16.11.2012 Views

1 Political authority and obligation Political authority and obligation

1 Political authority and obligation Political authority and obligation

1 Political authority and obligation Political authority and obligation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Political</strong> <strong>authority</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>obligation</strong> 11<br />

Th e following sections will discuss various arguments in support of the claim that we have<br />

a duty to obey the law. In order to assess these arguments, you should try to work out on<br />

what normative <strong>and</strong> descriptive premises they rely, <strong>and</strong> how plausible you think those<br />

premises are.<br />

Consent<br />

By far the most widely discussed justifi cation for political <strong>authority</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>obligation</strong> is what<br />

is o ft en called consent theory (o r contract theory). C onsent t heorists c laim t hat w e<br />

should obey the law because we have consented to do so. Consent theory is a type of voluntarism,<br />

because it says that our <strong>obligation</strong> to obey the law derives from a v oluntary<br />

undertaking on our part.<br />

Consent theory is oft en associated with the seventeenth-century English philosophers<br />

Th omas Hobbes <strong>and</strong> John Locke, <strong>and</strong> with the eighteenth-century French philosopher<br />

Jean-Jacques Rousseau. But the thought that we have consented to obey the law was fi rst<br />

given currency by the Greek philosopher Plato, in his dialogue ‘Crito’ (360 bc; 1892). Plato<br />

recounts how Socrates was condemned to death by an Athenian court for corrupting the<br />

minds of the youth with his ideas. Whereas Socrates’ friends urge him to escape, Socrates<br />

himself refuses to fl ee <strong>and</strong> stays to drink the fatal hemlock. Socrates argues, among other<br />

things, t hat his lo ng residence in A thens constitutes an agreement to ob ey t he laws of<br />

Athens. By living in Athens he has, in o ther words, consented to obey the law. He must<br />

therefore respect the court’s verdict <strong>and</strong> submit to his execution.<br />

KEY CONCEPTS<br />

Consent<br />

When someone consents to something, he or she either takes on a duty to do a particular<br />

thing or permits others to do a particular thing. Consent is important not only to politics, but<br />

also to a whole range of contexts. We talk, for example, about whether sex was consensual,<br />

about consenting to some medical treatment, <strong>and</strong> so on. As Hurd writes (1996: 123): ‘Consent<br />

turns a trespass into a dinner party; a battery into a h<strong>and</strong>shake; a theft into a gift; an invasion<br />

of privacy into an intimate moment; a commercial appropriation of name <strong>and</strong> likeness into a<br />

biography.’<br />

Consent theorists make two claims. First, they claim that, by consenting to obey the law,<br />

each of us can impose on ourselves an <strong>obligation</strong> to obey the law. Second, they claim that<br />

we have, in fac t, consented to obey the law. Th e fi rst of these claims has g enerally been<br />

regarded as uncontroversial; it is the second claim that has provoked one of the liveliest<br />

<strong>and</strong> most enduring debates in the history of political thought. As the eighteenth-century<br />

Scottish philosopher David Hume wrote:

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!