01.10.2014 Views

Hume's General Rules - Serjeantson

Hume's General Rules - Serjeantson

Hume's General Rules - Serjeantson

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Serjeantson</strong>-22<br />

philosophy. Secondly, for Berkeley, the ‘general rules’ formulated by philosophers<br />

are a direct reflection of the regulation of nature effected by God (‘or the intelligence<br />

which sustains and rules the ordinary course of things’). 71 In something more than a<br />

simple play on words, human rules reflect divine rule. Hume may have accepted the<br />

basic structure of Berkeley’s account of general rules, but he never accepted that they<br />

were underwritten by the deity. 72 Finally and most characteristically, Berkeley does<br />

not regard the natural philosophers’ ‘general rules’ as providing any knowledge about<br />

relations of cause and effect. Instead, they are simply a reflection of our perception of<br />

signs: ‘Those men who frame general rules from the phenomena, and afterwards<br />

derive the phenomena from those rules, seem to consider signs rather than causes.’ 73<br />

Here again we may see Hume’s account of general rules as a response to Berkeley.<br />

Hume acknowledges that it is ‘only by signs’ that we become sensible of effects. 74<br />

But he does not accept Berkeley’s doubts about our ability to discern their causes,<br />

since that is precisely what his ‘<strong>Rules</strong> by which to judge of causes and effects’ are<br />

intended to accomplish.<br />

With this account behind us are now in a position to assess where Hume’s Treatise<br />

stands in relation to previous accounts of ‘general rules’ in early modern philosophy.<br />

The first and perhaps most important point to make is that in his hostility to long<br />

systems of ‘rules and precepts to direct our judgment, in philosophy’, Hume is an<br />

inheritor and in some senses the culmination of seventeenth-century tendencies<br />

71 Berkeley, Principles, p. 125 (§62). For discussion, see Michael Ayers, 'Natures and laws from<br />

Descartes to Hume', in The Philosophical Canon in the 17th and 18th Centuries: Essays in honour of<br />

John W. Yolton, ed. G. A. J. Rogers and Sylvana Tomaselli (Rochester, NY: University of Rochester<br />

Press, 1996), pp. 83-108, pp. 101-04.<br />

72 See Hume, Treatise, pp. 159-60 (1.3.14)<br />

73 Berkeley, Principles, p. 142 (§108); see also p. 126 (§65): ‘the connexion of ideas does not imply the<br />

relation of cause and effect, but only of a mark or sign with the thing signified.’<br />

74 Hume, Treatise, p. 151 (1.3.13).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!