27.04.2015 Views

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

Computability and Logic

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

234 THE UNPROVABILITY OF CONSISTENCY<br />

18.3 Theorem (Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem, abstract form). Let T be a<br />

consistent, axiomatizable extension of P, <strong>and</strong> let B(x) be a formula having properties<br />

(P1)–(P3) above. Then not ⊢ T ∼B( 0 = 1 ).<br />

The proof will occupy the remainder of this chapter. Throughout, let T be an<br />

extension (not necessarily consistent) of Q. A formula B(x) with properties (P1)–<br />

(P3) of Lemma 18.2 we call a provability predicate for T .Webeginwithafew<br />

words about this notion. The formula Prv T (x) considered so far we call the traditional<br />

provability predicate for T , though, as we have indicated, we are not going to give the<br />

proof of Lemma 18.2, <strong>and</strong> so are not going to be giving the proof that the ‘traditional<br />

provability predicate’ is a ‘provability predicate’ in the sense of our official definition<br />

of the latter term.<br />

If T is ω-consistent, taking the traditional Prv T (x) for B(x), we have also the<br />

following property, the converse of (P1):<br />

(P4)<br />

If ⊢ T B( A ) then ⊢ T A.<br />

[For if we had ⊢ T Prv T ( A ), or in other words ⊢ T ∃y Prf T ( A , y), but did not have<br />

⊢ T A, then for each b, ∼Prf T ( A , b) would be correct <strong>and</strong> hence provable in Q <strong>and</strong><br />

hence in T , <strong>and</strong> we would have an ω-inconsistency in T .] We do not, however, include<br />

ω-consistency in our assumptions on T , or (P4) in our definition of the technical<br />

term ‘provability predicate’. Without the assumption of (P4), which is not part of our<br />

official definition, a ‘provability predicate’ need not have much to do with provability.<br />

In fact, the formula x = x is easily seen to be a ‘provability predicate’ in the sense<br />

of our definition.<br />

On the other h<strong>and</strong>, a formula may arithmetically define the set of Gödel numbers<br />

of theorems of T without being a provability predicate for T .IfT is consistent <strong>and</strong><br />

Prv T (x) is the traditional provability predicate for T , then not only does Prv T (x)<br />

arithmetically define the set of Gödel numbers of theorems of T , but so does the<br />

formula Prv* T (x), which is the conjunction of Prv T (x) with ∼Prv T ( 0 = 1 ), since the<br />

second conjunct is true. But notice that, in contrast to Theorem 18.1, ∼Prv* T ( 0 = 1 )<br />

is provable in T . For it is simply<br />

∼(Prv T ( 0 = 1 )&∼Prv T ( 0 = 1 ))<br />

which is a valid sentence <strong>and</strong> hence a theorem of any theory. The formula Prv* T (x),<br />

however, lacks property (P1) in the definition of provability predicate. That is, it<br />

is not the case that if ⊢ T A then ⊢ T Prv* T ( A ). Indeed, it is never the case that<br />

⊢ T Prv* T ( A ), since it is not the case that ⊢ T ∼Prv T ( 0 = 1 ), by Theorem 18.1.<br />

The traditional provability predicate Prv T (x) has the further important, if nonmathematical,<br />

property beyond (P0)–(P4), that intuitively speaking Prv(x) can plausibly<br />

be regarded as meaning or saying (on the st<strong>and</strong>ard interpretation) that x is the Gödel<br />

number of a sentence that is provable in T . This is conspicuously not the case for<br />

Prv* T (x), which means or says that x the Gödel number of a sentence that is provable<br />

in T <strong>and</strong> T is consistent.<br />

The thought that whatever is provable had better be true might make it surprising<br />

that a further condition was not included in the definition of provability predicate,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!