27.04.2015 Views

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

94 EQUIVALENT DEFINITIONS OF COMPUTABILITY<br />

8.2 Universal Turing Machines<br />

The connection we have established between Turing computability <strong>and</strong> recursiveness<br />

enables us to establish properties of each notion that it would have been more difficult<br />

to establish working with that notion in isolation. We begin with one example of this<br />

phenomenon pertaining to Turing machines, <strong>and</strong> one to recursive functions.<br />

8.3 Theorem. The same class of functions are Turing computable whether one defines<br />

Turing machines to have a tape infinite in both directions or infinite in only one direction,<br />

<strong>and</strong> whether one requires Turing machines to operate with only one symbol in addition to<br />

the blank, or allows them to operate with any finite number.<br />

Proof: Suppose we have a Turing machine M of the kind we have been working<br />

with, with a two-way infinite tape. In this chapter we have seen that the total or<br />

partial function f computed by M is recursive. In earlier chapters we have seen how<br />

a recursive function f can be computed by an abacus machine <strong>and</strong> hence by a Turing<br />

machine simulating an abacus machine. But the Turing machines simulating abacus<br />

machines are rather special: according to the problems at the end of Chapter 5, any<br />

abacus-computable function can be computed by a Turing machine that never moves<br />

left of the square on which it is started. Thus we have now shown that for any Turing<br />

machine there is another Turing machine computing the same function that uses only<br />

the right half of its tape. In other words, if we had begun with a more restrictive notion<br />

of Turing machine, where the tape is infinite in one direction only, we would have<br />

obtained the same class of Turing-computable functions as with our official, more<br />

liberal definition.<br />

Inversely, suppose we allowed Turing machines to operate not only with the blank<br />

0 <strong>and</strong> the stroke 1, but also with another symbol 2. Then in the proof of the preceding<br />

sections we would need to work with ternary rather than binary numerals, to code<br />

Turing machines by sequences of length a multiple of six rather than of four, <strong>and</strong><br />

make similar minor changes. But with such changes, the proof would still go through,<br />

<strong>and</strong> show that any function computable by a Turing machine of this liberalized kind<br />

is still recursive—<strong>and</strong> therefore was computable by a Turing machine of the original<br />

kind already. The result generalizes to more than two symbols in an obvious way:<br />

for n symbols counting the blank, we need n-ary numerals <strong>and</strong> sequences of length a<br />

multiple of 2n.<br />

Similar, somewhat more complicated arguments show that allowing a Turing machine<br />

to work on a two-dimensional grid rather than a one-dimensional tape would<br />

not enlarge the class of functions that are computable. Likewise the class of functions<br />

computable would not be changed if we allowed the use of blank, 0, <strong>and</strong> 1, <strong>and</strong> redefined<br />

computations so that inputs <strong>and</strong> outputs are to be given in binary rather than<br />

stroke notation. That class is, as is said, stable under perturbations of definition, one<br />

mark of a natural class of objects.<br />

8.4 Theorem (Kleene normal form theorem). Every recursive total or partial function<br />

can be obtained from the basic functions (zero, successor, identity) by composition, primitive<br />

recursion, <strong>and</strong> minimization, using this last process no more than once.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!