. (4d. 1'). However, since<br />

x0 is any given initial density <strong>of</strong> the prey, it can take any positive value. Thus, we<br />

can choose a value <strong>of</strong> Xo smaller than b. Under these circumstances, z can exceed<br />

the value <strong>of</strong> x0, which suggests that the predators can eat more than supplied, <strong>and</strong><br />

this is <strong>of</strong> course absurd.<br />

It is clear that IVLEV's symbol u cannot be z, <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e we have to give up<br />

the hypothesis that eq. (4d. 2) represents an overall hunting equation. The second<br />

alternative is there<strong>for</strong>e that u is the number <strong>of</strong> prey taken by a given number <strong>of</strong><br />

predators per unit area <strong>for</strong> a given period <strong>of</strong> time when the prey density is kept<br />

constant; the equation represents an instantaneous relationship. Under this hypothesis,<br />

u is equivalent to n, <strong>and</strong> it follows that v is X, a fixed prey density. Hence, from<br />

eqs. (4d. 1) <strong>and</strong> (4d. 2) we have<br />

<strong>and</strong><br />

dn/dX:a (b- n) (4d. 1")<br />

n = b (1 - e -~x) (4d. 2").<br />

Equation (4d. 2") has no contradiction as an instantaneous<br />

hunting equation, i.e.<br />

n =f(X)Yt, if the factor Yt in eq. (4d. 2") is either unity or involved in the factor<br />

b. The latter situation is a general one, <strong>and</strong> so we can write:<br />

b~bYt.<br />

So that we have<br />

n =b(1-e -~x) Yt (4d. 3).<br />

IVLEV, when fitting his eq. (4d. 2) to observations with some fish species (figure<br />

1 <strong>of</strong> his book), stated that five young fish were introduced into a container <strong>and</strong><br />

allowed to feed <strong>for</strong> 1.5 to 2 hours. No mention was made, however, <strong>of</strong> either how


37<br />

big the container Was or if the prey density was kept constant; though, judging from<br />

his statement (chapter 2, p. 18 <strong>of</strong> his book) that "Food consumption was studied...<br />

by estimation <strong>of</strong> the food left over out <strong>of</strong> the quantity given .... ", the prey density<br />

was apparently not kept constant. Obviously, in the light <strong>of</strong> my analysis leading to<br />

eq. (4d. 3), IVLEV's variable u must have been influenced by the size <strong>of</strong> container <strong>and</strong><br />

consequently the density <strong>of</strong> fish: more precisely, the size <strong>of</strong> container influence-~ the<br />

density <strong>of</strong> fish, <strong>and</strong> consequently the coefficient b, if the density <strong>of</strong> food species was<br />

kept constant to meet the condition required <strong>for</strong> describing the instantaneous relationship.<br />

If the food species diminished gradually during the course <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong>, the<br />

estimates <strong>of</strong> both coefficients a <strong>and</strong> b obtained by fitting eq. (4d. 3), even though it<br />

takes factors Y <strong>and</strong> t into account, would have been different between observations<br />

with different predator density, simply because it amounts to fitting an instantaneous<br />

equation to one particular cross-section <strong>of</strong> the hunting surface. Hence, these coefficients<br />

a <strong>and</strong> b estimated in IVLEV'S experiments are specific to these experiments <strong>and</strong><br />

have no universal meaning. This is the same criticism I raised in regard to HOLLINO'S<br />

model. In order to eliminate the awkwardness pointed out above, it is necessary to<br />

deduce an overall hunting equation. But be<strong>for</strong>e doing so, I shall examine in more<br />

detail the reason why IVLEV'S instantaneous equation takes such specific <strong>for</strong>m: although<br />

eq. (4d. 3) has no apparent contradiction as an instantaneous hunting equation, the<br />

justification <strong>for</strong> starting our inference from the differential eq. (4d. 1) is yet to be<br />

rationalized.<br />

IVLEV obtained his idea concerning eq. (4d. 1) from three existing equations<br />

developed in physical chemistry <strong>and</strong> physiology. The first was an equation <strong>for</strong> unimolecular<br />

reaction. The velocity equation <strong>for</strong> a simple unimolecular reaction takes<br />

the <strong>for</strong>m<br />

dx/dt = -ax<br />

where x is the density <strong>of</strong> molecules at time t, <strong>and</strong> a the reaction coefficient. So,<br />

letting x0 be the initial density <strong>of</strong> the molecules, we have<br />

z =x0 (1 - e -~)<br />

where z--xo-x. As already seen, this is the NICHOLSON-BAILEY equation in which<br />

Y=I. Of course, there is a resemblance between the velocity equation <strong>and</strong> IVLEV's<br />

equation in their mathematical <strong>for</strong>m, but the meanings are entirely different since<br />

the derivative dx/dt in the velocity equation is the rate <strong>of</strong> change in time, whereas<br />

dn/dX in IVLEV'S is the rate <strong>of</strong> change with density. These two attributes are,<br />

needless to say, totally irrelevent to each other. There<strong>for</strong>e, the quotation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

velocity equation by IVLEV is absolutely irrelevant in his context.<br />

IVLEV also quoted the "WEBER-FECHNER law" (but without citing the literature<br />

source). As far as I know, this is a law in neuro-physiology representing the relationship<br />

between the strength <strong>of</strong> a stimulus <strong>and</strong> the reaction <strong>of</strong> a nerve. However,<br />

there appears to be no possible resemblance between this law <strong>and</strong> IVLEV'S equation<br />

in their mathematical <strong>for</strong>ms.


38<br />

The last one is MITSCHERLICH'S <strong>for</strong>mula concerning the relationship between<br />

plant growth <strong>and</strong> nutrient supply. MITSCHERLICH (cited by RUSSELL 1961) assumed<br />

that a plant or crop should produce a certain maximum yield if all conditions were<br />

ideal, but ins<strong>of</strong>ar as any essential factor is deficient there is a corresponding short-<br />

age in the yield. Further, it is assumed that the increase <strong>of</strong> crop produced by unit<br />

increment <strong>of</strong> the lacking factor is proportional to the decrement from the maximum,<br />

thus<br />

dn/dx=a(b-n)<br />

where n is the yield obtained when the amount <strong>of</strong> the factor present is X, b the<br />

maximum yield obtainable if the factor was present in excess, <strong>and</strong> a is constant.<br />

While it may be underst<strong>and</strong>able that IVLEV quoted MITSCHEgLmH'S equation,<br />

since prey density can, in a way, be compared to the nutrient supply in plants, the<br />

comparison is more like a metaphorical juxtaposition <strong>and</strong> does not really aid his<br />

argument in <strong>predation</strong>. IVLEV'S failure to recognize the distinction between the overall<br />

<strong>and</strong> instantaneous relationships, <strong>and</strong> also to incorporate the factors Y <strong>and</strong> t, implies<br />

that such comparisons did not give a sufficient insight into the structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong>.<br />

Also, as already mentioned, there will be a number <strong>of</strong> mathematical equations which<br />

can equally well describe the trend <strong>of</strong> the hunting curve that IVLEV obtained <strong>for</strong><br />

fish <strong>predation</strong> (figure I <strong>of</strong> IVLEV'S book).<br />

For instance, HOLLING's disc equation<br />

shows a very similar trend, yet the meaning <strong>of</strong> the equation is quite different from<br />

MITSCHERLICH'S <strong>for</strong>mula. As I have shown in w 3, the <strong>for</strong>mulation <strong>of</strong> a differential<br />

equation in <strong>predation</strong> <strong>models</strong> has a definite significance as a means <strong>of</strong> inference. That<br />

is, it is <strong>of</strong>ten an instantaneous relationship, between the components concerned, that<br />

is self-explanatory <strong>and</strong> so can be <strong>for</strong>mulated intuitively <strong>and</strong> correctly. IVLEV's equa-<br />

tion, however, appears not to have been developed theoretically, but has been borrow-<br />

ed by metaphor from other fields in which the development <strong>of</strong> a differential equation<br />

has no relevant significance to <strong>predation</strong>.<br />

It is, however, true that IVLEV'S equation has a remarkable descriptive power.<br />

It might there<strong>for</strong>e be that some essential meaning or some fundamental structure <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>predation</strong> processes is reflected in the equation. To find this out, the following sim-<br />

ulation experiments will be considered.<br />

Suppose a set-up similar to the disc experiments by HOLLING. The only difference<br />

is that the distribution <strong>of</strong> the discs is ideally at r<strong>and</strong>om, <strong>and</strong> hence the discs may<br />

overlap each other. To make calculation easier, however, the model is slightly modified,<br />

though the principle <strong>of</strong> the model process remains unaffected. It will be assumed that<br />

the prey individuals are particles <strong>and</strong> a predator has a ring <strong>of</strong> radius R around itself.<br />

Then, the ring, representing the recognition zone <strong>of</strong> the predator, is tossed over the<br />

hunting area (a table), again at r<strong>and</strong>om; it should be strictly at r<strong>and</strong>om so that every<br />

part <strong>of</strong> the table has an equal chance <strong>of</strong> receiving a toss <strong>of</strong> the ring.<br />

Under these circumstances, the total number <strong>of</strong> particles (written as n~) falling<br />

within the ring after a number <strong>of</strong> tosses will be in proportion to the density <strong>of</strong> the


39<br />

particles.<br />

As the average number <strong>of</strong> particles within the ring is 7rR2X <strong>and</strong> the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> tosses in time ts is kt,, where k is the frequency <strong>of</strong> tosses per unit time,<br />

the total number caught by the ring will be<br />

n~ =~R~kXt~.<br />

Although the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> the above <strong>for</strong>mula is the same as in eq. (4c. 4)<br />

describing HOLLING'S experiment, notation n, in the left-h<strong>and</strong> side is not n as in eq.<br />

(4c. 4). It was assumed in HOLLING'S model that all the discs tapped were taken,<br />

<strong>and</strong> it was a justifiable assumption since only one disc was discovered at a time as<br />

there was no overlap <strong>of</strong> the discs. In the present model, however, more than two<br />

particles may occur within the ring at one toss. Thus, if the predator is allowed to<br />

catch only one prey individual within its recognition zone at a time, the total number<br />

captured (i. e. n) will be the number <strong>of</strong> successful tosses rather than ns, the total<br />

number discovered.<br />

In the present model, the distribution <strong>of</strong> the prey individuals <strong>and</strong> the tosses <strong>of</strong><br />

the ring are ideally at r<strong>and</strong>om, <strong>and</strong> so, provided that R is not too large as compared<br />

with the table, the frequency <strong>of</strong> tosses in which a given number <strong>of</strong> particles falls<br />

must follow a POISSON series with its mean equal to the average number <strong>of</strong> particles<br />

in the ring at one toss, i.e. rcR~X. Hence, as the frequency with which no particle<br />

occurs within the ring in the period t, will be kt,e -~R*X the total frequency <strong>of</strong><br />

successful tosses in t, will be<br />

n =kt, (l-e- ~R~X ).<br />

In the above model, only one ring was assumed to be tossed at the frequency <strong>of</strong> k<br />

per unit time per table.<br />

If there are Y rings per unit area tossed independently,<br />

each at the average frequency <strong>of</strong> k per unit time, the total frequency is kYts, <strong>and</strong><br />

so the above equation becomes<br />

n=kYt~(1-e -'~R~X ) (4d. 4).<br />

If kYt~ in the above equation is set equal to b, <strong>and</strong> rcR 2 to a, we have IVLEV'S eq.<br />

(4d. 2"). Thus, we find that IVLEV'S equation, in terms <strong>of</strong> the toss-a-ring simulation,<br />

is a generalized version <strong>of</strong> HOLLING'S experiment, since eq. (4d. 4) is a generalization<br />

<strong>of</strong> eq. (4c. 5). That is, recognition zones can overlap, <strong>and</strong> so there is no restriction<br />

to the range <strong>of</strong> variation in the prey density X (remembering that HOLLING'S eq.<br />

(4c. 5) holds in the disc experiment only <strong>for</strong> X


40<br />

finding a disc. So in HOLLING's disc experiment, the value n/Yt should never exceed<br />

k/(l+hk). It should be noticed, however, that eq. (4c. 6) describing HOLLING'S disc<br />

situation also holds <strong>for</strong> sweep-feeding <strong>predation</strong> as in the NICHOLSON-BAILEY model.<br />

In this case, there is no limitation to the prey density, <strong>and</strong> so the maximum ration<br />

is set at n/Yt~l/h.<br />

The effect <strong>of</strong> the h<strong>and</strong>ling time, h, can easily be incorporated into the toss-a-ring<br />

equation by eliminating t~ from eqs.<br />

kYt(l_e -~R2X)<br />

n=l + hk(l_e- ~R2x )<br />

(4c. 2) <strong>and</strong> (4d. 4). Thus we have<br />

(4d. 5).<br />

In the above equation, the maximum value <strong>of</strong> n/Yt is k/(l+hk) which is reached<br />

asymptotically as X becomes infinity. This elaboration, however, may be <strong>of</strong> doubtful<br />

value, <strong>for</strong> the following reasons. First, the purpose <strong>of</strong> the toss-a-ring model is only<br />

to explain why IVLEV'S equation takes that <strong>for</strong>m, <strong>and</strong> also to find where the missing<br />

variables, the predator density <strong>and</strong> the time factor, should appropriately be placed.<br />

Secondly, if the model is to reflect a certain type <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> process, it may be<br />

compared only to that <strong>of</strong> some shore birds probing with their beaks to find food,<br />

but it is not a common method <strong>of</strong> hunting <strong>for</strong> the predators <strong>of</strong> interest. There<strong>for</strong>e,<br />

it would be wise to leave IVLEV's equation in the <strong>for</strong>m, i.e. eq. (4d. 3) :<br />

n = b (1 - e -~x) Yt,<br />

as purely descriptive without attaching any serious meaning to it. Equation (4d. 3)<br />

has an excellent power <strong>of</strong> describing instantaneous hunting curves <strong>of</strong> the shape <strong>of</strong><br />

the one in Fig. 1, which has been widely observed with various predators.<br />

As long as it is remembered that eq. (4d. 3) is an empirical <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> an instant-<br />

aneous hunting equation, it may be used safely, according to the situation to which<br />

the equation is applied, either as in the present <strong>for</strong>m or as the basis <strong>of</strong> deducing a<br />

theoretical trend in the higher order <strong>of</strong> synthesis. For example, I have used IVLEV'S<br />

equation <strong>for</strong> my model <strong>of</strong> the clutch size variation in birds (RoYAMA 1969) <strong>and</strong> the<br />

instantaneous <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> HOLLING'S equation <strong>for</strong> explaining the hunting behaviour <strong>of</strong><br />

the great tit (Parus major L.) (ROYAMA 1970). In both cases, I could neglect depletion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the prey density caused by <strong>predation</strong> by the birds. If, however, eq. (4d. 3) is to<br />

be applied to a situation in which the prey density is being depleted, further synthesis<br />

is needed to deduce an overall hunting equation. This has in fact been done in w 3,<br />

as in eq. (3. 12) derived from eq. (3.10). If eq. (4d. 3) is used to describe the<br />

instantaneous relationship in <strong>parasitism</strong> <strong>of</strong> the indiscriminate type, eq.<br />

than eq.<br />

(3.12) should be used.<br />

(3. 24) rather<br />

A brief mention will be made <strong>of</strong> an equation that GAUSE (1934) had proposed<br />

be<strong>for</strong>e IVLEV. GAUSE, in his <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> protozoan predators, found that the rate <strong>of</strong><br />

increase per individual in the predator population was not a linear function <strong>of</strong> prey<br />

density, <strong>and</strong> he proposed an exponential function to replace the equation, i.e. eq.<br />

(4. lb), proposed by LOTKA <strong>and</strong> VOLTERRA <strong>for</strong> that relationship. Thus


41<br />

(dy/dt)/y = C (1- e-~) (4d. 6)<br />

where C <strong>and</strong> ,t are positive constants. I shall examine in the following: (1) whether<br />

GAUSE'S proposal <strong>of</strong> eq.<br />

(4d. 6) takes the same <strong>for</strong>m as that <strong>of</strong> IVLEV'S eq.<br />

(4d. 6) is acceptable, <strong>and</strong> (2) why the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq.<br />

(4d. 2').<br />

Although GAUSE was aiming at the <strong>for</strong>mulation <strong>of</strong> the relationships between a<br />

protozoan predator <strong>and</strong> its prey, his experimental justification <strong>of</strong> eq. (4d. 6) came<br />

from an observation by ~MIRNOV <strong>and</strong> WLADIMIROW (cited by GAUSE 1934, pp. 139-140)<br />

<strong>of</strong> a parasite, Mormoniella vitripennis, attacking its host, Phormia groenl<strong>and</strong>ica. It<br />

should be remembered that the relationship expressed in the <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> a differential<br />

equation as in eq. (4d. 6) will not be appropriate in the case <strong>of</strong> an entomophagous<br />

parasite in which generations are discrete.<br />

This is because, while the expression<br />

C(1-e -~*) st<strong>and</strong>s <strong>for</strong> the number <strong>of</strong> progeny (per unit area) produced per parasite<br />

during t in the present generation to <strong>for</strong>m the next generation, these progeny will<br />

not reproduce in the present generation. There<strong>for</strong>e, it is incorrect to equate the (dy/<br />

dt)/y to C(1-e-~*). Be<strong>for</strong>e making further comments on eq. (4d. 6), however, I shall<br />

investigate the second point, i.e. why were changes in the density <strong>of</strong> the parasites'<br />

progeny, in relation to changes in host density as observed by SMIRNOV <strong>and</strong> WLADI-<br />

MIROW, described by the <strong>for</strong>mula C(1-e -~) which is <strong>of</strong> the same <strong>for</strong>m as IVLEV'S ?<br />

Let Y' be the density <strong>of</strong> progeny in the parasite population produced to <strong>for</strong>m the<br />

next generation, <strong>and</strong> z the density <strong>of</strong> hosts attacked in the present generation. Let<br />

us assume hypothetically that Y' is more or less proportional to z, i.e. Y'=c'z where<br />

c' is a proportionality constant. In the meantime, it has been shown that although it<br />

is an instantaneous equation, eq.<br />

(4d. 3) can nevertheless describe one cross-section,<br />

parallel to the z-X plane, <strong>of</strong> an overall hunting surface <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>, e. g. eq.<br />

(3.22). In other words, although eq. (4d. 3) should correctly be used to estimate the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> n, the equation can, because <strong>of</strong> its considerable flexibility in fitting, also<br />

describe the z-X relationship, provided that the coefficients a <strong>and</strong> b are appropriately<br />

chosen <strong>for</strong> a given value <strong>of</strong> Yt, i.e. <strong>for</strong> a given cross-section <strong>of</strong> the hunting surface.<br />

Under these circumstances, one may obtain, though only superficially,<br />

Y'=c'b(1-e -ax) Yt,<br />

or by transposing Yt to the left-h<strong>and</strong> side,<br />

Y'/Yt =c'b (1 -e -ax) (4d. 7).<br />

In the SMIRNOWWLADIMIROW observation, as presented in figure 40 <strong>of</strong> GAUSE'S<br />

(1934) book, the factor Yt appears to be fixed at the same value <strong>for</strong> different values<br />

<strong>of</strong> X throughout the observation, <strong>and</strong> this consistency satisfies the condition under<br />

which eq. (4d. 7) has been derived.<br />

Clearly, the expressions Y'/Yt <strong>and</strong> X in eq.<br />

(4d. 7) are equivalent to (dy/dt)/y <strong>and</strong> x respectively in eq. (4d. 6), <strong>and</strong> the constants<br />

c'b <strong>and</strong> a in eq. (4d. 6) can be written as C <strong>and</strong> 2 respectively as in eq. (4d. 6).<br />

And this is why GAUSE's equation can be deduced from IVLEV'S.<br />

The reasoning which led to eq. (4d. 7) explains why GAUSE adopted eq. (4d. 6),<br />

<strong>and</strong> also why GAUSE <strong>and</strong> IvLgv proposed the same function, though GAUSE was


42<br />

thinking <strong>of</strong> a function equivalent to g2 in eq. (4a. 2b) while IVLEV was thinking <strong>of</strong><br />

one equivalent to the function f in eq.<br />

(4a. 2a). This reasoning suggests, however,<br />

that GAUSE'S propgsal <strong>of</strong> his equation, the justification <strong>of</strong> which was based erroneously<br />

on an observation <strong>of</strong> parasites with discrete generations, is not acceptable, <strong>for</strong> two<br />

reasons, if applied to predators with continuous generations. First, as pointed out by<br />

NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY (1935, p. 552, first paragraph), the number <strong>of</strong> progeny in a<br />

predator population, unlike that in a parasite population, will not in general be propor-<br />

tional to the number <strong>of</strong> prey eaten by the parental predators.<br />

be avoided if it could be verified that the exponential function as in eq.<br />

This objection might<br />

(4d. 6) still<br />

holds <strong>for</strong> protozoan predators in which the value <strong>and</strong> the ecological significance <strong>of</strong><br />

the coefficient ~ are different from those <strong>of</strong> the coefficient a in eq. (4d. 7), <strong>and</strong> there-<br />

<strong>for</strong>e that the similarity between the two equations is only coincidental.<br />

My second objection, however, seems unavoidable. Clearly, dy/dt is a linear func-<br />

tion <strong>of</strong> y in eq. (4d. 6), suggesting that the predator population exhibits a geometric<br />

increase <strong>for</strong> any given value <strong>of</strong> x. This contradicts GAUSE'S own suggestion <strong>of</strong> a<br />

logistic law with respect to the natural increase <strong>of</strong> the prey population in the absence<br />

<strong>of</strong> predators; in particular with respect to the function gl (x) in the generalized LOTKA-<br />

VOLTERRA eq. (4a. 2a). GAUSE'S inconsistency in this respect, i.e. adopting the logistic<br />

law <strong>for</strong> gl <strong>and</strong> neglecting it <strong>for</strong> gz, appears to be attributed to the misconception in<br />

his statement (GAuSE 1934, p. 53, last paragraph): "In the general <strong>for</strong>m the rate <strong>of</strong><br />

increase in the number <strong>of</strong> individuals <strong>of</strong> the predatory species resulting from the<br />

devouring <strong>of</strong> the prey dN2/dt Eequivalent to dy/dt in my notation] can be represented<br />

by means <strong>of</strong> a certain geometrical increase which is realized in proportion to the<br />

unutilized opportunity <strong>of</strong> growth.<br />

This unutilized opportunity is a function <strong>of</strong> the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> prey at a given moment." It appears that GAUSE overlooked in the last<br />

sentence above that the 'unutilized opportunity <strong>of</strong> growth' in the predator population<br />

is a function not only <strong>of</strong> the density <strong>of</strong> prey but also <strong>of</strong> the density <strong>of</strong> the predators<br />

at the same time.<br />

To summarize, in section IV <strong>of</strong> chapter III in his book, GAUSE (1934) tried to<br />

improve the LOTKA-VOLTERRA <strong>for</strong>mulation <strong>of</strong> the prey-predator system. His sugges-<br />

tions, however, were reasonable only with respect to the function gl (x) in eq. (4a. 2a)<br />

<strong>and</strong> not with g2(x, y) in eq. (4a. 2b). As to the function f(x, y) in eq. (4a. 2a),<br />

there was no suggestion by GAUSE, <strong>and</strong> the function f was left uncriticized as a<br />

linear function <strong>of</strong> x, which is unreasonable. For these reasons, GAUSE'S mathematical<br />

investigations into the prey-predator interaction system are unsatisfactory.<br />

e). ROYAMA'S model <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om searching <strong>and</strong> probability <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om encounters<br />

In the previous sections, it has been shown that the instantaneous hunting func-<br />

tion, i. e. f, is, unlike the simple assumption by LOTKA <strong>and</strong> VOLTERRA <strong>and</strong> by<br />

NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY, not a linear function <strong>of</strong> prey or host density. This finding<br />

influences the notion <strong>of</strong> 'the area <strong>of</strong> discovery' that was originally used by NICHOLSON


<strong>and</strong> BAILEY but redefined in w<br />

43<br />

as /~=(1/Y) In{xo/(Xo-Z)} <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong>, <strong>and</strong> /i=<br />

(l/Y) ln{X/(X-z)} <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>. If the instantaneous function f(x)is a non-linear<br />

function, z is also a non-linear function <strong>of</strong> x0 or X, <strong>and</strong> hence /~ cannot be constant.<br />

Although the <strong>models</strong> proposed by HOLLING <strong>and</strong> IVLEV, reviewed in w 4c <strong>and</strong> d, are<br />

adequate to show that /~ will not be constant theoretically, these <strong>models</strong> are not quite<br />

sufficient to show how /~ can logically vary. One <strong>of</strong> the key points <strong>for</strong> this analysis<br />

seems to lie in underst<strong>and</strong>ing the coefficient a (not /~).<br />

The coefficient a appeared consistently in the instantaneous hunting function <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>models</strong> reviewed in preceding sections, with the same geometric meaning, namely the<br />

size <strong>of</strong> an area immediately around either a prey or a predator individual within<br />

which the predator would take action to catch the prey. In all the <strong>models</strong>, it was<br />

assumed that the coefficient a was constant, or independent <strong>of</strong> variables x, y, <strong>and</strong> t.<br />

Some objections arose among ecologists (see below) against the validity <strong>of</strong> the assump-<br />

tion that the coefficient was constant,<br />

yet. The main purpose <strong>of</strong> the present<br />

nature <strong>of</strong> this coefficient.<br />

The justification <strong>of</strong> the assumption<br />

<strong>and</strong> the debate has not quite been settled<br />

section is to give a much clearer idea <strong>of</strong> the<br />

that a is constant is partly concerned with<br />

the validity <strong>of</strong> the assumption <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om searching--whether or not such an assumption<br />

is reasonable in <strong>predation</strong> or <strong>parasitism</strong> theories. The idea <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om searching <strong>and</strong><br />

r<strong>and</strong>om encounter is not new. It has been used very widely among theorists, <strong>and</strong><br />

while the concept <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>omness is clearly defined in the field <strong>of</strong> mathematics,<br />

confusion has resulted from loose application <strong>of</strong> the concept to an ecological situation.<br />

First, one must separate the concepts <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om searching <strong>and</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om encounters,<br />

as the one does not necessarily follow the other. Perhaps the most satisfactory defini-<br />

tion <strong>of</strong> the term 'r<strong>and</strong>om searching' is that the path <strong>of</strong> each individual predator is<br />

affected neither by the location <strong>of</strong> prey individuals in the hunting area nor by the<br />

paths <strong>of</strong> other members <strong>of</strong> the predator population. 'R<strong>and</strong>om encounter', as opposed<br />

to 'r<strong>and</strong>om searching', can be defined as meaning that every prey individual in the<br />

area concerned has an equal probability <strong>of</strong> being encountered by predators searching<br />

<strong>for</strong> a limited time interval. Now, the simple theory <strong>of</strong> the kinetics <strong>of</strong> gas molecules,<br />

used by LOTKA, VOLTERRA, <strong>and</strong> NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY, assumes r<strong>and</strong>om encounters<br />

between molecules, <strong>and</strong> so the theory can be a model <strong>for</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om searching to a<br />

limited extent. This is because, as pointed out earlier, the analogy can be reasonably<br />

applied to hunting behaviour only when an encounter is made by bodily contact;<br />

otherwise, r<strong>and</strong>om encounters are approximately guaranteed only if either (1) the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> predators searching independently is high, (2) the time <strong>for</strong> searching is<br />

unlimited, or (3) the density <strong>of</strong> prey is relatively low.<br />

This can be illustrated by assuming that a few molecules are marked as predators,<br />

<strong>and</strong> all other molecules, unmarked, are prey. Then the movement <strong>of</strong> these few marked<br />

molecules <strong>for</strong> a certain limited time interval must be limited to a small fraction <strong>of</strong><br />

the total area concerned, so that the unmarked molecules located in the immediate


44<br />

vicinity <strong>of</strong> any one <strong>of</strong> the marked molecules must have higher chances <strong>of</strong> being<br />

encountered by the marked ones than those located remotely. However, if the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> marked molecules is high, all the unmarked molecules have an equal chance <strong>of</strong><br />

being encountered by any <strong>of</strong> the marked one~.<br />

LAING (1937) <strong>and</strong> ULLYETT (1947) were aware <strong>of</strong> a part <strong>of</strong> the above point <strong>and</strong><br />

stated, in their criticism <strong>of</strong> the NICHOLSON-BAILEY theory based on r<strong>and</strong>om searching,<br />

that a predator or a parasite can perceive the location <strong>of</strong> prey or host at a certain<br />

distance away from it ; the search there<strong>for</strong>e can only be at r<strong>and</strong>om (a free path or<br />

undirected path would be better words <strong>for</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om searching : my comment) as long<br />

as the predator or parasite remains outside this zone <strong>of</strong> perception;as soon as it<br />

enters this zone, its actions cease to be r<strong>and</strong>om <strong>and</strong> become, instead, directed towards<br />

the prey or host. THOMPSON (1939) thus wrote that a theory that equates animal<br />

action <strong>and</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om action covers at least only a fraction <strong>of</strong> the field, <strong>and</strong> that any<br />

theory based on the assumption that search is r<strong>and</strong>om cannot be accepted as a valid<br />

general theory.<br />

Although these criticisms sound reasonable, no attempt has been made, as far<br />

as I am aware, to find what <strong>and</strong> how much bias might be involved in a theory based<br />

on r<strong>and</strong>om searching as against the more likely situation raised by the above authors.<br />

I investigated this problem to some extent in a previous paper (RoYAMA 1966), but<br />

because it was written in a language not normally accessible to English-speaking<br />

readers, <strong>and</strong> also because I have since found some mathematical errors in it, all the<br />

points will be revised here.<br />

The investigation will be made with a situation in which a predator recognizes a<br />

prey from some distance. For the moment, it is assumed that only one predator is<br />

searching <strong>and</strong> that the prey density is kept constant. Suppose a number <strong>of</strong> particles<br />

<strong>of</strong> kind P (prey) are scattered at r<strong>and</strong>om over a sufficiently large plane (a two-dimensional<br />

space), each particle being given a circle <strong>of</strong> radius R as the recognition radius.<br />

One particle <strong>of</strong> another kind Q (a predator) can recognize P only within the area<br />

covered by the circles, so that Q's path is undirected when Q is outside the recognition<br />

area, but it is directed towards the nearest P within the recognition area. For<br />

simplicity, it is supposed that all P's remain stationary, but that Q moves around in<br />

the manner described. Also the radius R is the same <strong>for</strong> each P (although this assumption<br />

is not quite essential). At the moment, the time spent h<strong>and</strong>ling P's after<br />

they are caught by Q is not considered.<br />

Now, the starting point <strong>of</strong> Q will be determined on the plane at r<strong>and</strong>om. Then<br />

one or other <strong>of</strong> the following two cases wilt occur (see Fig. 5). Case 1: the starting<br />

point happens to be outside any <strong>of</strong> the circles <strong>of</strong> P's. Then Q determines the direction<br />

<strong>of</strong> its movement at r<strong>and</strong>om <strong>and</strong> moves along a (straight) free path until it contacts<br />

a P's circle; then goes to the centre <strong>of</strong> the circle to capture the P. Case 2: the starting<br />

point happens to be within one <strong>of</strong> the circles. Then Q immediately goes to the<br />

nearest centre, where the P is located, along the shortest path. A situation is first


45<br />

Fig. 5. ROYAMA'S first geometric model in which a predator (Q) recognizes<br />

its prey (P's, black dots) within a circle around each P, <strong>and</strong> searching<br />

by Q is discontinued each time a P is captured. A starting ponit (cross)<br />

is determined at r<strong>and</strong>om <strong>for</strong> each new search. For further explanation<br />

see the text.<br />

considered in which Q discontinues searching each time it captures a P, <strong>and</strong> so the<br />

next starting point is determined again at r<strong>and</strong>om over the plane.<br />

This is perhaps<br />

comparable to a bird collecting food <strong>for</strong> its young, <strong>and</strong> each time a food item is found<br />

it is taken to the nest, <strong>and</strong> the next hunting starts independently <strong>of</strong> the previous<br />

search.<br />

Suppose n <strong>of</strong> P's were caught by Q during the total time spent in searching, ts,<br />

(note that the number caught can be smaller than the number seen).<br />

Let n~ be the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> occurrences <strong>of</strong> case 1, L1 the average distance that Q travelled between<br />

the starting point outside any circle <strong>and</strong> the periphery <strong>of</strong> the first circle that Q hap-<br />

pened to encounter, <strong>and</strong> G the average speed <strong>of</strong> movement while Q was on an undi-<br />

rected path. Similarly, let n2 be the number <strong>of</strong> occurrences <strong>of</strong> case 2, L2 the average<br />

distance between the starting point inside the circles <strong>and</strong> the nearest centre <strong>of</strong> the<br />

circles, <strong>and</strong> Ve the average speed <strong>of</strong> movement along a directed path. Then we have<br />

the following <strong>for</strong>mula<br />

ts = ( L1/ VI +R/V2) nl q- ( L2/ V2) ne (4e. 1).<br />

Now, let Pr{nff <strong>and</strong> Pr{ne} be the probability that cases 1 <strong>and</strong> 2 occur respectively,<br />

then<br />

but since nl+n2=n,<br />

m=nPr{n,}<br />

n2 = nPr {n2},<br />

n2 =n (1-Pr {nd),<br />

<strong>and</strong> so eq. (4e. 1) becomes


46<br />

t,=[ (LJV~ + R/V2) Pr {nl} + L2(1-Pr{n~} )/V2]n (4e. 2).<br />

There<strong>for</strong>e, if L~, L~, <strong>and</strong> Pr{nl} are evaluated as functions <strong>of</strong> the density <strong>of</strong> pts (i. e.<br />

X), n can be determined as a function <strong>of</strong> X. Details <strong>of</strong> the evaluation <strong>of</strong> L1 <strong>and</strong><br />

L2 will be given in Appendices 1 <strong>and</strong> 2 respectively, <strong>and</strong> the end results alone will<br />

be shown below:<br />

L1 = 1/2RX (4e, 3)<br />

<strong>and</strong><br />

L2= {$(V'2rcX R)/1/X-Re ,R X }/(1--e ,,R X ) (4e. 4)<br />

where $(1/2~XR)=~2~f~Re<br />

-02/2d0"<br />

Now if we assume a sufficiently large area, the probability <strong>of</strong> Q's starting point<br />

happening to be outside any <strong>of</strong> the circles <strong>of</strong> P's must be the 0-term <strong>of</strong> a PomsoN<br />

series with its mean zcReX. Thus<br />

-~rR2X<br />

Pr {Ytl} =e (4e. 5).<br />

Eliminating L~, L2, <strong>and</strong> Pr{n~} from eqs. (4e. 2) to (4e. 5) inclusive <strong>and</strong> solving with<br />

respect to n, we have<br />

- ~r R~X<br />

n=[2RV~ V2/{V2 e +2R V~/X ~(v~2rcXR)} ]Xt8 (4e. 6).<br />

Now, if there is Y number <strong>of</strong> Q's per unit area, the total number <strong>of</strong> P's caught will<br />

be obtained simply by multiplying the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq. (4e. 6) by II, since the<br />

equation is an instantaneous one. So, if the expression in the outer brackets on the<br />

right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq. (4e. 6) is denoted by a function a(X), where a is a functional<br />

symbol, we have<br />

n =a(X) XYt, (4e. 7).<br />

Equation (4e. 7) is clearly comparable to eq. (4b. 5) in the NICHOLSON-BAILEY model<br />

(note that in the NICHOLSON-BAII.EY model there is no distinction between t <strong>and</strong> ts)<br />

<strong>and</strong> is also comparable to eq. (4c. 5) in HOLLING'S model. That is to say, the coeffi-<br />

cient a <strong>for</strong> the two <strong>models</strong> is in fact comparable to the function a(X) in my model.<br />

Now, it is clear that the coefficient a can no longer be considered to be independent<br />

<strong>of</strong> X if a predator recognizes a prey from a distance <strong>and</strong> has to approach to seize it.<br />

The new coefficient a(X) is normally a decreasing function <strong>of</strong> prey density. (It should<br />

be noticed that the coefficient a in the NICHOLSON-BAILEY model is equal to 5 per<br />

unit time, but neither the a in HOLLINa'S disc model nor a(X) in eq. (4c. 7) is /i<br />

per unit time.) Let us examine the nature <strong>of</strong> a(X) more closely.<br />

If the density <strong>of</strong> P's (i. e. X) is very low, then<br />

lim a(X)=2RV1.<br />

X+O<br />

So, if R <strong>and</strong> 171 are independent <strong>of</strong> X, eqs. (4e. 6) or (4e. 7) converges with the NICHOLSON-<br />

BAILEY equation (cf. eq. (4b. 3)), or with HOLLISG'S be<strong>for</strong>e the introduction <strong>of</strong> the<br />

factor h. This is reasonable because, if the prey density is low, a large part <strong>of</strong> the<br />

predator's movement should be undirected <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e independent <strong>of</strong> the location<br />

<strong>of</strong> prey individuals, in which case the analogy <strong>of</strong> unimolecular reaction is approxi-


47<br />

mately true. Consequently, HOLLING'S disc equation should be a good approximation<br />

<strong>for</strong> low prey densities.<br />

On the other h<strong>and</strong>, if X is very large, then<br />

lira a(X)=lim 2V~/v'X.<br />

X~o~ X~oo<br />

Thus, when X increases, a (X) decreases in inverse proportion to the square root <strong>of</strong><br />

X. This is because the probability <strong>of</strong> any one P being found in the recognition<br />

radius <strong>of</strong> a O increases as X increases, <strong>and</strong> so in its extreme situation, the movement<br />

<strong>of</strong> the Q is largely governed by the location <strong>of</strong> P's. Under these circumstances, the<br />

movement <strong>of</strong> the Q can no longer be independent <strong>of</strong> the location <strong>of</strong> P's. More<br />

precisely, if the Q is most attracted to the closest one <strong>of</strong> the P's found in the recog-<br />

nition area, then O's path consists largely <strong>of</strong> the distance to the closest P. As already<br />

demonstrated by MORISITA (1054) <strong>and</strong> CLARK <strong>and</strong> EVANS (1954), the distance between<br />

an arbitrarily selected point <strong>and</strong> the closest one <strong>of</strong> a number <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>omly distributed<br />

points in a two-dimensional plane is inversely proportional to the square-root <strong>of</strong> the<br />

density <strong>of</strong> the r<strong>and</strong>om points. The same conclusion applies when the recognition<br />

radius R is large relative to X. This suggests that HOLLING'S disc equation would<br />

show its bias, even if X is low, when R is very large. Conversely, if R is <strong>comparative</strong>ly<br />

small, the disc equation is again a good approximation even if X is high. That is to<br />

say, the equation holds whenever the R is reduced to an immediate area around the<br />

prey so that a capture is made practically by bodily contact, <strong>and</strong> this confirms my<br />

previous conclusion.<br />

It should be pointed out, however, that the inverse proportionality <strong>of</strong> a(X) to<br />

the square-root <strong>of</strong> X holds only when the hunting area is a two-dimensional plane.<br />

If the hunting area is one-dimensional, such as thin branches <strong>of</strong> a tree, a (X) is in-<br />

versely proportional to X;<strong>and</strong> if it is a three-dimensional space, a(X) is inversely<br />

proportional to the cubic-root <strong>of</strong> X (<strong>for</strong> the pro<strong>of</strong>, see CLARK 1956).<br />

The above investigation suggests that if HOLLING'S disc eq. (4c. 6) is applied to<br />

my present model, the coefficient a thus estimated will show a decreasing trend as X<br />

increases. MORRIS (1063) applied the disc equation to the instantaneous hunting curve<br />

observed with Podisus maculiventris (Hemiptera) eating larvae <strong>of</strong> Hyphantria cunea<br />

(Lepidoptera). (MORRIS kept the density <strong>of</strong> the prey constant during the observation<br />

to meet the condition <strong>for</strong> an instantaneous hunting curve.) It was found that, when<br />

the factor h was assumed to be constant, the factor a decreased as the prey density<br />

was increased. MORRIS thought that this was due to satiation by the predator. While<br />

this interpretation is reasonable, it is equally tenable that the trend observed was due<br />

to a decrease in the factor a as in my a(X). Hence, it is not known, unless the<br />

experiment is designed accordingly, to what extent the trend is attributable to satiation<br />

<strong>and</strong> to what extent to the geometric property <strong>of</strong> the hunting behaviour.<br />

MILLER (1960) pointed out that both HOLLING'S <strong>and</strong> WATT'S equations (to be<br />

reviewed in the next subsection) tended to deviate from the observed trend in various


48<br />

animals when the prey densities were increased. My factor a(X) suggests that in<br />

the case <strong>of</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>, in which satiation might not be important, a deviation from<br />

the observed would become greater as host density became higher.<br />

Now, the h<strong>and</strong>ling-time factor h can be incorporated into my model by eliminating<br />

t~ from eqs. (4c. 2) <strong>and</strong> (4e. 7), i.e.<br />

n = {a (X) XYt}/{1 + a (X) hX} (4e. 8).<br />

Some interesting characteristics are observed in curves generated by eq. (4e. 8).<br />

The shape <strong>of</strong> the curves will change with changes in the ratio between the speed <strong>of</strong><br />

the predators' undirected movement <strong>and</strong> directed movement (see Fig. 6). As pointed<br />

out already, eqs. (4e. 6) or (4e. 7) has two asymptotes, the one <strong>for</strong> X-~0 where n approac<br />

2RVI Xt,, a straight line passing through the origin <strong>of</strong> the n-X coordinates; <strong>and</strong> the<br />

other <strong>for</strong> X~oo where n-~2V~v'Xt,. There<strong>for</strong>e: (1) If the speed <strong>of</strong> undirected movement<br />

is not lower than that <strong>of</strong> directed movement, i.e. V~ > V~, the curve generated<br />

by eq. (4e. 8) will be a monotonically increasing one with its tangent ever-decreasing;<br />

this is very much like the curve generated by HOLLING'S or IVLEV'S equations. (2) If<br />

Va is considerably smaller than V2, the curve may be a gentle sigmoid. (3) If V1<br />

<strong>and</strong> V~ have a certain ratio, the curve may be approximately linear <strong>for</strong> a wide range<br />

<strong>of</strong> the prey density, in which case NICHOLSON-BAILEY'S model, rather than HOLLING'S<br />

or IVLEV's, could be a better approximation (the Iinearity must sooner or later break<br />

down as X increases, however). All <strong>of</strong> these trends have been observed with living<br />

predators <strong>and</strong> parasites (see e.g. HOLLING 1959a). Equation (4e. 8) would not,<br />

however, generate very strongly sigmoid curves. A probable mechanism which causes<br />

such a strong sigmoid <strong>for</strong>m has been discussed elsewhere (RoYAMA 1970).<br />

R= 2<br />

v2-- 200<br />

h = 0.0'1<br />

(~) V~ = 600<br />

{2) = 50<br />

{3) = 1 0<br />

Fig. 6. Three examples <strong>of</strong> curves generated by eq. (4e. 8).<br />

:~X<br />

Now, from eqs. (4e. 8) <strong>and</strong> (3. 4), we have<br />

dx/dt = -a (x) xY/ {1 +a (x) hx} ,<br />

<strong>and</strong> so the overall hunting equation <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong> is obtained by integrating the above<br />

differential equation, i.e.<br />

Yt = (1/2R V1) [ln (nR 2x) - nR 2x + (nR 2x) 2/2.21 - (nR ~x) 3/3.3 ! + ....<br />

]xo


49<br />

-- -- rr R~x Xo<br />

+ (l/V2) [2fO(V'2rrxR)l/x + (e )/rrR] x +h(xo-x) (4e. 9)<br />

(the expression [f (0)] 0~ reads f(Oo) -f(O)).<br />

Although I am unable to solve eq. (4e. 9) with respect to z:xo-x, the hunting surface<br />

on the Z-Xo-Yt coordinate system can be calculated numerically with a computer.<br />

Incidentally, the numerical values <strong>for</strong> the normal (or GAUSSIAN) integral ~ in eq.<br />

(4e. 4) can easily be obtained from a table <strong>of</strong> the normal (or GAUSSIAN) probability<br />

function.<br />

Surfaces generated by eq. (4e. 9) will almost certainly fit a wide variety <strong>of</strong> hunting<br />

surfaces actually exhibited by various predators, since the equation has four (rather<br />

than two as in HOLLING'S <strong>and</strong> IVLEV'S ones) independent coefficients, R, V,, Vz, <strong>and</strong><br />

h, to be estimated from the observed surfaces. This suggests that a close fit does<br />

not prove anything, unless the coefficients are measured independently <strong>and</strong> directly<br />

in separate observations, which at the moment is technically difficult. However, the<br />

model was designed primarily to show what degree <strong>of</strong> deviation <strong>of</strong> a(X) from the<br />

constant a in simpler <strong>models</strong> could be expected. No attempt was there<strong>for</strong>e made to<br />

fit the equation to any observed data.<br />

Another inquiry by a similar model will be made, secondly, into a situation in<br />

which a predator or a parasite continues to hunt without leaving the area each time<br />

a victim is captured, so that the starting point <strong>of</strong> a new path <strong>of</strong> search is the place<br />

where the previous victim is captured. This situation is too complex to h<strong>and</strong>le with<br />

an analytic (mathematical) method, <strong>and</strong> so a Monte Carlo simulation has been used.<br />

Two hundred points, representing prey, were plotted at r<strong>and</strong>om on a sheet <strong>of</strong><br />

graph paper (30• each point being given a circle <strong>of</strong> 2cm in radius. The<br />

predator's starting point was determined also at r<strong>and</strong>om. The direction <strong>of</strong> walk was<br />

then determined again by chance with predetermined probability <strong>of</strong> occurrence; five<br />

angles measured from a reference line, which was the previous path except <strong>for</strong> the<br />

starting point, i.e. 0, • <strong>and</strong> • were given an equal chance <strong>of</strong> occurrence (a<br />

backward movement with reference to the immediately previous path was excluded).<br />

When the predator had moved up to the periphery <strong>of</strong> a circle, it went to the centre,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the point was removed permanently from the area. If a second point was within<br />

the 2-cm recognition radius from that point, the predator went straight to the second<br />

one to catch it. If another point was not within 2cm, the predator determined its<br />

direction in the manner described above, <strong>and</strong> carried on. A part <strong>of</strong> this simulation<br />

experiment is shown in Fig. 7. The number <strong>of</strong> points removed is plotted on the<br />

horizontal axis against the distance traversed by the predator on the vertical axis<br />

(Fig. 8).<br />

If we assume an equal speed <strong>of</strong> movement <strong>for</strong> the undirected <strong>and</strong> the directed<br />

paths (i. e.<br />

VI= Vz), the distance traversed, L, per unit area is the product <strong>of</strong> the<br />

speed <strong>of</strong> movement <strong>and</strong> the predator-hours. Thus, if VI~V2=I, then L=Yt,. Also<br />

the effect <strong>of</strong> h<strong>and</strong>ling time is not essential in the present discussion <strong>and</strong> so is not


50<br />

Fig. 7. I{OYAMA'S second geometric model in which predator Q continues to search<br />

<strong>for</strong> prey without shifting the starting point after each capture. Other features<br />

are the same as in Fig. 5.<br />

(3<br />

LI.I<br />

0<br />

~E<br />

hl<br />

r,."<br />

U")<br />

I.I.I<br />

200<br />

~.~ 100<br />

I'--<br />

n"<br />

R= 2CN<br />

~._--<br />

I.L<br />

0<br />

6<br />

Z<br />

I I f I I I<br />

I00 200 300 400 500 600<br />

DISTANCE TRAVERSED (CM)<br />

Fig. 8. An observed relationship (solid line with black dots) between the<br />

number <strong>of</strong> prey taken (vertical axis) <strong>and</strong> the distance traversed by a<br />

predator (horizontal axis) in a Monte Carlo simulation <strong>of</strong> the <strong>predation</strong><br />

model <strong>of</strong> continuous search (cf. Fig. 7). The broken curve is generated<br />

by eq. (4e. 9) <strong>for</strong> R=2, 12"1=1, <strong>and</strong> h=0 as in the present Monte Carlo<br />

simulation. For details see text.<br />

considered; thus L= Yr. So the horizontal axis in Fig. 8 is equivalent to the Yt-axis<br />

in Fig. 2a, <strong>and</strong> the vertical axis is <strong>of</strong> course the z-axis. Thus the graph in Fig. 8 is<br />

equivalent to a cross-section in which x0=200/(30x39) parallel to the z-Yt plane in<br />

Fig. 2a, i.e. it is a competition curve in the NICHOLSON-BAILEY sense.<br />

The curve with solid circles is not monotonic but wavy, <strong>and</strong> there is a clear ten-


5T<br />

dency towards a number <strong>of</strong> miniature waves. The explanation <strong>of</strong> this trend is rather<br />

simple. As the direction <strong>and</strong> the length <strong>of</strong> each path are determined by chance, the<br />

predator's track is a kind <strong>of</strong> MA~KOV'S chain, although the probability distributions<br />

<strong>of</strong> both the direction <strong>of</strong> directed paths <strong>and</strong> the length <strong>of</strong> all paths are dependent<br />

stochastically on the location <strong>of</strong> the prey which were encountered9 This is a complex<br />

(or a generalized) 'r<strong>and</strong>om walk'9 Thus the predator's path <strong>of</strong> search was <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

deflected in an irregular manner <strong>and</strong>, because <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> a 'r<strong>and</strong>om walk', the<br />

predator tended to stay in a restricted area <strong>for</strong> some time. Consequently, the prey<br />

density in that vicinity was gradually depleted, <strong>and</strong> this caused a temporary drop in<br />

the predator's hunting efficiency. However, as the density <strong>of</strong> prey in the vicinity was<br />

lowered, the predator's undirected paths increased in length <strong>and</strong> eventually led to a<br />

pIace where the prey had not been exploited. Then the hunting efficiency increased<br />

temporarily be<strong>for</strong>e decreasing again. Thus the hunting curve was a kind <strong>of</strong> composite<br />

competition curve <strong>and</strong> became wavy. Figure 8 also includes a curve (broken line)<br />

calculated from eq. (4e. 9) <strong>for</strong> the same values <strong>of</strong> R <strong>and</strong> V (h=0, <strong>of</strong> course)9 The<br />

observed curve in this simulation model is always lower than the calculated one,<br />

but this is because factor h is not considered (see p. 54).<br />

Now, the same principle should also apply to an indiscriminate parasite9 The<br />

same set-up was used again except that none <strong>of</strong> the points (hosts) was removed from<br />

the area <strong>and</strong> parasitized hosts were left exposed to super<strong>parasitism</strong>. It was assumed<br />

that one egg was laid at each encounter. The result <strong>of</strong> the first experiment is shown<br />

•,,• 100<br />

ILl<br />

N<br />

I-.-<br />

8C<br />

/-<br />

2 OBS. .o'"<br />

/ "/jl~ -o<br />

c>- ..... ~ THEOR. /-'/<br />

O'/<br />

oJ"<br />

o<br />

n<br />

k.-<br />

if)<br />

O<br />

212<br />

tL<br />

O<br />

o<br />

Z<br />

9<br />

4s<br />

2c<br />

/<br />

~<br />

..ff7<br />

I I L i i i<br />

0 50 73 93 I10 13C, ~5~<br />

No. OF EGGS LAID (.n)<br />

Fig. 9. An observed relationship (solid line with black dots) between<br />

the total number <strong>of</strong> hosts parasitized (z) <strong>and</strong> the total number <strong>of</strong><br />

eggs laid (n) in the~first serie~<strong>of</strong> Monte Carlo simulation <strong>of</strong> the<br />

<strong>parasitism</strong> model <strong>of</strong> continuous search. The broken line with open<br />

circles is a theoretical relationship expected from the binomial distribution9


52<br />

in Fig. 9, in which the total number <strong>of</strong> hosts parasitized, z, is plotted on the vertical<br />

axis against the total number <strong>of</strong> eggs laid, n, on the horizontal axis. It should be<br />

noticed, however, that this method <strong>of</strong> presentation is comparable to that in Fig. 8<br />

<strong>for</strong> the <strong>predation</strong> model, showing the effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing return3. Here again, a<br />

wavy tendency is discernible, which shows that the occurrence <strong>of</strong> super<strong>parasitism</strong> is<br />

periodically increased in accordance with changes in the number <strong>of</strong> eggs laid.<br />

One important difference between the <strong>predation</strong> model <strong>and</strong> the present <strong>parasitism</strong><br />

one is that the number <strong>of</strong> hosts freshly found hardly increased after 130 eggs had<br />

been laid in this example. This is because the parasite could not get out <strong>of</strong> the area<br />

already searched because no host individuals were removed from the area <strong>and</strong> the<br />

parasite repeatedly re-parasitized them. Also, it is noticeable that the observed number<br />

<strong>of</strong> hosts attacked was always lower than that expected in a r<strong>and</strong>om encounter, i.e.<br />

a binomial series (SToY's <strong>for</strong>mula; see w 4g), because <strong>of</strong> excessive super<strong>parasitism</strong>.<br />

Although the indiscriminate parasite in this model is unable to avoid superparasit-<br />

ism, to continue searching in the area already searched is obviously inefficient. If,<br />

however, the parasite periodically moved to start a new search elsewhere, it would<br />

raise its hunting efficiency, <strong>and</strong> so would be favoured by natural selection. If the<br />

parasite is unable to know whether the area where it starts a new search has already<br />

been searched by itself or by other parasites, the shift <strong>of</strong> hunting area can be only<br />

at r<strong>and</strong>om. Of course, a r<strong>and</strong>om shift <strong>of</strong> hunting area certainly involves the risk <strong>of</strong><br />

hitting an area which has already been searched by itself or by other parasites; but<br />

the parasite at least avoids the disadvantage <strong>of</strong> staying in an area which has just<br />

been searched by itself.<br />

In the second series <strong>of</strong> 'experiments', the parasite left the area after each five<br />

eggs had been laid <strong>and</strong> travelled <strong>for</strong> a certain distance in a r<strong>and</strong>omly determined<br />

direction (Fig. 10 a). Again, a wavy trend is seen, but the observed number <strong>of</strong> hosts<br />

v<br />

: ~- OBS,<br />

80<br />

....... THEOR.<br />

/o".-'" /<br />

__N<br />

nr<br />

ff~ 4O<br />

l.--<br />

ffl<br />

0<br />

212<br />

~ 20<br />

o<br />

6<br />

Z<br />

o 40 ~ 1oo 12o ~o<br />

No. OF EGGS LAiD (n)<br />

Fig. 10a. A result from the second series <strong>of</strong> Monte Carlo simulations<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> similar to the first series, except that a parasite, after<br />

every five eggs have been laid, moves 7. 5 unit lengths in a r<strong>and</strong>omly<br />

determined direction.


.... -o<br />

~ 300<br />

O<br />

1.1.1<br />

N<br />

I.--<br />

9 0BS.<br />

o- ..... ~ THEOR.<br />

20O<br />

nr"<br />

n<br />

U~<br />

U')<br />

0<br />

"r 100<br />

b-<br />

o<br />

Z<br />

/<br />

I<br />

I<br />

I I i i i i i J<br />

SO0 1000<br />

No. OF EGGS LAID (n)<br />

Fig. 10 b. A relationship between z <strong>and</strong> n actually observed with a parasite<br />

species, Encarsia <strong>for</strong>mosa G^~AN, laying eggs on its host species,<br />

Trialeurodes vaporariorum (W~sTW.), in BURNETT'S experiment. The<br />

solid line with black dots is the observed relationship <strong>and</strong> the broken<br />

line with open circles is the one expected from the binomial distribution<br />

(adapted from BURI~ET1" 1958; table IV).<br />

attacked is much closer to that expected by THOMPSON'S <strong>for</strong>mula <strong>for</strong> a r<strong>and</strong>om distri-<br />

bution <strong>of</strong> eggs. Thus the efficiency was on the whole raised in the second experi-<br />

ment as compared with the first; it should be noticed that <strong>for</strong> the lower numbers <strong>of</strong><br />

eggs laid, less super<strong>parasitism</strong> occurred than expected in a r<strong>and</strong>om distribution.<br />

Only two published sets <strong>of</strong> data are available to compare with my simulation<br />

model; in other published data, changes in the distribution pattern were not observed<br />

in accordance with the number <strong>of</strong> eggs laid. The first is BURNETT'S (1958) <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong><br />

the distribution <strong>of</strong> the eggs laid by Encarsia <strong>for</strong>mosa GAHAN on Trialeurodes vapora-<br />

riorum (WESTW.), in which periodic deviations from a r<strong>and</strong>om distribution in accord-<br />

ance with the number <strong>of</strong> parasites searching is clearly shown.<br />

For <strong>comparative</strong><br />

purposes, the number <strong>of</strong> hosts attacked is plotted against the number <strong>of</strong> eggs laid<br />

by all parasites (Fig. 10b, adapted from BURNETT'S table IV). A striking similarity,<br />

in the way that the observed curve deviates from the expected, is immediately apparent<br />

in Fig. 10a<strong>and</strong> b.<br />

BURNETT (Op. cit.) also showed a periodic deviation from a r<strong>and</strong>om distribution<br />

in accordance with changes in host density, rather than parasite density. Although I<br />

did not attempt to make any simulation experiment to compare with this experiment<br />

by BURNETT, the result may be deduced from Fig. 10a <strong>and</strong> b. Obviously, the curves<br />

shown in Fig. 10a <strong>and</strong> b are cross-sections <strong>of</strong> the hunting surface (as in Fig. 3a)<br />

parallel to the z-Yt plane, whereas the figure <strong>for</strong> BURNETT'S second experiment is<br />

a cross-section parallel to the z-xo plane. Now, the periodicity <strong>of</strong> waves (or wave<br />

length) is likely to be subject to change according to the initial prey density x0.<br />

That is, it is likely that the wave length becomes longer as x0 increases, since the


54<br />

effect <strong>of</strong> local depletion <strong>of</strong> prey upon the hunting efficiency will be less at higher<br />

values <strong>of</strong> x0. If a cross-section parallel to the z-xo<br />

circumstances, it should again be wavy.<br />

plane is observed under these<br />

A similar tendency to periodic deviation from a r<strong>and</strong>om distribution in accordance<br />

with changes in the host density was shown by SIMMONDS (1943, see also citation by<br />

WILLIAMS 1964). SIMMONDS, <strong>and</strong><br />

odic deviation in relation to the<br />

SIMMONDS' experiments, however,<br />

WILLIAMS as well, presented <strong>and</strong> analysed the peri-<br />

parasite/host ratio, rather than to the density. In<br />

parasite density was kept constant <strong>and</strong> host density<br />

changed <strong>for</strong> ratios between 1/200 <strong>and</strong> 1/25, but <strong>for</strong> those between 2/25 <strong>and</strong> 10/25 the<br />

parasite density was changed <strong>and</strong> the host density kept constant.<br />

There<strong>for</strong>e, the<br />

<strong>for</strong>mer corresponds to a cross-section parallel to the z-xo plane in the hunting surface,<br />

but the latter is a cross-section parallel to the z-Yt<br />

parable even if the ratio declines continually.<br />

plane, <strong>and</strong> so they are not com-<br />

Keeping this point in mind, one can<br />

compare my simulation model <strong>and</strong> SIMMONDS' observation, <strong>and</strong> find again a close simi-<br />

larity between them. It should be borne in mind that from the st<strong>and</strong>point <strong>of</strong> my<br />

simulation model, it is not the parasite/host ratio which is essential: it is the geo-<br />

metric properties <strong>of</strong> parasites' searching activity, changing as the densities change,<br />

that results in the pattern described above.<br />

Now, a question is posed as to whether the wavy trend in the hunting surface is<br />

inherent in <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>. As already shown, a hunting curve comes closer<br />

to the one expected in the r<strong>and</strong>om encounters between prey <strong>and</strong> predators, <strong>and</strong><br />

between hosts <strong>and</strong> parasites, when the predators, or parasites, shift their hunting area<br />

frequently.<br />

Of course, an approach to the curve expected in r<strong>and</strong>om encounters<br />

suggests a rise in the average hunting efficiency. This is, however, just an apparent<br />

relationship, because the time needed to h<strong>and</strong>le a victim has been excluded in the<br />

above <strong>models</strong>. If, in reality, a hunter shifts its hunting area much too <strong>of</strong>ten, the time<br />

involved in travelling from place to place will also increase. Consequently, the advan-<br />

tage <strong>of</strong> shifting will eventually be cancelled by the disadvantage.<br />

Hence, there must<br />

be an optimal frequency <strong>of</strong> shifts <strong>and</strong> an optimal distance (average) <strong>of</strong> travel that<br />

result in the highest hunting efficiency. There<strong>for</strong>e, a perfectly smooth hunting surface<br />

would not at any rate be expected.<br />

If, however, the prey or host individuals also<br />

move around independently <strong>of</strong> each other <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> the predators or parasites, then<br />

r<strong>and</strong>om encounters might again be expected.<br />

It should be mentioned that the wavy pattern <strong>of</strong> a hunting curve (i. e. z plotted<br />

against n) is caused entirely by uninterrupted searching in the first simulation experi-<br />

ment, i.e. the predator's path is continuously increased with time. If the experi-<br />

ment was designed, however, so that the paths <strong>of</strong> some predators consisted <strong>of</strong> a<br />

number <strong>of</strong> short ones, as in the second simulation experiment, the wavy trend will<br />

be less pronounced. If the predator's path was completely discontinuous, that is, if n<br />

was varied entirely by Y, <strong>and</strong> t was extremely short, the waves would eventually<br />

disappear. However, as long as the path <strong>of</strong> each predator is allowed to be continuous


55<br />

<strong>for</strong> a sufficiently long period <strong>of</strong> time, as in experiments on insect parasites cited in<br />

this section, the effect <strong>of</strong> the uninterrupted searching will not be eliminated entirely,<br />

<strong>and</strong> hence the wavy trend will result.<br />

Finally, it should be mentioned that my simulation <strong>models</strong> are not a postulational<br />

hypothesis but suggest some points to be borne in mind in order to make observa-<br />

tions systematic. A problem is left unconsidered as to what would be expected when<br />

the distribution <strong>of</strong> prey or hosts is non-r<strong>and</strong>om. However, the assumption <strong>of</strong> a non-<br />

r<strong>and</strong>om distribution <strong>of</strong> the prey or hosts further requires the consideration <strong>of</strong> non-<br />

r<strong>and</strong>om searching by predators or parasites. As countless non-r<strong>and</strong>om distributions<br />

or non-r<strong>and</strong>om searching patterns are conceivable from a theoretical point <strong>of</strong> view,<br />

it is impractical to try every combination <strong>of</strong> them.<br />

The one way to tackle the<br />

problem is to assume that natural selection will favour those predators or parasites<br />

which adjust their searching pattern in such a way that the highest efficiency is<br />

achieved. Then our task in model building is to find out the best searching pattern<br />

<strong>and</strong> to compare it with observations. My theoretical <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> this problem will be<br />

published elsewhere, however.<br />

f). WATT'S equation<br />

WATT (1959) proposed an equation which describes the relationship between the<br />

attacking <strong>and</strong> attacked species <strong>and</strong> which has been admired as one <strong>of</strong> the most precise<br />

<strong>and</strong> complete equations proposed to date (HoLLING 1966). The equation was fitted<br />

to some observed data <strong>for</strong> various parasites <strong>and</strong> predators in order to demonstrate<br />

its high descriptive power.<br />

WATT'S equation, however, is most difficult to comprehend, firstly because the<br />

definition <strong>of</strong> some notations is not clear, secondly because some assumptions are<br />

incomprehensible, <strong>and</strong> thirdly because there seem to be some errors in mathematical<br />

operation.<br />

In order to show the above points, WATT'S own presentation (WATT 1959, p. 133)<br />

will be quoted first <strong>and</strong> will later be compared with my general <strong>for</strong>mulae shown in<br />

w 3. The following quotation is verbatim except <strong>for</strong> equation numbers, the omission<br />

<strong>of</strong> one unnecessary equation, <strong>and</strong> changes in three symbols, i.e. g->r, a->a, <strong>and</strong> bo B.<br />

"Definition <strong>of</strong> Symbols:<br />

Na the number attacked<br />

No the initial number <strong>of</strong> hosts or prey vulnerable to attack<br />

P<br />

A<br />

K<br />

the number <strong>of</strong> parasites or predators actually searching<br />

coefficient <strong>of</strong> attack, the Na per P (an instantaneous rate)<br />

the maximum number <strong>of</strong> attacks that can be made per P during<br />

the period the No are vulnerable.<br />

"Since we seek an integral equation <strong>of</strong> <strong>for</strong>m Na :f(No, P), this could be obtained<br />

from a partial differential equation <strong>of</strong> type<br />

ON.~/ONo=r~(No, P) (4f. 1)


56<br />

or one such as<br />

ON~/OP=rz(No, P) (4f. 2).<br />

"The reason <strong>for</strong> starting with (4f. 1) rather than (4f. 2) was that the structure<br />

(4f. 1) should have was more intuitively obvious. In general, there will probably be<br />

more than one road to a complex integral equation, <strong>and</strong> a large part <strong>of</strong> the problem<br />

<strong>of</strong> obtaining it has been solved when we have ascertained the easiest route.<br />

"Equation (4f. 3) states that all parasites or predators can generate a total <strong>of</strong> PK<br />

attacks, <strong>and</strong> ON.#ONo diminishes gradually as NA approaches this maximum.<br />

ON~/ONo = PA (PK- N.4) (4f. 3)<br />

"However, the larger A is, the greater dA/dP will be [For this statement to be<br />

consistent with eq. (4f. 4) below, it must be ]dA/dPL rather than dA/dP: TANAKA<br />

in lit.I, because it will be more difficult <strong>for</strong> parasites or predators to find unattacked<br />

host or prey. At the same time, dA/dP [This must be [dA/dP[ again] must decrease<br />

in inverse ratio to P, because the greater P is, the greater inter-attack competition<br />

will be. This competition might take any <strong>for</strong>m from active interference to superpara-<br />

sitism. The above ideas are expressed in the equation<br />

dA/dP= - [~A/P (4f. 4)<br />

or<br />

A =trP-~ (4f. 5)<br />

where ~ <strong>and</strong> /~ are positive constants. Substituting (4f. 5) in (4f. 3) we get<br />

ON.~/ONo = PerP-~ (PK- N.4) (4f. 6)<br />

<strong>and</strong> integrating,<br />

NA=PK(1-e aNoP ) (4f. 7)."<br />

This is the first part <strong>of</strong> WATT'S modelling process, <strong>and</strong> some statements need to<br />

be reinterpreted <strong>for</strong> the following reason.<br />

First, the definition <strong>of</strong> Na is insufficient, since it does not specify whether the<br />

density <strong>of</strong> the attacked species is (1) subject to reduction as it is attacked, or (2)<br />

kept constant. If it is (1), Na is equivalent to my notation z, but if (2), N~ must be<br />

equivalent to n.<br />

Although WATT was not specific in this respect, it seems certain<br />

that he was aiming at the evaluation <strong>of</strong> z rather than n, since he stated, in the<br />

sentence following eq. (4f. 3), "because it wilt be more difficult <strong>for</strong> parasites or pred-<br />

ators to find unattacked hosts or prey", <strong>and</strong> also because his equation was fitted to<br />

data in which the reduction in the attacked individuals was unmistakable.<br />

Let us there<strong>for</strong>e assume (1), from which it automatically follows that No <strong>and</strong> P<br />

are equivalent to x0 <strong>and</strong> Y, respectively, in my notation.<br />

Also it is clear that the<br />

model is concerned with animals with discrete generations, because no account is<br />

taken <strong>of</strong> any changes in the density <strong>of</strong> the attacking species during the period the<br />

attacked species is vulnerable. Thus, WATT'S eq. (4f. 7) must be what I called an<br />

overall hunting equation, i.e. z=F(xo, Y, t), in which t is not considered as a vari-<br />

able. In fact, the factor t in WATT'S equation is concealed in factor K <strong>and</strong>, hence,<br />

is treated as constant, as will be shown later. Thus, NA=f(No, P) must be equivalent


57<br />

to z=F (xo, Y, t). Also one must remember that z should not under any circum-<br />

stances exceed x0 as no animal can eat more than is supplied.<br />

This is synonymous<br />

with saying that NA should not exceed No no matter how large P is. However, the<br />

calculation <strong>of</strong> N,,=lim f(No, P) as in eq. (4f. 7) shows the following results:<br />

p~<br />

when 1) 0~2, NA-~c~,<br />

2) ~=2, Na-~KNo, <strong>and</strong><br />

3) ~2, NA-~O,<br />

The first case is <strong>of</strong> course contradictory, <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e the coefficicnt t~ should not<br />

be smaller than 2. However, WATT did not give any such restriction to /~. Now, if<br />

we assume that no social interference between individuals <strong>of</strong> the attacking species is<br />

involved, then theoretically all the attacked individuals must eventually be wiped out<br />

if P increases indefinitely, i.e. NA must tend to No under these circumstances. The<br />

only possible instance in which NA can tend to No is the second case in which /~=2.<br />

However, since NA-~ozKNo there, ezK ought to be unity to be consistent with the<br />

above condition, i.e. NA-)No. In the meantime, ez <strong>and</strong> K are defined by WATT as<br />

constants.<br />

Then no matter what situation is considered (i. e. whether or not the<br />

system under consideration involves social interaction), the relationship ezK=I should<br />

hold. So that eq. (4f. 5) becomes A = 1/KP~ which should hold <strong>for</strong> all real <strong>and</strong> positive<br />

values <strong>of</strong> P. It follows that the smaller P is, the larger will A be without any limit.<br />

On the other h<strong>and</strong>, the coefficient A is defined by WATT as "the NA per P (an<br />

instantaneous rate)". So, it has to be concluded that N• per P-~c~ when P becomes<br />

infinitesimally small. This <strong>of</strong> course contradicts the assumption that each individual<br />

attacker has a capacity limited by K.<br />

In the third case, where /~2,<br />

NA-~0, suggesting that if social interference is<br />

involved, no attack could be made when the attacking species is crowded. Although<br />

this suggestion sounds reasonable, it is only superficial, because it does not remove<br />

the contradiction with respect to A <strong>and</strong> K as pointed out above.<br />

In subsequent<br />

paragraphs, it will be shown that WATT made serious mistakes in mathematics which<br />

reflect a certain misconception in his model-building approach, <strong>and</strong> that what is re-<br />

presented by the factor ~ is an artifact.<br />

Clearly, the partial derivatives ~NJONo <strong>and</strong> ON.~/OP are equivalent to Oz/Oxo <strong>and</strong><br />

Oz/OY, respectively, in my notations. The first is the tangent <strong>of</strong> cross-sections <strong>of</strong> the<br />

hunting surface f(No, P), equivalent to F(x0, Y) <strong>of</strong> my notation, parallel to the N•<br />

-No (or Z-Xo) plane; <strong>and</strong> the second is the tangent <strong>of</strong> cross-sections parallel to the<br />

N.~-P (or z-Y) plane. Hence, the functions rl <strong>and</strong> r2 should satisfy the following<br />

three conditions.<br />

No <strong>and</strong> P respectively, we have<br />

(1), a mathematical condition : integrating rl <strong>and</strong> r2 with respect to<br />

<strong>and</strong><br />

f lvo rldN~=NA+c~<br />

f p r2dP=N.4+c2


58<br />

where ci <strong>and</strong> ce are integral constants. Hence, the following relationship should hold:<br />

f ~f,dN~-cl= f<br />

r~dP-c~.<br />

That is, the functions rl <strong>and</strong> r2 are not independent <strong>of</strong> each other.<br />

(2), an ecological condition that the function rl should reflect: since rl is a partial<br />

derivative ON~/ONo, it should reflect the limited capacity <strong>of</strong> each predator according<br />

to its maximum number <strong>of</strong> attacks, i.e.K.<br />

(3), an ecological condition that the function r2 should reflect: since r2 is a partial<br />

derivative ONA/~P, it should reflect the effect <strong>of</strong> both types <strong>of</strong> competition, i.e. the<br />

effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns <strong>and</strong> the effect <strong>of</strong> social interference.<br />

In the derivation <strong>of</strong> eq. (4f. 7), WATT evaluated the factor A arbitrarily, neg-<br />

lecting the first condition <strong>and</strong> part <strong>of</strong> the third condition, i.e. the effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing<br />

returns.<br />

Although it seems as though WATT was considering the effect <strong>of</strong> compe-<br />

tition, i.e. condition (3), his consideration in terms <strong>of</strong> the factor A was concerned<br />

only with the effect <strong>of</strong> social interference. This is obvious because eq. (4f. 4) does<br />

not involve No, whereas the effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns should be a function <strong>of</strong><br />

No. The neglect <strong>of</strong> the effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns in WATT'8 mathematics, <strong>and</strong><br />

hence the failure to determine the function r2 in relation to r~, resulted in the contra-<br />

diction when eq. (4f. 7) was regarded as an overall hunting equation.<br />

My alternative interpretation <strong>of</strong> eq. (4f. 7) is there<strong>for</strong>e that it is an instantaneous<br />

hunting equation equivalent to eq. (3. 1); i.e. Na is not z, but n. It automatically<br />

follows that No is X, <strong>and</strong> this means that the density <strong>of</strong> the attacked species is kept<br />

constant during the attack period. Then P is Y. Now, K was defined by WATT as<br />

'the maximum number <strong>of</strong> attacks made per P during an attack period' (though the<br />

expression 'per P' is not clear, this is perhaps 'per individual predator'). Then K<br />

corresponds to the expression bt used in my toss-a-ring experiment, i.e. b was the<br />

frequency <strong>of</strong> tosses per unit time so that the maximum possible number <strong>of</strong> attacks<br />

<strong>for</strong> time t per individual ring was bt (see w 4d).<br />

mine as above, except A, eq. (4f. 3) is rewritten as<br />

On/OX= A Y(Ybt - n)<br />

So, changing WATT'S notations to<br />

<strong>and</strong> eliminating A from the above equation, using the relationship A--aY-a (cf. eq.<br />

(4f. 5) in which P~ Y, <strong>and</strong> a-=a), we have<br />

n=b(1-e -aYI-pX) Yt (4f. 8).<br />

If we set ~=1, then eq. (4f. 8) becomes<br />

n=b(1-e -~) Yt,<br />

<strong>and</strong> this equation is identical to eq. (4d. 3), i.e. IVLEV'S equation with the addition<br />

<strong>of</strong> the attack period t <strong>and</strong> the density, Y, <strong>of</strong> the attacking species.<br />

While WATT stated that the structure <strong>of</strong> eq. (4f. 3) was intuitively obvious, it<br />

appears that intuition was a poor guide in this case, <strong>and</strong> the structure has become<br />

intelligible in the light <strong>of</strong> the toss-a-ring experiment.<br />

That is, eq. (4f. 7), which is<br />

equivalent to eq. (4f. 8), represents a generalized instantaneous equation <strong>of</strong> the toss-


59<br />

a-ring model, m winch the area <strong>of</strong> the ring (t. e. a=a) diminishes, or increases, by<br />

the factor Y:-P, as the number <strong>of</strong> rings per unit area, i.e. Y, increases. There<strong>for</strong>e<br />

the equation is considered to imitate the effect <strong>of</strong> social interaction incorporated into<br />

the effective area <strong>of</strong> each attacking individual; the effective area is now aY a-~ rather<br />

than simply a.<br />

Clearly, (1) if 0


60<br />

diminishing returns (e. g. super<strong>parasitism</strong>). However, eq. (4f. 7)could behave as<br />

though the effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns was taken into account. This is because <strong>for</strong> a<br />

certain range <strong>of</strong> B (i. e. in the vicinity <strong>of</strong> 2) the cross-section <strong>of</strong> the hunting surface<br />

parallel to the NA-P plane (i. e. the z-Y plane in my notation) resembles, though<br />

only superficially, the effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing returns. There<strong>for</strong>e, if the equation is fitted<br />

to data in which the density <strong>of</strong> available attacked individuals is reduced, the estimate<br />

<strong>of</strong> 0 will inevitably be close to 2.<br />

Such estimates <strong>of</strong> 0 are artifacts which, while<br />

they avoid the logical contradiction that is inevitably encountered when N• applies<br />

to a diminishing population, reflect no logical interpretation with respect to social<br />

interactions. These clearly illustrate that fitting a curve is not in itself a verification<br />

<strong>of</strong> the model concerned. It is only necessary to add that case c2~ under C2 in w 2<br />

actually happened.<br />

In the second half <strong>of</strong> WATT's modelling process, it was assumed that the rela-<br />

tionship between the number <strong>of</strong> attacking individuals, P~, in one generation <strong>and</strong> that<br />

<strong>of</strong> the next generation, P~, could be derived from the following differential equation<br />

dP~/dNo~,: -cP~<br />

<strong>and</strong> this, according to WATT, yields<br />

-cNop<br />

P. =P2,e<br />

where No. is the initial density <strong>of</strong> the attacked species in the first generation, <strong>and</strong> c<br />

is a proportionality factor. The equation is totally incomprehensible, <strong>and</strong> I do not<br />

quite underst<strong>and</strong> why the attacking species manages to rear as many <strong>of</strong>fspring as<br />

the parents when food is practically unobtainable, i.e.<br />

when No, approaches zero.<br />

Because all the variables involved in the above equation should be able to take any<br />

positive real values, it should hold when No, tends to zero, in which case P~ tends to<br />

P..<br />

When he was working on gravitation, ISAAC NEWTON invented calculus, by which<br />

he managed to reduce the scattered distribution <strong>of</strong> the gravitational <strong>for</strong>ce on a solids<br />

sizable body into a sizeless point called the centre <strong>of</strong> gravity. The principle is to<br />

start from a simpler <strong>and</strong> self-explanatory situation <strong>and</strong> to draw a conclusion that is<br />

not intuitively obvious. As already mentioned in w 3, the process <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> is <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

self-explanatory only when an instantaneous situation is assumed, <strong>and</strong> this is why we<br />

<strong>of</strong>ten start from a differential equation.<br />

It may well happen, too, that an empirical<br />

equation is first found to describe an observed trend, then a differential equation is<br />

derived from this empirical one to see if it indicates something immediately intel-<br />

ligible. The differential equations used by WATT fit into neither <strong>of</strong> the two cases. Even<br />

though WATT claimed that eq. (4f. 3) was obvious, it turned out to be due to his<br />

illusion. The same criticism applies to IVLEV (see w 4d).<br />

If a differential equation<br />

does not suggest anything obvious, why do we have to start from it ? Clearly, the<br />

differential equations used by WATT <strong>and</strong> IVLEV have nothing to do with inferences;<br />

the same applies to the array <strong>of</strong> differential equations listed by WATT (1961, figure


61<br />

7; or 1968, figure ii. 2). It is a misuse <strong>of</strong> mathematical language as a <strong>for</strong>mal system<br />

<strong>of</strong> inferences, <strong>and</strong> its consequence is now obvious.<br />

Finally, model oscillations in the densities <strong>of</strong> an attacking <strong>and</strong> attacked species<br />

calculated by MILLER (1960) <strong>and</strong> IT5 (1963) using WATT'S equation must be men-<br />

tioned.<br />

Both authors found stable oscillations rather than <strong>of</strong> a relaxation type as<br />

expected in the NICHOLSON-BAILEV model. While the difficulty <strong>of</strong> the latter model<br />

was thus removed, this was done at the expense <strong>of</strong> logical meaning. First, because<br />

WATT'S equation is an instantaneous one, there is no way to estimate the final density<br />

<strong>of</strong> the attacked population. There<strong>for</strong>e in these examples the final density had to be<br />

calculated by subtracting the number eaten from the initial density, i.e. No-NA<br />

(=X-n in my notation). This was <strong>of</strong> course logically incorrect, but a numerical<br />

value was obtained anyway. In fact, as pointed out in the early part <strong>of</strong> w 3, n is<br />

always larger than z, <strong>and</strong> so the calculated value <strong>of</strong> X-n is smaller than xo-z. In<br />

other words, the estimates <strong>of</strong> the final density by MILLER <strong>and</strong> by IT3 must have<br />

been lower than they should actually be.<br />

Secondly, however, the factor /~ in the<br />

vicinity <strong>of</strong> 2 sets the upper limit <strong>of</strong> the number attacked when the density <strong>of</strong> the<br />

attacking species increases, <strong>and</strong> in conjunction with factor K <strong>and</strong> a in the range <strong>of</strong><br />

not greater than ozK=l, the upper limit <strong>of</strong> the number attacked could be set much<br />

lower than it could in the NICnOLSON-BAILEY model. In other words, with ~-~2 <strong>and</strong><br />

aK_


62<br />

hunting t, <strong>and</strong> z the total number <strong>of</strong> hosts parasitized per unit area by the end <strong>of</strong><br />

that period. If encounters between parasites <strong>and</strong> hosts are at r<strong>and</strong>om (<strong>for</strong> the defini-<br />

tion <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om encounter, see w 4e), a further increment <strong>of</strong> the number <strong>of</strong> eggs laid,<br />

i.e. An, will be distributed with equal probability among the unparasitized <strong>and</strong> the<br />

already parasitized hosts (this statement is not strictly true; see later). Then, letting<br />

Az be an increment in the number <strong>of</strong> hosts parasitized, the ratio Az/Jn must be<br />

proportional to the proportion <strong>of</strong> the hosts unparasitized, i.e.<br />

,~z/,~n = ( X- z) IX<br />

<strong>and</strong> thus <strong>for</strong> An-~O, the following differential equation is obtained,<br />

dz/dn = (X-z)/X (4g. 1)<br />

<strong>and</strong> integrating, we get<br />

z = X(1 - e -~/x) (4g. 2).<br />

This is THOMPSON'S equation. Note that the meaning <strong>of</strong> the differential equation in<br />

eq. (4g. 1) is entirely different from that in eq. (3. 5) which represents a <strong>predation</strong><br />

process.<br />

There<strong>for</strong>e the derivation <strong>of</strong> a parasite model by means <strong>of</strong> a differential<br />

equation as above may be justified, but this is not inconsistent with my earlier state-<br />

ment in w 3.<br />

If eq. (4g. 2) is compared to eq. (3. 20), it will be found that the probability <strong>of</strong><br />

a host individual receiving no parasite egg, i.e. Pr{0}, is equal to the expression<br />

e -'/z which is the 0-term <strong>of</strong> a PoIssON series. So it becomes clear that THOMPSON'S<br />

statement (in italics above) is not quite rigorous but requires an additional condi-<br />

tion: the statement is correct if the number <strong>of</strong> hosts is sufficiently large so that the<br />

probability <strong>of</strong> a given host individual being found by each parasite individual is<br />

sufficiently small.<br />

In a laboratory experiment, however, the animals are <strong>of</strong>ten confined to a small<br />

cage, <strong>and</strong>, unless the density <strong>of</strong> hosts is sufficiently large, the condition which could<br />

ensure the PoIssoN distribution is not satisfied. So, let us look at the problem more<br />

closely from the probabilistic point <strong>of</strong> view. As already mentioned, the precise ex-<br />

pression <strong>of</strong> 'r<strong>and</strong>om encounters' is that each host individual in the area concerned has<br />

an equal probability <strong>of</strong> being parasitized. Let this probability be p <strong>and</strong> the probability<br />

that a given host individual does not receive any egg be q, i.e. p+q=l.<br />

Then, the<br />

frequency distribution <strong>of</strong> nM eggs over the hosts in area M will be given by the<br />

following bionomial series,<br />

(p+q)'~ =q'~ +nMq~t-lp/1 !+ nM(nM- 1) q'~-2pz/2 ! + ...... +p~M<br />

where q~ is the proportion <strong>of</strong> hosts unparasitized, so that 1-q "~ is the proportion<br />

<strong>of</strong> the hosts parasitized.<br />

If the density <strong>of</strong> hosts is X, the probability <strong>of</strong> each host<br />

being parasitized (i. e. p) is equally 1/MX, <strong>and</strong> as q=l-p, we have<br />

q~ = (1 - 1/MX) "~.<br />

Also, the total number <strong>of</strong> hosts parasitized per area M (i. e. zM) is the proportion<br />

<strong>of</strong> hosts parasitized (i. e. 1-q "~) multiplied by the total number <strong>of</strong> hosts in area M<br />

(i. e. MX), thus


<strong>and</strong> so<br />

zM=MX {1- (1-1/MX) n~}<br />

z =X {1 - (1-1/MX) ~'~} (4g. 3).<br />

This is SwoY's model <strong>for</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om <strong>and</strong> indiscriminate <strong>parasitism</strong> (appendix to SALT<br />

1932), <strong>and</strong> holds <strong>for</strong> all values <strong>of</strong> p; that is, STOY'S equation is more general than<br />

THOMPSON'S.<br />

In order to compare THOMPSON'S model with STOY'S, let us calculate the deriva-<br />

tive dz/dn in eq. (4g. 3) which is differentiable <strong>for</strong> all real values <strong>of</strong> MX larger than<br />

1, <strong>and</strong> thus<br />

dZ (MX ln MX ) X-z<br />

dn MX- 1 X (4g. 4).<br />

If eqs. (4g. 4) <strong>and</strong> (4g. 1) are compared, it is at on ceclear that THOMPSON's differential<br />

equation is a special case <strong>of</strong> eq. (4g. 4) in which the expression in the brackets tends<br />

to 1. This occurs only when MX tends to infinity, i.e.<br />

lim MX ln{MX/(MX-1)} =1<br />

MX~oo<br />

<strong>and</strong> MX~c~ means that p=I/MX->O. This is <strong>of</strong> course the well-known relationship<br />

between the POISSON <strong>and</strong> bionomial distributions; i.e. the PolssoN distribution is a<br />

special case <strong>of</strong> the binomial distribution in which p is sufficiently small.<br />

The above analysis illustrates that although THOMPSON'S reasoning, as it appeared<br />

in his differential eq. (4g. 1) under the assumption <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om encounters, was appar-<br />

ently reasonable, it was in fact not sufficiently precise because it is not obvious that<br />

the equation requires the condition p~0. Here again a differential equation was used<br />

rather uncritically; it should have been noticed that calculus was not quite an appro-<br />

priate method <strong>of</strong> reasoning in a <strong>parasitism</strong> model.<br />

The above argument, however, excludes the possibility that THOMPSON'S eq.<br />

(4g. 1) might be more appropriate than STOY'S if, paradoxically, r<strong>and</strong>om encounters<br />

are not assumed. That is to say, there is a possibility, though not demonstrated here,<br />

that some non-r<strong>and</strong>om encounters might again satisfy the condition expressed in eq.<br />

(4g. 1). One such example is given in my simulation model <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> in w 4e, in<br />

which the observed frequency was fairly close to that expected in a PoIssoN series,<br />

while the underlying mechanism is clearly <strong>of</strong> a non-PoIssoN type. TORII (1956) has<br />

already pointed out that an agreement between the observed <strong>and</strong> expected frequencies<br />

alone would not imply that the same mechanism is involved, as it is possible that<br />

different mechanisms could yield an almost identical frequency distribution.<br />

suggests that an agreement between the observed <strong>and</strong> the expected in THOMPSON'S<br />

equation could be entirely irrelevant to the test <strong>of</strong> the hypothesis <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om encoun-<br />

ters. Conversely, it may be suggested that the assumption <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om encounters is<br />

not very important.<br />

63<br />

This<br />

In passing, we may note that TORII (1956) also showed that the index <strong>of</strong> disper-<br />

sion, i.e. the variance-mean ratio, which is unity in the PolssoN distribution, could<br />

statistically be less than unity if the binomial series was involved. This is because,


64<br />

in the binomial series, the variance is npq as against the mean which is np, <strong>and</strong> so<br />

the variance-mean ratio is npq/np=q (where n is the number <strong>of</strong> eggs laid, p the<br />

probability <strong>of</strong> a given host receiving one egg, <strong>and</strong> q=l-p).<br />

small, the variance-mean ratio, which is q=l-p,<br />

If p is not sufficiently<br />

must be smaller than unity. This<br />

refutes the common belief that if the ratio is less than unity the parasites concerned<br />

are <strong>of</strong> the discriminate type. The interpretation <strong>of</strong> frequency distribution <strong>of</strong> parasite<br />

progeny on hosts should there<strong>for</strong>e be made with the utmost caution.<br />

Another relevant point here is the use <strong>of</strong> the negative binomial series developed<br />

by BLISS <strong>and</strong> FISHER (1953). The expectation <strong>of</strong> the 0-term (the proportion <strong>of</strong> hosts<br />

receiving no parasite eggs) in the negative binomial series is given by<br />

Pr{0} = (1 +m/k) --k (4g. 5)<br />

where m is the mean number <strong>of</strong> eggs per host, which in my notation is n/X. Sub-<br />

stituting n/X <strong>for</strong> m in eq. (4g. 5) we have<br />

Pr {0} = (1+ n/kX) -k (4g. 6).<br />

Here k is a positive constant, <strong>and</strong> if k-~oo the negative binomial distribution coincides<br />

with the PoISsON distribution, <strong>and</strong> if k-~0, it becomes the logarithmic series (BLISS<br />

<strong>and</strong> FISHER 1953). When we choose an appropriate value <strong>of</strong> k, the negative binomial<br />

series describes various types <strong>of</strong> non-r<strong>and</strong>om distribution (excluding an even distribu-<br />

tion). Substituting the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq. (4g. 6) <strong>for</strong> Pr{O} in eq. (3.20) we have<br />

z =X {1 - (1 +n/kX) - k} (4g. 7).<br />

GRIFFITHS <strong>and</strong> HOLLING (1969) proposed the use <strong>of</strong> eq. (4g. 7) <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> in<br />

which the parasite egg distribution is not r<strong>and</strong>om (or, more precisely, the variance-<br />

mean ratio is larger than unity).<br />

The negative binomial series, however, does not<br />

distinguish the type <strong>of</strong> underlying mechanisms involved, <strong>and</strong> so it is purely a descrip-<br />

tive <strong>for</strong>mula. Although the negative binomial distribution is identical with what is<br />

known as the POLYA-EGGENBERGER distribution (IT(5 1963) which has a specific model<br />

structure, I found it difficult to relate this model structure to the process <strong>of</strong> para-<br />

sitism. In passing, although GRIFFITHS <strong>and</strong> HOLLING (lOt, cit.) suggested the use <strong>of</strong><br />

eq. (4g. 7) also <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong>, it is not legitimate to do so.<br />

As already discussed in w 3, <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> <strong>models</strong> will not differ from<br />

each other in the <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> the instantaneous hunting function, i.e. eq. (3. 1) holds<br />

<strong>for</strong> both cases as long as the prey or host density can be considered to be constant.<br />

In <strong>parasitism</strong>, the overall equation in general <strong>for</strong>m is eq. (3.22), in which f(X) can<br />

be anything as long as it is not influenced by the pattern <strong>of</strong> encounters between<br />

parasites <strong>and</strong> hosts. There<strong>for</strong>e, THOMPSON did not have to assume a particular <strong>for</strong>m<br />

<strong>for</strong> f(X) but only needed to say that n was the number <strong>of</strong> eggs laid.<br />

It does not<br />

matter whether n is an observed value or an assumed function <strong>of</strong> X, as long as one<br />

can justify the assumption <strong>of</strong> the POISSON or similar distribution. Consequently, if<br />

f(X) Yt in eq. (3. 1) is used as the theoretical expectation <strong>of</strong> n, the following simul-<br />

taneous equations will hold,<br />

,~n =f(X) Y, Jt


Az/An = (X-z)/X<br />

from which we get<br />

dz/dt = (X- z)f(X) Y/X<br />

<strong>and</strong> integrating we have<br />

z =X(1- e -f(I) r~/I) (4g. 8).<br />

Clearly, HOLLING'S introduction <strong>of</strong> the factor h, or IVLEV'S equation justified in a<br />

toss-a-ring model, does not influence the assumption <strong>of</strong> Po~ssoN-type encounters, <strong>and</strong><br />

so eqs. (4c. 10) or (3.24) as specific <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> eq. (4g. 8) are obtained <strong>for</strong> these two<br />

cases respectively (n in STOY'S equation can <strong>for</strong> the same reason be replaced by<br />

f (x) Yt).<br />

In the NICHOLSON-BAILEY <strong>predation</strong> model, however, it is crucial to assume a<br />

particular type <strong>of</strong> f(X), because the evaluation <strong>of</strong> the overall hunting equation is<br />

influenced by f(X), even if encounters are made at r<strong>and</strong>om. As already shown, if<br />

f(X) is a linear function <strong>of</strong> X, the overall equation is coincidentally <strong>of</strong> the same<br />

<strong>for</strong>m as THOMPSON'S, but if f(X) is <strong>of</strong> HOLLING'S type or IVLEV'S, the overall equation<br />

is eq. (4c. 9) or (3. 12), which are quite different from eqs. (4c. 10) <strong>and</strong> (3. 24) respectively.<br />

THOMPSON (1939) argued against NICHOLSON-BAILEY (1935) <strong>and</strong> stated that, while<br />

the NICHOLSON-BAILEY assumption <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om searching was not justifiable, the fact<br />

that THOMPSON himself arrived at the same equation "merely illustrates the well-<br />

known fact that identical quantitative relationship may be developed from biologically<br />

different postulates, since these postulates are not, in their ontological significance,<br />

incorporated in the <strong>for</strong>mula". Now it is clear that THOMPSON was mistaken in that<br />

he was comparing incomparables, i.e. <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>, <strong>and</strong> that the resem-<br />

blance does not signify anything. The ontological significance <strong>for</strong> the two postulates<br />

becomes obvious under general circumstances in which f(X) is not a linear function<br />

<strong>of</strong> X.<br />

WATT (1959), in his review <strong>of</strong> various <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> <strong>models</strong>, made<br />

similarly erroneous comments that the NICHOLSON-BAILEY <strong>and</strong> THOMPSON equations<br />

are identical, <strong>and</strong> furthermore, that THOMPSON'S equation should have a constant<br />

factor in front <strong>of</strong> the exponent, to express the efficiency <strong>of</strong> different parasites. The<br />

suggestion is nonsensical because the exponent n/X (in my notation) is just a straight-<br />

<strong>for</strong>ward "mean number <strong>of</strong> parasite eggs per host" laid by all the parasite individ-<br />

uals <strong>for</strong> the entire observation period, <strong>and</strong> the mean number is a mean number no<br />

matter how efficient are the parasites concerned.<br />

plied by a constant factor signify ?<br />

65<br />

What does a mean number multi-<br />

A correct interpretation is as follows. (1) If n<br />

is an observed value, it should be observed under st<strong>and</strong>ard conditions in which the<br />

time <strong>of</strong> observation <strong>and</strong> the densities <strong>of</strong> both host <strong>and</strong> parasite populations, i.e. t, X,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Y respectively, are fixed (a st<strong>and</strong>ard may be determined conveniently); then<br />

differences between values <strong>of</strong> n <strong>for</strong> different parasite species reflect differences in<br />

efficiency between the species. (2) If n is an expected value, i.e. a theoretical expec-<br />

:tation when t, X, <strong>and</strong> Y are known, it should be replaced by f(X) Yt as in eq.


66<br />

(4g. 8). Then f(X) <strong>for</strong> a st<strong>and</strong>ard X is the efficiency <strong>of</strong> the species concerned.<br />

further discussion, see the appendix to w 4i).<br />

It should be pointed out here that, on the whole, the review <strong>of</strong> <strong>models</strong> by WATT<br />

(1959) is invalid, firstly because his mathematics is <strong>of</strong>ten wrong, <strong>and</strong> secondly because<br />

he was confused between<br />

(For<br />

instantaneous <strong>and</strong> overall functions, between <strong>parasitism</strong><br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>predation</strong>, <strong>and</strong> between the Z-Xo <strong>and</strong> z-Y relationships. It should also be noticed<br />

that the criticism against the assumption f(x)=ax invalidating the NICHOLSON-BAILEY<br />

<strong>predation</strong> equation does not invalidate THOMPSON'S <strong>parasitism</strong> equation, since the latter<br />

does not assume f(x)=ax.<br />

h).<br />

The HASSELL-VARLEY model <strong>of</strong> social interference in parasites<br />

Although this model is called by the authors (HASSELL <strong>and</strong> VARLEY 1969) 'a<br />

new model' based on the NICHOLSON-BAILEY competition equation (see w it is in<br />

fact a special case <strong>of</strong> the generalized THOMPSON'S model <strong>for</strong> indiscriminate parasites,<br />

eq. (4g. 8), in which the instantaneous hunting function is a modified NICHOLSON-<br />

BAILEY linear function. As already pointed out, THOMPSON'S equation <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong><br />

takes the same <strong>for</strong>m as the NICHOLSON-BAILEY 'competition equation' <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong><br />

if the instantaneous hunting function f(X) is assumed to be a linear function <strong>of</strong> X,<br />

i.e. f(X) =aX, in which the coefficient a is the 'effective area <strong>of</strong> recognition per<br />

unit time'. Under these circumstances, the value <strong>of</strong> /~, as defined by eq. (4b. 8), becomes<br />

at, a constant.<br />

It has been shown in w 4e, however, that the /~ cannot be constant, but is at least<br />

a function <strong>of</strong> X, host density. HASSELL <strong>and</strong> VARLEY, however, found that in some<br />

published data the value <strong>of</strong> ~ was not independent <strong>of</strong> Y, parasite density. These data<br />

are shown graphically in Fig. 11; this is a reproduction <strong>of</strong> figure 1 in HASSELL <strong>and</strong><br />

VARLEY (1969) with a slightly different arrangement. These data show that the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> In ii tends to decrease as the value <strong>of</strong> In Y increases. The interpretation <strong>of</strong><br />

these relationships by HASSELL <strong>and</strong> VARLEY is that the parasites interfered with each<br />

other more strongly as their density increased, <strong>and</strong> hence the reduction in "the area<br />

<strong>of</strong> discovery", i.e. /f. The authors stated that "the striking feature <strong>of</strong> the relationships<br />

in (Fig. 11) is that they are linear over several orders <strong>of</strong> magnitude", <strong>and</strong> that "the<br />

data <strong>for</strong> Chelonus texanus CRESS. [curve (c)] cover a narrow range <strong>of</strong> parasite densities<br />

but seem to imply a curvilinear relationship".<br />

Thus, it was concluded that the relationships were described by the following<br />

<strong>for</strong>mula<br />

In ii=ln Q-m In Y (4h. 1)<br />

or<br />

= O Y-~ (4h. 1'),<br />

in which the factor Q is called "the quest constant" <strong>and</strong> m "the mutual interference<br />

constant".<br />

If the above relationships are incorporated into the NICHOLSON-BAILEY model


67<br />

0.200<br />

Iol<br />

0,100<br />

0.050<br />

0,020<br />

0,0]0<br />

0,005<br />

:O<br />

(~)0,002' , , , , T ~ I<br />

1.0<br />

W.<br />

0,05( 9<br />

I I I I I i m'f I<br />

10.0<br />

I n I I I I I II I I I<br />

100.0<br />

o.0~<br />

(el<br />

0,OLC<br />

0,00 ~ .<br />

0.002<br />

o.ool i i i i i i I i i i i i i i i I t i i i t i i i i I t<br />

1.o 1o.o IOO.O<br />

No. OF PARASITES PER FT 2<br />

Fig. 11. Observed relationships between the values <strong>of</strong> fi <strong>and</strong> parasite densities,<br />

in natural logarithmic scale on both axes. (a) Dahlbominus fuscipennis (ZETT.)<br />

attacking Neodiprion sertifer (GEoFr.) between 17. 5 <strong>and</strong> 24.0~ (BuRNETT<br />

1956; table I); (a') the same as (a) but below 17.5~ (b) Encarsia <strong>for</strong>mosa<br />

GAHAN attacking Trialeurodes vaporariorum (WEsrw.) (BURNETT 1958; table<br />

IV) ; (c) Chelonus texanus CRmss. attacking Ephestia kiihniella ZmLL. (ULLYEXT<br />

1949a; table II); (d) Cryptus inornatus PRAtt attacking Loxostege stricticalis<br />

L. (ULLYETT 1949b; table III); (e) Nemeritis canescens (GRAY.) attacking<br />

Anagasta kiihniella (ZsLL) (HuFFAK~m <strong>and</strong> KENN~rr 1969; figure 1). All figures,<br />

except (e), are calculated from original numerical data, <strong>and</strong> the densities <strong>of</strong><br />

parasites are expressed consistently as the number per square foot. However,<br />

the constant host density per square foot differs considerably between observations<br />

(i.e. 4/ft 2 in (a) <strong>and</strong> (a'), 2074 in (b), 3600 in (c), <strong>and</strong> 354 in (d)),<br />

<strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e these curves are not comparable with each other.


68<br />

(more correctly, into THOMPSON's equation, i.e. eq. (4g. 8), since the authors were<br />

dealing with <strong>parasitism</strong> rather than <strong>predation</strong>), the following relationship will be<br />

obtained:<br />

_Qyl-~.<br />

Z = X (1- e ) (4h. 2).<br />

The main theme <strong>of</strong> the HASSELL-VARLEY paper is to show that host-parasite<br />

oscillations, which are unstable under the NICHOLSON-BAILEY assumption <strong>of</strong> a constant<br />

~, can be stabilized if the value <strong>of</strong> m in eq. (4h. 1') is sufficiently large, so that the<br />

value <strong>of</strong> ~ becomes sufficiently small as Y increases. While the end conclusion by<br />

HASSELL <strong>and</strong> VARLEY, that the effect <strong>of</strong> social interference among parasites plays an<br />

important role in stabilizing host-parasite oscillations, might still be correct, their<br />

usage <strong>of</strong> eq. (4h. 2) as a basis <strong>of</strong> reasoning is not logically sound.<br />

First, if eq. (4h. 1) holds <strong>for</strong> any given constant value <strong>of</strong> Q <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong> all positive<br />

values <strong>of</strong> Y, then <strong>for</strong> m~0, the value <strong>of</strong> ~ increases without limit as Y increases.<br />

This is exactly the same misconception that is involved in WATT'S equation reviewed<br />

in ~4f; it has been shown that eq. (4f. 8) is a generalized instantaneous hunting equ-<br />

ation <strong>for</strong> the toss-a-ring model in which the effective area a diminishes by the factor<br />

YI-,~ as Y increases. If we use the same analogy, that the effective area a diminishes<br />

by the factor yl-.~ as Y increases, in the THOMPSONIAN model <strong>of</strong> the NICHOLSON-<br />

BAILEY type, rather than the toss-a-ring model, we have<br />

z :X(1-e -av'-~rt) (4h. 3).<br />

Equation (4h. 3) is perfectly equivalent to eq. (4h. 2) because, if the coefficients involv-<br />

ed in these two equations are estimated from the same set <strong>of</strong> data, the value <strong>of</strong> Q<br />

is the same as that <strong>of</strong> at <strong>and</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> m is the same as that <strong>of</strong> ~-1. As already<br />

pointed out in w 4f, however, the assumption that the effective area, d, changes by the<br />

factor yl-, as Y changes, is not acceptable.<br />

And if one criticizes NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong><br />

BAILEY in that the assumption <strong>of</strong> a constant a is biologically absurd, one may on the<br />

same logical basis criticize the postulation <strong>of</strong> an unlimited increase in 6 as equally<br />

absurd. It might have been that HASSELL <strong>and</strong> VARLEY, as well as WATT, thought<br />

that such an assumption was an approximation <strong>and</strong> could be used <strong>for</strong> practical purposes<br />

in the context <strong>of</strong> their argument. But, then, they should have referred to an objective<br />

criterion to set limits within which such an approximation could be tolerated <strong>for</strong> their<br />

further speculation on host-parasite oscillations based on that relationship. If, on the<br />

contrary, we start from an axiomatic view that the // will not exceed a certain finite<br />

value as Y decreases, a conclusion will be deduced that the relationship between the<br />

values <strong>of</strong> In gi <strong>and</strong> In Y has to be curvilinear. And from this point <strong>of</strong> view, it is<br />

obvious that every observed relationship in Fig. 11 is in fact curved to some degree;<br />

it varies from the most pronounced trend in (c) to the least pronounced one in (e).<br />

Secondly, it is clear, upon comparison with eq. (4h. 3), that eq. (4h. 2) ignores<br />

the fact that the d is also a function <strong>of</strong> X, the host density; the fact established in<br />

the preceding sections <strong>of</strong> this paper. Since HASSELL <strong>and</strong> VARLEY were fully aware


9<br />

<strong>of</strong> this fact, it is curious that they ignored it.<br />

One possible justification may be<br />

related to two statements. The first one (the last paragraph <strong>of</strong> the introductory part<br />

<strong>of</strong> their paper) stated:<br />

"These oscillations can be stabilized [the NICHOLSON-BAILEY equations generate<br />

host-parasite oscillations with ever-increasing<br />

amplitude] by reducing the area<br />

<strong>of</strong> discovery as parasite density increases, but changes in area <strong>of</strong> discovery in<br />

relation to host density do not promote stability".<br />

The second statement (the second <strong>and</strong> third paragraphs on p. 1135 <strong>of</strong> their paper)<br />

is summarized below:<br />

The NICHOLSON-BAILEY equation did not exactly fit the observed relationship<br />

between the winter moth, Operophtera brumata (L.), <strong>and</strong> its parasite Cratiech-<br />

neumon culex (MuELLER) in two aspects: (1) the calculated peak <strong>of</strong> the parasite's<br />

density lagged two generations after the peak <strong>of</strong> the host's density whereas the<br />

observed lag was only one generation; (2) while in the NICHOLSON-BAILEy model<br />

more than two parasite species could not coexist [because <strong>of</strong> the competitive<br />

exclusion <strong>of</strong> one species by another], there were several parasite species coexisting<br />

in the field. But, when eq. (4h. 2) was used instead <strong>of</strong> the NICHOLSON-BAILEY,<br />

it was found that both <strong>of</strong> the above difficulties disappeared.<br />

With respect to the first statement, it is certainly agreeable that reduction <strong>of</strong> "the<br />

area <strong>of</strong> discovery", i. e. d, in relation to increase in host density will not promote<br />

stability. It should be noticed, however, that such changes in the d tend to accelerate<br />

instability (see TINBERGEN <strong>and</strong> KLOMP 1960). This implies that the effect <strong>of</strong> changes<br />

in the d in relation to host density, which must be involved in actual host-parasite<br />

interaction systems, has to be counteracted by other factors, or conditions, more<br />

strongly than in a hypothetical situation in which changes in host density have no<br />

influence on the value <strong>of</strong> d. Since the HASSELL-VARLEY equation assumes that the d<br />

is independent <strong>of</strong> host density, this bias has to be cancelled out by another bias, <strong>and</strong><br />

this latter bias is in fact involved in the assumption expressed by eq. (4h. 1). Hence,<br />

the fact that the observed relationship between O. brumata <strong>and</strong> C. culex agreed with<br />

the theoretical relationship expressed in eq. (4h. 2) suggests that this model is another<br />

example <strong>of</strong> c21 under C2 in w 2.<br />

It was pointed out in w<br />

that HOLLING'S disc equation involved some bias, be-<br />

cause it assumed that the discovery <strong>of</strong> a prey was regarded as the capture <strong>of</strong> it.<br />

Nevertheless, the model enhanced the importance <strong>of</strong> the factor h, the h<strong>and</strong>ling time.<br />

By the same token, although these <strong>models</strong> involve certain contradictions, the HASSELL-<br />

VARLEY model, as well as WATT'S model, implies strongly the significance <strong>of</strong> social<br />

interference among parasites as one important regulatory mechanism in host-parasite<br />

interaction systems. As the effect <strong>of</strong> social interference seems very important, I shall<br />

investigate it more in detail in the following subsection.


7O<br />

i). A geometric model <strong>for</strong> social interaction among parasites (this <strong>study</strong>)<br />

In w 3, I introduced a function S, by which the effect <strong>of</strong> social interaction among<br />

attacking species upon the instantaneous hunting efficiency is indicated.<br />

Thus, if<br />

social interaction is involved, the instantaneous hunting equation <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong> is given<br />

by eq. (3. 14) rather than eq. (3. 4). As already explained, however, the instantaneous<br />

equation <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> does not take the <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> a differential equation as in eq.<br />

(3. 14), but, <strong>for</strong> indiscriminate parasites, it is expressed in terms <strong>of</strong> the number <strong>of</strong><br />

eggs laid per unit area, i.e. n, as in eq. (3. 1). Thus, the equation <strong>for</strong> indiscriminate<br />

<strong>parasitism</strong>, equivalent to eq. (3. 14) <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong>, will be written as:<br />

n=S(Y, X)f(X) Yt (4i. 1),<br />

<strong>and</strong> from eq. (3.22), we have an overall hunting equation <strong>for</strong> indiscriminate parasites<br />

as below:<br />

z=X{1-r (Y, X)f(X) Yt/X, V)} (4i. 2).<br />

In order to <strong>study</strong> some fundamental characteristics <strong>of</strong> the function S, I shall again<br />

use a geometric model similar to those used previously.<br />

Suppose, firstly, that a given parasite individual encounters, within an area 8<br />

around itself, other parasite individuals in the course <strong>of</strong> hunting.<br />

these other parasites encountered within the area 8 is 0, 1, 2 .......<br />

If the number <strong>of</strong><br />

or i, the instan-<br />

taneous hunting efficiency <strong>of</strong> the given parasite, i.e. f(X), is changed by factors 2o,<br />

21, ~2 ...... or 2~ respectively. It is conceivable, as a more general case, that 2 is<br />

influenced not only by the number <strong>of</strong> parasites in the 8, but also by the number <strong>of</strong><br />

hosts. This is because, as already pointed out in w 3, the effect <strong>of</strong>, say, interference<br />

might be strengthened or weakened if a lesser or greater number <strong>of</strong> hosts, respec-<br />

tively, is available within the 8. Thus, it is more appropriate to indicate the number<br />

<strong>of</strong> hosts too. Thus, 1~ is the index <strong>of</strong> the degree <strong>of</strong> social interaction when there<br />

are i parasites <strong>and</strong> j hosts within the area 8; it should be noted that both i <strong>and</strong> j<br />

take discrete values, 0, 1, 2 ..... , independently <strong>of</strong> each other.<br />

Secondly, let m (j) be the probability <strong>of</strong> finding j hosts within the 6. Then the<br />

average partial realization <strong>of</strong> the potential efficiency <strong>for</strong> a fixed value <strong>of</strong> i will be<br />

oo<br />

2~:~o(j). Similarly, let o(i) be the probability <strong>of</strong> finding i parasites within the 3.<br />

j-0<br />

Then the overall degree <strong>of</strong> changes in the instantaneous hunting efficiency <strong>for</strong> all j's<br />

<strong>and</strong> i's, i.e. S(Y, X), will be<br />

S(Y, X)= ~{ ~ 2~:~o(j)} o(i) (4i. 3).<br />

i=o j=0<br />

Now, ~o is the probability-distribution function <strong>of</strong> j (<strong>and</strong> can be determined when both<br />

the average number <strong>of</strong> hosts within the area 8 <strong>and</strong> its variance are known).<br />

So the<br />

oo<br />

value <strong>of</strong> ~2~jco(j) can be determined <strong>for</strong> a given value <strong>of</strong> X <strong>and</strong> <strong>for</strong> each value <strong>of</strong> i.<br />

j-0<br />

There<strong>for</strong>e, if the value <strong>of</strong> X is fixed in the following argument, the expression<br />

co<br />

~,~o(j) can be indicated simply by 2,(X). Then, eq. (4i. 3) will be written as<br />

j=o<br />

co<br />

S(Y, X) = ~ ,~,(X) o(i) (4i.4).<br />

i~0


71<br />

Now, if interference is involved among parasites, the value <strong>of</strong> ~l~ must decrease as i<br />

increases while j is fixed, i.e. 2~j~2~+lj, <strong>and</strong> facilitation is indicated conversely by<br />

,~ 2~+I(X), this indicates that the effect <strong>of</strong> interference<br />

outweighs that <strong>of</strong> facilitation, <strong>and</strong> vice versa. If all 2's are equally unity, this indicates<br />

that there is no social interaction, since from eq. (4i. 3),<br />

c~ co<br />

S(Y, X)=32,~o(j) ~o(i)=1.<br />

j=0 i=0<br />

In order to make further investigations <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> the function S <strong>and</strong> its<br />

influence on eq.<br />

(4i. 2), it may be more convenient to assume a certain concrete<br />

<strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> the function 0. For this purpose, let us assume that 0 is a PomsoN distribu-<br />

tion function, i.e.<br />

p (i) : e -~r' (8 Y') '/i ! (4i. 5),<br />

where 6Y' is the mean number <strong>of</strong> parasites within the area 6 around a given parasite<br />

individual (excluding the given individual), <strong>and</strong><br />

6Y' = 8Y/(1-e -~r) -1 (4i. 6).<br />

(For the derivation <strong>of</strong> eq. (4i. 6), see Appendix 3.)<br />

If we adopt at this stage the<br />

THOMPSONIAN model, i.e. eq. (4g. 8), as a concrete <strong>for</strong>m <strong>for</strong> eq. (4i. 2):<br />

z :X(1 -e- {f(X) Yt/X} e -~Y' X (2~ (X) (5II')*/i !} ) (4i. 7).<br />

The evaluation <strong>of</strong> the // in eq. (4i. 7) is, from eq. (4b. 8),<br />

d= {f (X)t/X} e -at' X {,is(X) (6Y')'/i !} (4i. 8).<br />

Equation (4i. 8) is compared to eq. (4h. 1'), <strong>and</strong> if we take the logarithm <strong>of</strong> both<br />

sides <strong>of</strong> eq. (4i. 8), i.e.<br />

In ii =In {f (X) t/X} + ln[e-Sr'X {~, (X) (6 Y') '/i !} ] (4i. 9),<br />

<strong>and</strong> this equation is directly comparable with eq. (4h. 1) or with the curves in Fig.<br />

11.<br />

The following are comparisons between eqs.<br />

(4h. 1) <strong>and</strong> (4i. 9), or between eqs.<br />

(4h. 1') <strong>and</strong> (4i. 8). First, while the value <strong>of</strong> In Q in eq. (4h. 1) is constant, the equi-<br />

valent term (i. e. the first term <strong>of</strong> the right-h<strong>and</strong> side) in eq. (4i. 9) is a function <strong>of</strong><br />

X; this term in eq. (4i. 9) can be treated as constant when the value <strong>of</strong> X is fixed,<br />

since the term is independent <strong>of</strong> Y.<br />

Secondly, while the second term <strong>of</strong> the right-<br />

h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq. (4h. 1) is a linear function <strong>of</strong> In Y, <strong>and</strong> independent <strong>of</strong> X, the equi-<br />

valent term in eq. (4i. 9) is not a linear function <strong>of</strong> In Y, <strong>and</strong> at the same time it is<br />

generally a function <strong>of</strong> X too; the term becomes independent <strong>of</strong> X only when 2,5 is<br />

independent <strong>of</strong> X <strong>for</strong> a given value <strong>of</strong> i. Thirdly, while the value <strong>of</strong> // in eq. (4h. 1)<br />

will increase without limit as Y decreases, the d in eq. (4i. 9) will converge to a<br />

finite value <strong>for</strong> a given fixed value <strong>of</strong> X, i.e.<br />

lim ?i =20 (X) f (X) t/X (4i. 10).<br />

Y~0<br />

Now, I shall examine the shape <strong>of</strong> curves that are generated by eq. (4i. 9), <strong>and</strong><br />

compare them with the observed data in Fig. 11. For the purpose <strong>of</strong> maintaining<br />

the generality <strong>of</strong> this model, the examination will be made analytically (i. e. mathemati-<br />

cally), <strong>and</strong> some concrete examples will be shown later.<br />

In order to find conditions


72<br />

Under which the value <strong>of</strong> In ~, <strong>for</strong> a given fixed value <strong>of</strong> X, is increasing, decreasing,<br />

or remaining constant, the first order partial derivative Oln ii/Oln Y will be calculated<br />

below:<br />

Oln ii .. dY' ~-Y,~+I (X) (~Y')~ 1 ) (4i. 11)<br />

Oln Y= o" ~ d Y ----;~Y'\~<br />

L z2,(x) ~ ~i )<br />

in which the derivative d Y'/dY is, from eq. (4i. 6):<br />

d Y'/d Y= { (1 - e -~r) -/~ Ye -~r } / (1 - e -st) 2>0.<br />

From the above evaluation <strong>of</strong> the partial derivative, the following conclusions will be<br />

drawn:<br />

(1). When Y->O, the partial derivative converges to zero, so that the curve is parallel<br />

to the In Y axis at the level <strong>of</strong><br />

In ii=ln{f (X)t/X} +ln 20(X)<br />

(see eq. (4i. 10)).<br />

~ oo<br />

(2). When Y is sufficiently small, so that ~ 2i+1 (X) (~Y') ~/i [ <strong>and</strong> 2E 2i (X) (~Y') ~/i !<br />

i=1 i~l<br />

are negligible as compared with ,h(X)<strong>and</strong> ;o(X) respectively, then<br />

Oln ii/Oln Y~--~Y(dY'/dY) {2~(X)/2o(X)-1}.<br />

There<strong>for</strong>e: (a) if 2~ (X) >20 (X) , i.e. social facilitation, the curve is increasing<br />

as Y increases, but (b) if At (X) ~ At(X) (SY')'/i [,<br />

i=0 i=0<br />

the partial derivative in eq. (4i. 11) is positive, <strong>and</strong> so the curve is increasing,<br />

but (b) if the effect <strong>of</strong> interference outweighs that <strong>of</strong> facilitation, the curve is<br />

decreasing.<br />

(4). When Y becomes sufficiently large, both lower <strong>and</strong> higher terms in the series<br />

{2,(X)(~Y')~/i!} will become negligible as compared with mid-terms, i.e. <strong>for</strong><br />

certain numbers k <strong>and</strong> k', we have<br />

co<br />

k t<br />

2~(X) (~Y')~/i ! ~ ~ At(X) (~Y')'/i !<br />

i=O<br />

i=k<br />

<strong>and</strong> the same applies to the series {A,+~(X)(~Y')*/i!}. Now it is unlikely that<br />

the degree <strong>of</strong> social facilitation increases indefinitely as i increases; the effect<br />

<strong>of</strong> interference must sooner or later become apparent. Hence, beyond a certain<br />

number <strong>for</strong> i, e. g. k, the inequality A, (X) >Ak+~ (X) will always hold. Under<br />

these circumstances, the partial derivative becomes always negative, <strong>and</strong> hence


73<br />

the curve must be decreasing <strong>for</strong> large values <strong>of</strong> Y. Although the pro<strong>of</strong> is<br />

curtailed here (because it can easily be confirmed by calculating the second<br />

order derivative), it should be mentioned that whether the rate <strong>of</strong> decrease is<br />

accelerated or decelerated depends on the rate <strong>of</strong> decrease in 2~(X) with increasing<br />

i; the curve is decreasing with an increasing rate if the value <strong>of</strong> 2<br />

decreases <strong>comparative</strong>ly fast as i increases, but the rate <strong>of</strong> decrease in the curve<br />

may become lower if the value <strong>of</strong> 2 decreases only slowly with increasing i.<br />

Some examples <strong>of</strong> curves generated by eq. (4i. 9) are shown in Fig. 12. These hypothetical<br />

curves cannot be compared directly with the observed curves <strong>and</strong> scattergram<br />

in Fig. 11, because the values <strong>of</strong> f(X), t, <strong>and</strong> ~ are not known in these observations.<br />

tOO<br />

0,50<br />

Xo(x} = 1.0<br />

e<br />

)h(x) = 0,5 I<br />

(i~<br />

1l<br />

0,10<br />

(1} o= 0<br />

(2) = 0,25<br />

0,0. ~<br />

13) = 0.50<br />

[z, ) = 0,75<br />

X<br />

:0<br />

l,f,-<br />

0<br />

=,<br />

~ 1.0C<br />

i ' ' ' I I<br />

0,1<br />

I I I L I I I i| I I I I I I I II I I<br />

1.0 10,0<br />

o~5o<br />

t<br />

{1)<br />

(2)<br />

0 , 2 0 , 5 , B,0,2,,,5 \ \,~,<br />

1.00 1,50 0,80 0.50 0.25 0,21 0.18 014 011 0.09 0.08 0.07<br />

1oo ,.,2o loo .... o.o oJo 0,50 o: 030 21; 0.27 ::: 0.25 ::; 0,23<br />

0,IC<br />

(1}<br />

..... 0:, . . . . . . . . ,'0 . . . . . . . . ,~0 ' '<br />

MEAN No. OF PARASITES PER EFFECTIVE AREA OF INTERACTION<br />

Fig. 12a. Hypothetical relationships between the values <strong>of</strong> ii/{f(X)t/X} <strong>and</strong> 6Y,<br />

(mean number <strong>of</strong> parasites per effective area) calculated from eqs. (4i. 6) <strong>and</strong><br />

(4i. 8), plotted in the natural logarithmic scale on both axes. The values <strong>of</strong><br />

2i (X) shown in the figure decreases as i increases, indicating that social<br />

interference only is considered here.<br />

Fig. 12b. The same as in Fig. 12a, but the value <strong>of</strong> 2i(X) increases from i=0<br />

to 1, indicating social facilitation, <strong>and</strong> then decreases towards higher values <strong>of</strong> i.


74<br />

However, the similarity in their shapes can be compared, if desired, by parallel<br />

translation <strong>of</strong> the relative position <strong>of</strong> the coordinate systems between the observed<br />

<strong>and</strong> hypothetical relationships, since the curves are drawn on the ln-ln scale. Then,<br />

the shapes <strong>of</strong> curves (a) <strong>and</strong> (a') in Fig. lla are comparable to a certain part <strong>of</strong><br />

curve (1) in Fig. 12b. The scattergram (e) in Fig. llb resembles curve (3) in Fig.<br />

12a, <strong>and</strong> so on. A strict comparison will not be attempted here <strong>for</strong> the above reason,<br />

however.<br />

It should be mentioned finally that fitting a straight line to these observed relationships<br />

may be justified only <strong>for</strong> the purpose <strong>of</strong> showing the declining tendency <strong>of</strong><br />

the value <strong>of</strong> ~ with increasing parasite density. In other words, the only conclusion<br />

that one can draw from such linear regression analysis is restricted to the suggestion<br />

that social interference is involved among parasites. However, there is no justified<br />

basis <strong>for</strong> adopting the hypothesis that the relationship is linear. Also, the assumption<br />

<strong>of</strong> the 'quest constant' by HASSELL <strong>and</strong> VARLEY (1969) (see w 4h) is justified only in<br />

the linear regression analysis <strong>of</strong> those data in which host density is known to be<br />

constant: the assumption is, however, hardly justified <strong>for</strong> speculating about the stability<br />

<strong>of</strong> host-parasite oscillations in which host density is changing all the time. The<br />

possibility <strong>of</strong> stable oscillations induced by social interference among parasites is yet<br />

to be demonstrated on a more reasonable basis; until it is, the suggestion by HASSELL<br />

<strong>and</strong> VARLEY is only a possibility.<br />

Appendix to w 4i. Is the concept <strong>of</strong> 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery' useful in studies<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> ?<br />

It has been shown in this paper that the concept <strong>of</strong> 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery', originally<br />

introduced by NICHOLSON (1933), cannot be used as a geometric attribute <strong>of</strong> the<br />

hunting process, since this simple, but highly hypothetical, concept involves a contradiction<br />

from the energetics point <strong>of</strong> view. But the concept has been shifted, as one<br />

way <strong>of</strong> expressing the hunting efficiency <strong>of</strong> predators or parasites, <strong>and</strong> has been widely<br />

used in the literature <strong>of</strong> population dynamics. The shifted concept is now defined as<br />

d in eq. (4b. 7) <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> in eq. (4b. 8) <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>. The definition, however,<br />

is not a straight<strong>for</strong>ward expression <strong>of</strong> hunting efficiency, as it is the logarithm<br />

<strong>of</strong> the reciprocal value <strong>of</strong> the survival rate, <strong>for</strong> a specified value <strong>of</strong> the initial density<br />

<strong>of</strong> the hunted species per hunter.<br />

My question here is whether this concept <strong>of</strong> 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery' is altogether<br />

useful in the <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>. Of course, the concept has played a<br />

significant role in its original context as a species specific constant under a given<br />

condition. But, once the original meaning <strong>of</strong> this index as a species specific constant<br />

is lost, what does the shifted concept signify ? Is there any particular advantage in<br />

using this index in shifted, <strong>and</strong> more general, situations ? In order to answer these<br />

questions, the index d will be evaluated in various <strong>models</strong> reviewed in this paper<br />

<strong>and</strong> will be compared with the instantaneous hunting function on which each model


75<br />

is based. As the evaluation <strong>of</strong> the//is in general different between <strong>models</strong> <strong>for</strong> preda-<br />

tion <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>, I shall use a symbol //, <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> i/2 <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>, so<br />

that:<br />

//1 : 1 x0<br />

In<br />

_r Xo--z<br />

ii2=l_ln<br />

X<br />

X-z"<br />

Also, the expression f(x, Y) will be used as a general <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> the instantaneous<br />

hunting function; x should be replaced by X <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>.<br />

1. The LOTKA-VOLTERRA model<br />

The definition <strong>of</strong> //1 does not fit here, since the model takes into account changes<br />

in the densities <strong>of</strong> both predator <strong>and</strong> prey populations during the hunting period, t.<br />

In other words, first, the value <strong>of</strong> Y, defined as a fixed predator density during t,<br />

does not exist, <strong>and</strong> secondly the value <strong>of</strong> z is influenced by mortality in the prey<br />

population due to factors other than <strong>predation</strong>.<br />

Under these general circumstances,<br />

the redefined concept <strong>of</strong> 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery' just does not exist. If, however, it is as-<br />

sumed as a specific case that mortality in the prey population does not occur except<br />

by <strong>predation</strong>, <strong>and</strong> that predator density is fixed during t, the model converges to the<br />

NICHOLSON-BAILEY model.<br />

2. The NICHOLSON-BAILEY model<br />

f(x, Y)=ax<br />

//1 =at.<br />

3. HOLLING'S disc model<br />

f(x, Y)=ax/(l+ahx)<br />

//1 :at-ahz/Y<br />

//2-at/(l+ahX), under the THOMPSONIAN assumption.<br />

4. IVLEV'S model<br />

f(x, Y) = b (1 - e -~')<br />

//1 = - (1/Y) In [-1 + (1/axo) In { (1 - e- axo) e- abYt + e- aXo } ]<br />

5. WATT's model<br />

Same as IVLEV'S, but<br />

a~ayl-~.<br />

iiz-bt(1-e-~x)/x, under the THOMPSONIAN assumption.<br />

6. ROYAMA'S model in w 4e<br />

f(x, Y) =a (x) x Yt/{1+ a (x) hx}<br />

where a (x) is defined in p. 46, w 4e.<br />

7. THOMPSON'S model<br />

~i2=n/XY,<br />

//1: may be evaluated from eq. (4e. 9), but since its analytical solution<br />

with respect to z is difficult, the evaluation will not be attempted<br />

here.<br />

62 =a (X) t~ {1 +a (X) hX}, under the THOMPSONIAN assumption.


<strong>and</strong> if n is evaluated as f(X, Y)Yt,<br />

ii2=f(X, Y)t/X.<br />

So, if f(X, Y)=aX as in the NICHOLSON-BA[LEY model,<br />

gi 2 - at.<br />

8. The HASSELL-VARLEY model<br />

ii2_O y -,~<br />

or, using my system <strong>of</strong> notations,<br />

5z =aY1-Bt.<br />

(Note that the THOMPSONIAN assumption is inherent to this model. )<br />

9. ROYAMA'S model in w<br />

52-e -~y' ~. ~2~(X) (~Y')~/i!} f(X)t/X, under the THOMPSONIAN assumption.<br />

i-0<br />

(For symbols, see eq. (4i. 8).)<br />

A comparison between the evaluation <strong>of</strong> the 52 <strong>and</strong> the function f (as in the<br />

second equation in 7 above) clearly shows that the 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery' <strong>of</strong> parasites<br />

<strong>of</strong> the indiscriminate type is directly related to the instantaneous hunting efficiency<br />

under the THOMPSONIAN assumption, i.e.<br />

lows a POISSON series.<br />

that the distribution <strong>of</strong> parasite eggs fol-<br />

In other words, the shifted concept <strong>of</strong> 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery',<br />

under the THOMPSONIAN assumption, still maintains its significance as an index <strong>of</strong><br />

the hunting efficiency <strong>of</strong> the parasites concerned.<br />

Such significance, however, is re-<br />

stricted only to the situation in which the THOMPSONIAN assumption holds. If a gener-<br />

alization is made to cover those indiscriminate parasites which do not distribute<br />

eggs after the POISSON fashion, those which discriminate between parasitized <strong>and</strong><br />

unparasitized hosts, or predators, the 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery' is not directly related to the<br />

hunting efficiency (compare, <strong>for</strong> instance, the 5Vs with corresponding f's in the above<br />

list). Furthermore, if the 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery' is calculated from data in which mortality<br />

in either hunting or hunted, or both, species occurs during the hunting period, as is<br />

the case with the LOTKA-VOLTERRA model, the index cannot be calculated.<br />

suggests that the calculation <strong>of</strong> the index from the data obtained in the field is theo-<br />

retically difficult, since mortality among the hunting species certainly occurs; calcu-<br />

lating the index by using the average density might be attempted, but then it has to<br />

be remembered that the index could not be linearly related to the efficiency.<br />

Thus, the concept <strong>of</strong> 'area <strong>of</strong> discovery' loses its significance on general ground,<br />

<strong>and</strong> there is no particular<br />

This<br />

advantage in using it. What is essential is to find the<br />

method <strong>of</strong> determining the instantaneous hunting function directly. This problem is,<br />

however, beyond the scope <strong>of</strong> this paper.<br />

j). HOLLING'S hunger model<br />

In w 3, I showed one method <strong>of</strong> incorporating the hunger component. The hunger<br />

level there was defined by function H which expressed a partial realization <strong>of</strong> the<br />

potential maximum per<strong>for</strong>mance that each predator can exert in hunting at given<br />

prey <strong>and</strong> predator densities. HOLLING (1966), in his <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> the <strong>predation</strong> behaviour


77<br />

<strong>of</strong> Hierodula crassa GIGLIO-TOs., approached the problem from a different direction.<br />

A female mantid, H. crassa, had been deprived <strong>of</strong> food <strong>for</strong> various lengths <strong>of</strong> time<br />

be<strong>for</strong>e flies (as prey) were <strong>of</strong>fered, <strong>and</strong> then the weight <strong>of</strong> flies eaten by the mantid<br />

was measured <strong>for</strong> each length-class <strong>of</strong> deprivation time. It was found that the weight<br />

<strong>of</strong> flies eaten increased as the deprivation time increased (<strong>and</strong> hence the mantid was<br />

hungrier), gradually leading to a plateau.<br />

The effect <strong>of</strong> hunger revealed itself not only in the mantid's increased dem<strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>for</strong> food to the level <strong>of</strong> satiation, but also in other components, e.g. the size <strong>of</strong> the<br />

area <strong>of</strong> reaction to the prey, speed <strong>of</strong> reaction, capture success, time spent in pursuing<br />

<strong>and</strong> in eating prey, <strong>and</strong> in the digestive pause. The influence <strong>of</strong> the deprivation time<br />

on each <strong>of</strong> these components was expressed by separate descriptive equations which<br />

were then synthesized to describe the relationship between the number <strong>of</strong> prey killed,<br />

the density <strong>of</strong> prey, <strong>and</strong> the time involved; the relationship thus obtained was illustrated<br />

by HOLLING (1966) in his figure 29.<br />

It is not my intention here to review critically every detail <strong>of</strong> HOLLING'S mathematical<br />

treatment, as the <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> the effect <strong>of</strong> hunger is still in its infancy, <strong>and</strong> also<br />

because I have not had sufficient experience with the problem myself. There are,<br />

however, a few things to be pointed out which HOLLINC seems to have missed.<br />

First, in this <strong>study</strong> again HOLLING did not recognize the effect <strong>of</strong> diminishing<br />

returns. It is not certain whether, in the observation that appeared in his figure 29,<br />

the prey density was kept constant during each set <strong>of</strong> observations. If so, the figure<br />

represents an instantaneous hunting surface equivalent to eq. (3. 18) in which dx/dt<br />

is written simply as n. If, however, the prey density was depleted during the course<br />

<strong>of</strong> observation, the figure represents a particular one <strong>of</strong> the overall hunting surfaces<br />

which is specific only to the mantid density used in this particular experiment. In<br />

this case, the density <strong>of</strong> predators should have been stated (the number <strong>of</strong> mantids<br />

used might have been just one, but as the fly density was expressed per square centimetre,<br />

the mantid density could not be unity). Also, the theoretical curve fitted to<br />

the data in the same figure is in fact an instantaneous rate, <strong>and</strong> so if the density was<br />

depleted, the comparison is not justifiable.<br />

Secondly, if our aim is to obtain an overall hunting equation, which is no doubt<br />

needed in population dynamics, an appropriate instantaneous hunting equation is<br />

required, the reason <strong>for</strong> this being explicit in earlier sections <strong>of</strong> the present paper.<br />

To obtain an instantaneous hunting equation, from which the final synthesis is made,<br />

the experimental analysis <strong>of</strong> the elemental components should have been designed<br />

accordingly. However, the observed relationship, <strong>for</strong> instance, between the amount <strong>of</strong><br />

prey eaten <strong>and</strong> the deprivation time in HOLLING'S original paper (1966, figures 4 <strong>and</strong><br />

5) is not appropriately tailored <strong>for</strong> the above purpose. This is because the time<br />

involved in consuming a given amount <strong>of</strong> prey was not explicitly considered by the<br />

author. Suppose the amount eaten up to the state <strong>of</strong> satiation (see HOLLING'S definition,<br />

1966 p. 16) was W~ <strong>and</strong> W2, when the deprivation time was 7", <strong>and</strong> 2"2, <strong>and</strong> tl


78<br />

<strong>and</strong> t2 hours were required to consume WI <strong>and</strong> Wz, respectively, after the flies were<br />

<strong>of</strong>fered. Then the rates <strong>of</strong> consumption W~/t~ <strong>and</strong> W2/t~ could be considered as<br />

instantaneous rates if tl <strong>and</strong> t2 were not too large. It might be technically difficult to<br />

keep tPs sufficiently small, <strong>for</strong> otherwise W's could not be measured. If t's are long,<br />

then digestion may take place during those hours, <strong>and</strong> this must influence the value<br />

<strong>of</strong> W. Then what is required is the measurement <strong>of</strong> the relationship between W <strong>and</strong><br />

t <strong>for</strong> various Tts, from which the instantaneous rate, d W/dt, may be obtained. And,<br />

<strong>of</strong> course, it is d W/dt which should be incorporated in the synthesized instantaneous<br />

hunting equation.<br />

Although HOLLING'S approach, which he called an 'experimental component analy-<br />

sis', is no doubt important, some technical difficulties are expected, namely how to<br />

design experiments to meet theoretically required conditions; the example cited above<br />

clearly illustrates these difficulties. This is why I proposed a simpler approach in w 3,<br />

which can tentatively be used <strong>for</strong> calculating a predator-prey interaction without going<br />

through the details <strong>of</strong> physiological studies <strong>of</strong> hunger.<br />

In passing, HULLING tOO used differential equations, which could yield curves<br />

resembling observed ones, without attaching any significance to the equations as the<br />

means <strong>of</strong> inference. I must again suggest avoiding this unjustifiable operation.<br />

5. DISCUSSION AND CONCLUSIONS<br />

In this section, I shall deal with problems that are more methodological than<br />

technical. Be<strong>for</strong>e doing so, however, what was dealt with in w 4 will be summarized<br />

in the following diagram (Fig. 13).<br />

It is a flow diagram <strong>of</strong> reasoning leading to<br />

each model reviewed, <strong>and</strong> shows the scope that is covered by that model. The dia-<br />

gram is based on my own <strong>study</strong> <strong>and</strong> not necessarily identical to what the authors<br />

claimed in their original papers, as their verbal statements were <strong>of</strong>ten wrong.<br />

The reasoning starts from (A), a generalized instantaneous hunting equation.<br />

This generalization is obvious from eq. (3. 18), in which H(x, Y, t)f(x) can be written<br />

as f(X, Y, t) if x is fixed at X. From (A) there are two main streams, dealing with<br />

<strong>parasitism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>predation</strong>.<br />

The <strong>predation</strong> flow is further divided into subflows 1 <strong>and</strong> 2.<br />

Subflow 2 goes<br />

directly to the determination <strong>of</strong> specific <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> (A) to evaluate n, the number <strong>of</strong><br />

prey taken per unit area in time interval t when the prey density is kept constant.<br />

All the <strong>models</strong> after 1955 (except mine) belong to this flow. Since (A) is an instan-<br />

taneous equation, it cannot be used <strong>for</strong> comparison with observation except <strong>for</strong> cases<br />

in which reduction in the prey density can be neglected. Also (A) does not give any<br />

means <strong>of</strong> estimating the final density <strong>of</strong> the prey or host population at the end <strong>of</strong><br />

each generation.<br />

Hence, these equations in the category <strong>of</strong> (A) cannot be used, as<br />

they st<strong>and</strong>, <strong>for</strong> the <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> prey-predator or host-parasite interaction systems.<br />

Subflow 1, however, incorporates the effects upon the number <strong>of</strong> prey taken per<br />

unit area (i. e. z) <strong>of</strong> (a) diminishing returns, (b) changes in the number in the prey


79<br />

population caused by factors other than <strong>predation</strong>, <strong>and</strong><br />

(c) changes in the numbers<br />

in the predator population. All the classical <strong>models</strong> be<strong>for</strong>e 1935, <strong>and</strong> also mine, come<br />

into this flow. In the diagram, (a), (b), <strong>and</strong> (c) are assumed to be independent <strong>of</strong><br />

each other, <strong>and</strong> under this assumption the simultaneous equations (B) are a priori.<br />

However, if there is any interaction between these effects, the equations are not a<br />

priori <strong>and</strong> so need experimental confirmation. Also, the use <strong>of</strong> calculus can be justi-<br />

fied only under the assumption that the pattern <strong>of</strong> the~ispatial distribution <strong>and</strong> move-<br />

ments <strong>of</strong> the animals concerned remain unchanged throughout the time-interval t.<br />

This is perhaps only approximately so, or may be even a very poor approximation as<br />

my first simulation model <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong> in w<br />

clearly shows, <strong>and</strong> it requires experi-<br />

mental verification. Until then calculus is only a tentative method.<br />

In the step under the heading 'special cases' in the diagram, the flows diverge<br />

according to the more specific assumptions adopted, <strong>and</strong> within the scope <strong>of</strong> each<br />

hypothetical situation (or assumption adopted), all <strong>of</strong> them are legitimate in that<br />

there is no logical contradiction at this stage. This step is followed by the specification<br />

<strong>of</strong> the functions involved, under the heading 'specific equations'.<br />

The specific <strong>for</strong>ms <strong>of</strong> the function f(X, Y, t) are one <strong>of</strong> the major concerns in<br />

this <strong>study</strong>. The meaning <strong>of</strong> each <strong>for</strong>m was interpreted in the light <strong>of</strong> the geometric<br />

properties <strong>of</strong> hunting behaviour under the assumption <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om distribution in the<br />

prey population. The assumption <strong>of</strong> r<strong>and</strong>om distribution is legitimate in a theoretical<br />

<strong>study</strong> like this, as the first step towards more general, irregular distribution patterns<br />

in future studies (the problem will be discussed elsewhere). Some other assumptions<br />

appearing in certain specific <strong>for</strong>ms in WATT (1959), NICHOLSON-BAILEY (1935), LOTKA-<br />

VOLTERRA (1925-1926), <strong>and</strong> GAUSE (1934) are not legitimate: in the WATT equation,<br />

as well as in HASSELL <strong>and</strong> VARLEY, rl-,~ as a measure <strong>of</strong> the degree <strong>of</strong> social inter-<br />

action is contradictory to the premise that a predator has a limited capacity to attack<br />

its prey; in the NICHOLSON-BAILEY equation, f(x) as a linear function <strong>of</strong> x is a priori<br />

impossible; in the LOTKA-VOLTERRA equations, the same criticism as in the NICHOLSON-<br />

BAILEY applies, <strong>and</strong> also the assumption <strong>of</strong> a constant r' is theoretically incorrect;<br />

finally, in GAUSE'S equation, his suggestion concerning g~(x)--f(x)y (GAusE 1934,<br />

<strong>for</strong>mula (25), p. 57) is not comprehensible.<br />

The evaluation <strong>of</strong> z (the reduction <strong>of</strong> the prey density during time-interval t in<br />

a system with discrete generations) is possible only through the reasoning <strong>of</strong> subflow<br />

1. Such an evaluation was made in the original literature only by NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong><br />

BAILEY. All <strong>of</strong> the three recent <strong>models</strong> (i.e. IVLEV, HOLLING, <strong>and</strong> WATT) were<br />

concerned only with the evaluation <strong>of</strong> n, <strong>and</strong> LOTKA <strong>and</strong> VOLTERRA gave only one<br />

special solution <strong>for</strong> a system with continuous generations. There<strong>for</strong>e, tho~e evaluations<br />

in the diagram were made in the present <strong>study</strong> (w 4). It should also be mentioned<br />

here that the evaluation <strong>of</strong> z made in this <strong>study</strong>, except <strong>for</strong> the LOTKA-VOLTERRA<br />

equations, assumed that both functions gl <strong>and</strong> g2 were zero as in the NICHOLSON-<br />

BAILEY equation, but this is only possible in an idealized, experimental set-up. The


80 84<br />

assumption, however, plays a legitimate role in the process <strong>of</strong> inferences as discussed<br />

in w 2. If the assumption does not hold, the functions gl <strong>and</strong> gz have to be determined<br />

experimentally, as there seems no method presently available to deduce specific<br />

<strong>for</strong>ms <strong>for</strong> these functions by analogy. But this problem is not relevant to the present<br />

<strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> hunting behaviour.<br />

GAUSE'S model is inadequate, because the logistic law was taken into account<br />

only in gl <strong>and</strong> not in g2. Also, f is not specified. It is pointed out here, however,<br />

that GAUSE'S equation is applied specifically to a system with continuous generations,<br />

since the introduction <strong>of</strong> a logistic function as a specific <strong>for</strong>m <strong>for</strong> g~ positively excludes<br />

the case <strong>of</strong> discrete generations.<br />

It is clearly shown in this <strong>comparative</strong> <strong>study</strong> that it is LOTKA <strong>and</strong> VOLTERRA,<br />

the pioneers in the theoretical <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> the prey-predator interaction system, whose<br />

thought <strong>and</strong> insight covered the widest scope, <strong>and</strong> who laid the foundation <strong>for</strong> the<br />

<strong>for</strong>malization <strong>of</strong> the system, although their specific <strong>for</strong>ms were unsatisfactory. All<br />

other later <strong>models</strong> covered only a fraction <strong>of</strong> the basic structure <strong>of</strong> the system. Yet,<br />

surprisingly, none <strong>of</strong> the later authors appeared to be aware <strong>of</strong> this fact. Thus,<br />

NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY proposed their model as an alternative to the LOTKA-VOLTERRA<br />

one without noticing that the scope <strong>of</strong> their model had already been potentially covered<br />

by the earlier model. In other words, while LOTKA <strong>and</strong> VOLTERRA gave one solution<br />

to a system with continuous generations, the NICHOLSON-BAILEY competition equation<br />

is nothing more than another solution <strong>of</strong> the LOTKA-VOLTERRA equations in a system<br />

with discrete generations. The attempts by HOLLING, IVLEV, <strong>and</strong> WATT were concerned<br />

only with the improvement <strong>of</strong> the specific <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> function f, <strong>and</strong> completely<br />

neglected the reasoning along subflow 1 in Fig. 13, <strong>and</strong> thus these authors failed to<br />

separate n from z. WATT'S proposal <strong>of</strong> his equation even involves a contradiction;<br />

the proposal can hardly be called an improvement. Yet, the claims by these recent<br />

authors that their <strong>models</strong> were more realistic than the classical ones have been accepted<br />

by many ecologists in this field. These facts are an indication <strong>of</strong> the lack <strong>of</strong><br />

rigorousness in the attitude <strong>of</strong> ecologists, <strong>and</strong> this will be considered below.<br />

First, some concepts <strong>and</strong> terminology used in this field <strong>of</strong> ecology are too loose;<br />

thus confusion occurs in communication between ecologists or even within the mind<br />

<strong>of</strong> a single person. For example, WATT (1962) stated that the classical <strong>models</strong> failed<br />

because the reasoning started from 'a priori assumption' <strong>and</strong> was purely deductive,<br />

<strong>and</strong> thus he proposed (WATT 1959) what he called a 'deductive-inductive method'.<br />

This criticism <strong>of</strong> the classical <strong>models</strong> <strong>and</strong> the proposal <strong>of</strong> the alternative are not<br />

convincing <strong>for</strong> the following reasons.<br />

First, the premise in the classical <strong>models</strong> as appeared in specific <strong>for</strong>m, e.g. f(x)<br />

=ax, is not a priori. Strictly speaking, the phrase a priori means that which is<br />

"marked by being knowable by reasoning from what is considered self-evident <strong>and</strong><br />

there<strong>for</strong>e without appeal to the particular facts <strong>of</strong> evidence" (WEBSTER'S 3 rd International<br />

Dictionary 1968), from which is derived secondarily that which is 'intuitive' or


81<br />

'without experience'. If one uses the phrase to mean just 'intuitive or without expe-<br />

rience' completely emancipated from the original meaning, one might include any as-<br />

sumption set <strong>for</strong>th without confirmation by observation. Then, the expression 'a priori<br />

assumption' is tautological, since an 'assumption' is a premise adopted be<strong>for</strong>e a thing<br />

is known. Although the premise in the classical <strong>models</strong> was set <strong>for</strong>th without support<br />

from factual evidence, it is not a priori.<br />

On the contrary, the premise is a priori<br />

impossible as it violates the second law <strong>of</strong> thermodynamics. If any reasoning starts<br />

from an assumption which is a priori impossible, the conclusion drawn deductively<br />

is bound to be contradictory upon comparison with a fact. (This is the case with c22<br />

under C2 in w<br />

Thus, it is to be expected that the specific <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> the classical<br />

<strong>models</strong> would fail to describe real events satisfactorily.<br />

entirely invalidate the classical <strong>models</strong>, as will be shown later.<br />

This, however, does not<br />

The second point is concerned with deductive <strong>and</strong> inductive methods <strong>of</strong> inference.<br />

Today everyone knows, as WALKER (1963) pointed out (see w 2), that deduction<br />

does not produce more than has been involved in the premise, <strong>and</strong> there<strong>for</strong>e this<br />

method <strong>of</strong> inference alone will not contribute to our knowledge <strong>of</strong> natural order. It<br />

is impossible to believe that mathematicians like LOTKA <strong>and</strong> VOLTERRA did not know<br />

this rule: rather, they must have had a firm reason to present their <strong>models</strong> as deduc-<br />

tive ones. We know, as FRANCIS BACON himself had long ago pointed out, that a<br />

simple induction, i.e. a mere enumeration <strong>of</strong> facts, is no better, <strong>and</strong> even 'childish',<br />

<strong>and</strong> that a new concept would be <strong>for</strong>med only by what BACON called 'gradual induc-<br />

tion', i.e. a gradual passage from concrete facts to broader <strong>and</strong> broader generaliza-<br />

tions (DucASSE 1960). The process <strong>of</strong> gradual induction, however, does not exclude<br />

a phase which is deductive, e.g. once a certain assumption is made, perhaps by<br />

induction, a conclusion can be drawn only by reasoning, <strong>and</strong> then this conclusion is<br />

compared with observation. This is very similar to what I described in w 2. My<br />

interpretation <strong>of</strong> the LOTKA-VoLTERRA method is that they were showing what such<br />

deductive phases <strong>of</strong> reasoning could be like. That is, what they have shown is a<br />

model <strong>of</strong> deductive reasoning which is conveniently separated from the entire process<br />

<strong>of</strong> inference.<br />

It was rather un<strong>for</strong>tunate that the premise in the classical <strong>models</strong> was in fact<br />

biologically absurd (IVLEV 1961) <strong>and</strong> did not appeal to ecologists. However, <strong>for</strong> a<br />

mathematician who tries to show the basic structure <strong>and</strong> the method <strong>of</strong> analysis (to<br />

<strong>for</strong>m a hypothesis), the adoption <strong>of</strong> such specific <strong>for</strong>ms might have been merely<br />

trivial <strong>and</strong> only tentative since it can be changed readily if desired; but the principle<br />

<strong>of</strong> the mathematical method remains uninfluenced. This attitude is very clear in<br />

LOTKA'S work. It is un<strong>for</strong>tunate that ecologists became too much concerned with<br />

such a casual premise <strong>and</strong> failed to see the more fundamental aspect <strong>of</strong> the idea.<br />

This point is clearly illustrated in the three recent model builders, as reviewed above,<br />

who failed to distinguish n from z. This failure to underst<strong>and</strong> the classical model<br />

is not only seen in these authors but also in others (e. g. ANDREWARTHA <strong>and</strong> BIRCH


82<br />

1954; MILNE 1957) who thought that the premise <strong>and</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong> the classical<br />

<strong>models</strong> were far too simple to be realistic.<br />

It should be pointed out, however, that<br />

those who proposed what was claimed to be more realistic, taking so many conceiv-<br />

able factors into account, have never been able to <strong>for</strong>malize the ideas that they stated<br />

only verbally, or have not even tried to do so.<br />

From such verbal statements, one<br />

cannot draw a quantitatively expressed conclusion that can be compared with ob-<br />

served quantities <strong>for</strong> testing.<br />

Now it is clear that the criticism <strong>of</strong> the classical <strong>models</strong> was due to insufficient<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> inferences.<br />

As pointed out in w 4f, although WATT<br />

claimed that the assumption <strong>of</strong> the coefficient A as it appeared in eq. (4f. 5) was<br />

based on an empirical fact, it was in fact an illusion, since the assumption proved to<br />

be nothing but dogmatic <strong>and</strong> even impossible a priori. Obviously, the author did not<br />

test his hypothesis (i, e. eq.<br />

(4f. 5)) by any means <strong>and</strong> this positively violates, con-<br />

trary to what was claimed, the code <strong>of</strong> rules <strong>for</strong> inferences by induction. The same<br />

criticism applies to the HASSELL-VARLEY model in w 4h.<br />

The above discussion suggests that the stage we are in is still very primitive,<br />

with an evident lack <strong>of</strong> rigor in methodology. This, however, may well be because<br />

the nature <strong>of</strong> the objects we are <strong>study</strong>ing have influenced the development <strong>of</strong> ideas<br />

in this field. My point may be illustrated by contrast with the development <strong>of</strong> the<br />

physical sciences.<br />

In physics, some properties <strong>of</strong> certain objects were, very <strong>for</strong>tunately, describable<br />

deterministically (sensu BORN 1964--predictable without the causal relationships being<br />

known; a timeless <strong>and</strong> spaceless link between the events, e.g. a railway time-table).<br />

The arithmetic prediction <strong>of</strong> the stars' motion by the Babylonians or, more recently,<br />

KEPLER'S Law, are perhaps typical examples. As modern physicists went into the<br />

more minute details <strong>of</strong> atoms, <strong>and</strong> as the required measurements became finer <strong>and</strong><br />

finer, they eventually reached a stage where the classical method <strong>of</strong> induction was no<br />

longer applicable. A positive barrier was encountered when HEISENBERG enunciated<br />

his Uncertainty Principle in 1927; this predicts that some physical attributes <strong>of</strong> the<br />

object being measured are influenced by interaction between the object <strong>and</strong> the meas-<br />

uring system. However, be<strong>for</strong>e this stage was reached, there were enough examples<br />

<strong>of</strong> success in macrophysics, i.e. in NEWTONIAN physics, which encouraged the phys-<br />

icists to explore thoroughly the method <strong>of</strong> induction.<br />

In the field <strong>of</strong> population dynamics, however, difficulties similar to those that<br />

modern physics is currently facing have been a major problem from the beginning.<br />

Some may be only technical difficulties in obtaining accurate measurements.<br />

example, the concept <strong>of</strong> the h<strong>and</strong>ling time (h), originally suggested by HOLLING<br />

(1956), was found to be highly idealized in my <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> the great tit, Parus major<br />

L. (ROYAMA 1970). I tried to time the tit as it searched <strong>for</strong> food <strong>and</strong> as it h<strong>and</strong>led<br />

each item.<br />

The in<strong>for</strong>mation was used to calculate a theoretical value <strong>for</strong> the amount<br />

<strong>of</strong> food that the tit could collect per day using HOLLING'S disc equation (<strong>for</strong> the<br />

For


83<br />

justification <strong>of</strong> its use, see ROYAMA 1970). It was found that, <strong>for</strong> an intuitively rea-<br />

sonable magnitude <strong>for</strong> the factor a, the calculated value <strong>for</strong> h was ridiculously high.<br />

When the factor a was so adjusted as to obtain a more reasonable value <strong>for</strong> h, then<br />

such values <strong>of</strong> a were inexplicably low. My conclusion was there<strong>for</strong>e that the estima-<br />

tion <strong>of</strong> h by observation was far lower than it actually was. This is perhaps because<br />

what was recorded as searching time must have contained a high proportion that was<br />

spent upon various activities other than pure searching, e.g. watching <strong>for</strong> enemies.<br />

These activities must have occupied such short intervals that they were hardly separable<br />

by direct observation.<br />

Beside such difficulties in measuring each activity separately <strong>and</strong> accurately, there<br />

are more pr<strong>of</strong>ound ones which may not be solved technically. The first is the time<br />

factor. In order to take a sufficiently reliable measurement, say, <strong>of</strong> the fluctuation in<br />

numbers <strong>of</strong> an animal species from year to year, the life span <strong>of</strong> a single ecologist<br />

may not be sufficiently long: perhaps he can <strong>study</strong> only some twenty generations <strong>of</strong><br />

a univoltine species.<br />

From a mere accumulation <strong>of</strong> sampling data, he can draw<br />

conclusions by guessing, not by induction. The second difficulty lies in differences<br />

between natural <strong>and</strong> experimental situations. The development <strong>of</strong> <strong>comparative</strong> ethology<br />

in the past decade shows that the behaviour <strong>of</strong> animals has so evolved that its biologi-<br />

cal goal is attained by responding appropriately to a chain <strong>of</strong> stimuli provided in<br />

the animals' natural environment (see e.g. TINBERGEN 1951; <strong>for</strong> more recent develop-<br />

ment see HINDE 1966). We cannot be certain on the one h<strong>and</strong>, however, if some <strong>of</strong><br />

the necessary stimuli are lacking in an experimental set-up in which the animals<br />

concerned may not behave in an intelligible manner. But, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, we may<br />

not be able to know, without experimental studies, what stimuli are involved in the<br />

animals' normal environment where evolution has taken place. Then we will not be<br />

certain whether we can establish a fact from which to follow the <strong>for</strong>mula <strong>of</strong> induction<br />

laid out by the classical physics, or rather if a fact at h<strong>and</strong> is a meaningful one that<br />

can be used to start the gradual process <strong>of</strong> induction.<br />

These arguments may be metaphysical problems, but are sufficient to show that<br />

the primitive stage we are in at the moment, as compared with physical sciences, is<br />

perhaps due to the above-mentioned difficulties, which prevented us consciously or<br />

subconsciously from developing the method <strong>of</strong> inference by induction, starting from<br />

an elemental stage where a deterministic prediction would not have been hard to make.<br />

For the time being, ecology will perhaps remain largely descriptive, even if we<br />

cannot expect to develop a deterministic law governing the hunting behaviour <strong>of</strong><br />

animals directly from such enumerations. A theoretical <strong>study</strong> by <strong>models</strong>, i.e. infer-<br />

ence by analogy, will not replace the tedious process <strong>of</strong> enumeration, but it will at<br />

least partially help in the interpretation <strong>of</strong> observed facts. The method will be useful,<br />

however, only provided that the <strong>models</strong> are appropriately constructed <strong>and</strong> used. The<br />

idea is perhaps the same as that suggested by OPPENHEIMER (1956) to a group <strong>of</strong><br />

psychologists as 'pluralism' in the method.


84<br />

What is required at the present stage is to make use <strong>of</strong> the <strong>for</strong>malism <strong>of</strong> mathematics<br />

to a thorough extent in the quest <strong>of</strong> certitude. Some ecologists might suggest<br />

that the complexity <strong>of</strong> natural order almost prohibits this <strong>for</strong>malism. But this amounts<br />

to giving up the quest <strong>for</strong> certitude, because, if mathematics cannot h<strong>and</strong>le the complexity,<br />

it would be even more difficult <strong>for</strong> the verbal method <strong>of</strong> inference to cope<br />

with the problem, <strong>and</strong> we do not have a better alternative, at least at the present<br />

stage <strong>of</strong> the development in population dynamics.<br />

6. SUMMARY<br />

1. This is a critical <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> major existing <strong>models</strong> <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>,<br />

<strong>and</strong> its aim is to evaluate the roles played, or those not played, by these <strong>models</strong> in<br />

helping our insight into the relationships underlying prey-predator <strong>and</strong> host-parasite<br />

interaction systems.<br />

2. The concept <strong>of</strong> a model, <strong>and</strong> the role it plays in the process <strong>of</strong> reasoning that<br />

leads eventually to underst<strong>and</strong>ing <strong>of</strong> the system, is considered first in general terms.<br />

It is pointed out that a model is a means through which a<br />

hypothesis is <strong>for</strong>med;<br />

the model is an analogy to the thing to be understood, constructed from already<br />

known concepts.<br />

3. The basic structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong> are then presented in terms <strong>of</strong><br />

mathematical equations <strong>of</strong> general <strong>for</strong>ms. This is to help readers to underst<strong>and</strong> the<br />

examination <strong>of</strong> existing <strong>models</strong> which follows in the subsequent sections. Two differ-<br />

ent sets <strong>of</strong> inferences are discussed, the one leading to a model <strong>for</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

the other to a model <strong>for</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>. The role played by a differential equation as a<br />

means <strong>of</strong> deduction is explained.<br />

4. Models proposed by LOTKA, VOLTERRA, NICHOLSON <strong>and</strong> BAILEY, HOLLING,<br />

IVLEV, GAUSE, ROYAMA, WATT, THOMPSON, STOY, <strong>and</strong> HASSELL <strong>and</strong> VARLEY are<br />

critically examined, with particular attention to their logical structures rather than<br />

to their ability to generate a theoretical trend that superficially fits an observed one.<br />

The logical structures <strong>of</strong> these <strong>models</strong> are summarized in the <strong>for</strong>m <strong>of</strong> diagrams in<br />

w 5. The critical <strong>study</strong> is developed by means <strong>of</strong> analogies to various geometric<br />

<strong>models</strong>, which clearly show some misconceptions involved in each model reviewed.<br />

It also shows that the logical structure in the classical <strong>models</strong> (those proposed be<strong>for</strong>e<br />

1935) are sound, but the assumptions involved are <strong>of</strong>ten inadequate to describe an<br />

actual biological system; on the other h<strong>and</strong>, recent <strong>models</strong> (proposed after 1955) either<br />

involve contradiction in logic or are much too <strong>of</strong>ten erroneously applied to the analysis<br />

<strong>of</strong> actual <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>. It is pointed out that the mere fitting <strong>of</strong> curves<br />

to data can neither establish a particular mechanism nor provide verification <strong>of</strong> the<br />

model concerned.<br />

5. Finally, the types <strong>of</strong> inferences, which can or cannot help us in underst<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

the processes <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>, are considered by comparison to similar<br />

problems in the development <strong>of</strong> physical sciences. In ecology, inference by induction,


85<br />

which has been <strong>and</strong> Still is to a large extent the major scientific method, has inherently<br />

many <strong>of</strong> the same problems as modern physics, such as HEISENBERG'S Uncertainty<br />

Principle. Perhaps certain types <strong>of</strong> difficulty that are encountered by the observational<br />

method can be overcome, if not entirely, with the aid <strong>of</strong> inferences by analogy, <strong>and</strong><br />

it is in inferences where the model plays its role.<br />

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS: I am grateful to the following people <strong>for</strong> their very constructive comments<br />

<strong>and</strong> suggestions which led to much greater clarity in my presentation: Drs. R.F. MORRIS,<br />

G.L. BASKERVILLE <strong>and</strong> M.M. NEILSON (Canadian Forestry Service, Fredericton), M.E. SOLOMON<br />

(University <strong>of</strong> Bristol), <strong>and</strong> Y. IT6 (National Institute <strong>of</strong> Agricultural Sciences, Tokyo). Pr<strong>of</strong>essor<br />

S. TANAKA'S (Ocean Research Institute, University <strong>of</strong> Tokyo) comments on my mathematical treatments<br />

helped to minimize erroneous arguments.<br />

REPERENCES<br />

ANDREWARTItA , H.G. <strong>and</strong> L.C. BIRcH (1954) The distribution <strong>and</strong> abundance<br />

Chicago Press, Chicago.<br />

<strong>of</strong> animals. Univ.<br />

BLiss, C.I. <strong>and</strong> R. A. FISHER (1953) Fitting the negative binomial distribution to biological data<br />

<strong>and</strong> note on the efficient fitting <strong>of</strong> the negative binomial. Biometrics 9 : 179-200.<br />

BORN, M. (1964) Natural philosophy <strong>of</strong> cause <strong>and</strong> chance. Dover, New York.<br />

BURNETT, T. (1956) Effects <strong>of</strong> natural temperatures on oviposition <strong>of</strong> various numbers <strong>of</strong> an insect<br />

parasite (Hymenoptera, Chalcidoidae, Tenthredinidae). Ann. Ent. Soc. Amer. 49:55-59.<br />

BURNETT, T. (1958) Effect <strong>of</strong> host distribution on the reproduction <strong>of</strong> Encarsia <strong>for</strong>mosa GAHAN<br />

(Hymenoptera : Chalcidoidae). Can. Ent. 90 : 179-191.<br />

BURNSIDE, W. (1928) Theory <strong>of</strong> probability (1959 ed.). Dover, New York.<br />

CHAeMA~, R.N. (1931) Animal ecology. McGraw-Hill, New York & London.<br />

CLAaK, P.J. (1956) Grouping in spatial distributions. Science 123 : 373-374.<br />

CLARK, P.J. <strong>and</strong> F. C. EVANS (1954) Distance to nearest neighbor as a measure <strong>of</strong> spatial relation-<br />

ship in populations. Ecology 35 : 445-453.<br />

DRAKE, S. (1957) Discoveries <strong>and</strong> opinions <strong>of</strong> GALILEO. Doubleday, New York.<br />

DUCASSE, C.J. (1960) FRANCIS BACON'S philosophy <strong>of</strong> science. Chapter 3 in "Theories <strong>of</strong> scientific<br />

method : Renaissance through the nineteenth century". Univ. Washington Press, Seattle.<br />

ELTON, C. (1935) Review <strong>of</strong> A. J. LOTKA (1934). ~ Anita. Ecol. 4 : 148-149.<br />

GAMOW, G. (1962) Gravity. Doubleday, New York.<br />

GAuss, G.F. (1934) The struggle <strong>for</strong> existence. Williams & Wilkins, Baltimore.<br />

GRIFFITnS, K.J. <strong>and</strong> C.S. HoLLInG (1969) A competition submodel <strong>for</strong> parasites <strong>and</strong> predators.<br />

Can. Ent. 101 : 785-818.<br />

HASSELL, M.P. <strong>and</strong> G. C. VARLEY (1969) New inductive population model <strong>for</strong> insect parasites <strong>and</strong><br />

its bearing on biological control. Nature 223 : 1133-1137.<br />

HAYNES, O.L. <strong>and</strong> P. SIsojEvtc (1966) Predatory behavior <strong>of</strong> Philodromus rufus WALCKENAER (Ara-<br />

neae : Thomisidae). Can. Ent. 98 : 113-133.<br />

HINDS, R.A. (1966) Animal Behavior. McGraw-Hill, New York.<br />

HOLLIN6, C.S. (1959a) The components <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> as revealed by a <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> small mammal<br />

<strong>predation</strong> <strong>of</strong> the European pine sawfly. Can. Ent. 91 : 293-320.<br />

HOLLINC, C.S. (1959b) Some characteristics <strong>of</strong> simple types <strong>of</strong> <strong>predation</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>parasitism</strong>. Can.<br />

Ent. 91 : 385-398.


86<br />

HOLLING, C.S. (1961) Principles <strong>of</strong> insect <strong>predation</strong>. Ann. Rev. Ent. 6 : 163-182.<br />

HOLLING, C.S.<br />

(1966) The functional response <strong>of</strong> invertebrate predators to prey density. Mere.<br />

Ent. Soe. Can. 48:3-86.<br />

HUFFAKER, C.B. <strong>and</strong> C. E. KENNETT (1969) Some aspects <strong>of</strong> assessing efficiency <strong>of</strong> natural enemies.<br />

Can. Ent. 101 9 425-447.<br />

ITb, Y. (1963) DSbutsu Seitai-gaku Ny~mon (Introduction to animal ecology]. Kokin-shoin, Tokyo.<br />

IVLF.V, V.S.<br />

(1955) Experimental ecology <strong>of</strong> the feeding <strong>of</strong> fishes (English translation by D. SCOTT<br />

1961). Yale Univ. Press, New Haven.<br />

LAING, J. (1937) Host finding by insect parasites. I. Observations on the finding <strong>of</strong> hosts by<br />

Alysia m<strong>and</strong>ucator, Mormoneilla vitripennis, <strong>and</strong> Trichogramma evanescens. J. Anita. Ecol.<br />

6 : 298-317.<br />

LOTKA, A.J.<br />

MILLSR, C.A.<br />

(1925) Elements <strong>of</strong> physical biology. Williams & Wilkins, Baltimore.<br />

(1960) The interaction <strong>of</strong> the spruce budworm, Choristoneura fumiferana (CLsM.),<br />

<strong>and</strong> the parasite Glypta fumiferana (VIEs.). Can. Ent. 92 : 839-850.<br />

MILNE, A. (1957) Theories <strong>of</strong> natural control <strong>of</strong> insect populations.<br />

Quant. Biol. 22 : 253-267.<br />

MORRIS, R.F.<br />

Cold Spring Harbor Syrup.<br />

(1963) The effect <strong>of</strong> predator age <strong>and</strong> prey defence on the functional response <strong>of</strong><br />

Podisus maculiventris SAY to the density <strong>of</strong> Hyphantria cunea DRURY. Can. Ent. 95 : 1009-1020.<br />

MORISXTA, M. (1954) Estimation <strong>of</strong> population density by spacing method. Mere. Fac. Sci. Kyushu<br />

Univ. E 1 : 187-197.<br />

NICHOLSOS, A.J. (1933) The balance <strong>of</strong> animal populations. J. Anim. Ecol. 2 9 132-178.<br />

NmaoLsor~, A.J. <strong>and</strong> V. A. BAILEY (1935) The balance <strong>of</strong> animal populations. Part 1. Proc. Zool.<br />

Soc. London 1935, Part 3 : 551-598.<br />

OeeENamMsa, R. (1956) Analogy in science. Amer. Psychol. 11 : 127-135.<br />

PEARL, R. (1927) The growth <strong>of</strong> populations. Quart. Rev. Biol. 2 : 532-548.<br />

POINCARL H. (1952) Science <strong>and</strong> hypothesis (English ed.). Dover, New York.<br />

PogvA, G. (1955) Mathematics <strong>and</strong> plausible reasoning. Vol. 2. Patterns <strong>of</strong> plausible inference.<br />

Princeton Univ. Press, Princeton.<br />

ROYAMA, T. (1966) Mathematical <strong>models</strong> <strong>of</strong> predatory behaviour in population dynamics.<br />

Japanese.) Biol. Sci., Tokyo, 18 : 97-105.<br />

ROYAMA, T. (1969) A model <strong>for</strong> the global variation <strong>of</strong> clutch size in birds. Oikos 20 : 562-567.<br />

RO~rAMA, T.<br />

(1970) Factors governing the hunting behaviour <strong>and</strong> selection <strong>of</strong> food by the great<br />

tit, Parus major L. ]. Anita. Ecol. 39 : 619-668.<br />

(In<br />

RUSSELL, E.M.<br />

(1961) Soil conditions <strong>and</strong> plant growth (9th ed.) Longmans, Norwich.<br />

SCHON, D.A. (1967) Invention <strong>and</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> ideas. Butler & Tanner, Frome & London.<br />

SMITH, H.S. (1939) Insect populations in relations to biological control. Ecol Monogr. 9 : 311-320.<br />

SIMMONDS, F.J. (1943) Occurrence <strong>of</strong> super<strong>parasitism</strong> in Nemeritis canescens. Rev. Can. Biol.<br />

2 : 15-40.<br />

STov, R.H. (1932) Appendix to G. SALT (1932) [Super<strong>parasitism</strong> by Collyria calcitrator GRAV.]<br />

Bull. Ent. Res. 23 : 215-216.<br />

THOMPSON, W.R. (1924) La th6orie math6matique de Faction des parasites entomophages et le<br />

facteur du hassard. Ann. Fac. Sci. Marseille 2".69-89.<br />

THOMeSON, W.R. (1939) Biological control <strong>and</strong> the theories <strong>of</strong> the interaction <strong>of</strong> populations.<br />

Parasitology 31 : 299-388.


87<br />

TINBERGEN, L. <strong>and</strong> H. KLOMP (1960) The natural control <strong>of</strong> insects in pinewoods. II. Conditions<br />

<strong>for</strong> damping <strong>of</strong> Nicholson oscillations in parasite-host systems. Arch. ne~rl. 7.ooi. 13 : 344-379.<br />

TINBERGEN, N. (1951) The <strong>study</strong> <strong>of</strong> instinct. Clarendon Press, Ox<strong>for</strong>d.<br />

TORII, T. (1956) Konchfe-Shftdan no Suikei-h5 [Statistical analysis <strong>of</strong> insect populations]. Chapter 7<br />

in "Seitai-gaku Gaisetsu" [Outline <strong>of</strong> ecology,, (ed. by N. YAGI <strong>and</strong> K. NOMURA). Yoken-do,<br />

Tokyo.<br />

TOULMIN, S. (1961) Foresight <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>ing. Harper (Torchbook ed. 1963), New York & Evanston.<br />

ULLY~TT, G.C. (1947) Mortality factors in populations <strong>of</strong> Plutella maculipennis CURTIS (Tineidae :<br />

Lep.), <strong>and</strong> their relation to the problem <strong>of</strong> control. Ent. Metal, Dep. Agr. Forest., Union <strong>of</strong><br />

South Africa 2 (part 6) : pp. 202.<br />

ULLY~TT, G.C. (1949a) Distribution <strong>of</strong> progeny by Chelonus texanus CRESS. (Hymenoptera : Braconidae).<br />

Can. lent. 81:25-44.<br />

ULLYETT, G.C. (1949b) Distribution <strong>of</strong> progeny by Cryptus inornattus PRATT (Hymenoptera : Ichneumonidae).<br />

Can. Ent. 81:285-299.<br />

VBRnURST, P.E. (1838) Notice sur la loi que la population suit dans son accroissement. Corresp.<br />

Math. Phys. 10 : 113-121.<br />

VOLT~RRA, V. (1926) Variazioni e fluttuazioni del numero d'individui in specie animali conviventi.<br />

Mere. R. Accad. Naz. dei Lincei, Ser. VI, Vol. 2 [English translation in CHAeMAr~ 1931].<br />

WALKER, M. (1963) The nature <strong>of</strong> scientific thought. Prentice-Hall, New Jersey.<br />

WATT, K. E.F. (1959) A mathematical model <strong>for</strong> the effect <strong>of</strong> densities <strong>of</strong> attacked <strong>and</strong> attacking<br />

species on the number attacked. Can. Ent. 91 : 129-144.<br />

WATT, K. E.F. (1961) Mathematical <strong>models</strong> <strong>for</strong> use in insect pest control. Can. Ent. Suppl.<br />

19 : 1-62.<br />

WATT, K.E.F. (1962) Use <strong>of</strong> mathematics in population ecology. Ann. Rev. Ent. 7:243-260.<br />

WATT, K. E.F. (1968) Ecology <strong>and</strong> resource management. McGraw-Hill, New York.<br />

WILLIAMS, C.B. (1964) Patterns in the balance <strong>of</strong> nature <strong>and</strong> related problems in quantitative<br />

ecology. Academic Press, London & New York.


88 84<br />

Appendix 1. The pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> LI=I/2RX :<br />

Suppose particles <strong>of</strong> kind P are distributed at r<strong>and</strong>om with density X over a two-dimensional<br />

plane <strong>of</strong> sufficiently large area. Let l be the distance between Q's starting point A <strong>and</strong> the periph-<br />

ery <strong>of</strong> the circle <strong>of</strong> radius R around P that Q first encountered from outside the circle when<br />

moving in an arbitrarily determined direction. Suppose that l comprises very small sections <strong>of</strong><br />

length ,~l, <strong>and</strong> that l~ is defined by izll (i=1, 2 .....<br />

c~o). Let ~7l be the probability that at least<br />

one particle <strong>of</strong> kind P falls within, <strong>and</strong> only within, a locus (li, li+dl). Then the average distance<br />

that Q travels from outside to encounter the periphery <strong>of</strong> the first, i.e. L~, is<br />

oo<br />

Lt=lim ~2 IpT~<br />

dl~O i=l<br />

Now, ~2~ is the product <strong>of</strong> the following probabilities:<br />

(1) probability that at least one particle <strong>of</strong> kind P is found within area 2R(li+zff), which <strong>for</strong><br />

the assumption <strong>of</strong> the Po~ssos distribution is, <strong>for</strong> j=l, 2 .....<br />

~,, [ {2R(l~+dl) X} J/j !] e -2R(I,+aI)X,<br />

j-1<br />

(2) probability that all <strong>of</strong> these j particles within area 2R(li+dl) are found within locus (li, li<br />

+dl), i.e.<br />

{2RJ1/2R (l~ +all) } ~.<br />

Thus,<br />

~= ~ [ (2R (li + AI) X} J/j !]e-2R(h + ~l)X {2Rdl/2R (li + Jl) }<br />

cr<br />

(i).<br />

= ~, { (2RJIX) J/j !} e<br />

j=l<br />

2RJIX- 2RI~X<br />

=(1-e<br />

- 2RdlX - 2RliX<br />

Since, by a theorem in the theory <strong>of</strong> limit,<br />

) e<br />

lira (1 - e- 2R~IX) ~all = 2 RX,<br />

Jl~0<br />

<strong>and</strong> so, by writing l~ simply as l, we have<br />

Hence, from eq. (i),<br />

lira ~7~ = 2RXe- 2RIX dl.<br />

6l ~0<br />

L~=2RX f :Ie -2RlX dl<br />

=I/2RX.<br />

Appendix 2. The pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> L2={O(V'~XR)/1/X-Re -TrR2X }/(1-e -~rR~X )<br />

on a two dimensional plane<br />

Suppose that the radius R consists <strong>of</strong> a number <strong>of</strong> very small sections <strong>of</strong> length dr, <strong>and</strong> that<br />

ri is defined as idr(i=l, 2 ..... oo). Let tti be the probability <strong>of</strong> at least one point <strong>of</strong> A's falling<br />

within, <strong>and</strong> only within, a locus (ri, ri+dr). Then the average distance between the centre <strong>of</strong> a<br />

circle <strong>of</strong> radius R <strong>and</strong> the nearest A within the circle, i.e. L2, is<br />

oo<br />

co<br />

Lz=limar~o { i=5-2'1 r~pd / { ~lt~}~<br />

Now, pi is the product <strong>of</strong> the following probabilities:<br />

(ii).


(1)<br />

assumption <strong>of</strong> a PoxssoN distribution,<br />

~E [ {z (r, + Jr)'Aq s~ j!] e - ~'(' '+ dr)2X ,<br />

j~l<br />

(2) probability that all <strong>of</strong> these j points fall within a locus (ri, ri+dr), i.e.<br />

[ {z (r~ +dr) 2_ r, ri~}/~r (ri +dr) 2],,.<br />

With a similar calculation as <strong>for</strong> 7] in Appendix 1, we have<br />

Thus,<br />

Similarly,<br />

probability that at least one point <strong>of</strong> A's falls within radius ri+dr; this is, under the<br />

l. - wr~.X<br />

~m ta~=2~rXe dr.<br />

d r--*O<br />

co PR - *rr2X<br />

lira i=<br />

J r--~0 '=<br />

a~lFi=|o 2r, rXe dr<br />

=l_e-~rR~X<br />

oo PR ~ -wrO-X<br />

lira ]E rq2~=l 2.'rr Xe dr<br />

zIr~O i=1 dO<br />

<strong>and</strong> integrating by parts,<br />

(iii).<br />

fR2~,r,e-,rrO~X, ar=Jo ['R-wr~<br />

e ' dr-Re -'R~'x (iv).<br />

Let O(t) be the normal probability function, i.e.<br />

1 t - t 2/2<br />

$(t) =. 7,-- f e dt,<br />

V~Tr JO<br />

<strong>and</strong> setting t equal to l/2zXr,<br />

9 (1/~R)/V'X.<br />

the integral in the right-h<strong>and</strong> side <strong>of</strong> eq. (iv) will be written as<br />

Thus, from eqs. (ii), (iii), <strong>and</strong> (iv) <strong>and</strong> using symbol ~, we have<br />

L.=[, )<br />

89<br />

Appendix 3. The pro<strong>of</strong> <strong>of</strong> eq. (4i. 6)<br />

Let Y be the density <strong>of</strong> particles distributed at r<strong>and</strong>om over an area A, each one <strong>of</strong> the<br />

particles having a circle <strong>of</strong> area 6 around it. Then the density <strong>of</strong> the particles, Y", within the<br />

total area covered with these circles, i.e. A', is<br />

Y"-=-AY/A'<br />

Suppose that a large number <strong>of</strong> points, i.e. U, with circles <strong>of</strong>, also, area ~ are placed to<br />

cover the whole area <strong>of</strong> A independently <strong>of</strong> the distribution <strong>of</strong> the particles. Then, the number<br />

U' <strong>of</strong> these points that include at least one <strong>of</strong> the particles will he, on the assumption <strong>of</strong> the<br />

Poissos distribution,<br />

U'= U(1-e -~r)<br />

(vi),<br />

<strong>and</strong> the proportion U/U ~ must be equal to the proportion A/A'. Thus from eqs. (v <strong>and</strong> vi), we<br />

find<br />

Y"=Y/(1-e-~Y).<br />

Thus a circle <strong>of</strong> area c~ around each particle contains on the average 6Y~P number <strong>of</strong> particles.<br />

However, since ~Y~ is, as defined in w 4i, the mean number <strong>of</strong> particles in each circle less<br />

the one at the centre, we have<br />

6Y'=6Y"--I<br />

=~Y/(1-e -~r) -1.


90<br />

Appendix 4.<br />

List <strong>of</strong> symbols<br />

The following symbols with the same meaning appear in more than two sections <strong>and</strong> in the<br />

flow diagram <strong>of</strong> Fig. 13. Sections indicated in the parentheses are the places where definitions<br />

are given. Symbols used in one section only, or those defined each time they appear, are not<br />

listed.<br />

Variables :<br />

x (w Prey or host density.<br />

X (//) Fixed prey or host density during t. (For t see below. )<br />

x0(H) Initial prey density when /-=-0.<br />

y (H) Predator or parasite density.<br />

Y (/t) Fixed predator or parasite density during t.<br />

t (tt) Interval <strong>of</strong> a hunting period.<br />

(It) Number <strong>of</strong> prey taken, or number <strong>of</strong> parasite eggs laid, per unit area, when the density<br />

<strong>of</strong> the hunted species is fixed during t.<br />

z (tt) Number <strong>of</strong> prey taken, or number <strong>of</strong> hosts parasitized, per unit area during t, when<br />

the density <strong>of</strong> the hunted species is not replenished.<br />

L(w 4c) Time spent in searching only.<br />

:Functional symbols :<br />

f (w 3) Instantaneous hunting function.<br />

F ( tt ) Overall hunting function.<br />

gl(w 4a) Function characterizing the instantaneous rate <strong>of</strong> increase (or decrease) <strong>of</strong> prey population<br />

in the abscense <strong>of</strong> predators.<br />

g, (M) Characterizing the instantaneous rate <strong>of</strong> increase (or decrease) <strong>of</strong> predator population<br />

in the presence <strong>of</strong> food species.<br />

S(w Characterizing the degree <strong>of</strong> social interaction (interference or facilitation) among<br />

predators or parasites by which the f changes.<br />

H( ~t ) Characterizing the partial realization <strong>of</strong> the potential per<strong>for</strong>mance in hunting in accordance<br />

with the degree <strong>of</strong> hunger or satiation.<br />

(tt) Probability <strong>of</strong> a host receiving no parasite egg.<br />

:Factors independent <strong>of</strong> the variables listed above :<br />

a (w 4b) Effective area <strong>of</strong> recognition.<br />

b (w 4d) Positive proportionality factor.<br />

c (zt) Positive proportionality factor.<br />

/~ (w 4f) Coefficient <strong>of</strong> social interaction. (See also w 4h. )<br />

r(w 4a) Coefficient <strong>of</strong> increase in prey population in the absense <strong>of</strong> predators.<br />

r t (//) Coefficient <strong>of</strong> decrease in predator population in the absense <strong>of</strong> food species.<br />

a'(#) Coefficient <strong>of</strong> increase in predator population due to feeding.<br />

h (w 4c) Time spent in h<strong>and</strong>ling an individual prey or host.<br />

M(w 4g) Size <strong>of</strong> hunting area.<br />

Other parameters :<br />

~(w 4b) 'Area <strong>of</strong> discovery' defined as in eqs. (4b. 9) <strong>and</strong> (4b. 10).<br />

k (w 4g) Factor characterizing the degree <strong>of</strong> aggregation in the negative binomial distribution.<br />

(The symbol k used in w w 4c <strong>and</strong> d st<strong>and</strong>s <strong>for</strong> the frequency <strong>of</strong> tapping fingers or that<br />

<strong>of</strong> tossing rings. )


91<br />

4. LOTKA, VOLTERRA, NICHOLSON ~ BAILEY, HOLLING, IVLEV, GAUSE, ~JJ, WATT, THOMPSON, STOY,<br />

~ , ~ ~'~:~i~~.l:l;~b~'~:~6~bt: P__ ~8, ~A.~~ ~, ~/~6~o~

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!