09.07.2015 Views

Subjectivism and Economic Analysis: Essays in memory of Ludwig ...

Subjectivism and Economic Analysis: Essays in memory of Ludwig ...

Subjectivism and Economic Analysis: Essays in memory of Ludwig ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

SUBJECTIVISM ANDECONOMIC ANALYSISThe extraord<strong>in</strong>ary heterogeneity <strong>of</strong> the scholars <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> thework <strong>of</strong> <strong>Ludwig</strong> M.Lachmann—Austrians, Keynesians, PostKeynesians, New Institutional economists, Old Institutionaleconomists <strong>and</strong> even some Sraffians—testifies to the importance <strong>of</strong>his ideas. Lachmann made important contributions to the defence<strong>and</strong> development <strong>of</strong> the modern Austrian school <strong>of</strong> economicthought. Few economists have rivalled his will<strong>in</strong>gness to confrontproblems that appear to fall outside the grasp <strong>of</strong> the conventionaltools <strong>of</strong> the discipl<strong>in</strong>e. His methodological <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong> the area <strong>of</strong>radical subjectivism are particularly important <strong>and</strong> are the focus <strong>of</strong>this collection.The contributions <strong>in</strong> this volume explore, from a variety <strong>of</strong>perspectives, the methodological issues raised by Lachmann’s work.Lead<strong>in</strong>g scholars discuss such issues as:• the connection <strong>of</strong> Lachmanns ideas to those <strong>of</strong> Max Weber• the critique <strong>of</strong> equilibrium analysis• the implications <strong>of</strong> radical subjectivism for policy activism• the philosophical foundations <strong>of</strong> radical subjectivism<strong>Subjectivism</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Analysis</strong> is a fitt<strong>in</strong>g tribute to a groundbreak<strong>in</strong>geconomist <strong>and</strong> makes a major contribution to animportant field <strong>of</strong> research.Roger Koppl is a Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> F<strong>in</strong>ance at FairleighDick<strong>in</strong>son University, New Jersey, USA. He has published widely <strong>in</strong>the fields <strong>of</strong> political economy <strong>and</strong> economic history. Gary Mongioviis an Associate Pr<strong>of</strong>essor <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s at St John’s University, NewYork, USA <strong>and</strong> co-editor <strong>of</strong> The Review <strong>of</strong> Political Economy.


ROUTLEDGE FRONTIERS OF POLITICALECONOMY1 EQUILIBRIUM VERSUSUNDERSTANDINGTowards the rehumanization <strong>of</strong>economics with<strong>in</strong> social theoryMark Addleson2 EVOLUTION, ORDER ANDCOMPLEXITYEdited by Elias L.Khalil <strong>and</strong> Kenneth E.Bould<strong>in</strong>g3 INTERACTIONS INPOLITICAL ECONOMYMalvern after ten yearsEdited by Steven Pressman4 THE END OF ECONOMICSMichael Perelman5 PROBABILITY INECONOMICSOmar F.Hamouda <strong>and</strong> Rob<strong>in</strong> Rowley6 CAPITAL CONTROVERSY,POST KEYNESIAN ECONOMICSAND THE HISTORY OFECONOMICS<strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> honour <strong>of</strong> Ge<strong>of</strong>f Harcourt,volume oneEdited by Philip Arestis, Gabriel Palma<strong>and</strong> Malcolm Sawyer7 MARKETS, UNEMPLOYMENTAND ECONOMIC POLICY<strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> honour <strong>of</strong> Ge<strong>of</strong>f Harcourt,volume twoEdited by Philip Arestis, Gabriel Palma<strong>and</strong> Malcolm Sawyer8 SOCIAL ECONOMYThe logic <strong>of</strong> capitalist developmentClark Everl<strong>in</strong>g9 NEW KEYNESIANECONOMICS/POST KEYNESIANALTERNATIVESEdited by Roy J.Rotheim10 THE REPRESENTATIVEAGENT IN MACROECONOMICSJames E.Hartley11 BORDERLANDS OFECONOMICS<strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> honour <strong>of</strong> Daniel R.FusfeldEdited by Nahid Aslanbeigui <strong>and</strong> YoungBack Choi12 VALUE DISTRIBUTION ANDCAPITALEdited by Gary Mongiovi <strong>and</strong> Fabio Petri13 THE ECONOMICS OFSCIENCEMethodology <strong>and</strong> epistemology as ifeconomics really matteredJames R.Wible14 COMPETITIVENESS,LOCALISED LEARNING ANDREGIONAL DEVELOPMENTSpecialisation <strong>and</strong> prosperity <strong>in</strong> smallopen economiesPeter Maskell, Heikki Eskel<strong>in</strong>en, IngjaldurHannibalsson, Anders Malmberg <strong>and</strong> EirikVatne15 LABOUR MARKET THEORYA constructive reassessmentBen J.F<strong>in</strong>e16 WOMEN AND EUROPEANEMPLOYMENTJill Rubery, Mark Smith, Colette Fagan,Damian Grimshaw17 EXPLORATIONS INECONOMIC METHODOLOGYFrom Lakatos to empirical philosophy<strong>of</strong> scienceRoger Backhouse18 SUBJECTIVITY INPOLITICAL ECONOMY<strong>Essays</strong> on want<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> choos<strong>in</strong>gDavid P.Lev<strong>in</strong>e19 THE POLITICAL ECONOMYOF MIDDLE EAST PEACEThe impact <strong>of</strong> compet<strong>in</strong>g Arab <strong>and</strong>Israeli tradeEdited by J.W.Wright, Jnr20 THE ACTIVE CONSUMERNovelty <strong>and</strong> surprise <strong>in</strong> consumerchoiceEdited by Mar<strong>in</strong>a Bianchi21 SUBJECTIVISM ANDECONOMIC ANALYSIS<strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>memory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Ludwig</strong> M.LachmannEdited by Roger Koppl <strong>and</strong> Gary Mongiovi


SUBJECTIVISM ANDECONOMICANALYSIS<strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>memory</strong> <strong>of</strong><strong>Ludwig</strong> M.LachmannEdited by Roger Koppl <strong>and</strong>Gary MongioviLondon <strong>and</strong> New York


First published 1998by Routledge11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EEThis edition published <strong>in</strong> the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2003.Simultaneously published <strong>in</strong> the USA <strong>and</strong> Canadaby Routledge29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001Editorial material <strong>and</strong> selection © 1998 Roger Koppl <strong>and</strong> GaryMongioviIndividual chapters © 1998 the <strong>in</strong>dividual contributorsAll rights reserved. No part <strong>of</strong> this book may be repr<strong>in</strong>ted orreproduced or utilised <strong>in</strong> any form or by any electronic,mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter <strong>in</strong>vented,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g photocopy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> record<strong>in</strong>g, or <strong>in</strong> any<strong>in</strong>formation storage or retrieval system, without permission<strong>in</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g from the publishers.British Library Catalogu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Publication DataA catalogue record for this book is available from the British LibraryLibrary <strong>of</strong> Congress Catalog<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Publication Data<strong>Subjectivism</strong> <strong>and</strong> economic analysis: essays <strong>in</strong> <strong>memory</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Ludwig</strong> M.Lachmann/edited by Roger Koppl <strong>and</strong> Gary Mongiovi.Included bibliographical references.1. Lachmann, <strong>Ludwig</strong> M. 2. <strong>Economic</strong>s. 3. <strong>Economic</strong>s—methodology.4. <strong>Economic</strong>s—History—20th century. I. Lachmann, <strong>Ludwig</strong> M.II. Koppl, Roger, 1957– . III. Mongiovi, Gary.HB107.L33S83 1998330–dc21 98–7044CIPISBN 0-203-41081-5 Master e-book ISBNISBN 0-203-71905-0 (Adobe eReader Format)ISBN 0-415-11058-0 (Pr<strong>in</strong>t Edition)


CONTENTSNotes 57References 594 Lachmann on the subjectivism <strong>of</strong> active m<strong>in</strong>ds 61ROGER KOPPLIntroduction 61The Lachmann problem 62<strong>Ludwig</strong> von Mises <strong>and</strong> the Lachmann problem 64J.M.Keynes <strong>and</strong> the Lachmann problem 67Alfred Schutz <strong>and</strong> the Lachmann problem 68F.A.Hayek <strong>and</strong> the Lachmann problem 72Conclusion 77Acknowledgements 77Notes 78References 785 <strong>Subjectivism</strong> <strong>and</strong> ideal types: Lachmann <strong>and</strong> themethodological legacy <strong>of</strong> Max Weber 80LÁSLÓ CSONTOSIntroduction 80<strong>Subjectivism</strong> 80Ideal types 92Conclusion 97Notes 98References 1026 Endogenous change, open systems <strong>and</strong> provisionalequilibrium 104MAURIZIO CASERTAIntroduction 105The nature <strong>of</strong> change 106Hahn’s notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium 109Models <strong>of</strong> provisional equilibrium 113An open-system approach 114Four regimes <strong>of</strong> growth 118Conclusion 122Acknowledgements 122viii


CONTENTSNotes 122References 1247 Radical subjectivism <strong>and</strong> Austrian economics 125CARLO ZAPPIAIntroduction 125Rational ignorance 127<strong>Economic</strong> order <strong>and</strong> economic <strong>in</strong>stitutions 133Conclud<strong>in</strong>g remarks 138Acknowledgements 139Notes 139References 1408 Hierarchical metaphors <strong>in</strong> Austrian <strong>in</strong>stitutionalism:a friendly subjectivist caveat 143STEVEN HORWITZAustrian <strong>in</strong>stitutionalism 144<strong>Subjectivism</strong> <strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>stitutional order 148Parallels between Austrian theories <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> capital 151Bank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> the law: an illustration 155Conclusion 158Notes 158References 1609 Lachmann’s policy activism: an Austrian critique <strong>of</strong>Keynesian proclivities 163PETER J.BOETTKE AND STEVEN T.SULLIVANIntroduction 163Underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g the capital-us<strong>in</strong>g economy 166Lachmann on the price system <strong>and</strong> the trade cycle 170Lachmannian stabilisation policy 173Conclusion 178Notes 180References 181ix


CONTENTS10 Expectations <strong>and</strong> stock market prices 183JOCHEN RUNDE AND JÖRG BIBOWExpectations 184Divergent expectations <strong>and</strong> equity prices 186Diverse op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>and</strong> equity prices 188Conclusion 196Notes 197References 199Index 201x


CONTRIBUTORSJörg Bibow, University <strong>of</strong> Hamburg, Germany.Peter J.Boettke, George Mason University, Fairfax, Virg<strong>in</strong>ia.Maurizio Caserta, University <strong>of</strong> Catania, Italy.Lásló Csontos † , Central European University, Budapest, Hungary.Steven Horwitz, St Lawrence University, Canton, New York, USA.Roger Koppl, Fairleigh Dick<strong>in</strong>son University, Madison, NewJersey, USA.Brian J.Loasby, University <strong>of</strong> Stirl<strong>in</strong>g, Scotl<strong>and</strong>.Gary Mongiovi, St John’s University, New York, USA.Stephen D.Parsons, DeMontfort University, Leicester, Engl<strong>and</strong>.Jochen Runde, Girton College, Cambridge, Engl<strong>and</strong>.Steven T.Sullivan, New York University, New York, USA.Carlo Zappia, University <strong>of</strong> Siena, Italy.xi


1INTRODUCTIONRoger Koppl <strong>and</strong> Gary MongioviThe extraord<strong>in</strong>ary heterogeneity <strong>of</strong> the scholars <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> thework <strong>of</strong> <strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann testifies to the importance <strong>of</strong> his ideas.Lachmann gets serious attention from Austrians, Keynesians, PostKeynesians, New Institutional economists, Old Institutionaleconomists, <strong>and</strong> even some Sraffians. Most <strong>of</strong> these schools arerepresented <strong>in</strong> this volume. Even the two editors <strong>of</strong> this volume arevery far apart on issues <strong>of</strong> political economy, technical economictheory, <strong>and</strong> methodology. This unusual diversity suggests that whatLachmann had to say was significant. He was work<strong>in</strong>g at thefoundations <strong>of</strong> our science, where depth <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>sight counts for morethan technical prowess. And the problems Lachmann found at thefoundations have been recognised as important by very diverseeconomists. The path lead<strong>in</strong>g to Lachmann’s broad <strong>in</strong>fluence ledhim through four different countries on three different cont<strong>in</strong>entsspeak<strong>in</strong>g two different languages, unit<strong>in</strong>g one very long <strong>and</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>guished career.Lachmann’s career as an economist began <strong>in</strong> his native Berl<strong>in</strong>dur<strong>in</strong>g the years <strong>of</strong> the Weimar Republic. In 1924 he enrolled <strong>in</strong>the University <strong>of</strong> Berl<strong>in</strong> where Werner Sombart would become hisdissertation advisor. As a member <strong>of</strong> the ‘younger historicalschool’, Sombart had a respect for the ideas <strong>of</strong> Max Weber <strong>and</strong> adistaste for the Austrian school. While a student <strong>in</strong> Berl<strong>in</strong>,Lachmann hired Emil Kauder as his tutor. Study<strong>in</strong>g both Pareto<strong>and</strong> the Austrians, they came to view the subjective theory <strong>of</strong> valueas essentially correct <strong>and</strong> the general equilibrium theory <strong>of</strong> Walras<strong>and</strong> Pareto as <strong>in</strong>adequate. Thus, Lachmann ended his studies <strong>in</strong>Germany an adherent <strong>of</strong> both the method <strong>of</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g(Verstehen) practised by German <strong>in</strong>terpretive sociology <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> theAustrian theory <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al utility.The <strong>in</strong>tellectual position to which Lachmann was led by his1


ROGER KOPPL AND GARY MONGIOVIstudies with Sombart <strong>and</strong> Kauder was hardly welcome or natural <strong>in</strong>German academic circles. The German historical school had alwaysbeen hostile to the Austrians. Moreover, Lachmann was a liberal<strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> his own words, ‘support for, <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>, themarket economy, never very strong <strong>in</strong> these circles, had almostvanished’ by the late twenties (Lachmann 1981). Lachmann was tospend most <strong>of</strong> his pr<strong>of</strong>essional life defend<strong>in</strong>g positions that weredismissed out <strong>of</strong> h<strong>and</strong> by academic orthodoxy.Lachmann, twice damned as both Jew <strong>and</strong> liberal, left Hitler’sGermany for Engl<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> 1933. There he studied under Hicks <strong>and</strong>Hayek at the London School <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s. In London, he metanother student <strong>of</strong> Hayek, George Shackle. But it was not Shacklewho taught him the importance <strong>of</strong> expectations <strong>in</strong> economics. It wasthrough his contacts with another refugee scholar, Paul Rosenste<strong>in</strong>-Rodan, that Lachmann learned the importance <strong>of</strong> expectations.Rosenste<strong>in</strong>-Rodan had been an assistant to Hans Mayer, who heldMenger’s chair <strong>in</strong> the University <strong>of</strong> Vienna. ‘It was Rosenste<strong>in</strong>-Rodan’, Lachmann once expla<strong>in</strong>ed, ‘who <strong>in</strong> discuss<strong>in</strong>g Austriantrade cycle theory with me said, “Ah yes, but whatever happens <strong>in</strong>the bus<strong>in</strong>ess cycle is <strong>in</strong> the first place determ<strong>in</strong>ed by expectations”’(Lachmann 1978). The subjectivism <strong>of</strong> expectations was to becomea peculiarly Lachmannian theme.In the 1930s, Hayek’s thought dom<strong>in</strong>ated discussion at the LSE.The Great Depression put an end to that. Keynes had the rightmedic<strong>in</strong>e. Or so it seemed. Hayek <strong>and</strong> the Austrians were eclipsed.Hicks, Kaldor, Lerner, <strong>and</strong> Shackle were all carried along <strong>in</strong> theKeynesian tide. Even Robb<strong>in</strong>s quietly distanced himself from hisearly <strong>in</strong>discretion, the Mises-Hayek theory <strong>of</strong> the trade cycle. AsWalter Gr<strong>in</strong>der (1977) has put it, by the time the war began, ‘theonly consistent <strong>and</strong> thoroughgo<strong>in</strong>g Hayekians left were Lachmann<strong>and</strong> Hayek himself. Lachmann found himself <strong>in</strong> considerable<strong>in</strong>tellectual isolation once aga<strong>in</strong>, just as <strong>in</strong> Berl<strong>in</strong> before.After a fellowship which permitted him to visit many schools <strong>in</strong>the United States <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the University <strong>of</strong> Chicago where heparticipated <strong>in</strong> Frank Knight’s sem<strong>in</strong>ar, Lachmann taught at theUniversity <strong>of</strong> London <strong>and</strong> then the University <strong>of</strong> Hull. In 1949, hewas appo<strong>in</strong>ted to the chair <strong>in</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> History atthe University <strong>of</strong> Wittwatersr<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> South Africa. Dur<strong>in</strong>g theseyears he developed his radical subjectivist position with a constancy<strong>of</strong> purpose that never flagged <strong>in</strong> the face <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream <strong>in</strong>difference.The renaissance <strong>of</strong> the Austrian school began <strong>in</strong> the 1970s <strong>and</strong>soon came to be centred at New York University. Under the2


INTRODUCTIONdirection <strong>of</strong> Israel Kirzner, a programme <strong>in</strong> Austrian economics wasbegun. At Kirzner’s <strong>in</strong>vitation, Lachmann was brought to NYU <strong>in</strong>1975 as a Visit<strong>in</strong>g Research Pr<strong>of</strong>essor. Until 1987 when his healthprevented it, Lachmann travelled each spr<strong>in</strong>g to NYU to participate<strong>in</strong> the Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s Colloquium <strong>and</strong> to give a sem<strong>in</strong>ar on‘Topics <strong>in</strong> Advanced <strong>Economic</strong> Theory’.In these f<strong>in</strong>al years Lachmann’s patient exposition <strong>of</strong> his radicalsubjectivist views f<strong>in</strong>ally received the sort <strong>of</strong> attention it deserved.Young Austrians were not the only students com<strong>in</strong>g under his<strong>in</strong>fluence. Post Keynesians <strong>and</strong> other opponents <strong>of</strong> neoclassicalorthodoxy also discovered him. By the time Lachmann died <strong>in</strong>December 1990 he had ensured a future for his ideas by leav<strong>in</strong>gbeh<strong>in</strong>d him a large <strong>and</strong> heterogeneous group <strong>of</strong> young scholarsstrongly <strong>in</strong>fluenced by his work.The difficulty <strong>in</strong> classify<strong>in</strong>g Lachmann accord<strong>in</strong>g to schools <strong>of</strong>thought testifies to the orig<strong>in</strong>ality <strong>of</strong> his thought. Lachmann isgenerally thought <strong>of</strong> as an Austrian economist. And yet theacademics who most zealously claim that label generally repudiateLachmann’s views as ‘nihilistic’. Lachmann’s closest <strong>in</strong>tellectual allywas probably G.L.S.Shackle, a scholar generally counted among theKeynesian or Post Keynesian ranks. Hayek once describedLachmann’s Capital <strong>and</strong> its Structure (1956) as conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g all thatwas <strong>of</strong> value <strong>in</strong> Hayek’s own Pure Theory <strong>of</strong> Capital. Nevertheless,Lachmann was to reject his teacher’s def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> economics as thestudy <strong>of</strong> the un<strong>in</strong>tended consequences <strong>of</strong> human action (Lachmann1986:32–3). The <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> Sombart was to be reflected <strong>in</strong>Lachmann’s book The Legacy <strong>of</strong> Max Weber (1971b). Sombartmay even have been one <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>fluences encourag<strong>in</strong>g Lachmann totake a sceptical view <strong>of</strong> the predictive powers <strong>of</strong> economic theory.As we have seen, however, Sombart’s <strong>in</strong>fluence was not sufficient tokeep Lachmann from identify<strong>in</strong>g with the Austrian tradition <strong>of</strong>Menger, Mises, <strong>and</strong> Hayek.The great variety <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluences on Lachmann <strong>and</strong> the greatvariety <strong>of</strong> persons upon whom he had an <strong>in</strong>fluence are reflections <strong>of</strong>a marked openness <strong>of</strong> his thought <strong>and</strong> character. Lachmann waspersonally a very open-m<strong>in</strong>ded th<strong>in</strong>ker. He was one <strong>of</strong> the fewserious scholars, for <strong>in</strong>stance, to give careful consideration to theanti-<strong>in</strong>flation proposal <strong>of</strong> Abba Lerner <strong>and</strong> David Col<strong>and</strong>er. (For atime, their proposal was required read<strong>in</strong>g for students <strong>in</strong> NYU’sprogramme <strong>in</strong> Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s.)Lachmann’s attitude towards students was also that <strong>of</strong> openness.He was always available for discussions with graduate students. He3


ROGER KOPPL AND GARY MONGIOVImade graduate students feel like equal participants <strong>in</strong> an ongo<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> urgent discussion. He encouraged them to apply their ownm<strong>in</strong>ds to the issues <strong>of</strong> economic theory. Lachmann taught hisstudents what the lead<strong>in</strong>g problems <strong>of</strong> economics theory are. Hepursued them with undeviat<strong>in</strong>g attention. Even when his denturesonce fell out dur<strong>in</strong>g class lecture, he was unperturbed. Wrapp<strong>in</strong>g thedentures <strong>in</strong> a h<strong>and</strong>kerchief <strong>and</strong> stuff<strong>in</strong>g them <strong>in</strong> his pocket, hecont<strong>in</strong>ued to lecture as if noth<strong>in</strong>g had happened. But the gr<strong>in</strong> hecould not suppress betrayed his amusement. Perhaps his aplomb onthis occasion was a lesson. Let s get on with the bus<strong>in</strong>ess at h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong>not be disturbed by such trifles as loose dentures.Lachmann’s openness <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>and</strong> spirit was frequently passedon, as if by osmosis, to the students who came under his <strong>in</strong>fluence.Lachmann charmed his students <strong>and</strong> held them, fasc<strong>in</strong>ated, <strong>in</strong> hisgrip. We believe the ultimate source <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s magic was asimple characteristic that has become <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly rare <strong>in</strong> academe<strong>and</strong> out: <strong>in</strong>tellectual honesty.His undeviat<strong>in</strong>g pursuit <strong>of</strong> truth as he saw it led him to amethodological position whose central element is ‘subjectivism’.Lachmann’s subjectivism embraced three <strong>in</strong>terrelated themes thatrun through his work: the explanatory primacy <strong>of</strong> subjectiveevaluations; the importance <strong>of</strong> expectations; <strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>adequacy <strong>of</strong>equilibrium models <strong>of</strong> the market.Lachmann viewed historical events as the outcome <strong>of</strong>purposeful human action that orig<strong>in</strong>ates <strong>in</strong> the formation <strong>of</strong> plans;S<strong>in</strong>ce it is purposeful action that economists seek to underst<strong>and</strong>,their pr<strong>in</strong>cipal task, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Lachmann, is to elucidate themental processes by which plans are formed. <strong>Subjectivism</strong> is themethodological doctr<strong>in</strong>e that economic explanation must trace allcausality to such mental acts, which differ from person to person.This subjectivist view <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs is what Lachmann meant bymethodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism.Lachmann dist<strong>in</strong>guished three ‘levels’ <strong>of</strong> subjectivism (1990).First, the subjectivism <strong>of</strong> wants recognises that different people havedifferent tastes <strong>and</strong> pursue different ends. Second, the subjectivism<strong>of</strong> ends <strong>and</strong> means recognises that people may pursue similar ends <strong>in</strong>dissimilar ways. People have diverse, sometimes erroneous, ideasabout the best ways to achieve any goal. F<strong>in</strong>ally, the subjectivism <strong>of</strong>active m<strong>in</strong>ds recognises that <strong>in</strong> all aspects <strong>of</strong> action the active m<strong>in</strong>dmay produce <strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>and</strong> possibilities the observ<strong>in</strong>geconomist cannot imag<strong>in</strong>e <strong>in</strong> advance. ‘The mental activity <strong>of</strong>order<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> formulat<strong>in</strong>g ends, allocat<strong>in</strong>g means to them, mak<strong>in</strong>g4


INTRODUCTION<strong>and</strong> revis<strong>in</strong>g plans, determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g when action has been successful, allthese are its forms <strong>of</strong> expression’ (Lachmann 1982:37). This is‘radical subjectivism’.The radical subjectivism to which Lachmann was committed wentfar beyond the specification <strong>of</strong> agents’ preferences as part <strong>of</strong> the datawhich regulate prices, outputs, <strong>and</strong> distribution <strong>in</strong> a market economy.His notion <strong>of</strong> subjectivism derives <strong>in</strong>stead from the fact that agentsmust form plans on the basis <strong>of</strong> their <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> events that takeplace <strong>in</strong> a chang<strong>in</strong>g world about which they have <strong>in</strong>completeknowledge. The mental acts that precede action are therefore theproducts <strong>of</strong> human <strong>in</strong>genuity—imag<strong>in</strong>ative responses to the uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty<strong>of</strong> social existence; <strong>and</strong> they are based to a significant degree on agents’expectations about future states <strong>of</strong> nature.As early as 1943 Lachmann <strong>in</strong>sisted that ‘it is the subjectivenature <strong>of</strong>…beliefs which imparts <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ateness to expectationsas it is their mental nature which renders them capable <strong>of</strong>explanation’ (Lachmann 1943:72–3). In this essay Lachmannmapped out a position from which he never retreated. Becauseexpectations are themselves shaped by the course <strong>of</strong> economicevents, they cannot be regarded as parametric. Nor, accord<strong>in</strong>g toLachmann, can we connect them <strong>in</strong> any systematic way toobservable phenomena: he denies the possibility <strong>of</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g anyunivocal l<strong>in</strong>k between events <strong>and</strong> the expectations to which theygive rise. A given configuration <strong>of</strong> events, he argues, can generateany number <strong>of</strong> expectational responses. A price rise <strong>in</strong> a particularmarket, for example, could lead some agents to expect further price<strong>in</strong>creases <strong>and</strong> others to expect a reduction <strong>in</strong> price, withcorrespond<strong>in</strong>g consequences for their subsequent actions.Thus expectations ‘have to be regarded as economically<strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ate’ (ibid.: 67). For underly<strong>in</strong>g the price signals given <strong>of</strong>fby the market, ‘there lurks ultimately the problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation’(Lachmann 1956:67). This reason<strong>in</strong>g, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Lachmann,shatters the usefulness <strong>of</strong> equilibrium analysis as a device forunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g market-level phenomena (though he allowed alimited heuristic role for equilibrium at the level <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dividualeconomic actor). The problem is that the system has no way <strong>of</strong>gett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to equilibrium, because the market process itself entailscont<strong>in</strong>uous revision <strong>of</strong> the expectations that would presumably berequired to susta<strong>in</strong> such a position. Accord<strong>in</strong>gly, he rejects thenotion that theoretical models are capable <strong>of</strong> predict<strong>in</strong>g what willhappen <strong>in</strong> a particular set <strong>of</strong> circumstances, because no model cananticipate agents’ expectational responses to those circumstances.5


ROGER KOPPL AND GARY MONGIOVILachmann’s radical subjectivism led him to oppose ‘late classicalformalism’ <strong>and</strong> what he called the ‘Neo-Ricardiancounterrevolution.’ Lachmann co<strong>in</strong>ed the term late classicalformalism’ <strong>in</strong> 1971 to characterise neoclassical economists who had‘adopted an arid formalism as their style <strong>of</strong> thought, an approachwhich requires them to treat the manifestations <strong>of</strong> the human m<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong> household <strong>and</strong> market as purely formal entities, on par withmaterial resources’ (Lachmann 1971a:181). This formalism,Lachmann argued, had dra<strong>in</strong>ed the theory <strong>of</strong> any value. The theory‘has noth<strong>in</strong>g to say’ when ‘confronted with real problems’ (ibid.:182). He quotes Mises’s diagnosis that the theory is ‘A superficialanalogy…spun out too long, that is all’ (ibid.: 182). Lachmann’ssumm<strong>in</strong>g up is scath<strong>in</strong>g: ‘From Walras to Samuelson we f<strong>in</strong>d thesame manner <strong>of</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g, the same arbitrary assumptions, thesame unwarranted conclusions’ (ibid.: 189).Lachmann’s radical subjectivism led him to criticise the ‘Neo-Ricardian counterrevolution’. As Lachmann used the term, ‘Neo-Ricardianism’ identified the Cambridge followers <strong>of</strong> Piero Sraffa<strong>and</strong> Joan Rob<strong>in</strong>son, the UK side <strong>of</strong> the Cambridge-Cambridgecontroversy. Lachmann did not carefully dist<strong>in</strong>guish KeynesianCambridge economists from Sraffian Cambridge economists, acurious lapse <strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the important methodological differencesthat dist<strong>in</strong>guish the two traditions. His criticisms relate, <strong>in</strong> any case,ma<strong>in</strong>ly to the Sraffian branch, <strong>and</strong> were directed at what heregarded as its excessive formalism, at its attachment to the concept<strong>of</strong> equilibrium, <strong>and</strong> at its emphatic rejection <strong>of</strong> subjectivism: ‘A style<strong>of</strong> economic th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> which there is no place for humanpreferences, let alone time preferences, is hardly acceptable to theheirs <strong>of</strong> Menger’ (Lachmann 1977:29). Nevertheless, he didrecognise some po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> common ground between Austrian <strong>and</strong>Sraffian criticisms <strong>of</strong> orthodoxy, <strong>in</strong> particular concern<strong>in</strong>g the<strong>in</strong>adequacy <strong>of</strong> the neoclassical treatment <strong>of</strong> capital as a valueaggregate;but <strong>of</strong> course he differed with the Sraffians on howeconomic theory might be reconstructed to avoid capital-theoreticproblems.For Lachmann ‘it is <strong>in</strong>telligibility <strong>and</strong> not determ<strong>in</strong>ateness thatsocial science should strive to achieve’ (Lachmann 1943:68). Wemust take account not only <strong>of</strong> the ‘subjectivism <strong>of</strong> wants’ (that is,preferences), but also the ‘subjectivism <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation’. Theproper aim <strong>of</strong> economic theory, then, is to make events <strong>in</strong>telligibleby show<strong>in</strong>g why, <strong>in</strong> a given episode, a set <strong>of</strong> facts were <strong>in</strong>terpreted byagents <strong>in</strong> a particular way.6


INTRODUCTIONAs the language <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s 1943 essay shows, the problems<strong>of</strong> ‘<strong>in</strong>terpretation’ were central to his underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> expectations<strong>and</strong> radical subjectivism. In The Legacy <strong>of</strong> Max Weber (1971b),Lachmann identifies the ‘method <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation’ or, what is thesame th<strong>in</strong>g, the ‘method <strong>of</strong> Verstehen’ as the proper method <strong>of</strong> thesocial sciences. This was the same method espoused by Max Weber.Lachmann denied that the method was peculiarly related to thephilosophical idealism <strong>of</strong> the German Historical School from whichWeber emerged. It is ‘much older than German idealism <strong>and</strong> theHistorical School which, partly, sprang from it…. It is noth<strong>in</strong>g lessthan the traditional method <strong>of</strong> classical scholarship’ (1971b:18).The method <strong>of</strong> Verstehen is simply the traditional method <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g texts, but applied to human action. From about 1980,Lachmann began to use the word ‘hermeneutics’ to describe thismethod. Orig<strong>in</strong>ally hermeneutics was the science (Wissenschaft) <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g the Christian Bible. But as the term is employed today, itis the same method <strong>of</strong> classical scholarship that Lachmann extolled.From Weber, Lachmann also drew <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the role <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>stitutions. The traditional method <strong>of</strong> economic analysis expla<strong>in</strong>sthe co-ord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g function <strong>of</strong> markets <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> a process <strong>of</strong>gravitation towards some well-def<strong>in</strong>ed equilibrium position.Lachmann’s scepticism towards the notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium led him tolook elsewhere for the source <strong>of</strong> social order. He found it <strong>in</strong> theprevail<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stitutional framework. Institutions are rules that limitthe range <strong>of</strong> actions <strong>in</strong>dividuals are likely to take <strong>in</strong> a particularsituation, as for example, when two cars meet at an <strong>in</strong>tersection.Such rules simplify the formulation <strong>of</strong> plans by creat<strong>in</strong>g a sett<strong>in</strong>gwith<strong>in</strong> which many sorts <strong>of</strong> behaviour are governed by convention<strong>and</strong> can therefore be anticipated with some degree <strong>of</strong> confidence. Inthis way a network <strong>of</strong> social <strong>in</strong>stitutions contributes to the coord<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>of</strong> the plans <strong>of</strong> atomistic agents.An important task <strong>of</strong> social science, then, is to expla<strong>in</strong> howparticular <strong>in</strong>stitutions emerged <strong>and</strong> how they perform their coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>gfunctions. Lachmann’s approach to this task <strong>in</strong>volves amore-or-less straightforward application <strong>of</strong> his subjectivist method.He contends that <strong>in</strong>stitutions orig<strong>in</strong>ate as un<strong>in</strong>tended by-products <strong>of</strong>purposeful human action (Lachmann 1971b:67–8). A successful<strong>in</strong>novative practice, discovered by <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>in</strong> the pursuit <strong>of</strong> theirown <strong>in</strong>terests, will be imitated by other <strong>in</strong>dividuals who recognise itsutility, until it crystallises <strong>in</strong>to st<strong>and</strong>ard practice: ‘Successful plansthus gradually crystallize <strong>in</strong>to <strong>in</strong>stitutions’ (ibid.: 68). A systematicstatement <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s views on <strong>in</strong>stitutions can be found <strong>in</strong> his7


ROGER KOPPL AND GARY MONGIOVIbook on Max Weber, but he appears to have recognised theimportant co-ord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g function <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions much earlier (seeLachmann 1937).Throughout his long <strong>and</strong> fruitful career Lachmann embracedproblems that fall outside the reach <strong>of</strong> the conventional tools <strong>of</strong>economics. His enthusiasm for his subject never waned, though hecould not have been unaware that his words were <strong>of</strong>ten cast beforean <strong>in</strong>different, sometimes hostile, audience. The endur<strong>in</strong>g relevance<strong>of</strong> his message is evident <strong>in</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> Austrian <strong>and</strong> Post Keynesianscholars who cont<strong>in</strong>ue to grapple with, <strong>and</strong> cast new light upon,those same problems.The characteristic themes <strong>and</strong> problems <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’smethodological thought have been taken up <strong>in</strong> various ways by theauthors <strong>of</strong> this volume.In Chapter 2, Brian Loasby draws on his correspondence withLachmann to compose an <strong>in</strong>tellectual portrait <strong>of</strong> him as ‘an optimistwithout illusions.’ Loasby shows how several elements <strong>of</strong>Lachmann’s personal <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual life fit together. Lachmann’spersonal openness is related to both his methodological pluralism<strong>and</strong> his political pluralism. Lachmann eschewed gr<strong>and</strong>iose claimsfor open societies. In Loasby’s <strong>in</strong>terpretation this reflects, <strong>in</strong> part,Lachmann’s own treatment at the h<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> powers who thoughtthemselves uniquely competent to judge the truth. Loasby showshimself to share Lachmann’s <strong>in</strong>tellectual honesty <strong>and</strong> humility whenhe describes his portrait as ‘an <strong>in</strong>terpretation’ which is ‘defensible’but ‘certa<strong>in</strong>ly not def<strong>in</strong>itive’.Stephen Parsons <strong>in</strong> Chapter 3 views Lachmann’s notion <strong>of</strong> ‘aPlan’ from, e.g., The Legacy <strong>of</strong> Max Weber as both development<strong>and</strong> criticism <strong>of</strong> Mises’s praxeological theory <strong>of</strong> action. Lachmann’semphasis on <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> his later emphasis on ‘the context <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>tersubjective mean<strong>in</strong>g’ call <strong>in</strong>to question Mises’s claims regard<strong>in</strong>gthe role <strong>of</strong> deduction <strong>in</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g human action. They may also<strong>in</strong>duce us to question the ‘privileg<strong>in</strong>g’ <strong>of</strong> the Cartesian subjectcharacteris<strong>in</strong>g Mises’s theory <strong>of</strong> action.In Chapter 4, Koppl attempts to exam<strong>in</strong>e the ‘problem <strong>of</strong>expectations’ as Lachmann represented it. Koppl relates theproblem to the ideas <strong>of</strong> Keynes <strong>and</strong> Mises whose systems are foundunable to resolve the problems Lachmann posed. Draw<strong>in</strong>g onHayek <strong>and</strong> Schutz, he adumbrates a theory <strong>of</strong> expectations thatsatisfies Lachmann’s call for a subjectivism <strong>of</strong> active m<strong>in</strong>ds.The gifted Hungarian economist Lásló Csontos died tragically <strong>of</strong>congenital heart failure at the age <strong>of</strong> 43. His work was notable for8


INTRODUCTIONits deep <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>and</strong> meticulous argument. Tra<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> both sociology<strong>and</strong> economics, Csontos had an extraord<strong>in</strong>ary grasp <strong>of</strong> the complexrelationship between Weber <strong>and</strong> the Austrians. In the essayposthumously published as Chapter 5 <strong>of</strong> this volume, Csontos usedhis rich underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Weber’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs on the method <strong>of</strong> idealtypes to argue for a weaker version <strong>of</strong> methodological dualism thanthat adopted by Lachmann. Because Lachmann neglected Weber’sdist<strong>in</strong>ction between subjectively <strong>and</strong> objectively rational ideal types,Csontos argued, he wrongly imag<strong>in</strong>ed his notion <strong>of</strong> ‘Plan’ to be adeparture from Weber’s ideal type. The notion <strong>of</strong> ‘<strong>in</strong>tentionalexplanation’ covers all these cases <strong>and</strong> br<strong>in</strong>gs Lachmann’s notion <strong>of</strong>Plan back under the umbrella <strong>of</strong> cause <strong>and</strong> effect. The logical structure<strong>of</strong> explanation is just about the same <strong>in</strong> the natural <strong>and</strong> social sciences.Draw<strong>in</strong>g on his earlier work with Victoria Chick, Maurizio Caserta<strong>in</strong> Chapter 6 develops the idea <strong>of</strong> ‘provisional equilibrium’ (Chick<strong>and</strong> Caserta 1994). This concept is an attempt to address the problem<strong>of</strong> novelty. ‘As soon as we permit time to elapse we must permitknowledge to change,’ Lachmann argued, ‘<strong>and</strong> knowledge cannotbe regarded as a function <strong>of</strong> anyth<strong>in</strong>g else’ (Lachmann 1959:92). InLachmann’s system the flow <strong>of</strong> time <strong>and</strong> novelty implied that marketequilibrium is at best fleet<strong>in</strong>g. Through the device <strong>of</strong> partialspecification, however, provisional equilibria can be def<strong>in</strong>ed. Theseequilibria are provisional because they may be upset by factors thatare <strong>in</strong>ternal, but not fully specified. Caserta illustrates with an openeconomymacroeconomic model.In Chapter 7, Carlo Zappia uses Karen Vaughn’s recent survey <strong>of</strong>Austrian economics as a spr<strong>in</strong>gboard for a critical assessment <strong>of</strong> trendswith<strong>in</strong> the school. Vaughn’s book, Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>in</strong> America:The Migration <strong>of</strong> a Tradition, is an <strong>in</strong>ternal history <strong>of</strong> the Americanrevival <strong>of</strong> the Austrian school told by one <strong>of</strong> its most importantleaders. Vaughn concludes her survey with an endorsement <strong>of</strong>Lachmann’s ‘clarion call’ to build from a more radical subjectivism<strong>of</strong> real time <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>complete knowledge. Zappia ranges beyond theself-imposed limits <strong>of</strong> Vaughn’s survey to encourage Austrians to<strong>in</strong>corporate the ideas <strong>of</strong> such figures as Bowles <strong>and</strong> G<strong>in</strong>tis. Unlikemost Austrians, who dist<strong>in</strong>guish ‘<strong>in</strong>formation’ from ‘knowledge’ (see,for example, Thomsen 1992), Zappia argues that a carefulconsideration <strong>of</strong> the economics <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation greatly weakensAustrian arguments aga<strong>in</strong>st equilibrium models.Steven Horwitz <strong>in</strong> Chapter 8 unites Lachmann’s two mostimportant book-length essays: Capital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure (1956) <strong>and</strong>The Legacy <strong>of</strong> Max Weber (1971b). Horwitz draws on the Austrian9


ROGER KOPPL AND GARY MONGIOVItheory <strong>of</strong> capital to criticise l<strong>in</strong>ger<strong>in</strong>g elements <strong>of</strong> objectivism <strong>in</strong>Lachmann’s account <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions. We <strong>of</strong>ten recognise a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong>hierarchy among <strong>in</strong>stitutions that puts some <strong>in</strong> the background ashigher-order <strong>and</strong> unchang<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> others <strong>in</strong> the foreground as lowerorder<strong>and</strong> subject to change. This hierarchy, however, is entirely‘subjective’. Which <strong>in</strong>stitutions are background depends on theproblem at h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> the perspective adopted. No one ‘true’ hierarchyexists. Horwitz illustrates with the history <strong>of</strong> bank<strong>in</strong>g. Institutionalchanges have come about through a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> dialectic between legal<strong>and</strong> market <strong>in</strong>stitutions. Dur<strong>in</strong>g this dialectic, each set <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutionshas been background to the other. The whole <strong>in</strong>stitutional structureis characterised by the k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> complementarities <strong>and</strong> multispecificitydiscussed <strong>in</strong> the Austrian theory <strong>of</strong> capital.Lachmann has sometimes been called an ‘Austro-Keynesian’. InChapter 9, Peter Boettke <strong>and</strong> Steven Sullivan ask if such a positioncan be ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>ed consistently. Can one advocate radical subjectivism<strong>in</strong> economic method <strong>and</strong> Keynesian <strong>in</strong>terventions <strong>in</strong> economic policy?Draw<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> part, on Lachmann’s 1935 MSc thesis, ‘Capital Structure<strong>and</strong> Depression’, they show that such a position was adopted byLachmann. They argue, however, that a non-<strong>in</strong>terventionist policypreference is more consistent with radical subjectivism.In Chapter 10, Jochen Runde <strong>and</strong> Jörg Bibow enrich Lachmann’sanalysis <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> expectations on share prices. Lachmann’stheory, as developed <strong>in</strong> Chapter 2 <strong>of</strong> his Capital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure(1956), concerns the role <strong>of</strong> divergent or convergent expectationsabout the value <strong>of</strong> a f<strong>in</strong>ancial asset. Draw<strong>in</strong>g on J.M.Keynes <strong>and</strong>E.M.Miller, Runde <strong>and</strong> Bibow dist<strong>in</strong>guish between the expectation<strong>of</strong> a share’s future price <strong>and</strong> the appraisal <strong>of</strong> its ‘correct’ value.Liquidity, carry<strong>in</strong>g costs, risk aversion <strong>and</strong> estimates <strong>of</strong> the riskaversion <strong>of</strong> others are just some <strong>of</strong> the complicat<strong>in</strong>g factors driv<strong>in</strong>gthis dist<strong>in</strong>ction.Each chapter responds to Lachmann’s work <strong>in</strong> a different <strong>and</strong>challeng<strong>in</strong>g way. We submit them to the reader <strong>in</strong> the hope that heor she will share our enthusiasm for them. We hope the reader willalso share our cont<strong>in</strong>ually enriched appreciation <strong>of</strong> the ideas <strong>of</strong> one<strong>of</strong> the most impressive scholars we have been privileged to know,<strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann.AcknowledgementsThe editors wish to express their gratitude to Don Lavoie, whoprovided the photograph <strong>of</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Lachmann, which appears <strong>in</strong>10


INTRODUCTIONthe frontispiece to this volume, <strong>and</strong> The Mises Institute, forpermission to utilise <strong>in</strong> this Introduction material that haspreviously appeared <strong>in</strong> The Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s Newsletter.ReferencesChick, V. <strong>and</strong> Caserta, M. (1994) ‘Provisional equilibrium <strong>and</strong>macroeconomic theory’, discussion paper, University College, London.Gr<strong>in</strong>der, W. (1977) ‘In pursuit <strong>of</strong> the subjective paradigm’, Introduction toL.Lachmann, Capital, Expectations <strong>and</strong> the Market Process, KansasCity: Sheed, Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel (1977 edn).Lachmann, L. (1937) ‘Uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>and</strong> liquidity preference’, <strong>Economic</strong>aN.S., 4:295–308.——(1943) ‘The role <strong>of</strong> expectations <strong>in</strong> economics as a social science’, <strong>in</strong>Capital, Expectations <strong>and</strong> the Market Process, Kansas City: Sheed,Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel, pp. 65–80 (1977 edn).——(1956) Capital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure, London: Bell <strong>and</strong> Sons, Ltd.——(1959) ‘Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Shackle on the economic significance <strong>of</strong> time’, <strong>in</strong>Capital, Expectations <strong>and</strong> the Market Process, Kansas City: Sheed,Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel (1977 edn).——(1971a) ‘<strong>Ludwig</strong> von Mises <strong>and</strong> the market process’, <strong>in</strong> Capital,Expectations <strong>and</strong> the Market Process, Kansas City: Sheed, Andrews <strong>and</strong>McMeel, pp.181–93 (1977 edn).——(1971b) The Legacy <strong>of</strong> Max Weber, Berkeley: The Glendessary Press.——(1977) ‘Austrian economics <strong>and</strong> the present crisis <strong>of</strong> economicthought,’ <strong>in</strong> Capital, Expectations, <strong>and</strong> the Market Process, KansasCity: Sheed, Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel, pp. 25–41.——(1978) ‘An <strong>in</strong>terview with <strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann’, Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>sNewsletter, 1:1–15.——(1981) ‘Foreword’, <strong>in</strong> L.von Mises, Epistemological Problems <strong>of</strong><strong>Economic</strong>s, New York: New York University Press.——(1982) ‘<strong>Ludwig</strong> von Mises <strong>and</strong> the extension <strong>of</strong> subjectivism’, <strong>in</strong> I.M.Kirzner (ed.) Method, Process <strong>and</strong> Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong>Honor <strong>of</strong> <strong>Ludwig</strong> von Mises, Lex<strong>in</strong>gton, MA: D.C.Heath.——(1986) The Market as an <strong>Economic</strong> Process, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.——(1990) ‘G.L.S.Shackle’s place <strong>in</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> subjectivist thought’, <strong>in</strong>S.F.Frowen (ed.) Unknowledge <strong>and</strong> Choice: Proceed<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> aConference <strong>in</strong> Honour <strong>of</strong> G.L.S.Shackle, New York: St Mart<strong>in</strong>’s Press.Thomsen, E. (1992) Prices <strong>and</strong> Knowledge: A Market Process Perspective,New York: Routledge.11


2LUDWIG M.LACHMANN<strong>Subjectivism</strong> <strong>in</strong> economics <strong>and</strong> theeconomyBrian J.LoasbyI never met <strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann. I did not even beg<strong>in</strong> correspond<strong>in</strong>gwith him until the last years <strong>of</strong> his life. That was my fault, for Irepeatedly delayed tak<strong>in</strong>g the opportunity on the <strong>in</strong>sidious excusethat I would have someth<strong>in</strong>g more <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to say <strong>in</strong> a fewmonths’ time. I should have been more aware, because <strong>of</strong> what I hadalready learned from his work, that he had many <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gsto say at any time. This was immediately demonstrated when I didwrite, as was the courtesy <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual curiosity that impressedso many who knew him <strong>and</strong> his work much better than I did. S<strong>in</strong>cehis objective was to make what contribution he could—<strong>and</strong> thatwas not small—to our common underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> economicquestions, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> the ways <strong>in</strong> which we might best improve thatunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, it seems appropriate <strong>in</strong> this chapter to outl<strong>in</strong>e thethemes that I have taken from his publications <strong>and</strong> from hiscorrespondence with me. (I shall cite his f<strong>in</strong>al book, which <strong>of</strong>fers anadmirable conspectus <strong>of</strong> his vision.) As he would be the first to po<strong>in</strong>tout, what follows is an <strong>in</strong>terpretation; but s<strong>in</strong>ce it is based on someshared po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> reference—for example, admiration for the work <strong>of</strong>George Shackle <strong>and</strong> George Richardson, similar ideas about thecompatibility <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> Keynes’s major ideas with an Austrianview, the need to enquire <strong>in</strong>to what happens <strong>in</strong> markets—<strong>and</strong> s<strong>in</strong>ceparts <strong>of</strong> this <strong>in</strong>terpretation were tested <strong>in</strong> our correspondence, I amreasonably confident that, though certa<strong>in</strong>ly not def<strong>in</strong>itive, it isdefensible.12


SUBJECTIVISM IN ECONOMICS AND THE ECONOMYMethodology<strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachman was a radical subjectivist—too radical for many<strong>of</strong> his fellow Austrians, for he did not believe it possible todemonstrate that market processes were necessarily always superiorto any alternative. There could be serious failures <strong>of</strong> co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation(as will be noted later); <strong>and</strong> s<strong>in</strong>ce the market process had no end, nodef<strong>in</strong>itive judgement was possible. His advocacy <strong>of</strong> market systems,which did not preclude specific criticisms, was based on a reasonedfaith. Like Sir Karl Popper’s advocacy <strong>of</strong> an open society, whichPopper knows is not capable <strong>of</strong> empirical pro<strong>of</strong>, it reflected both theunreliability <strong>of</strong> human benevolence <strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>adequacy <strong>of</strong> humanknowledge, which were also the grounds <strong>of</strong> Adam Smith’sreason<strong>in</strong>g. Assume these human limitations away, <strong>and</strong> it is easy toreach the apparent conclusion <strong>of</strong> the plann<strong>in</strong>g debate, that aplanned economy can equal the best that a market system can do,<strong>and</strong> surpass it <strong>in</strong> cop<strong>in</strong>g with externalities, public goods <strong>and</strong> thedistribution <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>come. That this conclusion was so widely acceptedamong economists followed naturally from the use <strong>of</strong> the very sameassumptions <strong>in</strong> the plann<strong>in</strong>g model as underlay the formal analysis<strong>of</strong> market systems: though these assumptions denied the existence <strong>of</strong>the fundamental difficulties that face us, they were necessary toarrive at a determ<strong>in</strong>ate solution to the tw<strong>in</strong> problems <strong>of</strong> efficientallocation, as def<strong>in</strong>ed by Jevons, <strong>and</strong> efficient co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation, asdef<strong>in</strong>ed by Walras.Yet many economists still appear to believe that we do not needto worry about methodology. In fact such economists normally havea strong methodological commitment to the use <strong>of</strong> formal models,<strong>and</strong> to the use <strong>of</strong> whatever false assumptions (such as given tastes,rational expectations <strong>and</strong> common knowledge) may seem necessary<strong>in</strong> order to yield a determ<strong>in</strong>ate, if sometimes multiple, answer. Thatfalse assumptions can lead, not only to false theories, but—moredangerously—to false policies, does not seem to be a possibility thatmost economists take seriously. <strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann did. Like manyEuropeans <strong>in</strong> the 1930s, the course <strong>of</strong> his life was changed by such afalse policy. Moreover, it was not merely false notions <strong>of</strong> plann<strong>in</strong>gthat he criticised. Plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Eastern Europe had been unable toprevent massive mal<strong>in</strong>vestment; but <strong>in</strong> a letter <strong>of</strong> 29 April 1990—atime, it may now be hard to recall, <strong>of</strong> widespread optimism—heforesaw that ‘gett<strong>in</strong>g market economies started <strong>in</strong> Eastern Europe,after half a century, will give rise to a host <strong>of</strong> problems hardly as yetappreciated’; <strong>and</strong> on 22 July 1990 wrote: ‘The more I th<strong>in</strong>k about13


BRIAN J.LOASBYRussia the more pessimistic I become. How can this end well? Ofcourse market <strong>in</strong>stitutions cannot be <strong>in</strong>troduced by political fiat.’Formal theories <strong>of</strong> market co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation are no less dangerous thanformal models <strong>of</strong> plann<strong>in</strong>g.One should never underrate the ability <strong>of</strong> very clever people tobe very silly, even to the public peril. It was, perhaps, above all as adefence aga<strong>in</strong>st illusions that Lachmann <strong>in</strong>sisted on ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gthe subjectivist perspective. The economic problem is not toallocate known resources to clearly def<strong>in</strong>ed ends, but to make thebest <strong>of</strong> the knowledge that each person has, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> theopportunities that that person can envisage, <strong>and</strong> also, significantly,to f<strong>in</strong>d ways <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g that knowledge <strong>and</strong> discover<strong>in</strong>g newopportunities. As Mises above all <strong>in</strong>sisted, it is a problem <strong>of</strong>human <strong>in</strong>itiative, conditioned by the perception <strong>of</strong> humancircumstances, not <strong>of</strong> programmed response to objective data.Human activity is problem-solv<strong>in</strong>g. This is Popper’s view also;<strong>and</strong>, like Popper, Lachmann saw that problems had to be def<strong>in</strong>edbefore they could be solved, <strong>and</strong> moreover, that the way <strong>in</strong> whichthey were def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>of</strong>ten had a major <strong>in</strong>fluence on the solution thatwas chosen. ‘Information’ must be <strong>in</strong>terpreted, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretationis problematic. All this is true both <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dividual agent, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>the observer who is try<strong>in</strong>g to make sense <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dividual’sactions; my exploration <strong>of</strong> this perspective <strong>in</strong> Equilibrium <strong>and</strong>Evolution (1991) owed someth<strong>in</strong>g to Lachmann, <strong>and</strong> I greatlyregret that I was unable to discuss it with him.Lachmann was the most resolute advocate <strong>of</strong> subjectivism as themeans <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g the consequences <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual purposes,underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> expectations, all <strong>of</strong> which differ between people,<strong>and</strong> change with time <strong>and</strong> experience. He was also the most resolutecritic <strong>of</strong> formalism, <strong>in</strong> which all these elements are transformed <strong>in</strong>todata supposedly available to the analyst, <strong>and</strong> usually to the agent aswell. It is sometimes asserted that it is important to work out theproperties <strong>of</strong> an equilibrium based on this data, either because, ifpeople eventually learn the true facts, this equilibrium may be<strong>in</strong>terpreted as the dest<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> a process that is itself too difficult toh<strong>and</strong>le directly or, more ambitiously, that identify<strong>in</strong>g the dest<strong>in</strong>ationis a useful prelude to <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g such a process. The latterargument, which Walras took very seriously, is rarely heardnowadays, s<strong>in</strong>ce the algorithms <strong>of</strong> rational choice, which aresupposed to guide, or at least predict, action at all times, are def<strong>in</strong>edonly for situations <strong>in</strong> which everyone other than the chooser isalready pursu<strong>in</strong>g an optimal strategy. But s<strong>in</strong>ce rational choice is14


SUBJECTIVISM IN ECONOMICS AND THE ECONOMYbelieved to be <strong>in</strong>dispensable, the discovery that it requiresequilibrium has been used to justify the claim that all situationsmust necessarily be rational choice equilibria.Now Lachmann recognised the necessity <strong>of</strong> abstraction, for every<strong>in</strong>terpretation is an abstraction. Economists <strong>and</strong> economic agents,all human be<strong>in</strong>gs, use models. But the choice <strong>of</strong> model is not<strong>in</strong>nocuous: It does matter which features <strong>of</strong> reality we accentuate <strong>in</strong>our schemes, <strong>and</strong> which we abstract from’ (Lachmann 1986:42). Itmatters for the management <strong>of</strong> General Motors just as much as for amonetary theorist; <strong>in</strong>deed it is characteristic <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’sperspective that the central issues <strong>of</strong> economic method are thecentral issues <strong>of</strong> human action. In neither is there any sure route tosuccess; <strong>in</strong> both there are many opportunities for failure. Onecommon pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is that the s<strong>in</strong>gle-m<strong>in</strong>ded pursuit <strong>of</strong> any model, orfamily <strong>of</strong> models, will eventually lead one astray. The art is know<strong>in</strong>gwhen to stop. This, I suggested <strong>in</strong> a letter to him, is the central issue<strong>in</strong> apprais<strong>in</strong>g Marshall, who was acutely conscious <strong>of</strong> the problem;<strong>and</strong> we can now see, <strong>in</strong> counterpo<strong>in</strong>t to the st<strong>and</strong>ard compla<strong>in</strong>t thatMarshall failed to pursue the logic <strong>of</strong> his models, the occasionalsuggestion that he pursued that logic too far, <strong>and</strong> should have givenmuch more emphasis to evolutionary concepts.Marshall <strong>and</strong> equilibriumLachmann was very sympathetic to Marshall, <strong>and</strong> to my<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> Marshall. In a letter <strong>of</strong> 22 July 1990 hecommented that:I know less about Marshall than I should. Moreover some <strong>of</strong>what I did learn <strong>in</strong> 62 years has turned out to be wrong. E.g. Ilearned from Schumpeter that there is no real differencebetween him <strong>and</strong> Pareto. This is surely wrong. On the otherh<strong>and</strong>, Schumpeter used to praise Marshall’s Book V as theseeds <strong>of</strong> everyth<strong>in</strong>g worth study<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> economics. The validity<strong>of</strong> this view now seems to turn on how important equilibriumwas to Marshall.He had earlier (Lachmann 1986:142–3) praised Marshall’s partialequilibrium analysis as ‘a model with<strong>in</strong> the framework <strong>of</strong> whichequilibrium <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>teraction between (a somewhat limited number<strong>of</strong>) <strong>in</strong>dividuals can be reconciled’. If equilibrium entailsconsistency—because otherwise there is the possibility <strong>of</strong> chang<strong>in</strong>g15


BRIAN J.LOASBYsometh<strong>in</strong>g for the better—then its extension from a s<strong>in</strong>gle plan to aset <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g plans must be problematic, <strong>and</strong> if this set isexp<strong>and</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>to a general equilibrium, especially so. This is why themodel <strong>of</strong> central plann<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> which, by def<strong>in</strong>ition, there is only as<strong>in</strong>gle plan, looks so plausible <strong>in</strong> comparison with a generalequilibrium <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependently formulated plans, which seems onlytoo likely to be frustrated by the ‘wastes <strong>of</strong> competition’. ButMarshall <strong>of</strong>fers ‘a restricted environment as regards time <strong>and</strong> space’<strong>in</strong> which an approximate compatibility <strong>of</strong> plans might beachievable—especially when we pay due attention to Marshall’sconcern for the pattern <strong>of</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g relationships with<strong>in</strong> which thecriticism <strong>and</strong> test<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> plans takes place.In his letter <strong>of</strong> 22 July 1990, Lachmann went on to agree with methat Marshall:was nearer to Menger than to Jevons. This is what hasimpressed me for some time. Why, then, did he stressequilibrium? I th<strong>in</strong>k there is this to consider. An economistespous<strong>in</strong>g equilibrium need not do so because he believes that<strong>in</strong> the real world equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g forces are overwhelm<strong>in</strong>g. Fewpeople hold this view. But if we are concerned with ‘wealth’<strong>and</strong> feel we must be able to ‘measure’ it we will sooner or laterf<strong>in</strong>d out, as Wicksell did, that such measurement is possibleonly <strong>in</strong> equilibrium, hence the latter’s importance. Could it bethat here we have the real reason why Marshall espousedequilibrium, as he undoubtedly did?It seems to me that <strong>in</strong> this paragraph Lachmann illustrates a majortheme <strong>in</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> economic theory. Adam Smith’s <strong>in</strong>itialthesis <strong>in</strong> the Wealth <strong>of</strong> Nations was that wealth could mosteffectively be <strong>in</strong>creased through the division <strong>of</strong> labour, because thisled to the cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g development <strong>of</strong> specialised capabilities. But ifwe contrast <strong>in</strong>dividual self-sufficiency with specialisation, we canimmediately identify two problems. Our first thoughts nowadays goto the question <strong>of</strong> co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation; but we may also be concerned howto add up the outputs <strong>of</strong> all these specialists, <strong>in</strong> order to see whetherthe total really is greater than that achievable by self-sufficiency, or<strong>in</strong>deed by a different degree or pattern <strong>of</strong> specialisation. Much thebest solution to this problem <strong>of</strong> evaluation is an unvary<strong>in</strong>gmeasure—if it can be found; <strong>and</strong>, as we know, Adam Smith <strong>and</strong> hissuccessors tried hard to f<strong>in</strong>d one <strong>in</strong> costs <strong>of</strong> production. That anunvary<strong>in</strong>g measure <strong>of</strong> value could also provide an anchor for the16


SUBJECTIVISM IN ECONOMICS AND THE ECONOMYprice system, <strong>and</strong> thus help to co-ord<strong>in</strong>ate specialised activities, wasextremely convenient; but we should not forget that the signals onwhich Smith relied to stimulate movement <strong>in</strong> the direction <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ationthrough a competitive process which should not beconfused with perfect competition, were market prices that were out<strong>of</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e with natural prices. Smith thus had what we would now callboth a theory <strong>of</strong> equilibrium <strong>and</strong> a theory <strong>of</strong> equilibration, acomb<strong>in</strong>ation that has proved beyond the grasp <strong>of</strong> neoclassicaleconomists.The logical flaw <strong>in</strong> Smith’s value system is that the process thatgenerates <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g wealth does so by chang<strong>in</strong>g the costs <strong>of</strong>production by which this <strong>in</strong>crease is to be measured. But thisdifficulty is relatively m<strong>in</strong>or compared with that <strong>of</strong> bas<strong>in</strong>g any k<strong>in</strong>d<strong>of</strong> natural value <strong>in</strong> an evolv<strong>in</strong>g system upon marg<strong>in</strong>al utility, foreconomic progress extends consumption to lower-rated uses. Theeventual solution was found by postulat<strong>in</strong>g a general equilibrium <strong>in</strong>which price measured not only the marg<strong>in</strong>al utility <strong>of</strong> everycommodity but also its marg<strong>in</strong>al cost, which was itself a precisemeasure <strong>of</strong> the marg<strong>in</strong>al utility forgone by not divert<strong>in</strong>g an<strong>in</strong>crement <strong>of</strong> resources to the best alternative use. It will be observedthat this precise measure requires not only general equilibrium, butperfect competition, together with such other well-knownconditions as the absence <strong>of</strong> public goods.This was not good enough for Marshall, who saw that welfaredepended on what happened <strong>in</strong>side the marg<strong>in</strong>; so he adaptedRicardo’s concept <strong>of</strong> rent to devise a general measure <strong>of</strong> bothproducers’ <strong>and</strong> consumers’ surplus. In pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, such measurescould provide rank<strong>in</strong>gs which might be very different from thosebased on equilibrium values alone, but their validity depended onequilibrium. Although Marshall did not expect that his measureswould be adequate for anyth<strong>in</strong>g more than estimates <strong>of</strong> themagnitude <strong>of</strong> changes <strong>in</strong> welfare as a result <strong>of</strong> changes with<strong>in</strong>particular <strong>in</strong>dustries, even that proved to be an extravagant hope;but it is noteworthy that the measurements employed <strong>in</strong> cost-benefitanalysis rely on Marshall’s ideas, <strong>and</strong> on the conception <strong>of</strong>equilibrium that underlies them. If the validity <strong>of</strong> such <strong>in</strong>crementalmeasurement is doubtful, what are we to make <strong>of</strong> measures <strong>of</strong>national <strong>in</strong>come that depend on a set <strong>of</strong> assumptions that are alwaysviolated, <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>ten grossly violated, by the economies to whichthose measures are applied?It is easy to underst<strong>and</strong> why some economists are not satisfiedwith such a basis <strong>of</strong> valuation, but it is not so easy to agree that17


BRIAN J.LOASBYNeo-Ricardian valuation is an adequate alternative. Joan Rob<strong>in</strong>sondid not accept it. As Lachmann agreed, <strong>in</strong> a letter <strong>of</strong> 17 August1989, she was never quite a Sraffian. If we do not know how tomeasure someth<strong>in</strong>g that we would like to measure, then, as LordKelv<strong>in</strong> remarked, our knowledge may be <strong>of</strong> a meagre <strong>and</strong>unsatisfactory k<strong>in</strong>d; but if we <strong>in</strong>sist on fictitious measurement thenour knowledge, if apparently less meagre, will be much moreunsatisfactory—for it will be false.CatallacticsLachmann shared the common perception that <strong>in</strong> the last quarter <strong>of</strong>the n<strong>in</strong>eteenth century the focus <strong>of</strong> economic analysis turned fromplutology—the science <strong>of</strong> wealth—to catallactics—the theory <strong>of</strong>exchange. Yet catallactics proved to conta<strong>in</strong> a deep <strong>in</strong>ternalcontradiction. For Lachmann, its essential feature is the exploration<strong>of</strong> purposeful action: that implies an orientation towards the future,which is unknown, but not unimag<strong>in</strong>able. Uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty—or, asLachmann’s k<strong>in</strong>dred spirit, George Shackle, came to call it,unknowledge—does not imply chaos (Lachmann 1986:139); reason<strong>and</strong> experience allow us to create <strong>in</strong>telligent, if fallible, expectations.But such expectations do have to be created; they cannot bemechanically formed. We may, if we choose, rely on some formalprocedure to convert data <strong>in</strong>to forecasts, but the choice is ourchoice, <strong>and</strong> any procedure that we choose must itself be a humancreation. Even if it were to be, <strong>in</strong> some sense, a ‘correct model’, itwould nevertheless be a human <strong>in</strong>vention, as is every scientifictheory, <strong>and</strong> its correctness would rema<strong>in</strong> forever open to doubt.Lachmann understood Popper’s arguments. But, like many naturalscientists, he also understood their liberat<strong>in</strong>g potential: predictivefailure is an opportunity to improve our knowledge, for we learn asa consequence <strong>of</strong> our mistakes, <strong>and</strong> the improvement <strong>of</strong> ourknowledge depends on our ability to make conjectures which gowell beyond the evidence (ibid.: 152). That the key to humanprogress is imag<strong>in</strong>ation, <strong>and</strong> that imag<strong>in</strong>ation is <strong>in</strong>conceivablewithout ‘unknowledge’, is a theme that belongs uniquely to GeorgeShackle; but no one was more aware <strong>of</strong> its significance than <strong>Ludwig</strong>Lachmann.Yet such modes <strong>of</strong> thought are <strong>in</strong>compatible with modernformalism. Lachmann (1986:25) endorsed Joan Rob<strong>in</strong>son’scompla<strong>in</strong>t that:18


SUBJECTIVISM IN ECONOMICS AND THE ECONOMY<strong>Economic</strong> analysis, serv<strong>in</strong>g for two centuries to w<strong>in</strong> anunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the Nature <strong>and</strong> Causes <strong>of</strong> the Wealth <strong>of</strong>Nations, has been fobbed <strong>of</strong>f with another bride—a Theory <strong>of</strong>Value…economists for the last hundred years have sacrificeddynamic theory <strong>in</strong> order to discuss relative prices.(Rob<strong>in</strong>son 1956: v)We have already seen why the rejection <strong>of</strong> cost-<strong>of</strong>-productiontheories should apparently evoke an urgent need to <strong>in</strong>vent somealternative basis <strong>of</strong> value, <strong>and</strong> why utility-based measures should be<strong>in</strong>adequate unless anchored <strong>in</strong> a perfectly competitive generalequilibrium. We might now observe also that the centre <strong>of</strong>gravitation provided by ‘natural values’ had to be replaced by someother pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation if economists were to <strong>of</strong>fer a formalsolution to the allocation problem <strong>in</strong> a decentralised economy.Unfortunately the chosen solution to these tw<strong>in</strong> requirementsentailed a very high opportunity cost, as Joan Rob<strong>in</strong>son (eventually)<strong>and</strong> Lachmann clearly realised.One <strong>of</strong> the first to recognise the problem was Alfred Marshall;<strong>and</strong> he was prepared to tolerate a good deal <strong>of</strong> ambiguity <strong>in</strong> order toexploit the advantages <strong>of</strong> mechanical metaphors <strong>in</strong> the (<strong>in</strong>tendedly)first volume <strong>of</strong> his Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples while ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g that, even <strong>in</strong> itsfoundations, the theme <strong>of</strong> economics must be ‘liv<strong>in</strong>g force <strong>and</strong>movement’. Moreover, Marshall believed that he saw an eventualprospect <strong>of</strong> comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a theory <strong>of</strong> growth with a theory <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ation:co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation is achieved, imperfectly <strong>and</strong> with cyclicallapses, by a comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> organisation <strong>and</strong> competitive selection,<strong>and</strong> this comb<strong>in</strong>ation also provides both <strong>in</strong>centives <strong>and</strong>opportunities for the generation <strong>of</strong> new ideas.Lachmann became <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly conscious <strong>of</strong> his aff<strong>in</strong>ity withMarshall: his own account (Lachmann 1986:16–17) <strong>of</strong> the<strong>in</strong>tramarket processes <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>novative variation <strong>and</strong> imitation, thattransform both products <strong>and</strong> technology by cont<strong>in</strong>uouscompetitive improvement, is thoroughly Marshallian, withChamberl<strong>in</strong>ian touches. In a letter <strong>of</strong> 29 April 1990, he wrote:‘The Firm is very much Marshall’s child. Neither Walras/Paretonor the Austrians know it. Why? What did Marshall need it for?’The prime reason, I suggest, is that firms were the pr<strong>in</strong>cipal agents<strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>tra-market processes to which Lachmann drewattention—<strong>in</strong> the British economy, which Marshall knew from hisfactory visits no less than <strong>in</strong> the pages <strong>of</strong> the Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. A secondmajor reason is that his conception <strong>of</strong> the firm as a source <strong>of</strong>19


BRIAN J.LOASBYvariation allowed him to construct an <strong>in</strong>dustry equilibrium that<strong>in</strong>corporated ceaseless change. We should never forget that thelong-run equilibrium model <strong>of</strong> the firm, which has become afamiliar textbook tradition, though <strong>of</strong>ten attributed to Marshall,is actually a rejection <strong>of</strong> Marshall’s theory, for it depicts theext<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>of</strong> enterprise, <strong>and</strong> the end <strong>of</strong> hope.We should not accuse either Jevons or Walras <strong>of</strong> a lack <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong> the analysis <strong>of</strong> economic progress. Jevons died young, with agreat potential unrealised, <strong>and</strong> Walras declared that his eventualobjective was to construct a theory <strong>of</strong> change. But when Walrastried, as an important step towards that theory, to move fromequilibration <strong>in</strong> exchange to equilibration <strong>in</strong> production, <strong>and</strong> to doso by means <strong>of</strong> a theory <strong>of</strong> entrepreneurial action, he found thatdisequilibrium production entailed path-dependency, <strong>in</strong> whichequilibria derived from the orig<strong>in</strong>al data were <strong>of</strong> doubtful relevance.He was unable to resolve this difficulty, <strong>and</strong> therefore fell back on aprior co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> pledges to ensure that only equilibriumquantities were ever produced. But, as Lachmann (1986:118)po<strong>in</strong>ted out, this is a false production economy, <strong>and</strong> it excludes themeans <strong>of</strong> progress that Walras had himself <strong>in</strong>troduced:entrepreneurial conjectures. Marshall understood that generalequilibrium analysis would not allow him to h<strong>and</strong>le creativity <strong>and</strong>turned <strong>in</strong> the opposite direction from Walras, <strong>in</strong> order to preservethe l<strong>in</strong>k with the classical tradition. In do<strong>in</strong>g so he implicitly alignedhimself with Menger, who had no desire to construct a generalequilibrium, preferr<strong>in</strong>g the freedom to discuss knowledge,uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>and</strong> the un<strong>in</strong>tended consequences <strong>of</strong> purposeful action.An aff<strong>in</strong>ity between Marshall <strong>and</strong> Lachmann, who is perhaps themost Mengerian <strong>of</strong> Austrian economists, is thus perfectly natural:for this most radical <strong>of</strong> subjectivists was no less anxious thanMarshall to conserve the wisdom <strong>of</strong> Adam Smith.Human actionLachmann shared Marshall’s conception <strong>of</strong> ‘the fundamentalcharacteristics <strong>of</strong> modern <strong>in</strong>dustrial life…. They are…a certa<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>dependence <strong>and</strong> habit <strong>of</strong> choos<strong>in</strong>g one’s own course for oneself…a habit <strong>of</strong> forecast<strong>in</strong>g the future <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> shap<strong>in</strong>g one’s course withreference to distant aims’ (Marshall 1920:5). Action depends on theknowledge that the actor possesses at the time <strong>of</strong> action, <strong>and</strong> theway <strong>in</strong> which it is used. Even if, as <strong>in</strong> neoclassical practice, thisaction is triggered by some exogenous impulse, the actor’s20


SUBJECTIVISM IN ECONOMICS AND THE ECONOMYknowledge is crucial. It has long seemed to me extraord<strong>in</strong>ary thateconomists subject the agents <strong>in</strong> their models to shocks, which bydef<strong>in</strong>ition are events for which no provision has already been made,<strong>and</strong> assume that these agents nevertheless know immediately whatis the optimal response. With<strong>in</strong> the logic <strong>of</strong> a neoclassical model, ashock is a refutation <strong>of</strong> the agent’s <strong>in</strong>terpretative system <strong>and</strong>requires a reconstruction <strong>of</strong> the procedure for mak<strong>in</strong>g optimaldecisions. But the recognition that someth<strong>in</strong>g is wrong is notsufficient to demonstrate precisely what is wrong, let alone how toput it right. Learn<strong>in</strong>g from experience, as Lachmann (1986:46)po<strong>in</strong>ted out, is a problem-solv<strong>in</strong>g activity; <strong>and</strong> we cannot knowwhat people will learn. That it will be ‘the correct model’ is apresumption that closes the model by clos<strong>in</strong>g it aga<strong>in</strong>st commonobservation, <strong>and</strong> begs the question <strong>of</strong> effective co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation, whichwas once supposed to require analysis.Lachmann emphasised three aspects <strong>of</strong> knowledge that receivelittle attention <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream economics: its heterogeneity <strong>and</strong> theconsequent need to impose our personal order upon it; thecomplementarity <strong>of</strong> different k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>in</strong> develop<strong>in</strong>gunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> formulat<strong>in</strong>g a sensible plan <strong>of</strong> action; <strong>and</strong> theentanglement <strong>of</strong> knowledge with time. Because the past isknowable, though not def<strong>in</strong>itively, <strong>in</strong> a way that the future is not,the flow <strong>of</strong> time creates knowledge, <strong>and</strong> simultaneously destroyspart <strong>of</strong> the stock. For none <strong>of</strong> us is knowledge ‘given’: it has to beacquired, <strong>and</strong> outdated knowledge has to be replaced. Theeconomics <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation seeks to grasp some <strong>of</strong> the shadows castby this process; but it allows only for the progressive elim<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong>possibilities as they come nearer, not for the cont<strong>in</strong>uous creation <strong>of</strong>possibilities hitherto unthought <strong>of</strong>. New ideas, even the possibilitythat there might be new ideas, are outside the scope <strong>of</strong> formaleconomics, for how can we model what has not yet been thought <strong>of</strong>?Lachmann’s view <strong>of</strong> human knowledge is orthogonal to formalconventions, <strong>of</strong> game theory no less than general equilibrium. Hesummarised his criticism <strong>in</strong> a letter <strong>of</strong> 13 August 1989:In their irrational zeal to imitate the style <strong>of</strong> classicalmechanics neoclassical formalists use the words ‘rationality’<strong>and</strong> ‘choice’ <strong>in</strong> such a fashion as to pervert their mean<strong>in</strong>g. Forthem reason has come to mean the maximisation <strong>of</strong> GIVENfunctions! Choice has come to designate situations <strong>in</strong> which itcannot exist! With a ‘given’ preference set, what choice do wehave? It is clear that those who have perpetrated these21


BRIAN J.LOASBYconfusions are confus<strong>in</strong>g human action with mere reaction tochang<strong>in</strong>g circumstances. Our m<strong>in</strong>d is <strong>in</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>uous motion,mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> order<strong>in</strong>g experience. The formalists confuse thisactivity with its momentary product, which is an order, butnot one that could last.When people try to work out what to do they break problems up<strong>in</strong>to manageable units; <strong>and</strong> if we wish to underst<strong>and</strong> human actionso must we. I do not know what Lachmann thought <strong>of</strong> the ways <strong>in</strong>which Herbert Simon used his concepts <strong>of</strong> decomposability <strong>and</strong>bounded rationality, but he certa<strong>in</strong>ly made effective use <strong>of</strong> similarideas. Instead <strong>of</strong> general theoris<strong>in</strong>g about ‘the market process’, itwas necessary to get down to the detail <strong>of</strong> particular markets, <strong>and</strong>subsequently to explore <strong>in</strong>ter-market relationships. Lachmann’semphasis can be clearly differentiated from that <strong>of</strong> both Schumpeter<strong>and</strong> Kirzner: unlike Schumpeter, he believed that most progressresulted from a multitude <strong>of</strong> specific changes with<strong>in</strong> particularmarkets, <strong>and</strong> unlike Kirzner, he believed that people were creative<strong>and</strong> not merely alert—the ten-dollar bill had to be imag<strong>in</strong>ed before itcould be brought with<strong>in</strong> one’s grasp.These differences arise from a more fundamental dist<strong>in</strong>ction:Lachmann <strong>in</strong>sisted not only that all action, <strong>and</strong> all thought, relies onrules <strong>and</strong> conventions, but that these rules <strong>and</strong> conventions arelikely to vary between markets <strong>in</strong> ways that significantly affect thecourse <strong>of</strong> history. In a letter <strong>of</strong> 2 July 1989 he wrote:I entirely agree with you when you exhort us Austrians to paymore attention to <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> organisations.…In fact myChapter 6 is at bottom an attempt to expla<strong>in</strong> fixprice markets<strong>of</strong> our world <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> their <strong>in</strong>stitutional <strong>and</strong> organisationalpeculiarities, with salesmen <strong>and</strong> the hierarchies to which theybelong rather than merchants.In that chapter (Lachmann 1986:103–38), Lachmann explores thecauses <strong>and</strong> consequences <strong>of</strong> the different ranges <strong>of</strong> action envisagedby different classes <strong>of</strong> agent, not<strong>in</strong>g (ibid.: 120–1) that <strong>in</strong> Keynes’sGeneral Theory entrepreneurs have a much wider range than workers.Realis<strong>in</strong>g the potential ga<strong>in</strong>s from the division <strong>of</strong> labour requires ast<strong>and</strong>ardisation <strong>of</strong> tasks <strong>and</strong>, to a substantial extent, <strong>of</strong> the productsthat result from those tasks. And so markets <strong>in</strong> which productioncosts are fall<strong>in</strong>g are likely to be markets <strong>in</strong> which customers are notonly price-takers but product-takers, dependent for their range <strong>of</strong>22


SUBJECTIVISM IN ECONOMICS AND THE ECONOMYchoice on the ways <strong>in</strong> which entrepreneurs exploit their own broaderscope for <strong>in</strong>itiative. The large organisations that deliver thesest<strong>and</strong>ardised products must also restrict the range <strong>of</strong> action <strong>of</strong> theiremployees—notably <strong>of</strong> their salesmen, for the advantages <strong>of</strong> efficientproduction must not be frittered away <strong>in</strong> the costs <strong>of</strong> negotiat<strong>in</strong>gprices <strong>and</strong> conditions with every customer. Whether the need forconformity <strong>in</strong> large organisations can be reconciled with theencouragement <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>itiative through ‘empowerment’ is a questioncurrently be<strong>in</strong>g explored <strong>in</strong> many companies. If it is to be achieved,it will clearly require new <strong>in</strong>stitutions, probably <strong>in</strong> some variety tosuit different specific situations.Industrial markets <strong>in</strong> which there are few customers each plac<strong>in</strong>glarge orders operate with different conventions, <strong>and</strong> there are otherk<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> markets with their own particular patterns <strong>of</strong> behaviour,<strong>and</strong> variations between classes <strong>of</strong> participants <strong>in</strong> the degree <strong>and</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d<strong>of</strong> discretion. All these patterns are open to challenge, <strong>and</strong> many arechallenged, sometimes successfully. The process <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutionbuild<strong>in</strong>g has no determ<strong>in</strong>ate conclusion. Here is scope for a majorAustrian programme <strong>of</strong> empirical research, <strong>of</strong> a k<strong>in</strong>d withoutprecedent <strong>in</strong> economics. It would be much more like bus<strong>in</strong>ess historythan econometrics, but if, as Lachmann agreed with Hicks,economics is on the edge <strong>of</strong> history, why not?In any study <strong>of</strong> particular markets, we should not forget theobvious po<strong>in</strong>t, on which Mises <strong>in</strong>sisted, that goods are exchangedfor money. The analysis <strong>of</strong> a barter economy is not sufficient for aneconomy that runs on money <strong>and</strong> credit. Credit <strong>in</strong> particular, asLachmann (1986:85) rem<strong>in</strong>ds us, is endogenous: its creationrequires agreement between lender <strong>and</strong> borrower, <strong>and</strong> thus aperceived convergence between their purposes <strong>and</strong> between their<strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>of</strong> the appropriate ways <strong>of</strong> achiev<strong>in</strong>g them. So muchis obvious from any reasonably diligent observation <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancialmarkets. Convergence does not mean identity: <strong>in</strong> some transactions,for example where there is a pool<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> risk, someth<strong>in</strong>g very close toidentity is required, but a banker mak<strong>in</strong>g a secured loan is much less<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>itability <strong>of</strong> the bus<strong>in</strong>ess than <strong>in</strong> the prospectivevalue <strong>of</strong> the hypothecated assets <strong>in</strong> the best alternative use to whichthey could be put should that bus<strong>in</strong>ess fail; <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> speculativemarkets it is the conflict <strong>of</strong> expectations that motivates agreementon a specific transaction. F<strong>in</strong>ancial markets cannot be properlyunderstood by postulat<strong>in</strong>g a representative market, any more than<strong>in</strong>teraction between <strong>in</strong>dividuals can be understood by postulat<strong>in</strong>g arepresentative agent.23


BRIAN J.LOASBYF<strong>in</strong>ancial assets provide purchas<strong>in</strong>g power; but they also providethe power to delay purchases, <strong>in</strong> the hope <strong>of</strong> seiz<strong>in</strong>g futureopportunities, to allow speedy response to future threats aga<strong>in</strong>stwhich no satisfactory <strong>in</strong>surance can be purchased, or simply whileattempt<strong>in</strong>g to assess the significance <strong>of</strong> some development. Theimplications <strong>of</strong> such delays for the co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> economicactivities will be considered shortly, but first we should give duecredit to Lachmann’s recognition that people may also develop thepower <strong>of</strong> future action by the accumulation <strong>of</strong> physical assets.Indeed, the durability <strong>of</strong> physical assets impels their owner to lookto the future, which cannot be known. No one has given moreemphasis than Lachmann to the importance <strong>of</strong> capitalcomb<strong>in</strong>ations, which enable complementarities to be exploited forspecific purposes, but at some <strong>in</strong>evitable cost <strong>in</strong> flexibility.Capital <strong>and</strong> capabilitiesEconomists who have little sympathy for Austrian conceptions havepaid attention to capital comb<strong>in</strong>ations only as part <strong>of</strong> the conditions<strong>of</strong> equilibrium, either <strong>in</strong> neoclassical terms or as an implication <strong>of</strong>the gravitational pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> a uniform rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it; but thepractical question for those who have charge <strong>of</strong> capital is how toshape their own particular comb<strong>in</strong>ations to suit their own particularpurposes <strong>in</strong> the light <strong>of</strong> their own particular knowledge <strong>and</strong>expectations. As Menger taught us, there are no goods withoutknowledge, <strong>and</strong> what good is constituted by a particular assemblage<strong>of</strong> capital is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by those who are contemplat<strong>in</strong>g its use. Thisgood changes as knowledge changes, even if there is no change <strong>in</strong>the capital <strong>in</strong>struments. Capital comb<strong>in</strong>ations must be understood<strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> their orientation. The need to review the orientation <strong>of</strong> afirm’s capital, <strong>and</strong> to reshape it accord<strong>in</strong>gly, as knowledge,expectations <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>novative ideas change, implies a particularconcern for the problems <strong>of</strong> capital ma<strong>in</strong>tenance. Lachmann(1986:68–70) rem<strong>in</strong>ded us that the preservation <strong>of</strong> a constant<strong>in</strong>come stream can hardly ever be secured by the direct replacement<strong>of</strong> particular items as they wear out, or even by the purchase <strong>of</strong>improved equipment sufficient to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> production <strong>of</strong>unchanged products at an unchanged rate. Keynes’s (1936:69–70)user cost, which <strong>in</strong>fluences the entrepreneur’s choice betweenconserv<strong>in</strong>g or us<strong>in</strong>g up his equipment, depends on ‘the expectedsacrifice <strong>of</strong> future benefit’, <strong>and</strong> this expectation is likely to differbetween firms, <strong>and</strong> to change over time.24


SUBJECTIVISM IN ECONOMICS AND THE ECONOMYS<strong>in</strong>ce, as Lachmann <strong>in</strong>sisted, the plans <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals, or <strong>of</strong>organisations, rest on complementary assemblages <strong>of</strong> knowledge<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> other k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> capital, the productive capacity <strong>of</strong> an economydepends upon complementarities, which are partly crafted, but alsopartly the un<strong>in</strong>tended consequences <strong>of</strong> human action which wasdirected towards other purposes. People learn by do<strong>in</strong>g, by us<strong>in</strong>g(Rosenberg 1982: Chapter 6) <strong>and</strong> by choos<strong>in</strong>g (Woo 1992: Chapters5 <strong>and</strong> 6); but neither they nor we, as analysts or observers, canforesee what they will learn. Here Lachmann’s perspective comesvery close to that <strong>of</strong> Penrose (1959), <strong>and</strong> it comes even closer <strong>in</strong> hisemphasis on the orientation <strong>of</strong> each particular capital comb<strong>in</strong>ation,which is equivalent to the ‘productive opportunity’ available tothose <strong>in</strong> charge <strong>of</strong> a Penrosian firm. This productive opportunity,like Lachmann’s orientation, is subjective, but not arbitrary.Lachmann’s treatment <strong>of</strong> capital comb<strong>in</strong>ations, <strong>and</strong> particularlytheir relationship with complementary structures <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong>the overrid<strong>in</strong>g importance <strong>of</strong> orientation, give him a substantialclaim to be recognised as a founder <strong>of</strong> the modern capability-basedtheory <strong>of</strong> the firm. He recognised that complementarity <strong>of</strong>tendom<strong>in</strong>ates relationships between particular pairs or groups <strong>of</strong> firms,<strong>and</strong> that when it does it may need to be managed by work<strong>in</strong>gagreements, as has been argued by Richardson (I960, 1972), whomLachmann admired (letter <strong>of</strong> 2 July 1989). Relationships betweenthe capital comb<strong>in</strong>ation that is embodied <strong>in</strong> a particular firm <strong>and</strong>those who buy <strong>and</strong> sell the shares that are its f<strong>in</strong>ancial counterpartmay not be so easy to manage because stock exchanges aremerchants’ markets, <strong>in</strong> which participants can be either buyers orsellers, switch<strong>in</strong>g rapidly between the two, <strong>and</strong> enter<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> leav<strong>in</strong>gthe market at will, whereas the managers <strong>of</strong> the firm are committedto their side <strong>of</strong> the markets <strong>in</strong> which they operate, <strong>and</strong> to the capitalstructures that they have built up. This particular k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>termarket relationship deserves particular attention.I would much like to have heard Lachmann’s comments onAlfred Ch<strong>and</strong>ler’s (1992) argument that some <strong>of</strong> the majorproblems <strong>of</strong> the American economy have resulted from the attemptby many bus<strong>in</strong>ess leaders to behave as merchants, buy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> sell<strong>in</strong>gcompanies or divisions <strong>of</strong> companies, at the expense <strong>of</strong> theirtraditional role <strong>of</strong> shap<strong>in</strong>g the capabilities <strong>of</strong> their bus<strong>in</strong>esses tomatch their chang<strong>in</strong>g long-term visions <strong>of</strong> the markets <strong>in</strong> whichthose capabilities are to be used. A portfolio <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>esses can beswiftly rebalanced, but the capabilities that constitute theproductive assets with<strong>in</strong> that portfolio cannot. Nor can the25


BRIAN J.LOASBYrelationships between those capabilities. This seems to be preciselythe type <strong>of</strong> analysis for which Lachmann argued, <strong>and</strong> it exposes thelimitations <strong>of</strong> contemporary theories <strong>of</strong> corporate governance.Co-ord<strong>in</strong>ationThe analysis <strong>of</strong> economic processes operat<strong>in</strong>g with<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> betweenmarkets <strong>of</strong>fers a dist<strong>in</strong>ctive perspective on the co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong>economic activities. The economic problem is the cont<strong>in</strong>ual creation<strong>of</strong> order on the basis <strong>of</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>ually chang<strong>in</strong>g knowledge, which iswidely dispersed <strong>and</strong> always imperfect. It is a problem that is neverperfectly solved, <strong>and</strong> that Lachmann, unlike most Austrianeconomists, <strong>in</strong>sisted could sometimes prove too difficult for amarket system, because the requisite knowledge was not availableor not effectively communicated. If the division <strong>of</strong> labour promisesgreater productivity but imposes greater dem<strong>and</strong>s for co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation,the division <strong>of</strong> knowledge promises an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>of</strong> local knowledgebut threatens to prevent the effective communication, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>particular the shared <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> communication, thateffective co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation requires.Each person tries to construct a plan that is <strong>in</strong>ternally consistent,for there are always ga<strong>in</strong>s from elim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>consistency.Moreover, one can learn more from the failure <strong>of</strong> a plan, as from thefailure <strong>of</strong> a scientific hypothesis, if it is <strong>in</strong>ternally consistent <strong>and</strong> thefailure <strong>of</strong> plans, as <strong>of</strong> scientific hypotheses, is a necessary, thoughnot sufficient, condition <strong>of</strong> progress. That a perfectly co-ord<strong>in</strong>atedeconomy is an economy <strong>in</strong> which progress has ceased is a thoughtthat might disturb some orthodox economists; it is a thought thatimpelled Schumpeter, despite his great admiration for Walras’sachievement, to go outside Walras’s theory for an explanation <strong>of</strong>economic development.Because agents’ plans are based on different knowledge <strong>and</strong>different expectations about an unknowable future, there is noreason to believe that they will be entirely compatible, even with<strong>in</strong> as<strong>in</strong>gle market. Will they be adjusted towards compatibility? Theymay be, but the process may be impeded by differences <strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>terpretation—Why did customers refuse to buy? Why do ourcompetitors seem to have lower costs?—by divergent expectations,<strong>and</strong> by unexpected changes. Learn<strong>in</strong>g by do<strong>in</strong>g, us<strong>in</strong>g or choos<strong>in</strong>gmay lead different people <strong>in</strong> different directions, as Penrose (1959)observed, although the <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>of</strong> a particular market, like the<strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>of</strong> a scientific community, may <strong>in</strong>hibit conjectures.26


SUBJECTIVISM IN ECONOMICS AND THE ECONOMYOften there will be no wish to make plans compatible. As we havepreviously noted, speculation depends on a conflict <strong>of</strong> expectations,that must lead to the frustration <strong>of</strong> some plans. In his letter <strong>of</strong> 17September 1989, Lachmann commented that Hayek was never<strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong> speculation, <strong>and</strong> that Mises, who was, failed to see itssignificance for the analysis <strong>of</strong> co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation. And so it was left toShackle to po<strong>in</strong>t out that a speculative equilibrium must necessarilybe based on <strong>in</strong>compatible plans. But speculation is by no means theonly problem, as Lachmann (1986:5) knew very well. Even thesimple act <strong>of</strong> arbitrage with which Kirzner (1973) <strong>in</strong>troduces hisconcept <strong>of</strong> entrepreneurship is designed to <strong>in</strong>validate the plans <strong>of</strong>high-price sellers <strong>and</strong> low-price buyers: <strong>and</strong> the process <strong>of</strong>competition—<strong>in</strong> contrast to the myth <strong>of</strong> perfect competition—entails the deliberate collision <strong>of</strong> plans. That the competitive idealshould have become a model <strong>of</strong> perfect co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation exemplifiesthe ability <strong>of</strong> economists to exclude from their analysis the problemsthat they set out to solve.Inter-market co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation is also problematic. Walrasrecognised that the atta<strong>in</strong>ment <strong>of</strong> a general equilibrium could beassured only by simultaneous contract<strong>in</strong>g. Where this does nothappen, the sequence <strong>in</strong> which markets operate may be important.Changes that improve co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>in</strong> one market are likely todisrupt plans <strong>in</strong> other markets; <strong>and</strong> the cha<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> responses—whichare based, let us not forget, on human <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> what hashappened, <strong>and</strong> human forecasts <strong>of</strong> what will happen next—maymove the economy away from, rather than towards, generalequilibrium. This is particularly likely if people are unsure <strong>of</strong> their<strong>in</strong>terpretations, lack confidence <strong>in</strong> any forecast they can make <strong>and</strong>,as noted earlier, decide to delay commitment to any new plan untilprospects appear clearer.The importance <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess confidence <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g high levels<strong>of</strong> activity was clearly recognised by both Marshall <strong>and</strong> Keynes; <strong>and</strong>Keynes <strong>in</strong>corporated it <strong>in</strong>to the simplest possible k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>termarketanalysis with his division between <strong>in</strong>vestment (much <strong>of</strong>which could not, Keynes <strong>in</strong>sisted, be based on probabilityjudgements) <strong>and</strong> consumption goods, <strong>in</strong> which equilibrium with<strong>in</strong>the former market set the conditions for the latter. Lachmann, likeall Austrians, was not happy with such a level <strong>of</strong> aggregation, but heemphasised the importance <strong>of</strong> complementarity. In a world full <strong>of</strong>substitutes, noth<strong>in</strong>g actually matters very much: as Fogel (1964)demonstrated, the United States could have managed very wellwithout the railways, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> such a world each <strong>of</strong> us could manage27


BRIAN J.LOASBYvery well without any particular item <strong>of</strong> consumption or anyparticular job, because a slight adjustment <strong>of</strong> aspirations wouldimmediately produce an acceptable alternative. But that is not ourworld <strong>and</strong> the dangers <strong>of</strong> complementarity are the obverse <strong>of</strong> theopportunities that it br<strong>in</strong>gs.‘Every market <strong>of</strong> course tends to elim<strong>in</strong>ate excess dem<strong>and</strong> orsupply, but may do so by quantity, not price adjustment, <strong>and</strong> thusengender multiplier effects’ Lachmann wrote on 17 September1989. However, these effects are not adequately represented by amechanical sequence. Lachmann echoed Ohl<strong>in</strong>’s (1937:239)criticism <strong>of</strong> Keynes’s formulation, which was based on the Swedishconception <strong>of</strong> subjective expectations: consumption decisions, likeproduction <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment decisions, depend on assessments <strong>of</strong>future prospects, <strong>and</strong> though these assessments are <strong>in</strong>fluenced by thepast they are not determ<strong>in</strong>ed by it. Consumption, like <strong>in</strong>vestment,can change without any change <strong>in</strong> the data; <strong>and</strong> it does. In this, as <strong>in</strong>other respects, Lachmann was a constructive as well as asympathetic critic <strong>of</strong> Keynes, <strong>and</strong> believed that the quarrel betweenKeynes <strong>and</strong> the Austrians was quite unnecessary: This is a view Ihave held for a long time’ wrote Lachmann on 13 August 1989. Herecognised Keynes as a major, if not always consistent, proponent <strong>of</strong>subjectivist ideas, <strong>and</strong> the Austrians had no explanation <strong>of</strong> generalunemployment.ConclusionLachmann was a thoroughgo<strong>in</strong>g subjectivist. <strong>Subjectivism</strong> is anepistemological stance that does not imply the rejection <strong>of</strong> asubstantive reality; it certa<strong>in</strong>ly does not imply that ‘th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g makesit so’. But it does imply that th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g depends on <strong>in</strong>terpretativeframeworks, that no framework can be comprehensive <strong>and</strong> thatlogical argument, though necessary for consistency, is <strong>in</strong>sufficientfor truth. The future is unknowable. But though mistakes aretherefore <strong>in</strong>evitable, creativity is thereby made possible.Lachmann was consistent <strong>in</strong> the application <strong>of</strong> his scheme <strong>of</strong>thought to the economy <strong>and</strong> to the practice <strong>of</strong> economists. Therewere no determ<strong>in</strong>ate equilibria, <strong>and</strong> no pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> any persistentlydom<strong>in</strong>ant tendencies to co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation—not by the exercise <strong>of</strong>rational choice, nor by reason <strong>of</strong> gravitational pr<strong>in</strong>ciples, nor byevolutionary selection, nor even by unimpeded market processes;nor was there any uniquely correct way <strong>of</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g economics. Thediscipl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> economics, the economy <strong>and</strong> the polity were therefore28


SUBJECTIVISM IN ECONOMICS AND THE ECONOMYbest ordered as open <strong>and</strong> pluralist societies. This was a practicalappraisal, but also a moral judgement, for <strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann hadexperienced the consequences <strong>of</strong> a belief by the powerful that theyhad access to the truth, <strong>and</strong> was rightly disturbed by the evidence <strong>of</strong>such belief among some <strong>of</strong> the most powerful with<strong>in</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>ession<strong>of</strong> economics. He was correspond<strong>in</strong>gly ready to acknowledge (<strong>in</strong> hisletter <strong>of</strong> 2 July 1989) that Frank Hahn ‘is really much too <strong>in</strong>telligent<strong>and</strong> sensible a man, <strong>and</strong> too good an observer <strong>of</strong> the academic scene,to be happy with neoclassical formalism’.<strong>Economic</strong> agents <strong>and</strong> economists are human, with human powers,human propensities <strong>and</strong> human limitations. By assembl<strong>in</strong>gcomplementary capabilities <strong>in</strong> pursuit <strong>of</strong> a well-ordered plan, theycan achieve a great deal, but by attempt<strong>in</strong>g to assemble all thecapabilities <strong>of</strong> a society with<strong>in</strong> a s<strong>in</strong>gle plan they forgo manypossibilities. Moreover, those people who believe themselves capable<strong>of</strong> direct<strong>in</strong>g such a plan are almost certa<strong>in</strong>ly unfit for the task, both<strong>in</strong>tellectually <strong>and</strong> morally; <strong>and</strong> if they are not unfit when theyundertake it, they can hardly fail to become so. Co-ord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g amultitude <strong>of</strong> plans is very costly, never completely successful, <strong>and</strong>cont<strong>in</strong>ually needs to be redone; <strong>and</strong> the process is marked by somespectacular failures, the penalties for which are distributed withoutmuch regard for merit. To make strong claims for pluralistic, opensocieties is to court disappo<strong>in</strong>tment; but it is reasonable to believethat they are less bad than any alternative. This, on my <strong>in</strong>terpretation,was Lachmann’s view. He was an optimist without illusions.ReferencesCh<strong>and</strong>ler, A.D. (1992) ‘Corporate strategy, structure <strong>and</strong> control methods<strong>in</strong> the United States dur<strong>in</strong>g the 20th century’, Industrial <strong>and</strong> CorporateChange, 1:263–84.Fogel, R.W. (1964) Railroads <strong>and</strong> American <strong>Economic</strong> Growth: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong>Econometric History, Baltimore: Johns Hopk<strong>in</strong>s University Press.Keynes, J.M. (1936) The General Theory <strong>of</strong> Employment, Interest <strong>and</strong>Money, London: Macmillan.Kirzner, I.M. (1973) Competition <strong>and</strong> Entrepreneurship, Chicago:University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press.Lachmann, L.M. (1986) The Market as an <strong>Economic</strong> Process, Oxford:Basil Blackwell.Loasby, B.J. (1991) Equilibrium <strong>and</strong> Evolution, Manchester: ManchesterUniversity Press.Marshall, A. (1920) Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s, 8th edn, London: Macmillan.Ohl<strong>in</strong>, B. (1937) ‘Some notes on the Stockholm Theory <strong>of</strong> Sav<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong>Investment, Part II’, <strong>Economic</strong> Journal, 47:221–40.29


BRIAN J.LOASBYPenrose, E.T. (1959) The Theory <strong>of</strong> the Growth <strong>of</strong> the Firm, Oxford:Oxford University Press.Richardson, G.B. (1960) Information <strong>and</strong> Investment, Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press.——(1972) ‘The organisation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dustry’, <strong>Economic</strong> Journal, 82:883–6.Rob<strong>in</strong>son, J. (1956) The Accumulation <strong>of</strong> Capital, Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.Rosenberg, N. (1982) Inside the Black Box, Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.Woo, H.K.H. (1992) Cognition, Value <strong>and</strong> Price, Ann Arbor: University <strong>of</strong>Michigan Press.30


3MISES AND LACHMANNON HUMAN ACTIONStephen D.ParsonsIn his book on Weber, Lachmann sets out a framework for<strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g human action, which he reta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> his f<strong>in</strong>al works(e.g. Lachmann 1990). Lachmann’s analysis is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g for anumber <strong>of</strong> reasons. First, from the perspective <strong>of</strong> the history <strong>of</strong>Austrian economics, Lachmann must have been aware <strong>of</strong> the extentto which his approach would be controversial. Lachmann claims to‘carry forward Weber’s ideas <strong>in</strong> the circumstances <strong>of</strong> today’(Lachmann 1971:1), although recognis<strong>in</strong>g that Weber, as a student<strong>of</strong> Schmoller, ‘rema<strong>in</strong>ed very much the heir <strong>of</strong> the German HistoricalSchool all his life’ (ibid.: 17). This, <strong>of</strong> course, was the very schoolthat Menger had subjected to a rather vitriolic attack. Further, Weberwas a friend <strong>of</strong>, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>fluenced by, Rickert, whom Mises had similarlyaccused <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g ‘bound to historicism’ (Mises 1981:5). 1 There thusarises the suspicion that, <strong>in</strong> draw<strong>in</strong>g his analysis <strong>of</strong> human actionfrom the one provided by Weber, Lachmann may be adopt<strong>in</strong>g aperspective that earlier Austrians had specifically rejected.Second, although Lachmann’s analysis was published <strong>in</strong> 1971, itanticipates, <strong>in</strong> significant ways, some <strong>of</strong> the arguments recentlyadvanced <strong>in</strong> the philosophy <strong>of</strong> action (e.g. Bratman 1987). Third,once this perspective on Lachmann’s argument is appreciated, hisanalysis can be read as an implicit critique <strong>of</strong> the rational choicetheory that underp<strong>in</strong>s conventional neoclassical economics. 2Fourth, given the above, it is somewhat surpris<strong>in</strong>g that Lachmann’sanalysis appears not to have been taken up by economistssympathetic to the Austrian tradition. 3It will be argued that Lachmann’s theory <strong>of</strong> human action, ratherthan signify<strong>in</strong>g some betrayal <strong>of</strong> the Austrian tradition, can be31


STEPHEN D.PARSONS<strong>in</strong>terpreted as an attempt to develop a more coherent underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> human action than that prevalent <strong>in</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> Mises. This isbecause Mises’s account is deficient both <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> hisunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g as to how human action is to be <strong>in</strong>vestigated <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>his underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g as to what human action consists <strong>of</strong>. In fact, thesetwo problems are <strong>in</strong>terrelated: it is precisely because <strong>of</strong> hismethodological approach that Mises encounters problems <strong>in</strong>expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g human action. Lachmann’s theory can thus beunderstood as a criticism <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> an attempt to resolve difficulties <strong>in</strong>both Mises’s <strong>and</strong> rational choice theories <strong>of</strong> human action. Thesetheories can be classified together <strong>in</strong> this respect because Lachmannis implicitly draw<strong>in</strong>g attention to a problem they both share:expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g future <strong>in</strong>tentions.Mises <strong>and</strong> Lachmann on history <strong>and</strong> economicsInitially, it seems quite clear that Mises <strong>and</strong> Lachmann are <strong>in</strong> directopposition concern<strong>in</strong>g the subject matter <strong>of</strong> economics. Misesdef<strong>in</strong>ed economics as an a priori universally valid science <strong>of</strong> humanaction:The science <strong>of</strong> human action that strives for universally validknowledge is the theoretical system whose hitherto bestelaborated branch is economics. In all its branches this scienceis a priori, not empirical…it is not derived from experience; itis prior to experience.(Mises 1981:12–13)The science <strong>of</strong> human action, or praxeology, was concerned withestablish<strong>in</strong>g certa<strong>in</strong> universal categories, which are necessary withreference to human action: ‘The cognition <strong>of</strong> praxeology isconceptual cognition. It refers to what is necessary <strong>in</strong> human action.It is a cognition <strong>of</strong> universals <strong>and</strong> categories’ (Mises 1949:51).The ‘necessity’ referred to here is meant <strong>in</strong> a dual sense: the apriori categories <strong>of</strong> human action are required both <strong>in</strong> order to act<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> order to comprehend the actions <strong>of</strong> others. As praxeologywas a ‘cognition <strong>of</strong> universals’, then it could not comprehend the<strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>and</strong> unique. Because the unique could not be brought underuniversal categories, it was ‘irrational’, <strong>and</strong> thus the concern <strong>of</strong> history,not economics: ‘Individuality is given to the historian, it is exactlywhat cannot be exhaustively expla<strong>in</strong>ed or traced back to other entities.In this sense <strong>in</strong>dividuality is irrational’ (Mises 1990:12).32


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONMises is not mak<strong>in</strong>g some ontological claim to the effect thatreality is ‘irrational’. Rather, he is advanc<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> claim<strong>in</strong>g that anyexplanation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuality cannot claim to be either ‘exhaustive orunique’ (ibid.: 13). It is impossible to <strong>in</strong>dicate what would count asan exhaustive or unique explanation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuality, as ‘history canbe written from different po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> view’ (ibid.: 12). In this Misesfollows Rickert, 4 for whom ‘reality is irrational <strong>in</strong> the sense thatthere is no criterion that can specify what would constitute acomplete description <strong>of</strong> its aspects’ (Oakes 1986: xvii). 5For Mises, as history, but not economics, was concerned with the<strong>in</strong>dividual, it attempts to underst<strong>and</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> action:‘Underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> action is the specific method <strong>of</strong>historical research’ (Mises 1990:12).In direct contrast to Mises, Lachmann attempts to develop atheory <strong>of</strong> action relevant to economics that commences from ‘theWeberian notion that action derives its mean<strong>in</strong>g from the m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong>the actor’ (Lachmann 1971:9), or from the <strong>in</strong>dividuality that, forMises, was the concern <strong>of</strong> the historical method. Accord<strong>in</strong>g toLachmann, the emphasis on <strong>in</strong>dividual mean<strong>in</strong>g signified ‘a“positive” method <strong>of</strong> the German Historical School which Webertook over <strong>and</strong> adapted to his purpose’ (ibid.: 10). The differencesseem quite clear: from Mises’s perspective, Lachmann is <strong>in</strong>terested<strong>in</strong> the methods <strong>of</strong> history, not those <strong>of</strong> economics. 6Lachmann’s implicit rejection <strong>of</strong> Mises’s framework is quiteunderst<strong>and</strong>able if it can be argued that Mises’s attempt to derivecerta<strong>in</strong> a priori categories <strong>of</strong> human action is both futile <strong>and</strong> sterile.An argument along these l<strong>in</strong>es would certa<strong>in</strong>ly be sympatheticallyreceived by Codd<strong>in</strong>gton:If subjectivist logic is followed to the po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> becom<strong>in</strong>gconv<strong>in</strong>ced that there is noth<strong>in</strong>g for economists to do but tounderst<strong>and</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> (praxeological) concepts, then the onlyproblem that rema<strong>in</strong>s is that <strong>of</strong> subjugat<strong>in</strong>g one’s consciencelong enough to draw one’s salary <strong>in</strong> exchange for impart<strong>in</strong>gthis piece <strong>of</strong> wisdom.(Codd<strong>in</strong>gton 1983:61)In contrast to this dismissal, it is quite plausible to argue that certa<strong>in</strong>aspects <strong>of</strong> Mises’s appeal to the a priori can be defended. However,such an argument does not signify that Lachmann’s analysis mustthus be rejected. This is because a modified notion <strong>of</strong> the a priori,although possibly necessary <strong>in</strong> order to grasp human action, is33


STEPHEN D.PARSONS<strong>in</strong>sufficient <strong>in</strong> elucidat<strong>in</strong>g the nature <strong>of</strong> human action.Consequently, rather than view<strong>in</strong>g Lachmann as reject<strong>in</strong>g Mises’saccount, it is quite plausible to argue that Lachmann’s account issupplementary to that <strong>of</strong> Mises. However, not surpris<strong>in</strong>gly, thisargument does require the rejection <strong>of</strong> Mises’s strict demarcationbetween economics <strong>and</strong> history.Mises <strong>and</strong> the a prioriMises <strong>and</strong> Lachmann are both strongly anti-naturalistic <strong>in</strong> theirunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> economics, believ<strong>in</strong>g that there is a sharpdemarcation between the methods <strong>of</strong> economics <strong>and</strong> the naturalsciences. With Lachmann, this anti-naturalism constitutes both areason why Weber’s work ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s significance <strong>and</strong> serves todist<strong>in</strong>guish Austrian <strong>and</strong> neoclassical economics:Weber espoused the method <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation (Verstehen) forthe social sciences. In economics today the prevail<strong>in</strong>g style <strong>of</strong>thought is a neoclassical formalism which is quite untouchedby Weber s methodology <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to take it for grantedthat the methods <strong>of</strong> the natural sciences are the only scientificmethods known to man. We shall try to show why <strong>in</strong> our viewthis is a field <strong>in</strong> which the dissem<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> Weberian ideaspromises to yield a rich harvest.(Lachmann 1971:2)In contrast, Mises rejects the relevance <strong>of</strong> a Weberian-<strong>in</strong>spiredVerstehen for the reasons already <strong>in</strong>dicated. As <strong>in</strong>dividuality isirrational, it is not possible to provide any unique <strong>in</strong>terpretation:‘The experience with which the social sciences have to deal is alwaysthe experience <strong>of</strong> complex phenomena. They are open to various<strong>in</strong>terpretations’ (Mises 1990:18).It is precisely because experiences are open to various<strong>in</strong>terpretations that economics must proceed deductively.Consequently, economics cannot appeal to experience <strong>in</strong> order tovalidate its theorems. This is because the striv<strong>in</strong>g for universallyvalid knowledge cannot be threatened by experiences open to amultiplicity <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretations: ‘The social sciences can never useexperience to verify their statements. Every fact <strong>and</strong> everyexperience with which they have to deal is open to various<strong>in</strong>terpretations’ (ibid.: 5).Given Mises’s explicit rejection <strong>of</strong> the relevance <strong>of</strong> the historical34


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONmethod for economics, it may <strong>in</strong>itially appear puzzl<strong>in</strong>g that he also,like Lachmann, <strong>in</strong>dicates the significance <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g for the socialsciences: ‘What makes natural science possible is the power toexperiment; what makes social science possible is the power to graspor to comprehend the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> human action’ (ibid.: 9).However, by ‘comprehend<strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> action’ <strong>in</strong>economics, Mises does not refer to the Weberian notion <strong>of</strong>underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>g. Mises dist<strong>in</strong>guishes the comprehension <strong>of</strong>mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to two k<strong>in</strong>ds: conceiv<strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> an action, whichis the concern <strong>of</strong> economics; <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>action, which is the concern <strong>of</strong> history. The dist<strong>in</strong>ction betweenconceiv<strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>g is both importantyet not immediately obvious. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Mises:We conceive the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> action, that is to say, we take anaction to be such. We see <strong>in</strong> the action the endeavour to reacha goal by the use <strong>of</strong> means. In conceiv<strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> anaction we consider it as a purposeful endeavour to reach somegoal, but we do not regard the quality <strong>of</strong> the ends proposed<strong>and</strong> the means applied. We conceive activity as such, its logical(praxeological) qualities <strong>and</strong> categories.(Mises 1990:9, emphasis added)This statement is amenable to a number <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretations. First,Mises could be argu<strong>in</strong>g that we require certa<strong>in</strong> a priori concepts <strong>in</strong>order to identify anyth<strong>in</strong>g as human action, where human action isnecessarily means/ends orientated. Second, Mises could be argu<strong>in</strong>gthat we must be <strong>in</strong> possession <strong>of</strong> concepts applicable to types <strong>of</strong>action, <strong>in</strong> order to comprehend any <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>stances, or tokens,<strong>of</strong> any type <strong>of</strong> action. For example, we must be <strong>in</strong> possession <strong>of</strong> theconcept <strong>of</strong> ‘means’ <strong>in</strong> order to comprehend any specific action as‘means/ends orientated’. Third, Mises could be argu<strong>in</strong>g that everyaction can only be comprehended if we can apply the whole range <strong>of</strong>praxeological concepts to each action. Unfortunately, each <strong>of</strong> these<strong>in</strong>terpretations receives textual support from Mises’s own writ<strong>in</strong>gs.To appreciate some <strong>of</strong> the ambiguities <strong>in</strong> Mises’s position, takethe follow<strong>in</strong>g argument:<strong>Economic</strong>s therefore is not based on or derived (abstracted)from experience. It is a deductive system, start<strong>in</strong>g from the<strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong>to the pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> human reason <strong>and</strong> conduct. As amatter <strong>of</strong> fact all our experience <strong>in</strong> the field <strong>of</strong> human action is35


STEPHEN D.PARSONSbased on <strong>and</strong> conditioned by the circumstances that we havethis <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>in</strong> our m<strong>in</strong>d. Without this a priori knowledge <strong>and</strong>the theorems derived from it we could not at all realize what isgo<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>in</strong> human activity. Our experience <strong>of</strong> human action<strong>and</strong> social life is predicated on praxeology <strong>and</strong> economictheory.(Mises 1990:9)Ambiguities arise because Mises appears to:1 conflate phenomenological <strong>and</strong> epistemological concerns. Herefers both to our ability to experience someth<strong>in</strong>g as humanaction <strong>and</strong> our specific knowledge concern<strong>in</strong>g human action;2 dist<strong>in</strong>guish between a priori knowledge <strong>and</strong> theorems derivedfrom it, yet argue that both are somehow necessary <strong>in</strong> order to‘realize what is go<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>in</strong> human activity’;3 dist<strong>in</strong>guish between praxeology <strong>and</strong> economic theory, yet aga<strong>in</strong>argue that both are necessary <strong>in</strong> order to experience humanaction.The weakest, yet most readily defensible, claim advanced by Misescan be <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g manner: <strong>in</strong> order to identify orrecognise any movement as a human action, then we are a prioricommitted to ascrib<strong>in</strong>g certa<strong>in</strong> concepts to this action. This could betermed the ‘Davidsonian argument’: If we are <strong>in</strong>telligibly toattribute attitudes <strong>and</strong> beliefs, or usefully to describe motions asbehaviour, then we are committed to f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> the pattern <strong>of</strong>behaviour, belief <strong>and</strong> desire, a large degree <strong>of</strong> rationality <strong>and</strong>consistency’ (Davidson 1980:237).Davidson further argues that this a priori commitment to view<strong>in</strong>gbehaviour as goal-orientated rational behaviour dist<strong>in</strong>guishes thesocial sciences from the natural sciences:S<strong>in</strong>ce psychological phenomena do not constitute a closedsystem, this amounts to say<strong>in</strong>g they are not, even <strong>in</strong> theory,amenable to precise prediction or subsumption underdeterm<strong>in</strong>istic laws. The limit thus placed on the social sciencesis set not by nature, but by us when we decide to view men asrational agents with goals <strong>and</strong> purposes.(Davidson 1980:239)36


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONArguments similar to these can be readily extracted from Mises’swork. For example, Mises argues that we can only differentiate<strong>in</strong>tentional action from reactive behaviour if we assume that all<strong>in</strong>tentional action is rational:Praxeology does not employ the term rational. It deals withpurposive behaviour, i.e., human action. The opposite <strong>of</strong>action is not irrational behaviour, but a reactive response tostimuli on the part <strong>of</strong> the bodily organs <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>cts,which cannot be controlled by volition. If we were to assign adef<strong>in</strong>ite mean<strong>in</strong>g to the term rational as applied to behaviour,we could not f<strong>in</strong>d another mean<strong>in</strong>g than: the attitude <strong>of</strong> men<strong>in</strong>tent on br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g about effects.(Mises 1990:23)Consequently, it could be argued, from Mises’s position, that weare a priori committed to discern<strong>in</strong>g rationality <strong>in</strong> purposivebehaviour. In other words, the concept <strong>of</strong> rationality is ‘a priori’ <strong>in</strong>so far as it must be employed prior to identify<strong>in</strong>g anyth<strong>in</strong>g asaction. As action is assumed, a priori, to be rational, then a certa<strong>in</strong>‘pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> charity’ is <strong>in</strong> operation: we must assume that, fromthe perspective <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual actors themselves, they are act<strong>in</strong>grationally:In speak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> human action, we have <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d conduct that, <strong>in</strong>the op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>of</strong> the actor, is best fitted to atta<strong>in</strong> an end he wantsto atta<strong>in</strong>, whether or not his op<strong>in</strong>ion is also held by a better<strong>in</strong>formed spectator or historian.(Mises 1990:45)The problem Mises is address<strong>in</strong>g can be formulated thus: we do notfirst identify an action, <strong>and</strong> then work out whether or not it isrational. Rather, <strong>in</strong> identify<strong>in</strong>g anyth<strong>in</strong>g as a human action, wealready assume, or assume ‘a priori’, that this action is rational.Consequently, Mises is appeal<strong>in</strong>g to a much broader conception <strong>of</strong>rationality than that operat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> rational choice theories:<strong>Economic</strong>s does not deal with an imag<strong>in</strong>ary homo economicusas <strong>in</strong>eradicable fables reproach it with do<strong>in</strong>g, but with homoagens as he really is, <strong>of</strong>ten weak, stupid, <strong>in</strong>considerate, <strong>and</strong>badly <strong>in</strong>structed…. Its theorems are valid for all actions…. It isthe scope <strong>of</strong> history <strong>and</strong> not <strong>of</strong> praxeology to <strong>in</strong>vestigate what37


STEPHEN D.PARSONSends people aim at <strong>and</strong> what means they apply for therealization <strong>of</strong> their plans.(ibid.: 24)Whereas rational choice theory is normative, <strong>in</strong> the sense that itstipulates how <strong>in</strong>dividuals ought to behave if their behaviour is to becharacterised as ‘rational’, Mises’s theory assumes a priori that allhuman action is rational, <strong>and</strong> thus economics ‘does not deal with theought, but with the is’ (ibid.: 23). Consequently, on this<strong>in</strong>terpretation, Mises is argu<strong>in</strong>g that we are a priori committed toview<strong>in</strong>g human behaviour as rational <strong>and</strong> purposive, <strong>and</strong> we mustmake this commitment a priori to identify<strong>in</strong>g (‘comprehend<strong>in</strong>g’)anyth<strong>in</strong>g as an action.Given this, as economics is concerned with human actions thatcan only be recognised as such through certa<strong>in</strong> constitutivepr<strong>in</strong>ciples, then economics is logically prior to the historical concernwith the <strong>in</strong>dividual. As noted earlier, history is concerned to ‘graspthe mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuality’ (ibid.: 12). However, <strong>in</strong> order that themean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> any <strong>in</strong>dividual action can be understood, this <strong>in</strong>dividualaction must have already been identified as an action. Consequently,praxeology is not only dist<strong>in</strong>ct from historical <strong>in</strong>vestigations, buthistorical <strong>in</strong>vestigations presuppose praxeology: ‘The radicalempiricism <strong>of</strong> the historicists went astray <strong>in</strong> ignor<strong>in</strong>g this fact. Noreport about any man’s conduct can do without reference to thepraxeological a priori’ (ibid.: 49).From this perspective, it can be argued that praxeology isconcerned to establish the most basic concepts relevant toidentify<strong>in</strong>g motions as actions. Unfortunately, as noted, Mises’swrit<strong>in</strong>gs also appear to v<strong>in</strong>dicate alternative <strong>in</strong>terpretations. Forexample, Mises argues that:If we had not <strong>in</strong> our m<strong>in</strong>d the schemes provided bypraxeological reason<strong>in</strong>g, we should never be <strong>in</strong> a position todiscern or grasp any action. We would perceive motions, butneither buy<strong>in</strong>g nor sell<strong>in</strong>g, nor prices, wage rates, <strong>in</strong>terestrates, <strong>and</strong> so on.(Mises 1949:40)If this is taken as argu<strong>in</strong>g that we must be a priori committed toapply<strong>in</strong>g certa<strong>in</strong> concepts to motions <strong>in</strong> order to render them<strong>in</strong>telligible as human actions, then the ‘Davidsonian argument’ f<strong>in</strong>dsadditional support. However, if Mises is also attempt<strong>in</strong>g to establish38


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONthat the various ‘theorems’ <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al analysis that have beendeductively arrived at are also necessary to comprehend humanaction, then this is a substantially stronger claim. In other words,why exactly are the concepts <strong>of</strong> ‘buy<strong>in</strong>g’, ‘sell<strong>in</strong>g’, etc., be<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong> connection with ‘praxeological reason<strong>in</strong>g’?One way <strong>of</strong> reconstruct<strong>in</strong>g the argument is as follows. Mises doesrecognise that, <strong>in</strong> order to ‘have’ a concept, we must both be able toth<strong>in</strong>k coherently with it <strong>and</strong> to recognise th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> the world towhich it applies. Consequently, Mises could be taken as argu<strong>in</strong>gthat, unless we know how to use the concept <strong>of</strong>, say, ‘buy<strong>in</strong>g’, wewould discern only un<strong>in</strong>telligible motions. We must be capable <strong>of</strong>apply<strong>in</strong>g the type concept ‘buy<strong>in</strong>g’ to any <strong>in</strong>dividual actions that fallunder this type. Further, presumably if we are to construct aneconomic theory concerned with the activity <strong>of</strong> buy<strong>in</strong>g, then wemust be able to locate this concept, <strong>and</strong> thus use it <strong>in</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g,with<strong>in</strong> a system <strong>of</strong> other concepts.However, if Mises’s argument is reconstructed <strong>in</strong> this form, thena number <strong>of</strong> problems surface. First, it is not clear why suchconcepts can claim an a priori status: they may just be learned, say,through socialisation. Second, the a priori categories Mises isconcerned with must be both necessary <strong>and</strong> universal. This couldmean either that all concepts are required <strong>in</strong> order to comprehendall possible human actions, or that all are required <strong>in</strong> order tocomprehend each <strong>in</strong>dividual action. The former is considerablyweaker than the latter, <strong>and</strong> would seem to run foul <strong>of</strong> the problemdiscussed <strong>in</strong> more detail below. It would seem to require that weknow which concepts to apply to which actions, although it is onlythrough these concepts that we can comprehend any actions at all.This leaves the third possible <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> Mises’s argument,which appears relevant to statements such as:No report about any man’s conduct can do without referenceto the praxeological a priori. There is no human action thatcan be dealt with without reference to the categoricalconcepts <strong>of</strong> ends <strong>and</strong> means, <strong>of</strong> success <strong>and</strong> failure, <strong>of</strong> costs,pr<strong>of</strong>it or loss.(Mises 1990:49)This implies that, <strong>in</strong> order to conceive the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> any actionwhatsoever, we must be able to apply concepts such as ‘costs’ <strong>and</strong>loss’ to it. This suggests that Mises is attempt<strong>in</strong>g to establish thatconceiv<strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> any action requires all the concepts39


STEPHEN D.PARSONSrelevant to a marg<strong>in</strong>al analysis. It is extremely difficult to appreciatehow such an extravagant claim could be defended.This problem is compounded by a related issue. Mises subscribesto the Cartesian assumption that it is the content <strong>of</strong> our ownconsciousness that can be most reliably known, <strong>and</strong> this forms thebackground to the attempt to <strong>in</strong>dicate how various a priori conceptscan be determ<strong>in</strong>ed. Consequently, his ‘natural’ assumption is that, asthese concepts are necessary <strong>in</strong> order to grasp the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> anyaction, <strong>and</strong> as ‘we’ act, they can be arrived at through anexam<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> our own consciousness:To the obvious question, how a purely logical deduction fromaprioristic pr<strong>in</strong>ciples can tell us anyth<strong>in</strong>g about reality, wehave to reply that both human thought <strong>and</strong> human actionstem from the same root <strong>in</strong> that they are both products <strong>of</strong> thehuman m<strong>in</strong>d.(Mises 1990:11)The various problems <strong>in</strong>dicated earlier cannot be avoided. Misesmoves from the phenomenological concern with experienc<strong>in</strong>gaction to the epistemological concern with our knowledge <strong>of</strong> action,from a priori concepts to the concepts <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al analysis, frompraxeology to economic theory. At one level, Mises can be<strong>in</strong>terpreted as start<strong>in</strong>g from the premise that we must assume <strong>and</strong>ascribe rationality to <strong>in</strong>dividual actors <strong>in</strong> order to identify their‘movements’ as actions <strong>in</strong> the first place. This <strong>in</strong>dicates that wecannot identify human action <strong>in</strong>dependently <strong>of</strong> the a priori conceptsthat permit this identification <strong>in</strong> the first place. However, thisargument becomes confused with that <strong>of</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g the ‘truths’ <strong>of</strong>marg<strong>in</strong>al analysis. Further, given the lack <strong>of</strong> discrim<strong>in</strong>ation betweenphenomenological <strong>and</strong> epistemological concerns, Mises th<strong>in</strong>ks he isjustified <strong>in</strong> adopt<strong>in</strong>g a ‘first person’ approach. Consequently, giventhe argument that thought <strong>and</strong> action spr<strong>in</strong>g from ‘the same root’,Mises th<strong>in</strong>ks that we can arrive at deriv<strong>in</strong>g the concepts <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>alanalysis solely from analys<strong>in</strong>g thought:However, what we know about our action under givenconditions is derived not from experience, but from reason.What we know about the fundamental categories <strong>of</strong>action…is not derived from experience. We conceive all thisfrom with<strong>in</strong>.(Mises 1981:13–14)40


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONHowever, action <strong>and</strong> thought are quite dist<strong>in</strong>ct: because ‘the m<strong>in</strong>d’ isnecessary to identify action does not mean we can ‘read <strong>of</strong>f certa<strong>in</strong>truths about action directly from it. M<strong>in</strong>d might be necessary foridentification, but it is not sufficient: we also require the actionsthemselves. Mises thus obliterates the differences betweencomprehend<strong>in</strong>g human action <strong>and</strong> perform<strong>in</strong>g valid deductionsfrom the axioms <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al analysis, between establish<strong>in</strong>g thenecessary conditions for comprehend<strong>in</strong>g action <strong>and</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>gcerta<strong>in</strong> a priori ‘truths’.In summaris<strong>in</strong>g the above, two po<strong>in</strong>ts are worth emphasis<strong>in</strong>g.First, certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> the concepts Mises def<strong>in</strong>es as ‘a priori’ appear morebasic, <strong>in</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> possibly be<strong>in</strong>g universal, than others withregard to human action. Concepts such as ‘rationality’ <strong>and</strong>‘purposive’ are significantly more general than concepts such as‘buy<strong>in</strong>g’ or ‘pr<strong>of</strong>its’. The less generalised concepts appear <strong>in</strong> theanalysis because Mises confuses comprehend<strong>in</strong>g action withexpla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g action with the assistance <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al theory. Second, wecannot, solely from an <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>in</strong>to the contents <strong>of</strong>consciousness, recognise th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> the world to which conceptsapply. In order to justify our ‘hav<strong>in</strong>g’ a concept, it is not sufficient to<strong>in</strong>dicate how it coherently <strong>in</strong>tegrates with other concepts.Exp<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g on the first <strong>of</strong> these po<strong>in</strong>ts: the question <strong>of</strong> theuniversality <strong>of</strong> a priori concepts raises problems for Mises’s analysis.As noted, Mises lists the concepts <strong>of</strong> ends <strong>and</strong> means as a prioripraxeological categories. He also refers to the concept <strong>of</strong> causalityas ‘a category or an a priori <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> act<strong>in</strong>g’ (1962:20), yetadmits that the concepts <strong>of</strong> means <strong>and</strong> ends presuppose the category<strong>of</strong> causality (1958:92). This suggests that Mises acknowledges someform <strong>of</strong> hierarchy with<strong>in</strong> the various a priori categories. Now it maybe plausible to defend the category <strong>of</strong> causality as a priori, as Kanthimself argued. 7 However, as Mises himself recognises (1958:92),the category <strong>of</strong> causality is also applicable <strong>in</strong> the natural sciences.Consequently, with<strong>in</strong> the hierarchy <strong>of</strong> a priori categories, some, likecausality, are universally applicable, whilst others, such as means<strong>and</strong> ends, are only applicable to human action. However, thisimplies that we must already know, prior to us<strong>in</strong>g any a prioricategories <strong>of</strong> human action, that we are apply<strong>in</strong>g them to humanaction, <strong>and</strong> not to natural events. Yet it seems that it is only because<strong>of</strong> the a priori categories that we can comprehend anyth<strong>in</strong>g ashuman action. Thus we must have comprehended certa<strong>in</strong>movements as human actions, <strong>and</strong> not natural events, prior to thepossibility <strong>of</strong> us be<strong>in</strong>g capable <strong>of</strong> so comprehend<strong>in</strong>g them.41


STEPHEN D.PARSONSGiven these various problems with Mises’s account, it is fruitfulto make the transition to Lachmann’s explanation <strong>of</strong> human action.Earlier it was suggested that Mises’s sharp demarcation between themethods <strong>of</strong> economics <strong>and</strong> the methods <strong>of</strong> history cannot besusta<strong>in</strong>ed. It has been argued that Mises’s defence <strong>of</strong> an a priorieconomics is not susta<strong>in</strong>able, although it may be possible to defendthe weaker claim that comprehend<strong>in</strong>g human action requires someform <strong>of</strong> a priori concepts or pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. 8 However, <strong>in</strong> so far as onlythis weaker claim seems capable <strong>of</strong> defence, then Mises’s claim thatwe can somehow ‘deduce’ truths about human action a priori mustbe rejected. Consequently, although we may now know how humanaction is to be approached (through constitutive concepts orpr<strong>in</strong>ciples), we do not know <strong>of</strong> what such action consists. Indeed,because Mises is committed to an a priori approach, his analysis <strong>of</strong>human action is deficient, <strong>and</strong> requires supplement<strong>in</strong>g withLachmann’s account. In appreciat<strong>in</strong>g how, their differentunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>gs as to what human action consists <strong>in</strong> must be<strong>in</strong>vestigated.The problem <strong>of</strong> future <strong>in</strong>tentionsEbel<strong>in</strong>g outl<strong>in</strong>es Mises’s theory <strong>of</strong> human action as follows.Purposeful behaviour is characterised by:Dissatisfaction with exist<strong>in</strong>g or expected conditions orcircumstances; <strong>and</strong> imag<strong>in</strong>ed preferred state <strong>of</strong> affairs; <strong>and</strong>beliefs that methods were or could be available to br<strong>in</strong>g aboutthe desired change. ‘Action’ was a relationship betweenchosen ends, selected means <strong>and</strong> conduct or consciousbehaviour to achieve the ends preferred with the meansavailable.(Ebel<strong>in</strong>g 1994:87)Consequently, we have a desire or preference, beliefs <strong>and</strong> consciousbehaviour. In contrast, Lachmann suggests that conscious behaviourcan only be understood <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> ‘a plan’. Consequently,Lachmann argues that the historian: ‘Has to ascerta<strong>in</strong> “The Plan”,the coherent design beh<strong>in</strong>d the observable action <strong>in</strong> which thevarious purposes as well as the means employed are bound together’(Lachmann 1971:20).The argument that purposive or <strong>in</strong>tentional behaviour can onlybe understood <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> a plan is reiterated by Lachmann <strong>in</strong>42


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONa later work: ‘Phenomena <strong>of</strong> human action…display an <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sicorder we dare not ignore: that which the human actors assigned tothem <strong>in</strong> the mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> carry<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> their plans’ (Lachmann1990:136, emphasis <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al). Lachmann can thus be perceived asrais<strong>in</strong>g two objections to Mises’s analysis. First, purposive or<strong>in</strong>tentional behaviour can only be adequately comprehended <strong>in</strong> thecontext <strong>of</strong> plans. Second, this necessitates a focus on the <strong>in</strong>dividual.Through detail<strong>in</strong>g problems with Mises’s account <strong>of</strong> human nature,it will be argued that Lachmann is correct on the first po<strong>in</strong>t,although the second po<strong>in</strong>t requires some modification.Mises’s emphasis on desires or preferences <strong>and</strong> beliefs, but notplans, suggests that his account <strong>of</strong> human action can be identified <strong>in</strong>terms <strong>of</strong> draw<strong>in</strong>g a conclusion from an Aristotelian practicalsyllogism. 9 Consequently, we have, for example:Major premise: I desire to eat someth<strong>in</strong>g sweet;M<strong>in</strong>or premise: I believe that the eat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this cake is theeat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g sweet;Conclusion: Therefore, I eat this cake.This is also the underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> action underly<strong>in</strong>g modern rationalchoice theory (Sugden 1991). However, there is a major problemwith this underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> human action. Say I desire to avoid pa<strong>in</strong><strong>and</strong> believe that go<strong>in</strong>g to the dentist will lead to my <strong>in</strong>curr<strong>in</strong>g pa<strong>in</strong>,then I conclude that I should avoid go<strong>in</strong>g to the dentist. However, Ialso desire that my broken tooth no longer disfigures myappearance, <strong>and</strong> believe that go<strong>in</strong>g to the dentist will lead to mybroken tooth be<strong>in</strong>g repaired, <strong>and</strong> thus conclude that I should go tothe dentist. Consequently, my desires <strong>and</strong> beliefs lead tocontradictory conclusions. The problem here is that we may want toreflect upon our desires <strong>and</strong> beliefs, <strong>and</strong> modify them. However,there is no component with the Aristotelian practical syllogism thatallows for such reflection.This immediately raises a problem for Mises’s argument. Accord<strong>in</strong>gto Mises: ‘Praxeology…does not enter <strong>in</strong>to a discussion <strong>of</strong> the motivesdeterm<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g choice…. It deals with the choos<strong>in</strong>g as such, with thecategorical elements <strong>of</strong> choice <strong>and</strong> action’ (1990:20–1).However, if it is <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic to the nature <strong>of</strong> choice that act<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>dividuals reflect upon the ‘motives determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g choice’, then anytheory attempt<strong>in</strong>g to encompass the nature <strong>of</strong> choice must <strong>in</strong>clude43


STEPHEN D.PARSONSthis act <strong>of</strong> reflection as one <strong>of</strong> the ‘categorical elements <strong>of</strong> choice’.Certa<strong>in</strong> elements Mises wishes to exclude from praxeologicalconsideration appear not to be capable <strong>of</strong> omission. Thus, accord<strong>in</strong>gto Mises: ‘The ultimate judgements <strong>of</strong> value <strong>and</strong> ultimate ends <strong>of</strong>human action are given for any k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> scientific <strong>in</strong>quiry; they arenot open to further analysis’ (1949:21).However, if these ends are not merely ‘given’ to the actor, butarrived at through reflection, <strong>and</strong> thus they are subject to furtheranalysis by the actor, how can praxeology ignore this feature <strong>of</strong>human action, yet claim to grasp ‘the categorical essence <strong>of</strong> choice<strong>and</strong> action as such’ (Mises 1990:21)? If it is part <strong>of</strong> the ‘essence <strong>of</strong>choice’ that ends are reflected upon, this must form part <strong>of</strong> thepraxeological concern. Lachmann himself saw problems withMises’s account here, argu<strong>in</strong>g that ‘s<strong>in</strong>ce ends lie <strong>in</strong> the unknowablefuture, how can they be “given” to us?’ (Lachmann 1982:38).The severity <strong>of</strong> this problem for Mises can be appreciated if anattempt is made to modify his account to accommodate thisproblem. It could be argued that human action must be taken ascorrespond<strong>in</strong>g to an ‘unconditional’ or ‘all out’ evaluativeproposition that an action is desirable. 10 Thus, <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> the visitto the dentist, after weigh<strong>in</strong>g various considerations, I would arriveat an ‘all out’ judgement that go<strong>in</strong>g to the dentist was desirable. AsBratman (1985) po<strong>in</strong>ts out, this <strong>in</strong>dicates that evaluativeconclusions are both implicitly comparative <strong>and</strong> concern particularactions, not types <strong>of</strong> actions: for example, certa<strong>in</strong> ways <strong>of</strong> do<strong>in</strong>gth<strong>in</strong>gs may be undesirable.Yet if evaluative conclusions concern particular actions, not types<strong>of</strong> action, then they would appear not to be <strong>of</strong> any concern forpraxeology, for whom the particular is the concern <strong>of</strong> history.However, if human action necessarily entails evaluative conclusions,yet these refer to particular actions, not types <strong>of</strong> actions, then wehave a universal feature <strong>of</strong> human action that can only be madesense <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong> connection with particular actions. Mises’s claim thatpraxeology, as a priori, is concerned with ‘the pure elements <strong>of</strong>sett<strong>in</strong>g aims <strong>and</strong> apply<strong>in</strong>g means’ (1990:21) becomes highly suspect,as the ‘purity’ <strong>of</strong> these elements is directly threatened: the ‘elements<strong>of</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>g aims’ only appear comprehensible <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong>specific actions.Mises desires to establish the <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>of</strong> human action on ana priori basis. However, if <strong>in</strong>dividuals do have <strong>in</strong>compatible ends,then any ‘sett<strong>in</strong>g’ <strong>of</strong> aims must refer to the actual context with<strong>in</strong>which an action occurs. Further, if an <strong>in</strong>dividual is <strong>in</strong>different between44


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONalternative means to satisfy a particular end (say, there are twopossible keyboard keys that can produce the same sign), then, aga<strong>in</strong>,any relationship between ends <strong>and</strong> means cannot be deduced a priori:If the antecedent situation conta<strong>in</strong>s the agent’s hav<strong>in</strong>g a desirefor each <strong>of</strong> two or more <strong>in</strong>compatible ends or her be<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>different between alternative means to an <strong>in</strong>tended end, thenit has the potential to expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> the reasons way whichever <strong>of</strong>the alternative actions occurs.(G<strong>in</strong>et 1990:147)However, be<strong>in</strong>g capable <strong>of</strong> reconstruct<strong>in</strong>g the reasons for an actionfrom an antecedent situation is emphatically not the same as deduc<strong>in</strong>geveryth<strong>in</strong>g about action from reason. 11 In tak<strong>in</strong>g this further, it isnecessary to supplement Ebel<strong>in</strong>g’s <strong>in</strong>itial account through referenceto Mises’s notion <strong>of</strong> ‘sett<strong>in</strong>g aims’. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Mises:Praxeology does not deal with technological problems, butwith the categorical essence <strong>of</strong> choice <strong>and</strong> action as such, withthe pure element <strong>of</strong> sett<strong>in</strong>g aims <strong>and</strong> apply<strong>in</strong>g means….Praxeology deals with choice <strong>and</strong> action <strong>and</strong> with theiroutcome.(Mises 1990:21)The reference to ‘sett<strong>in</strong>g aims’, <strong>and</strong> the acknowledgement thataction is purposive, allows the idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentionality to be<strong>in</strong>troduced. Thus, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Mises, action consists <strong>in</strong> desir<strong>in</strong>gsome preferred state <strong>of</strong> affairs to those perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g at present,believ<strong>in</strong>g that certa<strong>in</strong> actions would lead to this preferred state <strong>of</strong>affairs, aim<strong>in</strong>g (or <strong>in</strong>tend<strong>in</strong>g) to br<strong>in</strong>g about this state <strong>of</strong> affairs, <strong>and</strong>consequently perform<strong>in</strong>g the required action. 12 Mises’s theory thusshares the follow<strong>in</strong>g assumptions with many theories <strong>of</strong> action,<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g rational choice theories (Bratman 1987):1 the methodological priority <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tention <strong>in</strong> action;2 the desire-belief theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tention <strong>in</strong> action. That is, theassumption that we underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentional action, <strong>and</strong> actiondone with an <strong>in</strong>tention, <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> an agent’s desires <strong>and</strong> beliefs,where actions st<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> appropriate relations to those desires <strong>and</strong>beliefs;3 the strategy <strong>of</strong> extension. The assumption that once we have anadequate account <strong>of</strong> act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tentionally <strong>and</strong> act<strong>in</strong>g with an45


STEPHEN D.PARSONS<strong>in</strong>tention we have all the necessary materials for a satisfactorytreatment <strong>of</strong> future-directed <strong>in</strong>tentions;4 comb<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g 2 <strong>and</strong> 3 above: the reduction <strong>of</strong> future-directed<strong>in</strong>tentions to appropriate desires <strong>and</strong> beliefs.It has been argued above that assumption 2 raises problems forMises’s own theory. However, assumptions 3 <strong>and</strong> 4 also raiseproblems, a possible resolution <strong>of</strong> which leads directly <strong>in</strong>toLachmann’s theory <strong>of</strong> human action.Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Bratman (1987), the attempt to extend an<strong>in</strong>tentional account <strong>of</strong> action to deal with future-directed casesresults <strong>in</strong> two problems. The first problem is analogous to theproblem encountered by Buridan’s ass. Bratman argues that rational<strong>in</strong>tentions should be agglomerate. That is, if at one <strong>and</strong> the sametime I rationally <strong>in</strong>tend, or aim, to A <strong>and</strong> rationally <strong>in</strong>tend, or aim,to B then it should be both possible <strong>and</strong> rational for me, at the sametime, to <strong>in</strong>tend or aim to A <strong>and</strong> to B. Thus, if two actions are knownto be compatible, I can have the <strong>in</strong>tention or aim to perform both, aswell as the separate <strong>in</strong>tention or aim to perform each. Also, if twoactions are known to be <strong>in</strong>compatible, I cannot have the <strong>in</strong>tention oraim to perform both. However, suppose, on my way back fromwork one even<strong>in</strong>g, I can stop at either <strong>of</strong> two book shops, but not atboth, <strong>and</strong> that both options are attractive. That is, I form an all-outjudgement that stopp<strong>in</strong>g at one is as desirable as stopp<strong>in</strong>g at theother. In this case, do I have both <strong>in</strong>tentions or aims, or do I haveneither <strong>in</strong>tention nor aim?The second problem can be illustrated as follows. Suppose I wantto buy copies <strong>of</strong> two books, <strong>and</strong> I know I will be <strong>in</strong> a certa<strong>in</strong>bookstore. Further, I know that the bookstore will have one <strong>of</strong> thebooks, but not both, <strong>and</strong> do not know which one. In this case,although I <strong>in</strong>tend or have an aim to buy both books, I believe Icannot. However, as I cannot <strong>in</strong>tend or aim to do what I do notbelieve, then I cannot have the required <strong>in</strong>tention or aim.Bratman argues the problems with theories shar<strong>in</strong>g the aboveassumptions is that they do not recognise that we form future<strong>in</strong>tentions as parts <strong>of</strong> larger plans whose role is to aid the coord<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>of</strong> activities over time. Consequently, Bratman arguesthat the desire/belief/reason model can only have relevance if it issituated with<strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> plans. Practical reason thus has twolevels. On one level there are prior <strong>in</strong>tentions <strong>and</strong> plans, which bothpose problems <strong>and</strong> provide filters on options as potential solutions.On another level are desires, beliefs <strong>and</strong> reasons, which enter as46


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONconsiderations to be weighed <strong>in</strong> deliberat<strong>in</strong>g between relevant <strong>and</strong>admissible options.If future <strong>in</strong>tentions are necessary <strong>and</strong> sufficient conditions <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>tentional action, yet such <strong>in</strong>tentions are only <strong>in</strong>telligible with<strong>in</strong> thecontext <strong>of</strong> plans, then there would appear to be good reasons as towhy Lachmann’s account <strong>of</strong> human action appears preferable tothat <strong>of</strong>fered by Mises. In defence <strong>of</strong> this, it seems quite plausible toargue that correctly follow<strong>in</strong>g a future <strong>in</strong>tention is a sufficientcondition <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentional action, <strong>in</strong> the sense that if someone has afuture <strong>in</strong>tention <strong>and</strong> correctly follows it <strong>in</strong> behav<strong>in</strong>g, then thisbehaviour is an <strong>in</strong>tentional action <strong>of</strong> theirs (Moya 1990). However,establish<strong>in</strong>g future <strong>in</strong>tentions as a necessary condition <strong>of</strong> fully<strong>in</strong>tentional action is more difficult. The problem here concernswhether there are <strong>in</strong>tentional actions which are not <strong>in</strong>tended. Ifthere are such actions, then future <strong>in</strong>tentions are not necessaryconditions <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentional action.The follow<strong>in</strong>g example, aga<strong>in</strong> drawn from Bratman, reveals theproblem. Suppose dur<strong>in</strong>g a war a comm<strong>and</strong>er encounters a villagethat is full <strong>of</strong> both enemy soldiers <strong>and</strong> civilians. The comm<strong>and</strong>erweighs his options, <strong>and</strong> considers that bomb<strong>in</strong>g the village <strong>in</strong> orderto kill the enemy soldiers is a viable option, even though it will<strong>in</strong>volve the kill<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>nocent civilians, which the comm<strong>and</strong>er verymuch regrets. If the bomb<strong>in</strong>g takes place, it is <strong>in</strong>tentional underthree descriptions—(i) bomb<strong>in</strong>g the village; (ii) kill<strong>in</strong>g enemysoldiers; (iii) kill<strong>in</strong>g many <strong>in</strong>nocent civilians. However, although theaction is <strong>in</strong>tentional under these three descriptions, it is only<strong>in</strong>tended under the first two. It is necessary to make this dist<strong>in</strong>ctionto differentiate this act from one where the comm<strong>and</strong>er may want tokill the civilians, <strong>and</strong> thus, <strong>in</strong> bomb<strong>in</strong>g the village, <strong>in</strong>tends to do justthat. However, if the action <strong>of</strong> kill<strong>in</strong>g civilians is <strong>in</strong>tentional,although not <strong>in</strong>tended, then a future <strong>in</strong>tention is not a necessarycondition <strong>of</strong> fully <strong>in</strong>tentional action.However, two po<strong>in</strong>ts are relevant. First, it has been argued thatthis problem is not as <strong>in</strong>tractable as it may <strong>in</strong>itially appear (see Moya1990). Second, it would also appear to raise problems for Mises’saccount <strong>of</strong> human action. This is because, to adopt Mises s preferredterm<strong>in</strong>ology, the action detailed above is describable as purposiveunder three descriptions, yet only as aim-directed under the first two.However, it would seem that Mises regards all purposive behaviouras aim-directed, or as orientated towards ends. Therefore, if thereare <strong>in</strong>tentional actions that are not <strong>in</strong>tended, or purposive actionsthat are not orientated towards ends, these raise at least as many47


STEPHEN D.PARSONSproblems for Mises’s account as for Bratman’s. Consequently, adefence <strong>of</strong> Mises could not appeal to such action <strong>in</strong> order to rebutBratman’s argument that an adequate account <strong>of</strong> human action musttake account <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual plans. Given this, Lachmann’s own account<strong>of</strong> human action requires <strong>in</strong>vestigat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> more detail.Lachmann on human actionLachmann’s notion <strong>of</strong> a plan allows him to br<strong>in</strong>g the relationshipbetween the method <strong>of</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, action <strong>and</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g togetheras follows:All human action, if it is to be successful, requires a plan toguide it. To underst<strong>and</strong> an action means to underst<strong>and</strong> theplan which is be<strong>in</strong>g carried out here <strong>and</strong> now…all actionderives its mean<strong>in</strong>g from the plan which guides it.(Lachmann 1971:12)The plans that actions derive their mean<strong>in</strong>g from have severalcharacteristics. First, as Mises also recognised, <strong>in</strong>dividuals maydesire to pursue a number <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>compatible ends. Lachmann’sargument here is that it is precisely through a plan that agents areable to establish some priority amongst these ends: In fact, “plan” isbut a generalization <strong>of</strong> purpose. In reality actors, <strong>in</strong>dividuals as wellas groups, pursue many purposes simultaneously <strong>and</strong> have toestablish an order <strong>of</strong> priority amongst them’ (Lachmann 1971:33).This is strongly rem<strong>in</strong>iscent <strong>of</strong> Bratman’s argument, noted earlier,that plans act as ‘filters’. For Lachmann, <strong>in</strong> so far as plans allowpurposes to be ordered, they also enable a ‘comprehensive survey <strong>of</strong>means’ (Lachmann 1971:30) to be undertaken, <strong>and</strong> thus allow acoherent arrangement <strong>of</strong> means <strong>and</strong> ends to be formulated. It is thetask <strong>of</strong> the social scientist to underst<strong>and</strong> this coherence. Therefore,as noted previously, the historian:Must ask how far the variety <strong>of</strong> purposes pursued by the<strong>in</strong>dividual whose action he studies…‘fitted together’. He hasto ascerta<strong>in</strong> ‘The Plan’, the coherent design beh<strong>in</strong>d theobservable action <strong>in</strong> which the various purposes as well as themeans employed are bound together.(ibid.: 20)As situat<strong>in</strong>g means <strong>and</strong> ends with<strong>in</strong> a coherent whole, plans<strong>in</strong>troduce a certa<strong>in</strong> stability <strong>in</strong>to human action:48


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONHuman action is not determ<strong>in</strong>ate, but neither is it arbitrary. Itis bounded…by the circumstances that, while men are free tochoose ends they pursue, once they have made their choicethey must adhere to it if consistent action with a chance <strong>of</strong>success is to be possible at all.(ibid.: 37)Plans thus do not merely arrange means <strong>and</strong> ends coherently, theyentail a certa<strong>in</strong> commitment. Once an <strong>in</strong>dividual is committed to acerta<strong>in</strong> plan, then this plan is adhered to. Consequently, with hisnotion <strong>of</strong> a plan, Lachmann can expla<strong>in</strong> how future-directed<strong>in</strong>tentions play a role <strong>in</strong> the period between the <strong>in</strong>itial formation <strong>of</strong>any plan <strong>and</strong> its eventual execution:The fact…that human action exists <strong>in</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> plans, i.e.mental design, before it is carried out <strong>in</strong> time <strong>and</strong> space,permits us to study the relationship between human action<strong>and</strong> the plans which guide it.(ibid.: 30)Of course, the commitment entailed <strong>in</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g a plan does notmean that plans cannot be modified or even ab<strong>and</strong>oned. As plansmay require revision <strong>in</strong> the light <strong>of</strong> new knowledge, they must beflexible:Every plan <strong>of</strong> course has to be flexible to succeed. The need forflexibility partly stems from the fact that some <strong>of</strong> theknowledge relevant to the action will only be acquired <strong>in</strong>agendo, i.e. after the plan has been drawn up <strong>and</strong> the course <strong>of</strong>action started.(ibid.: 40)Plans thus enable the provision <strong>of</strong> coherence amongst actions, entailcommitment, <strong>in</strong>corporate the significance <strong>of</strong> future <strong>in</strong>tentions <strong>and</strong>require flexibility. Lachmann thus argues that his analysis <strong>of</strong> thesignificance <strong>of</strong> plans allows human action to be <strong>in</strong>vestigated <strong>in</strong> thespirit <strong>of</strong> Weber’s analysis:In social theory our ma<strong>in</strong> task is to expla<strong>in</strong> observablesocial phenomena by reduc<strong>in</strong>g them to the <strong>in</strong>dividual plans(their elements, their shape <strong>and</strong> design) that typically giverise to them. This is what Weber meant by the explanation49


STEPHEN D.PARSONS<strong>of</strong> action ‘<strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g attached to it by theactor’.(Lachmann 1971:31)Lachmann takes this Weberian legacy seriously: the notion <strong>of</strong> a planprovides ‘a firmer <strong>and</strong> more convenient start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t for themethodology <strong>of</strong> the social sciences than the controversial notion <strong>of</strong>the Ideal Type’ (ibid.: 33). Lachmann thus appears to acceptSchutz’s (1972) criticism <strong>of</strong> Weber’s ‘ideal type’. For Weber, the‘ideal types’ were both methodological constructs that permitted thesocial scientist to <strong>in</strong>vestigate social life <strong>and</strong> yet were themselvesgenerated <strong>in</strong> social life. However, as Schutz noted, if ‘ideal types’were generated <strong>in</strong> everyday social life, then the social scientist hadno privileged access to them. Lachmann also <strong>in</strong>tends his ‘plan’ tosignify a phenomenon generated by <strong>in</strong>dividual actors themselves(Lachmann 1971:29).However, although Lachmann’s explanation <strong>of</strong> human actioncan consequently be read as an advance upon, <strong>and</strong> improvement <strong>of</strong>,Mises’s own account, it generates certa<strong>in</strong> problems <strong>of</strong> its own. Inattempt<strong>in</strong>g to extend Weber’s own analysis, Lachmannacknowledges that Weber identified purposes as causes <strong>of</strong> action.Lachmann situates this concern for a causal explanation with<strong>in</strong> hisexploration <strong>of</strong> the significance <strong>of</strong> plans as follows:It is readily seen (with the benefit <strong>of</strong> h<strong>in</strong>dsight) that thisconception <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> causal explanation <strong>of</strong> humanaction <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> purposes would have provided a firmer <strong>and</strong>more convenient start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t for the methodology <strong>of</strong> thesocial sciences than the controversial notion <strong>of</strong> the Ideal Type.It is also easy to see how it is naturally l<strong>in</strong>ked to our concept <strong>of</strong>Plan. In fact, ‘plan’ is but a generalization <strong>of</strong> purpose.(Lachmann 1971:33)However, Lachmann appears to be unaware <strong>of</strong> the extent to whichhis <strong>in</strong>corporation <strong>of</strong> the ‘plan’ <strong>in</strong>to the <strong>in</strong>vestigation seriouslydisrupts the possibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g causal explanation <strong>in</strong> therequired form. Lachmann argues that the coherence <strong>of</strong> any plan canbe tested on two levels:1 whether the purposes he ascribes are <strong>in</strong> fact consistent with oneanother <strong>and</strong> fit <strong>in</strong>to the framework <strong>of</strong> a general plan, theexecution <strong>of</strong> which would account for the known facts;50


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTION2 whether the design <strong>and</strong> execution <strong>of</strong> such a plan are <strong>in</strong> factconsistent with whatever else is known about the <strong>in</strong>tentions,circumstances, etc. <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dividual whose action is the subjectunder study (ibid.: 20).However, Lachmann does not appear to acknowledge the differencebetween follow<strong>in</strong>g a plan <strong>and</strong> act<strong>in</strong>g accord<strong>in</strong>g to a plan (Br<strong>and</strong>1984). An <strong>in</strong>dividual may have a consistent plan, <strong>and</strong> the execution<strong>of</strong> this plan may ‘account for the known facts’, but this does notentail that the <strong>in</strong>dividual is follow<strong>in</strong>g the plan correctly. Forexample, an <strong>in</strong>dividual may be presented with a complicatedmathematical puzzle, may <strong>in</strong>dicate what plan they will pursue <strong>in</strong>attempt<strong>in</strong>g to arrive at a solution, may arrive at the correct solution,yet may not have followed the plan correctly. That is, the <strong>in</strong>dividualmay have made mistakes, yet arrived at the correct conclusion.Consequently, even if we know what an <strong>in</strong>dividual’s plan is, <strong>and</strong>know that this is coherent, <strong>and</strong> can expla<strong>in</strong> the ‘known facts’ withthis plan, we cannot conclude that, therefore, there is some form <strong>of</strong>causal relationship between the plan <strong>and</strong> the ‘known facts’. We needto know that the plan has been followed correctly, <strong>and</strong> this<strong>in</strong>evitably <strong>in</strong>troduces a normative element <strong>in</strong>to the <strong>in</strong>vestigation: weneed to establish how the <strong>in</strong>dividual ought to have acted, not justhow he or she did act.The question <strong>of</strong> the relationship between Lachmann’s ownanalysis <strong>and</strong> that provided by Weber raises further problems for theformer’s account. In connection with the question <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g,Lachmann notes that ‘natural phenomena have no “mean<strong>in</strong>g”’, <strong>and</strong>thus sides with Weber aga<strong>in</strong>st Menger: there are no ‘exact laws’govern<strong>in</strong>g economic conduct analogous to those found <strong>in</strong> nature. 13As the study <strong>of</strong> economic conduct requires the underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>mean<strong>in</strong>g, then it is committed to the ‘method <strong>of</strong> Verstehen’.Lachmann consequently describes his own theory <strong>of</strong> action as‘<strong>in</strong>spired by the Weberian notion that action derives its mean<strong>in</strong>gfrom the m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> the actor’ (Lachmann 1971:9).However, from Weber’s perspective, there is a problem with thisargument. For Weber, reference to the <strong>in</strong>dividual m<strong>in</strong>d is neithernecessary nor sufficient for underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>g:The ‘conscious motives’ may well, even to the actor himself,conceal the various ‘motives’ <strong>and</strong> ‘repressions’ whichconstitute the real driv<strong>in</strong>g force <strong>of</strong> his action. Thus <strong>in</strong> suchcases even subjectively honest self-analysis has only a relative51


STEPHEN D.PARSONSvalue. Then it is the task <strong>of</strong> the sociologist to be aware <strong>of</strong> thismotivational situation <strong>and</strong> to describe <strong>and</strong> analyse it, eventhough it has not actually been concretely part <strong>of</strong> theconscious <strong>in</strong>tention <strong>of</strong> the actor.(Weber 1978:9–10)Weber’s reference to the ‘motivational situation’ does not appear tobe recognised <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’s account. In Weber’s analysis,underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g the subjective, or <strong>in</strong>tended mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> any actionrequires a reference to the context, which Weber callsS<strong>in</strong>nzusammenhang. This is usually translated as ‘mean<strong>in</strong>gcomplex’ or ‘context <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g’. For example, Weber argues that‘we underst<strong>and</strong> the motive <strong>of</strong> a person aim<strong>in</strong>g a gun if we know thathe has been comm<strong>and</strong>ed to shoot as a member <strong>of</strong> a fir<strong>in</strong>g squad, thathe is fight<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st an enemy, or that he is do<strong>in</strong>g it for revenge’(Weber 1978:9). We may know the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> any action when weknow the <strong>in</strong>tention it was performed with, but this does not reducemean<strong>in</strong>g to a solely mental product:For a science which is concerned with the subjective mean<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> action, explanation requires a grasp <strong>of</strong> the complex <strong>of</strong>mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> which an actual course <strong>of</strong> underst<strong>and</strong>able actionthus <strong>in</strong>terpreted belongs. In all such cases, even where theprocesses are largely affectual, the subjective mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> theaction, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g that also <strong>of</strong> the relevant mean<strong>in</strong>gcomplexes (S<strong>in</strong>nzusammenhang), will be called the <strong>in</strong>tendedmean<strong>in</strong>g.(ibid.)Lachmann’s <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> Weber is perhaps underst<strong>and</strong>able,given the argument that Weber’s methodological pronouncementstend to reduce the emphasis on ‘mean<strong>in</strong>g complexes’: ‘Weber paidconsiderable attention to the way <strong>in</strong>dividual motivation wasembedded <strong>in</strong> larger complexes <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> it was only that hisvital methodological statements appeared to give less weight to thisvital element <strong>in</strong> his work’ (Albrow 1990:127).However, even if Lachmann’s <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> Weber isunderst<strong>and</strong>able, it is unfortunate. In attend<strong>in</strong>g solely to the<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> the ‘m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> the actor’,Lachmann <strong>in</strong>vites the follow<strong>in</strong>g comparison with textualanalysis:52


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONWhenever one is <strong>in</strong> doubt about the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a passage onetries to establish what the author ‘meant by it’, i.e. to whatideas he attempted to give expression when he wrote it…. It isevidently possible to extend this classical method <strong>of</strong>scholarship to human acts other than writ<strong>in</strong>gs.(Lachmann 1971:10)Lachmann’s explorations <strong>of</strong> the underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g thus beara strong psychological impr<strong>in</strong>t—it is a matter <strong>of</strong> discover<strong>in</strong>g whatlies <strong>in</strong> the m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> the other. However, as Gadamer notes,psychological underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the act <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation‘presuppose that only a m<strong>in</strong>d on the same level can underst<strong>and</strong>another m<strong>in</strong>d’ (Gadamer 1979:466). Lachmann’s account <strong>of</strong>underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g mean<strong>in</strong>g has unfortunate consequences for hisunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the relevance <strong>of</strong> plans.Lachmann wants to cont<strong>in</strong>ue what he identifies as the Austriantradition’s emphasis on subjectivism. Consequently, accord<strong>in</strong>g toLachmann, even given the same ‘objective’ situation, different<strong>in</strong>dividuals will respond differently because they regard thesituation with ‘different eyes’ (1971:11). In l<strong>in</strong>e with the possibility<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>corporat<strong>in</strong>g future <strong>in</strong>tentions with<strong>in</strong> his analysis, Lachmanngives this observation a temporal slant: any attempt to underst<strong>and</strong>human action must take account <strong>of</strong> differences <strong>in</strong> perceptions <strong>of</strong> thefuture, <strong>and</strong> thus ‘to underst<strong>and</strong> it (human action) we have tounderst<strong>and</strong> what image <strong>of</strong> the future the actors are bear<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> theirm<strong>in</strong>ds’ (ibid.).However, <strong>in</strong> flesh<strong>in</strong>g out this observation about the relevance <strong>of</strong>images <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> plans, Lachmann also acknowledges that planscan only be formulated <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> what he terms‘<strong>in</strong>stitutions’:Human action <strong>in</strong> society is <strong>in</strong>teraction. Each plan must takeaccount <strong>of</strong>, among many other facts, favourable <strong>and</strong>unfavourable, the plans <strong>of</strong> other actors. But these cannot beknown to the planner. Institutions serve as orientation mapsconcern<strong>in</strong>g future actions <strong>of</strong> the anonymous mass <strong>of</strong> actors.(Lachmann 1971:12–13)However, if <strong>in</strong>stitutions serve as ‘orientation maps’, then unless any<strong>in</strong>dividual is conscious, at the time <strong>of</strong> formulat<strong>in</strong>g plans, <strong>of</strong> thecomplete <strong>in</strong>stitutional context with<strong>in</strong> which these plans areformulated, then the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> action cannot be deduced solely53


STEPHEN D.PARSONSfrom the contents <strong>of</strong> consciousness. Lachmann’s problem heresurfaces <strong>in</strong> an ambiguity concern<strong>in</strong>g the notion <strong>of</strong> ‘orientation’. Inthe above, <strong>in</strong>stitutions serve as ‘orientation maps’ which,presumably, must be taken account <strong>of</strong> by any <strong>in</strong>dividual whenformulat<strong>in</strong>g a plan. However, Lachmann also argues that:‘Orientation entails plan. A plan has to conta<strong>in</strong> a comprehensiveaccount <strong>of</strong> ends, means, <strong>and</strong> obstacles to which a course <strong>of</strong> action isorientated’ (ibid.: 38).This appears to suggest that orientation is only possible through,<strong>and</strong> because <strong>of</strong>, the formation <strong>of</strong> a plan. ‘Plann<strong>in</strong>g’ thus allowsorientation to ends, means <strong>and</strong> obstacles to occur:What we may hope to accomplish here is to be able to show towhat ends, means, <strong>and</strong> obstacles human action is orientated.Orientation thus emerges as a concept as fundamental topraxeological study as determ<strong>in</strong>ateness to natural science.(ibid.: 37)However, if a plan provides a form <strong>of</strong> horizon that enables anorientation to means, ends <strong>and</strong> obstacles, how do we first becomeaware <strong>of</strong>, <strong>and</strong> thus orientate ourselves towards, certa<strong>in</strong> possibleends, means, <strong>and</strong> obstacles? Lachmann appears to neglect theconsideration <strong>of</strong> the context with<strong>in</strong> which plans are formulated.Aga<strong>in</strong>, this can be contrasted to Weber:Weber differentiates the concept <strong>of</strong> practical rationality fromthe three perspectives <strong>of</strong> employ<strong>in</strong>g means, sett<strong>in</strong>g ends, <strong>and</strong>be<strong>in</strong>g orientated to values. The <strong>in</strong>strumental rationality <strong>of</strong> anaction is measured by effective plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the application <strong>of</strong>means for given ends; the rationality <strong>of</strong> choice <strong>of</strong> an action ismeasured by the correctness <strong>of</strong> the calculation <strong>of</strong> ends <strong>in</strong> thelight <strong>of</strong> precisely conceived values, available means, <strong>and</strong>boundary conditions; <strong>and</strong> the normative rationality <strong>of</strong> anaction is measured by the unify<strong>in</strong>g, systematiz<strong>in</strong>g power <strong>and</strong>penetration <strong>of</strong> the value st<strong>and</strong>ards <strong>and</strong> the pr<strong>in</strong>ciples thatunderlie action preferences.(Habermas 1984:172)It is some underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> what is here referred to as the‘orientation to values’ that appears miss<strong>in</strong>g from Lachmann’saccount. Consequently, a hiatus between the <strong>in</strong>dividual actor <strong>and</strong>the <strong>in</strong>stitutional context with<strong>in</strong> which plans are formulated appears.54


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONThis is significant <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> Austrian theory, becauseLachmann is consequently unable to l<strong>in</strong>k the methods <strong>of</strong> thehistorian with those <strong>of</strong> the social scientist, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the economist.At one level, Lachmann attempts to forge this l<strong>in</strong>k by argu<strong>in</strong>g thatplans are ‘observable’:To underst<strong>and</strong> an action means to underst<strong>and</strong> the plan whichis be<strong>in</strong>g carried out here <strong>and</strong> now. A phenomenon <strong>of</strong> humanaction is an observable event; so, <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple, is the mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>plans.…Plans, strategic, economic or otherwise, areobservable events.(Lachmann 1971:12)However, even if <strong>in</strong>dividual actions are observable events, themak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual plans is not necessarily so. Further, given thedist<strong>in</strong>ction between follow<strong>in</strong>g a plan <strong>and</strong> act<strong>in</strong>g accord<strong>in</strong>g to a plan,we cannot deduce the nature <strong>of</strong> a plan be<strong>in</strong>g followed from resultantactions. Consequently, Lachmann is forced to admit there exists anapparently unbridgeable gulf between the respective methods <strong>of</strong> thehistorian <strong>and</strong> the social scientist:There seems to be no reason why a method which is useful <strong>in</strong>the explanation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual action should be less so <strong>in</strong> theexplanation <strong>of</strong> classes <strong>of</strong> such actions…. It is true that <strong>in</strong>expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g recurrent patterns <strong>of</strong> action, the essential subjectmatter<strong>of</strong> all social sciences, we cannot provide suchexplanation <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> purposes, as elements <strong>of</strong> plans,because the purposes pursued by millions <strong>of</strong> people are <strong>of</strong>course numbered <strong>in</strong> millions. But <strong>of</strong>ten we are none the lessable to provide explanations <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> the elements commonto all these plans, such as norms, <strong>in</strong>stitutions, <strong>and</strong> sometimes<strong>in</strong>stitutionalized behaviour.…As long as we are able toaccount for the recurrence <strong>of</strong> patterns <strong>of</strong> action <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong>such elements <strong>of</strong> plans, we are successfully employ<strong>in</strong>g theclassical method <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation.(Lachmann 1971:22–3)Although Lachmann commences his argument by stat<strong>in</strong>g that themethods <strong>of</strong> the historian are equally applicable to the socialscientist, he is forced to admit that the social scientist is <strong>in</strong>terestednot <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual plans as such, but <strong>in</strong> the ‘elements common to allthese plans’. Because Lachmann has not <strong>in</strong>corporated norms, from55


STEPHEN D.PARSONSthe start, <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> the sett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual plans, we are leftwith a gulf between the methods <strong>of</strong> the historian <strong>and</strong> the socialscientist, between the <strong>in</strong>dividual actor <strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>of</strong> society.Lachmann starts from the <strong>in</strong>dividual, <strong>in</strong> keep<strong>in</strong>g with his desire toma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> the Austrian emphasis on subjectivism, <strong>and</strong> then attemptsto <strong>in</strong>corporate <strong>in</strong>stitutions with<strong>in</strong> an account that is conceived, fromthe start, <strong>in</strong>dividualistically.In his later work, Lachmann modifies his analysis to take account<strong>of</strong> the context with<strong>in</strong> which human action occurs:Most economic phenomena are observable, but ourobservations need an <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> their context if they areto make sense <strong>and</strong> add to our knowledge. Only mean<strong>in</strong>gfulutterances <strong>of</strong> a m<strong>in</strong>d lend themselves to <strong>in</strong>terpretation.Furthermore, all human action takes place with<strong>in</strong> a context <strong>of</strong>‘<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity’; our common everyday world (the Schutzian‘life-world’) <strong>in</strong> which the mean<strong>in</strong>gs we ascribe to our own acts<strong>and</strong> those <strong>of</strong> others are typically not <strong>in</strong> doubt <strong>and</strong> taken forgranted.(Lachmann 1990:138)However, if <strong>in</strong>terpretations are ‘context dependent’, <strong>and</strong> yet thesecontexts are ‘taken for granted’, then they are not necessarilyaccessible to <strong>in</strong>dividual consciousness. Consequently, <strong>in</strong> situat<strong>in</strong>g‘mean<strong>in</strong>gs’ with<strong>in</strong> a context which may simply be ‘taken forgranted’ by the author, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> engag<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> acts <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretationfrom with<strong>in</strong> our own ‘taken for grantedness’, any act <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>terpretation necessarily transcends the self-underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> theauthor. 14ConclusionLachmann s analysis <strong>of</strong> the relevance <strong>of</strong> ‘a Plan’ <strong>in</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>ghuman action allows for a resolution <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> the problems fac<strong>in</strong>gMises’s account <strong>of</strong> human action. In his later work, Lachmannacknowledges that these plans are formulated with<strong>in</strong> a ‘context <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>tersubjective mean<strong>in</strong>gs’ (Lachmann 1990:139). If this is the case,then the <strong>in</strong>stitutional context with<strong>in</strong> which plans are formulated isrelevant on two levels. First, it must be taken <strong>in</strong>to account, even ifonly implicitly, by <strong>in</strong>dividual actors. Second, it must be taken <strong>in</strong>toaccount <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g human action.However, this argument raises a number <strong>of</strong> problems for56


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONAustrian economics. If human actions can only be understoodwith<strong>in</strong> a context, then any claim that certa<strong>in</strong> truths concern<strong>in</strong>ghuman action can be arrived at deductively is simply wrong.Further, if emphasis is now placed on the <strong>in</strong>tersubjective contextwith<strong>in</strong> which any human action occurs, then the much vaunted‘subjectivism’ <strong>of</strong> Austrian economics would seem to becompromised. The Cartesian privileg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> ‘the subject’ fits ratheruneasily, if at all, with<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectual traditions stress<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity. 15 These are major issues that clearly warrant moredetailed exam<strong>in</strong>ation. However, it is difficult to appreciate how‘Austrian economies’ can avoid confront<strong>in</strong>g them. Unless thedifficulties <strong>in</strong> Mises’s project can be resolved <strong>in</strong> an alternativemanner, then, despite the possibility <strong>of</strong> defend<strong>in</strong>g a weak notion <strong>of</strong>‘the a priori’, Lachmann’s analysis would seem to form a viablestart<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t for any Austrian discussion <strong>of</strong> human action.Notes1 As Ebel<strong>in</strong>g observes ‘but Mises believed that Weber had rema<strong>in</strong>ed toomuch the child <strong>of</strong> the German Historical School, with its theoreticalrelativism’ (Ebel<strong>in</strong>g 1994:86).2 Lachmann himself does not explore how his theory differs fromrational choice theory.3 In a recent collection <strong>of</strong> essays devoted to Austrian economics (Boettke<strong>and</strong> Prychitko 1994), several authors refer to ‘plans’. However, theredoes not appear to be any awareness that this emphasis raisesquestions for rational choice theories.4 Rickert was a lead<strong>in</strong>g Neo-Kantian philosopher. For a more detaileddiscussion <strong>of</strong> Mises’s relationship to Rickert, see Parsons (1990).5 Rickert’s reference to the irrationality <strong>of</strong> reality was meantphenomenologically: it referred to our experience <strong>of</strong> reality. As notedbelow, Mises tends to confuse phenomenological <strong>and</strong> epistemologicalquestions.6 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Mises, historical concepts are type concepts, or ‘idealtypes’,which organise data <strong>in</strong>to classes. As such, they are ‘<strong>in</strong>exact’ <strong>in</strong>the sense that, as mental constructs, they simplify reality. To useMises’s own example, the type concept ‘entrepreneur’ refers to a class<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals engaged <strong>in</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess who, <strong>in</strong> other regards, differgreatly. In contrast, <strong>in</strong> economics, the concept ‘entrepreneur’ refers toa ‘specific function, that is the provision for an uncerta<strong>in</strong> future. Inthis respect everybody is an entrepreneur…it is not the task <strong>of</strong> thisclassification <strong>in</strong> economic theory to dist<strong>in</strong>guish men, but todist<strong>in</strong>guish functions’ (Mises 1990:14). Aga<strong>in</strong>, as economics is notconcerned with <strong>in</strong>dividuality, it does not matter that all <strong>in</strong>dividualsare not only entrepreneurs, or that they perform this function <strong>in</strong>different ways.57


STEPHEN D.PARSONS7 For a defence <strong>of</strong> Mises’s argument concern<strong>in</strong>g the a priori status <strong>of</strong> thecategory <strong>of</strong> causality along Kantian l<strong>in</strong>es, see Parsons (1997).8 Boettke <strong>and</strong> Prychitko argue that a formal, deductive theory is one <strong>of</strong>the def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g characteristics <strong>of</strong> Austrian theory, stat<strong>in</strong>g thatpraxeology is:a strictly formal, logically deductive approach that starts fromallegedly self-evident axioms (such as the claim that <strong>in</strong>dividualsact purposively), <strong>and</strong> attempts to derive apodictically certa<strong>in</strong>(logically irrefutable) conclusions…a praxeological economictheory which is grounded upon an absolutely true axiom (or set<strong>of</strong> axioms) generates absolutely true conclusions.(Boettke <strong>and</strong> Prychitko 1994:288–9)I have argued that a dist<strong>in</strong>ction must be made between any a prioriconcepts relevant to comprehend<strong>in</strong>g human action <strong>and</strong> the axioms <strong>of</strong>marg<strong>in</strong>al analysis. If a formal deductive approach is a def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>gcharacteristic <strong>of</strong> Austrian theory, then this approach requiresconsiderably more defence.9 This is also the view espoused by Bhaskar: ‘Aristotle was correct: theconclusion <strong>of</strong> a practical syllogism is an action’ (Bhaskar 1979:122).10 This discussion <strong>of</strong> the problem with the Aristotelian syllogism <strong>and</strong>subsequent attempt at modification reflect the problems that Davidson(1980) came to recognise with his own account <strong>of</strong> human action.Initially, Davidson characterised <strong>in</strong>tentional action as actionexplicable, <strong>in</strong> appropriate ways, by appeal<strong>in</strong>g to the agents’ reasons foract<strong>in</strong>g, where these reasons are appropriate pairs <strong>of</strong> agents’ desires <strong>and</strong>beliefs. Consequently, <strong>in</strong> act<strong>in</strong>g for a reason, there is an appropriatedesire-belief pair that causes the action—hence, the practical syllogism.For an attempt to <strong>in</strong>troduce a causal theory <strong>of</strong> action <strong>in</strong>to Austrianconcerns, see Mäki (1990). Unfortunately, <strong>and</strong> somewhat surpris<strong>in</strong>gly,Mäki does not discuss Davidson.11 At issue here is not only Mises’s claim that ‘what we know about ouraction under given conditions is derived not from experience, but fromreason’ (Mises 1981:13–14), but also his claim that ‘economics toocan make predictions <strong>in</strong> the sense <strong>in</strong> which this ability is attributed tothe natural sciences’ (ibid.: 118). If desires or preferences are<strong>in</strong>compatible, or there is <strong>in</strong>difference between means, then predictionsare not possible.12 The <strong>in</strong>troduction <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentionality does not remove the problemsdiscussed above.13Weber denied Menger’s contention that the ‘laws’ govern<strong>in</strong>geconomic conduct (among which was Menger’s own creation,the law <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al utility) are ‘exact laws’ <strong>in</strong> the same sense asthose found <strong>in</strong> nature.…In fact, abstract economic theoryconsisted essentially <strong>of</strong> rational schemes <strong>in</strong> which the conditions<strong>of</strong> successful action were def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> such a way as to require58


MISES AND LACHMANN ON HUMAN ACTIONcerta<strong>in</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> action. This is someth<strong>in</strong>g very different from theway <strong>in</strong> which natural events are ‘determ<strong>in</strong>ed’ by their causes.(Lachmann 1971:25–6)14 This is the argument advanced by Gadamer (1979). To put thisargument <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’s terms: any act <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation makes usaware <strong>of</strong> elements <strong>of</strong> both our own ‘taken for grantedness’ <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong>the author.15 Husserl encountered severe problems <strong>in</strong> attempt<strong>in</strong>g to reta<strong>in</strong> aCartesian subject <strong>and</strong> yet emphasise the importance <strong>of</strong> ‘the lifeworld’.If the notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity is <strong>and</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g isfleshed out <strong>in</strong> either Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>ian or Heideggerian terms, then any‘subjectivism’ is seriously curtailed.ReferencesAlbrow, M. (1990) Max Weber’s Construction <strong>of</strong> Social Theory,Bas<strong>in</strong>gstoke: Macmillan.Bhaskar, R. (1979) The Possibility <strong>of</strong> Naturalism, Brighton: Harvester.Boettke, P.J. <strong>and</strong> Prychitko, D.L. (1994) ‘The future <strong>of</strong> Austrianeconomies’, <strong>in</strong> P.J.Boettke <strong>and</strong> D.L.Prychitko (eds) The MarketProcess:<strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> Contemporary Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s , Aldershot: EdwardElgar.Br<strong>and</strong>, M. (1984) Intend<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> Act<strong>in</strong>g: A Naturalized Action Theory,Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Bratman, M.E. (1985) ‘Davidson’s theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tention’, <strong>in</strong> B.Vermazen <strong>and</strong>M.B.H<strong>in</strong>tikka (eds) <strong>Essays</strong> on Davidson: Actions <strong>and</strong> Events, Oxford:Clarendon Press.——(1987) Intention, Plans, <strong>and</strong> Practical Reason, Cambridge, MA:Harvard University Press.Codd<strong>in</strong>gton, A. (1983) Keynesian <strong>Economic</strong>s: The Search for FirstPr<strong>in</strong>ciples, London: George Allen <strong>and</strong> Unw<strong>in</strong>.Davidson, D. (1980) <strong>Essays</strong> on Actions <strong>and</strong> Events, Oxford: ClarendonPress.Ebel<strong>in</strong>g, R.M. (1994) ‘Expectations <strong>and</strong> expectation formation <strong>in</strong> Mises’stheory <strong>of</strong> the market process’, <strong>in</strong> P.J.Boettke <strong>and</strong> D.L.Prychitko (eds)The Market Process: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> Contemporary Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s,Aldershot: Edward Elgar.Gadamer, H.-G. (1979) Truth <strong>and</strong> Method, 2nd edn, London: Sheed <strong>and</strong>Ward.G<strong>in</strong>et, C. (1990) On Action, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Habermas, J. (1984) The Theory <strong>of</strong> Communicative Action: Volume 1:Reason <strong>and</strong> the Rationalization <strong>of</strong> Society, London: He<strong>in</strong>emann.Lachmann, L.M. (1971) The Legacy <strong>of</strong> Max Weber, Berkeley: GlendessaryPress.Lachmann, L.M. (1982) ‘<strong>Ludwig</strong> von Mises <strong>and</strong> the extension <strong>of</strong>subjectivism’, <strong>in</strong> I.M.Kirzner (ed.) Method, Process <strong>and</strong> Austrian<strong>Economic</strong>s: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> Honor <strong>of</strong> <strong>Ludwig</strong> von Mises, Lex<strong>in</strong>gton, MA:Lex<strong>in</strong>gton Books.59


STEPHEN D.PARSONS——(1990) ‘Austrian economics: a hermeneutic approach’, <strong>in</strong> D.Lavoie(ed.) <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Hermeneutics, London: Routledge.Mäki, U. (1990) ‘Practical syllogism, entrepreneurship, <strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>visibleh<strong>and</strong>’, <strong>in</strong> D.Lavoie (ed.) <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Hermeneutics, London:Routledge.Mises, L.von (1949) Human Action: A Treatise on <strong>Economic</strong>s, London:Hodge.——(1958) Theory <strong>and</strong> History, London: Cape.——(1962) The Ultimate Foundations <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Science, Pr<strong>in</strong>ceton:Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>.——(1981) Epistemological Problems <strong>in</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s, New York: New YorkUniversity Press.——(1990) Money, Method <strong>and</strong> Market Process: <strong>Essays</strong> by <strong>Ludwig</strong> vonMises, Norwell, Mass: Kluwer.Moya, C.J. (1990) The Philosophy <strong>of</strong> Action, Cambridge: Polity Press.Oakes, G. (ed.) (1986) ‘Introduction: Rickert’s theory <strong>of</strong> historicalknowledge’, <strong>in</strong> H.Rickert The Limits <strong>of</strong> Concept Formation <strong>in</strong> NaturalScience, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Parsons, S. (1990) ‘The philosophical roots <strong>of</strong> modern Austrian economics:past problems <strong>and</strong> future prospects’, History <strong>of</strong> Political Economy, 22(2): 295–320.——(1997) ‘Mises, the a priori <strong>and</strong> the foundations <strong>of</strong> economics: aqualified defence’, <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Philosophy, 13:175–96.Schutz, A. (1972) The Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the Social World, London:He<strong>in</strong>emann.Sugden, R. (1991) ‘Rational choice: a survey <strong>of</strong> contributions fromeconomics <strong>and</strong> philosophy’, <strong>Economic</strong> Journal, 101:751–85.Weber, M. (1978) Economy <strong>and</strong> Society: Volume 1 (G.Roth <strong>and</strong> C.Wittich(eds)), Berkeley: University <strong>of</strong> California Press.60


4LACHMANN ON THESUBJECTIVISM OF ACTIVEMINDSRoger KopplIntroduction<strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann cast a spell. Almost, as it were, aga<strong>in</strong>st your will,this modest <strong>and</strong> amiable man would <strong>in</strong>duce you to change yourth<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g radically. He carried an unpalatable message that most <strong>of</strong>us, at first, wanted to reject. But for many <strong>of</strong> us the message camethrough <strong>in</strong> the end. When Lachmann first came to participate <strong>in</strong> theAustrian revival <strong>of</strong> the 1970s, few Austrians found his messagehospitable. But when he left this group with his much grieved death,many <strong>of</strong> its most creative th<strong>in</strong>kers, most perhaps, were won over tothe general contours <strong>of</strong> his position (Vaughn 1994).What produced this great personal achievement <strong>of</strong> Lachmann? Itwas not, I th<strong>in</strong>k, his solution to any economic problem, but hisidentification <strong>of</strong> one. The problem Lachmann drew our attention towas the need for a theory <strong>of</strong> expectations <strong>in</strong> which each person’sactions are animated by the spontaneous activity <strong>of</strong> a free humanm<strong>in</strong>d. I will call the problem <strong>of</strong> build<strong>in</strong>g a radically subjectivisttheory <strong>of</strong> expectations, the ‘Lachmann problem’.It is not obvious how such a th<strong>in</strong>g is to be done. How can I let theagents <strong>of</strong> my model be free <strong>and</strong> still predict anyth<strong>in</strong>g—even with<strong>in</strong>the model! If we take seriously the ‘subjectivism <strong>of</strong> active m<strong>in</strong>ds’, weseem to fall <strong>in</strong>to the horrible pit <strong>of</strong> open possibility with no ladderupon which to get out. This, we have been told, is nihilism.I th<strong>in</strong>k there is a way out. We can comb<strong>in</strong>e the radical subjectivistattention to human thoughts with a more ‘objective’ underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> rule-governed action. Do<strong>in</strong>g so may permit us to61


ROGER KOPPLcorrelate observable market conditions with certa<strong>in</strong> properties <strong>of</strong>economic expectations. It may help us learn when economicexpectations will be more prescient <strong>and</strong> when less. It may help uslearn when markets are driven mostly by fundamentals <strong>and</strong> whenthey are more subject to fads <strong>and</strong> fashion. To anticipate, myproposal for solv<strong>in</strong>g the Lachmann problem puts Schutz <strong>and</strong> Hayektogether. (Alfred Schutz was a sociologist notable for his use <strong>of</strong>Husserl’s phenomenology. F.A.Hayek, <strong>of</strong> course, was one <strong>of</strong> thelead<strong>in</strong>g figures <strong>of</strong> Austrian economics.)I will argue for an <strong>in</strong>tegration <strong>of</strong> Schutz <strong>and</strong> Hayek <strong>in</strong> thepenultimate section. First though, I wish to review some <strong>of</strong>Lachmann s radical subjectivist ideas about expectations <strong>and</strong> toexpla<strong>in</strong> the ‘Lachmann problem’. Lachmann drew on Keynes <strong>and</strong>Mises. It may be <strong>of</strong> some <strong>in</strong>terest, then, to briefly <strong>in</strong>dicate whyneither Keynes nor Mises is likely to lead us to a solution <strong>of</strong> theLachmann problem. After mak<strong>in</strong>g that argument, I will turn to myproposed <strong>in</strong>tegration <strong>of</strong> Schutz <strong>and</strong> Hayek. The <strong>in</strong>tegration <strong>of</strong>Schutz <strong>and</strong> Hayek, I will argue, may let us solve the Lachmannproblem. To make my case I will need to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between twomean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> ‘expectations’. On the one h<strong>and</strong>, economic‘expectations’ are what the word most naturally suggests, namely,ideas about the future. These are the sorts <strong>of</strong> ‘expectations’ radicalsubjectivists have generally been talk<strong>in</strong>g about. On the other h<strong>and</strong>,the ‘expectations’ <strong>of</strong> many economic models are really dispositionsor propensities to act <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> ways. I ‘expect’ <strong>in</strong>flation if I raise myoutput price. I will call expectations <strong>in</strong> the first sense ‘psychologicalexpectations’. I will call expectations <strong>in</strong> the second sense‘dispositional expectations’. If the argument <strong>of</strong> the latter part <strong>of</strong> thischapter is right, <strong>in</strong>tegrat<strong>in</strong>g Schutz <strong>and</strong> Hayek to solve theLachmann problem means expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g both psychological <strong>and</strong>dispositional expectations <strong>and</strong> correlat<strong>in</strong>g the two explanations.The Lachmann problemIn his 1943 essay ‘The role <strong>of</strong> expectations <strong>in</strong> economics as a socialscience’ ([1943] 1977), Lachmann mapped out a position fromwhich he never deviated. It is this same position, for <strong>in</strong>stance, thathe adopted <strong>in</strong> an important essay for the Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>Literature, ‘From Mises to Shackle: an essay on Austrian economics<strong>and</strong> the Kaleidic Society’ (Lachmann 1976). Lachmann calls for atheory <strong>of</strong> expectations that goes beyond the efforts proposed byma<strong>in</strong>stream economists.62


THE SUBJECTIVISM OF ACTIVE MINDSThe ‘modern theory’ <strong>of</strong> the 1930s had brought the ‘<strong>in</strong>troduction<strong>of</strong> expectations’ <strong>in</strong>to economics (ibid.: 65). Some, Keynes amongthem, had treated expectations as ‘data’ (ibid.). Others hadproposed to treat them as ‘variables it is our task to expla<strong>in</strong>’(Schumpeter 1939, vol. I:55 as quoted <strong>in</strong> Lachmann 1943:66).Lachmann rejected both ways <strong>of</strong> treat<strong>in</strong>g expectations.We cannot regard expectations as mere ‘data’ given to us butmust ask ‘why they are what they are’ (Lachmann 1943:65). We are,<strong>in</strong>deed, ‘compelled’ to seek out a ‘causal explanation’ <strong>of</strong> economicexpectations (ibid.: 65). Expectations, after all, are on a ‘somewhatdifferent plane’ (ibid.: 66) from the distribution <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>eral depositsor the public’s preference between movie directors. The distribution<strong>of</strong> expectations, unlike that <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>eral deposits, is ‘largely the result<strong>of</strong> the experience <strong>of</strong> economic processes’ (ibid.).But neither can we regard expectations as variables to be <strong>in</strong>ferredfrom the ‘bus<strong>in</strong>ess situation’. Different <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>ds will drawdifferent <strong>in</strong>ferences from the same ‘objective’ data. Thus, ‘there willbe as many “bus<strong>in</strong>ess situations” as there are different<strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>of</strong> the same facts, <strong>and</strong> they will all exist alongsideeach other’ (ibid.: 67).Here we come to the dark heart <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s ideas onexpectations. Expectations are not constant, or even chang<strong>in</strong>g, dataimp<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g, as it were, from outside the economic process; they are<strong>in</strong>terpretations. But <strong>in</strong>terpretations differ <strong>in</strong> ways that defyprediction: ‘The absence <strong>of</strong> a uniform relationship between a set <strong>of</strong>observable events which might be described as a situation on the oneh<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> expectations on the other h<strong>and</strong>, is thus seen to be the crux<strong>of</strong> the whole matter’ (ibid.: 67). We are thus obliged to viewexpectations as ‘economically <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ate’ (ibid.). For Lachmann,‘it cannot be emphasised too strongly’ that attempts to test empiricalhypotheses with historical data will be ‘quite useless’ if they are‘conf<strong>in</strong>ed to the study <strong>of</strong> [the] relations between objective facts <strong>and</strong>expectations’ (ibid.: 68). The best we can do is to renderexpectations ‘<strong>in</strong>telligible’ by see<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> them a plan based on an<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> the facts <strong>of</strong> experience (ibid.: 68–73).For Lachmann, ‘it is by reduc<strong>in</strong>g “action” to “plan” that we“underst<strong>and</strong>” the actions <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals’ (ibid.: 69). He <strong>in</strong>fers fromthis that ‘it is the subjective nature <strong>of</strong> beliefs which imparts<strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ateness to expectations’ but ‘it is their mental naturewhich renders them capable <strong>of</strong> explanation’ (ibid.: 73). He drawsthe further conclusion that economists must (<strong>in</strong> 1943), exp<strong>and</strong>beyond ‘the subjectivism <strong>of</strong> wants’ to embrace ‘the subjectivism <strong>of</strong>63


ROGER KOPPL<strong>in</strong>terpretation’ (ibid.). I take this to be the same position expressed<strong>in</strong> 1976 as the <strong>in</strong>vitation to ‘extend’ subjectivism from Mises toShackle, from the subjectivism <strong>of</strong> ‘tastes’ to the subjectivism <strong>of</strong>‘expectations’ (Lachmann 1976:58). The theory <strong>of</strong> expectationswhose absence Lachmann calls our attention to must embrace the‘subjectivism <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation’ (ibid.: 69).Lachmann has put a hard task <strong>in</strong>deed to economics. Expectationsare to be neither data nor variables. They are to be endogenous, butnot functionally related to observable facts. Rather than functionalrelations, we are to see <strong>in</strong> expectations subjective <strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>of</strong>facts whose mean<strong>in</strong>g for future action is always more or less obscure.A theory that satisfies Lachmann’s call for a subjectivism <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>terpretations must satisfy three criteria. First, it must giveexpectations a place with<strong>in</strong> economic theory. Second, the theorymust be subjectivist <strong>in</strong> a strong sense: Expectations are produced byactive m<strong>in</strong>ds, each <strong>of</strong> which is more or less unique. F<strong>in</strong>ally,expectations must be endogenous to the market process.The hard th<strong>in</strong>g is to satisfy the second <strong>and</strong> third criteriasimultaneously. Expectations may be right or wrong. Marketefficiency depends crucially on the accuracy <strong>of</strong> economicexpectations. If one doubts that markets tend to co-ord<strong>in</strong>ate action,one may be <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ed to th<strong>in</strong>k that expectations are formed throughan essentially psychological process as <strong>in</strong> Keynes’s Chapter 12.Greater faith <strong>in</strong> the market may <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>e one to th<strong>in</strong>k thatexpectations are <strong>in</strong>deed ‘rational’ <strong>in</strong> a sense close to that <strong>of</strong> Lucas<strong>and</strong> Muth. Both the New Classical <strong>and</strong> old Keynesian approaches toexpectations, unfortunately, require one to choose <strong>in</strong> advance one’smodell<strong>in</strong>g strategy. One must decide a priori whether to representexpectations as ‘rational’ <strong>and</strong> co-ord<strong>in</strong>ative or as ‘psychological’<strong>and</strong> disequilibrat<strong>in</strong>g. The trick, I th<strong>in</strong>k, is to represent endogenouslyformed expectations <strong>in</strong> a way that skirts the unsatisfactory choicebetween faith <strong>and</strong> doubt <strong>in</strong> the co-ord<strong>in</strong>ative prowess <strong>of</strong> markets. Ifwe are stuck with an a priori choice between faith <strong>and</strong> doubt, anessential question <strong>of</strong> our discipl<strong>in</strong>e is not empirical or logical, butpurely ideological. 1 If the Lachmann problem can be solved, perhapswe can avoid this ideologically charged choice.<strong>Ludwig</strong> von Mises <strong>and</strong> the Lachmann problemLachmann claimed that Mises never extended his subjectivism fromtastes to expectations. This may seem an odd claim to make <strong>of</strong> anauthor who emphasised uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty as strongly as did Mises. Mises64


THE SUBJECTIVISM OF ACTIVE MINDSshowed a real appreciation for the subjectivism <strong>of</strong> expectationswhen he argued that the:farmer who <strong>in</strong> earlier ages tried to <strong>in</strong>crease his crop byresort<strong>in</strong>g to magic rites acted no less rationally than themodern farmer who applies fertilizer. He did what accord<strong>in</strong>gto his—erroneous—op<strong>in</strong>ion was appropriate to his purpose.(Mises 1957:268)And what are subjective expectations but op<strong>in</strong>ions that might proveerroneous? An action based on failed expectations is ‘contrary topurpose’, but it is not irrational (Mises 1963:20). And yetLachmann’s claim was a fair one. In spite <strong>of</strong> the very great role <strong>of</strong>subjective expectations <strong>in</strong> Mises’s economics, Mises never let thesubjectivism <strong>of</strong> expectation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation enter <strong>in</strong>to thestructures <strong>of</strong> his pure economic theory.The response <strong>of</strong> Mises to Lachmann’s 1943 essay is <strong>in</strong>formative(Mises 1943). Lachmann drew from his general considerationsregard<strong>in</strong>g expectations the specific <strong>in</strong>ference, quoted by Mises, that‘Without fairly elastic expectations there can therefore be no crisis<strong>of</strong> the Austro-Wicksellian type’ (ibid.: 79). With this claim, m<strong>in</strong>orterm<strong>in</strong>ological po<strong>in</strong>ts aside, Mises could ‘fully agree’ (ibid.: 251).Indeed, Mises reports, he had said as much <strong>in</strong> hisNationaloekonomie <strong>of</strong> 1940. He then produces a quote from itsay<strong>in</strong>g the ‘teach<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> the monetary theory <strong>of</strong> the trade cycle’ mayhave spread widely enough that <strong>in</strong> the next credit expansionbus<strong>in</strong>essmen will replace the ‘naive optimism’ <strong>of</strong> the past with a‘greater scepticism’ though it is ‘too early to make a positivestatement’ (ibid.).Mises develops the po<strong>in</strong>t. As long as a bus<strong>in</strong>essman is ‘abus<strong>in</strong>essman only <strong>and</strong> does not view th<strong>in</strong>gs with the eye <strong>of</strong> aneconomist’, the cycle story applies. But if a bus<strong>in</strong>essman wears thehat <strong>of</strong> an ‘economist’ too, then he may ‘look askance at the low level<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rates brought about by the credit expansion’ (ibid.). The‘bus<strong>in</strong>essman’ must be an ‘economist’ <strong>in</strong> order to see that today’scredit conditions are false <strong>and</strong> temporary manifestations <strong>of</strong>excessive money growth.Mises <strong>in</strong>sists on view<strong>in</strong>g the more sophisticated actor assomehow more than a bus<strong>in</strong>essman; he is also an ‘economist’. Thus,if expectations behave differently than we predict, it is because someoutside element has entered the story. This is the rhetorical tropeImre Lakatos deftly labelled ‘monster-barr<strong>in</strong>g’ (Lakatos 1976:14). A65


ROGER KOPPLbus<strong>in</strong>essman who knows the monetary theory <strong>of</strong> the trade cycle islike a man with two heads: He is a monster <strong>and</strong> ruled out <strong>of</strong> court.A monster is a counterexample to your theory. When you call thecounterexample a monster, you deny that it counts as acounterexample. This is how Mises h<strong>and</strong>led Lachmann’s commenton the elasticity <strong>of</strong> expectations. The case Lachmann mentions,accord<strong>in</strong>g to Mises, is the one <strong>in</strong> which the bus<strong>in</strong>essman is also aneconomist. Mises takes his ‘pure a priori’ theory to discuss thebehaviour <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>essmen <strong>and</strong> not economists. Thus, Lachmann’sexample br<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g that doesn’t perta<strong>in</strong> to the theory. Themonster is barred, no mention <strong>of</strong> him may be made <strong>in</strong> futurediscussions <strong>of</strong> the subject.Such monster-barr<strong>in</strong>g might seem so ad hoc that Mises wouldhave been forced to confront the subjectivism <strong>of</strong> expectations. ButMises’s epistemological views led him to see the problems <strong>of</strong>subjective <strong>in</strong>terpretation as radically divorced from economictheory <strong>and</strong> the canons <strong>of</strong> scientific reason.In an essay published orig<strong>in</strong>ally <strong>in</strong> 1933, Mises dist<strong>in</strong>guishedbetween ‘Conception <strong>and</strong> Underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g’ (Mises 1933a).Conception is rational; it is ‘discursive reason<strong>in</strong>g’. Underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g isthe English translation <strong>of</strong> the German word ‘Verstehen’.‘Underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g seeks the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> action <strong>in</strong> empathic <strong>in</strong>tuition <strong>of</strong>the whole’ (ibid.: 133). When both apply, conception ‘takesprecedence over underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> every respect’ (ibid.: 133). Butunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g can penetrate to someth<strong>in</strong>g conception cannot reach:‘the apprehension <strong>of</strong> the quality <strong>of</strong> values’ (ibid.: 134). It is whenunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g enters that ‘subjectivity beg<strong>in</strong>s’ (ibid.: 134). ForMises, ‘[c]onception is reason<strong>in</strong>g; underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g is behold<strong>in</strong>g’(ibid.). Mises would later call underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g ‘the specificunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the historical sciences <strong>of</strong> human action’ (Mises1957:264).The ‘underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g’ Mises dist<strong>in</strong>guishes from ‘conception’ ishistorical, he thought, not scientific. <strong>Economic</strong> theory is scientific,not historical. Thus, any knowledge we might have about the‘subjectivity’ <strong>of</strong> others is historical, not theoretical. (Mises’sdist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>and</strong> its relation to the problem <strong>of</strong> expectations isdiscussed by Butos 1997 <strong>and</strong> Koppl 1997.)It is very significant that Mises equates underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g with thesubjective. It relegated the issue raised by Lachmann to theextratheoretical categories <strong>of</strong> ‘historical underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g’ <strong>and</strong>‘<strong>in</strong>tuition <strong>of</strong> the whole’. It neatly immunised economic theory fromthe issue that so occupied Lachmann. It is thus with good reason66


THE SUBJECTIVISM OF ACTIVE MINDSthat Lachmann would say Shackle, not Mises, had ‘extended thescope <strong>of</strong> subjectivism from tastes to expectations’ (Lachmann1976:58). Lachmann claims that ‘Mises hardly ever mentionsexpectations’ (ibid.: 58). And a look at the <strong>in</strong>dex <strong>of</strong> Mises’s magnumopus, Human Action (1963), shows no entry under ‘expectations’.Though Mises was a subjectivist, his system <strong>of</strong> thought does notpermit the development <strong>of</strong> a subjectivist theory <strong>of</strong> expectations.J.M.Keynes <strong>and</strong> the Lachmann problemLachmann gave Keynes a mixed review. He clearly disliked the‘diatribe aga<strong>in</strong>st the Stock Exchange’ to be found <strong>in</strong> Chapter 12 <strong>of</strong>Keynes’s General Theory (Lachmann [1969] 1977:142). But hequotes G.L.S.Shackle favourably to the effect that the ‘whole spirit’<strong>of</strong> Keynes’s 1936 book was subjectivist <strong>and</strong> laudable (ibid.: 159).This is a more positive view <strong>of</strong> J.M.Keynes than many otherAustrians take today. It is strik<strong>in</strong>g when put <strong>in</strong> its context: Thearticle orig<strong>in</strong>ally appeared <strong>in</strong> a 1969 festschrift for F.A.Hayek! Inthis same essay Lachmann credits Keynes with <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>gexpectations to ‘Anglo-Saxon economies’ <strong>in</strong> 1930 (ibid.: 157–8).The subjectivism <strong>of</strong> Keynes has <strong>in</strong>spired more than one author topropose a synthesis <strong>of</strong> the ideas <strong>of</strong> Keynes <strong>and</strong> the Austrians (seeButos <strong>and</strong> Koppl 1997). But Butos <strong>and</strong> I have argued aga<strong>in</strong>st that, atleast for the Hayekian str<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> Austrian economics. Thephilosophical differences separat<strong>in</strong>g the thought <strong>of</strong> Keynes <strong>and</strong>Hayek make any synthesis <strong>of</strong> them difficult (Butos <strong>and</strong> Koppl1997). The basic philosophical ideas <strong>of</strong> Keynes drove him to viewexpectations as disconnected from any aspect <strong>of</strong> the market processexcept the self-referenc<strong>in</strong>g process <strong>of</strong> mass psychology that createsobjectively baseless waves <strong>of</strong> optimism <strong>and</strong> pessimism.Butos <strong>and</strong> I argue, <strong>in</strong> agreement with O’Donnell <strong>and</strong> others,that Keynes was a rationalist. Keynes believed that knowledgeproperly speak<strong>in</strong>g was philosophically grounded <strong>and</strong>epistemologically certa<strong>in</strong>. But he also believed that the conditionsthat permit <strong>in</strong>duction <strong>and</strong>, therefore, knowledge <strong>of</strong> the future donot apply to the social world. As Butos <strong>and</strong> I put it, ‘Keynes was aCartesian rationalist who saw about him a non-Cartesian socialworld.’ The impossibility <strong>of</strong> apply<strong>in</strong>g philosophical reason to thepractical problems <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>and</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>ess forecast<strong>in</strong>g ledKeynes to emphasise ‘animal spirits, a spontaneous urge to actionrather than <strong>in</strong>action’ (see Keynes, Collected Writ<strong>in</strong>gs [1936] 1972,vol. VII:161).67


ROGER KOPPLAnimal spirits are neither subjective expectations nor the source<strong>of</strong> them. They are the spr<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> action <strong>in</strong> a world where reason mustdefault for lack <strong>of</strong> data (Koppl 1991). It is the default <strong>of</strong> reason thatmakes long-term expectations necessarily ‘subjective’ for Keynes <strong>in</strong>the extreme sense <strong>of</strong> disconnection from underly<strong>in</strong>g scarcities. InKeynes’s scheme <strong>of</strong> thought, the actions to which animal spiritsimpel us cannot be grounded <strong>in</strong> a rational calculation <strong>of</strong> futureconsequences. The extreme unknowability <strong>of</strong> the future ensures asmuch. The expectations beh<strong>in</strong>d such actions are psychologicalbeliefs <strong>and</strong> more or less <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>of</strong> market data. Subjectiveexpectations are determ<strong>in</strong>ed by an autonomous process <strong>of</strong> masspsychology. They are therefore fundamentally exogenous to themarket process.The exogeneity <strong>of</strong> subjective expectations <strong>in</strong> Keynes contrastswith the criterion stated above, namely, that a Lachmannian theory<strong>of</strong> expectations must represent expectations as endogenous to themarket process. Lachmann was right to see Keynes as a pioneer <strong>in</strong>the theory <strong>of</strong> subjective expectations. But Keynes’s pioneer<strong>in</strong>g workis not one on which we might build a theory <strong>of</strong> expectations thatmeets the challenge Lachmann put to the science <strong>of</strong> economics.Alfred Schutz <strong>and</strong> the Lachmann problemSchutz on anonymityThe works <strong>of</strong> F.A.Hayek <strong>and</strong> Alfred Schutz give us a way to solvethe Lachmann problem. The work <strong>of</strong> Schutz teaches us that radicalsubjectivism can sometimes make use <strong>of</strong> a less psychologicallydetailed picture <strong>of</strong> action than Lachmann seems to have thoughtpossible. The work <strong>of</strong> F.A.Hayek may be used to <strong>in</strong>fer someth<strong>in</strong>gabout when it is appropriate to use those less detailed pictures.Putt<strong>in</strong>g together the <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>of</strong> these two great subjectivists allowsus to construct a theory <strong>of</strong> expectations that builds from thesubjectivism <strong>of</strong> active m<strong>in</strong>ds to a picture <strong>of</strong> orderly <strong>and</strong>endogenously determ<strong>in</strong>ed economic expectations.A subjectivism <strong>of</strong> active m<strong>in</strong>ds must start with a picture <strong>of</strong>thought. Schutz gives us such a picture. The key notion <strong>in</strong> Schutz’sphenomenological description <strong>of</strong> thought <strong>and</strong> action is‘typification’. A typification is just a stereotype. 2 All th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g,Schutz taught, is stereotypical. When we form an idea, we form atypification. Typifications <strong>of</strong> people are ‘personal types’;typifications <strong>of</strong> actions are ‘course-<strong>of</strong>-action types’. The structure <strong>of</strong>68


THE SUBJECTIVISM OF ACTIVE MINDSour thoughts, then, is a structure <strong>of</strong> typifications. Some <strong>of</strong> thesetypifications are filled with many particulars; others are quiteempty. My typification <strong>of</strong>, say, my old pocket knife is quiteparticularistic. I know the heft <strong>of</strong> it <strong>and</strong> where the blade is nicked.By contrast, my typifkation <strong>of</strong>, say, a postal worker is rather empty.In ways I don’t quite underst<strong>and</strong>, the faceless postal worker sorts<strong>and</strong> delivers. The personal types conta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g more particulars have alow degree <strong>of</strong> ‘anonymity’. At the other end are the personal typeswith a high degree <strong>of</strong> ‘anonymity’.What has been said about types <strong>of</strong> higher <strong>and</strong> lower anonymity isstill true if the typifications are those <strong>of</strong> social science. The scientist’sideal types are <strong>of</strong> higher or lower anonymity accord<strong>in</strong>g to theproblem he studies. Whether we are speak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> everyday thought<strong>and</strong> action or <strong>of</strong> our scientific underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> that thought <strong>and</strong>action, our thoughts sp<strong>in</strong> a web <strong>of</strong> stereotypes, some <strong>of</strong> which arevery spare or th<strong>in</strong> descriptions <strong>of</strong> their objects, others <strong>of</strong> which arevery detailed or thick descriptions.The stereotypes I must rely on when I th<strong>in</strong>k about social life aregotten by tak<strong>in</strong>g ‘a cross-section <strong>of</strong> our experience <strong>of</strong> another person<strong>and</strong>, so to speak, “freez<strong>in</strong>g it <strong>in</strong>to slide”’ (Schutz 1932:187). Thus,the personal types <strong>of</strong> my mental picture <strong>of</strong> the world know n<strong>of</strong>reedom. They cannot act out <strong>of</strong> character. The real peoplecorrespond<strong>in</strong>g to them may, <strong>of</strong> course, act out <strong>of</strong> character, but notmy typifications <strong>of</strong> them. The personal types <strong>of</strong> scientists <strong>and</strong> socialparticipants are equally unfree.Max Weber’s method <strong>of</strong> ideal types ‘consists’, for Schutz, ‘<strong>in</strong>replac<strong>in</strong>g the human be<strong>in</strong>gs which the social scientist observes asactors on the social stage by puppets created by himself (Schutz1967, vol. II:17). The puppet is a personal ideal type. Each puppet’s‘dest<strong>in</strong>y is regulated <strong>and</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ed beforeh<strong>and</strong> by his creator, thesocial scientist, <strong>and</strong> with such a perfect pre-established harmony asLeibniz imag<strong>in</strong>ed the world created by God’ (ibid.: 83).Schutz showed that the propositions we make about highlyanonymous (ideal) types are more reliable guides to ourexpectations than those we make about (ideal) types <strong>of</strong> lowanonymity. Schutz’s concept <strong>of</strong> anonymity helps us to underst<strong>and</strong>how social order is achieved <strong>in</strong> spite <strong>of</strong> the subjectivism <strong>of</strong>expectations. We can co-operate with anonymous others preciselybecause <strong>of</strong> their anonymity. The types <strong>of</strong> high anonymity are th<strong>in</strong>descriptions <strong>of</strong> rather robot-like be<strong>in</strong>gs. We know that each realpostal worker is unique. But we rely on a stereotyped picture <strong>of</strong> himthat quite effaces his personality. To the extent that I can rely on69


ROGER KOPPLsuch anonymous types, I can ignore the idiosyncrasies <strong>of</strong> my fellowsocial actors.I can predict the actions <strong>of</strong> the typical postal worker withconfidence. My usual carrier is a named <strong>in</strong>dividual. I cannot guesswhat he does <strong>of</strong>f the job, nor how <strong>of</strong>ten he calls <strong>in</strong> sick or shows uplate. This named <strong>in</strong>dividual is more or less a cipher to me. But I canbe reasonably sure that he or someone like him will show up midmorn<strong>in</strong>gto drop letters <strong>in</strong> my box.Social co-operation with strangers is possible because we mayrely on highly anonymous personal types <strong>in</strong> formulat<strong>in</strong>g our picture<strong>of</strong> the world <strong>and</strong> our expectations <strong>of</strong> the future. When ourexpectations may reasonably rely on personal types <strong>of</strong> highanonymity only, we have reason for confidence <strong>in</strong> thoseexpectations. When, <strong>in</strong>stead, we must formulate expectations on thebasis <strong>of</strong> personal types <strong>of</strong> relatively low anonymity, we have reasonto doubt the reliability <strong>of</strong> our expectations.Here is a case where ‘Austrian’ economists may make use <strong>of</strong> aKeynesian concept. In his Treatise on Probability, Keynesdist<strong>in</strong>guished between the ‘probability’ <strong>of</strong> proposition <strong>and</strong> its‘weight’. The weight <strong>of</strong> a probability judgement measures howconfident we may be <strong>in</strong> it. I’m quite sure that the chance <strong>of</strong> a seven atcraps is one <strong>in</strong> six. I may judge the chance <strong>of</strong> civil unrest to be one <strong>in</strong>six, but I cannot have confidence <strong>in</strong> that judgement. ‘The weight, tospeak metaphorically, measures the sum <strong>of</strong> the favorable <strong>and</strong>unfavorable evidence, the probability measures the difference’(Keynes, Collected Writ<strong>in</strong>gs [1921] 1972, vol. VIII:77). This notion<strong>of</strong> weight resurfaces <strong>in</strong> Chapter 12 <strong>of</strong> the General Theory (CollectedWrit<strong>in</strong>gs [1936] 1972, vol. VII: 148; see also Runde 1990.) FrankKnight may have been gett<strong>in</strong>g at more or less the same po<strong>in</strong>t whenhe dist<strong>in</strong>guished the ‘favorableness’ <strong>of</strong> an op<strong>in</strong>ion from ‘the amount<strong>of</strong> confidence <strong>in</strong> that op<strong>in</strong>ion’ (Knight [1921] 1971:227).We may apply Keynes’s notion <strong>of</strong> weight to restate Schutz’s po<strong>in</strong>tabout anonymous types. Expectations rely<strong>in</strong>g only on personal types<strong>of</strong> high anonymity may have high weight. Those rely<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> part onpersonal types <strong>of</strong> low anonymity should generally have low weight.<strong>Economic</strong> actors can better predict the actions <strong>of</strong> anonymousthan non-anonymous personal types. Someth<strong>in</strong>g similar may be said<strong>of</strong> economic theorists. Social scientists may be able to predictconfidently the results <strong>of</strong> processes whose descriptions are givenus<strong>in</strong>g only personal ideal types <strong>of</strong> high anonymity. But when thedescription <strong>of</strong> a social process requires the use <strong>of</strong> some personaltype(s) <strong>of</strong> low anonymity, the predictions <strong>of</strong> social science are more70


THE SUBJECTIVISM OF ACTIVE MINDSor less unreliable. This po<strong>in</strong>t is illustrated by three propositionsdiscussed by Fritz Machlup (1978) <strong>in</strong> a paper <strong>in</strong>tended to conveysome <strong>of</strong> Schutz’s ideas to an audience <strong>of</strong> economists (see also thediscussion <strong>in</strong> Langlois 1986 <strong>and</strong> Langlois <strong>and</strong> Koppl 1991).Statement (1): If, because <strong>of</strong> an abundant crop, the output <strong>of</strong>wheat is much <strong>in</strong>creased, the price <strong>of</strong> wheat will fall.’Statement (2): ‘If, because <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>creased wage-rates <strong>and</strong>decreased <strong>in</strong>terest rates, capital becomes relatively cheaperthan labor, new labor-sav<strong>in</strong>g devices will be <strong>in</strong>vented.’Statement (3): ‘If, because <strong>of</strong> heavy withdrawals <strong>of</strong> foreigndeposits, the banks are <strong>in</strong> danger <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>solvency, the CentralBank Authorities will extend the necessary credit.’(Machlup 1978:64)The first statement is more reliable than the second <strong>and</strong> the second ismore reliable than the third. Why? As we go down from the firststatement, we reach ideal types <strong>of</strong> lower anonymity. Machlupexpla<strong>in</strong>ed that:the causal relations such as stated <strong>in</strong> (2) <strong>and</strong> (3) are derived fromtypes <strong>of</strong> human conduct <strong>of</strong> a lesser generality or anonymity. Tomake a statement about the actions <strong>of</strong> bank authorities (such as(3)) calls for reason<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> a stratum <strong>of</strong> behavior conceptions <strong>of</strong>much less anonymous types <strong>of</strong> actors. We have to know orimag<strong>in</strong>e the act<strong>in</strong>g persons much more <strong>in</strong>timately.(Machlup 1978:68)That greater <strong>in</strong>timacy implies a greater chance that the actor willsurprise us by act<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> character. (Later I will discuss the role <strong>of</strong>the ‘system constra<strong>in</strong>t’ <strong>in</strong> determ<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g when to use anonymoustypes.) We cannot be sure the central bank authorities will extendcredit. It is a good guess they will; but they may surprise us with anact <strong>of</strong> monetary restra<strong>in</strong>t. We can be much more confident <strong>in</strong> thecom<strong>in</strong>g reduction <strong>of</strong> wheat prices. We can rely on an anonymoustypification <strong>of</strong> the wheat farmer. We need non-anonymoustypifications <strong>of</strong> the central bank’s high <strong>of</strong>ficials.The Lachmann problem aga<strong>in</strong>I identified the Lachmann problem as the need to have a theory <strong>of</strong>expectations that builds on the idea that each person’s actions are71


ROGER KOPPLanimated by the spontaneous activity <strong>of</strong> a free human m<strong>in</strong>d.Lachmann’s recognition <strong>of</strong> this problem led him to his ‘subjectivism<strong>of</strong> expectations’ accord<strong>in</strong>g to which expectations must be seen asneither data nor variables. They are ‘<strong>in</strong>terpretations’, each one moreor less unique to the <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividual. Lachmann calls forthick description.The personal <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretive quality <strong>of</strong> expectations spellstrouble for any theory <strong>of</strong> expectations. We seem to require a detailedpsychological portrait <strong>of</strong> each economic actor if we are to sayanyth<strong>in</strong>g at all about the market process. Moreover, each actorseems to require the same sort <strong>of</strong> psychological detail <strong>in</strong> his mentalportrait <strong>of</strong> each <strong>of</strong> his fellow actors.Schutz’s discussion <strong>of</strong> anonymity shows that we do not alwaysneed to rely on a psychologically rich picture <strong>of</strong> economic actors.Both economic actors <strong>and</strong> economic analysts may sometimes forgothick description <strong>in</strong> favour <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong> description. When the observer orhis subject requires reference to non-anonymous types, we may notbe able to say much about expectations. In that case the results <strong>of</strong>the market process will be hard to predict.In other words, the ‘Lachmann problem’ is more acute <strong>in</strong> somecontexts, less acute <strong>in</strong> others. When it is most acute, the marketprocess will be hard to fathom <strong>and</strong> economic theory <strong>of</strong> limitedpredictive value. When the Lachmann problem is least acute, themarket process will be more transparent <strong>and</strong> economic theory willhave greater predictive value.F.A.Hayek <strong>and</strong> the Lachmann problemI have argued that sometimes th<strong>in</strong> description is good enough. Thetrick is to know when. On this po<strong>in</strong>t, to my knowledge, Schutz issilent. Lachmann did emphasise <strong>in</strong>stitutions, call<strong>in</strong>g them ‘nodalpo<strong>in</strong>ts’ to guide the <strong>in</strong>dividual. I th<strong>in</strong>k he was right about that, butthe notion <strong>of</strong> nodal po<strong>in</strong>ts is not a very detailed analysis. I th<strong>in</strong>k itis fair to say that ‘radical subjectivism’ has so far failed to tell usmuch about when economic actors might get along withanonymous types.Perhaps we should not be surprised if radical subjectivism has nottold us when th<strong>in</strong> description is enough. A radically subjectivistaccount would have to run <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> the thoughts <strong>of</strong> economicactors. What we want to know is when those thoughts employ nonanonymoustypes. But a radically subjectivist account would beobliged to beg<strong>in</strong> with the thoughts <strong>of</strong> the agent. It is hard to see how72


THE SUBJECTIVISM OF ACTIVE MINDSa pure subjactivist could get beyond the circular claim that agentsuse th<strong>in</strong> description when they use th<strong>in</strong> description. What we seemto require is a set <strong>of</strong> ‘objective’ conditions under which the‘subjective’ thoughts <strong>of</strong> agents may be represented as employ<strong>in</strong>gonly anonymous types. 3 Similarly, we need a set <strong>of</strong> objectiveconditions under which our own th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g as scientific observersmay employ only anonymous types.Consider aga<strong>in</strong> Machlup’s three statements. Statement (1)asserted that if, ‘because <strong>of</strong> an abundant crop, the output <strong>of</strong> wheat ismuch <strong>in</strong>creased, the price <strong>of</strong> wheat will fall’. What is it that lets ourreason<strong>in</strong>g be guided by anonymous types <strong>in</strong> this case? Why is a th<strong>in</strong>description enough? As Langlois <strong>and</strong> I have argued, it is the ‘systemconstra<strong>in</strong>t’ (Langlois <strong>and</strong> Koppl 1991:92). Imag<strong>in</strong>e we have one or afew idiosyncratic wheat farmers or wheat traders. They may actfoolishly or arbitrarily. But these few oddballs cannot reverse thetide <strong>of</strong> events. And if they try, they risk losses <strong>and</strong> banishment fromthe market. The large numbers <strong>of</strong> competitors <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>and</strong> thediscipl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>and</strong> loss ensure that we may safely ignore anyidiosyncracies <strong>of</strong> behaviour <strong>in</strong> the wheat market. Th<strong>in</strong> descriptionswill do for economic observers.Now consider the positions <strong>of</strong> participants <strong>in</strong> the wheat market.If they are operat<strong>in</strong>g under a tight system constra<strong>in</strong>t, their actionswill be driven <strong>in</strong>to approximate conformity with the underly<strong>in</strong>gsituational logic. Those whose actions stray too far from this logicwill suffer losses which, if uncorrected, will drive them from themarket. A tight system constra<strong>in</strong>t produces a relatively highcorrespondence between action <strong>and</strong> circumstance. Under suchconditions, we may represent the thoughts <strong>of</strong> agents as express<strong>in</strong>gthe same correspondence; agents act as if they had prescientexpectations. The condition that lets us represent agents <strong>in</strong> this as-ifway is the tight system constra<strong>in</strong>t. But this is also the condition thatlets observers rely exclusively on anonymous types. When thesystem constra<strong>in</strong>t is tight, economic actors forgo thick description <strong>in</strong>favour <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong> description.Butos <strong>and</strong> I have developed some <strong>of</strong> these po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> a paperdraw<strong>in</strong>g on Hayek’s theories <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> social evolution (Butos<strong>and</strong> Koppl 1993). We argue that the market’s evolutionary selectionmechanism sometimes keeps anticipations <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e, but sometimesdoes not. We identify two conditions that promote prescientexpectations. The first is that the rules <strong>of</strong> the game <strong>of</strong> marketcompetition are stable. The second is that competition is atomistic.The rules <strong>of</strong> the game are stable when changes <strong>in</strong> them are small73


ROGER KOPPL<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>frequent. The rules that count here are both formal <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>formal. Indeed, the only formal rules that count are those that areenforced at least some <strong>of</strong> the time. Human habits are constantlychang<strong>in</strong>g piecemeal. Thus, perfect stability is impossible. But we can<strong>of</strong>ten say that the rules <strong>of</strong> the game are more stable <strong>in</strong> this market,less stable <strong>in</strong> that one.Competition is atomistic when it is rivalrous. When each supplierconsiders his own actions to have an <strong>in</strong>significant impact on theoverall market, when there is little ‘rival consciousness’ (Machlup1952), then competition is ‘atomistic’ <strong>in</strong> the relevant sense.Under these conditions <strong>of</strong> stability <strong>and</strong> atomism, Butos <strong>and</strong> Ihave argued, evolutionary selection mechanisms <strong>of</strong> the sort Hayekanalysed will produce relatively prescient economic expectations<strong>and</strong> relatively high levels <strong>of</strong> economic efficiency. Stable evolutionaryenvironments produce prescient expectations <strong>in</strong> the social world,goodness <strong>of</strong> fit <strong>in</strong> the biological world.The evolutionary <strong>and</strong> Hayekian considerations <strong>of</strong> the presentsection may not seem to fit well with the phenomenological <strong>and</strong>Schutzian considerations <strong>of</strong> the previous section. Butos <strong>and</strong> Iadopted the Hayekian view <strong>of</strong> expectations as (mostly) dispositionsto act. The Schutzian framework takes expectations to bepsychological states. It is not immediately obvious that these areconsistent perspectives. Some def<strong>in</strong>itions may help to clarify theissues.Let the term ‘dispositional expectations’ refer to the Hayekianview <strong>and</strong> the term ‘psychological expectations’ refer to thephenomenological or hermeneutical view <strong>of</strong> expectations.Psychological expectations refer to people’s thoughts. Dispositionalexpectations refer to people’s actions.The ‘expectations’ <strong>of</strong> economic theory are <strong>of</strong>ten dispositionalexpectations. We say that creditors ‘expect’ zero <strong>in</strong>flation if they donot <strong>in</strong>sist on an <strong>in</strong>flation premium. This ‘expectation’ may benoth<strong>in</strong>g more than the conformity to old habits <strong>and</strong> ways <strong>of</strong> do<strong>in</strong>gbus<strong>in</strong>ess. Conceivably, some creditors might even have apsychological expectation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>flation. If they don’t underst<strong>and</strong> theeffect <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>flation on purchas<strong>in</strong>g power, they won’t ask for an<strong>in</strong>flation premium. The case imag<strong>in</strong>ed is not purely hypothetical.Recently, an important Italian labour leader expressed concern overthe government’s low <strong>in</strong>flation target. Such low <strong>in</strong>flation, heclaimed, would reduce the purchas<strong>in</strong>g power <strong>of</strong> workers’ wages.Methodological subjectivists <strong>in</strong>sist that one must be able to give areasonable account <strong>of</strong> the psychological expectations animat<strong>in</strong>g the74


THE SUBJECTIVISM OF ACTIVE MINDSactions <strong>of</strong> economic actors. This is a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> test. If your modelrequires that we imag<strong>in</strong>e agents act<strong>in</strong>g on unreasonable psychologicalexpectations, the model is unreasonable. If the psychologicalexpectations at work are reasonable, the model passes the test.Dispositional <strong>and</strong> psychological expectations are dist<strong>in</strong>ct objects.On narrow logical grounds, any comb<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> them is possible.But it seems reasonable to suppose the two typically fit together. Atheory <strong>of</strong> dispositional expectations without a correlated theory <strong>of</strong>psychological expectations is tenuous. We may wonder if anyplausible psychological expectations could correlate with theposited dispositions. Rational expectations, for example, are anassumption about dispositional expectations. Traders act as if theyhad, on average, the true model <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d. The assumption isreasonable under some circumstances. But rational expectations arenot reasonable assumptions when the implied psychologicalexpectations entail, say, superhuman powers <strong>of</strong> calculation.A theory <strong>of</strong> psychological expectations without a correlatedtheory <strong>of</strong> dispositional expectations is also dubious, <strong>and</strong> for aparallel reason. Without the latter we cannot be sure the positedpsychological expectations would really come to prevail.Expectations are, as Lachmann <strong>in</strong>sisted, endogenous to the marketprocess. If we do not correlate our underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> psychologicalexpectations with a story <strong>of</strong> the emergence <strong>of</strong> dispositionalexpectations, we have to doubt that the imag<strong>in</strong>ed psychologicalexpectations would really survive the test <strong>of</strong> market competition.An example may clarify some <strong>of</strong> these issues. Consider theoperation <strong>of</strong> a modern asset market. Traders must anticipate futurevalues at least passably well if they are not to be forced out <strong>of</strong> thegame by losses. Pr<strong>of</strong>its will encourage those with unusually goodforesight to keep at it. An evolutionary selection mechanism worksto keep anticipation more or less <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e with underly<strong>in</strong>g values asrevealed by future returns. If the market filter <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>and</strong> lossworks well, prices will reflect fundamental values. If the filter worksbadly, prices may w<strong>and</strong>er freely from fundamental values. Whetherthe filter works well or not is an empirical question.Efficient market theories predict that market prices will reflect allavailable <strong>in</strong>formation. An important implication <strong>of</strong> such theories(together with a few subsidiary assumptions) is that the pastchanges <strong>in</strong> an asset’s return give no evidence about future changes.In consequence the expected value <strong>of</strong> an asset’s return <strong>in</strong> any periodis simply its return <strong>in</strong> the previous period. This property <strong>of</strong> thereturn series def<strong>in</strong>es a ‘mart<strong>in</strong>gale’. (A r<strong>and</strong>om walk is a special case75


ROGER KOPPL<strong>of</strong> a mart<strong>in</strong>gale <strong>in</strong> which the higher moments are not expected tochange over time. See LeRoy 1989 for a review <strong>of</strong> basic issues.)The statistical evidence for the efficiency <strong>of</strong> asset markets isstrong enough to have persuaded many serious <strong>and</strong> competentjudges. Others doubt. There are many apparent counterexamples.Evidence reviewed below suggests that observable marketconditions help determ<strong>in</strong>e how efficient asset markets are. Thedegree <strong>of</strong> efficiency may be an endogenous variable.Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the ‘Big Players theory’, the order-giv<strong>in</strong>g properties<strong>of</strong> the filter <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it <strong>and</strong> loss are corrupted when ‘Big Players’derange markets (Koppl <strong>and</strong> Yeager 1996; Butos <strong>and</strong> Koppl 1993).Yeager <strong>and</strong> I def<strong>in</strong>e a Big Player as ‘anyone who habitually exercisesdiscretionary power to <strong>in</strong>fluence the market while himselfrema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g wholly or largely immune from the discipl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it<strong>and</strong> loss’ (Koppl <strong>and</strong> Yeager 1996:368). An <strong>in</strong>terventionist f<strong>in</strong>ancem<strong>in</strong>ister is our paradigm <strong>of</strong> a Big Player. But a Big Player may be anyactor who comb<strong>in</strong>es three th<strong>in</strong>gs, namely, the power to <strong>in</strong>fluencemarkets, a degree <strong>of</strong> immunity from competition <strong>and</strong> use <strong>of</strong>discretion <strong>in</strong> the exercise <strong>of</strong> his power. We produce qualitative <strong>and</strong>statistical evidence that Big Players <strong>in</strong>duce herd<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> asset markets<strong>and</strong> thus reduce market efficiency.The po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> the Big Players theory can be put <strong>in</strong> Schutzian terms.It is a matter <strong>of</strong> psychological expectations. Big Players divert eachtrader’s attention from underly<strong>in</strong>g conditions <strong>of</strong> supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>towards the personality <strong>of</strong> the Big Player. It is hard to know what aBig Player will do. Traders must base their expectations on a picture<strong>of</strong> the market <strong>in</strong> which a highly non-anonymous personal type isprom<strong>in</strong>ent. But this picture is always more or less dubious. Traderscome to place a lower weight on their own expectations <strong>and</strong> moreweight <strong>in</strong> the op<strong>in</strong>ions <strong>of</strong> other traders. The importance <strong>of</strong> thisnon-anonymous type <strong>and</strong> the ignorance <strong>and</strong> uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty traders feelregard<strong>in</strong>g the Big Player encourage them to follow the trend. BigPlayers encourage herd<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> asset markets.The po<strong>in</strong>t may also be put <strong>in</strong> Hayekian evolutionary terms. It is amatter <strong>of</strong> dispositional expectations. The presence <strong>of</strong> Big Playersdestabilises the evolutionary environment. The disposition to followtrends is less likely to br<strong>in</strong>g losses; the disposition to respond t<strong>of</strong>undamentals is more likely to produce losses. Big Players make luckcount for more, skill count for less. Traders who survive marketcompetition under Big Players will have a higher average propensityto herd. Big Players encourage herd<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> asset markets.In the Big Players theory psychological <strong>and</strong> dispositional76


THE SUBJECTIVISM OF ACTIVE MINDSexpectations fit together. This complementarity is a strength <strong>of</strong>the theory. Keynes’s treatment <strong>of</strong> long-run expectations runsmostly <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> psychological expectations. It is not clear, <strong>in</strong>his analysis, what <strong>in</strong>stitutional properties <strong>of</strong> asset marketsencourage the perversities he identifies <strong>and</strong> what propertiesdiscourage them. (Keynes refers only to liquidity.) Rationalexpectations models refer, presumably, to dispositionalexpectations. They seem to imply that psychologicalexpectations are perfectly plastic, tak<strong>in</strong>g on whatever form isneeded to generate the predicted behaviour. As Thomas Sargenthas noted, this may imply that economic agents know withcerta<strong>in</strong>ty the very structural parameters <strong>of</strong> the economy thateconometricians can only estimate with uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty (Sargent1993:21). The examples <strong>of</strong> Keynes <strong>and</strong> rational expectationshelp to show that we should prefer economic arguments thatcomb<strong>in</strong>e <strong>and</strong> correlate plausible treatments <strong>of</strong> both psychological<strong>and</strong> dispositional expectations.Dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g dispositional <strong>and</strong> psychological expectationshelps us to see how we might fit Schutz <strong>and</strong> Hayek <strong>in</strong>to a consistenttheory <strong>of</strong> expectations. The Big Players theory suggests the utility <strong>of</strong>do<strong>in</strong>g so. The proposed <strong>in</strong>tegration seems to yield testablehypotheses. It may be true, then, that <strong>in</strong>tegrat<strong>in</strong>g Schutz <strong>and</strong> Hayekwill help to solve the Lachmann problem.ConclusionThe Lachmann problem was stated at least as early as 1943. For themost part it has rema<strong>in</strong>ed unsolved. Some progress has been madeby Lachmann <strong>and</strong> others through the recognition <strong>of</strong> theco-ord<strong>in</strong>ative function <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions, ‘nodal po<strong>in</strong>ts’ <strong>of</strong>co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation as Lachmann called them. But much rema<strong>in</strong>s to bedone. I conjecture that this <strong>in</strong>tractability has been due <strong>in</strong> part to atendency by researchers follow<strong>in</strong>g Lachmann to look for eitherKeynesian or Misesian solutions. If <strong>in</strong>stead we try to placeconsiderations <strong>of</strong> anonymity raised by Schutz <strong>in</strong> a Hayekian context<strong>of</strong> social evolution, we may make more progress.AcknowledgementsI thank William Butos for useful comments. Any deficiencies <strong>of</strong> thetext are my fault.77


ROGER KOPPLNotes1 For an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g discussion <strong>of</strong> ‘Vision’ <strong>and</strong> analysis <strong>in</strong> economics seeBoettke 1992.2 Today the term ideal type is commonly used only for the typification <strong>of</strong>science, especially social science. In his Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the SocialWorld (1932) Schutz used the term ‘ideal type’ to refer to both thetypifkations <strong>of</strong> common sense <strong>and</strong> those <strong>of</strong> science.3 I have been ignor<strong>in</strong>g the difference between the thoughts <strong>of</strong> agents <strong>and</strong>our representations <strong>of</strong> those thoughts. This difference can matter. Asfar as I can tell, however, it doesn’t matter for the po<strong>in</strong>ts be<strong>in</strong>g made <strong>in</strong>this paper.ReferencesBoettke, P.J. (1992) ‘<strong>Analysis</strong> <strong>and</strong> vision <strong>in</strong> economic discourse’, Journal <strong>of</strong>the History <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Thought, 14 (1):84–95.Butos, W.N. (1997) ‘Toward an Austrian theory <strong>of</strong> expectations’, Advances<strong>in</strong> Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s’, 4:75–94.Butos, W.N. <strong>and</strong> Koppl, R.G. (1993) ‘Hayekian expectations: theory <strong>and</strong>empirical applications’, Constitutional Political Economy, 4 (3):303–29.——(1997) ‘The varieties <strong>of</strong> subjectivism: Keynes <strong>and</strong> Hayek onexpectations’, History <strong>of</strong> Political Economy, 29 (2):327–59.Keynes, J.M. ([1921] 1972) Collected Writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> John Maynard Keynes,vol. VIII, A Treatise on Probability, London: Macmillan.——([1936] 1972) Collected Writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> John Maynard Keynes, vol. VII,The General Theory <strong>of</strong> Money, Employment, <strong>and</strong> Interest, London:Macmillan.Knight, F.H. ([1921] 1971) Risk, Uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>and</strong> Pr<strong>of</strong>it, Chicago: TheUniversity <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press.Koppl, R.G. (1991) ‘Animal spirits’, Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Perspectives, 5(3): 203–10.——(1997) ‘Mises <strong>and</strong> Schutz on ideal types’, Cultural Dynamics, 9 (1):63–76.Koppl, R. <strong>and</strong> Yeager, L. (1996) ‘Big players <strong>and</strong> herd<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> asset markets: acase <strong>of</strong> the Russian ruble’, Explorations <strong>in</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> History, 33: 367–83.Lachmann, L. ([1943] 1977) ‘The role <strong>of</strong> expectations <strong>in</strong> economics as asocial science’, <strong>in</strong> Lachmann, L., Capital, Expectations, <strong>and</strong> the MarketProcess, ed. by Gr<strong>in</strong>der, W.E., Kansas City, Missouri: Sheed Andrews<strong>and</strong> McMeel, pp. 65–80.——([1969] 1977) ‘Methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism <strong>and</strong> the marketeconomy’, <strong>in</strong> Lachmann, L., Capital, Expectations, <strong>and</strong> the MarketProcess ed. by Gr<strong>in</strong>der, W.E., Kansas City, Missouri: Sheed Andrews <strong>and</strong>McMeel, pp. 149–65.——(1976) ‘From Mises to Shackle: an essay on Austrian economics <strong>and</strong>the Kaleidic Society’, Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Literature, 14 (1): 54–62.Lakatos, I. (1976) Pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Refutations: The Logic <strong>of</strong> MathematicalDiscovery, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.78


THE SUBJECTIVISM OF ACTIVE MINDSLanglois, R.N. (ed.) (1986) ‘Rationality, <strong>in</strong>stitutions, <strong>and</strong> explanation’, <strong>in</strong><strong>Economic</strong>s as a Process: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> the New Institutional <strong>Economic</strong>s,New York: Cambridge University Press.Langlois, R.N. <strong>and</strong> Koppl, R.G. (1991) ‘Fritz Machlup <strong>and</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>alism: areevaluation’, Methodus, 3 (2): 86–102.LeRoy, S.R. (1989) ‘Efficient capital markets <strong>and</strong> mart<strong>in</strong>gales’, Journal <strong>of</strong><strong>Economic</strong> Literature, 27 (4):1583–621.Machlup, F. (1952) The <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Sellers’ Competition: Model<strong>Analysis</strong> <strong>of</strong> Sellers’ Conduct, Baltimore: The Johns Hopk<strong>in</strong>s Press.——(1978) Methodology <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Other Social Sciences, NewYork, San Francisco <strong>and</strong> London: Academic Press.Mises, L.von ([1933a] 1981) ‘Conception <strong>and</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g’, <strong>in</strong>Epistemological Problems <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s, New York <strong>and</strong> London: NewYork University Press.——([1933b] 1981) ‘The science <strong>of</strong> human action’, <strong>in</strong> EpistemologicalProblems <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s, New York <strong>and</strong> London: New York UniversityPress.——(1943) ‘“Elastic expectations” <strong>and</strong> the Austrian theory <strong>of</strong> the tradecycle’, <strong>Economic</strong>a, N.S. 10 (39):251–2.——([1957] 1985) Theory <strong>and</strong> History: An Interpretation <strong>of</strong> Social <strong>and</strong><strong>Economic</strong> Evolution, Auburn University, Alabama <strong>and</strong> Wash<strong>in</strong>gton,DC: The <strong>Ludwig</strong> von Mises Institute.——(1963) Human Action, New Haven: Yale University Press.Runde, J. (1990) ‘Keynesian uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>and</strong> the weight <strong>of</strong> arguments’,<strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Philosophy, 6 (2):275–92.Sargent, T. (1993) Bounded Rationality <strong>in</strong> Macroeconomics, Oxford:Clarendon Press.Schumpeter, J.A. (1939) Bus<strong>in</strong>ess Cycles, 2 vols, New York: McGraw-Hill.Schutz, A. ([1932] 1967) The Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the Social World,Evanston, Ill<strong>in</strong>ois: Northwestern University Press.——(1967) The Collected Papers, vol. II, The Hague: Mart<strong>in</strong> Nijh<strong>of</strong>f.Vaughn, K. (1994) Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>in</strong> America: The Migration <strong>of</strong> aTradition, New York: Cambridge University Press.79


5SUBJECTIVISM ANDIDEAL TYPESLachmann <strong>and</strong> the methodologicallegacy <strong>of</strong> Max WeberLásló CsontosIntroductionThe follow<strong>in</strong>g essay is based on the conviction that a betterunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann’s <strong>and</strong> Max Weber’smethodological views is vital for a proper <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> themethodological groundwork <strong>of</strong> the social sciences. Two key elements<strong>in</strong> Max Weber’s much debated <strong>and</strong> multifarious methodologicallegacy are the subjectivism <strong>of</strong> the method <strong>of</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> thenotion <strong>of</strong> ideal types. In what follows, I want to contrast <strong>and</strong> comparewhat I believe to be Weber’s authentic methodological position onthese issues with Lachmann’s ideas about the subjectivism <strong>of</strong> thesocial sciences <strong>and</strong> his critique <strong>of</strong> Weber’s concept <strong>of</strong> ideal types.<strong>Subjectivism</strong>Lachmann considered himself an advocate <strong>of</strong> subjectivism <strong>in</strong> thecentral area <strong>of</strong> economic theory. ‘<strong>Subjectivism</strong>’ <strong>and</strong> ‘subjectivistmethodology’ are phrases with many mean<strong>in</strong>gs, however. They arenot very helpful when it comes to identify<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> describ<strong>in</strong>g aparticular methodological tradition. There is a thick conceptualunderbrush surround<strong>in</strong>g the very idea <strong>of</strong> subjectivism <strong>in</strong> thephilosophy <strong>of</strong> science that should be removed before we embarkupon clarify<strong>in</strong>g Lachmann’s methodological position. As a result,<strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g that his methodological attitude exemplifies80


SUBJECTIVISM AND IDEAL TYPESthis or that, or some ‘true’ version <strong>of</strong> subjectivism, I’d rather create aclean term<strong>in</strong>ological slate, <strong>and</strong> argue that Lachmann’s views can bebest described as belong<strong>in</strong>g to the general category <strong>of</strong> methodologicalsolipsism.I consider methodological solipsism as a variety <strong>of</strong> methodological<strong>in</strong>dividualism. 1 The programme <strong>of</strong> methodological solipsism seemsto be especially relevant to a thorough underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> themethodological underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> economic theory.Methodological solipsism, just like methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism,is founded on a dist<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>and</strong> def<strong>in</strong>ite view <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> socialreality. Methodological solipsism s ontological doctr<strong>in</strong>e, as a moreor less coherent picture <strong>of</strong> the world, can be reconstructed on thebasis <strong>of</strong> scattered remarks <strong>in</strong> the works <strong>of</strong> Hayek, Mises, Lachmann<strong>and</strong> others.The world, more precisely the world <strong>of</strong> human action is, accord<strong>in</strong>gto these authors, unimag<strong>in</strong>ably complex, <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>and</strong> multifaceted(see Hayek 1952a; Mises 1940). Its elements are constantly chang<strong>in</strong>g(Lachmann 1976) <strong>and</strong> its phenomena are <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>itely diverse (Hayek1952b, 1964). These complex phenomena <strong>and</strong> states <strong>of</strong> affairs areproduced by the <strong>in</strong>terplay <strong>of</strong> an endless number <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualcircumstances <strong>and</strong> qualitatively different causal sequences; <strong>and</strong> theyare always given to us as a tangled web <strong>of</strong> countless <strong>in</strong>dividual causes<strong>and</strong> effects (Mises 1940:45). Everyth<strong>in</strong>g hangs together witheveryth<strong>in</strong>g else <strong>in</strong> the world <strong>of</strong> human action, but social reality lacksany k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> objective structure. It doesn’t comprise regulatorypr<strong>in</strong>ciples that would br<strong>in</strong>g order <strong>in</strong>to the chaos <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualphenomena. I want to emphasise, however, that, accord<strong>in</strong>g to theauthors whose views we are discuss<strong>in</strong>g here, the world <strong>of</strong> naturalsciences, as opposed to social reality or the realm <strong>of</strong> human action, ishomogeneous, ordered <strong>and</strong> governed by causal uniformities (Hayek1964:25; Mises 1940:63).In Lachmann’s words:From a methodological po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view we may regard theeconomic thought <strong>of</strong> the last hundred years as marked by along drawn-out struggle between two contend<strong>in</strong>g forces,subjectivity <strong>and</strong> formalism. While the formalists present modelscharacterized by constant relationships between formal entities(even though these are <strong>in</strong> general supposed to reflect measurablemagnitudes), subjectivists see social phenomena as the outcome<strong>of</strong> human action guided by plans (even though these <strong>of</strong>ten fail)<strong>and</strong> prompted by mental acts. While subjectivist models also81


LÁSLÓ CSONTOS<strong>of</strong> course depict relationships between formal entities these neednot, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> a world <strong>of</strong> chang<strong>in</strong>g knowledge cannot, rema<strong>in</strong>constant.(Lachmann 1986:22–3)Or, as Lachmann (1986:48), quot<strong>in</strong>g Shackle (1972:76) approv<strong>in</strong>glynotes, ‘ours is “a kaleidic society, <strong>in</strong>terspers<strong>in</strong>g its moments or<strong>in</strong>tervals <strong>of</strong> order, assurance <strong>and</strong> beauty with sudden dis<strong>in</strong>tegration<strong>and</strong> a cascade <strong>in</strong>to a new pattern”’.F<strong>in</strong>ally, Lachmann (1986:30) fully shares Shackles view that‘economics, concerned with thoughts <strong>and</strong> only secondarily withth<strong>in</strong>gs, the objects <strong>of</strong> those thoughts, must be as protean as thoughtitself. To adopt a rigid frame <strong>and</strong> appeal exclusively to it is bound tobe fatal.’ The fact that<strong>in</strong> the real world knowledge requisite to action as a rule <strong>in</strong>volvesA’s knowledge <strong>of</strong> B’s knowledge <strong>of</strong> C’s knowledge compoundsthe difficulty for the economist as observer no less than for theagents hav<strong>in</strong>g to face it <strong>in</strong> reality.(Shackle 1972:246)It was not Hayek, Mises, Shackle or Lachmann, however, who firstthought out, formulated <strong>and</strong> brought to their logical conclusions thebasic tenets <strong>of</strong> methodological solipsism, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the ontologicalbeliefs discussed above. Although the most elemental components <strong>of</strong>this methodological position can be traced back to Carl Menger, itsconsequences as to the methodology <strong>of</strong> the social sciences, mostnotably economic theory, were first noted <strong>and</strong> systematically exploredby a now practically unknown, but at the turn <strong>of</strong> the century veryhighly regarded, German economist <strong>and</strong> philosopher <strong>of</strong> science,Friedrich von Gottl-Ottlilienfeld.I want to present a small collection <strong>of</strong> some <strong>of</strong> the metaphors thatexpress very clearly Gottl’s overall Weltgefühl <strong>and</strong>, at the same time,reveal the roots <strong>of</strong> the methodological position under discussion. 2Gottl compares <strong>and</strong> contrasts repeatedly ‘the greenness <strong>of</strong> life’ withgrey theories; talks about ‘the green reality <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g’; ‘the entangledweb <strong>of</strong> experience’, ‘current <strong>of</strong> events’, ‘events whirl<strong>in</strong>g around us’.He claims that ‘the occurrence <strong>of</strong> an act is a variation on the endlessmelody <strong>of</strong> life’ <strong>and</strong> he discusses ‘the surge <strong>of</strong> the colorful world’, ‘theendless sea <strong>of</strong> action’, ‘the warm life’, ‘the endless stream <strong>of</strong> the world<strong>of</strong> human action’, <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ally ‘the confus<strong>in</strong>g totality <strong>of</strong> connections’.There is no need to comment extensively on the ontological imagery82


SUBJECTIVISM AND IDEAL TYPES<strong>of</strong> Gottl. Clearly, if the world <strong>of</strong> human action can adequately bedescribed only <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> these <strong>and</strong> similar metaphors, then socialreality is unpredictable <strong>and</strong> irrational, <strong>and</strong> as such not fully accessibleto discursive reason<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> can at most be only partially understoodby the human m<strong>in</strong>d.If this is what social reality looks like, that is, enigmatic,<strong>in</strong>comprehensible, although everyth<strong>in</strong>g hangs together witheveryth<strong>in</strong>g else, then how do methodological solipsists describe socialrelations <strong>and</strong> how do they expla<strong>in</strong> the emergence <strong>of</strong> society? In theirview, society is made up <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>and</strong> isolated <strong>in</strong>dividuals(Hayek 1952b:50–1) who not only lack a common social knowledgeor common experiences but who are made even more isolated bytheir exist<strong>in</strong>g knowledge because the latter is scattered, imperfect,specific knowledge based on familiarity with particular circumstances(Hayek 1952b:29–30). 3 Isolated <strong>in</strong>dividuals organise <strong>in</strong>to societiesas a result <strong>of</strong> utilitarian considerations, although the emergence <strong>of</strong>organised societies can be an un<strong>in</strong>tended by-product <strong>of</strong> their actions.Accord<strong>in</strong>g to the proponents <strong>of</strong> methodological solipsism, theexchange relationship is the social relation par excellence, <strong>and</strong> thecement that holds society together is a general normative consensus(Mises 1940:125, 128, 167, 180–1).The ma<strong>in</strong> epistemological difficulty <strong>of</strong> this methodologicalprogramme lies <strong>in</strong> the assumption, however, that the ‘dispersion <strong>and</strong>imperfection <strong>of</strong> all knowledge is one <strong>of</strong> the basic facts from whichthe social sciences have to start’ (Hayek 1964:30). If this is the case,<strong>and</strong> if <strong>in</strong>dividuals—as implied by the ontological position describedabove—are bound together only by social relations modelled afterthe exchange relationship, then how do they underst<strong>and</strong>—or, as socialscientists, what k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> epistemological guarantees do we have thatwe will be able to underst<strong>and</strong>—the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> the words,gestures <strong>and</strong> actions <strong>of</strong> other human be<strong>in</strong>gs?On the basis <strong>of</strong> the premises sketched above, adherents <strong>of</strong>methodological solipsism seem to suggest there is only one possibleanswer to this question. We have to make the further assumption thatthere exists a mental structure common to all men, that is, the structure<strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g is the same for every human be<strong>in</strong>g, or, <strong>in</strong> other words, thestructure <strong>of</strong> human th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g is constant (Hayek 1964:23–4, 33–4;1952b:77–8, 102; Mises 1933:126). To put it more simply: we canunderst<strong>and</strong> human action only by accept<strong>in</strong>g the heuristic <strong>and</strong>scientifically unverifiable pr<strong>in</strong>ciple accord<strong>in</strong>g to which the uniformity<strong>of</strong> human nature guarantees that the act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividual has the samek<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> mental outfit, <strong>in</strong>tentions <strong>and</strong> objectives as we do. (The phrase83


LÁSLÓ CSONTOS‘a mental structure common to all people’ refers <strong>in</strong> this context to thisalleged fact, <strong>and</strong> not, as it usually does, to the universal validity <strong>of</strong> thelaws <strong>of</strong> logic.) Accord<strong>in</strong>gly, to recognise someth<strong>in</strong>g as a m<strong>in</strong>d meansto recognise it as someth<strong>in</strong>g analogous to our own m<strong>in</strong>d (Hayek1964:76–7; 1967:15, 18, 60). As a result, we underst<strong>and</strong> human actionby imput<strong>in</strong>g to the agent <strong>in</strong>tentions <strong>and</strong> objectives similar to ours. Weare epistemologically entitled to this analogical <strong>in</strong>ference for tworeasons. First, because <strong>of</strong> the postulated similarity <strong>of</strong> mental structures,<strong>and</strong> second, because we are act<strong>in</strong>g human be<strong>in</strong>gs as well, that is, wehave a first-h<strong>and</strong> knowledge <strong>of</strong> what it means to act <strong>in</strong> a certa<strong>in</strong> way.In Gottl’s openly irrationalistic language: the a priori <strong>and</strong> holisticallygiven personal experience <strong>of</strong> act<strong>in</strong>g makes it possible that we directlyunderst<strong>and</strong> human action on the analogy <strong>of</strong> our own past <strong>and</strong> presentactions (Gottl 1925:154, 161–2, 169, 244–5).These two assumptions, i.e., the ontological supposition <strong>of</strong> an<strong>in</strong>conceivably complex, ever-chang<strong>in</strong>g world <strong>of</strong> human action <strong>and</strong>the epistemological postulate <strong>of</strong> the direct <strong>in</strong>telligibility <strong>of</strong> humanaction by virtue <strong>of</strong> a legitimate analogical <strong>in</strong>ference, are meant tobolster another fundamental tenet <strong>of</strong> methodological solipsism.Representatives <strong>of</strong> methodological solipsism advocate rather extremeforms <strong>of</strong> methodological dualism (see Wright 1971).Methodological dualists tend to hold the follow<strong>in</strong>g views: (i)The subject matter <strong>of</strong> the social sciences is fundamentally differentfrom that <strong>of</strong> the natural sciences. It is human action <strong>in</strong> the first case<strong>and</strong> brute facts <strong>and</strong> lifeless uniformities <strong>in</strong> the second, (ii) Themethodological autonomy <strong>of</strong> social sciences is grounded <strong>in</strong> socialscientists’ unique <strong>and</strong> immediate access to the subject matter <strong>of</strong>their discipl<strong>in</strong>es. 4 (iii) Consequently, social scientists are able to useepistemic techniques, methods <strong>of</strong> analysis <strong>and</strong> explanatoryarguments unavailable <strong>and</strong> superior to those used by naturalscientists. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Gottl (1925:203), an early <strong>and</strong> radicalmethodological dualist, the scientific outlook is delirious withcausality <strong>and</strong> drunken with laws.The heavy emphasis on methodological dualism seems even moreparadoxical consider<strong>in</strong>g the fact that the orig<strong>in</strong>s <strong>of</strong> the ontologicalworld view <strong>of</strong> methodological solipsism can <strong>in</strong> all probability betraced back to the late n<strong>in</strong>eteenth century ‘scientific’ positivism <strong>of</strong>Mach <strong>and</strong> Avenarius. While Gottl’s views, as Max Weber had alreadypo<strong>in</strong>ted out (Weber 1975:211–12), could directly be l<strong>in</strong>ked to thissource, Hayek, Mises <strong>and</strong> Lachmann were <strong>in</strong>directly <strong>in</strong>fluenced bythis sort <strong>of</strong> positivism through their Austrian connections. Let meillustrate this by present<strong>in</strong>g some strik<strong>in</strong>g similarities.84


SUBJECTIVISM AND IDEAL TYPESIn the view <strong>of</strong> Avenarius (1891:6–7), the ‘naturalistic conception<strong>of</strong> the world’ is made up <strong>of</strong> two components. One <strong>of</strong> them is a generalexperience, the other is a hypothesis. The experience <strong>in</strong> question‘encompasses me <strong>and</strong> my environment, together with its constituentparts (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g my fellow human be<strong>in</strong>gs), plus certa<strong>in</strong> relationships’.The hypothesis under discussion ‘lies <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terpretation I give tothe motions <strong>of</strong> fellow human be<strong>in</strong>gs (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the l<strong>in</strong>guistic<strong>in</strong>struments <strong>and</strong> the noises <strong>and</strong> sounds used <strong>and</strong> made by them)—<strong>in</strong>the <strong>in</strong>terpretation that is, accord<strong>in</strong>g to which these motions areassertions (Aussagen) that refer to sounds, noises or tastes or wills orfeel<strong>in</strong>gs, etc. aga<strong>in</strong>, just like my words <strong>and</strong> deeds do.’ Somewhatlater Avenarius has this to say about the hypothesis under discussion:To say that other people are human be<strong>in</strong>gs just like me <strong>and</strong> Iam a human be<strong>in</strong>g just like they is noth<strong>in</strong>g but to assume thatmotions (<strong>and</strong> sounds) made by humans have not onlymechanistic mean<strong>in</strong>gs. This form <strong>of</strong> the hypothesis could becalled the card<strong>in</strong>al empiriocriticist assumption <strong>of</strong> basic humanequality.(Avenarius 1891:9)The objective structure <strong>of</strong> the world <strong>and</strong> reality, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Mach,falls apart <strong>in</strong>to unanalysable elements—sensations—<strong>and</strong> there areno permanent, constant or autonomous entities over <strong>and</strong> above theamorphous <strong>and</strong> chaotic mass <strong>of</strong> these sensations (Mach 1905:435–6; 1915: passim). Moreover, <strong>in</strong> Mach’s view, observ<strong>in</strong>g ‘other people’sbehavior…makes me assume…that my recollections, desires etc. existfor them only as a result <strong>of</strong> a compell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ference by analogy just astheir recollections, desires, etc. do for me’(Mach 1905:6).Notice, however, that although the hypothesis underly<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>v<strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g this <strong>in</strong>ference by analogy is <strong>in</strong>timately related to the worldview <strong>of</strong> methodological solipsism, it is not an ontological but anepistemological assumption, <strong>and</strong> as such belongs to the generalcategory <strong>of</strong> epistemological isolationism. I want to emphasise aga<strong>in</strong>though that its compell<strong>in</strong>g force (<strong>and</strong> the compell<strong>in</strong>g force <strong>of</strong> the<strong>in</strong>ference by analogy) derives from the world view under discussion.To fix ideas, let me review the epistemological stance <strong>of</strong>methodological solipsism. Suppose that on the basis <strong>of</strong> previousexperience we know what act<strong>in</strong>g means, that is, we know that humanaction always <strong>in</strong>volves beliefs, desires, objectives <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentions.Suppose also that these beliefs, desires, objectives <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentions arenot only the subjective data <strong>of</strong> actors but are also <strong>in</strong>accessible to85


LÁSLÓ CSONTOSoutside observers because outside observers can hardly do more thanto establish the fact <strong>of</strong> an action. If we make the further assumptionthat the thought processes <strong>of</strong> the actors are just like ours, then weare allowed to attribute beliefs, desires, objectives <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentions tothem on the analogy <strong>of</strong> our own mental states, mak<strong>in</strong>g their actionsthus directly <strong>and</strong> empathically underst<strong>and</strong>able to us.How do we learn about our own mental states <strong>and</strong> thus how dowe get to know the mental states <strong>of</strong> other people? Accord<strong>in</strong>g to one<strong>of</strong> the fundamental epistemological postulates <strong>of</strong> methodologicalsolipsism, we can learn about our own mental states only by way <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>trospection (Hayek 1964:44–5, 50, 75–6; Mises 1933:41, 122).Introspection is a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner perception, <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>of</strong> any bodilyorgan <strong>of</strong> sense, through which we can acquire (so the theory goes) as<strong>in</strong>gularly reliable form <strong>of</strong> self-knowledge. This <strong>in</strong>trospectively ga<strong>in</strong>edself-knowledge, as a result <strong>of</strong> the basic similarity <strong>of</strong> the human m<strong>in</strong>d<strong>and</strong> the commonalities <strong>of</strong> our mental structures, gives us direct accessto those thoughts, concepts <strong>and</strong> objectives with the help <strong>of</strong> which wecan underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>and</strong> collective attitudes <strong>and</strong> actionsobservable <strong>in</strong> the world around us. In the view <strong>of</strong> the advocates <strong>of</strong>methodological solipsism, this <strong>in</strong>trospective knowledge is not onlythe methodological start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t for the social sciences, but <strong>in</strong> itssubjective nature lies the ultimate explanation for the systematicsubjectivism <strong>of</strong> these sciences (Hayek 1952a: 192–3; 1964:50). Thisunique method <strong>of</strong> acquir<strong>in</strong>g knowledge <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation stretchesthe methodological rift between the social <strong>and</strong> the natural scienceseven further. While the natural sciences approach their subject mattermechanistically <strong>and</strong> externally (Mises 1940:27; Gottl 1925:255),social scientists possess a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> a priori <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal knowledge <strong>of</strong>their field <strong>of</strong> study, superior to the shallow knowledge <strong>of</strong> simple causalconnections (Mises 1933:122).The pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> epistemological isolationism has some veryunpleasant substantive <strong>and</strong> methodological consequences, however.To avoid them, methodological solipsists tend to qualify their positionby say<strong>in</strong>g, as Hayek (1952b:89–90) does, for example, that theassumption <strong>of</strong> the basic similarity <strong>of</strong> human consciousness is trueonly under certa<strong>in</strong> circumstances <strong>and</strong> that the likelihood <strong>of</strong>underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g the actions <strong>of</strong> other human be<strong>in</strong>gs dim<strong>in</strong>ishes as wemove away from our habitual <strong>and</strong> familiar social environment.Moreover, methodological solipsists are forced to admit that fromtheir epistemological po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view ‘crazy’ or mentally ill peoplecannot be considered part <strong>of</strong> humanity (Hayek 1964:79; Gottl1925:161), because it is doubtful that their mental structures are86


SUBJECTIVISM AND IDEAL TYPESsufficiently similar to that <strong>of</strong> social scientists to provide for a direct<strong>and</strong> empathic underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> their actions.Notice, however, that one <strong>of</strong> the unwelcome consequences <strong>of</strong> thismethodological pr<strong>in</strong>ciple would be to ban cultural <strong>and</strong> economicanthropology from the family <strong>of</strong> social sciences. It seems, for oneth<strong>in</strong>g, very unlikely that researchers <strong>of</strong> tribal-religious rites or <strong>of</strong>economic transactions <strong>in</strong> tribal societies, for <strong>in</strong>stance, could rely onthe k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>trospective knowledge that guides them more or lesssuccessfully through the mores <strong>of</strong> their own societies <strong>and</strong> cultures.Br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> epistemological isolationism to its logicalconclusion implies a denial <strong>of</strong> the adage, first formulated <strong>and</strong>vaguely expla<strong>in</strong>ed by Simmel <strong>and</strong> later fully v<strong>in</strong>dicated by MaxWeber (1978:5): ‘one need not have been Caesar <strong>in</strong> order tounderst<strong>and</strong> Caesar.’The third tenet <strong>of</strong> methodological solipsism is concerned with thelogical-methodological status <strong>of</strong> models <strong>and</strong> theories <strong>in</strong> the socialsciences. Adherents <strong>of</strong> the methodological programme underdiscussion tend to believe that the <strong>in</strong>formation provided by<strong>in</strong>trospection <strong>and</strong> the knowledge based thereupon are true simply byvirtue <strong>of</strong> our privileged access to this k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> thisk<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation. In Mises’ view, the theoretical statements <strong>of</strong> thesocial sciences are apodictically certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> a priori, that is,<strong>in</strong>dependently <strong>of</strong> any subsequent factual evidence, true (Mises1933:12, 26–7; 1940:18, 21; see also Hayek 1952b:51–3).Moreover, the social sciences do not strive for causalexplanations; their cognitive goal is to underst<strong>and</strong> human behaviourthrough <strong>in</strong>trospection, <strong>and</strong> to classify <strong>and</strong> order <strong>in</strong>trospectivelyunderstood forms <strong>of</strong> behaviour (Hayek 1952b:91–2). Theories <strong>in</strong>the social sciences are not sets <strong>of</strong> laws, that is, hypotheses withexplanatory power <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>formative content to be bolstered byempirical evidence, but are, like logic <strong>and</strong> mathematics, collections<strong>of</strong> tautologies furnished by the above mentioned process <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>trospection. In other words, theories <strong>of</strong> complex phenomena arenot nomological (Hayek 1967:41); they cannot be used to establishcausal connections. Thus economics, which, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Mises(1933:12, 27–9), is only a part <strong>of</strong> praxeology, i.e., the general theory<strong>of</strong> human action, is not an empirical but an a priori science, thetheorems <strong>of</strong> which are timeless <strong>and</strong> unchang<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> cannot beverified or falsified on the basis <strong>of</strong> empirical data or evidence. Agiven theory rema<strong>in</strong>s true as long as mental errors or fallacious<strong>in</strong>ferences don’t blemish it <strong>and</strong> as long as it is free <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternalcontradictions. Marg<strong>in</strong>al utility theory or general equilibrium87


LÁSLÓ CSONTOStheory both belong to the realm <strong>of</strong> the ‘pure logic <strong>of</strong> choice’, i.e.,both <strong>of</strong> them are tautological constructs used to classify action typescreated or generated by <strong>in</strong>trospection <strong>and</strong> the researchers’theoretical imag<strong>in</strong>ation.Methodological solipsism imputes eternal validity to the theoreicalstatements <strong>of</strong> the social sciences just because they were formulatedon the basis <strong>of</strong> data to which we allegedly have privileged access,thus repudiat<strong>in</strong>g the trivial <strong>in</strong>sight accord<strong>in</strong>g to which the truth <strong>and</strong>reliability <strong>of</strong> our knowledge is guaranteed by its testability <strong>and</strong> notby the royal or less royal method that helped us acquire it. Notice,however, that the same argument is also be<strong>in</strong>g used to neutralise thetheoretical social sciences aga<strong>in</strong>st the impact <strong>of</strong> any eventual correctivemeasure grounded <strong>in</strong> empirical evidence.Let me recapitulate the reason<strong>in</strong>g that makes methodologicalsolipsists question the empirical nature <strong>of</strong> social sciences <strong>and</strong> rejectthe idea <strong>of</strong> factual verification or falsification. The argumentillustrates the <strong>in</strong>terconnections between the basic postulates <strong>of</strong>methodological solipsism. In Hayek’s view (1964:42, 65; 1967:21),for <strong>in</strong>stance, the social sciences can aim not at the ‘detailedexplanations’ supplied by the natural sciences, but at ‘explanations<strong>of</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple’ only; that is, at most they can, with the help <strong>of</strong> simplifiedmodels, provide an <strong>in</strong>tuitive underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> general pr<strong>in</strong>ciples. Thetruth value <strong>of</strong> an explanation <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple cannot be decided on thebasis <strong>of</strong> some k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> a mechanical test.The social sciences have to be content with explanations <strong>of</strong>pr<strong>in</strong>ciple because their subject matter is strik<strong>in</strong>gly complex <strong>and</strong> thenumber <strong>of</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>and</strong> specific conditions to be taken <strong>in</strong>to accountwhen try<strong>in</strong>g to construct a genu<strong>in</strong>e explanation is so large that noteven computers, not to mention the human m<strong>in</strong>d, are able to masterthem. Because the social sciences cannot devise simplifiedexperimental conditions, it is the same complexity that prevents themfrom check<strong>in</strong>g the validity <strong>of</strong> their explanations by subject<strong>in</strong>g themto the critique <strong>of</strong> facts <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> reality.It is noteworthy that Menger, although from a somewhat differentmethodological perspective, had already made a similar argument.In his view:the ma<strong>in</strong> objective <strong>of</strong> the method to be called exact <strong>in</strong> thefuture is…to establish strict laws <strong>of</strong> phenomena;…laws whichnot only appear to be uniform to us but their uniformity isguaranteed by the cognitive routes lead<strong>in</strong>g to them.(Menger 1883:38)88


SUBJECTIVISM AND IDEAL TYPESAccord<strong>in</strong>gly, ‘to check the exact theory <strong>of</strong> the national economy onthe basis <strong>of</strong> the totality <strong>of</strong> empirical reality is a methodologicalabsurdity.’ Or:try<strong>in</strong>g to corroborate the pure theory <strong>of</strong> the national economyby match<strong>in</strong>g it to the full reality <strong>of</strong> experience would be similarto the procedure followed by a mathematician who wouldwant to correct the theorems <strong>of</strong> geometry by measur<strong>in</strong>gobjects <strong>of</strong> the real world.(ibid.: 64)For Menger, the ‘full empirical reality <strong>of</strong> phenomena’ is just anothername for the complexity <strong>and</strong> totality <strong>of</strong> the real world, that is, forthe impenetrable mass <strong>of</strong> concrete events <strong>and</strong> sensationssurround<strong>in</strong>g us <strong>in</strong> the world <strong>of</strong> human actions. Of course, this fullempirical reality cannot be used to verify or refute the laws <strong>of</strong>economic theory, <strong>and</strong> thus our methods <strong>of</strong> discover<strong>in</strong>g them,comb<strong>in</strong>ed with the laws <strong>of</strong> logic, should vouch for their validity.This is, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Menger, only a temporary solution, however.Although these laws are basically <strong>in</strong>struments <strong>of</strong> causal explanationfor him, they are also founded <strong>in</strong> one particular segment <strong>of</strong>empirical reality, namely the economic aspect <strong>of</strong> the heterogeneousempirical phenomena. Hence the empirical validity <strong>of</strong> economiclaws can only be decided if we have at our disposal thecomprehensive <strong>and</strong> ‘exact’ theory that is able to embrace allimportant aspects, that is, the full reality, <strong>of</strong> these phenomena. Thisdigression was necessary to po<strong>in</strong>t out the similarities, implied by thecommon world view, between the position <strong>of</strong> Menger <strong>and</strong> that <strong>of</strong>methodological solipsism.F<strong>in</strong>ally, I want to say a few words about the alleged apodicticcerta<strong>in</strong>ty or a priori validity <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>trospectively obta<strong>in</strong>edtheoretical statements <strong>of</strong> the sciences <strong>of</strong> human action. Max Weberhad already answered some <strong>of</strong> these questions when he made adist<strong>in</strong>ction between the clarity <strong>and</strong> certa<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>and</strong>underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g on the one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> the validity <strong>of</strong> adequate causalexplanations on the other. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Weber, it is easy for us tocomprehend clearly <strong>and</strong> with great <strong>in</strong>ner certa<strong>in</strong>ty the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>forms <strong>of</strong> behaviour <strong>and</strong> types <strong>of</strong> action that we are either able toperform or that can be made empathically accessible to us throughsympathetic participation. The same is true <strong>of</strong> the rationalunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> mathematically or logically related propositions,the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> which can be grasped immediately <strong>and</strong>89


LÁSLÓ CSONTOSunambiguously. Although ‘every <strong>in</strong>terpretation’, says Weber,‘attempts to atta<strong>in</strong> clarity <strong>and</strong> certa<strong>in</strong>ty’, it does not really matter‘how clear an <strong>in</strong>terpretation as such appears to be from the po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong>view <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g, it cannot on this account claim to be the causallyvalid <strong>in</strong>terpretation. On this level it must rema<strong>in</strong> only a peculiarlyplausible hypothesis’ (Weber 1978:5)—a hypothesis, we may add,the truth value or validity <strong>of</strong> which can be decided only bycompar<strong>in</strong>g it with the facts <strong>of</strong> experience. Although the behaviour <strong>of</strong>Caesar or a mentally ill person may not be immediately accessible toour empathic underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, we may still be able to come up with arational <strong>in</strong>terpretation or causal explanation <strong>of</strong> their behaviour withthe help <strong>of</strong> our nomological knowledge <strong>and</strong> the behaviouraluniformities <strong>of</strong> psychopathology.The nomological knowledge Weber talks about is noth<strong>in</strong>g but aloose collection <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tersubjectively valid rules <strong>of</strong> experience,assign<strong>in</strong>g particular means to particular ends <strong>in</strong> a given society.Acquisition <strong>and</strong> consistent application <strong>of</strong> this nomologicalknowledge <strong>in</strong> a causal explanation or rational <strong>in</strong>terpretation is theprecondition for the ‘underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g’ <strong>of</strong> a tribal or religious rite or <strong>of</strong>an economic transaction that happens to take place <strong>in</strong> a social oreconomic sett<strong>in</strong>g different from ours. Possess<strong>in</strong>g this k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong>nomological knowledge <strong>and</strong> not the special status <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formationobta<strong>in</strong>ed through <strong>in</strong>trospection enables the social scientist to cope <strong>in</strong>his own society, <strong>and</strong> to underst<strong>and</strong> the behaviour <strong>and</strong> actions <strong>of</strong> hisfellow human be<strong>in</strong>gs. It is simply not true that ‘a m<strong>in</strong>d has a tw<strong>of</strong>old“privileged access” to its own do<strong>in</strong>gs, which makes its selfknowledge superior <strong>in</strong> quality, as well as prior <strong>in</strong> genesis, to its grasp<strong>of</strong> other th<strong>in</strong>gs’ (Ryle 1966:154).The last assumption would imply the absurdity that societyconsists <strong>of</strong> w<strong>in</strong>dowless monads who obta<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation about theirown m<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>and</strong> souls by a cont<strong>in</strong>uous process <strong>of</strong> non-sensuous <strong>in</strong>nerperception, <strong>and</strong> who would have to peek <strong>in</strong>to the other monadsthrough the miss<strong>in</strong>g w<strong>in</strong>dow to get a direct knowledge <strong>of</strong> theirm<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>and</strong> souls. In reality, however,the problem is…simply the methodological question <strong>of</strong> howwe establish, <strong>and</strong> how we apply, certa<strong>in</strong> sorts <strong>of</strong> law-likepropositions about the overt <strong>and</strong> the silent behaviour <strong>of</strong>persons. I come to appreciate the skill <strong>and</strong> tactics <strong>of</strong> a chessplayerby watch<strong>in</strong>g him <strong>and</strong> others play<strong>in</strong>g chess, <strong>and</strong> Ilearn that a certa<strong>in</strong> pupil <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>e is lazy, ambitious <strong>and</strong>witty by follow<strong>in</strong>g his work, notic<strong>in</strong>g his excuses, listen<strong>in</strong>g90


SUBJECTIVISM AND IDEAL TYPESto his conversation <strong>and</strong> compar<strong>in</strong>g his performances withthose <strong>of</strong> others. Nor does it make any important differenceif I happen myself to be that pupil. I can <strong>in</strong>deed listen tomore <strong>of</strong> his conversations, as I am the addressee <strong>of</strong> hisunspoken soliloquies; I notice more <strong>of</strong> his excuses, as I amnever absent, when they are made. On the other h<strong>and</strong>, mycomparison <strong>of</strong> his performances with those <strong>of</strong> others ismore difficult, s<strong>in</strong>ce the exam<strong>in</strong>er is himself tak<strong>in</strong>g theexam<strong>in</strong>ation, which makes neutrality hard to preserve <strong>and</strong>precludes the demeanour <strong>of</strong> the c<strong>and</strong>idate, when under<strong>in</strong>terrogation, from be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> good view.(Ryle 1966:169)By gett<strong>in</strong>g rid <strong>of</strong> the myth <strong>of</strong> the epistemological <strong>in</strong>evitability <strong>of</strong>analogical <strong>in</strong>ference <strong>in</strong> the social sciences, reject<strong>in</strong>g the fantasy <strong>of</strong>the absolute certa<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>trospective knowledge, <strong>and</strong> realis<strong>in</strong>g thatcausal explanations do not necessarily tarnish the vibrant <strong>and</strong>irrational reality <strong>of</strong> human action, we can get a more adequatepicture <strong>of</strong> the methodological discrepancies between the social <strong>and</strong>natural sciences. The alleged extreme methodological dualism <strong>of</strong> thesocial <strong>and</strong> natural sciences turns out to be a misconception <strong>of</strong> theirtrue relationship, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong> fact neither the natural sciences are able to<strong>of</strong>fer detailed explanations as Hayek seems to assume, nor are theexplanations <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> the social sciences ‘someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> an art’(Hayek 1967:18). The logical structure <strong>of</strong> explanations claim<strong>in</strong>gempirical validity shows far-reach<strong>in</strong>g similarities <strong>in</strong> both groups <strong>of</strong>sciences.If we reject the tenets <strong>of</strong> methodological solipsism, we can alsodismiss the case aga<strong>in</strong>st attempts at construct<strong>in</strong>g theories withexplanatory power <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>formative content <strong>in</strong> the social sciences <strong>in</strong>general, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> economics <strong>in</strong> particular. Similarly, the arguments putforward aga<strong>in</strong>st methodological solipsism raise serious doubtsabout the legitimacy <strong>of</strong> stripp<strong>in</strong>g much <strong>of</strong> modern economic theory<strong>of</strong> any connection to reality, <strong>of</strong> shield<strong>in</strong>g it from the control <strong>of</strong>empirical tests <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g it as a pure logic <strong>of</strong> choice, serv<strong>in</strong>gsolely heuristic <strong>and</strong> classificatory purposes. To avoid a possiblemisunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, let me emphasise that I do not want to banish thelogic <strong>of</strong> choice from economic theory. What I have been try<strong>in</strong>g toargue aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>in</strong> this chapter is simply the fallacious characterisation<strong>of</strong> the methodological foundations <strong>of</strong> the social sciences <strong>of</strong>fered byem<strong>in</strong>ent researchers who, unfortunately enough, happen to beadvocates <strong>of</strong> the tenets <strong>of</strong> methodological solipsism.91


LÁSLÓ CSONTOSIdeal typesThis section <strong>of</strong>fers an analysis <strong>of</strong> the logic <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentionalexplanations by way <strong>of</strong> a partial rational reconstruction <strong>of</strong> MaxWeber’s views on the methodological foundations <strong>of</strong> economictheory. My aims are, first, to demonstrate that Lachmann, <strong>in</strong> at leastone important respect, misconstrued Weber’s methodologicallegacy; <strong>and</strong> second, to shed new methodological light on the notion<strong>of</strong> ideal types. The discussion will largely be based on Weber’swrit<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> the philosophy <strong>of</strong> science, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g a neglected earlyarticle that was first published <strong>in</strong> 1908 <strong>in</strong> the Archiv fürSozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik.Whereas the natural sciences, behaviouristically conceivedpsychology <strong>in</strong>cluded, deal with brute facts, the subject matter <strong>of</strong> thesocial sciences proper, argues Weber, is human action. Humanaction, however, whether <strong>in</strong>dividual or collective, cannot be takenas a factum brutum, because it is not someth<strong>in</strong>g given to us ex ante.That is, it is not someth<strong>in</strong>g given before or without analysis. On thecontrary, human action is someth<strong>in</strong>g that must be <strong>in</strong>terpreted orproperly understood before we go about expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g it. Lachmann isseem<strong>in</strong>gly <strong>in</strong> complete agreement with Weber. ‘Phenomena <strong>of</strong>human action’, he ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s:unlike phenomena <strong>of</strong> nature, are manifestations <strong>of</strong> thehuman m<strong>in</strong>d. Action has a mean<strong>in</strong>g to the agent. We areunable to underst<strong>and</strong> phenomena <strong>of</strong> human action otherwisethan as outward manifestations <strong>of</strong> human plans which mustexist before action is taken <strong>and</strong> which subsequently guide allaction. To underst<strong>and</strong> phenomena <strong>of</strong> action we thereforehave to elucidate those acts <strong>of</strong> the m<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> agents whichshape <strong>and</strong> steer their plans which <strong>in</strong> turn guide their overtaction. In other words, our task as social scientists isprimarily an <strong>in</strong>terpretative one: we have to elucidate themean<strong>in</strong>g observable human acts have to their respectiveagents.(Lachmann 1986:49)The upshot <strong>of</strong> this argument is that the ‘facts’ <strong>of</strong> the social sciencesare ‘artifacts’, <strong>in</strong> the sense that <strong>in</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> a pre-explanatory<strong>in</strong>terpretation we make them. In other words, when we set out toexpla<strong>in</strong> human action, first we have to construct the raw materialfor our explanations.92


SUBJECTIVISM AND IDEAL TYPESEconomists, argues Weber, take it for granted that people, <strong>in</strong>general, act purposefully or <strong>in</strong>tentionally. 5 This, Weber might havesaid, is a theoretically more fruitful hypothesis than (ap<strong>in</strong>g thenatural sciences) to conceive <strong>of</strong> human actors as puppets on thestr<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> obscure psychological stimuli or <strong>of</strong> mysterious socialforces. 6Second, economists not only assume that people <strong>in</strong> general arecapable <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentional action, but they add to this the furtherassumption that people—at least <strong>in</strong> economic matters or, moregenerally, <strong>in</strong> matters relat<strong>in</strong>g to their own <strong>in</strong>terests—do actcalculatively, that is, <strong>in</strong> this sense rationally. In Weber’s words:Marg<strong>in</strong>al utility theory, <strong>in</strong> order to atta<strong>in</strong> specific objects <strong>of</strong>knowledge, treats human action as if it ran its course frombeg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g to end under the control <strong>of</strong> commercialcalculation—a calculation set up on the basis <strong>of</strong> all conditionsthat need to be considered. It treats <strong>in</strong>dividual ‘needs’ <strong>and</strong> thegoods available (or to be produced or to be exchanged) fortheir satisfaction as mathematically calculable ‘sums’ <strong>and</strong>‘amounts’ <strong>in</strong> a cont<strong>in</strong>uous process <strong>of</strong> bookkeep<strong>in</strong>g. It treatsman as an agent who constantly carries on ‘economicenterprise’, <strong>and</strong> it treats his life as the object <strong>of</strong> his ‘enterprise’controlled accord<strong>in</strong>g to calculation. The outlook <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong>commercial bookkeep<strong>in</strong>g is, if anyth<strong>in</strong>g, the start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong>the constructions <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al utility theory.(Weber 1908:32)If <strong>in</strong>dividual people, <strong>in</strong> the light <strong>of</strong> everyday experience, really do act<strong>in</strong>tentionally <strong>and</strong> calculatively, then <strong>in</strong> the great majority <strong>of</strong>economically relevant cases, we can regard their actions as means toachieve a desired end. 7 This is equivalent to say<strong>in</strong>g that we canfrequently expla<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual actions <strong>and</strong> collective outcomes byreferr<strong>in</strong>g to the particular ends people are seek<strong>in</strong>g to achieve. Wecan call explanations couched <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> means <strong>and</strong> goals<strong>in</strong>tentional explanations <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual actions <strong>and</strong> teleologicalfunctionalexplanations <strong>of</strong> collective outcomes.In a similar ve<strong>in</strong>, Lachmann suggests, ‘actors, <strong>in</strong>dividuals as wellas groups, pursue many purposes simultaneously <strong>and</strong> have toestablish an order <strong>of</strong> priority among them. Moreover, the manifoldconstra<strong>in</strong>ts imposed upon the pursuit <strong>of</strong> our ends by the scarcity <strong>of</strong>means as well as by the ubiquitous presence <strong>of</strong> obstacles, actual orpotential (negative means), compels all <strong>of</strong> us to br<strong>in</strong>g all our means93


LÁSLÓ CSONTOS<strong>and</strong> ends with<strong>in</strong> the framework <strong>of</strong> a comprehensive computationbefore we set out on our course <strong>of</strong> action’ (Lachmann 1971:34).The social sciences, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Lachmann, should follow whathe calls the praxeological method. In a brief outl<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> the scope <strong>and</strong>nature <strong>of</strong> this method, Lachmann presents the follow<strong>in</strong>gcharacterisation:Human action is not determ<strong>in</strong>ate, but neither is it arbitrary.It is bounded, firstly, by the scarcity <strong>of</strong> means at the disposal<strong>of</strong> actors. This circumstance imposes a constra<strong>in</strong>t on thefreedom <strong>of</strong> action. It is bounded, secondly, by thecircumstance that, while men are free to choose ends topursue, once they have made their choice they must adhere toit if consistent action with a chance <strong>of</strong> success is to bepossible at all. In other words, human action is free with<strong>in</strong> anarea bounded by constra<strong>in</strong>ts. Obstacles <strong>of</strong> various k<strong>in</strong>dsfurther limit the area <strong>of</strong> freedom.(Lachmann 1971:37)The praxeological method has to take these circumstances <strong>in</strong>toaccount. Causal explanation <strong>in</strong> the field <strong>of</strong> action cannot hope toatta<strong>in</strong> determ<strong>in</strong>ateness, but this does not mean that we must giveup all hope <strong>of</strong> explanation. What we may hope to accomplish hereis to be able to show to what ends, means <strong>and</strong> obstacles humanaction is oriented. Orientation thus emerges as a concept asfundamental to praxeological study as determ<strong>in</strong>ateness is tonatural science (ibid.: 37).Let me try to elucidate the logical structure <strong>of</strong> the abovearguments <strong>and</strong> the logic <strong>of</strong> teleological explanations <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualhuman action with the help <strong>of</strong> a simple example. 8 Suppose weobserved the conduct <strong>of</strong> a certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual, B, <strong>and</strong> we found, after<strong>in</strong>tentionalistically <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g her action, that she did x, where xdenotes a particular action type or action. In other words, wesuppose that we have succeeded <strong>in</strong> giv<strong>in</strong>g an empirically soundanswer to a ‘What did B do?’ type <strong>of</strong> question, <strong>and</strong> the answer,astonish<strong>in</strong>gly enough, turned out to be: ‘B did x.’Now suppose that, as good <strong>and</strong> curious scholars, we do not stophere, but go a step further, <strong>and</strong> decide to f<strong>in</strong>d out: ‘Why did B do x?’How can we answer, or, for that matter, how do economists answerthese k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> ‘Why?’ questions? Of course, by construct<strong>in</strong>g idealtypes <strong>of</strong> human action <strong>and</strong> putt<strong>in</strong>g forward empiricalgeneralisations, Weber replied. Lachmann, however, f<strong>in</strong>ds this94


SUBJECTIVISM AND IDEAL TYPESanswer unsatisfactory. He not only repudiates the use <strong>of</strong> empiricalgeneralisations <strong>in</strong> the social sciences as tenuous at best <strong>and</strong>irrelevant at worst, 9 but also rejects the very notion <strong>of</strong> ideal types.His argument is worth quot<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> full:there is one (to us overwhelm<strong>in</strong>g) reason why we are unable toaccept the ideal type as our fundamental concept. The reasonlies <strong>in</strong> the simple fact that Weber’s ideal type lacks any specificreference to human action <strong>and</strong> seems to be as readilyapplicable to the animal k<strong>in</strong>gdom or the plant world as to thehuman sphere. It seems better to start our journey on morepromis<strong>in</strong>g ground <strong>and</strong> adopt as our fundamental concept anotion germane to human action, a notion, that is, <strong>in</strong> whichthe mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> action is preconceived even before the verymoment at which the course <strong>of</strong> action beg<strong>in</strong>s to unfold.(Lachman 1971:29)Lachmann then proceeds to make a case for substitut<strong>in</strong>g his notion<strong>of</strong> a ‘plan’ for that <strong>of</strong> the ideal type. Weber, argues Lachmann:po<strong>in</strong>ts out that causal explanation is just as necessary <strong>in</strong>culture as <strong>in</strong> nature. But <strong>in</strong> the former case ‘its specificsignificance rests only <strong>in</strong> that we are able, <strong>and</strong> want, notmerely to state but to underst<strong>and</strong> human action’. Thepossibility <strong>of</strong> such underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g is warranted by thepurposive character <strong>of</strong> human action. But ‘purpose’, he says,‘is for us an imag<strong>in</strong>ed end which becomes the cause <strong>of</strong> anaction; we take account <strong>of</strong> it <strong>in</strong> the same way as we have totake account <strong>of</strong> any other cause which does, or may,contribute to a significant effect.(Lachmann 1971:32–4)Then Lachmann adds:It is readily seen (with the benefit <strong>of</strong> h<strong>in</strong>dsight) that thisconception <strong>of</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> causal explanation <strong>of</strong> humanaction <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> purpose would have provided a firmer <strong>and</strong>more convenient start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t for the methodology <strong>of</strong> thesocial sciences than the controversial notion <strong>of</strong> the Ideal Type.It is also easy to see how it is naturally l<strong>in</strong>ked to our concept <strong>of</strong>Plan. In fact, ‘plan’ is but a generalization <strong>of</strong> purpose.(ibid.: 32–4)95


LÁSLÓ CSONTOSBut what exactly do the terms ‘ideal type’ <strong>and</strong> ‘plan’ mean <strong>in</strong> thiscontext? 10 My purpose <strong>in</strong> propos<strong>in</strong>g a rational reconstruction <strong>of</strong>these notions is aga<strong>in</strong> tw<strong>of</strong>old. First, I want to substantiate myearlier claim that Lachmann misunderstood, <strong>and</strong> consequentlymisconstrued, Weber’s methodological legacy at least <strong>in</strong> oneimportant respect. Second, I want to show that the concepts <strong>of</strong> plan<strong>and</strong> ideal types can be fruitfully united under the methodologicalumbrella <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentional explanation.Let us return to the ‘Why did B do x?’ question. Suppose weknow from the outset that B wanted <strong>and</strong> managed to achieve y,where y st<strong>and</strong>s for some desired end. For simplicity’s sake, let’smake the further assumption that the only means to be taken <strong>in</strong>toaccount, if a means is to be taken <strong>in</strong>to account at all, or the onlymeans B had considered if she had considered any means at all, wasnoth<strong>in</strong>g else but the action x. Could we then put forward thefollow<strong>in</strong>g argument?1 B wanted to achieve y.2 The only means to achieve y was action x. Therefore,3 B did x.Clearly, we cannot always expla<strong>in</strong> B’s action this way. First, B maynot have known that x was a means to achieve y, <strong>in</strong> which case shedid x perhaps for some other reason, <strong>and</strong> obta<strong>in</strong>ed y only as a fluke.Second, B may have acted on a wrong reason, that is, she may havebelieved, mistakenly, that x was the only means to achieve y,whereas <strong>in</strong> fact x was not an effective means to this end at all.We can take care <strong>of</strong> these possibilities, Weber came to argue later,<strong>in</strong> either <strong>of</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g two ways. The first option is to show, byfactor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the agent’s epistemic situation, 11 that B, given her beliefsabout the relevant means-ends relationships, acted <strong>in</strong> a subjectivelyrational way. The second route is to exam<strong>in</strong>e what B should or couldhave done, had she acted <strong>in</strong> accordance with the objective logic <strong>of</strong>the situation, that is <strong>in</strong> an objectively rational fashion. 12 It is easy tosee that construction <strong>of</strong> what Weber calls subjectively rational idealtypes, pace Lachmann, produces straightforward <strong>in</strong>tentional orteleological explanations <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual action. Objectively rationalideal types, however, as explanatory frameworks have only, asWeber po<strong>in</strong>ts out, <strong>in</strong>strumental <strong>and</strong> heuristic value. 13Thus the logical structure <strong>of</strong> a subjectively rational ideal type isthe same as that <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>tentional explanation. In the simplestpossible case the explanatory argument runs as follows:96


SUBJECTIVISM AND IDEAL TYPES1 B wanted to achieve y.2 B thought (believed) that she could achieve y best by do<strong>in</strong>g x.Therefore3 B did x.When we construe empirically adequate ideal types <strong>of</strong> this k<strong>in</strong>d,then, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Weber, we arrive at a motivational, as dist<strong>in</strong>ctfrom actual, underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> human action. ‘Actual’underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g is equivalent to select<strong>in</strong>g the ‘right’, i.e., theempirically adequate, <strong>in</strong>tentionalistic description. 14 Motivationalunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, argues Weber, rests on our nomological knowledge.To have the required type <strong>and</strong> amount <strong>of</strong> nomological knowledge atour disposal is the same as to know—either by acqua<strong>in</strong>tance or bydescription—the rules <strong>of</strong> experience that <strong>in</strong> the eyes <strong>of</strong> people liv<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong> a particular society or culture assign given means to given ends.In the case <strong>of</strong> objectively rational ideal types the reason<strong>in</strong>g ishypothetical, <strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>strumental or technical sense <strong>of</strong> theword, normative. Tak<strong>in</strong>g as our paradigm the simplest possiblesituation aga<strong>in</strong>, we have the follow<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>ed maximisationtype argument.1 Let us assume BB wanted to achieve y.2 In the light <strong>of</strong> the available evidence, <strong>and</strong> under the exist<strong>in</strong>gconstra<strong>in</strong>ts, B could have achieved y only if she had done x.Therefore3 B should have done x.It requires only a modicum <strong>of</strong> methodological imag<strong>in</strong>ation torecognise <strong>in</strong> the forego<strong>in</strong>g primitive models the germ or analyticalcore <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al utility or, for that matter, modern microeconomictheory. In fact, argued Weber, economic analysis is founded not onsome allegedly fundamental psychological laws, but on the use <strong>of</strong>the categories ‘ends’ <strong>and</strong> ‘means’, that is, on the use <strong>of</strong> more or lesssophisticated ‘praxeological’ ideal types (Weber 1908:3).Conclusion<strong>Economic</strong> analysis, for both Weber <strong>and</strong> Lachmann, is possible onlybecause we are capable <strong>of</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividual humanconduct. By imput<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tentions (or, <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’s term<strong>in</strong>ology,plans) to persons, we <strong>in</strong>terpret <strong>in</strong>dividual behaviour as deliberate,subsume it under some specific ‘action type’ (utility maximisation,97


LÁSLÓ CSONTOScost m<strong>in</strong>imisation, etc.), <strong>and</strong> clear the ground for an <strong>in</strong>tentionalexplanation <strong>of</strong> a particular <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>of</strong> the action type <strong>in</strong> question.This is the rational core, if there is one, <strong>of</strong> the more radicalsubjectivist claims <strong>of</strong> methodological solipsism.Intentional explanations <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual actions <strong>in</strong> economictheory, Lachmann’s misguided criticism notwithst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, arebased on ideal types. Ideal types, <strong>in</strong> turn, are theoreticalconstructs, the logical structure <strong>of</strong> which is just about the same <strong>in</strong>both the natural <strong>and</strong> the social sciences. Moreover, the use <strong>of</strong>properly constructed ideal types is methodologically fundamental,because these constructs fulfil <strong>in</strong>dispensable classificatory,heuristic, <strong>and</strong> explanatory functions (Weber 1978:21). Theconstra<strong>in</strong>ed maximisation models <strong>of</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard economic theory,for <strong>in</strong>stance, help us pigeonhole economic behaviour <strong>in</strong>to thecategories <strong>of</strong> expected utility maximisation, pr<strong>of</strong>it maximisation,price discrim<strong>in</strong>ation, etc. Furthermore, if we want to expla<strong>in</strong> aparticular <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>of</strong> any <strong>of</strong> these categories (the actions taken bythe managers <strong>of</strong> a specific firm, for example), <strong>and</strong> it turns out thatthese actions deviate from the course <strong>of</strong> action ‘prescribed’ orpredicted by our pet model, we are still go<strong>in</strong>g to have to use ourideal type as a benchmark, because without hav<strong>in</strong>g that heuristicdevice at our disposal we will not be able to arrive at mean<strong>in</strong>gfulhypotheses about the possible causes <strong>of</strong> this clash between theory<strong>and</strong> reality.Notes1 For a good overview <strong>of</strong> different forms <strong>of</strong> methodological<strong>in</strong>dividualism see Bhargava (1992). The term ‘methodologicalsolipsism’ itself was first used <strong>in</strong> a somewhat different sense from theone <strong>in</strong>tended here (Carnap 1928).2 We should heed Schumpeter s advice with regard to Gottl’s work: ‘Ifear that the only way <strong>of</strong> appreciat<strong>in</strong>g Pr<strong>of</strong>essor F. von Gottl-Ottlilienfeld, who held a conspicuous place <strong>and</strong> found manyadherents…is to read him’ (Schumpeter 1954:854). For a sympathetic<strong>and</strong> tolerant, but <strong>in</strong> the end devastat<strong>in</strong>g, criticism <strong>of</strong> Gottl’s views onthe epistemology <strong>of</strong> the social sciences, see Weber’s essay on ‘Knies <strong>and</strong>the problem <strong>of</strong> irrationality’ (Weber 1975). In Weber’s view, Gottl:scrupulously eschews conventional, conceptually bound,<strong>and</strong>, from his po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view, ‘denatured’ language. Instead,he attempts to reproduce the contents <strong>of</strong> immediate‘experience’ <strong>in</strong> some sort <strong>of</strong> ideogram. Admittedly, many <strong>of</strong>Gottl’s views, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the pr<strong>in</strong>cipal theses <strong>of</strong> his work, arecontroversial. Nor has he succeeded <strong>in</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g genu<strong>in</strong>e98


SUBJECTIVISM AND IDEAL TYPESconclusions. Nevertheless, this idiosyncratic work must berecognised for what it is: a subtle <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectually stimu-lat<strong>in</strong>gillum<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> the problem.(Weber 1975:212)3 Although the logic <strong>of</strong> this reason<strong>in</strong>g is very similar to Hayek’sepistemic argument aga<strong>in</strong>st central plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> socialism, themethodological status <strong>of</strong> the two arguments is very different.4 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Lachmann:Natural phenomena exist <strong>in</strong> time <strong>and</strong> space only, <strong>and</strong> observabilityis the only criterion <strong>of</strong> their existence. The fact, on theother h<strong>and</strong>, that human action exists <strong>in</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> plans, i.e.mental design, permits us to study the relationships betweenhuman action <strong>and</strong> the plans which guide it. The method <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>in</strong> the social sciences ultimately rests on thepossibility <strong>of</strong>, <strong>and</strong> the need for, such comparative study. In thissense, then, we may say that we are able to give an ‘<strong>in</strong>telligibleaccount’ <strong>of</strong> human action by reveal<strong>in</strong>g the plans which guide it,a task beyond the grasp <strong>of</strong> the natural sciences. The mere factthat this possibility exists is the foundation <strong>of</strong> the method <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>and</strong> thus <strong>of</strong>fers a v<strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> the plea for themethodological autonomy <strong>of</strong> the social sciences.(Lachmann 1971:30)5 Cf. Weber:In the economic theory <strong>of</strong> marg<strong>in</strong>al utility <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> every ‘subjective’value theory…there is, to beg<strong>in</strong> with, not an external ‘stimulus’but a ‘need’. This is <strong>of</strong> course the reverse <strong>of</strong> the situation we have<strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> the fundamental law <strong>of</strong> psychophysics. Accord<strong>in</strong>gly,if we wish to express ourselves <strong>in</strong> ‘psychological’ terms, we dealwith a complex <strong>of</strong> ‘sensations’, ‘feel<strong>in</strong>g-states’, states <strong>of</strong> ‘tension’,‘discomfort’, ‘expectation’, <strong>and</strong> the like, which may at any timebe <strong>of</strong> most <strong>in</strong>tricate character. And these, moreover, comb<strong>in</strong>e with‘<strong>memory</strong> images’, ‘purposes’, <strong>and</strong> perhaps conflict<strong>in</strong>g ‘motives’<strong>of</strong> the most various k<strong>in</strong>ds. Also, while the fundamental law <strong>of</strong>psychophysics <strong>in</strong>structs us about how an external stimulus evokespsychic conditions,…economics, rather, is concerned with thefact that <strong>in</strong> virtue <strong>of</strong> such ‘psychic’ conditions a specificallyoriented external behaviour (action) is evoked.(Weber 1908:27–8)6 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Weber:It is not only that, at least by <strong>and</strong> large, the most generalhypotheses <strong>and</strong> assumptions <strong>of</strong> the ‘natural sciences’ (<strong>in</strong> theusual sense <strong>of</strong> this term) are the most irrelevant ones for ourdiscipl<strong>in</strong>e. But further, <strong>and</strong> above all, precisely as regards the99


LÁSLÓ CSONTOSpo<strong>in</strong>t which is decisive for the peculiar quality <strong>of</strong> the questionsproper to our discipl<strong>in</strong>e: In economic theory (‘value theory’) west<strong>and</strong> entirely on our own feet.(Weber 1908:31)7 ‘Marg<strong>in</strong>al utility theory <strong>and</strong>, more broadly, any subjective theory <strong>of</strong>value are not psychologically, but—if a methodological term isdesired—“pragmatically” founded, that is, on the use <strong>of</strong> the categories“ends” <strong>and</strong> “mans”’ (Weber 1908:33).8 On what follows see also Langlois <strong>and</strong> Csontos (1993).9 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Lachmann:Some readers may feel that <strong>in</strong> doubt<strong>in</strong>g whether there is muchscope <strong>in</strong> economics for empirical generalisations <strong>of</strong> acomprehensive character, apply<strong>in</strong>g equally to future <strong>and</strong> past,we have gone too far. They may rem<strong>in</strong>d us that <strong>in</strong> the Austriantradition all economic action is embedded <strong>in</strong> a network <strong>of</strong> means<strong>and</strong> ends.…Mises even attributed a priori character to thenetwork <strong>of</strong> means <strong>and</strong> ends, <strong>and</strong> Hayek <strong>in</strong> 1937 spoke <strong>of</strong> thispart <strong>of</strong> economics as the ‘pure logic <strong>of</strong> choice’. It is <strong>in</strong>deedevident that all human activity is purposeful. Why should such abody <strong>of</strong> thought have to be regarded as <strong>in</strong>capable <strong>of</strong> provid<strong>in</strong>g asolid basis for empirical generalisations <strong>of</strong> the k<strong>in</strong>d mentioned?The answer has to be that our network <strong>of</strong> means <strong>and</strong> ends,precisely by virtue <strong>of</strong> the logical necessity <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> it, isimpotent to engender empirical generalisations. Its truth ispurely abstract <strong>and</strong> formal truth. The means <strong>and</strong> ends itconnects are abstract entities. In the real world the concretemeans used <strong>and</strong> ends sought are ever chang<strong>in</strong>g as knowledgechanges <strong>and</strong> what seemed worthwhile yesterday no longer seemsso today. We appeal <strong>in</strong> va<strong>in</strong> to the logic <strong>of</strong> means <strong>and</strong> ends toprovide us with support for empirical generalisations <strong>of</strong> the k<strong>in</strong>dmentioned.(Lachmann 1971:3D10 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Weber:Now the tenets which constitute specifically economic theory donot represent,…‘the whole’ <strong>of</strong> our science. These tenets affordbut a s<strong>in</strong>gle means (<strong>of</strong>ten, to be sure, an underestimated means)for the analysis <strong>of</strong> the causal connections <strong>of</strong> empirical reality. Assoon as we take hold <strong>of</strong> this reality itself, <strong>in</strong> its culturallysignificant components, <strong>and</strong> seek to expla<strong>in</strong> it causally,economic history is immediately revealed as a sum <strong>of</strong> ‘idealtypical’concepts. This means that its theorems represent a series<strong>of</strong> conceptually constructed events, which, <strong>in</strong> ‘ideal purity’, areseldom, or even not at all, to be found <strong>in</strong> the historical reality <strong>of</strong>any particular time.(Weber 1908:33–4)100


SUBJECTIVISM AND IDEAL TYPESOn the structure <strong>and</strong> functions <strong>of</strong> ideal types, see further Weber(1978:6, 9, 20; 1949:50–113).11 Lachmann is pla<strong>in</strong>ly wrong when he asserts that hypotheses orempirical generalisations cannot be tested <strong>in</strong> the social sciences becauseit is impossible to specify knowledge. Cf. the follow<strong>in</strong>g characteristicstricture:The scientist who proposes an experiment to test his hypothesismust pay close attention to specify<strong>in</strong>g the conditions <strong>in</strong> whichthe experiment is to take place. But <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> human action,even were we to grant the existence <strong>of</strong> ‘universal laws’, it isimpossible to specify such an <strong>in</strong>itial situation for the simplereason that it is impossible to specify knowledge. Evidently theknowledge <strong>of</strong> the actor is an important element <strong>of</strong> his action.Were we to test hypotheses concern<strong>in</strong>g action, the canon <strong>of</strong>scientific method would require us to describe <strong>in</strong> detail all theknowledge possessed by the actors—an evident impossibility.We see thus that while ‘description <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>itial situation’ is afairly <strong>in</strong>nocuous requirement <strong>in</strong> nature, where all we have to dois enumerate objects <strong>in</strong> time <strong>and</strong> space, for human action thisrequirement cannot be met because we should have to <strong>in</strong>cludesometh<strong>in</strong>g unspecifiable—knowledge! A human situationwithout specific knowledge makes no sense. It follows that the‘scientific method’ <strong>of</strong> the natural sciences will be <strong>of</strong> little use tothe student <strong>of</strong> action because he is unable to use the test<strong>in</strong>gprocedure this method prescribes.(Lachmann 1971:35–6)12 Weber (1913) dist<strong>in</strong>guishes between subjectively rational <strong>and</strong>objectively rational ideal types (the latter he calls Richtigkeits-Typen)<strong>in</strong> ‘Über e<strong>in</strong>ige Kategorien der verstehenden Soziologie’; this essayrepresents his first attempt at a positive <strong>and</strong> systematic exposition <strong>of</strong>his methodological views.13 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Weber:[T]hese theorems—s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong> fact their elements are derived fromexperience <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensified to the po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> pure rationality only <strong>in</strong>a process <strong>of</strong> thought—are useful both as heuristic<strong>in</strong>strumentalities <strong>of</strong> analysis <strong>and</strong> as constructive means for therepresentation <strong>of</strong> the empirical manifold.(Weber 1908:34)14 On the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between actual <strong>and</strong> motivational underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g seeWeber (1978:8–13). ‘Actual’ underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g (aktuelles Verstehen) isrendered <strong>in</strong> the English translation, somewhat mislead<strong>in</strong>gly, as ‘directobservational’ underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g.101


LÁSLÓ CSONTOSReferencesAvenarius, R. (1891) Der menschliche Weltbegriff, Leipzig:O.R.Reisl<strong>and</strong>.Bhargava, R. (1992) Individualism <strong>in</strong> Social Science, New York: OxfordUniversity Press.Carnap, R. (1928) Der logische Aufbau der Welt, Berl<strong>in</strong>-Schlachtensee:Weltkreis-Verlag.Gottl-Ottlilienfeld, F.von (1925) Wirtschaft als Leben, Jena: Fischer Verlag.Hayek, F.A.von (1952a) The Sensory Order, Chicago: University <strong>of</strong>Chicago Press.——(1952b) Individualismus und wirtschaftliche Ordnung, Erlenbach-Zürich: E.Rentsch Verlag.——(1964) The Counter-Revolution <strong>of</strong> Science, Glencoe, Ill: The Free Press<strong>of</strong> Glencoe.——(1967) Studies <strong>in</strong> Philosophy, Politics, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s, Chicago:University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press.Lachmann, L.M. (1971) The Legacy <strong>of</strong> Max Weber, Berkeley: GlendessaryPress.——(1976) ‘From Mises to Shackle’, Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Literature, 14:55–6.——(1986) The Market as an <strong>Economic</strong> Process, Oxford: Blackwell.Langlois, R.N. <strong>and</strong> Csontos, L. (1993) ‘Optimization, rule follow<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong>the methodology <strong>of</strong> situational analysis’, <strong>in</strong> B.Gustaffson, C.Knudsen,<strong>and</strong> U.Müki (eds) Rationality, Institutions, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>Methodology, London: Routledge.Mach, E. (1905) Erkenntnis und Irrtum, Leipzig: J.A.Barth.——(1915) Die Analyse der Empf<strong>in</strong>dungen (6, vermehrte Auflage), Jena:Fischer Verlag.Menger, C. (1883) Untersuchungen Ober die Methode derSozialwissenschaften, Leipzig: Duncker <strong>and</strong> Humblot.Mises, L.von (1933) Grundgrobleme der Nationalökonomie, Jena: FischerVerlag.——(1940) Nationalökonomie, Genf: Ed. Union.Ryle, G. (1966) The Concept <strong>of</strong> M<strong>in</strong>d, London: Hutch<strong>in</strong>son.Schumpeter, J.A. (1954) History <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Analysis</strong>, New York: OxfordUniversity Press.Shackle, G.L.S. (1972) Epistemics <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s, Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.Weber, M. (1908) ‘Die Grenznutzenlehre und das “psychophysischeGrundgesetz”’, transl. as ‘Marg<strong>in</strong>al utility <strong>and</strong> “the fundamentallaws <strong>of</strong> psychophysics”’, The Social Science Quarterly (1975),56:21–36.——(1913) ‘Über e<strong>in</strong>ige Kategorien der verstehenden Soziologie’, <strong>in</strong>Gesammelte Autsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre, 4th edn, Tüb<strong>in</strong>gen: J.C.B.Mohr [1973].——(1949) ‘“Objectivity” <strong>in</strong> social science <strong>and</strong> social policy’, <strong>in</strong> TheMethodology <strong>of</strong> the Social Sciences, Glencoe, Ill: The Free Press <strong>of</strong>Glencoe.102


SUBJECTIVISM AND IDEAL TYPES——(1975) Roscher <strong>and</strong> Knies: The Logical Problems <strong>of</strong> Historical<strong>Economic</strong>s, New York <strong>and</strong> London: The Free Press.——(1978) Economy <strong>and</strong> Society, Berkeley: University <strong>of</strong> CaliforniaPress.Wright, G.H.von (1971) Explanation <strong>and</strong> Underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, Ithaca, NY:Cornell University Press.103


6ENDOGENOUS CHANGE,OPEN SYSTEMS ANDPROVISIONALEQUILIBRIUMMaurizio CasertaAlthough he dismissed it as an essentially <strong>in</strong>adequate construct for aproper underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the market process, equilibrium was arecurrent theme <strong>in</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> <strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann. He rejected theidea <strong>of</strong> equilibrium as an atta<strong>in</strong>able position <strong>of</strong> rest <strong>in</strong> which<strong>in</strong>dividual plans become mutually compatible; he also rejected theidea <strong>of</strong> equilibrium as a position towards which the economy tendsbut may never actually reach. The only notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium thatLachmann thought should be reta<strong>in</strong>ed was the notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualequilibrium. 1 This is the axiom <strong>of</strong> the purposeful <strong>in</strong>dividual.For Lachmann, the market process was to be viewed as asequence <strong>of</strong> actions <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>teractions. It would be understood bymeans <strong>of</strong> a voluntaristic theory <strong>of</strong> action where the freedom <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>dividuals’ will would represent a fundamental assumption. 2 The<strong>in</strong>clusion <strong>of</strong> this chapter <strong>in</strong> a memorial volume for <strong>Ludwig</strong>Lachmann is justified by this emphasis on action, which it shareswith all Austrian th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g. Such an emphasis enlarges the scope <strong>of</strong>economic analysis: <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>in</strong>stream economic analysis only reactions,that is, responses to known stimuli, are permitted; equilibrium isprecisely a state <strong>of</strong> affairs where no further reaction is justified.When action is contemplated, equilibrium can be either dismissedaltogether, or reconceived as identify<strong>in</strong>g a less def<strong>in</strong>itive state <strong>of</strong>affairs. The latter route is followed here.104


ENDOGENOUS CHANGEIntroductionAmong the different notions <strong>of</strong> equilibrium <strong>in</strong> economic theory, onecontends that equilibrium is a state <strong>of</strong> affairs that can be disruptedonly by an exogenous change. This fundamentally implies that allforeseeable changes have been discounted <strong>and</strong> that what is there tobe learned has been learned. This notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium, therefore, is<strong>in</strong>consistent with the emergence <strong>of</strong> novelty. Cont<strong>in</strong>uity cannot bepreserved if novelty emerges; such an occurrence will necessarilybreak cont<strong>in</strong>uity. As far as economic theory goes, such noveltiesrema<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>explicable.In Chick <strong>and</strong> Caserta (1994) a different notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium isput forward, <strong>in</strong> which it is argued that equilibrium <strong>and</strong> thepossibility <strong>of</strong> novelty are not necessarily <strong>in</strong>compatible. Equilibriumcan be dissolved from with<strong>in</strong> as well as from without. Cont<strong>in</strong>uitycan be preserved without hav<strong>in</strong>g to portray equilibrium asencompass<strong>in</strong>g all possible developments. All this becomessusta<strong>in</strong>able if equilibrium is not seen as the outcome <strong>of</strong> a fullyspecified model, where all cont<strong>in</strong>gencies have been taken <strong>in</strong>toaccount <strong>and</strong> where choice is predeterm<strong>in</strong>ed.A partially specified model implies that not all aspects <strong>of</strong> relevantbehaviour have been spelled out nor that all the relevant actors havebeen <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the picture. This partial specification, however,does not render the model necessarily wrong. This would be the caseif those aspects <strong>of</strong> behaviour or those actors were fully operative <strong>in</strong>that particular situation. Let us take, for <strong>in</strong>stance, the neoclassicalmodel <strong>of</strong> economic growth. There entrepreneurial propensities arealtogether neglected. One can deem entrepreneurial propensitiesrelevant or not relevant. If the latter is the case, it would be right toignore them <strong>in</strong> the model; if the former is the case, the neoclassicalmodel <strong>of</strong> economic growth would be <strong>in</strong>correctly specified. There is athird option, however: entrepreneurial propensities may beconsidered relevant, but <strong>in</strong> a state <strong>of</strong> quiescence <strong>in</strong> that particularsituation. What this means is that they are suspended but notsuppressed. S<strong>in</strong>ce suspension presupposes resumption, the state <strong>of</strong>rest that is represented <strong>in</strong> the model may be dissolved from with<strong>in</strong>rather than from without.It must be noticed that the difference between a partially <strong>and</strong> afully specified model is not the same as that between a short-term<strong>and</strong> a long-term model. The difference between a short-term <strong>and</strong> along-term model turns on the number <strong>of</strong> variables that are keptconstant, this number decreas<strong>in</strong>g as we move from a short-term to a105


MAURIZIO CASERTAlong-term model. The difference between a partially <strong>and</strong> a fullyspecified model is one between a model whose functions, throughignorance <strong>of</strong> the agent or the analyst, cannot all be precisely specified,<strong>and</strong> a model where noth<strong>in</strong>g impedes such specifications. 3 Thus ashort-term model can be fully specified if what is treated as given isnot liable to generate at some po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> time an unpredictable dynamics,either because fixity <strong>of</strong> that variable is a realistic assumption orbecause the analyst is not prepared to take <strong>in</strong>to account the possibility<strong>of</strong> change. That assumption, therefore, is not conceal<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>ability<strong>of</strong> the theorist to properly specify that function.If this argument is accepted, equilibrium will cease to conveynecessarily the idea <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ality, that is, the idea <strong>of</strong> a state <strong>of</strong> affairsthat can be changed only by external occurrences. More generally, itmight become associated with endogenous as well as withexogenous change. The notion <strong>of</strong> provisional equilibrium,<strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>in</strong> Chick <strong>and</strong> Caserta (1994) mentioned above, wasdesigned precisely to represent a state <strong>of</strong> rest that has with<strong>in</strong> itselfthe seeds <strong>of</strong> its own destruction. Thus, equilibrium becomesconsistent with <strong>in</strong>novation, learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> evolution.The purpose <strong>of</strong> this chapter is to pursue further the notion <strong>of</strong>provisional equilibrium. In particular, what k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> theoreticalpurpose is served by this notion will be discussed. Then attentionwill be devoted to the idea that equilibrium is consistent withlearn<strong>in</strong>g. To do so, Hahn’s notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium is taken as thestart<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t. 4 F<strong>in</strong>ally, an example, taken from the theory <strong>of</strong>economic growth, <strong>of</strong> what implications the notion <strong>of</strong> provisionalequilibrium could have for actual theoris<strong>in</strong>g will be suggested. It willbe argued that the need to ensure cont<strong>in</strong>uity to the economicdiscourse can be served by an approach to growth based on amultiplicity <strong>of</strong> growth regimes, each <strong>of</strong> which is associated with adifferent set <strong>of</strong> exogenous <strong>and</strong> endogenous variables. Such anapproach can cope with novelty <strong>in</strong> a non-traditional way: <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong>hav<strong>in</strong>g shifts <strong>in</strong> the parameters <strong>of</strong> the functions (which obviouslycan still take place), it h<strong>and</strong>les novelty by means <strong>of</strong> shifts from oneregime to another. This implies that there is a higher level <strong>in</strong> theanalysis, a general framework, which is what is required for thenotion <strong>of</strong> provisional equilibrium to make any sense.The nature <strong>of</strong> changeAny account <strong>of</strong> change <strong>in</strong> theoris<strong>in</strong>g is bound to be unsatisfactory. Ifchange is viewed as the emergence <strong>of</strong> novelty, one can only trace its106


ENDOGENOUS CHANGEconsequences. If, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, one wants to expla<strong>in</strong> change, itmust be deprived <strong>of</strong> its novelty. The treatment <strong>of</strong> change <strong>in</strong>economic theory reflects this <strong>in</strong>adequacy, for change is portrayedeither as entirely exogenous, or as entirely generated with<strong>in</strong> themodel. When it is entirely exogenous, no explanation can be givenwith<strong>in</strong> the realm <strong>of</strong> economic theory; when it is entirely generatedwith<strong>in</strong> the model, it becomes <strong>in</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>guishable from an equilibriumrelation, as all changes have been pre-reconciled. One cannot fail tosee that a pre-reconciled change is not a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> change that displaysany novelty. Novelty <strong>and</strong> explanation appear therefore as mutuallyexclusive categories.This difficulty <strong>in</strong> the treatment <strong>of</strong> change might be thought to beeasily overcome by tak<strong>in</strong>g one <strong>of</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g routes. When changeis portrayed as entirely exogenous, one could have recourse to adifferent field <strong>of</strong> study other than economics <strong>and</strong> supply anexplanation <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> the factors relevant to that field. But thiswould just shift the problem onto a different area, as change willthen be portrayed as entirely explicable with<strong>in</strong> that model. Noveltywould be preserved only as far as economic theory goes.In the case <strong>of</strong> model-generated change, there is no novelty tospeak <strong>of</strong>. All change is governed by pre-determ<strong>in</strong>ed relations. Infact, some degree <strong>of</strong> novelty could be <strong>in</strong>troduced by assum<strong>in</strong>guncerta<strong>in</strong>ty. However, as long as uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty is associated withprobabilistic knowledge, <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g determ<strong>in</strong>istic prereconciliation,we would have pre-reconciliation <strong>of</strong> the probabilistictype. Novelty would here appear under the guise <strong>of</strong> chance, <strong>and</strong> thushardly be explicable. Consider, for example, the growth <strong>of</strong> thecapital stock. In a model <strong>of</strong> growth the change <strong>in</strong> the capital stock isgenerated with<strong>in</strong> the model. The model outcome ensures that allchanges are reconciled. Growth <strong>of</strong> the capital stock could beassumed to depend on the growth <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>. When this is the case,the model outcome ensures that capacity <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> grow at thesame rate. With uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, the growth <strong>of</strong> the capital stock willdepend on the expected growth <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>. A grow<strong>in</strong>g capital stockwill thus be consistent with a grow<strong>in</strong>g dem<strong>and</strong> only on average.Deviations from this average will just be chance deviations.It appears impossible therefore, as one tries slowly to moveaway from one treatment <strong>of</strong> change <strong>in</strong> order to <strong>in</strong>clude someaspects <strong>of</strong> the other, to rema<strong>in</strong> halfway <strong>and</strong> have novelty <strong>and</strong>explanation at the same time. As one tries to make novelty lessnovel <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>troduce some explanation, novelty is totally lost.Similarly, as one tries to reduce the degree <strong>of</strong> pre-reconciliation by107


MAURIZIO CASERTA<strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g r<strong>and</strong>om events, explanation is totally lost. All thisgoes to show that the question <strong>of</strong> change should be approached <strong>in</strong>a different way.The follow<strong>in</strong>g suggestion <strong>of</strong> Loasby’s might be a useful start<strong>in</strong>gpo<strong>in</strong>t:The dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>in</strong>cremental <strong>and</strong> discont<strong>in</strong>uouschange is an imposed dist<strong>in</strong>ction. All change <strong>in</strong>volves at leastone discont<strong>in</strong>uity; no change obliterates the past. The<strong>in</strong>vention <strong>of</strong> such categories as revolutionary <strong>and</strong> normalscience, or the hard core <strong>and</strong> protective belt <strong>of</strong> a researchprogramme, like the familiar dist<strong>in</strong>ction between short-<strong>and</strong>long-run effects (…) is part <strong>of</strong> the process through which wetry to make sense <strong>of</strong> the world by impos<strong>in</strong>g manageablecategories upon it. If driven hard, all such dist<strong>in</strong>ctions breakdown.(Loasby 1991:19)Instead <strong>of</strong> portray<strong>in</strong>g change as an unexpected event, thusstress<strong>in</strong>g discont<strong>in</strong>uity, or as a fully known development, imply<strong>in</strong>gstrict cont<strong>in</strong>uity, it might be possible to th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> change as anunderly<strong>in</strong>g process whose developments are, as yet, unknown.Such a process may not imp<strong>in</strong>ge on the established relations thatare be<strong>in</strong>g studied, but may produce some consequences at a laterdate. Here novelty is preserved, but a l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> development isidentified. When this is acknowledged <strong>in</strong> the establishment <strong>of</strong> a set<strong>of</strong> equilibrium relations, equilibrium by its very nature becomesprovisional.This argument could appear to be very easily countered by theremark that there is always someth<strong>in</strong>g go<strong>in</strong>g on <strong>in</strong> the world that isbeyond our underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g. There is always someth<strong>in</strong>g left out <strong>of</strong>the picture that is difficult to fit <strong>in</strong>to it. When it becomes possibleto fit the new piece <strong>in</strong>, the picture will be enlarged. Thus, despitethe perception that there is more to the world than we can makeout, we should say no more than what our coherent model allowsus to say. In fact, this counter-argument can be questioned. Just asthe analyst perceives that there is more to the world than he or shecan make out, so there is no reason to rule out that the actors <strong>of</strong>the theoretical model enterta<strong>in</strong> the very same perception. It will beargued below that it is through this l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g that Loasby’sremarks can be supported <strong>and</strong> a different treatment <strong>of</strong> changesuggested.108


ENDOGENOUS CHANGEHahn’s notion <strong>of</strong> equilibriumHahn’s notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium is well known: ‘an economy is <strong>in</strong>equilibrium when it generates messages which do not cause agentsto change the theories which they hold or the policies which theypursue’ (Hahn 1984:59). Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Hahn, an agent’s theory isthe result <strong>of</strong> the process<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the messages from the economy <strong>and</strong>nature received by the agent up to the date t. An agent’s policy is amapp<strong>in</strong>g from messages to acts. It is <strong>in</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> the equilibriumposition that the agents are not learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> equilibrium, whichmeans that the agents’ theory is <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>of</strong> the date t. It is also<strong>in</strong> the nature <strong>of</strong> the equilibrium position that policies are notchang<strong>in</strong>g, which requires that agents are not learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> that theirobjectives are not chang<strong>in</strong>g. 5As long as agents are learn<strong>in</strong>g, the economy is not <strong>in</strong>equilibrium. The economy is generat<strong>in</strong>g messages that do notcause agents to ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> their theories. 6 Hahn contents himselfwith the hypothesis that theories are ab<strong>and</strong>oned when they are‘sufficiently <strong>and</strong> systematically falsified’. Any such message fromthe economy will prompt a reconsideration <strong>of</strong> the theoriesenterta<strong>in</strong>ed that far <strong>and</strong> a change <strong>in</strong> regime. How the new theory<strong>and</strong> hence the new equilibrium are reached is not known.However, if a ‘higher-level’ theory <strong>of</strong> the learn<strong>in</strong>g process wereavailable, such a change <strong>in</strong> regime would not cause anydiscont<strong>in</strong>uity, as it would represent an equilibrium behaviour <strong>of</strong>the economy be<strong>in</strong>g studied. If such a theory were available,analysts <strong>and</strong> agents alike would know how to discard a theory <strong>and</strong>put another one <strong>in</strong> its place. 7Strictly speak<strong>in</strong>g the process whereby theories are rejected <strong>and</strong>replaced does not imply, on the part <strong>of</strong> agents, any learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>Hahn’s sense. Therefore, equilibrium <strong>and</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g carry on be<strong>in</strong>gtwo <strong>in</strong>compatible ideas. The argument put forward here is thatequilibrium <strong>and</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g can <strong>in</strong>deed coexist. What this argumentis built on is the equal treatment <strong>of</strong> economic agents <strong>and</strong> economicanalysts. 8 Let us see what is a typical attitude <strong>of</strong> economicanalysts. Respond<strong>in</strong>g to an objection on the axiomatic methodHahn says:Axioms, like special hypotheses, are there to specialise. It isnot that they are divorced from experience or observation butrather that they mark the stage beyond which one does notseek to expla<strong>in</strong>. The axiom that firms maximise some function109


MAURIZIO CASERTA<strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>its is stated as such because the theorist is not propos<strong>in</strong>gto answer the question why firms should do so.(Hahn 1984:6)Once this axiom is accepted, agents <strong>and</strong> theorists can develop atheory <strong>of</strong> the determ<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> the rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it. It is true that theassumption <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it maximisation may conflict with a differentobjective on the part <strong>of</strong> firms. Such an objective, however, is notcontemplated: one has to start somewhere. Hahn cont<strong>in</strong>ues: ‘Myown position is that economists are at their most useful when theygive an account <strong>of</strong> the alternative scenarios which the present state<strong>of</strong> our knowledge allows’ (ibid.: 8) This implies that economists dotheir job properly only when they set very clearly the limits <strong>of</strong> theiranalyses. Even when they perceive that someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g couldbe said <strong>of</strong> what lies beyond those limits, they should conf<strong>in</strong>ethemselves only to what can be said with sufficient clarity. However,future developments <strong>of</strong> the subject are not ruled out. On thecontrary, they are sought <strong>and</strong> encouraged. In fact, the need forclarity is emphasised precisely <strong>in</strong> view <strong>of</strong> the future development: ‘Itis one <strong>of</strong> the great virtues <strong>of</strong> the way good economic theoriz<strong>in</strong>gproceeds that it allows us to p<strong>in</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t difficulties precisely <strong>and</strong> to beprecise about the difficulties’ (Hahn 1984:50–1).It is fair to say, therefore, that good economic theorists alwaysperceive the limits <strong>of</strong> the present state <strong>of</strong> their knowledge. Such aperception, however, is not prevent<strong>in</strong>g them from construct<strong>in</strong>gsound logical arguments. They perceive the complexity <strong>of</strong> theworld, but nevertheless try to make some sense <strong>of</strong> it. Thus, they holdto a theory, but never rule out that a new development might put<strong>in</strong>to question the current state <strong>of</strong> their knowledge. In fact, theymight be even directly <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> pursu<strong>in</strong>g such developments,which means that they might be learn<strong>in</strong>g.Thus learn<strong>in</strong>g is compatible with adherence to a theory. In fact,adherence to a good theory will facilitate the evolution <strong>of</strong>knowledge, as it will mark clearly the boundaries <strong>of</strong> currentknowledge. This means that adherence to a theory is always donewith reservations. Theorists know that their theory may besupplanted by a new one but they do not know which theory willsupplant the old one. Now, if we want to treat economic analysts<strong>and</strong> economic agents equally, we must assume that agents, too, canadhere to a theory <strong>and</strong> carry on learn<strong>in</strong>g at the same time.The important implication <strong>of</strong> this equal treatment is that learn<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> equilibrium are no longer <strong>in</strong>compatible ideas. Agents can110


ENDOGENOUS CHANGEenterta<strong>in</strong> theories <strong>and</strong> follow policies such that equilibrium results.But there is no reason why they should not do it with reservations,which means that a process <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g may be tak<strong>in</strong>g place. Hahn’sclaim that: ‘it will be a condition <strong>of</strong> the agent be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> equilibriumthat he is not learn<strong>in</strong>g’ is therefore put <strong>in</strong>to question by thisargument. Agents may fail to have a fully comprehensive theory <strong>of</strong>the world, but may content themselves with a less comprehensiveone that leaves out a subset <strong>of</strong> the messages from the economy <strong>and</strong>nature. 9 The benefit from this partition<strong>in</strong>g is that a coherent set <strong>of</strong>propositions can be put together <strong>and</strong> a policy can be def<strong>in</strong>ed. Butjust like economists, agents will select a l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> research <strong>and</strong> pursue ituntil some new theory is ready to be used. The new theory may bemore comprehensive than the previous one or consist <strong>of</strong> analtogether different set <strong>of</strong> propositions.It is the perception <strong>of</strong> complexity, on the part <strong>of</strong> economicanalysts <strong>and</strong> economic agents alike, that this argument is based on.Any theory enterta<strong>in</strong>ed by both groups is enterta<strong>in</strong>ed withreservations. Such reservations, however, do not prevent them fromus<strong>in</strong>g that theory. This is especially true for economic agents whoneed theories to act. What these reservations imply is that atendency is cont<strong>in</strong>uously at work to try new l<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> research whosepossible developments <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al outcome are as yet unknown.We have reached a po<strong>in</strong>t when Loasby’s remarks can bereconsidered to see whether they can be substantiated by thearguments put forward so far. As quoted above, Loasby questionsthe adequacy <strong>of</strong> the dist<strong>in</strong>ction between discont<strong>in</strong>uous <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>cremental change, argu<strong>in</strong>g that it is an imposed dist<strong>in</strong>ction. Thequestion we have to ask, then, is whether this dist<strong>in</strong>ction breaksdown when learn<strong>in</strong>g is shown to be compatible with equilibrium,which is precisely the conclusion reached above. The answer is thatit does break down. When learn<strong>in</strong>g is compatible with equilibrium<strong>in</strong> the way that was described earlier, change is no longerdiscont<strong>in</strong>uous or <strong>in</strong>cremental or, alternatively, is both discont<strong>in</strong>uous<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>cremental. This is the case because the change that resultsfrom the process <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g has an element <strong>of</strong> discont<strong>in</strong>uity <strong>and</strong> anelement <strong>of</strong> cont<strong>in</strong>uity. The element <strong>of</strong> discont<strong>in</strong>uity orig<strong>in</strong>ates fromthe fact that the unknown outcome <strong>of</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g mightdisrupt the established equilibrium relations. The element <strong>of</strong>cont<strong>in</strong>uity comes from the simple fact that a process <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g isassumed, with the result that a l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> development is identified. 10This is just another way <strong>of</strong> say<strong>in</strong>g that novelty <strong>and</strong> explanation areboth preserved. For this k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> change the most appropriate111


MAURIZIO CASERTAdef<strong>in</strong>ition seems to be that <strong>of</strong> endogenous change. The f<strong>in</strong>alimplication <strong>of</strong> this l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> reason<strong>in</strong>g is that the notion <strong>of</strong> provisionalequilibrium is strengthened. When equilibrium is correctlyassociated with a process <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g, equilibrium by its very naturebecomes provisional.One may wonder at this po<strong>in</strong>t whether there is any differencebetween provisional equilibrium <strong>and</strong> Hahn’s equilibrium. Bothequilibria are disrupted by a change <strong>in</strong> the theory enterta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>both cases no disequilibrium dynamics are spelled out. There is afundamental difference, however. Hahns equilibrium presupposesthat agents form theories that, however simple, are comprehensive,that is, theories which result from the process<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> all messagesreceived from the economy <strong>and</strong> nature. Provisional equilibrium, onthe other h<strong>and</strong>, does not rule out that a subset <strong>of</strong> messages, althoughperceived, are not processed or are just partially processed. Thismeans that a subset <strong>of</strong> messages is provisionally, as it were, put onone side, while a theory is formed on the basis <strong>of</strong> another subset <strong>of</strong>messages <strong>and</strong> acted upon. However, the process<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the othersubset does not necessarily stop, so that a new theory may result atsome po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> time. The new theory may or may not be compatiblewith the set <strong>of</strong> propositions the old theory consists <strong>of</strong>; as a result itmay or it may not <strong>in</strong>clude the material covered by the old theory.It should become clear then that while Hahn’s equilibrium can bedisrupted when the theory is sufficiently <strong>and</strong> systematically falsified,this is not a necessary requirement for provisional equilibrium to bedisrupted. Provisional equilibrium can be disrupted because thetheory that results from the ongo<strong>in</strong>g process <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g is notcompatible with the old one, regardless <strong>of</strong> whether the old theory isfalsified or not. Therefore, the notions <strong>of</strong> equilibrium <strong>and</strong>disequilibrium do not co<strong>in</strong>cide <strong>in</strong> the two different stories. WhileHahn’s equilibrium is not compatible with learn<strong>in</strong>g, provisionalequilibrium is; while Hahn’s disequilibrium orig<strong>in</strong>ates fromsystematic falsification <strong>of</strong> theories, disruption <strong>of</strong> provisionalequilibrium does not have to orig<strong>in</strong>ate from that.The important implication <strong>of</strong> this difference is that whereasdisruption <strong>of</strong> Hahn’s equilibrium represents a discont<strong>in</strong>uity <strong>in</strong> theprocess <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g that does not proceed smoothly, disruption <strong>of</strong>provisional equilibrium does not alter the fundamental unity <strong>of</strong> theprocess <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g. It is this fundamental unity that lies at the heart<strong>of</strong> provisional equilibrium <strong>and</strong> serves as its ma<strong>in</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>gpo<strong>in</strong>t. But when it comes to economic analysis, is there anypossibility <strong>of</strong> discrim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g between the two notions? In other112


ENDOGENOUS CHANGEwords, is it possible to tell a model <strong>of</strong> provisional equilibrium apartfrom a model <strong>of</strong> static or f<strong>in</strong>al equilibrium? Can the notion <strong>of</strong>provisional equilibrium make any difference for actual theoris<strong>in</strong>g?A tentative answer to this question will be given below.Models <strong>of</strong> provisional equilibriumWhen the theorist comes to construct a model <strong>of</strong> provisionalequilibrium, the difference between endogenous change <strong>in</strong> the sense<strong>of</strong> this chapter <strong>and</strong> endogenous change <strong>of</strong> the pre-reconciled typebecomes more strik<strong>in</strong>g. Unlike the change <strong>of</strong> the pre-reconciled type,endogenous change does not imply any actual change: no change isgenerated by a model <strong>of</strong> provisional equilibrium. In this respect amodel <strong>of</strong> provisional equilibrium is more similar to a model <strong>of</strong> staticequilibrium, where change can only be imposed from outside themodel. What is different <strong>in</strong> a model <strong>of</strong> provisional equilibrium is the<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> equilibrium; equilibrium is no longer thought to bea state <strong>of</strong> affairs which can be disrupted only by exogenousoccurrences. Thus the concept <strong>of</strong> provisional equilibrium iscompatible with the proposition that change will occur, while theconcept <strong>of</strong> static or f<strong>in</strong>al equilibrium is not.However, different <strong>in</strong>terpretations are relevant <strong>in</strong> so far as theycarry implications for actual theoris<strong>in</strong>g. Just a different<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> the positions <strong>of</strong> provisional <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al equilibriumwould not by itself take us very far. It is argued here that one can g<strong>of</strong>urther than that. S<strong>in</strong>ce provisional equilibrium is based on a nonfullycomprehensive theory, that is a theory with a clearly limitedscope, it becomes possible to associate different non-fullycomprehensive theories with different models. This possibility is notwithout consequences.Despite the fact that each model will carry on look<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>guishable from a static model, the simple fact that a number <strong>of</strong>alternative models is simultaneously considered carries importantimplications. It shows that there is a higher level <strong>of</strong> analysis where the<strong>in</strong>dividual models <strong>and</strong> their relations can be understood as parts <strong>of</strong> as<strong>in</strong>gle conceptual framework. The different models, however, will notbe related to each other <strong>in</strong> the same way as short-term models arerelated to long-term models: there will be no hierarchy among them.Shift<strong>in</strong>g from one model to another will not be due to the relaxation<strong>of</strong> some previously fixed variable. It is not simply a matter <strong>of</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>gendogenous what was previously exogenous. That would certa<strong>in</strong>lynot disturb the above-mentioned novelty-versus-explanation113


MAURIZIO CASERTAdichotomy. Similarly this dichotomy would not be disturbed bymodels that differ because they are based on different fullycomprehensive theories: shift<strong>in</strong>g from one model to another would bethe result <strong>of</strong> a structural break. On the contrary, the collection <strong>of</strong>models based on different non-fully comprehensive theories willdisturb the novelty-versus-explanation dichotomy. Shift<strong>in</strong>g from onemodel to another will not be the result <strong>of</strong> a structural break, but theresult <strong>of</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> one regime <strong>in</strong>to another with<strong>in</strong> the sameongo<strong>in</strong>g process <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g. What would be preserved <strong>in</strong> this case isthe unity <strong>of</strong> the process <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g: the various models would appearas different closures <strong>of</strong> the same general system. Provisionalequilibrium, therefore, turns out to be a quite appropriate notion <strong>of</strong>equilibrium to associate with this k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> approach.It is not neglected here that the approach sketched above is just atentative answer to the question <strong>of</strong> the relevance <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong>provisional equilibrium. There is at least one other route that wouldbe <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to take. It concerns the possibility <strong>of</strong> modell<strong>in</strong>g aprocess <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g that is neither determ<strong>in</strong>istic, which would killnovelty, nor evolv<strong>in</strong>g through exogenous changes, which would killexplanation. This l<strong>in</strong>e is not pursued here.The reason why emphasis is placed on an approach based on amultiplicity <strong>of</strong> models lies <strong>in</strong> the fact that there is already anexample <strong>in</strong> the literature, <strong>in</strong> particular, <strong>in</strong> the theory <strong>of</strong> economicgrowth. By play<strong>in</strong>g with endogenous <strong>and</strong> exogenous variables anumber <strong>of</strong> growth regimes is established. Each <strong>of</strong> these regimes ishere re<strong>in</strong>terpreted as be<strong>in</strong>g associated with a non-fullycomprehensive theory. The whole approach is thus re<strong>in</strong>terpreted asan application <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> provisional equilibrium. It is to thediscussion <strong>of</strong> this approach that the rest <strong>of</strong> this chapter is devoted.An open-system approachAn analytical approach that admits <strong>of</strong> a multiplicity <strong>of</strong> solutionswas the subject matter <strong>of</strong> an article Sen published <strong>in</strong> 1963. Thisarticle has become the source <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>spiration for a number <strong>of</strong> growththeorists. What Sen argues <strong>in</strong> this article, which focuses ondistributional problems rather than on growth, is that it is notpossible to satisfy simultaneously an <strong>in</strong>vestment function<strong>in</strong>dependent from sav<strong>in</strong>g, full employment <strong>of</strong> capital <strong>and</strong> labour,<strong>and</strong> the marg<strong>in</strong>al productivity theory <strong>of</strong> distribution.Sen uses the follow<strong>in</strong>g equations:114


ENDOGENOUS CHANGEX=X (L*,X*) [1]w=X/L [2]X=p+wL* [3]I= s p+s p wwL* [4]I=I* [5]Equation [1] is a production function where X is the flow <strong>of</strong> theonly good produced; L* the amount <strong>of</strong> labour available <strong>in</strong> theeconomy <strong>and</strong> X* the stock <strong>of</strong> capital <strong>in</strong> existence; the output <strong>and</strong>the capital comprise the same good. Equation [2] says that thewage rate must be equal to the marg<strong>in</strong>al product <strong>of</strong> labour.Equation [3] requires pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>and</strong> wages to exhaust the product.Equation [4] requires <strong>in</strong>vestment to be equal to sav<strong>in</strong>g. In thisequation s p<strong>and</strong> s ware the marg<strong>in</strong>al propensities to save out <strong>of</strong>pr<strong>of</strong>its <strong>and</strong> wages, respectively. F<strong>in</strong>ally, Equation [5] represents the<strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>in</strong>vestment function. There are five equations, butonly four unknowns: X, w, p, I. The problem, then, is a problem <strong>of</strong>overdeterm<strong>in</strong>acy: one equation should be dropped or a furtherunknown <strong>in</strong>troduced. Therefore, someth<strong>in</strong>g must be given up. Itcould be, <strong>in</strong> turn, the <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>in</strong>vestment function, marg<strong>in</strong>alistdistribution, full employment, etc.The approach adopted by Sen <strong>in</strong> the treatment <strong>of</strong> distributionalproblems has been revived <strong>in</strong> the treatment <strong>of</strong> growth. Works byMargl<strong>in</strong> (1984a, b), Dutt (1987, 1990) <strong>and</strong> Taylor (199D havefollowed Sen’s procedure by start<strong>in</strong>g from a general framework <strong>and</strong>present<strong>in</strong>g different growth regimes as different ways <strong>of</strong> clos<strong>in</strong>g thesame general framework. Such a procedure amounts to decid<strong>in</strong>g onwhich variables are go<strong>in</strong>g to be exogenous <strong>and</strong> which ones are go<strong>in</strong>gto be endogenous <strong>in</strong> each particular case. Thus, by play<strong>in</strong>g withexogenous <strong>and</strong> endogenous variables, various comb<strong>in</strong>ations areobta<strong>in</strong>ed. It is argued here that this procedure proves appropriatefor generat<strong>in</strong>g a set <strong>of</strong> models, each <strong>of</strong> which is associated with anon-fully comprehensive theory. In any case such a comb<strong>in</strong>ationmust be compatible with the purpose <strong>of</strong> produc<strong>in</strong>g a determ<strong>in</strong>atesystem, that is, a system that yields an equilibrium solution.In present<strong>in</strong>g the analytical foundations <strong>of</strong> the approach, Dutt’sformulation will be followed. 11 However, while <strong>in</strong> Dutt’s work theemphasis is on closures, that is, on what is assumed to be exogenous,here the emphasis is on what is given up, that is, on the variablesmade endogenous for the sake <strong>of</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g a determ<strong>in</strong>ate system. Thepurpose <strong>of</strong> this shift <strong>of</strong> emphasis is to highlight which set <strong>of</strong>messages is provisionally left out <strong>and</strong> not processed to form a115


MAURIZIO CASERTAtheory. Here an exogenous variable is a variable that underlies aparticular policy, <strong>and</strong> hence a particular theory, while anendogenous variable is a variable that can assume whatever value,as there is no policy <strong>and</strong> no theory for it.Dutt assumes a closed capitalist economy that produces one goodus<strong>in</strong>g two factors only: homogeneous labour <strong>and</strong> capital.Technology is given <strong>and</strong> exhibits fixed coefficients <strong>and</strong> constantreturns to scale. Moreover, capital is eternal <strong>and</strong> all firms areidentical. No government or money is <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the model. Thebasic structure <strong>of</strong> the system is made up <strong>of</strong> two equations, aproduction equation <strong>and</strong> a price equation. Production is eitherconsumed or <strong>in</strong>vested. So we have:X=CL+gKwhere X is total output, C consumption per worker, L employment,g the rate <strong>of</strong> growth <strong>of</strong> capital <strong>and</strong> K productive capacity. S<strong>in</strong>ceconstant returns to scale have been assumed, unit coefficients can beused <strong>in</strong>stead. Thus we get:1=Ca 0+ga 1where a 0is the labour coefficient <strong>and</strong> a 1the capital coefficient,obta<strong>in</strong>ed by divid<strong>in</strong>g L <strong>and</strong> K by X. K/X, however, is made up <strong>of</strong> twodifferent components, a technical coefficient <strong>and</strong> a given degree <strong>of</strong>capacity utilisation. This becomes clear when we divide both K <strong>and</strong>X by full capacity output X f:(K/X f)/(X/X f)where the numerator represents the capital coefficient proper, <strong>and</strong>the denom<strong>in</strong>ator the degree <strong>of</strong> capacity utilisation. Only if currentoutput equals full capacity output, i.e. when X=X f, will the capitaloutputratio be equal to the capital coefficient. It follows that <strong>in</strong> thegeneral case the capital-output ratio will be different from thecapital coefficient a 1. Thus the production equation is best kept <strong>in</strong>this general form:1=Ca 0+g(K/X).Price per unit <strong>of</strong> production goes to wages or pr<strong>of</strong>its. We havetherefore the follow<strong>in</strong>g price equation:116


ENDOGENOUS CHANGEP=Wa 0+rP(K/X)where P, W <strong>and</strong> r have the usual mean<strong>in</strong>g: the price, the money wage<strong>and</strong> the rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it, respectively. Assum<strong>in</strong>g P=1 we get:1=Wa 0+r(K/X)with W now represent<strong>in</strong>g the real wage rate. The reason for us<strong>in</strong>g(K/X) <strong>in</strong>stead <strong>of</strong> the capital coefficient a 1is the same as before.The equations presented above can be said to constitute thecommon analytical core <strong>of</strong> any model <strong>of</strong> growth. They imply nomore than the follow<strong>in</strong>g propositions: for any given degree <strong>of</strong>capacity utilisation (a) production can be either consumed or<strong>in</strong>vested; (b) what is not paid as wages is paid as pr<strong>of</strong>its. This means,for example, that only if we know the degree <strong>of</strong> capacity utilisation,the consumption rate <strong>and</strong> the real wage rate can we determ<strong>in</strong>e theaccumulation rate <strong>and</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>it rate. In other words, we have fiveunknowns, but only two equations to play with. So three additionalexplanations, <strong>in</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependent relations, have to besupplied. Provided no further unknown is <strong>in</strong>troduced, the systemwill yield a determ<strong>in</strong>ate solution. At the same time no more thanthree <strong>in</strong>dependent relations can be added to the model, otherwisethe model will become overdeterm<strong>in</strong>ed. A particular model <strong>of</strong>growth, therefore, will be dist<strong>in</strong>guished by what set <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependentrelations is added to that common analytical core, <strong>in</strong> particular, bywhat is go<strong>in</strong>g to be exogenous <strong>and</strong> what is go<strong>in</strong>g to be endogenous.This choice is not obviously unconstra<strong>in</strong>ed: if, for example,<strong>in</strong>dependent relations are <strong>in</strong>troduced to determ<strong>in</strong>e the degree <strong>of</strong>capacity utilisation, the accumulation rate <strong>and</strong> the pr<strong>of</strong>it rate, theconsumption rate <strong>and</strong> the real wage rate must be determ<strong>in</strong>edendogenously. In other words, if all actors <strong>in</strong> the economy hadtheories on all the relevant variables, no consistency <strong>of</strong> plans orpolicies could be possible. This implies that any particular choicecan be characterised by what one is prepared to sacrifice <strong>in</strong> order toavoid overdeterm<strong>in</strong>acy.What follows will be devoted to a brief illustration <strong>of</strong> fourpossible alternative choices. In each case emphasis will be placedon the relations that could not be added because otherwise thesystem would become overdeterm<strong>in</strong>ed. Such relations areassociated with the set <strong>of</strong> messages from the economy <strong>and</strong>nature, which are provisionally not <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the currentlyenterta<strong>in</strong>ed theory.117


MAURIZIO CASERTAIt must be noticed that any regime that is associated with a nonfullycomprehensive theory cannot be said to be <strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al equilibrium.The whole approach, based as it is on a multiplicity <strong>of</strong> regimes,provides a solution to the problem posed by the provisional nature<strong>of</strong> the equilibrium position: a different regime will replace the oldone when the set <strong>of</strong> messages previously neglected are processed t<strong>of</strong>orm a theory. Thus, the overall picture which one gets from theadoption <strong>of</strong> this approach is that <strong>of</strong> a succession <strong>of</strong> growth regimesbrought about by the creation <strong>of</strong> new knowledge <strong>and</strong> theundertak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> new policies.Four regimes <strong>of</strong> growthLet us consider one possible selection <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependent relations to beadded to the common analytical core. The market-clear<strong>in</strong>ghypothesis, typical <strong>of</strong> neoclassical th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g, def<strong>in</strong>es one. Thisimplies add<strong>in</strong>g to the price <strong>and</strong> production equations two<strong>in</strong>dependent relations requir<strong>in</strong>g full employment <strong>of</strong> labour <strong>and</strong>equilibrium <strong>in</strong> the goods market. So we can write:g=nK/X=a 1where n is the rate <strong>of</strong> growth <strong>of</strong> the labour force. The two equationsimply, respectively, that accumulation is go<strong>in</strong>g on at a rate equal tothe rate <strong>of</strong> growth <strong>of</strong> the labour force <strong>and</strong> the capacity is be<strong>in</strong>g usedat its normal level. F<strong>in</strong>ally we need a relation l<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g distribution togrowth. This is provided <strong>in</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> a sav<strong>in</strong>g function. A classicalsav<strong>in</strong>g function is assumed, imply<strong>in</strong>g that workers save noth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>capitalists save a constant fraction <strong>of</strong> their <strong>in</strong>come. The fifth relationwe need is therefore the follow<strong>in</strong>g:g=srwhere s is the capitalists’ propensity to save. We are now endowedwith five <strong>in</strong>dependent relations that determ<strong>in</strong>e five unknowns: thedegree <strong>of</strong> capacity utilisation, the accumulation rate, the pr<strong>of</strong>itrate, the consumption rate <strong>and</strong> the real wage rate. It is clear thatthe <strong>in</strong>troduction <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>in</strong>vestment function, allow<strong>in</strong>gfor entrepreneurial <strong>in</strong>vestment propensities, would overdeterm<strong>in</strong>ethe system. This case can be assumed to be characterised,therefore, by the absence <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>in</strong>vestment function.118


ENDOGENOUS CHANGEThere is no room <strong>in</strong> this world for <strong>in</strong>dependent <strong>in</strong>vestmentdecisions.In this model <strong>of</strong> a grow<strong>in</strong>g economy the agents who are usuallysupposed to make <strong>in</strong>vestment decisions are passively accept<strong>in</strong>g theequilibrium rate <strong>of</strong> accumulation. Various reasons expla<strong>in</strong> theirbehaviour. Here emphasis is placed on the possibility that <strong>in</strong>vestorshave not yet formed a theory <strong>of</strong> the growth <strong>of</strong> the economy, with theresult that they do not act on that. No theory implies no policy. Thefact that the rate <strong>of</strong> accumulation is determ<strong>in</strong>ed as the rate thatclears the labour market shows that no theory is currentlyenterta<strong>in</strong>ed by entrepreneurs on the variables relevant to theirpotential <strong>in</strong>vestment decisions, like, for example, the rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it.Otherwise <strong>in</strong>vestment decisions would be changed accord<strong>in</strong>g tosome established behavioural function. Precisely because <strong>of</strong> theabsence <strong>of</strong> any such behavioural function, equilibrium cannot butbe provisional.If accumulation is supposed to be governed by decisions <strong>of</strong> firms,the equation l<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g the rate <strong>of</strong> accumulation with the rate <strong>of</strong>growth <strong>of</strong> the labour force can be replaced by an equation l<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>gaccumulation with someth<strong>in</strong>g more congenial to firms, such as theexpected rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it on <strong>in</strong>vested capital. This replacement is thedist<strong>in</strong>guish<strong>in</strong>g characteristic <strong>of</strong> another regime <strong>of</strong> growth, which hasa clear Keynesian flavour. The set <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependent relations to beadded to the common analytical core to obta<strong>in</strong> this case is thefollow<strong>in</strong>g:g s=srK/X=a 1g i=g(r)where g s<strong>and</strong> g irepresent desired sav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> desired <strong>in</strong>vestment perunit <strong>of</strong> capital. Aga<strong>in</strong> we have a set <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dependent relations thatdeterm<strong>in</strong>e the usual set <strong>of</strong> five unknowns. Clearly, the addition <strong>of</strong> afurther relation requir<strong>in</strong>g accumulation to be carried out at the naturalrate would overdeterm<strong>in</strong>e the system. Thus, this particular regime<strong>of</strong> growth implies <strong>in</strong> the general case g¹n. It also implies thatdistribution can no longer be expla<strong>in</strong>ed as the result <strong>of</strong> the marketclear<strong>in</strong>ghypothesis. The rate <strong>of</strong> growth <strong>of</strong> employment <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>comedistribution are turned <strong>in</strong>to residual variables. Individual behaviour<strong>in</strong> the field <strong>of</strong> employment <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>come distribution is not modelledthen: the supply <strong>of</strong> labour is presented as perfectly elastic, the realwage rate is just a consequence <strong>of</strong> entrepreneurs’ <strong>in</strong>vestment decisions.119


MAURIZIO CASERTAWhat is left out <strong>in</strong> this regime, then, is the behaviour <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>dividuals as labour suppliers. Such <strong>in</strong>dividuals are not supposed toreact to the endogenous rate <strong>of</strong> growth <strong>of</strong> employment or to theendogenous wage rate. No policy <strong>and</strong> hence no theory exist on thisaccount. A learn<strong>in</strong>g process can be assumed to be <strong>in</strong> place, however,to form such a theory. Only when the theory becomes available cana policy be developed. Aga<strong>in</strong>, this k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> equilibrium is necessarilyprovisional <strong>in</strong> nature.When, unlike the previous case, distribution is not allowed to beresidually determ<strong>in</strong>ed, but is supposed to play a crucial role <strong>in</strong> thesystem, a different regime <strong>of</strong> growth is established. We then have asituation where the state <strong>of</strong> class conflict, reflected <strong>in</strong> a particular<strong>in</strong>come distribution, acts as a b<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g constra<strong>in</strong>t on the capability <strong>of</strong>the system to grow over time. To see why this is the case supposethat the equation:W=W 0where W 0 represents the exogenously given real wage rate, is addedto the previous system. S<strong>in</strong>ce we already have five <strong>in</strong>dependentrelations that determ<strong>in</strong>e five unknowns, this additional relationwould clearly overdeterm<strong>in</strong>e the system. As a consequence, one<strong>in</strong>dependent relation has to be given up to make room for therelation reflect<strong>in</strong>g the state <strong>of</strong> class conflict over the distribution <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>come. If the sacrificed relation is the <strong>in</strong>vestment function, wewould get what <strong>in</strong> the literature is known as the neo-Marxian case.Unlike the previous case, here distribution determ<strong>in</strong>esaccumulation. Thus, accumulation is no longer determ<strong>in</strong>ed by thedesire <strong>of</strong> firms to grow, but serves the <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>of</strong> the class conflict.Aga<strong>in</strong>, as <strong>in</strong> the full-employment neoclassical case, animal spiritshave been suppressed; entrepreneurial <strong>in</strong>vestment propensities havenot been modelled. No policies are pursued, no theories are checked<strong>in</strong> the light <strong>of</strong> the messages received from the economy <strong>and</strong> nature.In the cases considered so far the degree <strong>of</strong> capacity utilisationhas not figured among the variables that are determ<strong>in</strong>ed residually.The assumption K/X=a 1has always ensured that the degree <strong>of</strong>capacity utilisation rema<strong>in</strong>s fixed at its normal level. A theory <strong>of</strong> thedegree <strong>of</strong> capacity utilisation is somehow <strong>in</strong>cluded <strong>in</strong> the model.When that assumption is relaxed, a new regime <strong>of</strong> growth can beobta<strong>in</strong>ed where the degree <strong>of</strong> capacity utilisation turns <strong>in</strong>to avariable to be determ<strong>in</strong>ed endogenously. If this assumption isreplaced by another one fix<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>come distribution, we have a120


ENDOGENOUS CHANGEmodel that Dutt has named after Kalecki <strong>and</strong> Ste<strong>in</strong>dl. The follow<strong>in</strong>gequations def<strong>in</strong>e the model:1=a 0C+g(K/X)1=Wa 0+r(K/X)g=sr1=Wa 0(1+z)g=g(r, X/K).Given the mark-up rate z, the propensity to save j, the labourcoefficient a 0<strong>and</strong> the parameters <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>vestment function (whichis here kept implicit), the model will determ<strong>in</strong>e C, W, g, r <strong>and</strong> X/K.The forces affect<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>come distribution will here manifestthemselves through the determ<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> the mark-up rate z. Thisimplies that the rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it r can change without this plac<strong>in</strong>g anyconstra<strong>in</strong>t on such forces. This can be realised by means <strong>of</strong> avariable degree <strong>of</strong> capacity utilisation whose variations will producethe sav<strong>in</strong>g per unit <strong>of</strong> capital required to susta<strong>in</strong> desiredaccumulation. As a further consequence <strong>of</strong> the variability <strong>of</strong>capacity utilisation, desired accumulation g will now depend on thedegree <strong>of</strong> capacity utilisation as well as on the rate <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>it.There is no theory <strong>of</strong> the degree <strong>of</strong> capacity utilisation <strong>in</strong> thismodel. It will be fixed at the level required to make sav<strong>in</strong>g per unit<strong>of</strong> capital equal to <strong>in</strong>vestment per unit <strong>of</strong> capital. It is, therefore, aresidual variable. No theory implies no policies. The messages fromthe economy show<strong>in</strong>g a degree <strong>of</strong> capacity utilisation different fromany pre-determ<strong>in</strong>ed one will not cause any revision or confirmation<strong>of</strong> theories. No theory <strong>of</strong> the degree <strong>of</strong> capacity utilisation is be<strong>in</strong>gchecked aga<strong>in</strong>st reality. However, such a theory may be <strong>in</strong> theprocess <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g formed. When this process is completed it maybr<strong>in</strong>g about a change <strong>in</strong> regime. Aga<strong>in</strong>, equilibrium is provisional.The concept <strong>of</strong> provisional equilibrium, therefore, has animplication for actual theoris<strong>in</strong>g. By play<strong>in</strong>g with exogenous <strong>and</strong>endogenous variables, different comb<strong>in</strong>ations are obta<strong>in</strong>ed, wherethe exogenous variables are the variables for which a theory exists,<strong>and</strong> the endogenous those for which a theory is not yet formed. It isthis extraord<strong>in</strong>ary flexibility that renders this approach particularlysuitable for treat<strong>in</strong>g change as neither determ<strong>in</strong>istic nor<strong>in</strong>explicable. The succession <strong>of</strong> regimes that results from theadoption <strong>of</strong> this approach can adequately reflect the formation <strong>of</strong>new theories <strong>and</strong> the undertak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> new policies. What thisapproach cannot do is expla<strong>in</strong> how new theories are formed <strong>and</strong> old121


MAURIZIO CASERTAtheories are discarded. It only shows that learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> equilibriumare not necessarily <strong>in</strong>compatible.ConclusionThe fundamental proposition <strong>of</strong> this chapter is that learn<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>equilibrium are not <strong>in</strong>compatible ideas. This is argued start<strong>in</strong>g fromHarm’s notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium where, however, equilibrium <strong>and</strong>learn<strong>in</strong>g are said to be <strong>in</strong>compatible. The argument rests on theequal treatment <strong>of</strong> economic analysts <strong>and</strong> economic agents. Just aseconomic analysts cannot afford a fully comprehensive theory <strong>of</strong> theeconomy, but need to set clear limits to what they can say <strong>in</strong> anorderly way, so economic agents form theories which cover only asubset <strong>of</strong> the messages received from the economy <strong>and</strong> nature. Noone could deny, however, that while theories are propounded <strong>and</strong>applied by economic analysts, a process <strong>of</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g is tak<strong>in</strong>g placeaimed at generat<strong>in</strong>g new <strong>and</strong> better theories. Similarly, no one coulddeny that economic agents, while us<strong>in</strong>g the available theories foraction, cont<strong>in</strong>ually process <strong>in</strong>formation that has not yet found itsway <strong>in</strong>to a theory. The question posed <strong>in</strong> this chapter is whether thisrecognition bears any relevance to the notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium. Theanswer is that it does, <strong>and</strong> that the notion <strong>of</strong> provisional equilibriumis thus substantiated.Another question concerns the relevance <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong>provisional equilibrium to the method <strong>of</strong> analysis. The answer aga<strong>in</strong>is <strong>in</strong> the positive. It has been argued that a method <strong>of</strong> analysis basedon a multiplicity <strong>of</strong> models or regimes proves adequate for thepurpose <strong>of</strong> fitt<strong>in</strong>g the creation <strong>of</strong> new theories <strong>in</strong>to an analyticalframework. It must also be noticed that such an approach iscompatible with the axiom <strong>of</strong> the purposeful <strong>in</strong>dividual typical <strong>of</strong>Lachmann’s th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g.AcknowledgementsI wish to thank Gary Mongiovi <strong>and</strong> Roger Koppl for helpfulcomments <strong>and</strong> suggestions. However, the responsibility for theviews expressed <strong>in</strong> this chapter lies entirely with the author.Notes1 See, for example, Lachmann 1976.2 See Lachmann 1990:137.122


ENDOGENOUS CHANGE3 The difficulty <strong>in</strong> specify<strong>in</strong>g a particular function should immediatelyplace it outside the <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>of</strong> economic theory. If some functioncannot be properly specified, how would one go about it or whyshould one <strong>in</strong>troduce it <strong>in</strong> the analysis at all? The sensible th<strong>in</strong>g to do<strong>in</strong> such a case is to put it <strong>of</strong>f until somebody comes up with anacceptable specification. However, when the function <strong>in</strong> question is for<strong>in</strong>stance the production <strong>of</strong> new knowledge, there is no acceptablespecification to speak <strong>of</strong> as it is logically impossible to predict thecontent <strong>of</strong> new knowledge. The question <strong>in</strong> this case is whether theproduction <strong>of</strong> new knowledge is to be left out <strong>of</strong> economic discourse.The answer given <strong>in</strong> this chapter is that it is not.4 See Hahn 1973.5 See Hahn 1984:56.6 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Hahn, agents are learn<strong>in</strong>g if, for example, hav<strong>in</strong>gobserved ra<strong>in</strong> at time t+1 the probability they attach to ra<strong>in</strong> at time t+2is different from the probability they attached to that event at time tconditional on ra<strong>in</strong> at time t+1.7 Loasby makes an <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g comment on this:Such meta-theories <strong>and</strong> meta-policies cannot be preciselyspecified, because it is logically impossible for the content <strong>of</strong> newknowledge to be predicted <strong>in</strong> advance or, what comes to thesame th<strong>in</strong>g, to be specified as the output, determ<strong>in</strong>ate orprobabilistic, <strong>of</strong> a well-def<strong>in</strong>ed process. This may be why, <strong>in</strong>1973, Hahn placed the generation or revision <strong>of</strong> theories <strong>and</strong>policies beyond the scope <strong>of</strong> economic analysis. He now (1991)believes that we cannot deal adequately with some importantproblems without extend<strong>in</strong>g that scope, <strong>and</strong> recognizes thatsuch extensions imply substantial revisions <strong>of</strong> the theories <strong>and</strong>policies which economists use.(Loasby 1991:48)8 Loasby starts his book with this comment:I would like to direct readers’ attention to a basic similaritybetween the problems faced by economists <strong>and</strong> by the economicagents whom they attempt to study. Both sets <strong>of</strong> people aretry<strong>in</strong>g to make sense <strong>of</strong> the world <strong>in</strong> which they f<strong>in</strong>d themselves,<strong>and</strong> to behave <strong>in</strong>telligently <strong>in</strong> it…. So the behaviour <strong>of</strong>economists may help us to underst<strong>and</strong> the behaviour <strong>of</strong>economic agents, <strong>and</strong> vice versa.(Loasby 1991:2)9 As an example <strong>of</strong> bounded rationality Hahn mentions the possibilitythat agents peer only a short distance <strong>in</strong>to the future, or that a wholeclass <strong>of</strong> messages is ignored despite their relevance. However he doesnot pursue this po<strong>in</strong>t any further (see Hahn 1984:56).10 This assumption can be viewed as an aspect <strong>of</strong> the axiom <strong>of</strong> thepurposeful <strong>in</strong>dividual typical <strong>of</strong> Austrian th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g.11 Dutt (1990) represents the most comprehensive treatment <strong>of</strong> thisapproach.123


MAURIZIO CASERTAReferencesChick, V. <strong>and</strong> Caserta, M. (1994) ‘Provisional equilibrium <strong>and</strong>macroeconomic theory’, discussion paper, University College, London.Dolan, E.G. (ed.) (1976) The Foundations <strong>of</strong> Modern Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s,Kansas City: Sheed <strong>and</strong> Ward.Dutt, A.K. (1987) ‘Alternative closures aga<strong>in</strong>: a comment on “Growth,Distribution <strong>and</strong> Inflation”’, Cambridge Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s, 11 (1):75–82.——(1990) Growth, Distribution <strong>and</strong> Uneven Development, Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Hahn, F.H. (1973) ‘On the notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium <strong>in</strong> economies’, <strong>in</strong> Hahn(1984).——(1984) Equilibrium <strong>and</strong> Macroeconomics, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Lachmann, L.M. (1976) ‘On the central concept <strong>of</strong> Austrian economics:market process’, <strong>in</strong> E.G.Dolan (ed.) The Foundations <strong>of</strong> ModernAustrian <strong>Economic</strong>s, Kansas City: Sheed <strong>and</strong> Ward.——(1990) ‘Austrian economics: a hermeneutic approach’, <strong>in</strong> D.Lavoie(ed.) <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Hermeneutics, London: Routledge.Lavoie, D. (ed.) (1990) <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Hermeneutics, London: Routledge.Loasby, B.J. (1991) Equilibrium <strong>and</strong> Evolution, Manchester: ManchesterUniversity Press.Margl<strong>in</strong>, S.A. (1984a) ‘Growth, distribution <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>flation: a centennialsynthesis’, Cambridge Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s, 8 (2):115–44.——(1984b) Growth, Distribution <strong>and</strong> Prices, Cambridge, MA: HarvardUniversity Press.Sen, A.K. (1963) ‘Neoclassical <strong>and</strong> neo-Keynesian theories <strong>of</strong> distribution’,<strong>Economic</strong> Record, 39:53–64.Taylor, L. (1991) Income Distribution, Inflation, <strong>and</strong> Growth, Cambridge,MA: MIT Press.124


7RADICAL SUBJECTIVISMAND AUSTRIANECONOMICSCarlo ZappiaIntroductionIn her vivid description <strong>of</strong> the conference held at South Royalton <strong>in</strong>1974 to revitalise the Austrian tradition <strong>in</strong> the US, Karen Vaughnconsiders <strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann as ‘the odd man out’ at the conference,ma<strong>in</strong>ly because he was the ‘only speaker who seemed to see muchtheoretical work still to be done <strong>in</strong> def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> develop<strong>in</strong>g anAustrian economies’. It is by follow<strong>in</strong>g the way <strong>in</strong> which Lachmann<strong>in</strong>fluenced the subsequent evolution <strong>of</strong> Austrian th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g thatVaughn ma<strong>in</strong>ly reconstructs the Austrian paradigm <strong>in</strong> her recentbook on Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>in</strong> America: The Migration <strong>of</strong> aTradition (1994). 1Vaughn proposes an exhaustive reconstruction <strong>of</strong> the traditionalAustrian school <strong>of</strong> thought—rang<strong>in</strong>g through Menger, Mises,Hayek <strong>and</strong> their followers—which ma<strong>in</strong>ly stresses those aspects <strong>of</strong>the Austrian approach that have rema<strong>in</strong>ed outside neoclassicaldevelopments. Vaughn’s view is that it is the rediscovery <strong>of</strong> thoseaspects <strong>of</strong> Austrian th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g eschewed by the ma<strong>in</strong>stream that hasbrought about the emergence <strong>of</strong> an American tradition <strong>of</strong> Austrianeconomics. Vaughn’s explicit purpose is thus to highlight those‘American Austrians’, 2 who have successfully managed to draw onthat tradition <strong>of</strong> thought.Vaughn’s book is an important attempt to answer the question:What is Austrian economics? Needless to say, this is the k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong>question one must address <strong>in</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g to assess any paradigmaticalternative to the dom<strong>in</strong>ant corpus <strong>of</strong> the discipl<strong>in</strong>e. It is also thek<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> question that <strong>of</strong>ten generates only negative heuristics (i.e. a125


CARLO ZAPPIAset <strong>of</strong> methodological options that does not necessarily entail a clearpositive analytic content).The answer provided by Vaughn <strong>in</strong> her attempt to give analyticcontent to her def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> the Austrian paradigm is that if Austrianeconomics is to be someth<strong>in</strong>g different from ma<strong>in</strong>streameconomics—a fact that is seen as essential for the survival <strong>of</strong> aseparate tradition <strong>of</strong> economic th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g—then it must be foundedon a cont<strong>in</strong>uous effort to develop a radically subjectivist approach.Vaughn contends that many fundamental concepts <strong>of</strong> Austrianeconomics such as the market process <strong>and</strong> spontaneous order can beconsistently opposed to neoclassical equilibrium constructs only ifthey are based on an approach to <strong>in</strong>dividual choice which stressesnot only the subjectivity <strong>of</strong> agents’ preferences <strong>and</strong> decisions, butalso the subjectivity <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> expectations. Lachmann’slegacy is thus central to the whole <strong>of</strong> Vaughn’s analysis, because <strong>of</strong>the way <strong>in</strong> which Lachmann forced the Austrians to deal withsubjectivism. In fact, the overall purpose <strong>of</strong> the book is to def<strong>in</strong>e amore comprehensive concept <strong>of</strong> ‘order’, which can take <strong>in</strong>to accountboth Lachmann’s viewpo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>and</strong> the traditional Austrian referenceto co-ord<strong>in</strong>ated patterns <strong>of</strong> behaviour.In what follows I <strong>in</strong>tend to argue that while one may agree withVaughn’s emphasis on the necessity <strong>of</strong> further develop<strong>in</strong>g thesubjectivism proper to the Austrian tradition, it might be arguedthat the way <strong>in</strong> which this methodological option is implemented isunconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g, at least with respect to one central issue. I willma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> that with respect to the analysis <strong>of</strong> economic<strong>in</strong>stitutionswhich Vaughn considers essential for the notion <strong>of</strong> ordershe suggests—some dist<strong>in</strong>guished Austrian arguments are not onlycritical <strong>of</strong> the ma<strong>in</strong>stream, but also <strong>in</strong>conclusive. This is ma<strong>in</strong>lybecause these arguments are derived from an analysis <strong>of</strong> economic<strong>in</strong>stitutions, which is limited to the usual comparison betweendecentralised <strong>and</strong> centralised economies <strong>and</strong> devoid <strong>of</strong> appropriatereference to a number <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g developments—generatedwith<strong>in</strong> the ma<strong>in</strong>stream, even if critical <strong>of</strong> the st<strong>and</strong>ard account <strong>of</strong>it—which try to deepen the underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the organisation <strong>of</strong>exchanges <strong>in</strong> decentralised economies. To be specific, I will arguethat the Austrian attitude towards the ma<strong>in</strong>stream sometimes showslittle knowledge <strong>of</strong> the relevance <strong>of</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> recent developments fora number <strong>of</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctive Austrian themes. In order to provide thebackground for my argument, I will give a prelim<strong>in</strong>ary account <strong>of</strong>the relationship between the Austrian approach <strong>and</strong> thema<strong>in</strong>stream, with specific regard to the question <strong>of</strong> how to deal with126


RADICAL SUBJECTIVISMdecisions under uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty. It is from this prelim<strong>in</strong>ary question thatmy argument will start.Rational ignoranceIt is usual to f<strong>in</strong>d reconstructions <strong>of</strong> the Austrian tradition whichemphasise a Kirznerian <strong>and</strong> a Lachmannian ve<strong>in</strong> (for example, seeO’Driscoll <strong>and</strong> Rizzo 1985). But the way <strong>in</strong> which Vaughn presentsthe former as a ‘supplement to neoclassical economies’ <strong>and</strong> the latteras the only possible way to a mean<strong>in</strong>gful ‘alternative conception <strong>of</strong>order’ is uncommonly persuasive. The most prom<strong>in</strong>ent example canbe found <strong>in</strong> the consideration <strong>of</strong> the analytical tools needed to dealeffectively with uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>and</strong> the passage <strong>of</strong> time.Vaughn argues that Kirzner has been successful <strong>in</strong> provid<strong>in</strong>g ananalysis <strong>of</strong> the process through which competitive markets mayreach equilibrium. His notion <strong>of</strong> the alert entrepreneur is a def<strong>in</strong>itestep forward <strong>in</strong> the appreciation <strong>of</strong> the role <strong>of</strong> those economicagents who ‘notice opportunities that others miss <strong>and</strong> act upon thatknowledge to br<strong>in</strong>g markets closer to equilibrium’ (165). But whenreal time <strong>and</strong> genu<strong>in</strong>e uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty are taken <strong>in</strong>to account there is nolonger any reason to argue that each entrepreneur is ‘correct’ <strong>in</strong> hisor her action, <strong>and</strong> thus no reason for expect<strong>in</strong>g their jo<strong>in</strong>t actions tobe equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g, as Kirzner assumes. This is why any attempt t<strong>of</strong>ormalise entrepreneurial behaviour as a problem <strong>of</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>edmaximisation under uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty is bound to be unproductive.Genu<strong>in</strong>e uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty must imply that the entrepreneur cannotanticipate all possible future consequences <strong>of</strong> his action. Thereforeequilibrium cannot be considered an ex ante reference po<strong>in</strong>t foranalysis.Lachmann’s contribution, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, takes stock <strong>of</strong> thetraditional Austrian emphasis on heterogeneous <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>completeknowledge <strong>and</strong> comes to the conclusion that only those descriptions<strong>of</strong> economic activities that consider endogenous <strong>and</strong> unpredictablechange are apt to underst<strong>and</strong> agents’ behaviour. The market processdriven by <strong>in</strong>dividuals whose act<strong>in</strong>g is ‘undeterm<strong>in</strong>ed creative choice’(152) is necessarily an open-ended process. Not just the possibility<strong>of</strong> anticipat<strong>in</strong>g it ex ante, but the very notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium is called<strong>in</strong>to question.The ma<strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> disagreement between the two alternativeviews <strong>of</strong> Kirzner <strong>and</strong> Lachmann not only orig<strong>in</strong>ated <strong>in</strong> a differentattitude towards the modell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual behaviour, but also <strong>in</strong>the explanation <strong>of</strong> what the achievable aggregate outcomes are.127


CARLO ZAPPIAThey both recognise that the question is not so much that <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>correctly perceived opportunities by <strong>in</strong>dividual agents—which isusually dealt with <strong>in</strong> neoclassical economics—as that <strong>of</strong> unperceivedopportunities. Still, Kirzner admits that equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g actions can beconsistently def<strong>in</strong>ed, thus stick<strong>in</strong>g implicitly to a (perhapsgeneralised) constra<strong>in</strong>ed optimisation approach <strong>in</strong> the Robb<strong>in</strong>siantradition. As Vaughn contends, ‘he has improved upon a model <strong>of</strong>market behaviour that still fails to capture the central problem <strong>of</strong>human action’ (150). In fact, ‘he rejects the notion thatentrepreneurs create anyth<strong>in</strong>g ex nihilo, <strong>in</strong>stead argu<strong>in</strong>g that bydiscover<strong>in</strong>g opportunities already “there” to be discovered, they are<strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g genu<strong>in</strong>e novelty <strong>in</strong>to the system’ (148). Thus it wouldseem that, from Vaughn’s viewpo<strong>in</strong>t, ‘genu<strong>in</strong>e novelty’ <strong>and</strong>unperceived opportunities are dist<strong>in</strong>ct.In contrast, Lachmann th<strong>in</strong>ks that, if equilibrium is no longer auseful tool, then the notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g action is un<strong>in</strong>telligible.Therefore he argues for an entirely different approach. Follow<strong>in</strong>gShackle, Lachmann ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s that it is the undeterm<strong>in</strong>ed nature <strong>of</strong>the future that expla<strong>in</strong>s why the consequences <strong>of</strong> creative choice areunpredictable. ‘Genu<strong>in</strong>e novelty’ rests <strong>in</strong> the fact that ‘no two m<strong>in</strong>dsare alike’ (153), so that neither <strong>in</strong>dividual choices nor their outcomecan be fully predicted. As a consequence, economic theory mustdraw on the notion <strong>of</strong> a plan ‘to make the world <strong>in</strong>telligible <strong>in</strong> terms<strong>of</strong> human action’. But the passage <strong>of</strong> time accounts for the fact that‘revision <strong>of</strong> plans is the norm rather than the exception’ (154), thusrender<strong>in</strong>g co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation almost unachievable as a state <strong>of</strong> theeconomy. Lachmann’s suggested solution, Vaughn contends, is thento be sought <strong>in</strong> the study <strong>of</strong> those <strong>in</strong>stitutions that can favour ordereven <strong>in</strong> the face <strong>of</strong> unco-ord<strong>in</strong>ated patterns <strong>of</strong> behaviour. But, asregards the possibility <strong>of</strong> hav<strong>in</strong>g a formal theory <strong>of</strong> economicdecisions, we are only left with a series <strong>of</strong> negative statements. InVaughn’s words ‘Lachmann, <strong>in</strong> an attempt to take radicalsubjectivism <strong>and</strong> real time seriously <strong>in</strong> his <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong>economic action, tries to devise an alternative to equilibriumtheoris<strong>in</strong>g but fails to produce the k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> overall theoreticalstructure that would seriously challenge the neoclassical hegemony’(161). In particular, one might add, Lachmann does not provide anydescription <strong>of</strong> the characteristics <strong>of</strong> the doma<strong>in</strong> encompass<strong>in</strong>g notonly unperceived but also <strong>in</strong>conceivable opportunities.The fact that the modell<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual behaviour is crucial tothe whole <strong>of</strong> Vaughn’s reassessment <strong>of</strong> the Austrian tradition isdemonstrated <strong>in</strong> her attempt to summarise what aspects can be128


RADICAL SUBJECTIVISMconsidered as ‘hard core’ Austrian. She po<strong>in</strong>ts to a widely agreedop<strong>in</strong>ion on the assumption <strong>of</strong> perfect knowledge used <strong>in</strong> neoclassicaleconomics as head<strong>in</strong>g the list <strong>of</strong> commonly shared beliefs amongAustrian scholars:Austrians agree with neoclassical economics that humanbe<strong>in</strong>gs attempt to act rationally to achieve their purposes.However, because human action always takes place <strong>in</strong> time<strong>and</strong> always under conditions <strong>of</strong> partial ignorance about thepresent <strong>and</strong> total ignorance about the future, a theory <strong>of</strong>market processes can be neither static <strong>in</strong> nature nor based onthe assumption <strong>of</strong> perfect knowledge. Nor is rationalignorance a promis<strong>in</strong>g assumption for Austrians who denythat all the relevant future states <strong>of</strong> the world are listable bythe choos<strong>in</strong>g agent.(163, my italics)Given that perfect knowledge is obviously not a common assumption<strong>in</strong> most modern economic theory, the real mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> rationalignorance deserves closer <strong>in</strong>vestigation. Austrian economics, Vaughnstresses, ‘cannot usefully be considered merely a variation on theeconomics <strong>of</strong> rationality <strong>and</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>ed maximisation’ (162). Thisstatement accounts for her position, which is critical <strong>of</strong> Kirzner’sideas <strong>and</strong> supportive <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s. But the ma<strong>in</strong> question that theanalysis <strong>of</strong> the two different positions leaves open is the follow<strong>in</strong>g:what does rational ignorance really mean?If one looks at the theory <strong>of</strong> decision adopted by ma<strong>in</strong>streameconomic theory for the last forty years, th<strong>in</strong>gs appear to be pla<strong>in</strong>.The theory <strong>of</strong> economic decisions has been based—start<strong>in</strong>g fromSavage’s def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> states <strong>of</strong> nature—on Bayesian decision theory,which requires that the possible events must be ‘listable’ <strong>and</strong> thattheir (subjective) probabilities <strong>of</strong> realisation add up to unity. Indeed,the basic assumption <strong>of</strong> decision theory under uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty is thateconomic agents know with certa<strong>in</strong>ty the doma<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> theiruncerta<strong>in</strong>ty. This is <strong>of</strong> course not a theoretically appeal<strong>in</strong>gassumption if one is <strong>in</strong>terested, as the Austrians are, <strong>in</strong> ‘themes suchas the importance <strong>of</strong> dynamic growth <strong>and</strong> development, thegeneration <strong>and</strong> function <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>in</strong> economic action, theuncerta<strong>in</strong>ties associated with processes <strong>in</strong> time <strong>and</strong> the pivotalimportance <strong>of</strong> diversity <strong>and</strong> heterogeneity <strong>in</strong> economic life’ (162).But one should notice that <strong>in</strong> recent years some perceptivema<strong>in</strong>stream theorists have shown that they share with the Austrians129


CARLO ZAPPIAthe same discomfort. The difficulties <strong>in</strong> represent<strong>in</strong>g formally howthe knowledge <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual agents changes—which is the upshot <strong>of</strong>Lachmann’s <strong>in</strong>sistence on the subjective nature <strong>of</strong> knowledge—hastroubled many neoclassical economists. More <strong>and</strong> more <strong>of</strong> themhave <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly acknowledged these difficulties. This is apparent<strong>in</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium towards amore dynamic conception, as <strong>in</strong> the works <strong>of</strong> Hahn (1973) <strong>and</strong>Fisher (1983). 3What is more important with respect to the Austrian themes isthat there is now an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g number <strong>of</strong> attempts to deal explicitlywith the question from a choice theoretic perspective (among others,see Kreps 1992 <strong>and</strong> Hahn 1995a). Let us take as an example Kreps’sanalysis <strong>of</strong> unforeseen cont<strong>in</strong>gencies. In an effort to give choicetheoretic foundations to Williamson’s contention that many <strong>of</strong> theforms <strong>of</strong> contractual arrangements one can observe <strong>in</strong> markets <strong>and</strong>organisations are to be attributed to the need to adapt tocont<strong>in</strong>gencies which cannot be anticipated at the date <strong>of</strong> thesignature <strong>of</strong> the contract, Kreps provides a model <strong>of</strong> choice <strong>in</strong> whichthe <strong>in</strong>dividual agent is aware, at the outset, that unforeseencont<strong>in</strong>gencies may arise. In other words, the <strong>in</strong>dividual agent mightnot have been able to imag<strong>in</strong>e at an earlier date an event which henow has to face up to. The analytical trick is to leave room for astate <strong>of</strong> nature which can be called ‘none <strong>of</strong> the other states’, whosecontent is not conceivable ex ante. In this way one can imag<strong>in</strong>edifferent degrees <strong>of</strong> flexibility preserved by agents for futuredecisions about possibly new events (Kreps 1992:259–61). 4 One canalso refer to the related, <strong>and</strong> probably more powerful, notion <strong>of</strong>unawareness presented <strong>in</strong> Modica <strong>and</strong> Rustich<strong>in</strong>i (1994), where thediscussion <strong>in</strong>volves unforeseeable cont<strong>in</strong>gencies. In other words, the<strong>in</strong>dividual agent might have been unable not only to th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>of</strong> theevent but even to underst<strong>and</strong> it before its realisation. It is also worthstress<strong>in</strong>g that this k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> approach h<strong>in</strong>ts at a departure fromtraditional choice theory, which is not <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple limited toexogenous uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty as <strong>in</strong>dicated by Hahn’s conjecture (1995a)about the possibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g endogenous uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>in</strong>toequilibrium theory via the notion <strong>of</strong> unawareness. I believe that thenotion <strong>of</strong> unawareness can account for certa<strong>in</strong> aspects <strong>of</strong> Vaughn’sidea <strong>of</strong> ‘genu<strong>in</strong>e novelty’.The aspects <strong>of</strong> decision theory just mentioned do not represent anisolated contention by certa<strong>in</strong> lead<strong>in</strong>g authors. The astonish<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> studies concerned with <strong>in</strong>formational asymmetries,<strong>in</strong>complete contracts, non-additive probability theory <strong>and</strong> so on do130


RADICAL SUBJECTIVISMnot simply entail a major extension <strong>of</strong> formal exercises <strong>in</strong>constra<strong>in</strong>ed maximisation. They <strong>in</strong>dicate the attitude <strong>of</strong> moderneconomic theory towards the question <strong>of</strong> rational ignorance. Thetraditional formulation <strong>of</strong> the problem <strong>of</strong> decision underuncerta<strong>in</strong>ty is still dom<strong>in</strong>ant, above all because <strong>of</strong> the central roleassigned to utility-maximis<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividuals; but an <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gnumber <strong>of</strong> papers are devoted to alternative ways <strong>of</strong> formalis<strong>in</strong>guncerta<strong>in</strong>ty. The literature on <strong>in</strong>complete contracts is a notableexample. The argument for sign<strong>in</strong>g an <strong>in</strong>complete contractconceives fully rational agents who decide not to spend time <strong>in</strong>describ<strong>in</strong>g states that <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple can be described (for <strong>in</strong>stance,because they are not easily observed from outside by a judge, assuggested <strong>in</strong> Hart <strong>and</strong> Holmstrom 1987). In this <strong>in</strong>stance agentsmay form beliefs that can be represented as probabilities over the set<strong>of</strong> unexplored states.It might be argued that there are different, <strong>and</strong> much moreconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g, reasons for justify<strong>in</strong>g an analysis <strong>of</strong> ignorance, asargued <strong>in</strong> the Austrian tradition. But it is difficult to underst<strong>and</strong> whyone should not take stock <strong>of</strong> the effort <strong>of</strong> ‘erroneously’ justifiedanalyses. If the ma<strong>in</strong> analytical po<strong>in</strong>t is the one that concerns thepossibility <strong>of</strong> list<strong>in</strong>g the future events, it is counterproductive todeny that there are many studies seriously confront<strong>in</strong>g it.One possible objection to my po<strong>in</strong>t might be that it is difficult tosay which contributions can be labelled as part <strong>of</strong> the ma<strong>in</strong>stream<strong>and</strong> which not. Of course, Williamson is not a typical neoclassicalrepresentative. But his contribution draws on opportunisticbehaviour at least as much as other neoclassical work. If the crucialpo<strong>in</strong>t is whether or not we are deal<strong>in</strong>g with utility maximisers, allthe studies I have mentioned can be considered ma<strong>in</strong>stream. It mightalso be argued that these studies do not constitute a coherent entity.For <strong>in</strong>stance, Kreps’s formalisation holds only if the ‘sureth<strong>in</strong>gpr<strong>in</strong>ciple’ is assumed, while studies <strong>in</strong> non-additive probabilitytheory are based precisely on its denial, which emerges from theEllsberg paradox (for example, see Mach<strong>in</strong>a 1987 <strong>and</strong> Camerer <strong>and</strong>Weber 1992). But that does not change the substance <strong>of</strong> theargument: the question <strong>of</strong> how to formalise decision mak<strong>in</strong>g underuncerta<strong>in</strong>ty is central <strong>in</strong> much <strong>of</strong> modern economic theory, <strong>and</strong> thesuggested solutions cannot be simply considered variations <strong>in</strong>constra<strong>in</strong>ed optimisation. 5To sum up on this question <strong>of</strong> rational ignorance: my po<strong>in</strong>t is thatthe comparison between neoclassical theory <strong>and</strong> alternativeparadigms, such as the Austrian, should take <strong>in</strong>to account the131


CARLO ZAPPIAmultiple aspects <strong>of</strong> neoclassical theory. It is unhelpful to comparethe Austrian <strong>in</strong>sights on knowledge <strong>and</strong> time with a mere travesty <strong>of</strong>neoclassical theory. Even if one po<strong>in</strong>ts at the efforts <strong>of</strong> generalequilibrium theorists, it can be shown that they are now <strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong>account<strong>in</strong>g for endogenous uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>formationasymmtries. The st<strong>and</strong>ard framework is one <strong>of</strong> miss<strong>in</strong>g markets <strong>and</strong>impossibility <strong>of</strong> complete <strong>in</strong>surance aga<strong>in</strong>st future events.Indeterm<strong>in</strong>acy <strong>of</strong> equilibria, that is multiplicity, is regarded as thenorm; Pareto-constra<strong>in</strong>ed efficiency <strong>of</strong> equilibria is not guaranteed(Hahn 1995b).We have seen that while she considers Kirzner’s analysis tooclosely l<strong>in</strong>ked to the ma<strong>in</strong>stream, Vaughn f<strong>in</strong>ds it difficult to clarifythe Lachmannian alternative. Of course, Lachmann’s attitudetowards what other Austrian scholars have characterised as‘theoretical nihilism’ leaves economic theory without a clear path t<strong>of</strong>ollow, at least as regards the study <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual behaviour. As weshall see <strong>in</strong> a moment, Vaughn’s viewpo<strong>in</strong>t is that the solution to thisproblem can be found <strong>in</strong> an elaboration <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong> order whichtakes the role <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>in</strong>to due account.But the attitude that denies the possibility <strong>of</strong> any solution at the<strong>in</strong>dividual level is unconv<strong>in</strong>c<strong>in</strong>g. Moreover, it is fruitless <strong>in</strong> thecomparison between Austrian <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>and</strong> the ma<strong>in</strong>stream, becauseit makes it difficult to underst<strong>and</strong> whether the ma<strong>in</strong>stream hasactually understood the Austrian message. To take an example, <strong>in</strong>the Austrian literature the <strong>in</strong>fluences <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s work on theeconomics <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation are <strong>of</strong>ten noted, as Vaughn po<strong>in</strong>ts out(165). But the unanimous conclusion by the Austrians is thatHayek’s pr<strong>of</strong>ound <strong>in</strong>sights have been misunderstood <strong>and</strong> notproperly dealt with. It is worth not<strong>in</strong>g that non-Austrian theoristsshow an opposite attitude on this historiographic matter. Hahn(1990) has recently contended that a typical Hayekian theme suchas that prices may reflect the different expectations <strong>of</strong> agents <strong>and</strong>thus reveal <strong>in</strong>formation has been carried well beyond Hayek’s vagueremarks, <strong>and</strong> ‘fully absorbed’ <strong>in</strong> neoclassical economics, only byvirtue <strong>of</strong> the literature on revelation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation prompted byRadner (1979) <strong>and</strong> Grossman (1989). Milgrom <strong>and</strong> Roberts (1992:Chapter 4) consider Hayek’s notion <strong>of</strong> personal knowledge centralbut <strong>in</strong>sufficient on its own for the comparative analysis <strong>of</strong>organisations <strong>and</strong> the market. Similar viewpo<strong>in</strong>ts can be found <strong>in</strong>Arrow (1994), with respect to the notion <strong>of</strong> personal knowledge ascompared to that <strong>of</strong> technological knowledge, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> Bowles <strong>and</strong>G<strong>in</strong>tis (1993) <strong>and</strong> Stiglitz (1994), with respect to those functions132


RADICAL SUBJECTIVISMperformed by the market that are not simply allocative. I haveargued elsewhere that an attitude different from Vaughn’s withrespect to the relationships between Hayek’s <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>and</strong> modernattempts to deal with asymmetries <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation may be morefruitful (Zappia 1997). I shall now turn to this issue.<strong>Economic</strong> order <strong>and</strong> economic <strong>in</strong>stitutionsThe most important <strong>of</strong> Vaughn’s recurrent themes is the necessityfor current Austrian economics to consistently develop an analysis<strong>of</strong> economic <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>in</strong> the direction <strong>in</strong>dicated by Menger <strong>and</strong>Hayek. Her book is written under the firm, <strong>and</strong> clearly argued,belief that the unorthodox component <strong>of</strong> Menger as a founder <strong>of</strong> theneoclassical paradigm—his theory <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>in</strong>stitutions—is thecornerstone <strong>of</strong> the Austrian approach. Thus, although equilibrium isthe dom<strong>in</strong>ant organis<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>in</strong> most economic theory, theAustrians, especially s<strong>in</strong>ce Hayek’s reconsideration <strong>of</strong> Menger’stheory <strong>of</strong> the orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>in</strong>stitutions, have turned theirattention to the more general notion <strong>of</strong> social order. The ultimategoal <strong>of</strong> this shift <strong>of</strong> focus is not, as the evolution <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s thoughtmight suggest, the search for a qualitative notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium tocounterbalance the quantitative notion <strong>of</strong> the ma<strong>in</strong>stream. (This hasbeen argued even recently <strong>in</strong> Donzelli 1993 <strong>and</strong> Moss 1994.) In fact,Vaughn ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong>s, it is <strong>in</strong> the way order is conceived, as ‘a system <strong>of</strong>rules established to enable <strong>in</strong>dividuals to achieve their ownobjectives’ (123), that the impact <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s work (especially Law,Legislation <strong>and</strong> Liberty) can best be appreciated. A corollary <strong>of</strong> thisview <strong>of</strong> order is that the objectives <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>and</strong> the specificaction they set <strong>in</strong> motion:depend upon their [the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s] perception <strong>of</strong>opportunities,…but the process for tak<strong>in</strong>g these actionsdepends upon the legal <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>formal rules structure <strong>in</strong> whichthey operate, a rules structure that <strong>in</strong>cludes rules <strong>of</strong> bus<strong>in</strong>esstrad<strong>in</strong>g as well as <strong>of</strong> cultural norms <strong>and</strong> legal prescriptions.(124–5)Vaughn’s view is that Hayek’s <strong>in</strong>sistence on the heterogeneous <strong>and</strong>dispersed nature <strong>of</strong> market knowledge not only implies a vision <strong>of</strong>the market order as a discovery procedure, ‘a means <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>duc<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>dividuals to learn more about the opportunities available tothem <strong>and</strong> to create new products <strong>and</strong> new methods <strong>of</strong> production’.133


CARLO ZAPPIAIt also allows an ‘evolutionary theory <strong>of</strong> social <strong>in</strong>stitutions where<strong>in</strong>those that survived only did so because they better helped<strong>in</strong>dividuals with<strong>in</strong> a society to achieve their goals.…It is<strong>in</strong>disputable’, Vaughn concludes, ‘that [Hayek’s] theory <strong>of</strong> socialevolution helped to po<strong>in</strong>t Austrian economists toward the study <strong>of</strong>economic <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> evolutionary orders <strong>in</strong> a systematic way’(126–7). The Austrian alternative to conventional equilibriumtheoris<strong>in</strong>g is thus to be found <strong>in</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> anevolutionary theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions.The implicit assumption <strong>in</strong> Vaughn’s read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Hayek <strong>and</strong> thesubsequent evolution <strong>of</strong> the Austrian paradigm is that a specificanalysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual behaviour no longer matters once themethodological implications <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s work are correctly drawn.The Hayekian notion <strong>of</strong> spontaneous order is not to be <strong>in</strong>terpretedsimply as a fundamental shift <strong>in</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g about the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> thetype <strong>of</strong> co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation that is conceptualised by general equilibrium(as <strong>in</strong> Moss 1994). Neither can it be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as a qualitativeequilibrium construct with<strong>in</strong> which formal economic theory canhelp <strong>in</strong> clarify<strong>in</strong>g the phases <strong>of</strong> plan co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation. On the contrary,it is a def<strong>in</strong>ite step towards an underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> economics largely as‘a study <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>in</strong>stitutions with<strong>in</strong> a nonequilibrium context’(127). This is why Kirzner’s approach to <strong>in</strong>dividual behaviour isregarded merely as a variation <strong>in</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>ed optimisation. As forLachmann, his <strong>in</strong>ability to give analytic content to his <strong>in</strong>sights onthe <strong>in</strong>herently cont<strong>in</strong>uous revision <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals’ plans is deemedunimportant <strong>in</strong> comparison to the alternatives to conventionalequilibrium theoris<strong>in</strong>g suggested <strong>in</strong> his work. One might even arguethat Vaughn’s assessment <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s role <strong>in</strong> the development <strong>of</strong>Austrian thought po<strong>in</strong>ts to the ‘beneficial’ <strong>in</strong>fluences <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’sbelief that no formal theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual decision mak<strong>in</strong>g can bearrived at.Vaughn’s proposal, then, is to follow the implications <strong>of</strong> herread<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s ab<strong>and</strong>onment <strong>of</strong> general equilibrium analysis,that is to <strong>in</strong>vestigate a different notion <strong>of</strong> order. But the notion <strong>of</strong>spontaneous order <strong>in</strong> itself cannot accomplish this task. ForVaughn’s contention about the impossibility <strong>of</strong> giv<strong>in</strong>g formalsupport to the analysis <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual behaviour when newknowledge is prompted by the passage <strong>of</strong> time implies that themarket tendency towards a spontaneous order is not guaranteed.Here Lachmann makes his contribution; he improves on Hayek’sidea <strong>of</strong> spontaneous order by po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g out ‘that markets are subjectto both disequilibrat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g tendencies’ <strong>and</strong> that pure134


RADICAL SUBJECTIVISMeconomic theory cannot help <strong>in</strong> show<strong>in</strong>g ‘which k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> tendenciesdom<strong>in</strong>ate the system’ (160). Lachmann’s most fruitful suggestion isthus to ab<strong>and</strong>on the search for alternative equilibrium constructs,<strong>and</strong> to pursue the analysis <strong>of</strong> those <strong>in</strong>stitutional sett<strong>in</strong>gs that favourthe market’s order. But Lachmann’s drawback is that he failed toprovide a ‘clearly articulated theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions’ (157). As aconsequence, <strong>in</strong> order to move forward <strong>in</strong> the development <strong>of</strong> anAustrian alternative to the ma<strong>in</strong>stream, it is necessary to address thequestion <strong>of</strong> how <strong>in</strong>stitutions can evolve, persist <strong>and</strong> justify thedesirability—if not the efficiency—<strong>of</strong> the market order. 6The upshot <strong>of</strong> Vaughn’s assessment <strong>of</strong> the Austrian paradigm isclearly summarised <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g:<strong>Economic</strong>s is a social science that by def<strong>in</strong>ition is concernedwith underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g order <strong>in</strong> human society. As human be<strong>in</strong>gswe recognise many recurrent patterns <strong>of</strong> behaviour that result<strong>in</strong> orderly social processes—customs, manners, laws,<strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> relationships. In addition, <strong>of</strong>ten what seemsdisorderly <strong>and</strong> chaotic at first glance, upon further<strong>in</strong>vestigation, can be shown to reflect some deeperunsuspected pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> order, usually some purposefulresponse to perceived constra<strong>in</strong>ts…. The question is, how dowe expla<strong>in</strong> this social order that goes beyond our immediateperceptions while rema<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g true to our recognition thathumans act not only to make themselves better <strong>of</strong>f, but they doso <strong>in</strong> a world <strong>of</strong> limited resources, <strong>in</strong>complete knowledge <strong>and</strong>radical uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty?(164)In their cont<strong>in</strong>uous search for an alternative theoretical structurethat would provide a better explanation <strong>of</strong> economic order thanneoclassical economics, the Austrians have provided a number <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g equilibrium constructs, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Mises’s notion <strong>of</strong> anevenly rotat<strong>in</strong>g economy, Hayek’s notion <strong>of</strong> plan co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>and</strong>O’Driscoll <strong>and</strong> Rizzo’s notion <strong>of</strong> pattern co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation. These threenotions are all carefully exam<strong>in</strong>ed by Vaughn, but the one she seemsmost supportive <strong>of</strong> is O’Driscoll’s <strong>and</strong> Rizzo’s. Their approach is anattempt to develop a def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation that is <strong>in</strong>tended todescribe an economic system <strong>in</strong> which new endogenous knowledgeis fostered by the actions <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual agents <strong>and</strong> thus toaccommodate endogenous <strong>and</strong> unpredictable change.But even though pattern co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation has its attraction for135


CARLO ZAPPIAVaughn, the major component <strong>of</strong> a satisfy<strong>in</strong>g notion <strong>of</strong> order is stillmiss<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>Economic</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions can be considered as ‘po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong>orientation’ for <strong>in</strong>dividual agents <strong>and</strong> thus favour pattern coord<strong>in</strong>ation—thatis co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation among the typical, recurrentfeatures <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual actions—even if specific aspects <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualactions ‘fail to mesh’, as O’Driscoll <strong>and</strong> Rizzo contend. On the otherh<strong>and</strong>, even those specific aspects <strong>of</strong> human action that do turn out tobe unco-ord<strong>in</strong>ated are relevant for the endogenous change <strong>of</strong>prevail<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stitutions. What the Austrian tradition has h<strong>in</strong>ted at,but not dealt with as much as it should, is the fact that ‘errors thatconstitute part <strong>of</strong> the market process should be construed as both<strong>in</strong>tegral <strong>and</strong> beneficial’. Therefore, the proper approach to learn<strong>in</strong>gis ‘how can mistakes <strong>and</strong> error be channelled <strong>in</strong>to productiveknowledge’ (173). At this po<strong>in</strong>t, Vaughn abruptly concludes that acogent explanation <strong>of</strong> the market process as a process <strong>of</strong> trial <strong>and</strong>error thus requires an evolutionary theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions, whereexperimentation <strong>and</strong> learn<strong>in</strong>g, which lead to ‘new modes <strong>of</strong> human<strong>in</strong>teraction’, can expla<strong>in</strong> ‘the orig<strong>in</strong>, persistence or failure <strong>of</strong> human<strong>in</strong>stitutions, those regular observable patterns <strong>of</strong> action that lendstability <strong>and</strong> predictability to human life’ (175).So Vaughn seems to be support<strong>in</strong>g a def<strong>in</strong>itive withdrawal fromthe traditional ways <strong>of</strong> economic theoris<strong>in</strong>g, by argu<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> favour <strong>of</strong>a shift <strong>of</strong> focus from spontaneous to social order, <strong>and</strong> for almost thesame reasons that prompted Hayek’s withdrawal from equilibriumtowards spontaneous order. But Vaughn’s discussion <strong>of</strong> those<strong>in</strong>stitutions that ‘permit the use <strong>of</strong> new knowledge <strong>in</strong> human action’(174) is not very satisfy<strong>in</strong>g. She only refers to the tradition <strong>of</strong> thoseeconomists, notably Nelson <strong>and</strong> W<strong>in</strong>ter, who have attempted to adaptevolutionary reason<strong>in</strong>g to economic processes, <strong>and</strong> to the similaritiesbetween certa<strong>in</strong> features <strong>of</strong> evolutionary theory <strong>and</strong> the Austrianviewpo<strong>in</strong>t, as represented by Witt (1992) <strong>and</strong> Horwitz (1992). Shealso concedes, ‘there is much work to be done’ (175). Indeed, theneed for the Austrian research programme to ab<strong>and</strong>on the equilibriummetaphor <strong>and</strong> to elaborate an evolutionary notion <strong>of</strong> social order issupported only by a few suggestions for future research. This<strong>in</strong>evitably leaves the reader feel<strong>in</strong>g discontented, for Vaughn doesnot even discuss the difficulties <strong>of</strong> reconcil<strong>in</strong>g methodological<strong>in</strong>dividualism with group selection processes on which theevolutionary approach h<strong>in</strong>ges. Moreover, it seems to imply that theanalytic content <strong>of</strong> the Austrian paradigm is yet to be developed.The future relevance <strong>of</strong> Austrian economics might probablydepend on the viability <strong>of</strong> Vaughn’s suggestions, although current136


RADICAL SUBJECTIVISMAustrian researchers are still divided on the research strategies to befollowed <strong>in</strong> order to avoid the sidel<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Austrian economics (forexample see Rizzo’s (1992) <strong>and</strong> White’s (1992) sharplydifferentiated positions). Although it is not an aim <strong>of</strong> my chapter tomake conjectures about the future Austrian impact on economicresearch, let me conclude by mak<strong>in</strong>g some remarks on a differentimplication <strong>of</strong> Vaughn’s proposal.One issue Vaughn leaves undiscussed is why the analysis <strong>of</strong>economic <strong>in</strong>stitutions cannot be based on the study <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividualbehaviour, as is traditional <strong>in</strong> the Austrian approach. She arguesthat:people carry out their projects <strong>and</strong> plans with<strong>in</strong> a variety <strong>of</strong>social <strong>in</strong>stitutions, all <strong>of</strong> which have both tacit <strong>and</strong> explicitrules <strong>of</strong> behaviour…. Indeed, an agreement between twopeople to engage <strong>in</strong> a recurrent pattern <strong>of</strong> behaviour vis à viseach other is also a form <strong>of</strong> ‘<strong>in</strong>stitution’ or typical behaviour.(171)But here Vaughn neglects to refer to the fact that a lead<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> the recent developments <strong>in</strong> the economics <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>formation is that if opportunistic behaviour is properly taken <strong>in</strong>toaccount, then the typical contract between two asymmetrically<strong>in</strong>formed agents can be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as the outcome <strong>of</strong> tacit rules <strong>of</strong>behaviour (for a summary, see Bowles <strong>and</strong> G<strong>in</strong>tis 1993). A morethorough <strong>in</strong>spection <strong>of</strong> the market as an <strong>in</strong>stitution reveals thatmany aspects <strong>of</strong> economic activity such as repeated <strong>in</strong>teraction forexchange purposes do not necessarily <strong>in</strong>volve the emergence <strong>of</strong>organisations, but can be expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong>stead as the emergence <strong>of</strong>conventional behaviour among dist<strong>in</strong>ct market participants, <strong>and</strong>that this can be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as ‘a form <strong>of</strong> “<strong>in</strong>stitution”’. This view isconsistent with the Austrian view <strong>of</strong> the market as represented byHayek. Hayek’s conception <strong>of</strong> the superiority <strong>of</strong> the market overalternative organisational sett<strong>in</strong>gs is not exclusively l<strong>in</strong>ked to theimpersonal work<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the price system <strong>and</strong> its efficiency <strong>in</strong>diffus<strong>in</strong>g exist<strong>in</strong>g knowledge <strong>and</strong> creat<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>centives fordiscover<strong>in</strong>g new knowledge. It also emphasises the role <strong>of</strong> thoseforces <strong>of</strong> competition, such as imitative behaviour, rules <strong>and</strong>traditions, which were excluded by the Walrasian <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong>competition. The view that the exchange <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation that isdispersed throughout the system is achieved through a process thatis more complex than the Walrasian process <strong>of</strong> impersonal137


CARLO ZAPPIAallocation through prices is not only compatible with Austrianthought, but has also been strongly supported by Hayek (1948 <strong>and</strong>1968). I have argued elsewhere (Zappia 1997) that a superficialdenial <strong>of</strong> the relevance <strong>of</strong> many recent microeconomic developmentsto underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g the market as an <strong>in</strong>stitution is <strong>in</strong>consistent withHayek’s <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to the matter. 7Here a paradox seems to emerge: follow<strong>in</strong>g Vaughn’sreconstruction <strong>of</strong> Austrian thought, it might be argued (as <strong>in</strong> Bowles<strong>and</strong> G<strong>in</strong>tis 1993) that new developments <strong>of</strong> what Vaughn considersneoclassical theory have done more than the Austrians for provid<strong>in</strong>gan <strong>in</strong>dividualistically based explanation <strong>of</strong> those elements—such ashabits <strong>and</strong> customary bus<strong>in</strong>ess procedures—which characteriseeconomic <strong>in</strong>stitutions. But this is <strong>of</strong> course untrue, as Vaughn herselfstresses <strong>in</strong> her reassessment <strong>of</strong> Hayek s theory <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> therelated efforts by O’Driscoll <strong>and</strong> Rizzo to develop an economics <strong>of</strong>time <strong>and</strong> ignorance <strong>in</strong> which ‘the existence <strong>of</strong> private <strong>and</strong> tacitknowledge implies that nonprice signals can conta<strong>in</strong> importantmarket <strong>in</strong>formation’ (136).A similar issue arises as regards the application <strong>of</strong> game theory tothe explanation <strong>of</strong> spontaneous orders (see Sudgen 1989) <strong>and</strong> theevolution <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions. The Austrian explanation <strong>of</strong> economic<strong>in</strong>stitutions is essentially a causal-genetic theory, tak<strong>in</strong>g Menger’stheory <strong>of</strong> money as exemplar. This explanation describes thedevelopment <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions as the outcome <strong>of</strong> a sequence <strong>of</strong> actionsby <strong>in</strong>dividual agents, where the aggregate outcome <strong>of</strong> these actionsis not necessarily the <strong>in</strong>tended outcome. Indeed, what dist<strong>in</strong>guishesAustrian theory from the ‘pure’ methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism <strong>of</strong>neoclassical theory is that it necessarily <strong>in</strong>volves the explanation <strong>of</strong> acomposition pr<strong>in</strong>ciple. It might thus be argued that to represent theprocess <strong>of</strong> compos<strong>in</strong>g the effects <strong>of</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ct <strong>in</strong>dividual plans bymeans <strong>of</strong> the theory <strong>of</strong> games is a valuable complement to theevolutionary theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions (see Langlois 1992; Bianchi1994). Furthermore, this approach attributes a primary role to thedecisions <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals, which is contrary to the <strong>in</strong>terpretationsuggested by Vaughn.Conclud<strong>in</strong>g remarksIn this assessment <strong>of</strong> Karen Vaughn’s Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>in</strong>America, I have stressed that her call for a def<strong>in</strong>itive shift <strong>in</strong> Austrianthought away from the search for equilibrium constructs <strong>and</strong>towards the analysis <strong>of</strong> those <strong>in</strong>stitutions that favour ordered138


RADICAL SUBJECTIVISMoutcomes <strong>of</strong> the market process, is not justified by the <strong>in</strong>ability <strong>of</strong>pure economic theory to deal with rational ignorance. In fact, mostAustrians seem to use this argument to avoid discuss<strong>in</strong>g the<strong>in</strong>evitable withdrawal from methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism, which isimplicit <strong>in</strong> the endorsement <strong>of</strong> an evolutionary approach toeconomic theory.My aim here has not been to argue that future developments <strong>in</strong>Austrian economics should not follow this l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> research, butrather to po<strong>in</strong>t out that a withdrawal from equilibrium theoris<strong>in</strong>g—which seems contradictory both to traditional Austrian thought <strong>in</strong>general <strong>and</strong> to Hayek’s theory <strong>in</strong> particular—cannot be based on an<strong>in</strong>accurate representation <strong>of</strong> recent developments <strong>in</strong> orthodoxmicroeconomics.Furthermore, a critical, but positive, attitude towards theattempts to formalise rational ignorance might suggest that theAustrian tradition may actually <strong>in</strong>fluence future research ratherthan merely constitute an optional supplement to it. As I haveargued, the k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> formal representation <strong>of</strong> decision mak<strong>in</strong>g underuncerta<strong>in</strong>ty one f<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>in</strong> recent developments <strong>in</strong> microeconomictheory is not <strong>in</strong>tended to describe agents ‘striv<strong>in</strong>g to formulate thecorrect vision <strong>of</strong> the future as if the future were someth<strong>in</strong>g alreadyimplicit <strong>in</strong> the data <strong>and</strong> one’s only problem is to guess correctly whatthe future will be’ (147). On the contrary, it recognises as a start<strong>in</strong>gpo<strong>in</strong>t for research the view that ignorance is an <strong>in</strong>herent feature <strong>of</strong>every decision regard<strong>in</strong>g future events. In this, it resembles theShackleian—<strong>and</strong> Lachmannian—assertion that the future is theunpredictable consequence <strong>of</strong> creative choices made by <strong>in</strong>dividualagents. And it seems to po<strong>in</strong>t towards a re-elaboration <strong>of</strong> the notion<strong>of</strong> equilibrium that is compatible at least with Hayek’s, if not withthe whole Austrian, tradition.AcknowledgementsI wish to thank J.Birner, L.Moss <strong>and</strong> the editors for their commentson a previous draft <strong>of</strong> this paper.Notes1 Throughout this chapter, unless otherwise noted, the page numbers <strong>in</strong>parentheses refer to this book. The passage quoted <strong>in</strong> this paragraph istaken from p. 108.2 The <strong>in</strong>verted commas are <strong>of</strong> course necessary because it is generally139


CARLO ZAPPIAconsidered that one <strong>of</strong> the most <strong>in</strong>fluential ‘American Austrian’scholars is Lachmann.3 In their exam<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> the models provided by Hahn <strong>and</strong> Fisher,Currie <strong>and</strong> Steedman (1990:215) f<strong>in</strong>d it ‘strik<strong>in</strong>g that much recentwork has more <strong>in</strong> common…with Lachmann’s conception <strong>of</strong> marketprocesses than it does with the Arrow-Debreu economy’. Theirop<strong>in</strong>ion is relevant with respect to my argument because their analysis<strong>of</strong> economists who have dealt with the behaviour <strong>of</strong> economies overtime highlights the importance <strong>of</strong> Shackle’s <strong>and</strong> Lachmann’scontributions.4 A previous attempt is Loomes <strong>and</strong> Sudgen 1986. It is worth not<strong>in</strong>g,however, that the predictive power that is usually attributed to theBayesian process <strong>of</strong> updat<strong>in</strong>g beliefs seems bound to be lost <strong>in</strong> Kreps’srepresentation.5 A recent <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> the approach <strong>of</strong> non-additive utility theorypo<strong>in</strong>ts to the fact that while Bayesian decision theory is unable to dealwith the <strong>in</strong>fluence that choices can have on future states <strong>of</strong> nature, ama<strong>in</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> the agenda <strong>of</strong> the non-additive utility theory approach isto address the issue <strong>of</strong> the degree <strong>of</strong> irreversibility that characterises theconsequences <strong>of</strong> sequential actions (Vercelli 1995).6 Vaughn mentions, but does not discuss, Lachmann’s explicit retreat(1986) from the <strong>in</strong>stitutional issue.7 But see also the ‘Austrian rationale’ for the existence <strong>of</strong> organisationsprovided by M<strong>in</strong>kler 1993.ReferencesArrow, K.J. (1994) ‘Methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism <strong>and</strong> social knowledge’,American <strong>Economic</strong> Review, 84 (2):1–11.Bianchi, M. (1994) ‘Hayek’s spontaneous order: the “correct” versus the“corregible” society’, <strong>in</strong> J.Birner <strong>and</strong> R.Van Zijp (eds) Hayek, Coord<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>and</strong> Evolution, London: Routledge.Bowles, S. <strong>and</strong> G<strong>in</strong>tis, H. (1993) ‘The revenge <strong>of</strong> Homo <strong>Economic</strong>us:contested exchange <strong>and</strong> the revival <strong>of</strong> political economy’, Journal <strong>of</strong><strong>Economic</strong> Perspectives, 7:83–102.Camerer, C. <strong>and</strong> Weber, M. (1992) ‘Recent developments <strong>in</strong> model<strong>in</strong>gpreferences: uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>and</strong> ambiguity’, Journal <strong>of</strong> Risk <strong>and</strong>Uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, 5:325–70.Currie, D. <strong>and</strong> Steedman, I. (1990) Wrestl<strong>in</strong>g with Time, Ann Arbor:Michigan University Press.Donzelli, F. (1993) ‘The <strong>in</strong>fluence <strong>of</strong> the socialist calculation debate onHayek’s view <strong>of</strong> general equilibrium theory’, Revue Européenne desSciences Sociales, 31:47–83.Fisher, F.M. (1983) Disequilibrium Foundations <strong>of</strong> Equilibrium<strong>Economic</strong>s, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Grossman, S. (1989) The Informational Role <strong>of</strong> Prices, Cambridge, MA:MIT Press.Hahn, F.H. (1973 [1984]) ‘On the notion <strong>of</strong> equilibrium <strong>in</strong> economies’, <strong>in</strong>Equilibrium <strong>and</strong> Macroeconomics, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.140


RADICAL SUBJECTIVISM——(1990) ‘Expectations’, <strong>in</strong> J.Hey <strong>and</strong> D.W<strong>in</strong>ch (eds) A Century <strong>of</strong><strong>Economic</strong>s, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.——(1995a) ‘On economies with Arrow Securities’, mimeo. Paperpresented at the ISER on ‘Decisions under uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty’, Siena.——(1995b) ‘Uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>in</strong> general equilibrium’, mimeo. Paper presentedat Annual Meet<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the Società Italiana degli Economisti, Firenze.Hart, O. <strong>and</strong> Holmstrom, B. (1987) ‘The theory <strong>of</strong> contracts’, <strong>in</strong> T.Bewley(ed.) Advances <strong>in</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Theory, Fifth World Congress, Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.Hayek, F.A. (1948) ‘The mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> competition’, <strong>in</strong> Individualism <strong>and</strong><strong>Economic</strong> Order, London: Routledge <strong>and</strong> Kegan Paul.——(1968 [1978]) ‘Competition as a discovery procedure’, <strong>in</strong> New Studies<strong>in</strong> Philosophy, Politics, <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Ideas, Chicago:Chicago University Press.Horwitz, S. (1992) Monetary Evolution, Free Bank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>Order, San Francisco: Westview Press.Kreps, D.M. (1992) ‘Static choice <strong>in</strong> the presence <strong>of</strong> unforeseencont<strong>in</strong>gencies’, <strong>in</strong> P.Dasgupta, D.Gale, O.Hart <strong>and</strong> E.Mask<strong>in</strong> (eds)<strong>Economic</strong> <strong>Analysis</strong> <strong>of</strong> Markets <strong>and</strong> Games. <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> Honor <strong>of</strong> FrankHahn, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Lachmann, L.M. (1986) The Market as an <strong>Economic</strong> Process, Oxford:Basil Blackwell.Langlois, R.N. (1992) ‘Orders <strong>and</strong> organizations: toward an Austriantheory <strong>of</strong> social <strong>in</strong>stitutions’, <strong>in</strong> B.Caldwell <strong>and</strong> S.Boehm (eds) Austrian<strong>Economic</strong>s: Tensions <strong>and</strong> New Directions, Boston: Kluwer AcademicPublishers.Loomes, G. <strong>and</strong> Sudgen, R. (1986) ‘Disappo<strong>in</strong>tment <strong>and</strong> dynamicconsistency <strong>in</strong> choice under uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty’, Review <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Studies,53: 271–82.Mach<strong>in</strong>a, M.J. (1987) ‘Choice under uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty: problems solved <strong>and</strong>unsolved’, Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Perspectives, 1:121–54.Milgrom, P. <strong>and</strong> Roberts, J. (1992) <strong>Economic</strong>s, Organizations <strong>and</strong>Management, Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.M<strong>in</strong>kler, A.P. (1993) ‘Knowledge <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal organizations’, Journal <strong>of</strong><strong>Economic</strong> Behavior <strong>and</strong> Organization, 21:17–30.Modica, S. <strong>and</strong> Rustich<strong>in</strong>i, A. (1994) ‘Awareness <strong>and</strong> partitional<strong>in</strong>formation structures’, Theory <strong>and</strong> Decisions, 37:107–24.Moss, L.S. (1994) ‘Hayek <strong>and</strong> the several faces <strong>of</strong> socialism’, <strong>in</strong> M.Colonna, H.Hagemann <strong>and</strong> O.Homouda (eds) Capitalism, Socialism<strong>and</strong> Knowledge, vol. II, Aldershot: Edward Elgar.O’Driscoll, G.P. <strong>and</strong> Rizzo, M.J. (1985) The <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Time <strong>and</strong>Ignorance, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Radner, R. (1979) ‘Rational expectations equilibrium, generic existence<strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>formation revealed by prices’, Econometrica, 47:655–78.Rizzo, M. (1992) ‘Afterword: Austrian economics for the twenty-firstcentury’, <strong>in</strong> B.Caldwell <strong>and</strong> S.Boehm (eds) Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s:Tensions <strong>and</strong> New Directions, Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Stiglitz, J.E. (1994) Whither Socialism?, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Sudgen, R. (1989) ‘Spontaneous order’, Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Perspectives,3 (4):85–97.141


CARLO ZAPPIAVaughn, K. (1994) Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>in</strong> America: The Migration <strong>of</strong> aTradition, New York: Cambridge University Press.Vercelli, A. (1995) ‘From s<strong>of</strong>t uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty to hard environmentaluncerta<strong>in</strong>ty’, Economie Appliquée, 48:251–69.White, L.H. (1992) ‘Afterword: apprais<strong>in</strong>g Austrian economics:contentions <strong>and</strong> misdirections’, <strong>in</strong> B.Caldwell <strong>and</strong> S.Boehm (eds)Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s: Tensions <strong>and</strong> New Directions, Boston: KluwerAcademic Publishers.Witt, U. (1992) ‘Evolutionary theory—the direction Austrian economicsshould take?’ <strong>in</strong> B.Caldwell <strong>and</strong> S.Boehm (eds) Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s:Tensions <strong>and</strong> New Developments, Dodrecht: Kluwer Academics.Zappia, C. (1997) ‘Private <strong>in</strong>formation, contractual arrangements <strong>and</strong>Hayek’s knowledge problem’, <strong>in</strong> W.Keizer, B.Tieben <strong>and</strong> R.Van Zijp(eds) Austrians <strong>in</strong> Debate, London: Routledge.142


8HIERARCHICALMETAPHORS IN AUSTRIANINSTITUTIONALISMA friendly subjectivist caveatSteven HorwitzThanks <strong>in</strong> large part to the later work <strong>of</strong> Hayek <strong>and</strong> the variedcontributions <strong>of</strong> <strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann, the post-revival generation <strong>of</strong>Austrian economists is rediscover<strong>in</strong>g the importance <strong>of</strong> a theory <strong>of</strong>economic <strong>and</strong> social <strong>in</strong>stitutions for a healthy underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>economic <strong>and</strong> social order. One can legitimately say ‘rediscover<strong>in</strong>g’because an emphasis on <strong>in</strong>stitutions was at the heart <strong>of</strong> CarlMenger’s work that founded a dist<strong>in</strong>ct Austrian approach. 1 WhileHayek’s work on the evolution <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions (e.g., Hayek 1988)put the notion <strong>of</strong> spontaneous order back at the centre <strong>of</strong> Austrianeconomics, Lachmann’s endur<strong>in</strong>g contribution can be seen asrem<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g us <strong>of</strong> the equal importance <strong>of</strong> see<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>in</strong> terms<strong>of</strong> the mean<strong>in</strong>g that they have for actors. Lachmann’s work on<strong>in</strong>stitutions can thus be seen as an attempt to extend subjectivismbeyond tastes, knowledge <strong>and</strong> expectations to our underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>the very <strong>in</strong>stitutions that help to co-ord<strong>in</strong>ate our diversesubjectivities.What I hope to accomplish <strong>in</strong> this chapter is to search for anyunacceptable l<strong>in</strong>ger<strong>in</strong>g objectivism <strong>in</strong> the treatment <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutionsby both Lachmann <strong>and</strong> other post-revival Austrians. My po<strong>in</strong>t isnot merely to be deconstructive (although that is important),rather I want to give the discussion <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions a nudge towardsbe<strong>in</strong>g more completely subjectivist, <strong>and</strong> thus more true toLachmann’s own conception <strong>of</strong> economic theory <strong>and</strong> social order. 2143


STEVEN HORWITZMore specifically, there is a sense <strong>in</strong> Austrian discussions <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>stitutions that there is a certa<strong>in</strong> ‘hierarchy’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions, orthat, <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’s (1971:81) words, there are ‘<strong>in</strong>ternal’ <strong>and</strong>‘external’ <strong>in</strong>stitutions. My argument is that this way <strong>of</strong> talk<strong>in</strong>gabout <strong>in</strong>stitutions can easily lead us to posit <strong>in</strong>correctly anobjective structure or order<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions that exists separatelyfrom either the particular questions posed by theorists, or thesubjective perspectives <strong>of</strong> actors <strong>in</strong> those <strong>in</strong>stitutions. Theargument will be fleshed out by borrow<strong>in</strong>g some concepts from theAustrian theory <strong>of</strong> capital to sketch a different conceptualframework for discuss<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stitutions, <strong>and</strong> by an illustration fromthe history <strong>of</strong> bank<strong>in</strong>g.Austrian <strong>in</strong>stitutionalismThe focus <strong>of</strong> my critical attention will be the work on economic <strong>and</strong>social <strong>in</strong>stitutions by both Lachmann (1971, 1986) <strong>and</strong> RichardLanglois (1986a, b, c, 1992). The reason for this narrow focus isthat these two authors have developed the most ‘Austrian’treatments <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions. 3 It is also <strong>in</strong> their work that notions <strong>of</strong>‘externality/<strong>in</strong>ternality’ <strong>and</strong> hierarchy come to the fore. It should benoted that none <strong>of</strong> my critical comments should be seen as directedtowards the general idea <strong>of</strong> an Austrian <strong>in</strong>stitutionalism. To thecontrary, the analysis <strong>of</strong> the orig<strong>in</strong>, evolution, <strong>and</strong> function <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>stitutions is one <strong>of</strong> the most powerful contributions Austrians canprovide <strong>and</strong> the hope is that a more thorough subjectivism canimprove work along these l<strong>in</strong>es. 4Lachmann’s theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions is most clearly sketched out <strong>in</strong>his book The Legacy <strong>of</strong> Max Weber (1971). After focus<strong>in</strong>g on theplan as his central conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual human action,Lachmann asks about ‘the <strong>in</strong>terrelationship between the actions <strong>of</strong>various actors’ (1971:49). When the success <strong>of</strong> each <strong>in</strong>dividual’splan depends on the success or failure <strong>of</strong> the plans <strong>of</strong> millions <strong>of</strong>others, how are we able to acquire <strong>in</strong>formation about those plans <strong>of</strong>others? In the face <strong>of</strong> this apparent ignorance <strong>of</strong> others’ plans, howdoes social co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation ever come about? The answer, accord<strong>in</strong>gto Lachmann (as taken from Weber) is through social <strong>in</strong>stitutions.This question, <strong>in</strong> a variety <strong>of</strong> forms, is one that has been woventhrough Austrian economics for many years. From Menger’s (1985[1883]) orig<strong>in</strong>al emphasis on undesigned <strong>in</strong>stitutions, to Hayek’s(1937) def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> equilibrium <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> plan co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation, toO’Driscoll <strong>and</strong> Rizzo’s (1985:86) discussion <strong>of</strong> ‘pattern144


HIERARCHICAL METAPHORScoord<strong>in</strong>ation’, which ‘<strong>in</strong>volves the coord<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> plans but not <strong>of</strong>actual activities’, Austrians have always asked a version <strong>of</strong>Lachmann’s question. 5 The novelty <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s answer was thatit rem<strong>in</strong>ded Austrians <strong>of</strong> their roots <strong>in</strong> the Germanic sociologicaltradition <strong>of</strong> Weber, Georg Simmel <strong>and</strong> Alfred Schutz. 6Central to that tradition, especially <strong>in</strong> its Weberian extensions,was the role <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions as social co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation processes. InLachmann’s conception, <strong>in</strong>stitutions:enable each <strong>of</strong> us to rely on the actions <strong>of</strong> thous<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong>anonymous others about whose <strong>in</strong>dividual purposes <strong>and</strong> planswe can know noth<strong>in</strong>g. They are nodal po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> society,coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g the actions <strong>of</strong> millions whom they relieve <strong>of</strong> theneed to acquire <strong>and</strong> digest detailed knowledge about others<strong>and</strong> form detailed expectations about their future action.(Lachmann 1971:50)Lachmann ties the role <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>in</strong>to Austrian conceptions <strong>of</strong>divided <strong>and</strong> contextualised knowledge. In a generalised version <strong>of</strong>Hayek’s (1945) pioneer<strong>in</strong>g work on how the price system enables usto have access to knowledge that would otherwise be<strong>in</strong>communicable, Lachmann suggests that Weber’s theory <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>stitutions po<strong>in</strong>ts us towards see<strong>in</strong>g all economic <strong>and</strong> social<strong>in</strong>stitutions as communication processes that make our diverse <strong>and</strong><strong>of</strong>ten tacit knowledge socially usable.This aspect <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions figures prom<strong>in</strong>ently <strong>in</strong> Langlois’sextensions <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s work. He describes <strong>in</strong>stitutions as‘<strong>in</strong>terpersonal stores <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ative knowledge; as such, they serveto restrict at once the dimensions <strong>of</strong> the agent’s problem-situation<strong>and</strong> the extent <strong>of</strong> the cognitive dem<strong>and</strong>s placed on the agent’(Langlois 1986b:237). In the context <strong>of</strong> game-theoreticapplications, Langlois (1986c) discusses how <strong>in</strong>stitutions enable usto solve ‘coord<strong>in</strong>ation’ problems. By everyone agree<strong>in</strong>g (whetherexplicitly or tacitly) on a particular practice, we no longer have toout-guess or out-strategise other actors. The classic example <strong>of</strong> sucha co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation problem is which side <strong>of</strong> the road to drive on. Aslong as all agree, the particular choice is irrelevant. Know<strong>in</strong>g whichside others will drive on lowers ‘the extent <strong>of</strong> cognitive dem<strong>and</strong>s’ <strong>in</strong>specific situations. Important <strong>in</strong> Langlois’s formulation is that byremov<strong>in</strong>g some elements <strong>of</strong> social <strong>in</strong>teraction from consciousdeliberation, <strong>in</strong>stitutions free us to focus on other situations thatlack <strong>in</strong>stitutional solutions:145


STEVEN HORWITZthe existence at higher levels <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions that stabilize theenvironment <strong>and</strong> reduce environmental entropy effectivelyfrees behavioral entropy for use at lower levels. In a stableregime, the agent’s reliability is high enough that he can addnew actions to his repertoire…at lower levels.(Langlois 1986c:186–7)This idea parallels the <strong>of</strong>t-quoted dictum <strong>of</strong> Alfred Whitehead that‘Civilization advances by extend<strong>in</strong>g the number <strong>of</strong> importantoperations which we can perform without th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g about them’(as quoted <strong>in</strong> Hayek 1960:22). In the light <strong>of</strong> an Austrianapproach to <strong>in</strong>stitutions, we can <strong>in</strong>terpret ‘civilisation advances’ asa proxy for ‘as <strong>in</strong>stitutions evolve <strong>and</strong> mature’. 7 By serv<strong>in</strong>g as coord<strong>in</strong>ativenodes, <strong>in</strong>stitutions reduce the knowledge needed toexecute our plans, <strong>and</strong> enhance our ability to execute those planssuccessfully.Given this description <strong>of</strong> what <strong>in</strong>stitutions do, Lachmann <strong>and</strong>others have pursued the question <strong>of</strong> how <strong>in</strong>stitutions come about.In short, <strong>in</strong>stitutions emerge as the un<strong>in</strong>tended consequence <strong>of</strong>successful <strong>in</strong>dividual acts <strong>of</strong> rule-follow<strong>in</strong>g behaviour.Individuals try<strong>in</strong>g to improve themselves construct plans <strong>of</strong>action <strong>and</strong> attempt to carry them out. Individuals will cont<strong>in</strong>ueto use modes <strong>of</strong> behaviour that are successful <strong>and</strong> will treat themas ‘rules-<strong>of</strong>-thumb’ as to how to act <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> circumstances. Tothe extent the ways <strong>of</strong> behav<strong>in</strong>g exhibited <strong>in</strong> the successful planscan be observed by others, they will be imitated, <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g thenumber <strong>of</strong> actors behav<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> particular ways. As this imitationprocess cont<strong>in</strong>ues, <strong>and</strong> the number <strong>of</strong> users <strong>of</strong> particular rules-<strong>of</strong>thumb<strong>in</strong>creases, people learn to expect similar behaviour fromothers. A larger number <strong>of</strong> rule followers makes us<strong>in</strong>g the rulemore attractive to potential newcomers as more users mean moreopportunities to use the rule as a predictor <strong>of</strong> behaviour,enhanc<strong>in</strong>g the likelihood <strong>of</strong> co-ord<strong>in</strong>ated outcomes. 8 When thebehaviour <strong>in</strong> question is so widespread that we can call it‘generally accepted’, the rule-<strong>of</strong>-thumb has become a social<strong>in</strong>stitution.As Lachmann describes it:Successful plans thus gradually crystallize <strong>in</strong>to <strong>in</strong>stitutions….Imitation <strong>of</strong> the successful is, here as elsewhere, the mostimportant form by which the ways <strong>of</strong> the elite become theproperty <strong>of</strong> the masses…. Institutions are the relics <strong>of</strong> the146


HIERARCHICAL METAPHORSpioneer<strong>in</strong>g efforts <strong>of</strong> former generations from which we arestill draw<strong>in</strong>g benefit.(Lachmann 1971:68)Lachmann <strong>and</strong> others <strong>in</strong> the Austrian tradition po<strong>in</strong>t to CarlMenger’s (1892) theory <strong>of</strong> money as the exemplary story <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>stitutional emergence <strong>and</strong> evolution. 9An Austrian conception <strong>of</strong> social order sees it as an<strong>in</strong>terconnected set <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions, most spontaneous, some designed<strong>and</strong> all evolv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> serv<strong>in</strong>g as communicative processes thatenhance the ability <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuals or collectivities (such as firms) t<strong>of</strong>ormulate <strong>and</strong> execute their plans. The next, <strong>and</strong> perhaps moreimportant, question deals with the relationships among all <strong>of</strong> these<strong>in</strong>stitutions. In Lachmann’s (1971:69) words: ‘how can we knowthat these undesigned products <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual pursuit will all becompatible with one another?’ Just how do the various <strong>in</strong>stitutionalarrangements <strong>of</strong> a modern society <strong>in</strong>teract to form what mightlegitimately be called an ‘<strong>in</strong>stitutional order’?Both Lachmann <strong>and</strong> Langlois <strong>of</strong>fer us a way <strong>of</strong> conceptualis<strong>in</strong>gthis order that enables us to say someth<strong>in</strong>g about the relationshipsamong <strong>in</strong>stitutions. For Lachmann, the crucial dist<strong>in</strong>ction isbetween ‘<strong>in</strong>ternal’ <strong>and</strong> ‘external’ <strong>in</strong>stitutions:the undesigned <strong>in</strong>stitutions which evolve gradually as theun<strong>in</strong>tended <strong>and</strong> unforseeable result <strong>of</strong> the pursuit <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual<strong>in</strong>terests accumulate <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terstices <strong>of</strong> the legal order. The<strong>in</strong>terstices have been planned, though the sedimentsaccumulat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> them have not <strong>and</strong> could not have been. In asociety <strong>of</strong> this type we might then dist<strong>in</strong>guish between theexternal <strong>in</strong>stitutions which constitute, as it were, the outerframework <strong>of</strong> society, the legal order, <strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>ternal<strong>in</strong>stitutions which gradually evolve as a result <strong>of</strong> marketprocesses <strong>and</strong> other forms <strong>of</strong> spontaneous <strong>in</strong>dividual action.(Lachmann 1971:81, emphasis <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al)Although Lachmann, on the follow<strong>in</strong>g page, admits someshortcom<strong>in</strong>gs to this scheme, he also claims it is one <strong>in</strong> which a‘praxeological theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions…most readily f<strong>in</strong>ds its place’(ibid.: 81). As seen <strong>in</strong> the lengthy quote above, Lachmann’s primeexample <strong>of</strong> an ‘external’ <strong>in</strong>stitution is the legal order <strong>in</strong> so far asmarket <strong>in</strong>stitutions emerge <strong>and</strong> evolve by tak<strong>in</strong>g the law as a givenframework with<strong>in</strong> which to develop. For example, given the147


STEVEN HORWITZframework provided by contract law, what sorts <strong>of</strong> practices willbanks <strong>and</strong> their customers develop to engage <strong>in</strong> lend<strong>in</strong>g activities?The <strong>in</strong>stitution <strong>of</strong> a mortgage is <strong>in</strong>ternal to the external legal order<strong>of</strong> contract law.Along the same l<strong>in</strong>es, Langlois argues for a ‘hierarchy’ <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>stitutions. For example: ‘Highest-level <strong>in</strong>stitutions coord<strong>in</strong>ate thehighest level <strong>of</strong> plans. Institutions at lower levels coord<strong>in</strong>ate lowerlevelor more concrete plans…. lower-level <strong>in</strong>stitutions “grow” on thetrellis <strong>of</strong> higher-level <strong>in</strong>stitutions’ (Langlois 1986c:185–6).One can imag<strong>in</strong>e all sorts <strong>of</strong> visual metaphors that capture thepo<strong>in</strong>ts both Lachmann <strong>and</strong> Langlois wish to make. One that seems<strong>in</strong> the spirit <strong>of</strong> both is to visualise <strong>in</strong>stitutions as concentric spheres,with the outermost spheres be<strong>in</strong>g the most ‘external’ or‘highestlevel’ <strong>in</strong>stitutions, which provide the framework with<strong>in</strong>which the more <strong>in</strong>ner spheres can arise. This image is compatiblewith all <strong>of</strong> the observations that Langlois (1992) makes concern<strong>in</strong>gthe relationship between <strong>in</strong>ternality <strong>and</strong> externality <strong>and</strong> Hayek’sdist<strong>in</strong>ction between orders <strong>and</strong> organisations. My po<strong>in</strong>t is that sucha visual metaphor seems to capture the essence <strong>of</strong> what bothLachmann <strong>and</strong> Langlois are articulat<strong>in</strong>g, even if it is not consistentwith all <strong>of</strong> the details.Before I proceed to argue why these hierarchical conceptionsare problematic, let me recognise the important <strong>in</strong>sight theyconta<strong>in</strong>. It is surely true that when we theorise or act, we treatmany <strong>in</strong>stitutions as ‘given’ or at ‘higher levels’. It is cruciallyimportant to realise that both describ<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> participat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> theevolution <strong>of</strong> specific <strong>in</strong>stitutions always take place with<strong>in</strong> aframework <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutional practices that are treated as stable.What Lachmann <strong>and</strong> Langlois are say<strong>in</strong>g is largely correct. What Iwish to object to is the implication, if not the explicit argument,that the hierarchy <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions is someth<strong>in</strong>g objective, even at aspecific moment <strong>in</strong> time.<strong>Subjectivism</strong> <strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>stitutional orderOne <strong>of</strong> the most important subjectivist <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>of</strong> the past few years,particularly <strong>in</strong> its hermeneutical version, has been the emphasis onthe actor’s <strong>in</strong>terpretive perspective <strong>in</strong> underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g both humanaction <strong>and</strong> economic theory. A thoroughgo<strong>in</strong>g subjectivism sees ‘themarket’ as the outward manifestation <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terpretive acts <strong>of</strong> themyriad actors who comprise it. What ‘the market is say<strong>in</strong>g’ to<strong>in</strong>dividuals is not someth<strong>in</strong>g objectively known by all, but can only148


HIERARCHICAL METAPHORSbe understood with, at the very least, some reference to theperspective <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>in</strong> question. Try<strong>in</strong>g to def<strong>in</strong>e orexpla<strong>in</strong> market processes without tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to consideration thediffer<strong>in</strong>g subjective perspectives <strong>of</strong> actors is highly problematic.Start<strong>in</strong>g where Lachmann surely would have, we note thatAustrian economics began with Menger’s subjective theory <strong>of</strong> value.In that theory, a good’s value could not be def<strong>in</strong>ed by its objectivecharacteristics, rather only by its role <strong>in</strong> the purposes <strong>and</strong> plans <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>dividual actors. In contrast to the labour theory <strong>of</strong> value, whichsaw the value <strong>of</strong> outputs determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the value <strong>of</strong> the labour<strong>in</strong>puts that comprised them, the subjective theory <strong>of</strong> value saw thevalue <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>puts deriv<strong>in</strong>g from the value <strong>of</strong> consumer goods, whichitself derived from the m<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> choos<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividuals. In the sameway, I want to argue that which <strong>in</strong>stitutions are <strong>in</strong>ternal or external,or which ones are higher or lower, depends on either the questionthe theorist is ask<strong>in</strong>g or the plan an actor is consider<strong>in</strong>g. Just as aspecific good has value only <strong>in</strong> the contexts <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual actors, socan <strong>in</strong>stitutions only be ordered hierarchically <strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> aspecific theorist or actor.Another way to see this is to analogise it to subjectivistepistemology for a moment. From the simple <strong>in</strong>sight that all factsare theory-laden to more sophisticated work <strong>in</strong> the theory <strong>of</strong>knowledge, it is generally accepted that humans do not see theworld unmediated. As Hayek’s (1952) work on theoreticalpsychology argues, the m<strong>in</strong>d is an order<strong>in</strong>g process. How weperceive the world today depends on the various abstractions thatthe m<strong>in</strong>d has evolved <strong>in</strong> the past. Thus, any given sensory order<strong>in</strong>gdepends to at least some degree on the particular history <strong>and</strong>experience <strong>of</strong> the perceiver. In language more congenial to<strong>in</strong>terpretive philosophical approaches, we always underst<strong>and</strong> ‘from’somewhere. As noted earlier, this same idea appears <strong>in</strong> the work <strong>of</strong>Michael Polanyi (1958:55ff.), who argued that our focal awareness(i.e. what we are focus<strong>in</strong>g on now) depends upon a certa<strong>in</strong>subsidiary awareness (i.e. the framework we take for granted whenwe focus). To some extent, these philosophical ideas cohere with thehierarchical conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>in</strong> that they stress thegivenness <strong>of</strong> some aspects <strong>of</strong> the world when we turn to exam<strong>in</strong>eothers.However, what the philosophical literature also emphasises isthat what is given, or what is subsidiary, or which experiences havecreated certa<strong>in</strong> neural l<strong>in</strong>kages, cannot be understood as objectivelythe same for everyone. Each person’s ‘facts’ are laden with different149


STEVEN HORWITZtheories, for example. This is the fundamental challenge to thenotion <strong>of</strong> a reality that is objectively knowable <strong>in</strong> its purest form.The danger with the hierarchical conception <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>stitutionalorder (as <strong>in</strong> the sphere analogy from earlier) is that it implies thatsome <strong>in</strong>stitutions are objectively external to others. Notice, too, thatthe po<strong>in</strong>t is not that the ‘position’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions might change overtime. Most theorists <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions agree that the hierarchy <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>stitutions today may be different from the hierarchy tomorrow.That is clearly true. The po<strong>in</strong>t here is deeper; we cannot objectivelydef<strong>in</strong>e which <strong>in</strong>stitutions are where <strong>in</strong> the hierarchy even at a po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong> time. The ‘hierarchical order’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions is contextual to thequestion or action under consideration.It is also true that the different ‘levels’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions can havefeedback effects on one another. For example, changes <strong>in</strong> thestructure <strong>of</strong> firms may call for a re<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> aspects <strong>of</strong>property or contract law, or a new bank<strong>in</strong>g practice may lead tochanges <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>stitutional arrangements <strong>of</strong> the money supplyprocess. My po<strong>in</strong>t is not just to say that such feedback effects occur.Austrian <strong>in</strong>stitutionalists recognise this po<strong>in</strong>t. However, tak<strong>in</strong>gthose feedback effects seriously should imply that as such effectsoccur, they force analysts <strong>and</strong> actors to reverse the hierarchicalrelationships among the <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>in</strong> question.If one wants to underst<strong>and</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> contract law s<strong>in</strong>ce themid-1700s, one will have to take certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions as ‘external’ tothe law. Surely such an evolutionary explanation will show howactual commercial activities exposed ‘gaps’ <strong>in</strong> the law that werefilled by judicial <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>and</strong> application <strong>of</strong> the exist<strong>in</strong>g law tothe new circumstances. When a legal historian performs this task, hecan be seen as <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g an explanation <strong>of</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> an<strong>in</strong>stitution with<strong>in</strong> the framework provided by market <strong>in</strong>stitutions<strong>and</strong> the monetary order. Judicial decisions cause the law to evolveaga<strong>in</strong>st a background <strong>of</strong> given market practices. In this story the‘fixed’ <strong>in</strong>stitutions are those <strong>of</strong> the market, while the evolv<strong>in</strong>gpractices are the legal rules. Of course if one wanted to expla<strong>in</strong> whymodern corporations have the structure they do, some portion <strong>of</strong>that story would illustrate how that structure emerged as a responseto exist<strong>in</strong>g contract <strong>and</strong> property law. In such a case the legal orderis external to the market process.Mov<strong>in</strong>g away from theory to actual practice, the same po<strong>in</strong>tapplies. The judge mak<strong>in</strong>g case law is, <strong>in</strong> effect, treat<strong>in</strong>g his<strong>in</strong>stitution as <strong>in</strong>ternal to the market order, much as the ownersdecid<strong>in</strong>g how to structure their firm have to treat it as <strong>in</strong>ternal to the150


HIERARCHICAL METAPHORSlegal order. Aga<strong>in</strong>, where particular <strong>in</strong>stitutions are <strong>in</strong> thehierarchical structure will vary depend<strong>in</strong>g on the perspective one istak<strong>in</strong>g on the issue at h<strong>and</strong>.To avoid any premature charges <strong>of</strong> nihilism, I am not argu<strong>in</strong>gthat we throw out all <strong>of</strong> the valuable <strong>in</strong>sights provided byhierarchical metaphors. Instead I would suggest that we reconsiderour metaphors to make them more consistent with a radicallysubjective underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> both knowledge <strong>and</strong> the social order.After <strong>of</strong>fer<strong>in</strong>g an alternative way <strong>of</strong> conceiv<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>stitutionalorder, I will briefly discuss an application.Parallels between Austrian theories <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions<strong>and</strong> capitalAn alternative way to conceptualise the <strong>in</strong>stitutional order mightdraw from Austrian analyses <strong>of</strong> another, equally complex,<strong>in</strong>terconnected economic structure: capital. 10 In fact, Lachmannused the same phrase ‘nodal po<strong>in</strong>ts’ to describe both <strong>in</strong>stitutions (seethe quote above on p. 145) <strong>and</strong> capital goods: ‘Capital goods aremerely the nodal po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> the flows <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>put…which they absorb,<strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> output…which they emanate’ (Lachmann 1978:58, emphasis<strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al). Austrian approaches to capital are the logical extension<strong>of</strong> subjectivist value theory. Once it is recognised that value is theproduct <strong>of</strong> consumer perceptions, then capital goods have to beunderstood <strong>in</strong> their roles as possible contributors to the production<strong>of</strong> valued goods. S<strong>in</strong>ce production does not occur automatically, butrather reflects the choices <strong>of</strong> producers/entrepreneurs, the waycapital gets used will reflect the purposes <strong>and</strong> plans <strong>and</strong> expectations<strong>of</strong> its users. Whether a given good is capital depends on the role itplays <strong>in</strong> producers’ attempts to anticipate the valuations <strong>of</strong>consumers. Production is <strong>in</strong>herently speculative as owners <strong>of</strong> capital‘bet’ on it produc<strong>in</strong>g what consumers desire.The implication <strong>of</strong> this theory <strong>of</strong> capital is that, as with value, thecapital status <strong>of</strong> a good is not amenable to some objective def<strong>in</strong>ition.It is not the physical properties <strong>of</strong> a good that make it capital, ratherit is the good’s role <strong>in</strong> the plans <strong>of</strong> producers that give it the quality<strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g capital. The same slice <strong>of</strong> bread I use to make my hams<strong>and</strong>wich at home would be considered capital if used for arestaurant s<strong>and</strong>wich <strong>and</strong> then sold to d<strong>in</strong>ers. 11 In a more completediscussion, stemm<strong>in</strong>g from Menger (1981 [1871]), we can recognisethat capital goods can be ‘ordered’. If consumer goods are ‘firstorder’goods, then the immediate <strong>in</strong>puts that comprise them are151


STEVEN HORWITZ‘second-order’ goods, <strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>puts <strong>in</strong>to those <strong>in</strong>puts are ‘thirdorder’goods, etc. Such a schema gives the analyst a nice way tolocate a specific good <strong>in</strong> the whole production process.However, as with the hierarchical metaphors used <strong>in</strong> discussion<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions, the danger here is <strong>in</strong> forgett<strong>in</strong>g that the place <strong>of</strong> aspecific good <strong>in</strong> this hierarchy is not objectively def<strong>in</strong>able. Forexample, flour might be second-order for a bakery-made cakebought directly by consumers. On the other h<strong>and</strong>, the very sameflour might be <strong>of</strong> a much higher order if it goes to a largecommercial bakery that makes breads that are then sold to variousfood-supply wholesalers. Austrian capital theorists, especiallyLachmann (1978), have long recognised the essential subjectivity <strong>of</strong>the concept <strong>of</strong> capital. In fact, one read<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the failure <strong>of</strong> Austriansto conv<strong>in</strong>ce ma<strong>in</strong>stream critics dur<strong>in</strong>g the two debates <strong>of</strong> the 1930s(with Keynes <strong>and</strong> the market socialists), was that no one, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>gperhaps the Austrians, really understood the centrality <strong>of</strong> asubjectivist capital theory to underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g the market process. Aswe conceptualise the relationships among <strong>in</strong>stitutions, we shouldbear <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d the analogy from the capital ‘structure’. Where aparticular <strong>in</strong>stitution falls <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>stitutional order depends on thequestion we are ask<strong>in</strong>g.Another set <strong>of</strong> concepts that can be taken from the Austriantheory <strong>of</strong> capital are ‘complementarity’ <strong>and</strong> ‘specificity’. AsLachmann argues, capital is essentially heterogeneousimply<strong>in</strong>g that:each capital good can only be used for a limited number <strong>of</strong>purposes. We shall speak <strong>of</strong> the multiple specificity <strong>of</strong> capitalgoods…. For most purposes capital goods have to be usedjo<strong>in</strong>tly. Complementarity is <strong>of</strong> the essence <strong>of</strong> capital use.(Lachmann 1978:2–3, emphasis <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al)When producers formulate plans, they have to underst<strong>and</strong> the range<strong>of</strong> possible uses for each capital good <strong>and</strong> how each good might fitwith other goods needed to execute the plan at h<strong>and</strong>. In addition, asexternal circumstances (e.g., consumer dem<strong>and</strong>s) change, exist<strong>in</strong>gcapital comb<strong>in</strong>ations may no longer be appropriate, <strong>and</strong> areshuffl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> capital must occur. How capital will be reshuffleddepends greatly on how specific it is <strong>and</strong> how complementary it willbe with other newly required capital goods. This constant arrang<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> rearrang<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the capital structure is driven by the everchang<strong>in</strong>gdem<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> consumers.152


HIERARCHICAL METAPHORSMany <strong>of</strong> these same concepts could be applied to the <strong>in</strong>stitutionalorder. Certa<strong>in</strong>ly complementarity is a central concept <strong>in</strong> discuss<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>stitutions. How well <strong>in</strong>stitutions mesh together is crucial to theirepistemological roles. One <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s (1971:75ff.) fourcharacteristics <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutional order is ‘over-all complementarity’.He argues that clusters <strong>of</strong> related <strong>in</strong>stitutions might have highdegrees <strong>of</strong> complementarity (e.g., all <strong>of</strong> those <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g written ororal communication), but the relationships among clusters are notalways so ‘gapless’. For Lachmann, the ‘gap’ metaphor is a way <strong>of</strong>flesh<strong>in</strong>g out how complementary a set <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions is. He says <strong>of</strong>the legal system: ‘It has no “gaps”. A judge before whom a legal caseis brought can never refuse to give a decision on the grounds that heknows <strong>of</strong> no legal norm to apply to it. He has to f<strong>in</strong>d one’(Lachmann 1971:76–7).Interest<strong>in</strong>gly this same notion <strong>of</strong> ‘gaps <strong>in</strong> the structure’ appears <strong>in</strong>his discussion <strong>of</strong> capital <strong>and</strong> the way <strong>in</strong> which new<strong>in</strong>vestorentrepreneurs see opportunities for pr<strong>of</strong>it: ‘The shape <strong>in</strong>which new capital goods make their appearance is determ<strong>in</strong>edlargely by the exist<strong>in</strong>g pattern, <strong>in</strong> the sense that “<strong>in</strong>vestmentopportunities” really mean “holes <strong>in</strong> the pattern”’ (Lachmann1978:10). In both cases, what is at issue is the <strong>in</strong>ternal coherence <strong>of</strong>each structure, rather than some externally observable objectivepattern (ibid.: 57).Rather than see<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stitutions as <strong>in</strong> hierarchical relationshipswith each other, a more fruitful conceptual device might be anexploration <strong>of</strong> the ways <strong>in</strong> which they can work together <strong>and</strong> thelimits to such complementarity. Concerns about <strong>in</strong>stitutionalcomplementarity are <strong>in</strong>herently l<strong>in</strong>ked with real historical time <strong>and</strong>unexpected change. How social order can be preserved <strong>in</strong> the face <strong>of</strong>an unknowable but not unimag<strong>in</strong>able future may well rest on theease with which different <strong>in</strong>stitutions can work together <strong>in</strong> variouscomb<strong>in</strong>ations to react to <strong>and</strong> anticipate (to the degree possible)future events.The issue <strong>of</strong> specificity also comes <strong>in</strong>to play with <strong>in</strong>stitutions.Rather than exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g how a particular <strong>in</strong>stitution fits with others,the specificity <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>stitution might refer to its own adaptability <strong>in</strong>the face <strong>of</strong> social change. The flexibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions may becrucial for provid<strong>in</strong>g social order. An example <strong>of</strong> this might be seen<strong>in</strong> the way <strong>in</strong> which many <strong>in</strong>digenous <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>in</strong> the Third Worldhave changed <strong>and</strong> adapted to be<strong>in</strong>g further permeated by marketforces. 12 Overly specific <strong>in</strong>stitutions may <strong>in</strong>hibit social order bybe<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>sufficiently flexible.153


STEVEN HORWITZL<strong>in</strong>ked with specificity is the fact that <strong>in</strong>stitutions display a highdegree <strong>of</strong> path-dependency. Institutions always change <strong>and</strong> adaptfrom their earlier <strong>in</strong>carnations; they normally cannot be constructedwhole cloth. Path-dependency also suggests that objectivistmeasures <strong>of</strong> optimality (such as Pareto criteria) are difficult to apply<strong>in</strong> an Austrian view <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions. Institutions are never likely to beperfectly fitted for solv<strong>in</strong>g exist<strong>in</strong>g problems because they are theproducts <strong>of</strong> imperfect processes <strong>of</strong> historical evolution. Just as arelatively specific capital good refitted to perform a task differentfrom its orig<strong>in</strong>al one may not do so as well as a new mach<strong>in</strong>e, so aremany <strong>in</strong>stitutions imperfect adaptations to exist<strong>in</strong>g socialenvironments. 13Of course, completely non-specific <strong>in</strong>stitutions are likely to beproblematic also, s<strong>in</strong>ce they would have to be at a level <strong>of</strong>generality that would probably require other sorts <strong>of</strong>(complementary!) <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>in</strong> order to generate concrete coord<strong>in</strong>ativeresults. An example here might be language. Languageis extremely flexible (though perhaps not perfectly). However thatvery flexibility creates the problem <strong>of</strong> jargon or dialects that makel<strong>in</strong>guistic co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation more difficult. Other social <strong>in</strong>stitutionsmight be necessary to enable language to adapt smoothly tooutside change. An example <strong>of</strong> this might be the technospeak <strong>of</strong>the very computer-literate compared to the average person’sunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> such issues. The very flexibility <strong>of</strong> language cancreate communication barriers.One problem all <strong>in</strong>stitutions face is be<strong>in</strong>g sufficiently flexible toadapt to the unexpected, yet sufficiently coherent to serve as nodalpo<strong>in</strong>ts for current attempts at co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation. With capital goods,complementarity <strong>and</strong> specificity are ways <strong>of</strong> conceiv<strong>in</strong>g these issues.As conditions change, producers have to work with capital goods <strong>of</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>ct specificity <strong>and</strong> reshuffle them <strong>in</strong>to complementarycomb<strong>in</strong>ations that will meet the new change. Transferr<strong>in</strong>g the sameconcepts to <strong>in</strong>stitutions might provide a useful way <strong>of</strong> conceiv<strong>in</strong>g the<strong>in</strong>stitutional order without posit<strong>in</strong>g some objectively given,hierarchical structure. Th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions as nodal po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> coord<strong>in</strong>ationthat are constantly <strong>in</strong> motion <strong>and</strong> shuffl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>reshuffl<strong>in</strong>g their relationships with each other need not lead totheoretical chaos. The pr<strong>of</strong>undity <strong>and</strong> longevity <strong>of</strong> the Austriantheory <strong>of</strong> capital attests to how such a theory (even when<strong>in</strong>sufficiently developed) can provide important <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>and</strong> beradically subjectivist.154


HIERARCHICAL METAPHORSBank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> the law: an illustrationA quick overview <strong>of</strong> the relationship between the growth <strong>of</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>in</strong>termediaries <strong>and</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> the relevant portions <strong>of</strong>the law can illustrate the complex <strong>and</strong> varied relationships among<strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> the difficulties <strong>of</strong> view<strong>in</strong>g them as hierarchical. Theevolution <strong>of</strong> bank<strong>in</strong>g provides some excellent examples <strong>of</strong>complementarity <strong>and</strong> specificity <strong>and</strong> the flexibility/coherencebalance. 14It is generally argued that what we now underst<strong>and</strong> as f<strong>in</strong>ancial<strong>in</strong>termediaries probably grew out <strong>of</strong> earlier <strong>in</strong>stitutions that weresimply warehouses for stor<strong>in</strong>g precious metals. Traders who did notwish to undertake the risk <strong>of</strong> hold<strong>in</strong>g large stocks <strong>of</strong> gold could storethem for safekeep<strong>in</strong>g with goldsmiths or others who <strong>of</strong>fered securityfor a fee. At first, transferr<strong>in</strong>g these gold ‘balances’ was cumbersomeas the law <strong>of</strong>ten required the presence <strong>of</strong> both parties to the transfer<strong>and</strong> perhaps their legal representatives <strong>in</strong> order to execute theexchange <strong>of</strong> gold. At this po<strong>in</strong>t, the proto-banks were act<strong>in</strong>g with<strong>in</strong>the given legal order <strong>and</strong> us<strong>in</strong>g the accepted processes <strong>of</strong> transfer.However, entrepreneurial gold storers realised that transferscould be made more easy by issu<strong>in</strong>g receipts to gold <strong>in</strong> storage <strong>and</strong>allow<strong>in</strong>g traders to simply exchange those receipts (viaendorsement) rather than by actually meet<strong>in</strong>g at the storage facility<strong>and</strong> sign<strong>in</strong>g the relevant paperwork. The issue fac<strong>in</strong>g this <strong>in</strong>novationwas how the legal order would <strong>in</strong>terpret those receipts <strong>and</strong> the use <strong>of</strong>signature endorsements to transfer them. This uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty reflects amiss<strong>in</strong>g complementarity between two <strong>in</strong>stitutions. In most cases,the law recognised the receipts as contractual obligations <strong>and</strong>endorsement as an acceptable transfer process.This issue also illustrates a limit <strong>of</strong> hierarchical metaphors. To theextent that the popularity <strong>of</strong> this bank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>novation put pressureon the legal system to decide on their status, it reflects the degree towhich legal <strong>in</strong>stitutions were ‘<strong>in</strong>ternal’ to f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong>practices. However, once such a decision was made, banks couldtreat the legal status <strong>of</strong> such receipts as given <strong>and</strong> move to <strong>in</strong>novatefurther, thus treat<strong>in</strong>g the legal order as ‘external’. The metaphor <strong>of</strong>complementarity seems much more appropriate here.One <strong>of</strong> the next major steps <strong>in</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> bank<strong>in</strong>g was themove to fractional reserve bank<strong>in</strong>g. Once aga<strong>in</strong>, entrepreneurialwarehousers realised they could pr<strong>of</strong>it by lend<strong>in</strong>g out depositedspecie at <strong>in</strong>terest to the extent that depositors had no direct use forit. The transferr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> receipts had dim<strong>in</strong>ished the actual amount <strong>of</strong>155


STEVEN HORWITZmetal that flowed <strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> out <strong>of</strong> the ‘bank’, facilitat<strong>in</strong>g the move t<strong>of</strong>ractional reserves. Early bankers understood that the challenge wasto maximise their <strong>in</strong>terest returns while still ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g sufficientreserves to meet the dem<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> depositors. 15 The question thatneeded to be answered was how the legal system would <strong>in</strong>terpretdeposit receipts <strong>in</strong> the absence <strong>of</strong> 100 per cent reserves.Whereas deposit receipts under 100 per cent reserve bank<strong>in</strong>g areeffectively bailments, not unlike the receipt one might have forfurniture at a self-storage facility, fractional reserve bank notescannot be seen this way. The exact legal st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the contractbetween a depositor <strong>and</strong> a fractional reserve bank has been thesubject <strong>of</strong> much discussion among Austrian monetary theorists. 16Historically, however, the law has generally seen those contracts asdem<strong>and</strong> deposits, <strong>in</strong> that the legal obligation <strong>of</strong> the bank is toredeem bank notes when customers dem<strong>and</strong> it. 17 Under this<strong>in</strong>terpretation, the bank is free to do what it pleases with the specieas long as it can deliver the required amount when dem<strong>and</strong>ed. 18 Inthis case aga<strong>in</strong>, the legal order had to respond to an <strong>in</strong>novationcom<strong>in</strong>g from the f<strong>in</strong>ancial sector. As both note users <strong>and</strong> issuersgenerally began to f<strong>in</strong>d fractional reserve notes to be acceptable,judges worked with<strong>in</strong> that set <strong>of</strong> practices <strong>in</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g the legalst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the notes. Aga<strong>in</strong>, however, hav<strong>in</strong>g established theacceptability <strong>of</strong> fractional reserve notes, banks now treated the lawas external <strong>and</strong> were able to pursue other related <strong>in</strong>novations withthe assumption that the legal order would treat such <strong>in</strong>novations thesame way.One example might be the decision to give borrowers bank notes(or deposit credits) rather than actual specie. Bank<strong>in</strong>g historiansgenerally agree that banks first lent actual specie <strong>and</strong> somewhatlater realised they could lend out notes rather than specie. With theuncerta<strong>in</strong> legal st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> fractional notes, banks were likely tohave been hesitant to use them for all customers at first. Once thelaw <strong>in</strong>dicated it would accept such notes as redeemable on dem<strong>and</strong>,then banks probably extended the practice to new borrowers ratherthan just to old depositors. The complementary <strong>in</strong>terrelationshipsbetween bank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> the law are clearly illustrated here.One last bank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>novation that reflects issues <strong>of</strong>complementarity <strong>and</strong> specificity is the ‘option clause’. 19 Scottishbanks dur<strong>in</strong>g their free bank<strong>in</strong>g period <strong>in</strong> the eighteenth centurydeveloped a way <strong>of</strong> deal<strong>in</strong>g with the danger <strong>of</strong> massive withdrawalsthat could dra<strong>in</strong> a fractional reserve bank by rewrit<strong>in</strong>g the contractconta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> a bank note. Rather than be<strong>in</strong>g redeemable ‘on156


HIERARCHICAL METAPHORSdem<strong>and</strong>’, their notes were redeemable on dem<strong>and</strong> or <strong>in</strong> six monthsat 5 per cent <strong>in</strong>terest, at the bank’s discretion. The notes gave thebank the option <strong>of</strong> suspend<strong>in</strong>g redemption for a limited period <strong>of</strong>time with compensation paid to the note holder.This <strong>in</strong>novation can be viewed as an example <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutionalflexibility <strong>in</strong> the face <strong>of</strong> uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty. Scottish bank<strong>in</strong>g practices werenot so <strong>in</strong>stitutionally specific as to be unable to react to externalchange. At first, the Bank <strong>of</strong> Scotl<strong>and</strong> simply unilaterally declaredthat note redemption would be suspended for some period <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>terest would be paid to note holders, without hav<strong>in</strong>g specified this<strong>in</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g on the note. This ad hoc policy was used on threeoccasions <strong>in</strong> the early 1700s (White 1984:25–6). Eventually, such adhoc manoeuvres faced legal challenges.The period (1727–30) dur<strong>in</strong>g which an actual option clause wasadded to Scottish notes was one <strong>of</strong> new entry <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>tensecompetition (Dowd 1991:769). Faced with the uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>in</strong>herent<strong>in</strong> such a situation, the Bank <strong>of</strong> Scotl<strong>and</strong> first used the ad hoc<strong>in</strong>vocation <strong>of</strong> temporary suspension with <strong>in</strong>terest to prevent itselffrom be<strong>in</strong>g dra<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>of</strong> reserves by a new competitor, the Royal Bank<strong>of</strong> Scotl<strong>and</strong>. In this case, however, a suit was brought charg<strong>in</strong>g theBank <strong>of</strong> Scotl<strong>and</strong> with violat<strong>in</strong>g the terms <strong>of</strong> its charter by notredeem<strong>in</strong>g notes on dem<strong>and</strong>. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to White (1984:26): ‘Aftermuch legal wrangl<strong>in</strong>g the note holder’s right <strong>of</strong> “summarydiligence” or immediate payment on Bank <strong>of</strong> Scotl<strong>and</strong> notes…. wasupheld’. Shortly after this decision, the Bank <strong>of</strong> Scotl<strong>and</strong> added anexplicit option clause on the obverse <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> its notes <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g itsright to suspend redemption <strong>and</strong> the correspond<strong>in</strong>g payment <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>terest.The problem fac<strong>in</strong>g both the banks <strong>and</strong> the law was how to besufficiently flexible to deal with the challenges <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>novation <strong>and</strong>uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, while still ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g a coherence <strong>and</strong>complementarity that could provide a stable <strong>in</strong>stitutionalenvironment for market actors. The whole Scottish option clauseepisode can be seen as an attempt to fill <strong>in</strong> the ‘gaps’ <strong>in</strong> both themonetary <strong>and</strong> legal <strong>in</strong>stitutional orders. 20 Judges had to react t<strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>in</strong>novations, <strong>and</strong> banks had to wait to learn the <strong>of</strong>ficiallegal status <strong>of</strong> their <strong>in</strong>novations before extend<strong>in</strong>g or advanc<strong>in</strong>g onthem. It would be difficult <strong>in</strong> this case to po<strong>in</strong>t to either the legal ormonetary order as be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ternal or external or up or down <strong>in</strong> somehierarchy. Rather it seems more like a story <strong>of</strong> shuffl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>reshuffl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> search<strong>in</strong>g for complementarity <strong>in</strong> the face <strong>of</strong>external change, much like the Austrian theory <strong>of</strong> capital.157


STEVEN HORWITZThis illustration <strong>in</strong>dicates that the complexities <strong>of</strong> historicalprocesses <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutional evolution cannot be fully captured byhierarchical conceptions <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutional order. A more subjectivistview <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutional order would seek out more circular or<strong>in</strong>teractive relationships among <strong>in</strong>stitutions. The evolution <strong>of</strong> anyspecific <strong>in</strong>stitution will <strong>in</strong>deed proceed aga<strong>in</strong>st the backdrop <strong>of</strong>other <strong>in</strong>stitutions, but may also affect the future evolution <strong>of</strong> thoseother <strong>in</strong>stitutions. Our approach to <strong>in</strong>stitutional evolution needs tobe forward-look<strong>in</strong>g as well, by underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g the un<strong>in</strong>tendedconsequences that emanate from <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>stitutional change.The idea <strong>of</strong> ‘co-evolution’ <strong>and</strong> notions <strong>of</strong> complementarity <strong>and</strong>specificity should beg<strong>in</strong> to play more prom<strong>in</strong>ent roles <strong>in</strong> Austrianconceptions <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>and</strong> social <strong>in</strong>stitutions.ConclusionOne <strong>of</strong> the subtexts <strong>of</strong> this chapter has been the claim that it is notaccidental that <strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann was a pioneer <strong>in</strong> both Austriancapital theory <strong>and</strong> the theory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions. Both theories <strong>and</strong> theirsubject matters share important characteristics. What they sharemost, though, is that they are both rooted <strong>in</strong> a subjectivist approachto social phenomena. That subjectivism is Lachmann’s true legacy.However, consistently adher<strong>in</strong>g to a subjectivist paradigm is acont<strong>in</strong>ual challenge. Debates over equilibrium theory amongAustrians, <strong>and</strong> debates between Austrians <strong>and</strong> post-Keynesiansconcern<strong>in</strong>g the theoretical <strong>and</strong> political implications <strong>of</strong> subjectivismdemonstrate this challenge quite vividly. As subjectivists pursue atheory <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions, we need to be careful not to accidentally driftfrom the friendly seas <strong>of</strong> subjectivism <strong>in</strong>to the rapids <strong>of</strong> mechanistic,hierarchical or objectivistic conceptions <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>stitutional order.Extend<strong>in</strong>g Lachmann’s legacy dem<strong>and</strong>s no less <strong>of</strong> us.Notes1 For a larger treatment <strong>of</strong> these issues <strong>in</strong> the post-revival generation <strong>of</strong>Austrians <strong>and</strong> their relationship to Menger’s orig<strong>in</strong>al work, seeVaughn (1994).2 In that sense, my mission parallels that <strong>of</strong> Prychitko (1994) who arguesthat Lachmann’s focus on ‘the plan’ is untrue to Lachmann’s ownpr<strong>of</strong>essed hermeneutic orientation as it ignores or downplays theun<strong>in</strong>tended consequences <strong>of</strong> the play<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual plans.3 Of course there are numerous other treatments <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions. Avariety <strong>of</strong> perspectives can be found <strong>in</strong> Hodgson (1988); Mäki et al.158


HIERARCHICAL METAPHORS(eds) (1993); <strong>and</strong> Rutherford (1994), among others. Explorations <strong>of</strong>the relationship between Austrian economics <strong>and</strong> the OldInstitutionalism (from each side) can be found <strong>in</strong> Boettke (1989) <strong>and</strong>Samuels (1989).4 For my own partial attempts at such work, see Horwitz (1992a,1993, 1994).5 Philosophically this question is also at the bottom <strong>of</strong> modernphenomenology. As the Austrian philosopher Alfred Schutz put it:‘What makes my behavior social is the fact that its <strong>in</strong>tentional object isthe expected behavior <strong>of</strong> another person’ (Schutz 1967:149).6 On Schutz <strong>and</strong> the Austrians, see Prendergast (1986). On Simmel <strong>and</strong>the Austrians, see Horwitz (1992b).7 There is also a parallel here to Michael Polanyi’s (1958) dist<strong>in</strong>ction between‘focal’ <strong>and</strong> ‘subsidiary’ awareness. I shall return to this issue later.8 This phenomenon is frequently referred to as a ‘network effect’, as <strong>in</strong> atelephone network. With any network or other communicationprocess (like language), the more users there are, the more attractive isthe process to potential participants. A phone network with only threeusers is not very attractive compared to one with millions.9 Indeed, note my use <strong>of</strong> the phrase ‘generally accepted’, which isnormally associated with the def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> money as a ‘generallyaccepted medium <strong>of</strong> exchange’. One can extend that def<strong>in</strong>ition to othersocial <strong>in</strong>stitutions by chang<strong>in</strong>g the practice that is be<strong>in</strong>g generallyaccepted. For example, one might def<strong>in</strong>e law as a ‘generally acceptedset <strong>of</strong> rules for <strong>in</strong>terpersonal <strong>in</strong>teraction’. For more on the parallelsbetween money <strong>and</strong> law, see Horwitz (1993).10 Lachmann’s capital theory is see<strong>in</strong>g a bit <strong>of</strong> a revival. See Horwitz(1994) <strong>and</strong> Lew<strong>in</strong> (1994 <strong>and</strong> 1997).11 Of course one could argue that my bread is capital too, <strong>in</strong> that thes<strong>and</strong>wich is a ‘capital’ good that produces utility. Although that <strong>in</strong>sightis <strong>in</strong> some sense true, it is also trivial. A better way <strong>of</strong> conceiv<strong>in</strong>g theissue is <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> trade on a market. Capital goods have marketprices, as do the items they produce. The ham s<strong>and</strong>wich I make <strong>and</strong> eatis, <strong>in</strong> Marxian terms, not a commodity; the restaurant s<strong>and</strong>wich is. Thecommodity status <strong>of</strong> the product confers capital status on the <strong>in</strong>puts. Itis neither accidental, nor <strong>in</strong>correct, that Marx started Capital with adiscussion <strong>of</strong> the commodity.12 See, for example, Chamlee (1993).13 The analogies to evolutionary biology are obvious here. For more seeHorwitz (1992a: Chapter 2) <strong>and</strong> Hodgson (1992). Darw<strong>in</strong> himselfunderstood that exist<strong>in</strong>g biological species will not meet criteria <strong>of</strong>perfection: ‘We cannot doubt that each structure is <strong>of</strong> use to each k<strong>in</strong>d<strong>of</strong> squirrel <strong>in</strong> its own country…[b]ut it does not follow from this factthat the structure <strong>of</strong> each squirrel is the best that it is possible toconceive under all possible conditions’ (Darw<strong>in</strong> 1859:129).14 This section draws on the work <strong>of</strong> Selg<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> White (1987) <strong>and</strong>extensions <strong>of</strong> that work <strong>in</strong> Horwitz (1992a: Chapter 4).15 The two criteria necessary for fractional reserve bank<strong>in</strong>g are that themedium <strong>of</strong> exchange is fungible <strong>and</strong> that withdrawal patterns aresufficiently r<strong>and</strong>om so that the law <strong>of</strong> large numbers can be said to159


STEVEN HORWITZhold. If the law <strong>of</strong> large numbers holds, then the chance <strong>of</strong> anysignificant amount <strong>of</strong> withdrawals on any given day is small, enabl<strong>in</strong>gbanks to hold fractional reserves.16 See Rothbard 1983: Chapter 1.17 One <strong>of</strong> the ironies <strong>of</strong> the 100 per cent reserve position is that itsadherents correctly recognise the historicity <strong>of</strong> the particular goodsthat get used as media <strong>of</strong> exchange, but forget the importance <strong>of</strong>historical evolution when discuss<strong>in</strong>g the legal st<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> fractionalreserve notes. They wish to impose a legal/ethical theoretical positionby fiat, despite the historical evolution <strong>of</strong> case law on that practice. Tothis extent, the more ‘traditional’ Austrian view on bank<strong>in</strong>g was verymuch non-<strong>in</strong>stitutional, <strong>and</strong> a more subjectivist <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutionalistview would stress the complementary evolution <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial<strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> legal practices.18 One <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g issue here is whether the bank has a legal obligation toma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong> the purchas<strong>in</strong>g power <strong>of</strong> the specie while it is <strong>in</strong> its custody.Some Austrian defenders <strong>of</strong> 100 per cent reserve bank<strong>in</strong>g argue thatfractional reserve banks by def<strong>in</strong>ition depreciate the value <strong>of</strong> specie,thus violat<strong>in</strong>g the bank note contract. The validity <strong>of</strong> this argumentdepends on one’s def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>flation/depreciation <strong>and</strong> the role <strong>of</strong>the dem<strong>and</strong> for money, issues which are beyond the scope <strong>of</strong> this paper.See Horwitz (1988) for more.19 A good overview <strong>and</strong> defence <strong>of</strong> this practice is <strong>in</strong> Dowd (1991).20 Interest<strong>in</strong>gly enough, option clauses were eventually outlawed <strong>in</strong>Scotl<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> 1765. Various players <strong>in</strong> the bank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dustry were will<strong>in</strong>gto give up the right to the option clause <strong>in</strong> exchange for differ<strong>in</strong>gpolitical favours. Prov<strong>in</strong>cial banks wanted full legal recognition <strong>and</strong>the chartered banks wanted to politically elim<strong>in</strong>ate their competition.The prov<strong>in</strong>cial banks eventually won <strong>and</strong> the option clause <strong>and</strong> smalldenom<strong>in</strong>ation notes were the price. See the accounts <strong>in</strong> Dowd (1991)<strong>and</strong> White (1984).ReferencesBoettke, P.J. (1989) ‘Evolution <strong>and</strong> economics: Austrians as<strong>in</strong>stitutionalists’, Research <strong>in</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Thought <strong>and</strong>Methodology 6:73–89.Chamlee, E. (1993) ‘Indigenous African <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> economicdevelopment’, Cato Journal 13:1, Spr<strong>in</strong>g/Summer.Darw<strong>in</strong>, C. (1859) The Orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> Species, New York: Modern Library edn.Dowd, K. (1991) ‘Option clauses <strong>and</strong> bank suspension’, Cato Journal 10:3,W<strong>in</strong>ter.Hayek, F.A. (1937) ‘<strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> knowledge’, <strong>in</strong> Individualism <strong>and</strong><strong>Economic</strong> Order, Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1948.——(1945) ‘The use <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>in</strong> society’, <strong>in</strong> Individualism <strong>and</strong><strong>Economic</strong> Order, Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press, 1948.——(1952) The Sensory Order, Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press.——(1960) The Constitution <strong>of</strong> Liberty, Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> ChicagoPress.160


HIERARCHICAL METAPHORS——(1988) The Fatal Conceit: The Errors <strong>of</strong> Socialism, W.W.Hartley III(ed.), Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press.Hodgson, G.M. (1988) <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Institutions, Philadelphia:University <strong>of</strong> Pennsylvania Press.——(1992) ‘Institutional evolution <strong>and</strong> methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism’, <strong>in</strong>B.J.Caldwell <strong>and</strong> S.Boehm (eds) Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s: Tensions <strong>and</strong>NewDirections , Boston: Kluwer Academic.Horwitz, S. (1988) ‘Misread<strong>in</strong>g the “Myth”: Rothbard on the theory <strong>and</strong>history <strong>of</strong> free bank<strong>in</strong>g’, repr. <strong>in</strong> P.Boettke <strong>and</strong> D.Prychitko (eds) TheMarket Process: <strong>Essays</strong> on Contemporary Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s,Aldershot, UK: Edward Elgar, 1994.——(1992a) Monetary Evolution, Free Bank<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Order,Boulder: Westview Press.——(1992b) ‘Monetary exchange as an extra-l<strong>in</strong>guistic socialcommunication process’, Review <strong>of</strong> Social Economy 50:2, Summer.——(1993) ‘Spontaneity <strong>and</strong> design <strong>in</strong> the evolution <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions: thesimilarities <strong>of</strong> money <strong>and</strong> law’, Journal des Economistes et des EtudesHuma<strong>in</strong>es 4:4, December.——(1994) ‘<strong>Subjectivism</strong>, <strong>in</strong>stitutions, <strong>and</strong> capital: comment on Mongiovi<strong>and</strong> Lew<strong>in</strong>’, Advances <strong>in</strong> Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s, vol. 1, Greenwich, CT:JAI Press.Lachmann, L.M. (1971) The Legacy <strong>of</strong> Max Weber, Berkeley: TheGlendessary Press.——(1978) Capital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure, 2nd edn, Kansas City: SheedAndrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel.——(1986) The Market as an <strong>Economic</strong> Process, London: Basil Blackwell.Langlois, R. (1986a) ‘The New Institutional economics: an <strong>in</strong>troductoryessay’, <strong>in</strong> R.Langlois (ed.) <strong>Economic</strong>s as a Process: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> the NewInstitutionalist <strong>Economic</strong>s, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.——(1986b) ‘Rationality, <strong>in</strong>stitutions, <strong>and</strong> explanation’, <strong>in</strong> R.Langlois(ed.) <strong>Economic</strong>s as a Process: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> the New Institutional<strong>Economic</strong>s, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.——(1986c) ‘Coherence <strong>and</strong> flexibility: social <strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>in</strong> a world <strong>of</strong>radical uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty’, <strong>in</strong> I.M.Kirzner (ed.) <strong>Subjectivism</strong>, Intelligibility,<strong>and</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g, New York: New York UniversityPress.——(1992) ‘Orders <strong>and</strong> organizations: toward an Austrian theory <strong>of</strong> social<strong>in</strong>stitutions’, <strong>in</strong> B.J.Caldwell <strong>and</strong> S.Boehm (eds) Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s:Tensions <strong>and</strong> New Directions, Boston: Kluwer Academic.Lew<strong>in</strong>, P. (1994) ‘Knowledge, expectations, <strong>and</strong> capital’, Advances <strong>in</strong>Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s, vol. 1, Greenwich, CT: JAI Press.——(1997) ‘Capital <strong>in</strong> disequilibrium: a reexam<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> the capitaltheory <strong>of</strong> <strong>Ludwig</strong> M.Lachmann’, History <strong>of</strong> Political Economy, 29:3,Fall.Mäki, U., Gustafsson, B. <strong>and</strong> Knudsen, C. (eds) (1993) Rationality,Institutions <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Methodology, London: Routledge.Menger, C. (1892) ‘On the orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> money’, <strong>Economic</strong> Journal 2.——(1981 [1871]) Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s, New York: New YorkUniversity Press.——(1985 [1883]) Investigations <strong>in</strong>to the Method <strong>of</strong> the Social Sciences161


STEVEN HORWITZwith Special Reference to <strong>Economic</strong>s, New York: New York UniversityPress.O’Driscoll, G.P. <strong>and</strong> Rizzo, M.J. (1985) The <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Time <strong>and</strong>Ignorance, London: Basil Blackwell.Polanyi, M. (1958) Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-CriticalPhilosophy, Chicago: University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press.Prendergast, C. (1986) ‘Alfred Schutz <strong>and</strong> the Austrian School <strong>of</strong><strong>Economic</strong>s’, American Journal <strong>of</strong> Sociology 92:1:1–26, July.Prychitko, D.L. (1994) ‘<strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann <strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terpretive turn <strong>in</strong>economics: a critical <strong>in</strong>quiry <strong>in</strong>to the hermeneutics <strong>of</strong> the plan’,Advances <strong>in</strong> Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s, vol. 1, Greenwich, CT: JAI Press.Rothbard, M.N. (1983) America’s Great Depression, 4th edn, New York:Richardson <strong>and</strong> Snyder.Rutherford, M. (1994) Institutions <strong>in</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s: The Old <strong>and</strong> the NewInstitutionalists, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Samuels, W. (1989) ‘Austrian <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutional economics: some commonelements’, Research <strong>in</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Thought <strong>and</strong>Methodology 6: 53–71.Schutz, A. (1967) The Phenomenology <strong>of</strong> the Social World, Evanston:Northwestern University Press.Selg<strong>in</strong>, G.A. <strong>and</strong> White, L.H. (1987) ‘The evolution <strong>of</strong> a free bank<strong>in</strong>gsystem’, <strong>Economic</strong> Inquiry 25: July.Vaughn, K.I. (1994) Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>in</strong> America: The Migration <strong>of</strong> aTradition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.White, L.H. (1984) Free Bank<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Brita<strong>in</strong>, Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.162


9LACHMANN’S POLICYACTIVISMAn Austrian critique <strong>of</strong> KeynesianproclivitiesPeter J.Boettke <strong>and</strong> Steven T.SullivanIntroductionW.H.Hutt, upon notic<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann was to be one <strong>of</strong>the ma<strong>in</strong> lecturers at the first Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s InstructionalConference <strong>in</strong> South Royalton, VT <strong>in</strong> the summer <strong>of</strong> 1974, supposedlyturned to a crowd <strong>of</strong> students <strong>and</strong> said, ‘Why is Lachmann here? Heis a Keynesian, not an Austrian.’ Hutt, one <strong>of</strong> the foremost critics <strong>of</strong>Keynesian economics, was someone with authority to comment onthis issue. Indeed, why was Lachmann there if he possessed Keynesianproclivities <strong>in</strong> public policy? 1 Roger Garrison, perhaps the lead<strong>in</strong>gcontemporary authority on Austrian macroeconomics, <strong>of</strong>ten refers<strong>in</strong> lectures to Lachmann’s approach to economics as ‘Austro-Keynesianism’. 2 There can be no doubt that <strong>in</strong> the history <strong>of</strong> Austrianeconomics, Lachmann was the most charitable <strong>in</strong>terpreter <strong>of</strong> Keyneswith<strong>in</strong> the Austrian tradition. Indeed, <strong>in</strong> a 1983 essay Lachmannsought to del<strong>in</strong>eate the common ground that existed between Keynes<strong>and</strong> his followers <strong>and</strong> the Austrians. 3 Lachmann adhered soconsistently to the ‘pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> charitable <strong>in</strong>terpretation’ with respectto Keynes <strong>and</strong> many other <strong>of</strong> the Austrian School’s rivals that itbecame known around the NYU colloquium as ‘Lachmann’s Law’. 4Mises <strong>and</strong> Hayek certa<strong>in</strong>ly lacked both the patience <strong>and</strong> the<strong>in</strong>tellectual sympathy required to deal with Keynes <strong>in</strong> the mannerthat Lachmann did. Those familiar with the history <strong>of</strong> Austrianeconomics will also note that when Lachmann’s subjectivism ismentioned, Keynes <strong>and</strong> Shackle are never far beh<strong>in</strong>d.163


PETER J.BOETTKE AND STEVEN T.SULLIVANThere also can be no doubt that Lachmann played a significantrole <strong>in</strong> the resurgence <strong>of</strong> Austrian economics <strong>in</strong> the late 1970s <strong>and</strong>1980s. He was the catalyst for much <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>ternal development<strong>of</strong> Austrian economics among the resurgence generation, <strong>and</strong> his<strong>in</strong>fluence can be seen <strong>in</strong> the work <strong>of</strong> Gerald O’Driscoll <strong>and</strong> MarioRizzo, The <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Time <strong>and</strong> Ignorance (1985), KarenVaughn, Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>in</strong> America (1994) <strong>and</strong> Don Lavoie(ed.), <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Hermeneutics (1991) <strong>and</strong> Expectations <strong>and</strong>the Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Institutions (1994). Lachmann’s theoreticalchallenge to extend subjectivism from preferences to expectationshas had a deep <strong>and</strong> last<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>fluence among his Austriancolleagues, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g Israel Kirzner, who, despite his seriousreservations about aspects <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s research projectrema<strong>in</strong>ed Lachmann’s closest <strong>in</strong>tellectual ally <strong>in</strong> the Austrianrevival.Most scholars <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s generation, as we know, had theirfaith <strong>in</strong> the operation <strong>of</strong> unhampered market economies shaken bythe Great Depression <strong>of</strong> the 1930s. The Great Depression left an<strong>in</strong>delible mark on Lachmann as well. While work<strong>in</strong>g as F.A. Hayek’sassistant, Lachmann wrote an M. Sc. thesis at the London School <strong>of</strong><strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>in</strong> 1935 entitled ‘Capital structure <strong>and</strong> depression’—<strong>in</strong>which, despite his use <strong>of</strong> the Austrian theory <strong>of</strong> crises to expla<strong>in</strong> thedepression, he advocated a public works programme as a solution tothe depression problem (Lachmann 1935, esp. Chapter IV). The<strong>in</strong>stability <strong>of</strong> the stock market <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong> speculative <strong>in</strong>vestment wererecurr<strong>in</strong>g themes throughout his long research career (see, e.g.,Lachmann 1937, 1988). Lachmann was one <strong>of</strong> the most articulatespokesmen for the Austrian notion <strong>of</strong> a time structure <strong>of</strong>production, yet he was also a severe critic <strong>of</strong> any notion <strong>of</strong> adeterm<strong>in</strong>ate equilibrium as the outcome <strong>of</strong> economic processes(<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the unhampered market economy). These two positionsare not unrelated, but it takes some teas<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> the issues torealise the implications for theory <strong>and</strong> application.Can Lachmann be both radical subjectivist <strong>and</strong> policy activist?Could it be, as Garrison suggests, that Lachmann was bothAustrian <strong>and</strong> Keynesian? And, if Lachmann’s <strong>in</strong>fluence on theAustrian revival is as deep as it appears, then are contemporaryAustrian economists Keynesians? Lachmann took subjectivismseriously—subjectivists, then, might best take Lachmann’ssubjectivism seriously. And so can we correctly <strong>in</strong>fer from theactivist positions <strong>of</strong> subjectivism’s pre-em<strong>in</strong>ent modern championthat the charge <strong>of</strong> ‘nihilism’ it so <strong>of</strong>ten faces is misplaced? 5164


LACHMANN’S POLICY ACTIVISMLachmann presents us with quite a set <strong>of</strong> puzzles, <strong>and</strong> it seems onlyfitt<strong>in</strong>g that we should apply the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> charitable<strong>in</strong>terpretation to this subset <strong>of</strong> the writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> its ma<strong>in</strong> adherent <strong>in</strong>order to solve them.In his 1956 book Capital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure, Lachmann providedhis readers with a vision <strong>of</strong> the morphology <strong>of</strong> capital as an order<strong>in</strong> an exposition that was the clearest <strong>of</strong> its time. Draw<strong>in</strong>g on aview <strong>of</strong> capital as physically <strong>and</strong> functionally heterogeneouscomb<strong>in</strong>ations operated by plann<strong>in</strong>g act<strong>in</strong>g human m<strong>in</strong>ds,Lachmann traced out his vision <strong>and</strong> catalogued its implications forthe state <strong>of</strong> capital theory <strong>and</strong> macroeconomic policy. His<strong>in</strong>terpretive <strong>and</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ctly ‘Austrian’ system, thoroughly adheredto, would seem<strong>in</strong>gly deny <strong>in</strong>terventionist macroeconomic policies.Yet <strong>in</strong> the f<strong>in</strong>al analysis, Lachmann’s vision <strong>of</strong> the economy as asystem that does not necessarily possess a tendency towardsequilibrium, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> particular, his view <strong>of</strong> the operation <strong>of</strong> theprice system, led him to call for policy activism <strong>in</strong> times <strong>of</strong> generaleconomic distress. This is someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> a curiosity with<strong>in</strong> theAustrian camp.The purpose <strong>of</strong> this chapter is to trace out Lachmann’s vision <strong>of</strong>capital as an order, stress<strong>in</strong>g along the way those aspects <strong>of</strong> hisvision (<strong>and</strong> the Austrian concept <strong>of</strong> spontaneous order) that mosteffectively deny <strong>in</strong>terventionist macroeconomics <strong>in</strong> order todeterm<strong>in</strong>e whether Lachmann ultimately leaves us with a set <strong>of</strong>policy prescriptions that (despite whatever theoretical validity theymay be said to possess), could not rationally be carried out byanyone. We first present Lachmann s vision <strong>of</strong> capital as an order,<strong>and</strong> note those aspects that are most at odds with aggregatemacroeconomics—the view constitut<strong>in</strong>g the problem environment<strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terventionist policy maker. We then emphasise a second set<strong>of</strong> arguments extant <strong>in</strong> Capital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure (1956) (<strong>and</strong>elsewhere <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs) concern<strong>in</strong>g the function<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>the price system, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> particular its role <strong>in</strong> any self-correct<strong>in</strong>gtendency <strong>in</strong> the economy, <strong>in</strong> order to develop the sett<strong>in</strong>g forLachmann’s policy advocacy <strong>in</strong> times <strong>of</strong> massive pl<strong>and</strong>iscoord<strong>in</strong>ation. F<strong>in</strong>ally, we survey the possibility <strong>of</strong> reconciliation<strong>and</strong> explore the follow<strong>in</strong>g possibilities: That Lachmann: (1)contradicted himself <strong>in</strong> establish<strong>in</strong>g the validity <strong>in</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> thepolicy positions he takes; (2) presented us with a fully coherent set <strong>of</strong>policy arguments; (3) established the validity <strong>in</strong> theory <strong>of</strong> the policypositions he takes but left no basis for their rationalimplementation.165


PETER J.BOETTKE AND STEVEN T.SULLIVANUnderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g the capital-us<strong>in</strong>g economyThe concepts Lachmann employed to underst<strong>and</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dustrialstructure <strong>of</strong> a contemporary economically developed society,namely functional heterogeneity, complementarity as jo<strong>in</strong>t use,multiple specificity, the <strong>in</strong>dividuals production plan <strong>and</strong> itsphysical manifestation <strong>in</strong> the capital comb<strong>in</strong>ation, are rooted <strong>in</strong>the Austrian tradition. At the core <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s system is theproduction planthis is the means-ends framework <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dividual<strong>in</strong> the capitalus<strong>in</strong>g economy. In other words, Lachmann sunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the ‘macroeconomic’ world was thoroughlychoice-theoretic. The plan is a logical structure where objects <strong>and</strong>the causal relationships among objects are subjectively perceived;this focuses theoretical attention on how the plann<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dividualorganises the means <strong>of</strong> production at his disposal <strong>in</strong> order togenerate output. The plan is shaped by the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s subjectiveassessment <strong>of</strong> the economic environment, <strong>and</strong> its success or failureis judged by signals provided by the market process <strong>and</strong> filteredthrough that agent’s perceptions. The <strong>in</strong>dividual’s plan determ<strong>in</strong>esthe relationship between already exist<strong>in</strong>g capital goods <strong>and</strong>prospective new capital goods-Lachmann viewedcomplementarity as jo<strong>in</strong>t use <strong>of</strong> items with<strong>in</strong> the context <strong>of</strong> anexist<strong>in</strong>g plan, <strong>and</strong> substitution as a fundamental element <strong>of</strong> planrevision cont<strong>in</strong>gent on that plan’s failure as perceived by itscreator.Capital heterogeneity <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’s system, then, provides adifferent view <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>vestment relationship from that found <strong>in</strong> theaggregate macroeconomics or growth theory literature. Theassumption <strong>of</strong> homogeneity, <strong>in</strong> light <strong>of</strong> the Lachmannianalternative, can thus be seen to generate some analytical costs <strong>in</strong>terms <strong>of</strong> lost categories <strong>of</strong> capital relationships. It misleads theeconomist <strong>in</strong>to presum<strong>in</strong>g that new capital is a substitute for oldcapital, as Lachmann notes:As long as we cl<strong>in</strong>g to the view that all capital is homogeneous,we shall only see, as Keynes did, the unfavourable effects <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>vestment on the earn<strong>in</strong>g capacity <strong>and</strong> value <strong>of</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>gcapital goods, s<strong>in</strong>ce all the elements <strong>of</strong> a homogeneousaggregate are necessarily perfect substitutes for each other.The new capital competes with the old <strong>and</strong> reduces thepr<strong>of</strong>itability <strong>of</strong> the latter. Once we allow for heterogeneity wemust also allow for complementarity between old <strong>and</strong> new166


LACHMANN’S POLICY ACTIVISMcapital. The effect <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment on the pr<strong>of</strong>itability <strong>of</strong> oldcapital is now seen to depend on which <strong>of</strong> the various forms <strong>of</strong>old capital are complementary to, or substitutes for, the newcapital.(Lachmann 1956:6)The relationships between new <strong>and</strong> old capital are thus morecomplicated than a homogeneous aggregate conception would leadus to believe. The economics then becomes more complicated, <strong>and</strong>no small amount <strong>of</strong> damage is done to one <strong>of</strong> the central features <strong>of</strong>the Keynesian analysis <strong>of</strong> the macroeconomy:Look<strong>in</strong>g at the matter <strong>in</strong> the way we have done also opens upa new vista on the problem <strong>of</strong> the ‘<strong>in</strong>centive to <strong>in</strong>vest’. Newcapital goods are be<strong>in</strong>g used <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with exist<strong>in</strong>gones. This form <strong>of</strong> complementarity means that the lower theprice <strong>of</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g capital goods the greater the pr<strong>of</strong>itability <strong>of</strong>the new goods…Keynes, to be sure, did not neglect the effect <strong>of</strong> prices <strong>of</strong>exist<strong>in</strong>g capital goods on new <strong>in</strong>vestment, but, treat<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>characteristic fashion all capital as homogeneous, only sawthe possibility <strong>of</strong> substitution. So he held that prices <strong>of</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>gcapital goods below reproduction cost would weaken the<strong>in</strong>centive to <strong>in</strong>vest. But <strong>in</strong> reality capital is as a ruleheterogeneous <strong>and</strong> complementary. Except <strong>in</strong> the case, whichKeynes alone considered, where exist<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> new capitalgoods happen to be substitutes, low prices <strong>of</strong> the former willhave a favourable effect on the <strong>in</strong>centive to <strong>in</strong>vest. Neglect <strong>of</strong>the heterogeneity <strong>of</strong> capital thus vitiates the theory <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>vestment.(Lachmann 1956:49–50)Such issues <strong>of</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard economics, we shall argue below, whiledamag<strong>in</strong>g to the particulars <strong>of</strong> the Keynesian analysis, are secondary<strong>in</strong> importance to the implications <strong>of</strong> the Lachmannian vision for theproblem environment <strong>of</strong> the planner. To h<strong>in</strong>t at argumentsdeveloped more fully below, one can imag<strong>in</strong>e the <strong>in</strong>creased degree <strong>of</strong>technical knowledge required to centrally plan <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong> acapital-us<strong>in</strong>g economy if one recognises the heterogeneity <strong>of</strong> capital.Yet this daunt<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the data requirements merely reflectsthe task <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>vestment planner <strong>in</strong> a world where know<strong>in</strong>g that isall the relevant know<strong>in</strong>g; the relevant know<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’s167


PETER J.BOETTKE AND STEVEN T.SULLIVANframework is not merely a laundry list <strong>of</strong> eng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g relationshipsbut knowledge <strong>of</strong> context— know<strong>in</strong>g how.Add<strong>in</strong>g to this level <strong>of</strong> complexity, <strong>and</strong> generally rais<strong>in</strong>g the stakes<strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>tervention game, is another notion aris<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong>heterogeneity—that <strong>of</strong> multiple specificity. Capital goods arecharacterised by jo<strong>in</strong>t use, <strong>and</strong> are capable <strong>of</strong> many alternativecomb<strong>in</strong>ations, but the scope for their alternative use is not unlimited.Some modes <strong>of</strong> jo<strong>in</strong>t use are not feasible—there only exist certa<strong>in</strong>‘technically possible’ modes <strong>of</strong> complementarity; furthermore, theschedule <strong>of</strong> ‘economically significant’ <strong>and</strong> technically possiblecomb<strong>in</strong>ations is not given at once to the entrepreneur. Theentrepreneur must deploy resources (i.e. search) <strong>and</strong> be alert towardsthe discovery <strong>of</strong> such economical modes <strong>of</strong> complementarity, be<strong>in</strong>gcareful all the while because specification mistakes are admitted <strong>in</strong>tothe theory. Without multiple specificity, there would be no need toask why certa<strong>in</strong> capital comb<strong>in</strong>ations are used <strong>and</strong> others are not—the problem fac<strong>in</strong>g the capital comb<strong>in</strong>ation operator would be solvedex hypothesi. 6 Heterogeneity adds the possibility <strong>of</strong> mis-fits, or mal<strong>in</strong>vestment,<strong>in</strong> the comb<strong>in</strong>ations <strong>of</strong> capital goods employed by agents.In a world <strong>of</strong> capital factor homogeneity, <strong>of</strong> course, each additionaldK <strong>of</strong> capital is exactly like the last, except that its expected marg<strong>in</strong>alvalue product is different. In Lachmann’s world, an additional ‘dK’can cause the capital comb<strong>in</strong>ation to become <strong>in</strong>coherent <strong>and</strong> requirecostly revision <strong>of</strong> the plan. Furthermore, mistakes are durable—thefailed comb<strong>in</strong>ations <strong>of</strong> the past may shape the current problemenvironment, therefore contribut<strong>in</strong>g a pronounced degree <strong>of</strong> pathdependency. 7 Investment is an undertak<strong>in</strong>g on a higher plane <strong>of</strong>uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’s view <strong>of</strong> the world. This further adds tothe would-be planner’s problems.Heterogeneity <strong>and</strong> multiple specificity are not the end <strong>of</strong>Lachmann’s vision, however, but rather the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g. Investmentplann<strong>in</strong>g is not the computationally simple affair that emerges frommodels that assume homogeneity <strong>of</strong> capital goods. The problem <strong>of</strong>the ma<strong>in</strong>tenance <strong>of</strong> capital, <strong>and</strong> the role <strong>of</strong> signals employed by actorswith<strong>in</strong> the economy <strong>in</strong> form<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> revis<strong>in</strong>g capital-us<strong>in</strong>g plans, arem<strong>in</strong>imised <strong>in</strong> alternative models. 8 The Austrian analyticalcontribution to capital theory represents, rather, a way <strong>of</strong> look<strong>in</strong>g atcapital that effectively denies the theoretical aggregation, which is<strong>of</strong>ten employed to motivate <strong>in</strong>terventionist arguments. Why? Look<strong>in</strong>gat the texts provides us with a reveal<strong>in</strong>g dist<strong>in</strong>ction. The differencebetween the outcome <strong>of</strong> plans as envisioned at the firm level <strong>and</strong>manifested at the level <strong>of</strong> the market is reflected <strong>in</strong> the concepts <strong>of</strong>168


LACHMANN’S POLICY ACTIVISM‘plan complementarity’ or ‘designed complementarity’, which referto the relationship between elements <strong>in</strong> the firm’s plan, versus‘structural complementarity’—which refers to the relationship <strong>of</strong>elements across firms <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>deed across <strong>in</strong>dustries, <strong>and</strong> thereforeacross plann<strong>in</strong>g consciousnesses. ‘Capital structure’ is given to bethe mode <strong>of</strong> complementarity expressed <strong>in</strong> the market as a whole, or‘a mode <strong>of</strong> the composition <strong>of</strong> the capital stock <strong>of</strong> society’ (Lachmann1986:63ff). In Capital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure, Lachmann dist<strong>in</strong>guishesbetween plan <strong>and</strong> structural complementarity along these l<strong>in</strong>es: ‘Thefirst type <strong>of</strong> complementarity is brought about directly byentrepreneurial action…. Our second type <strong>of</strong> complementarity is, ifat all, brought about <strong>in</strong>directly by the market, viz. by the <strong>in</strong>terplay<strong>of</strong> mostly <strong>in</strong>consistent entrepreneurial plans’ (Lachmann 1956:54,italics <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al). Aga<strong>in</strong>, <strong>in</strong> his last book The Market as an <strong>Economic</strong>Process, Lachmann draws the dist<strong>in</strong>ction:This second type <strong>of</strong> complementarity [here mean<strong>in</strong>g structuralcomplementarity] is not the direct result <strong>of</strong> planned action, butthe <strong>in</strong>direct result <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>teraction between the plans <strong>of</strong>different firms <strong>in</strong> the market. These latter plans need not havebeen consistent from the start, but were then made consistentby market forces.(Lachmann 1986:63)Structural complementarity is <strong>of</strong> the macro-level—on the order <strong>of</strong>the phenomena studied by policy makers; so is it valid to speak <strong>of</strong>policies on the macro-level, such as <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g the ‘level <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>vestment’, without mak<strong>in</strong>g reference to the coherence <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>dividual plans? If we follow Lachmann’s l<strong>in</strong>e <strong>of</strong> argument, we seeclearly that structural complementarity is a surface relationship orby-product, merely a manifestation <strong>of</strong> the dovetail<strong>in</strong>g (or failure todovetail) <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual plans, which are the more fundamental units<strong>of</strong> analysis. The morphology <strong>of</strong> capital at the structural level istherefore an order, which is to say that it is the result ‘<strong>of</strong> humanaction, but not <strong>of</strong> human design’—<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>and</strong> firm-level<strong>in</strong>vestment plann<strong>in</strong>g, but not <strong>of</strong> macroeconomic <strong>in</strong>vestment policy.To recognise this argument <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’s work is to drive thestake <strong>of</strong> subjectivism <strong>in</strong>to the heart <strong>of</strong> aggregate capital theory, <strong>and</strong>thus <strong>in</strong>to the heart <strong>of</strong> most arguments for macroeconomic<strong>in</strong>terventionism as well. This is because st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>in</strong>vestment theoryfails to perceive the differences between conscious or <strong>in</strong>tended plancomplementarity at the firm level <strong>and</strong> manifested structural169


PETER J.BOETTKE AND STEVEN T.SULLIVANcomplementarity at the ‘macro’economic level. Bl<strong>in</strong>d to thephenomenology <strong>of</strong> the capital structure, the decentralised choicedrivenprocess <strong>of</strong> the com<strong>in</strong>g-to-be <strong>of</strong> that capital structure, themacroeconomist speaks <strong>of</strong> the ‘level <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment’ without properreference to the causal agents <strong>of</strong> the capital structure, namely plann<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>and</strong> firms. ‘National’ <strong>in</strong>vestment, good or bad, high orlow, appropriate or misdirected, only makes sense if we can speak <strong>of</strong>a ‘national’ plan, a means-ends framework constructed by a direct<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> controll<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong>d. But such a plan is a fiction—at the level <strong>of</strong>structural complementarity, there is no one direct<strong>in</strong>g or controll<strong>in</strong>gm<strong>in</strong>d. Lachmann cites Hayek’s Pure Theory <strong>of</strong> Capital <strong>in</strong> thedevelopment <strong>of</strong> this po<strong>in</strong>t:Of consistent capital change, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, we may speakwhere ‘co<strong>in</strong>cident expectations about the quantities <strong>and</strong>qualities <strong>of</strong> goods which will pass from one person’spossession <strong>in</strong>to another’s will <strong>in</strong> effect co-ord<strong>in</strong>ate all thesedifferent plans <strong>in</strong>to one s<strong>in</strong>gle plan, although this “plan” willnot exist <strong>in</strong> any one m<strong>in</strong>d. It can only be constructed.’(Lachmann 1956:60)Yet the macroeconomist engages <strong>in</strong> the familiar conceit <strong>of</strong> extend<strong>in</strong>gthe <strong>in</strong>dividual’s problem-solv<strong>in</strong>g acts <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d to the social level, withall the attendant hazards. In its restatement <strong>of</strong> the problem at theplanner’s level, it also departs from a fully subjectivist underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> the problem world. Capital comb<strong>in</strong>ations are manifestations <strong>of</strong>logical structures composed <strong>of</strong> relationships among subjectivelyperceived objects, <strong>and</strong> the knowledge they embody is not fullyavailable to anyone except their operators. The macroeconomist whoemploys an aggregate production technology with ‘known’ <strong>and</strong> stablecharacteristics <strong>of</strong> factor complementarity <strong>and</strong> substitutabilitypresumes a level <strong>of</strong> knowledge that no one m<strong>in</strong>d or group <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>dscan ever possess. 9 A Lachmannian capital theorist, then, mightreasonably view macroeconomic <strong>in</strong>vestment policy as an undertak<strong>in</strong>gwith context-specific knowledge requirements that are simplyimpossible to satisfy. How, then, can Lachmann call for policyactivism <strong>in</strong> times <strong>of</strong> widespread plan discoord<strong>in</strong>ation?Lachmann on the price system <strong>and</strong> the trade cycleLachmann viewed the price system (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>terest rate) as acommunications network through which <strong>in</strong>dividual operators <strong>of</strong>170


LACHMANN’S POLICY ACTIVISMcapital comb<strong>in</strong>ations could receive signals as to the opportunities exante <strong>and</strong> the performance ex post <strong>of</strong> their plans, <strong>and</strong> co-ord<strong>in</strong>ate thetime pr<strong>of</strong>iles <strong>of</strong> their productive activities:In a market economy…prices are not merely exchangeratios between commodities <strong>and</strong> services but l<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>in</strong> amarket-wide system <strong>of</strong> economic communications.Through price changes knowledge is transmitted from anycorner <strong>of</strong> the market to the rest <strong>of</strong> the system. On eachmarket buyers <strong>and</strong> sellers, by vary<strong>in</strong>g their bids <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>fers,signal to each other the need for action. Buyers learn abouttheir opportunities grow<strong>in</strong>g or shr<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g, sellers receivenotice <strong>of</strong> the need for adjustment. In this way everyeconomic change has market-wide repercussions…. Wemay thus conclude that via knowledge transmitted throughthe price system economic change tends, <strong>in</strong> general, to giverise to expectations consistent with itself.(Lachmann 1956:62)In Lachmann’s work the above paragraph represents the zenith <strong>of</strong>market performance as a co-ord<strong>in</strong>ator <strong>of</strong> plans. The <strong>in</strong>stitutionalcontext <strong>of</strong> the real world, however, plays havoc with the idealisedworld <strong>of</strong> responsive, flexible prices. Rigid wages <strong>and</strong> adm<strong>in</strong>isteredprices degrade the signals <strong>in</strong> the system:But <strong>in</strong> reality the price system is not such an ideal system <strong>of</strong>economic communications as the picture just drawn mightsuggest. Our apparatus, we must remember, works by‘translat<strong>in</strong>g’ dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> supply changes <strong>in</strong>to price changes.Hence, whenever the translation does not take place, for<strong>in</strong>stance, where prices are <strong>in</strong>flexible, our apparatus ceases tooperate. Moreover, as we learnt before, transmission is <strong>of</strong>tendelayed <strong>and</strong> sometimes faulty. Where this is known to be thecase the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the messages received will lend itself todifferent, <strong>and</strong> perhaps contrast<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong>terpretations, both as tocontent <strong>and</strong> time <strong>of</strong> despatch. This all the more so wherenumerous, perhaps contradictory, messages follow each otherwith<strong>in</strong> a short time over the same ‘wire’.(Lachmann 1956:62)What are the ramifications <strong>of</strong> error <strong>in</strong> the model? In demonstrat<strong>in</strong>gthem, Lachmann makes use <strong>of</strong> the concept <strong>of</strong> the ‘ceil<strong>in</strong>g’, the171


PETER J.BOETTKE AND STEVEN T.SULLIVANmaximum available quantity <strong>of</strong> a given resource or set <strong>of</strong> resources<strong>in</strong> a given time frame. Let us exam<strong>in</strong>e for a moment how rigid factorprices may lead the economy <strong>in</strong>to widespread plan failure: Let usimag<strong>in</strong>e a factor <strong>of</strong> production which is a complement <strong>in</strong> productionplans economy wide. As the use <strong>of</strong> this product br<strong>in</strong>gs us closer toexhaustion, or <strong>in</strong> our case to the ceil<strong>in</strong>g, the price will normally beadjusted through bidd<strong>in</strong>g until agents either discont<strong>in</strong>ue their plansutilis<strong>in</strong>g the factor at a lower expected return or otherwiseeconomise on its use. Rigid prices, however, prevent agents fromsee<strong>in</strong>g the approach <strong>of</strong> the ceil<strong>in</strong>g—suddenly it is reached, <strong>and</strong> thefactor without which their plans cannot proceed becomesunavailable. Keep<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d Lachmann’s view <strong>of</strong> complementarity,we can see that shortages <strong>of</strong> complementary factors constra<strong>in</strong> f<strong>in</strong>alfactor output; many <strong>of</strong> the factors whose output levels areconstra<strong>in</strong>ed by the orig<strong>in</strong>al factor shortage are complements <strong>in</strong>other production processes. The shortage spreads—if an agent hadplanned to br<strong>in</strong>g to market a certa<strong>in</strong> quantity <strong>of</strong> other (secondround)capital goods based upon the expectation <strong>of</strong> complementaryresources, which expectation was disappo<strong>in</strong>ted because the ceil<strong>in</strong>gwas hit for those complementary resources, that agent might choosenot to br<strong>in</strong>g the second-round capital goods to market. Capitalcomb<strong>in</strong>ations to which those second-round resources notforthcom<strong>in</strong>g are complementary may now be <strong>in</strong> peril. The scarcityneed not even last for very long for widespread plan discoord<strong>in</strong>ationto occur—only an unexpected delay <strong>in</strong> the factor’savailability is necessary:It might be said that raw material prices be<strong>in</strong>g more flexiblethan fixed capital goods prices, relative price figures tell uslittle about relative scarcity. It is true that a fixed capital goodsceil<strong>in</strong>g will manifest itself, at least at first, <strong>in</strong> delayed deliveryrather than <strong>in</strong> higher prices, so that absence <strong>of</strong> higher pricesdoes not necessarily mean absence <strong>of</strong> excess dem<strong>and</strong>. But thedelay <strong>in</strong> delivery can only post-pone, <strong>and</strong> not prevent, theemergence <strong>of</strong> excess capacity, unless <strong>of</strong> course the rawmaterial shortage is merely temporary, not a ‘ceil<strong>in</strong>g’ but a‘bottleneck’. The mere fact that after both sub-ceil<strong>in</strong>gs havebeen reached the output <strong>of</strong> both, raw materials <strong>and</strong> fixedcapital goods, will slow down, is irrelevant. It is relativescarcity <strong>of</strong> complementary factors which here causes excesscapacity <strong>and</strong> upsets plans. For no factor can be used <strong>in</strong>isolation, complementarity is <strong>of</strong> the essence <strong>of</strong> all plans, <strong>and</strong>172


LACHMANN’S POLICY ACTIVISMwithdrawal <strong>of</strong> a factor, or its failure to turn up at theappo<strong>in</strong>ted time, will equally endanger the success <strong>of</strong> theproduction plans.(Lachmann 1956:107, italics <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al)We can recognise here the added analytical value <strong>of</strong> heterogeneity—producers who had expected resources to be available which were tobe needed at later dates (now the present) have organised theirproduction processes <strong>and</strong> generated highly specific resources to beused <strong>in</strong> comb<strong>in</strong>ation with the expected output <strong>of</strong> their suppliers.Many <strong>of</strong> these <strong>in</strong>ventories <strong>of</strong> midstream products are uselesswithout the complementary resources, <strong>and</strong> those capitalcomb<strong>in</strong>ations which generated them are not costlessly or<strong>in</strong>stantaneously re-specified:Rates <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest which are too low, i.e. fail to establish ex anteequilibrium between sav<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestment, are apt toconvey such a mislead<strong>in</strong>g picture <strong>and</strong> thus lead to wrongspecify<strong>in</strong>g decisions….The essence <strong>of</strong> the matter is that <strong>in</strong>vestment decisions arenot merely irreversible <strong>in</strong> time, so that excessive <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong>period 1 as a rule cannot be <strong>of</strong>fset by dis<strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong> period2, but that they are also irrevocable <strong>in</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d. Even if, at a laterpo<strong>in</strong>t dur<strong>in</strong>g the boom, <strong>in</strong>terest rates start to rise, the messagecomes too late for those who have made their irrevocabledecision before.(Lachmann 1956:118, italics added)This phenomenon, born out <strong>of</strong> heterogeneity <strong>and</strong> multiplespecificity, embeds plan failure <strong>in</strong> the system.Lachmannian stabilisation policyIf we found ourselves as Lachmannian capital theorists ‘on themorrow <strong>of</strong> the crisis’, asked to formulate a policy to shepherd theeconomy back to its more normal degree <strong>of</strong> plan co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation, whatwould we do? The post-boom economy, as Lachmann tells us, is <strong>in</strong>crisis because the <strong>in</strong>terest rate or price system has sent the wrongsignals—projects have been undertaken <strong>and</strong> have drawn scarceresources away from other projects based upon false <strong>in</strong>formation onpr<strong>of</strong>itability, factor availability <strong>and</strong> the buy<strong>in</strong>g public’s will<strong>in</strong>gnessto delay consumption. The l<strong>and</strong>scape is littered with failed <strong>and</strong> fail<strong>in</strong>g173


PETER J.BOETTKE AND STEVEN T.SULLIVANprojects, some <strong>of</strong> whose failure is based upon the lack <strong>of</strong>complementary resources, others fail<strong>in</strong>g because <strong>of</strong> the normal course<strong>of</strong> market activity. Bottlenecks have occurred <strong>and</strong> ceil<strong>in</strong>gs have beenhit <strong>in</strong> crucial sectors <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dustry—say, primary materials. The ma<strong>in</strong>problem is one <strong>of</strong> mal<strong>in</strong>vestment or mistaken allocation, <strong>and</strong> theprima facie solution would seem to be to reallocate the misallocatedresources. This is what Lachmann suggests:The situation the economy faces on the morrow <strong>of</strong> the collapse<strong>of</strong> a strong boom clearly calls for capital regroup<strong>in</strong>g on a largescale…. Plans have gone astray, hopes have been disappo<strong>in</strong>ted;capital comb<strong>in</strong>ations have to be dissolved <strong>and</strong> reshuffled…Some planned comb<strong>in</strong>ations cannot come <strong>in</strong>to operationbecause <strong>of</strong> lack <strong>of</strong> complementary factors; these factors haveto be created now…. Someth<strong>in</strong>g might be done by shift<strong>in</strong>gresources to where they are most needed. The critical sectorsare those sub-ceil<strong>in</strong>gs which lie <strong>in</strong> the path <strong>of</strong> expansion. Heremore <strong>in</strong>vestment is required <strong>in</strong> order to ‘lift the ceil<strong>in</strong>g’. To thisend not merely must <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong> other sectors be curtailed;additional factors able to help <strong>in</strong> lift<strong>in</strong>g the ceil<strong>in</strong>g must berecruited from wherever they happen to be, <strong>and</strong> this means asa rule that they must be withdrawn from those comb<strong>in</strong>ations<strong>of</strong> which they form part. Mobile resources from everywhere,even from the consumption goods <strong>in</strong>dustries, will have to bedrawn to the critical sectors…. These mobile resources have tobe detached from the specific <strong>and</strong> non-mobile resources withwhich so far they have co-operated, <strong>and</strong> this will lead todissolution <strong>and</strong> reshuffl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g comb<strong>in</strong>ations…In all probability mobile resources cannot be withdrawn<strong>and</strong> capital comb<strong>in</strong>ations will not be reshuffled withoutpressure be<strong>in</strong>g brought to bear on owners <strong>and</strong> managers <strong>of</strong>specific resources. In some cases it may not be possible at allwithout actual bankruptcy. To this end a ‘severe’ credit policyis required. But a credit policy sufficiently severe to ‘crackopen’ the tougher k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> unsuccessful capital comb<strong>in</strong>ationsmay discourage <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong> the critical sectors <strong>of</strong> theeconomy.…In such a situation there is much to be said for a‘selective’ credit policy which need not be arbitrary if it merelyreflects the degree <strong>of</strong> imperfection <strong>of</strong> the capital market whichis the natural product <strong>of</strong> the past record <strong>of</strong> success <strong>and</strong> failure<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual firms.174


LACHMANN’S POLICY ACTIVISM…Suppose our critical sub-ceil<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>eral m<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g. It issurely unnecessary to deprive exist<strong>in</strong>g coal m<strong>in</strong>es <strong>of</strong> theirm<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g equipment. Our purpose <strong>of</strong> mov<strong>in</strong>g mobile resourcesto the critical area may be as well served by the heavyeng<strong>in</strong>eer<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dustries switch<strong>in</strong>g their plants from produc<strong>in</strong>gequipment for coal-us<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dustries to produc<strong>in</strong>g m<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g (or‘m<strong>in</strong>eral-economiz<strong>in</strong>g’) mach<strong>in</strong>ery. In this way exist<strong>in</strong>gcomb<strong>in</strong>ations may be moved bodily to ‘another stage <strong>of</strong>production’ without the pa<strong>in</strong>ful need for dis<strong>in</strong>tegration.(Lachmann 1956:120–4)These passages reflect an undeniably activist bent to Lachmann’sanalysis. The policy maker is charged with select<strong>in</strong>g which capitalcomb<strong>in</strong>ations must be dissolved <strong>and</strong> perhaps manipulat<strong>in</strong>g a‘selective’ credit policy <strong>in</strong> order to break apart those capitalcomb<strong>in</strong>ations possess<strong>in</strong>g resources useful to the ‘critical sectors’. Ina later passage on the dynamics <strong>of</strong> the post-‘weak boom’ economy,Lachmann states that the excess capacity generated by plan discoord<strong>in</strong>ation,even <strong>in</strong> the absence <strong>of</strong> ceil<strong>in</strong>gs, might be combated bymeans <strong>of</strong> a budget deficit comb<strong>in</strong>ed with the aforementionedselective credit policy (Lachmann 1956:125–6).This is not the only occurrence <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s advocacy <strong>of</strong>government activism. In his 1935 Master’s thesis at the LondonSchool <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s, Lachmann advocates public works to arrestthe process <strong>of</strong> cumulative depression:But, once the cumulative process <strong>of</strong> destruction is sway<strong>in</strong>g theeconomic system, what shall we do? For this case <strong>of</strong>emergency we propose a Public Works Programme somewhaton the follow<strong>in</strong>g l<strong>in</strong>es:The great advantage a public works programme has over amere stabilization policy <strong>of</strong> the k<strong>in</strong>d just described consists <strong>in</strong>that it would affect both consumers good <strong>in</strong>dustries (via thepurchases <strong>of</strong> the workmen now <strong>in</strong> employment) <strong>and</strong> producersgoods <strong>in</strong>dustries (via the purchases <strong>of</strong> the necessary raw- <strong>and</strong>build<strong>in</strong>g-materials) at one <strong>and</strong> the same time: We are, so tosay, arrest<strong>in</strong>g the cumulative process with h<strong>and</strong>-brake <strong>and</strong>foot-brake. Its ma<strong>in</strong> disadvantage, as has <strong>of</strong>ten been po<strong>in</strong>tedout, lies <strong>in</strong> the necessity to <strong>in</strong>vest capital for, at the exist<strong>in</strong>g rate<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest, unproductive purposes, i.e. <strong>in</strong> the net capitalconsumption it implies. From this it follows that the object <strong>of</strong>such a policy has to be the stopp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the cumulative process175


PETER J.BOETTKE AND STEVEN T.SULLIVANwith a m<strong>in</strong>imum sacrifice <strong>of</strong> capital. Hence, a public worksprogramme has to be devised <strong>in</strong> such a way, the purchases <strong>of</strong>consumers goods <strong>and</strong> capital-goods have to be dosed so as tobr<strong>in</strong>g about re<strong>in</strong>vestment-equilibrium with<strong>in</strong> the shortest timepossible.(Lachmann 1935:95–6, our italics)Note the constructivist language. These are rather odd th<strong>in</strong>gs for anAustrian economist to advocate, especially an Austrian whoconsistently emphasises the subjective nature <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>and</strong> theattendant unpredictability <strong>of</strong> economic systems. In fact, the secondpassage was preceded by a warn<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>in</strong>flationary policies,shored up by a lengthy discussion <strong>of</strong> the unpredictable character <strong>of</strong>dis-hoard<strong>in</strong>g behaviour (Lachmann 1935:89ff). And the mostcompell<strong>in</strong>g subjectivist argument conceivable for governmentactivism <strong>in</strong> times <strong>of</strong> massive plan disco-ord<strong>in</strong>ation, namely that suchactivism provides a signpost or strong signal for the reco-ord<strong>in</strong>ation<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual means—ends frameworks, is nowhere to be found.The description <strong>of</strong> the crisis referred to <strong>in</strong> these passages iscerta<strong>in</strong>ly consistent with the Austrian theory <strong>of</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong>production, with Lachmann’s view <strong>of</strong> complementarity, <strong>and</strong> withthe Austrian Trade Cycle Theory, but what are we to make <strong>of</strong> theLachmannian policy agenda?In try<strong>in</strong>g to make sense <strong>of</strong> Lachmann on policy, we return to thechoices listed at the beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the chapter. The first <strong>of</strong> these isthat Lachmann’s economics are simply <strong>in</strong>correct. Let us approachthe argument: Is Lachmann’s call for a reshuffl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> capitalcomb<strong>in</strong>ations <strong>in</strong>consistent with end<strong>in</strong>g the crisis? Given that thecritical sectors can be identified <strong>and</strong> the proper path for theeconomy can be div<strong>in</strong>ed, it is conceivable that a set <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives canbe formulated to redirect resources to their highest-valued use <strong>in</strong> there-eng<strong>in</strong>eered structure <strong>of</strong> production, <strong>and</strong> that bankruptcy <strong>and</strong>sufficiently well-developed ‘used capital’ markets can be used toreorganise capital comb<strong>in</strong>ations economywide. We f<strong>in</strong>d, then, thatas a matter <strong>of</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>in</strong>centive-driven economic analysis,Lachmann’s prescription fits the diagnosis. 10 We can reject the firstalternative.We now turn to issues aris<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> the second <strong>and</strong> the thirdalternatives. These are that Lachmann either provided us with acoherent analysis or failed to shore up his economics with a firmepistemic foot<strong>in</strong>g. If we grant that Lachmann’s economics aresound, <strong>and</strong> that his policy suggestions are valid <strong>in</strong> theory given the176


LACHMANN’S POLICY ACTIVISMcha<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> events that has led us to the crisis, then we might concludethat the second alternative is satisfactory <strong>and</strong> our task is f<strong>in</strong>ished.Lachmann’s policy activism results from sound economic reason<strong>in</strong>g<strong>and</strong> would be a reasonable response for an Austrian given thesituation so described. But to take Lachmann’s system seriously, it is<strong>in</strong>sufficient to establish the validity <strong>of</strong> the theoretical mechanics <strong>and</strong>consider the problem <strong>of</strong> feasibility solved. Lachmann’s book was asmuch or more a statement about economic knowledge as it wasabout the hard empirics <strong>of</strong> the trade cycle, <strong>and</strong> it is the problem <strong>of</strong>economic knowledge that will not let us rest with the secondalternative. 11 Feasibility, it seems, is a more troubl<strong>in</strong>g problem thanLachmann appreciated. When we ask ourselves such questions as‘What rationale exists for the policy maker <strong>in</strong> decid<strong>in</strong>g which sectorsare critical to the recovery? What is the mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the proper path<strong>in</strong> an openended economy? How do we dist<strong>in</strong>guish normal projectfailures from those brought about by the crisis?’ we realise that thesecond alternative does not f<strong>in</strong>ish tell<strong>in</strong>g the story because it is notfully <strong>in</strong>formed by Lachmann’s view <strong>of</strong> ‘who knows what’ <strong>in</strong> theeconomy. The ‘critical sectors’ lie ‘<strong>in</strong> the path <strong>of</strong> expansion’—butthe economy is <strong>in</strong> crisis <strong>in</strong> the Lachmannian story precisely becauseagents’ expectations about the time pr<strong>of</strong>ile <strong>of</strong> productive activitiesare <strong>in</strong> disarray. Why is the theorist-as-policy-maker’s positionepistemically privileged?Our third alternative suggests that the problem is one <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal<strong>in</strong>consistency. Lachmann calls for a reshuffl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> complementaryresources to the ‘critical sectors’, which are supposedly simple toidentify—this is a result <strong>of</strong> the use <strong>of</strong> what is undeniably a macrooraggregate construct. It is an example <strong>of</strong> how Austrian economistssometimes f<strong>in</strong>d it mean<strong>in</strong>gful to talk about broad categories, heresurround<strong>in</strong>g capital goods’ functional character <strong>in</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong>production. But because one can stylise the structure <strong>of</strong> productionto underst<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual acts <strong>of</strong> choice <strong>and</strong> specification does notmean one can underst<strong>and</strong> well enough the entire <strong>and</strong> concreteeconomy on the operat<strong>in</strong>g table <strong>in</strong> order to diagnose the concreteproblem <strong>and</strong> target specific policy—the two are potentially<strong>in</strong>consistent acts <strong>of</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d. One <strong>in</strong>volves the theorist’s underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong> production from with<strong>in</strong>, from the po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view <strong>of</strong>the <strong>in</strong>dividual agents shap<strong>in</strong>g its particulars, while the other<strong>in</strong>volves a view <strong>of</strong> this structure from without—from the po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong>view no s<strong>in</strong>gle agent or group <strong>of</strong> agents possesses. Lachmann’sactivism, as most <strong>in</strong>terventionist arguments implicitly do, conflatesthe two perspectives. The categorical rejection <strong>of</strong> such a conflation177


PETER J.BOETTKE AND STEVEN T.SULLIVANrepresents one <strong>of</strong> the substantive implications <strong>of</strong> the Austriancriticism <strong>of</strong> aggregate macroeconomics.Ironically, Lachmann’s mistake <strong>in</strong> Capital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure(<strong>and</strong> elsewhere on this topic) is <strong>in</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>sufficiently subjectivist.On the one h<strong>and</strong>, capital comb<strong>in</strong>ations are outwardmanifestations <strong>of</strong> subjectively perceived relationships <strong>and</strong> objects,<strong>and</strong> on the other h<strong>and</strong> they are functionally categorised by theeconomist accord<strong>in</strong>g to a view <strong>of</strong> their place with<strong>in</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong>production. This second aspect is perfectly valid for underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>ghow a crisis might occur <strong>in</strong> theory, but its extension to diagnosis<strong>and</strong> economic policy <strong>in</strong> an actual crisis puts the economist <strong>in</strong> thegrip <strong>of</strong> an epistemic contradiction. Lachmann’s policy maker isbe<strong>in</strong>g asked to ‘bite <strong>of</strong>f more than she can chew’. Lachmann forgothis own analysis <strong>in</strong> fram<strong>in</strong>g the policy maker’s problem <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>mov<strong>in</strong>g from generalised classes <strong>of</strong> strong <strong>and</strong> weak boomproblems to an actual <strong>in</strong>stance <strong>of</strong> the ‘post-strong boom economy’type, with an objective knowledge requirement as large as thateconomy <strong>and</strong> a contextual knowledge requirement policy makerscannot beg<strong>in</strong> to address from their st<strong>and</strong>po<strong>in</strong>t. The problem <strong>of</strong> aradical subjectivist macroeconomics is this: The theorist hasmerely to th<strong>in</strong>k about how agents th<strong>in</strong>k; the policy maker mustknow what they th<strong>in</strong>k.ConclusionIf the market process, as Lachmann has stressed, is bestunderstood as ‘a pattern <strong>of</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>gful utterances <strong>of</strong> the humanm<strong>in</strong>d’, then economists must focus their theoretical attention onproblems <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation acquisition <strong>and</strong> how <strong>in</strong>stitutionsprovide signals to guide our actions with<strong>in</strong> the economic world(Lachmann 1986:165). This also means that we can never dropthe issue <strong>of</strong> knowledge from our attention for either modell<strong>in</strong>gpurposes or policy-mak<strong>in</strong>g convenience. As he put it <strong>in</strong> anothercontext:The market process is the outward manifestation <strong>of</strong> anunend<strong>in</strong>g stream <strong>of</strong> knowledge. This <strong>in</strong>sight is fundamental toAustrian economics. The pattern <strong>of</strong> knowledge is cont<strong>in</strong>uouslychang<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> society, a process hard to describe. Knowledgedefies all attempts to treat it as a ‘datum’ or an object <strong>in</strong> time<strong>and</strong> space.(Lachmann 1976:127)178


LACHMANN’S POLICY ACTIVISMKnowledge, to Lachmann, while essential to economicunderst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g is nevertheless elusive—a concept that simply cannotbe accounted for <strong>in</strong> the neoclassical model (or any determ<strong>in</strong>atemodel <strong>of</strong> economic affairs) because the very passage <strong>of</strong> time implieschange <strong>in</strong> the state <strong>of</strong> knowledge <strong>in</strong> society.Lachmann’s work stressed the extension <strong>of</strong> subjectivism frompreferences to expectations. In pursu<strong>in</strong>g this radical subjectivist l<strong>in</strong>e<strong>of</strong> research he <strong>of</strong>fered important <strong>and</strong> deep <strong>in</strong>sights <strong>in</strong>to the dynamicnature <strong>of</strong> market processes, the role <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutions as guideposts toactions, the difficulty <strong>of</strong> signal <strong>in</strong>terpretations, the role <strong>of</strong> time <strong>in</strong>human perception, <strong>and</strong> the l<strong>in</strong>k <strong>in</strong> economic life between thedispersion <strong>of</strong> knowledge, the dispersion <strong>of</strong> expectations <strong>and</strong> thedispersion <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretations. These <strong>in</strong>sights shook the foundation <strong>of</strong>any determ<strong>in</strong>istic render<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> the market process, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g theAustrian theory <strong>of</strong> entrepreneurial discovery. If Lachmann’s <strong>in</strong>sightsare valid, then the economic world is truly kaleidic.The kaleidoscope, despite its <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>acy, possesses a certa<strong>in</strong>pattern or order <strong>in</strong>ternal to its own operation. The market, from aLachmannian perspective, could be said to possess the same type <strong>of</strong>patterned order—neither clockwork nor completely r<strong>and</strong>om. Theorder <strong>of</strong> the market process has a logic <strong>of</strong> its own (see O’Driscoll<strong>and</strong> Rizzo 1985:71–91). Attempts to get outside <strong>of</strong> the system <strong>and</strong>control it do not so much direct its operation as distort the patternedorder that characterises a market economy with<strong>in</strong> a well-establishedsystem <strong>of</strong> property rules.In deal<strong>in</strong>g with Lachmann’s particular arguments for activismwe have suggested that he failed to consistently take his ownsubjectivist lessons to heart. If the world is truly kaleidic, then thepolicy maker must face the same confus<strong>in</strong>g array <strong>of</strong> signals as that<strong>of</strong> market participants (with the same diversity <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong>the signals). If private market actors do not face the <strong>in</strong>centives <strong>and</strong>lack the ability to acquire the <strong>in</strong>formation to co-ord<strong>in</strong>ate theirbehaviour with others <strong>in</strong> the market due to the constantlychang<strong>in</strong>g conditions <strong>and</strong> diversity <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretations <strong>of</strong> the signalsthese changes produce, then why should we expect policy makersto be able to co-ord<strong>in</strong>ate economic affairs <strong>in</strong> a successful manner?The very subjectivism that Lachmann championed underm<strong>in</strong>es hisKeynesian proclivities. The analytical arguments that flow fromsubjectivism, <strong>in</strong> other words, cannot susta<strong>in</strong> the Keynesian vision<strong>of</strong> policy activism. It is not the determ<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>of</strong> New Classicaleconomics that defeats Keynesian policy, but the ‘dark forces <strong>of</strong>time <strong>and</strong> ignorance’ that engulf us all.179


PETER J.BOETTKE AND STEVEN T.SULLIVANNotes1 Here we must be careful with our labels—the central issue <strong>of</strong> the paperis the juxtaposition <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’s subjectivism with his policyactivism. The fact that Keynes favoured activist policy (<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>particular, public works) should not lead us to the (false) conclusionthat all policy activism is somehow Keynesian. Lachmann’s advocacy<strong>of</strong> public works programmes <strong>in</strong> his LSE thesis predates the GeneralTheory, for example. Yet given the tendency <strong>of</strong> discussions <strong>of</strong>Lachmann to flow <strong>in</strong>to discussions <strong>of</strong> Keynes, the policy comparisonsto Keynes are an irresistible temptation <strong>and</strong> ‘Keynesian’ positionsshould here be narrowly <strong>in</strong>terpreted as those ‘adhered to most notablyby Keynes’.2 See, e.g., Garrison (1986 <strong>and</strong> 1994) where he carefully dist<strong>in</strong>guisheshis own Austrian approach from either the extreme subjectivism <strong>of</strong>Keynes, Shackle <strong>and</strong> Lachmann <strong>and</strong> the extreme determ<strong>in</strong>ism <strong>of</strong> Lucas<strong>and</strong> Sargent.3 L.Lachmann, ‘John Maynard Keynes: A view from an Austrianw<strong>in</strong>dow’, <strong>in</strong> D.Lavoie (ed.) Expectations <strong>and</strong> the Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>Institutions, London: Routledge, 1994.4 D.Lavoie (ed.) ‘Introduction’, <strong>in</strong> Expectations <strong>and</strong> the Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>Institutions, London: Routledge, 1994.5 Clearly there are ‘varieties’ <strong>of</strong> both subjectivisms <strong>and</strong> subjectivists—e.g. Keynes, Shackle, Lachmann, Hayek. To some extent, the propriety<strong>of</strong> subjectivist calls for policy activism is always (rightly) <strong>in</strong> question.This is particularly true, we th<strong>in</strong>k, for Lachmann. As Lavoie notes <strong>in</strong>his ‘Introduction’ to Expectations <strong>and</strong> the Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Institutions,subjectivism was for Lachmann more than a m<strong>in</strong>or po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong>methodology <strong>in</strong> value theory. Many economists can <strong>and</strong> do refer tothemselves as ‘subjectivists’ <strong>and</strong> yet ultimately base their predictions(as they must) on objectivist or mechanical-<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivist techniquesthat ultimately wr<strong>in</strong>g the subjectivism (<strong>and</strong> hence the fundamentalunpredictability) out <strong>of</strong> human systems. Yet from Lachmann we wouldexpect someth<strong>in</strong>g different.As for the obvious follow-up question about Keynes, our argumentbelow to the effect that Lachmann bestows an unjustifiable epistemicprivilege on the position <strong>of</strong> his policy maker can be extended toKeynes with no difficulty, despite the clear differences <strong>in</strong> the twoeconomists’ particular br<strong>and</strong>s <strong>of</strong> subjectivism. Here we must leavethe argument about Keynes so as to avoid gett<strong>in</strong>g too far afield <strong>of</strong> ourfocus, namely Lachmann’s activist views. For more on Keynes’ssubjectivism, see Butos <strong>and</strong> Koppl, ‘The varieties <strong>of</strong> subjectivism:Keynes <strong>and</strong> Hayek on expectations’, History <strong>of</strong> Political Economy,29 (2):327–59 (1997).6 This is true for both the assumption <strong>of</strong> homogeneity <strong>and</strong> for a world <strong>of</strong>unique specificity. The importance <strong>of</strong> economic calculation as a guidefor the allocation with<strong>in</strong> production plans <strong>of</strong> scarce capital goods isonly highlighted <strong>in</strong> the world <strong>of</strong> heterogeneity <strong>and</strong> multiple specificity.7 Though not always for the worse <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> economic allocations.Lachmann notes <strong>in</strong> Capital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure that ‘A number <strong>of</strong>180


LACHMANN’S POLICY ACTIVISM<strong>in</strong>vestment opportunities actually owe their existence to the failure <strong>of</strong>past capital comb<strong>in</strong>ations to achieve the purposes for which they weredesigned’ (1956:9–10).8 Kirzner (1966) provides an overview <strong>of</strong> the basic conceptual issues <strong>of</strong>concern <strong>in</strong> alternative formulations <strong>of</strong> capital theory. Also see Lew<strong>in</strong>(1994).9 This, <strong>of</strong> course, is the theme <strong>of</strong> Hayek’s Nobel Lecture, The pretense <strong>of</strong>knowledge’ (Hayek 1974).10 Of course, this analysis m<strong>in</strong>imises or denies that the very subjectivism<strong>of</strong> expectations that makes speculative markets suspect as coord<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>gdevices should be generalised to confront policy makers aswell. In Austrian analysis it is <strong>of</strong>ten argued that questions <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>centivescannot legitimately be separated from questions concern<strong>in</strong>gknowledge acquisition. For the sake <strong>of</strong> argument, however, we assumethat one can address these questions separately. Public choice theory,for example, <strong>of</strong>ten assumes perfect <strong>in</strong>formation on the part <strong>of</strong>government <strong>of</strong>ficials, but then asks the analyst to consider the<strong>in</strong>centive system. Austrians, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, typically assumebenevolence on the part <strong>of</strong> policy makers, but then exam<strong>in</strong>e thedifficulties <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>formation acquisition. A full-blown theory <strong>of</strong> policymak<strong>in</strong>g would have to account for both <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>centives,but the usefulness <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tellectually isolat<strong>in</strong>g these problems <strong>and</strong>exam<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the implications cannot be denied.11 It is for precisely this reason that the pr<strong>in</strong>ciple <strong>of</strong> charitable<strong>in</strong>terpretation is <strong>in</strong>apposite <strong>in</strong> this case—the policy conclusions <strong>in</strong>Capital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure (Lachmann 1956) <strong>and</strong> elsewhere run aga<strong>in</strong>stthe gra<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> what we know to be the knowledge-theoretic thrust <strong>of</strong> theLachmannian research programme. There can be little question butthat we are engaged <strong>in</strong> immanent criticism <strong>of</strong> Lachmann <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>d hisconclusions want<strong>in</strong>g.ReferencesGarrison, R. (1986) ‘From Lachmann to Lucas: on <strong>in</strong>stitutions,expectations, <strong>and</strong> equilibrat<strong>in</strong>g tendencies’, <strong>in</strong> I.M.Kirzner (ed.)<strong>Subjectivism</strong>, Intelligibility, <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong>Honor <strong>of</strong> <strong>Ludwig</strong> M. Lachmann on His Eightieth Birthday, New York:New York University Press, pp. 87–101.——(1994) ‘Interview’, <strong>in</strong> B.Snowdon, H.Vane <strong>and</strong> P.Wynarczyk AModern Guide to Macroeconomics: An Introduction to Compet<strong>in</strong>gSchools <strong>of</strong> Thought, Aldershot, UK: Edward Elgar Publish<strong>in</strong>g, pp. 383–97.Hayek, F.A. (1974) ‘The pretense <strong>of</strong> knowledge’, <strong>in</strong> New Studies <strong>in</strong>Philosophy, Politics, <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> the History <strong>of</strong> Ideas, Chicago:University <strong>of</strong> Chicago Press (1978), pp. 23–34.Kirzner, I.M. (1966) An Essay on Capital, New York: Augustus M.Kelly.Lachmann, L.M. (1935) ‘Capital structure <strong>and</strong> depression’,unpublishedM.Sc.(Econ.) thesis, London University .——(1937) ‘Uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>and</strong> liquidity-preference’, <strong>in</strong> D.Lavoie (ed.)181


PETER J.BOETTKE AND STEVEN T.SULLIVANExpectations <strong>and</strong> the Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Institutions: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s by<strong>Ludwig</strong> M.Lachmann, London: Routledge (1994), pp. 29–41.——(1956) Capital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure, Menlo Park: Institute for HumaneStudies (1978 edn).——(1976) ‘On the central concept <strong>of</strong> Austrian economics: marketprocess’, <strong>in</strong> E.G.Dolan (ed.) The Foundations <strong>of</strong> Modern Austrian<strong>Economic</strong>s, Menlo Park: Institute for Humane Studies, pp. 126–32.——(1986) The Market as an <strong>Economic</strong> Process, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.——(1988) ‘Speculative markets <strong>and</strong> economic complexity’, <strong>in</strong> D.Lavoie(ed.) Expectations <strong>and</strong> the Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Institutions: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>sby <strong>Ludwig</strong> M.Lachmann, London: Routledge (1994), pp. 270–5.Lavoie, D. (ed.) (1991) <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Hermeneutics, London: Routledge.——(ed.) (1994) Expectations <strong>and</strong> the Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Institutions: <strong>Essays</strong> <strong>in</strong><strong>Economic</strong>s by <strong>Ludwig</strong> M.Lachmann, London: Routledge.Lew<strong>in</strong>, P. (1994) ‘Capital theory’, <strong>in</strong> P.J.Boettke (ed.) The Elgar Companionto Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s, Aldershot, UK: Edward Elgar Publish<strong>in</strong>g, pp.209–15.O’Driscoll, G.P. <strong>and</strong> Rizzo, M.J. (1985) The <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Time <strong>and</strong>Ignorance, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Vaughn, K.I. (1994) Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>in</strong> America, New York:Cambridge University Press.182


10EXPECTATIONS ANDSTOCK MARKET PRICESJochen Runde <strong>and</strong> jörg BibowA familiar theme <strong>in</strong> <strong>Ludwig</strong> Lachmann’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs is the notion <strong>of</strong>‘divergent’ expectations <strong>in</strong> stock markets. The follow<strong>in</strong>g passage isfairly typical:The Stock Exchange consists <strong>of</strong> a series <strong>of</strong> markets for assets,i.e., future yield streams. In each market supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>are brought <strong>in</strong>to equality every day. Dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> supplyreflect the divergent expectations <strong>of</strong> buyers <strong>and</strong> sellersconcern<strong>in</strong>g future yields. Transactions take place betweenthose whose expectations diverge from the current marketprice. S<strong>in</strong>ce as much must be bought as is sold, we may saythat the equilibrium price <strong>in</strong> an asset market reflects the‘balance <strong>of</strong> expectations’. As without divergence <strong>of</strong>expectations there can be no market at all, we can say thatthis divergence provides the substrate upon which the marketprice rests.(Lachmann 1977:161)The many similar passages on the nature <strong>and</strong> role <strong>of</strong> expectations <strong>in</strong>stock markets that appear <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs are <strong>in</strong>variably<strong>in</strong>sightful <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>structive. His commitment to subjectivism, toanalys<strong>in</strong>g economic phenomena from the viewpo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> the<strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g economic actor, moreover, provides an importantperspective that is denied on more conventional assumptions aboutexpectations. Yet it seems to us that Lachmann is seldomparticularly explicit about what he takes the term ‘expectation’ torefer to or express <strong>and</strong>, accord<strong>in</strong>gly, that his dist<strong>in</strong>ctive <strong>and</strong> highlysuggestive writ<strong>in</strong>gs on expectations <strong>in</strong> stock markets <strong>in</strong>vite both183


JOCHEN RUNDE AND JÖRG BIBOW<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>and</strong> elaboration on this count. Our aim, then, is tooutl<strong>in</strong>e Lachmann’s conception <strong>of</strong> expectations <strong>and</strong> to use this to<strong>of</strong>fer an account <strong>of</strong> his dist<strong>in</strong>ction between convergent <strong>and</strong>divergent expectations. We go on to raise some problems withexpla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g equity prices <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> divergent expectations <strong>and</strong>,draw<strong>in</strong>g on Miller (1977) <strong>and</strong> Keynes, attempt to resolve them.ExpectationsLachmann <strong>of</strong>fers various h<strong>in</strong>ts about his views on the nature <strong>of</strong>expectations <strong>and</strong> their emergence. Three themes recur consistentlythroughout his writ<strong>in</strong>gs. The first is that expectations are <strong>in</strong>cidentalto the ‘mental pictures’ drawn to formulate the plans on whichhuman conduct is based. 1 Expectations thus concern future eventsor states <strong>of</strong> affairs that exist only <strong>in</strong> the imag<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> the actor atthe time that the expectation is formed. The second theme is thatexpectations are not strictly determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the ‘data’ <strong>of</strong> experiencebut are based on experience that is necessarily <strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>and</strong> thatis, to this extent, subjective. Lachmann emphasises, <strong>in</strong> thisconnection, that the ‘act’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation is never wholly passive<strong>and</strong>, accord<strong>in</strong>gly, that economic choice <strong>and</strong> action are never whollydeterm<strong>in</strong>ed by the actor’s circumstances. F<strong>in</strong>ally, Lachmann <strong>in</strong>siststhat it is not possible to have foreknowledge <strong>of</strong> future events <strong>and</strong>accord<strong>in</strong>gly, that expectations tend to be subject to uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty.Yet Lachmann’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong>fer few direct statements about thenature <strong>and</strong> structure <strong>of</strong> the expectations he has <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d. 2 In his mostexplicit <strong>and</strong> extended discussion <strong>of</strong> the topic, Chapter 2 <strong>of</strong> hisCapital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure, he beg<strong>in</strong>s by compar<strong>in</strong>g what thebus<strong>in</strong>essman does <strong>in</strong> form<strong>in</strong>g an expectation with what a scientistdoes <strong>in</strong> formulat<strong>in</strong>g a work<strong>in</strong>g hypothesis (Lachmann 1978:23).Bus<strong>in</strong>ess expectations <strong>and</strong> scientific hypotheses serve the samepurpose <strong>in</strong> that they both ‘reflect an attempt at cognition <strong>and</strong>orientation <strong>in</strong> an imperfectly known world’ <strong>and</strong> ‘embody imperfectknowledge to be tested <strong>and</strong> improved by later experience’.Expectations are formed, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Lachmann, by analys<strong>in</strong>gone’s situation <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> the impact <strong>of</strong> possible ‘forces’ ortendencies believed to be operative <strong>in</strong> the situation. 3 The aim is toidentify <strong>and</strong> separate dom<strong>in</strong>ant or ‘major’ tendencies from r<strong>and</strong>omor ‘m<strong>in</strong>or’ tendencies. Expectations are then a reflection <strong>of</strong> theanticipated effects <strong>of</strong> the operation <strong>of</strong> the major tendenciesidentified. Lachmann seems to suggest that <strong>in</strong>duction plays a majorrole <strong>in</strong> the formation <strong>of</strong> expectations:184


EXPECTATIONS AND STOCK MARKET PRICES<strong>in</strong> assess<strong>in</strong>g the significance <strong>of</strong> price changes observed <strong>in</strong> thepast for future changes we shall tend to neglect those webelieve to have been due to r<strong>and</strong>om causes, <strong>and</strong> to conf<strong>in</strong>e ourattention to those we believe due to more ‘permanent’ causes.(ibid.: 24)Expected values are then compared to realised values <strong>in</strong> order to<strong>in</strong>fer whether <strong>in</strong>itial assessments were correct.But even here, it is only possible to <strong>in</strong>fer his views on the possiblestructure <strong>of</strong> the expectations he has <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d from his application <strong>of</strong>Lange’s (1944) theory <strong>of</strong> the ‘Practical Range’. 4 In terms <strong>of</strong> thistheory, price expectations are taken to consist <strong>of</strong> an imag<strong>in</strong>ed ‘<strong>in</strong>ner’<strong>in</strong>terval <strong>of</strong> possible prices that the actor would consider ‘normal’over some period or at some date, bounded on either side by an‘outer range’ <strong>of</strong> prices considered ‘possible’. This conception isconsistent with Lachmann’s views on expectations be<strong>in</strong>g subject touncerta<strong>in</strong>ty: it appears to permit a rough gradation <strong>of</strong> possibleprices <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> a weak form <strong>of</strong> (comparative) epistemicprobability, while avoid<strong>in</strong>g the st<strong>and</strong>ard assumption about beliefscorrespond<strong>in</strong>g to numerically def<strong>in</strong>ite probabilities. From theactor’s perspective, then, prices that lie with<strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>ner price rangeare more probable than those ly<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the outer ranges, <strong>and</strong> pricesly<strong>in</strong>g with<strong>in</strong> the outer ranges are more probable than prices that fallbeyond the outer ranges. Lachmann does not say anyth<strong>in</strong>g about thetime horizon <strong>of</strong> the expectations he has <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d.Lachmann’s advocacy <strong>of</strong> the ‘Practical Range’ conception isbound up with his views on how actors <strong>in</strong>terpret the position <strong>and</strong>movement <strong>of</strong> actual prices with<strong>in</strong> the ranges <strong>and</strong>, accord<strong>in</strong>gly, howthis <strong>in</strong>fluences the formation <strong>of</strong> expectations. There are threepossibilities. First, actual prices may vary with<strong>in</strong> the normal<strong>in</strong>terval. In this case, Lachmann argues, their movement will beattributed to ‘m<strong>in</strong>or’ r<strong>and</strong>om causes <strong>and</strong>, as such, will be <strong>in</strong>terpretedas ‘functionless’ (mean<strong>in</strong>gless). If a particular view <strong>of</strong> the normalrange is widely held <strong>and</strong> firmly based, moreover, prices that movetowards the limits <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>ner range will tend to be brought backtowards the centre by speculative pressure (speculators sell<strong>in</strong>g nearthe upper limit <strong>and</strong> buy<strong>in</strong>g towards the lower limit).The second possibility is that prices may move <strong>in</strong>to the outerrange, perhaps as the consequence <strong>of</strong> the operation <strong>of</strong> ‘major’(permanent) forces. Whether or not such price movements are<strong>in</strong>terpreted as ‘mean<strong>in</strong>gful’, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Lachmann, depends onhow long the new prices are susta<strong>in</strong>ed. If prices sw<strong>in</strong>g back <strong>in</strong>to the185


JOCHEN RUNDE AND JÖRG BIBOW<strong>in</strong>ner range fairly quickly, this will confirm the conventional view <strong>of</strong>what is normal. However, if prices stay <strong>in</strong> the outer range, marketparticipants will gradually come to revise their notion <strong>of</strong> the normalprice. 5 This means that speculators will seek to buy at prices atwhich they would formerly have sold (<strong>and</strong> vice versa), suggest<strong>in</strong>gthat once the limits <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>ner range have been breached, pricemovements may be carried further by the very speculative pressuresthat formerly resisted them. F<strong>in</strong>ally, where prices move beyond thelimits <strong>of</strong> the outer range they become ‘unquestionably mean<strong>in</strong>gful’<strong>and</strong> carry a def<strong>in</strong>ite message that cannot be disregarded. The marketwill have to revise its views on what is normal: ‘It must now becomeclear to everybody that the hypothesis about the constellation <strong>of</strong>fundamental forces which formed the basis <strong>of</strong> our range structurehas been tested <strong>and</strong> failed’ (Lachmann 1978:32). But while thenegative message is clear enough, namely that the former hypothesis<strong>of</strong> what consisted as the normal is <strong>in</strong>valid, its positive content is lessso. The message still requires <strong>in</strong>terpretation, the soundness <strong>of</strong>which, accord<strong>in</strong>g to Lachmann, will depend on the <strong>in</strong>sight <strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>telligence <strong>of</strong> market participants.Divergent expectations <strong>and</strong> equity pricesWe are now <strong>in</strong> a position to say someth<strong>in</strong>g about Lachmann’sdist<strong>in</strong>ction between ‘convergent’ <strong>and</strong> ‘divergent’ expectations. Ifthe expectations <strong>in</strong> question were the po<strong>in</strong>t predictions <strong>of</strong> assetprices at some future date held by different <strong>in</strong>dividuals act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>the context <strong>of</strong> a social group, the dist<strong>in</strong>ction would seem to befairly straightforward. Convergent expectations would then bepo<strong>in</strong>t predictions that have a significant tendency to converge (orhave converged) on a unique value <strong>of</strong> the relevant variable overtime, perhaps because its value has been stable <strong>in</strong> the past.Divergent expectations, <strong>in</strong> contrast, would refer to the case <strong>in</strong>which <strong>in</strong>dividual po<strong>in</strong>t predictions <strong>of</strong> the value <strong>of</strong> some variableare not convergent, or display a tendency to diverge over sometime period.But we have seen that Lachmann rejects the assumption <strong>of</strong> po<strong>in</strong>texpectations <strong>in</strong> favour <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>terval-valued conception describedabove. Now it is possible to argue that the dist<strong>in</strong>ction betweenconvergent <strong>and</strong> divergent expectations still applies. Convergentexpectations might then be those the ‘normal’ <strong>in</strong>tervals <strong>of</strong> whichhave a tendency to co<strong>in</strong>cide more closely over time, or that doco<strong>in</strong>cide. But th<strong>in</strong>gs are not that simple. The trouble is that the wider186


EXPECTATIONS AND STOCK MARKET PRICESthe <strong>in</strong>terval regarded as ‘normal’ by different <strong>in</strong>dividuals, the morelikely it is that a significant portion <strong>of</strong> these normal <strong>in</strong>tervals willoverlap. In general, however, it seems that we would want toassociate wider ‘<strong>in</strong>ner’ <strong>in</strong>tervals with more uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, <strong>and</strong> hence,with less agreement about what the future price will be. So whetheror not the <strong>in</strong>terval-based price expectations <strong>of</strong> the members <strong>of</strong> somecommunity qualify as convergent will always be relative to someprior judgement <strong>of</strong> how narrow <strong>in</strong>tervals must be <strong>in</strong> order to beregarded as reflect<strong>in</strong>g ‘agreement’ about future prices. This willclearly not be a hard-<strong>and</strong>-fast matter. But it does suggest a way <strong>of</strong>characteris<strong>in</strong>g the two cases: <strong>in</strong> what follows ‘convergent’expectations or beliefs will refer to expectations held by themembers <strong>of</strong> a social group, where (i) the associated normal <strong>in</strong>tervalshave a tendency to co<strong>in</strong>cide more closely over time; <strong>and</strong> (ii) wherethis is not due to the <strong>in</strong>tervals widen<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>in</strong> general, convergentexpectations would be associated with relatively narrow normal<strong>in</strong>tervals that narrow further over time). ‘Divergent’ expectations orbeliefs, <strong>in</strong> contrast, will refer to expectations held by members <strong>of</strong> asocial group that are not convergent, or where (i) the degree <strong>of</strong>overlap between the associated normal <strong>in</strong>tervals has a tendency toreduce over time; <strong>and</strong> (ii) where this is not due primarily to such<strong>in</strong>tervals narrow<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>in</strong> general, divergent expectations would beassociated with relatively wide normal <strong>in</strong>tervals that may widenfurther over time).As we have already noted, the notion <strong>of</strong> divergent expectationscomes to the fore <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs on equity prices. The keytheme is that such prices reflect a balance <strong>of</strong> the heterogeneousbeliefs <strong>of</strong> market participants. 6 At a very general level, <strong>of</strong> course, thisis true enough. But the notion <strong>of</strong> a ‘bulls-bears’ equilibrium <strong>of</strong>oppos<strong>in</strong>g expectations is more complex than it at first appears, <strong>and</strong>not only because <strong>of</strong> the difficulties <strong>in</strong> arriv<strong>in</strong>g at a precisecategorisation <strong>of</strong> divergent expectations. In the first place, as weshall show, share prices reflect the ratio <strong>of</strong> holders <strong>of</strong> the share topotential holders <strong>in</strong> the market <strong>and</strong> generally do not correspond tothe ‘average expectation’ <strong>of</strong> the market. Second, expectations <strong>of</strong>future prices <strong>and</strong>/or prospective yields are only one <strong>of</strong> the th<strong>in</strong>gs thatdeterm<strong>in</strong>e the value <strong>of</strong> a share to <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>vestors, <strong>and</strong> whichthereby <strong>in</strong>fluence its market price. As Lachmann himself po<strong>in</strong>ts out,share values depend on how prevail<strong>in</strong>g prices are <strong>in</strong>terpreted. Otherimportant considerations <strong>in</strong>clude risk, 7 ambiguity, 8 <strong>and</strong> how actorsrespond to these. F<strong>in</strong>ally, there is the impact <strong>of</strong> all manner <strong>of</strong>uncerta<strong>in</strong>ties that need have no particular bear<strong>in</strong>g on the prospects187


JOCHEN RUNDE AND JÖRG BIBOW<strong>of</strong> the particular share itself, <strong>and</strong> which <strong>in</strong>troduce the more generalconsiderations <strong>of</strong> ‘market’ confidence <strong>and</strong> liquidity.These complexities suggest that the relation between divergentexpectations <strong>and</strong> equity prices must be qualified <strong>and</strong> extended. Wepropose to do so by focus<strong>in</strong>g on what we shall call the diversity <strong>of</strong>op<strong>in</strong>ion between market participants, not about future prices,yields, etc., but about the value they attach to any particular share.In particular we would like to focus on the fact that, at any po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong> time, there are likely to be marked differences between marketparticipants about what a share is currently worth to them <strong>in</strong>money terms whatever the source <strong>of</strong> these differences. The keydist<strong>in</strong>ction <strong>in</strong> what follows, then, is between the diversity <strong>of</strong>op<strong>in</strong>ion on the one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> divergent expectations or beliefs(about future prices, for example) on the other. The former term,to repeat, will refer to the money value that <strong>in</strong>vestors, potential orotherwise, attach to a share at some po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> time, the latter toexpectations about the future value <strong>of</strong> variables. Clearly, as<strong>in</strong>vestors’ valuations <strong>of</strong> a share are usually <strong>in</strong>formed by theirexpectations, divergent expectations will tend to lead to <strong>in</strong>creases<strong>in</strong> the diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion about that share. However, <strong>and</strong> as weshall see below, this need not always be the case.Diverse op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>and</strong> equity pricesAlthough the prices <strong>of</strong> shares traded on the Stock Exchange appearto be ‘cont<strong>in</strong>uously’ on the move, def<strong>in</strong>ite prices are determ<strong>in</strong>ed atdiscrete po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong> time. We shall call these ‘equilibrium’ prices,equilibrium <strong>in</strong> the sense that, at these po<strong>in</strong>ts, market participants(both holders <strong>and</strong> non-holders <strong>of</strong> the share <strong>in</strong> question) do not wantto change their position (Lachmann, 1976:60). In equilibrium, then,all exist<strong>in</strong>g shares are will<strong>in</strong>gly held at the prevail<strong>in</strong>g price. In whatfollows the term ‘average evaluation’ will refer to the average <strong>of</strong> thevalues the <strong>in</strong>dividual market participants attach to a particularshare at some po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> time, be they holders or non-holders. 9 As willbecome clearer below, this average evaluation will generally notcorrespond to the market price <strong>of</strong> the share. Optimists will bedef<strong>in</strong>ed as those <strong>in</strong>dividual market participants who value the shareat more than the average evaluation, pessimists as those who valueit at less. Not all optimists need be holders <strong>of</strong> the share.Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Miller (1977:1151) ‘the very concept <strong>of</strong>uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty implies that reasonable men may differ <strong>in</strong> theirforecasts’. It then follows that uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty will tend to lead to a188


EXPECTATIONS AND STOCK MARKET PRICESdiversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion about equity values. Two important features<strong>of</strong> his analysis are that it applies to a share with severely restrictedshort-sell<strong>in</strong>g opportunities <strong>and</strong> that the number <strong>of</strong> potentialholders <strong>of</strong> the share substantially outnumber the shares <strong>of</strong>fered bythe company. Miller s central result is as follows: only <strong>in</strong> thespecial case <strong>of</strong> the absence <strong>of</strong> any diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion about thevalue <strong>of</strong> the share will its market price correspond to the averageevaluation. In all other cases the share will tend to be held by thatproportion <strong>of</strong> potential <strong>in</strong>vestors who hold particularly optimisticviews about its value. 10 He derives this result from elementarydem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> supply analysis. The vertical axis measures the‘estimates <strong>of</strong> value’ per share made by heterogeneous <strong>in</strong>vestors, thehorizontal axis the number <strong>of</strong> shares dem<strong>and</strong>ed <strong>and</strong> supplied ateach estimate <strong>of</strong> value. 11 The equilibrium price is given as usual bythe <strong>in</strong>tersection <strong>of</strong> the dem<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> supply schedules. Withrestricted short sell<strong>in</strong>g, the supply curve is vertical at the number <strong>of</strong>shares outst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g. Furthermore, <strong>in</strong> the absence <strong>of</strong> diversity <strong>of</strong>op<strong>in</strong>ion, the dem<strong>and</strong> curve is horizontal. In this case, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> thiscase only, will the equilibrium price reflect the average <strong>of</strong> the<strong>in</strong>vestors’ evaluations. A diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion, <strong>in</strong> contrast, will bereflected <strong>in</strong> a downward slop<strong>in</strong>g dem<strong>and</strong> schedule, that is, thenumber <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestors will<strong>in</strong>g to hold the share will rise as the pricefalls. Here the price <strong>of</strong> the share will be higher than <strong>in</strong> the formercase, reflect<strong>in</strong>g the views <strong>of</strong> the more optimistic segment <strong>of</strong> themarket rather than the average evaluation. The po<strong>in</strong>t is that theslope <strong>of</strong> the dem<strong>and</strong> curve depends on the diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion. Thegreater the prevail<strong>in</strong>g uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, <strong>and</strong> hence the greater thediversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion about the value <strong>of</strong> the share (<strong>and</strong> the steeperthe dem<strong>and</strong> curve), the higher its price will be.What can be said about the impact <strong>of</strong> changes <strong>in</strong> the diversity <strong>of</strong>op<strong>in</strong>ion on the price <strong>of</strong> a share? First, we must stress that theconception <strong>of</strong> an ‘equilibrium’ share price implies noth<strong>in</strong>g about itsstability. In the present sett<strong>in</strong>g the price <strong>of</strong> the share will alterwhenever its supply, the dem<strong>and</strong> for it, or both, change. 12 A change<strong>in</strong> supply (a shift <strong>of</strong> the vertical supply curve) will occur as the result<strong>of</strong> the company issu<strong>in</strong>g new shares or buy<strong>in</strong>g back exist<strong>in</strong>g ones,<strong>and</strong> the effect on the price <strong>of</strong> such activity will be greater the greaterthe diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>in</strong> the market. 13 But this is probably the lessimportant case <strong>and</strong> we shall concentrate on the dem<strong>and</strong> for theshare, tak<strong>in</strong>g its supply as given. We have already seen that the sharewill tend to be more ‘overpriced’ relative to the average evaluationthe higher the diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>in</strong> the market. The question then189


JOCHEN RUNDE AND JÖRG BIBOWis, start<strong>in</strong>g from a given state <strong>of</strong> diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>in</strong> the market,what the impact <strong>of</strong> new <strong>in</strong>formation will be.There are a number <strong>of</strong> possibilities. First, new <strong>in</strong>formation mayreduce the diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion about its value. 14 The optimistsbecome less optimistic <strong>and</strong> the pessimists less pessimistic, so that, <strong>in</strong>the aggregate, the share price comes closer to the averageevaluation. In graphical terms, the dem<strong>and</strong> curve would flatten out<strong>and</strong> the price <strong>of</strong> the share would fall. S<strong>in</strong>ce the share can only be heldby a small proportion <strong>of</strong> the optimistic <strong>in</strong>vestors, it is the sell<strong>in</strong>gpressure <strong>of</strong> former optimists who have become less optimistic thatleads the price to fall until it is aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> l<strong>in</strong>e with their new op<strong>in</strong>ionsabout what the share is worth (clearly this <strong>in</strong>cludes the possibilitythat some former non-holders change their m<strong>in</strong>ds sufficiently tobecome holders). Conversely, it is possible that new <strong>in</strong>formationmay lead to an <strong>in</strong>crease <strong>in</strong> the diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>in</strong> the market. Inthis case, by parallel reason<strong>in</strong>g, the dem<strong>and</strong> schedule steepens <strong>and</strong>the price rises.A second possibility is that the new <strong>in</strong>formation may leadoptimists to become more (less) optimistic <strong>and</strong> pessimists to becomeless (more) pessimistic. In the limit<strong>in</strong>g case <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>vestors’op<strong>in</strong>ions about the value <strong>of</strong> the share would neither diverge fromnor converge towards the average evaluation, but the averageevaluation would itself shift. Recall that the price is alwaysdeterm<strong>in</strong>ed by the optimists <strong>in</strong> the market <strong>and</strong> will always exceedthe average evaluation by a greater or lesser amount. A thirdpossibility is that the new <strong>in</strong>formation may affect neither the slopenor the position <strong>of</strong> the dem<strong>and</strong> schedule <strong>and</strong> hence leave the priceunaffected, but that some trad<strong>in</strong>g nevertheless occurs. Such trad<strong>in</strong>gwill either be between holders who want to change the amount <strong>of</strong>the share that they hold <strong>in</strong> their portfolio or between holders <strong>and</strong>non-holders who have changed camps. Clearly both sorts <strong>of</strong> tradesmay also occur <strong>in</strong> the cases already mentioned above. 15Miller mentions a fourth channel through which new<strong>in</strong>formation may impact on price by affect<strong>in</strong>g the diversity <strong>of</strong>op<strong>in</strong>ion, the possibility that new <strong>in</strong>formation may affect the number<strong>of</strong> potential <strong>in</strong>vestors who are pay<strong>in</strong>g attention to the relevant share.This possibility is related to the number <strong>of</strong> potential <strong>in</strong>vestorsexceed<strong>in</strong>g the number <strong>of</strong> shares available, <strong>and</strong> draws attention tothe fact that <strong>in</strong>formation is not without cost. The new <strong>in</strong>formationmay then affect the ‘overhang’ <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestors over the number <strong>of</strong>shares, thereby possibly affect<strong>in</strong>g the diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>and</strong>,accord<strong>in</strong>gly, the share price.190


EXPECTATIONS AND STOCK MARKET PRICESThus far we have said noth<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>vestors’attitudes towards risk. Miller makes the novel po<strong>in</strong>t that <strong>in</strong> thesituation depicted above even risk-neutral <strong>in</strong>vestors have a reason toemploy some k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> ‘risk premium’, or better, ‘uncerta<strong>in</strong>typremium’. For risk-neutral <strong>in</strong>vestors who underst<strong>and</strong> the impact <strong>of</strong>the diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion on the price <strong>of</strong> shares would aim to discountthe value <strong>of</strong> the share <strong>in</strong> order to avoid ex post disappo<strong>in</strong>tment. If all<strong>in</strong>vestors were risk neutral <strong>and</strong> acted <strong>in</strong> this way, share prices wouldbe brought <strong>in</strong>to l<strong>in</strong>e with the hypothetical average evaluation (<strong>and</strong> ifthe average evaluation were ‘correct’ then neither over- nor under<strong>in</strong>vestmentwould occur). To be sure, the share would still be held bythose who are most optimistic about its value. But given that<strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>vestors do not know the average evaluation, they mustall guess by how much they must discount the price <strong>of</strong> the share tocompensate for the estimated bias <strong>in</strong> the price that results from theirbehaviour <strong>in</strong> the aggregate.This br<strong>in</strong>gs us to the question <strong>of</strong> risk-averse behaviour. AsLachmann argues, <strong>in</strong> situations <strong>of</strong> uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty, expectations willgenerally not take the form <strong>of</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t predictions. We have alreadysuggested that expectations with relatively wider <strong>in</strong>ner <strong>in</strong>tervalsmight be regarded as relatively more risky, from the perspective <strong>of</strong>the <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>vestor. Differences <strong>in</strong> risk<strong>in</strong>ess will generally bereflected <strong>in</strong> differences <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestors’ valuations <strong>of</strong> shares, the normalcase be<strong>in</strong>g that risk-averse actors discount projects that <strong>in</strong>volvegreater risk. What we have already said about the complexity <strong>of</strong> therelation between expectations <strong>and</strong> the price <strong>of</strong> a share, now seen toreflect rough judgement <strong>of</strong> <strong>and</strong> adjustment for risk, is given furtherforce. The proportion <strong>of</strong> risk averters <strong>and</strong> risk lovers <strong>in</strong> marketsegments may also change, moreover, aga<strong>in</strong> lead<strong>in</strong>g to changes <strong>in</strong>the diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion. 16Yet the picture is still far from complete. In the first place, it isimportant to dist<strong>in</strong>guish between what are generally regarded as‘blue chips’ on the one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> ‘non-blue chips’ as cover<strong>in</strong>g therest on the other. Miller’s framework seems to be most relevant forthe non-blue-chip category, s<strong>in</strong>ce short sell<strong>in</strong>g opportunities donormally exist <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> blue chips. Moreover, such shares arecarefully watched by large numbers <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancial analysts with vastf<strong>in</strong>ancial resources at their comm<strong>and</strong>. This is not to suggest that themarkets <strong>in</strong> such shares will not show a diversity <strong>in</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion, but thatthe possible impact <strong>of</strong> new <strong>in</strong>formation on the number <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestorsanalys<strong>in</strong>g the share relative to the number <strong>of</strong> shares outst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>gappears to be much less relevant <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> blue chips, <strong>in</strong>191


JOCHEN RUNDE AND JÖRG BIBOWparticular when the possibility <strong>of</strong> short sell<strong>in</strong>g is taken <strong>in</strong>to account.It appears, then, that Miller’s framework provides a possibleexplanation <strong>of</strong> the relative pric<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> non-blue chips on the oneh<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> blue chips <strong>and</strong> bonds on the other (bonds serve as abenchmark <strong>in</strong> Miller’s portfolio <strong>in</strong>vestment decision).This br<strong>in</strong>gs us to the temporal features <strong>of</strong> Miller’s analysis <strong>and</strong>, <strong>in</strong>particular, that his share-issu<strong>in</strong>g company has a very short life with adef<strong>in</strong>ite term<strong>in</strong>al date at which assets are liquidated. In practice, <strong>of</strong>course, equity <strong>in</strong>vestment differs from this <strong>in</strong> two important ways.In the first place, shares have an <strong>in</strong>def<strong>in</strong>ite life-expectation. Andsecond, shares are traded on liquid securities markets, <strong>in</strong>stitutionsthat serve to provide liquidity to the (portfolio) <strong>in</strong>vestor. These<strong>in</strong>stitutional factors have wide-rang<strong>in</strong>g implications. First <strong>of</strong>f, theypermit the <strong>in</strong>vestment horizon <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dividual portfolio <strong>in</strong>vestor todepart from the life span <strong>of</strong> the particular company <strong>in</strong>volved. Thetype <strong>of</strong> commitment that the portfolio <strong>in</strong>vestor enters <strong>in</strong>to whenbuy<strong>in</strong>g shares is therefore very different from the range <strong>of</strong>commitments that the management <strong>of</strong> the firm is sett<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>in</strong> orderto generate the cash flows that represent what the portfolio <strong>in</strong>vestoris ultimately <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong>. Whereas the firm is to some extent stuckwith its physical capital once this has been acquired <strong>and</strong>/orproduced (<strong>and</strong> has many other commitments that cannot be easilydissolved), <strong>in</strong>vestment <strong>in</strong> equities is liquid from the viewpo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> the<strong>in</strong>vestor <strong>and</strong> may be dissolved at any time. It follows that theportfolio <strong>in</strong>vestor is generally not concerned with the proceeds <strong>of</strong>liquidat<strong>in</strong>g the company, but with the possible proceeds <strong>of</strong> sell<strong>in</strong>ghis or her stake <strong>in</strong> the company as an ongo<strong>in</strong>g concern. And this <strong>in</strong>turn means that the <strong>in</strong>vestor also has to take <strong>in</strong>to account what thelikely price <strong>of</strong> the share will be <strong>in</strong> the future.An important consequence <strong>of</strong> all this is that market participantsmay rationally show little concern with attempt<strong>in</strong>g to assess the‘real’ prospects <strong>of</strong> the share. Instead they might try to anticipatehow new <strong>in</strong>formation may affect other <strong>in</strong>vestors’ evaluations <strong>of</strong> theshare, <strong>and</strong> what the likely effect on the price will be. It is <strong>of</strong> courseKeynes, more than anyone else, who stresses that securities marketsorganised to provide liquidity provide an <strong>in</strong>centive—undesirablefrom the social po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> view—for <strong>in</strong>vestors to focus less on thefactors that govern the yield <strong>of</strong> the real <strong>in</strong>vestment over its wholelife, than on anticipat<strong>in</strong>g changes <strong>in</strong> the share price before themarket. Keynes’s famous beauty contest parable describes theoutcome <strong>of</strong> behaviour directed at anticipat<strong>in</strong>g ‘what averageop<strong>in</strong>ion expects the average op<strong>in</strong>ion to be’. The notion <strong>of</strong> the192


EXPECTATIONS AND STOCK MARKET PRICES‘average evaluation’, far from reflect<strong>in</strong>g the wisdom <strong>of</strong> the market,then takes on an entirely different hue. Keynes refers to securitiesprices so determ<strong>in</strong>ed as the ‘conventional valuation’. In situations <strong>in</strong>which everyone is try<strong>in</strong>g to anticipate the anticipations <strong>of</strong> others,new <strong>in</strong>formation, which might have precious little to do with thereal prospects <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>vestment, may cause violent changes <strong>in</strong> theconventional valuation.We have taken Miller’s framework as a general start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong>our discussion. How does what we have said so far relate toLachmann’s notion <strong>of</strong> equity prices emerg<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>of</strong> a balance <strong>of</strong>divergent (bulls’ <strong>and</strong> bears’) expectations? Clearly we cannot domuch more than scratch the surface <strong>of</strong> the issue <strong>in</strong> the spaceavailable. Accord<strong>in</strong>gly, we shall simply remark on some <strong>of</strong> therelevant issues, draw<strong>in</strong>g on Keynes’s analysis <strong>of</strong> the ‘two views’ or‘bull-bear’ position <strong>in</strong> his Treatise on Money (1971) <strong>and</strong> hisconcepts <strong>of</strong> the own rate <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>and</strong> ‘liquidity premium’ <strong>in</strong> theGeneral Theory (1973). We beg<strong>in</strong> with <strong>in</strong>vestors’ beliefs aboutfuture price movements, keep<strong>in</strong>g questions about the diversity <strong>of</strong>op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>in</strong> the background. We then briefly return to the diversity <strong>of</strong>op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>in</strong> the section on own rates <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest.The bull-bear positionKeynes def<strong>in</strong>es a ‘bear’ as one ‘who prefers at the moment to avoidsecurities <strong>and</strong> lend cash, <strong>and</strong> correspond<strong>in</strong>gly a “bull” {as} one whoprefers to hold securities <strong>and</strong> to borrow cash—the formeranticipat<strong>in</strong>g that securities will fall <strong>in</strong> cash value <strong>and</strong> the latter thatthey will rise’ (Keynes 1971:224). In his Treatise on Money, theportfolio decision is simplified to a choice between bank deposits (ormore precisely, ‘sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits’) <strong>and</strong> securities (where no furtherdist<strong>in</strong>ction is made between shares <strong>and</strong> bonds). As <strong>in</strong> the laterGeneral Theory (Keynes 1973), the portfolio decision is not an ‘allor noth<strong>in</strong>g’ choice. Rather, <strong>in</strong>vestors tend to hold a proportion <strong>of</strong>their wealth <strong>in</strong> the form <strong>of</strong> ‘sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits A, which are not highlyunstable over the short period. The bear position shows up <strong>in</strong> theform <strong>of</strong> the proportion <strong>of</strong> wealth held <strong>in</strong> ‘sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits B’, whichare unstable. However, as Keynes po<strong>in</strong>ts out, bearish beliefs do notnecessarily have to be expressed through the bank<strong>in</strong>g system, butmay be expressed outside it (through direct lend<strong>in</strong>g to the moneymarket or the Stock Exchange, for <strong>in</strong>stance, or through shortsell<strong>in</strong>g). The po<strong>in</strong>t to note here is that Keynes allows bearish beliefsto be reflected <strong>in</strong> changes <strong>in</strong> the size <strong>and</strong> possibly the composition <strong>of</strong>193


JOCHEN RUNDE AND JÖRG BIBOWthe bank<strong>in</strong>g system s balance sheet. (In the General Theory, <strong>in</strong>contrast, all <strong>in</strong>stitutional detail is suppressed <strong>and</strong> the whole effect <strong>of</strong>changes <strong>in</strong> beliefs is necessarily on security prices, given that thestock <strong>of</strong> money, that is the size <strong>of</strong> the bank<strong>in</strong>g system s balancesheet, is constant by assumption.)To beg<strong>in</strong> with, <strong>in</strong> the Treatise on Money bearish views on the part<strong>of</strong> the public may have no effect on securities prices where theseviews are compensated by the bank<strong>in</strong>g system tak<strong>in</strong>g the oppositeview <strong>and</strong> buy<strong>in</strong>g the securities. An alternative possible case <strong>of</strong>divergent beliefs mentioned by Keynes occurs when ‘two views’develop with<strong>in</strong> the public. Whilst <strong>in</strong> the former case the bank<strong>in</strong>gsystem <strong>and</strong> the public hold oppos<strong>in</strong>g views, <strong>and</strong> the effect <strong>of</strong> a change<strong>in</strong> beliefs about future prices may be reflected partly <strong>in</strong> security prices<strong>and</strong> partly <strong>in</strong> changes <strong>in</strong> the size <strong>of</strong> the bank<strong>in</strong>g system’s balancesheet, <strong>in</strong> the latter case changes <strong>in</strong> the size <strong>of</strong> the bank<strong>in</strong>g system’sbalance sheet do not necessarily require the bank<strong>in</strong>g system to take aparticular view. Rather it may simply provide additional short-termadvances to the ‘bulls’ who buy securities from the ‘bears’ who endup hold<strong>in</strong>g more ‘sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits B’. Keynes f<strong>in</strong>ds that both ‘bull’<strong>and</strong> ‘bear’ markets may occur with either convergent or divergentexpectations about future prices. For <strong>in</strong>stance, <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> a bullmarket with convergent expectations, bears are clos<strong>in</strong>g their positionson a ris<strong>in</strong>g market <strong>and</strong> the volume <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gs deposits B falls. In abull market with divergent expectations, <strong>in</strong> contrast, bears may be<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g their positions on a ris<strong>in</strong>g market. To repeat, the size <strong>of</strong>the bank<strong>in</strong>g system’s balance sheet (<strong>and</strong> the amount <strong>of</strong> sav<strong>in</strong>gsdeposits B provided) may change either because the bank<strong>in</strong>g systemitself is tak<strong>in</strong>g a view on securities prices or because it decides t<strong>of</strong>acilitate the chang<strong>in</strong>g degree <strong>of</strong> divergence <strong>of</strong> beliefs with<strong>in</strong> the public,where the public may also take recourse to channels outside thebank<strong>in</strong>g system.Keynes (1971:225) ventures that both the volume <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ancialtransactions <strong>and</strong> the size <strong>of</strong> bear positions are ‘likely to bephenomena <strong>of</strong> rapidly chang<strong>in</strong>g prices rather than <strong>of</strong> an absolutelyhigh or low level’. The volatility <strong>of</strong> prices, for <strong>in</strong>stance, may reflectcontradictory <strong>in</strong>formation that becomes available <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>creases thediversity <strong>of</strong> beliefs about future prices. In addition, Keynes mentionsthe possibility <strong>of</strong> speculative excesses lead<strong>in</strong>g to what we would nowcall ‘bubbles’. He f<strong>in</strong>ds that such a development may be related <strong>in</strong> itsf<strong>in</strong>al stage to beliefs about future prices that have diverged widely,with abrupt falls <strong>in</strong> security prices resolv<strong>in</strong>g the tension betweenoppos<strong>in</strong>g views.194


EXPECTATIONS AND STOCK MARKET PRICESKeynes’s ‘bull-bear’ analysis goes beyond Miller’s <strong>in</strong> that itpermits short sell<strong>in</strong>g 17 <strong>and</strong> takes <strong>in</strong>to account the ‘conventional’behaviour <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestors on markets that have been organised toprovide liquidity. Furthermore, whereas Miller focuses on a s<strong>in</strong>gle(non-blue chip) share, Keynes’s general equilibrium analysis ismeant to expla<strong>in</strong> the core <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest rates <strong>in</strong> general. In its simplifiedform <strong>in</strong> the General Theory, the amount <strong>of</strong> liquidity is taken as given<strong>and</strong> securities prices alone (bonds <strong>and</strong> blue chip shares) have toadjust to br<strong>in</strong>g forth a bear position <strong>of</strong> equal <strong>and</strong> unchanged size.The po<strong>in</strong>t to note is that although these prices represent a crucialsegment <strong>of</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> prices for exist<strong>in</strong>g assets, theydo not reveal anyth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> particular about the differentconsiderations <strong>and</strong> beliefs that affect <strong>in</strong>vestors’ <strong>in</strong>dividualvaluations. Keynes’s notion <strong>of</strong> ‘own rates <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest’ sheds somelight on these matters, <strong>and</strong> it is to this which we now turn.Own rates <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest <strong>and</strong> the liquidity premiumKeynes def<strong>in</strong>es the total return on any asset measured <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong>itself as the sum <strong>of</strong> q-c+l, where q is the risk-adjusted yield, c thecarry<strong>in</strong>g cost <strong>and</strong> l the liquidity premium. The liquidity premium onan asset is not a pecuniary return, but a reflection <strong>of</strong> the potentialconvenience or security that the power <strong>of</strong> disposal over that assetdur<strong>in</strong>g some period <strong>of</strong>fers (Keynes 1973:226). To compare thereturns <strong>of</strong> different assets, changes <strong>in</strong> their relative values a oversome period must also be considered, <strong>and</strong>, expressed <strong>in</strong> somecommon measure, the total return on an asset is then the sum <strong>of</strong> q-c+l+a. An overall portfolio equilibrium requires, first, that allexist<strong>in</strong>g assets are held by someone <strong>and</strong>, second, that every portfolio<strong>in</strong>vestor is happy with the composition <strong>of</strong> his or her portfolio at thecurrent structure <strong>of</strong> asset prices. Clearly, such an equilibrium iscompatible with <strong>in</strong>vestors hold<strong>in</strong>g different beliefs about thestructure <strong>of</strong> relative returns <strong>and</strong> their components on different k<strong>in</strong>ds<strong>of</strong> assets.Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Keynes, the crucial po<strong>in</strong>t is that money, be<strong>in</strong>gliquid par excellence, bears the highest liquidity premium <strong>and</strong>consequently st<strong>and</strong>s at the core <strong>of</strong> the structure <strong>of</strong> own rates. Thedifference between the liquidity premium attach<strong>in</strong>g to anyparticular asset relative to money must be compensated by eitheran excess <strong>in</strong> the net yield q-c over money, by its expected rate <strong>of</strong>appreciation a, or both. Aga<strong>in</strong>, <strong>in</strong>vestors may differ <strong>in</strong> theirestimates <strong>of</strong> both these terms, as they may differ <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> their195


JOCHEN RUNDE AND JÖRG BIBOWassessments <strong>of</strong> the risk attach<strong>in</strong>g to those estimates <strong>and</strong> theirattitudes towards risk. This means that heterogeneous <strong>in</strong>vestorsmay attach the same monetary value to an asset on the basis <strong>of</strong>quite different comb<strong>in</strong>ations (<strong>and</strong> values) <strong>of</strong> the terms that enter<strong>in</strong>to their calculations. As before, no general statement can bemade about how new <strong>in</strong>formation might affect asset prices. Takethe special case <strong>of</strong> trad<strong>in</strong>g at unchanged prices, for <strong>in</strong>stance, whichmay occur when <strong>in</strong>vestors assess new <strong>in</strong>formation differently.These differences may impact on any <strong>of</strong> the values <strong>of</strong> the termsenter<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the own rates calculus, <strong>and</strong> beliefs (<strong>and</strong> attitudes)may be diverg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> one respect <strong>and</strong> converg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> another. In theextreme case, prices may change without any transactions tak<strong>in</strong>gplace at all (which does not imply that beliefs about any <strong>of</strong> therelevant terms rema<strong>in</strong> unchanged).But an additional complexity has now entered. Keynes relates theliquidity premium to the notion <strong>of</strong> confidence, uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty or doubtabout the general economic climate at the systemic level that mayhave no particular connection with the prospects <strong>of</strong> any particularasset concerned. Changes <strong>in</strong> the state <strong>of</strong> confidence will, he argues,be reflected <strong>in</strong> the size <strong>of</strong> the liquidity premium attach<strong>in</strong>g to money<strong>and</strong> other relatively liquid assets (Bibow 1998). While <strong>in</strong>vestors mayhave very different views on the relative liquidity premia ondifferent types <strong>of</strong> assets, <strong>and</strong> may change their views <strong>in</strong> differentways <strong>in</strong> the light <strong>of</strong> new <strong>in</strong>formation <strong>in</strong> this respect as well, what hecalls a ‘crisis <strong>of</strong> confidence’ will be characterised by a general ‘flight<strong>in</strong>to liquidity’. Aga<strong>in</strong>, changes <strong>in</strong> the state <strong>of</strong> confidence, with theirassociated impact on the relative liquidity premiums attach<strong>in</strong>g todifferent k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> assets, may occur with or without changes <strong>in</strong>beliefs <strong>in</strong> respect <strong>of</strong> any <strong>of</strong> the other elements enter<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to the ownrates <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest calculus.ConclusionWe have attempted to provide an <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> Lachmann’sdist<strong>in</strong>ction between convergent <strong>and</strong> divergent expectations,build<strong>in</strong>g on his conception <strong>of</strong> expectations as imag<strong>in</strong>ed price<strong>in</strong>tervals. This <strong>in</strong>terpretation was then used <strong>in</strong> a discussion <strong>of</strong> theidea that equity prices emerge out <strong>of</strong> a ‘balance’ <strong>of</strong> divergentexpectations. Two pr<strong>in</strong>cipal complications were <strong>in</strong>troduced, theimpact on the price <strong>of</strong> equities <strong>of</strong> their effective supply relative tothe number <strong>of</strong> market participants (holders <strong>and</strong> non-holders)valu<strong>in</strong>g them, <strong>and</strong> that the value that market participants attach to196


EXPECTATIONS AND STOCK MARKET PRICESequities generally depends on considerations over <strong>and</strong> aboveanticipated future prices <strong>and</strong>/or yields.These factors make it difficult to say much that is def<strong>in</strong>ite aboutthe relation between expectations <strong>and</strong> the course <strong>of</strong> equity prices. Infact, on the argument we have been develop<strong>in</strong>g, it is possible thatdivergent expectations about the future price <strong>of</strong> a share may lead toa correspond<strong>in</strong>g reduction <strong>in</strong> the diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion about its‘correct’ value (if, for example, the impact <strong>of</strong> such expectations onequity valuations are <strong>of</strong>fset by changes <strong>in</strong> perceptions <strong>of</strong>, <strong>and</strong>attitudes towards, risk <strong>and</strong> ambiguity, liquidity, confidence <strong>and</strong> soon). We have accord<strong>in</strong>gly proposed that attention be directed athow heterogeneous market participants value a share, beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>gwith the situation <strong>in</strong> which both holders <strong>and</strong> non-holders arecontent with their current position on that share. This provides asensible po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>of</strong> entry for the explanation <strong>of</strong> equity prices, that is,for an analysis that proceeds by beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g with exist<strong>in</strong>g equityprices <strong>and</strong> spell<strong>in</strong>g out the possible factors that give rise to <strong>and</strong>govern them. 18 One <strong>of</strong> these factors, clearly an important <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>tendom<strong>in</strong>ant one, is the divergence <strong>of</strong> expectations <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’ssense. We have merely taken the opportunity to draw attention to afew more.Notes1 Lachmann (1977:72). Clearly the def<strong>in</strong>iteness, scope <strong>and</strong> detail <strong>of</strong> the‘mental pictures’ he has <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d will depend on the situation <strong>in</strong> whichthey are arrived at, the relative importance <strong>of</strong> the ‘plan’ <strong>in</strong> the actor’sscheme <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs, as well as the <strong>in</strong>formation available to <strong>and</strong> thepowers <strong>of</strong> imag<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> the actor concerned. In the context <strong>of</strong> stockmarket transactions, <strong>and</strong> as the passage quoted <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>troductionsuggests, the focus <strong>of</strong> attention will generally be on the return onequities, which depend on estimates <strong>and</strong> assessments <strong>of</strong> the possiblefactors that may affect the future flow <strong>of</strong> dividends <strong>and</strong> future prices.2 Lachmann is curiously reticent as regards the nature <strong>and</strong> structure <strong>of</strong>the expectations he has <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d even <strong>in</strong> his important essay on ‘Therole <strong>of</strong> expectations <strong>in</strong> economics as a social science’ (repr<strong>in</strong>ted <strong>in</strong>Lachmann 1977).3 Lachmann does not specify what he means by ‘forces’. We shallsubstitute the term ‘tendency’ where this will be understood as a causalpower that would br<strong>in</strong>g about some specified phenomenon undercerta<strong>in</strong> conditions (Lawson 1994a).4 Lachmann considers <strong>and</strong> rejects the ma<strong>in</strong> alternatives then available:Shackles (1949) theory <strong>of</strong> ‘potential surprise’ <strong>and</strong> the practice <strong>of</strong>reduc<strong>in</strong>g well-def<strong>in</strong>ed probability distributions to certa<strong>in</strong>tyequivalents. He would therefore presumably also reject the modern197


JOCHEN RUNDE AND JÖRG BIBOWversion <strong>of</strong> the certa<strong>in</strong>ty equivalent assumption: the practice <strong>of</strong> reduc<strong>in</strong>gexpectations to the expected value <strong>of</strong> some utility function, where thebeliefs about future ‘states <strong>of</strong> the world’ are represented by aconditional probability measure that corresponds either to anobjective probability law (rational expectations) or to a subjectiveprobability measure.5 Lachmann po<strong>in</strong>ts out that prices that move <strong>in</strong>to the outer range willattract the attention <strong>of</strong> the ‘more thoughtful’ market operators:The mere fact that <strong>in</strong> spite <strong>of</strong> heavy ‘speculative’ pressureencountered near the limits <strong>of</strong> the <strong>in</strong>ner range, <strong>and</strong> engenderedby <strong>in</strong>elastic expectations <strong>and</strong> the sense <strong>of</strong> the ‘normality’ <strong>of</strong> the<strong>in</strong>ner range, price could pass these limits at all is a po<strong>in</strong>ter <strong>of</strong> thestrength <strong>of</strong> the forces which must have carried it past suchformidable obstacles. Such a move can hardly be due to r<strong>and</strong>omcauses.(Lachmann 1978:31)6 For example:To coord<strong>in</strong>ate bullish <strong>and</strong> bearish expectations is, as Keynesshowed, the economic function <strong>of</strong> the Stock Exchange <strong>and</strong> <strong>of</strong>asset markets <strong>in</strong> general. This is achieved because <strong>in</strong> suchmarkets the price will move until the whole market is divided<strong>in</strong>to equal halves <strong>of</strong> bulls <strong>and</strong> bears. In this way divergentexpectations are cast <strong>in</strong>to a coherent pattern <strong>and</strong> a measure <strong>of</strong>coord<strong>in</strong>ation is accomplished.(Lachmann 1976:59)7 Lachmann does not say anyth<strong>in</strong>g about how the actor may respond todifferences <strong>in</strong> the width <strong>of</strong> the imag<strong>in</strong>ed price <strong>in</strong>tervals (the analogue,<strong>in</strong> the present context, to the actor’s attitude towards risk <strong>in</strong> expectedutility theory). In general it seems that shares that are perceived asmore risky <strong>in</strong> the present sense will be discounted relative to those thatare perceived as less risky, that is, that actors are generally risk averse.8 The boundary between the <strong>in</strong>ner <strong>and</strong> outer <strong>in</strong>tervals is seldom likely tobe a hard-<strong>and</strong>-fast one, for example, <strong>and</strong> is likely to be more or lessvague at different times. As <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> differences <strong>in</strong> perceived risk<strong>and</strong> risk aversion, differences <strong>in</strong> ambiguity <strong>and</strong> attitudes to ambiguitymay affect the value <strong>in</strong>vestors attach to shares. It is <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g to note <strong>in</strong>this context that Shackle’s theory <strong>of</strong> potential surprise may be regardedas a generalisation <strong>of</strong> the Practical Range approach. The difference isthat on Shackle’s theory there is a cont<strong>in</strong>uous gradation <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tervals, theouter limits <strong>of</strong> each bear<strong>in</strong>g some degree <strong>of</strong> ‘potential surprise’.9 The average evaluation need not be the ‘correct’ evaluation <strong>in</strong> the sense<strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g that which corresponds to the ‘fundamentals’ <strong>of</strong> the economy(if such th<strong>in</strong>gs as fundamentals exist).10 This is no more than the familiar ‘w<strong>in</strong>ner’s curse’, an <strong>in</strong>formaldiscussion <strong>of</strong> which appears <strong>in</strong> Kreps (1990:83–7).11 Putt<strong>in</strong>g it another way, the share will always be held by a smallfraction <strong>of</strong> the potential <strong>in</strong>vestors <strong>in</strong> the market. Miller simplifies the198


EXPECTATIONS AND STOCK MARKET PRICESanalysis by limit<strong>in</strong>g each <strong>in</strong>vestor to one share, thereby avoid<strong>in</strong>gquestions about the relative size <strong>of</strong> each <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong>vestor’s hold<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong> the share. This assumption does not substantially affect theargument.12 Save for a few special cases discussed below.13 Short sell<strong>in</strong>g would <strong>of</strong> course also shift the supply curve to the right by<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g the effective supply <strong>of</strong> the share.14 This may <strong>of</strong>ten, but not necessarily, be the consequence <strong>of</strong> expectationsabout future prices or yields converg<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> Lachmann’s sense (see thesection on own rates <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest below).15 In fact this is a limit<strong>in</strong>g case <strong>in</strong> which trade occurs at an unchangedprice <strong>and</strong> the diversity <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion, though chang<strong>in</strong>g at the <strong>in</strong>dividuallevel, is neither decreas<strong>in</strong>g nor <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the aggregate. Moregenerally, trad<strong>in</strong>g at an unchanged price could also occur <strong>in</strong> all cases<strong>in</strong> which the slope <strong>and</strong> the position <strong>of</strong> the dem<strong>and</strong> curve change <strong>in</strong> anexactly <strong>of</strong>fsett<strong>in</strong>g way. This <strong>in</strong>cludes cases where op<strong>in</strong>ion is eitherconverg<strong>in</strong>g (the dem<strong>and</strong> curve flatten<strong>in</strong>g out while shift<strong>in</strong>g upwards)or diverg<strong>in</strong>g (the dem<strong>and</strong> curve steepen<strong>in</strong>g while shift<strong>in</strong>gdownwards).16 Much <strong>of</strong> what we have said about risk <strong>and</strong> risk aversion applies <strong>in</strong> thesame way <strong>in</strong> the case <strong>of</strong> ambiguity.17 Modern futures <strong>and</strong> options exchanges can be subsumed withoutmuch difficulty.18 Readers familiar with the emerg<strong>in</strong>g literature on Critical Realism willrecognise this as an example <strong>of</strong> the retroductive mode <strong>of</strong> argument thatit advocates (see Lawson 1994b).ReferencesBibow, J. (1998) ‘On Keynesian theories <strong>of</strong> liquidity preference’, TheManchester School, 66:238–73.Keynes, J.M. (1971) Treatise on Money, vol. 1. The Collected Writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong>John Maynard Keynes, vol. V, London: Macmillan.——(1973) The General Theory. The Collected Writ<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>of</strong> John MaynardKeynes, vol. VII, London: Macmillan.Kreps, D.M. (1990) Game Theory <strong>and</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Modell<strong>in</strong>g, Oxford: TheClarendon Press.Lachmann, L.M. (1976) ‘From Mises to Shackle: an essay on Austrianeconomics <strong>and</strong> the Kaleidic Society’ , Journal <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Literature,14: 54–62.——(1977) Capital, Expectations, <strong>and</strong> the Market Process, Kansas City:Sheed Andrews <strong>and</strong> McMeel, Inc.——(1978) Capital <strong>and</strong> Its Structure, 2nd edn, Kansas City: SheedAndrews<strong>and</strong> McMeel, Inc. (1st edn 1956).Lange, O. (1944) Price Flexibility <strong>and</strong> Employment, Bloom<strong>in</strong>gton:Pr<strong>in</strong>cipia Press.Lawson, T. (1994a) ‘Tendencies’, unpublished manuscript, Cambridge:Cambridge University.199


JOCHEN RUNDE AND JÖRG BIBOW——(1994b) ‘A realist theory for economies’, <strong>in</strong> R.E.Backhouse (ed.) NewDirections <strong>in</strong> <strong>Economic</strong> Methodology, London: Routledge, pp. 257–85.Miller, E.M. (1977) ‘Risk, uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty <strong>and</strong> divergence <strong>of</strong> op<strong>in</strong>ion’, TheJournal <strong>of</strong> F<strong>in</strong>ance, 32:1151–68.Shackle, G.L.S. (1949) Expectations <strong>in</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s, Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.200


INDEXaction: <strong>in</strong>dividual 32–3, 38–9,55–6, 136, 144; mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> 35,52–4; praxeological theory <strong>of</strong> 8,32, 33, 35–9, 41, 43–5, 87, 94,97, 147; see also human actionactive m<strong>in</strong>ds, subjectivism <strong>of</strong> 4–5,8, 61–77; see also radicalsubjectivismactual underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g 97agents 22, 26, 109; <strong>in</strong>dividual(behaviour) 127–30, 134,136–7, 146; preferences 5, 21,63, 126, 164Albrow, M. 52ambiguity 187animal spirits 67–8anonymity 68–71, 72, 73anti-naturalism 34a priori approach/concepts 32, 33,34–42, 44–5, 46, 57, 66, 87, 89arbitrage 27Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft undSozialpolitik 92Aristotelian practical syllogism 43asset markets 75–7, 183; own rates<strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest 195–6Austrian economics 1–3, 8;critique <strong>of</strong> Keynesianism 10,163–79; radical subjectivism<strong>and</strong> 9, 125–39Austrian <strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>in</strong> America(Vaughn) 9, 125–9, 133–9, 164Austrian <strong>in</strong>stitutionalism,hierarchical metaphors <strong>in</strong> 9–10,143–58Avenarius, R. 84–5average evaluation 188–91, 192–3axiomatic method/axioms 109–10balance <strong>of</strong> expectations 183, 193,196Bank <strong>of</strong> Scotl<strong>and</strong> 157bank<strong>in</strong>g sector 10, 150, 155–8,193–5barter economy 23Bayesian decision theory 129bear (bull-bear position) 187, 193–5beliefs 42–3, 45–6, 68, 85–6Bianchi, M. 138Big Players theory 76–7bottlenecks 172, 174bounded rationality 22Bowles, S. 9, 132, 137–8Br<strong>and</strong>, M. 51Bratman, M.E. 31, 44, 45–6, 47–8budget deficit 175bull-bear position 187, 193–5Butos, W.N. 66, 67, 73–4, 76buyers/buy<strong>in</strong>g 25, 39, 41, 171Camerer, C. 131capabilities 16; capital <strong>and</strong> 24–6capacity utilisation 116, 117, 118,120–1capital 6, 165; Austrian theories <strong>of</strong><strong>in</strong>stitutions <strong>and</strong> (parallels) 9–10,151–4; capabilities <strong>and</strong> 24–6;comb<strong>in</strong>ations 25, 174–5, 176;201


INDEX—output ratio 116; stock 107,169; -us<strong>in</strong>g economy 166–70capital goods 151–4, 166–8, 172,176–8Capital <strong>and</strong> its Structure(Lachmann) 3, 9, 10, 165, 169,178, 184–6carry<strong>in</strong>g costs 10Cartesian rationalism 67Cartesian subject 8, 40, 57Caserta, M. 9, 105, 106cash (bull-bear position) 187,193–5catallactics 18–20causal explanations 50–1, 63, 87,89–91, 94, 95causality 41ceil<strong>in</strong>gs (<strong>in</strong> price system) 171–2,174, 175Ch<strong>and</strong>ler, A.D. 25change: discont<strong>in</strong>uous 108, 109,111; endogenous 9, 104–22,135–6; exogenous 105–7,114–16, 121; <strong>in</strong>cremental 108,111; nature <strong>of</strong> 106–8; theory <strong>of</strong>20Chick, V. 9, 105, 106choice 130, 177; logic <strong>of</strong> 88, 91;rational 14–15, 28, 31, 37–8,43–4, 45, 54class conflict 120closures 115–17co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation 13, 16–17, 19, 21,77; function (<strong>of</strong> market) 7, 14,26–8, 64; pattern 135–6, 144–5; plan 134, 135, 144, 171,173; social 144, 145Codd<strong>in</strong>gton, A. 33Col<strong>and</strong>er, D. 3competition 17, 19, 27, 73–4, 75,137complementarity 152–8, 166–70,172conception, underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> 66constra<strong>in</strong>ed maximisation 129,131constra<strong>in</strong>ed optimisation 131, 134consumer goods 27, 149, 151,174, 175–6consumption 28cont<strong>in</strong>gencies 130contract law 148, 155, 156conventional evaluation 193conventions 22, 23convergence 23convergent expectations 10, 184,186, 187, 194, 196corporate governance 26cost-benefit analysis 17credit 23, 65, 71, 174, 175Davidson, D. 36decision theory 134; rationalignorance 127–33decomposability 22deductions, 35, 40, 42desires 42–3, 44, 45–6, 85–6discont<strong>in</strong>uous change 108, 109,111discursive reason<strong>in</strong>g 66disequilibrium 20, 112dispositional expectations 62, 74,75, 76–7distributional problems 114–15divergent expectations 10, 26–7,183–4, 186–8, 194, 196–7diverse op<strong>in</strong>ion, equity prices <strong>and</strong>188–96, 197division <strong>of</strong> labour 16, 22, 26Donzelli, E 133Dowd, K. 157Dutt, A.K. 115–16, 121Ebel<strong>in</strong>g, R.M. 42, 45economic agents 109–11economic analysts 109–11economic decisions (rationalignorance) 127–33economic growth 105, 106economic <strong>in</strong>stitutions 133–8economic order 133–8, 143economics: history <strong>and</strong> (Mises <strong>and</strong>Lachmann) 32–4; subjectivism<strong>in</strong> 8, 12–29<strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>and</strong> Hermeneutics(Lavoie) 164<strong>Economic</strong>s <strong>of</strong> Time <strong>and</strong>Ignorance, The (O’Driscoll <strong>and</strong>Rizzo) 164efficiency 64, 74, 75–6202


INDEXefficient allocation/co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation 13Ellsberg paradox 131empowerment 23endogenous change 135–6;provisional equilibrium 9,104–22endogenous expectations 64, 68endogenous uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty 130–1,132ends/means 4, 44–5, 48–9, 54,96, 97entrepreneurship 20, 22–4, 27,105, 127–8, 168, 169epistemological isolationism 85,86–7epistemology 36, 40, 66, 67, 83–7,149equilibration 17, 20equilibrium 4, 5, 6, 7, 14, 127–8,130, 132, 134–5, 165; Harm’snotion 109–13; <strong>in</strong>dividual 104,122; Marshall <strong>and</strong> 15–18, 20;prices 188, 189; provisional 9,104–22; see also generalequilibrium theoryEquilibrium <strong>and</strong> Evolution(Loasby) 14equity prices: divergentexpectations <strong>and</strong> 184, 186–8,197; diverse op<strong>in</strong>ion <strong>and</strong>188–96evaluative conclusions 44evolutionary approach 136exchange theory (catallactics)18–20excess capacity 175exogenous change 105–7, 114–16,121expectations 2, 3, 4, 5, 7, 18, 164;balance <strong>of</strong> 183, 193, 196;convergent 10, 184, 186, 187,194, 196; dispositional 62, 74,75, 76–7; divergent 10, 26–7,183–4, 186–8, 194, 196–7;endogenous 64, 68; Lachmannproblem 8, 61–77;psychological 62, 64, 74–5,76–7; rational 13, 64, 75, 77; <strong>in</strong>stock markets 16, 183–97Expectations <strong>and</strong> the Mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong>Institutions (Lavoie) 164explanation 107–8, 111, 113–14;causal 50–1, 63, 87, 89–91, 94,95; <strong>in</strong>tentional 9, 92–3, 96–8explanations <strong>of</strong> pr<strong>in</strong>ciple 88external <strong>in</strong>stitutions 144, 147–8, 155false assumptions/policies 13false production economy 20feedback effects 150f<strong>in</strong>ancial <strong>in</strong>termediaries, law <strong>and</strong>155–8f<strong>in</strong>ancial markets/assets 23–4Fisher, F.M. 130Fogel, R.W. 27forecasts 18, 20, 27, 188–9; seealso predictionformalism 6, 14, 18–19, 21–2, 29,34, 81–2fractional reserve bank<strong>in</strong>g 155–6future <strong>in</strong>tentions (problem <strong>of</strong>)42–8Gadamer, H-G. 53game theory 21, 138, 145Garrison, Roger 163, 164general equilibrium theory 1, 16,17, 19, 20, 27, 88, 132, 134,195General Theory (Keynes) 22, 67,70, 193–5German Historical School 2, 7, 31,33G<strong>in</strong>et, C. 45G<strong>in</strong>tis, H. 9, 132, 137–8gold stocks 155Gottl-Ottlilienfeld, F. von 82, 84,86–7Great Depression 2, 164Gr<strong>in</strong>der, W. 2Grossman, S. 132growth regimes 115, 118–22Habermas, J. 54Hahn, F. 29; equilibrium 106,109–13, 122, 130, 132Hart, O. 131Hayek, F.A. 2, 3, 8, 27, 163–4,203


INDEX170; <strong>in</strong>stitutionalism 143,144–5, 148; Lachmann problem<strong>and</strong> 62, 67, 68, 72–7; radicalsubjectivism 125, 132–9;subjectivism 81–4, 86–8, 91hermeneutics 7, 74heterogeneity 167, 168, 173Hicks, J.R. 2, 23hierarchical metaphors 9–10,143–58history <strong>and</strong> economics (Mises <strong>and</strong>Lachmann) 32–4Holstrom, B. 131Horwitz, S. 136human action 20–4, 128–9, 144;ideal types <strong>of</strong> 92–7; Lachmannon 31–57; Mises on 8, 31–48,67Human Action (Mises) 67Husserl, E. 62Hutt, W.H. 163ideal types 8–9, 50, 69, 71, 80,92–8imag<strong>in</strong>ation 18<strong>in</strong>come distribution 119, 120–1<strong>in</strong>complete contracts 131<strong>in</strong>cremental change 108, 111<strong>in</strong>dividual agents (behaviour)127–30, 134, 136–7, 146<strong>in</strong>dividual equilibrium 104, 127<strong>in</strong>dividual plan 134, 144<strong>in</strong>dividuality/<strong>in</strong>dividual action32–3, 38, 39, 55–6, 136, 144<strong>in</strong>duction 67, 184–5<strong>in</strong>flation premium 74<strong>in</strong>formation: asymmetries 130,132–3, 137; knowledge <strong>and</strong> 9,14, 22, 86–7<strong>in</strong>stitutional order 147, 148–51,152<strong>in</strong>stitutionalism (hierarchicalmetaphors) 9–10, 143–58<strong>in</strong>stitutions 7–8, 77; Austriantheories <strong>of</strong> capital <strong>and</strong>(parallels) 9–10, 151–4;economic 133–8<strong>in</strong>tentional explanation 9, 92–3,96–8<strong>in</strong>tentions 37, 85–6; future(problem <strong>of</strong>) 42–8<strong>in</strong>ter-market relationships 22, 25–8<strong>in</strong>terest rates 65; own 195–6; pricesystem 170–3<strong>in</strong>ternal <strong>in</strong>stitutions 144, 147–8,155<strong>in</strong>terpretation, subjectivism <strong>of</strong> 6–7,63–4, 65, 66, 72, 89–90<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivity/<strong>in</strong>tersubjectivemean<strong>in</strong>g 8, 56–7, 90<strong>in</strong>tra-market processes 19<strong>in</strong>trospective knowledge 86, 87,89–91, 166, 167, 169–70<strong>in</strong>vestment: decision 119, 173;function 114–15, 118–19, 120irrationality 32–3, 37Jevons, W. S. 13, 16, 20Kaldor, N. 2‘kaleidic society’ 62, 82Kant, I. 41Kauder, E.1, 2Kelv<strong>in</strong>, Lord 18Keynes, J.M. 2, 12, 22, 24, 27–8,152; Austrian critique 10, 163,166–7; equity prices 184,192–6; Lachmann problem <strong>and</strong>8, 62, 63, 64, 67–8, 70, 77Keynesian economies (Austriancritique) 10, 163–79Kirzner, I.M. 3, 22, 27, 127–8,129, 132, 134, 164Knight, F. 2, 70knowledge 24–6, 127, 137–8, 145,151, 176, 178; epistemology36, 40, 66–7, 83–7, 149;human action <strong>and</strong> 20–2, 49;<strong>in</strong>formation <strong>and</strong> 9, 14, 22,86–7; <strong>in</strong>trospective 86, 87,89–91; nomological 90, 97;perfect 129; personal 132; self-86, 90; social 83; technological132, 167Koppl, R. 66, 67, 68, 71, 73–4, 76Kreps, D.M. 130, 131labour: division <strong>of</strong> 16, 22, 26;204


INDEXmarket 119–20; theory <strong>of</strong> value149Lachmann, <strong>Ludwig</strong> M. 1–7;expectations <strong>in</strong> stock markets10, 183–97; hierarchicalmetaphors 9–10, 143–58; onhistory <strong>and</strong> economics 32–4;<strong>and</strong> Mises on human action 8,31–57, 67; policy activism 10,163–79; provisional equilibrium(endogenous change <strong>and</strong> opensystems) 9, 104–22; radicalsubjectivism 9, 125–39;subjectivism <strong>of</strong> active m<strong>in</strong>ds 8,61–77; subjectivism <strong>in</strong>economics/the economy 8,12–29; subjectivism <strong>and</strong> idealtypes 8–9, 80–98Lachmann problem 8, 61–3;Hayek <strong>and</strong> 72–7; Keynes <strong>and</strong>67–8; Mises <strong>and</strong> 64–7; Schutz<strong>and</strong> 68–72‘Lachmann’s Law’ 163Lakatos, I. 65Lange, O. 185Langlois, R.N. 71, 73, 138, 144–8passimlanguage 154late classical formalism’ 6Lavoie, D. 164law/legal <strong>in</strong>stitutions 10, 150, 153,155–8Law, Legislation <strong>and</strong> Liberty(Hayek) 133learn<strong>in</strong>g process 109–12, 114, 120,122Legacy <strong>of</strong> Max Weber, The(Lachmann) 3, 7, 8, 9, 144Leibniz, G.W. 69Lerner, A. 2, 3LeRoy, S.R. 76life-world 56liquidity 10, 77, 188, 192;premium 193, 195–6Loasby, B.J. 108, 111Lucas, R. 64Mach, E. 84, 85Mach<strong>in</strong>a, M.J. 131Machlup, F. 71, 73, 74marg<strong>in</strong>al analysis 39–41marg<strong>in</strong>al cost 17marg<strong>in</strong>al productivity theory <strong>of</strong>distribution 114–15marg<strong>in</strong>al utility 1, 17, 87–8, 93Margl<strong>in</strong>, S.A. 115market-clear<strong>in</strong>g hypothesis 118–19Market as an <strong>Economic</strong> Process,The (Lachmann) 169market equilibrium 5, 9market process 5, 13, 22–3, 28,64, 67–8, 72, 104, 126, 136,149–50, 152markets: conventions 22, 23;coord<strong>in</strong>ation functions 7, 14,26–8, 64; efficiency 64, 74,75–6; evolutionary selectionmechanism 73–4, 75; <strong>in</strong>termarketrelationships 22, 25–8;rules 22, 73–4, 133Marshall, A. 19–20, 27; <strong>and</strong>equilibrium 15–18mart<strong>in</strong>gales 75–6mass psychology 67, 68Mayer, H. 2mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> action 35, 52–4means/ends 4, 44–5, 48–9, 54, 96,97Menger, C. 2, 3, 6, 16, 24, 31, 51,82, 88–9, 125, 133, 138, 143,144, 147, 149, 151mental acts/activity 4–5‘mental pictures’ 184mental states 86mental structures 83–4, 86–7metaphors 82, 83; hierarchical (<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>stitutionalism) 9–10, 143–58methodological dualism 84methodological <strong>in</strong>dividualism 4,81, 136, 138methodological legacy <strong>of</strong> Weber80–98methodological solipsism 81, 82–3,84–9, 91, 98methodological subjectivism 74–5methodology (subjectivism <strong>in</strong>economics) 4, 13–15Milgrom, R 132205


INDEXMiller, E.M. 10, 184, 188–9,190–3, 195Mises, L. von 3, 6, 23, 27, 125,135, 163; a priori approach <strong>and</strong>34–42; on history <strong>and</strong>economics 32–4; on humanaction 8, 31–48; Lachmannproblem <strong>and</strong> 62, 64–7;subjectivism 81–4, 86–7Modica, S. 130money: bull-bear position 187,193–5; theory <strong>of</strong> 138, 147Moss, L.S. 133, 134motivational underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g 97Moya, C.J. 47multiple specificity 168, 173multiplier effects 28natural prices 17natural sciences 34–5, 36, 41, 81,88, 91, 92–3natural value 17, 19negative heuristics 125–6Neo-Marxism 120Neo-Ricardianism 6, 18neoclassical economics 6, 17, 31,34, 127–9, 131–3, 135neoclassical equilibrium 126neoclassical model 21, 29, 105New Classical approach 64, 179New Institutional economists 1nihilism 61, 132, 151, 164‘nodal po<strong>in</strong>ts’ 77, 151, 154nomological knowledge 90, 97non-additive probability theory130–1non-anonymous types 71, 72, 76novelty 9, 105, 106–7, 108, 111,113–14, 128, 130Oakes, G. 33objectively rational ideal type 96–7objectives 85–6O’Driscoll, G.P. 127, 135–6, 138,144, 164, 179Ohl<strong>in</strong>, B. 28Old Institutional economists 1ontological doctr<strong>in</strong>e 82, 83, 84–5open-systems approach,provisional equilibrium <strong>and</strong> 9,104–22op<strong>in</strong>ion, diversity <strong>of</strong> (equity prices)188–96option clause 156–7order 132; economic 133–8, 143;<strong>in</strong>stitutional 147, 148–51, 152;social 69, 133, 135–6, 143,147, 151, 153; spontaneous126, 134, 136, 143orientation 53–4, 94‘orientation maps’ 53–4Pareto,V. 1, 15Pareto-constra<strong>in</strong>ed efficiency 132Pareto optimality 154partial specification 9, 105–6path-dependency 20, 154, 168pattern co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation 135–6,144–5Penrose, E.T. 25, 26perfect competition 17, 19, 27phenomenology 36, 40, 62, 68, 74,170physical assets 24‘Plan’ notion 8, 9, 42, 48–57, 95–6plan co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation 134, 135, 144,171, 173plan complementarity 169–70planned economy 13–14plann<strong>in</strong>g models 13–14, 16plutology 18Polanyi, M. 149policy activism 10, 163–79Popper, K. 13, 14, 18positivism 84–5Post-Keynesians 1, 3, 8, 158‘Practical Range’ theory 185praxeology 8, 32, 33, 35–9, 41,43–5, 87, 94, 97, 147prediction 18, 63, 70–1; see als<strong>of</strong>orecastspreferences 5, 21, 63, 164price adjustments 28price signals 5price system 17, 137–8, 145, 165,170–3prices: equity, divergentexpectations <strong>and</strong> 186–8; relative206


INDEX19; stock market expectations10, 183–97Pr<strong>in</strong>ciples <strong>of</strong> <strong>Economic</strong>s (Marshall)19probabilistic knowledge 107probability judgement 70problem-solv<strong>in</strong>g 14, 21, 22production, structure <strong>of</strong> 177, 178production plan 166productive opportunity 25pr<strong>of</strong>it maximisation 109–10pr<strong>of</strong>its 41provisional equilibrium 9, 104–22psychological expectations 62, 64,74–5, 76–7psychopathology 90public works programmes 175–6Pure Theory <strong>of</strong> Capital (Hayek) 3,170purposeful <strong>in</strong>dividual 104, 122purposive behaviour 42–3, 47, 95radical subjectivism 3, 4–6, 7, 10,13, 164; <strong>and</strong> Austrianeconomics 9, 125–39; theory <strong>of</strong>expectations (Lachmannproblem) 8, 61–77Radner, R. 132rational behaviour 36–7rational choice theory 14–15, 28,31, 37–8, 43–4, 45, 54rational expectations 13, 64, 75,77rational ideal types 96–7rational ignorance 127–33rationality 36–7, 40–1, 129;bounded 22; Cartesianrationalism 67reason 42–3, 46rent 17Ricardo, D. 17Richardson, G. 12, 25Rickert, H. 31risk 187, 191, 196risk aversion 10, 191risk premium 191Rizzo, M.J. 127, 135–6, 137, 138,144, 164, 179Robb<strong>in</strong>s, L. 2Roberts, J. 132Rob<strong>in</strong>son, J. 6, 18–19Rosenberg, N. 25Rosenste<strong>in</strong>-Rodan, Paul 2Royal Bank <strong>of</strong> Scotl<strong>and</strong> 157rules 22, 73–4, 133rules-<strong>of</strong>-thumb 46Runde, J. 70Rustich<strong>in</strong>i, A. 130Ryle, G. 90–1Samuelson, P.A. 6Sargent, T. 77Schmoller, G. 31Schumpeter, J.A. 15, 22, 26, 63Schutz, A. 8, 50, 145; Lachmannproblem <strong>and</strong> 62, 68–72, 77scientific positivism 84–5self-knowledge 86, 90sell<strong>in</strong>g 39Sen, A.K. 114–15Shackle, G.L. S. 2, 3, 12, 18, 27,64, 67, 82, 128, 163share prices, expectations <strong>and</strong> 10,183–97Simmel, G. 87, 145Simon, H. 22S<strong>in</strong>nzusammenhang 52Smith, A. 13, 16–17, 20social co-ord<strong>in</strong>ation 144, 145social evolution 134social order 69, 133, 135–6, 143,147, 151, 153social reality 81, 83social sciences 6, 7, 35, 36, 48, 50,55; methodological legacy <strong>of</strong>Weber 8–9, 80–98Sombart, W. 1, 2, 3specificity 152, 153–4, 156, 158,168speculation/speculative equilibrium27spontaneous order 126, 134, 136,143Sraffa, P. 6Sraffians 1, 6, 18stabilisation policy, Lachmannian173–8st<strong>and</strong>ardisation 22–3static equilibrium 113207


INDEXstereotypes (typiflcations) 68–71,72, 73, 76Stiglitz, J.E. 132Stock Exchange 25, 67, 188, 193stock market prices 10, 183–97structural complementarity 169–70subjective evaluations 4subjective theory <strong>of</strong> value 1, 149subjectively rational ideal types96–7subjectivism 2, 53, 56, 57, 164; <strong>of</strong>active m<strong>in</strong>ds 4–5, 8, 61–77; <strong>in</strong>economics/the economy 8,12–29; hierarchical metaphors143–58; <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutional order148–51; levels <strong>of</strong> 4–5; radical(Austrian economics) 9, 125–39;Weber’s methodological legacy8–9, 80–91Sugden, R. 43, 138syllogism 43‘system constra<strong>in</strong>t’ 71, 73tastes 64, 67Taylor, L. 115technological knowledge 132, 167teleological-functionalexplanations 93, 94, 96Thomsen, E. 9trade cycle theory 2, 65, 66, 170–3,176–7Treatise on Money (Keynes) 193–4Treatise on Probability (Keynes) 70typiflcations 68–71, 72, 73, 76uncerta<strong>in</strong>ty 18, 20, 64, 76, 77,107, 127, 129, 157, 168;endogenous 130–1, 132; risk<strong>and</strong> 187, 191; stock marketprices 184, 185, 187–9, 191underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g 89; actual 97;motivational 97; Verstehen 1, 7,34, 51, 66unforeseen cont<strong>in</strong>gencies 130utility maximisation 131‘unknowledge’ 18value system 16–18value theory 19, 151Vaughn, K. 9, 61, 125–6, 127–9,130, 132–4, 135–8, 164Verstehen 1, 7, 34, 51, 66Walras, L. 1, 6, 13, 14, 20, 26wants, subjectivism <strong>of</strong> 4, 6, 63wealth 16, 17, 18Wealth <strong>of</strong> Nations (Smith) 16–17Weber, M. 1, 7, 31, 33, 34, 49–52,69, 131, 144–5; methodologicallegacy <strong>of</strong> 8–9, 80–98welfare 17White, L.H. 137, 157Whitehead, A. 146Wicksell, K. 16Williamson, O.E. 130, 131Witt, U. 136Woo, H.K.H. 25Wright, G.H.von 84Yeager, L. 76Zappia, C. 133, 138208

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!