27.04.2015 Views

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

17.3*. UNDECIDABLE SENTENCES WITHOUT THE DIAGONAL LEMMA 227<br />

representability of recursive functions. Once that apparatus is in place, a version of<br />

the incompleteness theorem, showing the existence of a true but unprovable sentence,<br />

can be established without the diagonal lemma. One way to do so is indicated in the<br />

first problem at the end of this chapter. (This way uses the fact that there exist semirecursive<br />

sets that are not recursive, <strong>and</strong> though it does not use the diagonal lemma,<br />

does involve a diagonal argument, buried in the proof of the fact just cited.) Some<br />

other ways will be indicated in the present section.<br />

Towards describing one such way, recall the Epimenides or liar paradox, involving<br />

the sentence ‘This sentence is untrue’. A contradiction arises when we ask whether<br />

this sentence is true: it seems that it is if <strong>and</strong> only if it isn’t. The Gödel sentence<br />

in effect results from this paradoxical sentence on substituting ‘provable’ for ‘true’<br />

(a substitution that is crucial for establishing that we can actually construct a Gödel<br />

sentence in the language of arithmetic). Now there are other semantic paradoxes,<br />

paradoxes in the same family as the liar paradox, involving other semantic notions<br />

related to truth. One famous one is the Grelling or heterological paradox. Call an<br />

adjective autological if it is true of itself, as ‘short’ is short, ‘polysyllabic’ is polysyllabic,<br />

<strong>and</strong> ‘English’ is English, <strong>and</strong> call it heterological if it is untrue of itself, as<br />

‘long’ is not long, ‘monosyllabic’ is not monosyllabic, <strong>and</strong> ‘French’ is not French. A<br />

contradiction arises when we ask whether ‘heterological’ is heterological: it seems<br />

that it is if <strong>and</strong> only if it isn’t.<br />

Let us modify the definition of heterologicality by substituting ‘provable’ for<br />

‘true’. We then get the notion of self-applicability: a number m is self-applicable<br />

in Q if it is the Gödel number of a formula μ(x) such that μ(m) is provable in Q.<br />

Now the same apparatus that allowed us to construct the Gödel sentence allows us<br />

to construct what may be called the Gödel–Grelling formula GG(x) expressing ‘x<br />

is not self-applicable’. Let m be its Gödel number. If m were self-applicable, then<br />

GG(m) would be provable, hence true, <strong>and</strong> since what it expresses is that m is not<br />

self-applicable, this is impossible. So m is not self-applicable, <strong>and</strong> hence GG(m) is<br />

true but unprovable.<br />

Another semantic paradox, Berry’s paradox, concerns the least integer not namable<br />

in fewer than nineteen syllables. The paradox, of course, is that the integer in question<br />

appears to have been named just now in eighteen syllables. This paradox, too, can be<br />

adapted to give an example of a sentence undecidable in Q. Let us say that a number<br />

n is denominable in Q by a formula φ(x) if∀x(φ(x) ↔ x = n) is (not just true but)<br />

provable in Q.<br />

Every number n is denominable in Q, since if worse comes to worst, it can always<br />

be denominated by the formula x = n, a formula with n + 3 symbols. Some numbers<br />

n are denominable in Q by formulas with far fewer than n symbols. For example, the<br />

number 10 ⇑ 10 is denominable by the formula φ(10, 10, x), where φ is a formula<br />

representing the super-exponential function ⇑. We have not actually written out this<br />

formula, but instructions for doing so are implicit in the proof that all recursive functions<br />

are representable, <strong>and</strong> review of that proof reveals that writing out the formula<br />

would not take more time or more paper than an ordinary homework assignment. By<br />

contrast, 10 ⇑ 10 is larger than the number of particles in the visible universe. But<br />

while big numbers can thus be denominated by comparatively short formulas, for any<br />

fixed k, only finitely many numbers can be denominated by formulas with fewer than

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!